GRACE COMMENTARY ON THE SUMMA THEOLOGICA OF ST. THOMAS. Ia Ilae, Q. 109-14 Garrigou-Lagrange PREFACE WE have already explained at length in the treatise on the one God the doctrine of St. Thomas about the knowledge and will of God. providence and predestination, and likewise in the treatise on God the Creator his doctrine on evil. Now it remains to apply the principles already expounded to the questions of grace, so that these may be considered in relation to man. and also in relation to God, the author of grace, who is the subject of sacred theology. Indeed this science considers all things in relation to God, as optics does in relation to color and light, mathematics in relation to quantity, metaphysics in relation to being as such. Hence the present treatise On grace depends on the treatise about the divine will in which we have already set forth the will for universal salvation and the distinction between antecedent will and consequent will, which is the ultimate basis, as we shall see, of the distinction between sufficient grace and efficacious grace. We presuppose, likewise, St. Thomas' doctrine on the intrinsic and infallible efficacy of the divine decrees, presented in la. q. 19. a. 8, which we have explained at length in the treatise on the one God, refuting the objections based on the violation of freedom, on insufficiency of help, and on affinity with Cah inism. Our treatise on grace is especially connected with question 20. Part I. on the love of God: I. whether love exists in God; 2. whether God loves all things; 3. whether God loves all tilings equally; 4. whether God always loves better things more. In explanation of this last article, we show the value of the principle of predilection: "Nothing would be better than anything else (as an act, easy or difficult, natural or supernatural, initial or final) unless it were more loved and sustained by God." "What hast thou that thou hast not received ?" (I Cor. 4:7.) As we shall see, this principle throws a light from on high upon all questions of predestination and grace. It is likewise the basis of Christian humility and of our gratitude to God, "who hath first loved us." At the same time, no less emphasis must be placed on another principle of St. Augustine, formulated and cited at the Council of Trent (Denz., no. 804): "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He incites thee to do what thou canst and to ask what thou canst not, and He assists thee so that thou mayst be able." These two principles taken together prevent opposing deviations, preserve balance of thought and the harmony of the divine word in regard to these most difficult questions. AUTHORS TO BE CONSULTED I. THE TEACHING OF THE FATHERS ON GRACE Schwane, Histoire des Dogmes, tr. Degert, 1904. J. Tixeront, Histoire des Dogmes. Vol. I: Théologie anteniceenne. 1905; Vol. II: S. Athanase a S. Augustin, 1909; Vol. Ill: La fin de I’age patristique, 1912, P.274 ff. Hefele, Histoire des conciles, tr. Leclerq (Paris, 1908). II. 168. St. Augustine, De natura et gratia', De gratia Christi'. Enchiridion'. Sex libr. adversus Julianum', De gratia et libero arbitrio', De correptione et gratia', De praedestinatione sanctorum', De dono perseverantiae. St. Prosper, PL. LI. 155-276. St. Fulgentius, De gratia et libero arbitrio. St. Bernard. De gratia et libero arbitrio. Peter Lombard, Sent., Bk. II, d. 26 28: De gratia. St. Bonaventure and St. Albert the Great, In II Sent. 2. WORKS OF ST. THOMAS AND OF THOMISTS ON GRACE St. Thomas, In II Sent., d. 26-28; la Ilae. q. 109-14; Contra Gentes, Quaest. disput. Principal commentators: Capreolus, In IISent., d. 26; Cajetan. In lam Ilae, q. 109 ff.; Medina, John of St. Thomas. Sylvius, Gonet, the Sahnanticenses, Gotti, Billuart. Soto, De natura et gratia, 1551. Thomas Lemos, Panopliagratiae, 4 vols., 1676. Alvarez, De auxiliis divinae gratiae, 1610. Gonzalez de Albeda, In lam, q. 19, 1637. Goudin, De gratia, 1874. Reginaldus, O.P., De mente Cone. Trident, circa gratiam seipsa efficacem, 1706. Among recent works by Thomists: Dummermuth: S. Thomas et doctrina praemotionis physicae, Paris, 1886; Defensio doctrinae S. Thomas, 1895. N. Del Prado, O.P.,: De gratia et libero arbitrio. 3 vols., Fribourg (Switzerland), 1907. Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P.·. La predestination des saints et la grace, 1936; Diet. theol. cath., arts., "Predestination," "Premotion." Schaezler: Natur und Gnade, Mainz, 1867. 3. OUTSIDE THE THOMISTIC SCHOOL Molina, Concordia, Paris, 1876. Suarez, De gratia. St. Robert Bellarmine, De controversiis (Prague. 1721). Vol. IV. St. Alphonsus de Liguori, De modo quo gratia operatur; De magno orationis medio. Scheeben. Natur und Gnade, Mainz, 1861. Strongly inclines toward Thomism. Billot, S. J., De gratia Christi, 2nd ed., 1921. Van derMeersch, De divina gratia (Bruges, 1910) and Diet, theol. cath., art., "Grace." J. Ude, Doctrina Capreoli de influxu Dei in actus voluntatis humanae, Graz, 1905. This author favors Thomism. TREATISE ON GRACE IA HAE, Q. 109-114 In the first place something must be said about the position of this treatise in the Summa theologica. St. Thomas treats of grace in the moral part of his Summa, for, after the questions of human acts themselves, must be considered the principles of human acts; first, the intrinsic principles, namely, good and bad habits, or virtues and vices; secondly, the external principles of human acts, namely. God's teaching us by means of His law, and His assistance to us by His grace. [1 ] Hence the treatise on grace belongs to the moral part of theology no less than the treatise on law. Moral theology is not a science distinct from dogmatic theology, since the formal object {objectum formale quod et quo) is ever the same: God under the aspect of His Deity so far as it falls under virtual revelation. It would be surprising if the moral part of sacred theology did not treat of the necessity of grace for doing good conducive to salvation and of the effects of grace. i.e., justification and merit. Indeed, if moral theology is deprived of these treatises, it will be reduced almost to casuistry, which is only its lowest application, as asceticism and mysticism are its highest applications. DIVISION OF THE TREATISE ON GRACE [diagram page viii]_________________________________ 1. The grace of God itself 1.1. the necessity of grace for our final end. q. 109 1.2. the essence of grace, q. 110 1.3. the divisions of grace, q. Ill 2. The cause of grace: q:l 12, the efficient cause and the prerequisite disposition 3. The effects of grace 3.1. justification, q. 113 3.2. merit, q. 114 Among Thomistic commentators the following, along with Cajetan, are especially to be read: Soto {De natura et gratia), John of St. Thomas, the Salmanticenses, Gonet. Gotti, Billuart. Cf. also among modern theologians, Scheeben {Natur und Gnade). This division of the whole treatise is methodical, corresponding to the division into four causes. I. Grace is considered beginning with the definition of the word and with reference to its necessity for the end of eternal life and to its existence. 2. Thus, in regard to its end, grace, as it is the seed of glory, is defined as a participation in the divine nature and is determined by the subject in which it resides, that is, the essence of the soul. 3. After the definition of grace, its subdivisions are given. Then its efficient cause and its effects are discussed. Thus all those things which belong to it per se are taken into consideration. A brief comparison may be made between this division of St. Thomas and the division made by various modern writers. Many modern scholars, such as Tanquerey, divide this treatise into three parts, but this division is rather material than formal. [diagram page ix]____________________________________________________________________________ Grace 1. Actual grace 1.1. Its necessity for supernatural works and good acts in the natural order 1.2. The dispensation of actual grace and its nature, including sufficient and efficacious grace (Thomism, Molinism) 2. Habitual grace, or the grace of justification 2.1. The nature of justification and the dispositions it requires 2.2. The essence of grace 2.3. Its properties, namely, the virtues and gifts 2.4. The graces gratis datae 3. Merit: its nature, conditions, and object This dix ision is less correct; in treating of the necessity of grace the necessity of habitual grace is also treated. And in the order of knowledge it is better to deal with justification, which is an effect of grace, after considering the essence of grace. Hence Father Billot. S.J., after his preliminary remarks, rightly divides his treatise on grace 1 Cf. la Ilae. q.90, introd. With regard to this heading, it should be noted that God assisting by His grace is an extrinsic principle. Grace, however, is not a principle extrinsic to man. but inhering in him. as w ill be explained later according to St. Thomas. Father Hugon, O.P.? does the same, as do many others. Nor may it be said that St. Thomas did not distinguish clearly between habitual and actual grace: this distinction is made time and time again in the articles, and thereby is made evident how St. Thomas perfected the Augustinian doctrine, regarding grace not only from the psychological and moral aspects, but ontologically: I. as an abiding form, and 2. as a transitory movement. This entire treatise is a commentary on the words of our Lord in John 4:10: "If thou didst know the gift of God," and our Lord's discourse by which they are elucidated, according to St. John. At the same time it may be said that St. Paul was the apostle of grace who opened to us the deep tilings of God. predestination and grace. And the two great doctors of grace are Augustine, who defended divine grace against Pelagius, and St. Thomas, of whom the liturgy sings: • • • • "Praise to the King of glory, Christ, Who by Thomas, light of the Church, Filled the earth with the doctrine of grace." This work is a translation of De gratia by Father Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P. CHAPTER I: INTRODUCTION BRIEF introductory remarks are necessary so as to avoid repetitions: 1. On the various meanings of the word "grace" and presupposed notions from the treatise on God: 2. On the errors invok ed in this subject. MEANINGS OF THE WORD GRACE The various meanings are indicated by St. Thomas (la lae, q. 110, a. I), but it is fitting that we say something of them at the beginning so that the connection may be apparent between the present question and the questions relating to God's love for us. First, there are of course three acceptations of this word "grace" even used in human affairs. For grace (Xarij) originally refers to something which is not due or is freely bestowed; this meaning is very common in both profane and biblical writings. Hence even in purely human matters the term "grace" has a threefold application, as follows: 1. The love of benevolence conferring a gift which is not due; for example, we say: This soldier has the grace of the king. 2. The gift itself freely bestowed; thus we say: I grant you this grace. 3. Gratitude for a benefit receh ed; thus: I render you thanks for your benefits. [2] Moreover, these three significations may be transferred to the supernatural order, whereupon the word grace applies to the following. 1. The love of benevolence on the part of God, conferring supernatural life. This love of God is uncreated grace. 2. The supernatural gift of grace itself, freely bestowed and ordained to eternal life; this is created grace, of which we are now treating, whether it is interior or exterior, such as the preaching of the gospel. 3. Our gratitude to God. 2 In Latin the word for "thanks" is "gratiae. " Hence the third meaning of gratia. (Tr. ) Between the human and the supernatural meanings of the word "grace" there lies a great difference which is principally based upon the fact that God's love of benevolence forus, as stated in la, q. 20. a. 2. infuses and creates goodness in things, whereas the love of benevolence of one man for another presupposes something lovable in that other. But "God's love for the creature is twofold, the common love whereby natural being is bestowed on created things, and the other special love by which God raises the rational creature above the state of nature unto a participation in the divine good. Thus grace is the effect of the love of God in us and signifies the supernatural gift freely granted by God to an intellectual creature ordained to eternal life" (la Ilae. q. 110, a. I). Thus the whole treatise on grace in the Summa theologica of St. Thomas depends upon the treatise on the love of God (la. q. 20). in which are expressed and explained two supreme principles which throw a light from above upon all the articles of the treatise on grace and virtually contain them. Hence St. Thomas says: "It is demonstrated above (q. 19, a. 4) that the will of God is the cause of all things; so it must be that so far as a thing possesses being or any good whatever, to that extent it is willed by God. Therefore God wills some good to whatever exists. And since loving is nothing else but wishing well to someone, it is clear that God loves all things that are. not however in the same way as we do. Our will is not the cause of the goodness of things. But the love of God infuses and creates goodness in things" (la, q. 20, a. 2). Accordingly the will of God is also the cause of the goodness of our acts, while preserving their liberty. As St. Thomas says: "If the will of God is most efficacious, it follows not only that those things will be done which God wills to be done, but that they will be done in the way God wills them to be done. Thus God wills certain tilings to be necessary, others to be contingent, that there may be order among things for the perfection of the universe" (la, q. 19. a. 8). From this first principle thus understood the second follows: "Since the love of God is the cause of the goodness of tilings, nothing is in any respect better, if God does not will one thing to be better than another" (la, q. 20, a. 4, 5). This is the principle of predilection which is valid for every created being and for the facility or difficulty of each of its acts : No created being is in any respect better if it is not preferred by God. St. Thomas deduces from this that "in God love precedes election... for His will, willing good to whatever it loves, is the cause of its possessing this good from Him beyond others" (ibid., q. 23, a. 4). This principle of predilection presupposes that the divine decrees in regard to our future acts conducive to salvation are infallibly efficacious of themselves and not from a foreknow ledge of our consent (la, q. 19, a. 8). Otherwise, of two men equally loved and assisted by God, one would be in some respect better. He would be better of himself and not so far as preferred by God; and therefore the free determination in him to be saved would be something good which would not proceed from the source of all good, contrary to the words of St. Paul: "For who distinguished! thee? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received ?" (I Cor. 4:7. ) These are the principles already laid down and explained in the treatises on the will and on the love of God; they virtually contain what is now to be said concerning grace, both habitual grace and actual grace. Finally, it must be remarked that the Pelagians, not wishing to recognize the love of God as being the first cause of all our good choices, were equally averse to distinguishing the natural from the supernatural meanings of this word "grace. " They therefore misused it in a broad, incorrect sense and applied the word "grace" to any free gift of God whatever; thus creation, preservation, and even free will are called by them graces. Likewise created grace properly so called is defined in a variety of ways: 1. As external grace, such as the preaching of the gospel, the example of Christ; and the Pelagians admitted this grace. 2. As internal grace, namely, that which is received in the interior of the soul, ennobling it. Moreover, this internal grace may be either that which makes one pleasing (gratum faciens), which is divided into habitual or sanctifying grace, and actual grace, or charismatic grace (gratia gratis data), which is principally or primarily for the benefit of others. [diagram page 6] Grace 1. 2. internal 1.1. whic h renders pleasing {gratum faciens) 1.1.1. hab itual orjustifyingors anc tify ing 1.1.2. actual, which includes sufficient and efficacious 1.2. charismatic {gratis data)·, for example, the fight of prophecy, the discernment of spirits, the gift of tongues external: e.g., the preaching of the Gospel Since grace is indeed supernatural, and frequently in this treatise there will be question of the distinction between what is supernatural substantially and what is supernatural modally, it will be well to recall the definition and division of supernaturalness itself as it has already been set forth in fundamental theology. The supernatural, according to the Catholic Church, is that which is above all created nature; which, although it exceeds the powers and requirements of any nature created or capable of being created, does not exceed the passive capacity of perfectibility and aptitude of our nature. (Cf. Denz., nos. 1790, 1795, 1808, 1816; Garrigou-Lagrange, De revelatione, I, 193, 197. 202. ) Moreover, according to the Church, supernaturalness is at least twofold, namely: 1. The supernaturalness of miracles, which surpasses the efficient powers and requirements of any created nature, but not, however, the cognitive powers of human nature. (Denz.. nos. 1790, 1818. ) 2. The supernaturalness of mysteries strictly' speaking and of the life of grace and glory is that which surpasses not only the efficient powers and requirements of any created nature, but also the cognitive and appetitive powers (or natural merit) of any intellectual nature created or capable of being created. Such is the declared doctrine of the Church as follows from the condemnation of naturalism, rationalism semi­ rationalism (which deviates in the matter of the powers), Baianism (an excess as to requirements), and agnosticism (denying that miracles are ascertainable). Cf. Denz., nos. 1795, 1808; cf. De Revelatione, I, 193. This division of supernaturalness may be otherwise expressed according to the terminology rather generally accepted among theologians, thus: [diagram page 7]________________________________________________________________________________________ The Absolute Supernatural exceeding the powers and requirements of any created nature 1. with respect to substance or to the formal cause 1.1. une reated substantial of itself 1.1.1. God in the most intimate sense of His Deity and Trinity 1.1.2. The uncreated person of the Word subsisting in the human nature of Christ 1.2. created (accidental) 1.2.1. Habitual and actual grace, the infused virtues, the gifts of the Holy Ghost (supernatural by virtue of their formal object) 2. with respect to the manner or to the extrinsic causes, that is. in the manner both of its extrinsic disposition and of its production 2.1. in regard to the end 2.1.1. Natural act, such as acquired temperance, as supernaturally ordered by charity to a supernatural end. 2.2. in regard to the efficient cause (la, q. 105. a. 8) 2.2.1. The miraculous substantially (the glorification of the body or prophecy) 2.2.2. The miraculous subjectively (nonglorified resurrection, the knowledge of the secrets of hearts 2.2.3. The miraculous modally (sudden cure of a fever, the gift of tongues). This is found in John of St. Thomas, the Salmanticenses, and Suarez. Cf. De revelatione, I, 205, for the explanation of this division and its reduction to the division of the four causes. The miraculous substantially is not to be confused with the supernatural substantially. [3] ERRORS CONCERNING GRACE In the introduction a brief reference must be made to the history of this doctrine of grace in relation to the mutually opposing errors on the subject: that is, Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism on the one hand, Baianism and Jansenism on the other. For at the appearance of these contrary errors, the Church solemnly defined its doctrine on grace. It is therefore advisable to determine at the start at least the principal opposing theses which have been condemned; thus will be brought to light the problems still disputed among Catholic theologians. It will be easier in explaining the articles later to show how St. Thomas' arguments prevail over such and such a heresy. Since St. Thomas preceded Bains, he could not have before his eyes, as we have, several definitions of the Church which clearly determined how the excess contrary to Pelagianism was to be avoided: yet St. Thomas was acquainted withpredestinationism from the Council of Lyons (475) and its subsequent condemnation at the Council of Quierzy against Gottschalk, who prepared the way for Lutheranism and thereby for Baianism and Jansenism. Generally, it is true, when great problems must be solved, there arise almost from the beginning mutually opposing theses, and only by degrees, under the inspiration of God, does the mind attain to the summit of truth whereon diverse aspects of reality are reconciled. St. Thomas reached this summit and escaped the excess of future Jansenism no less than the defect of Pelagianism. As we observed in De revelatione (I, 398), the two extremes that are to be avoided may be termed naturalism and pseudo-supernaturalism. Naturalism denies that the Christian life is beyond natural powers; in other words, it declares that what is in reality achieved by it can be achieved without interior grace. Indeed it maintains that the human intellect in its natural development is capable of attaining to the possession of every truth and good, even to the intuition of God. (Denz., no. 1808. ) Pseudo-supernaturalism denies that the Christian life is above the requirements of nature; in other words, human reason is so weak that it necessarily stands in need of revelation, which accordingly is not properly supernatural, and its exaltation to a participation in the divine nature was due to it for the integrity of its original state. In both errors there is a confusion of the two orders, but the first confusion sins by exaggerated optimism in regard to the powers of human nature, and the second by exaggerated pessimism in regard to the destitution of nature. Pelagian naturalism differs, as a matter of fact, from modern rationalism so far as it does not reject the external revelation of the Gospel confirmed by miracles, holding it to be divine, as did the Semi-rationalists (Froschammer, Gunther, and Hermes), who nevertheless wished to prove every mystery. But in all these doctrines the tendency is the same, namely, to deny the necessity of grace. Particularly it should be noted that naturalism proceeds historically from the pagans or Gentiles; many of thenphilosophers thought that moral powers came from man alone and not from God, and they besought God only for fortune or a happy outcome. Thus, in particular, Cicero and Seneca who agreed that "there is one good, which is the cause and foundation of a blessed life: to have faith in oneself" (Letter 31, 3). Such is the opinion of naturalists today, whether atheists or deists, who deny that providence extends to every individual thing, or theists. who admit providence in the natural order but not in the supernatural. Liberal Protestants adhere to this teaching in a greater or less degree. On the other hand, Judaism inclined toward naturalism in another way, for Judaism, contrary to the evident 3 The supernatural substantiali}' (such as sanctifying grace) is said to be formally so (formaliter quoad substantiam), for it is essentially supernatural. The substantiali} miraculous (such as the glorious resurrection) is said to be supernatural effectively {effective quoad substantiam) but not formali}'; that is, on the part of the agent, but not as to the exercise of the effect produced testimony of Holy Scripture, made justice or justification dependent, not on the supernatural grace of God, but on the external observance of the law and the physical origin of the children of Abraham. Against this, cf. Council of Jerusalem, Acts of the Apostles, A D. 50 (Acts. 15). and St. Paul (Rom. 2-4; Gal., 3-5) Likewise the Origenists and Theodore of Mopsuestia did not recognize sufficiently the necessity of grace. Pelagianism, the chief heresy of this kind, gathered together the preceding errors of like tendency into something of a system and spread it throughout the world in the fifth century. Historically speaking, there were three phases to the doctrine of the Pelagians. 1. It denied original sin, the necessity of baptism and interior grace for obtaining ordinary eternal life. It declared, however, that baptism and grace are necessary' for entering the kingdom of God, which is something excelling ordinary eternal life. Hence, to attain to eternal life as commonly accepted, no grace was necessary, not even the grace of faith or the knowledge of external revelation. But, said Pelagius, God gave us a power or faculty, i. e., free will; moreover, willing and doing are eminently proper to us. Grace would be only an unnecessary adornment, just as some souls have visions and ecstasies, without which, however, a man can be saved. 2. Later, to refute the objections drawn from Holy Scripture, Pelagius admitted the term "grace" and the necessity of grace, but by this name he designated free will, and subsequently the external grace of revelation or tire preaching of the gospel. 3. Finally. Pelagius, not knowing how to reply to the objections of Catholics, admitted internal grace, but first in the intellect alone, that is, as enlightenment; secondly, he recognized some habitual grace, but not as plainly gratuitous (he maintained that it was given according to the merits of nature) nor strictly supernatural; thirdly, the Pelagians ultimately admitted as more probable actual grace in the will, not however plainly gratuitous (but granted according to natural merits) nor necessary for doing good, but only for working more easily and perfectly. Cf. Billuart (De gratia, diss. I), who cites many texts of St. Augustine on the subject. Hence there are in Pelagianism two heresies in particular regarding internal grace. 1. If internal grace is given, it is not simply gratuitous, but is bestowed according to natural merit. 2. It is not necessary for merely acting as is needful for salvation, but for doing so with greater facility or for accomplishing some more excellent works. Thus without the internal grace of faith we can arrive at the formal motive of Christian faith. This is the teaching of Pelagius and of his principal disciples, Caelestius and Julian of Eclanum. against whom Augustine and Jerome wrote. Cf. Tixeront, Hist, des dogmes. This heresy was condemned by twenty-four separate councils, notably by the first and second councils of Carthage, that of Milevum, and finally by the ecumenical Council of Ephesus, 431; cf. Denz., nos. 101 ff.. 126, 129, 142, 174 ff„ 138. The Semi-Pelagians admitted not only external revelation but properly supernatural internal grace, although they erred in two respects, namely, in regard to initial grace and final grace. They said: 1. The beginning of salvation depends on man's petitioning for it, so far as man, without grace, by desiring through a pious disposition to believe, by knocking, by asking, can prepare himself for grace, which is bestowed on account of this natural preparation. Hence initial grace was not simply gratuitous. Likewise they all maintained that the consent to the initial grace offered is entirely ours. [4] 4 Not all the Semi-Pelagians understood in the same way that the initial step to salvation comes from us and not from God. Some who approached nearer to Pelagius placed the beginning of salvation in some acts performed, such as the act of believing, desiring, asking, seeking grace and salvation. Others, convinced by the arguments of Catholics, that every work conducive to salvation is from God, limited this initial movement to the consent to that grace which God 1. The last grace, namely, of final perseverance, is not strictly gratuitous but may be obtained by our merits; nay rather, they said, "man perseveres to the end, so far as he abides in that consent to the grace offered him, bestowed at the moment of justification" (Billuart, loc. cit. ). From these two errors it followed that predestination, whether to grace or to glory, is not strictly gratuitous for. according to this teaching, the first grace is conferred on account of the merits of nature, broadly speaking, and the term of salvation depends upon the preceding merits which have been foreseen. (See the canons of the Council of Orange; Denz., nos. 176 ff. ) It would be well to have a thorough knowledge of the history of Semi-Pelagianism so as to understand correctly what was condemned in it and in what respect Molinism differs from it. It is clear, as Billuart demonstrates {ibid. ), that the Semi-Pelagians taught that predestination, whether to grace or to glory, was not gratuitous, but that God accompanied all men, the reprobate as well as the predestinate, with equal love, and offered grace and glory to all equally: hence, according to the Semi-Pelagians, of two men to whom grace is offered equally by God, he possesses grace who consents to it of himself, he receives no greater help, and he receives glory who. of himself, perseveres in the grace received. Consequently the Semi-Pelagians declared in respect to foreknowledge: "God, from eternity, predestined to grace those who He foresaw would consent and utilize it well, and He predestined to glory those who He foresaw would similarly persevere in grace, of themselves. " Thus the knowledge of God is not the cause of tilings, at least it is not the cause of our determination toward the good, which is first in the affair of salvation. Hence men rather save themselves than are saved by God; in other words, God would not bestow our consent to good, but would expect it of us. (Denz., no. 177; Summa theol., la, q. 23, a. 5, 2nd error. ) Indeed the Semi-Pelagians hit upon mediate knowledge {scientia media) before Molina, as the Thomists in general clearly show, particularly, among the more recent, Father delPrado {De gratia et lib. arb., Ill, 312). And this is also evident from the epistles of St. Prosper to St. Augustine and from the book on the Predestination of the Saints, (chaps. 14 and 17). As a logical conclusion to their theory, the Semi-Pelagians necessarily arrived at mediate knowledge, at least in regard to the salvation of infants. They were therefore obliged to solve this objection: among infants, some, without any merit on their part, are predestined to baptism and eternal life. But not being willing to admit gratuitous predestination even in this case, the Semi-Pelagians replied: God know s even the conditional future, and predestined to baptism those infants who He foresaw would have consented to grace and persevered if they had reached the age of adults. [5] Similarly, they maintained, in regard to infidels: God foresaw what they would have done, of themselves, if the preaching of the gospel had been proposed to them. [6] Moreover, this foreknowledge of conditional future events or of events possible in the future, independent of divine decree, is the foreknowledge which is now called scientia media. But Molina admitted, above and beyond this, prevenient grace. From this theory' they further deduced many corollaries, for instance: Christ died equally for all, and dispenses the price of His death equally to all, so that the vessels of mercy receive no more of benefit than the vessels of wrath, offered each one that it might cooperate in a good act. On this beginning, whatever it might be, and on perseverance in it they based their argument for predestination. (Cf. Billuart, op. cit. ) They maintained that tills beginning of salvation, proceeding from us and not from God, merits the first grace, at the favorable moment, so to speak. This is evident from Faustus, who, as Geimadius relates in his life, used to say: "Whatever freedom of the will may ac quire of honest reward for labor is not, properly speaking, merit. " Likewise Cassian in his Collationes, chap. 14: "God is ready in the event of the offering of our will to bestow all these things upon it. " 5 And, on the other hand infants who die without baptism would be punished for sins which they would have committed if they had lived for a long time. Thus they would be punished for sins that were not real but only conditional, which is unjust 6 Cf. Summa theol, la. q. 23. a. 5s, 3rd error whatever St. Paul may say (Rom. 9:22). Otherwise, as they said, God would be an unjust respecter of persons if, without previous merit or disposition. He were to give grace to one and deny it to another. And, they added, this would lead to fatalism, would deprive reproof and prayer of their usefulness, and would lead to despair. Moderate Semi-Pelagians, such as Cassian (13th Conference), although they admitted initial grace, whenever it was given gratuitously without any merits, allowed that it was more often bestowed on the basis of merit. Further, certain Semi-Pelagians openly declared that perhaps prevenient grace was truly gratuitous in respect to initial acts, and was indeed conferred by God, although He expects our consent. And. as Billuart remarks (loc. Cit. ): "This was the last stand of this heresy, so far as its concessions are concerned, namely: it depends upon us to accept or reject grace, so that in those who accept it their consent does not depend on the grace of God, but on themselves. In this sense they withdrew from grace the initial step toward salvation as well as perseverance, and attributed them to free will. " The advocates of Semi-Pelagianism were certain monks of Hadrometam. as well as Cassian, Gennadius of Marseilles, and Faustus of Riez. The Semi-Pelagianism of Cassian is found particularly in bis thirteenth Conference entitled: "Of God's Protection, " in which he teaches: "Grace and free will certainly' concur in the matter of salvation to the extent that the initial good will and pious disposition to believe, that is. the first step toward salvation, is ordinarily from man alone, and not from God, although in exceptional cases the beginning of salvation and good will comes from God, as in the vocations of St. Matthew and St. Paul. " The adversaries of Semi-Pelagianism were the aged St. Augustine [7] and St. Prosper, St. Fulgentius, Hilary, and Caesarius of Arles. This heresy was condemned by Pope Celestine (432), Pope Gelasius (494), who denounced the books of Faustus and Cassian. and finally by the Second Council of Orange (529), which had the special approbation of Boniface II. In regard to the condemnation of Semi-Pelagianism, Denzinger records the entire Second Council of Orange (529). that is, twenty-four canons: see especially 3-12. 18-22. 25. Molinism differs from Semi-Pelagianism in three respects: 1. in regard to prevenient grace; 2. in regard to the covenant entered into betyveen God and Christ the Redeemer; 3. in regard to the circumstances of the life of the predestinate. Cf. Molina. Concordia. 1. Molina admits prevenient grace inclining to the initial movement to salvation, or consent to good, but he says: the distinction betyveen the yvill consenting to this grace offered and the yvill rejecting it depends on man's liberty alone. Cf. Molina, op. cit., pp. 230. 459. 7 De civ. Dei, Bk. XII, chap. 6: "If the efficient cause of bad is sought, none yvill be found.... If tyy o individuals similarly constituted soul and body, both perceive the beauty of the same body; if, having seen it. one of the tyvo is moved to illic it enjoyment, yy hereas the < perseveres firmly in a virtuous will, what shall yve consider to be the cause of bad yvill present in one and not in the other ?... If botl tempted by the same temptation and one yields and consents, yvhile the other remains unmoved, what else is evident but that one yy and the other did not will to fail in chastity?... The same beauty yvas seen equally by the eyes of both; the same interior temptation soli both equally; what, therefore caused that particular bad will in one of them?... Nothing presents itself. Can (human) nature be the can: evil will in that it is human nature? No, for it is found in both individuals. But so far as it is drawn from nothingness, it is deficient ir and not in the other. " (St. Thomas says: that which is defectible in itself can be reasonably expected to fail in some respect, with d permission. ) Chap. 7: "Let no one, therefore, seek the efficient cause of bad yvill, since it is not efficient, but deficient; for this is n< effect, but a defect. To fall ayvay then, from yvhat is greater to what is less is to begin to have an evil yvill. " Chap. 9: "These angels, were created with the good, and are yet bad, bad by their oyvn will, either received less grace of divine love than those w ho persever it. or if they were both created equally good, yvhen the former fell from evil yvill, the latter, receiving greater help, attained to that full of beatitude. " Whence the same Augustine says, commenting on St. John (tr. 26): "If you do not yvishto fall into error, do not attempt to judge why God drayvs this one and does not drayv that one. " Likewise St. Thomas (la, q. 23, a. 5). yvhen the Semi-Pelagians said: "God draws this person because He sees the initial step to salvation naturally in him and not in another. " The Thomists object that before this distinction, there is not yet any initial step toward salvation, because it is not found in those who resist first grace, as in Lessius, De gratia efficaci, chap. 18, no. 7. 2. Molina maintains that, if anyone does whatever he can by means of mere natural powers, God does not refuse grace; but he avoids Semi-Pelagianism by saying: God does not confer grace on account of this good natural disposition, but because of the covenant entered into between Himself and Christ the Redeemer. Cf. infra, q. 109, a. 6: q. 112, a. 3; Molina, op. cit., pp. 43, 564; Index, "Faciens quod in se est. 3. Molina says (pp. 51, 565): help being equal, it is possible for one of those called to be converted and another not converted. With less assistance from grace it is possible for the one assisted to make progress, while another, with greater help, does not improve, and hardly perseveres. They are not aids established as efficacious in themselves which distinguish between the predestinate and the nonpredestinate. However, according to Molina, the predestinate receives greater help than the reprobate from the standpoint of the situation in which he is placed by the divine good pleasure, for indeed he is placed in circumstances in which God foresees by mediate knowledge that he will consent to grace. Hence, from the viewpoint of circumstances, the gift of final perseverance depends solely on the divine good pleasure; thus, to a certain extent at least, the gratuity of predestination, denied by the Semi-Pelagians, is preserved; but, as the Thomists declare, this is seen to be gratuity of predestination only in regard to the circumstances which are more or less appropriate or suitable. THE PSEUDO-SUPERNATURALISM OF PREDESTINATIONISM, PROTESTANTISM, BAIANISM, AND JANSENISM This pseudo-supernaturalism is the error opposed to naturalism; it sins by excess, that is, it affirms the necessity of grace even for all natural good works, so that all the works of infidels are sins. But in reality, as we have said, it further confuses the order of grace with the order of nature, as it holds that grace is not above the exigencies of our nature, which it considers entirely impotent even in its own order. Whence it can be seen that it extolls grace, while it proclaims its necessity beyond measure, but it actually destroys the supernaturalness of grace and depreciates nature. It is pessimistic in regard to nature as Pelagianism is optimistic in its estimate of nature. This pseudo-supernaturalism appears in predestinationism (cf. Denz., nos. 316 ff._ 320 ff. ). The doctrine is attributed to Lucidus, a priest of the fifth century, who retracted his error. But the heresy is found especially in the writings of Gottschalk, in the ninth century (cf. Denz., nos. 316 ff. ; Diet, theol, cath., "Predestination." section on the Middle Ages, ninth century). According to predestinationism. grace and predestination are necessary for doing good; whence those who are not predestined to eternal life sin necessarily', justas the predestinate are necessarily saved. Thus no real liberty remains after original sin. According to predestinationism, there is not only predestination to eternal life, but also predestination to evil for the reprobate. All these errors were condemned, in 853, at the Council of Quierzy at which the following was defined (Denz., no. 317): "There is no predestination to evil.... We have a freewill for good, aided by prevenient grace.... We have a free will for evil deprived of grace. " Likewise Denz., no. 318: "Almighty God wills that all men without exception should be saved (I Tim.. 2:4) although all are not saved. That some are saved is due to the gift of salvation; that some are lost is due to the lack of merit in the reprobate. " Denz.. no. 319: "There never was and never will be a man... for whom Christ did not suffer... ; that all are not redeemed by the mystery of His passion pertains to the working of infidelity .... unless they drink, they cannot be cured. " This error was revived by Luther and Calvin. Luther maintained that grace and integrity were due to nature in the state of innocence; whereas in the state of fallen nature, free will is so corrupted that it is a mere name without a reality, and therefore requires grace, to such an extent that whatever is done without faith and grace is sin. Whence it follows that all the works of infidels and sinners are sins. Sanctifying grace is. in fact, only an external imputation of the merits of Christ, and man is justified by faith alone without works; man is justified by a "fiduciary " faith by which he believes that his sins are forgiven. Calvin agrees with Luther in this, and adds that God predestined some to hell and the faithful who believe themselves predestined are saved by this very faith. Further, children born of predestinate parents are by that very fact children of God and can be saved without baptism. Thus it is apparent how, in this pseudo-supernaturalism, nature is greatly depreciated and even grace is only apparently extolled, since it is due to nature and reduced to a mere extrinsic denomination or to an external imputation of the merits of Christ. The way was prepared for this teaching by Ockham and the Nominalists of whom Luther was a disciple at the University of Wittemberg. as Denifle shows in his Luther und Luthertum, 1904. For the Nominalists, habitual grace is not intrinsically supernatural, but only by extrinsic denomination, as a bank note is not gold. Baianism is again a somewhat attenuated Protestantism. It teaches in particular three doctrines: 1. The grace accorded to Adam was due to nature, and hence did not exceed the requirements of nature. 2. Faith is therefore necessary' even for natural good, so that all the virtues of infidels are vices. 3. Sanctifying grace is so necessary that all the works of sinners are sins. (Denz., nos. 1001 ff. ) Baianists almost identify grace and natural probity. Jansenism retained these same errors in substance, as is evident from the five propositions of Jansen. (Denz.. no. 1092. ) It suffices to note the first of these to make it clear how widely Thomism differs from Jansenism, whatever else may be sometimes asserted. This first Jansenist proposition is. in fact, thus expressed: "Some precepts of God to just men who are willing and striving, are. in the present state of their powers, impossible; grace is wanting to them, also, by which such precepts may become possible. " Augustine declared the contrary', as cited by the Council of Trent: "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He incites thee both to do what thou cans! and to ask what thou canst not, and He assists thee that thou mayest be able" (Denz., no. 804). Likewise, 101 propositions of Quesnel were condemned in the bull Unigenitus (1713) (Denz., nos. 1351, 1451); lastly the synod of Pistoia was condemned by Pius VI in the bull Auctorem fidei. (Denz.. nos. 1516 ff. ) As can be seen, Baianists and Jansenists agree in some respects withPelagianists, that is, in denying the gratuity and therefore the true supernaturalness of the state of innocence. Jansen also said that in the state of innocence efficacious grace in itself was not necessary. (He was a Molinist in this regard. ) In line with the same tendency, the immanentism of the Modernists, for example, Laberthonniere, asserts that grace is demanded by nature, and thus they destroy its supernaturalness (cf. Denz., no. 2103 andHugon, De gratia, p. 212). Finally, it should be remarked that, just as Molinism withdraws from Semi-Pelagianism. so Thomism recedes from Calvinism and Jansenism, as the Sovereign Pontiffs, Clement XI, Benedict XIII. and Paul V have declared. (Denz., p. 342 note. ) Benedict XIII forbade anyone to condemn the doctrine of St. Thomas and his school or to traduce it as condemned by the bull Unigenitus. Subsequently Clement XII forbade "the branding of this doctrine by any note or theological censure by the schools holding diverse opinions... until tire Holy See should pass judgment by some definition or pronouncement in regard to such controversies. " Cf. Denz.. no. 1097 note. Thomism differs particularly from predestinationism and Jansenism in the following respects. 1. It denies predestination to evil and the opinion that God is the author of sin. 2. It teaches that predestination to glory does not destroy, through intrinsically' efficacious grace, the freedom necessary for meriting, but rather brings it into play. 3. It admits that God wills the salvation of all men and gives to all adults truly sufficient graces; but if a man resists them, he deserves to be deprived of the efficacious graces which he would otherw ise receive. Hence God does not ask the impossible and wills the salvation of all men. but He does not will the salvation of all equally', contrary to what the Semi-Pelagians maintain. And herein lies a great mystery, namely, that God often but not always gives to sinners the efficacious grace of conversion: indeed, He always bestows it upon the predestinate to whom He has determined to grant the gift of final perseverance; often He even confers the grace of conversion upon others, but later denies them, for reasons of justice, on account of repeated sins, the grace of perseverance, which, absolutely speaking, He could grant them for reasons of mercy. Whence it becomes evident that in this treatise the following two principles are reconciled. 1. God does not ask the impossible, and sincerely wills the salvation of all contrary to predestinationism, Protestantism, Baianism, and Jansenism. 2. "Without Me ye can do nothing" in the order of salvation. "What hast thou that thou hast not received?" (I Cor. 4:7); or, as St. Thomas says (la, q. 20, a. 3), "Since the love of God is the cause of the goodness of things, nothing is in any respect better if God does not will greater good to one than to another. " These two principles are most certain, but their intimate reconciliation remains hidden, for it is the intimate reconciliation of infinite mercy, infinite justice, and supreme liberty in the sublime depth of the Deity. I have presented this matter in the volume entitled, La predestination des saints et la grace, pp. 49-51, 132 ff. The relative position of the various doctrines can thus be indicated. [diagram page 19] [8] [9] 8 The more rigid Thomists and Augustinians seem to minimize the will for universal salvation by saying that negative reprobation, which precedes the prevision of demerits, consists not only in permitting sins that will not be absolved, but in positive exclusion from glory as a benefit which is not due. This is justifiably rejected by Billuart and many Thomists. 9 The eclecticism of the Sorbonne maintains that grace is efficacious of itself for difficult acts conducive to salvation (such as contrition), but that grace is not efficacious of itself for easy acts conducive to salvation (such as attrition). Filially, it must be observed that two contradictory propositions cannot be true at the same time or false at the same time; one is true, the other false. On the other hand, Pelagianism and predestinationism are doctrines simultaneously false; they are not contradictory in this, but in other respects. For instance, Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism erroneously maintain that "God wills equally the salvation of all men, namely, the elect and the reprobate. " The contradictory proposition: "God does not will equally the salvation of all men, " is true. This indeed is what the predestinationists, Calvinists, and Jansenists declare and in so doing they do not err. but they do err by denying the will of universal salvation, which is affirmed by Augustine when he says: "God does not demand the impossible. " Likewise these contradictory propositions: "Grace is intrinsically efficacious. " and "Grace is not intrinsically efficacious, " cannot be true at the same time or false at the same time; one is true, the other is false. The first is maintained by Thomism, the second by Molinism and likewise by the congruism of Suarez. Which, then, is true remains to be discovered. THE VARIOUS STATES OF HUMAN NATURE St. Thomas speaks particularly of two states of nature which are properly states of this nature considered formally as a nature, namely, the state of original nature in the innocent Adam and the state of corrupt nature after the sin of our first parents, before baptismal regeneration. Cf. la, q. 94, a. 2; la Ilae, q. 109, a. 2. : "The nature of man may be considered in two ways, either in its integrity, as it existed in our first parents before sin, or as it exists in us, corrupted by the sin of our first parents, " and q. 114. a. 2, where he speaks of "corrupt nature, as it exists in us before its reparation by grace. " These last words show that St. Thomas further admits the state of repaired nature which is called the state of grace and subsequently the state of glory or of grace consummated. As we shall see, he certainly speaks of the possibility of another state merely natural or of pure nature, and in the state of innocence he distinguishes the integrity of nature itself from the grace which elevated it. Cf. Illa. q. 53. a. 2. Theologians now, more or less generally, distinguish five states of nature. State, as a general term, is the condition proper to man with a certain stability and permanence. (Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 184, a. 1. ) That which human nature possesses of itself as ordained to its final end is here taken as a stable condition and mode. Five such states are differentiated: 1. the state of pure nature. 2. the state of incorrupt nature. 3. the state of original justice, 4. the state of fallen nature, 5. the state of restored nature. We might add the state of glory and the state of damnation, but we arc not concerned with these, since we are now directing our attention to nature only so far as, with divine help, it tends toward its final end. The state of pure nature or the merely natural state. St. Thomas speaks of it. II Sent., d. 31. q. I. a. 2 ad 3. "In the beginning when God created man. He could also have formed another man from the slime of the earth and have left him in the condition of his nature, that is. mortal and passible, and experiencing the struggle between concupiscence and reason; nothing of human nature would have been removed thereby, for this condition follows from the principles of nature. Nor would this defect in it be a reason for blame or punishment, since the defect would not be caused by its own will. " Again, St. Thomas alludes to this state of pure nature as being possible: "Humankind in general suffers diverse pains, corporal and spiritual... (death, hunger, thirst... weakness of intellect... from which there results an inability to overcome animal appetites entirely). Nevertheless, one may say of such defects, corporal as well as spiritual, that they are not punitive, but rather natural defects consequent upon the requirements of matter. For instance, the human body, since it is composed of unlike substances, must of necessity be corruptible.... and the intellect... on account of the ease with which it may deviate from the truth through phantasms" (Contra Gentes, Bk. IV, chap. 52). St. Thomas adds, however, that, considering the sweet providence of God. it was fitting that man at his creation should be delivered from these defects by supernatural gifts. How is the state of pure nature to be defined? The state of pure nature means precisely nature with its intrinsic constituent principles and such as follow from them or are due to them; in other words, it implies all those notes which are included in the definition of man, a rational animal, and further the properties of man and the natural aids due to human nature that it may attain its final natural end. Aristotle thought that men are actually in this merely natural state. Hence in this state man would have a body and a rational soul, lower and higher faculties of the soul, would know the natural law, and would accept the helps of a natural order for arriving at his final natural end, which consists in the abstract knowledge of God and in the natural love of God above all things. However, since what is naturally deficient sometimes fails, in this state also God would permit sin against the natural law in one individual more than in another who received more assistance, and therefore, in this state, there would be given sufficient helps of the natural order to all, but efficacious helps to certain ones. These efficacious natural helps would be due, not to this individual in particular, in whom God could permit sin, but due to human nature as a whole; for God would be creating human nature incompetent for its final end if no individual of the species attained its end. This state of pure nature may thus be considered in accordance with the four causes: 1. formal cause: the rational soul with its faculties; 2. material cause: the body; 3. efficient cause: God, the author of nature, from whom proceed the natural law and the helps of the natural order, whether sufficient or efficacious; 4. final cause: God, the author of nature, known abstractly and loved above all things. This is the order that philosophy speaks of when it abstracts from both original sin and grace. First corollary'. Neither habitual grace nor the infused virtues and gifts nor actual grace of the supernatural order belong to this state of pure nature. Second corollary. Moreover, man, like any other animal, would be subject to pain, death, and so also to ignorance and concupiscence. Thus four unhappy natural consequences would follow. He would be subject to pain and death; for, as his body is composed of elements capable of suffering from exterior causes and often at war with one another, old age and death normally come upon man as upon other animals. Likewise man would be subject to ignorance because our intellectual knowledge, having its source in the senses, is very apt to deviate from the truth on account of its disordered phantasms, for example, by interpreting in an excessively material sense things which are spiritual and which are known only as through a glass in the natural manner of the senses. (Cf. ibid. ) Similarly he would be subject to concupiscence, for the sensitive appetite naturally obeys right reason only as a subject, not as a slave; indeed, it can be carried toward its own proper object, that is, toward a delectable good or toward a sensible good difficult of attainment, according to the suggestion of the senses and imagination without any rational direction. (Cf. la Ilae, q. 17, a. 7. ) Hence the subject may be divided thus: [diagram page 23]___________________________________________________________________________ 1. God, author of nature, directing and aiding 1.1. soul, faculties, natural final end; 1.2. body 2. Four unhappy natural consequences 2.1. ignorance, concupiscence 2.1.1. did not exist in Christ or B. V.M. 2.2. pain, death 2.2.1. present in Christ and in B.V.M. as a consequence of nature, not as a consequence of original sin, and Christ willed to endure them as means of redemption All theologians agree that this state of pure nature never existed. Bains and the Jansenists denied its possibility; we shall see later the refutation of this error. The state of incorrupt nature consists in the perfect subjection of the body to the soul and of the sense appetites to the reason; therefore it implies exemption from the four unfortunate natural consequences, that is, from ignorance, concupiscence, pain, and death. If only the sense appetites are subject to reason without the subjection of the body to the soul, the perfection of nature is only partial, not total, since the defects of old age and death will appear. In this integrity of nature Adam was created, according to revelation, which declares that "through sin death entered the world" (Rom. 5:12); and before sin, Adam and Eve, although naked, experienced no shame; but only after sin, as we read in Gen. 2:25, since before sin no inordinate passion of which they might be ashamed, could arise. This gift of integrity, according to St. Thomas (la, q. 97, a. I C. and 3 ad 2; la Ilae, q. 91, a. I), resided in a certain force of a natural order, just as we find even now that certain people possess greater health and sturdiness. In the beginning God made man perfect, for the works of God Himself are perfect, and as every agent produces something like himself, a most perfect agent produces a perfect work; for example, when God wills to establish a new religious order, He sends to the Church a holy founder, in whom all the perfections of this new order are at least virtually present. Hence, with all the more reason, when He created the first man He created him perfect, with full natural perfection; in other words, He created him in the adult state, with those virtues capable of being acquired although sometimes accidentally infused. Thus is explained this force in which the gift of natural integrity consisted. This gift of integrity in Adam sprang de facto from sanctifying grace, by which the higher reason was subjected to God. From this primary harmony there followed, as St. Augustine and St. Thomas maintain, two others, namely, between right reason and the sensitive appetite and between body and soul. Moreover, natural integrity belonged to the natural order (like the acquired virtues) and thus was differentiated from grace which elevated to the supernatural order. The gift of integrity did not constitute man an adopted son of God, a participant in the divine nature, an heir to the kingdom of heaven; all of these were bestowed by sanctifying grace. Hence nothing prevented God from being able to create man in the state of incorrupt nature without original grace; for, although these two states were combined in Adam, the Fathers and theologians often speak of them as if they were one. The state of original justice or of innocence is described by St. Thomas (la. q. 95, a. I). It consists: 1. in the perfect subjection of the reason to Godby grace and charity; 2 in the perfect subjection of the sense appetites to reason; 3. in the perfect subjection of the body to the soul. As long as the soul adhered to Godby grace, the rest were perfectly subject to it; however, it was capable of failing in this perfect subjection to God through sin, for the will was not yet confirmed in goodness. Some say. Father Kors among them, that, according to St. Thomas, sanctifying grace in Adam was not an endowment of nature but only a personal gift, as it is in us; and accordingly grace would be the external root of original justice, which would be nothing else but integrity of nature. [1011 ] Generally, in fact, Thomists hold that, according to St. Thomas, sanctifying grace was in Adam an endowment of nature: first, because it was to be transmitted with nature by way of generation; for if Adam had not sinned, his children would have been born with grace, receiving at the same time the spiritual soul and grace, at the time the body is ultimately disposed to receive the soul (la, q. 100, a. I ad 2). Thus sanctifying grace is the intrinsic root of original justice, as the root is an intrinsic part of a tree. [n] Secondly, because original sin is. as declared by the councils (Denz., no. 175, Council of Orange), the death of the soul. But the death of the soul is the privation not only of the integrity of nature, but of sanctifying grace or spiritual life. Thirdly, thus is explained the remission of original sin by baptism, although this sacrament does not restore the integrity of nature. Accordingly, to this state of original justice the following pertain: 1. sanctifying grace, the infused virtues whether theological or moral, the gifts of the Holy Ghost, actual graces; 2. exemption from the four lamentable consequences to nature, namely, ignorance, concupiscence, pain, and death. The first two consequences are also called wounds; two other wounds are malice and weakness. These are the six punishments of this life (la Ilae, q. 85, a. 3). Corollary. If original justice is understood adequately, it includes several habits, such as habitual grace, infused virtues, and preternatural privileges, namely, exemption from ignorance, concupiscence, pain, and death. In fact the root of all these perfections was habitual grace, or the union of the soul with God, the author of grace. Problem. Whether the sanctifying grace of the state of innocence was of the same kind as the sanctifying grace which is granted to us now unto justification. We answer in the affirmative that it was the same kind as to substance, since its formal effect was the same, to make man pleasing to God. an adopted son. a friend, and an heir to the kingdom of heaven. However, in regard to the manner of its being communicated to the subject, there is a twofold difference between the two. 1. On the part of the principle: the grace of the state of innocence as an endowment of nature proceeded from God as Creator establishing nature in its natural as well as in its supernatural being. On the contrary, habitual grace now proceeds from God as Redeemer, not as establishing nature but as restoring persons to health. 2. On the part of the subject, the grace of the original state regarded nature directly as an endowment of nature, and persons by reason of their nature, in other words it was communicated at the same time with nature, and fully, entirely communicated itself to nature in respect to all its operations (la, q. 100, a. I; la Ilae, q. 81, a. I and 2). On the contrary, habitual grace now regards, primarily and directly, the person to be restored by means of humility and penance; it does not look primarily and directly to nature, and accordingly it is no longer communicated with nature. Thus the son of Christian, even saintly, parents is now born in original sin, and the punishments of this life remain after baptism, as opportunities for struggle and merit (Illa, q. 69, a. 3 and 49, a. 5 ad I). The state of fallen nature is described at length in the treatise on original sin. It is the state of nature despoiled of sanctifying grace, of the virtues attached to it, and of the gift of integrity, in other words, subject to pain and death as 10 We examined this opinion in our treatise De Deo trino et creatore, 1944, pp. 430-38. 11 At the Council of Trent itwas declared (Denz.. no. 789) that Adam "lost for himself andforus the sanctity and justice received from God"; therefore he received it for himself and for us as an endowment granted to nature, not merely as a personal gift well as the four wounds of ignorance in the intellect, malice in the will concupiscence in the concupiscible appetite, and weakness in the irascible (cf. la Ilae, q. 85, a. 3. 5. 6. on the four wounds and also pain and death). Thomists generally hold that man in the state of fallen nature not yet restored has less strength for moral good than he would have had in the state of pure nature. The principal reason is that in the state of fallen nature, man is born with his will directly opposed to his final supernatural end and indirectly opposed to his final natural end, because even' sin against his supernatural end is indirectly against the natural law. according to which we ought always to obey God. whatever He commands us. On the contrary, in the state of pure nature, man would be bom with his will directed neither toward nor away from his final natural end, but with a capacity for directing himself either toward or away from this end. The state of restored nature. It belongs properly to the treatise on grace to deal with this state, and the whole of question 109 is a discussion of it, as well as of the state of fallen nature considered as its contrary. At the outset, however, certain general observations should be made to avoid repetition. This expression, "the state of restored nature, " is not actually found in St. Thomas, who rather speaks of the state of grace after justification or of the healing grace, but not expressly of the state of restored nature. Perhaps the reason is that after sin, habitual grace regards primarily and directly the person to be cured and nature by reason of the person. Moreover, nature is not fully or perfectly restored; there remain the four wounds, which are only in process of being healed in thebaptized; besides, pain and death remain. Therefore the state of restored nature will not be perfect except in heaven. Cf. Illa, q. 49, a. 5 ad I, and 69, a. 3. However, this expression may be accepted in treating of these different states of nature, as grace is the seed of glory and as grace is now considered as healing the person and, by reason of the person, the nature. [12] This state is expressed by various names in Holy Scripture; it is termed redemption, liberation, (spiritual) resuscitation, regeneration, vivification, reconciliation, renovation. Thus in I Tim. 2; Ephes. 2; II Cor. 5. This state resembles the state of innocence inasmuch as sanctifying grace is present in both, identical as to substance and similarly ordered to the supernatural beatitude of heaven. But there are several differences. 1. From the standpoint of their end: the remote end of the grace of the state of innocence was the manifestation of the divine liberality, whereas the end of the state of restored nature is the manifestation of mercy and now, certainly, the gift is greater, namely, the only-begotten Son of God: God so loved the world as to give His only-begotten Son. To be sure. God does not permit evil to be done except that He may bring good even out of evil, as St. Augustine says (Enchir., chap. II), that is, except on account of a greater good. The Church sings: "O happy fault which merited to have such and so great a reparation! " And St. Paul also said (Rom. 5:20): "Where sin abounded, grace did more abound. " Hence, according to several Thomists (for example, the Salmanticenses): God permitted the sin of Adam and original sin for the sake of the redemptive Incarnation, as for a greater good; cf. Illa, q. I, a. 3 ad 3. Likewise He permitted the threefold denial of Peter for the sake of the greater humility of the Apostle. Thus in the life of the predestinate the divine permission of sin is indirectly the working out of predestination, namely, that the elect may attain to greater humility. Hence Billuart (De gratia) rightly says that in the state of restored nature the charity of God toward us is greater, for it is a greater charity to do good to enemies and especially the gift itself is greater, namely, the only-begotten Son of God. The new Adam is infinitely above the first Adam, and the Blessed Virgin Mary far surpasses Eve in excellence; the worship of the Eucharist is higher than the worship in the Garden of Eden. Moreover, the proximate end of the grace of the state of innocence was the imprinting of the image of God the 1_ In this sense. St. Thomas says (Illa. q. 49, a. 5): "Christ by His passion opened to us the gate of Heaven"; the souls of the just under the Old Testament could not have the beatific vision before the Passion, because, although they had a certain grace "in respect to the purifying of their own persons, " there still remained "an impediment which was an arraignment of all humanity’, and which indeed is removed at the price of the blood of Christ. " Creator upon man; now it is, above and beyond this, the imprinting of the image of the redeeming Christ as well, according to the words in Rom. 8:29: "whom... He predestinated to be made conformable to the image of His Son"; and all things in the present state of restored nature are referred to the glory of Christ. 2. The second difference lies in the efficient cause, according as the order of action should correspond to the order of ends. God is the efficient cause of the state of innocence immediately, but of the state of restored nature through Christ, since Christ merited this restoration for us and is its efficient instrumental cause, as an instrument indissolubly united to the divinity. 3. The third difference is on the part of the subject. The subject in the state of innocence was nature possessing no right to the gratuitous gifts of this state, but with nothing, on the other hand, that would resist them. The subject of the state of restored nature is nature which must be cured of sin or, preferably, already cured and adorned with virtue. Problem. Whether in the state of restored nature man has less powers for doing good conducive to salvation than he had in the state of innocence. It is not easy to reply because innocent nature, healthy and vigorous, was in itself more capable of doing good and persevering in it than nature restored but still weak and harassed by many temptations; therefore the sin of Adam was all the more grave inasmuch as it could more easily have been avoided. But on the other hand, "Where sin abounded, grace did more abound, " "and with Him plentiful redemption. " Besides, the Redeemer, head of the Church, substantial!}' present in the Eucharist, is infinitely higher than Adam, head of elevated nature in the state of innocence. Eucharistic Communion which offers sustaining grace is infinitely above the tree of life, the proper effect of which was to preserve the vegetative faculty against the infirmity of old age. Hence, unless I am mistaken, the question must be solved by making a distinction, thus: in the state of restored nature, still weak and vexed by many temptations, man has less strength on the part of nature than in the state of innocence. [13] But on the part of C hrist the Redeemer, present in the Eucharist, good Christians who generously strive after intimacy with Christ and attain it seem, in spite of temptations, to receive greater graces, at least in the unitive life, than they would have had in the state of innocence, on account of their greater union with God through Christ the Redeemer. Nature, indeed, even in the unitive way is not yet fully restored; there remain pain, old age, death, a certain disorder in the feelings. But the life of the saints, after achieving the victory, is higher, most assuredly in the Blessed Virgin Mary and very probably, if not certainly, in St. Joseph, the apostles, and the great saints. As a matter of fact, in every fervent Eucharistic Communion it seems that the union with God through Christ is greater than it was in the earthly paradise. And in the Sacrifice of the Mass the consecration is infinitely above the worship rendered in the state of innocence. Objection. St. Thomas says (la. q. 95, a. 4): "The works of man would be more efficacious for meriting in the state of innocence than after sin. if the amount of merit is estimated from the standpoint of grace; for this latter would then have been more plentiful finding no obstacle in human nature. Likewise, also, if the absolute quantity of his work be considered, for if man were possessed of greater powers, he would do greater works. But if the amount is considered proportionately, the reckoning of merit after sin is found to be greater, on account of the weakness of man, for a work of less magnitude done under difficulty greatly exceeds a work of greater magnitude performed without any difficulty. " Reply. In this text St. Thomas seems to compare the merits of man in general in these two states. He is not really comparing the merits of Adam with the merits of any great saint of the New Testament; for, most certainly, the merits of the Blessed Virgin Mary are much higher than the merits of Adam. Moreover, when he says, "grace would be more plentiful finding no obstacle in human nature, " he is speaking of grace in relation to incorrupt nature in 13 Thus Billuart dec lares : "In the state of innoc enc e grac e, c onferred as an endow ment of nature, enc ountered nothing contrary to itself in integral nature, and accordingly communicated itself fully to nature, with regard to all its effects, primary as well as secondary'. " Now, grace regards directly (perse) and primarily the justified person, who previously was unworthy and finds in nature four wounds which are only in process of being healed: ignorance, malice, weakness, concupiscence, and, in addition, pain and death. Hence grace does not now communicate itself fully to nature. But the justified person ought to fight manfully and continually to implore the help of Christ. general, not in relation to such and such a person. Hence this article (la, q. 95, a. 4) is indeed true of men as a whole, and on the part of nature, but he does not compare Adam with the saints of the New Testament who, after the victory over all temptations, seem, by the power of Christ the Mediator, through the Sacrifice of the Mass and Communion, to attain a greater union with God. Cf. on this subject St. Thomas' Commentary on the words of St. Paul: "And where sin abounded, grace did more abound" (Rom. 5 20); "grace, which hath superabounded in us in all wisdom" (Ephes. 1:8); "Now the grace of our Lord hath abounded exceedingly with faith" (I Tim. 1:14); "I exceedingly abound with joy in all our tribulation" (II Cor. 7 4). These words could never be said of Adam. Commenting on the Epistle to the Romans (5:20), St. Thomas says: "Sin abounded, that is. in the human race, and especially' in the Jews (more enlightened and more ungrateful), but grace superabounded, that is, in Christ remitting sin. Hence it is said (II Cor. 9:8): 'God is able to make all grace abound in you. '" But two reasons may be assigned to what is said here. "One from the operation of grace,... for it required abundant grace to cure an abundance of sins; 'many sins are forgiven her. because she hath loved much' (Luke 7 47). " The other reason is derived from the disposition of the sinner, for whenever through divine assistance he is rendered more humble by the consideration of his sins, he attains to greater grace, according to these words of Ps. 15:4: "Their infirmities were multiplied: afterward they made haste. " Thus St. Peter after his conversion; thus, among mankind, the saints after the redemption of the human race by Christ. Besides, with God there is plentiful redemption, as has already been said regarding the Psalm De profundis and, in truth, redemption through Christ was superabundant. Cf. also Illa, q. I, a 3 ad 3 : "Nothing prevents human nature from being advanced to something greater after sin, for God permits evil to be done that He may draw something better therefrom. Hence it is said in Romans (5:20): 'Where sin abounded, grace did more abound, ' and in the blessing of the paschal candle we find the words: 'O happy fault, which deserved to have such and so great a Redeemer !'" In the article on whether God would have become incarnate had man not sinned, St. Thomas uses the above words ("O happy fault, " etc. ) to refute the following objection: "Human nature did not, through sin, become more receptive of grace; therefore even if man had not sinned God would have become incarnate. " Because of this reply of St. Thomas, I cannot doubt the proposition held by many Thomists. though not by all of them, namely, that according to St. Thomas and according to the true state of tilings, God permitted original sin that He might draw something better therefrom, the redemptive Incarnation. Thus there is mutual causality: merits dispose for the reception of glory, in the way of a disposing cause, but glory is the cause of merits, as a final cause (la, q. 23, a. 5). Another difficult problem in regard to the various states is this: What is the order of these states according to the decrees of divine providence ? There is not complete agreement even among Thomists on this problem (cf. Billuart, De incarnatione, d. II, a. 3), just as some (the Salmanticenses, Godoy, Gonet) admit that original sin was permitted by God for the sake of a greater good, that is, the redemptive Incarnation, whereas others do not (Billuart, John of St. Thomas). [14] For the solution of this question particular stress must be laid on the text of St. Thomas already quoted (Illa, q. I, a 3 ad 3): "Nothing prevents human nature from being advanced to something greater after sin, for God permits evil to be done that He may draw something better therefrom. Hence it is said in Romans (5:20): 'Where sin abounded, grace did more abound, ' andin the blessing of the paschal candle we find the words: 'O happy fault, which deserved to have such and so great a Redeemer. ' " Likewise Illa, q. 46, a. I ad 3. We consider the solution advanced by the Salmanticenses (Cursus theol., "De motivo incarnationis") as well as by 14 John of St. Thomas. Cajetan, and Billuart refuse to reply to this question: Why did God permit the sin of Adam, for what greater good ? And they thus multiply the divine decrees, asserting that: 1. God willed the order of nature with the intention of manifesting His goodness; 2. He ordered intellectual creatures to a supernatural end: 3. foreseeing the sin of Adam and original sin, He decreed the restoration of the human race by Christ the Redeemer; 4. in Christ He chose some more especially and efficaciously and left others. Thus these various decrees would be virtually distinct, and this question would remain unsolved: For what greater good did God permit the sin of Adam and original sin, so as to make this permission holy? The reply would be exceedingly general: God permitted this in order to manifest His mercy and His justice. But it must be admitted that this supreme manifestation of mercy and justice was made through the redemptive Incarnation. Goday and Gonet, to be true. They maintain the following views. 1. God, through the knowledge of simple intelligence, knows all tilings possible, among which is this possible world in which the order of nature, the order of grace with the permission of original sin. and the order of hypostatic union, or the redemptive Incarnation, are subordinate the one to the other. 2. God intends to manifest His goodness outside Himself. 3. God judges the aforesaid possible world to be a very suitable medium for manifesting the divine goodness. 4. God chooses this disposition of things (this is the determination of His will). 5. God commands the execution of these means to be set in action in time (this is, formally, providence). 6. For the operation of the aforesaid disposition of things God moves the universe by directing it. Thus by a single decree God simultaneously willed this possible world with all its parts: in the same way. a builder does not first design the foundation of the house and afterward the roof, but first he designs a suitable dwelling place and, with this in view, the whole house and all its parts in harmony. This interpretation seems profound because of its superior simplicity according as it answers the question: Why did God permit the sin of Adam ? Hence it is more and more accepted by modern Thomists. THE POSSIBILITY OF THE STATE OF PURE NATURE To complete these preliminary' observations in regard to the five states of nature, something must be said against Baius and the Jansenists and also against certain Modernists about the state of pure nature. Certainly this state never existed; and Augustine, writing against Pelagius, shows that Adam in the state of innocence received more than natural gifts. But Jansen maintained that the state of pure nature is impossible. This thesis is well explained by Billuart, who should be read; here it suffices to present his principal arguments. Augustine says {Retract., Bk. I, chap. 9. ): "Ignorance and difficulty belong to the wretchedness of just damnation... although, even if they were the natural beginnings of man, God is not to be blamed on this account, but rather praised. " Likewise {De dono perseverantiae, chap. II): "Even if it-were true that ignorance and difficulty, without which no man is born, were not the original penalties of nature, still the Manichaeans would be refuted. " That is, not on this account is the Author of nature to be blamed. St. Thomas is in agreement with this {Il Sent., d. 31, q. I, a. 2 ad 3; text cited above on the definition of pure nature. Cf. p. 21). Proof from reason. The state of pure nature is not contradictory either from the part of man or from the part of God; hence it is simply possible. On the part of man, neither sanctifying grace nor the gifts of integrity and immortality are due to human nature regarded in itself, but are merely gratuitous. Hence the state of pure nature without these gifts is not contradictory' from the side or part of man. The antecedent is evident from the very notion of grace; if it is due, it is no longer a grace; nor is the adoption of sonship due to us. for adoption is made by the free will of the one adopting; and neither to our nature nor to the angelic nature is due the elevation to a participation in the divine nature, as the Church declared against Baius (Denz., nos. 1021, 1026. 1055, 1078, 1079) and against Quesnel (Denz., nos. 1384 ff. ). Thus Augustine {De civitate Dei, Bk. XII. chap, g) says of the angels: "God created them, at the same time creating nature in them and bestowing grace upon them. " Nor is the gift of integrity' and immortality due to our nature; for ignorance, concupiscence, passibility, and mortality proceed from the elements of human nature, as St. Thomas teaches {Contra Gentes. Bk. IV, chap. 52). Thus man. created in a purely natural condition, would possess all those tilings that coincide with his nature, in both his physical and his moral being; in other words, he would have a body and rational soul with their properties and powers, spiritual as well as sensitive, that is, with free will and the potentiality of achieving his natural end. The proximate end of man in the state of pure nature would be an honorable good, and his final end God as the author of nature, known abstractly and loved above all things with a natural love. In this state all the sufficient aids of a natural order would be given to all, and to some certain efficacious helps which are indeed not due to any particular individual but are necessary to human nature so that, in some individuals it may attain the end for which it was created by God. Likewise this state of pure nature is not contradictory on God's part; for God could have denied gratuitous gifts to man without detriment to His justice, goodness, or wisdom, just as, without any injustice. He did not prevent the sin of Adam, which He most easily could have prevented. Hence even by His ordinary' power God could have created man in the state of pure nature. Against the possibility of the state of pure nature there is a particular objection which deserves to be considered: man cannot have even perfect natural happiness without a body, that is, without resurrection after death. But resurrection is a miracle and therefore would not be possible in the state of pure nature. Therefore this state is impossible. As a solution of this objection theologians propose three opinions. 1. In this state of pure nature there would not be the resurrection of bodies; and yet at the end of their way the just would be essentially happy, just as now, in the supernatural order, the souls of the saints are essentially happy before the resurrection of the body, which imparts only an accidental happiness. This first opinion is probable. 2. In this state of pure nature there would be a resurrection; and this is not unlikely, for the resurrection of the body is supernatural only as to mode (or modally), not as to substance (or substantially) as grace is. Therefore this state of pure nature in its term, for the just would have a certain perfection of integral nature. Moreover. God could perform a miracle in the state of pure nature to confirm the natural truths of religion. This second opinion is also probable. 3. In this state the just man would not die to be beatified; God would transfer him. body and soul to the place of beatitude. This third opinion seems least probable; perhaps the second opinion is the more probable. In order to defend the possibility of a state of pure nature, it is not necessary to prove conclusively by what means man would attain to beatitude, just as, to demonstrate the immortality of the soul it is not necessary to determine categorically the particular way by which the separated soul derives its knowledge. This will suffice, then, in regard to the possibility of the state of pure nature. The other objections of the Jansenists are of less consequence and may easily be found in the writings of Thomists. THE VARIOUS DEGREES OF DIVINE MOTION This is the last preliminary note to the understanding of our treatise. It is to be interpreted in the light of what has been said above (la, q. 105, a. 5 and 6; la Ilae, q. 9, a. 6; q. 10, a. 4; q. 79, a. I and 2). As explained by Father del Prado, O.P. (De gratia. II, 240, 253-57), according to the terminology of St. Thomas there are three degrees of divine motion in the natural order and three corresponding degrees in the supernatural; for in both the natural and the supernatural order divine motion is either before our deliberation or after it or above it. Before our deliberation, as long as we naturally desire to be happy, we are moved to desire happiness in general. For. since this desire is the first act of our will, we are not moved to it by virtue of a previous act of deliberation. There is something similar in the supernatural order when we arc moved to our final supernatural end, for we cannot be moved to it by virtue of a previous higher act by way of deliberation. After deliberation, or at its end, we are moved toward some good (on which we have deliberated) by virtue of a previous act; for by intending the end we are moved to choose the means to the end under divine cooperating concursus; this, indeed, whether in the natural order or in the supernatural by the exercise of the infused virtues. Above deliberation we are moved toward some object which surpasses our powers. Thus, in the natural order, under special inspiration of God, the author of nature, great geniuses in the philosophic, poetic, or strategic sphere, as well 15 Cf. Billuart, De gratia, diss. Ill, a. 1. as great heroes are moved. There is something similar and even more frequent in the supernatural order, when a just manis moved by special inspiration of the gifts of the Holy Ghost; this is properly above discursive deliberation and the human mode of operation. Si. Thomas often refers to the matter. [16] Whence the following synopsis may be drawn, reading from below in an ascending order. [diagrams page 36-37]_________________________________________________________________________ Divine motion by which the mind is moved in respect to its exercise 1. in the supernatural order 1.1. to acts of the gifts of the Holy Ghost (6) 1.1.1. Here the will does not move itself but freely consents to the motion, as a faithful pupil or obedient inferior (operating, but not really justifying grace, for the man is already justified 1.2. to determining to use the infused virtues (5) (co-operating grace, in a human manner). 1.2.1. Here it moves itself by virtue, of a previous act 1.3. to direct itself toward its final supernatural end (4) (operating and justifying grace). 1.3.1. Here it does not move itself by virtue of a previous act, but freely consents 2. in the natural order 2.1. to the good and also to the best without deliberation (3); this is an inspiration of particularly good fortune; thus, in the order of philosophy, poetry, strategy, or even of morals, great geniuses heroes. Here the will does not move itself, but freely consents to the motion of God (as obeying). 2.2. to determine itself to (2) 2.2.1. a real or apparent good 2.2.1.1. Here the will is moved, and moves itself freely by virtue of a previous act; it may be a sin 2.2.2. to the good in general (1); I will to be happy (an entirely general aid): the will is moved but does not move itself by virtue of a previous act; however, it elicits the act vitally, but not indeed freely as to specification; in this act there can be no sin These six degrees are reducible to the three which St. Thomas speaks of (la Ilae, q. 9, a. 6 ad 3; a. 109, 1, 2, 6, 9). the will is moved 1. before deliberation, property speaking, by counsel (no. 1 and also no. 4, since one does not deliberate, property speaking, about the ultimate end); 2. after deliberation, property speaking, by counsel (nos. 2 and 5); 3. above deliberation property speaking (nos. 3 and 6). [17] (N. B. Father del Prado distinguishes only five degrees, since he does not mention our third degree separately, but reduces it to the sixth. ) The first mode is explained in la Ilae. q. 9, a. 6 ad 3, q. 10, a. 1, 2, 4. The second mode is explained in la Ilae, q. 9, a. 6 ad 3; la. 63, a. I ad 4 and 5; la Ilae. n. a. I and 2, and whether the will may move itself, la Ilae, q. 9, a. 3. The third mode is explained in la Ilae. q. 68, a. I, where the Ethics, attributed to Aristotle, is cited. Bk. VII. chap. 14: "On good fortune. " 16 If these various degrees of divine motion are carefully studied according to St. Thomas, it will be easy to reply to several difficulties recently proposed by Father H. Bouillard, S. J., Conversion et grace chez S. Thomas d’Aquin, 1944. 17 These six modes of divine motion are explained at greater length in our Christian Perfection and Contemplation. pp. 286-99. Cf. below, p. 89 ff. The fourth mode is explained in la Ilae, q. Ill, a. 2 C and ad 2, operating grace before an interior act, especially when the will, which previously willed evil, begins to will the good. The will does not properly move itself, since the efficacious act is not given beforehand in respect to the final supernatural end, by virtue of which it could move itself toward that end. Further (Ila Ilae, q. 24, a. I ad 3) "Charity, whose object is the ultimate end, should rather be said to reside in the will than in free choice, " for choice properly applies to the means to the end (la Ilae, q. 13, a. 3). The fifth mode is explained in la Ilae, q. Ill, a. 2, cooperating grace (cf. Cajetan); and la, 63, a. I, 5, 6, concerning the second instant in the life of the angels when they were able to sin. The sixth mode is explained in la Ilae, q. 68, a. I ff. [diagram page 38]____________________________________________________________________________ To these may be added the miraculous mode • as in the instantaneous conversion of St. Paul; or as in prophetic illumination and the miraculous mode various graces gratis datae (cf. la Ilae, q. Ill, a. 4 and 5). GENERAL HELP AND SPECIAL HELP [diagram page 39]___________________________________________________________________________ Help 1. general 1.1. very general indicated in our synopsis as no 1 1.2. less general 1.2.1. in the natural order (no. 2), due to nature, not to any individual; 1.2.2. in the supernatural order (no. 5), due to nature raised to the supernatural not to this just man 2. special 2.1. properly speaking, includes special inspiration (nos. 3, 6) and justifying operating grace (no. 4); 2.2. less properly, even cooperating actual grace necessary for a special difficulty, for example, overcoming a grave temptation. St. Thomas and nearly all theologians employ this terminology. and commonly apply the term "general help" to that which is given for operations in accordance with the universal or common mode of acting. "Special help" is that which is given for operations above the aforesaid universal or common mode, and this in a variety of ways; for example, either because a particular difficulty' is to be overcome, or because this mode is properly extraordinary or miraculous. Hence there are many more or less special degrees. At the outset the principal degrees should be noted (cf. John of St. Thomas, De gratia, index under "gratia specialis"; also the Salmanticenses, Gonet, and Lemos). 1. The most general help is that by which the will is moved toward the universal good, as described above in the synopsis (no. I); without this help the will can will nothing, nor, in fact, can it sin. 2. General help often signifies the motion indicated in no. 2. as when the will is moved in the natural order toward some real good, for instance, honoring one's father. In fact this "general help" is sometimes called grace in a broad sense because, although it is due to human nature in general it is not due to this individual whom God may permit to sin by his not honoring his father; so in a certain sense this help is special in relation to this individual who does not sin (cf. also De veritate, q. 24, a. 14); [’8] see also the Salmanticenses on q. 109, a. 2. as well as Gonet, d. I, a. 3. nos. 18 la, q. 21. a. I ad 3: "It is due to every created tiring that it should have that which befits it, as fora manto have hands and to be serve the other animals, and thus again God exercises His justice when He gives to anything that which is due to it according to the purpose i nature and condition. " Rather does God owe it to Himself to give to creatures whatever is necessary so that at least many of such and 148. 170, Cajetan, Billuart, De gratia, diss. I. a. I, and Suarez. Indeed, "general help, " sometimes by many theologians of almost all schools, signifies the entirely common actual grace of the supernatural order, indicated in our synopsis as no. 5, provided that there is no special difficulty to be overcome. For example, it is said that, for overcoming slight temptations against supernatural precepts, general help of the supernatural order suffices, and that this help is due to elevated nature in general but not to this just one in particular. John of St. Thomas {De gratia, disp. 21. a. I. no. II) thus distinguishes between general and special help and also uses the terms "ordinary" and "extraordinary help, " but this extraordinary does not here signify miraculous. 3. The term "special help" is usually applied by theologians to that which is included under nos. 3, 4. and 6 of our synopsis, that is. to a special inspiration, particularly of the supernatural order, an operating grace either in the moment of justification or later in accordance with the exercise of the gifts. Sometimes "special help" signifies, although less properly, actual grace even cooperating necessarily in overcoming a great difficulty. Thus it is almost commonly said that to overcome grave temptations special help, or special grace, is required. (Billuart. diss. III. a. 6). Such help is not due to this just man. nor proximately due to elevated nature, but is particularly to be obtained by praying for-it. Corollary. In respect, not to nature, but to individual persons, all supernatural help is special according to John of St. Thomas (la Ilae. q. 109, disp. 21, a. I, no. II), for aid given to one person and not to another is special to the person to whom it is given; yet that aid can be called general in relation to common elevated nature, e.g.. in the overcoming of temptations. The following speak in like manner: Billuart, De gratia, beginning; the Sahnanticenses. De gratia, la Ilae. q. 109, disp. II, dub. II, nos. 27, 34, and disp. V, dub. VII. no. 171; Gonet. De gratia, disp. I. a. 3. 5. nos. 157. 170. 172; Lemos, Panoplia. t. IV. p. la, q. 85, no. 162. Lemos here maintains that general help is twofold; one is sufficient, bestowing the power to conquer a slight temptation, and this is given to all the other is efficacious, bestowing the conquest of this slight temptation, and this is not given to all; it is necessary to pray in order to receive it. This division corresponds to the division of the divine will into antecedent and consequent as explained in la. q. 19, a. 6, where it is stated that "whatever God wills absolutely, happens; although what He antecedently wills may not happen. He wills absolutely or simply when He wills a thing considering all its particular circumstances, here and now. as a just judge wills absolutely that a murderer be hanged, although in a certain sense he wills him to live inasmuch as he is a man. " Likewise in la, q. 20, a. 4, it is said that God always loves better men more, but they would not be better were they not loved more by God. (Cf. De veritate, q. 6. a. 2; la Ilae, q. 109. a. 9, at the end of the body of the article. ) CHAPTER II: QUESTION 109 THE NECESSITY OF GRACE IN this question there are ten articles, methodically arranged in progressive order, beginning with the lesser actions for which grace is necessary (for example, knowing some truth) and ending with the last supreme good work, that is, final perseverance. (Cf. titles. ) There are three parts, as Cajetan observes at the beginning of article 7: [diagram page 41]____________________________________________________________________________ necessity of grace 1. for fallen man 1.1. for doing good (a. 1-6) 1.2. for avoiding evil (a.7 and 8) 2. for the just (a. 9 and 10), 2.1. acting and persevering ARTICLE I. WHETHER WITHOUT GRACE MAN CAN KNOW ANY a nature may attain their end. [diagram page 39] TRUTH Statement of the question. It seems that grace is required for knowing any truth whatever, for it is said in II Cor. 3:5: "Not that we are sufficient to think anything of ourselves as of ourselves. " And St. Augustine maintained this answer in a certain prayer, but he himself retracted later {Retract., I, 4), as is said in the argument to the contrary' and declared that it could be refuted thus: "Many who are not sinless know many truths, " for example, those of geometry. The first conclusion is the following. To know any truth, man requires at least natural help from God. but he does not require a new supernatural illumination for it. The aforesaid natural help is due to human nature as a whole, but not to any individual. Proof of the first part. Since every created agent requires divine premotion in order to pass from potency to act, "however perfect the nature of any corporal or spiritual being, it cannot proceed to act unless moved by God. " [19] Proof of the second part. Because many truths do not surpass the power proper to our intellect, they are easily knowable naturally (cf. ad I, ad 2, ad 3). It should be noted that the natural concurrence called here by St. Thomas "motion" (motio) is not mere simultaneous cooperation. 2 Likewise, contrary' to Suarez, the virtual act of the will cannot, without divine motion, be reduced to a secondary act, for St. Thomas said: "However... " (cf. Suarez, Disp, met., disp. 29, sect. I, no. 7, on virtual act). We reply: there is more in the secondary act than in the virtual act, which in reality differs from the action, nor is it its own action. Already in this first article it is evident that St. Thomas withdraws nothing from divine motion. The second conclusion is the following. For attaining a knowledge of supernatural truths, our intellect stands in need not only of the natural concurrence of God, but of a special illumination, namely, the light of faith or the light of prophecy and of a proportionate motion. The reason is that these truths surpass the power proper to our intellect. OBJECTIONS Objection to the first conclusion. Vasquez presents several objections. In the first place, he says: The intellect, indifferent to truth and falsehood, is determined by grace toward any truth. But our intellect is indifferent to truth and falsehood. Therefore our intellect is determined by grace toward any truth. Reply. I distinguish the major: by grace, broadly speaking, granted; properly, denied. Let the minor pass, although the intellect is not so indifferent to truth and falsehood as not to incline naturally to truth. It is called grace broadly since, for example, it is given to Aristotle rather than to Epicurus. 1 insist. Grace properly speaking, is required in this case, at least after original sin, according to the fideists, such as Bautin, Bonetti. 2 In simultaneous concurrence, admitted by Molina, God and the secondary cause are like two men rowing a boat, that is, like two coordinated causes. On the contrary, for St. Thomas, God's premotion and the secondary cause thus moved are two causes of which the second is subordinated to the supreme first cause, with reference both to causality and to being. Grace, property speaking, is required that the wounded intellect may be healed. 19 Thus the Council of Orange (can. 22, Denz., no. 195): "No one has anything of Iris own but tying and sin. But if man has somethir truth and justice, it comes from that source after which we should thirst in this desert land. " At least natural concurrence is requiret But when it knows any truth, our intellect is at least partially healed. Therefore grace, property speaking, is required for knowing any truth. Reply. I distinguish the major: for knowing the whole body of natural truths, I concede; for any one truth, I deny. The intellect would thus be not merely darkened but extinct, were il incapable of knowing even the least truth without healing grace. Let the minor pass. I distinguish the conclusion in the same way as the major-I say transeat in regard to the minor but I do not concede since the intellect is not property healed when it knows a truth of geometry but rather when it knows the truth of natural religion. Instance: But the intellect is extinct or almost extinct, according to the Jansenists. Ignorance is opposed to knowledge as being a total deprivation. But the wound of ignorance is in the intellect, according to tradition. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the major: total ignorance, granted: partial ignorance, denied. I contradistinguish the minor; explanation: the wound of ignorance affects principally the practical intellect wherein prudence resides; but there remains in the practical intellect a synderesis. and the speculative intellect is less wounded, since it does not presuppose rectitude of the appetites. Objection to the second conclusion. Whatever does not surpass the object of our intellect can be known without grace. The mysteries of faith do not surpass the object of our intellect. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the major: a proportionate object, granted; an adequate object, surpassing a proportionate object, denied. I contradistinguish the minor. I insist. But the mysteries of faith do not surpass the proportionate object. That which is known habitually to the senses does not surpass the proportionate object. But the mysteries of faith are known habitually to the senses. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the major: whatever is so known without revelation, granted; after revelation, I distinguish further: they do not surpass the remotely proportionate object, granted; proximately proportionate, denied. I insist. But at least, after external revelation, the mysteries of the faith do not surpass the proximately proportionate object. That which is known by its species abstracted from the senses and through external signs does not surpass the proximately proportionate object. But the mysteries of faith are thus known. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the major: if this is known from a human motive, granted; and then it does not require supernatural grace; and contrariwise if it is known from a supernatural motive, that is, on the authority of God revealing in the order of grace (cf. below. Corollary 4). I insist But man is made in the image of the Trinity. And he is naturally capable of knowing this image. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the minor: so far as man is the image of God, the author of nature, granted; so far as he is the image of the Trinity, denied, since the term of this relationship is of a higher order. Thus if someone is given an image of an entirely unknown man. he cannot say whose image it is. (For a correct treatment, cf. Salmanticenses, De gratia, disp. III. dub. IV. no. 40. and Billuart, De gratia, diss. Ill, a. 2). Thomists have drawn several corollaries from this article, using more modern terminology. Corollary 1. Fallen man, without grace, with natural concurrence alone, is capable of knowing certain natural truths, namely, the first speculative and practical principles of reason and the conclusions which are easily drawn from them. This is contrary to some ancient writers who do not distinguish sufficiently between grace and natural concurrence; it is also contrary to Vasquez who. following the ways of the nominalists, disparaged the powers of reason excessively, as did Bains and the Jansenists. Quesnel and the nineteenth-century fideists, such as Bautin and Bonetty. [20] With regard to this conclusion, cf. the following condemned propositions. Denz., no. 1022. This one of Bains is condemned: "Those who consider, withPelagius, the text of the Apostle to the Romans (2:14): 'The Gentiles, who have not the (written) law, do by nature those things that are of the law, ' understand it to apply to the Gentiles who have not the grace of faith. " For it is certainly contrary to Bains that, without grace, man by natural reason can know the first precepts of the natural law: good ought to be done, thou shalt not kill. Denz., no. 1391. This proposition of Quesnel is condemned: "All knowledge of God, even natural even in pagan philosophy, can come only from God, and without grace it produces nothing but presumption, vanity, and opposition to God Himself, in place of sentiments of adoration, gratitude, and love. " Thus had spoken previously Luther and Calvin (I De Inst., chaps. I and 2), as if peripatetic philosophy had come from diabolic inspiration. The natural reason of Aristotle was capable of discovering the theory' of potency and act, of the four causes, and this without any opposition to God. Denz.. no. 1627. The following may probably' be attributed to Bautin: Although reason is obscure and weak through original sin, there still remains in it enough lucidity and power to lead us with certainty to (the knowledge of) the existence of God, to the revelation made to the Jews by Moses and to the Christians by our adorable God-man. " The Vatican Council defined the following (Denz., no. 1806): "If anyone says that the one true God. our Creator and Lord, cannot certainly be known by the light of natural human reason, let him be anathema. " This is contrary to the traditionalists. Kant, and the Positivists. Finally, in the oath against Modernism: "I acknowledge in the first place and of a truth, that, by the light of natural reason through the things which have been made, that is, through the visible works of creation, God. the beginning and end of all things, can be certainly known and even demonstrated. " Likewise in regard to miracles confirming the Gospel it is similarly declared that they are "most certain signs that the Christian religion is of divine origin... and even in the present time especially adapted to the intelligence of all men. " Moreover, the reason for this conclusion is the one given in the article, that is: Every power infused in created tilings is efficacious in respect to its own proper effect. But our intellect is a power infused into us by God and, granted that it is darkened by sin, yet it is not extinct. Therefore it can of itself, with natural concurrence, arrive at a knowledge of certain natural truths. 20 Bonetti misspelt? Otherwise intellectual power would be, in its own order, much more imperfect than are the powers of bodies, of plants and animals, in respect to their own objects, sight and hearing, for example. As a matter of fact, the natural concurrence required for the knowledge of any truth may be called grace in the broad sense, inasmuch as it is not due to any individual but to human nature in general; (cf. la. q. 21, a. I ad 3): "It is due to any created thing that it should have that which is ordained to it, as to a man that he have hands and that the other animals serve him; and thus again God works justice when He gives to anything that which is due to it by reason of its nature and condition. " God owes it to Himself to give to the various kinds of plants and animals and to humankind the natural concurrence enabling them to reach their final end on account of which they were made. But, on the other hand, it is not to be wondered at that what is deficient should sometimes fail, and God is not bound to prevent these defects, since, if He prevented them all, greater goods would not come about, and it is on account of these many goods that He permits the defect. Hence, as our intellect is defective, there is due to it, according to the laws of ordinary providence, that it should at least sometimes be moved toward the truth and not always fall into error. But the fact that Aristotle, for example, rather than another, let us say Epicurus, may be moved in the direction of truth, this is not due to him; it is by a special providence and benevolence, and in this sense such natural concurrence is called "grace" broadly speaking. And it is proper to pray that one may obtain this grace in the wide sense of the term. Corollary' 2. Fallen man. without a special added grace, cannot, at least with any moral power, know either collectively or even separately all natural truths, speculative or speculative-practical, or, for still greater reason, practical-practical; since for these last, as for prudence, rectitude of the appetite is required. Many hold, not without probability, that without special grace man can know all natural speculative truths, by physical power, since these truths do not exceed the capacity' of a man possessing a keen mind. But in the present corollary' it is a question of moral power, that is. such as may be rendered active without very great difficulty. And it is certain that this moral power is not given in regard to all the aforesaid kinds of truth taken together. Rather, it was on this account that the Vatican Council declared (Denz.. no. 1786) revelation to be morally necessary "so that those things concerning divine matters which are not of themselves impenetrable to human reason may nevertheless, in the present condition of the human race, be readily known by all with a firm certainty and no admixture of error. " This is explained by St. Thomas (Ia. q. I. a. I; Ila Ilae, q. 2. a. 3 and 4; Contra Gentes, Bk. I, chaps. 4 and 6; Bk. IV, Gentes, chap. 52). For the impediments are manifold: the shortness of life, the weakness of the body, domestic cares, the disorder of the passions, etc. It is clearly evident that, with all these impediments, fallen man without grace has not the moral power to attain to the knowledge of all natural truths together; nor even, as a matter of fact to the separate knowledge of them: 1. because the wound of ignorance is in the intellect, preventing especially that ease of understanding necessary to prudence, for prudence presupposes rectitude of the appetite; 2. because many speculative natural truths are very difficult, demanding long and rigorous study for a certain and complete knowledge of them and therefore a constantly good will, burning love of truth, a relish for contemplation, undisturbed passions, a good disposition of the senses, leisure uninterrupted by cares. All of this caimot be arrived at easily before regeneration by healing grace; indeed even afterward a special grace is required for it. Among natural truths, according to Billuart, there are some so extremely' difficult that no man has thus far been able to attain a certain knowledge of them, for example, the ebb and flow of the tides, the essence of light, electricity. magnetism, the inner development of the embry o; similarly', the inner nature of sensation, the active intellect and its functioning, the intimate relationship between the last practical judgment and choice, etc. ; likewise the reconciling of the attributes of God as naturally' knowable, although the knowledge of the existence of God, supreme Ruler, is easily arrived at by common sense from the order of the universe. Doubt. Whether this special grace required for a knowledge of all these natural truths is properly supernatural. Reply. It suffices that it is supernatural in respect to the manner of its production, by a special providence; these is no real need of a grace which is supernatural in respect to its substance, because the knowledge of which we are speaking is ontologically natural. Corollary 3. Supposing the existence of an external revelation, fallen man, with natural, general concurrence alone and without a special added grace, is able to know and enlarge on supernatural truths, from some human or natural reason. Thus the demons believe naturally, by a faith not infused but acquired, on the evidence of compelling miracles, as is demonstrated in Ila Ilae, q. 5. a. 2. And formal heretics retain certain supernatural truths, not from the supernatural motive of divine revelation (otherwise they would believe all that is revealed), but from a human motive, that is, on the bases of their own judgment and will; for example, because they consider this faith to be honorable or useful to themselves, or because it seems to them very foolish to deny certain tilings in the Gospel. The reason for this is that, although a true supernatural is in itself entitatively supernatural yet. as depending upon a human or natural motive, it is not formally supernatural. Why ? Because an object, not as a tiling, but by reason of object, is formally constituted by the formal motive through which it is attained. Thus when a formal heretic from a human motive and by human faith believes in the Incarnation, while rejecting the Trinity; then the object believed, as a tiling, is supernatural but, as an object, it is not supernatural. Therefore it may thus be attained by the natural powers, and then the supernatural truth is attained only materially because it is not attained formally in its supernaturalness, as it is supernatural. That a demon should naturally believe the mysteries of faith is analogical all proportions being maintained, to a dog's materially hearing human speech as sound but not really hearing formally the intelligible meaning of this same speech. Similarly, "the sensual man (for example, a heretic retaining certain mysteries of faith) pcrccivclh not these tilings that are of the Spirit of God; for it is foolishness to him, and he cannot understand" (I Cor. 2:14); cf. also St. Thomas' Commentary on this Epistle. We might draw another comparison with the case of one who listens to a symphony of Beethoven or Bach, possessed of the sense of hearing but devoid of any musical sense: he would not attain to the spirit of the symphony (cf. our De revelatione, I, 478, based on Ila Ilae. q. 5. a. 3). Corollary 4. Man camiot believe supernatural truths from the supernatural moin e of divine revelation without a special interior grace, both in the intellect and in the will. This is contrary, first, to the Pelagians, who say that external revelation is sufficient for the assent of faith (cf. Denz.. nos. 129 ff. ) and, secondly, to the Semi-Pelagians, who would have it that the beginning of faith comes from us (cf. Denz., nos. 174 ff. ; Council of Orange, C. 5, 6, 7); therein it is declared that the inspiration and enlightenment of the Holy Spirit is required in this matter (Denz.. nos. 178-80). These definitions of the Church are based upon several texts of Sacred Scripture cited by the Council of Orange, for example, Ephes. 2:8: "for by grace you are saved through faith, and that not of yourselves, for it is the gift of God; not of works, that no man may glory. " This does not refer to external revelation, for it is further said in the same Epistle (1:17 f. ): "That... God... may give unto you the spirit of wisdom and of revelation, in the knowledge of Him: the eyes of your heart enlightened, that you may know what the hope is ofhis calling"; and (Acts 16:14): "... Lydia... whose heart the Lord opened to attend to those things which were said by Paul. " Again, this fourth corollary is opposed to Molina and many Molinists who declare that fallen man can, without supernatural grace, believe supernatural truths from a supernatural motive, but then he does not believe as is necessary for salvation, for which grace is required. And therefore Molina holds that the assent of faith is supernatural not in respect to substance by virtue of its formal motive, but only in respect to mode, by reason of the eliciting principle and by reason of its extrinsic end. (Cf. Concordia, q. 14. a. 13, disp. 38. pp. 213 ff.. and our De revelatione, I, 489, where Molina and Father Ledochowski are quoted. ) This question has been treated at length and fully by the Salmanticenses in their Commentary on our article, De gratia, disp. Ill, dub. Ill, and I have quoted their principal texts in De revelatione, I, 494, 496, showing that therein they are in accord withall Thomists from Capreolus to the present day (pp. 458-514). Their conclusions, here cited, ought to be read. The argument put forth against Molina and his disciples is found in Ila Ilae. q. 6, a. I, "Whether faith is infused in man by God": "For, since man, assenting to the tilings which are of faith, is raised above his nature, it is necessary that this be instilled into him by a supernatural principle impelling him interiorly through grace. " for an act is specified by its formal object (objectum formale quo et quod): if, therefore, the latter is supernatural the act specified by it is essentially supernatural and cannot be elicited without grace. Further, St. Thomas affirms this to be true even of faith lacking form (informus), that is, faith without charity (Ila Ilae. q. 6, a. 2); even faith lacking form is a gift of God, since it is said to lack form on account of a defect of extrinsic form, and not on account of a defect in the specific nature of infused faith itself, for it has the same specifying formal object. Thus Billuart comments on our article: "the formally supernatural object as such cannot be attained except by a supernatural act. This upsets the basic assertion of Molina, who maintains that the assent to faith from the motive of divine revelation is natural in respect to its substance, and supernatural in respect to its mode.... This opinion does not seem to us sufficiently removed from the error of the Semi-Pelagians. " (Likewise, the Salmanticenses, loc. cit. ) Confirmation. The Council of Orange (c. 5, 6. 7; Denz., nos. 17880) defined grace to be necessary for the initial step toward faith and for the belief necessary to salvation. But to believe on account of the formal supernatural motive of infused faith itself is already to believe in the way necessary to salvation; what more formal belief can then be required ? Therefore, to believe on account of this supernatural motive is impossible without grace. Many difficulties would arise from any other opinion. 1. An act cannot be specified by an eliciting principle, for this eliciting principle itself requires specifying, and it is specified by the act toward which it tends, as the act is specified by its object. Otherwise specification would come from the rear rather than from the front, as if the way from the College "Angelicum" to the Vatican were specified by the terminus from which, and not by the terminus toward which. 2. An act of faith would be no more supernatural than an act of acquired temperance ordered by charity to a supernatural end; it would be less supernatural than an act of infused temperance, as referred to by St. Thomas (la Ilae, q. 63, a. 4). This supernatural in respect to mode is the supernatural almost as applied from without, like gold applied over silver for those who cannot afford to buy pure gold jewelry: it is "plated, " "veneered. " 3. What Molina says of the act of theological faith, could equally be said of the act of hope, and even of the act of charity, for the substance of which natural good will would suffice, and the supernatural mode would be added to make it what is required for salvation. But then the charity' of the viator thus specified by a formal object naturally attainable would not be the same as the charity of the blessed, which must be, like the beatific vision, essentially supernatural. Hence charity would be something different in heaven from what it is now, contrary to the words of St Paul "charity never fallethaway" (I Cor. 13:8). Thus even Suarez vigorously opposes Molina in this matter. There would be innumerable other consequences as indicated in De revelatione, I, 51 I — 14. We cannot therefore admit the following two theses of Cardinal Billot on the subject as put forward in lus book. De virtutibus infusis (71. 87, 88): "Supernatural formality, causing acts to be proportioned to the condition of objects conformable to themselves, does not proceed from the object in that it performs in respect to us the office of an object, nor, namely, either from the material object which is believed, hoped, or loved, or from the formal object on account of which it is believed, hoped, or loved, but solely from the principle of grace by which the operative faculty is elevated. " "Supernatural habits are not necessarilv distinguished from natural habits according to their objects" (p. 84). In opposition to our thesis, cf. the objections in De revelatione, I, 504-11. The principal one is the following. The demons believe (Jas. 2), and they believe without grace. But they believe from the motive of divine revelation. Therefore grace is not necessary to believe from a motive of divine revelation. Reply. I concede the major. I distinguish the minor: that the demons believe formally from the motive of divine revelation according as it is supernatural in respect to substance in itself and on that account, I deny; that they believe materially on the evidence of the signs of revelation, I grant; to this evidence their faith is ultimately reducible. (Cf. Ila Ilae, q. s, a. 2 ad I, 3. ) They believe, says St. Thomas, as it were under constraint from the evidence of miracles, for it would be exceedingly stupid for them to reject this evidence. They therefore attain to God the author of nature and of miracles, but not realty to God the author of grace, nor to revelation as it proceeds from God the author of grace. On the contrary, revelation as proceeding from God, the author of grace, specifies infused faith which is of a higher species than would be a faith, supernatural in respect to mode, based upon the revelation of God, author of nature. (Cf. Salmanticenses quoted in De revelatione, I, 496, 471. ) ARTICLE II. WHETHER MAN CAN WILL TO DO ANY GOOD WITHOUT GRACE State of the question. It seems that man can do some good without grace: 1. -for his acts are in his power, since he is ruler of his acts; 2. for everyone can do better that which pertains to him by nature than that which is beyond him by nature; but man can sin by himself, which is acting beyond and even against nature; therefore with even greater reason can he do good of himself. This objection raises the question whether not sinning, or persevering in good, is itself a gift of God; whether of two men, equally tempted and equally assisted, it can happen that one sins and the other does not. 3. Just as our intellect can, of itself, know truth, so our will can. of itself, will the good. This question concerns: 1. a morally or ethically good work in the natural order (such as proceeds from the dictates of right reason and is not vitiated by any circumstances) so that it is not a sin; and 2. good works conducive to salvation, such as are ordained to a supernatural end, not indeed always as meritorious acts presupposing habitual grace, but as salutary acts disposing to justification and presupposing actual grace. Reply. In respect to these two problems, certain truths are articles of faith. 1. It is of faith that not all the works of infidels or sinners are sins (against Wyclif. Denz., no. 606; JohnHus. no. 642. Bains, nos. 1008. 1027 ff. ; Quesnel, nos. 1351, 1372, 1388). Therefore without the grace of faith a man can do some morally or ethically good works. 2. It is of faith that supernatural good cannot be effected by fallen man without grace. Cf. Council of Orange (Denz., no. 174), can. 6, 7, 9, II, 12-20, 22; and Council of Quierzy (Denz.. no. 317), C. 2. These two articles of faith are based on many passages in Holy Scripture. 1. Holy Scripture does indeed praise certain works of infidels and testifies that they were rewarded by God; for example, it praises the kind-heartedness of the Egyptian midwives who did not wish to kill the children of the Hebrews in conformity with the iniquitous command of Pharaoh (Exod., chap. I); the hospitality of Rahab the harlot, who refused to betray the men sent by Josue (Josue, chap. 2), is also praised; likewise God gave the land of Egypt to King Nabuchodonosor, that he might wage a successful war against the inhabitants of Tyre, according to the command of God (Ezech. 29:20). St. Augustine says (De civ. Dei, Bk. V, chap. 15) that God granted a vast empire to the Romans as a temporal reward of their virtues and good works. But God neither praises nor rewards sins, but rather punishes. Therefore. Similarly it is said in Romans (2:14): "The Gentiles, who have not the law, do by nature those things that are of the law"; in other words, they do at least some good works, as St. Augustine shows (De spiritu et littera, chap. 27). 2 The other proposition of faith, that supernatural good works cannot be performed by fallen man without grace, is also based on many texts from Scripture cited by the Council of Orange: "A man cannot receive anything, unless it be given him from heaven" (John 3:27). "This is the work of God. that you believe in Him whom He hath sent" (John 6:29). "Without Me you can do nothing" (John 15:5). "I am the vine; you the branches" (ibid. ). "It is not of him that willeth, nor of him that runneth, but of God that showeth mercy" (Rom. 9:16). "It is God who worketh in you. both to will and to accomplish, according to His good will" (Phil. 2:13). "What hast thou that thou hast not received ?" (I Cor. 4:7. ) "No man can say the Lord Jesus, but by the Holy Ghost" (I Cor. 12:3). "Not that we are sufficient to think anything of ourselves, as of ourselves: but our sufficiency is from God" (II Cor. 3:5). "Every best gift, and every perfect gift, is from above, coming down from the Father of lights" (Jas. 1:17). There are innumerable texts from St. Augustine; for example, the one quoted in the Sed contra. In the body of the article are found four conclusions, which should be consulted in the text itself. 1. To accomplish any good whatever, man, in any state, requires the general concurrence of God. whether in the state of incorrupt or of corrupt nature (or even in the state of pure nature of which St. Thomas does not speak here, but the possibility of which he admits, as stated In II Sent., d. 31. q. I, a. 2 ad 3, and la. q. 95, a. I). The reason for this is that every creature, since it neither exists nor acts of itself, is in potency regarding action, and needs to be moved from without that it may act, as said in article 1. This efficacious concurrence toward a naturally virtuous good is due, as we have said, to human nature in general, not to any individual in whom God may permit sin. 2. In the state of integral nature, man did not require special added grace, except for performing supernatural works, not, that is, for morally good works commensurate with nature. For nature was then in a perfect state and needed only general concurrence, which is, of course, to be understood in the sense of a concurrence which is prior and efficacious in itself, not in the sense accepted by Molina. 3. In the state of fallen nature man requires supernatural grace not only to perform a supernatural work, but to observe the whole natural law (as will be made more evident later in article 5). 4. Fallen man can do some morally good work in the natural order with general concurrence alone, for example, build houses, plant vineyards, and other things of this kind; and he can do this on account of a duly virtuous end, so that this act may be ethically good from the standpoint of its object, its end, and all its circumstances; for instance, that a man build a home for the good of his family, that is, in such a way that there is no sin invoked. This is particularly evident from the fact that, for St. Thomas, there are no indifferent acts in regard to an individual (la Ilae. q. 18, a. 9; cf. above, la Ilae, 65, a. 2): "Acquired virtues, according as they are operative of good ordained to an end which does not exceed the natural faculty of man, can be deprived of charity, " but they are so on the part of the subject in the circumstance of his disposition, not in the circumstance of a virtue difficult to set in motion, nor closely connected actually. Thus not all the works of infidels and sinners are sins. The reason is that, since human nature "is not totally corrupted" by sin so as to be entirely deprived of natural good, therefore it can, through the power which remains, easily do some morally good works with general concurrence, just as a sick man may have some power of movement in himself, although he is not able to move perfectly unless he is cured. REFUTATION OF OBJECTIONS (CF. DE VERITATE, Q. 24, A. 14) First objection. That is in the power of a man of which he is master. But a man is master of his acts. Therefore it is in the power of a man to do good. Reply. I distinguish the major: without the concurrence of God, denied; with the concurrence of God, granted. I grant the minor. I distinguish the conclusion in the same way as the major. (Read St. Thomas' answer. ) Second objection. Everyone can do better that which pertains to him by nature than that which is beyond his nature. But man can sin of himself, which is beyond-nature. Therefore man can do good of himself. (See a similar objection in De veritate, q. 24, a. 14, objections 3 and 4, also objection 2 and the body of the article toward the end. ) Likewise some say that of two men, tempted in the same way and equally assisted, it may be that one perseveres in attrition or in an easy, imperfect prayer, whereas the other, on the contrary, sins by not continuing this easy act. St. Thomas' reply to objection 2 is as follows: "Every created thing needs to be preserved in the goodness proper to its nature by something else (that is, by God), for of itself it can fall away from goodness. At least, he who does not sin is divinely preserved in the goodness proper to his nature, while God does not preserve the other, but, on the contrary, permits sin in him; therefore they are not equally assisted. However, nature is not completely corrupt; it is able to do some good but with the help of God, which is due to nature in general but not indeed to this individual Therefore, as Augustine says, we ought to thank God inasmuch as we avoid sins which were possible to us, for the very fact of not sinning is a good coming from God; it is, in other words, being preserved in goodness. In reply to the third objection it is noted that "human nature is more corrupted by sin in regard to its appetite for the good than in regard to its knowledge of the truth. " This is because original sin first causes an aversion of the will directly from the final supernatural end, and indirectly from the final natural end; and consequently a disorder in the sensitive appetite tending toward sensible goods, not according to the dictates of right reason. Doubt. How is this general concurrence, necessary for fallen man to accomplish any moral good, to be understood ? Reply. The Molinists understand it as a natural, general, indifferent concurrence which the will, through its own volition, directs toward the good. But the Thomists reply that in that case God. by moving one as far as the exercise of the will is concerned, would be no more the author of a good work than of a bad one (contrary to the Council of Trent. Denz., no. 816). [21] Therefore they insist upon a prevenient. determining, and effective concurrence enabling a manto do good rather than evil. The early Thomists called this a special concurrence, since it is not due to this or that individual; but later Thomists call it a general concurrence, because it is, in a certain sense, due to human nature, even in its fallen state, for nature is not totally corrupt or confirmed in evil, but only weakened. However, it is not due to one individual rather than to another, and from this aspect it is special. In the same way various texts from Scripture, the councils, the Fathers, and St. Thomas, which seem to be contradictory, are reconciled. For example: "No one has anything of himself but sin and tying. " says the Council of Orange (can. 22). That is to say, no one tells the truth with honest intent without at least the natural assistance of God, which is a grace, broadly speaking, with respect to this man on whom it is bestowed rather than on another; otherwise it would have the meaning which Bains gives to it when he says: "Man's free will, without the grace and help of God, is of no use except to commit sin. " Bains means not only natural assistance, or grace broadly speaking, but grace in the proper sense, which comes from Christ, hence sanctifying grace and charity. ARTICLE III. WHETHER MAN CAN LOVE GOD ABOVE ALL THINGS WITHOUT GRACE, BY HIS MERELY NATURAL POWER We are especially concerned, in this article, with the love of God, author of nature, above all things, although there is still a reference in the reply to the first objection to the love of God, author of grace, which proceeds from infused charity. St. Thomas had already dealt with this subject (la, q. 60, a. 5) in respect to the angels, and Later (Ila Ilae, q. 26, a. 3), where he distinguishes more explicitly between natural and supernatural love of God. (Likewise on I Cor.. XIII, lect. 4; De virtutibus, q. 2, a. 2 ad 16; q. 4. a. I ad g; Quodl. I. q. 4, a. 3. ) In the statement of the question he sets down the objections to the possibility' of a natural love of God above all tilings. Later, Bains and Jansen again voice the same objections. This natural love of God above all tilings seems impossible: 1. because loving God above all things is proper to the act of infused charity ; 2. since no creature can rise above itself, it cannot naturally love God more than itself; 3. because grace would be added to no purpose. Let us examine: 1. the doctrine of St. Thomas; 2. its confirmation by the condemnation of Baius and Quesnel; 3. the controversy of modern theologians on this subject. I. THE TEACHING OF ST. THOMAS This teaching can be reduced to three conclusions treating of 1. the love of God, author of nature, above all things in the state of integral nature; 2. the love of God, author of nature, above all tilings in the state of corrupt nature; 3. the supernatural love of God, author of grace, above all tilings. We shall see later, in reference to a particular problem, whether man in the state of pure nature would be able to love God, author of nature, above all things. This question is not solved by the Sed contra, because in it the expression 'by merely natural powers" does not refer to pure nature but to integral nature. The article itself should be read. Conclusion 1. In the state of integral nature, man did not require an added gift of grace to love God, the author of nature, above all things efficaciously; he required only the help of God moving him to it. or natural concurrence. This is proved as above, in regard to the angels, that is, in forms. If anyone should say... that bad works as well as good are done by God, and not merely by His permission... let him be anathema. " Loving God. the author of nature, above all things is natural to man and to every' creature, even irrational in its own way; for. as the good of the part is for the sake of the good of the whole, every particular thing naturally loves its own good on account of the common good of the whole universe, which is God. But man in the state of integral nature could have performed, by virtue of his nature, the good which was natural to him. Therefore man in the state of integral nature could, by virtue of his nature without any added grace, efficaciously love God the author of nature above all things. The major is explained above (la, 60, a. 5) and later (Ila Ilae, q. 26, a. 3). According to la, 60, a. 5: "The natural inclination in those things which are without reason throws some light upon the natural inclination in the will of the intellectual nature. But in natural things, everything which, as such, naturally belongs to another, is principally and more strongly inclined to that other to which it belongs than toward itself. For we observe that a (natural) part endangers itself naturally for the preservation of the whole, as the hand exposes itself without any deliberation to receive a blow for the safeguarding of the whole body. And since reason imitates nature, we find an imitation of this manner of acting in regard to political virtues. For it is the part of a virtuous citizen to expose himself to the danger of death for the safety of the whole nation. And if a man were a natural part of this state, this inclination would be natural to him. Since, therefore, the universal good is God Himself, and angels and men and all creatures are encompassed by this goodness, and since every creature naturally by its very' being belongs to God, it follows that even by a natural love angels and men love God in greater measure and more fundamentally than they do themselves. Otherwise, if they naturally loved themselves more than God. it would follow that natural love was perverse and would not be perfected by charity but rather destroyed. " These last w ords imply that in the state of pure nature man would be able to love God naturally above all tilings, otherwise natural love would be perverse; but we shall see in the second conclusion that this is not so in the state of fallen nature on account of its wounds. The major of the present argument is entirety fundamental and a most beautiful concept. It is thus explained (la, q. 60, a. 5 ad I): "Every (natural) part naturally loves the whole more than itself. And every individual member naturally loves the good of its species more than its own individual good. " Hence onanism, preventing fertility, is a crime against nature, against the good of the species. A good Thomist, then, loves and defends the doctrine of St. Thomas more than his personal opinions. However, in the exposition of this major the excess of pantheism must be avoided, for then the creature would love God more than self naturally in such a way that sin would be impossible. This impossibility of sinning only follows confirmation in goodness, and especially the beatific vision. The contrary' excess would be a pessimism arising from dualism, which would lead to Manichaeism, that is. the doctrine of two principles. As Father Rousselot demonstrates in his thesis. "Pour l'histoire du problème de 1'amour au Moyen Age, " [22] there are various theories between these two mutually opposing excesses. There is already, therefore, in our nature an inclination to love God, the author of nature, more than ourselves. Conclusion 2. In the state of fallen nature, in order to love God, the author of nature, above all tilings efficaciously , man requires the help of grace restoring nature. (Cf. the end of the article's conclusion. ) The proof given in the words of St. Thomas is as follow s: 'because, on account of the corruption of nature, the will adheres to a private good, unless cured by the grace of God. " In other words, unless cured by grace, man does not referto God, efficaciously loved as an end, his love of self and of all other tilings; thus, unless cured by grace, man does not love God more than himself with a natural love. And inasmuch as this disordered inclination is perverse, it is called an inordinate love of self, self-love, or egoism. By original sin, man's will is directly averse to his final supernatural end and indirectly to his final natural end. For every sin against the supernatural law and end is indirectly' against the natural law which prescribes that God is to be obeyed, whatever He commands Hence fallen man is averse to God as his final end even naturally. Conclusion 3. Man in any state requires the help of special grace to love God, the author of grace, with an infused, supernatural love (cf. ad I). This is of faith, contrary to Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism (Council of Orange can 22 Beitrage zur Geschichte der Phil, desMittelalters, Munster, 1908. (ed. Cl. Baeumker). 17, 25; Denz., nos. 190, 198; Council of Trent, Sess. VI, can. 3; Denz. no. 813). It was declared that "if anyone should say that, without a prevenient inspiration of the Holy Ghost and His assistance, man can believe, hope, love, or repent in such a way that the grace of justification would be conferred on him, let him be anathema. " This definition of faith is based on the texts of Sacred Scripture quoted at the Council of Orange as follows: "The charity of God is poured forth in our hearts, by the Holy Ghost, who is given to us (Rom. 5:5). "No man can say the Lord Jesus, but by the Holy Ghost" (I Cor. 12:3). "The fruit of the Spirit is charity, joy, peace" (Gal. 5:22). "Peace be to the brethren and charity with faith, from God the Father, and the Lord Jesus Christ" (Ephes. 6:23). "Dearly beloved, let us love one another, for charity is of God. And everyone that loveth. is born of God, and knoweth God. He that loveth not, knoweth not God: for God is charity" (I John 4:7 f. ); that is, he does not know, as it were, experimentally, with an affective knowledge. Bains and Quesnel said that he does not know in any way. In regard to the explanation of this third conclusion, see the reply to the first objection, which was quoted against Baius. St. Thomas says: "Nature loves God above all things since God is the beginning and end of natural good; charity, however, loves God since He is the object of (supernatural) beatitude and since man has a certain spiritual fellowship (by grace) with God. " From which is to be intimated what man would be capable of even in the state of pure nature. Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 26, a. 3. where it is declared that: "We can receive a twofold good from God. the good of nature and the good of grace. Moreover, natural love is based upon the communication of natural goods made to us by God.... Hence this is much more truly evident in the friendship of charity, which is based upon the communication of the gifts of grace. " Again in the reply to the second objection: "Any part loves the good of the whole according as it is becoming to itself, not however in such a way as to refer the good of the whole to itself, but rather so as to refer itself to the good of the whole. " And in reply to the third objection: "We love God more with a love of friendship than with a love of concupiscence, for the good of God is in se greater than the good which we can share by enjoying Him. " And thus, absolutely, man loves God more in charity than himself. And he loves the God who is to be seen more than the beatific vision or the created joy following upon this vision. Thus, it may be said (Ila Ilae, q. 1% a. 6 ad 3): "Charity (inasmuch as it surpasses hope) properly causes a tending toward God, uniting the affections of a man with God, so that man does not live for himself but for God. " This is pure love properly understood, that is, above hope; but not excluding hope, as the Quietists would have it. Doubt. Whether in the state of pure nature man would be able to love God the author of nature, above all things, with a natural love. Reply. Thomists generally reply in the affirmative. 1. On account of the universality of the principle invoked by St. Thomas (la, q. 60, a. 5, and in the present article): "Every creature according to its being as such, is of God, and therefore it loves God with a natural love more than self. " This principle is valid for any natural state in which there is no disorder. But in the slate of pure nature there would be no disorder. 2. In Quodl, I, a. 8, St. Thomas enunciates the principle of our article in a very comprehensive way, so that it would be valid for any natural state in which there is no perversion. 3. Since it is said (la. q. 60, a. 5) that, "if (man) were to love himself naturally more than God, it would follow that natural love would be perverse, and that it would not be perfected by charity but destroyed. " But this natural love would not be perverse in the state of pure nature. Therefore. 4 Since man in the state of pure nature would not be born, as now, habitually averse to his final supernatural end directly and to his final natural end indirectly. There would be no aversion to the final natural end, but the possibility' of conversion or aversion. Corollary. Man has less powers in the state of fallen nature for naturally doing what is morally good than he would have in the state of pure nature. This is contested by several authors of the Society of Jesus. II. CONFIRMATION OF THIS DOCTRINE OF ST. THOMAS FROM THE CONDEMNATION OF BAIUS (CF. DENZ., NOS. 1034, 1036, 1038) AND QUESNEL (DENZ., NOS. 1394-5) The entire solution may be reduced to the following: [diagram page 61]___________________________________________________________________________ The love of God above all things 1. (supernatural) is impossible without grace in any state 2. (natural) is possible without grace in the state of integral nature and also in the state of pure nature, but not in the state of corrupt nature Hence it must be firmly maintained that the natural love of God above all things is the supreme precept of the natural law, and with still greater reason does this hold in the supernatural order, as it was already formulated in Dent. 6:5: "Thou shall love the Lord thy God with thy whole heart"; but there it was proclaimed as a law of the supernatural order as well, as also in Matt. 22:27, Mark 12:30, Luke 10:27. But the natural law is neither abolished by sin nor given by grace, since it is naturally stamped upon creatures. III. CONTROVERSIES AMONG MODERN THEOLOGIANS ON THIS SUBJECT The controversy is twofold, first on natural love and secondly on supernatural love. The first problem is whether fallen man can, without repairing grace, love God the author of nature above all things with a love that is affectively efficacious. (Cf. Billuart, De gratia, diss. Ill, a. 3. ) The second problem is whether the act of the love of God, author of grace, considered substantially, is impossible without grace. Molina denies this. First of all the terminology must be explained as follows: [diagram page 62]____________________________________________________________________________ Natural love 1. innate 1.1. before any knowledge whatever it is the faculty of the will w hich naturally is inclined to love God, author of nature, above all things (la, q. 60, a. 5) 2. elicited 2.1. necessary 2.1.1. the love of happiness in general, by which God is loved in a somewhat confused way, but not really distinctly above all things 2.2. free (in regard to God distinctly known as the highest good) 2.2.1. inefficacious 2.2.1.1. simple complacency in the goodness of God. not employing the means of pleasing God or withdrawing from mortal sin 2.2.2. efficacious (by force of the means put forth) 2.2.2.1. affectively 2.2.2.1.1.simple act of love of God above all things with the intention of pleasing Him in all things and withdrawing from mortal sin 2.2.2.2. effectively 2.2.2.2. l.practice of the aforesaid intention by the actual observance of the natural law 23 The excess of Jansenism is found to a certain extent in the argument proposed by Pascal as "the wager, " in which he says: a choice must be made between the Christian life which is set before us as the way to heaven, and the life of the libertine which is said to be the way of damnation. Some might add a third alternative: natural virtue. But in practice, the argument proposed by Pascal holds good, since the fullness of natural virtue is not present in fallen nature without grace 1. It is certainly true that without grace there can be: a) an innate love or natural inclination to love God above all things; this is the faculty of the will itself; b) a necessary, elicited love of God vaguely loved in happiness in general, which all desire; in this case God is not loved above all things, since He is not considered as distinct from all other goods; c) a free inefficacious love, or simple complacency in the goodness of God, not going so far as to adopt means of pleasing God nor of withdrawing from mortal sin, for which natural concurrence would be adequate. Thus many poets have written beautiful poems on the goodness and wisdom of God, ruler of the world, but without the intention of reforming their voluptuous lives. 2. We shall see in the following article that effectively efficacious love, at least absolutely, or the practice of all the commands of the natural law which are gravely obligatory, cannot now be possessed without a special healing grace. 3. The controversy, therefore, concerns affectively efficacious love, by which God, author of nature, distinctly known, is loved with esteem above all things, with the intention of pleasing Him in all things and of withdrawing from mortal sins against the natural law. Thomists maintain that this affectively efficacious love camrot exist in fallen man without healing grace. [24] And in this regard they differ especially from Molina, who teaches that fallen man can, by his natural powers, thus love God, the author of nature, with an affectively efficacious love, and even, after having been instructed in the teaching of faith, can, likewise by his natural powers, love God as author of grace substantially, although not in respect to supernaturalness of mode, which is bestowed by charity. [25] Molina adds to this that the affectively efficacious natural love of God, author of nature, is not meritorious of grace (that would be Semi-Pelagianism) but, on account of the covenant between God and Christ the Redeemer, if man thus does what in him lies through his natural powers, God will not refuse sanctifying grace. [26] With still greater reason, for Molina, if anyone imbued with the doctrine of faith undertakes an act, natural substantially, of affectively efficacious love of God, author of grace. God infuses charity, and this love become supernatural in respect to mode and thus available for salvation. Scotus, Gabriel and certain others are cited as holding the same opinion. Against the first of these teachings of Molina on the possibility of an affectively efficacious love of God. author of nature, above all things without grace, Thomists declare that: 1. This doctrine does not seem to preserve sufficiently the sense of the words of the Council of Orange (can. 25; Denz.. no. 199): "We must believe that by the sin of the first man free will was so inclined and weakened that no one subsequently is able either to love God as he ought.... or to do for the sake of God what is good, unless the grace of mercy anticipates him. " The Molinists reply that the Council says, "as he ought with regard to salvation. " and hence refers only to supernatural love. To this the Thomists answer that the Council is not referring to supernatural love alone, since it repeats that the impotence to love God above all things arises not from the supernaturalness of the act but from the infirmity of fallen nature; therefore it refers to natural love as well since the impotence arising from the supernaturalness of the act was already present in the state of innocence. This also seems to be the meaning of the Council of Trent (Sess. VI. can. 3; Denz., no. 813): "If anyone should say that without the inspiration of the Holy Ghost and His assistance man can believe, hope, love, or repent as is required in order that the grace of justification should be granted to him, let him be anathema. " Nevertheless, the Thomists add, it is not possible for the grace of justification not to be conferred upon one who loves God, the author of nature, above all things with an affectively efficacious love. (Cf. below, q. 109, a. 6. on whether man, without grace, can prepare himself for grace, and q. 112, a. 3. ) Moreover, the aforesaid teaching of Molina is contrary to the final proposition of the body of the present article of St. Thomas, where he contrasts the state of fallen nature with that of integral nature: "In the state of corrupt nature, man requires the help of grace healing nature, even for loving God naturally above all things. " There is no doubt but that St. Thomas is speaking also of affectively efficacious natural love, that is, with the intention of pleasing God in all things and of withdrawing from mortal sin. This is confirmed by what has been said above (la Ilae, q. 89, a. 6): 24 It is a question of the consequent power. Cf. Salmanticenses, De gratia, disp. II, dub. IV, no. 135, where other important Thomists are quoted; cf. also John of St. Thomas, Gonet, Billuart. 2? Cf. Molina, Concordia. Paris ed., 1876, pp. 31, 34, 68 ff., 73, 255 26 ibid., pp. 43, 73, 564 "When man begins to have the use of reason... (he should) deliberate concerning himself. And if anyone orders his life toward the proper end (that is, to God even as author of nature), he will obtain the remission of original sin by grace. In the present article St. Thomas is not yet speaking of effectively efficacious love, that is, of the fulfillment of every natural precept; but he refers to it in the following article. Finally, the opinion of Molina is thus refuted by theological argument: A weak power, inclined to selfish good opposed to the divine, cannot produce the superior act of a healthy power with reference to God, unless it is healed. But man in the state of fallen nature has a weak will, inclined to a selfish good. Therefore he cannot produce a pre­ eminent work with reference to God. This act is pre-eminently that of a healthy power, since it virtually contains the fulfillment of the whole natural law. for the actual accomplishment of the law follows from the efficacious will to fulfill it. Hence grace is necessary not only for the actual observance of the whole natural law, but also for the intention of fulfilling it. Nor is the efficacious natural volition granted for accomplishing anything which is now naturally impossible. This weakness of the will consists in its "following a selfish good unless healed by the grace of God, " as stated in the article. In other words, it is turned away from God and even its natural final end; for sin offends God even as author of nature. Moreover, it is a disorder of the concupiscence which the demon augments and enkindles. First doubt. What, then, of the natural love of God in the separated souls of children who die without baptism, of whom St. Thomas speaks (Ila, d. 33, q. 2, a. 2 ad 5) ? Reply. There is, first of all, an innate love and a necessary, elicited love of God. confusedly, as in happiness in general for this love remains even in the demons (la, q. 60, a. 5 ad 5). Secondly, there is a free, imperfect, inefficacious love, or love of complacency, toward God as principle of all natural good, but not really an efficacious love. Otherwise we should have to deny the last proposition in the body of the present article. In this connection it seems that, as stated in a. 2 ad 3, "Nature is more corrupted in regard to the appetite for good than in regard to the knowledge of the truth. " For the mind of fallen man is able by its own powers to judge speculatively that God is the highest good, lovable and worthy of love above all things; but without healing grace, he is incapable of recognizing this with his practical judgment, impelling him to action. Hence the words of Medea spoken of by the poet: "I see what is better, and I approve it (speculatively), but I follow what is worse. " Man, then, is more deeply wounded in his will by which he sins than in his intellect. If, therefore, a child, reaching the full use of reason, loves God, the author of nature, above all things with an affectively efficacious love, this can only be by means of healing grace. Objection. Fallen man can, without grace, love his country, or his friend, or his chastity more than his own life; therefore, with still greater reason can he so love God, the author of nature Reply. I reply by distinguishing the antecedent: fallen man does this without the special help of God, if it is done from a worldly motive, such as the desire for fame or glory, granted; but if from the pure motive of virtue, denied; for this requires the special help of God, as conceded to many pagans, according to Augustine. Moreover it is more difficult to love God, the author of nature, above all things in a manner that is affectively' efficacious than to love the attractiveness of any particular virtue more than one's life; for this is, at least virtually, to love all the virtues beyond all sensible feelings. This is more difficult; for instance that a soldier, ready to die for Iris country, is not willing to spare Iris enemy when he should. Second doubt. What grace is required for this affectively efficacious love of God, author of nature above all things ? Reply. Of itself, by reason of its object, it requires only help of a natural order, but accidentally and indirectly, by reason of the elevation of the human race to the supernatural order, it requires supernatural help, that is. healing grace (as declared in the article). This is because the aversion to a final natural end cannot be cured without the aversion to a final supernatural end being cured; for this latter contains indirectly an aversion to the final natural end, for every sin against the supernatural law is indirectly against the natural law: God is to be obeyed, whatever He may command. Moreover, as we shall state in the following article, the love of God virtually includes the fulfillment of the whole natural law. for which supernatural healing grace is required. The Thomists also reject the other opinion of Molina, that man imbued with the teaching of faith can without grace love God, the author of grace, in respect to the substance of this act, although not in respect to its mode as proper to salvation. Contrary to this, the Thomists generally hold, as for the act of faith, that the act is specified by its formal object; but the formal object of the aforesaid act is God, the author of grace; therefore this act is essentially supernatural, or supernatural in respect to substance and not merely in respect to mode (cf. Salmanticenses, De gratia, disp. Ill, dub. Ill; and our De revelatione, I, 498, 511). A natural act in respect to substance would be an act specified by a natural object, such as an act of acquired temperance, which might yet become supernatural in respect to mode, according as it is commanded by charity and ordered by it to the reward of eternal life. ARTICLE IV. WHETHER MAN, WITHOUT GRACE, BY HIS NATURAL POWERS, CAN FULFILL THE PRECEPTS OF THE NATURAL LAW State of the question. In this article, as is evident in the body, we are especially concerned with the precepts of the decalogue which already belong to the natural law and can substantially be fulfilled without charity; indeed, even the acts of faith and hope can be accomplished in the state of mortal sin. Let us examine: 1. St. Thomas' conclusions and arguments; 2. How they are based on Holy Scripture and tradition; 3. The refutation of the objections. (The article should be read. ) I. ST. THOMAS' CONCLUSIONS His first conclusion is that in the state of corrupt nature, man cannot, without healing grace, fulfill all the precepts of the natural law with respect to the substance of the works, while on the contrary' he would be able to do this without grace in the state of integral nature (supposing, however, natural concurrence). From these last words, which are found in St. Thomas, it is evident that he is concerned in this instance with the precepts of the natural law in respect to the substance of the works, for the substance of a work correlative with a supernatural precept is supernatural and cannot, even in the state of integral nature, be produced without grace. In fact, precepts are called supernatural because they enjoin acts which surpass the powers of nature. In article two it is stated that "grace was necessary to man in the state of integral nature in order to perform or will a supernatural work. " The argument supporting this conclusion is the same as in the preceding article for the impossibility of loving God, author of nature, with an affectively efficacious love; indeed the argument now holds with still greater reason, that is, in the case of effectively efficacious love or the fulfillment of all the precepts of the natural law. In other words, a weak man cannot of himself perform the very' superior work of a healthy man, unless he is first cured. Nor can a will turned away from even its natural final end be properly oriented in regard to all the means to that end. It would be rash to deny this first conclusion or to maintain that effectively efficacious love of God, author of nature, above all tilings can be attained without grace. This is conceded by the Molinists. [27] It would be rash because the Council of Orange (Denz., nos. 181 ff., 199) refers not only to impotence arising from the supernaturalness of the work, but from the weakness of fallen nature. The second conclusion is that in no state can man without grace fulfill the commands of the law with respect to the mode of acting, that is, performing them from charity. This is of faith. St. Thomas makes the assertion without proof, for he has already said, in article two, that man even in the state of incorrupt nature required "grace added to nature in order to perform or will supernatural good, " and particularly to elicit a supernatural act of charity'. For acts are specified by their objects and therefore the act specified by a supernatural object is essentially supernatural. II. THE BASES OF TRADITION 27 St. Thomas' first conclusion on the necessity of grace to fulfill substantially all the precepts of the natural law is commonly accepted by theologians, although it was formerly denied by Scotus (11. d. 28, a. I). Gabriele, and Durandus; to deny it would be rash or erroneous and savors of Pelagianism. Cf. Hugon, De gratia, p. 259. They are as indicated by Billuart. in addition to many texts of St. Augustine. 1. The Council of Milevum (Denz., no. 105), against the Pelagians who declared that without grace man can keep all the commandments of God, but with difficulty; with grace, however, he can do so with facility; it is defined that "if anyone should say... that grace... is given to us that we may more easily fulfill the divine commands, and... that, without it, we are able to fulfill them, although not easily, let him be anathema. " From this it is deduced that the commandments of God cannot be fulfilled as is necessary for salvation, that is, from charity, without grace. St. Augustine always defends this truth against the Pelagians in his De spiritu et littera, De gratia Christi, De libero arbitrio; in the book De haeresibus (heresy 88), speaking of the Pelagians, he says: "They are such enemies of the grace of God that they believe a man can accomplish all the divine commands without it. " Likewise, St. Augustine on Ps. 118, cone. 5, and in Sermon 148 (de tempore), chap. 5, where he is concerned with the precepts of the decalogue. The opposite error in Bains (Denz., nos. 1061, 1062) was condemned because it rejects the distinction between fulfilling the commandments in respect to substance and in respect to mode, supernaturally. 2. The Council of Orange (II, c. 25; Denz., no. 199) declared: "We must believe that through the sin of the first man free will was so inclined and weakened, that no one has since... been able to perform what is good for the sake of God unless the grace of divine mercy precedes him. " Hence St. Thomas' second conclusion is of faith; that is, without grace, men cannot fulfill the commandments with respect to supernaturalness of mode, namely, so as to be performed out of charity. And the Molinists admit this. Doubt. Whether grace is necessary for the fulfilling of any supernatural precept, in respect to its substance. Herein lies the controversy with the Molinists. Scotus and the Molinists hold that without grace men imbued with the teaching of faith can fulfill, substantially, even interior works correlative to the supernatural precepts of faith, hope, and charity. Reply. The Thomists reply that it is not possible, since precepts are called supernatural because they enjoin acts which, in themselves, essentially surpass the powers of nature, and these acts are such, in fact, because they are specified by a supernatural formal object. Thus, for example, an act of Christian faith differs from an act of acquired temperance. Insistence by Molina, Lugo, and Billot, that diversity of the activating principles (that is, of habits) alone is sufficient to cause acts to differ in species, even when they attain the same formal object. Reply. 1. These very activating principles, that is, habits and powers, should be specified by the formal object. 2. The Salmanticenses reply {De gratia, disp. Ill, dub. Ill, no. 60): "I deny the antecedent, for if it were true, as our adversaries contend, nothing in true philosophy but would waver (or be overturned) in regard to species and the distinction of powers and habits; we should be compelled to establish new bases such as were not taught by Aristotle, Master Thomas, or the leaders of other schools. Although younger writers would easily grant this, we should have no leader from among the ancients. The result would indeed be to the highest detriment of true wisdom; wherefore it is essential in this respect to hinder their proclivity with all our powers. " Cf. other texts of the Salmanticenses quoted in our De revelatione, I, 495. To the same effect Thomas de Lemos, O.P., replied in the celebrated discussions of the Congregatio de Auxiliis, on May 7 and 28, 1604. before Clement VIII (cf. De revelatione, I, 491). He challenged the opinion of Molina in the following words: "By which system he would overturn faith as well as philosophy; faith, certainly, because thus God is feared and loved by the powers of nature, as the end is supernatural; philosophy indeed since, in this way, the formal object of a superior habit is attained by the inferior powers. " And on May 28. 1604, session 54 settled a problem proposed according to the interpretation of tire Thomists explained by Lemos. Lemos expresses the same opinion in his Panoplia gratiae at the beginning of Bk. IV, nos. 24f. (Cf. De revelatione, I. 491; Del Prado, De gratia, I, 48; Suarez expresses agreement with us De gratia, Bk. II, c. II, nos. 22 f.. quoted in De revelatione, ibid. ) Thus Suarez, as well as Lemos and the Salmanticenses considers it rash to deny the aforesaid traditional teaching of theologians. In respect to this matter many Jesuits follow Suarez, including the Wurzburg school (De virtutibus theologicis, disp. II, c. III, a. 3); Bellarmine is also cited and, among more recent writers. Wilmers (De fide divina, 1902, pp. 352, 358, 375); Mazzella, in the first two editions of De virtutibus infusis, and Pesch (De gratia, nos. 69, 71, 410). Objection. The Molinists object, referring to la Ilae, q. 54, a. 2, where it is stated that "the species of habits are distinguished in three ways: 1. according to the activating principles of such dispositions. 2. according to nature, 3. according to objects. " Therefore, declare the Molinists, habits are not specified only by their objects. Reply. All of these are to be taken together and not separately. An act cannot be essentially supernatural from the standpoint of its eliciting principle and according as it presupposes habitual grace unless it is at the same time supernatural from the standpoint of its object. Moreover, we contend in De revelatione. I. 506. in agreement with the Salmanticenses and other Thomists, that from St. Thomas' context it is clearly evident that, when he says habits are specified according to their active principles, he means according to their objective, regulating, specifying principles; for he says in the answer to the second objection of the same article: "The various means (of knowledge) are like various active principles according to which the habits of science are differentiated. " And in answer to the third objection: "Diversity of ends differentiates virtues as diversity of active principles" or motives according as the end is the object of a prior act of the will, in other words, the intention. Similarly in la Ilae, q. 51, a. 3, St. Thomas shows that the regulating reason is the active principle of the moral virtues, and the understanding of principles is the principle of knowledge, that is, as proposing the formal object (objectum formale quo) or motive. Moreover, when he says that habits are specified according to nature, this is according as the habit is good or bad, suitable or not suitable to the nature; or according as it is suitable to human nature as such, or suitable to the divine nature in which man participates; but it cannot be of itself suitable to a higher nature, unless at the same time it has a formal object proportionate or of the same order; otherwise it would be an accidentally infused habit, such as infused geometry. Father Ledoc how ski, General of the Society of Jesus, further acknowledges that the teaching of Molina we are discussing is not that of St. Thomas (cf. De revelatione, I, 489). III. REFUTATION OF THE PRINCIPAL OBJECTIONS AGAINST THE NECESSITY OF GRACE FOR OBSERVING SUBSTANTIALLY ALL L HE PRECEPTS OF THE NATURAL LAW The first classical difficulty is indicated by St. Thomas in the first objection, taken from the text of St. Paul to the Romans (2:14): "The Gentiles who have not the (written) law, do by nature those things which are of the law. " Reply. According to St. Augustine, followed by St. Prosper, St. Fulgentius, and by St. Thomas here in his refutation, these words are to be understood of the Gentiles acting from grace; and then "by nature" is not interpreted according as it is opposed to grace, and according as it is equivalent to "the powers of nature, " but according as it is opposed to the Mosaic law, so that the meaning is: "The Gentiles who have not the written law. do naturally those things which are of the law, " in other words, without the law of Moses, but not without the spirit of grace. Thus Augustine in De spiritu et littera, Bk. I, c. 27, quoted here by St. Thomas; likewise St. Chrysostom. [:8] But other interpreters understand this of the infidel Gentiles and hence "by nature" of the powers of nature; but this disposes of the objection just as well for the meaning is that the Gentiles by their own natural powers perform certain works of the law, but not all. The second difficulty is as follows: if the observance of the whole natural law, in respect to the substance of the works, is impossible to fallen nature, then the Jansenist heresy follows logically, that is. that certain of the precepts of God are impossible to fallen man. Luther and Calvin held the same opinion. 28 St. Chrysostom, in Iris fifth homily on the Epistle to the Romans, declares: "The Apostle refers not to the idolatrous Greeks but to those who by worshipping God and obeying the natural law. practiced all those things that pertain to piety, even prior to the Jewish observances; such were those who lived with Melchisedech, such was Job such were the Ninivites, such finally was Cornelius. " St. Chrysostom, in his thirteenth homily on the same Epistle, commenting on the words "miserable man that I am, " teaches that the law without grace does not suffice. Reply. "What we can do with divine assistance is not altogether impossible for us"; and we avoid Jansenism by declaring that the grace necessary to accomplish the commandments is not wanting to anyone except by reason of his own fault. All adults receive graces at least remotely sufficient for salvation, and if they did not resist them, they would obtain further graces. The error of Luther and Calvin is apparent from this : according to them, Christ did not come to form observers of the law, but to redeem the faithful from the obligation of observing the law, in accordance with Luther's words: "Sin strongly and believe more strongly, " in other words, believe firmly that you are freely elect, and you are saved, even if you persevere in crimes and the transgression of the law until death. The Jansenists erred similarly by maintaining that certain commands of God are impossible not only to fallen man, but even to the just man. This is manifest from the first proposition of Jansen (Denz., no. 1092): "Other precepts of God are impossible to just, willing, zealous men with the powers which they now possess; they also lack the grace which would make them possible"; in 1653 this was condemned as heretical. The Council of Trent had previously defined (Denz., no. 804): "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He urges you both to do what you can and to ask what you cannot, and He assists you that you may be able. " Also in the corresponding canon (Denz.. no. 828). The foregoing words of the Council are taken from St. Augustine, and, according to them, sufficient grace to pray is never wanting, and by it man has at least the remote power of observing the divine precepts, for 'by commanding. God urges you to do what you can and to ask what you cannot, and He assists you that you may be able. " I insist. God cannot demand that a blind man see, although he may see by a miracle; therefore, neither can He demand that fallen man observe the law, although he may do so by means of grace. Reply. The disparity lies particularly in the fact that the blind man is not offered a miracle which would cure him; but fallen man is offered grace by which he may observe the law, and he would receive it if he did not voluntarily set obstacles in the way. Hence one must pray as did Augustine, saying: "Lord, grant what Thou commandest and command what Thou wilt, " that is, give us grace to fulfill Thy commands and command what Thou wilt. First doubt. Which grace is required by fallen man for the keeping of the whole natural law? Reply. As in the explanation of the preceding article: of itself, by reason of its object, help of the natural order would suffice, since the object is natural. Accidentally, however, and by reason of the elevation of the human race to a supernatural end, supernatural grace is required, which under this aspect is called healing grace. This is because in the present economy of salvation man cannot be converted to God, his final natural end, and remain estranged from God, his supernatural end, since this aversion is indirectly opposed to the natural law, according to which we ought to obey God, whatever He may command. Second doubt. To observe the whole natural law for a long time is supernatural actual grace sufficient, or is habitual grace required? Reply. According to ordinary providence, habitual grace is required, by which alone man is solidly well disposed toward his final end. And this firm disposition toward his final end is itself required that man may keep the whole natural law enduringly and perseveringly. Nevertheless, by an extraordinary providence, God can fortify a man's will in regard to the observance of all the natural precepts by means of continuous actual graces; but if a man does what lies within his power by the help of actual grace, God will not withhold habitual grace from him. As we shall see below (a. 9), over and above habitual grace, actual grace is required for the just man to perform any supernatural good work, and evento persevere for long in the observance of the whole natural law, in spite of the rebellion of the sense appetites against reason, and the temptations of the world and the devil. Third doubt Whether in the state of pure nature man would be able to observe enduringly the whole natural law without special help of the natural order. Reply. I reply in the negative with Billuart: Since to do so demands constancy of the will in good against the temptations that arise, a constancy which man established in the state of pure nature would not have had. of himself, with the aid of ordinary concurrence alone; hence, to persevere he would have had need of special natural help which God would have given to many, but not to those in whom He would have permitted the sin of impenitence of this natural order in punishment for preceding sins. Cajetan's opinion. In his commentary on the present article, which preceded the disputes aroused by Molina, at a time when the terminology of this subject was not yet fully established. Cajetan spoke less accurately in explaining the answer to the third objection. He says, "man, by nature, can believe, hope, love God, with respect to the substance of the act, " and he cites the example of a formal heretic who adheres to certain dogmas. He expresses himself similarly in regard to Ilallae. q. 171, a. 2 ad 3. But it is evident from the context and from this example that Cajetan is referring to the generic substance of the acts, not to the specific substance, not to the formal object itself {objectum formale quod et quo); for a heretic believes formally, not by divine, but by human faith. Later Cajetan corrects his terminology (commenting on Ila Ilae. q. 6, a. I. no. 3), declaring that "it should be said, therefore, that the act of faith springs forth as a result of no natural knowledge, of no natural appetite, but from the appetite for eternal beatitude and from an adherence to God supernaturally revealing and preserving His Church. " Cajetan likewise defends the common opinion of Thomists against Scotus and Durandus (la Ilae, q. 51, a. 4): "Infused habits are of themselves essentially supernatural. " Also. q. 62, a. 3: q. 63, a. 6. and Ila Ilae, q. 17, a. 5, no. I, where he defends the opinion that without infused virtue there would be no act "proportionate to the supernatural object, " nor to the supernatural end. (Cf. Del Prado. De gratia. I. 50 and our De revelatione, I, 484 f., note 1. ) ARTICLE V. WHETHER MAN CAN MERIT ETERNAL LIFE WITHOUT GRACE After considering the observance of the divine commands in themselves. St. Thomas considers it in relation to eternal life. The question is here posed generally and indefinitely: later, in q. 114. a. I. 2. 3, where he is dealing with merit properly speaking, the question will be more particularly treated as to whether man without grace can merit de condigno eternal life. The answer is negative and is of faith, against the Pelagians. 1. It is proved from authority in the argument Sed contra (Rom. 6:23): "the grace of God life eternal, " which is thus explained by Augustine, here quoted: "that it may be understood that God, in His compassion, leads us unto eternal life. " St. Augustine is also quoted in the answer to the second objection. (Cf. Council of Orange, II, can. 7, Denz., no. 180; and Trent, Sess. VI, can. 2, Denz.. no. 812. ) 2. It is thus proved by theological reasons: Acts leading to an end must be proportionate to the end. But eternal life is an end exceeding the proportion of human nature (cf la Ilae. q. 5. a. s, on supernatural beatitude). Therefore man cannot by his natural powers produce works meritorious of eternal life. Read the answer to the third objection with respect to the distinction between final natural end and supernatural end (cf. Contra Gentes, Bk. Ill, chap. 147, and De veritate, q. 14, a. 2). These references are clear, and whatever is to be said on this subject is reserved for consideration in q. 114, a. I and 2. that is, whether man can merit anything de condigno, and so merit eternal life. ARTICLE VI. WHETHER MAN CAN PREPARE HIMSELF FOR GRACE BY HIMSELF WITHOUT THE EXTERIOR HELP OF GRACE State of the question. The external help of grace with which we are here concerned, is not only the preaching of the gospel itself, confirmed by miracles (the Pelagians admitted this), nor is it only the natural concurrence of God for the performance of a naturally good act, the necessity of which the Semi-Pelagians did not deny, but, as the body of the article explains, it refers to actual supernatural help. That the difficulty of this question may be more manifest, St. Thomas considers the following. 1. The arguments maintained by the Pelagians or Semi-Pelagians, namely it seems that without actual grace man can prepare himself for habitual grace, for, we read (Zach. 1:3): "Turnye to Me. and I will turn to you. "2. It is frequently said. "To him who does what he can, God does not deny grace": and (Luke 11:13): "If you then, being evil, know how to give good gifts to your children, how much more will your Father from heaven give the good Spirit to them that ask Him?" 3. It would be an infinite process, since to prepare himself for a prior grace, man would require another, and so on ad infinitum. 4. In the Book of Proverbs (16:1) it is said that "it is the part of man to prepare the soul, " according to the Vulgate; but in many codices this verse is lacking and in the Greek codices in which it occurs, the sense is: "It is the part of man to form a proposal in his heart, " as if to say: man proposes and God disposes. On the other hand we find in the Gospel according to St. John (6:44): "No man can come to me. except the Father, who hath sent Me, draw him. " How are these quotations to be reconciled ? Let us examine 1. The errors on this subject which have been condemned; 2. the disagreement among Catholic theologians; and 3. the opinion of St. Thomas. I. The condemned errors. The Pelagians, denying original sin, maintained, at least at the beginning of their heresy, that man by his own powers, without grace, can prepare himself for grace so as to merit the first grace. This was condemned by the Councils of Neo-Caesaria and Milevum (Denz., nos. 104 ff., 133 ff. ). The Semi-Pelagians said that fallen man, without grace, can have of himself the beginning of salvation and can prepare himself for grace, by asking, desiring, knocking, seeking; thus he does not merit grace, but he disposes himself for it by himself alone, and God seizes upon this beginning of salvation as an occasion for conferring grace, otherwise He would be an acceptor of persons if He conferred grace upon one rather than another without any reason on the part of man. [29] . This was condemned by the Council of Orange (II, can. 3 and 6, Denz., nos. 176, 179). The same declaration was made by the Council of Trent (Sess. VI, can. 3, Denz., no. 813). IL. Among Catholic theologians, notwithstanding the condemnation of the Semi-Pelagians, Molina, following the lead of Durandus, Scotus, and Gabriel Biel, maintains in his Concordia (disp. 10). that if one does what one can by merely natural powers, God never denies actual grace, and at last bestows sanctifying grace; not that man may prepare himself positively for grace, but he prepares himself negatively by not placing obstacles to it and by removing impediments. [30] And in order to avoid Semi-Pelagianism, Molina declares that God confers actual grace and subsequently habitual grace, not on account of the merit of a natural act, but on account of the covenant between God and Christ from the beginning. Christ indeed presented His merits to the Father, and the Father promises that He will bestow grace upon anyone who does what is possible to his natural powers or who uses well the goods of nature. III. The doctrine of St. Thomas, as is clear from the last lines of the article and from the answer to the second objection, is that fallen man cannot prepare himself for habitual grace except by the help of prevenient actual grace, and "when it is said that man does what he can, the meaning is that this is within the power of man, as he is moved by God. " These words in the answer to the second objection are contrary to the opinion proposed subsequently by Molina. Stated more briefly the thesis of St. Thomas is: Fallen man can in no way dispose himself either for habitual or for actual grace by his natural powers alone. Scriptural proof. It is proved from the authority of Scripture in the argument Sed contra: "No man can come to Me, except the Father, who hath sent Me, draw him" (John 6:44). But if man could prepare himself, there would be no need of his being drawnby another. "Convert us. OLord, to Thee, and we shall be converted" (Lam. 5:21). See also Jer. 31:18. "The will is prepared by the Lord" (Prov. 8:35, according to the Septuagint, but the Hebrew text is not so clear). St. Augustine here and there puts it forward against the Semi-Pelagians, and it is quoted by the Council of Orange, Denz., no. 177). "Without Me you can do nothing" (John 15:15); therefore neither can one prepare oneself for grace, since that is doing something ordained to salvation. "Who hath first given to Him, and recompense shall be made him ? For of Him, and by Him, and in Him, are all things" (Rom. 11:35 f. ). According to the contrary opinion a man could reply: I first gave him my effort and disposition, "Who distinguisheth thee?" (I Cor. 4:7. ) Man may answer: my strwing. "What hast thou that thou hast not received ?" {ibid. ) Man may reply: I have my effort 29 The Semi-Pelagians held that the preparation for grace could be made naturally in three ways: 1) by positively disposing oneself for grace; 2) by meriting it. al least de congruo', or 3) by asking it through prayer. 30 Molina holds: To him who does what in him lies by Iris natural powers in easier matters, and by the powers of medicinal grace (which is natural from the standpoint of its being) in more difficult matters, God does not deny actual grace and. eventually, He grants sanctifying grace, on account of the covenant entered into with Christ. Molina does not give sufficient attention to the fact that man alone, by himself, can set up some obstacle, but he cannot, by himself, avoid setting up an obstacle, for this latter is a good act proceeding from the source of all good: "What hast thou that thou hast not received?" and my disposition. "You have not chosen Me: but I have chosen you" (John 15:16). The Semi-Pelagians would say: I chose Thee first by disposing myself for grace. This text is addressed to the apostles, of course, but in that they are the friends of God, and therefore it also applies to other friends of God. The Council of Orange (can. 3. Denz., no. 176). according to the obvious meaning of the words, declares that all preparation for grace is of itself prevenient grace; there is no reference to a covenant entered into between God the Father and Christ. Read canons 3. 4. 5. Likewise the Council of Trent (Sess. VI, chap. 5, Denz. 797. and chap. 6). St. Augustine (De peccatorum meritis. Bk. I. chap. 22). especially in the three arguments against the Semi-Pelagians, maintained the following. 1. In the affair of salvation nothing at all must be withdrawn from divine grace; but something would be withdrawn if the disposition for grace were not from grace. 2. The Church prays God not only to help those who will and strive after good, but also that those who will it not be made to will it. 3. It is said in II Cor. 3:5: "Not that we arc sufficient to think anything of ourselves, as of ourselves. " But the slightest preparation for grace is a good thought. Therefore. Hence the words of Augustine on St. John, at the beginning of tract 26: "Why does God draw this man and not that man ? Do not attempt to judge if you do not wish to err. " Theological proof. By theological argument St. Thomas thus proves lus thesis in the body of the article in form. Since every agent acts on account of a proportionate end, the order of agents corresponds to the order of ends, and the disposition toward a supernatural end cannot be produced except by God, the supernatural agent. But man prepares himself for grace according as he disposes himself for it as for a proximate supernatural end, and according as he turns to God as to his final supernatural end. Therefore man cannot prepare himself for grace except by the supernatural help of God, moving him. St. Thomas does not fear to repeat this principle often; these repetitions are a kind of leitmotiv in theology, like St. John's often repeated: "Beloved, let us love one another" (I John 4:7). The major of this argument is based on the principle of finality, not that from this metaphysical principle the dogma may be rationally demonstrated, but that the dogma cannot be contrary to the principle of finality. For the corollary of this principle is: the order of agents corresponds to the order of ends; hence it is necessary that man be converted to his final end by the motion of the prime mover, just as the will of the soldier is directed toward striving for victoiy by the motion of the leader of the army, and toward following the standard of some battle by the motion of the commander. Moreover, according to this principle, the disposition toward a supernatural end cannot be produced except by a supernatural agent, that is, except by God according as He moves toward something which exceeds all nature created or capable of being created. The minor of this argument, however, is explained later in more detail, but it is already self-evident (cf. q. 112, a. 3). More briefly, the argument can be stated thus: Every disposition, whether remote or proximate, should have a certain proportion to the form for which it disposes; otherwise it would not dispose for it. But merely natural acts have no proportion with supernatural grace; they do not attain to the life of grace nor do they in any way require it. Therefore man by his own natural powers cannot prepare himself even remotely for grace, without supernatural help; it is not only morally impossible, but physically and absolutely as well. Confirmation. In order to dispose himself, man would at least need to have a good thought from himself. But, according to II Cor. 3:5: "Not that we are sufficient to think anything of ourselves, as of ourselves. " in the order of salvation. Hence, with still greater reason, to desire, ask, merit even de congruo, or dispose ourselves in any way. For merit de congruo already pertains to salvation; it is a right, based on friendship, to a supernatural reward. And if man without grace could pray and thus obtain grace, the first step to salvation would be attributable to nature. Hence this is condemned by the Council of Orange, c. 7. The whole proof, therefore, is reducible to the infinite distance between the order of nature and the order of grace, since grace as essentially supernatural surpasses the powers and the requirements of any intellectual nature, created or capable of creation. God from all eternity might at any time create angels of greater and ever greater perfection so that they would have an ever loftier natural intelligence and an ever more steadfast will; but never could these superior angels naturally dispose themselves for grace, which is of a higher order. Thus the imagination may become ever better endowed in its own order but it will never arrive at the dignity of the intellect; thus the sides of a polygon inscribed in a circle may be ever multiplied but, however small each side, it will never be equivalent to a point. With still greater reason, when it is a question of the impossibility of disposing oneself naturally for the life of grace, natural good works can be ever increased, but they will never amount to a disposition proportionate to grace, which is essentially supernatural· whether for man or for any angel capable of being created, and they can always be created with greater perfection, since no limit of possibility can be named which would exhaust divine omnipotence. How beautiful· how wonderful; how great a light there is in this doctrine! "All bodies, the firmament and the stars, the earth and its kingdoms, are not worth the least of spirits, for it is conscious of all that and of itself; and bodies are conscious of nothing. All bodies and all spirits together and all their productions are not worth the slightest movement of charity, for that is of an infinitely higher order" (Pascal· Thoughts). Confirmation from the refutation of the objections. First objection. But it is said in Zach. 1:3: "Turn ye to Me... and I will turn to you. " Reply. It is indeed prescribed for man that he turn to God freely, but the free will cannot turn to God unless God Himself converts it to Himself, according to the words of Jer. 31:18: "Convert me, and I shall be converted. " Likewise Augustine and the Council of Trent (Sess. VI. chap. 6; Denz., no. 797). Second objection. But it is generally said that to him who does what he can God does not deny grace. Reply. Contrary to what Molina says, to him who does what he can, with God's help; and it is a question of supernatural help granted through Christ the Redeemer, since the following words of Christ are quoted: "Without Me ye can do nothing. " Nor does natural help suffice to produce a disposition which is supernatural in form, since the order of agents should correspond to the order of ends. And God, as author of nature, cannot move one to a supernatural end. Third objection. But this would be an infinite process, for man would need some grace to prepare himself for grace, and so on indefinitely. Reply. A disposition is required only for habitual grace, for every form requires a disposition capable of receiving it. But for actual grace a disposition is not required, since a disposition is not necessary for yet another disposition. Fourth objection. But in Prov. 16:1 it is written: "It is the part of man to prepare the soul and of the Lord to govern the tongue"; and further: "The heart of man disposes the way. but it is the Lord who directs his steps. " Reply. Certainly, because man does this through his free will· but he does not therefore do it without the help of God moving and drawing him. The meaning of Holy Scripture here is that it does not suffice to consider what thou wilt say or do, unless God directs the tongue and the work so that thou mayest succeed. And this is also a very common saying: Man proposes and God disposes. St. Thomas teaches this doctrine in several other places as well. (Cf. Quodl., la, a. 7; in Ep. ad Rom., c. 10, lect. 3; III C. Gentes, chap. 150: Deverit., q. 24, a. 15. ) Doubt. Whether according to St. Thomas, following the doctrine which he maintains in la Ilae, q. 89, a. 6, to all who arrive at the use of reason sufficient help is given for fulfilling the precept, there and then urgent, of loving God efficaciously above all things. Reply. The Salmanticenses reply in the affirmative (In lam Ilae, q. 89, a. 6, no. 65); God gives efficacious help only to those whom He at the same time decided to justify and with the aforesaid efficacious help He gives them sanctifying grace and explicit faith concerning the things which are necessary as means essential to salvation. Whether this sufficient help which is then given to all is supernatural. It is at least supernatural modally through the merits of Christ; but it may also be said that it is supernatural substantially since it gives the proximate power of accomplishing an efficacious act of the love of God above all things, beyond the powers of fallen nature. This supernatural help should result in a certain supernatural enlightenment for the intellect and, if man would not resist this enlightenment, he would receive the grace of faith with respect to the things necessary to salvation. (Cf. below, what is said on justification and the salutary but not meritorious acts which precede it; also Billuart, De gratia, diss. VII, a. 4, nos. 2, 3. ) It should be remarked that Quesnel's proposition was condemned: "No graces are given except through faith" (Denz., no. 1376); "Faith is the first grace and the source of all the others" (Denz., no. 1377); "The first grace which God grants to the sinner is the remission of sins" (Denz., no. 1378); likewise the Synod of Pistoia was condemned, denying grace preceding good will and faith. Concerning the Molinist interpretation of the common axiom: "to him who does what he can, God does not refuse grace. " Cf. Concordia, disp. X, latest edition, Paris, pp. 43 and 564: "God always confers the helps of prevenient grace on him who strives with natural powers to accomplish what in him lies. " Molina, as we have said maintained that: to him who does what he can by his natural powers alone, God never denies actual grace, and later He gives habitual grace. To avoid Semi-Pelagianism, he continues, 1. claiming that this is done not on account of the value of a natural good work, but for the sake of a covenant entered into between God and Christ the Redeemer, a covenant for thus certainly conferring grace; and 2. claiming that man thus naturally prepares himself negatively only, that is, by not raising obstacles, not sinning at least for some little time; but always, or as it were infallibly, actual grace is then conferred upon him. What is to be thought of this covenant and of this natural, negative preparation ? In regard to the covenant, we may say with the Thomists that it lacks a basis in tradition; on the contrary, it seems to be opposed to the testimony of tradition and to the principles of sound theology. 1. This pact has no basis either in Scripture or in the councils or in the Fathers. Hence it is clearly fictitious. Certainly the Council of Orange does not speak of it, although it would have been most useful for recalling the Semi-Pelagians to the faith, had this theory been true. The Semi-Pelagians would very easily have admitted it, since they did not deny Redemption through Christ nor did they deny that the primary grace was conferred on account of the merits of Christ upon those who prepared themselves naturally for it. The Semi-Pelagians did not contend that the primary? grace was given on account of natural merit, but by the occasion of natural good works. Neither does Pius IX (Denz., nos. 1648, 1677) refer to this covenant. [31] As a matter of fact, Valentia, S.J., attempted to demonstrate this pact at the Congregatio de Auxiliis from Augustine (The City of God, Bk. XIX, chap. 13) but to obtain this proof, in reading the text of Augustine he changed the particle scilicet to et. Immediately, however, Thomas de Lemos, recognizing the text of Augustine, replied: "The text is not being rendered correctly, " and taking up Augustine's book he read the text as it was. (Cf. Billuart, d. III. a. 7, and Serry, Histoire de la Congregatio de auxiliis, Bk. III. chap. 5. ) It is said in Scripture and tradition only that 31 Pius IX declares (Denz., no. 1677): "Those who labor under invincible ignorance in regard to our most holy religion, and who obs conscientiously (this presupposes the help of grace) the natural law whose precepts are inscribed by God in all hearts, and are rea< obey God, can lead an honorable, righteous life, by virtue of the operation of divine light and grace, and arrive at eternal life. " Pius 13 no recourse to the Molinistic pact, but speaks as does St. Thomas. God wills the sah ation of all men. that Christ died for alf and that, accordingly, graces sufficient for salvation are conferred upon all adults. 2. Not only is this covenant not affirmed by tradition, but it seems to be contrary to the Council of Orange (can. 6, Denz.. no. 179) which condemned anyone who should say that, "Without the grace of God, mercy is bestowed upon those who believe, will and desire it. " But supposing the aforesaid covenant, the mercy of Christ and of God would thus be conferred upon men naturally desiring it. (Likewise can. 4. ) [32] 3. This pact is opposed to the teaching of Augustine, who declared against the Pelagians (De peccatorum meritis, Bk. I, chap. 22) that there are among infidels and sinners some who observe many precepts of the law and are less wicked, more modest, temperate, and merciful, and yet grace passes them by and converts the most infamous: in other words, those who are converted are not always those who do more naturally good works. Moreover, according to St. Augustine, the judgment of God is inscrutable, for He draws one and does not draw another; as he says in regard to St. John (at the beginning of tract 26): "Why does He draw this man and not that one ? Do not attempt to judge if you do not wish to err. " St. Thomas refers to this in la, q. 23, a. 5 ad 3. But assuming the existence of the aforesaid covenant and the resulting law, God's judgment would not be inscrutable, rather could it be easily explained, for indeed God draws this man and not another because this one does what he canby his own powers and the other does not. 4. This pact seems to be contrary' to the principles of sound theology based on revelation. For, according to this hypothesis, man would have something of himself to distinguish him, in w hich he would glory, in other w ords, something ordained to salvation he w ould not receive from God, namely, a good w ork of nature which, according to the law established, would lead to salvation, and to which grace w ould infallibly be attached. Hence it is incompatible that Christ should merit the establishment of this law' on the part of God the father, by which the reason for grace would be destroyed. For if this pact w ere formed and this law established, grace would be given on account of works, and thus w ould no longer be grace, prevenient grace would be anticipated by the free will, the first place would be given to man, the last place to God. and thus the doctrine of grace defended by St. Augustine w ould be overthrow n. With this law in effect, a natural good w ork possesses some proportion and some right to the help of grace. All these suppositions seem to be contrary' to the words of St. Paul (I Cor. 4:7): "Who distinguisheth thee ? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received? And if thou hast received, why dost thou glory, as if thou hadst not received it ?" Particularly opposed to these w ords is the teaching of Molina which holds that man thus naturally disposes himself for grace with the aid of simultaneous natural concurrence only determinable by human liberty alone. But this doctrine is not very much developed by admitting general, indifferent premotion, ultimately determinable by man alone, since one man would thus distinguish himself from another who was not converted. Moreover, as we have said, intrinsically efficacious, predetermining premotion of a natural order does not suffice as a preparation for grace; the supernatural help of grace is required, because the order of agents should correspond to the order of ends. Here indeed the end, whether proximate (grace) or remote (glory), is supernatural. It is therefore not to be wondered at that the French clergy, in a general assembly, in 1700. condemned this teaching in regard to a covenant, declaring that "it restores Semi-Pelagianism, merely changing its language.... The pact which is held to exist between God and Christ, is an audacious, erroneous invention brought forth, not only under the silence of Holy Scripture and the tradition of the Holy Fathers, but even under their contradiction. " (Cf. Billuart. De gratia, diss. Ill, a. 7. ) 32 According to the Council of Orange (can. 4. Denz.. no. 177): "If anyone maintains that God waits upon our will in order to cleanse us from sin, and does not rather acknow ledge that even our willing to be cleansed is brought about in us through the infusion and operation of the Holy Ghost, such a one is resisting the same Holy Ghost. " And yet, according to Molina's theory'. God w aits upon our w ill, that is. our natural effort, which He foresees by scientia media, and wliich is produced simultaneously w ith only the concurrence of God, before the conferring of prevenient actual grace. Thus this natural effort precedes prevenient grace itself, and thus it seems to be the first step to salvation, wliich is therefore natural. On the contrary, it is God who knocks first, according to the words of the Apocalypse (3:20): "I stand at the gate and knock. " What, then, is to be said of the negative natural preparation, that is, not setting up obstacles to grace, which being accomplished. God infallibly confers grace, according to Molina ? Reply. 1. Not to set up any obstacles at all is to observe the whole natural law, avoiding every sin against it, and this cannot be done without healing grace, as we have already shown. 2. Not to set up obstacles in some respects, observing certain precepts, avoiding certain sins, with general natural help, does not infallibly dispose one for grace; since, as we asserted with Augustine and as experience demonstrates, some men observe many commandments, and yet grace is denied them which, at one time or other, is granted to the most profligate, who have no regard for any law. according to the words of Isaias (65:1 as quoted in Rom. 10:20: "I was found by them that did not seek Me: I appeared openly to them that asked not after Me. " 3. Nowhere is there a basis for this principle: upon him who does not setup obstacles to grace through his powers of nature alone, God infallibly confers grace. 4. All the aforesaid objections reappear; thus it would no longer be inscrutable why God confers grace upon one and not upon another; one could distinguish himself and glory over another; the beginning of salvation would not be the compassion of God alone, but the willing of man as well; and other conclusions opposed to the words of St. Paul: "It is not of him that willeth. nor of him that runneth, but of God that showeth mercy" (Rom. 9:16). How. then, are we to understand the common axiom: to him who does what he can, God does not deny grace ? I answer as St. Thomas here interprets it (q. 109. a. 6 ad 2), namely, "to him who does what he can, with the help of actual grace. God does not deny further grace. " We are concerned with supernatural help, which comes from Christ the Redeemer, for the words of Christ are quoted here: "Without Me you can do nothing. " And (q. 112. a. 3) St. Thomas shows that this preparation, since it is from God moving supernaturally, has an infallible connection with the infusion of sanctifying grace. Hence, as Father Hugon indicates (De gratia, p. 267), this axiom is threefold: 1. the necessity of a certain preparation for justification on the part of an adult man. 2. the infallibility of its connection with sanctifying grace. 3. the gratuity of justification, which is accomplished by God alone. "No one can come to Me unless the Father who sent Me draw him. " Therefore the meaning is: to him who does what he canby the power of actual grace. God does not deny sanctifying grace. Tins opinion is also held by Cardinal Billot, but with indifferent concurrence. The axiom thus explained is only the theological formula of the dogma of God's will to save. For, once it is admitted that God wills the salvation of all, it follows that sufficient grace necessary for salvation is conferred upon all; and if man does not resist this grace, he will receive a higher grace and thus arrive at justification. Man indeed resists by himself, but not to resist is already a good and proceeds from God preserving him in good and helping him, for at that moment God can permit resistance, as happens in the case of many. (Cf. Council of Trent, Sess. VI, chap. 5, Denz.. no. 797. ) "Hence. " says the Council, "when it is written in Holy Scripture: 'Turn ye to Me,... and I will turn to you' (Zach. 1:3). we are reminded of our liberty; when we reply: 'Convert us, O Lord, to Thee, and we shall be converted' (Lam. 5:21). we acknowledge that we are anticipated by the grace of God. " Corollary'. The real clarity of the principles of superior reasoning leads to a translucent obscurity of mysteries, while, on the contrary', the false clarity of the fiction of inferior reasoning, withdrawing from the principles of superior reasoning, shuns supernatural mysteries, denying their sublimity. This is particularly evident in the present question; thus, the true clarity of the principle, that the order of agents corresponds to the order of ends, leads to the translucent obscurity of the mystery: "No one can come to Me, unless the Father, who sent Me. draw him. " This obscurity is fully preserved by the contemplation of Augustine, when he says: "Why does He draw this man and not that one? Do not attempt to judge if you do not wish to err. " And the mysteries, which are the object of contemplation, are all the more obscure the higher they are. with this obscurity which is not incoherence or absurdity below the level of understanding, but light inacessible beyond understanding, with respect to us who are wayfarers. Therefore it is said that Thomism fears neither logic nor mystery, but. fearlessly following the logic of first principles, arrives at the highest and most profoundly inscrutable my steries, which are the true object of infused contemplation. On the other hand, the false clarity of the fictions of inferior reasoning is evident in these words: to him who does what he can by his natural powers alone, God does not refuse grace; in other words, man can naturally prepare himself for supernatural grace. But this assertion of inferior reasoning withdraws from the principle: the order of agents should correspond to the order of ends, and a supernatural agent to a supernatural end. And thus withdrawing from this principle, this false clarity ignores the inscrutable mystery: "No one can come to Me, unless the Father, who sent Me, draw him. " Nor indeed is it true any longer to say: "Why does He draw one man and not another ? Do not attempt to judge if you do not wish to err. " But on the contrary, all things are clearly explained by the fiction: "this man is drawn by God because he disposed himself naturally. " The mystery is removed, and with it is taken away the highest object of contemplation; we descend to an inferior order of reasoning by rational subtleties, and inordinately so. which leads not to the obscurity of a mystery, but to the absurd denial of a principle: that the order of agents should correspond to the order of ends, every agent acts on account of a proportionate end. Hence false clarity must not be confused with true clarity. The purification of the spirit by the gift of understanding dispels such deceptive clearness and purifies "from phantasms and errors" (Ila Ilae, q 8, a. 7). REFUTATION OF THE PRINCIPAL OBJECTIONS OF THE MOLINISTS 1. In Holy Scripture many are mentioned who attained to grace by a natural good work, such as the Egyptian midwives moved by natural compassion for the Hebrew children, Rahab the harlot receiving and not exposing the scouts sent by God, Zachaeus welcoming Christ to his house. Cornelius practicing almsgiving and prayer before he believed in Christ. Reply. These natural good works do not exclude the necessity of interior grace, but remain inadequate unless God disposes the heart interiorly by His grace; in other words, these naturally good works as such do not infallibly prepare for grace, and it is erroneous to declare that "to him who of himself does natural works. God does not deny grace. " Moreover, as Augustine says, among infidels and sinners, those who are converted are often not those who at first were less wicked. And at the Council of Orange (can. 25) it was stated that in the good thief, in Zachaeus and Cornelius, their pious disposition to believe was the result of a gift of God. But it is true that the occasions by which some seem to reach grace were procured for them by the special favor of providence disposing external matters in such a way that they would combine to lead these rather than others to grace. Thus in the cases of Zachaeus and Cornelius. I insist. St. Paul says (I Tim. 1:13): "I obtained the mercy of God, because I did it ignorantly in unbelief. " Therefore he disposed himself negatively infallibly. Reply. Ignorance is alleged not as a negative and infallible disposition for grace, but as matter more appropriately calling forth mercy, since indigence as such is involuntary, such as ignorance, and for this reason induces mercy. On the other hand, sin. inasmuch as it is voluntary, does not call forth mercy, but avenging justice, and this all the more so in proportion to its gravity. Thus St. Augustine explains in his eighth, ninth, and tenth sermons on the words of the Apostle. The meaning is the same as when Christ says: "Father, forgive them for they know not what they do. " Estius is also thus interpreted. I insist. But at times Cy ril of Jerusalem, Chrysostom, and Clement of Alexandria, quoted in this regard by Billuart, seem to teach that grace does not anticipate our wills but awaits them. Reply. I. [33] In these quotations they are speaking either of habitual grace or of the increase of actual grace for more perfect works, but they are certainly not speaking of the first actual grace, through which a beginning of good will is attained. Hence their meaning is: God awaits not our bare will, but our will supported by grace. These Fathers also deny that this first grace is an imposition of necessity, in opposition to the Manichaeans who would deprive man of free will (cf. la, q. 23. a. I ad I). This interpretation is confirmed by the fact that the aforesaid Fathers teach in various places the Catholic dogma on prevenient grace, when they explain the words of St. Paul: "What hast thou that thou hast not received? What then distinguisheth thee ?" Nor is it remarkable if they at times spoke less accurately on the need for prevenient grace, when the Pelagian heresy had not yet broken out flagrantly, particularly since they desired to defend free will against the Manichaeans. At that time no one was attacking grace. St. Augustine replied similarly in his De praedestinatione sanctorum (chap. 14). 331 can't find reply 2 either [Ed.] I insist. But St. Thomas himself says (Ila. d. 5, q. I, a. I): "For the eliciting of an act of conversion free will suffices, whichprepares and disposes itself for obtaining grace through this act. " Similarly (Ila, d. 28. q. I, a. 4) he declares: "Since the preparation made for grace is not by acts which are commensurate to grace itself with an equality of proportion, as merit is commensurate to its reward, therefore it is not necessary that the acts by which man prepares himself for grace should exceed human nature. " Reply. I. [34] If such were the meaning of these passages quoted, we should have to admit that St. Thomas had subsequently retracted his own words, changing the opinion which he had held when he was younger. He wrote on the Sentences at Paris when he was only twenty-five years of age. 2. But St. Thomas did not change his opinion, for in the Commentary on the Sentences he rejects the opinion of certain others who held that man. to prepare himself for habitual grace, requires a habitual supernatural light, preamble to sanctifying grace. (Cf. II, d. 28, q. I, a. 4. ) St. Thomas denies this, maintaining that this would go on into infinity, but he does not exclude actual grace which he clearly affirms in the Summa and in Quodl., I, a. 7, even more clearly: "It pertains to the Pelagian error to say that man can prepare himself for grace without the help of divine grace. " (Likewise la, q. 23, a. 5. on the beginning of good works. ) Indeed certain theologians attacking this opinion fell into the opposite excess and thus prepared the way for Molina. Nor did St. Thomas say that a preparation is not required "proportionate to grace, " but proportionate in the way in which merit is commensurate with reward. This is true since merit demands nature elevated by sanctifying grace; merit is a right to a supernatural reward. (Cf. Quodl., 1, a. 7 ad 1. ) The distance is greater between the sinner and the just man than between the just and the blessed, for grace is the seed of glory, but nature is not realty the seed of grace. I insist. But of what use, then, are natural good works performed at the dictate of reason alone without any grace ? Reply. They are meritorious de congruo of temporal good, to the extent that it is appropriate for divine liberality in consideration of them, to grant certain temporal benefits. Hence Christ says: "They have received their reward" (Matt. 6:2). And on the other hand, good works done outside of charity, but with the help of actual grace, are a disposition to habitual grace; St. Thomas refers to them in IV Sent., q. 14, a. 4. and also in De veritate, q. 14, a. II ad I, when he says: "If a person brought up in the wilderness follows the guidance of reason (with actual grace), it can be held for a certainty that God will either reveal to him by inspiration the things that are necessary to believe or will send some preacher of the faith to him, as he sent St. Peter to Cornelius. " I insist. Nevertheless, natural good works done without the help of actual grace seem to be at least a negative disposition to actual grace. Reply. An infallible negative disposition, excluding even impediment to grace: denied. A fallible negative disposition, excluding some impediment: let it pass. I insist. But man of himself can refrain from setting up an obstacle, at least at the moment when the grace is offered to him. Reply. At that moment, of himself, with general concurrence which is in some way special for this individual, he can do so partially: granted. Completely: denied; that would be loving God the author of nature above all tilings. I insist. St. Thomas (Contra Gentes. Bk. Ill, q. 159) declares: "Fallen man can hinder or not hinder the reception of grace. " Reply. Not hinder, in part (and this with the concurrence of God preserving Him in good whereas He could permit sin): granted; totally: denied, because of himself he cannot avoid every sin, observing every precept of the natural law (cf. ibid., c. 160). [35] 341 can't find reply 2 either [Ed.] 3~ Man alone of himself can resist grace (and this is sin permitted by God), but "not to resist grace" is itself a good which proceeds from God who preserves him in good whereas He might have permitted resistance. Cf. our La predestination des saints et lagrace. 1936, p. 381. Another objection. In la, q. 62, a. 6, it is taught that God conferred grace and glory upon the angels in proportion to their nature; hence there is no incompatibility in His conferring grace upon men who do what they can by natural powers alone. Reply. St. Thomas himself replies to this objection {ibid., ad 2): "The acts of a rational creature are from itself; but the nature is immediately from God. Hence it seems rather that grace is given according to the rank of the (angelic) nature than according to its works. " For thus man would single out himself, and God would be moved objectively by another, which is not the case when He gives grace to the angels at the instant of their creation according to the quantity of their nature, which He alone created. To the same effect it is said that "it is reasonable for the angels, who have a better nature, to be converted to God even more powerful!} and efficaciously, " since in them nothing retarded the movement of the intellect and will. There is, moreover, an analogy between converted angels and men. for "according to the intensity of their conversion is greater grace given. " I insist. But the disposition can be of an inferior order, as, for example, the disposition of the embryo to a spiritual soul. Reply. But then they belong to the same nature, which is not true of grace. Objection. God owes it to Himself to bestow His gifts upon those who are more worthy. But he is more worthy who does many natural good works of himself than he who does less. Therefore God should confer grace upon the former. Reply. I deny the minor: he is not more worthy because natural works have no proportion with grace; they are of an inferior order. I insist. Nevertheless he who sets up less impediments is less indisposed. Reply. Let it pass. But he is not more disposed and worthy; thus a worm and a dog are certainly unequal; yet the dog is not more disposed to rationality. Therefore it is not unusual for God to draw to Himself those who are worse. Thus we are back again at what we said at the end of the exposition of this thesis. ARTICLE VII. WHETHER MAN CAN RISE FROM SIN WITHOUT THE HELP OF GRACE State of the question. This article, following upon the preceding ones, may seem a useless repetition. Such is not the case, however, for, as Cajetan remarks: "thus far St. Thomas was dealing with the necessity’ of grace for doing good; now he is concerned with evil, " and in the last two articles with the necessity of grace for the man who is already’ just. What is meant by rising from sin ? It is not the same as ceasing from the act of sin, as Protestants claim, but it is man being restored to w hat, by sinning, he had forfeited. Now, by sinning, man incurs a threefold loss: the stain (habitual sin. privation of the ornament of grace), the incurring of punishment, and the decrease of the natural inclination to virtue, as stated previously (q. 85-87). The reply to the question thus posed is negative; that is certain, so that Pelagius himself did not deny it but only insisted that grace should be bestowed on account of merits. The answer is of faith, defined at the Council of Orange, can. 4. (Denz.. no. 177) also can. 14 and 19; and at the Council of Trent. Sess. VI, can. I (Denz.. no. 811), can. 3 (Denz.. no. 813). The teaching of the Fathers is clear; cf. the words of Augustine quoted in the argument Sed contra; otherwise "Christ died for nothing, " if man can rise from sin without the help of grace. Tliis conclusion is proved by theological argument as follows: To rise from sin is for man to be restored and liberated from the evils which he incurred by sin. But by sin he incurred a threefold loss which cannot be repaired except by grace. Therefore. The minor is proved thus: 1. The stain is a privation of the ornament of grace, therefore it cannot be repaired except by grace itself. 2. The decrease in the inclination of the will toward virtue cannot be repaired unless God draws the will to Himself. 3. The incurring of punishment cannot be remitted except by God against whom the offense was committed. Nevertheless there can be an imperfect resurrection without habitual grace, by actual grace which is present in attrition when the sinner aspires after reconciliation. Cf. on this subject the sixty-fourth proposition of Bains (Denz., no. 1064). ARTICLE VIII. WHETHER WITHOUT GRACE MAN CAN AVOID SIN State of the question. From the second article wherein it is said that fallen man can, with the natural concurrence of God, perform some good works, it is to be supposed likewise that with this natural concurrence he can, for a certain length of time, avoid sin and overcome slight temptations. For it is not necessary that he should continually sin by act. by a sin of commission, such as blasphemy, or of omission, such as never praying when he ought to pray, since the good of reason is not entirely extinct in him. As a matter of fact, this natural concurrence, although it is in a way due to human nature in general, may, as we have said, be called gratuitous in a certain sense with respect to this man to whom it is given here and now rather than to another in whom God permits sin; from this standpoint it may be called grace, broadly speaking. This observation is necessary in order to reconcile various texts of the councils and of the Fathers on this question. Hence the problem, properly stated, is: whether man without grace, strictly speaking, can, over a long period of time, avoid mortal sins. Cf. above. la Ilae, q. 109, a. 2 ad 2, and De veritate, q. 24 a. 14 ad 2 and 3. That such is the proper statement of the question is evident from the objections or difficulties which are raised against the first article: it seems that man can, without grace, avoid sin: 1. because no one sins in that which is unavoidable; 2. because otherwise the sinner would be blamed without cause, if he could not avoid sin; 3. because a person who sins does not cease to be a man, and it is within his power to choose good or evil; for human nature after the fall is not totally corrupt. However, as stated in the argument Sed contra, St. Augustine declared that: "Whoever denies that we ought to pray, lest we enter into temptation, ought to be removed from the ears of all and anathematized by the mouth of all, I have no doubt. " In the body of the article there are two principal conclusions, which, all things considered, can and ought to be proposed thus: 1. concerning fallen man avoiding mortal sin; 2. concerning the just man avoiding venial sins. The first conclusion, which is proved in the second part of the article is as follows: Fallen man being in the state of mortal sin, cannot, without the addition of healing, habitual grace, continually avoid all mortal sin against the natural law and overcome all temptations. In this regard, St. Thomas seems to correct what he had said in 11 Sent., d. 28, q. I, a. 2. 1. This is proved first of all from Holy Scripture: "By Thee I shall be delivered from temptation" (Ps. 17:30). "Being pushed I was overturned that I might fall: but the Lord supported me" (Ps. 117:13). "Unhappy man that I am, who shall deliver me from the body of this death ? (And he replies): The grace of God, by Jesus Christ" (Rom. 7:24f. ). This is true with still greater reason of fallen man before justification. "And God is faithful, who will not suffer you to be tempted above that which you are able: but will make also with temptation issue, that you may be able to bear it" (I Cor. 10:13). Likewise the Council of Neocaesarea (chap. II) against the Pelagians condemned the following proposition of Pelagius: "Our victory is not by the help of God. " Similarly the Council of Milevum (Denz.. nos. 103 f. ), Pope St. Celestine (Denz., no. 132), and the Council of Orange against the Semi-Pelagians (Denz.. nos. 184, 186, 192. 194). 2. The conclusion is proved, secondly, from theological argument which is the corollary of articles 3 and 4 (explained here in the second part of the article): fallen man cannot, without healing grace, efficaciously love God the author of nature above all tilings nor observe all the precepts of the natural law; therefore neither can he avoid every mortal sin, for they are committed by transgression of the commandments. The basis of this argument lies in the fact that man in the state of mortal sin has his will turned away from even his natural final end; therefore he is already inclined toward some mortal sins. In order, then, continually to avoid all mortal sins and overcome all temptations, he must have his will directed toward his final end. adhering to God so firmly that he will not be separated from Him for the sake of anything created; cf. the end of the body of the article. [36] In short, an infirm nature cannot efficiently produce an act of healthy nature. St. Thomas says that this requires healing grace, that is, habitual grace; for without it man is not firmly established in good dispositions with regard to his final end. Three principal objections are made to this first conclusion. First objection. Some pagans have withstood very serious temptations for the sake of virtue. Reply. As we have already said, perhaps they did so from a human motive of glory or pride, and, in that case, without the special help of God, or else they did so for love of virtue, in which case it was not without the special help of God. (See Augustine, Bk. IV against Julian, chap. 3. ) Second objection, which St. Thomas mentions first as follows: if man in the state of mortal sin cannot avoid sin, then by sinning he does not sin, for sin is always avoidable. Reply (ad I): "Man (in the state of mortal sin) can avoid individual acts of (mortal) sin. but not all, except by means of grace. Nevertheless man is not excused, since the fault is his own that he does not prepare himself to possess grace... "; mother words, grace is offered to him and is not lacking except through his fault. (Cf. above, a. 4 ad 2. ) Third objection. But then it would follow that man in the state of mortal sin is bound to repent instantly for otherwise he will always be in danger of committing sin again. Reply. He is bound to repent instantly when the danger of sinning is certain and definite; otherwise there is no grave obligation to repent instantly. Second conclusion. The just man, by the ordinary assistance of grace without any special privilege, can continually avoid all mortal sins, but not however, over a long period of time, all venial sins, although he can avoid individual venial sins. The first part of this conclusion is that the just man can, without very special help, continually avoid all mortal sins (to avoid them actually and continually until death, however, requires the gift of final perseverance, as we shall explain in article 10). In support of this first part of the conclusion the following scriptural texts are quoted: "If anyone love Me, he will keep My word, and My Father will love him, and We will come to him, and make Our abode with him" (John 14:23). "My grace is sufficient for thee" (II Cor. 12:9). Also the Council of Trent (Denz., no. 804): "For God will notforsake those who are once justified by His grace, unless He is first abandoned by them"; cf. below, q. 112, a. 3. The theological argument is the opposite of the reasoning in the preceding conclusion: since the just man firmly adheres to his final end, therefore he can avoid all mortal sin; he has even the proximate power to do so; whether he actually perseveres or not is another matter. Neither does the just man actual!) avoid sins of omission unless he performs a good work, with the help of actual grace. And that he should actually persevere in the state of grace until death, is still another question (cf. a. 10, and q. 114, a. 9). The second part of this conclusion is as follows: The just man cannot avoid all venial sins collectively. It is proven fromHoly Scripture: "There is no man who sinnethnot" (III Kings 8:46). "There is no just man upon earth, that doth 36 Here the words of Aristotle are cited: "In unexpected circumstances a man acts according to a preconceived objective and a pre-exi habit"; hence one who is in the state of mortal sin cannot long remain without mortal sin, especially in sudden temptation. Even should wish to act rationally, he cannot long maintain this intention on account of his habitually bad disposition. good, and sinneth not" (Ecclus. 7:21). "Inmany things we all offend" (Jas. 3:2). "If we say that we have no sin. we deceive ourselves, and the truth is not in us" (I John 1:8). This second part of this conclusion is also declared by the Council of Milevum (can. 6 and 7, Denz., nos. 106. 107) and of Trent (Sess. VI, can. 23, Denz., no. 833). where it was stated that it was the special privilege of the Blessed Virgin Mary that she could avoid all venial sin. Likewise, against the Beghards and several propositions of Michael Molinos (from 55 to 63, Denz., nos. 471, 127583). The second theological argument for this conclusion is proved in the body of the argument as follows: Although sanctifying grace heals a man with respect to his spirit, there still remains a disorder of the sensitive appetite, so that inordinate movements often arise. But allowing that his reason can repress individual movements (thus they have an element of involuntary' act) yet not all, because while he is endeavoring to resist one. perhaps another will arise and also because the reason cannot always be vigilant. In other words, the reason itself can be watchful to avoid some inordinate movement, but not all. But in order that this movement be voluntary it is essential that the reason have the power and duty' of considering this movement in individual cases. To continue in goodness without venial sin presents great difficulty the surmounting of which requires a very special grace, by which the instability of the will is stabilized, infirmity healed, weariness refreshed, and disgust overcome. It is a disputed question in mystical theology whether the soul that arrives at transforming union can continually avoid all venial sins collectively. It is admitted that it can avoid all fully deliberate venial sins, but not all semi­ deliberate ones, except while it is under the influence of the actual grace of union. But this actual union is not absolutely continuous, saving always the exception of the Blessed Virgin Mary. (Cf. St. Theresa. Interior Castle, Seventh Mansion, chap. 4) The fact remains that resisting sufficient grace is an evil, and man is sufficient unto himself to do so; but not resisting grace is a good, which proceeds from God, the source of every good. ARTICLE IX. WHETHER THE JUST MAN CAN PERFORM GOOD WORKS (AVAILING TO SALVATION) AND AVOID SIN WITHOUT ACTUAL GRACE The state of the question appears from the objections at the beginning of the article. Some hold with Molina [37] that natural concurrence suffices (cf. Hugon, De gratia, p. 282). St. Thomas' answer is: The just man needs the help of actual grace to act aright supernaturally. 1. This is proved from authority; Augustine is quoted in the argument Sed contra, which should be read. a) Holy Scripture: "As the branch cannot bear fruit of itself, unless it abide in the vine, so neither can you, unless you abide in Me" (John 15:4); as the branch cannot bear fruit without a continual infusion from the vine, neither can the just man without a continual infusion of Christ. Therefore does He say: "Without Me ye can do nothing, " and "You must pray always. " (Cf. Council of Orange, can. 10, Denz.. no. 183. ) b) Pope Zozimus (Epist. tractoria, PL, XX, 693, quoted by Denz., nos. 135 ff. ) says: "Therefore our aid and our protector should be appealed to in all acts, causes, thoughts, and movements. " Also Council of Orange (can. 10 and 25, Denz., nos. 183, 200) and Pope Celestine I (Denz., no. 132). c) Council of Trent (Denz., no. 809): "Since indeed this same Christ Jesus, as head in the members and as the vine in the branches, continually infuses power into justified souls, which power always precedes, accompanies, and 37 Molina, Concordia, q. 14, a. 13. disp. 8, p. 36; also quoted by Billot. De virt. infusis, 1905. p. 176. follows their good works, and without which they cannot be pleasing to God or meritorious in any way. " [38] Also Trent. Sess. VI. can. 2. 2. The theological proof is twofold: by title of dependence and by title of infirmity. a) The first proof is general, by title of dependence. St. Thomas states only the major, but the syllogism is easily completed from what has previously been said, thus: No created thing can proceed to any act except by the power of divine motion (a. I). But for any supernatural act in a just soul a proportionate motion is required, since the order of agents should correspond to the order of ends (as has been said in a. 6). Therefore the just man requires supernatural actual grace for any supernatural act. A certain law of metaphysics, namely, the principle of finality, requires that the introduction of the agent which is to make the transition from potency to act must be of the same order as the act and the end toward which it moves. As stated in the reply to the first objection, even in the state of glory man requires commensurate actual help (cf. ad 2). Hence natural concurrence does not suffice, as Molina would have it (op. cit., p. 36), and as Cardinal Billot sometimes seems to imply (Virt. infusis, 1905. thés. VII. p. 176). Thus even Pesch declares (De gratia, no. 109): "Should it be denied that any supernatural help is required (for any work conducive to salvation), this doctrine is most generally and deservedly rejected by theologians. " Similarly Mazzella (De gratia, disp. II, a. 2, prop. 8, ) declares: "The opinion maintaining the necessity of actual grace for individual acts conducive to salvation, even in a man trained to supernatural habits, seems altogether to be held more consistently, considering the authority of Holy Scripture, the constant teaching of the Fathers, and the decrees of the Church. " b) The second proof from theology is somewhat special: 'by reason of infirmity " applies to the condition of human nature, not as fallen, since we are concerned with a just man. but as not fully regenerated, thus: He who is not perfectly cured requires external assistance in order to act properly. But. allowing that the just man is cured by sanctifying grace, he is still subject to inordinate concupiscence and the obscurity of ignorance. Therefore, for this special reason, the just man requires the help of God to direct and protect him; hence he should say daily: "and lead us not into temptation. " First corollary. This second argument should be distinguished but not separated from the first as if it were interpreted thus: infallibly efficacious concurrence is required only for difficult acts conducive to salvation, but not for easy ones. This is false for, according to the first argument, in every state, general concurrence, at least, is required, but infallibly efficacious concurrence for any good act proposed here and now. [39] 38 This cannot all be regarded as applying to habitual grace, which is not a subsequent but a permanent aid; hence it must refer to actual grace. 39 Cf. De malo, q. 6, a. I ad 3. "In all things divine providence works infallibly, and yet effects to proceed from contingent ca dependently to the extent that God moves all things proportionately, each according to its own mode. " For, as St. Thomas declares (la, q. 19, a. 6 ad 1): "Whatever God wills absolutely is done, even if what He wills antecedently is not done. " But all the good which takes place here and now, even the least, was from eternity the object of the consequent divine will which concerns, as stated in the same place, not the absolute good, as it were abstractly, with which the antecedent will deals, but the good here and now clothed in all its circumstances; forno good comes about except by the intention of the consequent will. And the antecedent will never produces any good, even the slightest and easiest here and now, except by virtue of the accompanying consequent will which is concerned with the good regarded here and now and infallibly produces it. Cf. our La predestination des saints et la grace, 1936, pp. 381-94. In thus explaining metaphysically the distinction of Damascene, reconciling it with the dogmas of divine omnipotence and predestination, St. Thomas shows the supreme, fundamental distinction between Second corollary. In connection with this article Billuart brings forward a new distinction which may be admitted but it is not necessary, that is: the just man requires the general help of God, as author of the supernatural, for any easy supernatural acts, and this general help, although, in a sense, due to nature raised to the supernatural, is yet not due to this individual rather than to another, since free will remains defectible and God is not always bound to profer a remedy for this defectibility. even for the just. But the just man requires special help for more difficult acts and also for constant perseverance. Thus, Billuart maintains, several texts of the Fathers are more easily reconciled. And C. Billot, referring to the thesis that general concurrence is sufficient in the just man for individual supernatural acts (which are not difficult), seems to mean, in agreement with Billuart, general supernatural concurrence or ordinary actual grace; this is admissible. But Billot is more probably referring to general supernaturalconcurrence with respect to mode, whereas we refer to it with respect to substance. Cf. above, p. 51. his theory on the supernaturalness of faith. ARTICLE X. WHETHER MAN IN THE STATE OF GRACE REQUIRES THE HELP OF GRACE TO PERSEVERE State of the question. We are not concerned here with perseverance taken as a virtue inclining one to elicit the intention of persevering (cf. Ila Ilae, q. 137) nor with the intention of persevering itself, but with the actual exercise of perseverance in good conducive to salvation until the end of one's life. That this is the sense in which it is used is evident from the body of the article, at the very beginning of which St. Thomas eliminates the consideration of the acquired virtue of perseverance, discussed by Aristotle, and of the infused virtue of temperance, annexed to fortitude, which are infused with sanctifying grace. Here it is rather a question "of the continuation in good until the end of life. " Moreover, perseverance thus defined is capable of a twofold acceptation: 1. the enduring continuation in grace and good works until death, as attained to by many predestined adults; and 2. the coincidence of habitual grace and death, without prolonged continuation, as occurs in children who die after their baptism [40] and also in adults who die shortly after obtaining justification, [41] for example, the good thief; and thus it becomes the grace of a happy death. Reply. To the question thus stated, the Church, as we shall presently see, replies that a special gift of perseverance is required. But in what does this special gift consist? Is it a habitual gift or an actual grace ? This is the statement of the question which is quite complex. Let us examine: 1. the errors involved, 2. the teaching of Holy Scripture and the Church, 3. St. Thomas' conclusion, and 4. the problems to be solved. I. ERRORS ON THIS SUBJECT The Pelagians, at least in the beginning, attributed perseverance to the powers of nature alone. The Scini-Pclagians maintained that grace was required for it. but not a special gift distinct from sanctifying grace, and, according to them, grace is given to those who possess the beginning of salvation through their natural effort. Hence the grace of final perseverance is always given to those who persevere in this natural effort. In opposition to them, St. Augustine proved that the gift of final perseverance is a special gift and not subject to merit. Certain theologians, such as Duval and Vega, hold that a special gift is required for perseverance which is active and protracted over a long period of time, but not for a brief perseverance during which no special difficulties occur. II. THE TEACHING OF SCRIPTURE AND THE CHURCH In Scripture our perseverance in good until the end is attributed to God. "I set the Lord always in my sight: for He is at my right hand, that I be not moved" (Ps. 15 8). "Perfect Thou my goings in Thy paths: that my footsteps be not efficacious grace, which proceeds from the consequent will of God. ant sufficient grace, which proceeds from His antecedent will. 40 Then it is final passive perseverance, requiring no cooperation, since an infant is not capable of cooperation. 41 Then it is perseverance not only passive but active, including at least a certain brief cooperation moved" (Ps. 16:5). "Be Thou my helper, forsake me not; do not Thou despise me" (Ps. 26:9). Likewise Ps. 37:22. "When my strength shall fail, do not Thou forsake me" (Ps. 70:9). "And unto old age and gray hairs: O God, forsake me not" (Ps. 70:18). Christ says to His disciples in the Garden of Gethsemane: "Watch ye, and pray that ye enter not into temptation. The spirit indeed is willing, but the flesh weak" (Matt. 26:41). "And now I am not in the world, and these are in the world, and I come to Thee. Holy Father, keep them in Thy name whom Thou hast given Me; that they may be one, as We also are" (John 17:11). "He that thinketh himself to stand, let him take heed lest he fall" (I Cor. 10:12). "With fear and trembling work out your salvation. For it is God who worketh in you, both to will and to accomplish, according to His good will" (Phil. 2:12 f. ). The doctrine of the Church. It is of faith that final perseverance is something gratuitous, not due to the powers of nature, and more a gift distinct from the grace of justification. This was defined against the Pelagians and Semi­ Pelagians whom St. Augustine specifically refuted in his book on the gift of perseverance. Cf. Denz., no. 132, the letter of Pope Celestine I: "No one. even among the baptized, is sufficiently restored by grace to triumph over the wiles of the devil and overcome the temptations of the flesh unless by the daily help of God he receives perseverance in the frequent practice of good. " Also the Council of Orange, can. 10 (Denz., no. 183): "The help of God. even for the redeemed and sanctified, is ever to be implored, that they may come to a good end or continue in good works. " (Likewise can. 25. Denz.. no. 200. ) The Council of Trent (Sess. VI. can. 16. Denz., no. 826) declares: "If anyone should say with absolute and infallible certainty that he surety will have the great gift of perseverance to the end. unless he learns it from special revelation, let him be anathema. " Likewise (can. 22, Denz., no. 832): "If anyone should say either that a justified soul can persevere in the justice it has received without the special help of God. or that with it it cannot do so, let him be anathema. " Father Hugon (De gratia, p. 286) asks whether this canon also includes perseverance for a short space of time (for instance, between justification shortly before death and death itself) and passive perseverance (of infants dying after baptism). The Council does not distinguish; several authorities consider that a real distinction is not to be excluded from the sense of the definition. At least, it is of faith that for the active perseverance of adults over a long period of time a special aid is required distinct from habitual grace. Among the Fathers. Augustine in particular is cited (De dono perseverantiae, chap. 2); he refutes the objections of the Pelagians, to which may be added those which are presented by St. Thomas at the beginning of the article, as follows: 1. Perseverance in virtue is something less than the virtue of perseverance itself which can be acquired by repeated acts. 2. Christian perseverance is a certain moral virtue, annexed to fortitude, and infused at the same time as grace. 3. Adam in the state of innocence would have been able to persevere, but those who are justified by Christ are not in a less perfect state with respect to grace. Against these difficulties. St. Thomas explains, in the body of the present article, that the term "perseverance" is used in a threefold sense: 1. Acquired perseverance, described by Aristotle (Ethics, Bk. VII, chap. 7). This is a moral virtue attached to fortitude which consists in a certain firmness of the reason and will, so that a man may not be dissuaded from the path of virtue by the onslaught of melancholy. This perseverance maintains itself against such an onslaught as continence does against the temptations of the flesh. Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 137, a. 2 ad 2. 2. The infused virtue of perseverance. By this virtue man has the intention of persevering in good until the end. But many had this intention during their lives and yet, in fact, did not persevere to the end. This virtue gives the power of persisting in the first act in spite of the difficulty which arises from the long duration of the act itself. Cf. Ila Ilae. q. 137, a. 3 and 4 3. Perseverance in the sense of a continuation of a certain good work until the end of one's life. For this, the just man requires a special grace, not habitual but actual, directing and protecting him against the impelling force of temptation. This follows from the preceding article in wliich it was proved that the just man needs the help of actual grace to do good and avoid evil and therefore, with still greater reason, to do good and avoid evil until the end of his life. This is the perseverance of which we are now speaking. [42] Similarly, in Ila Ilae. q. 137, a. 4, the question, whether perseverance requires the help of grace, is answered thus: 1. the infused virtue of perseverance presupposes habitual grace; 2. for the act of perseverance lasting until death "man requires not only habitual grace, but also the gratuitous help of God preserving a man in good until the end of life. " "Since, with free will, man himself is changeable, and this condition is not altered by habitual grace in the present life, it is not within the power of free will, even restored by grace, to remain fixed in the good, although it is in its power to choose to do so. For the most part, election falls within our power, but not execution" (ibid. ). III. ST. THOMAS CONCLUSION The conclusion is thus proved. The just man requires the help of actual grace to do the good necessary for salvation and to avoid evil (preceding article). But perseverance is the continuation of a certain good work until the end of life. Therefore, for this perseverance until the end a special actual grace is required, distinct from habitual grace and even from the preceding actual graces, such, that is. as precede the moment of death. (Cf. ad 3. ) This argument thus proposed is metaphysical: no one is preserved in good works until death unless specially preserved by God. Some authors state this argument in a slightly different way, so that its metaphysical necessity is less evident. They say that for perseverance until the end there is a great threefold difficulty for the surmounting of which a special actual gift is required. Thus they rather proceed inductively. It is a great threefold difficulty': 1. to shun evil. 2. to fulfill every' commandment continually and enduringly. and 3. to have death coincide with grace, or to die at the opportune time. But all these taken together require a spec ial favor from God, distinct from habitual grace. Since man cannot, without additional help, overcome temptations and elicit supernatural acts, for still greater reason does he require aid to practice these until the end. Moreover, only God, who is master of grace and of death, can cause grace to coincide with death; in doing so He manifests a special providence toward the elect. Therefore final perseverance (at least such as endures for a long time before death) requires a special favor distinct from habitual grace. This point, at least, in the question, is of faith and is confirmed by this argument based upon still higher principles of faith. This argument is good, but is better formulated by St. Thomas, inasmuch as he shows more clearly why an utterly special actual gift is required for surmounting this great difficulty in fact, that is. preservation in good. IV. DOUBTS First doubt. Whether a special grace, distinct from ordinary, actual helps, is required for long-continued, active final perseverance. At present theologians generally reply' in the affirmative, which is thus proved by the following arguments, a) From authority, since Christ prayed especially for the perseverance of His disciples, who were already just: "Holy Father, keep them" (John 17:11-15). Likewise the Church thus prays in particular: "Enable us always to obey Thy commandments" (Tuesday after the Second Sunday of Lent). "Never pennit me to be separated from Thee" (prayer before Communion). The Council of Trent calls the gift of perseverance, "that great, special gift. " b) From theological argument. (Cf. ad 3. ) Long-continued, active final perseverance, that is. with our cooperation, demands not only sufficient grace, but efficacious grace, nay rather the most important of all efficacious graces wliich consummates the state of wayfarer and brings about an infallible coincidence between the state of grace and death. This efficacious grace confers the final act of the wayfarer connected with the attainment of the final end and therefore proceeds from a very special infusion by which God is the mover. And this, too. certainly depends upon the merits of Christ who merited for us all the graces, both sufficient and efficacious, which we receive and also all 42 Cf. Tabulam auream, s. v. Perseverantia the effects of our predestination. Second doubt. Whether a special gift distinct from the ordinary aids is required for final perseverance over a short space of time, either in adults or in infants who die soon after their justification. At present theologians more generally reply in the affirmative. a) Since this seems to be the obvious meaning of the Councils of Orange and Trent (Denz., nos. 183. 200, 806, 826. 832, 805 ff. ), although this was not expressly defined. The Council of Orange declared (no. 183). "The help of God is to be implored even by the redeemed and sanctified, that they may arrive at a good end or may continue long in good works. " In speaking thus, as Billuart remarks, the Council distinguishes perseverance taken as the attainment of the end from perseverance taken as a continuation of good over a long period of time, and for both of these require a special help which is to be implored by those who are living a holy life. Likewise the Council of Trent requires a special help for perseverance simply and without any limitations. b) Theological argument. The very special effect of predestination, which has an infallible relationship to glory, is a very particular gift. But the coincidence of grace with death is an effect of this kind, conferred only on the predestinate. Therefore it is a very special gift, surpassing ordinary aids, which are attributed to ordinary providence. This is confirmed from the consideration of death. Death may come about, for those who persevere, in a twofold manner: 1. Beyond the natural course of events, according to divine decree, the time of death is hastened or delayed; then it is manifestly a special favor. 2. Or it occurs according to the natural order, but even then providence had disposed natural events from all eternity so that they would bring about death at an opportune time, when a man is in the state of grace. And this indicates a special care on the part of providence, which extends to all tilings, ordains means to their end. and in particular to the glory of God and of the elect. Therefore the coincidence of the state of grace with death is a special favor from God, who alone can cause these two to coincide, since He is the master of grace and of death. At least, this disposition of circumstances is in some respects a special favor; this is admitted by Molina when he maintains that God foresees through mediate knowledge that, if a certain person at the moment of death were placed in such and such circumstances, he would elicit an act of contrition. (Cf. Concordia, ed. cit., p. 548. ) Third doubt. In what does this special gift of final perseverance consist ? A distinction must be made between adults and infants. a) In baptized children who die before attaining the use of reason, this special gift does not require internal actual grace but consists in an external grace, that is. in a special providence by virtue of which the infant dies when in the state of grace. b) In adults, however, the gift of final perseverance does not consist in any one indivisible thing, but comprises a great many, thus: 1. on the part of God it is the special providence causing grace to coincide with death; 2. on the part of man it consists in a series of helps by w hich he is preserved from temptation, or overcomes temptations, or, if he falls, he rises again at the opportune time; finally, it includes the last efficacious grace, connecting the last meritorious act with the end. which, as it is an efficacious grace, is called by antonomasia "the great and signal gift of God. " But whether this last grace is intrinsically efficacious, as the Thomists hold, or extrinsic through the prevision of the scientia media, Billuart (diss. Ill, a. 10) cites texts from Scripture and from St. Augustine in which it is attributed to the grace of final perseverance that man does persevere. "What hast thou that thou hast not received ?" (I Cor. 4:7. ) Therefore election "is not of him that willeth, nor of him that runneth, but of God that showeth mercy" (Rom. 9:16). That is. divine election does not depend on the will or the effort of man. but on God who shows mercy. "For it is God who worketh in you, both to will and to accomplish" (Phil. 2:13). St. Augustine's references to the subject include the following: They receive "grace which is not rejected by any hard heart, since it is first granted to them to have their hardness of heart taken away" {De praedestinatione sanctorum, chap. 8). "God has the wills of men in His power to a greater extent than they themselves have" {De correptione et gratia, chap. 14). "We are speaking of that perseverance which perseveres until the end; if it is granted, one perseveres until the end; but if one does not persevere until the end, it is not granted" {De dono perseverantiae, chap. 6). "Therefore the weakness of the human will is assisted, so that it may be moved invariably and inevitably by divine grace, and hence, although weak, it may not fail nor be overcome by any adversity" {De correptione et gratia, chap. 12). Cf. R. de Journel, Enchir. pair., no. 1958; read also the reply to the third objection of the present article. The question is whether this grace is efficacious because God wills it to be so or because man wills to render it so. In the answer to the third objection St. Thomas says: "By the grace of Christ many receive the gift of grace by which they can persevere and also it is further granted to them that they do persevere. " Hence if, of two equally obdurate sinners, one is converted rather than the other, this is the effect of a special mercy toward him. With still greater reason, if anyone perseveres in good throughout the whole of his life, this is the effect of a special mercy of God toward him. Fourth doubt. Whether perseverance was a very special gift for the angels. The Jansenists reply negatively, both for angels and for man in the state of innocence. The answer of St. Thomas and the generality of theologians is affirmative. Cf. Ill C. Gentes, chap. 155 and Ila Ilae, q. 137, a. 4. a) The foregoing arguments are also valid for the angels and for man in the state of innocence, in whom free will was capable of defection. b) Moreover, for the angels, final perseverance is the proper effect of predestination, and not all the angels were predestined. Further, this is implied by the Council of Orange (Denz., no. 192) when it declares: "Human nature, even had it remained in that state of integrity in which it was created, would by no means have preserved itself without the aid of its Creator. " And St. Augustine, in The City of God (Bk. XIII. chap, g) maintains- "If in both cases (the angels) were created equally good, some fell through bad will, while others, receiving more help, attained that fullness of beatitude, whence they were made absolutely certain that they will never fall. " Fifth doubt. Whether the gift of final perseverance is identical with the gift of confirmation in grace. Cf. Salmanticenses, De gratia, q. 110, disp. III. dub. XI, no. 259. The answer is in the negative, since the gift of final perseverance is common to all the predestinate, but not the gift of confirmation in grace, which was conferred upon the apostles on the day of Pentecost and upon souls that arrived at the intimate union with God which is called the transforming union. In what respects do they differ ? In this: the gift of confirmation in grace preserves one from mortal sin and also generally from deliberate venial sin, according to the mode in which it is given, that is, by a certain participation in the impeccability of the blessed, and the intrinsic gift requires to be completed by the extrinsic protection of God. Hence this gift of confirmation in grace adds something over and above the gift of perseverance, namely, something intrinsic and habitual which prevents sin, almost binding the power to preserve it from sin; on the other hand, the gift of final perseverance does not necessarily demand anything more than the conjunction of the state of grace with death. REFUTATION OF OBJECTIONS First objection. Final perseverance is the coincidence of grace with death. But shortly before death, the justified man with the ordinary helps can persevere for a considerable time in goodness until his death. Therefore final perseverance is not a special help. Reply. I distinguish the major: final perseverance is the coincidence of grace with death, willed in virtue of itself by God for the efficacious purpose of glory: granted; a fortuitous and accidental coincidence: denied. I likewise distinguish the minor: for a moderately long time until the accidental conjunction of grace and death: granted; for a definite interval of time until the conjunction of habitual grace with death willed in virtue of itself by God: denied. Second objection. To those who possess grace, glory- is due. Therefore with still greater reason is the help due to them for the continuation of grace with glory. Reply . I deny the conclusion, for, although glory- is due to a man who possesses grace, as long as he remains in grace, it is not however due to him that he be invariably preserved in grace until death, since he is of an erratic, defectible nature. Third objection. According to the Council of Trent, "God does not abandon a soul that is once justified unless He is first abandoned by it" (Denz., no. 804). But if. in order to persevere, the just man requires special help, which God denies to many of the just, He would desert him before being deserted by him. Therefore. Reply. The sense of the major is: God does not abandon by withdrawing efficacious actual grace, unless man first resists sufficient grace. But to ask why God does not give to all the just efficacious grace, by means of which they may not neglect sufficient grace, is equivalent to asking why He permits sin in one defectible soul rather than in another, whereupon the answer, in the words of St. Augustine (De dono perseverantiae, chap. 9), is that "in this respect the judgment of God is inscrutable"; and further, in his commentary on St. John 6:44, "No man can come to Me, except the Father, who sent Me. draw him, " he adds: "Why does He draw one and not another ? Do not judge if you do not wish to err; but accept and understand: if you are not yet drawn, pray that you may be drawn. " Cf. St. Thomas on John 6:44. Hence we should pray in the words of the Mass, before the Communion: "Grant me ever to adhere to Thy commandments and never permit me to be separated from Thee. " | l3| Further, according to the Council of Trent (Denz.. no. 806): "The gift of perseverance... can be possessed only by the one who is able to make him who stands, stand (Rom. 14:4). that he may persevere standing, and to raise up him who falls. " Cf. below (q. 114, a. 9) on the gift of perseverance which cannot be the object of merit, but which can be obtained by virtue of humble, persevering, impetratory prayer in union with the prayer of Christ, the High Priest of the Sacrifice of the Mass. How advantageous it is, then, to celebrate or hear Mass in order to obtain the grace of a happy death, as Benedict XV declared ! This terminates the question of the necessity of grace for knowing natural and supernatural truth, for doing natural and supernatural good, for avoiding evil, and for persevering unto the end. CHAPTER III: QUESTION 110 THE GRACE OF GOD WITH RESPECT TO ITS ESSENCE AFTER considering the necessity of grace for our final end. St. Thomas passes to the treatment of its essence. This question is particularly concerned with habitual or sanctifying grace which, by antonomasia, is called "grace, " whereby man is made pleasing to God. His child and heir. Actual grace is reducible to this habitual grace in a certain sense, as a disposition to a form or a proportionate movement within the same order and species. This actual grace is considered by itself in question III on the divisions of grace. The present question (110) is divided into four articles which are arranged progrèssively. proceeding from the general to the particular, from the genus to the specific differences, as follow s: 1. Whether grace posits something in the souf or whether it is something existing in God outside of us. 2. Whether grace is a quality. 3. Whether grace differs from infused virtue, especially from charity. 4. Whether it resides in the essence of the soul as in a subject; this question presupposes the solution of article three. We are therefore dealing both with the formal cause and with the quasi-material cause or subject in which grace is received. 43 It is obvious that the divine withdrawal of efficacious grace is a punishment, and as a punishment it presupposes at least an initial fault or resistance to sufficient grace. And on the other hand, even an initial fault presupposes the divine permission of it. To confuse this divine permission with a divine refusal or with the withdrawal of efficacious grace is to set the punishment before the fault, and this is the cruelty which is found in Calvinism, condemned at the Council of Trent ARTICLE I. WHETHER GRACE POSITS ANYTHING IN THE SOUL State of the question. In the first objections, St. Thomas already set forth the arguments which were later proposed by the Lutherans and Calvinists, who hold that sanctifying grace is not a gift intrinsic to the soul, but an extrinsic designation, thanks to the imputation of the justice of Christ, out of regard for whom God loves the sinner and dissimulates his sin, as long as the sinner, with trusting faith, firmly believes and hopes that God will condone his sins to the end of his life for the sake of the merits of Christ. Hence the words of Luther: "Sin strongly, but believe still more strongly. " These words are not a direct exhortation to sin. but an indirect one. St. Thomas anticipated this pernicious doctrine to a certain extent by proposing three objections at the beginning of the article: I) By the mere fact that a man is said to have the grace of the king, nothing is posited in him; it is only in the king that there resides an attitude of benevolence toward this man. 2) God vivifies the soul as the soul vivifies the body; but the soul vivifies the body immediately; therefore there is no medium between God who vivifies and the soul that is vivified. 3) Grace is the remission of sins; but this remission is effected according as God does not impute sin to us. Therefore grace does not posit anything in the soul. It is remarkable that the future doctrine of Protestants on grace should have been so explicitly formulated as early as the thirteenth century in such wise as to solve its difficulties. In the same way, St. Thomas, treating of the Sacrifice of the Mass (Illa. q. 83, a. I) under the title. "Whether in the celebration of this mystery Christ is immolated, " stated an objection (as did St. Albert also in liis Sentences) in terms almost word for word as the Protestants would later express it: "The immolation of Christ was made on the cross. But in the celebration of the Mass, Christ is not crucified; therefore neither is He immolated"; consequently the Mass is not a true sacrifice, but only a memorial of the past sacrifice. From these examples it should be evident how excellent is this method of proposing difficulties at the beginning of any particularly fundamental question, difficulties opposed to the solution which one accepts or which, at least, seems to be proved the best. By this means, theology' can more easily foresee errors and avoid them. For if the question is correctly stated, there cannot be many possible answers, but there are generally two opposite ones, affirmative and negative. And before proving the affirmative, it is profitable to examine the arguments which can be adduced in support of the negative. Thus the crux of the problem to be solved will be brought to light. Reply. Habitual grace is a supernatural gift of God inhering in the soul. 1. Proof from Scripture. "I will pour upon you clean water" (Ezech. 36:25). (Grace is thus referred to metaphorically, in the New Testament as well: cf. John 4:13. ) The following verse continues: "And I will give you a new heart, and put a new spirit within you" (Ezech. 36:26). "He hath given us most great and precious promises: that by these you may be made partakers of the divine nature" (II Pet. 1:4). "The charity of God is poured forth in our hearts, by the Holy Ghost, who is given to us" (Rom. 5:5). "Neglect not the grace that is in thee" (I Tim. 4:14). "I admonish thee, that thou stir up the grace of God which is in thee" (II Tim. 1:6). "Whosoever is born of God, committeth not sin: for His seed abideth in him" (I John 3:9). "Who also hath sealed us, and given the pledge of the Spirit in our hearts" (II Cor. 1:22). "Whosoever drinketh of this water,... the water... shall become in him a fountain of water, springing up into life everlasting" (John 4:13 f. ). As for the teaching of the Fathers, Rouet de Journel (Enchiridion patristicum, theological index, nos. 354-65) sums up their testimony according to the writings of each of them: the abiding, supernatural gift of habitual grace is infused in justification; sins are really removed; man is interiorly renewed; the Holy Ghost dwells in him; he is made a partaker of the divine nature, an adopted son of God, an heir to the kingdom of heaven, a friend of God; habitual grace ejects mortal sin. Man can never be certain of being just or in the state of grace. The just can merit eternal life. Hence the Council of Trent declares (Sess. VI, can. II. Denz.. no. 821): "If anyone should say that men are justified either by the imputation of Christ's justice alone or by the remission of sins alone, exclusive of grace and charity, which are diffused in their hearts by the Holy Ghost, and that it inheres in them, or even that grace, by which we are justified, is only a favor from God: let him be anathema. " Cf. also Council of Trent (Denz., nos. 799 ff., 809). [44] 2. The theological proof is presented by St. Thomas in the article, which should be read attentively: in it he begins with the definition of the word "grace" which, by analogy, has several meanings, even in its merely human signification. 1. Thus it means that by which someone is pleasing or gratifying to others: and in this sense it may be the beauty of the person, which is called grace of the countenance: or someone is said to be pleasing, for instance, to the king because of the king's benevolence toward him; thus it is said that a man is in the king's grace. 2. Grace means a gift gratuitously given to someone; for example: I grant you this grace. 3. It also signifies gratitude or the rendering of thanks. In these human connotations the word "grace" is already applied analogically. With still greater reason is it used in an analogical sense of divine tilings, yet not metaphorically. but properly , as will presently appear. 1. It is applied to the love of God toward those who are pleasing to Him; 2. to the gift gratuitously bestowed upon the just; 3. to the thanksgiving for a benefit received. From God's benevolent love proceeds the gratuitous gift, and thereupon, gratitude. On this basis St. Thomas establishes the most sublime theological argument, connecting the treatise on created grace with that on uncreated grace, or the uncreated love of God "which infuses and creates goodness in things, " as explained in la, q. 20, a. 2. This line of reasoning can be reduced to the following. What makes us pleasing to God is that which is really produced in us by the uncreated love of God for us. But grace is what makes us pleasing to God as children and heirs. Therefore grace is that which is really produced in us by the uncreated love of God for us. The major is proved in la. q. 20, a. 2, according as the uncreated love of God for us does not presuppose any lovableness in us. but bestows it upon us. In this respect it differs from created benevolence. For it is briefly stated in this question of the First Part that, whereas our love is not the cause of the goodness of things, but rather presupposes it, the love of God is the cause of the goodness of tilings. And in the present article St. Thomas adds: "Hence it is clear that any degree whatever of God's love is followed by some good caused in the creature. But God's common love is commensurate with what is bestowed on all created things in the natural order; the other is a special love by which He draws the rational creature up above the condition of nature to a participation in the divine goodness. " The minor is the nominal definition of the word "grace" with respect to us. Thus in Holy Scripture grace is said to be that by which we are pleasing to God, "graced" (Ephes. 1:6). "justified freely by His grace" (Rom. 3:24). His 'beloved" (Ps. 107:7), not merely with a natural love from which proceed natural benefits, such as being, life, but with a supernatural love whereby we are called children of God. 'born... of God" (John 1:13), "partakers of the divine nature" according to the expression of St. Peter: "He hath given us most great and precious promises: that by these you may be made partakers of the divine nature" (II Pet. 1:4). These texts are accepted by Protestants with respect to God's uncreated love for us. Hence, in accordance with the aforesaid major, it follows that grace is in us a supernatural gift of God inhering in the soul, by which we are truly children of God, born of God. and participators in the divine nature. Thus the love of God is effective in the supernatural as it is in the natural order. And grace generally signifies this gift habitually abiding in the soul as often referred to by St. Paul. Nevertheless, as St. Thomas observes in concluding the body of the article, grace sometimes denotes that very eternal, uncreated love of God, so that accordingly even predestination is called grace, "in that God predestined or elected some gratuitously and not because of merit, for it is said to the Ephesians (1:5): [He] 'hath predestinated us unto the adoption of children... unto the praise of the glory of His grace, in which He hath graced us in His beloved 44 Catechismus romanus, Pius V, Part II, no. 185: "But grace is a divine quality inhering in the soul as a certain brilliance and light which removes all the stains from our souls and renders these souls more beautiful and dazzling. Son' "; that is, unto the manifestation of the diffusion and splendor of His uncreated grace, by which we are made pleasing to God in His Son. Thus "grace" is applied analogically both in the natural and in the supernatural orders, but analogically, in the strict sense, and not merely metaphorically. [diagram page 114]_____________________________________ Grace signifies 1. in the supernatural order 1.1. uncreated grace 1.1.1. God's benevolence toward us 1.2. grace as a gratuitous, created gift 1.3. gratitude 2. in the natural order 2.1. benevolence ofa benefactor toward someone 2.2. a benefit which is not due. 2.3. gratitude In the first place, with respect to us, according to the application of the word, "grace" means that which is pleasing to others, for example, beauty of countenance or mental qualities; and to this grace, by which someone is pleasing to others, corresponds benevolence in others, which is present in a different mode in God and in men. Thereafter, from benevolence there arises some benefit and, thence, gratitude for the benefit received. But in itself, grace means in the first place that uncreated grace from which all benefits proceed. Hence St. Thomas likewise declares (la, q. 13, a. 6): Paternity, from our standpoint, denotes primarily an earthly father; but in itself, it applies primarily to the heavenly Father, according to Ephes. 3:14 f. : "I bow my knees to the Father of our Lord Jesus Christ, of whom all paternity in heaven and earth is named. " In all these acceptations, "grace" is applied not metaphorically (as when God is said to be angry) but properly. However, this proper meaning remains analogical; the analogous significations are such as bear a common name, and the meaning signified by the name is absolutely diverse, but under a particular aspect it is the same (under the analogy of proportionality, it is proportionately the same). Thus the notion of grace is proportionately realized in both its human and its divine applications. CONFIRMATION FROM THE REFUTATION OF OBJECTIONS Reply to first objection. That which in us is pleasing to our friends is presupposed by their love, and is not in us as received from them, whereas that which in us is pleasing to God is caused by the divine love. Reply to second objection. God does not vivify the soul as the soul does the body; for the soul is the form of the body and hence vivifies it immediately; on the contrary, God is not the form of the soul, but a separate agent; hence He vivifies the soul not immediately but by a form produced in the soul, that is, by grace, which is life in first act, while the vital operations are life in second act. Reply to third objection. As St. Augustine says (I Retract., chap. 23). to grace pertains not only the remission of sins, but also reconciliation and peace; moreover, the very remission of sins is itself accomplished by sanctifying grace received into the soul as will be clear from what follows below (q. 113, a. 2). Other objections. According to Isa. 43:4, God proclaims: "Since thou becomest honorable in My eyes, thou art glorious: I have loved thee. " Reply. The word "since" does not here signify cause, but concomitance, for "what hast thou that thou hast not received?" Moreover, one person may be more pleasing to God inasmuch as, receiving grace with more fidelity, he performs greater works. I insist. God loves the predestinate. But this love does not posit anything supernatural in them when they are in sin. Therefore not all the love of God posits something in the person loved. Reply. God does not love the predestinate with a terminative efficacious love while he is in sin, but He decreed from all eternity to grant him efficacious graces at such and such a time toward his salvation. I insist. Even if the love of God is efficacious, it suffices that it cause in man practical assistance. Reply. This is true of the imperfect love whereby God disposes the sinner for justification, not of the perfect love whereby God loves man as a son and heir; hence man ought to participate in the divine nature, "made partaker of the divine nature. " First corollary. A threefold love of God toward us wayfarers can be distinguished and designated by the effects of each. 1. Merely natural love, which causes natural goods such as being, life, intelligence. 2. Supernatural but imperfect love, which causes in the sinner supernatural faith, hope, and practical helps. 3. Supernatural and perfect love, which communicates habitual grace by which man is made absolutely pleasing to God, His friend, a partaker of the divine nature, and an heir to the kingdom of heaven. (Cf. below, what is said of justification in opposition to Protestantism. ) Second corollary. It is already vaguely apparent from the major premise (the love of God infuses and creates goodness m things), that grace is intrinsically efficacious, that is, because God wills, and not because man wills, to render it efficacious. "It is God who worketh in you both to will and to accomplish, according to His good will. " "What hast thou that thou hast not received?" (Cf. below, on efficacious grace. ) From the foregoing it is evident that he who actually fulfills the commands of God is better than he who can fulfill them and, in fact, does not do so. But no one would be in any respect better were he not more loved and assisted by God (la, q. 20, a. 3 f. ). "What hast thou that thou hast not received ?" Therefore the grace whereby we actually fulfill the precepts of God contains more in itself than the sufficient grace whereby we can fulfill it, without however doing so in fact. ARTICLE II. WHETHER GRACE IS A QUALITY OF THE SOUL State of the question. Having established that habitual grace is something created inhering in the soul, we must discover to what category of created being it can be reduced, whether to the category of a quality rather than to a substance, a quantity, a relation, an action, or a passion. It seems that it is not a quality, for the following reasons. 1. Grace acts in the soul, justifying it; but a quality does not act upon its subject. 2. Grace is nobler than the soul, therefore it should not be an accident or quality, but a substance. 3. If grace were an accident or quality, it would be corrupted upon the entrance of mortal sin; this is unbecoming, since grace is the beginning of eternal life. Note. The Nominalists, before Luther, declared that habitual grace is something ontologie ally natural, but something which bestows a moral right to eternal life, just as a bank note is physically, ontologically only a slip of paper, although its possession gives one a moral right to the equivalent gold. On the contrary , certain Cartesian and Ontologist theologians said that grace and charity are the Holy Ghost Himself dwelling in the soul, as the Master of the Sentences might say. The Cartesians in particular maintained this, for they did not admit of a real distinction between substance and accident: hence grace could not be a real supernatural accident distinct from the soul, but must be a substance, that is, God inhabiting it and impelling it to meritorious works availing to salvation. Reply. St. Thomas replies to the question with a twofold conclusion regarding 1. actual grace and 2. habitual grace. First conclusion. Actual grace is not a quality but a certain motion of the soul. Proof. Actual grace is a gratuitous effect of God by which the soul of man is impelled by God toward something which ought to be known or willed or done. But that by which the soul is thus moved is not a permanent quality, but something transient, that is, a certain motion of the soul quite distinct both from the uncreated action of God whence it proceeds and from our action thus produced. It should be noted that certain Molinists, misinterpreting St. Thomas, understand him thus: actual grace is a certain motion of the soul that is, an indeliberate operation on our part which inclines toward a deliberate act, determinable by man alone. On the contrary, when St. Thomas says that actual grace is a certain motion of the soul, he does not say it is an operation of the soul but, as he himself wrote, it is a motion whereby "the soul is moved by God toward something which is to be known or willed or done. " In other words, it is the application of the faculties that they may pass from potency to act and may elicit their operation; for an operation, even indeliberate, is vitally elicited by the faculty and not produced immediately by God alone; but under the infusion of actual grace, the soul elicits vitally even indeliberate operations. On the other hand, actual grace is not elicited by us. Hence St. Thomas says: "The act of a mover in the moved is a motion" according to Aristotle (III Physics). For, as Aristotle declares, motion, inasmuch as it is produced by an agent, is called action or motion, and motion, as it is in the one moved, is "passion. " But the action of a bodily agent is formally transitive and terminates in the "patient, " whereas the uncreated external action of God is formally immanent and only virtually transitive. Therefore actual grace is something created, as an effect of God, according to St. Thomas (he does not say that actual grace is our action, our vital operation), and it is in us as a motion-passion received in the will by which the will is moved to elicit its operation. Zigliara explains this well (Theol. nat., Bk. Ill, art. 4, 5, p. 498) by the example of heat. 1. Heat is an action in the fire, or by the fire (formally transitive action); 2. Heat is a passion in the wood, in that the wood is heated; 3. Heat is an operation, since the wood, once heated, gives heat. Likewise, with respect to divine motion. 1. Motion is an action in God, uncreated, formally immanent and virtually transient action. 2. Motion-passion by which the will is moved, or is made to pass from the potency of willing into the act of willing is the completion of causality, referred to by St. Thomas {Contra Gentes. Bk. Ill, chap. 66). 3. The operation elicited by the wiU, even if indeliberately. is yet vitally elicited. St. Thomas says {Contra Gentes, Bk. Ill, chap. 66): "For the completion of the power of the secondary agent comes from the first agent. " And again (De potentia, q. 3. a. 7 ad 7): "That which is made by God in the natural order, by which He may actually operate, is. as a mere intention He has, in a certain sense incomplete, in the way that colors exist in the air or the power of an art in the artist's instrument"; hence the power of an art is distinguished from the action which proceeds from this power. (Cf. our Dieu, 8th ed., p. 480, and the Salmanticenses. De gratia, disp. 5, dub. 1-6, on actual grace as distinct from the uncreated action of God and from our indeliberate operation. ) Objection. An immanent action elicited by us is reduced, as immanent, to the category of quality, [45] and consequently actual grace ordained toward this action may be reduced to a quality. Reply. Certainly thus actual grace reductivety belongs to the category of quality, but not as something habitual and permanent. What St. Thomas is particularly insistent upon is that actual grace is not something habitual and abiding as a quality property so called, but something passing in a transitory manner. Second conclusion. Sanctifying grace is a certain supernatural quality abiding in the soul. 1. Scriptural proof. Proof from the passages of Sacred Scripture quoted in the explanation of the preceding article wherein grace is referred to as the seed of glory, a pledge, a seal a fountain; likewise from St. Augustine here quoted in the argument Sed contra, who calls it the luster of the soul. But all these expressions signify something permanent in the souf by reason of which God abides in the soul according to the words of John 14:23: "We will come to him, and will make Our abode with him. " Similarly the Council of Trent (Denz., no. 821) speaks of grace as diffused and inhering in the soul; again (Denz., no. 809): "It is called our justice because by its inherence in us we are justified. " As Gonet observes in his commentary on this article (p. 87), the Council of Trent proscribes the error of the Master of the Sentences according to whom charity is the Holy Ghost Himself dwelling in us and moving us to the act of charity. 2. Theological proof. God does not provide less amply for our souls with respect to supernatural good than with respect to natural good. But with respect to natural good He not only moves us actually, but gives us qualities or faculties, namely, principles, eliciting operations, so that these may be vital and connatural to us. Therefore it is fitting that God should likewise not only move us to act, but should also give us a habitual principle of supernatural operation, that is, a certain quality, namely, grace itself. Thus has He disposed all things sweetly. St. Thomas here differentiates between habitual and actual grace more decidedly than does St. Augustine, since he considers the matter more deeply from the ontological aspect, and not merely from the psychological and moral point of view. Again in Ila Ilae, q. 23, a. 2, he makes it clear that charity is something created in the soul and not, as the Master of the Sentences would have it, the Spirit Himself moving us to an act of charity. In the latter case, the soul would not produce the act of charity connaturally or meritoriously; to do so requires an infused habit elevating the will. Otherwise the supernatural order would be less perfect than the natural order. At the same time, an infused habit is, as it were, a second nature in us, so that our supernatural acts are also connatural. Confirmation from the reply to the objections. 1. Grace, as a quality, acts in the soul not effectively but formally. justifying it or making it just, as whiteness makes a thing white and justice renders one just. 2. Grace cannot be the substance of God since it is the effect of the uncreated love of God (according to Article I); nor can it be the substance of the soul, since it would then be something natural, would be identified with nature, from which it is to be distinguished, according to revelation. Therefore it can only be an accident and is thus inferior to the soul with respect to the mode of its being, that is, being in something else; but it is nobler than the soul according as it is a certain supernatural participation in the divine nature as it is divine, that is, in the intimate life of God. Deity is in a certain sense above being, above unity, above life, and above knowledge, for these are contained 45 Cf. St. Thomas, Contra Gentes, Bk. 1, chap. 100, and John of St. Thomas, Phil, nat., q. 4, a. 4: action, which property belongs to the category of action, is transitive action producing a correlative passion in the patient; immanent action is reducible to the category of quality. within it formally and eminently. Corollary. The essentially supernatural cannot be in us or in the angels otherwise than as an accident; in God alone is it substance. Reply to third objection. Since grace is an accident, it is not that which is made or corrupted, but that by which someone is made pleasing, who may subsequently become unpleasing; in other words, grace is drawn forth from the obediential power of the soul, and after its loss nothing but the obediential power remains, that is, no repugnance to receiving a return of grace. The present conclusion may be confirmed by showing that sanctifying grace cannot be classified under any other category of created being. 1. Not under quantity, for quantity results from the composite nature of matter. 2. It is not a relation, since relation demands a foundation, and sanctifying grace is itself the foundation of the relationship by which we are called children of God and it ordains us to glory, inasmuch as it is the seed of glory. It is likewise the foundation or root of the infused virtues, wherein there is a transcendental relationship to our supernatural object. 3. It cannot be an action, not even an immanent action, but is the radical principle of immanent actions, such as acts of charity, faith, hope. 4. It is not a passion; in this it differs from actual grace, which is in us a motion of the soul, or a motion-passion. Finally, it is evident that habitual grace does not belong to any other categories which are found only in bodies, for instance, location, position, time, habit or adornment, although metaphorically it is called the adornment of the soul. It should be remarked that theologians generally maintain, in opposition to Ripalda and, in a certain measure, to Scotus, not only that grace is not a substance but that God, even by His absolute power, cannot produce a created, supernatural substance to which the vision of the divine essence would be natural. (Cf. De revelatione, I. 364. and Billuart, De Deo, diss. 4, a. 5, 4; Gonet, De gratia, disp. II. a. 3. ) This would be incompatible from the standpoint of the object, since such a substance would have an intellect of the same nature as the divine intellect, for it would be specified by the same formal object; hence it would be a created divine nature, which is repugnant by its terms as is pantheism. It would also be inconsistent on the part of the subject, for something created cannot be essentially supernatural without being essentially related to the Deity as such and specified by it, since only the essence of God is above all created nature. But no created substance can be essentially related to the Deity and specified by it, because substance is being in itself and for itself (in se et ad se), that is, it has within itself its own specification and cannot be defined with reference to anything else. On the contrary, any accident, such as a power or habit, can be essentially related to something else; thus grace, which is the seed of glory, is specified by the essence of God, of which it is a participation and toward the vision of which it ordains us. But Scotus did not understand this well, for he held that grace and the light of glory are supernatural only in fact, because God so willed it, but that He could have willed them to be natural, so that there could be a creature to whom the beatific vision would be natural. There are several problems to be examined in connection with this article on account of the errors of the Nominalists who came after St. Thomas and prepared the way for Lutheranism. First doubt. Is it of faith that sanctifying grace is a quality and a habit ? Reply. It is not a defined article of faith, for the Council of Trent as well as the Council of Vienne, refrained from using the words "quality" and "habit" so as not to define a question disputed among theologians. Hence it seems that the demands of faith would be satisfied by holding that sanctifying grace is a habitual gift, permanently inhering in the soul. Second doubt. Is it, nevertheless, a certain theological conclusion that sanctifying grace is a quality and a habit, entitatively ? Reply. Assuredly, on account of the argument given by St. Thomas and commonly accepted at present. For habitual grace cannot be conceived as belonging to any other category than that of a quality, as we have said; and within this category it is reducible to a habit. For a habit is a permanent quality, difficult to dislodge (at least by any internal cause), disposing the subject to a certain state, whether for good or evil, in regard to its being (an entitative habit, such as beauty', health) or in regard to its operation (an operative habit). But sanctifying grace is a permanent quality, as has been shown; moreover it is difficult to dislodge, as far as itself and its principles are concerned, supported as it is by the divine infusion, and indeed being in the spiritual soul the very seed of glory, or life eternal already begun; it is therefore difficult to dislodge, although accidentally, by reason of the subject and of the aberrations and caprices of its free will, it can be lost. "For we carry this treasure in fragile vessels. " (Cf. De veritate, q. 27, a. 1-9. ) [46] Finally, it disposes the subject in a good, or favorable, state toward God and for avoidance of sin. But in the following article, where habitual grace is distinguished from charity, we shall see that the former is an entitative and not an operative habit, except radically. Third doubt. Is habitual grace a habit univocally or only by analogy, properly speaking ? Reply. It is called a habit not only metaphorically, but property. However, in agreement with several Thomists (Gardeil, Billot, De virt. inf., pp. 30, 33) it seems to us that it does not correspond univocally with habits of the natural order, by the very fact that it belongs to a higher order which surpasses all nature, created or capable of creation. Hence St. Thomas often speaks of it as a certain quality or as reducible to the genus: quality (cf. la Ilae, q. 63, last article). That this solution is indeed St. Thomas' teaching can be proved from four arguments. 1. He observes (la Ilae, q. 61, a. I ad I) that "virtue" is applied analogically even to the moral and intellectual virtues; hence, with still greater reason, to the supernatural virtues. Likewise, according as prudence directs the moral virtues, the notion of virtue belongs causally by priority to prudence as directing, rather than to the other moral virtues. 2. St. Thomas declares {De veritate, q. 14, a. 9, 2) that 'belief, as it exists in the demons, is not conformable to infused faith, except equivocally"; the demons believe by acquired faith based on the evidence of miracles, forced, as it were, to accept this evidence. 3. St. Thomas maintains in several places that the infused virtues differ from the acquired inasmuch as they not only bestow the power to act rightly, but bestow it absolutely, according as they give the first upward impetus to a higher order; therefore they partake in a certain sense of the nature of a power and in a certain sense of that of a habit. 4. St. Thomas states in various articles that "grace is reducible to the primary species of a quality" (habit); cf. la Ilae, q. 110, a. 3 ad 3; De veritate, q. 27, a. 2 ad 7; II, d. 26, q. I, a. 4 ad 1. However, John of St. Thomas, commenting on De virtutibus, la Ilae. disp. 16, a. 6, fol. 152, seems to hold that grace and the infused virtues are in accord univocally with the acquired virtues as classified by predicates and analogically as classified by their causative motive or regulative force. But John of St. Thomas states in his Cursus phil., dealing with the four causes, that they conform univocally in the general notion of cause, which seems to be false. The argument which impels John of St. Thomas is that acquired virtue is logic ally univocal in kind, that is. in the order of logic; yet. causally, virtue is predicated of prudence in a prior sense to that of the virtues which are directed by it. Fourth doubt. Whether habitual grace is a gift entitativety (that is, intrinsic ally, essentially) and supernatural!}. 46 St. Thomas says {De verit., q. 27, a. I ad 9): "Although by one act of mortal sin grace may be expelled, grace is not. however, expelled easily; for it is not easy for one who possesses grace to perform such an act, on account of the inclination in a contrary' direction; thus the Philosopher says in his Ethics. Bk. V, chap. 6. that it is difficult for the just manto commit an injustice. " This is denied by Scotus (q. I of the introduction and 4, dist. 10, q. 8), where he says that if God so willed, He could give us grace and the light of glory as natural properties; and he maintains that the supernatural differs from the natural only on the part of the efficient cause, as sight supematurally given to a man born blind differs from natural sight. Hence grace would not be something intrinsically and essentially supernatural; it would not be supernatural substantially or essentially, but only with respect to the mode of its production under present circumstances. Thus the distinction between the order of grace and the order of nature would not be necessary, in other words, not based upon its divine nature according to wliich it exceeds all nature, created or capable of creation, but would be a contingent distinction, founded upon the free will of God. This is "contingentism" and "libertism. " The Nominalists, such as Ockham, followed, maintaining that grace should be looked upon as a bank note (cf. Salmanticenses, dub. II. 3. no. 34). For as this note, of its nature, before being issued by the government, has no monetary value, but subsequently is equal to gold; so sanctifying grace intrinsically is a certain entity, lacking sufficient value to render man acceptable to God. but by the accession of an extrinsic disposition of God, or by the favor of God, without any intrinsic transformation, this entity receives a moral value, comparable to that of the bank note. Such, according to the Salmanticenses. was the teaching of Ockham. Gabriel, and a disciple of Ailly (probably Gerson), Durandus (I. d. 17. q. I, nos. 7 and 8) and Scotus (ibid., q. 2) seem to agree with them. To the same effect, Ockham declared that man can merit eternal life by a natural act, if this act is accepted by God. This is absolute contingentism. Molina retains something of this Nominalism when he says that the theological virtues are supernatural modally, but not by virtue of their formal object. Thus the Nominalists denied the principles of traditional theology and prepared the way for Lutheranism, which holds that grace is only an extrinsic denomination; in other words, corruption remains in man, but sin is no longer imputed to him. as long as a man believes himself to be predestined. Therefore, "sin strongly, and believe even more strongly. " This is the Nominalist tendency. On the contrary. immoderate realism would tend to identify being in general with the divine being, and to identify grace with God dwelling in us. as the Master of the Sentences maintained. Toward this latter error the Cartesian and ontologistic theologians inclined, refusing to admit that habitual grace is an accident, since they denied any real distinction between substance and accident. Against Scotus and the Nominalists what is to be said ? Gonet (a. 3) states that this opinion is commonly rejected because it does not distinguish between what is intrinsically or substantially supernatural, and what is extrinsically or modally supernatural. However, this distinction is generally accepted by theologians, especially since the Council of Trent's condemnation of Protestantism, as Lichetto himself acknowledges, referring to Scotus. (Cf. Scotus, Opera, ed. Vives. XV. 200; and our De revelatione, I. 216. ) Lichetto maintains, after Trent, that there are habits which of themselves are necessarily infused, such as the theological virtues. Moreover, the Church has always distinguished between the supernaturalness of miracles naturally intelligible, and the supernaturalness of grace and of mysteries wliich are naturally unintelligible even for the angels (Council of the Vatican). Hence even the Molinists hold that, although the theological virtues are supernatural substantially, yet they are not supernatural by virtue of their formal object; and therein lies the inconsistency of their position. At present theologians generally' agree, in opposition to Scotus and Ripalda. that God, even by His absolute power, cannot create a supernatural substance or a substance to which the vision of the divine essence would be natural. (Cf. Council of Trent. Sess. VI, chap. 7, Denz., no. 800. ) In regard to the justification of sinners: "By it we are renewed in spirit... ; we are indeed called just and so we are. Hence in this same justification, together with the remission of sins, man receives simultaneously the infusion of all these: faith, hope, and charity. " Thus the virtues are, by thenvery' nature, infused, not accidentally infused, as infused geometry would be. But we shall give the complete refutation of the foregoing theory of the Nominalists in the solution of the next problem. Fifth doubt. Whether sanctifying grace is a formal and physical participation in the divine nature. State of the question. In articles 3 and 4 of the present question, as well as in q. 112. a. I, St. Thomas says that grace is a participation in the divine nature, and St. Thomas was speaking formally ; but later, in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, there were great discussions between Thomists and Nominalists over that word "participation. " AU CathoUc theologians have certainly always held that sanctifying grace is in some sense a participation in the divine nature, on account of the express testimony of Sacred Scripture and the Fathers, to be quoted below, particularly on account of the words of St. Peter's Second Epistle (1:4): "that by these [gifts] you may be made partakers of the divine nature. " In the first place, the Nominalist definition of "participation" should be noted. The expression "to participate" means to take part; thus are distinguished the subject participating and the perfection participated. Cf. Tabula aurea of the works of St. Thomas, s. v. Participatio. "Participate" means to take part: it is primarily apphed to quantitative things which possess integral parts, for instance, to participate in this meal: subsequently it can be apphed to qualities, for example, to participate in or partake of heat, light, whiteness, or to spiritual qualities, as a pupü participates in the knowledge of his master when he receives a share in it, or a soldier participates in the victory of his general. Thus Plato often used this word in the pliilosophical order when, for instance, he stated that men participate in the idea of humanity, and bulls in the idea of bovinity; but he thought that these exemplary ideas had separate being. On the contrary, a separate man or buU cannot exist, since they would have to have bones and flesh, in other words, a common, not an individual material, and bones and flesh camrot exist without being these particular bones and flesh, as Aristotle maintained. But God is essential being, essential good, and essential truth. It is commonly said that stones participate in being, plants and animals participate in life, men participate in intellect, and thus they are analogically like unto God with regard to being, life, and intellect respectively. Now it must be determined whether by habitual grace the just man participates in the divine nature, in the intimate life of God or in the Deity by which God is, properly speaking, God; in other words, whether he participates in the radical principle of operations which are properly divine, by which God knows and loves Himself immediately. As the Salmanticenses here record (dub. Ill, no. 54), the Nominalists, consistently with their thesis, mentioned above, denied that sanctifying grace is a physical and formal participation in the divine nature. (Likewise Coninck, In Ilam Ilae. d. 21, no. 75, and Lessius Bk. II, De summo bono. ) The Nominalists declare that sanctifying grace is a moral participation, consisting in a rectitude of the will and an imitation of the sanctity and justice of God, just as those who imitate the faith of Abraham are called sons of Abraham, and those who imitate the malice of the devil are called his sons, although physically they are not born of either. In accordance with this tendency, the Protestants held that man is by grace a son of God, since he believes Iris sins are externally removed or no longer imputed to him. And Baius, who was a moderate Protestant, denied the strict supernaturalness of sanctifying grace, which he limited to natural Christian virtue. [47] Other Catholic theologians maintained that sanctifying grace is a physical participation in the divine nature, not however formal but virtual; that is, not formal as the light of the air is a participation in the light of the sun, but virtual as the seed is a participation in the procreator, by a power derived from it to produce a likeness of itself. (Cf. Gonet. ) Lastly, the Thomists hold that sanctifying grace is a physical and formal participation in the divine nature; but with respect to some secondary points they are not agreed. Cajetan, Ledesma. Martines, Gonet. and the Salmanticenses claim that it is even a physical formal analogical participation in the very' infinity of God; others (Curiel for example) declare that a participation in infinity is impossible. But this minor disagreement seems to be a mere matter of terminology, for John of St. Thomas and Billuart reconcile these two opinions of Thomists. as will presently be explained (cf. below: the dignity of sanctifying grace). The more general conclusion is that sanctifying grace is a participation in the divine nature, not only moral but physical not only virtual but formal analogical however, imperfectly imitating as an accident what, in God, is '' Cf. Denz., no. 1021: "The elevation and exaltation of human nature to a participation in the divine nature was due to the integrity of its primary state and accordingly is called natural and not supernatural. " No. 1023: "Absurd is the opinion of those who say that man. from the beginning, was exalted by certain supernatural and gratuitous gifts above the condition of his nature, that he might seek God supernaturally by faith, hope, and charity. " substance. 1. This conclusion is based upon Sacred Scripture: "By whom [Christ| ... hath given us most great and precious promises: that by these you may be made partakers of the divine nature" (II Pet. 1:4). Likewise in Sacred Scripture it is attested in various places that the just are. by grace, generated, born, reborn, of God and made sons of God: but by generation and birth, nature is communicated. "Of His own will hath He begotten us by the word of truth, that we might be some beginning of His creature" (Jas. 1:18). "He gave them power to be made sons of God... who are born, not of blood, nor of the will of the flesh..., but of God" (John 1:12f. ). What would remain of this text, according to Nominalism and Lutheranism ? "Unless a man be born again of water and the Holy Ghost, he cannot enter into the kingdom of God" (John 3:5). "Whosoever is born of God committed! not sin: for His seed abideth in him" (I John 3:9). And again {ibid., 5:1): "Whosoever... is born of God" does not sin. but the grace of God preserves him; that is, he who remains in the state of grace, as a child of God. does not sin mortally. Thus it is proved from Sacred Scripture that grace is a participation in the divine nature. Similarly this is the obvious meaning of the Church's definitions which are thus brought together by Denzinger in his index (p. 598): "Habitual grace is distinct from actual grace (nos. 1064 ff. ): it is an infused, inherent quality of the soul by which man is formally justified, made a partaker of the divine nature, regenerated, abides in Christ, puts on the new man, is made an heir to eternal life" (cf. references according to Denz.. ibid. ). |'lx| 2. Theological proof. There are two arguments in particular: a) taken from the definition of nature; b) from the essential supernaturalness of grace itself. The first argument is stated thus: By divine nature is meant the radical principle of the divine operations by which God sees Himself intuitively and loves Himself. But sanctifying grace imitates physically and formally this radical principle of property divine operations, for it radically disposes man to see God intuitivety and to love Him with the beatific love. Therefore sanctifying grace is a physical and formal participation in the divine nature. The major is based on the very definition of nature, which is the root of the properties and the radical principle of operations in any being. Thus analogically but according to the strict and not the metaphorical sense, nature is in God that which is conceived in Him as the root of the divine perfections and the radical principle of property divine operations, which are specified by the very essence of God. seen and loved: whereas, on the Contran-, the creative act proceeds, not from the divine nature, but from the divine liberty, for God does not operate outside of Himself from any necessity of nature. The minor is clear especially with regard to grace consummated, which is called glory, from which proceeds the light of glory in the intellect and the charity of beatitude in the will. Moreover, according to St. Paul the charity of the wayfarer never falls away, but is the same as in heaven: and faith is the substance of tilings hoped for. Hence grace is spoken of, in tradition, as the seed of glory, a certain beginning of eternal life, according to the words of Christ: "He that believeth in the Son, hath life everlasting" (John 3:36); "He that believeth in Me, hath everlasting life" {ibid.. 6:47. also 6:40 and 6:55); "Every one that... believeth in Me, shall not die forever" {ibid.. 11:26). It is a question of grace, which establishes the adoptive sonship. which is a certain participated likeness in the sonship of the Word, for in natural filiation the whole undivided nature is communicated, essence and substance, as it is in the Father; but to us is communicated a participation in the divine nature by accidental gift. Objections. Adversaries of this conclusion raise the following objections. First objection. It is said in the book of Job (38:28): "Who is the father of rain ? or who begot the drops of dew ?" That is, God; but the rain does not participate in the nature of God; therefore neither do the other texts quoted prove anytiling. With regard to the testimony of the Fathers, cf. Rouet de Journet Enchirid. patristicum. index theologicus, no. 358 Reply. The language of the book of Job is frequently poetical in style, and in this text "the father of rain" is poetically used for the creator of rain. Likewise when it asks "who begot the drops of dew, " the word "begot" is taken in abroad and not a strict sense. But this is not so when it is declared of the just (II Pet. 1:4) that they are made "partakers of the divine nature. " I insist. Sacred Scripture also calls "children of God" those who lead good lives and do the will of God; for example, "Do good to them that hate you... that you may be the children of your Father" (Matt. 5:44 f. ). "But love ye your enemies... and you shall be the sons of the Highest" (Luke 6:35). In these texts only a moral relationship with God is meant, and we are made His sons morally, or by imitation of His ways. Reply. To be sure, we are also made children of God, morally, by imitation of His ways, but this moral relationship does not exclude the other but rather, indeed, presupposes it. For God first infuses grace by which we are partakers of the divine nature and are made pleasing to God and His children, by a physical participation in His nature. Then man, by meritorious acts, also becomes a child of God morally, imitating the paternal manner of acting. Thus the child of any distinguished man, if he follow s the practices of his father, is said to be made his son to that extent, and this is implied by the words of Christ: "Do good to them that hate you... that you may be the children of your Father who is in heaven. " These words presuppose that God is already a father on some other account than that of the love of enemies. I insist. By grace we are made only adoptive sons of God. However, adoption does not communicate nature, but only a moral right to an inheritance. Therefore grace is only a moral participation in the divine nature by imitation of the divine ways. Reply. Adoption communicates only a moral right to an inheritance in human affairs: granted: in divine things: denied. In human affairs this is true for two reasons: 1) because human adoption presupposes in the child adopted the same nature specifically as in the person adopting; it is otherwise in divine adoption; 2) because the love of the man adopting is only affective, and produces no physical effect in the child adopted, but only a moral right to an inheritance; on the contrary, "the love of God infuses and creates goodness in things. " First confirmation. Grace partakes of the divine nature as charity7 and the light of glory partake of the divine attributes. But charity participates strictly and physically in the divine love as divine, since it is specified by the same formal object; and the light of glory participates in the same way in the divine light as divine. Thus Christ says: "The glory whichthou hast given Me, I have given to them" (John 17:22). Therefore habitual grace partakes of the divine nature as divine, that is, in the Deity itself, not only with reference to being, but to Deity as such. Second confirmation. A cause the effects of which are real and physical is itself real and physical. But the effects of sanctifying grace, as a participation in the divine nature, are real and physical, namely, the supernatural virtues which follow upon it as properties. For, according to the Council of Trent, charity is something diffused and inhering in our hearts. The end of sanctifying grace is also something real and physical, that is, the beatific' vision. Therefore sanctifying grace itself, as a participation in the divine nature, is something real and physical, not something merely moral as an imitation of the divine ways. It must, however, be termed an analogical, not a univocal, participation, since it is something created; moreover it is an accident. The Fourth Lateran Council (Denz.. no. 432). explaining the words, "Be ye perfect even as your heavenly Father is perfect. " declares that it is "as if our Lord were to say: Be perfect, with the perfection of grace, as your heavenly Father is perfect, with the perfection of nature; manifestly, each in his own mode, since between the Creator and the creature such a similarity cannot be acknowledged, without acknowledging that the dissimilarity between them is even greater. " Therefore it is only an analogy, not however a mere metaphor, but strictly speaking, according as grace properly ordains us to the operations of beatitude which are properly divine and have the same formal object as the uncreated operations of God Himself. Thus grace is more than a virtual participation in Deity; it is participation as a permanent form and by reason of the specifying, connatural formal object. [49] That which can be called a virtual participation in the divine nature is the instrumental power residing in the sacraments for the 49 Our supernatural operations are said to be connatural inasmuch as they7 proceed from grace and the infused virtues as from a second nature in which we participate as in the manner of a permanent form production of grace and likewise the actual grace which disposes one for habitual grace. Second theological argument. Following this first argument with its confirmations, another can thus be proposed which is drawn from the essential supernaturalness of grace. Sanctifying grace, in both men and angels, is, according to the Church, an essentially supernatural gift, exceeding any nature created or capable of being created. But sanctifying grace cannot thus exceed any nature capable of creation unless it is a formal and physical participation in the divine nature. Therefore sanctifying grace is a formal and physical participation in the divine nature. It should be remarked that this argument can be inverted and proposed as a corollary of the preceding argument, to prove against the Nominalists that grace is intrinsically supernatural since it is a physical participation in the divine nature. This is done by Billuart. But our major can be proved from the authority of the councils, for, according to the Vatican Council (Denz., 1796) : "divine mysteries (among which is sanctification by grace) by their very nature so exceed the created intellect that even when transmitted by revelation and received by faith, they yet remain covered over by the veil of faith itself and enshrouded in a certain darkness, as long as we are making our way in this life toward God. " Similarly with respect to the essential supernaturalness of grace, according as it surpasses the powers and merits of nature (cf. the condemnation of Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism by the Second Council of Orange) and according as it exceeds the requirements of our nature (cf. the condemnation of Baius, especially Denz., nos. 1021, 1023, and the reference just quoted). Moreover, the Vatican Council (Denz., no. 1813), teaching that "miracles can certainly be known" even naturally, distinguishes expressly between the supernaturalness of miracles, which exceeds our efficient created powers but not our cognoscitive powers, and the supernaturalness of mysteries and of grace, which exceed the powers of understanding of any intellect capable of being created. Thus without a special revelation no one is absolutely certain of being in the state of grace. Our minor is thus proved: natures created or capable of being created have a participated likeness to God with respect to being, life, and intellect, but not with respect to Deity as such. For God exceeds all nature created or capable of being created by reason of the radical principle of properly divine operations which have God Himself for specifying object. This is the intimate life of God, belonging to God by the very strict, intimate reason of His Deity', which is in a certain sense above being, unity, life, and intellect, because it contains formally and eminently these absolute!}' simple perfections. Therefore grace, according as it exceeds all nature created or indeed capable of creation, is a formal and physical participation in the divine nature, or Deity as such. Objection. But even a stone is a certain physical participation in the divine nature inasmuch as it is substantial, and so is a plant inasmuch as it has life in first act and second act; with still greater reason the intellectual soul is a physical participation in the divine nature with respect to intellectual life at least in first act and our understanding with respect to life in second act; cf. Gardeil, O.P.. Structure de fame et experience mystique, 1927, I, 373. Reply. The stone docs not participate in the divine nature. It participates in being, being in general· not divine being; and thus it is an anological likeness of the divine being since it is being, not as being God. Likewise the plant participates in life in general· not divine life; and in the same way the rational soul participates in intellectual life in general and thus has a participated likeness of the divine intellect on the general analogical basis of intellection. In all of these there is present the common resemblance (being, life, intellect) which God and the creature share analogically. On the other hand, sanctifying grace as such is not a participation in being in general· nor in life in general· nor in intellectuality in general· but a participation in Deity, which is found naturally only in God. Thus only grace is called a participation in the divine nature according as it is in us the radical principle of operations strictly divine, of which the formal object is (in heaven, at least) absolutely the same as the formal object of the uncreated operations of God. All of this may be diagrammed as foUows: [diagram page 134]____________________ Being life intellectuality • God • God • God Deity • plant • stone • soul grace Thus the stone participates in being and has a likeness to God on the basis of being: grace, on the contrary, is directly and immediately a participation in the divine nature, not in any perfection analogically shared by God and the creature. Therefore Deity as such cannot be partaken of except by some essentially supernatural gift. And. conversely, grace cannot be essentially supernatural unless it is a formal and physical participation in the divine nature as divine, that is, in the intimate life of God, or Deity as Deity, ordaining us to the knowledge of God as He Himself knows Himself immediately and to the love of God as He loves Himself. Furthermore, sanctifying grace is a participation in Deity as it is in itself and not merely as it is known to us. For it is produced in our soul by an immediate infusion altogether independently of our knowledge of the Deity; and just as Deity as such is communicated to the Son by eternal generation, so Deity as such is partaken of by the just, especially by the blessed, through divine adoption. [50] Hence, materially, grace is a finite accident, an entitative habit, but formally it is a formal participation in Deity as it is in it self, as it subsists in the three persons. Thus it is clearly evident that Deity as such in a certain sense surpasses being and intellection, since all absolutely simple perfections are identified in the eminence of Deity and can be naturally participated in, but Deity cannot be participated in naturally. (Cf. below, pp. 138 ff. : The dignity of sanctifying grace. ) First corollary. Our adoptive sonship is formally and physically a participated likeness of the eternal sonship of the Son of God. (Cf. St. Thomas on Rom. 8:29: "He... predestinated to be made conformable to the image of His Son"; the Tabula aurea, "Adoptio, " 21; Ia, q. 93, a. 4, 2; Ila Ilae, q. 45, a. 6; Illa, q. 3, a. 8; q. 23, a. I, 2, 3, 4. ) The reason is that, just as the Father communicates to His only-begotten Son the whole of His nature, without multiplication or division of this nature, so He communicates to us physically and formally, by an accidental gift, a participation in this divine nature, or in His intimate life, that we may see Him as He sees Himself immediately, although in a finite manner; for to participate is to take a part and to leave a part; Deity is substance in God, its participation is an accident in us. The principal texts of Holy Scripture on the divine adoption are the following: "For whosoever are led by the Spirit of God, they are the sons of God. For you have not received the spirit of bondage again in fear; but you have received the spirit of adoption of sons, whereby we cry: Abba (Father). For the Spirit Himself giveth testimony to our spirit, that we are the sons of God. And if sons, heirs also" (Rom. 8:14-17). "For whom He foreknew, He also predestinated to be made conformable to the image of His Son; that He might be the first-born among many brethren" {ibid., 8:29). "God hath predestinated us unto the adoption of children through Jesus Christ unto Himself, according to the purpose of His will" (Ephes. 1:5). "God sent His son... that we might receive the adoption of sons. And because you are sons. God hath sent the Spirit of His Son into your hearts, crying: Abba. Father. Therefore now he is not a servant, but a son; and if a son, an heir also through God" (Gal. 4:4-7). St. Thomas treats of our adoptive sonship particularly in Illa, q. 23, a. I, 2, 3, 4. He shows how divine adoption differs from human adoption (inasmuch as God by the gift of grace makes the man or angel whom He adopts fit for his inheritance). He shows especially how adoptive sonship through grace is a participated likeness of natural 50 Cf. on this subject our article: "La grace est-elle une participation de la Deite telle qu'elle est en soi?" Revue thomiste, July, 1936, pp. 470-85. The reply is in the affirmative. Thus, in this question it is not necessary to ask what the formal constituent of divine nature is according to our way of conceiving it; whether it is subsistent being itself or intelligence itself, we are concerned with Deity as it is in itself, which is in some ways above being and above intelligence, according as it eminently and formally contains these simple perfections absolutely. Cf. Cajetan In lam, q. I. a. 3, no. 4; q. I, a. 7, no. I; q. 13, a. 5, nos. 7, 10 ff. ; q. 39, a. 1, no. 7. sonship: as the only-begotten Son of God receives eternally the whole divine nature from His Father, the adoptive son of God receives, in time, a participation of the divine nature, or grace, the seed of glory, the beginning of eternal life. Adoption belongs to the whole Trinity, but is appropriated to the Father as its author, to the Son as its exemplar, to the Holy Ghost as engraving upon us the likeness of this exemplar. Second corollary. The existence and actual possibility of grace cannot be strictly proved by reason alone, since the supernatural substantially, taken formally, is also supernatural with respect to intelligibility; truth and being are convertible. For that which is essentially supernatural has no necessary, evident connection with things of the natural order; otherwise it would be reduced to the philosophical order, as is the existence of God as author of nature. Third corollary. Grace is nobler than all other created being, since it participates more perfectly in the divine good than any nature capable of being created. Hence St. Thomas says (below, la Ilae, q. 113, a. 9 ad 2): "The goodness of the grace of one (man) is greater than the goodness of the nature of the whole universe. " (Cf. Cajetan's Commentary on this, and Gonet. ) Confirmation. That is better which is loved more by God. But, as the Apostle says, God did all things for the sake of the elect (II Tim. 2:10), and therefore He loves the just more than all creatures of the natural order, as a father loves his son more than his fields, Iris house, and liis cattle. (Cf. Salmanticenses. ) Fourth corollary. For perfect knowledge of the value of grace we would need to know glory itself experimentally, just as the knowledge of the value of an infant's intelligence requires a knowledge of intellectual life in its full evolution. How great, then, is the evil of mortal sin! "If thou didst know the gift of God. " Thus the three orders of sensitive life, natural life, intellectual life, and the life of grace were clearly distinguished long before Pascal. Final doubt. Whether sanctifying grace of itself alone ensures one's being formally the adopted son of God. State of the question. Adoption is generally defined as "a gratuitous admission of a stranger into the inheritance of another. " According to revelation, God adopts men as children, as is evident from the Epistle to the Romans (8:15): "You have received the spirit of adoption"; from Galatians (4:5): "that we might receive the adoption of sons"; and from Ephesians (1:5): "Who hath predestinated us unto the adoption of children through Jesus Christ. " And this definition of adoption is, in fact, verified according as God gratuitously admits and elevates an alien into a beatitude which exceeds the natural requirements or rights of this person. This is generally accepted by the Fathers, especially Cyprian, Pope Leo, and Augustine. [5152 ] Moreover, adoptive sonship is taken either formally, as it consists in a relationship, or fundamentally, as the foundation of the aforesaid relationship. We are now inquiring what this foundation is. In the natural order natural sonship is formally the relationship, and fundamentally it is passive generation or nature received through generation. Hence, proportionately, the primary formal effect of sanctifying grace is the deification of the soul; the secondary formal effect is adoptive sonship. [’2] To the question thus stated the Nominalists replied, with Scotus and Durandus, that through sanctifying grace we are adopted sons of God. not on account of the very' nature of grace, but because God wished to concede this by way of an extrinsic favor. The Thomists maintain, on the contrary, that we are adoptive sons of God through sanctifying grace on account of its very nature, without looking for any extrinsic favor. To understand this teaching the difference between human and divine adoption must be kept well in mind. It is twofold: 1. Human adoption presupposes in the one adopted the same nature specifically as in the one adopting; it is otherwise in divine adoption. 2. The love which the man adopting bears toward the one adopted produces no physical effect in the latter, but only something moral and civil, that is, the right of inheritance. On the contrary, the love of God whereby He adopts men through grace is effective and efficacious, and by it He effects a participation in the divine nature, or sanctifying grace. Therefore this 51 Rouet de Journel, Enchir. patristicum, index theologicus, no. 359 52 This secondary effect is not present in Christ, since He is already the natural Son of God. Cf. Illa. q. 23, a. 4 sanctifying grace of itself is the foundation of the relationship of adoptive sonship; just as the communication of the whole divine nature, by eternal, quasi-passive generation of the Second Person of the Trinity, is the foundation of the relationship of natural sonship. Hence, as sanctifying grace is not merely a moral, but also a physical and formal, participation in the divine nature, it lays the foundation of adoptive sonship immediately, without the need of looking for any extrinsic favor. Confirmation. Habitual grace is nature proportioned to the beatific vision, that is, to the eternal inheritance. Likewise, we maintain, in opposition to Lessius, that the divinity of the Holy Ghost intrinsically united to us or assisting and dwelling in us does not produce, by way of form, adoptive sonship, since the form terminating spiritual generation is that by which the generated term lives, spiritually. But God is our life not formally, but only effectively. (Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 23. a. 2 ad 2, against the Master of the Sentences. ) We also hold, contrary to the opinion of Suarez, that to be the adopted son of God without habitual grace implies a contradiction. For there is required by this sonship at least an analogical conformity with God in His nature; but this is brought about only by habitual grace whereby man is spiritually begotten by God. Thus to live the divine life radically without grace implies a contradiction; without it man would have only natural justice, and not eventhat, since in the present state healing grace is required for the observance of the whole natural law. RECAPITULATION: THE DIGNITY OF SANCTIFYING GRACE Whether sanctifying grace is formally and physically a participation in infinite pure Act. This is a disputed question among Thomists. Cajetan, Gonet, and the Salmanticenses answer in the affirmative, since it is a participation in Deity. Curiel and certain others deny it, since, as they say, the infinite as such cannot be participated in, for it is always received in a finite way. John of St. Thomas, Billuart, and also the Salmantic enses reconcile these two opinions thus: Grace participates in the nature of infinite, pure Act not adequately and subjectively (since whoever receives it does so in a finite way) but objectively and inadequately, for he participates in what is proper to God, or Deity itself, as the root of strictly divine operations which terminate objectively in the Deity itself clearly seen and loved. The disagreement is rather a matter of terms than of ideas. John of St. Thomas says that grace is a participation in infinity objectively, as it is the likeness and splendor of the divine intellect; elevating the rational creature so that he may receive, as specifying, connatural object, God in His infinity, or rather we should say, in that He is God, according to the most eminent and proper reason of Deity. Deity as such, of which grace is a participation, in a certain sense surpasses infinity, which is a mode, as it were, of the attributes of God which are identified in the eminence of the Deity. As Gonet declares (De essentia gratiae, no. 52): "The beatific vision, which is the operation of consummated grace, corresponds to God as He is the infinite being and in His essence. Therefore consummated grace participates in the divine nature as it is an infinite being, " for it is the connatural principle of the beatific vision. Sanctifying grace does not take unto itself the whole infinity' of God, but infinity in a certain manner, or inadequately; that is, it has the divine essence for its connatural, immediate object; but it is not identified with this infinite object, nor does it comprehend it as God does. For this reason grace, like charity, can be increased infinitely (cf. Ila Ilae, q. 24, a. 7; Gonet, op. cit., for the solution of objections). First corollary. Habitual grace is a participation in the divine nature as a nature, just as charity is a participation in divine love as being its operation. But both are participations of the intimate life of God. In contrast to natural vegetative, sensitive, or intellectual life, it is said of grace that it is a participation in the divine nature or life as divine. Second corollary. Sanctifying grace is, through itself, directly, but secondarily, a participation in the nature of God as it is in the three persons; for the nature of God as such subsists as suchin three persons and has an infinite inward fecundity by way of the divine processions. Hence from grace rises charity, which is an inclination toward God as He subsists in three persons, and also from grace, in heaven, rises the light of glory and the vision of the Trinity itself. However, grace is not a participation in the personal divine fatherhood, since the adoptive sonship which follows from grace is a participated likeness in the eternal sonship of the Word; even by the eternal generation of the Word the divine nature is indeed communicated, but not the paternity. Therefore by divine adoption a participation of the divine nature is communicated, but not of the personal fatherhood. But from-the infusion of grace there does follow the adoptive sonship which renders us like the Word, who is the image of the Father, and from grace flows that charity which produces in us a likeness to the Holy Ghost. Third corollary. The infused virtues flow from sanctifying grace physically, as properties of the soul (Cf. Sahnanticenses. ) Fourth corollary. From the absolute power of God several kinds of sanctifying grace, essentially differing among themselves, cannot be bestowed, whatever some modern theologians may assert, for grace is a formal participation in the divine nature which is absolutely simple, nor can anything higher be conceived in which it would participate. Hence, whatever Father Billot may hold (De Verbo incarnato, thés. XVII, 6th ed., p. 208). not even in the most holy soul of Christ is habitual grace of a higher species than in any just man. although it is much more intense and extensive. Moreover, in C hrist this habitual grace is derived from the uncreated grace of union or from the Word terminating the human nature; but considered intrinsically. habitual grace is not of a higher species in C hrist than in us: it is always and everywhere a formal and physical participation of the divine nature; nor is it possible to conceive of anything higher in which it could participate than the Deity itself as such. If habitual grace in Christ were of a higher kind, so also would be His beatific vision, as Father Billot declares (ibid. ), and then the following principle would not be observed: habit and act are specified by their formal object, for the formal object of the beatific vision of Christ is identical with that of the beatific vision of all the other blessed in heaven. And on account of the absolute power, habitual grace, charity. and the light of glory, even in the most holy soul of C hrist, could always be increased. We cannot conceive of the highest possible degree of this participation, for between any degree, even the highest, and the Deity itself, there is always an infinite distance, as there is between the incomprehensive beatific vision on the one hand, and the uncreated, comprehensive vision on the other. (Cf. Illa, q. 10. a. 4 ad 3. and q. 7. a. 12 ad 2. ) Confirmation. If there were two graces of essentially different kinds, there would likewise be two charities of essentially different kinds and two lights of glory essentially distinct. But this is impossible, for the essential reason of charity is to tend supernaturally toward God as He is in Himself, to be loved with a love of esteem above all things, and the light of glory' is terminated in God as He is. No higher specifying object can be conceived, and habits are specified by their formal object. Fifth corollary. Hence in Adam before the fall and in Christ sanctifying grace was not of another kind than in us; but it did have other effects [’3] in them, how ever; in fact, even in the natural order the same human species has different effects in man and in woman. Thus grace causes repentance in us, but not in Christ since He was impeccable; in us it caused adoptive sonship, but not in Christ, for He was already the natural Son of God and therefore incapable of adoption. Likewise in the innocent Adam grace was the root of original justice which involves integrity of nature; tliis is not true in us. In the angels it does not produce the virtues of temperance and fortitude, since the angels have no passions. By' the same token, sanctifying grace remaining but one in species has nevertheless two states, that of the present life and that of heaven. In the former it requires faith and hope connaturally, but not in the latter, which, in turn, demands the light of glory and, after the resurrection, the glorification of the body. Nor is it to be wondered at, considering the diversity of these states, that the same grace is the root of different virtues. Sixth corollary. Sanctifying grace is absolutely more perfect than charity, the light of glory, or the beatific vision. 53 For an accidental form (as grace) perfects the subject into which it is received according to the mode and requirements of the latter in a diversity of subjects it produces diverse effects occasionally differing in species Thus grace does not produce in the angels vii which moderate the passions, as it does in us. which have their source in it, as an essence is more perfect than any of its properties; for grace participates in the divine nature, under the concept of nature, not under the concept of intellectual power or intellection or love. However, the beatific vision is more perfect, under a certain aspect, than grace, as second act is more perfect than first act. Thus a tree is something more perfect than its fruit, but the tree is rendered still more perfect when it bears fruit. Seventh corollary'. Specifically, sanctifying grace is absolutely more noble than the substance of any soul, even the soul of Christ. more noble than any angelic substance created or capable of being created; accidentally, however, according to its mode of being, that is, under a particular aspect, it may be less noble. With respect to the soul of Christ, cf. De verit., q. 27. a. I ad 6; and Ila Ilae. q. 23, a. 3: "Charity is absolutely more perfect than the essence of the soul, "just as the intellectual faculty, although an accident, is more noble than a stone. Eighth corollary. Grace is, then, more spiritual and incorruptible in itself than the human soul; "we have this treasure in fragile vessels. " However, sanctifying grace is absolutely less noble than the divine motherhood of the Word incarnate, for this motherhood by reason of its term belongs to the order of the hypostatic union, and this order surpasses not only the order of nature, but also the order of grace and glory. St. Thomas says (la, q. 25, a. 6 ad 4): "The Blessed Virgin, because she is the Mother of God, has a certain infinite dignity deriving from the infinite good which is God; and because of this nothing better than this can be made. " On this account the cult of hyperdulia is due to her (cf. Illa, q. 25. a. 5); for. as Cajetan declares, her "dignity borders upon the confines of divinity'. " Doubt. Whether actual grace disposing toward justification is a physical and formal participation of the divine nature. I reply that it is a physical, virtual, but not formal participation, as the seed is a participation in the generator as a power derived from it to produce a likeness of itself. It is not a formal participation, however, since it does not yet confer the power of eliciting connaturally supernatural operations of the order of grace. It is, as it were, a supernatural regeneration in process only, as we should say. referring to justification. Second doubt. Whether sanctifying grace formally procures the adoptive sonship of God and whether it alone can bring about such an effect (cf. Gonet. loc. cit. ). Adoption is usually defined as a gratuitous admission of a stranger into the inheritance of another. Thus an adopted son is distinguished from a son by nature in both human and divine applications. It is assumed as certain from faith drat the just man is an adopted son of God: "That we might receive the adoption of sons" (Gal. 4:5); "You have received the spirit of adoption" (Rom. 8:15); "Who hath predestinated us unto the adoption of children through Jesus Christ" (Ephes. 1:5). To the question as stated the reply is more commonly in the affirmative, since, just as natural sonship is a formally real relationship based on passive generation, or on nature received through generation, in like manner adoptive sonship is formally a real relationship based on a passive participation of the divine nature received through regeneration. This is true even independently of the subsequent acceptation of God. in opposition to the Nominalists, Durandus, and Scotus. This is confirmed by the fact that no other reality' can be the foundation of this real relationship: I) not indeed the Holy Ghost, whatever Lessius may say, since He assists us as an extrinsic cause, and is not the form by which anyone is regenerated as a child of God; 2) nor charity, which presupposes habitual grace as its root, as will be more clearly demonstrated later. First corollary. Hence, contrary to the followers of Suarez, Thomists hold that there is a contradiction implied in being the adoptive son of God without habitual grace. For this sonship requires an analogical conformity' to God in the divine nature; and it implies a contradiction that the creature be conformed analogically to God in His nature without a participation of the divine nature by grace. Thus by the very fact that the just man possesses grace he is the adoptive son of God and has a right to be received into glory. (Cf. Gonet, op. cit., no. 136. ) Second corollary'. The adoption of man as a son is common to the three persons, in that the act of infusing grace, since it is a free, external operation, is common to the whole Trinity as omnipotence is. However, as stated in Illa, q. 23. a. 2, active adoption is appropriated to the Father, according as adoptive sonship is a certain participated likeness in the eternal sonship. Moreover, to the extent that this adoption is brought about through grace, which is the work of divine love, it is appropriated to the Hob Ghost, the sanctifier. Third corollary. During the time that he is in the state of grace, the reprobate is an adopted son of God; and when the predestinate is not in the state of grace, he is not an adopted son of God. ARTICLE III. WHETHER GRACE IS IDENTICAL WITH VIRTUE, PARTICULARLY WITH CHARITY State of the question. We are not considering whether grace is identical with the acquired virtues, nor with faith or hope, for these can be possessed in the state of mortal sin, that is, without sanctifying grace. But since the state of grace is inseparable from charity, some were of the opinion that sanctifying grace was not really distinguished from charity. According to the Master of the Sentences, as quoted in the article, they seem to be distinguished only as concepts, since, for him, both grace and charity are the Holy Ghost indwelling and moving to the act of love. In the opinion of Durandus, they are distinguished in name only (Nominalism removes almost all real distinctions); Scotus declares them to be formally distinguished; according to certain others, they are distinguished virtually by reason of a diversity of functions. St. Thomas, those of his school and many outside of it maintain that they are really distinct. (Cf. De veritate, q. 27, a. 2. ) St. Thomas' conclusion is that sanctifying grace is something beyond the infused virtues which are derived from it, just as the natural light of reason is something beyond the acquired virtues derived from that light. 1. Scriptural proof. Holy Scripture speaks of grace and of charity as of two separate things. "The grace of our Lord Jesus Christ, and the charity of God" (II Cor. 13:13). "The charity of God is poured forth in our hearts, by the Holy Ghost, who is given to us" (Rom. 5:5); but He is given to us through grace, by reason of which He dwells in us. "The grace of our Lord hath abounded exceedingly with faith and love" (I Tim. 1:14). Likewise the Council of Vienne (Denz., no. 483) speaks of the baptized as those to whom "grace and the virtues" were imparted. The Council of Trent (Sess. VI, can. 7. Denz.. no. 799) declares that "the renewal of the inner man is brought about by the voluntary' acceptance of grace and the gifts"; canon II (Denz., 821) defines "man as not justified without grace and charity. " Moreover, in this sense the mind of the Council is interpreted by the Catechism of the Council (part 2, "Baptism. " chap. 38) wherein sanctifying grace is described, while not yet speaking of charity, and then (chap. 39) it is declared: "To this is added the most noble train of all the virtues, which are infused in the soul together with grace. " St. Augustine speaks in the same strain as quoted in the argument Sed contra (De dono persever., chap. 16): "Grace precedes charity. " But no reason can be adduced to explain why Holy Scripture, the Councils, and the Fathers, referring to a matter of dogma, should always understand one and the same thing under diverse names; it would be, at least, useless repetition; and since it occurs frequently, we may draw from these authorities, at least as more probable, the opinion that grace and charity are really distinct. 2. Theological proof, based on the definition of virtue and on a parallelism between the natural and supernatural orders. Virtue is really' distinct from the proportionate nature which it presupposes; as the acquired virtues from the nature of the soul. But the supernatural virtues presuppose nature elevated by sanctifying grace. Therefore the supernatural virtues, even charity, are really distinct from sanctifying grace. The major is based on the Aristotelian definition of virtue, namely, "a disposition of a perfect thing is that which is best"; in other words, virtue presupposes a nature proportioned to itself, is a perfection of a power corresponding to that nature, and hence is realty distinct from nature as already constituted. Thus the acquired virtues, such as wisdom and prudence, are really distinguished from the light of reason which they presuppose and which existed before the acquisition of these virtues. Regarding the minor: As human virtue presupposes human nature which it disposes in the direction of its natural end. so does supernatural virtue presuppose nature elevated to supernatural being, which it disposes aptly toward its consequent supernatural end. Moreover, there is no doubt but that charity is a supernatural virtue and that it is supernaturally communicated by grace. Therefore charity is really distinguished from sanctifying grace which it presupposes, as a habit which is immediately operative is differentiated from an entitative habit by which the essence of the soul is itself elevated, as will be made more evident in Article 4. But even here in the reply to the third objection it is declared: "Grace is reducible to the primary species of a quality [that is. of a habit] ; nor is it indeed the same as a virtue, but rather a certain habit [entitative habit] which is presupposed by the infused virtues as their principle and root. " Opponents object: But the same accidental form can simultaneously elevate a nature and dispose it to operate, as heat causes wood both to be hot and to give off heat. Reply. 1. The same accidental form cannot be received by two really distinct subjects; but the elevation of a nature must be effected in the essence of the soul, while charity, as a virtue, must be in some faculty, that is, the will. Therefore. 2. Byr the same token one and the same accidental form would be capable of producing the effects of all the virtues and gifts. And hence there would be no distinction between the three theological virtues, the four infused cardinal virtues, and the seven gifts, a distinction which is made by the whole of tradition on the basis of Holy Scripture itself. 3. In any order, operation follows being; especially does connatural operation presuppose a proportionate principle of being. The answer to the example of heat in the wood is: the disparity arises from the fact that heat is not a virtue in the wood, but a simple sensible quality. | S || Confirmation of the conclusion. 1. God hath first loved us (I John 4:10); but the effect of this love is grace; but charity is the proximate principle by which we love God. 2. Grace is a participation in the divine nature: charity is a participation in the divine will. 3. Every' inclination follows upon form: but charity is an inclination of the supernatural order; therefore it presupposes the supernatural form upon which it follows. 4. God makes no less provision for the soul in the supernatural order than in the natural order; but in the natural order the faculties follow upon the essence of the soul; therefore in the supernatural order the infused virtues follow upon grace. And what we have said applies also to the angels, since their essence is not immediately operative, and thus differs from the divine essence w Inch alone is its own being and act. Objection. But then faith and hope could not exist without habitual grace, as properties cannot exist without essence. Reply. Faith and hope remain in the sinner as in a subject to which they are not connatural, but praeternatural. And they do not have the element of virtue except with grace. A sinner can indeed believe, but not so well as one ought " Nor is Scotus' distinction, "formal-actual " admissible, which would be a medium between a real distinction and a rational distinction based on the reality, for there cannot be given a medium between a distinction existing before being considered by our mind and one which does not exist before being considered by the mind: there is no medium between tw o opposites. And the distinction which existed before being considered by our minds, however slight it may be. is nevertheless real to believe. Thus, in the natural order, heat is in fire as in a connatural subject, but in water as in a subject under compulsion, for heat is not a property of water, which is naturally cold. However, the same effects are often attributed to both grace and charity, since they are inseparably connected. The proper effects of charity thus proceed from grace as from a root. (See Billuart for less important objections. ) ARTICLE IV. WHETHER HABITUAL GRACE IS IN THE ESSENCE OF THE SOUL AS IN A SUBJECT State of the question. Those who say that grace is identical with charity hold grace to be attributable to the will and not immediately to the essence of the soul. Thus Scotus (II Sent., dist. 26), who adopted as his own doctrine St. Thomas' objections, as he frequently did. St. Thomas' conclusion: Habitual grace, inasmuch as it is presupposed by the infused virtues, is in the essence of the soul as in a subject, and not in any faculty. Proof 1. Commonly, as found in the argument Sed contra: "By grace we are regenerated as children of God. according to Holy Scripture. " But generation has its term first in the essence and then in the powers. It is so in the natural order; why not in the supernatural order ? Proof 2. In particular, as a corollary of the preceding article, thus: Even' perfection of a rational faculty' is a virtue or good operative habit. But habitual grace is not a virtue, but is presupposed by the infused virtues (cf. preceding article). Therefore habitual grace is not in the faculties of the soul but in the very essence of the soul presupposed by the faculties. Hence it is a participation in the divine nature by a certain regeneration or re-creation, whereas charity is a participation by the will in divine love, and faith a participation of divine knowledge in the intellect, although all these infused habits are formally participations in the intimate life of God. But we are now considering them rather under their material aspect, that is, on the part of tire subject in which they reside. Reply to third objection. The soul is the subject of grace, since it resides in a species of intellectual nature, or in the intelligent soul, although the infused virtue of chastity is in the sensitive appetite. Confirmation. It would be unbecoming for the essence of the soul to be less perfected supernaturally than its own faculties. The whole man would not be supernaturally complete, with respect both to being and to operation: and its radical vitality would not be elevated. Such would be the result if Scotus' teaching w ere true. First corollary. Glory, taken as the root of the light of glory and of charity, is likewise in the essence of the soul; for it is grace consummated. It is also an entitative habit, for St. Thomas says in several places that habitual grace, the seed of glory, is a certain beginning of eternal life, for it is the same habit. On the contrary, infused faith, which is obscure, is not a certain beginning of the beatific vision. Second corollary. Grace is the radical principle of merit, but charity is its proximate principle. Third corollary. Mortal sin, being the privation of sanctifying grace, is death to the soul in the essence of the soul, and in that it is a vicious habit or act it is in the will, or in some other faculty under the command of the will. As a complement to this question of the essence of grace, two articles in the treatise De lege nova (la Ilae, q. 106, a. I) should be read on whether the new law is writtenor set in the heart. The reply is as follows: "That whichis most powerful in the law of the New Testament, and in wliich all its virtue consists, is the grace of the Holy Ghost, wliich is given through the faith of Christ. Therefore the new law is principally that very grace of the Holy Ghost, which is given to the faithful of Christ.... Hence St. Paul declares that 'the law of the spirit of life, in Christ Jesus, hath delivered me from the law of sin and of death' (Rom. 8:2).... Therefore it may be said that the new law is primarily a law set in the heart, but secondarily it is a written law. " Likewise the Summa (la Ilae, q. 106, a. 2) declares that "the law of the Gospel (by means of what is primary in it) justifies. " And in the answer to the second objection {ibid. ), St. Thomas states: "On account of what it is of itself [as habitual grace] it gives sufficient help to avoid sin, " that is, of itself it bestows the power not to sin, although as long as we are wayfarers the power to do the opposite remains in us. Again (Illa, q. 8, a. I, 2, 5), Christ as man merited for us all the graces we receive and He communicates them to us now as instrumental, physical cause of our divinization. (Cf. Illa, q. 62, a. 5; q. 43, a. 2; q. 48, a. 6. ) According to Illa, q. 62, a. 2: "Sacramental grace adds, over and above [habitual] grace generally so called and above the virtues and gifts, a certain divine help toward the attainment of the end of the sacrament. " In the reply to the first objection of the same article St. Thomas maintains that "the grace of the virtues and gifts perfects the essence and powers of the soul sufficiently with respect to the general ordering of the acts of the soul (so it was in Adam before the Fall and in the angels in whom did not reside Christian grace strictly speaking, which was conferred upon men by Christ the Redeemer). But with respect to certain special effects which are demanded by a Christian life, sacramental grace is required. " Thus it may also be said that in the angels and in Adam before the Fall there resided supernatural grace, as a participation of the divine nature, but not however as Christian grace proceeding from Christ the Redeemer and forming souls in the image of Christ crucified. Sacramental grace is not anew infused habit really distinct from habitual grace, but it adds over and above ordinary grace a certain right to actual graces to be received at the appropriate time and corresponding to the special end of the sacraments; for example, the grace of holy orders confers the right to the actual graces necessary to celebrate Mass. And this moral right is a relationship which requires a realbasis; the realbasis is sacramental grace, properly speaking, inasmuch as it is really permanent in the soul. And the more probable opinion, as Thomists assert, is that it is a special mode and a special force of sanctifying grace, which overflow into the acts of the virtue. (Cf. St. Thomas, De veritate, q. 27, a. 5 ad 12. ) Thus we speak of priestly charity, of priestly prudence. John of St. Thomas, the Salmanticenses, Contenson, Hugon, Merkelbach, and several other Thomists accept this explanation. Accordingly, as sanctifying grace is the principle of the sanctification of the just, whether men or angels, so is the sacramental grace of baptism the principle of Christian sanctification, and the sacramental grace of holy orders the principle of sanctification of priests, who are the ministers of Christ. We must now compare habitual grace with the graces gratis datae and with actual graces. CHAPTER IV: QUESTION 111 THE DIVISIONS OF GRACE HAVING arrived at a definition of sanctifying grace, we must now consider the divisions of grace. As a matter of fact, at the beginning of this treatise, when we were establishing our terminology, we enumerated the various significations of created grace which may be reduced to the following outline. [diagram page 150] created grace 1. internal 1.1. sanctifying 1.1.1. habitual 1.1.1.1. grace of the virtues and gifts 1.1.2. actual 1.1.2.1. effic ac ions or suffic ient 1.1.2.2, operative orc ooperative __ ___________________ 1.2. 2. 1.1.2.3. prevenient or subsequent gratis data 1.2.1. for example, the gift of prophecy, of tongues external 2.1. such as preaching of the gospel, the written divine law, miracles, the example of Christ and the saints, opportunities of doing good or avoiding evil. In the present question St. Thomas examines the basis of these principal traditional divisions. He does so in five articles. The first and the last two deal with the graces gratis datae as compared with sanctifying grace; the second and third are concerned with the division into operative and cooperative grace, prevenient and subsequent grace, this latter division being the occasion for a discussion of efficacious and sufficient grace. ARTICLE I. WHETHER GRACE IS PROPERLY DIVIDED INTO SANCTIFYING GRACE AND GRACE GRATIS DATA State of the question. This article endeavors to explain the text of I Cor. 12:8-10, wherein St. Paul enumerates nine graces gratis datae: "To one indeed, by the Spirit, is given the word of wisdom: and to another, the word of knowledge, according to the same Spirit; to another faith in the same spirit; to another the grace of healing in one Spirit: to another the working of miracles; to another prophecy; to another the discerning of spirits; to another diverse kinds of tongues; to another interpretation of speeches"; and further {ibid., 12:31 and 13:1 f. ): "I show unto you yet a more excellent way. If I speak with the tongues of men and of angels, and have not charity, I am become as sounding brass or a tinkling cymbal. And if I should have prophecy and should know all mysteries and all knowledge, and if I should have all faith so that I could remove mountains, and have not charity, I am nothing. " (Cf. St. Thomas on this Epistle. ) From this contrast has arisen the traditional division between the graces gratis datae, also called charismata, and sanctifying grace. The statement of the question will be more manifest from the problems raised at the beginning of the article. Reply. St. Thomas shows the appropriateness of this traditional twofold division. 1. In the argument Sed contra, on the authority of St. Paul who attributes both characteristics to grace, namely, that of making us pleasing ("He hath graced us, " Ephes. 1:6) and that of being a gratuitous gift (Rom. 11:6). Hence grace may be differentiated according to whether it possesses but one of these notes, that is. being a free gift (and every grace is gratuitous) or both notes, not only that of being given freely, but also that of making us pleasing. [diagram page 151]___________________________________________________________________________ Grace, or a gratuitous gift • which renders pleasing • which does not render pleasing This is explained more clearly in the answer to the third objection: "Sanctifying grace adds something beyond the reason of graces gratis datae,... that is, it makes man pleasing to God. And therefore grace gratis data, which does not have this effect, retains merely the generic name, " just as brute beasts are called "animals"; the name of the genus is applied to the least distinguished member. Hence this division is between an affirmation and a negation. In other words, grace in general is defined as a supernatural gratuitous gift bestowed by God upon a rational creature; and grace thus defined is divided according to whether it renders him pleasing or does not. Thus grace gratis data is not opposed, strictly speaking, to the other, in the sense that it camiot be the object of merit, for neither can the first sanctifying grace be merited, nor the last, that is, final perseverance, nor efficacious actual grace to persevere in good acts throughout the course of life. Nevertheless, as stated in the body of the article, grace gratis data is granted over and above the merits of the person. (Cf. below, q. 114. ) 2. By a theological argument the appropriateness of the aforesaid divisions is proved from a consideration of the ends. Since grace is ordained to the end that man may be restored to God. grace is twofold according to the twofold restoration to God. But the restoration to God is twofold, thus: 1. uniting man himself to God immediately, and this is effected by sanctifying grace; 2. not of itself uniting man to God. but causing him to cooperate in the salvation of others, and this is brought about by grace gratis data. Therefore this traditional division is correct. In other words, the union with God is either formal or only ministerial This division is adequate since to render pleasing and not to render pleasing are contradictory opposites to one another and there can be no middle ground between them. Grace gratis data is per se primarily ordained to the salvation of others, or "unto profit. " [55] Sanctifying grace is per se primarily ordained to the salvation of the recipient, whom it justifies. It should be noted that these two statements are qualified as "per se primarily, " that is. essentially and immediately; however, grace gratis data may secondarily lead to the salvation of the recipient, provided, that is, it be employed by charity. Likewise, sanctifying grace may secondarily lead to the salvation of others through the example of virtue. But the primary end of each is the one assigned to it above. Corollary. Unlike sanctifying grace, the graces gratis datae may sometimes be found in the wicked or sinners; for although sinners neglect their own salvation, they may procure the salvation of others and cooperate in it. after the manner of those who built Noah's ark and yet were submerged in tire waters of the flood. Thus Caiphas prophesied as one divinely inspired, saying "It is expedient... that one man die for the people" (John 11:50). Again, as narrated in the Book of Numbers (23:22 ff. ). Balaam, although a soothsayer and idolater, received the gift of prophecy; likewise the sibyf in spite of being apagan. (Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 172. a. 4);with respect to prophecy (q. 178, a. 2), the wicked can perform miracles in order to confirm revealed truths; but if the gift of prophecy, which is the highest among the graces gratis datae, exists in the wicked, with still greater reason is this true of the others. Hence St. Paul himself says: "I chastise my body,... lest perhaps, when I have preached to others, I myself should become a castaway" (I Cor. 9:27). Doubt. Whether "sanctifying grace" can be taken in a twofold sense. Reply. Undoubtedly. 1. Strictly, it refers to habitual grace, distinct from the infused virtues, by which we are justified or formally rendered pleasing to God. 2. Broadly, it includes that which is ordained to the justification of its subject, whether antecedently as stimulating grace which disposes us for justification, or concomitantly, or consequently, as, for example, supernatural helps, the infused virtues, the gifts, the increase of grace, and glory, which is the consummation of grace. In the present question sanctifying grace is thus broadly taken in contrast to grace gratis data. And thus the aforesaid division is adequate. Vasquez did not take this extended use of the term into account when, in commenting on the article, he declared this division to be insufficient since faith, hope, and actual helps could not be found under either of its members. Hence sanctifying grace is identical here with the "grace of the virtues and gifts with their proportionate helps, " which St. Thomas speaks of (Illa, q. 62, a. I): w hether sacramental grace adds something over and above the grace of the virtues and gifts. Indeed to sanctifying grace also belong the sacramental graces which are the proper effects of the sacraments; for example, baptismal grace, the grace of absolution, of confirmation, nutritive grace (cf. p. 148 above). Corollary. It is of great importance to determine clearly whether infused or mystical contemplation, according as it is distinguished from private revelations, visions, and even from words of wisdom or knowledge, pertains to sanctifying grace and is in the normal way to sanctity, or to the graces gratis datae as something extraordinary. Theologians generally teach that infused contemplation belongs to sanctifying grace, or to the grace of the virtues and gifts; it is something not properly extraordinary but eminent, for its proceeds not from prophecy but from the gifts of wisdom and understanding as they exist in the perfect. Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 180, on contemplative life, after he 55 Cf. I Cor. 12:7 considered graces gratis datae in particular. [56] Let us pass immediately to articles four and five which deal with the same material, because afterwards there will be a longer consideration of articles 2 and 3 with reference to operative and cooperative grace, sufficient and efficacious grace. ARTICLE IV. WHETHER GRACE GRATIS DATA IS ADEQUATELY SUBDIVIDED BY THE APOSTLE (I COR. 12:8 - 10) State of the question. St. Paul here enumerates nine graces gratis datae. St. Thomas shows the appropriateness of this division. Many Thomists. Gonet among them, hold this division to be adequate; so also does Mazella. On the other hand. Medina. Vasquez. Bellarmine, Suarez, and Ripalda do not consider this division all-embracing, but maintain that St. Paul was enumerating only the principal graces. Suarez would further add to them the priestly character, jurisdiction in the internal forum, and the special assistance conferred upon the Sovereign Pontiff. St. Thomas seems to judge the enumeration given by St. Paul to be entirely sufficient and he defends it brilliantly in a remarkable discussion both here and in Iris commentary on I Cor. 12 (cf. De revelatione, I. 209). It should be noted that St. Thomas, treating of these graces in particular (Ila Ilae, q. 171-79) in that case divides them according as they pertain either to knowledge or to speech or to action; and under the heading "prophecy" he includes all those which refer to the knowledge of divine things, except words of wisdom and knowledge. For those which pertain to prophecy are knowable only by divine revelation, whereas whatever is included under words of wisdom and science and interpretation of speeches can be known by man through his natural reason, although they are manifested in a higher mode by the illumination of divine light. Confirmation from the refutation of objections. 1. The graces gratis datae exceed the power of nature, as when a fisherman is fluent in words of wisdom and science; they are thus differentiated from the natural gifts of God which likewise do not make us pleasing to God. [diagram page 155]___________________________________________________________________________ Graces gratis datae ordained for instructing one's neighbor in divine things 1. for possessing the fullness of knowledge of divine things 1.1. faith 1.1.1. regarding princ iples, 1.1.1.1. that is, a supereminent certitude of faith, for example, in preaching 1.2. utterance of wisdom 1.2.1. regarding the principle conclusions known through their highest causes (as by St. Paul, St. Augustine. St. Thomas; cf. Ila Ilae, q. 177, a. 1) 1.3. utterance of knowledge 1.3.1. concerning example and effects, (as by St. Matthew, St. James, St. Gregory the Great, St. Alphonsus Liguori) 2. for confirming the revelation of divine tilings 2.1. operating 2.1.1. grace of healing by which is manifested the benignity of God toward the sick 2.1.2. performance of miracles by which is manifested God's omnipotence, for example, the sun standing still 2.2. knowing 2.2.1. prophecy regarding future contingencies; (cf. Ila Ilae, q. 171 ff.) 2.2.2. discernment of spirits regarding the hidden things of the heart 3. to facilitate of the word the conveying of God to one's hearers 3,1, kinds of tongues ?6 We have treated this question at length elsewhere: Christian Perfection and Contemplation', The Three Ages Of the Interior Life when a preacher speaks several tongues; this is a higher mode; when a preacher speaking one language is understood by all; this grace is below prophecy interpretation of speeches 3.2.1. reducible to prophecy and therefore higher than the gift of tongues; for example. Joseph interpreting Pharaoh's dream. 3.1.1. 3.2. 2. The faith of which it is a question here is not the theological virtue present in all the faithful, but a super-eminent certitude of faith by which a man is rendered capable of instructing others in the things that pertain to faith 3. The grace of healing, the gift of tongues, and the interpretation of speeches possess a certain special motivation impelling faith, according as they excite admiration or gratitude. In the grace of healing the benignity’ of God toward the misery of man shines forth; in the performance of miracles, such as the opening of a passage through the sea or the stopping of the sun in its course, the omnipotence of God appears. 4. Wisdom and knowledge are included among the graces gratis datae not because they are gifts of the Holy Ghost, but because, by means of them, a man may instruct others and vanquish his opponents. Therefore thev are purposely set down in the present enumeration as utterances of wisdom or knowledge. (Cf. St. Thomas, Ila Ilae. q. 45, a. 5 and on I Cor. 12, lect. 2. ) According to Thomists, in opposition to Suarez, the sacramental character and jurisdiction in the internal forum, and the assistance of the Holy Ghost do not belong to the graces gratis datae, but to the ministries and operations which St. Paul himself distinguishes from the graces gratis datae. "There are diversities of graces, but the same Spirit; and there are diversities of ministries, but the same Lord; and there are diversities of operations, but the same God. " And they are indeed distinguished, as Billuart observes, inasmuch as grace gratis data concerns only an act which manifests faith, whereas ministration or the ministry refers to the authority’ to perform some act with respect to other men. such as the apostolate. the episcopate, the priesthood, or any other dignity. An operation, moreover, is the exercise of a ministry. Thus in the Old Testament priests and prophets were differentiated. Doubt. Whether the aforesaid graces gratis datae reside in man after the maimer of a habit or rather as a transient movement. (Cf. Gonet. De essentia gratiae. ) Reply. Gonet replies: Generally they are present as transient movements, such as the gift of prophecy, the grace of healing or of prodigies, the discerning of spirits. This is evident from the fact that a prophet or wonder-worker does not prophesy or work miracles whenever he wills. (Cf. Ila Ilae, q. 171, a. 2. ) However, according to the same authority, faith, words of wisdom and of knowledge do exist after the manner of habits, -since one who receives them uses them when he so wills. In Christ all these graces were present as habits for two reasons. 1. On account of the hypostatic union He was an instrument united to the divinity. 2. He had supreme power, by reason of which He disposed of all creatures and hence at will He could perform miracles or cast out demons, as explained in the treatise on the Incarnation, Illa, q. 7, a. 7 ad 1. ARTICLE V. WHETHER GRACE GRATIS DATA IS SUPERIOR TO SANCTIFYING GRACE This question is of great importance with respect to mystical theology’; for example, which are higher among the works of St. Theresa, those which pertain to sanctifying grace or those pertaining to graces gratis datae? State of the question. It seems that grace gratis data is superior: 1. because the good of the Church in general, to which graces gratis datae are ordained, is higher than the good of one man, to which sanctifying grace is ordered; 2. because that which is capable of enlightening others is of greater value than that which only perfects oneself; it is better to enlighten than merely to shine; and 3. because the graces gratis datae are not given to all Christians, but to the more worthy members of the Church, especially to the saints. However, in spite of these arguments, St. Thomas' conclusion is in the negative; and so is that of theologians generally. The reply is: Sanctifying grace is much more excellent than grace gratis data. First proof, from the authority of St. Paul, who, after enumerating the graces gratis datae, continues: "And I show unto you yet a more excellent way. If I speak with the tongues of men and of angels, and have not charity, I am become as sounding brass or a tinkling cymbal. And if I should have prophecy and should know all mysteries and all knowledge, and if I should have all faith so that I could remove mountains, and have not charity, I am nothing" (I Cor. 12:31-13:2). But prophecy is the highest of all the graces gratis datae (cf. Ila Ilae, q. 171), and this is said to be below charity, which pertains to sanctifying grace. Therefore. In his commentary on the first Epistle to the Corinthians (chap. 13), St. Thomas thus explains the words "I am nothing, " that is, with respect to the being of grace, described in Ephesians (2:10): "For we are His workmanship, created in Christ Jesus in good works"; likewise II Cor. 5:17, and Gal. 6:15. [57] In the same place it is shown that charity surpasses all these charismata in three respects: 1. From necessity, since without charity, the other gratuitous gifts do not suffice. 2. From utility, since it is through charity that every evil is avoided and every good work performed. "Charity is patient,... beareth all tilings, hopeth all tilings, endureth all tilings. " 3. From its permanence, for "charity- never falleth away, " as St. Paul declares, whether prophecies shall be made void or tongues shall cease. Hence charity is said to be the bond of perfection uniting the soul to God and gathering together all other virtues to ordain them toward God. Therefore can Augustine say: "Love and do what you will. " Second proof from theological argument. The excellence of any virtue is higher according as it is ordained to a higher end; and the end is superior to the means. But sanctifying grace ordains men immediately to union with his final end; and the graces gratis datae ordain him toward something preparatory to his final end, since by miracles and prophecies men are led to conversion. Therefore sanctifying grace is much more excellent than grace gratis data. In a word, sanctifying grace unites man immediately to God, who dwells in him; on the other hand, grac e gratis data serves only to dispose others for union with God. This argument appears even more profound when we observe that sanctifying grace, inasmuch as it unites man immediately to God, his final supernatural end, is supernatural substantially. It is indeed the root of the theological virtues which are immediately specified by their formal supernatural object (objectum formale quo et quod), and it is the seed of glory, the beginning of eternal life which is essentially supernatural. On the contrary', the graces gratis datae are generally supernatural only with respect to the mode of their production, in the same way as miracles. As a matter of fact, with respect to this supernaturalness, the division of the charismata corresponds to the division of miracles given by St. Thomas (la, q. 105, a. 8); the comparison may be made as follows: [diagram page 159]__________________________________________________________________________ To the miraculous 1. substantially, 1.1. for example, to the glorification of the body, corresponds prophecy of future events of a natural order 2, with respect to the subject in which it resides. 57 In fact, without charity our will is turned away from God as final end. Hence we read in I John 3:14: "We have passed from death to life, because we love the brethren. He that loveth not abideth in death. " 2.1. 3. for example, to a nonglorious resurrection, corresponds the knowledge of the secrets of hearts, which can be known by human revelation modally, 3.1. for example, to the sudden cure of a fever, corresponds the gift of tongues, for we can acquire languages naturally, although not suddenly. cf. De revelatione, I, 205 ff. Thus the great difference becomes evident between the supernatural substantially and the miraculous substantially: in the former "substantially" means formally, by virtue of its formal object; in the latter "substantially" means effectively, or concerning an effect the substance of which cannot be produced by a created cause in any manner or in any subject, such, for instance, as the glorification of the body. Hence below intrinsically supernatural knowledge, such as the beatific vision or infused faith, there exist the following three kinds of effectively supernatural knowledge the object of which is intrinsically natural. 1. Effectively, with respect to the substance of cognition, such as the prophetic knowledge of future natural events taking place at a remote time. This exceeds every created intellect, not by reason of the essential supernaturalness of its object, as would be that of the Trinity, but by reason of the uncertainty or indetermination of the future, for example, the date when some war would end. 2. Effectively, with respect to the subject in which it resides, such as the knowledge of a natural object already actually existing, but removed in regard to place or exceeding the faculty of vision of this particular man, although not of all men (Ila Ilae, q. 171, a. 3). Likewise the knowledge of the secrets of hearts which are known naturally’ by the person whose secrets they are. 3. Effectively, modalh'. such as the instantaneous knowledge of some human science or unknown tongue without human study. Thus the supernaturalness of prophecy is of an inferior order to the supernaturalness of divine faith Therefore St. Thomas says (111 Sent., d. 24, a. I ad 3): "Although prophecy and faith treat of the same matter, such as the passion of Christ, they do not do so in the same way: for faith considers the Passion formally under the aspect of something which borders on the eternal, that is, according as it was God who suffered, although materially it considers a temporal event. This is not true of prophecy. " But what has been said of the supernaturalness of prophecy, the highest of all the graces gratis datae, can be said of all the charismata, as is very evident in the case of the gift of tongues, the grace of healing, the performing of prodigies, and the discernment of spirits. The same may be said of utterances of wisdom and knowledge and of the interpretation of speech, for these latter three supply in a supernatural way for what would be attained naturally by acquired theology or hermeneutics. Thus, in general, the charismata are supernatural modalh only, and therefore sanctifying grace, which is supernatural substantially, as a participation in the divine nature, is "much more excellent. " as St. Thomas declares. Confirmation of the aforesaid conclusion from the refutation of objections. First objection. The common good of the Church is better than the good of one man. But sanctifying grace is ordained only to the good of one, whereas grace gratis data is ordered to the common good of the Church. Therefore. Reply. The major is to be distinguished: the common good which is in the Church is below the separated common good, that is, God: granted; otherwise, denied. I distinguish the minor: sanctifying grace is ordained to the good of the individual and also to the separate common good, that is, to God to whom it unites us immediately: granted; otherwise, denied. Hence, above the common good of the Church, which is the ecclesiastical order, there is the separate common good, which is God Himself, to whom sanctifying grace unites us immediately. Similarly, above the common good of an army, which is its order, there is the common good considered separately, namely, the good of the country. On this account St. Thomas says later (Ila Ilae. q. 182. a. 1-4) that contemplative life, which is immediately ordained to the love and praise of God, is, in an absolute sense, better, higher, and more meritorious than the active life, which is ordained toward the love of neighbor and to the common good of the Church not considered apart. Therefore did Christ say (Luke 10:42): "Mary hath chosen the best part, which shall not be taken away from her. " Many moderns would do well to read this response to the first objection. Again St. Thomas declares (Ila Ilae, q. 182, a. I ad I): "It not only pertains to prelates to lead the active life, but they should also excel in the contemplative life"; which St. Gregory had already expressed in the words: "Let the leader be eminent in action, and sustained in contemplation above all others. " Second objection. It is better to enlighten others than merely to be enlightened; but by the graces gratis datae man enlightens others; by sanctifying grace he is only enlightened himself. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the major: it is better than merely to be enlightened to enlighten others formally: granted; to enlighten others merely by disposing them: denied. I distinguish the minor: that man. by grace gratis data, enlightens others formally: denied; by disposing them, granted; on the contrary he is formally enlightened by sanctifying grace. For, by the graces gratis datae man cannot produce sanctifying grace in another, but only offer him certain disposing or preparatory factors toward justification, such as preaching to him or performing miracles. God alone directly or through His sacraments infuses sanctifying grace. Similarly, in the natural order, St. Thomas maintains, the heat by which fire acts is not more estimable than the form of fire itself. I insist. Then St. Thomas was wrong when he said later (Ila Ilae, q. 188, a. 6) that the apostolic or mixed life "proceeding from the fullness of contemplation is to be preferred absolutely to contemplation, since it is a greater thing to enlighten than merely to shine. " Reply. The apostolic life is preferred to simple contemplation inasmuch as it includes this and something more; on the contrary, grace gratis data does not include sanctifying grace and something more. Third objection. That which is proper to the more perfect is better than that which is common to all. But the graces gratis datae are gifts proper to the more perfect members of the Church. Therefore they are higher than the grace common to all the just, as reasoning power is superior to sensation. Reply. There is a disparity, for sensation (which is common to all animals) is ordained to ratiocination. But on the contrary the graces gratis datae (which are proper) are ordained to the conversion of men, in other words, to sanctifying or justifying grace. First corollary. Sanctifying grace or the grace of the virtues and gifts belongs to the normal supernatural. But it exists in three degrees, that of beginners, proficients, and perfect; in other words, the purgative, illuminative· and unitive ways, the last being the age of maturity of the spiritual life. Second corollary. The graces gratis datae belong to the extraordinary supernatural, so called not so much in relation to the Church as to the individual, for example, private revelations, visions, and internal words pertaining to prophecy. Third corollary. Infused contemplation, proceeding from the gifts of wisdom and understanding as they exist in the perfect, is therefore not something extraordinary, like prophetic revelation, but something normal and eminent, that is, in the normal way of sanctification. Fourth corollary. Cajetan In Ilam Ilae, q. 178, a. 2 (quoted by Father Del Prado, De gratia et libero arbitrio, p. 268) : "It is a most pernicious error to consider the gift of God in the working of miracles to be greater than in the works of justice. And this, contrary to the popular idea and common error of humankind, which judges men who perform miracles to be saints and, as it were, gods, whereas these dull-minded people have almost no esteem whatever for just men. The complete opposite ought to be considered of high value, as it truly is. " Although the sanctity of the servants of God is outwardly manifested by miracles, the saint who performs more miracles than another is not, on that account, a greater saint. Fifth corollary. Del Prado (op. cit., p. 261): "The graces gratis datae may exist without sanctifying grace for the manifesting of divine truth: for of themselves they do not justify. Hence St. Thomas says, commenting on I Cor. (13, lect. I): 'It is obvious with regard to prophecy and faith, that they may be possessed without charity. But it is to be remarked here that firm faith, even without charity, produces miracles. Wherefore the apostle Matthew (7:22). in reply to those who will ask: 'Have we not prophesied in Thy name... and done many miracles?' declares that our Lord will reply: 'I never knew you. ' For the Holy Ghost works prodigies even by the wicked, just as He speaks truth through them. " Sixth corollary. However, the graces gratis datae are. in the saints, also a manifestation of their sanctity (Del Prado, ibid. ); cf. St. Thomas on I Cor. (12, lect. 2); whence it is said in Acts (6:8) that "Stephen, full of grace and fortitude, did great wonders and signs among the people. " ARTICLE II. WHETHER GRACE IS PROPERLY DIVIDED INTO OPERATIVE AND COOPERATIVE GRACE State of the question. This article explains the division made by St. Augustine (De gratia et libero arbitrio, chap. 17); it should be carefully studied, for Molina maintains (Concordia, q. 14. a. 13, disp. 42, p. 242) that St. Thomas misinterprets Augustine. After giving his own interpretation. Molina says: "This is manifest in the clearest light, although Augustine has been understood otherwise by St. Thomas (la Ilae. q. III. a. 2 and 3). by Soto and by certain others. " In fact, Molina attempts to demonstrate (ibid., p. 243) that Augustine cannot be interpreted in any other way, in the light of faith. Since this is a most serious charge, the question must be considered attentively. The principal point at issue between Thomists and Molinists on this subject may be formulated thus: For Molina (Concordia, p. 565). Suarez. [?8] and their disciples, operative actual grace urges only by moral and not by physical impulsion, and leads only to indeliberate acts, but never of itself alone to free choice or consent. But cooperative actual grace, according to Molina, produces, by moral impulsion, a free choice, with simultaneous concurrence, in such a way that man is determined by himself alone. Thus man and God seem to be rather two causes acting coordinately, like two men rowing a boat, than two causes of which one is subordinate, acting under the impulsion of the superior cause. For Thomists, on the other hand, operative actual grace does not merely urge by moral impulsion, but operates physically as weU, with respect to the performance of an act and sometimes even leads to free choice; that is, when man cannot move himself to this choice deliberately by virtue of a previous higher act, such as the moment of conversion to God or the acts of the gifts of the Holy Ghost, which proceed from a special inspiration. Cooperative actual grace, moreover, is also a physical impulsion under which man, by virtue of a previous act of willing the end, moves himself to will the means to the end. Let us examine: 1. the text of St. Augustine, 2. the interpretation of Molina, 3. the article of St. Thomas referred to and also the reply to objections (la Ilae, q. 9, a. 6 ad 3). The teaching of St. Thomas will be defended. 1. St. Augustine. The text of St. Augustine (De gratia et libero arbitrio, chap. 17) reads thus: "God Himself works so that we may will at the beginning what, once we are willing, He cooperates in perfecting; therefore does the Apostle say: 'Being confident of this very thing, that He who hath begun a good work in you. will perfect it unto the day of Christ Jesus' (Phil. 1:6). That we should will therefore, He accomplishes without us; but when we do will and so will as to do. He cooperates with us. " 2. Molina's opinion. For Molina, operative grace is nothing more than prevenient grace morally urging us; cooperative grace assists us. Hence, according to Molina, "a person assisted by the help of less grace may be converted, although another with greater help does not become converted and continues to be obdurate. " Cf. De auxiliis divinae gratiae, Bk. Ill, chap. 5, no. 4; cf. Del Prado, De gratia et libero arbitrio I, 228 Concordia, p. 565. As Father Del Prado observes {De gratia, I, 226): "Molina departs from the ways of St. Thomas in the explanation of the nature of divine grace, operative and cooperative, and refuses to admit that the grace of God alone transforms the wills of men or that only God opens the heart. Consequently, whether Molina will have it or not, although it is God who stands at the gate and knocks, it is man who begins to open and man alone who, in fact, does open it.... Hence the beginning of consent, for Molina, resides in man, who alone determines himself to will, whereas God, who stands at the gate knocking, awaits his will. " Before this beginning of consent proceeding from us alone, Molina maintains, however, against the Semi-Pelagians, that there are moral divine impulsions drawing us as well as the indeliberate movement of our will, but that they are equal and even stronger in him who is not converted. This is corroborated by some of his well-known propositions; for instance, in the Concordia under the heading "auxilium" in the index, we read: "It may happen that with equal assistance, one of those who are called may be converted and another not converted" (p. 51). Furthermore, "he who is helped by the aid of less grace may be converted, although another with more does not become converted and perseveres in liis obstinacy" (p. 565). Hence, as Lessius declares, "not that he who accepts does so by his freedom alone (since there was grace attracting him) but that the turning point arose from his freedom alone and thus not from a diversity of prevenient helps. " (Cf. Salmanticenses, De gratia, tr. XIV, disp. 7. ) St. Thomas, on the contrary, referring to the words of St. Matthew (25:15), "And to one he gave five talents, and to another two, and to another one, " comments: "He who makes more effort has more grace, but the fact that he makes more effort requires a higher cause. " Again, with reference to the Epistle to the Ephesians (4:7), "to everyone of us is given grace, according to the measure of the giving of Christ, " he repeats this observation, and similarly in la Ilae, q. 112, a. 4, on whether grace is equal in all men. The root of the disagreement is manifold, but the principal point of contention is the one mentioned by Molina himself in the Concordia (q. 14, a. 13, disp. 26, P. 152). "There are two difficulties, it seems to me, in the teaching of St. Thomas (la, q. 105, a. 5); the first is that I do not see what can be that impulse and its application to secondary' causes, by which God moves and applies them to act.... Wherefore I confess frankly that it is very difficult for me to understand this impulsion and application which St. Thomas requires in secondary causes. But, as Father Del Prado observes {op. cit., p. 227): "In this article, such application and impulsion is clearly affirmed even in free secondary causes, and so, with respect to the interior act of the free will, 'the will is situated as moved only and not as moving, God alone being the Mover. ' Here, as we shall presently see, physical premotion conquers, rules, and triumphs. Thence proceed the anger and the unmentioned recriminations which Molina gives vent to against the teaching of St. Thomas, under the pretense of vindicating St. Augustine. " For Molina holds {Concordia, disp. 42. P. 242) that according to St. Augustine {De gratia et libero arbitrio, chap. 17) "whatever God effects in us that is supernatural, until the moment when He leads us to the gift of justification, whether we cooperate in it by our free will or not, is called 'operative grace'; that, however, by which He henceforth assists us to fulfill the whole law and persevere... is called 'cooperative grace. '... And this is plainly the sense and intention of Augustine in this place when he draws a distinction between operative and cooperative grace, which will be obvious in the clearest light to anyone examining that chapter, notwithstanding the fact that St. Thomas understands Augustine otherwise in the two articles quoted (la Ilae, q. Ill, a. 2 and 3), as well as Soto {De natura et gratia. Bk. I. chap. 16) and some others. " However. Molina is obliged to explain on the following page (p. 243) the words of St. Paul to the Philippians (2:13): "It is God who works in you. both to will and accomplish, " with regard to which Augustine had said: "Therefore, that we will is brought about by God. without us; but when we will, and so will as to act, He cooperates with us. " With regard to this text, Molina says: "But neither does Augustine mean to assert that we do not cooperate toward willing, by which we are justified, or that it is not effected by us, but by God alone. That certainly would be both contrary to faith and opposed to the teaching of Augustine himself in many other places. " Referring to these last words of Molina, Father Del Prado {op. cit. I, 226) declares: "Does St. Thomas teach something contrary to faith in drawing the distinction between operative and cooperative grace ?... From the lofty and profound teaching of St. Thomas propounded in this article, wherein all is truth and brilliance, does something follow which is contrary to the Catholic faith and the teaching of Augustine himself ?... Molina departs from the ways of St. Thomas (since he will not admit that God applies and moves the will beforehand, but).... He holds that, while God, drawing the soul morally, stands at the gate and knocks, it is man who begins to open, and man alone who actually does open. " In the Apocalypse (3:20) we read: "I stand at the gate, and knock. If any man shall hear My voice, and open to Me the door, I will come in to him, and will sup with him. and he with Me. " But man does not open it alone; he opens in fact according as God knocks efficaciously. Otherwise how would the words of St. Paul be verified: "What hast thou that thou hast not received ?" In the business of salvation, not everything would then be from God. Conclusion with respect to Molina's opinion. For Molina and Suarez and the Molinists in general, operative grace is nothing else but prevenient grace which urges morally, but does not really assist, [59] and only cooperative grace assists the soul. [60] Suarez himself admits this. For the beginning of consent, according to Molina, comes from man, who alone determines himself to will: while God almost waits for our consent. Indeed, for Molina, "he who is aided by the help of less grace may be converted, whereas another, with greater help, is not converted and persists in his obduracy" (op. cit., p. 365). Thus the salient point at issue, as Father Del Prado says (op. cit., I, 223). is: "Whether the free will of man. when moved by the gratuitous impulsion of God to accept and receive the gift of the grace of justification, at that very instant of justification, is in a condition of being moved only, and not of moving, while God alone moves. When God stands at the gate of the heart and knocks, that we may open to Him, is it man who alone opens his heart, or God who begins to open and is the first to open and. having opened, confers upon us that we, too. may ourselves open to Him?" This is the question which St. Thomas solves in that celebrated article 2 and explains more fully below, in question 113. But Molina jumps from what precedes our justification to what follows it, and is not willing to examine the very moment when the free will of man is moved by God, through the love of charity, and from one who is averse to Him is made a convert to Him. and is intrinsically transformed by God who infuses sanctifying grace. " This is the crux of the present controversy. 3. St. Thomas' opinion. St. Thomas rightly interprets St. Augustine (cf. Del Prado, op. cit., I, 224 and 202); for Augustine declares: [61] "God, cooperating with us, perfects what He began by operating in us; because in beginning He works inns that we may have the will, and cooperates to perfect the work with us once we are willing. For this reason the Apostle says (Phil. 1:6): 'Being confident of this very thing, that He, who hath begun a good work in you, will perfect it unto the day of Christ Jesus. ' That we should will is, therefore, accomplished without us; but once we are willing, and willing to such an extent that we act, He cooperates with us; however, without either His operation or His cooperation once we will, we are incapable of any good works of piety. With regard to His bringing it about that we will, it is said in Philippians (2:13): 'For it is God who worketh in you.... to will. ' But of His cooperation, when we already are willing and willingly act, it is said: 'We know that to them that love God, all things work together unto good' (Rom. 8:28). " St. Augustine reiterates this opinion in chapters 5 and 14 of the same book. Again, writing to Boniface (Bk. II, chap. 9): "God accomplishes many good things in man which man does not accomplish (operative grace); but man does nothing good which God does not enable him to do (cooperative grace). " This is observed by the Council of Orange (C. 20. Denz., no. 193). Moreover, according to Augustine, operative grace is not simply grace urging equally him who is converted and him who is not, for Augustine repeats in several places, with reference to predestination: "Why does He draw this man and not that ? Do not judge if you do not wish to err" (Super Joan., tr. 26; cf. la, q. 23, a. 5). This teaching of Augustine is mentioned by St. Gregory (Moral., Bk. XVI, chap. 10) and by St. Bernard (De gratia et libero arbitrio, chap. 14); both are quoted by Del Prado (op. cit., I, 203). In article 2 of the present question there are two conclusions, one concerning actual grace and the other habitual 59 Cf. Suarez, De auxiliis divinae gratiae, Bk. Ill, chap. 5. no. 4 60 This is contrary to the answer ad 3 of the present article: "By operative grace man is aided by God to will what is good. 61 De gratia et libero arbitrio, chap. 17 grace. [62] First conclusion. Actual grace is properly divided into operative and cooperative grace. a) Council of Orange. Above and beyond the aforesaid authority of St. Augustine, this conclusion is supported by the Council of Orange (Denz., no. 177, can. 4): "It must be acknowledged that God does not wait upon our wills to cleanse us from sin, but also that we should wish to be cleansed by the infusion and operation of the Holy Ghost in us. " In canon 23 it is said that God prepares our wills that they may desire the good. Again (can. 25, Denz., no. 200): "In every good work, it is not we who begin... but He (God) first inspires us with faith and love of Him, through no preceding merit on our part. " All these texts pertain to operative grace, as does the beginning of canon 20 (Denz., no. 193), as follows: "God does many good works in man wliich man himself does not do. " But the second part of this canon applies to cooperative grace, thus: "But man does no good works which God does not enable him to do. " b) Theological proof. An operation is not attributed to the thing moved, but to the mover; for example, the fact that a cart is drawn is attributed to the horse. But in the first interior act, the will is situated as moved only, whereas God is the mover: whereas in the exterior act, ordered by the will, the will is both moved and moves. Therefore in the first act the operation is attributed to God. and therefore the grace is termed operative; in the second act the operation is attributed not only to God, but also to the souL and the grace is termed cooperative. The major is clear with regard to an inanimate thing that is moved, as the cart is moved by the horse, but if the thing moved is a living thing and the operation is a vital act, it is elicited, indeed, from it. Thus, the very first act of the will is elicited vitally from it; however, the will is not said to move itself to it. properly speaking, since, as explained above (la Ilae, q. 9, a. 3). "the will, by the very' fact that it desires the end, moves itself to will those things which conduce to the end; just as the intellect, by the fact that it knows a principle, reduces itself from potency to act, with respect to the knowledge of the conclusion. " To move oneself is. indeed, to reduce oneself from potency to act. Hence it is not to be wondered at that, in this act wherein the will caimot move itself by virtue of a previous efficacious act of the same order, it should be referred to as moved only, and the operation attributed to God. The minor needs explanation. What is this interior act ? It is manifold. It is that first of all by which we desire happiness in general, and for this, supernatural help is not required (cf. la Ilae, q. 9, a. 4. c. 2); it is particularly, according to St. Thomas {ibid. ), "that the will which previously desired evil now begins to will the good. " This is explained (Ila, q. 86. a. 6 ad I): "The effect of operative grace is justification of the wicked, as stated in la Ilae, q. 113, a. 1-3, wliich [justification] consists not only in the infusion of grace and the remission of sins, but also a movement of the free will toward God, which is the act of formed faith, and a movement of the free will in relation to sin. wliich is the act of penance. But these human acts are present as effects of operative grace, produced in the same way as the remission of sins. Hence the remission of sin is not accomplished without an act of the virtue of penance, even if it is the effect of operative grace. " These acts are therefore vital, rather are they even free, but the will does not move itself toward them, strictly speaking, by virtue of a previous efficacious act of the same order, since beforehand, a prior act of this kind did not exist. The following synopsis, which we have already given in the introduction and which can now be explained, should be read in an ascending order, from the natural to the supernatural [diagram page 170]__________________________________________________________________________ our intellect (means) is moved by God 1. in the supernatural order 1.1. (6) by special inspiration which we receive with docility, in accordance with the gifts of 62 Operative and cooperative grace, according to St. Thomas; cf. la Ilae. q. Ill, a. 2. o.. 4; a. 3. c; 11 Sent., dist. 26, a 5. o., 4; De veritate, q. 27, a. 5, 1, 2; II Cor.. 6, lect. (at the beginning); Illa. q. 86, a. 4. 2; a. 6 ad 1: q. 88, a. 1, 4 2. the Holy Ghost - operative grace 1.2. (5) to determining to exercise the infused virtues - cooperative grace 1.3. (4) to become converted to its final supernatural end - operative grace in the natural order 2.1. (3) by the special inspiration, for example, poetic, philosophic, or strategic - operative motion 2.2. (2) to determine 2.2.1. this true good - cooperative motion 2.2.2. this apparent good - cooperative motion 2.3. (1) to desire happiness in general upon - operative motion We explained this elsewhere (Christian Perfection and Contemplation, p. 285). From the same point of view Father Del Prado has made an excellent study of the present article (op. cit., I, 206, 235; II, 220); and before him, Cajetan, commenting on this article, as well as Soto, Lemos, and Billuart. Wherefore St. Thomas declares in the reply to the second objection: "Through the movement of the free will, when we are justified, we consent to the justice of God. " But man does not move himself, properly speaking, to justification; he is moved to it, freely of course, but moved nonetheless; hence it is the effect of operative, not cooperative grace. [63] This operative grace given at the instant of justification is, as Father Del Prado states (ibid., II, 220), a kind of introduction to all the free movements toward the good, meritorious for salvation, a quasi door into the supernatural order, and, as it were, the first step in the work of divine predestination. And this first act of charity is rather a simple willing of the final end than election, for election as such, properly so called, belongs to those things that are means to an end. Cf. Ila Ilae. q. 24, a. I ad 3: "Charity, the object of which is the final end, should rather be said to reside­ in the will than in free choice. " Hence operative grace includes not only vocation to the Christian life or the prompting by which God knocks at the gate (wherein our cooperation is non-existent; they precede our consent at any time whatever), but also the movement by which we are justified, freely consenting to it. Thus we read in Ezechiel (36:25 f. ): "I will pour upon you clean water, and you shall be cleansed from all your filthiness.... And I will give you a new heart, and put a new spirit within you: and I will take away the stony heart out of your flesh, and will give you a heart of flesh. " Again in the Acts of the Apostles (16:14): "whose heart [Lydia's] the Lord opened to attend to those things which were said by Paul. " Hence, when God says (Apoc. 3:20): "Behold, I stand at the gate and knock, " it is not man who begins to open and separates himself from sinners. Rather, as God opened the heart of Lydia, so does He open the heart of any of the just at the instant of justification. "God begins to open, He first opens, and in doing so, confers upon us that we, too, may open to Him, " as Father Del Prado so well expresses it (op. cit., I, 223). The third example of operative grace is the special inspiration we receive with docility by means of the gifts of the Holy Ghost, according to Cajetan (cf. la Ilae, q. 68, a. 1-3), since "the gifts are certain habits by which man is perfected so as to obey the Holy Ghost promptly.... But man, thus acted upon by the Holy Ghost, also acts, according as it is by free choice, " as stated in the same article 3, ad 2. Hence these operations proceeding from the gifts, for instance, from the gift of piety in the will, are vital, free, and meritorious, and yet the will does not, 63 St. Thomas had also said, la Ilae q. 55, a. 4 ad 6: "Infused virtue is caused in us by God, without our action, not however without our consent"; and further, la Ilae, q. 113, a. 3: "By infusing grace God at once moves the free will to accept the gift of grace, in those who are capable of this movement. " As Del Prado rightly observes, op. cit., 1, 213: The will cannot strictly move itself to this first act of charity, foras a supernatural conclusion is not contained in a natural principle, neither is a super-natural choice contained in man's primary natural intention. In fact, before the gift of justifying grace, the will of man is turned away from God on account of mortal sin. Hence it is God who must begin to move the free will of man determinately by grace toward the initial volition of supernatural good, as stated in the famous reply to the third objection, la Ilae, q. 9, a. 6. Similarly, Soto, De nat. et gratia, chap. 16. This is the true interpretation of St. Thomas given by Cajetan, Soto, Lemos, etc. ; also by the Salmanticenses, disp. V, dub. VII, no. 165. properly speaking, move itself to perform them, as it moves itself by deliberation to works of virtue in a human manner, but is specially moved by the Holy Ghost. This is well explained by St. Thomas in his Commentary on the Epistle to the Romans (8:14, lect. 3), a beautiful commentary on the present article. Regarding the words: "Whosoever are led by the Spirit of God, they are the sons of God, " he writes as follows: "They are said to be led who are moved by some superior instinct: thus we say of brutes, not that they act, but that they are led or impelled to act, since they are moved by natural instinct, and not by personal movement, to perform their actions. Likewise the spiritual man is inclined to perform some act, not, as it were, mainly by the movement of Iris own will, but by an instinct of the Holy Ghost. " This does not, however, prevent spiritual men from using their will and free choice, since what the Holy Ghost causes in them is precisely the movement of their will and free choice, according to Phil. 2:13: "For it is God who worketh in you. both to will and to accomplish. " In the explanation of the minor, we now come to the question of cooperative grace. This is conferred for good works in which our will is not only moved, but moves itself, that is. when, already actually willing the final supernatural end, it converts itself to willing the means conducive to that end. This act is said to be external, although it may be only internal, since it is commanded by the will in virtue of a previous efficacious act of the same order. Thus it is in the use of the infused virtues, by deliberation properly so called, that the act is performed in the human mode, for example, when the will commands an act of justice or religion or fortitude or temperance, by virtue of a previous act of love of God. Not only are these acts vital, free, and meritorious, but the will properly moves toward them or "determines itself to will this or that, " as is said in the well-known reply to the third objection, la Ilae, q. 9, a. 6. It is this cooperative grace that is referred to in Sacred Scripture; indeed there is even a comparison made with operative grace; for example, in Ezech. 36:27: "And I will put My spirit in the midst of you [operative grace] : and I will cause you to walk in My commandments, and to keep My judgments, and do them [cooperative grace] . " Again in I Cor. 15:10: "But by the grace of God, I am what I am [operative grace] ; and His grace in me hath not been void, but I have labored more abundantly than all they: yet not I, but the grace of God with me. " This latter is cooperative grace. The Angelic Doctor always speaks in harmony with these texts. According to him, under operative grace, the will elicits its act vitally, in fact, it freely consents to the divine motion or inspiration, but it does not strictly move itself by its own proper activity in virtue of a previous efficacious act of the same order, for this previous efficacious act is wanting at that time; for example, in justification, in the acts of the gifts of the Holy Ghost, such as the gift of piety. With respect to justification, St. Thomas declares (la Ilae, q. Ill, a. 2 ad 2): "God does not justify us without ourselves, since by the movement of free will when we are justified we consent to the justice of God. However, this movement is not the cause of grace, but its effect; hence the whole action pertains to grace. " Again, he states (Illa, q. 86, a. 4 ad 2): "It pertains to grace to operate in man, justifying him from sin, and to cooperate with man in right action. Therefore the remission of sins and of the guilt deserving of eternal punishment belongs to operative grace, but the remission of guilt which merits temporal punishment pertains to cooperative grace, that is, according as man, enduring sufferings patiently w ith the help of divine grace, is also absolved from the guilt of temporal punishment.... the first effect is from grace alone, the second from grace and free will. " (See also q. 86, a. 6 ad 1. ) It is previously declared (q. 85, a. 5 C. ): "Penance as a habit is immediately infused by God. without any principal operation on our part, but not however without our disposing ourselves to cooperate by some acts. " Conclusion of Father Del Prado {op. cit., I, 211): By operative grace God operates in us without our acting or moving ourselves, but not without our consent. Cf. a. 2: Thus in the instant of justification and in the operation of the seven gifts. In fact, certain operative grace is even antecedent in time to our consent, such, for instance, as vocation and admonition when God stands at the gate and knocks before it is opened. Here, however, the free consent may, broadly speaking, be called cooperation on our part; but not in the strict and formal sense in which the term is used by St. Thomas in this article. On the contrary, by cooperative grace, God works in us, not only with our consent, but with our action or motion. This is the Thomistic interpretation of St. Augustine's teaching; it is eminently profound and in full conformity with faith. Corollary. Thus the opposition between St. Thomas' doctrine and that of heresy is manifest. Of the operative actual grace by which we are justified (cf. Del Prado, op. cit., I, 213): Calvin holds that free will is moved without any action on its own part, and is merely passive. Jansen holds that free will is moved necessarily, and camrot resist even if it wills to do so; Pelagius holds that free will begins to move itself to this first volition; Molina holds 1. that free will is moved by virtuous, indeliberate impulses which, willy-nilly, are supernatural. 2. Then it begins to deliberate within itself, freely accepting them. In his first contention, Molina borders on Jansenism; in the second he does not seem sufficiently removed from Pelagius. In both respects, the opinion of Molina deviates from the teaching of St. Thomas. As declared in the reply to the third objection, grace is not called "cooperative" in the sense that God here places Himself in the position of a secondary agent; He ever remains the principal agent. But the will also moves itself in this case "once the end is taken for granted" in the intended act, and God assists it in the pursuit of this intended end. The second conclusion is that habitual grace can also be referred to as operative and cooperative (cf. end of article) since it has two effects: 1. it justifies the soul; this is operative grace, not effectively but formally, that is. it makes pleasing, just as whiteness makes a tiling white, as stated in the reply to the first objection; 2. it is the root principle of meritorious works, which proceed from the free will; in this sense it is cooperative. First doubt, arising from the reply to the fourth objection (cf. Del Prado, op. cit., I. 228): Whether operative and cooperative grace may be the same grace. Reply. Yes. if it is a question of habitual grace, which is at the same time justifying (formally) and the root principle of meritorious works. This is clearly stated here in the answer to the fourth objection and in article 3 ad 2, where it is clearly a question of habitual grace, which is said to remain numerically the same in glory, where it is consummated Cf. also De veritate, q. 27, a. 5 ad I, and Illa. q. 60. a. 2; q. 72. a. 7. Sacramental grace is a mode of habitual grace and is applied with various effects. But if the question is about actual grace, then operative grace and cooperative grace are not one and the same numerically; for the reason is the same for actual grace and for the act of the will, of which it is the principle and beginning. But the act is twofold, interior wherein the will does not move itself, exterior wherein it does. Therefore there are likewise two actual graces, for actual grace passes and ceases with the veiy operation toward which it moves. John of St. Thomas and the Salmanticenses hold this opinion. In fact sometimes, after an act proceeding from operative grace, there is not elicited an act for which cooperative grace is required, as is evident in the case of one who. immediately after absolution and justification, sins, by not performing the act of virtue which he ought to perform. In such a one. operative grace efficaciously produced justification freely accepted, but it did not produce the follow ing act. To produce it a new actual grace is required, that is. cooperative grace, for there is a new passage from potency to act. and whatever is moved to a new supernatural act. is moved supernaturally by another. Operative actual grace and cooperative actual grace are therefore distinct, since at times the first is given without the second or vice versa. But if the superior and inferior acts are simultaneous, as in infused contemplation which is prolonged by some discourse, or an inspiration of the gift of council which is simultaneous with an act of prudence, then perhaps it suffices that operative grace should be given, provided that, according to God's decree, it contains cooperative grace eminently; it is then more perfect than if it did not contain it. Second doubt. Whether operative actual grace requires a twofold motion, namely, moral on the part of the object and physical on the part of the subject. (Cf. Del Prado, op. Cit.. I. 233. ) Reply. I reply in the affirmative, together with John of St. Thomas and Father Del Prado; for operative grace first enlightens the intellect, then touches the will and causes a sudden desire for the object proposed through the representation of the intellect; and this is the inspiration that opens the heart, as the heart of Lydia was "opened to attend to those things which were said by Paul" (Acts 16:14). Hence operative grace not only excites by moral movement, but also operates physically, so that by it the heart of man is opened and led not only to indeliberate acts but sometimes to consent as well, for example, in justification or in acts of the gifts of the Holy Ghost. Third doubt. What are the effects of operative grace in us ? There are three. (Cf. Father Del Prado, op. cit., I, 234. ) 1. The enlightenment of the intellect and the objective pulsation of the heart: this is a moral movement prior to any consent; thereupon the acts are indeliberate, and with respect to this stage operative grace is nothing but a grace which urges. 2. The application of the free will to the holy affection or action, that it may be converted to God; this application is the complement in the secondary cause of the power to operate. 3. The very act of willing, applied to the action, namely, the very act of believing, hoping, and loving: in these acts the will does not remain passive, but elicits the acts freely. However, the will does not properly move itself to such an act as a result of a preceding act, since this act is first in the order of grace and relates to the final end. Hence, contrary to the opinion of Molina, operative grace determinately moving toward these acts is more than a mere urging, and yet liberty is safeguarded, according to St. Thomas. Fourth doubt. Whether cooperative grace produces in us three similar effects. Undoubtedly, for cooperative grace is also a previous movement according to a priority not of time but of causality. But these three effects are in another way. since with cooperative grace the will moves itself on account of some preceding act: thus it wills, presupposing the end already intended. On the contrary, with operative grace the will wills by tending toward the end. and the act of the will resembles that first act of the angels discussed in la, q. 63, a. 5, or that first act of the soul of Christ which is considered in Illa. q. 34. a. 3. In the first instant of His conception, Christ merited not incarnation but the glory of immortality’, just as an adult at the instant of justification acquires not the grace of justification but the subsequent grace. Final corollary. We may now read again the well-known reply to the third objection of la Ilae, q. 9. a. 6, and easily grasp its meaning: "Occasionally God moves some men especially toward willing something determinate which is good, as in those whom He moves by grace, as stated below. " that is. in our article 2. This is operative grace moving determinately. but with which liberty' still remains. SOME FALSE NOTIONS CONCERNING OPERATIVE AND COOPERATIVE GRACE (CF. SALMANTIC ENSES) Operative grace does not consist in an indeliberate act. according as it depends upon God, as Ripalda would have it. since an indeliberate supernatural act presupposes operative help moving one to this act. Nor does it consist in an indeliberate act. with God's assistance, as Suarez holds, for God is not united to us in the maimer of an operative power. Again, in opposition to Alvarez and Gonet, operative grace is not a simple movement apply ing a previous one. for operative grace thus understood pertains to all operations of the w ill, indeliberate as well as deliberate, as these authors admit, whereas St. Thomas declares that operative grace, specifically' so called, pertains only to the act of the will by which it is moved toward something freely', but does not move itself by discursive deliberation. Cooperative grace is not the indeliberate act itself inclining toward deliberate consent, because cooperative grace, and not this indeliberate act. has an infallible connection with the deliberate operation to which it moves us and which, in fact, it produces, since by such grace God cooperates and influences the eliciting of the aforesaid act. But the indeliberate affection, left to itself, has no infallible connection with deliberate assent, since we often resist a sudden inspiration or inclination: therefore cooperative grace cannot consist in an indeliberate affection; but there must be added a motion which joins the indeliberate act with the deliberate act or which ensures that the deliberate act is effective. Cf. below, p. 230, the opinion of Gonzales, where it is a matter of the fundamental distinction between efficacious and sufficient grace. ARTICLE III. WHETHER GRACE IS PROPERLY DIVIDED INTO PREVENIENT AND SUBSEQUENT GRACE State of the question. This article is intended to explain the classical division of grace, according to Augustine, De natura et gratia, chap. 31, and ad Bonifacium, Bk. II, chap. 9. as here cited at the end of the article. These terms should be carefully defined that it may be clear wherein lay the error of the Pelagians and Semi-Pelagians, who denied the necessity of prevenient grace. According to them, generally, every internal grace was subsequent with respect to free will; only external preaching of the word was antecedent, according as the beginning of salvation came from us and not from God. Thus did they interpret the words of Apoc. 3:20: "I stand at the gate, and knock. If any man shall hear My voice, and open to Me the door, I will come in to him, and will sup with him, and he with Me. " We shall presently see that grace can never be thus termed "subsequent" with respect to free will, but only in the sense that it follows another grace or another effect of grace; cf. below, la Ilae, q. 112, a. 2: "Whatever preparation (for grace) may be present in man is derived from the help of God moving the soul to good"; and in IV Sent., d. 17, q. I, a. I, solut. 2 ad 2: "Our will is entirely attendant upon divine grace and in no way before hand. " Conclusion. Grace, habitual as well as actual, is properly divided into prevenient and subsequent. Scriptural proof, in the argument Sed contra; namely, that the grace of God proceeds from His mercy. But it is said (Ps. 58:11): "His mercy shall prevent me, " and again (Ps. 22:6): "Thy mercy will follow me. " Therefore. Likewise in the prayers of the Church; the collect Pretiosa: "Anticipate, O Lord, we beseech thee, our actions by Thy inspiration, and continue them by Thine assistance; that every one of our works may begin always from Thee, and through Thee be ended. " The collect for the Sixteenth Sunday after Pentecost: "O Lord, we pray Thee that Thy grace may always go before and follow us. " And the collect of Easter Sunday: "Grant that the vows Thou inspirest us to perform, Thou wouldst thyself help us to fulfill. " Similarly on the authority of St. Augustine, here cited in the body of the article, from De natura et gratia, chap. 31 : "(God) precedes us that we may be healed; He follows us that, even healed, we may yet be invigorated. He precedes us that we may be called; He follows us that we may be glorified. He precedes us that we may live piously: He follows us that we may live with Him forever, since without Him we can do nothing. " Theological proof. Grace is properly classified according to its various effects. But there are five effects appointed to grace: 1. that the soul may be healed; 2. that it may will the good; 3. that it may efficaciously perform the good it wills; 4. that it may persevere in the good; 5. that it may attain to glory. Therefore the grace causing the first effect is properly termed "prevenient" with respect to the second effect, and as causing the second it is called "subsequent" in relation to the first effect; and so with the rest. Thus the same act is at once prevenient and subsequent with respect to different effects. Corollary. Thus grace is called prevenient with respect to some following act, although it is also prevenient witii respect to the act toward which it moves immediately, according as it is previous to it with the priority of causality. And grace is not said to be subsequent in relation to free will, as Pelagius held, but relative to another grace or effect of grace. As St. Thomas remarks (De veritate, q. 27, a. 5 ad 6): "Prevenient and subsequent grace may be understood in another way with respect to the man whom it moves; thus prevenient grace causes a man to will what is good, and subsequent grace causes him to perform the good which he has willed. " As Augustine declares in the Enchiridion, chap. 32: "He precedes the unwilling, that he may will, and follows the willing lest he will in vain. " Reply to first objection. Since the uncreated love of God for us is eternal, it is always prevenient. (Cf. Del Prado, op. cit., I, 247. ) Corollary 2. Both operative and cooperative grace, since they move toward diverse acts, may be called prevenient and subsequent. Doubt. Whether prevenient and subsequent grace may be the same grace numerically. The solution is found in the reply to the second objection, that is, in the case of habitual grace, yes; but in that of actual grace, no, for the same reason as for operative and cooperative grace. For it is evident that the same habitual grace, numerically, is called prevenient inasmuch as, justifying us, it precedes meritorious works; it is called subsequent inasmuch as it will be consummated, thus it is called glory. " In fact, St. Thomas expressly states here in the reply to the second objection: "Subsequent grace pertaining to glory is not different numerically from prevenient grace by which we are justified now; for as the charity of the wayfarer is not made void but perfected in heaven, so also can this be said of the light of grace, for neither of them bears any imperfection in its principle. " But if it is a question of actual grace, which ceases with the ven act toward which it moves immediately and of which it is the beginning, then it is multiplied along with the acts enumerated above, as we said before of operative actual grace and cooperative actual grace. To complete this Question III on the division of grace, two articles must be added since the Council of Trent and the condemnation of Jansenism: 1. The distinction between exciting or stimulating grace and assisting grace, which was considered by the Council, Sess. VI, chap. 5; 2. The difference between sufficient and efficacious grace, in respect to which the Protestants and Jansenists erred. THE DIVISION OF ACTUAL GRACE INTO STIMULATING AND ASSISTING GRACE (CF. DEL PRADO, O.P.. CIT., I, 243) This division is explained at the Council of Trent, Sess. VI. chap. 5 (Denz., no. 797): "It is declared, moreover, that the beginning of this very justification in adults is received from God through Christ Jesus by prevenient grace (can. 3). that is, by His vocation, in that none are called on account of their own existing merits; that they who were turned away from God by sin, may be disposed by His stimulating and assisting grace to become converted to their own justification, freely (can. 4 and 5) assenting to and cooperating with the same grace. " According to this text, grace rousing one from the sleep of sin by moral movement, that is, by enlightenment and attraction, and grace assisting one to will the good, by the application of the will to its exercise, are included under prevenient grace, which precedes the free consent of man's w ill, whereby we consent to justification and may be prepared for it. Hence this prevenient grace to which the Council refers is the same as the operative grace considered by St. Thomas in article two, especially in the reply to the second objection: "God does not justify us without ourselves, since by the movement of free w ill, when we are justified, we consent to the justice of God. However, this movement is not the cause of grace [as the Semi-Pelagians held] , but its effect; hence the whole operation belongs to grace. " (Cf. Del Prado, De gratia, I, 228. ) Thus is corroborated our interpretation of article two, that is: operative grace is not only stimulating but assisting. Under Sess. VI, chap. 5 of the Council the same doctrine is explained as in article two of the present question (III). The Council of Trent, Sess. VI, can. 4 (Denz., no. 814) uses the term "moving grace" for assisting grace. Doubt. Whether the prevenient grace which stimulates the intellect and assists in the application of the will is absolutely prior to our consent, or subsequent to it. How are we to understand the following text of the Apocalypse (3:20) ? "Behold. I stand at the gate and knock. If any man shall hear My voice, and open to Me the door, I will come in to him. " Reply. This grace is, with respect to its efficient cause, absolutely prior to our consent, according to St. Thomas (la Ilae, q. Ill, a. 2 ad 2; q. 113, a. 8 c. ). At the same instant: 1. there is an infusion of grace; 2. a movement of the free will with respect to God; 3. a movement of the free will in regard to sin; 4. the remission of sin. Similarly in the answers to the first and second objections. (Cf. Dominico Soto. De natura et gratia, Bk. I, chap. 16, and Del Prado, De gratia, I, 245. ) Corollary. Del Prado, op. cit. (I, 248): From the notion of operative and cooperative grace, propounded by St. Thomas in article two, it can easily be demonstrated that the gratuitous movement of God, whereby He impels us to meritorious good, is efficacious, not on account of the consent of the free w ill that has been moved, but on account of the will and intention of God who moves it, as St. Thomas expressly declares in the following question (112, a. 3). Even in article two of the present question, the Angelic Doctor has already said with reference to operative grace, that "with it. our mens is moved and not the mover"; and, in the answer to the second objection, that the movement of the free will, when we are justified and consent to the justice of God, "is not the cause of grace, but its effect, so that the whole operation belongs to grace. " Again in the body of this second article it is declared of cooperative grace: "And since God also helps us in this (deliberate) act. both by interiorly strengthening the will that it may accomplish the act, and by exteriorly supplying the faculty to perform it, with respect to this kind of act it is called cooperative grace. " As a matter of fact. Molina would not have denied the interpretation of Augustine given by St. Thomas, were it not declared in this interpretation that grace is efficacious of itself. CHAPTER V :THE DOCTRINE OF THE CHURCH The question of sufficient grace and efficacious grace is here treated in four chapters according to the following summary. CHAPTER V. PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS AND THE DOCTRINE OF THE CHURCH I. Preliminary remarks: statement and difficulty of the question. II. Doctrine of the Church on sufficient grace. III. How did St. Augustine and St. Thomas understand this doctrine of the Church on sufficient grace ? IV. Doctrine of the Church on efficacious grace. CHAPTER VI. SUFFICIENT GRACE I. Various systems of Catholic theologians with regard to sufficient and efficacious grace. II. To what extent sufficient grace is to be admitted and how it is divided. III. Refutation of the objections against the Thomistic doctrine of sufficient grace. IV. What is to be thought of the opinion of J. Gonzales de Albeda, O.P. V. The opinion of St. Alphonsus Liguori. CHAPTER VII. EFFICACIOUS GRACE Conclusion I. Its efficacy cannot be attacked from without. Corollary with respect to spirituality. Conclusion II. Its internal efficacy is not sufficiently explained by moral motion. Conclusion III. Its internal efficacy is properly and formally a predetermining physical premotion. IV. Refutation of objections. CHAPTER VIII. EXCURSUS ON EFFICACIOUS GRACE I. Efficacious grace and easy acts conducive to salvation. II. Efficacious grace in relation to spirituality. III. Efficacious grace in holy wayfarers, particularly in martyrs. IV. Efficacious grace in those burning with intense love of God. V. Efficacious grace in the impeccable and freely obedient Christ. 1. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS: STATE OF THE QUESTION Terminology' used. It is evident from revelation that graces are conferred by God and that some of them miss their final effect, whereas others achieve their effect. The former are called "truly sufficient" and "merely sufficient" since they give the power for a good work, but they are resisted. The latter are called "efficacious" since they really produce their effect in us, they act indeed that we may act. From this difference the question arises: How are sufficient grace and efficacious grace distinguished from each other ? In other words, is efficacious grace efficacious of itself, intrinsically, because God so wills, or is it efficacious extrinsical^, that is, on account of our consent foreseen by God's knowledge ? Underlying principles from the treatise on God: statement and difficulty of the question. After St. Thomas, in the early days of Protestantism and Jansenism, this question has been widely debated and at length; it may fittingly' be explained here, for its solution is deducible from what St. Thomas has said. (la Ilae. q. 110, a. I; q. Ill, a. 2; q. 112. a. 3. ) However, the basic principles of the solution are first enunciated in the treatise on God. la, q. 14, a. 8: "The knowledge of God is the cause of things inasmuch as His will is joined to it. " And further, la, a. 19, a. 4: "The effects determined by the infinite perfection of God proceed in accordance with the determination of His will and intellect" (that is, by a decree of the divine will). Again, la, q. 19, a. 6 ad 1 : "Whatever God wills absolutely', is done (otherwise He would not be omnipotent), although what He wills antecedently (or only conditionally) may not be done, " for in this instance God permits the opposite evil for the sake of a greater good: thus He wills antecedently that all the fruits of the earth come to maturity, but He permits that many actually do not reach this maturity. It is similar in the matter of the salvation of men. St. Thomas goes on to explain this in the same article (ad I): On consequent or unconditional will. "The will is compared to tilings according as they are in themselves: but in themselves they are individual. Hence we will something absolutely inasmuch as we will it considering all its individuating circumstances; this is to will consequently. " Thus whatever God (omnipotent) wills absolutely is done; although what He wills antecedently may not be done. Antecedently God wills a thing according as it is good in itself, for example, that all men be saved, that all His commands be ever fulfilled; but at the same time He permits to some extent the opposite evil for the sake of a greater good, and thus "what He wills only antecedently or conditionally is not done. " Hence it is said in psalm 134:6: "Whatsoever the Lord pleased He hath done, in heaven, in earth. " And the Council of Toucy (PL, CXXVI, 123) adds: "For nothing is done in heaven or on earth, except what God either graciously does Himself or permits to be done, in His justice. " That is to say. no good, here and norv. in this man rather than in another, comes about unless God Himself graciously wills and accomplishes it, and no evil, here and now, in this man rather than another, comes about unless God Himself justly permits it to be done. Nevertheless God does not command the impossible, and grants even to those who do not actually observe His commandments the power of observing them. But those who observe His commandments are better than others and would not keep them in fact, had not God from eternity efficaciously decreed that they should observe these precepts. Thus, these good servants of God are more beloved and assisted by Him than others, although God does not command the impossible of the others. Furthermore, this very resistance to sufficient grace is an evil which would not occur, here and now. without the divine permission, and nonresistance itself is a good which would not come about here and now except for divine consequent will. Therefore, there is a real difference between sufficient grace, to which is attached the divine permission of sin and by reason of which the fulfillment of the commandments is really possible, and efficacious grace, on the other hand, which is a greater help whence follows not only the real possibility of observing the commandments, but their effective fulfillment. Moreover, in sufficient grace, efficacious grace is offered to us, as the fruit is in the flower: but if resistance is made on account of our defectibility, then wc deserve not to receive efficacious grace. For this reason Bossuet declares: "Our intellect must be held captive before the obscurity of the divine mystery and admit two graces (sufficient and efficacious) of which the former leaves our will without any excuse before God, and the latter does not permit the will to glory in itself. " {Oeuvres completes. Paris, 1845, I, 644. ) St. Thomas states further (la, q. 19, a. 8): "Since the divine will is efficacious in the highest degree, it follows not only that those things are done which God wills to be done, but also that they are done in the way God wills them to be done. But God wills certain things to be done necessarily, others contingently, that there may be order among things for the completion of the universe. " This is the basis of grace efficacious in itself. Again (la. q. 20, a. 2): "The will of God is the cause of all things, and hence, necessarily, to the extent that a tiling has being or any good whatever, it is willed by God. Therefore, since loving is nothing else but wishing well to someone, it is evident that God loves all things that are, but not in the way that we do.... Our will is not the cause of goodness in tilings. " including the goodness of our choices, as appears from la. q. 19. a. 8. There follows from this the great principle of predilection, by which the whole treatise on grace is elucidated and which is formulated in la. q. 20, a. 3: "Since the love of God is the cause of the goodness of tilings, no one would be better than another if God did not will a greater good to one than to another. " Likewise, in article 4 of the same question and also in la. q. 23, a. 4: "In God. love precedes election. " Already it is evident that the man who. in fact, observes the commandments is better than the one who is able to do so but actually does not. Therefore he who keeps the commandments is more beloved and assisted. In short, God loves that man more to whom He grants that he keep the commandments than another in whom He permits sin. This principle of predilection is valid for all created being, even free beings, and for all their acts, natural or supernatural, easy or difficult, initial or final; in other words, no created being would be in any respect better if it were not better loved by God. This truth is clear in the philosophical order, for it follows from the principle of causality and of the eminently universal causality of the will or love of God. In the order of grace, this principle is revealed by several scriptural texts, for instance: "I will have mercy on whom I will and I will be merciful to whom it shall please Me" (Exod. 33:19); and "For who distinguished! thee ? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received?" (I Cor. 4:7. ) This principle of predilection presupposes, according to St. Thomas, a decree of the divine will rendering our salutary acts intrinsically efficacious (la, q. 19. a. 8). For. if they were efficacious on account of our foreseen consent, of two men equally loved and helped by God, one would be better in some respect. He would be better of himself alone and not on account of divine predilection. But this principle must be reconciled with another which ought to be maintained with equal firmness: "God does not command the impossible, but He teaches thee by commanding to do what thou canst and to ask what thou canst not, and He helps thee that thou mayest be able" (St. Augustine, De natura et gratia, chap. 43, no. 50, and the Council of Trent, Denz., no. 804). Herein lies a great mystery of reconciliation between infinite mercy, infinite justice, and supreme liberty. They are indeed reconciled in the intimate life of the Deity, but of Deity as such we have no positive or proper conception: "Deity is above being, above unity, which are contained in it formally and eminently . " (Cf. Revue thomiste, May-June, 1937, the author's article, "Le fondement supreme de la distinction des deux graces suffisante et efficace. ") [64] These conclusions from the treatise on God are, then, presupposed in the present discussion. This question must now be divided into two sections. First the dogmas of faith must be sought out dealing with grace which is truly, yet merely, sufficient, and with efficacious grace which nevertheless does not take away man's 64 This article will also be found in the Last section of the present volume freedom. Secondly, we must consider the various notions of theologians with respect to the nature of sufficient grace and of efficacious grace, whether the latter is efficacious intrinsically' or extrinsically, that is, on account of our foreseen consent. [65] With the object of better determining the status of the question, it will be well to consider the differences which exist in this matter between the opposing heresies of Pelagianism and Jansenism, and between the theological notions of Molinists and Thomists. For the Pelagians, actual grace (such as the preaching of the gospel) is either efficacious on account of man's consent to the good, or inefficacious on account of the evil will of man. For the Jansenists, internal actual grace is twofold: one is efficacious of itself, the other inefficacious and insufficient as well. For Thomists, internal actual grace is twofold: one is efficacious of itself, producing of itself the virtuous act; the other is inefficacious but truly' sufficient, bestowing the possibility either proximate, or at least remote, of acting virtuously. For the Molinists, sufficient actual grace itself is either efficacious from its effect, or from our consent foreseen by mediate knowledge, or else inefficacious and merely sufficient. 2. THE DOCTRINE OF THE CHURCH ON SUFFICIENT GRACE Grace is given which is truly yet merely sufficient: "truly" because it really confers the power; "merely" because, through the fault of the will, it fails in its effect, with respect to which it is said to be inefficacious, but sufficient. This doctrine of the Church is formulated against the Predestinationists and later, much more explicitly, against the Jansenists. (Cf. De praedestinianisrao, Denz., nos. 316 ff., 320 ff. ) The Predestinationists, including Lucidus, a fifth-century priest, Gottschalk in the ninth century, and later revivers, taught predestination to evil, before the prevision of demerits, and consequently must have denied the existence of sufficient grace; for, according to them, those who are damned lack the power of doing good (Denz., no. 321, at the end); and those who are saved are so necessitated to the good that they cannot resist grace. "Therefore the wicked themselves are not lost because they could not be good, but because they would not. " declares the Council of Valence (Denz., no. 321). Calvin followed the ways of Predestinationism (cf. Inst., Bk. Ill, chaps. 14-21). At first, the Jansenists denied sufficient grace. Jansen himself {De gratia Christi, Bk. Ill, chap. I) admits no grace that is not efficacious. Quesnel (Denz., nos. 1359 ff. ) and the Pistoians (Denz., no. 1521) adhere to this fully. Jansen's first proposition (Denz.. no. 1092) should be cited in particular: "Some commands of God are impossible to just men who are willing and striving, according to their present powers; moreover they lack grace which would make their observance possible to them. " In other words, many just men of good will, who make an effort, are deprived of sufficient grace which gives a real power or faculty for good works commanded by God; it would follow that the wicked are punished unjustly, since they could not be good. This proposition is declared heretical. The second proposition is closely related to the first: "In the state of fallen nature, interior graces are never resisted. " that is to say, interior grace is always efficacious, which is heresy. Likewise the third proposition of Jansen: "For meriting and demeriting in the state of fallen nature man does not require freedom from necessity: freedom from constraint is sufficient. " This proposition pertains rather to efficacious grace which, according to the Jansenists, removes freedom from necessity and leaves only spontaneity. Their fourth proposition is that the Semi-Pelagian heresy consisted in maintaining that the human will can resist or 65 Cf. John of St. Thomas, O.P., Cursus theol., De gratia, disp. XXIV; the Salmanticenses, Cursus theol., De gratia. disp. V, dub. 7; Lemos, O.P., Panoplia gratiae, Vol. IV, Part II, p. 36; Del Prado, O.P., De gratia, Vol. II, chaps. 13. obey grace. The fifth proposition declares that Christ did not die for all men. Quesnel's propositions (Denz., nos. 1359-75) were also condemned for the same reason, that is, for denying sufficient grace and reducing all internal grace to efficacious, under which, for him, liberty from necessity would not remain. Similarly, the twenty-one propositions of the Synod of Pistoia (Denz., no. 1521) were condemned. The motive fortheir condemnation, as set down, is that, like the Jansenists, they hold "the interior grace of Christ is not given to him by whom it is resisted... but only that is properly the grace of Christ which makes us act. " Hence, according to the Pistoians, the only sufficient grace which is given is external, such as preaching or good example. However, it should be remarked that, after the condemnation of the five propositions of Jansen, several of his followers, including Arnauld (dissertation in four parts: De gratia efficaci and apologie pour les saints Peres, Bk. IV), to avoid being held as heretics, admitted a little interior grace which might be given to certain of the just. But what is this little grace of Arnauld's ? According to him, it is grace which may be given in general, but not here and now in particular; or it is sufficient for acting generally, but not sufficient with respect to such and such a precept to be fulfilled or some particular temptation to be overcome. This little grace, according to Arnauld, is remiss charity; when charity is really intense and predominant, it is truly sufficient even here and now in particular, to such an extent that man resists- temptation, and hence it is efficacious. [66] This is the famous theory of little grace which certain Jansenists hit upon to avoid the condemnation of the Church. (Cf. Guillermin, Revue thomiste, 1902, pp. 47 ff. ; Paquier, Le Jansénisme; and Petitot, Revue thomiste, September, 1910, "Pascal et la grace suffisante. ") [67] It should be observed that the Augustinians admitted little grace, but not in the sense of the Jansenists; for them it is really sufficient but remiss. Does Arnauld's explanation preserve sufficient grace ? I reply: not really, but only as a matter of verbiage, for actions to be accomplished are not general but concrete and individual. Hence, if grace does not suffice for each particular precept or each individual temptation, it is simply insufficient. Therefore Arnauld does not escape from Jansen's first proposition: "Some commands of God are impossible to just men who are willing and striving, according to their present powers; moreover, they lack grace which would make their observance possible to them" here and now. Since this proposition is condemned as heretical, it is a dogma of faith that at least grace which is truly, yet merely, sufficient is not lacking to the just; truly, since it confers a real power of acting virtuously; merely, since it is resiste d and fails of its final effect. This dogma of faith had already been equivalently expressed in several councils. The Council of Orange (Denz., no. 200) declared that "all the baptized, by the help and cooperation of Christ, can and ought to accomplish whatever pertains to salvation, if they are willing to work faithfully. " The Second Council of Valence maintained against Scotus Erigenus (Denz., no. 321): "Therefore the wicked themselves are not lost because they could not be good, but because they would not. " And the Council of Trent (Denz., no. 804) adopts the formula: "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He teaches thee to do what thou canst and to 66 This theory is similar to the doctrine of those who, following Leibnitz' idea, maintained that man is indeed free, as a class, inasmuc his will is specified by a universal, abstract good, so to speak, surpassing any particular good; however, actually and in the concrete, and now, our choice is never free, since nothing is willed unless it is foreknown, and nothing is preferred unless it is foreknown as i advantageous here and now. That is, the will always follows the leadership of reason and whatever is, in the judgment of reason, here now, the stronger motive. Hence this stronger motive is always efficacious as a victorious satisfaction, and the opposite motive is nc fact, really sufficient. Thus psychological determinism is arrived at. Man would be free in the abstract but not in the concrete. And theory persists in a certain sense in Kant, who holds that man has liberty in the noumenal order which may be conceived, but not ii phenomenal order. But this doctrine is subjective conceptualism, to which moderate realism is opposed, declaring that the human v specified by the universal good not only according to our abstract conception, but in reality; our will even here and now preserve nature and capacity, which infinitely surpasses any particular, eligible good. Hence the stronger objective motive even here and nc indeed fully sufficient for choosing freely, but not for necessitating the will; in this respect it differs from the clear vision of God. Arnauld in his theory seems to proceed in conformity with the idea of subjective conceptualism, according to which really and merely sufficient grace may be given in the abstract but not in the concrete; as if. for instance, man might be conceived but a real man could not be given in the concrete, in whom human nature would really exist with individuating conditions. 67 Cf. Dictionnaire de théologie catholique, "Jansénisme, " col. 388 99; "La grace suffisante, " col. 431-47; "La predestination" (J. Carreyre); also the articles "Premotion" and "Predestination" (Garrigou-Lagrange). ask what thou canst not, and He assists thee that thou mayest be able. " Therefore God confers sufficient help to enable us, not only in general, but in individual cases, to observe His commandments. What, then, is the scriptural basis for this dogma of sufficient grace ? Especially worthy of citation are the words of the Lord in Isa. 5:4: "What is there that I ought to do more to My vineyard, that I have not done to it ?" For if God ought not to do any tiring more, then His help is truly sufficient. However, in this text it does not say: "What is there that I could do more. " and we shall see that God can do more, although not bound to do so. Again. Scripture often bears witness to graces offered or conferred whereby God calls and urges, and which are nevertheless resisted, or received in vain. Thus we read: "I called, and you refused" (Prov. 1:24); "I have spread forth My hands all the day to an unbelieving people, who walk in a way that is not good after their own thoughts" (Isa. 65:2); "Jerusalem, Jerusalem, thou that killest the prophets, and stonest them that are sent unto thee, how often would I have gathered together thy children, as the hen doth gather her chickens under her wings, and thou wouldest not! Behold, your house shall be left to you, desolate" (Matt. 23:37). [68] Commenting on St. Matthew, St. Thomas says of the passage just quoted: "This is that Jerusalem of which Ezechiel (5:6) declares: 'This is Jerusalem, I have set her in the midst of the nations, and the countries round about her. And she hath despised My judgments. ' They might excuse themselves saying: 'We had no one to tell us'; therefore does Jesus add: 'and stonest them that are sent unto thee, ' w hereupon I sent prophets and many helps and thou didst not recognize them. 'How often would I have gathered together thy children, as the hen doth gather her chickens under her wings, and thou wouldest not ?' The perpetuity of His divinity is here implied, as declared explicitly in His words: 'Before Abraham was made. I am' (John 8:58). Hence Christ Himself sent the prophets, patriarchs, and angels. As often as He sent, He wished to gather the Jews together. Those who were converted to the Lord were indeed gathered, for they are united in Him; whereas sinners, who are withdrawn from unit) , are dispersed. Wherefore: I wish to gather as a hen gathers her chickens under her wings. It is said that no animal is so solicitous for its young as the hen. She defends them against the hawk and endangers her own life for them, gathering them under her wings. So is Christ solicitous for us; 'surety He hath borne our infirmities' (Isa. 53:4); and likewise exposed Himself to the hawk, that is, the devil. "Sed contra: the Lord willed thus to protect them, but they refused; therefore their evil will prevailed over the will of God. Hence it could be said: As often as I willed, I acted; but I invite thee, acting as I did (for instance, sending the prophets); whereupon thy will prevented My action. Or again, the fact that He sent the prophets was a sign that He wished to gather thee in. and thou wouldst not. Then follows the punishment: behold, your house shall be left to you, desolate. " So speaks St. Thomas. This is the great mystery’ of antecedent will and the simultaneous permission of sin, but the grace was realty sufficient; had there not been resistance to it. the Lord would have given greater grace. Similarly, we read in the Acts (7:51): "You stiff-necked and uncircumcised in heart and ears, you always resist the Holy Ghost"; and in II Corinthians (6:1): "We... do exhort you, that you receive not the grace of God in vain"; cf. St. Thomas on this text. This is the case often when habitual grace is lost by mortal sin; likewise prevenient grace is received in vain when man does not persevere in good. However, graces of this kind are really sufficient, for through them God truly invites, but they are merely sufficient since they fail in their effect. Whence many accusations are unjustifiably adduced against us by the Molinists on the basis of these texts, to show that grace is not intrinsically efficacious; but as a matter of fact, these texts are not concerned with efficacious grace, but with merely sufficient grace, since it fails in its effect. The aforesaid dogma of faith regarding sufficient grace is also based on I Timothy (2:4-6) where it is written: "God will have all men to be saved, and to come to the knowledge of the truth"; and "Christ Jesus... gave Himself a redemption for all. " For if God really wills the salvation of all, He offers truly sufficient helps to all; many, however, are not saved, and thus it is evident that these helps often remain actually' inefficacious or merely sufficient. Cf. St. Thomas on I Tim. 2:9, and la. q. 19, a. 6: Whether the will of God is always accomplished. In this article, reptying to the first objection, St. Thomas maintains that God wishes all men to be saved, not by His consequent or efficacious will, but by His antecedent will "as a just judge antecedently desires alimento live, but wills consequently that a murderer should be hanged. In the same way, God wills antecedently the salvation of all 68 With regard to this symbolic expression of divine truth, cf. St. Thomas, la, q. I, a. g ad 3 : "It is more fitting that the divine things in the Scriptures should be presented under less dignified bodily figures. " men (for this is good absolutely), but He wills consequently that some should be damned according to the requirements of justice. " Further, He permits sin to happen, since it is not to be wondered at that what is defective should fail to a certain extent, that a greater good may issue from it, such as the manifestation of divine mercy and justice. With respect to this antecedent will. cf. the commentators on la, q. 19. a. 6 (Billuart); moreover, from this antecedent will for the salvation of all men proceeds the aggregate of sufficient graces to all adults. It would be equally easy to find among patristic writings the aforesaid dogma of the faith on truly, yet merely, sufficient grace, in equivalent terms at least, when they declare that we need divine aid and with it are able to do good, even if we do not, so that man remains inexcusable after sin. for he could have avoided it. Thus the wicked are justly to be punished. Cf. St. Irenaeus: "They did not do good when they could have done it" (Contra haereses, Bk. IV, chap. 37, no. 9. ) Commenting on the Epistle to the Hebrews (12:13), St. John Chrysostom writes: "Unless you receive heavenly aid, all your actions are in vain; but it is evident that you will attain whatever you apply yourself to, with that help, provided you are also attentix c and desirous of doing so. " This text affirms the existence of really sufficient grace but does not deny the existence of grace which is efficacious of itself. [69] 3. THE MIND OF ST. AUGUSTINE AND ST. THOMAS How did they understand the aforesaid doctrine of the Church on sufficient grace ? St. Augustine, in particular, defends efficacious grace, as will be explained later; here it suffices to quote the classic words found in the book, De dono perseverantiae, chap. 14: "Those who are set free are most certainty set free by the help of God"; and again in the De praedestinatione sanctorum, chap. 8: "Grace which is not rejected by any hard-heartedness, since it is bestowed, in the first place, to remove hardness of heart. " Likewise in the book, De gratia Christi, chap. 24, he described efficacious grace: "internal, hidden, wonderful, and ineffable power by which God effects in the hearts of men not only true revelations but even upright wills. " Augustine also admitted the principle of predilection: no created being would be better in any respect if it were not better loved and assisted more by God. This principle is affirmed in various terms; for example, in the City of God, Bk. XII, chap. 9, referring to good and bad angels, he says: "Thus, both were created equally good, these falling on account of their bad will, and those, receiving greater help, attaining their full beatitude, from which they most assuredly would never fall. " Similarly, in De dono perseverantiae, chap. 9, we find: "Of two adults leading lives of great wickedness, that one should be called in such a way as to follow the call, while the other is not called, or not called in that way, is in the inscrutable judgments of God. " But this principle of predilection presupposes, as we have said, that grace is efficacious of itself. For if it were efficacious on account of our foreseen consent, then, of two angels or men equally loved and assisted by God, one would be better than the other; he would be better on his own account and not as a result of divine predilection. This is contrary to St. Paul's "For who distinguisheththee? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received ?" These words of St. Paul are often quoted by Augustine. 2. Nevertheless, St. Augustine elsewhere maintains very definitely that "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He instructs thee both to do what thou canst and to beg what thou canst not, and He assists thee that thoumayestbe able" {Dénatura et gratia, chap. 43, no. 50, cited at the Council of Trent; Denz., no. 804). In this last text Augustine affirms sufficient grace without any ambiguity, and God's will that the fulfillment of His commands should be really possible to all, and, in this sense, His will that all should be saved. Hence St. Augustine admits that before efficacious grace, in the state of fallen nature, sufficient grace is given, without which the keeping of the commandments of God would be really impossible. And it is this grace which is called truly sufficient, in opposition to the Jansenists. Likewise in the book De correptione et gratia, chap. 7, discounting the excuse of those who say: we did not persevere because we did not have perseverance, he declares: 69 Cf. Rouet de Journel, Enchir. patrist., theological index, nos. 310, 318, 330. God does not command the impossible; all the just can persevere if they so will, but not for long without the help of grace; on assistance whereby and on assistance wzt/iowtw/i/c/i one cannot, nos. 1556, 1850, 1954 ff "Man, thou mayest persevere in that which thou hearest and boldest, if thou wiliest. " Again in De natura et gratia, chap. 67: "Since God... recalls the hostile, teaches the believing, consoles the hopeful, encourages the loving, assists him who strives, and hears him who prays, thou art not condemned to sin because thou art ignorant against thy will, but because thou dost neglect to seek after what thou knowest not; not because thou failest to bind up the wounded members, but because thou disdainest the will to be healed. " And similarly, commenting on psalm 40:5: "Do not say: I am not able to restrain, endure, and bridle my flesh; for you are assisted that you may be able. " Furthermore, St. Augustine presented the best formulated distinction between that help without which we cannot act and that help by which we infallibly act, just as later Augustinians and Thomists distinguish between sufficient grace, which gives the power to act, and efficacious grace, which infallibly imparts that action itself. This Augustinian distinction is found in De correptione et gratia, chap. II, where he teaches that Adam in the state of innocence had received sufficient help with which he could persevere in good, but not efficacious help whereby he would infallibly persevere; however, both helps are conferred on the predestinate. St. Augustine's words are as follows: "The first grace is that which enables a man to have justice if he so wills; therefore more is possible with the second, whereby it is also brought about that he does will.... Nor was the former by any means small, through which the power of free will was demonstrated; for the help is such that without it he would not have continued to do good; but if he wills, he may forfeit this help. The latter, however, is so far superior, that it is not enough for man to recover his lost liberty through it... unless it is effected that he wills.... In fact, it lies within us, through this grace of God received with good dispositions and perseveringly maintained, not only to be able to will but also to will actually what we will. This was not so in the first man; for he possessed one of these but not the other. "(Cf. Salmanticenses, Cursus theol., De gratia, q. Ill, disp. V, dub. VIII, no. 173. ) After Augustine, the older theologians generally used the expression "help without which we cannot" for what, since the condemnation of Jansenism, has been commonly referred to as sufficient grace, and "help whereby" we do good for what is now called efficacious grace. Objection. It seems that Augustine does not mean, by the difference between "help whereby" and "help without which, " the same distinction which is now understood between efficacious help and sufficient help. For in many instances he excludes "help whereby" from the state of innocence. If therefore "help whereby" were admitted to represent grace efficacious in itself, it would follow that efficacious grace was not necessary for Adam and the angels to persevere. Reply. This question was discussed at great length in the time of the Jansenist heresy, as can easily be seen from Billuart's Cursus theol., De gratia, diss. II, a. 4. But from the many texts of St. Augustine quoted there it appears that the holy doctor excluded from the state of innocence the "help whereby" for being healed, but not for being assisted. [ °] And he holds that grace efficacious of itself was necessary for perseverance even in the innocent Adam and in the angels. To prove this it suffices to quote the very famous passage in the City of God, Bk. XII, chap. 9, regarding the good and bad angels: "Thus both were created equally good, these falling on account of their bad will, and those, receiving greater help, attaining their full beatitude, from which they most assuredly would never fall. " This is affirmed by Augustine in virtue of the principle of predilection: "For w ho distinguished! thee? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received?" In other words, no man or angel, in any state, would be better than another, if he were not more loved and assisted by God. The angels who fell had sufficient grace, which they resisted; the others, that is, the predestinate, were more loved and assisted. This is the doctrine of predestination itself. Moreover, as Bossuet demonstrates (Defense de la tradition, Bks. X and XI, chaps. 19-27), Augustine, as well as many others of the Greek and Latin Fathers, maintains, when explaining the threefold denial of Peter during our Lord's passion, that Peter could have avoided that sin, for he was not deprived of all grace; but on account of his previous movement of presumption, he lacked the efficacious help by which he later came even to martyrdom. Cf. Bossuet, ibid., where several texts from Origen, Chrysostom, Augustine, and Gregory the Great are quoted and also Book XII, De doctrina Augustini de praedestinatione, wherein Bossuet distinguishes very well between sufficient and efficacious grace in accordance with tradition.* 70 That is, Adam in the state of innocence required grace efficacious in itself to persevere, by reason of his dependence on God, not by reason of any weakness in himself. The whole question is briefly formulated in the proposition already quoted from the same authority: "Our intelligence must be held captive before the divine obscurity of this great mystery, confessing these two graces (sufficient and efficacious), the first of which leaves our will without an excuse before God, while the second does not allow it to glory in itself. " [71] In other words. "It must be admitted (in opposition to the Jansenists) that there are two interior graces, of which one (namely, sufficient grace) leaves our soul inexcusable before God after sin, and of which the other (that is, efficacious grace) does not permit our will to glory in itself after accomplishing good works. " "What hast thou that thou hast not received ? For who distinguished! thee ?" These two propositions, thus formulated, are as two very luminous semicircles surrounding the deepest obscurity of the mystery. Above these semicircles is the mystery of the divine good pleasure, combining infinite mercy, infinite justice, and supreme liberty, which are identified in the Deity. Below, however, is the abyss of our defectibility and the gravity of mortal sin. Finally, this doctrine of really sufficient grace distinct from efficacious grace is expressed in several texts from St. Thomas. Cf. Illa, q. 79, a. 7 ad 2: "The passion of Christ does indeed benefit all men, with respect to its sufficiency, the remission of sin, and the attainment of grace and glory, but it produces its effect only in those who are united to the passion of Christ by faith and charity. " Likewise Illa, dist. 13, q. 2, a. 2; qc., 2 ad 5: "Christ satisfied for all human nature sufficiently, but not efficiently, since not all become participants in His satisfaction; but this is the result of their unfitness, not of any insufficiency in His satisfaction. " Similarly in De veritate, q. 29, a. 7 ad 4 Again on the First Epistle to Timothy (2:6), with reference to the words, "Christ gave Himself a redemption for all, " St. Thomas explains: "For some efficaciously, but for all sufficiently, since the price of His blood is sufficient for the salvation of all; but it is not efficacious except in the elect on account of impediments. " Therefore in like manner, according to St. Thomas, sufficient helps and efficacious helps are given, which may correspond for their effect to the aforesaid passion and the mode by which it benefits us. And in la Ilae, q. 106, a. 2 ad 2: God "gives sufficient help to avoid sin"; and again on the Epistle to the Ephesians, chap. 3, lect. 2. In certain texts of St. Thomas the term "sufficient" is not explicitly contrasted with "efficacious, " and his meaning is not always clear except from the context; but in many instances we really find this explicit contrast or distinction which was already common among theologians long before Jansenism and the discussions which it aroused. Moreover, in the Tabula aurea of St. Thomas' works, under "satisfactio, " no. 36, are giveneighteen quotations from the Angelic Doctor wherein he declares substantially that Christ satisfied for the whole of human nature sufficiently, but not efficaciously. Lastly, St. Thomas evidently holds that all infused virtue gives the power to do good in the order of grace, but not the actual doing good, for which divine motion is necessary; and furthermore, the divine motion which inclines one effectively toward a good thought does not suffice to incline one efficaciously toward a pious desire nor toward agreeing to a good or proposing it, nor. for still greater reason, toward carrying out this proposal. The actual motion which inclines one to have a good thought does give the potentiality with respect to the pious desire, but not the actual desire itself, and so on through the series. The mind of St. Thomas is clear on this point and may be demonstrated by many texts quoted below. Nor does St. Thomas merely distinguish between sufficient grace and efficacious grace; he indicates the supreme basis of this distinction when, in la. q. 19. a. 6 ad I. he establishes the difference between antecedent will (or the will for universal salvation) and consequent will. We explained this in our treatise, De Deo uno, 1937, p. 425. According to his argument, antecedent will is concerned with the good considered absolutely and not here and now, whereas consequent will has to do with the good considered here and now. But since the good which exists in things themselves is effected only here and now. it follows from this that the antecedent will of itself alone, without the addition of the consequent will remains inefficacious. Hence the division into these two wills is the supreme basis of the distinction between sufficient grace which proceeds from the antecedent will and grace which is efficacious of itself proceeding from the consequent will. But man. on account of his resistance to sufficient grace, deserves to be 71 "Avertissement sur le livre des Reflexions morales, " a brief treatise in the Oeuvres completes, Paris. 1845, 1. 643; see also the index to Bossuet's works under "grace,... resistance a la grace. " deprived of efficacious grace. Objection. This distinction between efficacious actual grace and sufficient grace is not found in the early Councils, not even Trent, which treated of grace and free will more accurately in order to counteract Lutheranism. Reply. Granted that these identical terms are not encountered in the pronouncements of the councils, nevertheless terms in every respect equivalent are to be found; for instance, it is a question of efficacious grace when the Council of Orange declares (chap. 9, Denz., no. 182): "Whenever we do good, God operates in us and with us in order that we may act"; and again when the Council of Trent (Sess. VI, chap. 4, Denz., no. 814) defines "free will moved and stimulated by God, as that which assents to cooperate with God who stimulates and invites. " Likewise, the Council of Trent (Sess. VI, chap. II, Denz.. no. 804) refers equivalently to sufficient grace when it states that "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He teaches thee both to do what thou canst and to ask what thou c anst not, and He assists thee that thou mayest be able. " It was fitting, moreover, for theologians in their disputations to avoid such complex terms as "sufficient grace and efficacious grace. " Finally, the aforesaid dogma of faith regarding grace which is truly yet merely sufficient is confirmed by theological argument. God. even in the present economy of salvation, imposes the observance of the commandments upon all most rigorously, and the delinquents who die in final impenitence will be punished by eternal torments. But God cannot impose a precept unless at the same time He supplies the necessary means for observing it, nor justly punish him who cannot avoid evil. Therefore God offers helps by which man may be sufficiently equipped to keep the commandments and avoid sin. He does not provide less in the order of grace than in the order of nature, in which latter there are truly sufficient principles, that is, faculties, which nevertheless require final application to the act. (Cf. the Salmanticenses. ) This, then, is the dogma of faith regarding truly and merely sufficient grace. Later we shall examine the various opinions of theologians on the nature of sufficient grace. Let us first consider the Church's teaching on efficacious grace. 4. THE DOCTRINE OF THE CHURCH ON EFFICACIOUS GRACE This doctrine contains two articles: 1. efficacious grace is conferred; 2. with efficacious grace, liberty remains. First article. Efficacious, or effective, grace is conferred which causes us to act. This is maintained especialty' in the condemnation of Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism. For the Pelagians did not precisely deny that grace confers the power of doing good, but that it bestows the very willing and acting. Against them the Second Council of Orange (can. 9, Denz., no. 182) defined: "Whatever good we do, God operates in us and with us that we may operate. " Hence a certain grace is given which is effective of an operation, although it does not exclude our cooperation but rather demands it. This is the meaning of the words of Ezechiel (36:27): "I will cause you to walk in My commandments, and to keep My judgments, and do them. " And the Council of Orange quotes in the same sense (no. 177): "It is God who works in us both to will and to do. " But the grace which causes us to act, whatever it achieves of willing or completing, is efficacious, not only with the efficacy of powers, in the sense that it confers real and intrinsic powers in the supernatural order (this is already given by interior sufficient grace), but it is efficacious with an efficacy of operation, or effective, since it produces the very operation with us, whatever may be the mode whereby the will and grace concur in the act. This is confirmed by the condemnation of the pseudo-synod of Pistoia (Denz., no. 1521) where it is stated that this false synod is condemned "in that it maintains that alone to be properly the grace of Jesus Christ as creates holy love in the heart and causes us to act... and also that the grace whereby the heart of man is touched by the illumination of the Holy Ghost is not, strictly speaking, the grace of Christ, and that the interior grace of Christ is not really given to him who resists it. " Thus the Church affirms the existence of efficacious grace while maintaining that it is not the only grace. Moreover, this dogma of the existence of efficacious grace is confirmed by theological argument- for it is de fide that no act conducive to salvation can be performed without grace, and no man can persevere without grace (Council of Orange; Denz., no. 182). But experience proves that many acts conducive to salvation are performed and many men persevere in the accomplishment of salutary acts. Therefore grace is given which achieves its effect and which is therefore rightly called efficacious. We shall consider below, in explaining the Thomistic doctrine of efficacious grace, the texts of Sacred Scripture which refer to this grace. The second point of the Church's doctrine on efficacious grace is that, with it. liberty, not only from coercion but from necessity, remains, as required for merit. Cf. Hugon. De gratia, p. 339. This can be drawn from the condemnation of Predestinationism (Denz.. no. 317): "We have a free will for good, anticipated and assisted by grace, and we have a free will for evil devoid of grace. " Likewise in the condemnation of Calvinism by the Council of Trent (Sess. VI. chap. 7. Denz.. no. 797): "freely assenting to and cooperating with the same grace"; and again {ibid., can. 4, Denz.. no. 814): "If anyone should say that the free will of man, moved and stimulated by God, in no wise cooperates by assenting to the encouragement and invitation of God. whereby he disposes himself and prepares to receive the grace of justification, and further, that he cannot refuse if he so wills, but, as if he were something lifeless, does not act at all but merely keeps himself in a passive state, let him be anathema. " Similarly, against the third proposition of Jansen (Denz.. no. 1094) it is declared that "for meriting and demeriting, liberty is required both from constraint and from necessity. " This dogma is confirmed by the following theological argument. Faith teaches that glory is conferred upon merit. (Councils of Orange, Denz.. no. 191; Trent, nos. 809. 842. ) But merit is an act which proceeds from liberty and efficacious grace. Therefore the coexistence of liberty and efficacious grace is a fundamental truth. Hence St. Augustine says: "He who made thee without thy help, does not justify thee without thy help" (Sermon 15 de Verb. Apost.. chap. II, no. 13; PL, XXXVIIL 923). These two dogmas on truly and merely sufficient grace and on efficacious grace are wonderfully coordinated in the proposition quoted above from Bossuet which expresses the Christian idea profoundly: "We must admit two graces of which the one leaves our will without any excuse before God, while the other does not permit it to glory in itself. II CHAPTER VI SUFFICIENT GRACE IN treating this question we should always keep before our eyes the following texts. "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He teaches thee both to do what thou cans! and to ask what thou cans! not, and He helps thee that thou mayest be able" (St. Augustine, quoted at the Council of Trent, Denz., no. 804). "Christ is the propitiation for our sins, for some efficaciously', but for all sufficiently, since the price of His blood is sufficient for the salvation of all" (St. Thomas on I Tim. 2:5. and elsewhere). "The help of grace is twofold: one. indeed, accompanies the power; the other, the act. But God gives the power, infusing the virtue and grace whereby man is made capable and apt for the operation; whereas He confers the operation itself according as He works in us interiorly, moving and urging us to good" (St. Thomas on Ephes. 3:7) 1. VARIOUS THEOLOGICAL SYSTEMS WITH REGARD TO SUFFICIENT AND EFFICACIOUS GRACE Generally speaking, there are two systems. The first is held by those who declare efficacious grace to be intrinsically efficacious, that is, from the very intrinsic force of grace which of itself and with us infallibly produces consent saving free will. They consequently insist upon a real distinction, before consent, between efficacious and sufficient grace. The Thomists and Augustinians accept this view; but they are divided according as they explain "intrinsically efficacious" as signifying: by moral motion only, as pleasure is victorious, which the Augustinians hold, or as signifying also: by predetermining physical premotion, saving free will however; this is the position of Thomists. [72] Cf. the synopsis. Another general system is that of the theologians of the Society of Jesus, who deny that efficacious grace is intrinsically efficacious since, as they declare, intrinsically efficacious grace deprives man of his liberty. In this major, as Del Prado shows, they are in agreement with Protestants and Jansenists. For these heretics say that intrinsically efficacious grace takes away liberty’; but grace efficaciously moving one toward the good is intrinsically efficacious; therefore freedom from necessity' is not required in order to merit, but only freedom from force. The theologians of the Society of Jesus agree with these in the major and distinguish the minor, thus: intrinsically efficacious grace takes away freedom; but freedom from necessity is required in order to merit; therefore grace is not intrinsically efficacious but only extrinsical^ so. that is. on account of our consent foreseen by mediate knowledge. We, on the other hand, disagree with the heretics in the major, that is, in the ven' basic principle bv which the problem is solved: whether God can, gently and firmly, in other words, infallibly, move our will to this free act rather than to another. To this fundamental question we reply in the affirmative; the heretics, however, deny it, and with them the Molinists and Congruists. It is clear from this how greatly Thomism differs from Calvinism and Jansenism; the difference appears in our rejection of the five propositions of Jansen; cf. Billuart, De gratia, diss. V. a. 2, 2: seven differences between Thomism and Jansenism. Two synopses are presented: the first for the systems which admit intrinsically efficacious grace, the second for those which hold grace to be extrinsically efficacious; in the third place will be added the middle ground of the eclectics. The last opinion which practically seems to be good, theoretically has all the difficulties of both Molinism and Thomism; nor is it so easy for prayer to possess all the required conditions even for impetratory force. It should be remarked that, before Molina, almost all the traditional theologians taught that grace was intrinsically efficacious, except a few such as the very small perversely inclined minority among the Dominicans, among them Durandus and Catharinus. who invented Molinism before Molina. The true sense of St. Alphonsus' doctrine is a disputed question, but Father Jansen {Revue thomiste, 1903, p. 341) maintains that St. Alphonsus in no wise favored Molinism but rather admitted intrinsically efficacious grace for all acts conducive to salvation. The theologians of the Society of Jesus are divided among themselves, depending on whether they are pure Molinists or Congruists after the fashion of Suarez. Molina, at the end of the sixteenth century, taught (cf. Concordia, quaest. 14, a. 13; disp. 40, pp. 230. 459): "Whether sufficient help is efficacious or inefficacious depends on the will of him to whom it is given. That is, no graces are given except those sufficient in themselves, but they are made efficacious by the consent of the human will foreseen by mediate knowledge. (Cf. Concordia, index under "Auxilium. " and the text, pp. 230. 459. 462, 565. ) Moreover. Molina holds that "One who is aided by less help from grace can rise, while another with greater help does not rise but may persevere in Iris obduracy" (p. 565). Therefore before our consent, sufficient grace and efficacious grace do not really differ, either physically or morally. But God predestined to glory those whom He foreknew, by mediate knowledge, would consent with their innate free will to the grace offered to all and would persevere therein, if placed in such and such circumstances. [diagram page 204]___________________________________________________________________________ Grace 1. intrinsically efficacious 1.1. not only by moral movement, but also by (causally) predetermining physical premotion [73] (Thomists) 1.2. through infallible moral motion alone 1.2,1, by victorious delight saving free will (Augustinians, Berti. Noris) 72 VARIOUS 73 Some writers accept indifferent physical premotion, although not predetermining physical premotion; but in that case efficacious grace would not be strictly efficacious of itself, intrinsically and. whether they will or no, they are forced to admit of scientia media, by that name or by another. Thus Pignataro. Cardinal Pecci. Satolli, Paquet. L. Billot by sympathy between the first and the second cause, or extrinsic assistance (Scotus) 1.2.3. by a multitude of aids (Thomassin) [74] 2. extrinsic ally efficacious 2.1. from the consent of the will alone, foreseen by mediate knowledge 2.1.1. hence ,sufficient grace is rendered efficacious by our consent, and before consent sufficient grace and efficacious grace are indistinguishable (Molina) 2.2. from the congruity or opportuneness with which grace is given, according to the prevision of mediate knowledge. However congruous grace is not infallibly efficacious of itself 2.2.1. efficacious (or congruous) grace and sufficient (or incongruous) grace do not differ in their physical being but in their moral being, by reason of their benefits (Congruists such as Suarez) middle ground 1. intrinsically efficacious grace is for more difficult acts 2. Extrinsically efficacious grace is for easier acts, such as prayer, according to this opinion. So also the Congruism of the Sorbonne and Tournely. [75] 1.2.2. Hence gratuitous predestination, being gratuitous, is not peculiar either to glory or to grace, but to favorable circumstances. For example, God decreed to place Peter in favorable circumstances where He foresaw Peter would consent to the grace offered, and He decreed to place Judas in circumstances where He foresaw that Judas would not consent to the grace offered. But, according to this theory, the grace offered to Peter is not of itself greater than the grace offered to Judas, even if it is a question of the interior grace offered at the last moment of their careers. It is a moral motion with simultaneous indifferent concurrence. However, the gratuity of predestination is saved by the divine choice of circumstances. Lessius retains this teaching of Molina. [7677 ] Molina holds {Concordia, pp. 546, 548) that if this doctrine had been known in the fifth century’, "from the opinion of Augustine, so many of the faithful would not have been disturbed. " (Cf. Salmant.. De gratia, disp. V. dub. VII, no. 173. ) This doctrine seemed an innovation to many and was a cause of displeasure, as Billuart relates {De gratia, diss. V, a. 6); the Thomists disputed it before Clement VIII and Paul V. as bordering on Semi-Pelagianism. and their accusation was pursued for ten years in the famous debates de Auxiliis. Nor were the Thomists alone in attacking this doctrine of Molina; so, even among Jesuit theologians, did St. Robert Bellarmine. De gratia et libero arbitrio, Bk. I, chap. 12 (cf. DelPrado, III. 373). [ ] Henry Henriquez in two judgments, dated 1594 and 1597 respectively, and Mariana. De regimine Societatis, chap. 4. Hence the Society of Jesus, which supported Molina's defense in the Congregationes de Auxiliis, after more mature deliberation on the matter, moderated the system of this author and 4 Thomassin. De consensu Scholae de gratia, tr. III. maintains that, if single helps may fail to produce their effect, a combination of them never does 75 Likewise Isambert and Lemoine, as it appears. St. Alphonsus adhered to tins party, according to some, but not absolutely. Cf. St. Alphonsus. Op. dogm., II, 707 ff.. against the heretical so-called reformers. St. Alphonsus rejects scientia media 76 Lessius, De gratia efficaci, chap. 18, no. 7: "That, of two men who are similarly invited, one accepts the preferred grace and the other rejects it. it may rightly be said to proceed from free will alone; not that he who accepts does 50 by his liberty alone, but because the difference arises from free will alone and thus not from any diversity of prevenient help. " The Thomists replied straightway: this is contrary’ to St. Paul's words in I Cor. 4:7: "For who distinguished! thee? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received? And if thou hast rcccrvcd. why dost thou glory, as if thou hadst not received it?" Cf. Salmanticenses. De gratia efficaci, disp. VII, dub. I, IV, no. 18. 77 St Robert Bellarmine. I De gratia et lib. arb.. chap. 12. where he explains the extent to which the efficacy of grace is accepted: he distinguishes three opinions of which the first is attributed to those who "regard it as within the power of manto render grace efficacious which would otherwise of itself be only sufficient. "Bellarmine adds that "this opinion, a) is entirely' foreign to the thought of divine Scripture itself... For who distinguished! thee? b) and it is opposed to St. Augustine, who will not have efficacious grace depend on human w ill. but on the divine, and c) this opinion utterly' destroys the basis of divine predestination which St. Augustine established so solidly from Holy Scripture. " Thus St. Robert Bellarmine withdraws from Molinism to embrace Congruism abandoned it as it stood, taking up the advocacy of the Congmism of Suarez "as more conformable with the teaching of St. Augustine and St. Thomas. " It is expressly declared in these very terms by a decree of the Most Reverend Claude Aquaviva, General of the Society of Jesus, in 1613. This very celebrated decree is quoted by the Jesuits, Tanner, de Regnon (Banez and Molina), and by Billuart {op. cit. ). The distinction between Molinism and Congruism appears clearly in the decree. Thus. Father Claude Aquaviva declares: "We ordain and command that in propounding the efficacy of divine grace... our fathers should in the future explicitly teach that between the grace which has an effect of itself, called "efficacious. " and that which is termed "sufficient, " the difference is not so much as regards second act. since it still obtains its effect by the use of free will possessed of cooperating grace, nor likewise the other, but in first act itself, which, assuming a knowledge of the conditionals, on account of God's disposition and intention of most certainly effecting good in us. by His own actix itx selects those means and confers them in the way and at the time when He sees the effect will be produced infallibly. whereas He would have foreseen these as inefficacious under other circumstances. Wherefore, something more is always contained, morally, in efficacious than in sufficient grace, both by reason of its benefit and with respect to first act; and thus God effects that we may act of ourselves, not so much because He gives grace by which we are able to act. The same may be said of perseverance which, without any doubt, is a gift of God. " So writes the Most Reverend General Aquaviva. whose decree was confirmed by the seventh general Congregation of the Society of Jesus, in the year 1616, at which Muzio Vitelleschi was elected presiding General. He declared that Father Aquaviva held efficacious grace to differ from sufficient grace in first act, not physically but morally , by reason of greater congruous benefits. This decree of Father Aquaviva was subsequently confirmed at the ninth general Congregation of the Society of Jesus, in 1651, under General Picolomini. At present, however, the theologians of the Society are actually free to choose either of the two opinions. Otherwise all the theologians of the Society agree in this matter, that they should not return to the infallible, intrinsic efficacy of grace, that is, as coming from divine omnipotence. And Congruism is therefore only whitewashed Molinism, for even in the former, ultimately, grace is infallibly efficacious, not because God so wills, but because man wills it to be efficacious. Hence God is always regarded as a created cause, urging and attracting, as a friend persuades a friend to choose the good. Whereas God is in reality infinitely more powerful than my most beloved friend to persuade me, more so than the guardian angels, or the highest angels capable of being created, and God does not only move by attracting objectively, but interiorly by contact with the will from within, inasmuch as He is closer to it than it is to itself, as we shall see. This suffices for an explanation of the system of these theologians. Let us now proceed to the proof of the Thomistic opinion: 1. with respect to sufficient grace, that is, in what sense it is to be accepted; 2. with respect to efficacious grace: whether it is efficacious intrinsically and by physical premotion not ultimately determinable by us. We shall examine the objections to both theses. 2. IN WHAT SENSE SUFFICIENT GRACE IS TO BE ACCEPTED AND HOW IT IS DIVIDED Conclusion. Sufficient grace is that which confers upon man the power of doing good, beyond which he requires another grace, namely, efficacious, that he may do good. (Cf. Lemos, Panoplia, Vol. IV, Part II, p. 36; Gonet. De voluntate Dei, disp. IV, no. 147; John of St. Thomas, De gratia, d. 24; the Salmanticenses, Gotti, Billuart. ) The first part is proved, since it must be admitted that grace which gives the power to do good is given even to those who do not do good. For this is a dogma of faith defined, as we have seen, in the condemnation of the first proposition of Jansen (Denz., no. 1092). The commandments would be impossible to those who. in fact, do not keep them. (Cf. St. Thomas on the Epistle to the Ephesians. 3:7. ) The second part of the conclusion is proved as follows: God is the first cause of salvation and of that which is peculiar to the affair of salvation. But the salutary action, as distinct from the potentiality of doing good, is that which is peculiar to the affair of salvation. Therefore, beyond sufficient grace, which gives the power of doing good, efficacious grace is required, which causes us to perform the good action. (Cf. la, q. 109, a. 1. ) Otherwise, and this is the refutation of Molinism, the greatest activity of all. namely, the passage into a free, supernatural act, would belong exclusively to the free will and not to God. Thus, what is greatest in the affair of salvation would not derive from the author of salvation; from God would proceed only the unstable sufficient grace which effects nothing but an indeliberate motion. God would wait upon our will for our consent, which seems to be contrary to the Council of Orange (Denz., no. 177): "If anyone maintains that God waits upon our will to cleanse us from sin, and does not rather acknowledge that even our willingness to be cleansed is brought about in us through the infusion and operation of the Holy Ghost, he resists the Holy Ghost Himself, who declares... : 'It is God who worketh in you both to will and to accomplish, according to His good will' " (Phil. 2:13). The Molinists admit, of course, against the Semi-Pelagians, prevenient grace, but an unstable prevenient grace, no greater in one who is converted than in another who perseveres in obduracy, and therefore it still remains that, according to this theory, God waits upon our consent and does not produce it. The foregoing argument is quite certain; but that its conclusiveness may appear even more clearly, let us examine the force of both the major and the minor. The major is evident from reason according as God is the supreme, universal first cause of all being and act. Moreover it is contained in revelation: "The salvation of the just is from the Lord" (Ps. 36:39); "Salvation is of the Lord: and Thy blessing is upon Thy people" (Ps. 3:9); "The Lord is my light and my salvation, whom shall I fear?" (Ps. 26:1); "My God is... my protector and the horn of my salvation" (Ps. 17:3); "Attend unto my help, O Lord, the God of my salvation" (Ps. 37:23); "OLord, Lord, the strength of my salvation: Thou hast overshadowed my head in the day of battle" (Ps. 139:8); "The Lord... is become my salvation" (Ps. 117:14); "Neither is there salvation in any other" (Acts 4:12); "It is the power of God unto salvation to everyone that believeth" (Rom. 1:16); "Who then shall separate us from the love of Christ ? Shall tribulation or distress or famine or nakedness or danger or persecution or the sword ?... But in all these things we overcome, because of Him that hath loved us. For I am sure that neither death nor life nor angels nor principalities nor powers nor tilings present nor things to come nor might nor height nor depth nor any other creature shall be able to separate us from the love of God, which is in Christ Jesus our Lord" (Rom. 8:35-39). Cf. St. Thomas' commentary on the words of our Lord, "Without Me you can do nothing" (John 15:5), and "Have confidence, I have overcome the world" (John 16:33). [78] From all of these and many other texts of Sacred Scripture it is evident that God is the author of salvation. This is the very expression of St. Paul to the Hebrews (2:10): "For it became Him, for whom are all tilings, and by whom 8 St. Thomas, commenting on the Epistle to the Romans (8:35), "Who then shall separate us from the love of Christ?" says of these w "All benefits are conferred upon us by God so efficaciously that no man can withstand them. However, all these aforesaid benefits tei this end: that we should be founded and rooted in charity.... Many waters could not quench charity, according to the Canticle. But St. enumerates the evils the endurance of which may constrain a person to abandon the charity of Christ.... Tribulation or distress or famii persecution or the sword. But in all these tilings we overcome, because of Him that hath loved us. We overcome; that is. in all these we preserve charity intact, according to the words of Wisdom (10:12): 'She... gave him a strong conflict, that he might overcome. ' this not by our own power, but by the help of Christ, wherefore he adds: because of Him that hath loved us, that is. on account of His or on account of the disposition produced in us by Him, not as if we had first loved Him. but because He hath first loved us. As declar I Corinthians (15:57): 'Thanks be to God, who hath given us the victory' through our Lord Jesus Christ. ' 'Death is swallowed up in vic "Fori am sure that neither death... nor principalities nor powers... nor any other creature shall be able to separate us from the love of God, which is in Christ Jesus our Lord. " St. Thomas asks: "How is it that St. Paul says he is sure that nothing can separate him from charity when 'no man knows whether he is worthy of love or of hate?' To this question answer may be made that the Apostle is not speaking of himself individually but in the person of all the predestinate, of whom he declares, on account of the certainty of predestination, that nothing can separate them from charity.... However, if St. Paul is speaking of himself, he could not be certain of this statement unless perhaps by revelation. " are all things, who had brought many children into glory, to perfect the author of their salvation, by His passion. " Hence the title often occurs in the liturgy: "O Lord, the author of salvation"; for example, in the second prayer of the Office of the Dead: "O God, bestow er of pardon and author of human salvation, we beseech Thy clemency" (at least, in the Dominican rite); and again: "O God, the Creator and Redeemer of all the faithful. " Our major is therefore incontrovertible; that is: "That which is peculiar to the affair of salvation ought to proceed from God, the author of salvation. " [79] The minor is equally certain: that which is peculiar to the affair of salvation is not the power to do good, but the actual consenting to the good and the good act itself. Thus our Lord says (Matt. 7:21): "Not everyone that saith to Me, Lord, Lord, shall enter into the kingdom of heaven: but he that doth the will of My Father in heaven. " And in Ezechiel we read: "I will cause you to walk in My commandments, and to keep My judgments, and do them" (36:27). Therefore the conclusion follows: Beyond sufficient grace, which gives the power of doing good, is required efficacious grace, wliich actuates us to perform that good. And this is admitted by all theologians except the pure Molinists, even by the Congruists who hold that, beyond sufficient grace, congruous grace is required, differing not physically but morally in first act. that is, before consent. Moreover, Molina does not seem to observe canon 9 of the Council of Orange (Denz., no. 182): "Whatever good we do. God operates in us and with us that we may operate. " Hence a certain grace is given which confers on us, not only the power to act. but the veiy act itself. Nor does Molinism seem to respect the words of the Council of Trent (Sess. VI, chap. 13, Denz.. no. 806): "For, unless men themselves fall short of His grace, God as He began a good work (by sufficient grace), so does He perfect it, working both the willing and the accomplishment" (Phil. 2:13). Likewise, Denz., no. 832. For Molina. God does not effect the willing and accomplishment except by simultaneous concurrence, and therefore what is peculiar to the business of salvation does not derive from God, namely, the good determination itself, and what may be in this man rather than in another who is equally tempted and equally assisted. There are several confirmations of the Thomistic conclusion. First confirmation. God provides proportionately in the same way for the supernatural as for the natural order. But in the natural order the power of acting and the impulsion to act are differentiated. Therefore in the supernatural order sufficient grace, which confers the power of doing good, and efficacious grace, which causes us to do it, are likewise distinct. (Cf. la Ilae, q. 109, a. 1. ) Moreover, in the natural order, as stated in this article, however perfect a power may be, it never passes into act without the efficacy of divine motion. Therefore in the same way, grace which bestows a power, however completely sufficient it may be. never passes into act without efficacious grace. Second confirmation. (Cf. Gotti's commentary. IX. 128. ) Otherwise it would follow that those who have such sufficient grace should not pray to God for further grace, since it is supposed that for performing a good act, nothing more is required on the part of God beyond this sufficient grace. Third confirmation. It would follow that efficacious grace would not be necessary for doing good and persevering in a good act for wliich sufficient grace gives the power; or else that man could render sufficient grace efficacious without any further help from God; and consequently not from grace would a doer of good be distinguished from a doer of evil equally assisted, but rather from himself. For he would himself, without any further help on the part of God, have rendered sufficient grace efficacious, whereas another man would not have done so. This contradicts the words of St. Paul: "For who distinguished! thee ? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received ?" (I Cor. 4:7. ) Therefore St. Robert Bellarmine. when he examined the opinion of those who hold that it is within the power of man to make grace efficacious, which would otherwise of itself be only sufficient, writes as follows {De gratia et libero arbitrio, Bk. I. chap. 12): "This theory is entirely alien to the opinion of St. Augustine and. in my judgment, even to the meaning of Holy Scripture. " For St. Augustine declares in his book on the predestination of the saints (chap. 8): "Grace (manifestly efficacious grace) is not rejected by a hard heart, since of itself it softens the heart. " Whenever efficacy is attributed to grace, not to the human will Tanner expresses the same view of Molina's opinion. 79 Cf. P. Guillermin, O.P., "De la grace suffisant. "Revue Thomiste, 1902. p. 75 Fourth confirmation. Otherwise the distinction between sufficient and efficacious grace would not be justified as given by Augustine {De correptione et gratia, chap. 12), between merely sufficient, inefficacious grace ("help without which we cannot, " conferring the power) and efficacious, not merely sufficient, grace ("help whereby, " conferring the act). This distinction, as we have seen, is based on Sacred Scripture: "For it is God who worketh in you. both to will and to accomplish according to His good will" (Phil. 2:13); "I will cause you to walk in My commandments, and to keep My judgments, and do them" (Ezech. 36:27); here it is a question of efficacious grace. On the contrary, sufficient grace is referred to when St. Stephen says: "You always resist the Holy Ghost" (Acts 7:51); and similarly: "I called, and you refused: I stretched out My hand, and there was none that regarded" (Prov. 1:24). The division of sufficient grace [diagram page 212]__________________________________ sufficient grace 1. internal 1.1. actual 1.1.1. proximately sufficient 1.1.2. remotely suffic ient 1.2. habitual 2. external, for example, the preaching of the gospel Sufficient grace is manifold and involves the following. 1. External helps, such as external revelation, the preaching of the faith, exhortation, example, miracles, salutary trials, benefits, and indeed a certain disposition of events ordained by a special providence toward salvation. 2. Internal helps, which are either permanent (such as infused habits, for instance, sanctifying grace, the virtues and gifts) or transient (such as supernatural movements which excite in us indeliberate acts, pious thoughts and aspirations). These helps are infallibly efficacious for producing those indeliberate acts, and sufficient for the deliberate act for which they give the proximate power. These various helps are extremely useful; it is obvious that they render our powers noble and elevated; they are truly sufficient in their order, just as the intellectual faculty is for understanding; and they really confer the proximate power. But they are called merely sufficient with respect to salutary acts which, on account of man's culpable resistance, are not performed. Indeed, as has been said, grace which is termed sufficient with respect to a perfect act, for example, contrition, is infallibly efficacious with respect to an imperfect act, such as attrition. [80] Sufficient help is divided into remote and proximate. Proximate help is that by which a person can immediately perform a good work, such as the infused habits with respect to their acts, and with still greater reason indeliberate devout thoughts and aspirations inspired by God and inclining toward consent to the good. Remote sufficient help is that by which a person is not yet capable of the act. but can do something easier, for instance, pray, which, if he does it well, will enable him to act, for example, to overcome temptation. The Council of Trent (Sess. VI, chap. II) indicates this difference drawn from St. Augustine: "God does not command the impossible, but by commanding He teaches thee to do what thou canst (proximately sufficient help) and to ask for what thou canst not (remotely sufficient help. )" Furthermore, sufficient help is divided into conferred help and offered sufficient help, which we would certainly receive were there not an obstacle. Sufficient help is also either immediate and personal or mediate, for instance, conferred upon the parents for their cliildren who are incapable of receiving personal sufficient help; thus the parents 80 As Gonet states, Clypeus, De voluntate Dei, disp. 4, no. 14, Thomists generally agree with Alvarez, Bk. Ill, De auxiliis disp. 80, that: "All help which is sufficient with respect to one act is at the same time also efficacious in the order of another act to the accomplishment of which it is ordained by an absolute decree of divine providence, so that it is sufficient absolutely (for example, with respect to contrition) and efficacious under a certain aspect"; in other words, it is efficacious with respect to an imperfect act, such as attrition, and infallibly efficacious with respect to this imperfect act. might receive from God the pious thought of the necessity of having their children baptized and not do so. Hence truly and merely sufficient help does not consist in some one, indivisible, definite thing, but in many helps, whether external or internal, permanent or transitory, whereby a man has the proximate power of doing good or at least of praying, and nevertheless resists it. All of this is commonly taught by Thomists; but in addition reference should be made to the opinion of Gonzalez de Albeda, O.P., in his Commentary on la, q. 19. a. 8, disp. 58, sect. 2, Naples, 1637. II, 85. Gonzalez holds that sufficient grace gives the ultimate completion to the power, or proximate power in readiness to consent when God calls (in fact, it impels toward second act, although it does not remove the impediments to this act); on the contrary, efficacious grace simultaneously moves toward second act and removes all impediments, and hence it is not resisted. Thus Gonzalez still preserves a real distinction between sufficient grace, impelling toward second act, and efficacious grace, surmounting obstacles; and he explains this distinction, not as residing in our free will, but before our consent, on the part of God Himself assisting us. He says {ibid. ): "I consider that it ought to be held without doubt that the created will only sufficiently helped by God, possesses the ultimate fullness of active power and the prevenient concurrence of God.... It is otherwise, however, with the created will efficaciously assisted; for the ultimate fullness in this latter case (efficaciously assisted) establishing it finally in first act is more particular and extrinsically efficacious with greater power to incline the will to consent here and now. " Other texts of Father Gonzalez in the same connection should be consulted. We have examined this theory at length in another work. [81] 0 Gonzalez, then, maintains the principle of predilection, namely, no one would be better than another if he were not better loved by God. Cf. below, 4, for the value of this opinion; and the excursus on efficacious grace, chap. 1. 3. REFUTATION OF OBJECTIONS AGAINST THE THOMISTIC THESIS OF SUFFICIENT GRACE Objection. Some have objected, declaring this grace to be useless; for that grace is useless which no one ever uses. But no one ever uses sufficient grace, as defined by Thomists. Therefore this grace is useless. Reply. I distinguish the major: that it is useless of itself, denied, since of itself it confers a real power which is truly useful; that it is useless accidentally, on account of a defect in man, granted; in other words, if man does not use this suffic ient grace, it is not the fault of grace, but of man. I counterdistinguish the minor: no one ever uses sufficient grace by reduplication as merely sufficient, granted, and this is so by reason of our resistance permitted by God; that no one ever uses sufficient grace specifically, in that it confers the power of doing good, denied; for we often make good use of infused habits which are in themselves sufficient. Similarly in the natural order, although the power in plants of bearing fruit may often remain ineffectual, on account of accidental defects, it is not thereby rendered useless, since in other plants it does produce fruit. I insist. But sufficient grace as defined by Thomists is even pernicious, as the following proves. Grace by which a manis made worse is pernicious. But man is made worse by sufficient grace in the Thomistic sense, for, if he lacked it. he would not sin. whereas, possessing it, he so many times sins. Therefore this grace is pernicious. Hence some used to say: From the sufficient grace of the Thomists, deliver us, O Lord. First reply. This argument proves too much, for in the same way it can be proved that reason is pernicious, since he who lacks it does not sin, and he who possesses it sins. Second reply. I distinguish the major: grace by which man is made worse on account of a defect in this grace is pernicious, granted; but on account of a perverse will denied. I counterdistinguish the minor and deny the conclusion and its consequence. For it is utterly false to say that man is made worse by sufficient grace considered in itself, since through habitual grace which is sufficient he is made pleasing to God and capable of acting supernaturally. 81 La predestination des saints et lagrace, 1935, pp. 386-92 I insist. No one, not even the Church itself, asks God for sufficient grace in the Thomistic sense. Therefore it is not a good. Reply. I distinguish the antecedent: no one asks for it as merely sufficient, by reduplication, since that would be asking God to permit us to decline from grace, granted. That no one asks for it taken specifically and entitatively, denied; since we ask for the power of doing good, for instance, faith, hope, and charity. Further objection is made to the novelty of this conception. The aforesaid real distinction between sufficient and efficacious grace is not derived from St. Thomas; it was invented by Banez to avoid censure after the condemnation of Jansenism. Reply. We have seen that the aforesaid division is also found long before Banez and even before St. Thomas, in Augustine, De correptione et gratia, chap. 12, as "help without which" conferring power, and "help whereby" producing the good act. With respect to the term "Banezianism, " see Del Prado, De gratia et libero arbitrio, III, 427-59, for a discussion of whether Banezianism is not really a farce invented by the Molinists. He replies in the affirmative and proves that this little diversion was staged by the Molinists to avoid the appearance of any opposition between Molinism and St. Thomas himself, declaring that their teaching was contrary to Banez, not to St. Thomas. Molina himself proceeded with more straightforwardness, stating expressly {Concordia, p. 152) that he rejected the divine application of secondary causes as laid down by St. Thomas. And again (pp. 546, 548) he admits that he is abandoning the teaching of St. Augustine and St. Thomas on predestination, which was a source of anxiety to so many of the faithful. Hence Cardinal Gonzales. O.P., in his philosophical work, Theodicea, chap. 4, a. 3. writes as follows: "Some, who strive to cast a light on the darkness, are not afraid to declare that St. Thomas is considering only simultaneous concurrence and not really physical premotion. In which matter, indeed, Molina and certain other of his disciples act more honorably and becomingly when they frankly acknowledge that, in this matter, they depart from St. Thomas. " This admission is made, together with Molina, by the Coimbrian school by Bellarmine, Tolet, and Suarez, whom I have quoted elsewhere (God, II, 154). Moreover, it is clear from many texts of St. Thomas that he admitted a twofold grace: first, grace which gives the power of doing good; second, grace which makes us do good. Cf. la Ilae, q. 106, a. 2 ad 2: "The grace of the New Testament... to the extent that it is sufficient of itself gives help to avoid sin but it does not confirm a man in good so that he is not able to sin... and hence if, after receiving the grace of the New Testament, a man should sin, he is deserving of greater punishment for not using the help given to him. " Again, in his commentary on the Epistle to the Ephesians (chap. 3, lect. 2): "God gives the power by infusing virtue and grace through which man is made capable and apt for action. But He confers the action itself according as He works within us interiorly impelling and urging us toward the good... in the measure that His power effects in us both to will and to accomplish on account of His good will. " Likewise in la Ilae, q. 109, a. 1 : "The act of the intellect and of any created being depends upon God in two respects: 1. inasmuch as it has received from Him the form by which it operates; 2. according as it is moved to the action by Him"; and further in article two: "Man... requires a power superadded to his natural power on two accounts, namely, that he maybe healed and. beyond this, that he may perform good works of supernatural virtue. See also ibid., a. g and 10; and Ila Ilae, q. 137, a. 4; De perseverantia; la Ilae, q. 113, a. 7 and 10. At least it may be said that St. Thomas always distinguishes the infused habits, which give the power of doing supernaturally good works, and actual grace which confers the working of good itself; indeed he distinguishes between good thoughts which come from God and consent to good which presupposes greater assistance. [82] 8~ cf.. Ia Ilae, q. 112, a. 3 : "If it is in the intention of God who moves that the man whose heart He moves should attain grace, he attai infallibly, according to the words of St. John (6:45): 'Everyone that hath heard of the Father, and hath learned, cometh to Me Furthermore, St. Thomas gives the supreme basis of the distinction between efficacious and sufficient grace (la. q. 19, a. 6 a "Whatever God wills absolutely is done, although what He wills antecedently may not be done. " The treatise on evil {De malo). q. 6, a. I ad 3: "God moves some wills immutably on account of the efficacy of the moving power w A third objection is raised as follows. That grace is not sufficient beyond which another is required. But beyond sufficient grace in the Thomistic sense another is required. Therefore this sufficient grace of the Thomists does not suffice. Reply. I distinguish the major: this grace is not sufficient in its own genus, denied; in every genus, granted. I grant the minor, and distinguish the conclusion- does not suffice in its own order, denied; in every order, granted. This distinction was made long before Banez by Ferrariensis. [* 83] Explanation. This is the specifically philosophical and theological sense of the term "sufficient"; a thing is really sufficient in its own order, even though another cause may be required in another order. Thus, of the four causes, any one of which is sufficient in its own order, but requires the concurrence of the others in order actually to operate; for example, we generally say with reference to the order of final cause: this motive is sufficient for free action, and yet there does not follow an infallible choice, for which the concurrence is required of both the intelligence proposing the motive as an object and will actually willing it. Indeed, the stronger motive at the end of the deliberation seems so sufficient that the Determinists after the fashion of Leibnitz deny the liberty of indifference. In fact, however, this sufficient motive gives, on the part of the object, only a proximate potentiality, and so likewise does sufficient grace, which is either a habit of charity or of some other virtue, or an indeliberate pious aspiration toward a good conducive to salvation. And just as this motive is truly sufficient, although it may not incline one infallibly to act, so it is with this grace. We have developed this at greater length elsewhere (God, II, 368-79). On the contrary, the Megarians held that power does not exist without act; consequently a teacher, not actually teaching, would lose the power of teaching. We should say nowadays that heat is sufficient to cause burning, although it must first be applied to combustible matter; and bread, similarly, is sufficient for nourishment, although it must further be masticated, swallowed, and assimilated. The intellect is sufficient for understanding, but beyond this its object must be correctly presented to it; for instance, the doctrine of St. Thomas must be presented to it correctly, and not according to the interpretation of theMolinists; otherwise the student will not understand although he may have sufficient intelligence. The passion of Christ is sufficient to save us, but, in addition, its merits must be applied to us, for example, in the sacrament of baptism. Hence St. Thomas says (Illa, q. 61, a. I ad 3): "The passion of Christ is a sufficient cause of man's salvation, but it does not therefore follow that the sacraments are not necessary for salvation, since they operate by virtue of the passion of Christ. " Again, he declares {De malo, q. 6, a. I ad 15): "Not every cause necessarily' produces its effect, even if it is a sufficient cause, on account of the fact that a cause may be impeded. " Thus, natural causes produce their effect only in the greater number of cases. cannot fail; but on account of the nature of the will moved, which holds itself in indifference toward various objects, neces sity i< introduced, but liberty remains; just as in all things divine providence works infallibly , and yet contingent effects proceed from contin causes, inasmuch as God moves all things proportionately, each according to its own mode"; cf. ibid., ad 15. Cf. la Ilae, q. 10, a. 4 ad 3 : "If God moves the will toward something, it is incompatible with this affirmation that the will should not be moved thereto. But it is not absolutely impossible. Hence it does not follow that the will is moved by God of necessity. " Those who admit fallibly efficacious premotion, with respect to what is really effected, must reconcile their theory with this last text; "it is incompatible, " and we shall see later whether such a reconciliation is possible, that is, whether fallibly efficacious premotion may be conferred with respect to what it actually' produces in us, for example, with respect to the continuation of attrition or of prayer, here and now, produced in this sinner rather than in another. 83 Ferrariensis, commenting on the Contra Gentes, Bk. Ill, chap. 86, no. 5, says: "Any cause is said to be sufficient when it has enough power, from its own form, to be able to produce an effect without the concurrence of any other cause of its own order; just as fire is a sufficient cause of heat, for it canby itself, without the concurrence of any other particular effective cause, produce heat (presupposing, however, the influence of the first cause). On the contrary, a cause is said to be insufficient which does not possess, from its own form, sufficient power so that by itself, without the concurrence of any other cause of its own order, it can produce an effect; as when many men are rowing a boat together which no one of them could row alone, each of them is said to be an insufficient cause of the boat's being drawn. " Therefore sufficient grace is really sufficient in its own order, since it confers the proximate power of doing good. Indeed it cannot be more sufficient; nor is the grace admitted by Molina any more sufficient, nor does it manifest the mercy of God any more. Rather, on the contrary, Molina minimizes the mercy and gifts of God by denying that efficacious is distinct from sufficient grace; for thus God is not the true author of salvation to that extent. (Cf. Bossuet. Elevations, eighteenth week, fifteenth elevation. ) I insist. For observing in act the divine commandments, that grace is insufficient which lacks something not in our power. But the sufficient grace of the Thomists is wanting in efficacious grace, which is not in our power. Therefore this sufficient grace of the Thomists is insufficient for the actual observance of the commandments, for which it ought to be sufficient, since God commands us not merely to be able to observe His precepts, but to observe them in fact. St. Thomas raised a similar objection to his own opinion {De veritate, q. 24. a. 14, objection 2). [84] First reply. I distinguish the major: lacks something on account of our negligence, denied; otherwise, granted. Second reply. I distinguish the major: efficacious grace is not in our power, as our own effect, granted; as a cause offered to us in sufficient grace, denied. I counterdistinguish the minor in the same way and deny the logical sequence and the conclusion. Explanation. God, to the extent that it lies with Him, is prepared to give efficacious grace to all who have sufficient grace, and does not deny it to any man except through his own fault, at least by a priority of nature, if not antecedent in time. Hence a defect in operation by no means proceeds from an insufficiency of help, but only from negligence or a defect of free will, which resists it and sets up obstacles. Even the more rigid Thomists agree to this, such as Lemos, {Panoplia gratiae, Vol. IV, Bk. IV, Part II, tr. 3, chap. 2); his very words are quoted by Billuart {De gratia sufficienti, diss. V, a. 4). However, the reason for this is, as Lemos himself declares {ibid., chap. 6), that "God, by bestowing sufficient help, offers us, in it, efficacious grace; but since man resists sufficient grace, he is deprived of the efficacious grace which was offered to him. " Likewise Alvarez, (De auxiliis, Bk. XI, disp. 113, no. 10, and disp. 80 ad 4); and this is entirely conformed to the teaching of St. Thomas, who says expressly (III C. Gentes, chap. 159): "God. to the extent that it lies with Him, is ready to give grace to all, for He wills all to be saved and come to the knowledge of the truth (I Tim., 2); but they alone are deprived of grace who present some obstacle to grace within themselves. In the same way, since the sun illuminates the world, the blame is imputed to one who shuts his eyes if some evil results therefrom, although he caimot see unless preceded by the light of the sun. " St. Thomas explains this at greater length in la, d. 40, q. 4, a. 2, and Ia Ilae, q. 112, a. 3 ad 2: "The first cause of a defect of grace lies in us, but the first cause of the bestowal of grace is in God, according to the words of Osee (13:9): 'Destruction is thy own, O Israel: thy help is only in Me. ' " And again, De veritate, q. 24, a. 14 ad 2: "From man arises the negligence which accounts for his not having grace whereby he can keep the commandments. " Indeed, this reply is fully in accord with the Council of Trent, which declared (Sess. VI, chap. 13, Denz., no. 806): "If men did not fail His grace, God would perfect the good work, just as He began it, bringing about both the willing and the accomplishing"; also ibid., chap. II. [85] 84 St. Thomas in De verit., q. 24, a. 14, proposes to himself the same objection: Whether free will can choose the good without grace. Second objection: "No one should be blamed for not doing what he caimot do. But a man is justly blamed if he omits doing good. Therefore by his free will man is capable of doing good (without grace). " St. Thomas replies : "to the second objection, it must be said, that man is rightly blamed for not fulfilling the commandments, since it is on account of his own negligence that he does not have the grace whereby he is enabled to keep the commandments modally; although he call observe them by his free will, substantially" with general concurrence 85 Council of Trent, Sess. VI, chap. II, teaches: "The divine precepts are not impossible to any just man. " Therefore the precept of ft persevering is possible to the justified man. But the same holy synod teaches, in the same session, chap. 13 (Denz., no. 806) and canoi that the singular gift of perseverance, necessary for the act of persevering, is not given to all the just, and this is not in the power of but only in that of God. Hence the Council already presupposes that there is in all the just a potency for the act of perseverance, alth< not in all is the efficacious help present which is required on the part of God for the act of perseverance. Therefore the sufficient grace of the Thomists is not. as their adversaries maintain, a power, sterile in itself, from which God, according to His good pleasure, withholds the outpouring necessary for reducing it to act. but rather, in sufficient grace God offers us efficacious grace. Doubt. How is efficacious grace offered to us in sufficient grace? Reply. As the fruit is offered to us in the flower, although, if a hailstorm occurs, the flower is destroyed and the fruit does not appear which would have developed from the flower, under the continued influence of the sun and of the moisture in the plant, so is efficacious grace offered to us in sufficient grace, although, if resistance or sin occurs, sufficient grace is rendered sterile and efficacious grace is not given. I insist. But this is only a metaphor. Reply. It is not a mere metaphor, but a strictly proportionate analogy; that is, so far as in both cases an act is contained in its correlative potency. For sufficient grace is indeed the principle of a good work, virtually containing it, and would in fact accomplish it (under the continuous influence of God, as the flower under the continuous influence of the sun), did not man. by his defective liberty, resist it. Thus a good seed, consigned to the earth, bears fruit unless it is prevented by some deficiency in the soil. And hence sufficient grace is the seed of the gospel referred to by our Lord in the parable of the sower (Matt. 13:3-9): "Behold the sower went forth to sow. And while he soweth some fell by the wayside, and the birds of the air came and ate them up. And other some fell upon stony ground, where they had not much earth.... And others fell among thorns: and the thorns grew up and choked them. And others fell upon good ground: and they brought forth fruit, some a hundredfold, some sixtyfold, and some thirtyfold. He that hath ears to hear, let him hear. " And again, in the same chapter (13:37): "He that soweth the good seed, is the Son of man. And the field is the world, And the good seed are the children of the kingdom. " (Cf. St. Thomas' Commentary on Matthew. ) Similarly, the seed of glory is habitual grace itself which, as such, is sufficient, that is, as an infused habit. Nor should it be thought that after the supernatural sowing is received into the soul, the increase derives from us and not from God. On the contrary, St. Paul says (I Cor. 3:6-9): "I have planted. Apollo watered, but God gave the increase... you are God's husbandry; you are God's building. " And again (II Cor. 9:6-15): "He who soweth sparingly, shall also reap sparingly: and he who soweth in blessings, shall also reap blessings.... And God is able to make all grace abound in you; that ye always, having all sufficiency in all things, may abound to every good work. As it is written: He hath dispersed abroad, He hath given to the poor; His justice remaineth forever. And He that ministereth seed to the sower, will both give you bread to eat, and will multiply your seed, and increase the growth of the fruits of your justice; that being enriched in all things, you may abound unto all simplicity, which worketh through us thanksgiving to God.... Thanks be to God for His unspeakable gift. " (Cf. St. Thomas' Commentary. ) I insist. Nevertheless it seems unjust that to some merely sufficient grace alone is given and to others efficacious grace besides, without which in fact the commandments are not observed. Reply, from St. Thomas, IlaIlae, q. 2, a. 5 ad 1: "Man is held to many things which he cannot do without grace.... That help is in fact given to some from on high is an effect of mercy, but that it is not in fact given to others is an effect of justice, as a punishment of preceding sins or at least of original sin, as Augustine says in his book De correptione et gratia. " It is the absolutely free external exercise of justice and mercy, with the mystery of the intimate reconciliation of these infinite perfections in the Deity. Hence the denial of efficacious grace is an act of justice, inasmuch as it is the punishment for preceding sin, at least with the priority of nature, that is, sin at least in its incipiency. But sin itself presupposes, not indeed as a cause, but as a condition, divine permission. Therefore the divine refusal of grace thus inflicting punishment on account of sin means something more than a simple divine permission of sin or the beginning of sin; for the permission of the incipiency of the first sin has no reason of punishment with respect to any preceding sin, and this incipiency of sin could not occur without divine permission, since if God, at that instant, were to preserve a man in goodness, there The Congmists must say the same of congruous grace for persevering in act; indeed, Molina would have to declare something of the same kind with respect to the favorable circumstances in which God decrees to place those whom He has judged will persevere, according to scientia media, if placed in these circumstances. would be no sin. But God is not bound to preserve in good forever a creature in itself deficient, and if He were held to this, no sin would ever take place. Cf. la Ilae, q. 79. a. I. toward the end of the body of the article: "For it happens that God does not grant help to some men for avoiding sin which, if He granted it, they would not sin; but He does all this according to the order of His wisdom and justice since He is wisdom itself and justice itself; hence it is not to be imputed to Him that a person sins, as if He were the cause of sin. In the same way. a pilot is not said to be the cause of a ship's sinking for the mere reason that he does not steer the ship, unless he relinquishes the steering of it when he can and ought to steer it. " Again, ibid, ad I. and also la Ilae, q. 109. a. 2 ad 2: "Every created tiring needs to be preserved in the good proper to its nature by another; but it can, by itself, fall away from that good. " I insist. To neglect or resist sufficient grace is not to consent to it or to sin at least by a sin of omission. But in order that a man may not neglect or resist sufficient grace, efficacious grace is required. Therefore man sins because he is deprived of efficacious grace, in other words, from an insufficiency of help. Reply. I grant the major, and the minor as well but deny the conclusion, for the real conclusion is: "therefore, in order that a man may not sin. but consent to sufficient grace, efficacious grace is required, " and this is true. (Cf. De malo. q. 3. a. I ad 9. ) But it is false to say that man sins because he is deprived of efficacious grace; rather, on the contrary', it should be said that he is deprived of efficacious grace because by sinning he resists sufficient grace. For a man to sin. Iris own defective will suffices, and resistance to sufficient grace always precedes, at least by a priority of nature (on the part of the material cause, man) the divine denial of efficacious grace; in other words, God refuses efficacious grace only to one who resists sufficient grace; otherwise there would be an injustice involved. And what on the part of God precedes this resistance is only the divine permission of sin. But this divine permission must not be confused with a denial of efficacious grace, which signifies something more; cf. Summa. la. d. 40, q. 4 a. 2: "Since God wills nothing but good, He does not will that man should lack grace (that would be a denial of efficacious grace), except to the extent that it is a good; but that he should lack grace is not a good absolutely. Hence, considered absolutely', this is not willed by God. However, it is a good for him to lack grace if he does not will to have it or if he prepares himself carelessly for receiving it, because this is just, and from this aspect it is willed by God. " But God can permit sin on account of a higher good and He is not bound always to preserve in goodness what is itself defective, for it is reasonable that a tiring which is in itself deficient should sometimes evince a defection. Therefore the problem is solved according to the words of Osee (13:9) already quoted: "Destruction is thy own. O Israel: thy help is only in Me. " Consult the Thomists, especially' on la, q. 19, a. 8, concerning the divine decrees, where the objections on the grounds of insufficient help are refuted; for example. Billuart and John of St. Thomas. Moreover, all the foregoing arguments, as well as that which follows, can be thrown back upon the Congruists, or against sufficient grace in the Congruist sense. I insist. At least the permission of the first sin is formally a denial of the efficacious grace necessary' to avoid it. But, according to Thomistic teaching, it depends upon tire absolute will of God that He permits the first sin in any one man or angel rather than in another whom God preserves in good. Therefore, according to this doctrine, the denial of efficacious grace to avoid the first sin would in like manner depend upon the divine will alone, and would not be a punishment presupposing a fault, which is exceedingly severe. Reply. I deny the major, for the notion of a denial of grace, formally, signifies more than a simple permission of sin, since it includes, in addition, the punishment due to sin which is at least incipient, which punishment is not implied in the concept of permission of sin. since this latter is entirely antecedent to the sin. Moreover, the beginning of the first sin. from the standpoint of its material cause, precedes the divine denial of efficacious grace, just as "in the order of nature, liberation from sin is prior to the consequence of justifying grace, " as St. Thomas declares (la Ilae, q. 113. a. 8). He there explains further that "on the part of the efficient cause the infusion of grace precedes the remission of sin"; indeed it precedes absolutely. since these two are effects of God and the consideration of the efficient cause prevails absolutely. Whereas, on the contrary, sin as such is a defect proceeding from a defective cause; consequently here the consideration of priority on the part of the material cause, man, prevails; hence, absolutely, the beginning of sin precedes the divine refusal to confer efficacious grace which, as a punishment, differs from the simple divine permission of sin. (Cf. above, the tract on sin. la Ilae. q. 79. a. 1 : God is not the cause of sin. ) This whole question had already been ven' well expounded before the time of Molina and Banez by Ferrariensis, in his commentary on Bk. Ill Contra Gentes, chap. 161, no. 4: "Since in the reprobate four elements are found, namely, the permission of the fall into sin, the sin itself, abandonment by God who does not raise him from sin. not pouring out His grace, and the punishment, or damnation.... With respect to the sin, reprobation means only foreknowledge,... but with respect to the permission, the abandonment to sin by God, and the damnation or punishment, it signifies not only foreknowledge but also causality. " (But the punishment of damnation is on account of the foreseen demerits, whereas the permission of the first sin is not. ) Ferrariensis declares in the same text: "Although sin is the demeritorious cause of abandonment by God and the disposing cause of eternal punishment, the permission, which exists first in the reprobate, is not the cause of sin. for it does not invest the reprobate with anything whereby he falls into sin, since he sins with his free will, nor does it remove anything which would withhold him from sin. " Thus it appears that negative reprobation, according to Ferrariensis, precedes the foreseeing of demerits. Cf. la Ilae. q. 79, a. I, the end of the conclusion: "It happens that God does not grant help to some men for avoiding sin which, if He granted it, they would not commit. But He does all this according to the order of His wisdom and justice;... hence it is not to be imputed to Him that a person sins, as if He were the cause of sin. " The universal foreseer permits for the sake of a greater good that a deficient cause should sometimes fall into defect. (Cf. la. q. 23, a. 3 and a. 5 ad 3. ) I insist. If an affirmation is the cause of an affirmation, a negation is the cause of negation. But the bestowal of efficacious grace is the cause of fulfilling the commandment and of nonresistance to it. Therefore the withdrawal of efficacious grace is the cause of not fulfilling the commandment, even in the beginning of the first sin. Reply. I distinguish the major: if it is the only cause, granted; thus the presence of the pilot is the cause of the ship's safety, and his absence when he ought to be on duty is the cause of shipwreck. If there are two causes, of which the first is indefectible but not bound to prevent an evil, and the other is deficient: denied, for then this second cause alone is responsible for the defection. St. Thomas proposed this objection to himself in De malo, q. 3, a. I, objection 8: "If grace is the cause of merit, then contrariwise the withdrawal of grace is the cause of sin. But it is God who withdraws grace. Therefore God is the cause of sin. " Reply (ad 8): "God as He is in Himself communicates Himself to all according to their capacity; hence if a thing is deficient in the participation of this goodness, this is because there is to be found in the thing itself some impediment to this divine participation... according as [a man] keeps his back turned to a light which itself does not turn away, as Denis Dionysius says in the Book of the Divine Names, chap. 4. " So that a man fails on his own account and he is sufficient unto himself when it comes to failing; but he requires the divine help preserving him in good in order to persevere in it. To be preserved in goodness is a good and proceeds from the source of all good; but to fall away from goodness presupposes only a deficient cause. Thus, with regard to this objection: it is granted that if efficacious grace were given to a man he would not sin, but it does not follow that he sins for this reason or cause of not being given efficacious grace. The permission of sin is only a condition of sin, not its cause. We must beware of confusing a cause which exerts a positive influence with an indispensible condition which does not exert an influence; otherwise there would be a vicious circle, as when it is said: I believe the Church to be infallible because God revealed this; and I believe God revealed it because it is affirmed by the Church. In the second proposition ’because" is not taken in the same sense as in the first, for it does not signify the formal motive of faith, but only the indispensable condition of faith, that is, the infallible proposition of the object of faith. Similarly, in our present case, the permission of the first sin and not being preserved in good is an indispensable condition of this sin but not its cause, for sin as such requires only a deficient cause. But on the other hand, not sinning or being preserved in good is an effect of the preserving hand of God. Cf. De malo, q. 3, a. I ad 9: "Considering the state of fallen nature, St. Augustine attributes to divine grace the avoidance of any evil whatever that he did not commit, " at least that he is preserved in good by God. In fact, the foregoing objection is found in almost the same terms in St. Thomas, la. d. 40, q. 4, a. 2: the third objection: "He who by his presence is the cause of the ship's safety, that is, the pilot, is by Iris absence the cause of the ship's danger. But God is by His presence in the soul the cause of grace. Therefore by His absence He is the cause of its obduracy. " Reply. "An effect does not follow unless all its causes work together; whereas from the defection of one of them the negation of the effect results. Therefore I say that the cause of grace as agent, is God Himself, and as recipient is the soul by way of subject and matter.... Nor is it essential that every' defect should arise on the part of the agent; it can occur on the part of the recipient, as it does in this proposition. Hence the major of the preceding objection, (i. e., if an affirmation is the cause of an affirmation, a negation is the cause of a negation) is valid when there is but one cause, which is bound to act. as the pilot by' Iris presence is the cause of the ship's safety and by his absence, when he is bound to be present, the cause of its danger. But this major is not true if there are two causes of which the first is indefectible and not bound to prevent every evil and the second is deficient; for then this latter alone is the deficient cause of its own defection. Billuart has well said: "These dialectic rules are valid to the extent that all the principles on both sides concur in the same way, not so if another principle is lacking. But in the reception of grace all the principles concur, not however in its negation. In order than an adult should receive grace, two causes must work together: God must will to infuse the grace, and man must will to receive it, since the infusion of grace is a good and a good is produced by the concurrence of all its causes; on the other hand, for man to be wanting in grace, it suffices for one cause to be in default, obviously the unwillingness of man. " Thus many of Tourneh 's objections are solved, as Billuart declares. Tournely held that, from the necessity of the decree and of grace efficacious in itself for individual acts of piety, the sufficient grace of the Thomists is insufficient and the commandments of God are impossible to some men. On the contrary' , it is truly sufficient and in it efficacious grace is offered to us. but man himself so resists sufficient grace, by which he could observe the commandments, that he is thus deprived of efficacious grace whereby he would in fact observe them. I insist. Franzelin thereupon makes an objection which has been recently revived; cf. Franzelin, De Deo uno. Rome, 1876, pp. 458 f., where he declares: "By no explanations can these two statements, affirmed by Gonet in the text cited with regard to God (tr. 4, disp. 8, no. 254). be reconciled: proposition 1. 'Unless a man or an angel previously by nature were to determine himself toward formal sin (which is foreseen by providence), he would not be predetermined by God to the material in sin. '... But I ask. and Gonet himself asks: 'In what medium God foresees this self-determination of the created will, by nature prior to the divine decree of predetermination (to the material in sin) ?' " Gonet offers two answers of which Franzelin considers only the second, which he impugns. Gonet's reply is that God foresees the defective determination of the will toward formal sin "in the decree denying the efficacious help to avoid sin"; but this denial has its reason in punishment, which presupposes sin, whereas the divine permission of the fault precedes it. Hence it is better expressed by many Thomists, Billuart among them, who say that God foresees the sin and its beginning in His permissive decree (cf. Father Hugon. De Deo uno, p. 213): "The permissive decree is a sufficient, certain, infallible medium. For if God wills to permit something, it most certainly will happen, not by causal necessity, but by logical necessity, just as, if God withholds efficacious concurrence, the good effect is not produced (however, the divine permission of sin implies the non-preservation of the defective will in good, to which preservation God is not bound; otherwise a defective will would never fall into defect). Granting the divine permission of sin, anyone can become good, since man retains his real antecedent power; and he can avoid evil, since the omission of the decree or the permissive decree itself removes none of that real antecedent power; but as a matter of fact, if God wills to permit the evil which He is not bound to prevent, that real power will never be reduced to act. Hence, knowing His permissive decree, God infallibly recognized the deficiency, although He does not cause it. It remains true that the divine refusal of efficacious grace signifies more than the simple permission of sin, more than the non-preservation in good. Similarly, non-election, which is merely negative reprobation and is prior to the foreseen demerits, as a will permitting sin, is distinguished from positive reprobation, which inflicts punishment for sin (la, q. 23, a. 3). Of course, the divine permission of the first sin does not have the reason of penalty, but the divine permission of the second sin is already a punishment for the first. Gonet had said as much in substance (Clypeus. De scientia Dei disp. IV, a. 6, no. 195) and indeed St. Thomas himself had enunciated the principle (la Ilae, q. 79. a. I): "It happens that God (as universal foreseer) does not grant (efficacious) help to some men for avoiding sin which, if He granted it. they would not commit. But He does all this according to the order of His wisdom and justice. " I insist. (Cf. Gonet. ibid., no. 192. ) "The permissive decree cannot have an infallible connection with future sins by reason of non-preservation in good; for otherwise it would follow that the will, left to itself with only general concurrence, would be of itself determined toward evil and this would be the heresy of the Manichaeans and Lutherans. It would also follow that the human will with general concurrence alone could not perform any morally good work, which is contrary' to St. Thomas. " Thus Gonet presents the objection to his own opinion according to Tournely, and the objection has recently been raised again. Gonet's reply {ibid., no. 196): Although the permissive decree may thus have an infallible connection with future sin. a consequence not of causality but of logical sequence, "it does not follow, however, that the free will of man is, of itself and by nature, determined toward evil and sin; not only because by reason of sufficient help it can do good and avoid sin (against the Jansenists), but also because it is one tiring for free will to be deficient of itself and by nature and not capable of preserving itself in good according to right reason, on account of God's not preserving it by special means, and another thing for it to be of itself and by nature determined toward evil (as if it were destroyed altogether and not merely weakened). "In the first case is signified only the deficiency and potentiality for sinning which belong to the rational creature by the very fact that he is made from nothing and is not the rule of Iris own operations. The second case implies further in the free will a natural determination toward evil, arising from the sin of our first parents. This is the heresy of the Lutherans. " If God were indeed bound to preserve in goodness every will which is deficient in itself, no sin would ever occur, the will of every' wayfarer would already be confirmed in good, as was the will of the Blessed Virgin Mary. And since general concurrence is due to nature, but not to any particular individual, man is capable of performing certain natural good works, such as caring for his parents, governing the state. (Cf. Gonet, ibid., and what precedes. ) I insist. But even if God, in tliis permissive decree, infallibly foresees future sin, He does not infallibly recognize which particular sin it will be. Reply. I deny that this follows, for by the knowledge of vision God knows that at that particular time such a man so disposed will be in these circumstances, for instance, Peter in the circumstances attending the Passion; and He sees that for this man in these circumstances there are two alternatives: either to confess the faith or to commit the opposite sin. Cf. p. 236 below on the last difficulty with respect to sufficient grace and the profundity of this mystery'. 4. THE OPINION OF J. GONZALEZ DE ALBEDA O.P. J. Gonzalez de Albeda [8