Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 245–68 245 Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming B ERNHARD B LANKENHORN, OP Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology Berkeley, California O NE OF THE MOST original elements of Hans Urs von Balthasar’s theology is his method of predicating attributes of the triune God, combining divine immutability and divine suffering love. Although Balthasar explicitly rejects the God of process theology, he understands the mystery of the Trinity to include death, surprise, potentiality, becoming, faith, and time.Yet at the same time, Balthasar enthusiastically adopts the Dionysian and Thomistic threefold way of affirmation, negation, and eminence, a method that Dionysius the Areopagite and St.Thomas Aquinas used to exclude all change, suffering, and potentiality from God. How can these apparently contradictory views of God stand together in the thought of one of the greatest speculative theologians of the twentieth century? Not surprisingly, this element of Balthasar’s theology has sparked a lively debate in the past few years. David Schindler1 and Gerard O’Hanlon, SJ2 have argued for the internal coherence of Balthasar’s thought, holding that his theology is an organic development of the Fathers and the great Scholastics. Guy Mansini, OSB3 and Richard Schenk, OP4 have 1 David L. Schindler, book review of Gerard O’Hanlon’s The Immutability of God in the Theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Thomist 58 (1994): 340–41; “The Person: Philosophy,Theology, and Receptivity,” Communio 21 (1994): 172–90. 2 Gerard F. O’Hanlon, SJ, The Immutability of God in the Theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). 3 Guy Mansini, OSB, “Balthasar and Theodramatic Enrichment of the Trinity,” The Thomist 64 (2000): 499–519. 4 Richard Schenk, OP, “Ist die Rede vom leidenden Gott theologisch zu vermeiden? Reflexion über den Streit von K. Rahner und H. U. von Balthasar,” in Der Leidende Gott: Eine philosophische und theologische Kritik, ed. Peter Koslowski and Freidrich Hermanni (Munich:Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 2001), 225–39. 246 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP questioned some of Balthasar’s divine attributes like becoming and suffering. Perhaps this debate can be advanced by asking the question:What is Balthasar’s method of divine naming? More specifically, how does Balthasar recognize perfections in creation and the history of salvation, and how are these perfections then attributed to God? This approach, a particularly Scholastic one, can shed much light on the Trinitarian theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar. Such a study necessarily involves the investigation of a number of essential themes in Balthasar’s thought.We will begin with a brief look at Balthasar’s approach to the relationship between philosophy and theology. Second, we will consider his adoption and critique of negative theology. Third, we will examine his doctrine of Christ as the concrete analogy of being (analogia entis). Fourth, we will consider his principle that the economic Trinity, the Trinity as it operates in the history of salvation, is the only way to the immanent Trinity, the Trinity as it is in itself. These four studies will prepare the way for a closer look at individual divine attributes: although Balthasar did not think of himself a systematic theologian, we can still look for a certain order, not only in his statements about divine naming, but also in his use of divine names. At the same time, our discussion of divine attributes will provide an overview of Balthasar’s adoption of the Dionysian and Thomistic threefold way of affirmation, negation, and eminence.We will conclude with a critique of some elements of Balthasar’s method of naming God. The Relationship Between Philosophy and Theology Balthasar’s view of the relationship between philosophy and theology can be found above all in his book on Karl Barth and in the first volume of Theologik. Balthasar was very sympathetic to Barth’s theological outlook, adopting a Christo-centric theology that places great emphasis on the analogy of faith, which identifies Christ as the ultimate manifestation of the true similitude between creatures and God, a manifestation that includes but also corrects a philosophical analogy of being.Yet there is a marked distinction between the two great Swiss theologians of the twentieth century in their understanding of the relationship between faith and reason, between theology and philosophy. Balthasar points out the tension in Barth’s thought between his desire to give philosophy its due and his insistence on the absolute primacy of graced knowledge. For Barth, theology must employ the concepts and categories of philosophy.5 Yet, as Balthasar recognizes, while grace presup5 Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Theology of Karl Barth (San Francisco: Holt, Rinehart, Winston, 1971), 85. Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 247 poses and is distinct from the order of creation, all too often Barth’s theology reduces everything to the order of grace.6 In an effort to distance himself from Barth, Balthasar explains that “the real source of controversy here was Barth’s refusal to grant any trace of theological relevance to man’s philosophical knowledge of God.”7 Balthasar asks:“Doesn’t the analogy of faith (or grace) presuppose an analogous (by no means identical) analogy in the order of creation and even in the order of sin? Without the latter analogy as its external ground, can the analogy of faith become truly and effectively operative?”8 Balthasar warns us that “if there is no philosophy, then the whole hierarchy of values and scholarly disciplines collapses. If there is no philosophy, then there are no absolute truths and values any more.”9 Instead,“a real priority of nature and reason is presupposed if there is to be a real Incarnation.”10 In Theologik I, especially its revised prologue, Balthasar again insists on an autonomous place for philosophy. Theology presumes an ontological structure;11 revealed truth does not destroy but perfects the world’s truth.12 Yet Balthasar also questions to what extent the world’s ontological structure is already known by reason.13 In fact, he holds that because reason is weak, it must be illumined in order to be able to penetrate thoroughly the being of natural realities.14 His attitude of caution toward reason’s ability to entirely discern the world’s ontological structure moves Balthasar toward a Bonaventurian outlook on faith and reason. Balthasar’s critique of philosophy goes one step further in Theologik II, in which he argues that in some ways, philosophical or worldly logic can no longer assist Christian life and thought. As proof for his position, he points out that for Sts. John and Paul, Jesus’ resurrection contradicted all earthly logic and experience. The Christian, therefore, can no longer orient himself by using earthly logic.15 This argument implies a sharp critique of the power of ungraced reason, leaving the role of philosophy in theology very uncertain. 6 Ibid., 126. 7 Ibid., 296. 8 Ibid. 9 Ibid., 297. 10 Ibid., 270. 11 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theologik I (Einsiedeln, Switzerland: Johannes Verlag, 1985), vii. 12 Ibid., xi. 13 Ibid., vii. 14 Ibid., xii. 15 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theologik II (Einsiedeln, Switzerland: Johannes Verlag, 1985), 98. 248 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP Does this exegesis of Sts. Paul and John on the resurrection conflict with Balthasar’s praise of philosophy in Theologik I? Is the world’s logic not a reflection of the divine logos as it shines forth in creation? Does Balthasar tend toward Karl Barth’s view of the relationship between faith and reason? We cannot give a definitive answer to these questions now. Our study of Balthasar’s method of divine naming will place us within closer reach of a solution. As Peter Casarella has pointed out, Balthasar’s notion of faith generating new experience does not necessarily entail fideism.16 On the other hand, Richard Schenk has argued that Balthasar’s theological method, which Schenk identifies with the Augustinian–Franciscan tradition, involves a receptivity to graced knowledge that is theoretically open-ended to the point that philosophy is no longer a measuring stick for revelation, but is transformed by received public and private revelation.17 Nevertheless, Balthasar did recognize the indispensable role of philosophy in theology.The question for us is not whether Balthasar was a fideist, but what role philosophy plays in his theology. According to Balthasar, philosophy unaided by grace can discover perfections in creation that may be truly predicated of God analogously. However, since the illumination of grace may be needed to recognize what is in nature, theology may discover additional perfections in nature that were not accessible to ungraced reason. Balthasar’s Appropriation and Critique of Negative Theology One of Balthasar’s main concerns in Theologik II is a defense of positive language about God against Neo-platonic apophatic theology and Eastern mysticism.The latter’s approaches to God lead to such a radical negative theology that they form the greatest fortress against Christianity, leaving God wholly unknown and wholly distant from us.18 Yet a biblical foundation for negative theology exists already in the Old Testament.19 The Church Fathers even adopted elements of pagan Neo-platonic negative theology, although their outlook was balanced by a recognition of the primacy that is due to the way of eminence, 16 Peter Casarella,“Experience as a theological category: Hans Urs von Balthasar on the Christian encounter with God’s image,” Communio 20 (1993): 118. Reflexion über den Streit von K. Rahner und H. U. von Balthasar,” in Der Leidende Gott: Eine philosophische und theologische Kritik, ed. Peter Koslowski and Freidrich Hermanni (Munich:Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 2001), 235–36. 18 Theologik II, 88. 19 Ibid., 82–83, 94. 17 Schenk, “Ist die Rede vom leiden Gott theologisch zu vermeiden?” Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 249 which is a way of affirmation.20 Following Thomas Aquinas, Balthasar affirms that the more knowable in se is less knowable quoad nos.21 Furthermore, since God the Father remains invisible, he is beyond our concepts.22 Despite the wondrous revelation that God has made in Christ, the infinite God-creature distance remains, even with Christological analogy.23 Balthasar assents to the classic position in Christian theology that God is incomprehensible, a position that goes back to Philo and scriptural revelation.24 Balthasar’s creative contribution to the critique of negative theology is his approach to the negation of materiality and finitude. This way of purification, in which one abstracts from materiality, corporeality, the sensible, the imaginable, and the conceivable, has led to great problems, even as practiced by the medievals and St. John of the Cross.25 In a bold move, Balthasar never clearly supports a full negation of material limitations when speaking of God.26 Why does he do this? We can provide only a brief answer to this question, yet one that seems to reflect the entire spirit of Balthasar’s theology.As already seen, he hesitates to use worldly logic to evaluate revelation.This hesitation is rooted in a deep desire to have our finite, fallen reason corrected by a marvelous graced illumination from above. Balthasar wants to let the incarnate Word speak, to be attentive to the divine attributes which our philosophical logic and analogies may have overlooked or rejected, but which are manifested in the glorious revelation of Christ. Balthasar’s motivation is praiseworthy. His reverence and awe before the Word revealing itself is a model for theologians. Indeed, theology on one’s knees is the only way to a fruitful theology. But does Balthasar’s method present an approach to divine naming which possesses both internal coherence and coherence with the Fathers and the Scholastics? Some possible solutions to this question will emerge as we consider how Balthasar attributes perfections to God. For the moment, we can say that Balthasar recognizes both a need for negative theology and a limit to affirmation. God remains incomprehensible. Even attributes that seem to imply an intrinsic finitude will only be predicated of God within a negative theology that excludes 20 Ibid., 91. 21 Ibid., 110–11, 246. 22 Theologik I, 15; Theologik II, 87. 23 Theologik II, 288. 24 Ibid., 87. 25 Ibid., 101–2. 26 Ibid., 89, 91. 250 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP from him all inner-worldly experience.27 But Balthasar has also left the door open for the possibility of attributing characteristics like sacrifice and becoming to God, attributes that philosophical negative theologies have usually identified as intrinsically material or finite, suggesting that, for Balthasar, salvation history and the intellect’s graced illumination will open up a radically new perspective on nature. Jesus Christ as the Concrete analogia entis Balthasar’s theology is centered on Christ as the perfection of creation manifesting his divinely ordained relationship to God,28 the concrete analogy of being revealing all of God’s attributes.29 He is the standard with which every philosophical analogy of being must be measured: “Theological analogy sheds definitive light on what the philosophical analogy is as such.”30 In his perfect humanity Christ manifests our proper relationship of similarity and dissimilarity to God. The analogy of faith that comes through Christ is so important because creation’s proper analogy to God is obscured by sin; in the words of Angela Franz Franks,“only Christ, as both divine Son and man, can express absolute Being within a worldly form.”31 It is the hypostatic union that really makes this analogy possible. The perfect qualities and attributes of the one nature can be applied to the other only because they are united in one person.32 This concrete analogia entis still presupposes a philosophical analogy of being, a natural similarity of God and creatures:“The theological analogy does not abolish the philosophical analogy.”33 However, “there is no upper limit to the concrete content that can be injected into this concept of nature . . . no creature can set arbitrary limits to what God does or could say to us . . . grace elevates and completes man in a radical way.”34 27 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theodrama IV (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1994), 324 (Theodramatik III [Einsiedeln, Switzerland: Johannes Verlag, 1980], 301–2); O’Hanlon, The Immutability of God, 38. 28 Angela Franz Franks, “Trinitarian Analogia Entis in Hans Urs von Balthasar,” The Thomist 62 (1998): 542. 29 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theodrama II (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1990), 267 (Theodramatik II.1 [Einsiedeln, Switzerland: Johannes Verlag, 1976], 243); Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theodrama III (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992), 221 (Theodramatik II.2 [Einsiedeln, Switzerland: Johannes Verlag, 1978], 203). 30 Theology of Karl Barth, 231. 31 Franks, “Trinitarian Analogia Entis,” 541, cf. 553. 32 Theodrama III, 222 (Theodramatik II.2, 203–4). 33 Theology of Karl Barth, 230; see Franks, “Trinitarian Analogia Entis,” 542. 34 Theology of Karl Barth, 236. Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 251 It should be pointed out that for Balthasar, the analogy between God’s being and created being is somewhat fluid. In Christ, however, the proper analogy between finite and infinite freedom is revealed.35 We are called to live out our freedom as a participation in Christ’s freedom, which will bring us into greater harmony with our essence, just as God’s freedom is in harmony with his.36 Freedom is a power by which one determines one’s position in being.37 There is a disjunction between the analogy of being in fallen nature and the analogy of being to which we are called in grace.We can recognize here a Plotinian,Augustinian, and Bonaventurian understanding of the hierarchy of being (ontological, epistemological, and moral) in which the human being’s place is somewhat fluid and temporary, in contrast to a Proclian, Dionysian, and Thomistic approach in which each being has a fairly permanent place within the hierarchy, with an absolute ontological determination and a relatively fixed epistemological and moral determination. By allying himself with the former tradition, Balthasar intensifies the radicality of the revelation of Christ as it opens up a new perspective, one that includes insights into the kind of perfections which will be attributed to God.38 The Economic Trinity as the Only Way to the Immanent Trinity In Balthasar’s view, statements about the immanent Trinity can only be made from the economic Trinity.39 This principle implies the critique of classic Trinitarian analogies (like those of St. Augustine and Richard of St. Victor) that Balthasar articulates in Theologik II.40 Instead of focusing on analogies in creation to describe the Trinity, one should look to the center of salvation history, especially the central event of that history, the paschal mystery.41 While non-biblical analogies can be used in theology, they 35 Franks, “Trinitarian Analogia Entis,” 536; Thomas G. Dalzell, SM, The Dramatic Encounter of Divine and Human Freedom in the Theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar (New York, Peter Lang, 1997), 48, 70–80. 36 Dalzell, The Dramatic Encounter of Divine and Human Freedom, 80, 98. 37 Ibid., 72–73, 97. 38 For this interpretation of the history of theology, see Richard Schenk, OP, Die Gnade Vollendeter Endlichkeit: Zur Tranzendentaltheologischen Auslegung der Thomanischen Anthropologie (Freiburg, Germany: Herder, 1986), 246–48, 279–80, 517–18. 39 Theodrama IV, 324 (Theodramatik III, 301–2);Thomas Rudolf Krenski, Passio Caritatis:Trinitarische Passiologie im Werk Hans Urs von Balthasar (Einsiedeln, Switzerland: Johannes Verlag, 1990), 117–18, 129. 40 Theologik II, 61. 41 Krenski, Passio Caritatis, 118; Matthew Levering,“Balthasar on Christ’s Consciousness on the Cross,” The Thomist 65 (2001), 570–71. 252 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP should be treated with great caution. Contra Karl Rahner, however, the economic Trinity cannot be identified with the immanent Trinity.42 Still, the two are closely connected, so that everything in creation, including finitude, suffering, and sin, must somehow have its foundation in the Trinity.43 However, because the immanent Trinity is distinct from the economic Trinity, we cannot simply read off the former from the latter. Because Jesus has two distinct natures, he cannot simply represent his own divinity, as this would involve a mono-physite heresy. Not everything about Jesus’ humanity can be taken as a direct revelation of God. To argue so would be to miss the crucial distinction between the form and the content of form, the distinction between form and the truth communicated by the form. Rather, Jesus manifests his relationship with the Father and transposes it into the creaturely-temporal.44 With the purifying method of the Dionysian threefold way (affirmation, negation, eminence), the revelation of that relationship will take us to the heart of the Trinitarian mystery. Divine Time and Space We are now ready to study the first set of Balthasar’s controversial divine attributes, which are divine time and space. The previous sections will shed much light on the method that Balthasar uses in predicating individual names of God. The divine processions, the procession of the Son from the Father, the procession of the Holy Spirit from the Father and the Son, are timeless.45 The Father is not “before” the Son, and the Son is not “after” the Father. The divine Persons are co-eternal, a thesis that Catholic dogma demands. God’s time cannot include any creaturely becoming.46 Here we have the negation of creaturely time from the life of the Trinity. Turning to the way of eminence, however, Balthasar posits a “supertime.”The first reason for this is that it maximizes divine love: The Father’s act of surrender calls for its own area of freedom: the Son’s act, whereby he receives himself from and acknowledges his indebtedness to the Father, requires its own area. . . . However intimate the relationship, it implies that the distinction between the persons is maintained. Some42 Theodrama III, 508 (Theodramatik II.2, 466); O’Hanlon, The Immutability of God, 37. 43 Theodrama V, 516 (Theodramatik IV, 472); Franks,“Trinitarian Analogia Entis,” 534, 542; O’Hanlon, The Immutability of God, 72. 44 Theodrama V, 120 (Theodramatik IV, 104); Peter Casarella, “The Expression and Form of the Word:Trinitarian Hermeneutics and the Sacramentality of Language in Hans Urs von Balthasar’s Theology,” Renascence 48 (1996): 115, 119. 45 Theologik II, 126. 46 Theodrama V, 77 (Theodramatik IV, 67). Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 253 thing like infinite “duration” and infinite “space” must be attributed to the acts of reciprocal love so that the life of the communio, of fellowship, can develop. While the Father from all eternity utters his eternal Word, the latter does not, as it were, keep interrupting him. . . .True, all temporal notions of “before” and “after” must be kept at a distance; but absolute freedom must provide the acting area in which it is to develop. . . .47 A kind of “super-time” and “super-space” allows for an interchange of love and thanksgiving between the divine Persons that is analogous to an intense experience of mutual love and thanksgiving among human beings, while the traditional understanding of eternity allows only one perfect divine act of love.The latter would mean that the Son cuts off the word of the Father, does not leave him room to communicate his love for the Son. Balthasar is taking his experience of human interpersonal love as a foundation for this description of divine communio.The beloved must leave the lover room for self-expression, the time to speak, before responding with thanksgiving. This understanding of interpersonal love is also rooted in dialogical philosophy and the mystical experience of Adrienne von Speyr. We will elaborate on Balthasar’s appropriation of this Trinitarian analogy later. Balthasar backs up this language about God by appealing to a very novel way of interpreting Johannine theological time: . . . God’s “abiding forever” must not be seen as a “non-time” but as a super-time that is unique to him; and this is illustrated in the fact that Christ’s time mediates between God’s “time” and world-time. Christ’s time recapitulates and comprehends world-time, while it also reveals God’s super-time. Jesus’ time, particularly in John, has a kind of inner periodicity that, while of course colored by the human time in which Jesus shares, has its own intrinsic validity as a result of his relationship with the Father; in other words, it has Trinitarian significance.48 47 Theodrama II, 257 (Theodramatik II.1, 233: “Der Akt des väterlichen Sichgebens fordert seinen eigenen Freiheitsraum, der Akt des Sichempfangens und— verdankens des Sohnes den seinen . . . Der Austausch kann noch so innig sein, er fordert das Sich-Durchhalten der Differenz. Den Akten der sich austauschenden Liebe muss so etwas wie unendliche ‘Dauer’ und unendlicher ‘Raum’ gewährt werden, damit das Leben der communio, der Gegenseitigkeit sich entfalten kann. Während der Vater von Ewigkeit her sein ewiges Wort spricht, fällt ihm dieses nicht gleichsam immer schon ins Wort. . . .Wenn aus diesem Austausch auch jedes zeitliche Früher und Später fernzuhalten ist, muss sich die absolute Freiheit doch den Spiel-Raum gewähren, sich zu entfalten.”) 48 Theodrama V, 30 (Theodramatik IV, 24: “. . . dass Gottes ‘Dauer’ nicht Unzeit, sondern eine ihm eigene Über-Zeit ist, wird vor allem daran ersichtlich, dass zwischen der ‘Zeit’ Gottes und der Weltzeit die Zeit Christi vermittelt: die Weltzeit in sich zusammenfassend, aber auch die Über-Zeit Gottes offenbarend. 254 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP Relegating Jesus’ sacred time to his human nature and excluding it from a revelation of the triune life would be an unjustifiable division of the Person of Jesus into his two natures.49 Rather, this salvific-historical time in the Gospel of John points to Jesus’ relationship with the Father. Balthasar sees an even stronger basis for this kind of exegesis in the sending of the Holy Spirit in the New Testament.50 Thus, the role of philosophical negative theology is acknowledged in the negation of purely worldly time. However, Christ moved in a special time distinct from this purely creaturely time.We cannot negate this from the immanent Trinity based on a previous notion of the nature of eternity, since this would bypass the economic Trinity that provides the only access to the immanent Trinity. A Boethian notion of eternity would involve the importation of a non-biblical analogy and ignore analogies that the Bible itself presents, a method which does not adequately recognize Christ as the exemplar for all of creation. Only the revelation of Christ can ultimately enlighten the mind sufficiently as it strives to recognize the true nature of eternity. Suffering Divine Love The main exposition of Balthasar’s controversial divine attributes is found in the fifth volume of Theodrama (volume four in the German). Early on in the work, he summarizes the difficult paradox that he maintains: We must resolve to see these two apparently contradictory concepts as a unity: eternal or absolute Being—and “happening.” This “happening” is not a becoming in the earthly sense: it is the coming-to-be, not of something that once was not (that would be Arianism), but, evidently, of something that grounds the idea, the inner possibility and reality of a becoming. All earthly becoming is a reflection of the eternal “happening” in God, which, we repeat, is per se identical with the eternal Being or essence.51 Die Zeit Jesu hat, gerade by Johannes, eine Art innere Periodik, die gewiss zunächst von der Menschenzeit, an der Jesus teilnimmt, tingiert wird, aber in sich selbst durch seine Beziehung zum Vater, also trinitarisch, relevant wird”). 49 Theologik II, 117. 50 Theodrama V, 31–32 (Theodramatik IV, 25–26). 51 Theodrama V, 67 (Theodramatik IV, 59: “. . . wir müssen uns entschliessen, diese beiden scheinbar unvereinbaren Begriffe zusammenzusehen: ewiges oder absolutes Sein—und Geschehen. Ein Geschehen, das also kein Werden im innerweltlichen Sinn ist, kein Enstehen dessen, was irgendwann nicht war (das wäre Arianismus), aber offenbar doch etwas, was die Idee, die innere Möglichkeit und Wirklichkeit eines Werdens fundiert. Innerwelt-liches Werden ist ein Abbild des ewigen Geschehens in Gott, das als solches—man muss das wiederholen—identisch ist mit dem ewigen Sein oder Wesen”). Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 255 While Balthasar affirms the immutability of God, he also sees becoming as analogous to the divine nature.And yet, God is the eternal, fully actual Absolute.“And since God is immutable, the vitality of his ‘becoming’ can never be anything other than his Being. . . .”52 Balthasar assents to the language of God’s pure and infinite actuality in this and many other passages:“The eternal life that is God . . . cannot be described as a becoming. . . .”53 Here we see the negation of attributes like created and becoming, suffering, and finitude, since immutability refers to the claim that God is not changing, and infinity points out that God is not finite. Turning to the way of affirmation, Balthasar posits a kind of death on the part of the Father in generating the Son: In giving of himself, the Father does not give something (or even everything) that he has but all that he is—for in God there is only being, not having. So the Father’s being passes over, without remainder, to the begotten Son. . . .This total self-giving, to which the Son and the Spirit respond by an equal self-giving, is a kind of “death,” a first, radical “kenosis,” as one might say. It is a kind of “super-death” that is a component of all love and that forms the basis in creation for all instances of “the good death,” from self-forgetfulness in favor of the beloved right up to that highest love by which a man “gives his life for his friends.”54 This explains how suffering can be possible in creation. Balthasar is operating on the premise that creaturely limitation must have its foundation in God.55 He posits an “infinite distance” between the Father and the Son as the ground for the possibility of creation, a distance that also allows for the possibility for sin. Searching for the source of suffering, he finds it in God’s own self. The suffering of the Father is the foundation for every “good death” in creation, that is, every death for the sake of love, every self-denial for the sake of the other. 52 Theodrama V, 512 (Theodramatik IV, 468:“Auch weil Gott unveränderlich ist, kann die Lebendigkeit seines ‘Werdens’ nie etwas anderes sein als sein Sein . . .”). 53 Theodrama V, 77 (Theodramatik IV, p/ 67: “Das ewige Leben, das Gott ist . . . kann keinesfalls als ein Werden bezeichnet werden . . .”). 54 TheodramaV, 84 (Theodramatik IV, 73–74:“Die Selbstpreisgabe des Vaters, der nicht nur etwas oder alles von dem gibt, was er hat, sondern alles, was er ist (in Gott ist nur Sein und kein Haben), geht restlos auf den erzeugten Sohn hin . . . diese totale Selbstpreisgabe, die der Sohn und der Geist antwortend mitvollziehen werden, bedeutet so etwas wie einen ‘Tod,’ eine erste radikale ‘Kenose,’ wenn man will: ein Über-Tod, der als Moment in jeder Liebe liegt und innerhalb der Schöpfung alles grundlegen wird, was in ihr guter Tod sein wird: vom Sichvergessen für den Geliebten bis zu jener höchsten Liebe, die ihr ‘Leben hingibt für ihre Freunde’ ”). 55 Ibid.; see Theologik II, 78. 256 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP This text also gives us a glimpse of Balthasar’s a priori understanding of love: “a kind of ‘super-death’ that is a component of all love. . . .” Suffering is that which every lover is willing to undergo for the beloved, the ultimate sign of love. We pointed out how Balthasar’s interpretation of human love relationships influenced his view of eternity. Another side of this interpretation of the nature of human love leads him to posit suffering in God. The Father’s suffering is a kind of total self-emptying of his own self into the Son, a giving of his whole divine essence to another. This suffering is appropriately predicated of the Father because of the nature of love, which must be in the divine Persons most of all. Balthasar backs up this radical notion of divine suffering with a number of authorities. First, God is described as crying, complaining, in pain, and in sorrow over eighty times in the Old Testament, far outnumbering the statements about God’s immutability in the old covenant.56 Second, passages about God’s compassion and mercy like John 3:16 and Romans 8:32 ought to be taken seriously, and ought to be seen as standing behind that of the earthly Jesus, meaning they should not be restricted to Jesus’ humanity.The economic revelation of the Trinity seems to demand some kind of suffering in God.57 Third, a number of Church Fathers, including Tertullian, Cyril of Alexandria, and Origen posited affects or suffering in God.58 Thomas G. Weinandy has also recently pointed out the place of divine suffering in patristic thought, especially in Origen.59 This suffering cannot be externally imposed on God, as it cannot occur without the assent of the divine will. God chooses to be affected by suffering in creation out of his love for all beings. Fourth, Balthasar approaches suffering as a kind of perfection based on the mystical visions of Speyr, who reported mystical experiences of divine suffering. Her writings become a support for Balthasar’s unique approach to the economic Trinity as revelatory of the immanent Trinity:“In the Christian context, sacrifice, suffering, the Cross and death are only the reflection of tremendous realities in the Father, in heaven, in eternal life.”60 56 Theodrama V, 214–15 (Theodramatik IV, 193). 57 Dalzell, The Dramatic Encounter of Divine and Human Freedom, 169; O’Hanlon, The Immutability of God, 38. 58 Theodrama V, 217–221 (Theodramatik IV, 195–99); see Krenski, Passio Caritatis, 62–70. 59 Thomas G. Weinandy, OFM, Cap., Does God Suffer? (University of Notre Dame Press, 2000), 97–102. 60 Theodrama V, 511 (Theodramatik IV, 467: “ ‘Opfer, Leiden, Kreuz und Tod sind christlich betrachtet nur die Widerspiegelung von gewaltigen Wirklichkeiten im Vater, im Himmel, im ewigen Leben . . .’ ”). Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 257 But is the attribution of suffering to God simply metaphorical language used to bring out the intensity of divine love? Such is the interpretation of Gerard O’Hanlon and Thomas Dalzell.61 But Balthasar himself does not describe God’s suffering as metaphorical.“So we can say that, if human love is enlivened by the element of surprise, something analogous to it cannot be excluded from divine love. It is as if the Son born of the Father ‘from the outset surpasses the Father’s wildest expectations.’ ”62 The language of divine surprise is much more than an attempt to describe the utter fullness of God’s love without predicating some kind of actual surprise in God. It seems that something analogous to surprise as experienced in this world is also found in God. Still, could Balthasar not be using the term “analogous” in a very loose way here? Balthasar’s poetic and dialectical rhetoric often make it difficult to grasp what he is trying to say. However, his Theologik II includes a fascinating passage on the nature of the revelation of Christ and its relationship to metaphor. It was already mentioned that all three spheres are claimed for the Word revealing itself as flesh: it is the “expression” of God (Heb 1:3), the “image” of the invisible God (Col 1:15, 2 Cor 4:4) and the “Word” of God ( Jn 1, 1:14, Rev 19:13). Here there is no hierarchy anymore, rather the three descriptions are equal, stand next to one another and are even in one another. Everything in the Word made flesh is an expression of the Father in the Holy Spirit. . . .63 Balthasar then turns to the work of E. Jüngel on metaphor, which is here taken in the Aristotelian sense of “translation into another form of speech.”64 Balthasar refuses to attribute such metaphor to the revelation of Christ, countering that grace gives the believer the light “to go beyond the boundaries of the metaphorical image to an understanding of the 61 O’Hanlon, Immutability of God, 141–43; Dalzell, Dramatic Encounter, 169–71. 62 Theodrama V, 79, quoting Speyr (Theodramatik IV, 69:“Darum ist ein Analogon zu dem, was in menschlicher Liebe das belebende Moment der Überraschung ist, aus der göttlichen nicht auszuschliessen. Der aus dem Vater geborene Sohn übertrifft gleichsam ‘die kühnsten Erwartungen des Vaters von vornherein’ ”). 63 Theologik II, 246: “Doch wurde schon angemerkt, dass für das als Fleisch sich offenbarende Wort alle drei Sphären in Anspruch genommen werden: es ist ‘Ausdruck’ Gottes (Heb 1:3),‘Bild’ des unsichtbaren Gottes (Col 1:15, 2 Cor 4:4) und ‘Wort’ Gottes ( Jn 1, 1:14, Rev 19:13). Hier herrscht keine Stufung mehr, viehlmehr stehen die drei Bezeichnungen ebenbürtig neben—ja ineinander.Alles am fleischgewordenen Wort ist Ausdruck des Vaters im Heiligen Geist. . . .” 64 Ibid., 249: “Übersetzung in eine andere Sprachform.” 258 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP primordial meaning.”65 He concludes that “to describe language in this context as metaphor at all means to drop out of the realm opened up by God’s revelation. The creaturely images . . . become transparent and included in the sacrificial love of God.”66 The grace of Christ elevates the earthly language of the God-man, language that includes “expression,” “image,” and “word,” to the divine.Thus, to interpret Christ’s revelations of divine time, suffering, faith, and surprise as metaphorical would be to veil what Christ himself never veiled, to close the curtain of “likenesses” that the disciples finally overcame in the Last Supper discourse of John.67 Instead, the divine modalities of expectation and fulfillment, of letting the other be, of faith and hope, of surprise, time and space, are “positive features of the eternal, free, animated life of the Trinity.”68 That Balthasar posits suffering as a properly analogous divine attribute is an interpretation held by Rudolf Krenski, Margaret Turek, and Anne Hunt. Krenski understands Balthasar to predicate suffering of God, pointing to a similitudo within a greater dissimilitudo, so that there is an identity of the suffering revealed in Christ and the suffering of God, although the latter’s is dissimilar because it is a freely accepted passio.69 Turek sees the predication of self-yielding surrender, weakness, dependency, and expectancy as perfections included in the Father’s infinite freedom.70 Hunt refers to Balthasar’s analogies from the paschal mystery to the immanent Trinity as “not just metaphor but analogy properly speaking.”71 Balthasar certainly realized the immense tension that his thought introduces into theology’s image of God. Applying this new notion of eternity as time-fullness, he states, “There is a primal beginning in which the Father is ‘alone,’ even if he was never without the Son, for 65 Ibid.: “um das Gleichnisbild über seine Grenzen hinaus zu seinem urbildlichen Sinn hin zu verstehen.” 66 Ibid., 250: “in diesem Rahmen Sprache überhaupt als Metapher zu bezeichnen, fällt aus dem in Gottes Offenbarung eröffneten Kreis. Die geschöpflichen Bilder . . . werden in die Sprache der sich entäussernden Liebe Gottes durchsichtig und darin einbezogen.” 67 Ibid. 68 Theodrama V, 98 (Theodramatik IV, 86: “. . . lauter Positivitäten der ewigen freien Lebendigkeit in der Trinität.”). 69 Krenski, Passio Caritatis, 362–70. See Schenk, “Ist die Rede vom leidenden Gott theologisch zu vermeiden?” 235–36. 70 Margaret M.Turek,“ ‘As the Father has Loved Me’ ( Jn 15:9): Balthasar’s Theodramatic Approach to a Theology of God the Father,” Communio 26 (1999): 300–304. 71 Anne Hunt, “Psychological Analogy and Paschal Mystery in Trinitarian Theology,” Theological Studies 59 (1998): 215. Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 259 ultimately it is he, unique and alone, who begets the Son.”72 The Father somehow sacrifices his solitude to generate the Son, even though the divine Persons must be co-eternal, since their divinity requires their eternity. Balthasar himself describes “emotions” as actually existing in the divinity: Furthermore, such forms of the eternal life as mercy, patience, and so on, can be understood on the analogy of human emotions, but this must not involve attributing “mutability” to God . . . the Bible, in both Old and New Testaments, look through this attitude and discern beyond a quality of the Divinity as such.73 Balthasar also presents a kind of divine generation, in which, although the Son proceeds from the Father, the Father has no assurances of the Son’s response to him: There are no in-built securities or guarantees in the absolute self-giving of the Father to Son, of Son to Father, and of both to the Spirit. Humanly speaking, it is a total surrender of all possessions, including Godhead. From the giver’s point of view, therefore, it could appear to be an absolute “risk. . . .”74 The Father makes a certain wager in generating the Son, “hoping” that the Son will assent to the will of the Father. The Father somehow does not know what the Son will do; he is filled with expectation; he waits for a response of obedience.This anxious “waiting” of the Father will become one of the bases for divine love. It is one instance of the Father’s suffering, the willingness to be rejected by his own Son, the “decision” to give up his solitude in favor of communio. And yet Balthasar admits that the divine processions are not a matter of the Father’s decision, but consequent upon 72 Theodrama V, 94, quoting Speyr (Theodramatik IV, 82:“ ‘Es gibt einen Uranfang, in welchem der Vater ‘allein’ ist, auch wenn er nie ohne den Sohn war, denn schliesslich ist er es, der den Sohn zeugt, in seiner Einzigkeit und Alleinheit’ ”). 73 Theodrama V, 222 (Theodramatik IV, 200: “Ferner können, ja müssen Formen der ewigen göttlichen Lebendigkeit (wie Erbarmen, Gedult, usf.) in Analogie zu menschlichen Affekten verstanden werden, ohne dass dadurch ‘Veränderlichkeit’ in Gott einzuzeichnen wäre . . . die Bibel Alten und Neuen Bundes blickt zweifellos durch seine ökonomische Haltung hindurch auf eine Eigenschaft der Gottheit an sicht selbst.”). 74 TheodramaV, 245 (Theodramatik IV, 221:“In der absoluten Selbsthingabe des Vaters an den Sohn, des Sohnes an den Vater, beider an den Geist sind keinerlei ‘Sicherungen’ eingebaut; es geht, menschlich gesprochen, um den restlosen Verlust des ‘ganzen Habens und Besitzens,’ die Gottheit einschliesslich, um etwas also, das vom Schenkenden her wie ein absolutes ‘Wagnis’ erscheinen könnte . . .”). 260 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP the very nature of the Godhead.75 He thereby negates any creaturely wager of God, since the Father did not choose to take a chance and generate the Son rather than to remain alone. Nevertheless, an eminent wager remains, one that is beyond our comprehension. Still, the divine Persons are co-eternal. How then can the Father be said to be “waiting” for the Son’s response? Furthermore, how could it even be possible that one divine Person reject another? This paradox may seem to pose a contradiction. But for Balthasar, such an approach is needed in order to acknowledge the divine freedom of each person of the Trinity: In begetting the Son, the Father does not determine him; rather “he endows him with freedom to explore the infinite realm of his own free Sonship, of his own divine sovereignty.” Accordingly, it is the Father’s will to be “outstripped, for all eternity, by the Son’s love. Faith is, as it were, the space that must be opened up so that there is room for infinite fulfillment, beyond the limits of all expectation.”“Faith is constant readiness, the basis of all love.”76 What is the economic basis for the predication of this kind of freedom in the Godhead? First, the incarnated Son of God displayed an assent to the Father’s will, one that did not come automatically and seems, following the Johannine narrative, to not have been fully desired at first. Jesus Christ’s decision to be obedient to the Father mirrors a divine reality.77Balthasar is applying the principle that Christ reveals not his own divinity but his relationship to the Father, which he can do because Christ “is the revelation of the Trinity . . . ‘he lives in a fully Trinitarian way yet is a man among men.’ ”78 The last two citations from TheodramaV also include Speyr’s exegesis of the New Testament several times: Balthasar consistently gives Speyr’s mystical understanding of the New Testament a great deal of authority. Finally, we can recognize Balthasar’s adoption of themes from dialogical philosophy, where the perfection of love and communio involves letting the other be other. 75 Theodrama V, 88 (Theodramatik IV, 77). 76 Theodrama V, 98 (Theodramatik IV, 86: “Der Vater legt den Sohn in der Zeugung nicht fest, ‘er lässt ihn vielmehr frei in den unendlichen Raum seiner eigenen sohnhaften Freiheit, seiner eigenen göttlichen Souveränität,’ deshalb will sich der Vater ‘in alle Ewigkeit von der Liebe des Sohnes übertreffen lassen. Der Glaube ist wie der Raum, der geöffnet werden muss, damit Platz für unendliche Erfüllungen über alle begrenzte Erwartung hinaus geschaffen wird.’ ‘Glaube ist die stete Bereitschaft, und so die Basis aller Liebe’ ”). 77 Theodrama V, 123 (Theodramatik IV, 106). 78 Theodrama V, 121 (Theodramatik IV, 104: “Der Sohn ist trinitarische Offenbarung . . . ‘er lebt vollkommen trinitarisch, obwohl er Mensch unter Menschen wird’ ”). Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 261 Thus the Father who gives the Son divine freedom, a freedom that integrates every perfection found in human freedom, must respect the autonomy of the Son, letting the Son be God in his way, giving him “room” to maneuver, the “space” to respond to the Father’s outpouring of himself. Thus the Father has faith that the Son will respond with obedience, which he does. The Father is overwhelmed by the immensity of the Son’s response, the Son’s thankfulness for being generated and adoration of the Father’s greatness: “Again and again, the Father and the Son are more in their mutual relationship than they themselves would have supposed.”79 The absolute negation of such freedom, faith, and surprise from God in philosophical negative theology is thus overcome by a reverent obedience to the revelation of Christ interpreted through mystical experience and dialogical philosophy.The content of nature expounded by philosophy not yet purified by the obedience of faith is radically transformed. Let us now step back and consider the overall Trinitarian analogy at work in Balthasar’s thought. This can only be approached through his critique of the Augustinian Trinitarian analogy and his adoption of the analogy of the family for the triune life. Balthasar maintains that St. Augustine’s analogies of mens, notitia, amor, and memoria, intellectus, voluntas are inadequate. The former remains accidental in relation to the substance, since each particular act of knowing and loving is nonsubstantial for the human person. The latter never moves beyond one person, as they represent the faculties of one soul.80 Here Balthasar points to Augustine’s emphasis on the unity of essence achieved through his analogies, one that seems to leave an inadequate representation of the three persons. Balthasar’s objection reminds us of the inherent weakness of every Trinitarian analogy. Either the unity of the divine essence is emphasized at the expense of the plurality of persons or vice versa. Balthasar puts a much greater emphasis on the distinction of persons, due to (1) his understanding of Jesus Christ as the concrete analogia entis who reveals not so much his own divinity but his relationship to the Father, which manifests a Trinity that dialogues as the incarnate Jesus dialogues with the Father; (2) the Trinitarian visions of Speyr; and (3) his adoption of the theme of personhood as intrinsically dialogical from philosophers like Martin Buber. Following an exposition of the dialogical philosophers Buber, Franz Rosenzweig, and Ferdinand Ebner, Balthasar compares the Augustinian analogy to the analogy of the family, which is “the simple but necessary supplement of the previously described dialogic, 79 Theodrama V, 515, quoting Speyr (Theodramatik IV, 471: “. . . ‘immer wieder sind sich Vater und Sohn gegenseitig mehr als sie selber vermutet hatten’ ”). 80 Theologik II, 35–37. Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP 262 and remains despite its clear differences the best imago Trinitatis given to creation. It overcomes the enclosure of self that is found in the Augustinian concepts. . . .”81 Not only does the analogy of the family avoid the isolated individualism of Augustine’s approach, but the latter’s analogy is not found in Scripture, and so should only be adopted with extreme care, since theology should always remain close to Scripture.82 Balthasar’s enthusiasm for this interpersonal analogy does not stop him from offering a critique of Richard of St.Victor’s intrasubjective Trinitarian analogy. Still, Balthasar’s own understanding of God seems to be much closer to Richard’s than to Augustine’s. As Matthew Levering has pointed out, Balthasar’s difficulty with Richard’s approach is caused not so much by the latter’s use of an analogy from three human persons but rather by Richard’s failure to ground this analogy in salvation history.83 So Balthasar’s preferred model for triune love is that of interpersonal human love. Whereas Augustine spoke of mind loving its knowledge, Balthasar insists on an analogy of love between one human person and another, the love of parents for their child. Using this model, Balthasar presents joy and wonder as part of the mutual love of the divine Persons: Above all we must fend off the “all-knowing” attitude . . . this eviscerates the joys of expectation, of hope and fulfillment, the joys of giving and receiving, and the even deeper joys of finding oneself in the other and of being constantly over-fulfilled by him; and finally—since we are speaking of God—it destroys the possibility of mutual acknowledgment and adoration in the Godhead. . . . [W]e cannot say that a particular hypostasis is rich in possessing and poor in giving away, for the fullness of blessedness lies in both giving and receiving both the gift and the giver. Since these acts are eternal, there is no end to their newness, no end to being surprised and overwhelmed by what is essentially immeasurable.The fundamental philosophical act, wonder, need not be banished from the realm of the Absolute.84 81 Ibid., 56: “die einfache aber notwendige Ergänzung der vorher geschilderten Dialogik, bleibt trotz allen klaren Verschiedenheiten die sprechendste dem Geschöpf eingestiftete imago Trinitatis. Sie übersteigt nicht nur die Ichgeschlossenheit des augustinischen Konzepts. . . .” 82 Theodrama III, 508 (Theodramatik II.2, 466). 83 Levering, “Balthasar on Christ’s Consciousness on the Cross,” 569–70. 84 Theodrama II, 257–58 (Theodramatik II.1, 233–34: “Vor allem ist daraus jedes für Menschen tödliche ‘Je-schon-Wissen’ . . . fernzuhalten, womit die Freuden des Erwartens, des Erhoffens und Erfüllens, die Freuden des Von-einander-Empfangens, tiefer noch die Freuden des sich im Andern immer neu Findens, des steten übertreffenden Erfülltwerdens durch ihn, schliesslich—da wir von Gott sprechen—der gegenseitigen Anerkenntnis und Anbetung des Gottseins verunmöglicht Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 263 This kind of divine love is made possible by Balthasar’s understanding of eternity and his refusal to fully negate attributes found in creation that seem to be intrinsically tied to limitations or temporality. A contradiction is avoided as long as these new divine characteristics of surprise and joy are posited as perfections within a dialectical theology, as part of God’s infinite actuality. The human experience of intense interpersonal love, one that overwhelms the lover with the goodness and mutual love of the other, becomes a divine perfection. But how can the Father be surprised by the Son, rejoicing in the unexpected love of the Son for the Father, and vice versa? Balthasar answers that Divine surprise occurs through one person seeing a new side of the other. Citing Speyr, he states: “It is characteristic of ‘genuine love’ that it ‘cannot tire of looking at the beloved. . . . Thus the Son, in the Father’s presence, is for ever beholding him in a new way. . . .’ ”85 But how can one person see a “new side” of the other if each is eternally and infinitely in act? Because each person keeps a mystery about himself from the other: “[T]he partners are perfectly transparent to one another, and they possess a kind of impenetrable ‘personal’ mystery.”86 One can see Balthasar’s dialectic at work in this last passage. In order to retain continuity with the theological tradition of the Fathers and the Scholastics, as well as the doctrine demanded by the ecumenical councils, he has to posit the absolute omniscience of each divine Person to protect the divinity of each. Thus, creaturely surprise must be negated.Yet his interpretation of Scripture through the lens of the concrete analogia entis, the mystical experience of Speyr, and dialogical philosophy lead him to posit an apparent contradiction: Divine Persons who always fully know one another and yet keep a secret to themselves in order to reveal it to the other, resulting in the surprise and joy of the other. This surprise includes the Son’s “decision” to answer the Father’s incredible gift of self with thanksgiving.87 The würden . . . man kann nicht sagen, eine Hypostase sei reich als Besitzende und arm als Verschenkende, denn erst im Geben wie auch im Entgegennehmen des Geschenkten und Schenkenden liegt die Fülle der Seligkeit. Da diese Akte ewig sind, ist das Neuseins, des Überrascht- und Über-wältigtwerdens durch das Masslose kein Ende. Der philosophische Grundakt des Staunens braucht aus dem Absoluten nicht verbannt zu werden”). 85 Theodrama V, 79 (Theodramatik IV, 68: “Es gehört zur ‘echten Liebe,’ ‘sich am Geliebten nicht sattsehen zu können . . .Wenn der Sohn, vor dem Vater stehend, ihn doch immer wieder neu sieht . . .’ ”). 86 Theodrama II, 258 (Theodramatik II.1, 234:“. . . liegt in diesem göttlichen Austausch oder Gespräch immer beides: voll-kommene Durchsichtigkeit füreinander und dennoch so etwas wie ein unlüftbares ‘personales’ Geheimnis”). 87 Theodrama V, 508–9 (Theodramatik IV, 465). Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP 264 Son is so filled with this gratefulness that he wants to be able to give the Father something “of his own.” Returning the love that springs from the divine essence would be to return what was given. So the Son becomes incarnate, in fact: “ ‘He must do this so that he can possess something, so that he can have something to give away,’ ”88 that he might “prove” his love for the Father. So he “gives up” his divinity and becomes man, in order to present a new gift to the Father, one not already in the divine essence.89 And yet, despite the expectation and surprise present in the relationship of the divine Persons, the now of fulfilled expectation already is, eternally: “What is ‘now’ always was, and it is so full that it is unsurpassable . . . in such a way that expectation and fulfillment exactly coincide.”90 This is the paradox of an eternally fulfilled expectation, joined to a kind of faith that the Son will respond to the Father’s self-emptying with love. The themes of suffering love, faith, and surprise all reveal Balthasar’s understanding of receptivity as a perfection, and here we mean a receptivity that includes far more than just the fact that the Son’s being is from another. By attributing suffering to the Father, an event mirrored in the Jesus’ abandonment on the Cross, Balthasar appears to posit the ability to be negatively affected by another as a divine perfection.The Father takes a risk in generating the Son, giving up his solitude. He gives the Son true divine sovereignty, which apparently does not involve the Son’s necessary assent to the Father’s will.Thus, the Father must be open to receive rejection. But the Father has faith that the Son will say yes to him, and the reception of this assent is also a perfection. Finally, the surprise involved in divine love means that each person must be open to receive a new insight into the other person, open to receive an unexpected love that overwhelms every expectation. Balthasar emphasizes the perfection of this receptivity for a new love: [C]onceiving and letting be are just as essential as giving. In fact, without this receptive letting be . . . the giving itself is impossible. . . . Hence there is “no less love in receiving than in giving. Perhaps there is even more, since what is received and conceived is divine.”91 88 Theodrama V, 516, quoting Speyr (Theodramatik IV, 472: “. . . ‘er muss es tun, um etwas zu besitzen, was er verschenken kann . . .’ ”). 89 Ibid. 90 Theodrama V, 126, quoting Speyr (Theodramatik IV, 109: “Das Jetzt war immer schon da, und es ist so voll, dass es uneinholbar ist . . . so, dass Erwartung und Erfüllung übereinfallen’ wobei die zukommende Erfüllung die Erwartung je übererfüllt”). 91 Theodrama V, 86–87, quoting Speyr (Theodrama IV, 75–77: “Das Empfangen und Geschehenlassen ist für den Begriff der absoluten Liebe ebenso wesentlich Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 265 Balthasar finds this complementary activity and receptivity in the Trinity, one that includes the reception of a love from the other which is somehow greater than expected. This receptivity includes a kind of new knowledge that one divine person shares with another, one that propels God’s love to new heights.The Son’s self-revelation of a mysterious side of himself to the Father is received with joy and surprise, spurring the Father on to a greater love for the Son, who is filled with wonder and awe. Balthasar sees this kind of dialogical receptivity as analogous to the reception of new knowledge and love which is a necessary element of any fruitful interpersonal love relationship on the human level. But all of these divine attributes are predicated in an eminent way, following the way of negation that excludes all strictly creaturely receptivity, surprise, and potentiality. Review Balthasar’s method of divine naming can be summarized thus. First, philosophy is indispensable, yet it must be elevated and perhaps radically transformed by grace. Second, negative theology is also necessary, but a philosophical negative theology cannot be allowed to exclude certain characteristics from the process of divine naming, if supernatural revelation points in another direction. This naturally leads to the third point, that only the revelation of Christ can determine the true nature of potentiality and finitude. Fourth, the economic Trinity must be the basis for any description of the immanent Trinity, and so one must look to Christ as the revealer of his relationship to the Father. Fifth, an understanding of true love as communio, as letting the other be, giving the other freedom, a doctrine of love inspired by dialogical philosophy and the visions of Speyr, is a hermeneutical key in the approach to supernatural revelation. The Trinitarian analogy of the family is closely connected to this. The first two steps take away the restriction on the predication of suffering and the related attributes we have discussed. Christ is the one standard for all analogies and doctrines of analogy. He reveals his relationship to the Father. However, this revelation must be interpreted, which is where the influence of dialogical philosophy and the mysticism of Speyr come in. Thus suffering, time, surprise, and other attributes are recognized as analogous perfections. Their creaturely modalities are negated of God, followed by the attribution of “super-death,” “supertime,” and so on.The eminent way in which suffering, sacrifice, and other attributes are present in God is beyond our comprehension, yet we must, wie das Geben, das ohne das empfangende Geschehenlassen . . . gar nicht zu geben vermöchte. . . . Also liegt ‘nicht weniger Liebe im Nehmen als im Geben. Vielleicht sogar mehr, weil das Empfangene göttlich ist’ ”). 266 Bernhard Blankenhorn, OP in obedience to divine revelation, maintain that these are perfections that are really and analogously present in the being and life of the Trinity. Critique We will conclude with a threefold critique of Balthasar’s approach to divine naming, regarding his notions of (1) Christ as the concrete analogia entis which is the standard for every other analogy, (2) Christ as revealing his relationship to the Father, and (3) modes of potentiality such as surprise and suffering as perfections. The teaching that Christ is the concrete analogia entis could be interpreted in a way to which every Christian would be forced to assent; for example, in the sense that reason must be obedient to faith, so that every philosophical analogy owes a certain obedience to supernaturally revealed analogies. The understanding of the content of supernatural revelation, however, itself requires reason and philosophical analogies.We must bring a philosophical understanding of humanity to the revelation of Christ, and while this understanding must be perfected by grace, it must include true philosophical insights into human nature. We cannot say what is creaturely and what is divine if we refuse to distinguish the content of the revelation of Christ and the humanity of Christ. Without a philosophical analogia entis that plays a determining role in the interpretation of revelation, the image and the original would fuse into one, and we would have no way of distinguishing the two.The very notion of Christ’s humanity presumes a pretheological understanding of what humanity is, which would have to include certain attributes, some of which would be recognized as perfections, others as limitations. Jesus himself did not teach us in his earthly life how to distinguish between the manifestation of his humanity as humanity and the manifestation of his humanity as a revelation of God and the divine perfections. Rather, he presumed knowledge gained from the created order, an order that was instituted through the eternal Logos himself. Balthasar seems to have sensed the problem we have mentioned, admitting that Jesus cannot simply represent his own divinity, as this would involve a mono-physite heresy. The solution for Balthasar is to approach Jesus as manifesting his relationship with the Father, one that Christ transposes into the creaturely-temporal.The problem is that Jesus has a twofold relationship with the Father: as man and as the eternal Son of God. Hence, Jesus’ relationship with the Father as the Son of God can only be understood if Jesus is manifesting his divinity. Balthasar gives priority to the manifestation of the relationship to the Father over the manifestation of Christ’s own divinity. But the two are inseparable. Balthasar, in fact, recog- Balthasar’s Method of Divine Naming 267 nized the need to distinguish the two natures of Christ. Can this be done, however, without an analogia entis that is brought to the reception of revelation, an analogy that enables the believer to distinguish the creaturely from the divine, the limited as limited and the limited as imperfect perfection? It seems that instead of turning to an analogia entis which is not already radically transformed by the analogia fidei though not disobedient to it, an analogia entis that both shapes the analogia fidei and is shaped by it, Balthasar turns to Christ as manifesting his filial relationship. Unfortunately, the problem of distinguishing perfections from limitations remains, and we are still without a sufficient hermeneutical principle to recognize these. Jesus’ relationship to the Father in his divinity is distinct from his relationship to the Father in his humanity ( Jn 10,30: “The Father and I are one”; Jn 14,28:“The Father is greater than I”). Can this distinction be recognized without letting the analogia entis play a greater role in the understanding of revelation? The third critique concerns Balthasar’s transformation of attributes (like suffering) into analogous divine perfections, attributes that are experienced in this life as potentialities. He states that potentiality in creation can be something highly positive, and that there is a vibrant becoming in God that is nothing but being.92 Here, potency and becoming are treated as positives and partial perfections either because they already include actuality in some way or because potency as such and becoming as such are now seen as perfections. In the former case, we are simply extracting actuality from mixed potency and becoming, so that calling potency and becoming perfections is a kind of equivocation, since we are not really predicating perfection of potency as such but of the actual element of partially actualized potencies. But in the first of the Theodrama passages just cited, Balthasar suggests that he is also thinking of the latter case, of passive potency as perfection.This would mean that potency as such is act as such, and becoming as such is being as such. If this is so, then has the order of creation not been reduced to the order of grace?93 Is theology still using philosophical concepts and categories, or is it creating its own?94 These questions are of the utmost importance. The intelligibility of Christian revelation is at stake. N&V 92 Theodrama V, 90, 512 (Theodramatik IV, 79, 468). 93 Theology of Karl Barth, 126. 94 Ibid., 85. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 269–82 269 Metaphysics and Mysticism G EORGES C OTTIER , OP Theologian of the Pontifical Household Vatican City I T HE GROWING and unflagging interest shown these recent decades in Plotinus and Neo-platonism, as well as the development in the west of studies devoted to the rich heritage of Indian thought, once more brings to the forefront the question of the relation between philosophy—above all metaphysics—and mysticism. As for Plotinus, we have a better insight into the force of his genius and the originality of a mental effort that was completely magnetized by a transcognitive experience, so to speak, of contact with the One. What does such an experience signify, especially as regards the metaphysical quest? The answer presupposes that we first address a certain number of preliminary problems.To start with, we must arrive at a common understanding of the very nature of metaphysics and mysticism. Though the definitions of both give rise to debates where a great deal is at stake, space does not permit us to enter into these debates at this point. The definitions I shall propose, without explicitly justifying them, will, I hope, allow us to proceed with our reflection. They require the examination of a series of questions that we cannot do otherwise but ask. Should metaphysics be propaedeutic to mysticism and serve as a kind of preliminary exercise to mysticism, understood as experience of the object? Or, on the contrary, should such an experience not be at the root of metaphysics, thereby making it a kind of conceptual thematization? Is there not continuity, an unbroken progression, and hence homogeneity, linking metaphysics with mysticism, with the result that mysticism marks the natural, normal crowning of metaphysics? And, supposing such to be the case, must we conclude that there is a need for 270 Georges Cottier, OP the mystical experience imbedded in the very nature of metaphysics? We shall weigh these questions. This quandary is of the utmost interest to metaphysics, but our consideration must begin with anthropology.And, in anthropology, two types of questions must be asked.The first type concerns the nature and structures of human knowledge.The second, to which we shall return later, is of the existential and historical order. These questions concern the concrete conditions of the exercise of knowing and more directly of the exercise of the metaphysical quest in mankind’s historical situation. The status of man’s metaphysical knowledge relates to the fact that man knows by drawing his concepts from sense data through a process of abstraction.This is what we mean when we say that the connatural object of human knowledge is the essence of bodily things. In virtue of our nature composed of a body and spiritual soul, these are the objects with which our mind feels at home, so to speak. But this connatural object of our mind is not its adequate object. Because it is a spiritual faculty, the human intellect, according to the highest and most purified degree of abstraction that it is capable of, attains the transcendentals: the true, the good, the one, and, above all, being, in all their universal fullness. However, it first attains this being in the analogues that are connatural to it by ridding them of all materiality. The intellect attains it secondly by way of analogy as realized in purely spiritual creatures and, still further, in the supreme analogue, God, . . . ipsum esse subsistens . . . and “cause of being,” as St.Thomas puts it. Thus we grasp the paradoxical status of metaphysics in man.The intellect is capable of grasping being in all its analogical fullness.Therein lies its extraordinary power and greatness. But it attains the highest analogues by beginning with the essences of lower analogues, which are bodily beings composed of form and matter. Therein lies the root of its limits and inferiority. A sign of this inferiority is that at the terminus of the process of the concept’s abstract elaboration there is the need for a conversio ad phantasmata, a condition for our intellectual knowledge of singular concrete beings.1 None of the foregoing owes anything to Kant. But it is not beside the point to note here that Kant, who lacked the metaphysical perception of being as such and its analogy, set limits that characterize our imperfect mode of knowing the highest realities, the building blocks of human reason that determine the very content of its object. But it is one thing to know a higher reality imperfectly if yet in truth, and another to assert that, 1 Cf. Saint Thomas, ST, I, 84, 7. Metaphysics and Mysticism 271 by restricting it, this imperfection determines the field of knowable things. Nor is it beside the point to observe that it is on this point that Hegel expressed his anti-Kantian reaction most vigorously. For Hegel, there is no true knowledge unless it is perfect knowledge, either as regards the object known—the Absolute—or as regards the mode of attaining this object. There comes into play here the Hegelian consideration of the limit.The limit, or finiteness, is always a provisional “moment” such that the dialectical process that is immanent in the Absolute itself and in its self-knowledge is a process of transgressing the limit. This position has a direct bearing on the question of mysticism, for Hegel attributes to speculative Logic, which in fact is metaphysics, the ability to know the Absolute itself through identification with the process of this Absolute’s self-positioning. With this, Hegel, while transposing it into the key of dialectics, harkens back to the ambition of Spinoza. For both thinkers mysticism is useless since its object—a kind of identification with the Absolute—is the same as that of philosophy.The outlook is one of monism. For our purposes, the consequences of Kantianism are just as negative, for with Kant we begin to see the rise of philosophies of feeling. Since reason is incapable of gaining access, albeit imperfectly, to being in all its fullness right up to the Absolute, man will ask another faculty, Gemüt or Gefühl, to grant him access thereto.This opens the door to the emotional and with it, and all too soon, the irrational. Mysticism, without any ties to reason and truth, thus becomes a kind of substitute for outlawed metaphysics. It is therefore by an ascending path and in an imperfect manner of knowing that the human intellect reaches the highest realities. Because these realities are the highest, knowledge of them finalizes and crowns the cognitive undertaking of the metaphysician; to know God is the end toward which every created intellect tends with an impetus that belongs to its very nature. Here we can gauge the considerable scope of St. Thomas’s assertion: Knowledge of God, however imperfect, has more worth than the perfect knowledge of lower beings.This assertion sheds a decisive light on the meaning of the intellectual quest as well as on what should give predominant inspiration to any culture. It puts the primacy of truth at the foundation. In this process, the intellect reflects upon itself and becomes aware of its own imperfect manner of knowing.The critique of the metaphysical knowledge of God rests upon the distinction between what is signified and the manner of signifying (quid significatur, modus significandi). Our intellect knows that it is unable to grasp the essence of God in itself.This 272 Georges Cottier, OP is what the Thomistic formula expresses: Of God we do not know what He is (quid est) but that He is (quia est). Of course, to say of God (as of anything, for that matter) that He is, we must know something, even in an imperfect way, of what He is. Such an understanding, which enjoys a keen sense of transcendence, allows for no traces of agnosticism. Imperfect knowledge on an ascending path involves the apophatic way of thinking. Metaphysics requires it, especially in its higher part, natural theology. The notion of pure perfections, such as the good, the beautiful, the just, does not carry with it any intrinsic limitation, and we grasp the pure perfections first of all in their lower analogues that are connatural to us. Since they do not possess in their intelligible content any imperfection, we legitimately attribute them to God by way of causality. A perfection found in the effect is found a fortiori and necessarily in the cause. Such an affirmation, then, constitutes the first step in the undertaking. But immediately our mind perceives through analogy that the manner in which this perfection exists in God is infinitely higher than the way it exists in creatures. Such is the via negationis or via remotionis. It has to do with divesting the perfection, encountered first in creatures, of all the limitations with which it is clad, for these limitations could in no way be applied to God. The divine mode in which these perfections are actual wholly escapes us, so that in the end we know God as unknown.To know God, St.Thomas will also say, is to know that we do not know what He is in Himself:2 An “unknowing that knows,” an unknowing that is not the negation of knowing but the height of knowing, since by it knowing is surpassed.Actually, the via negationis is not its own end, since it cannot be disassociated from the via eminentiae, which is like the intellect’s silent adoration before the mystery of the divine transcendence. It is as if wonder, which is the starting point of philosophical questioning, were here the end-result, as it were, of knowing.The intellect’s natural attitude of adoration of the mystery tends of itself to result in a religious attitude. But what it expresses is the awestruck sense of the infinite distance that separates every creature, that separates every created intellect and its means of knowing from the divine essence. Still, such a religious attitude fails to reach the mystical dimension, since mysticism signifies an experience of the Absolute. At this point, then, we must stress on the distinction between metaphysics and mysticism.We must never lose sight of this distinction, even if we have not yet said all there is to say. 2 In Div. Nom., c.VII, lect. 4. Metaphysics and Mysticism 273 II The foregoing relates to human knowledge insofar as it is specifically human.This knowledge depends upon the substantial union of the spiritual soul with the body and upon the role of the images required for the actualization, by means of abstraction and conceptualization, of the potential intelligibility contained in sensible objects. But this consideration remains to be completed. The human being is a showcase of the laws and requirements of every created being. In a series of chapters in Book Three of the Summa contra Gentiles, where he treats of the good and of God as the final cause of all things and, consequently, of beatitude for spiritual creatures, St. Thomas enumerates a weighty principle: All beings tend to become like God, each according to the possibilities of its own nature (Chapter 19). In other words, all beings, starting with the lowliest and most elementary viz. inanimate beings, each in its own way tends toward God. Thus a powerful aspiration toward the supreme source of being lifts up created being. To designate it, Thomas uses the ontological sense of love and desire. Each being fulfills this desire by attaining, as far as it can, its own perfection, since every created perfection is a likeness to the supreme and infinite perfection of God. But this love and this desire take a new form in the spiritual creature endowed with intellect and will. Here the tendency toward assimilation with the Source takes that higher form, which is by way of knowledge and love (as an act elicited by the will).Those activities that are intrinsically independent of matter, viz. knowing and loving, find their eminent realization in a spiritual union with God. From this a twofold question arises: Is such a union possible, and what is the nature and mode of this union which enables it to fulfill the potentiality of the desire? Such questions move us beyond the consideration of properly human knowledge and place the focus on the capacity that flows from spirituality as such, that goes beyond the specific and which, in Maritain’s felicitous expression, is “transnatural.”The human spirit is capable of participating in what belongs to every spirit insofar as it is spirit. An examination of the human spirit’s possibilities in relation to the metaphysical order would therefore be incomplete if it did not take this dimension into account. Prior to putting morality into practice, which presupposes rational deliberation, man has in him, as in every created being, a natural love of the Creator. Such love, of an ontological order, is inextricably love of self and love of God. And since the relationship of the creature to God can be likened to the relationship of a part to the whole, and since the part, by virtue of its being a part, tends first of all toward the good of 274 Georges Cottier, OP the whole, this natural love is a love of God above everything.To think of the good of a part as separated from the good of the whole of which it is a part is to think in contradictory terms. By loving itself, the creature spontaneously and with the same impulse loves God as supreme good.3 The will, which is the subject’s appetitus, takes on this love and this desire spontaneously in its first movement and before any deliberation or reflection.4 The consideration of ontological love touches on an altogether fundamental point. Other transnatural aspirations flow directly from the spiritual nature of the soul and its intellectual powers. Our will, the subject’s appetite, naturally tends toward happiness understood as the saturating possession of the fullness of the good.This good, such as our intelligence conceives it, is not known in itself, in its essence. Our will therefore tends toward it as toward a “bonum in communi.” Can it be reached in itself? Certainly not on this earth. But even if the soul could escape from the limits of space and time, it could not arrive at it by its own powers; it would have to love Him who is the sovereign Good within the limits of the indirect knowledge from afar that is connatural to it. It would achieve a kind of happiness; its felicity would be real, to be sure, but relative. But that he is called to participate in the very life of God, who is subsisting Beatitude, man could not even guess, much less demand. Nevertheless, the absolute gratuity of the gift of the life of grace comes to fulfill beyond all measure an aspiration of nature that nature, by itself, cannot satisfy and whose object it cannot even conceive of in all its depth.This is because the spiritual element in spiritual creatures is a participation, albeit imperfect, in Him who is Spirit, and everything that participates tends to become assimilated to its principle.Thus the will’s aspiration goes beyond its own possibilities of achievement. For as soon as the created spirit starts to think on itself, it becomes aware of the natural limitations of its capacity to act. This is where we broach the notion of the natural desire to see God. It is a desire of the mind as a particular faculty, while the desire for beatitude, the desire of the will, concerns the totality of the subject. Our 3 Cf. Saint Thomas, ST I, q. 60, a. 5; I–II, q. 109, a. 3; II–II, q. 26, a. 3. 4 In no way does original sin harm or diminish nature’s positive reality: “As a result, everything that belongs to nature in a positive way remains ‘intact,’ metaphysically considered (. . .) all that is ontological love, natural appetite, even the elicited natural appetite of the voluntas ut natura, remains intact. This love, moreover, focuses on the last end in communi; only implicitly is it a love of God.” On the other hand, the wound of original sin shows up at the level of free elicited love. At this level, love of God above all things is not possible for man except as a vague desire. See the Note of Fr. Michel Labourdette in Louis Gardet and Olivier Lacombe, L’expérience de Soi. Etude de Mystique comparée (Paris: Desclée, 1981), 183. Metaphysics and Mysticism 275 intellect has a mediate and indirect knowledge of God. It knows Him not in Himself but indirectly in the looking glass of things. But of itself, by its metaphysical nature, the intellect as intellect is not fully satisfied unless it knows perfectly the essence of the reality known first only imperfectly. To know perfectly is to see intellectually, to have a direct grasp of the essence. Thus the desire to see the first cause presupposes the effort of reason to trace back from the effect to the cause.The mediation of some reasoning, as a kind of precondition, is therefore required. But to see the first cause in itself is beyond the capabilities of any created intellect. By itself, our intellect cannot reach that far. Hence, when the intellect is called to the beatific vision by virtue of a gratuitous elevation to the supernatural life, the desire of nature finds fulfillment beyond all expectation. Still, because of the limitations of every created nature, such a desire can in no way be considered a command.The satisfaction of this desire is impossible from the resources of created nature, yet this desire is not vain; it is not a contradiction, which would mean the destruction of reason. As in the case of the desire for beatitude, its presence bears witness to the created spirit’s participation in Him who is Spirit, and to the tendency of that which participates in a perfection to be assimilated to its principle. Thus we find ourselves faced with the paradoxical conjunction of two affirmations: On the one hand, our intellect is only satisfied when it knows its object perfectly, for which reason it aspires to a perfect knowledge of God, the First Cause; on the other hand, this knowledge of God as First Cause is only granted in the beatifying vision, which our mind is not capable of attaining through its own powers. This incapability holds for the nature of every created intellect. The paradox disappears as soon as we consider the factors at work in the process of intellectual knowledge. As an illuminative power, the agent intellect abstracts essences from things as they are perceived first by the senses; it is an active power whose capability is proportionate to the knowledge of a spirit that is the form of a body. Its capability is therefore limited. But it is in the possible intellect that knowledge, properly so named, takes place when this intellect becomes intentionally the thing known.As to its spiritual nature, the possible intellect is a participated spiritual nature, to be sure, yet one common to all spirits. As such, then, the possible intellect is capable of receiving in itself every intelligible object, including the highest, God seen with clarity, when it is enlightened by the lumen gloriae. In relation to the reception of knowledge so sublime, knowledge that is literally divine, the possible intellect is in obediential potency. In other words, the receptive potency of the possible intellect goes beyond 276 Georges Cottier, OP the natural capabilities of the agent intellect (lumen naturale). It is open to receiving every intelligible object and since it is fully actuated only when it knows its object perfectly, a natural desire points it toward perfect knowledge of the first cause as soon as it gets an inkling of it. It should be noted that by naturally desiring an exhaustive knowledge of the First Cause, our intellect does not thereby formally desire the beatific vision of the Godhead or of the Trinitarian mystery. Because of the limited power of the agent intellect, our mind is incapable of responding to this desire by itself.This is what we mean in speaking of a transnatural desire. Thus we can formulate a second conclusion: To speak of a perfect knowledge of God, First Cause, is to evoke an experience, that is, a direct and fruitful knowledge of the Absolute, is it not? We should say, then, that although our metaphysical knowledge, which is a conceptual knowledge, is not mystical knowledge, a mystical surge nonetheless animates every great philosophy.5 III We are now in a position to address mystical knowledge itself. Even in the philosophy of religion there is today an inflated use of the word “experience.” And it should be noted that this short reflection does not concern religious experience or its manifold modalities as such, but mystical experience in the strict sense. Moreover, the word “mystical” itself is not exempt from abusive distensions. I borrow my definition from an author who is an authority on the subject, the philosopher and Islamicist Louis Gardet. By mysticism is understood “the fruitful experience of an absolute”: “experience,” and therefore knowledge through connaturality; “fruitful,” which has its completeness in itself. Further, the word “mysticism” connotes “the inwardly experienced grasping of a total and fulfilling reality.”6 That absolute is written with a minuscule will become clear shortly. 5 On this subject see the remarks of J. Maritain, The Degrees of Knowledge, chap. IV, “Metaphysical Knowledge,” trans. G. B. Phelan (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1959). 6 Louis Gardet, La mystique (Paris: PUF, 1982), 6. The quotation itself is borrowed from Jacques Maritain in a study on L’expérience mystique et le vide that makes up Chapter III of Quatre essais sur l’esprit dans sa condition charnelle (1939), cf. VII, 159–95. See Louis Gardet and Olivier Lacombe, L’expérience du Soi, Etude de mystique comparée, 382.We are further indebted to these two authors, one an Islamicist, the other a Hindologist, for articles and works that likewise deal with the subject. Let us cite Louis Gardet’s Expériences mystiques en terre non chrétienne (Alsatia, 1953); Mystique musulmane—aspects et tendances, expériences et techniques (Paris: Vrin, 1961), in collaboration with Georges C. Anawati; Etudes de philosophie et de Metaphysics and Mysticism 277 Let us begin by recalling the significance of mysticism in the Christian life. It is nothing other than the blossoming of the life of grace. In essence, then, it is supernatural. All extraordinary manifestations must be excluded from its definition.These latter, even when their authenticity is duly proven, do not make up the essence of mysticism, even if they are closely tied to it. The most perfect, immediate, and unveiled union is given in the face to face of the beatific vision, which by its very perfection gives rise to charity’s unfailing love.The soul that sees God is perfectly happy.Thus the beatific vision constitutes the terminus of Christian existence, the repose in an end everlastingly possessed, the object of a fulfilling fruition beyond all desire. But as long as we are viatores, pilgrims and wayfarers, our knowledge is imperfect: “We see now dimly through a mirror; but then face to face. Now I know in part; but then I shall know even as I am known” (1 Cor 13:12). It is by faith that we know the divine mysteries, we do not see them; our intellect accepts them because He who is in the bosom of the Father has made them known to us (cf. Jn 1:18). In order to communicate these mysteries to us, the Incarnate Word speaks to us in our human language in such wise that the knowledge from faith that bears directly on the divine reality is a very imperfect knowledge as regards its mode, which is a human one. There is no intermediary between knowledge from faith and vision. At this point mystical knowledge finds its place. For, while with knowledge the object is received in the knowing subject according to the mode of the knower, love is directed to the object in itself in such a way that here below love goes further than knowledge. It is from this “further” that mystical knowledge is born.The union of love, which attains the beloved as he is in himself, is the source of a connaturality, of an affinity, that makes the soul feel as if by instinct what belongs to the beloved.Thus the gifts of the Holy Spirit operating in the soul start with the connaturality of love. As regards the object known, this knowledge is none other than knowledge from faith; what it introduces is a new mode of knowing, which goes beyond the ordinary, human mode. This knowledge is without concepts because it is supra-conceptual; that is why we designate it as a fulfilling silence, a blessed night. A medieval manuscript uses the beautiful expression,“The Cloud of Unknowing.” On several occasions St.Thomas adopts the expression of Pseudo-Dionysius, pati divina, to suffer divine things, to mystique comparées (Paris: Vrin, 1972). Olivier Lacombe’s L’Absolu selon le Védânta (Paris: Librarie Orientaliste Paul Geuther, 1937); Indianité (Paris: 1979). Here we have no doubt the most remarkable effort of speculative philosophy on the subject, based on firsthand information. 278 Georges Cottier, OP undergo them experientially. In this unknowing (which we should not confuse with the via negative), the soul experiences the deepness of faith’s mysteries, their beauty and their beatifying power. Such in sum is the nature of Christian mysticism: experience of God’s depths through the connaturality of love.7 With her fraternal communion, with the bread of the word of God, and with her sacramental and Eucharistic life the Church constitutes the normal environment for the mystical union through love. At this point we may consider two essentially theological questions that are of interest to the philosopher who is investigating the ties between mysticism and metaphysics. The first question deals with whether mystical experiences, those falling under the heading of mystical union in charity, are possible outside the visible boundaries of the Church. The answer has to be affirmative. Christ’s grace is offered to all; we would not be able to exclude such an experience a priori. Still, such a union presupposes that the soul in question has faith, albeit an implicit faith, and lives an upright life. But since it is partially deprived of the word of God and of the sacramental life, this experience will most often take an atypical form and will show up sporadically. Only an in-depth examination of each case can allow us to recognize it. In Islam, al-Hallaj, whom Louis Massignon has studied, represents a particularily moving example of a mystic who experiences profound things of God.8 Is the supernatural mystical experience of God’s depths the unique form that, albeit masked, is to be found wherever there is mysticism?9 Or should we acknowledge another form of mysticism, which would be distinct in essence? The testimonies of India first of all, but also of Sufism in the land of Islam, witness to the existence of this other form. Let us try to draw a quick sketch of it. Because of its union with the body, our soul does not have direct knowledge of itself. To know what its essence is we must go by way of analysis and reasoning. When we perform acts of thinking and willing, these acts are accompanied by an imperfect and confused awareness of our 7 A fulfilling experience anticipating eternal bliss: We have no need here to deal with the meaning of the phases of desolation and fulfillment that mark the mystic’s life. 8 Cf. in Louis Gardet and Olivier Lacombe, L’expérience du Soi, Part II, chap. II (Louis Gardet), 209–48. 9 I took up this question in a contribution to the symposium organized by the Revue Thomiste, at Toulouse (26 and 27 May 2000), “Surnaturel,” Une controverse au coeur du thomism au Xxe siècle, forthcoming as Sur la mystique naturelle. Metaphysics and Mysticism 279 existence as spiritual subjects. Moreover, our being, like every being, is animated by an ontological love of self, which was spoken of earlier.Thus the human soul does not see its own essence but it knows, by the activity of its powers, that it exists. How could it not seek to get back to the sources it has so vaguely perceived in order to know them through a saturating experience? Such a seeking, which requires the use of refined techniques and a sometimes heroic asceticism, requires all its spiritual energy. Therefore, the experience in question has for its object the pure substantial to be of the self. Unlike the ordinary course of mental activity, which brings us first to the knowledge of things and, from there, indirectly to the knowledge of ourselves, this process of returning to the source obliges the soul to empty itself of every particular operation and of all multiplicity. Through this very abolition of every ideating act, it can thus “attain and know, in the night and beyond every concept, the metaphysical wonder, the absolute, the perfection of every act and of every perfection, which is to be—its own substantial to be.”This abolition of every act of thinking is itself an intensely vital act of the soul. In this supra-conceptual experience of the finite absolute, which is the pure to be of the human self, the Cause of being is attained mediately without the intervention of any rational reference. If this is so, it is because this negative experience attains existence, which is transcendent and limited only by the essence that receives it, of which precisely at this point nothing is known.When this negative experience attains the soul’s own proper existence, it attains at the same time be-ing, in the whole of its metaphysical scope, and the sources of being insofar as a creating influx, from which it receives everything, courses through the soul’s existence. Of course, we do not experience an influx of this kind in itself but in the effect it produces.“This is why the experience in question responds to the desire of everything to get back to its sources and the principle of its being, although only in a certain fashion and in so far as that is possible on a natural level.”10 It is essential that the metaphysician pay attention to this kind of experience. For we have here a quest for an experience that the human spirit attempts to acquire by its own strength and which is of an intellectual nature; at the end of the emptiness that the intellect creates in itself, there comes this “touching,” about which Plotinus speaks and which crowns a trajectory of unknowing. Metaphysics, which supposes the abstractive intuition of being as actus essendi, is a conceptual and rational knowledge. Its limitations are those of human reason, which the metaphysician must 10 Cf. J. Maritain, On the Church of Christ:The Person of the Church and Her Personnel, chap. X, “Invisible Presence in/of the Visible Church,” trans. Joseph W. Evans (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973). 280 Georges Cottier, OP know how to accept. He may have a great temptation to free himself from the natural limits of our knowing in order to gain possession of its proper object experientially. Moreover, a mystical impulse of this kind generally demands, by its very strength, the elaboration and architecture of metaphysics itself in him who surrenders himself to it. And it is no coincidence if this kind of metaphysics undergoes the allurement of monism. In Hindu thought, which is ignorant of creation in the proper sense, the Self (atman) is basically the same in man as in God. We can understand how the pressure exerted on the conception of the world and of man by the quest for a union obtained beyond every distinction shapes the vision of the word in the image of the soul’s journey toward the One. Hence, in order to judge a particular philosophy along with the meaning of its statements, we should look for the intention that is at its origin. Is this intention the building up of a knowledge based on the highest causes; in other words, is metaphysical wisdom the goal? Or is it the quest for a supra-conceptual experience that bends the use of conceptual knowledge and the real gifts of the metaphysician to its own ends? It is not easy to answer these questions. Each case must be examined on its own.This is especially the case if we keep in mind that with metaphysics on one hand and the search for the experience of its own sources by way of unknowing on the other, we are faced with attitudes that proceed from the root of the spirit and which may coexist in the same subject in their inceptive and atypical state; the possibility of passing from one attitude to the other cannot be excluded.To this must be added the possible conjunction with the poetic experience, an experience of the world and the self caught in its creativity.11 I have described pure types. In the state of touches, it is not rare that the experience of the self intervenes within the framework of a search that remains essentially metaphysical. From the consideration of the mysticism of the experience of the self, we can draw a third conclusion. More often, no doubt, than we would suspect, the presence of mystical touches of the self is discernible in more than one thinker who remains above all a metaphysician.This presence is not without repercussions in the metaphysical undertaking itself.12 A final remark concerns the problems bound up with what is called Christian philosophy, that is, a philosophy whose work of reasoning 11 Cf. L. Gardet and O. Lacombe, L’expérience du Soi, Part II (Louis Gardet), chap. III, “Poésie et expérience du Soi,” 249–317. 12 Louis Gardet interprets the thought of Heidegger in this sense, cf. L. Gardet and O. Lacombe, L’expérience du Soi, Part II, chap. IV, “Expérience du Soi et discours philosophique,” 319–69. Metaphysics and Mysticism 281 unfolds under the influence of the faith while, strictly speaking, remaining genuine philosophy.The philosopher who intends to reflect upon the mysticism of the profound things of God will not hesitate to borrow from a higher science, theology, the light needed to deal with an object that surpasses his own knowledge. Moreover, if from a subjective standpoint this philosopher has some experience of the things of God in faith, even if only in an attenuated and sporadic manner, metaphysical reasoning in him will by that very fact be enlivened and invigorated. As regards the mysticism of the self a somewhat different question arises.The ontological love of self and of God as cause of being is in itself a good thing, so basically the experience of the Self is a positive experience. But it is here that we must take into account man’s historical condition: Because of original sin, the natural love of God above all things is not efficacious when we reach the level of the elicited and free act of the will. Grace is needed to rectify the will. Speaking ethically, then, nothing prevents the experience of the self from being rectified in the soul in the state of grace. It should be noted, however, that grace does not transform our experience, which of itself is on a natural level, into an intrinsically supernatural experience. Grace enters here as a conditioning and as gratia sanans. We should add that since the experience of the self is attained at the end of a hard and often heroic effort, there is a strong temptation for the soul to make itself the center of everything, which, let us stress, would be the negation as it were of the ontological love that is at the root of the whole undertaking. But in itself, the experience of the self, even if it is N&V still perilous, does not in principle raise any objection.13 13 Cf. Heinz-R. Schmitz, Sur le rôle de la volonté dans l’expérience mystique du Soi, in Revue Thomiste 79 (1979): 409–23.This author points out that the mystical experience of the Self does not always have the strongly religious bent that it has in the traditions of India. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 283–302 283 Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance: The Contribution of Thomas Aquinas on the Question of the Res et Sacramentum of Penance* G ILLES E MERY, OP University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland S ACRAMENTAL PENANCE , which provides remission of sins, brings reconciliation with the Church and with God. Today, numerous theologians agree in recognizing more clearly that reconciliation with the Church constitutes the “first effect” of the sacrament of penance or its “proper effect,” which brings reconciliation with God (second effect) to the Christian sinner. Grounded in the study of the history of penance (the patristic theme of “peace with the Church”), this thesis constitutes one focus of contemporary reflection on this sacrament.1 Having arrived at maturity in the movement for the rediscovery of the ecclesial * Translation by Robert E. Williams, SSI, of “La réconciliation avec l’Église et la pénitence intérieure: l’apport de Thomas d’Aquin sur la question du res et sacramentum de la pénitence,” in Praedicando et docendo, Mélanges offerts à Liam Walsh OP, ed. Barbara Hallensleben and Guido Vergauwen (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires, 1998), 31–47. 1 Colman E. O’Neill, “Les Sacrements,” in Bilan de la théologie du XXe siècle, ed. Robert Vander Gucht and Herbert Vorgrimler, vol. 2 (Tournai, Paris: Casterman, 1971), 457–500, cf. 493–98; Herbert Vorgrimler, Busse und Krankensalbung, “Handbuch der Dogmengeschichte IV/3” (Freiburg, Basel, Wien: Herder, 1978), 195–96; Reinhard Messner, Feiern der Umkehr und Versöhnung, “Gottesdienst der Kirke, Handbuch der Liturgiewissenchaft 7/2, Sakramentliche Feiern 1/2,” (Regensburg: Friedrich Pustet, 1992), 185–86. Already Karl Rahner was able to produce a substantial list of theologians who accepted this determination of the res et sacramentum (Theologische Schriften, vol. 8 [Einsiedeln, Zürich, Köln: Benzinger Verlag, 1967], 449–50): H. de Lubac, M. Schmaus, E. Schillebeeckx, J. Ratzinger,Y. Congar, and many others. 284 Gilles Emery, OP dimension of the sacraments, which Vatican II sanctioned, today this thesis is one key to understanding the sacrament in its ecclesial dimension. It may be expressed thus: “reconciliation with God by means of reconciliation with the Church.”2 From the very beginnings of this approach, it was integrated into the Scholastic analysis of the sacrament’s structure; reconciliation with the Church, therefore, was defined as the “res et sacramentum of penance.”3 We find this to be the case with most of the theologians who hold to the sacraments’ symbolic causality along with its three elements: the sacramental sign itself (sacramentum tantum); the intermediate effect in the order of signification-causality, which is already a reality brought about by the sacrament (res et sacramentum); and finally, the ultimate effect, that is, sacramental grace or the “fruit” of the sacrament (res tantum). From this standpoint then reconciliation with the Church replaces the “inner penance” that for Thomas Aquinas and many medieval theologians constituted this res et sacramentum of penance.The present study is limited to an examination of reconciliation with the Church under the aspect of res et sacramentum. It aims at making a comparison of these two approaches to the intermediate sign-effect of penance in hopes of establishing that the Thomistic doctrine of “inner penance” offers a theological framework for a better understanding of the relation between “reconciliation with God” and “reconciliation with the Church.” Reconciliation with the Church It was Bartomeu M. Xiberta, a Spanish Carmelite, who first presented a systematic treatment of the statement: “Reconciliation with the Church is the res et sacramentum of penance . . . the proper and immediate effect 2 Bernard Rey, Pour des célébrations pénitentielles dans l’esprit de Vatican II (Paris: Cerf, 1995), 177; in particular, the author endeavors to position the ecclesial community (“Church of sinners”) as the subject of the collective action of reconciliation (cf. especially 163–65). 3 So, for example, Jean-Hervé Nicolas, Synthèse dogmatique, De la Trinité à la Trinité (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires, 1985), 1050–52. Without prejudice to the sacrament’s other names, in this paper we will keep using the term “penance,” which joins together the virtue and the sacrament. Let us remember that the word “penance” (paenitentia) does not come from the idea of pain (poena). It was used very early on by Christians: To do penance (paenitentiam agere) translates metanoia, the deep down conversion of which the Gospel speaks and from which the sacrament gets this name; Pierre-Marie Gy, “La documentation sacramentaire de Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques 80 (1996): 425–31; cf. 428 for the res et sacramentum of penance (Thomas and Rahner). Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 285 of sacramental absolution.” This thesis forms the subject of his doctoral dissertation defended in 1921 at the Gregorianum in Rome.4 In a rather traditional manner, his argument is built upon the witness of Scripture and Tradition, and then confirmed by a study of the Scholastic doctors.5 The proposition, or rather the demonstration, of Xiberta is not put forward as a criticism of Thomas Aquinas, since the author appeals to him, along with other Scholastics (Bonaventure in particular), in support of his thesis.6 At the most, Xiberta observes, the radical distinction between the individual forum and the social forum, on which his opponents base themselves by invoking St.Thomas, is not decisive. As regards the scope of his thesis, in his preface, as at the end of his study, Xiberta underlines its apologetical dimension: to hold in a historically sound way that reconciliation with the Church is the res et sacramentum of penance is to possess the means that allows us to establish the sacramental dignity of the penance practiced in the Church (relationship between the “divine element” and the “human element”) against those who only see in it an ecclesiastical institution.7 If Xiberta deserves the honor of this first historico-doctrinal study, we must nevertheless grant the initiative to the Jesuit theologian Maurice de la Taille, director of Xiberta’s thesis, who taught that the res et sacramentum of penance consists in “the extinction of [the sinner’s] debt to the Church” (extinctio debiti erga Ecclesiam). For Father de la Taille, sacramental absolution is first of all (per prius) the Church’s acceptance of the satisfaction the penitent offers after having confessed his sins (satisfaction performed or which he intends to perform): This relieving of the debt owed to the Church signifies the 4 Bartomeu M. Xiberta, Clavis Ecclesiae. De ordine absolutionis sacramentalis ad recon- ciliationem cum Ecclesia (Roma: Pontificia Università Gregoriana, 1922). We are using the reproduction of the 1922 text by J. Perarnau in Miscellania Bartomeu M. Xiberta, “Analecta sacra Tarraconensia 45/2” (Barcelona: Biblioteca Balmes,1972 [1973]), 241*–341* (with the original paging indicated by brackets). 5 “Reconciliatio cum Ecclesia est res et sacramentum sacramenti paenitentiae” (Clavis Ecclesiae, [12]; cf. [96]; “proprium et immediatum fructum absolutionis sacramentalis” ([11]); “(. . .) Ostendere conabor reconciliationem cum Ecclesia nedum abesse ab effectibus sacramenti, esse potius proprium et immediatum fructum. (. . .) Nos vere ostendere conabimur infusionem gratiae deletivae peccati esse finem sacramenti eiusque excellentissimum effectum, ordine tamen causalitatis intercedere alium effectum immediate significatum et causatum per sacramentum, videlicet reconciliationem cum Ecclesia” ([11]–[12]). 6 Clavis Ecclesiae, [89] “Iuxta Angelicum (. . .) reconciliationis vero per sacramentum proprium est reconciliare cum Ecclesia.” We will take a look at the position of Thomas Aquinas later. 7 The author names Wycliff, Luther, and “most of the heretics” who follow them, as well as certain “Modernists” (Clavis Ecclesiae, [3]–[4]; cf. [94]–[95]. 286 Gilles Emery, OP relieving of the debt owed to Christ.8 Between Xiberta’s apologetical dimension and the stress de la Taille puts on the “debt of sin,” the theme of reconciliation with the Church is still rather far from the theological interpretation it will have later. On the other hand, it underlines quite clearly the Church’s role as mediator in the signification and granting of forgiveness. Among the works of major influence, we cannot overlook Henri de Lubac’s Catholicism, which marks a decisive stage in the work of restoring value to the sacraments’ social dimension within Catholic dogma. Already Catholicism offers the main elements of reflection: a close analogy between baptism and penance, identical nature of the “disciplinary institution” and the “means of inner purification,” priority of reconciliation with the Church as the immediate effect of penance and “efficacious sign” of reconciliation with God.“There can be no return to the grace of God without a return to the communion of the Church.”9 In De Lubac’s quick summary, which provides a whole theological program for the sacrament of penance, there is however no mention of res et sacramentum, nor is there any need for it. Later historical studies—those of B. Poschmann in particular—will only confirm Xiberta’s thesis (which Poschmann explicitly took as his model)10 and there is no reason to dwell on them here.We should point out, however, that on the historical level, as on the theological level, Poschmann offers a radicalization of Xiberta’s thought. Poschmann explains that on the historical level the penitential teaching of the early Church can only be understood in light of Xiberta’s thesis.11 For Poschmann, on the theological level, only the concept of reconciliation with the Church as the immediate effect of penance allows the sacrament to preserve its full meaning (necessity of the Church’s sacramental intervention); it alone allows us to see penance as an authentic judicial process (an aspect to which Poschmann pays much attention).12 Once 8 Maurice de la Taille, Mysterium Fidei de Augustissimo Corporis et Sanguinis Christi Sacrificio atque Sacramento (Paris: Beauchesne, 1921), 581.The Eucharistic context of de la Taille’s teaching should be noted. For de la Taille’s influence on Xiberta’s thesis, cf. Herbert Vorgrimler, Busse und Krankensalbung, 195, no. 46. 9 Henri de Lubac, Catholicism: A Study of Dogma in Relation to the Corporate Destiny of Mankind (New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1950), 37–38. 10 Bernhard Poschmann, Paenitentia secunda, Die kirliche Busse im ältesten Christentum bis Cyprian und Origenes. Eine dogmengeschichtliche Untersuchung (Bonn: P. Hanstein, 1940), 12. 11 Ibid., footnote 1 (“nur von ihr aus”).This thesis of Xiberta is clearly formulated: “(. . .) dass ‘die Rekonziliation mit der Kirche res et sacramentum des Busssakraments’ sei” (ibid.). 12 Bernhard Poschmann, “Die innere Struktur des Busssakraments,” Münchener Theologische Zeitschrift 1/3 (1950): 12–30, cf. 25 & 29. Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 287 the central place of pax cum Ecclesia in early penance has been well established (this is what the historical studies do), it still remains to be shown that it amounts to precisely the res et sacramentum of penance. For this we need, besides history, a speculative analysis of the sacrament. Poschmann provides its outline: reconciliation with the Church constitutes a res— that is, the thing signified and the immediate effect of the sacramental action—but it is also the sign of reconciliation with God. The Church gives her forgiveness to the converted sinner, and God has promised His forgiveness to whomever the Church forgives.Already that was precisely Xiberta’s explanation. Furthermore, if we ask what efficacy reconciliation has in regard to sacramental grace (the res tantum), Poschmann’s answer is: A certain “right” to receive God’s grace. But we could also imagine that there is no reason to add a supplementary effect to reconciliation with the Church since this latter includes peace with God, forgiveness, and grace.13 Hence we may ask ourselves if the framework of res et sacramentum really allows us to take into account the historical thesis touted by Poschmann. B. Poschmann comes across as more critical of Thomas Aquinas and the Middle Ages overall. As a matter of fact, it is the subsequent controversy about contrition and attrition that he thinks got off on the wrong track by misunderstanding pax Ecclesiae as the “first goal” and the “indispensable means” of reconciliation with God. Poschmann points out that if Thomas Aquinas had presented reconciliation with the Church, and not inner penance, as the res et sacramentum, the development of penitential doctrine would have taken a wholly different path. For in this case “the sacrament then keeps its irreplaceable importance, even with the most perfect contrition, and there would have been no need to have recourse to imperfect repentance to insure its right to exist.”14 Perhaps such an observation applies to Duns Scotus or to those theologians denounced in Blaise Pascal’s tenth Provinciale, but certainly not to the position of Thomas Aquinas, as we shall see later. Nowhere do we find that St. Thomas had to “raise the ante on the requirements for repentance, resulting in an extrasacramental justification,”15 for the good reason that Thomas’s effort consists in tying together as closely as possible personal contrition and the sacramental dimension:The contrition Thomas speaks of is contrition at work in the Church’s sacramental process. 13 Ibid., 21. 14 Bernhard Poschmann, La pénitence et l’onction des malades, “Histoire des dogmes IV/3” (Paris: Cerf, 1966), 180 (German ed., 1951, 111); cf.“Die innere Struktur,” 25. 15 Bernhard Poschmann, La pénitence et l’onction des malades, 181. 288 Gilles Emery, OP On the speculative level, C. Dumont tried to determine more precisely the proper structure of this res et sacramentum.16 He points out that in order for us to be able to consider reconciliation with the Church as the res et sacramentum of penance, we have to uncover more than a relation of extrinsic analogy or simple likeness between it and grace; we must also be able to establish a distinction.This observation leads us to exclude immediately an understanding of reconciliation only in its juridical nature, and to retain the penitent’s real participation in the community in which he is reintegrated: The penitent becomes an “active member” in the Church once again. For Dumont, reconciliation with the Church and grace remain nevertheless distinct since grace designates a larger field of relations (the whole aspect of salvation), while integration into the Church “only introduces a necessary historical moment.”17 With this analysis Dumont gains a technical explanation that allows him to give an account of the res et sacramentum, but with an important consequence: a separation between grace and the Church, which have neither the same intensity nor the same depth. (Along with other nuances in his understanding of the Church, J. H. Nicolas resolves this difficulty by explaining that the notion of sacrament is not univocal: Here the res et sacramentum is so closely bound up with the res tantum that it can hardly be separated from it.)18 As for the relationship of causality that reconciliation with the Church has with grace, Dumont explains it in terms of “disposing causality” (thus, by comparison with Hervaeus Natalis, coming up short of Thomas Aquinas’s mature thought).19 Faced with this difficulty, he maintains the identity of the twofold affirmation: The penitent is received into the Church because God gives him back His grace, or, reciprocally, the penitent is taken back into ecclesiastical communion because the divine friendship has been given back to him. Consequently, extending the remarks of his predecessors, Dumont points out that this reconciliation with the Church allows us to show the necessity of the sacramental avowal made to the Church’s minister (Council of Trent), since we have here a reconciliation within the Church and a resumption of responsibility by the reconciling Church.The thesis of reconciliation with the Church as the res et sacramentum of penance is promoted anew, not without relevance, in order to defend Catholic teaching on the sacrament. 16 C. Dumont, SJ, “La réconciliation avec l’Église et la nécessité de l’aveu sacra- mentel,” Nouvelle Revue Théologique 81 (1959): 577–97. 17 C. Dumont, “La réconciliation avec l’Église,” 586. 18 Jean-Hervé Nicolas, Synthèse dogmatique, 1051. But then we are still faced with the problem of the distinction. 19 C. Dumont, “La réconciliation avec l’Église,” 586–87 & no. 18. Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 289 It cannot be denied, however, that the most important attempt at a synthesis belongs to Karl Rahner. Rahner definitely accepts the thinking of Thomas Aquinas on several key points, particularly the place of the penitent’s actions, with the priest’s absolution, at the heart of the sacramental sign, as well as the instrumental efficient causality of the sacrament thus constituted.20 Moreover, Rahner is unwilling to give up on finding a res et sacramentum, a “middle term” between the sign and the effect of penance: It is reconciliation with the Church, which respects both history (the patristic theme of pax et communio cum Ecclesia) and reality itself.Through his reconciliation with the Holy Community, the sinner, who has been reintegrated into the Church, acquires a new participation in the Spirit of the Church (res et sacramentum) that forgives and grants “peace with God” (res tantum).21 This explanation, which stresses the necessity of the priest’s absolution for there to be a reconciliation with the Church, is based upon a close parallel with baptism. In a way analogous to the baptismal character (the stable integration into the Church of which the baptized person is made a member), the res et sacramentum of penance consists in the restoration of the living bond with the Church.22 Rahner does not simply replace one theological explanation with another, but he fits the thinking of Thomas into his views. On the one hand, he shows that for Thomas (as for Bonaventure) the sacrament really produces reconciliation with the Church. On the other hand, he upholds “inner penance” as the effect produced or reinforced by the sacrament, while stressing that authentic “inner penance” (contrition) includes the desire to refer oneself to the ministry of the Church. True repentance includes the will to be reconciled with the Church in such a way that it bears the twofold aspect of reconciliation with God and with the Church. “The sacrament reconciles with the Church the sinner who approaches the Church with his ‘inner penance’ as the will to be reconciled with the Church.Through this, the sinner has a right to the ‘infusio gratiae’ that allows him to achieve fully this ‘inner penance’ by which he is able essentially to make his own the grace that is offered to him, in 20 Karl Rahner, “Vergessene Wahrheiten über das Busssakrament,” in Theologische Schriften, vol. 2 (Einsiedeln, Zürich, Köln: Benzinger Verlag, 1964), 143–83, cf. 161–71. In particular, Rahner challenges the assimilation of the thought of Thomas Aquinas to that of Duns Scotus. 21 Karl Rahner, “Vergessene Wahrheiten,” 180–81. 22 Ibid., 180–82. See Karl Rahner,“Das Sakrament der Busse als Wiederversöhnung mit der Kirche,” in Theologische Schriften, vol. 8 (Einsiedeln, Zürich, Köln: Benzinger Verlag, 1967), 447–71, cf. 468. 290 Gilles Emery, OP such a way that it becomes proper to him in a sanctifying and justifying fashion and he is thereby freed from his personal sins.”23 By designating reconciliation with the Church as the res et sacramentum of penance, Rahner takes inner penance with its existential fabric and orients it toward an immediate relationship with the Church in her visibility and her sanctifying dimension. Rahner’s thesis is grounded more profoundly in the Church’s sacramentality (the Church as primordial sacrament, Ursakrament) and the understanding of the sacraments as “self-achievements” (Selbstvollzüge) of the Church. This approach clarifies first of all the “duality” that we see in every sacrament, as well as in the Church: the sign (sacramentum) and the reality of grace (res). From this point of view, every res et sacramentum consists essentially in an ecclesial reality. Since Rahner has recourse to the comparison with baptism and the Eucharist, which showcase the ecclesial aspect in a particularly clear manner,24 it is fitting that we should consider the res et sacramentum in these two sacraments in particular. For Rahner, as we have said, baptism’s res et sacramentum consists of incorporation into the Church (das Eingegliedertsein, die Gliedschaft) in a stable and lasting way. Rahner excludes from this state the question of the “ontological status” of the baptismal character: whether it is thought of as simply a “bespeaking” (Beanspruchtheit) on the part of the Church, or if its fundamental aspect is an ontological grounding in the person (the quality or “spiritual power” that makes us apt for acts of worship and of Christian life, in the Thomistic tradition); all this is no longer of any importance to him.25 Here, as in the case of penance, the proper grounding of the res et sacramentum in the process of sacramental justification is reinterpreted in order to adapt it to the ecclesial scheme of things. Rahner adds weight to his choice by a critique of the Scholastic position: Without this “bespeaking” by the Church, we can only give an artificial explanation to the role of sign that belongs to the character. Put another way: Only the social dimension of the res et sacramentum allows us to establish its role of sacrament, for a sign requires visibility.26 The argument 23 Karl Rahner, “Das Sakrament der Busse als Wiederversöhnung mit der Kirche,” 469. 24 Karl Rahner, “Vergessene Wahrheiten,” 179–80. 25 Karl Rahner, Kirche und Sakramente, “Quaestiones Disputatae, 10” (Freiburg: Herder, 1960), 78–79. This thesis claims to be a return to the origins of the concept of “character”; without which, according to Rahner, the theory of character would remain “arbitrary” (ibid.); cf. “Vergessene Wahrheiten,” 180, no. 1. 26 Karl Rahner, Kirche und Sakramente, 78–80. Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 291 has weight (besides, it did not escape the Scholastics), but Rahner’s objection cannot be the deciding factor. Thomas Aquinas put forward the following response:The character is a sign through reference to the sensible rite of the sacrament’s celebration whereby it is imprinted27 (likewise, inner penance will have to be understood in reference to outward penance). In other words, the nature of sign and the “visibility” do not belong to the character as if this made up an independent reality, but rather when character is taken in the unity of the sacrament with its three moments (sacramentum, res et sacramentum, res) by which it is referred to the visible sacramental sign.The social dimension (present at each level of the analysis of the sacrament) doubtlessly does not oblige us to follow Rahner in such a definite fashion. The case of the Eucharist, which Rahner treats first in his Kirche und Sakramente, is still more interesting. Without questioning the truth of Christ’s Body and Blood, Rahner nevertheless refuses to see in it the res et sacramentum of the Eucharist. For Rahner this consists in a “deeper integration into the unity of the Mystical Body,” a renewed incorporation that is the first effect and the efficacious cause of the other effects of the Eucharist.28 For whomever would continue to hold that the true Body and Blood of Christ (the “Real Presence”) is the res et sacramentum, Rahner has the following objection: Even if we hold that the verum Corpus is the sign of its grace insofar as the Church possesses it as the sign of her own unity (which is necessary in this case), we would still have to be able to account for the ordering of the effects (res) of the Eucharist and the primary place (vorgeordnete Wirkung) that belongs here to the Church’s unity.29 Rahner’s view is profound, and the stress he lays upon ecclesial unity is altogether fundamental. Still, one can say that the position of Thomas Aquinas (here Rahner mentions the Eucharist as “the sacrament of the Church’s unity,” which is found in Thomas) in fact goes further than Rahner’s. Thomas firmly holds that the verum Corpus is the res et sacramentum of the Eucharist, but he does not consider the unity of the Church as one effect that procures other sacramental graces. There is not on one side an ecclesial effect of the sacrament, and on the other side a personal and individual effect. It is clearly the same reality of grace, incorporation into Christ given to the person, which is both the food of spiritual rebuilding and at the same time, by its very nature, 27 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae III, q. 63, a. 2, ad 4: “Character habet rationem signi per comparationem ad sacramentum sensibile a quo imprimitur.” 28 Karl Rahner, Kirche und Sakramente, 74. 29 Ibid., 75. 292 Gilles Emery, OP the building up of the Church whose unity is strengthened and achieved through charity.30 Reconciliation with the Church is a constituent of the ecclesial action of reconciliation with God. It is immediately obtained through the sacrament. The sinner receives forgiveness in his ecclesial reintegration. Grounded in Scripture and the practice of the early Church, this statement highlights very well the ecclesial dimension of the sacrament and meets the desires of contemporary thinking. From the start, it is also associated with the “defense” of several aspects of Catholic teaching (sacramentality, necessity of confession, necessity of absolution by a priest, etc.). However, its formulation in terms of res et sacramentum entails several difficulties: the distinction between the intermediate element and the res of the sacrament, the likening of the penitential framework to that of baptism, the nature of reconciliation with the Church in the person of the penitent, its “causality” in regard to sacramental grace (reconciliation with God), the modifications the very notion of res et sacramentum has undergone, as well as the articulation (Rahner) of this concept along the main lines of Thomas Aquinas’s treatment of penance. This is what we will now examine. Inner Penance in Thomas Aquinas Inner Penance The framework of Thomas Aquinas’s thinking is summarized in the following statement.“Even in Penance there is something which is sacramentum tantum, i.e., the actions done by the penitent sinner as well as by the absolving priest. Now, the res et sacramentum is the inner penance of the sinner, while the res tantum, which is not the sacrament, is the remission of sin.The first of these, taken integrally, is the cause of the second; the first and the second are the cause of the third.”31 This framework of understanding calls for several observations. First, it puts an important stress on the “outward” acts performed personally by the penitent (confession, satisfaction, expressions of repentance), obviously in relation with the inward acts of conversion. Here penance is 30 Cajetan has expressed this unity well:“When we hear that the fruit (res tantum) of the sacrament is grace, and that what is to be received is the unity of the Church or the Mystical Body of Christ, we do not understand by that that there are two diverse realities since all that is nothing else but God’s grace in His faithful” (Cajetan, In IIIam, q. 73, a. 1; Leonine Ed., t. XII, 139). Cf. my study:“Le fruit ecclésial de l’Eucharistie chez S. Thomas d’Aquin,” Nova et Vetera 72/4 (1997): 25–40. 31 Summa Theologiae (referred to as ST ) III, q. 84, a. 1, ad 3. Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 293 taken in the Gospel sense of “to do penance” (agere paenitentiam), the sensible character of which permits identification with an authentic sacramentum.32 These acts make up the “matter of the sacrament,” while the priest’s action (absolution) constitutes its “form.” This anthropological grounding of the sacrament’s matter provides the starting point for a theological analysis of the sacrament: What the penitent does, in action and word, signifies a holy reality.33 Thomas will go so far as to write that the penitent in person constitutes the “matter” of this sacrament.34 In agreement with the Thomistic teaching on the res et sacramentum, the latter will be understood with immediate reference to this sacramental sign.This stress is all the more important because, unlike the theologians who went before him (and numerous theologians who followed), Thomas attributes a real instrumental efficiency to the sacramental sign, and hence to the personal activity of the penitent, as regards the giving of grace. It seems that no theologian held this before him, and Thomas himself, in his early writing on the Sentences, speaks only of a disposing instrumental causality.35 In the Summa, however, it is no longer a question of a mere disposition to grace by the activity of the penitent and of the priest, but indeed of a real instrumental efficacy.36 By virtue of Christ’s passion, which acts in it, the sign or sacrament works effectively, as instrument, to obtain grace. Next we should note that the production of the res et sacramentum belongs to the first element, the sacramental sign taken integrally. In other words, the penitent’s acts of conversion do not have this efficacy except under the sway of their form, the priest’s sacramental absolution. Thus, Abelard’s thesis whereby the penitent’s contrition remits sins, and that of Hugh of Saint Victor, who held that the priest’s absolution remits them, 32 IV Sent. d. 22, q. 2, a. 3, qla 3, ad 2; ST III, q. 90, a. 2, obj. 1, ad 1. 33 ST, III, q. 84, a. 1, corpus. 34 De forma absolutionis, chap. 4 (Leonine Ed., t. 40 C, 40): “Ipse autem peccator confitens est sicut materia in hoc sacramento.” 35 Thomas was not the first to make the penitent’s actions the matter of the sacra- ment (that was already the opinion of Hugh of Saint-Cher and of Bonaventure), but nobody made them the efficacious cause of grace. 36 IV Sent. d. 22, q. 2, a. 1, qla. 1, ad 2; cf. qla 2. ST III, q. 86, a. 6; cf. q. 64, a. 1. See Bruno de Vaux Saint-Cyr, Revenir à Dieu. Pénitence, conversion, confession (Paris: Cerf, 1967), 151–78. For Thomas’s progress on instrumental causality, see JeanPierre Torrell, “La causalité salvifique de la résurrection du Christ selon saint Thomas,” Revue Thomiste 96 (1996): 179–208, cf. 186–92; Hyacinthe Dondaine,“A propos d’Avicenne et de saint Thomas. De la causalité dispositive à la causalité instrumentale,” Revue Thomiste 51 (1951): 441–53. For what follows I am indebted to Fr. Hyacinthe Dondaine’s unpublished course on penance given at Le Saulchoir. 294 Gilles Emery, OP are combined by Thomas into a more satisfactory position.37 In giving its full value to the thesis of an authentic instrumental efficacy, Thomas’s effort consists in showing the unity of the sacramental action and of personal conversion understood within the workings of the divine grace of forgiveness in the Church. Therefore, the sacramentum, considered as a whole, produces the intermediate element, the res et sacramentum, defined as “inner penance.”What are we dealing with? Inner penance designates contrition, which by its aim extends to all “parts” of penance since it overlaps equally confession (avowal of sins) and satisfaction, insofar as these are included virtually, or in voto, in full contrition.38 We may define contrition, for its part, as sorrow or remorse for sins committed with, under the impulse of charity, the intention of removing the consequence of sin, which is the offense committed against God.39 Thus understood, inner penance is at once signified and obtained by the actions of the penitent and the minister.40 Inner penance may be considered under two aspects. On the one hand, in as much as it is an act of virtue it is the origin (“cause”) of the outward penitential action, and is signified by it. On the other hand, in as much as it falls within a sacramental ecclesial gesture, inner penance acts efficaciously for the healing of sin; as such, it is obtained by the outward action.41 37 Paul Anciaux, La théologie du sacrement de pénitence au XIIe siècle (Louvain: E. Nauwelaerts, 1949), 275–302; Pierre Adnès, “Le rapport de la contrition et de l’absolution chez saint Thomas et les théologiens médiévaux,” in S.Tommaso Teologo, ed. Antonio Piolanti, “Studi Tomistici, 59” (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1995), 301–9. In the judgment of K. Rahner, this understanding of the causality of the acts of the person and of absolution provides “the conceptual assimilation of an authentic tradition going back to the patristic age” (“Vergessene Wahrheiten,” 165–66; cf. 162–64). 38 IV Sent. d. 22, q. 2, a. 1, qla 2, ad 3: “Tres partes paenitentiae sunt et in paenitentia exteriori et in interiori; quia confessio et satisfactio quae videntur tantum ad exteriorem paenitentiam pertinere, inveniuntur in interiori paenitentia quantum ad propositum et praemeditationem eorum,” ST III, q. 90, a. 2, ad 1: “[contritio] virtualiter autem pertinet ad paenitentiam exteriorem, inquantum scilicet implicat propositum confitendi et satisfaciendi.” But Thomas is not the first author to posit contrition or inner penance as res et sacramentum.That was already the position of Peter Lombard, of St. Bonaventure, and of many others. Rather,Thomas’s originality lies in the efficacy he sees in this contrition and its place within the process of sacramental penance. 39 ST III, q. 85, a. 1, ad 3; q. 85, aa. 5–6; cf. IV Sent. d. 17, q. 2, a. 1, qla 1 (here in its relation to confession and satisfaction). 40 IV Sent. d. 22, q. 2, a. 1, qla 2. 41 Ibid., ad 1. Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 295 The framework of the res et sacramentum appears here in broad daylight: Inner penance is res (effect) in relation to the penitent’s outward acts, which signify it; it remains somehow “proportionated” to them. It is likewise a sign in relation to the forgiveness of sins, in reference to the outward action with which it forms a whole. Lastly, it is the efficacious cause of the forgiveness of sins, together with the penitent’s personal action and the priest’s absolution, taken once again as an organic whole.42 What is at stake in this conception is clear. For Thomas, there can be no forgiveness of sins without an authentic inner conversion of the heart.43 We are miles away from a forgiveness obtained ex opere operato without the deep down participation of the penitent (here Thomas returns to the early doctrine). At the same time, this inner penance obtains forgiveness within the ecclesial action since it obtains its effect with penitential acts and absolution.44 Even outside the sacramental celebration, contrition includes the intention of confessing and desiring absolution (intention to “submit oneself to the keys of the Church”).This is the reason we would not willingly speak of the forgiveness of sins through a contrition that is “extrasacramental” (Poschmann). Such is the motive why Thomas has no difficulty holding that confession to a layman under such conditions is “somehow sacramental.”45 Lastly, the framework of the sacrament does not in itself require a temporal simultaneity of its components. Certainly contrition may be given at the moment of the sacrament’s celebration, but it may just as well precede it (Thomas deems this case the most common), or even follow it. Here, obviously, the doctrine matches Christian experience, which bears witness to the 42 Faced with the difficulty of conceiving the kind of causality of sacramental grace that belongs to inner penance, some Thomists and other theologians have been led to posit an “ornament of the soul” (ornatus animae) as res et sacramentum, a mysterious counterpart to the baptismal character. “Magna videtur altercatio de ornatu,” Cajetan too observes (In IIIam, q. 84, a. 1–2; Leonine Ed., t. XII, 288).We must however point out that inner penance or contrition is not the cause of charity; it is the cause of the remission of sins, which is the effect of the sacrament. 43 ST III, q. 86, a. 2; cf. q. 84, a. 5, ad 3.As a virtue, inner penance consitutes a fundamental disposition of Christian life, which is not limited to the celebration of the sacrament: q. 84, a. 8. As “contrition of the heart” for sin committed, inner penance is required for the fruitful reception of baptism:Thomas, ST III, q. 68, a. 6, ad 3; Super Ad Romanos 11,29 (Marietti Ed., #927). 44 ST III, q. 84, a. 1, ad 3 (“primum autem et secundum sunt causa tertii”); IV Sent. d. 22, q. 2, a. 1, qla 2. It is in this sense that inner penance constitutes the “immediate cause” of the remission of sins (ibid., sed contra 2). 45 IV Sent. d. 17, q. 3, a. 3, qla 2, ad 1. 296 Gilles Emery, OP complexity of the undertaking and to its character that may vary according to personal dispositions. To show this, Thomas does not hesitate to assert an anticipated causality of the complete sacrament (absolution already acts in the contrite sinner under the sway of charity).46 More profoundly, this analysis of penance places the conversion experience at the heart of the process of justification. Cooperating with the divine action, to which all initiative belongs, the virtuous act of penance engages faith, hope, charity, and filial fear.47 Thomas makes the scheme of Christian justification and sacramental forgiveness coincide. When all is said and done, he knows only one Christian penance: a virtuous labor undertaken in a sacramental action where grace is at work.48 As for the res of the Sacrament, obtained by means of the res et sacramentum,Thomas designates it as “the remission of sins.” Such is the proper effect of the sacrament of penance, expressed by the words of absolution (the sacrament effects exactly what it signifies, and Thomas follows this signification closely). This forgiveness of sins obtains the “reconciliation of friendship” (reconciliatio amicitiae) that best characterizes (better, in fact, than the category of strict justice, in Thomas’s judgment) the underlying intention of penance.49 The sacrament is shown here fundamentally as the “means” to rid the offense that thwarts the friendship God wishes to establish with His children. It is also with this theme of restored friendship that Thomas develops the pneumatological character of penance. The fruit of the sacrament, obtained through the power of Christ’s passion (passion “for the remission 46 Quodlibet IV, q. 7, a. 1 (Leonine Ed., t. 25/2, 330). See Daniel Ols,“ Saint Thomas a-t-il soutenu l’existence d’une causalité efficiente anticipée dans l’économie sacramentelle?”, in S.Tommaso Teologo, ed. Antonio Piolanti, “Studi Tomistici, 59” (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1995), 285–297. In my opinion, this concept allows us to explain in a coherent way why the remission of sins through the ministry of the priest is required even when contrition has already erased the guilt (IV Sent. d. 17, q. 2, a. 5 qla 1, ad 3, in the context of admission to the Eucharist). In his Commentary on the Sentences,Thomas distinguishes between the disposing action of contrition as a virtue and the instrumental action of contrition as part of the sacrament (ibid., sol.). In the Summa he stresses more strongly the relationship of all contrition with the ministry of the Church (“keys of the Church”) by which the virtue of penance is ordered to the Passion of Christ that remits sins (ST III, q. 86, a. 6, ad. 3; cf. sol.). 47 ST III, q. 85, a. 5; q. 86, a. 6, ad 2. 48 Hyacinthe F. Dondaine, La pénitence, type-written course (Le Saulchoir), 81. 49 ST III, q. 90, a. 2. This remark is important because for Thomas the virtue of penance is a species of justice. But here the theological virtues enrich and elevate justice (q. 85, a. 3, ad 4). Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 297 of sins”),50 is due to the Holy Spirit, since He is Love in person and Communion in the bosom of the Trinity, the underlying reason for the entire economy of salvation and mercy:“Since it is through the Holy Spirit that we are made friends of God, it is therefore through Him that God remits our sins.”51 Reconciliation with God and Reconciliation with the Church For Thomas the term “reconciliation” (reconciliatio) designates the restoration of friendship after the hindrance to friendship has been done away with. Thus reconciliation appears as the sinner’s return in grace into the heart of God. Penance, whose object is the sin that the penitent wants to work on eliminating, is wholly oriented toward reconciliation with God, which is its end.52 We are far removed from any reduction of reconciliation to the juridical: at its root reconciliation pertains to the love of charity.53 Reconciliation is closely associated with the theme of satisfaction (a part of penance) since it aims precisely at the reconciliation of the offended friend’s heart: reconciliation with God and reconciliation with our neighbor.54 Along with contrition and confession, satisfaction works for the total remission of the punishment due to sin, as well as for “reconciliation with the members of the Church.”55 Thus reconciliation is at the terminus of the penitential exercise of conversion, just as it is first in God’s saving plan.56 What place does Thomas give to reconciliation with the Church? If we look at the instances where the terms reconciliatio and reconciliare occur 50 Even more: the effect of penance is obtained “in so far as we are united to Christ suffering for our sins” (Summa contra Gentiles, Book IV, chap. 72; Marietti Ed., #4071). 51 Summa contra Gentiles, Book IV, chap. 21 (Marietti Ed., #3582), in reference to Proverbs 10:12, John 20:22, and Matthew 13:21. 52 IV Sent. d. 14, q. 1, a. 1, qla 4, ad 2; This distinction between the object and the end allows Thomas to explain the difference between penance and the theological virtues.Thomas fully accepts that “penance reconciles with God,” but only the theological virtues have God as their “object.” 53 IV Sent. d. 15, q. 1, a. 5, qla 2, sol.: “reconciliatio autem nihil aliud est quam amicitiae reparatio;” cf. a. 1, qla 2, obj. 1: “reconciliatio, cum sit amoris, ad caritatem pertinet.” 54 IV Sent. d. 15, q. 1, a. 1, qla 2, obj. 1 and ad 1; d. 15, q. 1, a. 5, qla 2; d. 15, q. 4, a. 7, qla 1, obj. 3 and ad 3; d. 16, q. 1, a. 1, qla 2; ST III, q. 85, a. 3, obj. 1. Let us recall that for Thomas works done without charity cannot count as satisfaction since then the motive for their acceptance by God would be wanting (IV Sent. d. 15, q. 1, a. 3, qla 2). It is charity (friendship) that accounts for the worth of satisfaction. 55 Super I Ad Cor. 11:27 (Marietti Ed., #690), in the context of participation in the Eucharist. 56 IV Sent. d. 18, q. 1, a. 2, qla 3. 298 Gilles Emery, OP in the treatise on the sacraments in the Commentary on the Sentences and the Summa theologiae, first we must say that this vocabulary shows up quite often in an ecclesial context. Here Thomas is drawing on the heritage of the patristic vocabulary, passed on by Augustine in particular, and by the texts cited in Gratian’s Decretals.This reconciliation, which finds its place at the end of the process of penance,57 is attached especially to admission to the Church’s sacraments (“reconciliation with the Church”) and above all to Eucharistic communion, which requires “peace with the Church.”58 The texts pay special attention here to the reconciliation of the dying, of persons engaged in an activity incompatible with the dignity of baptized persons, of apostates, heretics, priests degraded from their order, all with a heavy ecclesial content.59 In this context, “reconciliation with the Church” is closely tied with the activity of the ministers.60 Here we must highlight two aspects. In a way similar to what we have been able to observe in the contemporary rediscovery of the theme of reconciliation with the Church, Thomas here brings out the necessity of the activity of the Church’s ministers: “Through the sacraments man is not only reconciled to God, but he must also be reconciled to the Church. Now, he can only be reconciled to the Church if the Church’s sanctification reaches him. . . . But in penance the sanctification of the Church does not reach a man except through the minister. . . . He is not yet reconciled to the Church in such a way that he can be admitted to the sacraments of the Church unless he has first been absolved by a priest.”61 Reconciliation with the Church is understood 57 IV Sent. d. 14, q. 1, a.5, qla 3; ST III, q. 80, a. 6 58 IV Sent. d. 9, q. 1, a.5, qla 3, sed contra 2 and sol.; d. 14, q.1, a. 5, qla 3; d. 17, q. 3, a. 3, qla 2, ad 3; d. 17, q. 3, a. 3, qla 3; ST III, q. 80, a. 6. 59 IV Sent. d. 25, q. 1, a. 2, sed contra 1; ST III, q. 80, a. 6; q. 82, a. 8, sed contra. 60 IV Sent. d. 14, q. 1, a. 1, qla 2; d. 17, q. 3, a. 3, qla 2, ad 3. Just as Thomas interprets the canonical penance of the ancient Church in light of the public or solemn penance of the Middle Ages (IV Sent. d. 14, q. 1, a. 5, qla 3), just so he is incapable of giving a correct account of the role that the early practice reserved to the bishop in reconciliation (IV Sent. d. 20, div. text. and exp. text.).We should point out that he finds himself in the same difficulty when it comes to the ancient doctrine of the non-repeatability of penance (ST III, q. 84, a. 10). Indeed, his reflection starts from a very concrete point: the sacramental practice he knows, “penance as it is practiced in the Church” (ST III, q. 84, a. 1). 61 IV Sent. d. 17, q. 3, a. 3, qla 2, ad 3: “Per sacramenta homo non solum Deo, sed etiam Ecclesiae oportet quod reconciliatur. Ecclesiae autem reconciliari non potest nisi sanctificatio Ecclesiae ad eum perveniat (. . .) Sed in paenitentia Ecclesiae sanctificatio non pervenit ad hominem nisi per ministrum. (. . .) Non tamen adhuc Ecclesiae reconciliatus est, ut ad sacramenta Ecclesiae admitti debeat, nisi prius a sacerdote absolvatur;” cf. IV Sent. d. 14, q. 1, a. 1, qla 2. Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 299 essentially in reference to the Church’s sanctifying function and the grace of communion that constitutes it (in relation to the Eucharist especially). Here we are approaching the theme of the Church as sacrament developed by Rahner in this context.62 It is not surprising, then, to learn that it is in connection with the Eucharist that Thomas prefers to treat the ecclesial dimension of penance. “Whoever receives this sacrament (the Eucharist) shows thereby that he is united to Christ and incorporated in His members, which is achieved through faith informed [by charity], and nobody can have that together with mortal sin.”63 Thomas considers this incompatibility between the state of mortal sin and the fruitful reception of the Eucharist explicitly in the light of the “Mystical Body of Christ, which is a society of saints.”64 The Eucharist nourishes the communion of the Church in its two dimensions of relationship with Christ and fraternal unity of the members.The absence of this communion, if it occurs, wounds the signification of the sacrament and the reality of its effect.The sacrament of penance is as a matter of fact ordered to true and full participation in the Eucharist, the sacrament of charity and of the Church’s unity. Here we find reconciliation with God achieved at the very heart of the ecclesial communion. In Thomas, it is around the divine friendship which is charity (faith formed by charity) that the themes of the Church, of contrition, of the sacrament of penance, and of the Eucharist are bound together. At this level, it is quite difficult to assign priority to reconciliation with the Church or to reconciliation with God; in reality, the two coincide.65 However, Thomas endeavors vigorously to show that the proper virtue of the sacrament does not extend only to reconciliation with the Church, but indeed reaches to reconciliation with God. On this point he disagrees with Bonaventure. As already seen, the Franciscan Doctor, also, holds that contrition or inner penance is the res et sacramentum of penance. He likewise states that the sacrament reconciles with God and 62 For this relationship between Eucharist, ecclesial mediation, and reconciliation, cf. IV Sent. d. 13, q. 1, a. 3, qla 2. 63 ST III, q. 80, a. 4. 64 Ibid. For Thomas, all the sacraments are ordered to the Eucharist, which bestows its underlying unity on the sacramental organism (ST III, q. 65, a. 3). Now the Eucharist is a major source of Thomas’s ecclesiological thinking. 65 In Thomas’s view of the Church, which is at once moral, sacramental (Eucharistic), pneumatological, and theocentric, first place belongs to the grace of the Holy Spirit that incorporates into Christ (cf. especially ST I–II, q. 106, a. 1; ST III, q. 8, a. 3). See Yves Congar, “L’idée de l’Église chez saint Thomas d’Aquin,” in Esquisse du mystère de l’Église (Paris: Cerf, 1941), 59–91.The theme of contrition as res et sacramentum finds its full meaning within this vision of the Church as a body of faith and charity whose soul is the Holy Spirit. 300 Gilles Emery, OP the Church. But he distinguishes more sharply these two aspects of penance: (1) sacrament that reconciles with God; and (2) sacrament of the Church.66 This distinction crystallizes in the question of the scope of the “power of the keys” exercised by the Church’s ministers. In his function of “descending mediation,” the priest has the power to grant reconciliation with the Church; such is the goal that is proportionate to his status as human minister. But in his function of “ascending mediation” (reconciliation with God), the priest can only ask for the grace on behalf of the sinner. This is how Bonaventure explains the alternation of words that beseech and words that indicate a fact in the rite of absolution. Thus, Bonaventure goes on, if we wish to speak properly, we must say that the power of the keys confided to the Church does not go so far as the suppression of the fault since it only reaches this by way of prayer and petition (per modum deprecantis), while it actually extends to reconciliation with the Church, in regard to which it is in the position of being able to share (per modum impertientis). Consequently, if a priest absolves a penitent, it is because he judges that God has first of all absolved him of his fault; only God can absolve.The priest’s absolution presupposes divine forgiveness.67 As we have seen,Thomas’s position veers in another direction.Thanks to his notion of instrumental causality, he can assign a “divine effect” to the action of the penitent and the priest without undermining God’s prerogatives (“principal cause”).Through the personal cooperation of the penitent and by the action of Christ working through the minister, the fault that attacked the divine friendship is forgiven. He therefore gives full weight to the personal action of the penitent and to the Church’s mediation:The sacramental sign (the penitent’s acts and the priest’s absolution), with inner penance, are the (instrumental) cause of the remission of sins.68 Given this fact, he no longer has to distinguish between the realm of reconciliation with the Church and that of reconciliation with God in the remission of fault (culpa). In the same sense he will hold firmly to the indicative formula of absolution, since the sacrament effects what it signifies: “I forgive you of your sins.”69 66 Bonaventure, IV Sent. d. 22, a. 2, q. 2: the three elements of the sacrament’s make- up (sacramentum, res et sacramentum, res) are distributed successively under these two aspects. 67 Bonaventure, IV Sent. d. 18, 1, a. 2, q. 1; cf. ad 3: the priest can obtain grace for the sinner, but he does not give it: absolution from guilt belongs only to God.This concept will persist in the Scotist theory of the divine “pact.” 68 De forma absolutionis, chap. 2, no. 11 (Leonine Ed., t. 40 C, 37); ST III, q. 84, a. 1, ad 3; cf. q. 62, a. 1. 69 ST III, q. 84, a. 3; or more explicitly (perfectior expositio): “Ego te absolvo, idest, sacramentum absolutionis tibi impendo” (ibid., ad 5). Reconciliation with the Church and Interior Penance 301 The thought of Thomas is therefore distinguished by his taking into account the personal action of the penitent in all its depth, together with the minister’s action, to obtain efficaciously the remission of sins and, through this, a return to divine friendship in the bosom of the Church. Of this unique Christian penance, contrition, called forth by charity, is the heart: Penance is a conversion of love, an inner transformation, and reconciliation is a gift of love. Hence, in the sacramental action, the penitent’s person and ecclesial mediation converge in a profound unity. For Thomas Aquinas, this is what is at stake in inner penance as res et sacramentum. According to Thomas Aquinas—and this is another benefit of his thought—inner penance or contrition entails an internal relationship with the ministry of the Church and with Eucharistic communion, that is, the communion of the Church. We have seen that Rahner, while making reconciliation with the Church the res et sacramentum of penance, sought to maintain the merits of the Thomistic doctrine of contrition.We can now see how this doctrine of contrition is entirely capable of taking on the ecclesial dimension of the res et sacramentum of penance, which historical studies have restored to value.Thomas himself points us in the direction of understanding contrition, at the heart of the sacrament, as a personal engagement grasped in the ecclesial action and recognized or ratified by the Church: Such is the res et sacramentum of penance.70 In other words, reconciliation with the Church is the Church’s recognition of the penitent’s inner conversion under the sway of divine grace (justification), which operates in the sacrament through the ministry of the Church. We have seen that this understanding has the advantage of respecting the proper framework of the res et sacramentum. But, no matter if we keep this framework in all its details, it especially allows us to understand reconciliation with the Church as part of the renewal of life to which the Gospel calls the disciples of Christ and which marks the concrete participation in the communion of grace that the Church is. The Thomistic doctrine of contrition and the understanding of the res et sacramentum of penance truly aims at this depth of divine friendship of which the Church is the sacrament. N&V 70 C. E. O’Neill, “Les Sacrements,” 497; The author points out further—but that goes beyond our subject—that such an understanding can provide an interpretation suggestive of “devotional confession” and also clarifies the doctrine of indulgences (“contrition granted ecclesial aid”). Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 303–20 303 Biblical Scholarship New and Old: Learning from the Past J EREMY H OLMES Marquette University Milwaukee,Wisconsin Introduction S TUDENTS IN A MERICA are often warned about the tendency of American scholars to be “provincial,” that is, to stay complacently within the questions, answers, and assumptions of their own country. We must learn to be aware of our colleagues in Europe, especially those in the German- and French-speaking countries. There is however another kind of provincialism not often mentioned: The tendency we all share to stay complacently within the issues and assumptions of our own time in history. By learning to think with the authors of several ages, we form a frame within which to judge both our age and theirs, rather than letting our own age be our frame of judgment. As Roland Murphy states, How many far-fetched theories have been hazarded by modern writers who are locked up in their own crippling presuppositions? Even the vagaries and extravagances of ancient exegesis can have a sobering effect on current scholarship. . . . As David Steinmetz . . . has remarked, “The principal value of precritical exegesis is that it is not modern exegesis. . . .”1 That temporal provincialism is indeed a problem in the biblical guild can be seen by looking at how contemporary scholars treat the history of interpretation. The New Jerome Biblical Commentary (NJBC), for example, has a fourteen-page article devoted to the history of interpretation of the 1 Roland Murphy, Ecclesiastes (Dallas:Word, 1992), lv–lvi. Jeremy Holmes 304 Old Testament, but the title of the article limits the discussion to modern interpretation.The article begins this way: The modern era of biblical interpretation may be said to have begun ca. 1650. Until that date most Christian exegesis viewed the Bible as a heaven-sent collection of writings, a report of events that were independent of their cultural and historical milieux. A narrow view of inspiration neglected the role of the sacred writer in the composition of the books and ignored the possibility of development in Old Testament revelation. The criticism of that era was dogmatic and theological.There were, of course, individuals who questioned one or the other traditional viewpoint, but these isolated scholars failed to capture the attention of their contemporaries. By 1650, however, fresh intellectual currents had gathered sufficient impetus to alter the biblical sciences.2 This finishes the NJBC’s description of 1,650 years of interpretation, all the many centuries before the exegetes who walked in darkness saw a great light. To do justice to the NJBC, there is in fact another fifteen-page article, this one on the history of interpretation of the New Testament, in which the first 1,650 years of exegesis gets a little over a quarter of a page. But there again we find signs of provincialism:The title of the article restricts the discussion to modern interpretation, and after listing exegetes up to Augustine who contributed to New Testament criticism, the period from A.D. 430 to A.D. 1483 is leapt over by the following comment:“Although the Middle Ages, especially the great Scholastic period, contributed to the better understanding of Scripture, the contributions to real NT criticism were not major.”3 Were the author of this article to read commentaries from the time, or a chapter from a history of biblical studies in the Middle Ages, his impression would probably change.The thirteenth century was an exciting time to be an interpreter of Scripture. Biblical studies were moving from the monasteries to the schools, the works of Aristotle were being re-introduced into Europe, and the new mendicant religious orders were leading the way in a gospel-driven intellectual revolution;4 these converging forces were accompanied by an explosion of theoretical and technical 2 The New Jerome Bible Commentary (NJBC) 69:3, 1114. 3 NJBC 70:3, 1131; cf. 71:39–40, 1155, which offers some history of “spiritual” exegesis. 4 M. D. Chenu, Toward Understanding St.Thomas (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1964), 234–37, 241–32. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 305 innovations, including concordances, Bible dictionaries, renewed interest in and knowledge of Hebrew and Greek, interlinear and facing-page Hebrew–Latin Bibles, and the chapter and verse divisions we use today.5 The University of Paris took a particular descendent of Jerome’s Vulgate as their standard text, due to its unavoidable interconnection with the glosses, and it was (as they acknowledged) in a sad state, full of corruptions and interpolations.6 Even the original Vulgate translation was based a limited number of manuscripts.7 However, an enormous cooperative labor by Dominican exegetes produced the correctoria, long lists of variant readings and amendments to the text gathered from older Latin Bibles, the comments of the Church Fathers, and from the original Greek and Hebrew languages with the assistance of contemporary Jews; and as the thirteenth century progresses we see scriptural references become much more precise than before.8 It was only the beginnings of textual criticism as we have it today, but it was a significant advance over the previous centuries.9 In the first half of this essay, I will attempt an overview of and reflection on an influential commentary from the Middle Ages;10 I will complete my reflections in the second half by looking at medieval and modern commentary side-by-side. My purpose is not to rank them but 5 Ibid., 329–55.The focus of this essay is on Bonaventure’s commentary on Eccle- siastes. As Robert J. Karris has demonstrated with respect to the commentary on Luke, Bonaventure relied more on his tremendous memory for scriptural citations than on a concordance, often making connections that could not be made by word searches. See Karris,“Bonaventure and Talbert on Luke 8:26–39: Christology, Discipleship, and Evangelization,” Perspectives in Religious Study (PRSt) 28 (2002): 59–63. 6 Beryl Smalley, The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages (New York: Philosophical Library, 1952), 331. 7 See NJBC 68:139 and 147, 1101–2. 8 Smalley, 270, 334–36. 9 While Bonaventure’s commentary on Ecclesiastes is innovative in several ways, it does not seem to have taken advantage of the linguistic advances described here: He mentions variant readings found outside the Vulgate only four times (commenting on 1:17, 4:4, and two variations in 10:4), even though the older commentaries he relied upon included more information about such variants. See Dominic Vincent Monti, Bonaventure’s Interpretation of Scripture in His Exegetical Works (Ph.D. diss.,The University of Chicago, 1979), 94–95. 10 This seems to be the most neglected of periods. Relevant to the author and commentary I will discuss, see Monti, Bonaventure’s Interpretation, 3–4:“In fact, out of the 4,800 items included in a comprehensive bibliography of Bonaventurean research during the years 1850–1973, fewer than ten deal specifically with his biblical commentaries, which comprise two of the nine folio volumes of the Quaracchi edition of his works.” 306 Jeremy Holmes to contrast them, not to have a “duel of the commentaries” but rather a dialogue of the commentators.11 Bonaventure on Ecclesiastes For this purpose, I have chosen a commentary on Ecclesiastes by St. Bonaventure. His commentary on Ecclesiastes was a “classic,” according to Beryl Smalley, who writes, “I have seen a large number of postills on Ecclesiastes of the later thirteenth and early fourteenth centuries: all quote Bonaventure and all quote him anonymously.”12 Some have thought that Bonaventure’s Commentarius in Ecclesiasticam dates from the point in his studies when he was giving cursory commentary for beginning students. However, as Smalley has noticed, his commentary does not quite meet the usual description of these cursory commentaries:As a rule they are unoriginal, staying close to the accepted glosses and commentators, and necessarily sketchy, while Bonaventure’s postill on Ecclesiastes is in many respects original, even trend-setting, and thorough to the point of being exhaustive.13 For whatever reason, he singled out Ecclesiastes for special attention, leading others to conclude that the commentary dates from his later years as a master.14 Bonaventure shows close dependence on St. Jerome, Hugh of St. Cher, and the traditional anonymous glosses, in addition to his original achievements. I will not take up space in this short paper with identifying which aspects are original to Bonaventure and which are part of the tradition.15 The Prologue16 The prologue begins with a quotation from Ps 39:5 (40:5), “Blessed the man whose hope is the name of the Lord, and has not had regard for 11 At the same time as this article was being written, Karris was working on a simi- lar comparison between Bonaventure and Charles H. Talbert. However, Karris’s aim was to find points of contact between Talbert’s narrative criticism and Bonaventure’s approach to show what medievals and moderns can have in common; the aim of this article is to contrast Bonaventure’s approach with historical criticism to show where medievals and moderns could learn from one another. See Karris, 57–66. 12 Smalley, 274. 13 Roland E. Murphy, ed., Medieval Exegesis of Wisdom Literature: Essays by Beryl Smalley (Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1986), 40, 43, 45. 14 Monti, Bonaventure’s Interpretation, 82–83. 15 For a good overview of Bonaventure’s sources, see ibid., 98–99. 16 For my research, I have used the Peltier edition of Bonaventure’s opera, published in Paris in 1867.The commentary on Ecclesiastes is found in volume nine. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 307 vanities, and lying follies.”17 (It was customary to begin the prologue to a commentary with a quotation, meant to bring out the chief themes of the book at hand, from elsewhere in Scripture.) There follows a long, stirring, and heavily theological discourse on why the man who hopes in the Lord has beatitude or blessedness, while the man who sets his heart on the vanities of the world is himself rendered vain, in the sense of “empty” or “futile.” This section lays the remote intellectual foundations for understanding the theology of Ecclesiastes, introducing the ideas of beatitude and vanity, eternal and temporal, God and the world; the book of Ecclesiastes itself is not mentioned. Bonaventure moves into Ecclesiastes by noting that the wise man’s chief concern is to teach people the way to beatitude.18 This sets up an exposition of the “final cause” of the book. Shortly before the composition of this commentary, it had become the custom to use Aristotle’s “four causes” to analyze and introduce a book of Scripture: material, efficient, formal, final. Since these four causes can be found anytime something comes into being, and since all causes of coming to be can be grouped under these four headings, the medievals learned to use them as a tool for organizing thoughts and writings. Hence Bonaventure begins his proximate treatment of the book of Ecclesiastes by walking through its four causes. Final Cause The final cause of any book is the author’s purpose in writing.The wise man’s chief concern is to teach people the way to beatitude.And since— as Bonaventure has just argued at length—to arrive at beatitude one must love eternal things, despise temporal things, and lead a good life in interaction with a corrupt world, the wise Solomon produced three books: Proverbs, which teaches one to interact wisely with the world; Ecclesiastes, which teaches one to hold temporal things in contempt; and the Song of Songs, which teaches one to love heavenly things.19 Modern scholars have abandoned the notion that Solomon could have written Ecclesiastes, but there is still some profit in reflecting on Bonaventure’s approach to the problem of how the Wisdom books relate. There is a sense in which the mind only sees what it already knows. In a dark room, the brain uses previous memory together with imagination to organize and flesh out a few glints of light here and there into an amazingly accurate picture; in a similar way, the mind uses its pool of previously held ideas to organize and flesh out incoming data. Living in 17 Ibid., 579. 18 Ibid., 582. 19 Ibid. 308 Jeremy Holmes an age shaped by Darwin and Hegel, we look at the books of Solomon and see evolution and history. Proverbs, think many modern scholars, was an earlier stage, and then disillusionment with the optimistic viewpoint presented there led to the darker and more realistic views of Ecclesiastes. Bonaventure, however, living in a world shaped by Augustine and Francis, looks at these same books and sees mystical theology. Everyone who is serious about the spiritual life experiences the tension of being in the world but not of it. A very rough analogy would be to compare Thomas Aquinas’s Summa theologiae with the Imitation of Christ.The first is all about knowledge and how to get it; the second says repeatedly that the pursuit of knowledge is a snare and a pitfall. Both are true, both have been received into the stream of Catholic tradition, and one individual can even read them both and eventually hold them together in a single view (although it is very difficult to imagine one individual writing them both). This does not supplant the historical approach to the problem, but it does supplement it. It can be helpful to read an author whose mental interpretive filters are not the same as our own. Material Cause At a crude level, of course, the material cause of a book is the parchment and ink (or equivalents thereof) out of which it is made. But Bonaventure is thinking of the book as an intellectual product in the mind of its author and its readers rather than as a physical product, so the “stuff ” the book is made of is its subject matter. The material cause of the book is what it is about. Ecclesiastes is about the vanity of things.20 Bonaventure spends a fair amount of time unpacking the idea of “vanity,” or emptiness, futility, falsehood, which is opposed to fullness of being, to “truth” in the metaphysical sense.21 He distinguishes three kinds of vanity: the vanity of mutability, the vanity of guilt, and the vanity of punishment. The first vanity arises from the changeableness of created things, and means nothing more than that created things do not have the absolute fullness of being that God does; in itself this is a good thing, because the world is not supposed to be God anyway. The second vanity comes into play when a person clings to the changeable world and so is drawn into sin, which is both “empty” in the sense that it is lacking in being and “futile” in the sense that it can come to no good; this vanity is an evil, definitely 20 Ibid. 21 Ibid., 582–84.The root meaning of vanitas is “emptiness,” from which it comes to denote an illusory or unsubstantial quality, falseness, and pointlessness. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 309 not the way things are supposed to be. The third vanity consists in the punishments due to sin (by which Bonaventure seems to mean original sin rather than a particular personal sin), such as death and concupiscence. This kind of vanity leads to futility in actions, and is also an evil, at least for the person suffering it. Each vanity flows from the one before it:The vanity of mutability leads to the vanity of sin, and this in turn leads to the vanity of punishment. Formal Cause The formal cause is what gives a thing its particular nature, what puts it in a species.What makes a book be a particular kind of book is not what it is about but rather the way in which it is written, whether as a play or as a poem, as a treatise or a tragedy.When we ask about the formal cause of a book, we are asking about the way in which it is written. In modern terms, this would be the genre. According to Bonaventure, Ecclesiastes speaks in a manner “unique among the other books”: He speaks as one who solemnly proclaims serious truths,22 setting forth different opinions, speaking here in the manner of a wise man, and there in the manner of a fool, so that out of the clash of different opinions a single truth may become clear in the minds of the audience.23 A modern might then request a color-coded text in which the wise man speaks in red letters or something of that sort. Bonaventure means something more subtle than that. He does not mean that Ecclesiastes is a patchwork of different people speaking with no indication as to who they are, but that there is one wise man speaking who sometimes speaks as though he were a fool. Roland Murphy has recourse to a similar interpretation when he argues that Eccl 8:12b should remain a part of the original work:“But one can allow it to remain as part of the work if one recognizes that he is repeating, even quoting, the traditional doctrine that he does not adhere to.”24 Usually Bonaventure avoids leaning on this method, preferring instead to interpret everything (including 8:12b) as spoken in the author’s own voice.25 A good example of Bonaventure’s preference is his commentary on Eccl 5:17. After presenting the traditional view that the author speaks 22 At least, that seems to be the import of the word concionator, Jerome’s translation of the word qoheleth. 23 Ibid., 582. 24 Murphy, The Tree of Life:An Exploration of Biblical Wisdom Literature (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1996), 56. 25 Bonaventure, 649–50. Jeremy Holmes 310 here in the voice of an Epicurean, he goes on to suggest that the author may be speaking in his own voice: But nonetheless to understand the things he says, two things should be noted, namely the reason and manner of speaking. . . . [S]ome things he says truly, but other things ironically . . . some things he says approvingly, but in others he is merely recounting what he himself has done. . . . Likewise, some of the things he says recount what he has thought. And he uses this manner of speech often in this book, like a man telling the story of his temptations. Hence this book was, as it were, a kind of meditation of Solomon. And just as a man changes from one meditation to a different opinion on the basis of different considerations, as when he thinks something is good, and afterwards thinks differently about it, so Solomon tells the story [of his thoughts in this book].26 Efficient Cause As was said above, the efficient cause of a book is the author, and for Bonaventure, as for all premodern commentators, the author of Ecclesiastes is Solomon. Despite this sharp disagreement with modern historical-critical exegesis, however, it is interesting to see how he approaches the question of authorship. In favor of Solomonic authorship, he argues that Solomon was the most suitable person to write the book. After all, Ecclesiastes contains severe condemnations of riches, and honor, and the pursuit of knowledge, so the person condemning should be someone who has experience of these things. If a poor man condemned riches, who would believe him? So our author needs to be someone who was powerful, rich, pleasure-seeking, and a pursuer of knowledge. But we know of no one more powerful, rich, pleasure-seeking, and wise than Solomon, so he is the best candidate.27 Against Solomonic authorship, Bonaventure points out that it is not helpful for a sinner to condemn sin: It is more a source of scandal than of edification. Furthermore, it would seem to be a sin for Solomon to write the book, the sin of hypocrisy.28 He defends Solomon first by pointing to the traditional idea that Solomon repented at the end of his life, and wrote Ecclesiastes as a result. But even if he did not, Bonaventure argues, the Holy Spirit can speak true things through both good men and bad, as Christ implies when he 26 Ibid., 628–29. 27 Ibid., 582–83. 28 Ibid., 585. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 311 instructs the people to do what the Pharisees say but not what they do. Knowing that the book was written under the inspiration of the Holy Spirit, we do not need to bother ourselves about the moral quality of the man who wrote it. As for the problem of hypocrisy, he points out that Solomon was given the gift of wisdom in a rather impressive manner, and so he had a duty to use it for the people. It would have been a sin not to use his wisdom.29 The Commentary To describe the commentary itself in detail would require many, many pages, so I will limit my remarks to Bonaventure’s division of the text of Ecclesiastes, which actually gives a good sketch of the commentary as a whole. The three main parts of Ecclesiastes are, of course, the title (1:1), the body of the text (1:2–12:8), and the epilogue (12:9–14). Bonaventure does not consider the possibility that someone besides Solomon added these parts.30 More interesting is the body of the text. First, the author sets out his thesis (1:2), namely that “all things are vanity.” Then he spends almost all of the body proving his thesis. Lastly, he concludes by restating the thesis (12:8). This way of viewing the text is consonant with the view that the author writes as a concionator, trying to persuade his audience by various arguments.31 The proofs of the thesis fall into three parts. Bringing his analysis of vanity into play, Bonaventure says that the first part is about the vanity of mutability (1:3–3:15), the second part about the vanity of guilt (3:16–7:23), and the third part about the vanity of punishment (7:24–12:7).32 Although it is not clear to me that 7:24 is the right division point, the division of the text into these three categories is surprisingly convincing. The first part of Ecclesiastes does speak about things which are neither good nor bad in themselves, like the unceasing change of the sea, and the passing of times and seasons. Then the author begins in 3:16 to speak about the evil things that men do. At some point, whether 7:24 or elsewhere, he transitions to speaking about the evils that men suffer, concluding with death in chapter 12. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid., 585–86. He notes that the title manifests the efficient cause of the book, the body of the text manifests the material and formal causes, and the epilogue manifests the final cause. 31 Ibid., 587. 32 Ibid., 588. 312 Jeremy Holmes The section about the vanity of guilt is rather long, because unlike the vanity of mutability, this vanity is not the way things are supposed to be. So after the author sets out the vanity itself (3:16–4:16), he then spends a lot of time setting out a remedy against it (4:17–7:23). Bonaventure sees him as setting out three kinds of guilt, namely malice (3:16ff.), avarice (4:1ff.), and imprudence (4:13ff), and then setting out remedies in the same order, namely against malice (4:17ff), avarice (5:9ff), and imprudence (6:8ff).33 A couple of points for reflection occur here. First, Bonaventure sees the author of Ecclesiastes as being—at a certain level at least—very clear in his ideas and organized in his approach, rather than confused and wandering. These seem to be the two options: Given so convoluted a text, the author is either very organized or very disorganized. However, this should not be taken too far. If you pursue Bonaventure’s division to a certain level of detail, the author’s more human side emerges, with brief tangents, outbursts of emotion, and so on, as in 8:15, where he says that the author speaks “as a man who is disturbed.”34 Second, Bonaventure does not seem to have many literary techniques in his text-divisional tool bag. For example, he does not consider using repeated phrases as a clue to the division, and he obviously does not have the linguistic training to pursue a numerological argument of the sort proposed by Addison and Wright.35 He is forced to rely exclusively on a good grasp of the theme at hand and his tremendous ability to follow an argument.36 These limitations seem to be genuine limitations in training rather than results of premodern theological convictions about inspiration, because he seems quite ready to use the methods of textual division he learned in the study of Aristotle’s corpus, which he certainly did not regard as inspired. Bonaventure’s commentary on Ecclesiastes is thus heavily theological: He is more concerned that Ecclesiastes be written under the inspiration of the Spirit than that it be written by a morally upright man; the subject of Ecclesiastes is one you can find in a book of devotions; the division of the text is according to a theological analysis of vanity. He obviously operates on the assumption that—to rephrase a common line—theology is the soul of Scripture. 33 Ibid., 613, 621 & 632. 34 Ibid., 651. 35 See Murphy, Ecclesiastes, xxxviii. 36 Or as Karris somewhat more positively puts it (“Bonaventure and Talbert,” 59), he relied on “the insights of previous commentators, the Scriptures themselves, a keen literary sense, a compendious memory, a brilliant intellect, and a profound faith—excellent tools, it would seem, for any exegete.” Biblical Scholarship New and Old 313 Death and Afterlife in Ecclesiastes We are now prepared to address in more detail a particular theme in the commentary the theme of Ecclesiastes’ view of life after death. I will compare Bonaventure’s approach with that of a contemporary scholar so that, by setting modern and medieval side-by-side, we can get a sharper picture of both. Our modern representative is Father Roland Murphy, whose recent death was sad news indeed for Catholic biblical scholarship. Murphy on Death and Afterlife in Ecclesiastes In the introduction to his work, Murphy offers a quick overview of Qoheleth’s views on death.37 While ancient Israelites were remarkably resigned to death overall, Qoheleth simply cannot reconcile himself to it. They apparently found solace in the thought that they lived on in others’ memory (Prov 10:7) and in their own posterity, but Qoheleth denies that there will be any memory (Eccl 1:11; 2:16), and wonders whether his heir will be wise or disastrously foolish (2:18–19). Although he thinks that death would be preferable to certain extreme situations (4:2–3; 6:1–6), otherwise it is entirely unwelcome, as the lugubrious tone of 12:1–7 shows. Death is the complete opposite of the only good Qoheleth can find, the life of pleasure; after death there is nothing (9:10). Murphy’s commentary on particular passages fleshes out this summary of Qoheleth’s view of death and afterlife. His comments on each passage are divided into three parts: first the “notes,” a verse-by-verse analysis of textual-critical issues, grammatical questions, and other such things that would disrupt the flow of a commentary on the meaning; second the “comment,” another verse-by-verse analysis, this time of the meaning and import of the text; and lastly, the “explanation,” in which he takes a “wide-angle” view of the text, summarizing the main points and placing it within the flow of the book as a whole. While I will not present everything Murphy has to say about the theme of death and afterlife in Ecclesiastes, what I present will be representative of the whole. Ecclesiastes 3:16–2138 Qoheleth bemoans the fact that human justice is corrupt, and in the worst of places—public justice. While he clearly affirms that God will 37 Murphy, Ecclesiastes, lxvii–lxix. 38 Ibid., 37–38. 314 Jeremy Holmes judge both the good and the wicked, it is far from clear what form he thinks that judgment will take. “He did not deny that God is just,” Murphy says, “but he saw no evidence for it. The divine judgment, so often affirmed in his biblical tradition, was something he could not deny, but it appeared useless in reality.”39 Murphy finds it hard to see the connection between vv. 17 and 18. Perhaps Qoheleth means that human injustice shows that men are beasts despite the divine judgment. The description of death in v. 19 is rooted in Gen 2:7 and Ps 104:29–30. The statement in v. 21—“Who knows if the life-breath of humans goes upwards, and if the life-breath of animals goes down into the earth?”—is equivalent to a denial: There is no distinction in fate between the life-breath of man and the life-breath of animals. Although Murphy is not sure what exact position is being denied, he is sure that the proposition denied here is not the same as the proposition affirmed in 12:7, namely that “the life-breath returns to God who gave it.” The hopeful-sounding affirmation of 12:7 does nothing to mitigate the gloomy view of 3:21. Ecclesiastes 9:4 –1040 The comparison in v. 4 of a living dog with a dead lion is heavily ironic, especially given the low value of dogs in the ancient Middle East. Love, hatred, and jealousy are rhymed in the Hebrew of v. 6. Starting in v. 7, Qoheleth draws a carpe diem conclusion which is very closely parallel to a passage in the epic of Gilgamesh.41 These learned details are certainly not what one could find in Bonaventure’s commentary, since Bonaventure does not seem to have known Hebrew and was certainly not familiar with the epic of Gilgamesh, but it is difficult to see exactly what they add with respect to the meaning of the text. Verse 10, says Murphy, “is motivated by a dour but realistic perspective: in Sheol there is no real activity or life, so act now! This description of Sheol is classic; it portrays a state of non-life.” Ecclesiastes 12:742 The process described in this verse is a reversal of Gen 2:7. “This is a picture of dissolution, not of immortality, as if there were a reditus animae ad Deum,“return of the soul to God.” Qoheleth is not even talking about 39 Ibid., 37. 40 Ibid., 92–93. 41 ANET, 90. 42 Ibid., 120. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 315 a “soul,” but about the “life-breath,” which Murphy says is “a totally different category of thought.”43 In a polemical context, Qoheleth denied that there is any distinction between the life-breath of men and that of animals (3:21), but he certainly shares with the rest of the Old Testament the conviction that God is the possessor and giver of life, that is, the lifebreath. (Cf. Ps 104:29–30; Job 33:4; 34:15.) From what we have seen of Murphy’s commentary, Qoheleth was a dour individual who had no use for the consolations faith was supposed to offer in the face of difficulties. Although he was confused about many things, he was quite clear in his opposition to an unknown philosophy that seems to have leaned in the direction of a special postmortem fate for mankind. For Qoheleth, there is nothing after this life—at least, nothing to speak of—and death is simply a negative. Bonaventure on Death and Afterlife in Ecclesiastes Bonaventure does not have a section that summarizes the theme of death in Ecclesiastes. I will pull together the main points after we have looked at his commentary on particular passages. His commentary on each passage is divided into two or sometimes three parts: First, he explains the literal sense as briefly and clearly as possible; next he explains the spiritual sense of the text; lastly he takes up doctrinal or exegetical questions that arise from the text, dealing with them in the classic Scholastic “question” format.This separation of the tasks to be accomplished was one of Bonaventure’s major innovations, and later commentators on Ecclesiastes followed his example.44 43 The point is well-taken, but “a totally different category of thought” is a bit of an overstatement. Our western notion of “soul” was decisively shaped by the tradition of Greek philosophy, which started with just such vague notions as “lifebreath” (the original meaning of pneuma is after all “breath” or “wind”).The later tradition shaped and refined the early, imprecise attempts at stating the nature of the soul, but always in definite continuity with them. For a clear example of this continuity, see Aristotle’s On the Soul, Bk. 1, esp. chap. 2. 44 The emphasis in this commentary falls decidedly on the literal sense. Bonaventure offers a spiritual interpretation for 13 passages (1:5–7; 2:4–7; 3:2–8; 4:9–12; 4:13–16; 9:4–10; 9:12; 9:14–15; 11:1–7; 12:1–2; 12:3–7), in accord with his general principle that a spiritual sense is only appropriate when the text in question does not have a direct bearing on faith or morals; cf. Bonaventure, Breviloquium, trans. Jose de Vinck (Paris: St. Anthony Guild, 1963), 19. In contrast to this, there are 83 “questions” dealing with exegetical or doctrinal difficulties arising from the literal sense; altogether, these “questions” make up about 25 percent of the text of Bonaventure’s commentary. See Monti, Bonaventure’s Interpretation, 100–101. 316 Jeremy Holmes Ecclesiastes 3:16–2145 To begin, Solomon bemoans the perversion of justice by rulers.This leads him to look for God’s judgment; Bonaventure says that the “judgment” can be taken either to mean the time of judgment for each man, or the general time when all things will be revealed. Having described the evil, Solomon then discusses why things are the way they are now: God is testing men by making them very much like beasts. Evil men, seeing that their lives are like the beasts’, will become like the beasts in behavior as well, while good men will persevere and live spiritually. In the lines that follow, according to Bonaventure, Solomon illustrates in detail the likeness between men and beasts. After showing the similarity, he says that the difference (the spiritual element in man) is very difficult to discern.Those who have faith know about the difference, and 12:7 is said in their person (“the spirit returns to God”); but those without faith have great difficulty discovering any difference, and 9:3 is said in their person (“one fate comes to all”). In the “questions” on this section, Bonaventure raises the difficulty about the soul again: How can Solomon say “Who knows?” when there are abundant philosophical proofs of the immortality of the soul? To sharpen the point, Bonaventure runs quickly through a number of these proofs. In response to the objection, he says that, even though faith and philosophy are in agreement on this point, nevertheless without faith it is very, very difficult for philosophers to arrive at the truth. Even Plato, that stalwart defender of the soul’s immortality, erred by saying that animal souls are immortal—the other side of Solomon’s “who knows”!46 Ecclesiastes 12:747 “The dust returns to the earth” means simply that the body disintegrates into ashes, in accord with Gen 3:19 and Sir 40:11. The spirit returns to God who gave it (Ps 32:15 Vg.); since God gave the spirit, the spirit gives back to God, like someone repaying a debt (2 Cor 5:10).48 It is interesting to note that while Murphy cites Gen 2:7, the creation account, Bonaventure looks to Gen 3:19, the curse after the fall.This fits with Bonaventure’s take on this part of Ecclesiastes.According to his division, this part treats of the “vanity of punishment,” and therefore deals 45 Bonaventure, 613–15. 46 Ibid., 615–16. 47 An important point arises in 9:4–10 which I would rather save for the last, so I will turn now to 12:7. 48 Ibid., 678–79. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 317 with death insofar as death is a punishment for sin—and I take it that he means original sin specifically. Already at 7:24, Solomon has been discussing the vanity of punishment, that is, the results of original sin, but up to 12:1 he was talking about punishment which is itself an occasion of sin, such as concupiscence. Here at last, after working slowly through the miseries of a fallen and sinful world which seems on every side to alienate man from his creator, Solomon finds a kind of punishment which actually calls us back to God:“Remember your creator in the days of your youth, before the time of affliction comes” Death is indeed a negative in Ecclesiastes, as Murphy concludes, yet there is this one redeeming aspect to it. Bonaventure also offers a spiritual interpretation of this passage:The “dust” refers to sinners, who are thrust into the “depths of infernal darkness” (this is a technical term, as will become clear below). He arrives at this interpretation by connecting “dust” to Ps 1:4 and “earth” to Prov 25:3.49 Ecclesiastes 9:4–1050 We go back now to the earlier passage. Here Solomon describes how men are led into a false sense of security because they do not see any providential difference between the fate of good men and the fate of evil men.This false sense of security then leads them into sin. First, he points out that no one can avoid death. Next, he describes how death puts one into a bad state. Lastly, he states the conclusion that would follow if indeed a man could not know whether what he does is pleasing to God, and whether there will be any reward for virtue. In the “questions” on this passage, Bonaventure asks how Solomon could draw such an Epicurean conclusion. If we take the passage as being said in the person of an Epicurean, the answer is easy, of course; but Bonaventure prefers to take it all in the voice of Solomon. He says that Solomon draws the conclusion as what would follow if these premises were true, namely that a man cannot know whether what he does is pleasing to God and whether there will be any reward for virtue. Solomon himself does not hold these premises, but he draws the conclusion as a hypothetical “If X were, then Y would be.”51 But what about the statement that “the dead know nothing any more”? Surely this is not what we believe? In the commentary on the passage, Bonaventure simply notes that the act of knowing presupposes 49 Ibid., 681. 50 Ibid., 655–56. 51 Ibid., 657–58. 318 Jeremy Holmes life, while the dead have neither life, nor motion, nor sense.52 In the “questions,” he says further that Solomon means that the dead did not know the things of this world, nor were they in the memory of those in the world, nor did they have any affection for things of this world.53 What may seem odd to a modern reader is that Bonaventure not only accepts these gloomy views as Solomon’s, but accepts them himself as fact. He does not say that men of Solomon’s time thought the dead do not know about the things of this world; he simply says that dead men did not know about the things of this world. His comment on v. 10 reveals that the past tense “did not” is the key. Commenting on the line, “For there is neither work, nor reason, nor knowledge, nor wisdom in the depth (inferos) to which you are going,” Bonaventure cites Job 10:22 to support the claim that “there is no reason there” in the “depth,” and then explains: “Sinners went there, and everyone before the coming of Christ, as regards the outer part”54 (emphasis added). Bonaventure is referring to the limbus patrum, the “limbo” or “outer part” of the patriarchs. One finds the basic idea in The Catechism of the Catholic Church: Scripture calls the abode of the dead, to which the dead Christ went down, “hell”—Sheol in Hebrew or Hades in Greek—because those who are there are deprived of the vision of God. Such is the case for all the dead, whether evil or righteous, while they await the redeemer: which does not mean that their lot is identical, as Jesus shows through the parable of the poor man Lazarus who was received into “Abraham’s bosom.” . . . Jesus did not descend into hell to deliver the damned, nor to destroy the hell of damnation, but to free the just who had gone before him.55 Before Christ’s death and resurrection, everyone without exception went to “Sheol,” or Hell. However, Sheol had several layers: Those who died in the state of grace went to the “outer part,” or limbus in Latin; those who died outside the state of grace went to the deepest part of Sheol, the “depth of infernal darkness,” as Bonaventure calls it. When Christ died and descended into Sheol, he did not free those in the deepest part, 52 Ibid., 655–56. “Mortui vero nihil noverunt amplius, quia cognitio supponit vitam: et ita praecellunt in actu cognitionis viventes mortuos; non enim habent, nec motum, nec sensum. . . . ‘Qui descenderit ad inferos, non ascendet, nec revertetur ultra ad domum suum, nec cognoscet eum amplius locus eius.’ [Job 7:9.]” 53 Ibid., 657. 54 Ibid., 656. 55 CCC, 633. Biblical Scholarship New and Old 319 where the damned reside, but rather those in the outer part. These he released and brought with him into heaven. This idea can be found in some passages of the New Testament, as in 1 Pet 3:18–19, 4:6, and John 5:25, while other passages merely hint at it, such as Phil 2:10.The early Christian authors Ignatius of Antioch, Justin Martyr, Irenaeus, and Tertullian pass it on, and the Church Fathers as well.56 Knowing that Bonaventure has the doctrine of the limbus patrum in the background helps to explain why he simply accepts Solomon’s gloomy views of the afterlife as fact. Truth be told, there was not much to be said for being dead before Christ came. The ancient idea of the underworld as a shadowy realm of gibbering half-men may well be the way things were.57 Concluding Reflections Looking back on the two commentaries we have surveyed, we see different strengths in each. Murphy seems to be more historically aware, so to speak: He stops to question whether “breath” or “spirit” really means the same thing as “spirit” does for us today. When Qoheleth says that the spirit returns to God, is he really talking about the soul’s relation to its creator? Murphy’s linguistic skills are another strength. While Bonaventure chose not to use much of the linguistic and textual-critical data available to him, Murphy devotes a special section (the “notes”) to such matters. With such careful attention to ancient thought and language, Murphy measures up well against the words of Vatican II: To rightly understand what the sacred author wished to assert in writing, one must give due attention both to the customary and native manners of perceiving, speaking, and narrating which were in force at the time of the hagiographer, and to the customs which were wont to be observed at that time in men’s dealings with one another.58 Bonaventure’s strength seems to lie in what one might call theological awareness. How do Ecclesiastes’ statements about death and the state of souls after death relate to what the New Testament teaches, or for that matter to what theological or philosophical arguments can demonstrate? How does this treatment of death relate to the revealed cause of death, 56 See the citations in Ludwig Ott, Fundamentals of Catholic Dogma, trans. Patrick Lynch (Rockford, IL:Tan, 1974), 192; see ABD 2:156. 57 See the gloomy biblical passages quoted in Paul Heinisch, The Theology of the Old Testament, trans.William G. Heidt, OSB (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1955), 280–81. 58 Dei Verbum 12; this and all other translations are my own. Jeremy Holmes 320 namely the fall of Adam? Bonaventure measures up well against the next line of the document just quoted: But, since Sacred Scripture must also be read and interpreted by the same Spirit by whom it was written, to rightly unearth the sense of the sacred texts one must attend no less diligently to the content and unity of the whole of Scripture, with account being taken of the living tradition of the Church and of the analogy of faith.59 Just as each commentator has particular strengths, so each commentator has particular weaknesses. Bonaventure’s heavily theological approach risks keeping Ecclesiastes on a leash, so to speak: In the attempt to fit Ecclesiastes into the analogy of faith, there is a danger that we will not allow the sacred text to challenge our way of thinking about the contents of that faith. But there is also a weakness in Murphy’s very historical approach. Perhaps the most striking difference between Bonaventure and Murphy is that the question of whether Ecclesiastes teaches truth or falsehood does not seem to occur to Murphy, while for Bonaventure it is a constant concern. For Bonaventure, if Ecclesiastes has a gloomy view of the afterlife, this has to be explained by reference to the limbus patrum; in fact, he has a special section of his commentary (the “questions”) devoted mainly to this sort of question. For Murphy, if Ecclesiastes teaches that there is nothing after death—well, then that is what the author thought, and an exegete’s job is to recover an accurate historical account of what the author thought. This is the danger peculiar to the historical-critical approach: to make history itself the goal rather than the means of interpretation. Historical considerations are necessary as a means of interpreting Scripture, and this is the great strength of modern efforts. But at the same time, one must keep firmly in view that the ultimate goal of using historical considerations in exegesis is not to discover history, not to discover merely what a historical individual historically thought, but rather to discover “the truth which God wished to be recorded in the Sacred Letters for the sake of our salvation.”60 N&V 59 Ibid. 60Ibid., 11:“Since therefore everything which the inspired authors or hagiographers asserted must be held to be asserted by the Holy Spirit, the books of Scripture must be confessed to teach firmly, faithfully, and without error the truth which God wished to be recorded in the Sacred Letters for the sake of our salvation.” Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 321–40 321 The Philosophical Category of “Faith” at the Origins of Modern Scepticism A NTONIO L IVI Pontificia Università Lateranense Rome, Italy Toward a New Interpretation of the Cartesian Novelty I T IS OFTEN SAID that modern philosophy represents a rupture with the whole of the preceding tradition, classical and Christian, mainly through the epistemic turn performed by René Descartes with the Discours de la méthode, launching the long process that leads to the primacy of the subject and to immanentism.1 This historiographic interpretation boasts a tradition of several decades and is supported by many qualified authors.2 I supported it myself more than once, always in connection with the historical developments in epistemology.3 Even so, upon closer consideration, this interpretation is not altogether satisfactory 1 Translated by Juan Francisco Franck. 2 Cf. Cornelio Fabro, Introduzione all’ateismo moderno, II ed., 2 vol. (Rome: Edizioni Studium, 1966); Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern Ideality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989). Referring to Fabro, and quoting his celebrated motto—“Incipit tragoedia moderna”—Ralph McInerny wrote recently: “Descartes famously sought the beginnings of certain knowledge its primary instances, as the result of the application of a method.The application of this method to the contents of his mind, the inventory of cognitive claims he and others would make, revealed them all to be dubitable.This means that every claim to know for certain has been shown to be mistaken. More precisely, all knowledge claims dependent on sense perception and all mathematical propositions are susceptible of doubt, it is imaginable or conceivable that they are false, and therefore they must be set aside. No one has any warrant simply to assert that he knows these to be true.” See “Implicit Philosophy,” in Sensus communis 3(2002): 56. 3 See A. Livi, Filosofia del senso comune: Logica della scienza e della fede (Milan: Ares, 1990); Il senso comune tra razionalismo e scetticismo:Vico, Reid, Jacobi, Moore (Milan: Massimo, 1992); Il principio di coerenza: Senso comune e logica epistemica (Rome: 322 Antonio Livi because it does not tell the whole truth.After having studied the ventures of modern epistemology in more depth (the developments of rationalism and of empiricism, their final stages in skepticism, criticism, and idealism), I became convinced that the rupture, which certainly exists, is not so much with medieval philosophy—even if the polemics against the Scholastic characterize the time of Renaissance humanism, up through Descartes himself—but with classical philosophy. We must indeed admit that the epistemological question, so essential to modern thought, revolves around the problem of certainty, and that the problem of certainty, as set out by Descartes and by all philosophers who follow his method, consists specifically in the attempt to determine the conditions of assent to what is not, or is not considered, self-evident. In other words, it is the problem of faith, understood precisely as the firm assent to what is not self-evident. Now this problem does not exist in classical Greek philosophy but is instead at the core of Christian thought. Christian revelation, with its novelty and speculative fecundity so well brought to light by Étienne Gilson in the thirties,4 has not only had a positive impact in philosophy at the level of metaphysical, anthropological, and ethical notions, but also at the level of logical notions, among which the most important is doubtless that of “faith.” It is here that, in my opinion, modern philosophy so radically differs from classical philosophy, whereas it is homogeneous with Christian–medieval philosophy.5 Therefore, the rupture with tradition produced by the Cartesian method must be considered within the Christian philosophical universe. This universe, in turn, is at the roots of the modern theoretical framework, distinctly different from the pre-Christian philosophical universe and not reducible to it. In this article I will examine an emblematic case, that of skepticism. My conviction is that the origins of modern skepticism are to be found in the hypothesis—induced from the typically Christian problem of faith—that what is essential lies beyond the immediate and that the certainty about the essential is reached after a long critical journey and with the decisive participation of an act of free choice. Modern Skepticism as Catholic Fideism Even if in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries skeptically oriented philosophers were called “Pyrrhonists,” thus recalling ancient skepticism, Armando, 1997); La filosofia e la sua storia, vol. II: La filosofia moderna (Rome: Società Editrice Dante Alighieri, 1999). 4 See Etienne Gilson, L’Esprit de la philosophie médiévale (Paris:Vrin, 1931–1932). 5 See A. Livi, Il cristianesimo nella filosofia: Il problema della filosofia cristiana nei suoi sviluppi storici e nelle prospettive attuali (L’Aquila: Japadre, 1969). The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 323 modern skepticism, having developed within Christian culture, is very different from its pre-Christian precursor, since the latter, as Brochard pointed out, never denies completely the metaphysical value of common sense.6 The new elements in modern skepticism have been brought to light by the historian Richard H. Popkin,7 who has examined philosophical thought in a specific moment of transition, the years 1500 to 1675. During these years the reappearance in Europe of the works of Sextus Empiricus provoked a renewed interest in Hellenistic skepticism, precisely when the discussion about the epistemological problems raised by the Reformation was most intense. The main epistemological problems raised by the Reformation were about individual conscience and subjective certainty about faith, but the problem of philosophy and in general that of reason outside the domain of Revelation, and the problem of the doctrinal authority of tradition and of the Magisterium were also raised. Simona Morini, summarizing Popkin’s research, remarks that “at the origin of modern thought and science there is not a conflict of science and faith in the first place, but a religious one, a problem within faith.”8 I agree with this interpretation; furthermore, I extend it to the whole philosophical venture that begins with the encounter between Greek thought and Christian faith, which has given birth to entirely new problems and solutions, in relation to pre-Christian classical times. In particular, in the general context of the influence of Christianity on philosophy, the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries represent the beginning of modern philosophy, characterized—always through the influence of Christianity—by the primacy of gnoseology. One typical trait of the period from the mid-1500s to the end of the 1600s is precisely the skepticism of a large part of Catholic philosophical thought, whereas Catholic theological thought strengthened its dogmatism. Both dimensions— skepticism in philosophy and dogmatism in theology—seem to come from the crisis of religious conscience, and, more particularly, from the heightening of the problem of certainty about the “truth that saves”: namely, its sources, the channels through which it is transmitted, the criteria of verification, and the space for freedom of interpretation. It is well-known that Luther, against whom Erasmus of Rotterdam argued, denied the authority of the Church, or of any human magisterium 6 See Victor Brochard, Les Sceptiques grecs, II ed. (Paris:Vrin, 1923), 413. 7 See Richard H. Popkin, History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes (New York: Assen, 1960). 8 Simona Marini, Introduzione to Richard H. Popkin, La storia dello scetticismo: Da Erasmo a Spinoza, Italian translation from the second English edition (Milan: Anabasi, 1995), 12. 324 Antonio Livi whatsoever, in interpreting the Scriptures. After Luther, then, Christianity faces the problem of the regula fidei”:What is the criterion by which one can identify the true doctrine of faith? The criterion of truth taken up by Lutherans was subjectivist and individualistic: For the believer only that is true which his conscience constrains him to believe from the reading of the Scriptures. Erasmus, on the contrary, considering the insurmountable difficulties in determining the true meaning of Scripture, embraced skeptical wisdom and advised trusting the apostolic succession (Tradition), submitting oneself to the interpretation given by the Church. In this sense, Erasmus can be seen as the founding father of a tradition of Christian–Catholic fideism that extends throughout modernity and eventually becomes the prevailing position in Catholic culture in postmodern times. After him, many “will use the skeptical argument to defend their own faith: in the absence of incontrovertible rational arguments in favor of one confession instead of another, why not trust faith or tradition?”9 Paradoxically, a significant number of Catholic thinkers argued against the Lutherans on their same ideological ground, marked by antidogmatism and irrationalism.10 However, it is Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) who expresses at the time of Erasmus the attitude of skeptical modern Catholics (the “nouveaux pyrrhoniens”) in all its radicalism. He writes that “man’s plague is the conceit of knowledge” and the only way we have to know ourselves is God’s Revelation:“Everything we see without the light of his grace is nothing but vanity and madness.”11 The priest Pierre Charron (1541–1603) and the bishop Jean-Pierre Camus (1530–1600) were followers of Montaigne.The former, in a book written immediately after the death of his teacher Montaigne, extolled “the marvellous beauty of the union between skepticism and Catholicism.”12 The latter, who was also secretary of the bishop Saint Francis of Sales, argues against “protestant rationalism” and tries to protect Catholic faith from the dangers of a conceited human reason. The best thing, in his opinion, is a faith that does not rely on human certainties, easy to be destroyed, since the only truths that men know are those which God wanted to reveal to us: “All 9 Armando Massarenti, “Il dogmatismo (non la religione) è il vero nemico,” Il Sole–24 Ore (February 26, 1995): 28. 10 See Ramón García de Haro, Historia teológica del modernismo (Pamplona: Eunsa, 1969); R. Popkin, “Fideism, Quietism, and Unbelief: Skepticism For and Against Religion in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries,” in ed. Marcus Hester, Faith, Reason, and Skepticism, (Pennsylvania, PA: Temple University Press, 1992). 11 Michel de Montaigne, Apologie de Raymonde Sebond, I, 3. 12 Pierre Charron, Les trois livres de la Sagesse, III, 1. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 325 the rest is nothing but dream, wind, smoke and opinion.”13 In France, Montaigne’s, Carron’s, and Camus’s skeptical perspective becomes in the first decades of the 1600s the philosophy of the “erudite libertines,” including Gabriel Naudé (Richelieu’s and Mazzarino’s librarian), Guy Patin (rector of the School of Medicine at the Sorbonne), Léonard Morandé (Richelieu’s secretary), Pierre Gassendi (the famous priest, scientist, and philosopher, who corresponded with Descartes), Isaac la Peyrère (secretary to the Prince of Condé), and François de la Mothe le Vayer, for whom “the soul of a Christian skeptic is like a field clear of weeds, devoid of the dangerous axioms that cram the minds of so many cultivated people, and therefore ready to receive the dew of divine grace with much more happiness than if it were still full of the presumption that it has certain knowledge of all things and no doubts of any sort.”14 Few succeeded in opposing the cultural hegemony of the “Pyrrhonian” Catholic intellectuals. The Jesuit François Garasse dared to stigmatize Charron’s “alleged piety,” calling it a “very bad service done to his Country and to his faith.”Another religious, François Ogier, replied to Garasse in an irritated way: “Charron’s works are too elevated for a low and vulgar mind like yours.” Even Saint-Cyran reacted violently against Garasse, and his criticism of the Jesuit was so insistent that the authority of the Sorbonne finally censured Garasse. Meanwhile, the work of the Portuguese Francisco Sánchez (1560–1632), published in Lyon in 1581 and, significantly, titled Quod nil scitur, was becoming popular.This work expressed for the first time the idea of a voluntary and systematic doubt,15 which certainly inspired Descartes for his Discours de la méthode. Apologetic Attempts and Skeptical Value of the Cartesian Method In his history of skepticism, Popkin describes Descartes as somebody who, while claiming to have “triumphed over skepticism,” remained substantially its prisoner, to the point of becoming a “sceptique malgré lui.”16 This interpretation, if correct, entails a clear characterization of rationalism in terms of skepticism. Rationalism, accordingly, would be much closer to British empiricism (Locke, Berkeley, Hume) than critics 13 Jean-Pierre Camus, Essay sceptique, I, 2, 3. 14 “Cinq dialogues à l’imitation des Anciens,” Frankfurt 1606, in Oeuvres. vol. 1 (Mons 1671), 275. 15 Francisco Sánchez, Quod nihil scitur, ad lectorem: “Ad me proinde memetipsum retuli, omniaque in dubium revocans, ac si a quopiam nil unquam dictum, res ipsas examinare coepi, qui verus est sciendi modus.” 16 See Popkin, History of Scepticism, chap. 10. 326 Antonio Livi usually say. Moreover, this interpretation would offer a better account of how the “critical” Kant could perform a synthesis between the rationalism inherited from Wolff and the empiricist stances coming from the reading of Hume. In short, the novelty of transcendental philosophy would have to be severely reassessed, in the sense that it would be evident that the true “Copernican revolution” was the one brought about, well before Kant, by René Descartes with his new method. The Cartesian method, implicitly based on an a priori choice, namely the choice to privilege the certainty of self-consciousness (the consciously exercised indubitability of doubt) over the certainty of the “things” present to consciousness, represents indeed a turn of prime importance in the history of philosophy. From then on, the history of philosophy presents all thinkers necessarily aligned for or against the new methodological starting point, for or against “Cartesianism.” It being a question of choice— as Del Noce justly observed—modern philosophy after Descartes has always been aligned either for or against this choice of making the “primum cognitum” a pretext for affirming the subject’s freedom, for releasing consciousness from every dependency on the object.17 As is known, for Martin Heidegger this is not the essential point of the turn Descartes inaugurated. For Heidegger, the essential point was rather shifting the focus from the question of truth to the question of certainty, or, in other words, giving up of the Greek notion of truth as manifestation of being (aletheia) and adopting instead the Scholastic notion of “conformity” of thought to the object (adaequatio intellectus ad rem), but exaggerating the subjective dimension: namely, the dimension in which the object of thought is not “being” but only the “representation” of being.18 I do not want to focus now on the concept of truth proposed by Heidegger, which is compatible with the concept of truth as conformity of the thought to its object;19 neither do I want to discuss here Heidegger’s interpretation of the Cartesian turn, regarding which I would refer to Messinese’s accurate historiographical and critical study.20 In my opinion, Descartes’s turn consists rather in the substitution of the certainties proper to the common sense—which refer to the indubitable presence of 17 See Augusto Del Noce, Cartesio (Bologna: Il Mulino, 1989). 18 See Martin Heidegger, Parmenides, trans. A. Schuwer and R. Rojcewicz (Bloom- ington: Indiana University Press, 1992); and Nietzsche, trans. D. F. Krell (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1979). 19 See A. Livi, La ricerca della verità: Dal senso comune alla dialettica (Rome: Leonardo da Vinci, 2001). 20 See Leonardo Messinese, Heidegger e la filosofia moderna: L’“inizio” della soggettività: Descartes (Milan: Mursia, 2000). The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 327 things in the world—with the certainty of the “cogito.” Cartesian “cogito” is nothing else but the doubt itself assumed as a limit that cannot be transcended, or, in gnosiological terms, thought without an object different from itself. So, even if the declared aim of Descartes’s philosophy was to overcome the skepticism of his time and to elaborate a new apologetics of Catholic faith,21 this aim finally turns out to be substantially frustrated. Skepticism remains the substance of the method adopted by Descartes, even if his skepticism and that of his followers are radically different from the ancient one. In fact, Descartes’s skepticism was born and developed in the context of problems related to faith in Revelation and its defense from rationalistic criticisms. It must be acknowledged that post Cartesian skepticism is truly a new form of skepticism, theorized above all by Catholic thinkers who have followed Descartes’s method. In this regard, the different view adopted by Giambattista Vico is very interesting because this Neapolitan thinker dialectically opposed Cartesianism by focusing, not on its final outcomes, but precisely on its methodological principles. We can and must admit without suspicion that Descartes was entirely sincere when he declared that the final aim of the Discourse on Method is to remake the whole building of science, “first philosophy” at its head, upon a new and most certain alethic foundation.22 The problem with his alethic foundation, that is, with the indubitability of thought in act (the “cogito”), is that it does not recover what has been hopelessly lost at the beginning with the hyperbolic doubt, namely the object of thought (as knowledge), which primarily consists (primum cognitum) in the reality of the world.The “cogito,” in fact, is thought closed in upon itself, a thought that remained “empty,” having expelled from itself, via the “volo dubitare de omnibus,” the reality of the object. Certainly, this thought in act, from the point of view of formal logic, appears as indubitable. However, considered in relation to its content, that is, from the point of view of material logic, the “cogito” is nothing else but the same doubt with which the Cartesian investigation has begun its journey; the same doubt that has excluded all possible certainty about the world and all other evidences of common sense, considering them incapable of adjusting themselves to the concept of evidence previously adopted by Descartes. For this reason, I admit that 21 “Not only the aim of the Cartesian doubt differs from the aim of the sceptical doubt, but its method is not the same either.” See E. Gilson, in René Descartes, Discours de la méthode (Texte et commentaire),VI ed., ed. Etienne Gilson (Paris:Vrin, 1925, 1987), 269. 22 Descartes, Discourse on Method, trans. D. A. Cress (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1980), (II, 15) 8:“My plan has never been more than to try to reform my own thoughts and to build upon a foundation which is completely my own.” 328 Antonio Livi Descartes sincerely (from a psychological point of view) set out to overcome skepticism in a rigorous and definitive way. But he actually continued to revolve within a skeptical logic, whose reasons he accepts and grants altogether. The novelty of his method to find the alethic foundation of knowledge lies precisely in the extreme radicalization of the skeptical stance, with the conscious (and voluntary) acceptance of doubt even from the foundations of knowledge, to the point of holding back the assent to the “primum cognitum.” The “hyperbolic” doubt is therefore the most explicit expression of skepticism as universal “epoché.” It suffices to think that the rules of public morality and the dogmas of catholic faith are only pragmatically secured, that is prescinding from its truth. Such truth could eventually be recovered in a second moment, but only as conclusions that dialectical reasoning obtains from the certainties resulting from the new method: namely, the certainty of the thinking self and the certainty of the existence of God as an innate idea. Let us recall how Descartes refers to the maxims of provisional morality and to the dogmas of catholic faith: After having assured myself of these maxims and having put them aside, along with the truths of the faith, which have always held first place in my set of beliefs, I judged that, as far as the rest of my opinions were concerned, I could freely undertake to rid myself of them.23 In these words the typical traits of “Catholic Pyrrhonism” are easy to recognize. Faith is separated from philosophical reason, in the sense that whereas faith means to profess certainty (only externally?) without any rational foundation, philosophical reason adopts as starting point the “doute hyperbolique.” I repeat that at the psychological level there is no difficulty in admitting that Descartes’s programmatic intention is actually that of finally overcoming the skeptical doubt. The fact is that, contrary to his good intentions, he will never be able to get out of a doubt that embraces the evidences of common sense.The new certainties are of a different kind, as are different the criterion of truth and the credentials that those certainties can exhibit (in fact, such certainties will be abandoned one by one by those modern thinkers who adopted the Cartesian method). Regarding sixteenth-century Catholic skepticism, which was more ideological than theoretical, the Cartesian method presents itself as the powerful and suggestive synthesis of two opposite stances: on the one hand, the deconstructive stance, which leads to the hyperbolic extension of doubt; on the other hand, the constructive stance, which leads to the 23 Descartes, Discourse on Method, (III, 29) 15. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 329 ambitious project of a total science based upon absolutely incontrovertible foundations.The possibility of uniting both opposed rational stances (which the Baroque defines as the humility or weakness of human reason, opposed to pride or self-consciousness of one’s own faculties) lies in having changed the place of the verification of truth from the domain of knowledge (relation of thought with the object extra mentem) to the domain of consciousness (relation of thought with itself as representation, in the immanence of the object in the mind).With the methodical doubt the immediate presence of extramental reality to consciousness is eliminated, and so for the first time in the history of philosophy all certainties of common sense are disqualified in their pretension to truth. They had been until then, for all philosophers—Greek and Christian, the certainties that had to be rightfully considered, from a logical point of view, the primary, absolutely incontrovertible self-evident truths. For the first time then, philosophy expresses an act of freedom of thought: which means that thought emancipates itself from the metaphysical presence of things, of the self, of God, and of the moral law.The Cartesian revolution changes the way of understanding alethic logic.The world and all other objects of experience—until then a starting point of absolute alethic value for philosophical reflection—become with Descartes precarious and provisional conclusions one can obtain starting from the “cogito,” considered as a founding certainty and model of truth in general. From then on, the itinerary of the mind, for those who accept the Cartesian method, is from the self to the world (with the mediation, for Descartes, of divine truthfulness), where the “self ” means thought in act, or thought as act (of “representing,” of “identifying” the object).24 Since we had previously mentioned the Catholic intellectuals (including clerics) who in the seventeenth century professed skepticism, we now want to point out that the Catholic Descartes, despite all his precautions, was finally subject to the condemnation of the Church, who could not help noticing that the Cartesian method, with regard to revealed dogma, implies the voluntary decision of doubting also faith, which for a Catholic equals to an act of apostasy. (In 1680 all Descartes’s works were 24 The language of scientists is still borrowed from that of the philosophers who continue to hold the Cartesian turn as necessary and irreversible. See among others the Italian philosopher Virgilio Melchiorre, from the Catholic University of Milan, who has recently written: “That philosophy has regenerated herself finding the own starting point in the certainty of the cogito, is to be understood firstly as an essentially methodological gain, rather than as an ontological one.” See Dialettica del senso: Percorsi di fenomenologia ontologica (Milan: Vita e Pensiero, 2002), 16). 330 Antonio Livi included in the Index librorum prohibitorum.) But what is more interesting for us is that from a specifically logical viewpoint Descartes doubts the certainties of common sense, which have a capital importance for faith, as they are its necessary premises. Indeed, it can be said that the logic of common sense is even more fundamental than the notional contents of common sense, which constitute the “praembula fidei.”25 This logic can be condensed in the modern philosophical formula of “realism,” understood as Gilson did, namely as “methodical realism,” that is as the only method that allows philosophy to be seen as a “search for the truth” about the world, man and God.26 Metaphysical realism is indeed faith’s own logic, insofar as divine revelation is addressed to man with a language that presupposes in him a true experience of the world and of himself, and that he knows God as different from the world, as the first Cause and the ultimate End of everything—and all this with his natural reason alone, even if “as through a mirror, and in mystery.” The Cogito as “Thought Without Object” We now have to analyze Descartes’s way of expressing his conviction of having overcome skepticism, even though he had begun with hyperbolic doubt; that is, with the discovery of the evidence his mind has of the doubt itself: “I think, therefore I am [ Je pense, donc je sui].” Let us read what he writes: And noticing that this truth—I think, therefore I am—was so firm and so certain that the most extravagant suppositions of the skeptics were unable to shake it, I judged that I could accept it without scruple as the first principle of the philosophy I was seeking.27 The doubt—here lies the force of the Cartesian argument—is thought in act, and as such it is indubitably present to consciousness (presence of thought to thought). However, since this act of thought is a doubt—that is, a holding back of the judgment about the hypothesis of knowledge— it cannot be the thought of something; it can only be the thought of nothing (of nothingness as object of thought, of nothingness as true). The 25 See, about these contents, what John Paul II teaches in the encyclical Fides et ratio; see A. Livi, “Filosofia e fede nella Fides et ratio: Un’analisi epistemologica,” in DT 95 (1999): 123–45; “Verità della fede e verità della ragione: Considerazioni di logica aletica in margine alla Fides et ratio,” in Aquinas 44 (2001): 175–97. 26 See E. Gilson, Le Réalisme méthodique (Paris: Ed.Téqui, 1935). See A. Livi, “Il realismo gnoseologico, oggi,” in Aquinas 40 (1997): 221–35; Maria Antonietta Mendosa, Un sentiero interrotto: l’impossibile esito realistico del “cogito” (Rome: Aracne, 2000). 27 Descartes, Discourse on Method, (IV, 32) 17. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 331 certainty of the cogito, therefore, does not refer to anything outside the mind (aliquid extra mentem), let alone the realities from which hyperbolic doubt had freed itself. As has been rightly observed, “the cogito is not an act of reflection, it does not consist in thinking of the thought—since this would require a mental word—but it consists directly in pure thought, free from every thought object.”28 If somebody were to object that this interpretation is arbitrary, one should answer that it is Descartes himself who validated it. Indeed, to the objection that “there is no thought without object” he replied: “I deny that the thinking substance is in need of anything other than itself in order to perform its own activity.”29 The concept of “empty thought” misses a characteristic of subjectivity that I highlighted elsewhere,30 and that had already been analyzed by Antonio Millán-Puelles,31 namely that the subject, properly speaking, is never to himself an immediate object of knowledge. The reason is that the (human) subject knows himself only by reflecting upon his own acts (especially thoughts and wishes), which have the material world as their proper object. The (human) subject, accordingly, knows directly not himself (i.e., the source of thought and free will) but an object of his own knowledge. In other words, the knowledge that the subject has of himself is a second intention knowledge attained by reflectively focusing on his acts of knowing the world—this is the logical order that must be respected in philosophy.32 Now, this feature of human self-knowledge does not prevent thought from being “full” rather than “empty.” Empty thought is postulated only when the thinking self (res cogitans) wants to make of the existence of his own thought the first certainty absolutely speaking, in place of the certainty of the existence of the world. But this “empty thought” makes the very notion of “subject” meaningless, as well as that of “knowledge.”33 As Rafael Corazón incisively observes,“as long as the thought focuses on something, on an object, self-consciousness is 28 Rafael Corazón, “Naturaleza de las ideas innatas cartesianas,” in Anuario filosófico 62 (1993): 49. 29 Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Ad II Obiectiones, Responsiones, in ed. C. Adam and P.Tannery, Oeuvres de Descartes: vol.VII (Paris: J.Vrin, 1964), 136. 30 See A. Livi, Filosofia del senso comune. 31 See Antonio Millán-Puelles, La estructura de la subjetividad (Madrid: Rialp, 1970). 32 See Thomas Aquinas, ST I, q. 87, aa. 1, 3. 33 On this point, see Alberto Caturelli, “Meditaciones sobre el sentido y el alcance del cogito cartesiano,” in ed. Juan Fernando Ortega and Marco Parmeggiani, Retorno crítico a los orígenes de la modernidad (Málaga: Contrastes, 1997), 123–44; D. Murdoch, “The Cartesian Circle,” in Philosophical Review 29 (1999): 234–45; A. Livi,“Verità e certezza nella dialettica cartesiana,” in Sensus communis 2 (2001): 263–75. 332 Antonio Livi impossible, because the subject is never object: Descartes seizes the act of thinking, not the thought being thought of [il pensiero pensato].”34 Corazón concludes his analysis of the cogito (which he locates in the doctrine of innate ideas) as follows: “If the cogito is indeed an act of self-consciousness, thought is immediately known, without reflection: consequently, there is no thought thinking itself [pensiero pensato], because what appears is only thinking thought [pensiero pensante].What is distinctive in this, as well as in the other innate ideas, is that they are not ideas as objects of thought, they do not lie ‘in front of ’ the thought.The reason is that, were they objects of thought, Descartes would have fallen again into the state of doubt; now, instead, he cannot absolutely doubt that he doubts, i.e. that he thinks.”35 It should be noticed that, unlike ancient skepticism, Descartes’s does not consist in extending doubt to the widest possible range of objects of knowledge, but in remaining within thought, having removed its object. If it is true that Descartes, in so doing, finds a most certain starting point, which is a judgment of existence (as alethic logic requires), it is also true that, unlike the concept of first judgment in ancient philosophy—that is, a judgment that allows for the research of an always wider and better knowledge, starting from a most certain knowledge, or a primum cognitum, with objective value—the Cartesian judgment is, strictly speaking, the elimination of knowledge. The logic of founding science on the cogito, then, turns out to be a complete epistemic rupture with the whole of classical tradition, above all pre-Christian one. As a French critic points out: “[I]n the dubito, or cogito, thought is grasped in a pure state, as gold after being purified from the slag. It is a first and absolute notion, because it is perceived independently of everything that is not itself. . . . It is a notion that presupposes none other before.”36 We are therefore completely immersed in the realm of a “logic of presupposition” to which I referred elsewhere as the foundation of alethic logic,37 and which consists in looking for the “first uncaused cause” of the cognitive process.This cause is, for Descartes, thought perceived as actual by the thinking subject. This is the authentic revolution in the 34 R. Corazón, 49–50. 35 R. Corazón, 51. For similar (and even more radical) criticisms to Descartes, see Leonardo Polo, Evidencia y realidad en Descartes, II ed. (Pamplona: Eunsa, 1983), 92–97, and Ferdinand Alquié, La Découverte métaphysique de l’homme chez Descartes (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1950), 185. 36 Jean Laporte, Le Rationalisme de Descartes (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1950), 17. 37 See A. Livi, Verità del pensiero: Fondamenti di logica aletica (Rome: Lateran University Press, 2002), 12–34. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 333 history of philosophy, the complete reversal of the logical order, starting from the self-evident perception of the self that comes before the selfevident existence of the world. And, since this self is understood as pure thought without the world as its object, it is empty thought nourished by its sole self-consciousness. Let us see again how Descartes’s argument goes: I will now close my eyes, I will stop my ears, I will turn away my senses from their objects, I will even efface from my consciousness all the images of corporeal things; or at least, because this can hardly be accomplished, I will consider them as empty and false; and thus, holding converse only with myself, and closely examining my nature, I will endeavor to obtain by degrees a more intimate and familiar knowledge of myself.38 When Descartes says that he “will consider empty and false” “all the images of corporeal things,” he makes a judgment of alethic value (or disvalue) about the immediate self-evident truth of the world. In this way, this truth is condemned to be insignificant, whereas the self-evident truth of thought (of an empty thought) is privileged. That this thought is empty results from a careful reading of a passage of the Meditationes de prima philosophia in which Descartes, arguing for the certainty of the self, makes recourse to the hypothesis of an evil genius: But there is some deceiver or other who is supremely powerful and supremely sly and who is always deliberating deceiving me. Then too there is no doubt that I exist, if he is deceiving me. And let him do his best at deception, he will never bring it about that I am nothing so long as I shall think that I am something.39 The key words in this text are “so long as I shall think.” Descartes is clearly referring to the act of thinking. It is thought in act that is selfevident to itself, that is always self-evident in and of itself, independently of its content, whatever it may be; even independently of having a content at all. Surely, in this first instance of knowledge, there is nothing but a certain clear and distinct perception of what I affirm.40 More explicitly:“I only perceive the fact of perceiving, that is the fact that I think.”The object of thought does not exist any more, or better it becomes irrelevant.Therefore, the doubt about the reality of the objects 38 Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, (III, 35) 24. 39 Ibid., (II, 25) 18. 40 Ibid., (III, 35) 24. Antonio Livi 334 of thought is not eradicated. The skeptical doubt, Descartes argues, may still remain, and the hypothesis of error and complete deceit may be admitted. In order to give the new science a foundation it is enough to be aware of doubting, of thinking in some way whatsoever. Yet I certainly do seem to see [certe videre videor], hear, and feel warmth. This cannot be false. Properly speaking, this is what in me is called “sensing.” But this, precisely so taken, is nothing other than thinking.41 Not without reason do many scholars speak of Descartes’s substantial “skepticism.”42 In fact, the undeniable reality of the thinking self does not solve any problem about the truth of our knowledge; it just makes the subject “certain” (that is, it compels the subject to assent due to the intrinsic self-evident perception thought has of its own act of thinking). This interpretation is confirmed by the studies of those who have qualified the cogito” as a mere deixis [deissi], that is, as something of a purely indicative nature [di indicalità pura], without any notional content, but with an exclusively pragmatic function. As Andrea Bonomi states, The first guaranteed certainty is only possible on the basis of an experience that each of us can and should personally have. In this sense, the whole demonstration can be seen as an invitation to have this experience. . . . The use (essential here) of the indexical “I” makes this argument pragmatic in a double sense: first, in the ordinary one, since it prompts an activity, a “doing something” (which is basically a becoming aware from a first-person viewpoint); and, second, in the sense in which one speaks of pragmatic as opposed to syntax and semantics, as the argument is centered around the indexical “I,” which allows one to denote each time a different subject.43 A further confirmation is the impossibility of moving from this individual subjective certainty to a universal criterion of certainty. A deep logical inconsistency immediately becomes manifest as soon as Descartes tries this step. Some have even spoken of an “ontological fall,” in the sense that the step from the deixis of the cogito to the ontology of sum looks like a realistic remainder Descartes probably inherited from the medieval Scholastics.44 41 Ibid., (II, 29) 20. 42 See Marjorie Grene, “Descartes and Skepticism,” in The Review of Metaphysics 89 (1999): 553–72. 43 Andrea Bonomi, “Sul Cogito cartesiano: natura inferenziale e criteri di giustifi- cabilità,” in ed. Gabriele Usberti, Problemi fondazionali nella teoria del significato (Florence: Leo Olschki, 1991), 27. 44 See Michel Henry, Généalogie de la psychanalyse: Le commencement perdu (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1985), 53–56. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 335 A New Concept of Truth as “Methodology of the Unverifiable” To conclude on this point, we should say that from a historical viewpoint great attention should be given to the reversal brought about in the concept of truth by the Cartesian revolution. Indeed, Descartes understands the truth of the cogito as merely indicale [indicative].The “I” which is grasped with complete certainty is not a substance, but the act of thinking: thought in act. Consider the following sentence: “But doubtless I did exist, if I persuaded myself of something.”45 This and similar expressions should be interpreted in the light of what Descartes says immediately afterward: I am, I exist—this is certain. But for how long? For as long as I am thinking; for perhaps it could also come to pass that if I were to cease all thinking I would then utterly cease to exist.46 As has been rightly observed, “the cogito is the paradigm of every truth, because if there is thought, there is necessarily a thinking subject. . . . It is not a matter of having a subject that is ‘thought of,’ or of having an idea of the subject. . . . The criterion is the facticity of the subject, its existence as a plain and empirical fact, so much so that the investigation of the nature of this subject comes subsequently, and is not included in the first self-evident knowledge. . . .The reflexive dimension of truth is substituted for in Descartes by self-consciousness, because in him, much more than in the philosophy before him, truth resides properly in the faculty of knowledge, since reality is never known.Truth in short is not conformity, but consists in the clarity and distinction of ideas, which allow the formulation of a judgment.”47 Using the same paradigm, the empiricist David Hume says that the simplest and most “vivid” sensations are those which deserve to be taken as “true,” even if they do not provide us with the knowledge of substances and of causal processes.48 The existence of the physical world is reached by Descartes only at the end of his new metaphysical construction. The world is admitted as a conclusion of a demonstration, which starts with the cogito and continues by deducing the existence of God from the innate idea of the infinite.This 45 Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, (II, 25) 18. 46 Ibid., (II, 27) 19. 47 R. Corazón, 54–55. 48 See, on this point, A. Livi, “L’uomo alla prova del metodo empirico,” in Nuntium 18 (2002): 152–60. Antonio Livi 336 long and winding way takes the world as “non self-evident.”49 It is unavoidable, therefore, that the certainty about the existence of the world, which depends on an unlikely and complex demonstrative process, turns out to be a “faith,” a “belief ” based upon the will to believe (in fact, William James in the twentieth century will speak of a will to believe). Among the Cartesians, David Hume was the first who called the belief about the existence of the world a “faith” (belief). Hume’s openly skeptical outcome brings to light the logic at the bottom of the Cartesian method, which we could define—borrowing the expression from Pietro Prini, who applied it to Gabriel Marcel—the “methodology of the unverifiable.”50 Unverifiable, in Descartes, is not, as in the Christian philosophy of the Fathers and of the Middle Ages, the supernatural mystery—that is, God, Who absolutely transcends the world, and demands faith in His revealing word. It is rather the world itself that experience can no longer verify, and which is—hypothetically, in a precarious way—reached via a sequence of logical arguments that, incidentally, involve concepts (like “causality”) that in turn presuppose the knowledge of the world.51 But it is the will to believe in the existence of the world (res extensa) that makes what in itself is unverifiable an object of “faith.” Precisely the same will sets in motion the deconstructive method of hyperbolic doubt (volo dubitare de omnibus), and, for Descartes, has a power of determination over the intellect: [T]he will is also required, in order that assent may be given to the thing which has been perceived in some way. Moreover, complete perception of the thing is not required, at least not in order to judge [it] in some way or another; for we can assent to many things which we know only very obscurely and confusedly.52 Many interpreters of Descartes oppose demonstrative reason, which confirms the existence of the world, to faith, which in no way is able to 49 “The primordial and founding certainty, universally accepted by common sense—that is, the certainty of the existence of the visible world, made of matter—becomes problematic, and must be recovered by means of a complex reasoning, which is only possible at the end of the philosophical itinerary” See Salvatore Nicolosi, in ed. Angela Ales Bello, Pensare Dio a Gerusalemme (Milan: Mursia, 2000), 186. 50 See Pietro Prini, Gabriel Marcel o la metodologia dell’inverificabile (Rome: Studium, 1968). 51 See A. Livi, Il principio di coerenza, 55–65. 52 Descartes, Principles of Philosophy, trans. V. Rodger and R. P. Miller (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1939), (I, 34) 16. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 337 confirm the existence of what has been revealed through supernatural mysteries.53 In reality, Descartes does not distinguish between demonstrative reason and faith, but assumes as the paradigm of “pure” or “separated” philosophy precisely what should only appertain to faith, namely the certainty of what is not self-evident.54 Cartesianism at the Center of the Debate on Faith and Reason in France After Descartes, the fortune of Cartesianism and anti-Cartesianism in France—related also to Spinoza’s and Leibniz’s philosophies—shows how rooted the persuasion was that philosophy should be confronted in the first place with faith: a confrontation that should take place in the field of the certainty of what is not self-evident. The results of this confrontation are called “dogmatism” (or rationalism), on the one hand, and “neopyrrhonism,” on the other.These two approaches both assume the Cartesian non-self-evident truth of the sensible world, replaced by the equally Cartesian self-evident truth of (empty) thought.55 An attempt to open new critical horizons can be seen in Blaise Pascal’s (1623–1662) apologetic project. Pascal understood very well that the non-self-evident truth of the world was such only if one assumed deductive demonstration as the paradigm of rationality. We should recall the famous “thought” in which Pascal tries to distinguish the intuitive function from the discursive function (calling the former “heart,” and leaving the term “reason” to the latter): We know truth, not only by the reason, but also by the heart, and it is in this last way that we know first principles; and reason, which has no part in it, tries in vain to impugn them. The skeptics, who have only this for their object, labour to no purpose. We know that we do not dream. And however impossible it is for us to prove it by reason, this inability demonstrates only the weakness of our reason, but not, as they affirm, the uncertainty of all our knowledge. For the knowledge of first 53 See Jean-Pierre Deschepper, “Comptes-rendus” in RPL 89 (2001): 758: “The strict delimitation of the comprehensible of first philosophy, regarding the incomprehensible of faith, opens the field of philosophy to the sole reason.” 54 See Thomas C. Vinci, Cartesian Truth (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); André Robinet, Descartes, la lumière naturelle: Intuition, disposition, complexion (Paris: Vrin, 1999). 55 See, e.g., the arguments adopted by each party in two famous controversies: that of Geulincx against Spinoza (see Bernard Rousset, Geulincx entre Descartes et Spinoza [Paris: Vrin, 1999]); and that of Arnauld against Malebranche (see, Denis Moreau, Deux cartésiens: la polémique entre Antoine Arnauld et Nicolas Malebranche [Paris:Vrin, 1999]). Antonio Livi 338 principles, as space, time, motion, number, is as sure as any of those which we get from reasoning.And reason must trust these intuitions of the heart, and must base on them every argument.56 It is clear from this and many other passages that Pascal tried to give a new foundation to apologetics starting from the recognition of a “minimum” of natural, prescientific cognoscibility of reality, thus indicating to French philosophy of his time the way out of the false dilemma rationalism skepticism. Pascal proposes an attitude of trust in reason that may overcome skepticism, but without pretending to possess truth always and indubitably. He writes in another fragment:“This is our true state; this is what makes us incapable of certain knowledge and of absolute ignorance.”57 But it is also clear that Pascal’s attempt was not able to succeed fully, due to the impossibility of avoiding, in his historical circumstances, the language and therefore the logical categories employed by Descartes.58 No wonder then if we find as well in the Pensées clearly fideistic claims (selected and quoted later on by all those who, along the centuries, preferred to read Pascal as a fideist). For example: “Man is only a subject full of error, natural and ineffaceable, without grace. Nothing shows him the truth. Everything deceives him.”59 The unity of the human intellect in its two different but not conflicting functions of intellectus and ratio was still in need of being recovered. In this environment, and shortly afterward, a first outline of a philosophy of common sense came from the Jesuit Charles Buffier (1661–1737), who inspired the philosophy of Thomas Reid (1710–1796) and the Scottish School with his Traité des premières vérités et de la source de nos jugements, and who is still studied today with interest by those who look for a way out of fideism.60 But in those years in France, neither Buffier nor any other Catholic intellectual could contain the rising tide of fideism, which many theologians and clerics saw as the sole alternative to Cartesian rationalism and to the persistent attempts by Cartesians to rationalize Christian faith. Among Protestants, too (both Lutherans and Calvinists), fideism was the prevailing position; and philosophical skepticism seemed to be the only possible option for Christian believers. 56 Pascal, Thoughts, trans.W. F.Trotter (New York: P. F. Collier & Son, 1910), no. 282. 57 Ibid., no. 72. 58 See, A. Livi, Il senso comune tra razionalismo e scetticismo, 50–55. 59 Pascal, Thoughts, no. 83. 60 See Louise Marcil-Lacoste, Claude Buffier and Thomas Reid:Two Common-Sense Philo- sophers (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University, 1982); R. McInerny, “Implicit Philosophy,” 47–65. The Philosophical Category of “Faith” 339 Indeed, this was the opinion expressed by Pierre Bayle (1647–1706) in his famous Dictionnaire historique et critique, first published in Rotterdam (1695–1697) and then in Amsterdam (1702). On the Catholic side, Pierre-Daniel Huët’s work (1630–1721) is emblematic. He was bishop of Avranches and a great friend of two other important ecclesiastics, Bossuet and Fénelon.61 Huët, who corresponded also with Leibniz, is known for having started his philosophical production as a Cartesian and for having ended up as an anti-Cartesian, by publishing in 1689 his renowned Censura philosophiae cartesianae. In reality, both at the beginning and at the end, the bishop of Avranches reasons according to the skeptical assumptions present in the Cartesian method, even though his primary source is Gassendi. In Huët’s apologetic work, “the question at stake was the preliminary role that reason should have in the act of adhesion to faith. Huët was convinced that Cartesian reason, instead of being ‘auxilium fidei,’ constitutes a hardly surmountable obstacle. . . . In reassessing the boundaries between faith and reason, it was necessary to bring that ‘superbe raison’ back. . . . to the limitations of its own constitutive weakness, so that it could accept sua sponte the submission to revealed truth. Skepticism seemed to be a suitable instrument for that end, because it was able to show reason’s insufficiency already in the natural sphere. . . .The originality of Huët’s strategy was in this apologetic use of classical skepticism, reread and modernized through elements taken from Gassendi, and from Cartesian philosophy as well. Of the latter, Huët stressed its Pyrrhonist outcomes, thus attacking the Cartesian pretension of the self-evident [truth of the cogito], showing that it is impossible to reach it in any domain, and justifying at the same time the need of returning to tradition and authority.”62 This is how Huët’s argument proceeds. In his Traité philosophique de la faiblesse de l’entendement humain he holds that philosophy is the “search for truth” but is unable to reach some truths with certainty; philosophy must thus yield the way to faith.“Man cannot know the truth with perfect certainty if he relies upon his Reason alone,” because the senses deceive us, the intellect is fallible, and self-evident truth itself is frequently deceitful. For all these reasons we must admit that human reason is not capable of “true knowledge,” insofar it lacks a “certain rule of the truth,” that is, a procedure that would allow to distinguish truth from falsity in a definite way.63 61 See Elena Rapetti’s recent historiographic study, “L’epistolario di Pierre-Daniel Huet e la filosofia cartesiana,” in Rivista di filosofia neo-scolastica 93 (2001): 257–79. 62 E. Rapetti, 266–67. 63 Pierre-Daniel Huët, Traité philosophique de la faiblesse de l’entendement humain (Amsterdam: Henry du Sauzet, 1723), 234. 340 Antonio Livi The Traité philosophique came out in 1723, after Huët’s death.The Jesuit Baltus published a commentary in 1726, recognizing that the cultured bishop was motivated by the good intention of humiliating human reason—so prone to pride—by inducing it to submit itself again to the authority of Tradition. However, Baltus points out, Huët tended to grant too much to the stances of the “nouveaux Pyrrhonisme.”64 It is true—as Elena Rapetti rightly observes—that “Huët’s apologetic work can be read as the history of a long battle against Cartesian self-evident [truth of the cogito], in the name of the certainty of faith and of the reassessment of the historical facts in which Huët saw the foundation of Revelation.”65 It is true too that such reassessment of the historical facts related to Christian revelation is absolutely necessary, and deserved a better reception by Christian theologians and philosophers—who, due to the popularity of rationalism in the interpretation of Christianity (particularly after Lessing and Kant), preferred to follow instead other paths.66 However, it is also true that the discussion opposing rationalism to skepticism should have been overcome by bringing it back to its source; that is, by means of a radical criticism of Cartesian method and its assumptions, thus allowing for the recovery of the epistemic foundations of every truth in the incontrovertible self-evident truth of the existence of the world. Such a foundation is only implicit in Saint Thomas’s philosophy, because nobody, in ancient Greek and Christian thought, nor in Christian medieval culture, had yet formulated the philosophical hypothesis of denying the selfevident truth of the existence of the world as the starting point of metaphysics. But it is precisely by going back to Thomas’s method that many philosophers of the twentieth century have been able to oppose postCartesian immanentism with a valid realist theory, capable of resisting the criticism of dogmatism and ingenuity that Descartes’s heirs have always addressed against it.67 N&V 64 See Jean-François Baltus,“Sentiment sur le Traité de la faiblesse de l’esprit humain à M. l’Abbé d’Olivet, de l’Académie Françoise,” in Continuation des Mémoires de Litterature et della’Histoire de M de Salangre, 1(1726), part I, 220. 65 E. Rapetti, 279. 66 On the historical dimension of faith, see A. Livi, La ricerca della verità: Dal senso comune alla dialettica (Rome: Leonardo da Vinci, 2001), 170–79. 67 See Fortunato Tito Arecchi, “Truth and certitude in the scientific language,” in ed. F. Schweitzer, Self Organization of Complex Structures—From Individual to Collective Dynamics (London: Gordon and Breach, 1996), 3–20; A. Livi, Tommaso d’Aquino: il futuro del pensiero cristiano (Milan: Mondadori, 1997); Il realismo come metodo necessario della metafisica: Riflessioni sul pensiero di Etienne Gilson, in ed. Horst Seidl, Realismus als philosophisches Problem (Hildesheim: Olms, 2000), 131–38. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 341–58 341 An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory* S ERVAIS P INCKAERS, OP University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland I T WILL SOON be five years [at the time of writing in 2001] since Cardinal Jean-Jérôme Hamer left us. He had written in his spiritual testament,“I die in communion with the Church, in loving obedience to the Holy Father, in faithfulness to the Order of St. Dominic, of which I am a member and to which I owe much.” Before becoming Secretary of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, he had been professor of dogma at the Dominican Houses of Studies of La Sarte at Huy in Belgium and of the Saulchoir at Étiolles in France.We should recall here that one of the ways Cardinal Hamer’s devotion to the Church showed itself was in the debates about the July 1968 encyclical Humanae Vitae, which divided Catholic moralists, and in the discussions concerning the existence and content of a Christian moral doctrine being developed at the time. To clarify the problems, the cardinal took an intelligent and broadly conceived initiative; he organized a symposium in Rome, from March 22 to March 28, 1981, which gathered together the most competent Catholic moralists to deal with the widely debated question of the existence of universal . . . unchangeable moral laws that apply without exception. These moralists represented the different opinions then current. For the sake of the discussion, they were divided into “classicists” and “innovators.” Each one could express himself freely in the report expected of him, and in the linguistic group discussions as well as in the general assembly. In organizing the symposium, care was taken to broaden the field of inquiry for the moralists by consulting, with the help of exegetes, Sacred * Translation by Robert E.Williams, SSI of “Un Symposium de Morale Inconnu,” Nova et Vetera 77 (2001): 19–34. 342 Servais Pinckaers, OP Scripture, all too absent from moral manuals, and also by examining the thought of the Fathers of the Church and the medieval theologians, especially Thomas Aquinas.They took philosophy and the social sciences into consideration and, more especially, they dealt with the Magisterium’s role in moral questions. Finally, they put the New or Evangelical Law, too often ignored by moralists, at the forefront of their consideration. The fruits of the symposium were brought forth in later years. It was, in fact, a distant preparation for the encyclical Veritatis Splendor (August 6, 1993), which took up the same problems dealt with at the symposium, and we can easily recognize the influence of the symposium on the moral section of the Catechism of the Catholic Church published in 1992. The symposium reports appeared in two publications. The Germanic group took the initiative of publishing the papers of the mostly “innovator” camp in Sittliche Normen,1 edited by Walter Kerber. We ourselves published, in French, the other reports, whether “classic” or “innovator,” in Universalité et permanence des Lois morales,2 edited by Servais Pinckaers and C.-J. Pinto de Oliveira, which follows the outline of the symposium. The names of most of those who took part in the symposium can be found in these two works. As evidence of my gratitude to Cardinal Hamer, I am publishing here the symposium’s concluding report, which I drew up. It will help the reader appreciate the interest of the debates that were held there, both in the presentations and in the discussions. An Overview of the Symposium on Moral Theology (March 22–28, 1981) Introduction: General Assessment The symposium was a success in its genre, for it presented a real opportunity for meetings and exchanges among participants of different disciplines and schools on the subjects of fundamental moral theology, which is uncommon. It likewise established a good contact between the members of the congregation (for the Doctrine of the Faith) and theologians of diverse tendencies, which is not so frequent.The symposium also allowed for a certain clarification of problems and positions by getting to know people and through the points made in the debates. We must keep in mind, however, the inevitable limitations of such an interdisciplinary and interscholastic undertaking, especially when people 1 Walter Kerber, ed., Sittliche Normen (Düsseldorf: Patmos Verlag, 1982). 2 Servais Pincakers and C.-J. Pinto de Oliveira, eds., Universalité et permanence des Lois morales (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires; Paris: Cerf, 1986). An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 343 are meeting for the first time and within a limited timeframe.We should not confuse a symposium with a working group. If it wants to be effective, a working group must gather together persons sufficiently alike in their disciplines, methods, leanings, and views to form a coordinated team. A symposium offers the advantage of assembling persons whose disciplines, tendencies, origins, and opinions are different if not contradictory. It cannot claim to further a project, as would a team, but it can advantageously contribute useful information about the various problems and positions to clear up misunderstandings, to create agreement and collaboration, and to uncover new aspects, just as it brings to light the differences. In a word, it can help one see a problem as a whole and get a better view of trends. In this sense the symposium was a success, as seen in the assessments made by the three groups that composed it. The study of moral problems proposed to us would have had to have to proceeded by way of personal effort or teamwork to have arrived at clear and solid positions, if possible. It could be able to draw much material from the acts of the symposium.We must not forget the hidden work that always takes place when men meet in a climate of free and frank discussion. The Unfolding of the Symposium To assess correctly the results and documents of the symposium we must be aware of the fact that it unfolded in three stages. First, before the symposium, the participants sent in preparatory reports following the outline and subjects proposed by the steering committee, which were summarized in three categories: summaries sent to all; a digest of the issues for the steering committee; and lastly, a synthesis that served as an introduction to the symposium.These preparatory reports formed a necessary foundation and first approach for the symposium but did not yet entail any dialogue among the participants, which explains their limitations. The second stage consisted of the unfolding of the first part of the symposium, with its introductions, group discussions, and discussions in general assembly. The most interesting texts of this central stage are the reports of introduction to the sectors and the brief presentation of reports, which were able to take advantage of exchanges with a greater concentration on the issues of the symposium. They have the advantage of being more thought out and better written than accounts of the discussions in which interventions are at minimum length and which depend upon the give and take of exchanges. To them must be added certain longer interventions written throughout the symposium. The third stage consisted of responses to the questionnaire proposed for the last two days of the symposium.We have to keep in mind that we are 344 Servais Pinckaers, OP dealing here with a group effort written within a limited timeframe. It had the advantage of forcing the groups to indicate their reactions to the different aspects of the problem of intrinsece malum, as the classical language of the manuals puts it. But the short time available did not allow for a deep or very exact elaboration of the answers.The divergences within linguistic groups slowed the work. Also, certain participants could have formulated personal answers that would have been more complete, more precise, and different from those of the groups to which they belonged. The Germanic group experienced a particular division that concerned a fundamental problem.The Italian group split on most points.As for the French group, it wound up with two parallel, rather than opposed, texts. In conclusion, the substance of the symposium is to be found in the preparatory reports completed and clarified by the first part of the symposium. The responses to the questionnaire come as a complement and provide certain information of their own. Outline of a Synthesis We shall divide this attempt at synthesis into three headings: 1. The question of the relation between, on the one hand, Scripture, the patristic and theological tradition with the teachings of the New Law, and, on the other, current moral problems regarding norms and intrinsically evil acts, which brings in biblical scholars, patrology experts, and moral theologians. 2. The problem of unchangeable universal laws and objective judgment, or the intrinsece malum in moral discussions. 3. The question of the Magisterium’s intervention in moral questions. The Question of the Relations between Scripture, Patristic and Theological Tradition, and Current Research in Moral Theology Two general observations emerge from the unfolding of the symposium: 1. The realization of the gulf existing between biblical scholars, patristic experts, et cetera, and moralists. At the end of the first day, after the presentations on Scripture, several moralists expressed their impatience to get to what they thought was the real problem under consideration, as if they deemed that the exegetes and patristic scholars could hardly present them with something important or with something they did not already know. By contrast, on the third day during the moralists’ presentations and discussions, the other participants thought they were being completely sidelined by issues and by a technical language they could not penetrate. An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 345 2. After the exegetes and moralists had made their presentations on the New Law on the fourth day, we could notice a rather general satisfaction, expressed especially by the German-speaking moralists. It was evident that the theme of the New Law, drawn from the Gospel and the theological tradition, offered a broader perspective, and one that was better founded on Scripture, to serve as the basis for a renewed moral theology and a richer Christian anthropology. Thus, beyond the divisions and gulfs we had observed, there emerged, at least on the horizon, a point of agreement and unification that would likely steer further research and efforts. The criticisms voiced concerning the questionnaire of the last two days bore precisely on the fact that it seemed to forsake the perspectives the presentations on the New Law had opened and to confine the symposium once more within the narrower framework of traditional casuistry. Here then is the situation:A real separation exists between the biblical scholars and the moralists discussing the problems submitted to the symposium on the issues and on the technical language. However, there is a possible meeting point on the teaching of Evangelical Law, which is both scriptural and theological.To this encouraging observation we may add the favorable assessments voiced by the different groups, stating that one of the major interests for them was the interdisciplinary work accomplished together and the wish that it continue. Nevertheless, many questions remain. Let us look at things from the biblical scholars’ viewpoint.The reports dealing with Scripture agreed in affirming that there are unchangeable moral laws and that these were ordered, each in its own way, to Evangelical Law.The same goes, generally, for the presentations on the Fathers and the medieval theologians, whose thought was nourished by Scripture but with the constant and explicit use of the natural law. We should note, however, that the presentations of the biblical and patristic scholars, unlike those that dealt with St. Thomas and later Scholasticism, received hardly any attention from the moralists, apparently because they did not address their problems sufficiently.The discussions among moralists only took into consideration Schürmann’s contribution dealing with current topics. Obviously the biblical scholars can retort that the categories the moralists use are not found in Scripture, or in the Fathers for that matter.They can reproach the moralists with elaborating their theories on a purely rational level without, in practice, feeling the need to refer to the Bible unless incidentally. Even if in principle they admit the importance of Scripture as the primary source of moral theory, in fact they take scarcely any 346 Servais Pinckaers, OP account of it in the method they use, in their research, their discussions, their presentations. On the other hand, we can ask ourselves if the biblical scholars themselves do not employ certain categories and adopt certain positions borrowed from the moralists without critiquing them sufficiently, without, in particular, examining them to see if they agree with the givens of Scripture. For example, these categories are often taken over from the morality of obligation, which sets aside the question of beatitude, wisdom literature, et cetera, only to concern itself with commands.We may also add that up to now Catholic biblical scholars have busied themselves very little with scriptural morality. Likewise we must say that certain exegetes are well aware of the concrete problems raised in the symposium and hope to be able to provide answers to them based on Scripture. There remain different questions about the New Law and its relation to the Sermon on the Mount. Is the expression “New Law” adequate, especially as regards chapters 5 to 7 of St. Matthew? Besides the manifold interpretations of the Sermon, which we could not get into, and the question of its attribution to Jesus Himself, largely admitted by Monsignor Descamps, we may ask ourselves how far we should give a privileged place to this text. In this regard, let us point out that the Fathers’ reading of Scripture is unifying, for they see the Spirit as its principal Author. In their thought, then, the Sermon must not be taken in isolation but as a text calling for all other scriptural texts that deal with Christian morals, notably the passages where St. Paul describes living according to the Spirit. If we look at the problems of Scripture and the New Law from the standpoint of the moralists, it is appropriate that we distinguish the different positions among them. If we wish to employ the distinction between “classicists” and “innovators,” we should note a division among the former, which gives us three tendencies: 1. The tendency we might call post-Tridentine, in line with the moral manuals, for which the natural law is the basis of morality, with reason as its main source. 2. The tendency, inspired by Thomistic thought (in the German sense of “thomanisch”), which has rediscovered the primary importance in moral theology of Evangelical Law’s teaching, and tries to make Scripture’s leading role as the source of morality a reality again. 3. The so-called innovating tendency has taken a critical position in regard to the first classical one and usually operates on a very rational and technical level, but is interested in the current re-reading of St. Thomas and by the re-appreciation of Evangelical Law. An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 347 Attitudes toward Scripture and biblical scholars differ. The first tendency questions whether Scripture, as well as the Fathers, can bring anything new and solid to the solution of the moral cases under discussion, especially if we consider the multiplicity of interpretations among exegetes, patristic scholars, and historians. Also, its ultimate and surest reference point lies in the stances taken by the Church’s Magisterium. The second tendency insists upon a direct return to Scripture and the Patristic Tradition as sources of a renewed Christian morality. It seeks to establish a dialogue with the biblical scholars but wants to include in it the reading of Scripture done by the Fathers and the great theologians, which is rich in spiritual substance and experience.The third tendency is more attentive to Scripture and exegesis than it had been but it mistrusts any reading that might seem fundamentalist; it does not wish to get into Scripture without a hermeneutical reflection. However, this last requirement poses a serious question: Does not a hermeneutics, relying on rational criteria often elaborated a priori, risk setting up a distorting screen between the Bible and the reader and preventing the Word of God, with its power of truth, from reaching the moralist as well as the exegete himself? Hence we find ourselves presented with a fundamental problem of universal importance, the relationship between Scripture and moral theory, as well as with a hope felt during the symposium, that an interdisciplinary endeavor of collaboration among biblical scholars, patristic scholars, and moralists might be promoted.There is likewise the question of the renewal of Catholic moral theory with the help of the principles of Evangelical Law. The Discussion on Moral Laws (Universality, Immutability, Objectivity of Judgment) and the Existence of Intrinsically Evil Acts This is the core of the debate for the moralists, as well as the main preoccupation of the Congregation that organized the symposium. As we pointed out in the introductory synthesis, the reports and the discussion presupposed the Magisterium’s pronouncements, especially the encyclical Humanae Vitae and the declaration of the Congregation on the problems of sexuality, the classical teaching of the manuals on the fontes moralitatis, the theory of intrinsece malum and the cause with double effect elaborated therein, and the debates of the last years with the theory of “consequentialism,” in which the teleological perspective and the criterion of proportionate reason are dominant. Throughout the reports, the discussions, the fine-tuning, the drawing closer, and the differentiations, two currents of thought and two positions showed up that we might describe in broad outline as follows. 348 Servais Pinckaers, OP The so-called “innovator” school of thought is critical of the theory of the intrinsece malum and has worked out a precise stance on the problem by means of several distinctions. First, there is the distinction between transcendental norms—which deal with principles—and categorial norms—which it divides into categorial norms (still formal) focusing on the virtues and concrete and material norms that focus on single acts.To this it adds a distinction between the proper moral goodness of the action (the personal-formal aspect, sittliche Gutheit) and the rightness of the action (the objective-material aspect, Richtigkeit). The question under discussion about the intrinsece malum would in fact concern the concrete norms, the realm of rightness, of Richtigkeit.This school fully admits the existence of intrinsically evil acts in the realm of transcendental norms and formal categorials, on the level of personal moral qualities (being unjust, a liar, unchaste), but it questions whether we are able to find and formulate universal and unchanging norms on the level of concrete actions taken in their materiality. Let us make clear that here we are talking about negative norms that forbid an act as evil in itself, and, moreover, that the debate is at the level of human relations. The classic moralists based their judgment of acts mainly on a consideration of the object, while integrating into it the finis operis (inherent in the action), and thought of circumstances and the finis agentis (the goal of the one acting) as secondary, accidental elements. Unlike the classicists, the new school deems it necessary to take into consideration all the circumstances (as components of the action), including its historical evolution, that enter into the composition and situation of the act, and it especially stresses the importance of finality. This school considers the reasons of a deontological nature put forward by the classical moralists in support of the doctrine of the intrinsece malum as outmoded, and takes a mainly teleological view focused above all on the evaluation of the act’s consequences in order to determine its rightness.This is where the criterion of proportionate reason comes in. From this standpoint, the formulation of a concrete and unchanging norm becomes more difficult, for theoretically it presupposes a taking into account and an examination of all the possible consequences and all the potential finalities. Thus they would say that concrete norms of this sort are certainly universal, that they have value and are applicable ut in pluribus in most cases, but without excluding possible exceptions, especially if we keep in mind differences in culture. During the exchanges, those with critical leanings made an attempt to close the gap: We may entertain the possibility of an intrinsece malum act from a teleological standpoint when one good or one value clearly over- An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 349 rides any other, but that cannot happen easily. We recognize also that there are actions that can never be justified in practice, such as torture. This closing of the gap corresponds to the tendency of the “innovator” group to show that the differences are not as great as they seem.Yet this way of thinking did not convince the representatives of the other school of thought. We should add that the “innovating” trend of thought shows a particular interest in St. Thomas, who provides support for the teleological outlook, and for the phrase that laws are valid ut in pluribus. He likewise sheds light on the rich doctrine of the New Law and, lastly, gives grounds for a critique of the morality of the manuals.This school is also sensitive to how Christian morals are presented to the world of non-believers and to the data furnished by the social sciences. Against the innovating trend, there is a certain convergence of the criticisms leveled at it, which argue for the existence of concrete norms and of intrinsically evil acts, whatever expression is used to designate them (the expression intrinsece malum dates from the time of Suárez).These criticisms often presuppose knowledge of the problem and of the debates that go beyond the data provided to the symposium. First, there is the position of Monsignor Hörmann in regard to Father Fuchs. He uses the latter’s categories but relates them to St.Thomas: If it is true that, along with the object, we must also consider the circumstances and the intention in order to establish the Richtigkeit, the rightness of a concrete act, nevertheless a defect in one of these elements, for example, in the object by itself, is enough to render the act unrichtig (not right) and to set up an unchangeable negative norm (bonum ex integra causa, malum ex quocumque defectu). Obviously we have here a fundamental point.Yet we must add that the term “object” must not be taken too narrowly but may include the main circumstances to make up the substance of the act.The judgment of Unrichtigkeit would change if these elements were modified. Hence we really must agree on terminology. This narrows the gap with Father Fuchs, but is there any reality behind the words used? The sharpest criticisms focused on the distinction between transcendental norms and formal categorials, and concrete and material norms, between moral and premoral goods, between moral goodness and “rightness.”To be more precise, the criticism targets the too-great separation caused by these distinctions: On the one hand, without any direct intervention of so-called formal norms, Richtigkeit, judgment and norms in the concrete, are established by looking at all the circumstances from a teleological and consequentialist angle, which makes the establishment of 350 Servais Pinckaers, OP universal and unchanging concrete norms very problematic; on the other hand, the so-called formal, transcendent, and categorial norms (the theological and moral virtues, among others), which continue to be seen as abstract norms, find themselves deprived of the ability to be applied in the concrete and to be valued for their truly practical character. In such a case, it is easy to concede the existence of universal laws at the formal level, but the real problem lies in their application in the concrete, and it is precisely here that their ability to play a role is nullified by the distinction between formal and concrete norms. In practice, these latter can be treated apart from the former by an evaluation of the circumstances that considers all the factors for judging action expressed in the classical fontes moralitatis. The stakes are high, since it is not only about the problem of intrinsically evil acts, it also calls into question the connection between human and theological virtues and, therefore, the Christian contribution to morals and concrete action, that is, concrete norms. From the very beginning, Don Caffarra expressed this criticism: Is not the distinction between formal and concrete norms, as they employ it, based upon a certain anthropology, even a certain metaphysics? Can we use it to interpret Scripture? The criticism became sharper in regard to the basis of the so-called material norms: Knowledge of all possible factors and effects is not necessary, for only one essential factor is enough to establish that a concrete act is contrary to the truth about the human person. Father Styczen likewise vigorously rejects the separation set up between transcendental or formal norms and categorial or material norms.This, he holds, implies a division within man himself, an axiomatic dualism that prepares the way for the separation between the “categorial” realm of relations among men and the “transcendental” realm of divine action; in other words, it breaks apart the Christian view of the world. For Father Styczen, the foundation of moral norms lies in the ontological make-up of man, which can be known by a moral intuition that is valid even if not everyone recognizes it. Particular or “categorial” ethical norms are only the translation into normative language of the affirmation of the human person in accord with his objective make-up. They express the content of the “personalist norm.” We cannot at the same time affirm the general value of this latter while also denying the possibility of particular norms that are at the same time general. We ourselves have highlighted the problem of this excessive separation between formal and concrete norms which practically ends up establishing two separate orders, reminiscent of the separation between morals and spirituality, and which deprives the formal norms and the virtues of their specific impact on concrete conduct. An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 351 It is no doubt possible to establish a parallel between the distinction between Gutheit and Richtigkeit and the distinction between interior and exterior acts, which St.Thomas puts in the order of form and matter in the Summa theologiae. Here we have two parts of the concrete act that can be analyzed separately. Nevertheless their connection is essential, as between form and matter, body and soul; the goodness or evil of the interior act communicates itself to the exterior act and vice versa.We should add that with St.Thomas we are dealing with a moral theology of virtues and not merely of the Commandments.Virtue is formed by the repetition of concrete right actions which necessarily return to the concrete, for we cannot be prudent without actually acting. To loosen the tie between virtue and the concrete is, in practice, to annihilate virtue.The comparison deserves a closer examination. It is undeniable that here we have one of the nerve centers of the debate. Sometimes it may seem to come down to a tempest in a teacup, to an almost imperceptible difference. The criticisms that we have just presented help us to see that behind the hairline fracture there is a geographical fault big enough to affect all of moral theology. Let us add that this fault is extended by a division that is hardly showcased but which is of great consequence: The innovators maintain that the concrete criteria for action are found precisely at the level of relations with other men, which they call the horizontal or categorial level. This allows them to deal with the concrete problems in dispute today on the human plane, without bringing in our relationship with God or with Christ, in other words, without bringing in the vertical or transcendental level as supplying essential factors and criteria for moral judgment. As regards this central debate, numerous elements that enter into it cry out for clarification. “Finality” plays a leading role in the debate.The innovating school gives predominance to teleology, to consideration of the end as it relates to an evaluation of the action’s consequences from the circumstances considered. The Thomistic school wants finality to regain its place in the forefront of moral judgment, as the object of an interior act ordered to an ultimate end, while also highlighting the objectivity of this finality. It criticizes the use of the distinction between finis operis and finis operantis, which in the manuals has served to reduce the finality of the one acting (that is, finality properly speaking), to the rank of a secondary and entirely subjective factor in the action.A distinction must also be made between the technical kind of teleology based on a consideration of usefulness, at the level of Richtigkeit, and a proper moral teleology based on a consideration of the moral quality of the goods pursued, which goes further than the consideration of usefulness 352 Servais Pinckaers, OP and would transcend the opposition between teleology and deontology. The link between short-term finality, reduced to a single act, and longterm finality, ordered to an ultimate end, would have to be reestablished. The role of finality in moral conduct, as a principle uniting behavior and life, certainly deserves to regain its value; but that cannot happen without a judicious analysis of the nature of finality, as well as of the role it plays in moral judgment in relation to the other factors that form it. The terms “object” and “circumstances” must likewise be clarified. Object is spoken of in both a narrow and a broad sense, in which we also include circumstances; but, as the manuals show, object continues to be understood in a material, almost physical sense, in a word, as opposed to what is subjective and therefore to the finality of the one acting. The term “circumstances” is in practice used very broadly to designate all the elements that make up an action and constitute its status without making a distinction between the elements that are essential or substantial on the moral level and the accidental, secondary elements that, properly speaking, make up the circumstances.To sum up, it is the treatise on the fontes moralitatis that should be revised, not to shake the foundations of morality it presents, but to establish them more solidly and clearly. The term “nature”, which can be understood either as conformity to reason according to St. Thomas or as biological nature, conditions our understanding of the natural law. If, like Suárez, but unlike the Fathers and St.Thomas, we conceive of human nature as self-sufficient, the natural law becomes sovereign in morality and, strictly speaking, no longer has need of revealed law to govern our actions. The doctrine of natural law should undergo a deeper study, particularly in relation to the Evangelical Law.To be sure, it was astonishing to see that in the discussions and debates of the symposium, the natural law was hardly mentioned, which formed the main basis of post-Tridentine Catholic moral theology as the direct foundation of the universality of moral laws. This subject was left too much in the wings. The term “reason” evokes an enormous problem: the relationship between reason and faith (Revelation), that is, between philosophy and theology. Even if we cannot deal with the question in its entirety, it would nonetheless be good to make a distinction between a “rationalizing” reason that sets itself up as sovereign judge of all truth and science, including the realm of morality, independently of faith if not in opposition to it, and a reason open to faith, a reason which recognizes that the faith has its own light, especially in the field of the activity of man oriented toward his ultimate end. Only this allows us to understand adequately what right reason defines prudence and determines the criteria of moral judgment and their An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 353 application, particularly in Christian conduct. Speaking of which, it would be good to look again at the old problem of the relation between prudence and conscience and to pay special attention to the latter’s role: Is it simply declarative, imperative, or really creative, and, to a certain extent, legislative? Here again we encounter one knot of the main issue in the symposium. Indeed, contemporary trends tend to make personal conscience the last and decisive judge of whether any moral laws apply to concrete acts. The terms “immutability” and “universality” also require clarification. Immutability, which has a negative connotation, could advantageously be replaced by the more positive “permanence.” As for universality, we must study more precisely the scope of the expression ut in pluribus borrowed from St.Thomas and often used in a sense that diminishes the universality of laws. But above all, behind the adjective “universal,” as it is applied to laws, we find the long-standing debate over universals, that is, over the application of laws to the concrete, which concentrates all the divergences observed at the symposium. For the innovators, universal laws are abstract and formal, as are also the virtues, and of themselves do not come into contact with the concrete act.The concrete act is, indeed, entirely singular for, besides the object and the end, it is constituted by the totality of its circumstances. Thus, in order for a law to apply concretely in a universal way, we must be able to take into consideration all the concrete cases, present and future, with all the possible circumstances—individual, social, and cultural—which in practice makes the attainment and establishment of the universal impossible. Here we are in the nominalist and Kantian line of thought, separating the universal and the abstract from the concrete and from sense experience. Hence we must choose between the universal, which is often seen to smother the concrete, and the concrete, which somehow always escapes the universal: In a word, we must choose between law and personal conscience. The classical moralists opted for the law; the innovators favor the individual conscience. From this perspective, it is impossible to prove theoretically the existence of universal laws that apply without exception in the concrete and have a value in themselves, even though it is admitted that, practically speaking, there exist certain actions that are always evil.Yet this remains open to attack in theory and, therefore, is rather fragile. For the other school of thought, the universal applies to the concrete and to reality, thanks to the distinction between the essential and the accidental. This is achieved either by distinguishing the essence of an act, made up of its object or matter, and its end, and the circumstances understood at the moral level as secondary factors, or also by the determination 354 Servais Pinckaers, OP of the essential requirements of man’s dignity, of the human person in the concreteness of the action (Father Styczen), or again by the intuition, be it in one concrete experience only, of an absolute and unchangeable norm perceived as “intensive” at first, and which later the work of abstraction will develop to give it its general formulation (Newman). From this perspective, it is perfectly possible that there exist moral laws, at any rate negative, that are universal and which apply without exception even to the concrete and to personal experience. Here in fact, there is no choice to be made between the universal and the concreteness of the action, but the universal exists only if it becomes real in action, while the act can only acquire its moral value in conformity with universal laws. Such is quite clearly the task of the virtues: to unite the universal and the concrete in action, for we cannot really conceive of the virtues without the concrete action in which they are formed and which they regulate at the same time. The Role of the Magisterium in Moral Doctrine The question of the Magisterium’s authority in moral doctrine was tackled in three ways: through a consideration of its theological components; through an exact determination of the problem here and now; and through an examination of the various theological positions. Here again the positions and discussions proved the existence of two schools of thought: one traditional, defending the authority of the Magisterium in concrete moral questions, and the other rather critical in this respect, maintaining that other actors, such as the Christian people and moralists, have a role to play in solving moral questions. To be more specific, everyone admits that in its extraordinary and ordinary Magisterium the Church, according to Vatican I, has the power to define in moribus as far as what is contained in Revelation. Necessarily tied to this, explicitly or implicitly, is the question of whether this power extends further and reaches matters that fall under the natural law, touching even the concrete norms of moral conduct derived from the natural law. The Foundations of the Magisterium’s Authority Criticizing the modern separation of faith and reason, which is based on a concept of truth in which reason itself would be one of truth’s components, Don Caffarra wishes to re-establish the coordination between faith and reason by starting with the notion of Christ as Truth equalling Christ as Norm. Such would be the foundation of the power of the Magisterium, which is Christ’s witness in the fields of dogma and morals, as well as the source of the theological knowledge into which reason is An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 355 integrated in its search for truth and the good. Through faith reason is elevated, revealed to itself through metaphysical knowledge, and cured of its temptation to set itself up as its own end. In this way the Magisterium acquires a say even in matters concerning the natural law. It does not substitute itself for the personal judgment of conscience, but it offers conscience objective and necessary reference points. The work of the theologian implies fidelity to the Magisterium as witness to the Truth of Christ, and consists in removing the obstacles that are opposed to this normative Truth. Criticism of this presentation, which came chiefly from the Germanspeaking group, had to do especially with the identification of Christ as Truth with Christ as Norm, holding that this identification could lead to a Monophysite conception in moral theology, with the concepts of truth and autonomy it brings into play, with the hierarchical ecclesiology it presupposes, and with the neglect of the distinction between a transcendental decision and the rightness of categorial conduct, as well as between parenesis and normative ethics. The Problem Right Now The calling into question of the Magisterium’s authority in moral matters is quite recent, as it dates from the encyclical Humanae Vitae. The First Vatican Council, by defining the infallibility of the Magisterium in fide et in moribus, put morality in the genus of dogma, but it did not say precisely what it meant by doctrina de moribus. The Council determined infallibility’s subject but did not indicate how far exactly the power of the Magisterium extended beyond Revelation.The manuals of moral theology did not discuss this power, but assigned the field of natural law implied in Revelation to the Magisterium, which runs the risk of stretching the consequences too far into a foreign domain. This new issue introduces different levels of the faith, of general moral principles, and of concrete norms, which must take into account material factors tied to historical conditions. Following these various levels, therefore, we would have to set up a differentiation in the application of the givens of faith to morals and in the Magisterium’s power in moral matters. This brings us back to the question: Does the Magisterium have the power to define universal concrete norms that are valid without exception? Thus posed, this question was extended in the exchanges to other aspects of the exercise of the Magisterium.The ecclesiology of Vatican II describes the Church first as the People of God. Does this not imply a greater participation of the Christian people in forming the positions of the Magisterium on moral matters by creating a certain consensus, 356 Servais Pinckaers, OP despite the difficulty of verifying its authenticity? Must we not acknowledge that the Church sometimes has been mistaken in or has modified its position on certain questions? Would it not be better pastorally to avow the corrections made throughout history? Finally, can we concede more than an exemplary value to the saints recognized by the Church? The Theological Positions on the Ordinary Infallible Magisterium It behooves us to clarify that which pertains to certain faith: the power to define in moral matters that which is contained in Revelation or which is necessarily connected to it, like the natural law; that which is theologically certain, namely, the infallibility of the ordinary teaching of the pope and of the bishops together with him on these matters; and that which must be held publicly in theology, namely, the extension of the infallible Magisterium to the realm of natural law.The opinion that the encyclicals are infallible is less probable. The current controversy is provoked by criticisms of the traditional doctrine that tend to limit the Magisterium’s role either merely to the domain of revelation, which deprives it of the ability to make pronouncements at the natural and rational moral level, or to the level of formal norms in the natural and human order, which deprives it of the power to determine, in a decisive manner, concrete norms of action and to intervene on the level of concrete problems and cases of conscience, in a decisive manner. Thus there exists a direct and close connection between the question of the Magisterium’s authority and the questions about universal and unchanging laws, as about the relationship between morals and revelation. Throughout the last centuries, a too great separation between revelation and moral teaching, where moral teaching was looked upon as essentially rational and which was seen to rest primarily on the natural law, has favored a separation between the Magisterium and the “scientific” reflection of moralists.The problem becomes particularly acute when moralists get to the point of criticizing or even rejecting the doctrine of natural law, compromising the basis on which the Magisterium grounds itself to intervene in the order of natural ethics. At least the theoretical refusal of the possibility of determining concrete norms that would be truly universal, without exception, touches the Magisterium itself, whose interventions are necessarily of a universal nature. In the final analysis, then, the judgment of concrete cases, which modern Catholic moral theology has focused on since casuistry, is given over to personal conscience alone. It is therefore the power of the Magisterium over the whole of morality, and more precisely over concrete cases, that is called into question. An Unnoticed Symposium on Moral Theory 357 The problem thus posed, with its many aspects, stands out as one of the forms of the fundamental problem of the existence of a moral doctrine that is properly Christian, and of the contribution of Revelation, the Gospel, to moral theory right down to the concrete human level. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 1, No. 2 (2003): 359–80 359 The God of Israel and Jesus Christ: Luke, Marcion, and the Unity of the Canon* C. K AVIN ROWE Duke University Durham, North Carolina Introductory Remarks I N THE STUDY of history it is now almost a commonplace to note that the portrayal of certain persons or groups by their enemies or opponents is at best not accurate to the degree that we would wish and at worst totally distorted by the nature of the polemic. A well-known example from the world of New Testament scholarship of the apprehension of this methodological principle is the debate over Paul’s portrayal of the Judaism of his period. In opposition to much of the accepted view of Judaism disseminated by Bultmann et al., E. P. Sanders’s 1977 Paul and Palestinian Judaism sparked a widespread rethinking of the relationship of Paul’s portrayal of Judaism to a Judaism that would be allowed to speak on its own terms, that is, from its own sources.Though Sanders’s own picture has received critique,1 his methodological point is accepted by scholars on all sides of the debate: In order to come to the * This paper was delivered as a lecture for a joint Heidelberg—Tübingen OT/NT conference ( January 31–February 1, 2003) organized around the theme “In welchem Sinne ist die Schrift Verbindlich?”The text has only a few minor alterations and thus reflects in both orientation and style certain aspects pertinent to a set theme and to a particular location and audience. Further, due to the constraints of time and space, no attempt has been made within the footnotes to defend each subsidiary position taken herein with respect to complex and stilldebated issues in Lukan scholarship. 1 See, e.g., Charles H.Talbert’s presidential address to the Catholic Biblical Association, “Paul, Judaism, and the Revisionists,” Catholic Biblical Quarterly 63 (2001): 1–22 and the literature cited therein. 360 C. Kavin Rowe best understanding possible of a person or group, we must first let them speak for themselves. When we come to Marcion this methodological conviction, however, does not get us very far, except in the way of cautionary warning, since no writings of his are preserved except for partial appearances in the works of others. We must begin our study therefore with a caveat: The representation of Marcion or Marcionite theology in, for example,Tertullian’s Adversus Marcionem is not necessarily the same as the way in which Marcion or his followers would have presented their own theology.2 However, the position described by Tertullian does exist as a theological possibility, and it is to such a possible theological position that I take the word Marcionite to refer. But the precise relationship between the sources for Marcion’s theology, their accuracy, and so on, I will have to leave to the Church historians.3 The God of Israel, Jesus, and the Gospel of Luke in Marcionite Theology The purpose of this section is to remind us of the central issue that Marcionite theology raises and its implications for the relation of the Old and New Testaments (and, therefore, also for the possibility of the unity of the canon). The opening remarks of Book IV of Tertullian’s Adversus Marcionem bring the crucial point of importance immediately to the fore. For Tertullian, Marcion’s Antitheses (a’msihreiy, “Contradictions”), a work in which the latter set parts of (what we call) the Old and New Testaments against each other, made “such a division between the Law and the Gospel as thereby to make two separate gods [duos deos dividens], opposite to each other [proinde diversos], one belonging to one instrument (or, as it is more usual to say, testament [testamenti]), one to the other” (IV.1).Tertullian had no problem agreeing to a difference in dispensation as reflected in the Old and New Testaments: “I do not deny a difference in records of things spoken, in precepts for good behaviour, and in rules of law . . .” (IV.1). His irreconcilable disagreement with Marcion, however, was at the most basic of theological levels: that of the identity of God. In point of fact, 2 There is nevertheless a general and significant agreement between the diverse sources. For a very succinct discussion of this agreement, see the introduction of Evans’s translation of Adversus Marcionem, ed. and trans. Ernest Evans (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), ix–xi. 3 See, e.g., Gerhard May’s brief piece “Marcion ohne Harnack” and the first section of papers from the Mainz 2001 conference,“Die Quelle zu Marcion,” in Marcion und seine Kirchengeschichtliche Wirkung/Marcion and His Impact on Church History, ed. Gerhard May and Katharina Greschat in Gemeinschaft mit Martin Meiser, TU 150 (Berlin:Walter de Gruyter, 2002). The God of Israel and Jesus Christ 361 Tertullian’s admission of dispensational difference hinges on the self-sameness of the God of the Old and New Testaments, for the sentence cited just above continues “provided that all these differences [i.e., things spoken, behavioral precepts, rules of law] have reference to one and the same God [unum et eundem deum], that God by whom it is acknowledged that they were ordained and also foretold” (IV.1).4 Thus Tertullian does not reject the manifest difference between the Old and New Testaments but denies that this difference requires us to posit two different gods. This then is the issue raised by Marcionite theology: the relation of the God of the Old Testament to the God of the New Testament and to Jesus Christ himself. Marcionite theology holds that the God of the Old and the God of the New are not the same God; the creator and warrior god of the Old Testament is an entirely different entity from the good God and Father of Jesus Christ: “Marcion of Pontus developed this doctrine, with shameless blasphemy of the God of whom the law and the prophets tell, saying that he is the creator of evil things . . . but that Jesus came from that father who is high above the God who made the world.”5 Thus, for the Marcionites, the god of Israel and Jesus Christ have nothing to do with one another except for at the level of total discontinuity and contradiction, as the Antitheses were arranged to show. It is of considerable interest for our purpose that in addition to certain “Pauline” epistles (the pastorals and Hebrews were omitted from the a’porsokijm), Marcion selected Luke for his two-part canon as the one Gospel that would best fit with his teaching of a theology—in the strict sense—of separation.6 Of the explanations of his choice that have been offered, I wish to note especially Harnack’s suggestion that “[d]er ‘heidenchristliche’ und asketische Charakter des 3. Evangeliums gegenüber dem 1. und 2., nachdem die drei ersten Kapitel des Werks getilgt waren, muß ihm sympathisch gewesen sein.”7 While Lukan asceticism has not seen great discussion lately,8 the rest of Harnack’s view fits well with the traditional emphasis of modern scholarship upon Luke’s hellenism and further raises the important question of the theological significance of the opening scenes of the Lukan narrative for a reading of Luke’s Gospel. 4 Tertullian, Adversus Marcionem, IV.1 (Migne, PL, 2.362BC). 5 Irenaeus, Adversus Haereses, I.27.2 (Migne, PG, 7.1.688A). 6 The text was entitled simply e