Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 4, No. 1 (2006): 1–16 1 St. Thomas Aquinas: Theologian and Mystic J EAN -P IERRE TORRELL , OP University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland THE TITLE of this study may be surprising.1 Thomas Aquinas is unquestionably a great theologian, but is he also a mystic? A preliminary answer to this question could be found in the fact that he is a canonized saint, and that, in one way or another, God was at the heart of his life, as is true of all saints. While this answer is certainly true, it is not specific enough. Since this saint is a theologian, we can disregard neither his understanding of theology nor the way in which he practiced it, lived it, and finally surpassed it. I would like to show here that the experience of God, which is essential to the mystical life, is as much at the heart of Thomas’s knowledge as of his life. If this can be established, the title of this study will be validated:Thomas Aquinas can be counted among the mystics. But we must first avoid a false approach. If we want to discover Thomas Aquinas’s thoughts on what today is known as “mysticism,” it is almost useless to seek such terminology in his work. He is certainly familiar with the word and frequently uses it; but he adopts it above all in two specific areas, fairly remote from the meaning reserved for it by the manuals of “ascetical and mystical theology,” as this used to be called. He speaks of it, on the one hand, in relation to the Church as the body of Christ, which, he says, forms with its head one single mystical person.This signifies that, through the action of the Holy Spirit, Head and body constitute one single and unique organism of grace.This topic is certainly an essential dimension of his spirituality, but it is not necessary to dwell on it since it is a well-known topic and was 1 Translation by Therese C. Scarpelli of “Théologien et mystique: le cas de Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue des sciences religieuses 77 (2003): 350–65. 2 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP the subject of excellent recent studies.2 On the other hand,Thomas also uses this word to refer to one of the four senses that he regularly employs in his interpretation of sacred Scripture, the mystical sense being one of the names given to the spiritual sense that he distinguishes from the literal sense.After having highlighted the literal sense, which he favors,Thomas, like all medieval theologians, extracts the applications to be derived from it for the life of the ecclesial body or of its members. Although he does this with more or less consistency for the different passages he examines, it is a part of his method.3 Nevertheless, this second meaning of “mystical” does not shed any greater light on what we are looking for. Since this direct approach through terminology proves to be inconclusive, we must therefore seek for the reality itself rather than the words, and take up our question once again. Is there a way to verify whether Thomas Aquinas discusses what we designate as “mystical,” and can we say that he is himself a “mystic”? The answer to this question depends largely upon what we mean by the word “mystic.” If one does not restrict the meaning of this word to exceptional states accompanied by unusual phenomena, and if one agrees to use it in reference to the Christian experience of a high degree of exercise of the theological virtues (which seems today to be the common use of the word), we can certainly agree that Thomas Aquinas is truly a Christian mystic. But to content oneself with this statement is to risk banality; we must go further and try to understand why he is a mystic. Our task then is not simply to affirm that Thomas is at once theologian and mystic, as though these were two qualifications juxtaposed in his person and not specifically linked in any way. Rather, we must endeavor to show that he is a mystic in the manner of a theologian, that he is a mystic precisely because he is a theologian.There are numerous and explicit texts that support this conclusion; it will suffice to survey them and to extract the implications. For conclusion, a short review of the way in which Thomas ended his earthly existence should confirm our thesis.4 2 Cf. Martin Morard, “Les expression ‘corpus mysticum’ et ‘persona mystica’ dans l’oeuvre de saint Thomas d’Aquin. Références et analyse,” Revue Thomiste 95 (1995): 653–64. The author has found eighty-nine uses of “corpus mysticum,” about half of which refer to the Eucharist; the term “persona” is used ten times to designate the “Christus totus,” specifically with respect to its unity. 3 See Marc Aillet, Lire la Bible avec S.Thomas. Le passage de la littera à la res dans la Somme théologique (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires, 1993); but there are numerous studies on this subject. 4 I have already discussed these ideas in greater detail; see Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Vol. 2, Spiritual Master (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2003); idem, “Théologie et sainteté,” Revue Thomiste 71 (1971): 205–21. St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 3 Contemplatio primae veritatis The first question of the Summa theologiae, dedicated to the theory of theological knowledge, opens with an affirmation that today sounds somewhat surprising: “It was necessary for the salvation of the human race that besides the philosophical disciplines, works of human reason, there be a different doctrine received through divine revelation.The reason for this is that man is destined by God to an end which surpasses the capacities of his reason . . . and that it is necessary that this end be known to him in order that he might direct his intention and his actions towards it.” This assertion is insisted upon a second time at the end of the same text: “It was necessary that there should be . . . a sacred doctrine obtained from revelation.”5 This sacra doctrina, necessary for salvation, is a much broader reality than theology alone: In fact, in addition to revelation, which, properly speaking, is transmitted in Sacred Scripture, sacra doctrina incorporates all forms of Christian teaching at all levels.Theology is therefore not identical with sacra doctrina, but is rather its scientifically developed form.This is why, in order to distinguish it from metaphysics, the theology of the philosophers,Thomas designates it as theologia quae ad sacram doctrinam pertinet.6 At the same time, everything that he says about theology assumes that on its own level it participates in the necessity of sacra doctrina itself in relation to salvation. This position results immediately in an obvious consequence: Since sacra doctrina is received from divine revelation, it must be received through and practiced in theologal faith.Thus the subordination of theology to the science of God and of the blessed through faith is the first characteristic of theology, according to Thomas Aquinas. The theory of the subordination of the sciences, for Aristotle, verifies our own experience: Scientific disciplines are not all on the same level. Those sciences that proceed by way of knowledge acquired in other sciences exist in a relation of dependency on them, as in the case of optics in relation to geometry, or music in relation to the laws of mathematics.Without going into detail, it is enough to know that theology is in an analogous position, because the supernatural realities of which it speaks are not evident to us.The existence of God in his Trinitarian mystery and all that he has accomplished for the human race in the history of salvation are not evident except to the eyes of God himself; if they are made evident to the blessed by participation in the beatific vision face to face, men who are 5 St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 1; for a more in-depth proof of what is proposed here, see my study,“Le savoir théologique chez saint Thomas,” in Recherches thomasiennes (Paris:Vrin, 2000), 121–57. 6 ST I q. 1, a. 1, ad 2; for the distinction between the theology of the philosopher and the theologia sacrae scripturae, cf. Super Boetium de Trinitate q. 5, a. 4. 4 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP still journeying cannot have access to them except through and in faith. The subordination of theology to the knowledge that God has of himself and that the blessed have of God is simply the technical expression of the necessity of faith for the practice of theology. This fact is of utmost importance. It signifies that theologal faith is the spiritual locus where the ignorance of the theologian connects with God’s own knowledge; it is only by faith that the theologian’s science has real content, but it is also thanks to faith that theology finds itself situated on the path leading from the obscurity of this world to the full daylight of vision.Thus it is sufficient, but necessary, for the theologian as a scholar to direct the requisites of his knowledge right to their final end, in order to culminate by reaching him who is the ultimate end of his life as believer. Here, then, is the most profound reason why the theologian can also become a mystic.7 The second characteristic of theology, according to Thomas Aquinas, is that God is the “subject” of this unique science. We can leave aside the more technical aspects of what is implied by the Aristotelian notion of the subject of a science,8 but it is necessary to know at least why we speak here of subject and not of object. The subject is the extramental reality that the science seeks to know; the end of a science is no other than the knowledge of its subject. But this reality cannot exist in the soul, cannot be known, except through the mediation of concepts that are like so many holds upon it, and that constitute the object of this science. Thus the concepts do not exhaust the subject; they must be multiplied in order to render one’s approach to the subject a little less inadequate. It even happens that the knower must admit that he is conquered and recognize that the object as known remains perpetually inadequate in relation to the reality that is to be known.This is indeed verified to an unequalled degree where God is involved.Thomas Aquinas means precisely this, then, when he speaks of God as the subject of theology.“Everything in sacra doctrina is considered in relation to God (sub ratione Dei), whether it has to do with God Himself, or whether it is related to God as principle or as end.”9 It also means that in treating of God, the true theologian should never forget that the subject of his knowledge, the end which he pursues, is not the 7 For the theory of subordination, see Sentences I, Prol. a. 3; ST I, q. 1, a. 2; Super Boetium de Trinitate q. 2, a. 2, ad 5; cf. Saint Thomas Aquinas, Spiritual Master, 7–9; or Recherches thomasiennes, 140–44. 8 Cf. Recherches thomasiennes, 144–48. 9 ST I, q. 1, a. 7; the same expression is found in the Sentences I, Prol. a. 4:“Omnia enim quae in hac scientia considerantur sunt aut Deus aut ea quae ex Deo et ad Deum sunt”; each word of this definition is evidently weighted, since Thomas takes here a position relative to several other definitions current in his time, which he recalls in these two passages. St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 5 simple accumulation of objective facts about God the subject, but is rather the very knowledge of the living God of the history of salvation. In this regard, a mystic would naturally speak of a meeting with or experience of God; the theologian has no reason to repudiate such language. This second characteristic entails a third, concerning the nature of theology, which Thomas enunciates rather disconcertingly by saying that since it has God as its subject, theology is more a speculative than a practical science.10 This affirmation, which may seem rather esoteric to twentyfirst century readers, is also of great importance, since among the scholastic theorists of the science of theology who preceded him, Thomas Aquinas occupies, in this regard, a place entirely apart.Although those scholastics all admitted that theology is a speculative science, they also held that it was primarily practical, that is, essentially ordered to the perfect attainment of charity. Starting with his Commentary on the Sentences,Thomas is the first to affirm, on the contrary, that “the ultimate end of this doctrina is the contemplation of the first truth in the fatherland (contemplatio primae veritatis in patria).”11 And thus, given that each science must be judged in relation to the end which it pursues, we may conclude that this science, theology, is “principally speculative.” It can be immediately understood that in this context “speculative” in fact means “contemplative.”12 This is not to say that theology is nothing more than contemplative; Thomas likewise acknowledges that it is also “practical” and that it has the task of guiding human action according to the Gospel within sight of the beatitude that is to be attained, but this is not its determining attribute:“Action is not what is ultimately pursued in this scientia, but rather the contemplation of the first truth in the fatherland, to which we will attain once we have been purified by our good works, according to Mt 5:8: ‘Blessed are the pure in heart: they shall see God.’This is why it is more speculative than practical.”13 In other words, God is not the object of human action, of “something that is to be done.” The theologian does not have God at his disposal: He can only situate himself in relation to God, see in him his origin and his end, bring back to God everything in the universe as well as his own actions, and finally, pray to him, adore him, humble himself before him in contemplation. This supreme finality serves to express the fact that theology is a knowledge completely apart. This idea needs no more emphasis, but 10 ST I, q. 1, a. 4; Sentences I, Prol. a. 3. 11 Sentences I, Prol. a. 3. 12 Cf. Servais Pinckaers, “Recherche de la signification véritable du terme ‘spécu- latif,’ ” Nouvelle revue théologique 81 (1959): 673–85. 13 Sentences I, Prol. a. 3, ad 1. Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP 6 another dimension remains to be revealed:The end pursued by theology is identified in fact and by rights with the final end of man and of the universe. Indeed, if Thomas Aquinas, not only as Christian but also as thinker, is certain of one thing, it is that the entire universe, including man himself, can neither find its meaning nor be understood except in relation to God.This is not simply an affirmation but a well-reasoned and ceaselessly repeated conviction, the most beautiful illustration of which is found in the structure of the Summa theologiae: It begins with God and returns to God according to the well-known schema of “departurereturn” (exitus-reditus).14 This generic truth is expressed in a manner that is just as universal, but also specific to man himself, from the very first words of the Commentary on the Sentences, where Thomas categorically states, “All those who think rightly recognize that the end of human life is found in the contemplation of God (Omnes qui recte senserunt posuerunt finem humanae vitae Dei contemplationem).”15 It is significant that this statement immediately precedes the discussion on the end of theological knowledge, a clear sign that the latter extends and further defines the former. The same perspective, this time argued more at length, is found in the Summa contra Gentiles, where after having rejected everything which does not cause happiness (riches, satisfaction of the sensible appetite, good of the soul, or of the body, and so on), Thomas concludes forcefully,“Thus the ultimate beatitude of man resides in the contemplation of truth.”16 And again at the end of the Summa theologiae, practically at the close of his life, the author repeats unhesitatingly,“The contemplation of truth . . . is the end of the whole of human life (contemplatio divinae veritatis . . . est finis totius humanae vitae).”17 Clearly, Thomas sees no difference between God and the First Truth, and can make a transition between the two easily. We have just seen why theology occupies such a unique position in the organization of knowledge according to Thomas Aquinas: It is the sole body of knowledge whose end as a science (finis operis) is identical with the end of him who practices it (finis operantis). This much cannot be said of any other body of knowledge, but it can be said of theology. 14 Cf. Saint Thomas Aquinas, Spiritual Master, 53–58. 15 Sentences I, Prol. a. 1. 16 SCG III, ch. 37 (Marietti ed., no. 2152); this thought is rendered more precise several lines later:“At the end of our reasoning by induction it is thus shown that the ultimate beatitude of man can consist in nothing else than the contemplation of God” (no. 2160); cf. Super Boetium de Trinitate q. 5, a. 1, ad 4:“(finis) beatitudinis, ad quem tota vita humana ordinatur.” 17 ST II–II, q. 180, a. 4. St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 7 With fear and trembling, certainly, the theologian lives in the humble awareness that the practitioner does not always measure up to his own knowledge, but also in the peaceful certitude that the one who practices his science in theologal faith permeated with the love, which is charity, according to all the demands of the integral method required by its “subject,” can become a mystic in the manner of Thomas Aquinas. This first approach must nevertheless be supplemented, because not all contemplation is theological contemplation, and the latter must not be confused with nontheological contemplation. Contemplation of the Philosophers, Contemplation of the Saints Following a method for which he has great affection and which he employs every time he discusses his theory of theological knowledge, Thomas situates theology in relation to philosophy. A re-reading of the first pages of the Commentary on the Sentences demonstrates why. “All those who think rightly” certainly agree in seeing contemplation of the first truth as the final end of human life, but it must be acknowledged that there are two kinds of contemplation. Given up to the powers of reason alone, the philosophers were limited to seeking a contemplation of God starting from the created world. They could thus only attain an imperfect beatitude, restricted to this life. On the other hand, thanks to the theologal faith that leads it as though by the hand (manuducatur), doctrina theologiae makes it possible to pursue another contemplation, likewise temporarily incomplete, at least as long as it remains on this earth, but which will blossom into the perfect contemplation by which God will be seen in His essence in the everlasting fatherland.18 Here we can immediately see the two differences between philosophy and theology to which Thomas constantly refers.19 First of all, although they are not in themselves opposed to each other, they represent two intellectual ways in opposite directions.The first starts from creatures to culminate in God at the end of an inductive inquiry. The second, conversely, begins with God and, even if on occasion its reasoning proceeds exteriorly in the manner of the first, it remains under the influence of this divine origin that gives meaning and consistency to all its search. It is this that 18 Sentences I, Prol. a. 1; cf. Super Boetium de Trinitate q. 6, a. 4, ad 3. 19 In addition to the passage here in question, see Sentences II, Prol. S.Thomae (first lines); SCG II, ch. 4 (Marietti ed., no. 876); I have discussed this comparison at length in “Philosophie et théologie d’après le Prologue de Thomas d’Aquin au Super Boetium de Trinitate. Essai d’une lecture théologique,” in Documenti e Studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 10 (1999): 299–353. 8 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP allows Thomas to state that sacra doctrina is “like a certain imprint of the divine science.”20 Although this statement appears extravagant at first sight, it is merely one more expression of theology’s relationship of dependency on the revelation received from God.The privilege belongs less to theology than to the faith that is its very soul, since it is faith that ensures the continuity between the theologian’s knowledge (savoir) and God’s own knowledge of himself, enabling in this way the birth and growth of theological knowledge.21 The second difference is no less evident: Assuming that it succeeds (Thomas is not very optimistic about the potential of reason left to itself), the philosophical path can only end in an imperfect contemplation limited to this life, while because of the continuity established by faith, theological contemplation already procures, as it were, a foretaste of eternal beatitude, a praelibatio quaedam of the divine goods that we shall enjoy in the beatific vision.22 Besides these two characteristics linked to the very nature of things, philosophical contemplation is characterized by a more serious deficiency to which Thomas alludes here and there, but which he explains in more depth in a rare text deserving to be better known. Far from digressing from our topic, the clarifications that this text provides can definitely contribute to our progress: The contemplative life consists in an act of the cognitive power directed (praeacceptatae) by the will. Now, the operation is in a certain way the midpoint between the subject and the object; it is a perfection of the knowing subject, and is qualified by the specifying object. It follows therefore that the operation of the cognitive power can be qualified by affectivity (affectari) in two ways. On the one hand, insofar as it is the perfection of the knower, and in this case the affective quality of the cognitive operation proceeds from love of self; and this was the kind of affectivity in the contemplative life of the philosophers. On the other hand, insofar as it ends in the object, and in this case the desire of contemplation proceeds from love of the object, for where love is found, there also is found the gaze; cf. Mt 6:21:“Where your treasure is, there also is your heart.” And this is the kind of affectivity in the contemplative life of the saints of which we speak. Thus contemplation consists essentially in an act of the cognitive [power] which requires charity for the reason we have just mentioned.23 20 ST I, q. 1, a. 3, ad 2: “velut quaedam impressio divinae scientiae.” 21 It is indeed in a discussion of faith that Thomas employs a formula very similar to the preceding quote; cf. Super Boetium de Trinitate q. 3, a. 1, ad 4: “Lumen . . . fidei . . . est quasi quaedam sigillatio primae veritatis in mente.” 22 Compendium theologiae I 2; cf. ST II–II, q. 4, a. 1; De veritate q. 14, a. 2. 23 Sentences III, d. 35, q. 1, a. 2, qc. 1; see also qc. 3. St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 9 Despite its apparent serenity, this passage is a battle-text. It must be interpreted in the polemical context of the era, during which a whole philosophical current was born in the Paris faculty of arts, asserting that it was possible for philosophers to attain perfect beatitude already in this life.24 What Thomas disputes here is not philosophical research per se, nor the love of truth by which it may be inspired, nor the beatitude, no matter how limited, which it can procure; rather, he argues against an inaccuracy that he believes he has identified in Aristotle and in those who claim to follow Aristotle alone. For Aristotle, the happiness of the philosopher consists in contemplation, not by virtue of the object contemplated, but rather because contemplation is the highest activity of man, who finds his perfection therein. This strictly intellectual activity achieves its perfection in immanence, not in a transcendent object.25 Thomas could only disdain this enclosure of self in pure humanism, and it is this that he rejects under the name of contemplation of the philosophers. He certainly admits that contemplation is an act of intelligence, but he warns against what he calls “the love of knowledge for its own sake,”26 and explains that “the delectation which the contemplative life procures does not come only from the contemplation itself.”27 More than that, it is rooted in the love of the reality contemplated and it can only be fulfilled in this same love. In speaking of “contemplation of the first truth,” we must therefore not allow ourselves to be drawn into error as though we were dealing with a purely intellectual activity.Thomas speaks more precisely: “The end of contemplation as contemplation is nothing else than truth; but when contemplation becomes a way of life it also has the account of affectivity and the good.”28 It already happens likewise in relation to philosophical contemplation: Disinterested love of the truth sought and attained should suffice to prevent the temptation of becoming wrapped up in self, so that in this way the practice of philosophy could be an authentic springboard toward 24 Cf. my “Philosophie et théologie,” 339–43, for further details and the necessary bibliography. 25 Cf. R.-A. Gauthier, La morale d’Aristote (Paris: 1958), 101–4; nevertheless, the author underlines that Aristotle occasionally seems to raise himself to a more mystical view of contemplation. 26 ST II–II, q. 180, a. 1: “propter amorem ipsius cognitionis quam quis ex inspectione consequitur.” 27 ST II–II, q. 180, a. 7: “in vita contemplativa non solum est delectatio ratione ipsius contemplationis.” 28 Sentences III, d. 35, q. 1, a. 2, qc. 1, ad 1:“finis contemplationis, inquantum contemplatio est veritas tantum; sed secundum quod contemplatio accipit rationem vitae, sic induit rationem affectati et boni.” 10 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP the love of God.29 For an even greater reason, the same applies to Christian contemplation: “The contemplative life of the saints presupposes love of the reality contemplated and proceeds thence.”30 Here the saints are simply the faithful, among whom theologians clearly rank; theological contemplation thus can benefit from what is said of contemplation in general. The faith that is at the source of this very particular knowledge is itself already permeated with affectivity; it is “faith which works by charity” (Gal 5:6). But Thomas insists on further defining the place of theologal affectivity: “Since the contemplative life consists principally in the contemplation of God to which charity impels . . . , it follows that the delectation of the contemplative life does not result only from contemplation itself, but from the very love of God.”31 Although it resides essentially in the intellect, the contemplative life finds its origin (principium) in affectivity, since it is charity which impels towards the contemplation of God. And since the end corresponds to the beginning, it follows that the term and end of the contemplative life are equally found in affectivity, since we find joy in beholding the reality which is loved, and the very delectation which we feel therein further arouses our love for that object. This is why Gregory says in his commentary on Ezekiel that when the lover beholds the object of his love he is inflamed even more towards it. In this is truly found the ultimate perfection of the contemplative life, when the truth be not only known, but also loved.32 This perspective enables us to better comprehend how Thomas can speak of contemplation as though it were the beginning of a process that will only find its perfection later: “Here on earth the contemplation of divine truth is only possible for us in an imperfect way, ‘in a mirror and dimly’ [1 Cor 13:12], but in this way there appears in us the incipience, as it were, of this beatitude (inchoatio beatitudinis) which begins here on earth and will be completed in the age to come.”33 29 Cf. ST II–II, q. 180, a. 7, which connects the delectation procured in the contem- plation of truth, with the desire for knowledge that all men have by nature.The background context is clearly as much Aristotle’s affirmation at the beginning of the Metaphysics as Thomas’s own statements about the natural desire to see God. 30 Sentences III, d. 35, q. 1, a. 2, qc. 3. 31 ST II–II, q. 180, a. 7. 32 ST II–II, q. 180, a. 7, ad 1; the same doctrine, together with the same quotation from St. Gregory, is found in ST II–II, q. 180, a. 1. 33 ST II–II, q. 180, a. 4; a similar expression in another context shows the degree to which such language is familiar to St.Thomas and how much he is concerned with the totality of theologal life: “per gratiam acceptam et nondum consummatam (fuit) in eis [homo et angelus] inchoatio quaedam speratae beatitudinis quae quidem inchoatur in voluntate per spem et caritatem, sed in intellectu per fidem.” St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 11 It could not be clearer: Contemplation is not merely concerned with intellectual vision, but engages the whole theologal affectivity of the one who gives himself to it; and it engages not only his intellectual affectivity (will), but also his sensible affectivity, as Thomas does not hesitate to clarify at times.34 Contemplation, then, is an arduous experience that embraces the totality of the person who desires to follow his intention through to the end. Of course, all this is not said directly about theology, and we should be careful not to infer that all theologians show themselves worthy of the noble science that they practice. But it is no less certain that it is in practicing theology in this way that Thomas Aquinas himself became a saint. Theological Contemplation, Infused Contemplation Another clarification is necessary in order that these texts not be interpreted wrongly. As all-encompassing as it may be, this description of contemplation does not extend to the reality to which the same name normally refers after the sixteenth century. Beginning with St. John of the Cross, the word “contemplation” is used in a more distinctly specialized and restricted sense than that which characterizes its use in St. Thomas. For the latter, contemplation is the highest act of a mode of life (religious, philosophical, theological), which it defines and polarizes; and it is such a difficult act that it cannot be constantly sustained, so that one could speak more naturally and with greater exactitude of the contemplative life rather than of contemplation. Nevertheless, this supereminent act, which requires all the intellectual and affective powers of the person dedicated to it, all the resources of a graced nature open to the gifts of the Holy Spirit, remains an activity within the capacity of human potential. The religious, theologian, or philosopher is responsible for living in conformity with his ideal and for sharpening his capacity for intellectual intuition to the point that, at least at certain moments, he can free himself from all rational and conceptual baggage, in order to lift a purely contemplative gaze to the reality that he pursues.The goal of his knowledge or of his life is not reasoning itself, but rather the contemplation of the reality to be known and loved. Mystical contemplation operates in a different way. This kind of contemplation is not within the capacity of human potential: It is purely a grace. It too doubtless requires preparation, but this preparation derives from asceticism and prayer rather than science or intelligence. And this preparation can never be such as to procure in an assured fashion, much 34 Cf. Disputed question De Virtutibus a. 5, ad 8; ST II–II, q. 181, a. 1. 12 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP less automatically, the gift of contemplation. In this area, the initiative returns to God “who provides for his beloved as they sleep” (Ps 127:2). This is why we speak of infused contemplation, while for theological contemplation we speak rather of acquired contemplation. Although Thomas does not use this terminology himself, he is familiar with the distinction and uses it in his own way.35 Thus, when he questions whether theological science is the same as wisdom, he recalls that it is proper to wisdom to judge all things according to the highest causes, and since the “subject” of theology is the highest cause of all, God himself, theology is therefore wisdom par excellence. Nevertheless, he clarifies that there are two types of wisdom: one, theological wisdom, which is obtained through study ( per studium); the other, the effect of the gift of wisdom of the Holy Spirit, which is obtained by infusion ( per infusionem). It is true that the principles of the first are found in revelation, but its manner of judging derives from science in a human way; one is more or less wise to the degree that one is more or less learned about divine things. The second is the fruit of a freely granted divine gift, and the judgment which it procures derives from a knowledge by connaturality. In the way that the virtuous make right judgments about good and evil quasi-spontaneously, the one enlightened by the gift of wisdom possesses an intimate familiarity with divine things that the theologian cannot procure merely by his pure science. According to Dionysius, whose statement Thomas willingly applies to his own theme,“Hierotheus became wise not only by studying, but by experiencing the divine (non solum discens, sed patiens divina).”36 Thomas returned to this distinction several times, and he clearly considered the topic an important one. Beginning with the Sentences, in discussing the gift of wisdom he recognizes immediately that if one can only judge well that which one knows, it is no less true that this capacity for judgment is actualized in a different way in each person. For some, it derives from 35 To my knowledge, the term infusa is used near the word contemplatio only once in his writings, in his commentary on the verse: “No one has ever seen God.” He declares that amid the different ways of “seeing” God, there is one which comes “by a certain light infused into the soul by God during contemplation; it is in this way that Jacob saw God face to face [cf. Gen 28:19], in a vision granted to him, according to St. Gregory, through elevated contemplation” (In Ioan. 1:18, lect. 11 [Marietti ed., no. 211]; see the complete translation of this text in Saint Thomas Aquinas, Spiritual Master, 49–51). 36 ST I, q. 1, a. 6 and ad 3; this manner of distinguishing between the two types of wisdom, acquired and infused, is one of the points on which Thomas is most clearly distinguished from his contemporaries, for whom theological wisdom was in itself a delightful knowledge [connaissance]; cf. Recherches thomasiennes, 135–37. St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 13 study and knowledge, together with a certain penetration of intellect; in this case, wisdom is an intellectual virtue. For others, this capacity derives from a certain affinity to divine things, as Dionysius expressed with regard to Hierotheus, who “learned divine reality through his experience of it.” According to Thomas, it is this wisdom to which St. Paul refers when he affirms that “the spiritual man judges all things” (1 Cor 2:15); and St. John, in asserting that the “anointing [of the Holy Spirit] will teach you all things” (1 Jn 2:27). This passage, which serves to better clarify the difference between the two types of wisdom, is followed by another that characterizes the knowledge obtained through the gift “as an intuitive grasp (cognitio simplex) of the realities of the faith which are at the origin of all Christian wisdom [hence knowledge through the supreme cause].The gift of wisdom thus culminates in a deiform and in a certain sense explicit contemplation (deiformem contemplationem), of the realities which faith holds implicitly in a human manner.” Here, unequivocally distinguished from theological contemplation, is an exact description of the reality designated as mystical contemplation: While theological contemplation, primarily directed by theologal faith, remains available to human initiative, mystical contemplation, without separating itself from faith, is primarily directed by the gift and depends entirely on divine generosity.37 The comparison between the two types of wisdom does not end there, and when it comes time to make definitions according to essence,Thomas never forgets to clarify more exactly the relationships that intelligence and will enjoy in this regard. He says that one can judge of divine things from the point of view of the inquiries of reason, and this derives from wisdom as intellectual virtue, but the perception of these things “by connaturality” belongs to that wisdom that is a gift of the Holy Spirit, as in the case of Hierotheus who had perfect knowledge of divine things because he had learned them by lived experience: “This ‘compassion’ or connaturality with divine things is the work of charity which properly unites us to God: ‘he who unites himself to God is one spirit with Him’ (1 Cor 6:17).Thus the cause of wisdom as gift is found in the will, i.e., in charity; but its essence is found in the intellect, to which it pertains to judge rightly.”38 Here, one may notice not only the continuity with the immediately preceding texts, but also the parallel with previously cited texts concerning theological contemplation: In either of the two cases, the objective analysis that identifies contemplation as an act of the intellect does not take precedence over Thomas’s concern to uphold its status as all-encompassing 37 Sentences III, d. 35, q. 2, a. 1, qc. 1, ad 1. 38 ST II–II, q. 45, a. 2 14 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP act that lends full value to the status of its affectivity. One last text will provide a deeper understanding of this difference: “(Besides speculative knowledge), there is also an affective or experiential knowledge of the divine goodness or the divine will; one experiences in oneself the taste of the sweetness of God and the lovability of the divine will, according to what Denys says of Hierotheus who learned divine things from having experienced them in himself.We are thus invited to experience the will of God and to taste His sweetness.”39 Thus although he does not directly use the terminology of mystical contemplation, which would become widespread only after his time, Thomas is very familiar with the reality meant by these words. But his particular approach to things further has the advantage of better clarifying the existence and requirements of the other reality, which is theological contemplation. He therefore distinguishes the wisdom of the mystics that blossoms into infused contemplation, from the wisdom of the theologian that merely grants an acquired contemplation.Although he repeats that one who theorizes about divine things does not have the same kind of competence as the one who practices them, he does not preclude the theorist’s experiencing divine things as well. It is even possible to add without the risk of erring that the very demands of the wisdom that the theologian practices make it desirable for him not to remain a pure theorist. His knowledge could only become sharpened by this experience and thus increase in penetration.Without extrapolating too much outside the limits of the texts, we may even say that this is what happened for St.Thomas himself. Conclusion: Thomas Aquinas, Theologian and Mystic Relatively little is known about the life of St.Thomas apart from his own writings, and it must be honestly stated that the witnesses are hampered by the factor of uncertainty common to such documents, closer to hagiography than to history. I have nevertheless attempted elsewhere to unearth the solid kernel of what has been handed down to us, and I believe that we can say that these documents are for the most part credible enough, since they transmit scarcely more than the portrait of an exemplary religious “of great contemplation and prayer.”40 Without 39 ST II–II, q. 97, a. 2, ad 2; these little-known texts on a delightful knowledge through experience connect with an authentically Thomistic theme that is developed somewhat in Saint Thomas Aquinas, Spiritual Master, 90–99. 40 Cf. J.-P. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Vol. 1, The Person and his Work (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1996), 267–89 (here 286); cf. C. Le Brun-Gouanvic, Ystoria santi Thome de Aquino de Guillaume de Tocco (1323) (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1996). St.Thomas Aquinas:Theologian and Mystic 15 taking this up again here, it seems that we can retain as unquestionable three principal traits of Thomas’s religious life and in particular of his prayer: first of all his devotion to the crucifix, of which we have numerous moving testimonies,41 then his great veneration for the Eucharist, of which the most eloquent example is surely the prayer Adoro Te,42 and finally the link connecting Thomas’s prayer to his intellectual work. Under rigorous inspection—if there were any—the first two aspects could be imagined to be simply parallel to his theological research, but the third takes us directly back to this theological research and is frequently highlighted: We see Thomas engaging in prayer in the moments when he had to study, teach, write, or dictate, and in particular when he had to treat of difficult topics. His biographer has captured very well the stakes involved in the qualities that characterized Thomas and his confreres in this regard; in attacking their way of life, the secular masters of the university of Paris showed that they had not understood that one could reach salvation in sola studii contemplatione.43 When we recognize the concept that this phrase signifies in Thomas, we can better grasp its import and reasonably suppose that he effectively practiced what he taught.Thomas should be reread from this point of view in order to see how his contemplation as friar-preacher-theologian found its natural expression in his work.44 A reading of the life of Thomas reveals how he practiced theological contemplation, but it also manifests that his life ended in a confession-inact of the insufficiency of this first form of contemplation. Novelists and historians have made the most audacious and sometimes incredible suppositions about the death of St.Thomas.While remaining within the bounds of history, it can be said with certitude at least that the final months of his life were marked by repeated ecstasies, the last-known occurrence of which provoked the cessation of his writing activity. It was around the feast of St. Nicholas, December 6, 1273, and the author was still in the midst of composing the Summa.45 To his secretary who bemoaned this interruption, it is said that he simply replied,“I no longer can. Everything that I have written seems straw in comparison with what 41 Cf. Saint Thomas Aquinas,The Person and His Work, 287–88; idem, Le Christ en ses mystères, vol. 1 (Paris: Desclée, 1999), 325–27. 42 The authenticity of this prayer is now unquestioned: cf. Torrell, “Adoro Te. La plus belle prière de saint Thomas,” La vie spirituelle, no. 726 (March 1998): 29–36. 43 Cf. Saint Thomas Aquinas,The Person and His Work, 283–87. 44 This is precisely what I have attempted to accomplish in Saint Thomas Aquinas, Spiritual Master. 45 Cf. Saint Thomas Aquinas,The Person and His Work, 289–95. 16 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP I have seen.” These words have sometimes been interpreted as Thomas’s repudiation of his work as theologian.This is highly improbable. It would be closer to the truth to remember that straw is merely the support and the sheath of the grain. The words of the Summa or of his other works are very clearly not the reality of which they speak; they do not limit this reality, but they point it out and lead to it. Elevated by a special grace to contemplate the reality itself, Thomas had good reason to feel detached from the words he had employed until then, but this does not imply that he considered his work worthless. Simply, from that moment on, he had passed beyond it. In words relating back to our theme, we are assured that theological contemplation—without having thereby lost its merit— having played the role of a preparatory manuductio, could now give way to infused contemplation. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 4, No. 1 (2006): 17–28 17 Business Ethics and Catholic Social Thought G. J. M C A LEER Loyola College Baltimore, Maryland AT THE J ESUIT UNIVERSITY where I work there is a business school. At the suburban satellite campus of the business school there are no religious symbols inside the classrooms. The rationale is well known to many readers: Because graduate programs serve a diverse business community, reasons the administration, the classrooms should be a place of welcome and comfort.There is one symbolic nod to Christ allowed at the building. Drivers passing the building on the freeway see a tall oblong structure with a large square cross superimposed of the face of the oblong. Now, superimposed upon the cross are two short straight lines that move: the hands of a clock.This is the humiliation of the Cross in a sense different from that understood by Christians and theologians.You don’t need to have been at the planning meeting of that decision to know how it went. A consultant who has set up many such campuses for secular and Catholic institutions alike thought it would be a really cool symbol of the infusion of Christian life into business: the Cross regulating the time by which labor, commerce and production are ordered. It is easy to shake one’s head at such folly but this symbolic effort raises the profound issue of how to conceive the integration of business and Christian norms of action and social order. It is often assumed that the flashpoint of evangelization at universities is in medical schools, that science is the great competitor in matters of faith and morals. After all there is a President’s Committee on Bioethics which includes prominent Christian intellectuals that garners enormous attention, and rightly: It grapples in a serious, intellectual way with the life and death issues that arise from medical technology and basic science. It is undeniable that Christian combat is required in medicine to convert hearts 18 G. J. McAleer away from abortion, euthanasia, and the instrumentalization of the human. But when religious intellectuals say that science is “the only game in town”—meaning that religion has been marginalized by the prowess and progress of science—are they right? It is easy to forget to what degree business is an engine driving biotechnology forward. The Wall Street Journal is a remarkable illustration of this.A superb newspaper, it is the only conservative newspaper with national reach. Because it is conservative, much column space is given to intelligent writers on the positive role of religion in America today and it is the only national newspaper that has pro-life commentary. Nevertheless, there is a constant drumbeat of articles about the business potential of embryonic stem-cell research.This is responsible journalism, of course, for there is enormous business interest in the profits to be made from such research. So, whilst there are journals of Catholic bioethics and Catholic institutions devoted to those issues, there is no journal of Catholic business ethics and no special Catholic foundations devoted to business ethics. Not only has a vital field of evangelization been largely overlooked, but this fact perhaps illustrates that the enormity of the task of evangelization of business is radically underestimated. This is all the more strange in that John Paul II provided thorough leadership in this matter. Known to the public as someone with strong views about sex and fertility it is seldom realized that he probably wrote more frequently on business ethics than sexual ethics. This leadership perhaps fell on rocky ground because many American Catholic intellectuals are not especially business friendly.1 Much of this has to do with old political alliances that are probably now shifting, though sadly that shift will not come quickly in Catholic universities since the faculties are strongly opposed to business.At my own university, until very recently no permanent member of the faculty had taught business ethics in over a decade. This is not merely because of indifference, it is rather more a matter of contempt. Intellectuals believe themselves above business and the business faculty and their students. The lack of justice and charity demonstrated by this contempt is disturbing but far worse is the complete underestimation of the intellectual power and allure of thinkers like Adam Smith or the combination of philosophical imagination and technical virtuosity of thinkers like Donaldson, Dunphy, and Frederick in the contemporary American business school. 1 In no way do I mean to belittle the work of Catholic thinkers like Michael Novak or Richard John Neuhaus. My point is rather that these business-friendly thinkers are a minority and are often sneered at themselves. About this, I merely ask readers to think back to various comments they may have heard about them in theology departments, faculty lounges, and religious houses. Business Ethics and Catholic Social Thought 19 To establish what the task of evangelization is for business ethics, and of the students who take courses through business schools at Catholic universities, a consideration of the powerful intellectual vision of Adam Smith is necessary. Smith has a special claim to attention not only because of his foundational role in economic theory but because he is the author of one of the greatest masterpieces in ethics, his 1759 Theory of Moral Sentiments.2 Moreover, he was not only observing commercial life at the very moment of its modern birth but making observations in a thoroughly modern manner. Catholic social thought needs to be able to match its observational talent or phenomenology of commercial life to that of Smith’s and this, I insist, would be no small achievement. After a discussion of Smith, I want to argue, and somewhat darkly, I suppose, that two common ways Catholic social thought aims to introduce norms into business are not straightforwardly equal to the task. Concluding more positively, however, I argue that the moral realism of the Church is certainly equal to the task rightly understood. Catholic response to Smith is of two types: Smith is a utilitarian and a theorist of inequality. These critical responses3 to Smith can be found respectively in Joseph Pieper’s defense of leisure as the basis of culture and in a rather typical use of the idea of dignity in Christian discussions of business. At the heart of Adam Smith’s ethics of commercial life is his Platonism, a conviction that human imagination is governed by beauty.4 For Smith moral approbation is understood in terms of what is becoming and well-formed and moral disapprobation in terms of the unseemly and ill-formed. It is very important to appreciate that for Smith utility is not basic to commercial life, it is secondary to the pursuit of beauty.5 As one of his most famous passages has it, it is because of beauty that people wish to live close to palaces and avoid living near prisons.The utility of the prison is obvious but it is ugly whilst palaces are largely useless but because they are becoming they attract.6 Of course, Smith is here giving an analysis of desire and the property market and it is completely true:Academics and theologians can sneer all they like at business types but whom 2 Adam Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1982). 3 There is a third Catholic response to Smith that is positive. It is principally asso- ciated with Michael Novak. I shall not be discussing Novak in part because something like his approach must be right: The conclusion of this essay is that accommodation for Smith inside Catholic social thought is necessary. However, I shall not be discussing Novak partly because I am as yet unsure what to make of the “Catholic Whig” position. 4 Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments, 11; 35–37; 117; 179–87. 5 Ibid., 179–80. 6 Ibid., 35. G. J. McAleer 20 among us lives near the local prison? Smith gives dozens of similar examples—and a large part of why his writing is so convincing is the clarity and aptness of his examples—and they rather confound one of the classic Catholic responses to Smith. Basic to recent Catholic social thought is Scheler’s axiological hierarchy in which utility values stand lower than vital, personal, and spiritual values. Reversing this order of preference is immoral, a sign of value delusion or ressentiment. If commercial life is not an ordering of desire around utility values, however, but around beauty, then it is far from clear that Catholic social thought has a ready handle on Smith and his promotion of commercial life. Smith, as much as Scheler, thinks that values exist in the world distinct from the comprehension of values7 and, after all, a theologian of the stature of Bonaventure observed that beauty is a basic category by which God makes himself present to us.Which is to say, that if the mark of a contemplative is response to high value, then Smith’s ethics is contemplative.8 Pieper’s critique of work in the modern world assumes that work is done for its own sake and that the discipline and sacrifice required by work are purposeless.9 By contrast, Pieper quotes Thomas’s Summa that, “the end and norm of discipline is happiness.”10 Thomas’s insight, he thinks, is completely lost in the modern valorization of work. Yet, were Smith to paraphrase Thomas, he would write “the end and norm of discipline is beauty.” Commercial life, as understood by Smith, revolves around beauty, a high-ranking value on the axiological hierarchy. The Catholic critique of “economism”—the reduction of persons to utility values—has a genuine target, certainly, but in reading Smith it is not perhaps a target that is as pervasive in business as is commonly thought. The approach of Pieper—a major influence on the work of Michael Naughton, for example11—has limited potential, I fear. For Smith, leisure is the engine of ambition. However, that leisure provokes the sacrifice and production of ambition is more apparent than real. Underwriting leisure—and this is why it matters little that Pieper is interested in leisure that gives opportunity for contemplation—is the desire to complete a 7 Max Scheler, Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973), 266–67. 8 Josef Pieper, Leisure:The Basis of Culture (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1999), 7–11. 9 Pieper, Leisure:The Basis of Culture, 23. 10 Ibid., 17. 11 For the best book of American Catholic business ethics, see Naughton’s co- authored work with Helen Alford, Managing As If Faith Mattered (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001). Business Ethics and Catholic Social Thought 21 system or order of beauty.12 Smith’s portrait of the ambitious young man13—and just how evocative it is for today’s students will readily be seen by anyone who teaches it—describes a youth whose life is given over to work and production in service of a leisure that forever escapes him:That is because leisure is not the real object of pursuit but rather is the completion of a beautiful arrangement, a harmony and flow of objects. It is a matter of “enchantment,” says Smith. Ordering the active or contemplative life is beauty and the pursuit of its regularities. The Platonism of such a conception of human desire is obvious—and perhaps a recommendation—but its damage to Pieper’s concern about modernity is evident. The active life, argues Smith, is as thoroughly Platonic as the contemplative life and has the same object in view. In other words, it is not merely that Smith valorizes the active life—his horror of the contemplative life of monks is famous—it is rather that he thinks the tradition has misunderstood what is the object of the active life.The ordo amoris of the active life is the affirmation of a hierarchy and ranking of objects imposed by beauty. The “value-ception,” as Scheler would put it, is the same for both Pieper and Smith—contemplation, albeit in a different mode and with a narrower range of objects in the case of Smith.That is, Smith did not believe in a personal God. Pieper, of course, thinks contemplation that does not ultimately acknowledge God as the highest object truncated. Pieper is correct, but formally commercial life is contemplative, as least as compellingly described by Smith. And if this is so, then Pieper’s argument is not powerful against Smith and may well mischaracterize the modern world as well. A more fruitful Catholic approach to Smith is found in John Paul II’s use of dignity. But the idea of dignity as a norm of business ethics is not straightforward either. Relying on ideas of dignity and the person will require Catholic social thought to make a place for Smith even as an advocate of inequality. Thinkers like Novak argue that Catholic social thought has already allied itself to Smith. I think this is true when we look at John Paul II’s use of dignity as a norm, but his “concessions” to Smith, if I may put it that way, bring Catholic social thought into a high state of tension with itself. In fact, since Paul VI employed the same notion of dignity this tension has been present for nigh on forty years. I will argue that this tension is only really able to be resolved by a deepening alliance with Smith. John Paul II’s business ethics rests on an understanding of the active life as a participation in the work of Creation itself, work happens within 12 Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiment, 180–81. 13 Ibid., 181–82. G. J. McAleer 22 the “original ordering.”14 John Paul II is thoroughly modern, to be provocative, thoroughly Smithian, in seeing the issues of commercial life as directly issues of the active life. Eschewing stoicism, John Paul II has focused on the ethics of business organization as a support for virtue in the work place. Commercial life requires a management order that fosters human dignity. I think it thoroughly remarkable that John Paul in Laborem Exercens focuses upon dignity as a quality rather than as a fixture of the ontological order.15 It is a commonplace in discussions with Christians about commercial life that since man is made in the image of God, man’s dignity must be fostered.There can be no dispute about this, of course, but as a matter of explanation it is lacking in power. We run into almost complete silence as soon we ask what we mean by dignity.16 What is the content of this notion? For John Paul II work is intrinsically linked to dignity for in work, man “confirms his dominion over the visible world”17 but only so long as work affirms human dignity by affirming man as a person. For this “subjective meaning of work” to be realized, work, in its objective content, that is, the “strategic” organization of a successful business, must do three things: It must engage the intellect of its workers, require their self-management, and have a “tendency” to encourage human flourishing.18 Work that does these things affirms man as a person.What is striking here is not that dignity is cast as the actualization of various human powers—the intellect, the will, and the appetites more broadly—for this is what one would expect of any Aristotelian or Thomist. It is rather that dignity is not cast as an ontological object but as a set of qualities to be attained and achieved in the workplace. It is because dignity is a quality that business ethics is so imperative: Business must be organized to help man attain these qualities of dignity. Sometimes one’s role in business affirms these qualities. Workers in the “knowledge economy” use their intellects, are expected to manage themselves, and can well expect that their work environment and their salaries will permit human flourishing for them and their families. However, some jobs are simply not like this. Being a member of a team working at 14 Pope John Paul II, Laborem Exercens (1981), no. 15; hereafter. 15 For a brilliant treatment of dignity as quality, see Aurel Kolnai, “Dignity,” Philos- ophy 51 (1976): 251–71. 16 An interesting account of dignity as an ontological object can be found in Josef Seifert, What is Life? (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1997), chapter 4. Seifert’s theory of dignity contrasts significantly with that of Kolnai, but, as will become clear, I think John Paul II’s business ethics rather favors Kolnai’s approach. 17 Laborem Exercens, no. 15; Paul VI, Populorum Progressio, no. 28. 18 Laborem Exercens, no. 23. Business Ethics and Catholic Social Thought 23 a fast food restaurant requires little to no initiative, is highly regularized, and one’s function is completely managed.This work as such cannot affirm human dignity. It is not enough just to say, “But the workers still have their human dignity for dignity is an ontological object!” John Paul II was concerned about the ethics of business organization because dignity—as the English langauge makes quite clear—can be impaired, destroyed, and willfully thrown away.19 For this reason, Catholic social thought has argued that workers who perform a function will then require a role in the overall management order if their intellects and wills are to be engaged.20 In an extremely interesting article, David Herrera describes how this requirement of Catholic social thought is met in the business organization of the Spanish cooperative Mondragón.21 At Mondragón the workers own the various businesses that make up the cooperative, all major management decisions are vetted by the workers, and management cannot gain more than an 8:1 advantage in pay over the least paid member of the cooperative. He describes a dramatic contrast between the democratic equality of Mondragón’s business organization and the hierarchy and inequality of the contemporary “neo-American” corporation. Obviously, John Paul II must have found the move to a “knowledge economy” very satisfying, but the basic business environment in the United States, whether family-run businesses or corporations, is hostile to ideas of worker participation in management or the democratic equality of Mondragón’s ownership and pay structure. However, it is crucial to recognize that the inequalities of the contemporary “neo-American” corporation are not merely a matter of thoughtlessness or heartlessness.To use Scheler’s language, it is a matter of an ethos and “an order of preference” that is not merely a cultural phenomenon but has a remarkable philosophical and ethical basis that aspires to affirm some values central to Catholic social thought, namely, liberty, pluralism, justice, and even constitutional order. From a comparison of Mondragón and the typical American corporation we can see that two streams within Catholic social thought are in tension: the need for business organization to serve both equality and dignity. It is typically assumed that these two easily map the one onto the other.Yet this is very far from clear. A democratic organizational model is inevitably one that relies on the idea of function whilst 19 Cf. St.Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, II–II, q. 64, a. 2, ad 3. 20 Laborem Exercens, no. 14. 21 D. Herrera, “Laborem Exercens, ‘Traditional’ Organizations and the Democratic Mondragón Model,” Work as Key to the Social Question: The Great Social and Economic Transformations and the Subjective Dimension of Work (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2002), 235–53. 24 G. J. McAleer the “neo-American” is a promotion of privilege and the idea of roles: But it is the latter that fosters dignity, not the former. In fact, here there is more than a simple tension between values—which is a real enough problem!— there is also an exclusion built into the idea of dignity that prohibits the equality provided by the idea of function. In a fascinating reflection on the difference between role and function, Chantal Delsol argues that not everyone is equal to the same role and that these inequalities are essential to the very idea of what it is to be a person.22 In the idea of a role, comments Delsol, there is the original notion of person, the playing of a part in theatre with its irreducible particularity.As a rather critical friend of the Enlightenment, Delsol argues that there is real value in the idea of the function and its creation of individuals as opposed to persons:The idea did liberate whole classes, especially women, from confined, invariant roles in the social world. As a Catholic theorist and mother of five, however, she is equally eloquent that the abolition of roles is not only absurd (when your mother needs to go to the hospital can you really just call a cab?) but pernicious to ideas of personal uniqueness. A fundamental threat to Catholic values is subjectivism, but the idea of function and the equality it brings in its wake is a formal equivalent to subjectivism: It includes the elimination of the social fabric that otherwise emerges from the idea that not everyone can do the same tasks, that not everyone is equal to every task. Indeed, as Delsol points out, moral obligation is attached to roles whilst the essential substitutability of individuals in any function destroys any sense duty. One recent contributor to the voluminous literature on leadership has recently argued that business managers need to model themselves on the early Jesuits. If there is to be moral management of business, Chris Lowney argues,23 then a disciplining similar to that taught to the Jesuits is necessary. It is an implication of this use of early Jesuit priests as exemplars that managers are to be bearers of roles not functions. If Catholic social thought must be understood in the egalitarian way that Herrera believes, and there are elements within the tradition that point in this direction, then the mission of the Church to protect persons will be impaired. Evangelization of business requires the inequality of roles and power that typifies “neo-American” hierarchical corporate structure. Such business organization is required, I would argue, if the tradition of the Church’s moral realism is to be maintained. Rejecting hierarchy one 22 Chantal Delsol, Icarus Fallen:The Search for Meaning in an Uncertain World (Wilm- ington, DE: ISI Books, 2003), chapter 13. 23 An ex-Jesuit and former high-ranking manager of J. P. Morgan, Lowney’s book is Heroic Leadership: Best Practices from a 450-Year-Old Company that Changed the World (Chicago: Loyola Press, 2003). Business Ethics and Catholic Social Thought 25 necessarily rejects the vantage point needed if the priorities within the field of values and reality are to be properly appreciated. In a wonderful example, phenomenologist Aurel Kolnai (1900–1973) describes what happens when one climbs from a plain up a mountain and comes by a commanding vision of the landscape in which one had previously moved around with little understanding of its true contours. The phenomenon of “height” and its realization in the social order—whether this be elevation to the bench or high management—is really to inculcate structurally a discrimination in which order and the relationship between values can be observed.The social distinction that separates people—a basic phenomenon in commercial society, according to Smith24—enables distinctions amongst values to be clearly recognized; the diversity that issues from this is essential to Catholic social thought. Supporting hierarchy in business is not separable, I would argue, from the imperative of maintaining diversity within authority in the broader social order.The cultural crisis of our times, the culture of death, has occurred because “progressive democracy” (Kolnai) has increasingly rejected the distinction between public and private authority. In matters respecting abortion and euthanasia, it is now dogma amongst progressives that private individuals are free to exercise lethal authority that was once the provenance of constitutional government. It is because the diversity and hierarchy amongst authorities is rejected that the same people who insist upon the private authority to exercise lethal force against others also believe that government does not have the authority (“not in my name,” as the slogan goes) to kill in matters of war and capital punishment. Aquinas insisted upon these distinctions in his treatise on homicide in the Summa II–II, q. 64, and John Paul II in Evangelium Vitae reaffirmed Thomas’s teaching. Although John Paul II made the argument there that capital punishment was no longer applicable—technology restrains its use—there is no suggestion that constitutional government no longer has the authority to hand down capital punishment for certain crimes.The social philosophy of the Church will need to acknowledge, I think, that the principles that lead to the hierarchy between public and private authority are also those that make hierarchy and roles in business necessary. In conclusion, whilst certain kinds of labor in America sustain human dignity, other kinds do not and, if I can put it this way, and hopefully not too enigmatically, not without reason. Smith, of course, is a theorist of inequality, just as Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Burke, Nietzsche, and Scheler are, all in their different ways. An implication of Smith’s work is that 24 Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments,50–58. 26 G. J. McAleer inequality is constitutive of dignity as a quality.25 In suggesting the need for a fresh appropriation of Smith, I do not mean to imply that there is a contradiction at the heart of Catholic social thought—not at all. The argument presented here is to recall a moral realism (appreciated by John Paul II) that unless dignity be understood as a quality there is no purchase for business ethics. Business ethics is an attempt to bring about as much dignity in the workplace as there can be. And here one cannot be utopian. Evangelization must have an Augustinian tone:26 The Church must seek to moderate the diminishment of dignity that can occur and does occur in commercial life, but realism requires that the Church think in terms of moderation and not extirpation. And, of course, by realism, I am not talking of the knee-jerk realism of the person who says, “Ethics is not about the real world. It’s nice in theory but won’t work in practice.” Moral realism is the insight that reality and value stand intimately linked albeit in tension, that there is a landscape and a geology of values throughout reality with certain constants, gradations, emphases, and limitations.The Christian love of persons cannot ignore the Smithian love of beauty, nor expect to supplant its inequalities. Evangelization must happen within this “manifold” wherein values of beauty and person both limit and illuminate one another. The manifold includes liberty, cleanliness, justice, utility, loyalty, equality, efficiency, integrity, and many other values, and only excludes evil. It might be an unhappy fact, but surely not an immorality, that some jobs do not affirm human dignity as a quality: Such jobs are not thereby evil jobs.The moral and the dignified are part of the manifold of value but do not absolutely overlap, or overlay, one another. I draw this point from Aurel Kolnai, and it is one, I think, of the utmost importance. 27 It is a point that draws much from Augustine and Aquinas, as well as Scheler, and it is a point found in Adam Smith and one in continuity with basic insights of John Paul II’s business ethics, as well. John Paul II has expressed reservations about Scheler’s ethics,28 but his business ethics remains thoroughly rooted in Catholic realism: An ethics of business organization only makes sense if dignity is thought of 25 Ibid., 50–58. 26 For why this must be so, please see my Ecstatic Morality and Sexual Politics: A Catholic and Antitotalitarian Theory of the Body (New York: Fordham University Press, 2005). 27 Please see Early Ethical Writings of Aurel Kolnai, trans. F. Dunlop (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2002), 59–60. 28 Karol Wojtyla, “On the Metaphysical and Phenomenological Basis of the Moral Norm in the Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas and Max Scheler,” in Person and Community (New York: Peter Lang, 1993), 73–94. Business Ethics and Catholic Social Thought 27 as a quality and not an invariant ontological object.Yet, if this is so, it is necessary for all of us interested in the Church’s new evangelization to live up to the standards imposed by this moral realism. If personal values are served by the concept of role then inequality will have to be acknowledged as part of the social order, including business organization. A lot of work is required in Catholic business ethics, and some of it might be discomforting, but resources abound in the Catholic tradition, and the basic moral tenor of Catholic social thought is thoroughly sound and N&V equal to the task. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 4, No. 1 (2006): 29–54 29 Fallible Teachings and the Assistance of the Holy Spirit Reflections on the Ordinary Magisterium in Connection with the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian* G IOVANNI S ALA , SJ Hochschule für Philosophie Munich, Germany From the Missionary Command to the Magisterium of the Church M ATTHEW CONCLUDES his Gospel with the missionary mandate of the Risen Jesus to the Eleven: “Go therefore and make disciples of all nations, baptizing them . . . [and] teaching them to observe all that I have commanded you; and lo, I am with you always, to the close of the age” (Mt 28:19–20). During his earthly life, Jesus directed his public ministry, and particularly his proclamation of the Kingdom of God, to all men. However, at the same time he gave special attention to a group of disciples, the Twelve. Mark narrates the call of the Twelve in the following way: “And he went up on the mountain, and called to him those whom he desired. . . . And he appointed twelve, to be with him and to be sent out to preach” (Mk 3:13–14). The Acts of the Apostles recognizes a teaching authority belonging to the Apostles and to those whom the Apostles gradually associated with themselves in the work of founding and guiding Christian communities. It is because of this that Acts refers to the gospel by which these communities * Translation by Ivo Coelho, SDB, of “Insegnamenti ‘fallibili’ e assistenza dello Spir- ito Santo. Riflessioni sul Magistero ordinario in connessione con l’Istruzione su ‘la vocazione ecclesiale del teologo,’ ” Rassegna di Teologia 34 (1993): 516–543; also published in Kontroverse Theologie (Festschrift in Honor of Giovanni Sala, SJ), eds. Ulrich Lehner and Ronald K.Tacelli (Bonn: Nova et Vetera, 2005), 237–58. 30 Giovanni Sala, SJ were living, not vaguely as the teaching of the community, but rather as the “doctrine of the Apostles” (Acts 2:42).The council of Jerusalem is a further testimony that the early Church recognized in the Apostles the authority for resolving questions of doctrine and of discipline (Acts 15). The second and third centuries have left us numerous testimonies that the “apostolic succession” was considered a criterion for establishing the true doctrine of Christ.The pride that many churches took in their lists of bishops going back in an unbroken line to the apostles is a proof that the early Church recognized an essential connection between those “sent” and the Good News of Jesus Christ. In the process of development and clarification that the hierarchical constitution of the Church underwent, there is discernible from the very beginning a ministry of teaching, regarded as the official and normative proclamation of Revelation, and distinct from other forms of teaching, exhortation, and admonition, as for example the prophetic charisms about which St. Paul speaks to the Corinthians (1 Cor 14:5). Theological reflection on such an authoritative proclamation of the Gospel has given rise to the doctrine of the ecclesial magisterium—a magisterium linked to the ordination of successors to the apostles, one which therefore participates in the sacramental character of the Church. This is not the place to present a detailed exposition of the theology of the magisterium. The First and Second Vatican Councils have given an authoritative formulation to this theological doctrine. In this essay I wish rather to draw attention to that perspective under which the magisterium is often seen in the current debate and to the conception of the magisterium that derives from such a perspective. In my opinion an adequate understanding of the problem demands that we begin from the magisterium as a constitutive element of the Church, having the function of guiding and conserving it in the truth. From this it will then be possible to establish the significance of the well-known distinction between ordinary and extraordinary magisterium. Ordinary and Extraordinary Magisterium The Church, which the pastoral letters refer to as “the pillar and bulwark of the truth” (1 Tm 3:15), is the place of saving truth, and this not in the sense of a fossilized conservation of the preaching of Jesus but rather in the sense of a living presence of this preaching. Such a living presence and the corresponding actualization of Revelation is the work of the Holy Spirit who is the soul of the Church. Now in the course of history, tensions arise within the Church regarding the teaching of Jesus, caused by the emergence of new questions, formulated with conceptual and The Ordinary Magisterium 31 linguistic tools derived from diverse and changing cultures. Because of their content and implications, these tensions can become such as to call for definitive doctrinal decision, a binding “Yes” or “No” in response to a precise question.The first ecumenical council held at Nicea in A.D. 325, which discussed the question,“Who is he whom the New Testament calls the Son?” is a classic example of a situation that involved the very survival of the Christian faith.The council resolved this situation by defining Jesus as being “consubstantial with the Father.” Subsequent theological reflection has seen in this response the first dogma in the strict sense, and the first case of the exercise of that teaching office of the Church that came to be called the extraordinary magisterium. This magisterium is the supreme and, in a certain sense, timely exercise of a magisterial mission that touches the entire Church in its life in the truth. This extraordinary exercise of the magisterium does not embrace the whole life of the Church in the truth, nor does it exhaust the service to the truth proper to the successors of the apostles. Rather, it exercises a hermeneutical function that is supplementary to the ordinary and permanent mission entrusted to the pope and bishops of guiding the Church into the unity of truth. It represents the frontline of the journey toward the truth in which the Church is continually engaged. In order to indicate the specific character of this exercise of the magisterium, theology speaks of an “infallible” magisterium. A dogmatic definition issued by an ecumenical council, or an ex cathedra decision of the supreme pontiff, are actualizations of the promise of Christ to preserve his Church in the truth, and to lead her to the fullness of truth ( Jn 16:13) by means of a charism of infallibility in which the Church places her complete confidence and which, in decisive moments of her history, she has always experienced anew, without however being able to manage it and dispose of it according to merely human calculations. Seen from the perspective of saving truth, which is a constitutive element of the Church, the adjective “extraordinary” is not completely appropriate. What is extraordinary instead is the modality of the proposition enunciated with the intention of deciding in a definitive manner some point of Christian doctrine, with the purpose of preserving the Church indefectibly in the revealed truth.The extraordinary magisterium represents, therefore, the supreme expression, exceptional insofar as dependent on particular historical circumstances, of a finality to which the whole of the magisterium constantly addresses itself. At any rate, the term “extraordinary” suggests the existence of an “ordinary” magisterium. In reality the ordinary magisterium represents the usual means through which the Good News is announced and Giovanni Sala, SJ 32 received in the Church.At the basis of this magisterium is the promise of the Lord to his apostles to assist them “always, to the close of the age” (Mt 28:20). John intends precisely this assistance when in the farewell discourse he speaks of the “Paraclete” (the advocate, the one who helps; Jn 16:7), and of the “Spirit of truth” ( Jn 16:13) who will teach the disciples everything and will bring to their remembrance what Jesus had said to them ( Jn 14:16 and 26; 15:26). In recent years the discussion regarding the ordinary magisterium has intensified, practically replacing that of the seventies regarding the extraordinary and infallible magisterium, which had been occasioned partly by the centenary of the Vatican definition.The new discussion has its own very precise ecclesial context, which we can establish broadly by a double reference. First, there is the profound crisis that has affected the Church in the decades after Vatican II; second (and this is really part of the same crisis) there is the questioning of the moral norms traditionally taught by the Church and of the competence of the magisterium in moral matters.We must note, of course, that it is not solely in the sphere of morals that the magisterium is being challenged, though in this area, which affects every believer in a more immediate and existential manner, the polemic has been given massive publicity by the media. In this context may be placed the fact that in recent years the pastors of the Church, and in particular the Holy Father, have repeatedly raised their voices in defense of the ordinary magisterium as an element essential to the Church, and which therefore is not under the dominion of any human authority in the Church.The Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian (Donum veritatis) issued by the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith on the feast of the Ascension 1990, is also to be situated in the same context.1 In the pages that follow I do not intend to give a detailed commentary on the text of the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian. I would rather like to examine its relevance with regard to the debate on the ordinary magisterium. The Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian discusses this issue at length, with the aim of clarifying the proper task of the pastors of the Church as teachers of the faith, the way in which this task differs from the teaching of the theologian, and the relationship between the theologian and the successors of the Twelve. More particularly I wish to examine the sense in which Catholic doctrine, as reconfirmed by the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, 1 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian (1990). The Ordinary Magisterium 33 recognizes an assistance of the Holy Spirit proper to the bishops in the ordinary exercise of their mission as teachers of the faith.This does not, of course, constitute the whole of Catholic doctrine regarding the ordinary magisterium; it is however a key element, such that an erroneous or insufficient understanding of it leads inevitably to an erroneous or insufficient conception of the magisterium itself. The Magisterium and the Assistance of the Holy Spirit As a point of reference for my inquiry I take an article published by a theologian from Munich insofar as it takes up directly the question of an alleged particular assistance of the Holy Spirit to the magisterium of the Church.2 The author approaches the question whether and in what measure the ordinary magisterium enjoys a particular assistance of the Holy Spirit, by beginning from the extraordinary magisterium.This approach is in itself legitimate; in point of fact, however, it easily leads to a distortion of the proper tasks of the magisterium of the Church, insofar as it tends to identify the magisterium tout court with infallibility, and to thus eliminate the ordinary magisterium on the grounds of its not being infallible. Catholic doctrine holds that the magisterium of the Church enjoys a special assistance of the Holy Spirit. This is verified without a doubt, according to Weger, every time an ecumenical council or the pope in his role as head of the apostolic college infallibly defines a doctrine,3 in the 2 K. H. Weger, “Wie weit reicht der Schutz des Heiligen Geistes? Einige Fragen zur Unfehlbarkeit in der katholischen Kirche,” Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung ( July 28, 1990: 8). The article has been included, together with thirteen others, in Streitgespräch um Theologie und Lehramt: Die Instruktion über die kirchliche Berufung des Theologen in der Diskussion, ed. P. Hünermann and D. Mieth (Frankfurt am Main: Knecht-Verlag, 1991), 108–17 (in the course of my reflections I will refer to the pages of this publication). The articles differ among themselves in content and viewpoint; the balance, however, is in favor of those that are strongly negative, and many of these make use of a language that is manipulative and journalistic.Thus, for example, Christian Duquoc, observes that the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian addresses itself to “party intellectuals” (179) with the intention of “resurrecting procedures which seemed to have disappeared with the states of the Eastern bloc” (182). Such expressions are certainly efficacious in discrediting the document in the eyes of a public not specialized in theological matters, but they do not offer elements for a serious theological dialogue. Accordingly I will not concern myself with such arguments. 3 Weger speaks of infallible doctrines (“Wie weit reicht der Schutz,” 109).This terminology, which is not found in the theological tradition and does not correspond to that used by Vatican I, may be traced to one of the confusions that Hans Küng introduced in his book Unfehlbar? Eine Anfrage (Zürich: Benziger, 1970), and 34 Giovanni Sala, SJ case therefore of the so-called extraordinary or infallible magisterium. From here the theologians who argue in the manner just outlined continue in this way:What must be said about the assistance of the Holy Spirit when the bishops or the pope propose teachings that are of themselves not infallible, nor claim to be such, but are rather fallible in principle and therefore capable of being objectively erroneous? Once the question has been formulated in this way, it seems easy to pass to the conclusion that in this type of pronouncement the magisterium does not enjoy a proper assistance of the Holy Spirit. As evidence for such a conclusion that the ordinary magisterium lacks a proper assistance of the Holy Spirit (that is, an assistance that goes beyond that promised by Jesus to the Church as a whole),Weger points to the incontestable fact that the magisterium has repeatedly fallen into error in the exercise of its office. Surely, he concludes, no one would attribute such errors to the Holy Spirit (“Wie weit reicht der Schutz,” 110). Let us examine more closely this argument, which is typical of theologians who want to distance themselves from the (ordinary) magisterium of the Church. 1. Jesus has promised the assistance of the Holy Spirit to the Church as a whole. The most explicit magisterial text in this connection is found in the constitution Lumen gentium of Vatican II, in the discussion regarding the “people of God.”The council affirms that the whole body of the faithful who have an anointing that comes from the Holy One [cf. Jn 2:20 and 27] cannot err in matters of belief.This characteristic is shown in the supernatural appreciation of the faith (sensus fidei) of the whole people, when,“from the bishwhich was then taken up by other theologians. If we wish to express ourselves more exactly, however, it is not propositions that are infallible or fallible, but rather the act by which some particular subject makes an affirmation;“infallible” or “fallible” designates therefore a property of the subject who affirms or defines. A proposition or doctrine in itself is either true or false. The tendency that underlies the terminology of Küng is that of conceiving infallibility as a sort of increase in truth. Now this is nonsensical insofar as truth is already of itself absolute, an exclusion of the contradictory proposition on the basis of the principle of excluded middle. As we will see in what follows, the truth of a proposition is not connected necessarily with infallibility, and therefore does not in every case call for a subject who is infallible. However this is not the decisive point in the question under discussion. One could speak, for the sake of brevity, of infallible propositions, provided one means the proposition in its subjective aspect as the intentional act of an affirming subject. The Ordinary Magisterium 35 ops to the last of the faithful” they manifest a universal consent in matters of faith and morals. (no. 12) 2. This assistance of the Holy Spirit, insofar as it is promised to the whole Church, evidently holds good also for those members of the faithful who form part of the magisterium. The passage from St. Augustine cited by the council explicitly mentions the bishops. But the text of the council has more to say: By this appreciation of the faith, aroused and sustained by the Spirit of truth, the People of God, guided by the sacred teaching authority (magisterium), and obeying it, receives not the mere word of man, but truly the Word of God [cf. 1 Thes 2:13[, the faith once for all delivered to the saints [cf. Jude 3]. (no. 12) The magisterium, concretely the pope and the bishops, are introduced here not merely as members of the people of God and for that reason enjoying the assistance of the Holy Spirit; rather they are recognized as having, in addition, a special function as guides with the task of conserving the whole Church in the truth. Such a task entrusted to the magisterium implies a charism of truth proper to it: a special assistance of the Holy Spirit.There exists therefore an inseparable connection between the sensus fidei of the people of God and the guidance of this people by the magisterium of the Church (cf. Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, no. 35). 3. It is not possible here to examine the important doctrine of the sensus fidelium.4 This doctrine of the council, under different names, has a long history behind it.This is not surprising because it is really an expression of that abiding in the truth of which the Church has had a clear consciousness from the very beginning. But the ecclesial situation of today calls for a delicate clarification. Already before the council Yves Congar had noted that, notwithstanding the great importance of the sensus fidelium in the life of the Church, too much must not be attributed to it as far as its concrete realization and expression is concerned.5 It is quite possible that the sensus fidelium does not always correspond to the form and determination willed it 4 Cf.The excellent study of L. Scheffczyk, “Sensus fidelium–Zeugnis in der Kraft der Gemeinschaft,” in Internationale Zeitschrift “Communio” 16 (1987): 420–33. 5 Y. Congar, Lay People in the Church. A Study for a Theology of Laity (Westminster, MD:The Newman Press, 1965), 288. 36 Giovanni Sala, SJ by God. This makes it necessary to distinguish in the clearest possible way between the work of the Spirit in the faithful and erroneous developments in the life of the members of the Church. The sensus fidei is not to be identified with “public opinion,” which today, in the age of the mass media, can undergo distortions not only in civil society but also within the Church; it is not the result of majority decisions, nor can it be determined through opinion polls. It is the result rather of the promise of Christ to his Church; it is the capacity of judgment and of witness of believers, of those who live without compromise in the community of the Church, which is the place of the presence of the Spirit. Such an idea is not the fruit of an elitist attitude (such an attitude has no place in the realm of grace), but rather of an objective appraisal of the essence of the faith. In 1969 Karl Rahner had observed: [T]he present-day situation of the Church is one in which we are faced with the phenomenon of individuals only partially identifying with her, and so too of varying very greatly in the degree in which they do so identify themselves with the Church. Now in this situation there is a very real danger that under cover of the watchword of democracy many individuals will be carried away from the Church into positions which are un-Christian and un-Catholic.6 In its turn the declaration Mysterium Ecclesiae (1973) of the Congregation for the Doctrine of Faith had observed that although the magisterium profits from the contemplation, life, and study of the faithful, its task cannot be reduced to one of ratifying the consensus at which these have already arrived; rather, in the interpretation and explanation of the Word of God, whether written or handed down, it can anticipate and demand such a consensus. [no. 2, emphasis added] In the confusion, uncertainties, and divisions of a Church without consensus, the magisterium has the power and the obligation to propose the word of God, which both demands and grounds the consensus of all the faithful. 4. Not only in its discussion on the participation of the people of God in the prophetic office of Christ, but repeatedly also elsewhere, the constitution Lumen gentium recognizes a particular assistance of the 6 K. Rahner,“Das kirchliche Lehramt in der heutigen Autoritätskrise,” in Schriften zur Theologie, vol. 9 (Einsiedeln: Benziger, 1970), 356. The Ordinary Magisterium 37 Holy Spirit to the magisterium. In the words of the constitution Dei Verbum,“the task of giving an authentic interpretation of the Word of God, whether in its written form or in the form of Tradition, has been entrusted to the living teaching office of the Church alone. Its authority in this matter is exercised in the name of Jesus Christ” (no. 10, emphasis added). In number 25, dedicated to the magisterium, Lumen gentium affirms that the work of the magisterium, whether ordinary or extraordinary, takes place “in the light of the Holy Spirit,” “under the assistance of the Holy Spirit.”With respect to the ordinary magisterium in particular, it is the doctrine of the council that the faithful, for their part, are obliged to submit to their bishops’ decision, made in the name of Christ, in matters of faith and morals, and to adhere to it with a ready and respectful allegiance of mind. This loyal submission of the will and intellect must be given, in a special way, to the authentic teaching authority of the Roman pontiff, even when he does not speak ex cathedra. [emphasis added] It is therefore Catholic doctrine, proposed once again by Vatican II, that the magisterium of the Church in its entirety—including the ordinary magisterium—enjoys a special assistance of the Holy Spirit. It is this teaching that, in my opinion, leads to a more adequate understanding of Catholic teaching on the magisterium, rather than the doctrine of the extraordinary magisterium, the exercise of which remains in a certain sense exceptional. The “Fallible” Teachings of the Magisterium We have seen that for the theologians who deny that the ordinary magisterium enjoys a special assistance of the Holy Spirit, the medium probationis lies in the non-infallible character of what the pope and the bishops ordinarily teach.The point to be clarified is whether there really is such a connection between non-infallibility (= fallibility) of the acts of the ordinary magisterium and the absence of a special assistance of the Holy Spirit. An example may help obtain a better grasp of the question, keeping in mind the precautions necessary for any argument that begins from natural realities (and such a procedure is inevitable for us human beings!) to arrive at some understanding of what we profess in faith. The example is this: It is as inadequate and misleading to define the ordinary magisterium as a “fallible” magisterium (that is, through a negative definition) as to define human knowing in terms of its fallibility. Human knowing is the achievement of an intelligent and rational intentionality oriented by its very nature to being and therefore to truth. In its 38 Giovanni Sala, SJ concrete functioning this intentionality may well miss its objective, but this fact does not justify a methodical and universal doubt, which far from providing a more adequate access to truth, leads rather to an emptying of the mind of all knowledge—untrue as well as true.The case of the magisterium is analogous. If the magisterium is, within the hierarchical constitution of the Church, the means used by the Lord for maintaining his Church in the truth, then we must admit that it is by its nature oriented toward the truth. But since this is not realized by means of a scientific knowledge given to the successors of the apostles, which would make them superior to the faithful from a human point of view, it must be said that their ability to teach the truth in matters of faith is founded ultimately on a particular grace of state, granted them in conformity with the general principle in the order of salvation according to which there is a proper grace corresponding to every mission—a grace of state, which in this case may conveniently be called a “charism of truth.”7 What is the meaning of the “fallible” teaching on which some theologians insist, which results in the elimination of the ordinary magisterium? Taken in itself this term does not say anything about the effective status of the truth of the proposition in question: This may be either true or false. It is a question of a neutral qualification, which says only that the proposition originates from a subject who in every case, or at least in the specific realm of knowledge to which this proposition belongs, does not possess a criterion of infallibility. An “infallible” subject on the contrary would be one who in some particular realm of knowledge, or else in all realms, could not but make true judgments, that is, judgments therefore that are necessarily true. Now the criterion of infallibility8 is not the only criterion of truth. It is quite possible to possess a criterion of truth without being infallible. Such is the case for us human beings in all the concrete judgments of fact through which we arrive at knowledge of reality.9 For example, the judgment,“The Gulf war lasted six weeks,” is a 7 Cf. Ireneus, Adversus haereses, 4, 26.2:“Qui cum episcopatus successione charisma veritatis certum . . . acceperunt.”The expression is used also by Vatican I (DS, no. 3071), and is taken up by Vatican II in the constitution Dei Verbum, no. 8, without an indication however of the source. 8 It is not necessary to explain here exactly what constitutes this criterion of infallibility and which are the subjects for whom it is valid. 9 By a “concrete judgment of fact” I mean a judgment that is the term of a process of knowing that begins from data of experience, whether external or internal; a judgment therefore that is not based on mere hypothesis or convention, as in the case of hypothetico-deductive systems. Cf. B. Lonergan, Insight.A Study of Human Understanding (London: Longmans, Green and Co. Ltd., 1957), 281–83; also G. Sala, “Intentionalitat contra Intuition,” in Theologie und Philosophie 59 (1984): 259–63. The Ordinary Magisterium 39 judgment that is in fact true, and insofar as it is true, it absolutely excludes its opposite.This judgment is the result of an exercise of my intentionality that is in fact correct. But I could also have made use of my intentionality in a way that did not conform to its immanent laws, resulting thus in an erroneous judgment. Now all my judgments, insofar as they do not arise from an infallible subject, may possibly be false, and are therefore “fallible.” But this says nothing about the truth of the particular judgments that I have made.They may be true or false; and I am completely certain that at least some of them are true. At the root of the argument, which from the affirmation of “fallible teachings” concludes to the absence of an assistance of the Holy Spirit, lies the surreptitious passage from “fallible” teachings, in the sense explained to “false” teachings.And false teachings certainly cannot be the fruit of an illumination of the Holy Spirit! Once fallible teachings (and such are all the teachings of the ordinary magisterium!) are in fact made equivalent to erroneous teachings, the general thesis that the ordinary magisterium does not involve a special assistance of the Holy Spirit becomes altogether plausible. This sophism reveals the import of the misleading definition that takes “fallible” propositions as the defining characteristic of the ordinary magisterium: In the course of the argument, such propositions are taken as actually “false.” Such an equivocation is favored also by the erroneous epistemological conception of which we spoke above, which attributes infallibility and fallibility to the judgment rather than to the subject. Now nobody can deny that a fallible subject may be able to express judgments, which are true. Where then lies the difference between the natural orientation to truth that all men have and the orientation toward supernatural truth that belongs to the (ordinary) magisterium of the Church? The difference lies in the assistance of the Holy Spirit and therefore in a supernatural “illumination.” If one admits the existence of an ordinary magisterium—and this is doctrina communis—and therefore the existence of a special magisterial mission entrusted to some in the Church (otherwise we would not have a specific ministry), I do not see how this can be understood if not as a service to the truth in virtue of a special assistance of the Holy Spirit. In other words: We can speak of a teaching ministry in the strict sense only if this belongs exclusively to some in the Church, and if its exercise occurs in virtue of a specific assistance of the Spirit of truth. In sum, we can fix the salient points of Weger’s argument in the following manner:The ordinary magisterium is a fallible authority—the authority of fallible teachings is equivalent to the authority of erroneous teachings—erroneous teachings cannot be attributed to the Holy Spirit— 40 Giovanni Sala, SJ the ordinary magisterium does not enjoy a particular assistance of the Holy Spirit—there does not exist an ordinary magisterium. For the theologians who from “fallible” teachings conclude to a negation of the assistance of the Holy Spirit with regard to such teachings, there remains only the so-called extraordinary magisterium of the few popes and ecumenical councils that have either defined or will define a dogma. Consequently it becomes impossible for them to understand why, according to Catholic doctrine and in particular according to Lumen gentium, no. 25, the faithful ought to adhere to the teaching of the magisterium with a “loyal submission of the will and intellect” (religioso animi obsequio).This is an assent founded on theological faith, an “obedience of faith” in the words of St. Paul to the Romans (1:5, 16:26). Evidently, such obedience is not possible to those who see in the ordinary magisterium a fallible authority rather than a service to the truth founded on a supernatural illumination. If one separates the ordinary teaching of the bishops from the work of the Holy Spirit, then this teaching has as much weight as the rational arguments put forward in its favor. “Now to evaluate such arguments is the sacred right of every Christian! On this basis, religious assent can mean only that the documents of the Church must be studied with respect. But, whatever the pope says, the discussion must go on!”10 It is useful to mention also another consequence of this reduction of the magisterium to a scientific authority on the same level, as a matter of principle, as other such authorities. Given such an understanding, the service of guiding the Church entrusted to the successors of the apostles becomes separated from the truth—it becomes a guidance of the Church that is purely pragmatic. Authentic Magisterium and Theological Argumentation The denial of a special divine assistance proper to the magisterium raises the question regarding the specific role of the pope and bishops, and therefore also the question regarding the difference between the teaching of the bishops and that of theologians.The logic of the theological position under consideration suggests the following reply:The pope and the bishops may speak in the Church on the strength of the rational arguments that they are able to put forward in support of their teachings.This implies that there is no real difference between theology as a science and an authentic magisterium; in fact, there really does not exist any such authentic magisterium, or a hierarchical authority endowed with a supernatural power proper to 10 A. Laun, “Das Urteil des Gewissens—Richtige und falsche Subjektivitat,” in Ethos und Menschenbild. Zur Überwindung der Krise der Moral, ed. M. Rhonheimer et al. (St. Ottilien: EOS Verlag, 1989), 16 ff. The Ordinary Magisterium 41 it. There would exist only a reasoning that is rational as to its cognitive principle and theological as to its content11—a reasoning that is, in principle, open equally to all men. In the Church, as in any human enterprise, the decisive factor would be competence.And when the specialists are not in agreement, the only way out would be recourse to the decisions of the majority. A. Laun has described the role of such a magisterium in the following way, with particular reference to moral teaching: All the same the Church may intervene in the discussion regarding concrete norms of behavior, not however with its specific authority founded on the Holy Spirit, but only with its arguments as a partner with the same rights as the others. One could say: the pope may return to the University, but only if he first takes off his papal miter.12 The case of the teaching of Paul VI in the encyclical Humanae vitae is emblematic for the Catholic doctrine of an authentic magisterium. It shows in a dramatic manner what it means for the pope to take a doctrinal decision with full consciousness both of the authority given to Peter and to his successors and of his personal responsibility before Jesus Christ. The task which the Lord assigns to each of his disciples has a strictly personal character, such that the one concerned can be substituted neither by an anonymous commission of experts nor by a majority decision.This does not of course deny the opportuneness and even the moral necessity, in conformity with the historical and cultural situation, of having recourse to all available means for discovering the truth. It is not a relic of ancient times that in the Eucharistic prayer the celebrant explicitly mentions “our pope [name], our bishop [name],” just as the Gospels have left us the names of those to whom Jesus entrusted the mission of carrying his message to the ends of the earth. The proper nature of the teaching ministry of the bishops is linked in an essential manner to the sacramental character of the episcopate and therefore to the principle of the “apostolic succession,” which is really the uninterrupted succession in the sacrament of ordination.We have seen in the first section that the early Church used to consider as true the doctrines taught by those Churches in possession of a list of bishops going back without interruption to one of the apostles. This is not a purely historical question. The principle of the apostolic succession reflects the consciousness that the Church possesses a sacramental nature 11 Whether on the basis of these ecclesiological premises we can still speak of a Catholic theology, that is, of an intellectus fidei, is another question! 12 A. Laun, “Das Urteil des Gewissens,” 38. Giovanni Sala, SJ 42 proper to it. Because of this sacramental nature, the imposition of hands (ordination) and the ministry of teaching (authoritative testimony) form an intrinsic unity. For this reason the Catholic Church and the other churches that have preserved the reality of the apostolic succession “consider the insertion into the ecclesial ministry, realized through the imposition of hands with the invocation of the Holy Spirit, as the indispensable form for the transmission of the apostolic succession, which alone allows the Church to preserve in doctrine and in communion.”13 The sacramental character indicates the type of teaching proper to the magisterium: It is a teaching that does not originate in the preacher himself; it is neither a conquest of human intelligence, nor the expression of what some particular community thinks. Its origin is of a transcendent nature. It is not therefore the result of a merely extrinsic link that “the minister of the word [is] also the minister of the sacraments of faith, and first of all of the Eucharist.”14 An obscuring of the sacramental nature of ministry in the Church leads to an obscuring as much of the nature of the truth by which the Church lives as of the nature of the magisterium itself: Revelation tends to be reduced to truth within the limits of reason alone, and the magisterium to a service that is exclusively scholarly.15 From what has been said up to now, it follows that the magisterium and theology are situated on different planes and operate in different ways in their service to revealed truth.This does not detract from the fact that as a priest the theologian participates in the sacramental character of the proclamation of the Good News,16 and that as a teacher he receives from the Church the “canonical mission,” participating thus “in a certain sense . . . in the work of the magisterium to which he is linked by a juridical bond.”17 The Instruction speaks therefore of “mutual collaboration” between the magisterium and theology (part IV, A): “The living magisterium of the Church and theology, while having different gifts and functions, ultimately have the same goal: preserving the People of God in the truth which sets free.”18 It is a question of a reciprocal collaboration between different tasks: 13 International Theological Commission, “L’apostolicitá della Chiesa e la succes- sione apostolica,” in La Civiltá Cattolica 125 (1974) III, sec.VI. 14 Ibid., sec.V. Cf. Acts 2:47. 15 Regarding the sacramental nature of the magisterium, cf., besides the already mentioned document of the International Theological Commission, also the constitution Lumen gentium, no. 21. 16 This is true in the first place for the homily, which is an essential part of the liturgy. Cf. Codex Iuris Canonici (1984), canon 767, §1. 17 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, no. 22. 18 Ibid., no. 21. The Ordinary Magisterium 43 The magisterium proposes the doctrine of the apostles in an authentic manner, that is, in virtue of an authority received from Christ, while theology elaborates the same doctrine in a rational and reflective manner. The Brokenness of the Magisterium in the Pilgrim Church Once the existence of the magisterium of the bishops in union with Peter’s successor has been recognized, there arises once again the question about the errors into which this magisterium has fallen in the course of the centuries.This is precisely the reason why not a few theologians today hold a position that is in fact equivalent to a denial of the ordinary magisterium.19 Although strictly speaking history is not in a position to furnish any “demonstration” in favor of a theological doctrine, and much less of a dogma, a serious study of the history of the Church leads to the recognition 19 This is not the place to enter into a historico-theological examination of the errors attributed to the magisterium. It is striking however, as L. Scheffczyk has observed (“Die Freiheit des Glaubens bindet katholisches Forschen und Lehren. Zu einer Kritik an der romischen Instruktion über die kirchliche Berufung des Theologen,” in Deutsche Tagespost [January 19, 1991], 5f), that in this field those who challenge the magisterium capitalize on everything, without bothering to make those distinctions and differentiations that are necessary if one wants to have recourse to history with the purpose of demonstrating not only the fallibility of the magisterium, but also concretely, when and in what measure it allegedly led the faithful into error. Often recourse is made to historical institutions and customs that have no direct bearing on the faith as such; in other cases, it is a question of decisions that are not strictly of a doctrinal nature, but rather prudential directives with respect to exegetical hypotheses or new methods of research, which were in need of further perfecting before being used without danger to the faith. One may think, for example, of the judgments of the Pontifical Biblical Commission in the first decades of our century; while recognizing their limits and provisional nature, it cannot be denied today that they contributed to preserving Catholic theology, and with it the faithful, from the one-sidedness and excesses of the historical-critical method. But there is more. It is striking that while the theologians are so resolute in denouncing the shortcomings of the ecclesial magisterium, they rarely mention the errors into which theology has fallen in the course of the centuries (none of the critiques of the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian gathered in Hünermann and Mieth, Streitgespräch um Theologie und Lehramt [see note 3 above] contain so much as an allusion to this).Truth and justice demand that such errors be not passed over in silence, especially by those theologians who try to so inflate the importance and the necessity of theology as to show that it (that is, theology) is called to prevent or correct the errors of the magisterium.The outcome of such a dosing of criticism against the Church and of lack of self-criticism is the reversal of the relationship between magisterium and theology, not only from the theological but also from the historical viewpoint. On this point see also Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, no. 24. 44 Giovanni Sala, SJ of how positive and providential the work of the successors of the apostles has been down the centuries in preserving that saving truth by which the Church lives.With humility and gratitude, it is legitimate for the Catholic Christian to see in the innumerable divisions, reductions, deformations, and even negations of essential elements of Revelation in Christian communities outside the Catholic communion, a confirmation that the magisterium, both in its everyday exercise and in the “kairoi” of its extraordinary exercise, has functioned truly as an instrument through which Christ has maintained his Church in the truth and has allowed it, time and again, to actualize the one and enduring divine Revelation. It remains true, all the same, that in this ordinary service to Revelation, the magisterium has proved to be a “treasure” that we, the Church,“carry in vessels of clay” (cf. 2 Cor 4:7).The indefectible truth of God has been entrusted to men who, despite the grace and light which the Lord gives, remain fallible and sinful. In point of fact we are dealing here not with a unique case, but rather with something that corresponds to the incarnate structure of the Church, to its transitory status as a pilgrim Church. The Church, the community of eschatological salvation that has taken the place of the synagogue, is, in the period until the second coming of the Lord, also the assembly of believers that fails repeatedly and so is always called to conversion “in capite et in membris.” The Christian knows, or better believes, that Jesus assists his servants in the ministry of leading and of teaching.Therefore his attitude toward them is one of an obedience of faith, remembering the word of the Lord:“He who hears you, hears me” (Lk 10:16). But he also knows that these authentic witnesses of the Gospel remain fallible servants to whom the appeal to conversion is addressed, and that they have constantly to be “confirmed” so that they might fulfill the mission entrusted to them (cf. Lk 22:32). What attitude then should the believer have toward the vast body of teachings of the Church, which although binding are not properly speaking irreformable, insofar as they do not originate in a magisterial act that is formally infallible? To such a question there is no simple and univocal answer applicable like a recipe to all cases. But the indispensable presupposition in every case for finding the right response is an attitude of faith toward a magisterium willed by the Lord. From this attitude of faith, says the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, it follows that “the willingness to submit loyally to the teaching of the magisterium on matters per se not irreformable must be the rule” (no. 24).This willingness will lead to a search for the meaning and the reasons for the teaching itself. Such a search amounts to a retracing in faith of the way that the successors of the Apostles have earlier followed in virtue of the assis- The Ordinary Magisterium 45 tance of the Holy Spirit. But the same attitude of faith, precisely because it is not an ideological choice, equally implies loyalty and co-responsibility toward the truth of God, and therefore requires that the believer, in a filial and trustful dialogue with the pastors, penetrate deeper into the truth taught, and thus help purify it from one-sidedness, narrowness, and defects, even to the point of bringing to light erroneous elements present in a non-irreformable doctrinal decision of the magisterium. The obedience of faith that believers owe to those sent by the Lord does not imply the pretense of considering every word of the pope and bishops as absolutely guaranteed by the charism of infallibility. In this sense it is correct to speak of “fallible” teachings, teachings that could possibly turn out to be erroneous. In this same sense I spoke above of the incarnate and faulty character of the magisterium and of a Church journeying toward perfection. It is precisely this character that a part of contemporary theology refuses to recognize; instead, on the basis of a maximalist conception, it questions the magisterium in its non-infallible or ordinary exercise. As the article or Weger argues, “an illumination of the Holy Spirit should exclude all possible error.”20 The power of error, during the time of the Church, is broken but not completely overcome. But the obedience of faith toward the representatives of Christ, imperfect as they are, is not in vain.The choice between doctrines that are defined, and therefore to be accepted in faith, and doctrines that are not defined, and therefore, being fallible, to be rejected en masse or else considered as opinions having no greater value than what the individual faithful can know by himself, is arbitrary and ultimately impossible. It is not through such a choice that the Christian is able to remain in the fullness of truth. A growing adherence to saving truth is instead possible through a filial trust in the Church in which and with which the Christian believes, and therefore through a magnanimous acceptance of all that the Church teaches. If this acceptance is the fruit of theological faith, it will be marked by a sincere and open attitude, ready to recognize that the Spirit of truth operates even without the mediation of the magisterium and also outside the visible Church, and therefore ready to assume its own responsibility in that search for the truth in which the whole Church is engaged.This is true for every Christian, and in a particular way for the theologian in his “disinterested service to the community of the faithful.”21 The assent of the believer who receives the truth of God incarnated and concealed beneath aspects of this world that are transitory and even 20 Weger, “Wie weit reicht der Schutz,” 113. 21 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, no. 11. 46 Giovanni Sala, SJ false (cf. Gal 4:3–9) is of great religious significance.There is no need for a Catholic to claim absolute certitude for every word of his pastors, because he knows with St. Paul that “all things work for good with those who love God” (Rom 8:28).22 But precisely because this attitude of obedience arises not from a pathological need for security but out of respect for the truth, he is ready with intellectual honesty to bring his own contribution toward a fuller attainment of truth.The entire Church is also a learning Church, and the individual is called to participate in this movement of learning according to the post he occupies in the Church and in proportion to his personal gifts. The adequate basis for this service to a truth that is not a human achievement but rather a gift of God is precisely believing and “feeling with” the Church. And, adds the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian with reference to the proper task of the theologian,“a loyal spirit, animated by love for the Church” (no. 31). If this spirit is present, the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian will not be accused of being Utopian23 when it affirms that 22 A comparison may be helpful also here. The relationship between magisterium and faithful is, in some ways, analogous to the relationship between parents and children or teacher and pupils. Certainly it happens that with the passage of time one realizes that some knowledge communicated by one’s parents and educators was not exact and that the values inculcated by them were not completely genuine (at least in the way they were transmitted). Does this give one the right to conclude that every influence of parents, educators, and teachers should be rejected, except those affirmations that enjoy a mathematical certitude? It is not difficult to see that this presumed elimination of every error and of every prejudice does not in fact open up a viable way to a better education and a more solid intellectual formation; rather it leads to an impoverishment in the area of knowledge and values, to an estrangement from the culture in which one lives, and this without providing a better alternative. It is difficult not to see here a parallel with the attitude of numerous Catholics today toward the teaching of the Church.Think, for example, of the “partial identification” with the Church that is so popular today, which leads to a faith that is the fruit of a subjective selection (Auswahlglaube), where the criterion of choice is, within the horizon of a culture that defines itself as post-Christian, what is still plausible and what can still be demanded from a moral point of view. Speaking of faith, St.Thomas notes that the one who accepts certain articles of faith and rejects others (“pertinaciter”—otherwise it would be a question of error and not formally of heresy) does not in fact have supernatural faith at all, insofar as the formal object of supernatural faith is adherence to God, the first truth, who manifests himself in Scripture and in the teaching of the Church.That is why, writes St.Thomas, the heretic “ea quae sunt fidei alio modo tenet quam per fidem.” And he goes on, “si de his quae Ecclesia docet quae vult tenet et quae vult non tenet, non iam inhaeret Ecclesiae doctrinae sicut infallibili regulae, sed propriae voluntati.” Such a faith, he concludes, is in reality an “opinio quaedam.” ST II–II, q. 5, a. 3. 23 Weger, “Wie weit reicht der Schutz,” 116. The Ordinary Magisterium 47 the theologian who finds difficulties in some teaching of the Church, must, rather than having recourse to the media, find some other way to deepen, clarify, and, if necessary, even correct that teaching. Ever since the media discovered the theologians, experience has shown that theological disputes, conducted in the media for the benefit of a public, which for the most part lacks the necessary scientific preparation, often make use of categories and conceptual tools that are wholly inadequate. The choice of issues and spokesmen, as also the way in which the issues are discussed, is largely governed by the need to create a sensation and to gain the favor of the public. Such criteria are not adequate to a truth that by its very nature surpasses the human mind and at whose center stands the cross of Christ. With such recourse to the media as a means of pressurizing the magisterium, St. Paul’s words to Timothy have come true in a startling manner. Paul calls upon Timothy to proclaim the Word at every occasion, “in season and out of season,” because “the time is coming when people will not endure sound teaching, but having itching ears they will accumulate for themselves teachers to suit their own likings and will turn away from listening to the truth and wander into myths” (2 Tim 4:2–4). An Unacceptable Dilemma: Either Define a Doctrine or Keep Silent The questioning of the ordinary magisterium on the grounds of “fallible” propositions ends up by admitting only a miraculous assistance of the Holy Spirit, one that is not conditioned in any way by history and culture, and which would issue in “oracular” pronouncements on the part of the pope and the bishops.The theologians demand that these teachers of the faith make public the alleged special illumination on which they ground their teachings.24 If they fail to do this, the theologians consider themselves authorized to make the limits of dogmatic decisions coincide with the beginning of the realm of free opinions. Where there are no propositions of faith in the strict sense, the teachings of the magisterium 24 As regards the way in which the charism of the pastors operates in the realm of the proclamation of the truth, it is necessary to note two things. First, the illumination of the Holy Spirit, in virtue of which the successors of the apostles receive a particular understanding of the things of faith and morals, should be distinguished from the capacity to thematize this understanding on the level of scientific reflection. The former does not necessarily imply the latter. Secondly (and this is connected to the first), the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian recalls “the principle which affirms that magisterial teaching, by virtue of divine assistance, has a validity beyond its argumentation, which may derive at times from a particular theology” (no. 34). Pope Paul VI had already recalled this principle in his encyclical Humanae vitae, no. 28. 48 Giovanni Sala, SJ are to be considered in the same manner as opinions of some particular school of thought, in brief, as “fallible” teachings—no more. The attitude to be assumed toward fallible teachings is that of the “hermeneutic of suspicion” proposed by philosophers like Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud. This hermeneutic presumes the falsity of what is affirmed, as long as the contrary has not yet been demonstrated with absolute evidence. But since no rational demonstration is infallible, the suspicion always remains. It is on the basis of such a hermeneutic that the passage is easily made from “fallible” propositions to false propositions. Within the horizon of such a hermeneutic the place of the obedience of faith is taken by the so-called “critical” believer. On the practical plane, the challenge to the ordinary authentic magisterium is equivalent to constraining the sacred hierarchy, in its ministry of teaching the people of God, to choose between “issuing doctrinal decisions that are absolutely binding, or else simply keeping quiet and leaving everything to the opinion of the individual,” as the German bishops so appropriately expressed the problem already in 1967.25 But, continue the bishops, just as concrete human living requires that we make decisions on the basis of a knowledge that is not completely certain, but which nevertheless must be regarded hic et nunc as a valid norm for thought and for action, so (in an analogous manner!) the Church, in order to defend efficaciously the substance of the faith and to apply it effectively to new situations, must propose teachings that are binding to a certain degree and which nevertheless are in a certain measure provisional and even open to the possibility of error. The fact that the problem of the ordinary magisterium has become acute today is a direct consequence of this dilemma put before the magisterium: Either define a doctrine or else shut up.26 To demand infallible doctrinal decisions in every case, in order to have binding doctrines, amounts to a distortion of the nature of the magisterium and results in its elimination.What remains of its ordinary exercise is something merely “scientific,” equivalent in principle to other such authorities: not only universities and scholarly circles, but also journalism and its like. Once the real and supernatural principle of the assistance of the Holy Spirit has been rejected, on what grounds can there be attributed a priority and 25 Sekretariat der Deutschen Bischofskonferenz ed., Schreiben der deutschen Bischöfe an alle, die von der Kirche mit der Glaubenserkündigung beauftragt sind (Trier: Paulinus Velag, 1967), no. 18. 26 Not that the pope and bishops are prohibited from presenting their own opinions in the arena of diverse and contrasting opinions—but only inter pares! The Ordinary Magisterium 49 normativity to the teachings of the pope and bishops in the life of faith? Which of the many and discordant opinions disseminated by the media is the non-theologian to follow? Only one answer seems realistic: to that opinion presented with greater persuasiveness. Now this will be without doubt that opinion which best corresponds to the “Zeitgeist.”The confusion and bewilderment in which large sectors of Catholics find themselves today is a dramatic reproof of this. It is not therefore a question of an excessive insistence on the part of the Holy Father if, in recent years, he has repeatedly urged obedience toward the doctrine of the Church.We must not read here a hidden intention to put on the same plane the ordinary and the infallible magisterium; rather the pope wants to “save” the ordinary magisterium of the Church— if we may express ourselves thus in speaking of a tension that cannot be completely eliminated, being part of the mystery of the Church, between faith in God who guides his Church, and the personal responsibility of the successors of the apostles with regard to the same Church.The preoccupation of the Pastor of the Universal Church is about the needs of and the risks to so many faithful; the insistence on his right and duty to teach the Church is a tangible sign of his respect for the “simple,” that these may not be robbed of the treasure of the true faith.27 The repeated and preoccupied interventions of the Holy Father and the Roman congregations who participate in his universal magisterium must be seen against the background of the attack in course against practically the whole of Catholic doctrine. An inability to see this would be an indication of total abstraction from reality. By way of example, I note some of the doctrines that in recent years have become objects of debate and rejection: the divinity of Jesus Christ, the founding of the Church by Jesus, the ministerial priesthood, the Eucharistic presence, the sacrament of penitence, original sin, the virginity of Mary Most Holy, the last things. As far as moral teaching in the area of sexuality is concerned, it is superfluous to say anything. In addition, there is the tactic of allowing certain fundamental truths of the faith to disappear merely by not speaking any more about them: such is the case with the doctrine of grace and sin. In the third section above,“The Magisterium and the Assistance of the Holy Spirit,” I observed that, at least apparently, the theologians do not have any difficulty in admitting infallible definitions. Seen from the outside, the infallible magisterium has a formal logical structure: If the conditions laid down by the two Vatican councils are satisfied, it is evident 27 Cf. Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, nos. 37 and 27. 50 Giovanni Sala, SJ that, from the viewpoint of Catholic doctrine, we have an infallible teaching. But the assent to the dogmas of the Church, which at first does not seem to raise difficulties, may have motivations other than the theological virtue of faith. In fact many of these dogmas appear to us today as abstract formulas, extraneous to our lives and difficult to understand.The attitude of a Catholic toward these may well be one of practical indifference, leaving to the magisterium itself the task of seeing why they have been defined and what exactly they mean—granted that they mean something at all. But examined more closely, these infallible teachings appear as stray entities or as fruits of a tree from under which the ground has been removed. The disappearance also of these mythical remnants forms part of the logic of an attitude of spirit which regards autonomous reason as the ultimate criterion of truth.The spiritual and scientific itineraries of both well-known and lesser known Catholic theologians have already provided us with too many examples of such a logic. Calling into doubt the validity of the ordinary magisterium implies questioning the effective presence and action of those to whom Jesus has entrusted the mission of teaching all nations. The teachings of the ordinary magisterium are as many and as varied as the circumstances of place, time, and culture in which the Gospel is proclaimed and lived.The binding character of these teachings also varies according to the persons for whom they are directly intended, the tenor of the expressions used, the frequency and insistence of the pastors in proposing them, and many other factors.28 Only a life lived within and with the Church allows the believer to grasp the true meaning, significance, and degree of obligation of what the pastors say to the people of God. Now it is precisely this ordinary magisterium that touches the faithful in a close and sometimes painful way. For one who lives in communion with the Church, the magisterium becomes a constant point of reference, as concrete as everyday life itself. It is thus that the Christian realizes that life in the Church is not a vague ideological superstructure, but rather a way of life that envelops everything and that touches him personally. In the Church, the Christian experiences that Jesus Christ is not merely someone who said something two thousand years ago in a culture completely different from our own, but rather is “the Way, the Truth, and the Life” ( Jn 14:6) of every believer. Through his representatives, Jesus intervenes here and now in the life of the believer, both in what he does and in what he leaves aside, imposing a conduct of life that not infre28 Cf.Vatican Council II, Lumen gentium, no. 25; Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, no. 24. The Ordinary Magisterium 51 quently calls for the courage of non-conformism. Here lies the true existential problem of the ordinary magisterium today—a problem which has found its expression in the slogan: “Jesus yes, but not the Church.” Theological Research and Personal Sanctification In keeping with the faulty character of the magisterium of which I spoke above, the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian, while recognizing the possibility of inadequate doctrinal decisions on the part of the magisterium, not only exhorts the theologian to place his expertise at the service of the teachings of the Church in order to deepen, perfect, complete, and even, where necessary, to correct them through the channels of scientific publications and dialogue with the pastors (no. 40), but also considers the case in which the truth makes its way in the Church through the suffering, silence, and prayer of the theologian (no. 31). This is something that cannot be completely eliminated from a divine Revelation that is incarnate. The shortcomings of the servants of the Church in the ministry of government and of teaching is not due to historical and cultural conditioning alone; it can also be the consequence of personal failure. The saints, who were the ones who best understood Revelation, provide us with examples of situations in which the ways and times of God and of his truth do not coincide with our ways and our times. The reflections developed by the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian on this theme are not a way of circumventing the tasks proper to theology as science, nor do they exonerate the members of the magisterium from the obligation to make use of all available means for discovering the truth.They are rather a fraternal reminder of what ultimately counts in the Kingdom of God: charity, which in the time of the pilgrim Church can also be a charity that is called to suffering. Love for the Church, the mother of our faith, can also pass through the Cross. It is here that the science of the word of God, which cannot but be intellectus fidei, finds its confirmation. The effort of the theologian to give respect and obedience to a magisterium which he finds to be in error, together with the willingness to do whatever is possible so that the truth might prevail, in the firm hope that the Church, notwithstanding deviations and errors, will not be lacking in salvific truth, is a real service to Christian redemption.When the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian says:“The commitment to theology requires a spiritual effort to grow in virtue and holiness” (no. 9), it does not indulge in an empty phrase but rather touches the heart of the question and indicates the foundation on which alone the theologian can carry out his task within the mystical body of Christ.The history of theology confirms this: It is not merely coincidental that the great theologians have been saints. 52 Giovanni Sala, SJ In an allocution to the bishops of the United States of America on October 15, 1988, Pope John Paul II, after having recalled that “theology is an ecclesial science that constantly develops within the Church and is directed to the service of the Church,” went on to outline the spiritual figure of the theologian in the following terms: The authentic faith of the theologians, nourished by prayer and constantly purified through conversion, is a great gift of God to his Church. On it depends the well-being of theology in our day. As I mentioned at the Catholic University of Washington:“It behooves the theologian to be free, but with the freedom that is openness to the truth and the light that comes from faith and from fidelity to the Church” (October 7, 1979).29 The analysis made by the Instruction on the Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian of the situation in which theology finds itself today, has pinpointed the root of the problem and, it must be frankly admitted, of the disarray in which theological research and teaching find themselves in a number of particular churches.The disappearance of the supernatural horizon of faith with a culture which is drawing the ultimate consequences of an anthropological turn understood in an immanentist sense, is reflected in the tendency on the part of certain contemporary theologians to relegate a magisterium founded on the assistance of the Holy Spirit to the realm of mythical conceptions or of ideological constructions of the past. The indispensable condition for doing theology today is the existential recovery of the horizon of faith, within which alone the tools provided by modern culture can and must be used to mediate supernatural Revelation to the people of today. But the recovery of the horizon of faith is not a question of speculation or argumentation. Every argument is based ultimately upon premises that are not themselves the result of a demonstration. This is true not only for every human science but also, in its own way, for the science of faith. In the realm of natural knowledge the indemonstrable premise is the subjectivity of the scientist himself, his intelligence, rationality, and morality; it is the authentic human subject inasmuch as objectivity in human knowledge is the fruit of authentic subjectivity.30 In the realm of supernatural knowledge, the ultimate premise is the subjectivity of the theologian in his authenticity 29 Pope John Paul II, “The Universal Ordinary Magisterium Can Be Considered To Be the Usual Expression of the Church’s Infallibility,” ad limina address to the U.S. bishops of New York (October 15, 1988), L’Osservatore Romano (English), October 24, 1988, no. 7. 30 This is a key idea in B. Lonergan’s Method inTheology (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1990). The Ordinary Magisterium 53 as a Christian believer (in addition to his human authenticity on the level of intellect and will). For this reason Lonergan, in his Method in Theology, places the foundation of the last three theological functional specialties (discerning the true Christian doctrines, elaborating their meaning, communicating them in a manner conducive to the building up of the Church) in religious conversion. Now religious conversion is not some particular doctrine, but rather a highly personal event; it is the life itself of the theologian as tending towards sanctity. To say that the personal commitment to sanctity establishes the horizon of pre-understanding within which the theologian can do theology in the strict sense, is to indicate the point of conjunction between Christian life and reflection on the Christian mystery, the point at which an authentically Christian life expresses itself in a theology adequate to its object. This is not an attempt to blur the distinctions between the two, nor does it amount to establishing an automatic passage from the first to the second. Cultural and speculative problems have their own laws and are to be resolved by means of proper scientific procedures. But scientific procedures are at the service of the human mind and yield no results independently of the horizon of truth and values constitutive of the concrete subject. Now when the Christian existence of the subject, the theologian, is undermined by inauthenticity, an adequate understanding of Revelation cannot be expected—indeed, not even the indirect and analogous understanding of theology. A regress in Christian living, in prayer, charity, self-denial, and obedience, inevitably works as a negative factor with regard to the supernatural truth communicated by God to his Church.The transcendence of Christian truth—its supernatural character—calls for the transcendence of Christian living; otherwise it becomes an ideological superstructure which is then used to give a Christian veneer to a conception of the world whose matrix is no longer the Gospel. Revealed truth is an essential part of the Christian life. Reflection on this truth can therefore be done only by one who lives it, just as communication of that truth can be done only through a living testimony. Now there is no Christian life except in communion with the Church, the adequate subject of our faith. It is only within a communion with the Church and in a constant endeavor toward personal sanctification that a proper relationship is possible between the theologian and the living magisterium.To formulate the problem from the assumption that theology and magisterium are separate and opposing realities, is to miss the proper solution from the very start. It amounts to wanting to assure a space for theology, while forgetting that theology acquires its character as 54 Giovanni Sala, SJ a science only by entering into the realm of faith, which is always the faith of the ecclesial community. It is only in the realm of faith that the theologian finds that freedom of research and of teaching, which belong to him. Such a freedom is intrinsically linked to the mystery of the N&V Church, from which the theologian receives his mission. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 4, No. 1 (2006): 55–94 55 Francisco Marín-Sola, OP, and the Origin of Jacques Maritain’s Doctrine on God’s Permission of Evil M ICHAEL TORRE University of San Francisco San Francisco, California I N 1996, Editiones Universitaires Fribourg Suisse published the first volume of the lifelong correspondence between Jacques Maritain and Charles Journet.1 From it, one can discover the origin of the former’s view on God’s permission of evil (and other directly related ideas pertaining to God’s governance of created liberty). The correspondence reveals that Maritain’s thought depends, directly and substantially, on that of Francisco Marín-Sola, OP.2 This had already been surmised by some familiar with the latter’s published work on these matters;3 the correspondence 1 Journet Maritain: Correspondance, vol. 1, 1920–1929, ed. Mgr. Pierre Mamie (Paris: Éditions Universitaires Fribourg Suisse and Éditions Saint-Paul, 1996); vol. 2, 1930–1939, and vol. 3, 1940–1949, were published in 1997 and 1998. Their correspondence began in 1920; within two years, they were addressing each other as “friend”; by late 1924, they were corresponding very regularly. 2 Marín-Sola published three articles on this matter: “El sistema tomista sobre la moción divina,” La Ciencia Tomista 32 (1925): 5–54; “Respuesta a algunas objeciones acerca del sistema tomista sobre la moción divina,” La Ciencia Tomista 33 (1926): 5–74; and “Nuevas observaciones acerca del sistema tomista sobre la moción divina,” La Ciencia Tomista 33 (1926): 321–97. 3 This was noted by L.Vereecke, CSSR, in his entry “Alphonse Ligouri” in the New Catholic Encylopedia, vol. 1 (Washington, DC: Catholic University Press, 1967), 339; and by John Rock, sJ, in “St. Thomas on Divine Causality,” Philosophical Studies 5 (1955): 22. Jean-Hervé Nicolas, OP, also associates the two positions in his “La permission du mal” (Revue Thomiste 60 [1960], 5–37, 185–206, and 509–46), but he tries to show that they are really distinct positions (whereas, as will be seen herein, they are essentially the same). See also my “God’s Permission of Sin: Negative or Conditioned Decree?” (Ph.D. diss., Graduate Theological Union, 1983), 825–49. 56 Michael Torre reveals both the degree of this dependence and the very interesting way in which it developed. Charles Journet had a high opinion of Marín-Sola’s book on the evolution of Catholic dogma.4 In his second letter to Maritain after arriving in Fribourg, Journet asks him to send any objections he has to the book, after he has read it; he can then pass them on to Marín-Sola, who appreciates them, since they give him the opportunity to develop certain finer points.5 In a reply that has been lost,6 Maritain apparently forwarded to Journet some objections of Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, OP,7 for Journet says he knew of these, but does not find them telling: He had hoped for Maritain’s own objections.8 In his next letter, Maritain admits that he has not yet had time to read the book, passes on one difficulty he foresees, and says that he is also asking for the opinion of Roland Dalbiez.9 Journet then gives 4 Starting in 1911, Marín-Sola published a series of articles on this matter in La Ciencia Tomista (and occasionally in the Revue Thomiste). He then published a book on the subject, La Evolución homogénea del dogma catolico (Madrid: Biblioteca de Autores Cristianos, 1923), translated into French as L’Évolution homogène du dogme catholique (Fribourg: St. Paul, 1924). Emilio Sauras wrote a general introduction to the second, 1952, BAC edition (3–125), that supplies valuable information concerning Marín-Sola’s life and work (especially 12–34), including his as yet unpublished three-volume masterwork, the Concordia Tomista. 5 Journet, letter no. 87 (November 14, 1924), 247.The editors indicate that Maritain had previously received a dedicated copy of the book (Mamie, Journet Maritain, 252, note 1). 6 The editors note this in p. 250, note 1. In his own letter of November 14 (no. 86), 245, Maritain had thanked Journet for sending him some volumes of Norbert del Prado, OP, although we now possess no letter or note from Journet that may have accompanied this package. It is possible that Journet sent him Marín-Sola’s book in the same packet, since his next letter asks for Maritain’s views on it. It also seems likely that Journet did not keep the objections sent him, since they were not Maritain’s own, but ones of Garrigou-Lagrange that he already possessed. 7 Garrigou-Lagrange had himself dealt with this issue in his De Revelatione (Rome: Ferrari, 1918). He favored the view of Reginald Schultes, OP who had argued against Marín-Sola’s view. See the latter’s Introductio in historiam dogmatum (Paris: Lethielleux, 1922); and De Revelatione, vol. 1, 509, for Garrigou-Lagrange’s view. Marín-Sola acknowledged their differences (see Evolución, 465, note 42, in relation to Garrigou-Lagrange, and 809 ff. in relation to Schultes), but sought to minimize their differences and to laud their respective virtues. 8 Journet, letter no. 88, (November 20, 1924), 249–50.This letter immediately follows his previous one of the fourteenth. As Journet notes, their letters of the fourteenth had crossed in the mail. In this second letter, Journet also expresses his irritation with Garrigou-Lagrange for objecting to Marín-Sola’s views from his articles alone, and without reading his book. 9 Maritain, letter no. 89 (December 2, 1924), 251. God’s Permission of Evil 57 Maritain’s difficulty to Marín-Sola and sends back the latter’s answer to Maritain.10 Maritain replies to this letter by forwarding to Journet Dalbiez’s favorable “review” and expressing annoyance with himself for not yet having gotten to Marín-Sola’s book.11 Maritain seems content with Dalbiez’s opinion and willing to entertain Marín-Sola’s position. A month later, Journet forwards the latter’s answer to one matter Dalbiez had raised, reporting that he had liked Dalbiez’s remarks.12 This marks the end of the exchange. There are several features of this initial exchange worth noting. First, Marín-Sola is at the center of their correspondence at this time. Indeed, starting with Journet’s second letter from Fribourg (no. 88, November 20), Marín-Sola is mentioned in all of their next eleven letters save three (each a brief note). Second, while Journet greatly admires the latter’s person and work, Maritain is more hesitant. Third, the reason for this is clear: Maritain is aware of the opposition of Garrigou-Lagrange, with whom he was at that time very close. (Garrigou-Lagrange had only recently helped Maritain found the Cercles Thomistes and was giving its yearly retreat at Meudon.) Fourth, his own admiration of Garrigou-Lagrange and consequent hesitation in relation to Marín-Sola does not prevent Maritain from appreciating the latter’s work. Fifth, their relation follows a pattern: Maritain becomes familiar with Marín-Sola’s thought through Journet; he sends Journet his difficulties, which the latter gives to Marín-Sola in Fribourg; and Marín-Sola then replies to Maritain via the same conduit. All of these features also mark their second exchange, which concerns God’s permission of evil and the ideas directly related to it. That new exchange begins with Journet’s fifth letter from Fribourg (no. 92, December 10, 1924). In it, he indicates that Marín-Sola is “meditating on a way to restore the Thomistic notions of predestination, operating and efficacious grace, etc.” and that he is ready to publish a series of articles on them.13 Maritain shows an immediate interest in this question. In the same letter in which he forwards Dalbiez’s favorable opinion on evolution, he says he hopes that Marín-Sola will particularly address the issue of sin and its permission: He believes the Dominican position on 10 Journet, letter no. 90 (December 4, 1924), 254–55. 11 Maritain, letter no. 93 (December 26, 1924), 262. Dalbiez’s letter to Maritain was published seventy years later:“Une letter de Roland Dalbiez à Jacques Maritain,” Nova et Vetera 69 (1994/2), 155–59. 12 Journet, letter no. 95 ( January 28, 1925), 271–72, and letter no. 97 (February 11, 1925), 276. Maritain much later makes one further reference to this matter, indicating he had by then read Marín-Sola’s book (letter no. 237a [May 11, 1928]). 13 Journet, letter no. 92 (December 10, 1924), 260, my translation (and hereafter, of both Journet and Maritain). Michael Torre 58 the morally good act is clearly “triumphant,” but that there remain “difficulties to resolve” concerning the morally evil act.14 From this letter throughout 1925, Marín-Sola’s views on this matter become a central topic of their exchange, so much so that the editors include an explanatory appendix on it by Georges Cottier, OP.15 Save for two brief notes, Marín-Sola is discussed in their next six letters (nos. 94–99) and, after a month’s hiatus, four of their next six (nos. 104–109); after the summer, there are another eight letters devoted to his views (nos. 109, 111, 112, 123, 125, 127, 128, and 131), culminating in a long letter in early 1926 that Maritain sends to Marín-Sola via Journet (no. 138a); three further letters (nos. 139, 148, and 149) end their exchange, a total of some two dozen letters, mostly in a one-year period (February 1925–February 1926). From it, the way Maritain comes to his own views through the teaching of Marín-Sola emerges clearly. In his first letter expressing interest in this whole subject, Maritain says that he believes the “proposition” or “first initiative” of sin must come from the sinner (and not God).16 The sinner is actually present to God’s eyes by reason of the eternity of his creative knowledge, and, because he is created from nothing, because nothingness is in the very entrails of the creature, he is constantly tending towards that nothingness under the hands of God and is in this way constantly demanding permission to engage in such and such sins.17 God sees the possibility of such sins in his simple intelligence and, for a greater good, gives his permission for one such, “from which follows (not according to time, but according to priorities and posteriorities of nature) the pure privation, inordination, or inconsideration of which GarrigouLagrange speaks (Dieu, 689–99), which sterilizes sufficient grace and in reason of which occurs the refusal of efficacious grace; in this way, we ourselves are sufficient in order to sin (Dieu, 684).”18 Maritain also thinks that we should give a double sense to the words “without Me you can do nothing” (sine me nihil potestis facere):Without Me you cannot do anything 14 Maritain, letter no. 93 (December 26, 1924), 262. 15 See Cottier, Journet Maritain: Correspondance, appendice 2, “La Liberté Créée Devant Dieu (À propos de la prémotion physique),” 742–46. 16 Maritain, letter no. 93 (December 26, 1924), 262. 17 Ibid., 262. Throughout this paper, all emphases in this paper are original, unless otherwise noted. 18 Ibid., 262–63. Garrigou-Lagrange’s work is Dieu, son existence et sa nature (Paris: Beauchesne, 1914); English, God: His Existence and Nature (St. Louis: Herder, 1946). God’s Permission of Evil 59 and without Me you can “do nothing” (faire le rien).19 He allows that Garrigou-Lagrange says all of this, but “more in the conclusions than in the principles and without sufficiently dotting his ‘i’s.”20 This long paragraph is the first time Maritain gives his own personal view of this matter, one he had developed before possessing any knowledge of Marín-Sola’s view.There are several things especially worth noting about his ideas. First, they depend upon those of Garrigou-Lagrange in important ways.The latter had also argued that God’s refusal of efficacious grace supposed a defect on the part of the sinner (one that “sterilized sufficient grace”); but, he had also argued, that defect itself supposed God’s permissive will; and, furthermore, he had argued, that defect followed infallibly from the divine permission.21 Maritain follows him on these key ideas, so much so that one could speak of his view at this point as a variant on that of Garrigou-Lagrange (a characterization he himself more or less makes).Yet it is clear that already Maritain wants to find a way to give the first initiative in sin to the creature, and not to God’s permission:The creature “constantly tends towards nothingness” (“faisant constamment pression vers le néant”) and thus is “constantly demanding permission” (“demandant constamment la permission”) to engage in sin.22 In this crucial respect, his view tends to differ from Garrigou-Lagrange’s. Finally, in Maritain’s exegesis of sine me nihil potestis facere, the passage implies or suggests the “nihil” [“le néant”] that the creature tends toward on his own initiative.This creative exegesis and use of “nihil” is characteristic of Maritain’s writings on this matter throughout his career.23 This paragraph is also interesting for what it does not contain. There is here no distinction made between a “negatio pura” that precedes sin 19 Maritain, letter no. 93 (December 26, 1924), 263. 20 Ibid. 21 See Garrigou-Lagrange, God: His Existence and Nature, vol. 2, 365–96. 22 Maritain, letter no. 93 (December 26, 1924), 262. 23 He first uses it in Freedom in the Modern World (London: Sheed and Ward, 1936) and systematically thereafter. (See notes 143, 149, and 150, below, for his first two usages of this in French works and his first important usage of it in English.) He uses it first in an English work (albeit not “technically”) in “The Thomist Idea of Freedom,” in Maritain, Scholasticism and Politics (New York: Macmillan, 1940), 119. Other typical examples can be found in Maritain, Existence and the Existent, 92; idem, God and the Permission of Evil, 33; and idem, On the Philosophy of History, 119. He uses it last in “Réflexions sur le savoir théologique,” in Maritain, Approches sans entraves (Paris: Fayard, 1973), 292–326, esp. 308–9; English:“For an Existential Epistemology II: Reflections on Theological Knowledge,” in Untrammeled Approaches, trans. Bernard Döering (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997), 243–71, especially pages 248–64. 60 Michael Torre and the “privatio” of sin itself or between a “non-consideration” of the rule and an “inconsideration” of it. Neither is there any distinction between a divine permission that antecedes this “negatio pura” and one that supposes it. Nor, and even more importantly, is there any suggestion of a divine permission that simply permits sin to be possible and one that supposes a defect in the creature and from which sin infallibly follows. Similarly, there is no idea of God’s antecedent will being conditionally efficacious and grounding a divine motion that can effect a true good or that can be impeded (that is, a “motion brisable”). All of these ideas are characteristic of Maritain’s mature thought on sin and its cause, but there is not the least indication that he has yet thought of or embraced such ideas when he first begins to think about this matter. In his letter, Maritain apologizes to Journet for all of his “chatter” (“bavardage”) and asks Journet to correct it, should he think otherwise.24 He also is obviously much interested in what Marín-Sola may think about what he had written. For, upon learning from Journet that he had forwarded his ideas to Marín-Sola,25 but hearing nothing further from him in his next two letters about what the latter thinks, Maritain writes that he would be happy to learn of his views, should Marín-Sola mention something to Journet concerning the permission of sin.26 In his following letter, Journet sends back to Maritain Marín-Sola’s reaction.27 Journet says that Marín-Sola was very brief in his response, because this is precisely the question he is just beginning to address in his series of projected articles for La Ciencia Tomista.28 Journet passes on three comments. First, that Maritain is right to see that the issue that needs more debate is God’s permission of sin. However, in the second place, that for sin infallibly to follow God’s permission, one must suppose the creature to be totally corrupt (the unacceptable premise of Calvinism). Thirdly, what Thomists have not sufficiently exploited is that, for Thomas, the cause of evil stops with the secondary cause: God does not know evil in himself, but in knowing the evil will of the secondary cause. Three things should be noted here. First, Marín-Sola sees that Maritain is trying to move toward the position he himself had worked out, namely, that the first initiative for sin must lie with the creature’s will, not with God’s will (permissive or otherwise). Second, Marín-Sola puts his finger on the weakness in Maritain’s first view: In thinking that a defect 24 Maritain, letter no. 93 (December 26, 1924), 263. 25 Journet, letter no. 95 ( January 28, 1925), 271. 26 Maritain, letter no. 98 (February 14, 1925), 278. 27 Journet, letter no. 99 (March 5, 1925), 282. 28 Ibid., 282. God’s Permission of Evil 61 must follow infallibly from God’s permission, he inevitably makes the creature unable to do any good when left to himself.Third, he indicates why Maritain and Thomists make this error:They want to explain all of God’s knowledge, including sin, through himself alone—that is, through his own permissive will—rather than through the secondary cause. Journet writes Maritain again twenty-six days later (March 31) without mentioning Marín-Sola, while Maritain’s next surviving letter29 to Journet is only written on April 28, thus coming almost two months after receiving Marín-Sola’s response. It is perhaps not too surprising, then, that he makes no allusion to it in that letter. He remains, however, quite interested in what Marín-Sola has said, and thus six weeks later ( June 2), he asks Journet whether he has spoken further with him about the permission of sin.30 He also asks for the address of La Ciencia Tomista (having searched Paris in vain for months to find it!) and asks if Marín-Sola has begun to publish his articles there.31 That he has followed his thought can be seen in his response to it. He tells Journet that he can see how MarínSola’s view will “marvelously explain” that God’s will does not initiate sin, but will it not make God’s knowledge be determined by the creature? [I]f evil—I do not mean the evil act effectuated, but the deficience or inordination that is the root of evil in the will of the creature; I mean this determinate deficiency, here and now, and which could not have been— precedes the permission that God accords it. . . . Is not the divine knowledge going to find itself determined by the creature?32 He cannot see how to get past this obstacle posed by Marín-Sola’s view. Several observations are worth making here. First, Maritain also goes directly to the heart of the difficulty. Marín-Sola will himself affirm that how God knows sin is obscure for us, and that it may remain so in his account is practically its only real difficulty.33 Second, although Maritain 29 In a later letter (no. 106, June 12, 1925), Journet mentions some corrections Maritain had made in a book he had sent Marín-Sola. They had only recently referred to this book (in no. 95, January 28, 1925; and in no. 98, February 14, 1925), so Maritain must have only recently sent it to Marín-Sola; there is, however, no surviving letter that indicates when he did. There may have been, then, some exchange between Maritain and Marín-Sola during this two month period that is missing from his correspondence with Journet. 30 Maritain, letter no. 104 ( June 2, 1925), 293. 31 Ibid., 295. 32 Ibid., 293–94. 33 For the obscurity of God’s knowledge of sin, see Marín-Sola,“Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 41; for explaining it satisfactorily being practically the only difficulty his doctrine presents, see Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 360. As we 62 Michael Torre distinguishes the defect that is the “root” of sin from the sinful act, he is still conceiving of this defect as “inordinate” (that is, not a “negatio pura”). Similarly, he supposes that no divine permission “precedes” it, because he is conceiving of permission as infallibly entailing what is permitted; (that is, he has not yet conceived of a divine permission that makes a defect possible, but not infallibly entailed). Thus, we can see that Maritain’s initial response is much like the response of other Thomists (such as Garrigou-Lagrange or Jean-Hervé Nicolas), who will later object to Marín-Sola’s position. Journet writes Maritain within a week. He indicates that he has sent Marín-Sola Maritain’s difficulty, but does not yet have his response. He also reports a very revealing conversation. He had been saying that there was no middle ground between the scientia media and the divine decree. This prompted a sudden outrush of breath in Marín-Sola, who replied “yes, there was a middle ground for evil.”34 He said that many Thomists ought to have seen the difficulty, but they have not dared take it up: It has been twenty years since he thought so.35 Both Journet and Marín-Sola understood the risk he was taking in criticizing a position that many Thomists had taught all their life, and Journet describes him as “carrying a great weight.”36 He thinks his articles will be a “great event,” but worries especially about the reaction of Garrigou-Lagrange. Marín-Sola knew that the latter had wanted to denounce him to the Dominican Master General for his work on the evolution of dogma; the previous general had supported Marín-Sola, but Journet is worried that the new general will not be as sympathetic on this issue.37 Journet fears that “the good F. Garrigou or the Angelicum will immediately oppose him and will judge will have the occasion to see, Marín-Sola makes this last observation with Maritain very much in mind. 34 Journet, letter no. 105 ( June 9, 1925). 35 Ibid., 299. It would be interesting to know what prompted Marín-Sola’s initial interest. Perhaps it was the series of articles of Henri Guillermin, OP, (to whom he refers in his second article) on sufficient grace. See his “De la grâce suffisante,” Revue Thomiste 9 (1901): 505–19, Revue Thomiste 10 (1902): 47–76, 374–404, and 654–75; and Revue Thomiste 11 (1903): 20–31. In this last article (p. 23), Guillermin even says that sufficient grace might seem to be an impedible motion that will not always be impeded; he argues, however, that it will be. Were one not convinced by his arguments there, one would end with a view of sufficient grace very similar to Marín-Sola’s. 36 Ibid., 298. 37 Ibid. In this, Journet was prescient. He, not surprisingly, assumed that a Spanish Master General would look favorably upon his work. In fact, the new Master General—Buenaventura Garcia de Paredes—while Spanish, was not well disposed toward Marín-Sola. God’s Permission of Evil 63 him, with pen still in hand, from the Salmanticenses or some other later Thomist, without waiting to read all.”38 (This was what GarrigouLagrange had in fact done in relation to Marín-Sola’s Evolution, and it is what he was to do in relation to this question as well.What Journet feared is exactly what came to pass.) Three days later, Journet writes Maritain again, forwarding him Marín-Sola’s reply to his difficulty. He says that his first article on this question, which was to appear shortly, will be sufficient for him to resolve all the other questions.39 In response to his difficulty, Journet reports his reply as follows: [I]t is necessary to concede that God is determined, not subjectively and efficiently (by good!) but objectively and deficiently (by evil) and, at my astonishment, he placed under my eyes in two seconds a text of Billuart that places an objective determination in God. God knows evil post decretum non per decretum, in his eternity, not in his causality.40 Marín-Sola knows that Garrigou-Lagrange will shiver (“fremira”) when he reads his work. He believes that he is not changing the Thomistic view, but he also believes that Garrigou-Lagrange will not see this.41 Journet knows that Marín-Sola has deeply studied this matter, for he has seen his “enormous notebook of notes” that follow each historical development of this matter with great patience and method.42 Journet hopes 38 Ibid., 299. 39 Journet, letter no. 106 ( June 12, 1925), 303. 40 Ibid.The phrase “objective determination” affirms that there is a determination (one that is purely negative) in the created term or object of the divine decree. God knows the defect not in knowing himself alone, but in knowing the created object. This is just what Thomas himself says in Summa theologiae I, q. 14, a. 10, ad 3:“evil . . . is opposed to the effects of God, which He knows by His essence; and, knowing them, He knows the opposite evils.” When confronted with the objection that it is an imperfection to know a defect through another (“per aliud”), he replies (ad 4) that it is no imperfection, because this is the only way a defect can exist (in a created good) and that it can be known: “To know a thing by something else only belongs to imperfect knowledge if that thing is of itself knowable; but evil is not of itself knowable” (my emphases). Note that this answer holds equally for physical evils caused by God and for moral evils caused by free creatures. Marín-Sola’s merit lay as much in calling attention to what Thomas had, in fact, said in this text as it did to any further commentary he made on it. It is this text that Thomists had insufficiently “exploited.” 41 Journet, letter no. 106 ( June 12, 1925), 303–4. 42 Ibid., 305. There are presently some twenty notebooks of Marín-Sola’s notes on this matter (of some two hundred pages each, roughly) in the archives of the Spanish Dominicans in Avila.These are probably the notebooks to which Journet refers. 64 Michael Torre to avoid an antagonism between the two Dominicans: He will try to work on Marín-Sola, and he urges Maritain to do the same with Garrigou-Lagrange.43 The risk he was running can be seen from another of his comments that Journet passes on to Maritain. He told Journet that “the question in de Auxiliis had not been settled with the desirable sangfroid and objectivity.”44 To the Jesuit formula that with a general aid or “versatile grace,” man is able to have more than that to which God moved him, the Dominicans had opposed the formula that man is able to have only that to which God moved him; but the correct formula should have been that man is able to have less than that to which God moved him. And, against the Jesuit formula that God knows sin in the scientia media, the Dominicans had opposed the formula that God knows sin in His permissive decree; but the correct formula should have been that He knows sin in the sinner physically present to His eternity (“post decretum in his eternity,” as Journet reported).45 We have no evidence of Maritain’s first reaction to Marín-Sola’s reply.A month later, however, Journet writes him a second letter, in which he tells Maritain how very much Marín-Sola appreciates his work: “[H]e told me that he had for you more than admiration, a real veneration, and that you had spoken of things in a way that ‘we’ were not able.”46 He is in the process of reading Maritain’s Three Reformers,47 which had just appeared, and he finds it admirable, especially Maritain’s characterization of Descartes’s “angelism.” It is obvious, from this and from his previous comment, that MarínSola regards their exchange on God’s permission as one that is amicable, one proper to friends equally dedicated to Thomas. At this time, Marín-Sola published his first article in La Ciencia Tomista. Our interest in it here lies only in the way it bears upon Maritain’s later doctrine. Since Marín-Sola carefully distinguishes what he terms “the line of good” from the “line of evil,” and since his central interest is with the 43 Ibid. 44 Journet, letter no. 106 ( June 12, 1925), 304. 45 Ibid., 303–4. Those unfamiliar with the 1920s may be puzzled by this idea of “risk.”The recent Thomistic revival had also revived the dispute between Jesuits and Dominicans concerning the ideas of de auxiliis. In criticizing an idea held by many Dominicans, he ran the risk of being accused of betraying his order’s position.This is just what happened. 46 Journet, letter no. 109 ( July 13, 1925), 308–9. The “we” presumably refers to “Catholic clerics.” 47 Maritain, Trois Réformateurs: Luther, Descartes, Rousseau (Paris: Plon, 1925), English: Three Reformers: Luther, Descartes, Rousseau (London: Sheed and Ward, 1928). God’s Permission of Evil 65 second (which also is Maritain’s central interest in his later doctrine on the permission of evil), we will be concerned here mainly with this “line.”48 Marín-Sola makes the following points: God’s antecedent will that one attain a certain end (for example, salvation) is real and conditionally efficacious; in accord with it, God moves a creature toward the moral good (bonum honestum) in a way that is fallibly efficacious or impedible; God thus infallibly places a free creature in act or moves toward a determinate end, but it can impede this motion from reaching the end towards which it is moved; there is no other cause or explanation of this impediment than the creature’s own will; the first defect or impediment of the creature is its voluntary nonconsideration of the rule that should govern action; this is not yet sin itself (a faulty consent or election), but the cause of sin (a defective final practical judgment); the sinful election infallibly follows the defective judgment, unless God intervenes in a special way; God infallibly knows the creature’s defective judgment, because the creature is physically present to his eternity; God’s permission that a creature sin infallibly entails that a creature sin only on the supposition that the creature is defective; however, supposing a creature is not defective, God’s permission only makes sin possible; thus, it is the free creature’s (fallible) will, and not God’s (permissive) will, that determines the creature’s actual defect and consequent sin.49 Anyone familiar with Maritain’s views will find them in this first article. In substance and in almost all details, most of Maritain’s later views are simply those of Marín-Sola. Marín-Sola indicates that much in his doctrine is not new to Thomists. It is principally new in not trying to explain a creature’s initial defect by reference to a divine permission that would infallibly entail or determine that it exist; consequently, God’s infallible knowledge of this defect must derive not from a divine decree, but from something else, namely, the fact that God’s knowledge is eternal and all creation is present to it; finally, since a creature need not impede a divine motion to the moral good, the proper idea of a motion that is sufficient is one that effects the end toward which it moves, unless impeded. Let us attend to Marín-Sola’s own words regarding these crucial points of his position. In an interesting note, one can see Marín-Sola developing the same point on God’s permission that he had made in relation to Maritain’s own first ideas on this subject: 48 Marín-Sola’s first article was published in the July–August 1925 edition of La Ciencia Tomista. He begins his exposition by distinguishing the lines of good and evil (10). He later says that his main interest is with the second (11), and that he had arrived at his position some five years previously (1920), precisely in teaching a course devoted entirely to Thomas’s teaching on the origin of evil (11). 49 Marín-Sola, “El sistema tomista,” esp. 17–22 and 46–52 (my emphasis). 66 Michael Torre [T]he divine permission that a creature sin is infallibly connected with sin, once one supposes the actual defect of the creature, but it is not so on every supposition, unless one is supposing a creature who is essentially evil. In effect, my permission that Peter fall, when he has not yet begun to fall nor even tripped, and therefore can not fall, in spite of my permission, is one thing; and a very distinct thing is the permission that he fall when he has already tripped and begun to fall, and infallibly will fall, if I do not support him.50 To “trip” here is the inconsiderate final judgment that precedes choice; to “fall” is the sinful choice.51 Yet it is true, more generally, that there are two different senses to God’s permission: that we become defective (when we are not) and that we remain defective, when we already are. Given the first, to sin is only possible; given the second, to continue in sin follows infallibly. Many Thomists had mistakenly collapsed both suppositions. This yields a divine permission from which defect and sin infallibly follow, even though the creature is in a good (or graced) state. The key to Marín-Sola’s position lies in correcting this mistake.52 Since God’s decree (permissive or otherwise) is not the cause of the creature’s actual defect, God cannot know this in knowing his own will alone. Again in a note, Marín-Sola deals with a problem this raises: Perhaps someone will object that if the impediment or defect of the creature cannot be seen by God in his decrees insofar as decrees, but can be insofar as eternal, then God, before giving sufficient grace, does not know what this effect will have in the creature and He will be acting blindly.To this one responds that, in the first place, before giving sufficient grace is one thing and before decreeing to give it is another. Before giving it, He infallibly knows its effect, because He gives it in 50 Ibid., 49–50, my translation of Marín-Sola: both here and hereafter. 51 In an interesting note in his second article, Marín-Sola writes that “what in neces- sary agents is the specific form is for intelligent or free creatures the final practical judgment that terminates ‘consilium’ or deliberation,” (“Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” p. 57).The exercise of this act thus will follow infallibly, save by a miracle. 52 To see better Thomas’s teaching on God’s permissive will, one should consult his extensive treatment in the Sentences (1, 47, 1, 2). He there teaches that we may not choose the object that is permitted (sin): “potest fieri oppositum eius quod permissum est”; that is, we are able not to sin, even though God permits sin.We find the same teaching elsewhere: God “permits some to be attacked, but He gives the fortitude to resist against this attack” (On Divine Names, 8, 5); and “God does not permit one to be tempted without the aid of divine grace” (In 2 Corinthians, 11, 5).There is no hint that Thomas means that we are “able” not to sin or to resist temptation only in the divided sense, and that we de facto will infallibly sin, given a divine permission; rather, God even aids us not to sin. God’s Permission of Evil 67 time and God knows everything from eternity. In the second place, if it concerns the before of decreeing to give it, and by “before” one intends an anteriority that affects the very decrees of God, then the phrase has no sense, because all the decrees are one sole and eternal act, without before or after. Thus God, from the first moment, knows everything and in no moment is ignorant of anything. Finally, if by this “before” one refers, as one ought to refer, to the objects of the decrees or to our human manner of conceiving them, then there is no inconvenience in conceding, and I believe that it ought to be conceded, that God does not infallibly know the outcome of sufficient grace before decreeing to give it, nor even in the very decree of giving it, insofar as decree. . . .To pretend that God knows all before every decree is Molinism and the scientia media. Whereas to pretend that God knows all in the decrees insofar as decrees will lead to placing the first cause of the actual defect of the creature in the divine decree. To one who objects that, in this case, the knowledge of God will be determined by the creature, we remind them to go to the proposition of Billuart: “indebita voluntatis dispositio objective determinat Deum ad movendum ad actum malum.”53 This text is obviously the one he had earlier shown Journet when replying to Maritain’s question, and the “one” referred to here is presumably Maritain himself.That this passage, as the previous one, appears in a note suggests that at least in part Marín-Sola added some notes only at the end, to reply to the difficulties that Maritain (and some others) had raised. Finally, Marín-Sola is at pains to make clear that an impedible motion or sufficient grace does not imply that the creature is the first cause of any good. Some might argue that his theory entails that the creature’s “non-impediment” implies this and that it positively determines God’s grace or will. He anticipates this objection and replies to it as follows: From the fact that God always gives an ulterior grace to one who has not placed an impediment to an anterior grace, it does not follow that the one not placing an impediment is the cause or reason of conceding a new grace.A seed or plant continues in its course or growth, not because one does not place an impediment (because a stone is not placed as an impediment and still it does not grow), but by virtue of its own vital power. Thus, the grace or supernatural premotion, once given by God, follows its course or growth, not because the will does not place an impediment, but by its own proper virtue.Yes, it is true that this power or course of grace will not continue, if the will places an impediment; but from this, that the will can paralyze or deviate the course of the motion or the 53 Marín-Sola, “El sistema tomista,” 52–53. Billuart’s text is from his De Deo Uno, dissertation 8, article 5. The reference, here and to other commentators later referred to in this article, is taken from Marín-Sola. Michael Torre 68 divine grace, it does not follow that this motion is not intrinsically efficacious: it only follows that it is not infallibly or perfectly efficacious, as is no sufficient grace nor any motion of general providence. Neither does it follow that the not placing of an impediment is at least the condition sine qua non, since, even supposing the placing of an impediment, God can remove it and make it not interrupt the course of grace.54 In other words, that the creature does what is in him (“faciendi quod in se est”) follows from the very power of the sufficient motion or grace itself (“ex viribus gratiae”), since it is moving him towards a determinate moral good.55 As with Marín-Sola’s Evolution, so with this article, it comes to Maritain already under the negative judgment of Garrigou-Lagrange. For, when Maritain first mentions it to Journet, he says that the latter is up in arms against (“trés monte contre”) it. Maritain has been unable to get it and asks Journet to bring it with him (since later that month he is coming to Meudon for the fourth retreat of the Cercles Thomistes).56 Journet does better, immediately sending him an extra copy he possessed.57 A month later, Maritain travels to Fribourg to give a public lecture. Journet, reporting on its success in a letter to Raïssa, says that “F. MarínSola—he who never comes to conferences!—had attended in a beautiful, new, white robe.”58 In his next letter to Maritain, Journet pronounces the conference a complete success and adds that Marín-Sola had spoken of “the enchantment he had had in seeing you; he loves you for the affability of your manner and is content to see that you are following the thread of his thought (while I am all at sea).”59 This indicates that Maritain both had read his article and had spoken with him about it in Fribourg, but what he had thought of it is unclear, for Maritain does not mention Marín-Sola, in the letter immediately following his return to Meudon.60 In this same letter in which he speaks of Marín-Sola, Journet indicates that he will interrupt his series of articles just this once to reply to difficulties that are being raised. Journet worries about this affair: How will this end? I would have much preferred that F. GarrigouLagrange had reserved his objections to the end: in objecting after his 54 Ibid., 29. 55 Ibid., 31. 56 Maritain, letter no. 111 (September 9, 1925), 312. 57 Journet, letter no. 112 (September 12, 1925), 313. 58 Journet, letter no. 121 (October 23, 1925), 326. 59 Journet, letter no. 123 (October 30, 1925), 330–31. 60 Maritain, letter no. 122 (October 24–25, 1925), 328. God’s Permission of Evil 69 first article, he gives the air of a man who is too pushy [“trop pressé”] and fevered [“fievreux”].That annoys me the more inasmuch as I love him with all my heart.61 Maritain must have responded to this letter, sending him some questions; for, two weeks later, Journet writes to respond to them. He indicates that Marín-Sola has finished his second article, part of which deals with the divine knowledge. Marín-Sola told Journet that, in writing this part, he had thought constantly of Maritain.62 Journet (worried that he may be prevented from completing his work) had urged him to publish his book all at once, and Marín-Sola had said he could do so by the following Easter: Only the citations would take some time.63 In his reply to this letter, Maritain indicates that “this Marín–Garrigou controversy has caused me much worry.”64 He would very much like for the former to have reason, but my instinct continues to make me terribly suspicious of a humanization and facilitation that would be at the expense of the great essential principles that the [Dominican] order was created to maintain.To admit in God the least formal determination coming from the creature is to destroy God.65 The only way he thinks Marín-Sola can save his position is by showing how he can “safeguard the absolute independence of the divine knowledge, while avoiding Molina.”66 This needs to be addressed with metaphysical profundity, but he worries that Marín-Sola “prefers to concern himself with considerations that are more moral and less high.”67 Despite these misgivings, however, Maritain asks Journet to pass on to Marín-Sola “all my respectful sympathy.”68 Journet, in his reply, says that he is of the same mind: One cannot “put into the ‘homo est prima causa mali’ anything that would make God passive.”69 It makes him a little uneasy to “hear him say that it is too bad if one cannot explain the divine knowledge.”70 Yet, Journet thinks that Marín-Sola has 61 Ibid., 331. 62 Journet, letter no. 125 (November 12, 1925), 334. 63 Ibid., 334. 64 Maritain, letter no. 127 (November 19, 1925), 337. 65 Ibid. 66 Ibid. 67 Ibid., 337–38. 68 Ibid., 338. 69 Journet, letter no. 128 (November 29, 1925), 341. 70 Ibid., 340. Michael Torre 70 many resources to deal with his difficulties: He would have preferred Garrigou-Lagrange to remain calm, while waiting for further articles.71 The latter chose not to, however, opposing him in the November–December 1925 issue of the Revue Thomiste.72 After reading his article, Journet writes Maritain that he himself could resolve many of his difficulties without too much trouble.73 Maritain swiftly replies to this letter, but he makes no allusion to the controversy that has now “gone public.”74 Marín-Sola himself replied to each of Garrigou-Lagrange’s difficulties in the following issue of La Ciencia Tomista.75 Since our concern with it again is only as it bears upon Maritain, we will only review clarifications to the three central points earlier noted. To take the last first, Marín-Sola is again at pains to indicate that his doctrine does not entail any first causality of the creature in the good. First, he notes that theologians speak of motions that are “frustrable,” “fallible,” or “impedible,” but he prefers the third (which is evidently closer to Thomas’s own language); for God’s glory and the good of the universe are not frustrated (even if a creature sins), and it is not God’s motion that “fails,” but the sinner.76 Second, “the making use of grace comes from the grace itself; but the not making use or abuse comes from our own fault, in which we, and not God, are the first cause.”77 And thus, if Peter is moved by God most determinately to act well, he is thereby moved not to place an impediment to the divine motion, since in this precisely consists to act well. . . . If Peter does not place an impediment, then, he has in truth more than John, who places it, but he has neither more nor less than that to which God moves him.78 Furthermore, to the one who does not place an impediment to the sufficient prevenient or operating grace received, God will give a further aiding or cooperating grace, because God never interrupts the course of grace if 71 Ibid., 341. 72 Garrigou-Lagrange,“La grâce efficace est-elle nécessaire pour les actes salutaires faciles?” Revue Thomiste 30 (1925): 558–66. 73 Journet, letter no. 131 (December 24, 1925), 348. 74 Maritain, letter no. 132 (December 31, 1925), 350. 75 Marín-Sola, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones”: See note 2 above for the full reference. 76 Ibid., 33. 77 Ibid., 56–57. 78 Ibid., 60. God’s Permission of Evil 71 man does not interrupt it, and with this greater grace, he has a greater continuation of the act than the other.79 He again explains, now in greater depth, God’s knowledge of the defect he does not cause. He again refers to a teaching of some Thomists (now Gonet, not Billuart) that man “objectively and materially determines the divine motion.”80 He then adds: By only recalling that, in Thomism, all divine knowledge of the contingent is always posterior to [that is, supposes] the decree, one will immediately see that, if it is right to say that the divine motion and divine decree are modified by something of the creature, it will be right—and with greater reason—to say that the divine knowledge, always posterior to the decree, is modified. But all this is an objective and material modification made by the defect of the creature. It is, in a word, a defective modification.This in no way prejudices the rights and the dignity of the first cause, because God is the first cause only in the line of the good.81 His doctrine is that this defect is known in God’s eternal action and he offers the following analogy: [I]f I am raising in the air an object that can offer resistance to my action, a child for example, then in that very arm—that is, in my action or my causality—I am perceiving the effect of raising it; in that very arm, I perceive that the child struggles or resists my action; in that very arm, I perceive that the child has broken loose or escaped my action.82 Or again: “If I see a statue well and it has no head, I see the statue to be without head; that is, I see not only what it has, but also, seeing all that it has, I see ipso facto all that it does not have, all that it lacks, all its defects.”83 Or, finally: This action of God, this actual not potential causation, in being infinitely intimate to being insofar as being, which is its proper and formal effect, is present to everything; and, in being infinitely intelligent, sees all of it; and, in being eternal, foresees all of it: whether positive or negative, whether good or defective, whether infallibly or fallibly caused: absolutely all.84 79 Ibid., 54. 80 Ibid., 38–39. Gonet’s text is from his De Scientia Dei, disputation 4, no. 200 (Vives,Tome I, 426). 81 Ibid., 39. 82 Ibid., 49. 83 Ibid., 50. 84 Ibid. 72 Michael Torre As can be seen, Marín-Sola appeals to God’s eternity (or his decree as eternal) to explain how he can know infallibly something that is not caused infallibly. He points out that something can be present to another in two ways: by causality and by real containment. Thus, for example, water is contained in a vase or bodies in space (and are present to the latter without being caused by it); and thus, were these containers “by nature completely intellectual and infallibly comprehensive, they would contain all these things intellectually and would infallibly know them, without any relation to their causality.”85 Since, “in order for a thing to be present to eternity what is required according to Thomistic principles, neither more nor less, is that it exist in time”;86 and since this only requires that it be caused not that it be caused infallibly, it follows that something can be fallibly caused and yet be present to, or contained by, God’s eternity, and thus be known infallibly. Finally, as regards God’s permission itself, it might be wondered why God allows a creature to resist him, since he could move him irresistibly to the moral good.With other Dominicans, Marín-Sola allows that there is nothing contradictory to freedom in willing the moral good irresistibly; indeed, he holds that this is a perfection of freedom, one proper to God himself (who freely yet infallibly wills the moral good).87 And he holds that God does move the will this way: for example, in the process of justification, when he infuses sanctifying grace.88 Yet, Marín-Sola argues, God also (and generally) moves creatures in a way that is “exactly accommodated to the exigencies and conditions of the creature.”89 Since all free creatures are by nature defectible, God moves them in a way accommodated to their defectible nature, such that they can resist or not his solicitations to act rightly.90 In other words, God wills absolutely that a 85 Ibid., 36. 86 Ibid, 44. 87 Ibid., 24. 88 Ibid., 58. In Marín-Sola’s doctrine, if God calls, then one is infallibly called; like- wise, if God justifies, one is infallibly justified; and, finally, if God wills that one persevere in grace, then one infallibly perseveres. But there is a course between vocation and justification and between it and final perseverance, and one may impede that course.Thus, God moves free creatures in two different ways: sufficiently and efficaciously. The first is the general way proportioned to the free creature’s own nature, which is defectible; the second is the special way proportioned to God’s own indefectibility, when he introduces his divine life into his creature’s own: when the Holy Spirit first inspires it, in its vocation; when the Holy Spirit first dwells in the creature through sanctifying grace, in its justification; and when, by its final perseverance, the Holy Spirit ensures its entrance into God’s everlasting glory. 89 Ibid., 23. 90 Ibid., 24. God’s Permission of Evil 73 free creature be able to resist him or not. In his first article, Marín-Sola notes (following Ferrariensis) that God’s antecedent will of an end includes the consequent will of means to that end:91 that is, God wills absolutely that a free creature be moved toward an end defectibly, permitting the end to be, or not to be, impeded. Marín-Sola supports his position by an abundance of texts from his Dominican tradition. Indeed, no one—before, during, or since his time— has displayed a similar mastery of that tradition, at least in relation to these matters.92 He also quotes a number of important texts in Thomas. Here are just a few key examples: “quod aliquis dicitur extinguere Spiritus Sanctum in se, vel in alio, cum alius aliquid boni ex fervore Spiritus Sanctum vult facere, vel etiam cum aliquis bonus motus in ipso surgit, et ipse impedit: actorum 7—vos semper spiritui sancto restitistis” (In I Thessalonians, cap. 5, lect. 2);“in potestate liberi arbitrii est impedire divinae gratiae receptionem vel non impedire” (Summa contra Gentiles, III, 159); “in rebus volunatarius defectus actionis a voluntate actu deficiente procedit, inquantum non subjicit se actu suae regulae. Qui tamen defectus non est culpa, sed eum sequitur culpa, ex eo quod cum tali defectu operatur” (Summa theologiae I, q. 49, a. 1, ad 3); “ratio interdum cessat a consideratione regulae debitae, et sic voluntas producit actum peccati” (ST I–II, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1); “non uti regulae rationis praeintelligitur in voluntatem ante inordinatem electionem: huius autem quod est non uti regula rationis non oportet quaerere aliam causam nisi voluntatis libertatem quia videlicit in eius potestate est ut sinat moveri a ratione, vel non sinat” (De malo 1, 3).93 I note the above texts of Thomas, as I have various of Marín-Sola’s texts, only so that one can better see the degree to which Maritain’s later doctrine depends upon his. (It can still be difficult, as it was for Maritain, to obtain Marín-Sola’s articles.) As those familiar with Maritain know, he refers to many of these very same texts in support of his own position. This is not surprising, for they are central to the question at issue. Still, it 91 Marín-Sola, “El sistema tomista,” 16–17. Ferrariensis’s text is from his In Summa contra Gentiles, III, 94. 92 He quotes, often at length and from different works, the following Thomists: Juan de Aliaga, Alvarez, Bancel, Billuart, Cajetan, Capreolus, Contenson, Ferrariensis, Pedro de Godoy, Gonet, González de Albeda, Goudin, John of St.Thomas, Peter de Ledesma, Lemos, Massoulié, Medina, Navarette, Nicolaï, Reginald, the Salmanticenses, Serry, and Domingo Soto. He also quotes from works of his immediate predecessors (for example, Guillermin and del Prado) and from his contemporaries (for example, Hugon). 93 See Marín-Sola, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 12; and idem, “El sistema tomista,” 25 and 46 (my emphases). Michael Torre 74 was Marín-Sola who first called attention to the way they supported views Maritain will hold. Maritain apparently never had any difficulty with Marín-Sola’s views on permission. As noted earlier, he himself tended toward a somewhat similar view. Neither was he concerned with the idea of an impedible motion, although this considerably exercised Garrigou-Lagrange and thus seemingly gave him some pause. Maritain’s difficulties ever concerned the divine knowledge. This can be seen from a remarkable letter forwarded to Marín-Sola via Journet.94 Maritain thanks him for sending a copy of his second article and responds to it. Maritain begins by saying he remains much interested in his views and he desires that his thesis be demonstrated. He believes he has put his finger on difficulties that cannot be hidden, but a great “obscurity” remains for him: not so much in the infallibility of God’s knowledge (which MarínSola’s second article treated at length), but in its independence.95 Again with his customary intelligence, Maritain puts his finger on the key issue: what explains the way in which “the obstacle the creature opposes to the course of sufficient grace”96 passes from God’s simple knowledge (of its possibility) to his knowledge of vision (of its actuality). “Is it the will (at least permissive) of God that effects this passage? Or is it the defectus of the creature? And, in this last case, how avoid having the knowledge of God depend upon the creature?”97 The first option is the one defended by Garrigou-Lagrange (and many previous Dominicans); the second is the one proposed by Marín-Sola. Another way of putting the difficulty is to ask by what medium God knows the created deficiency: for the existence of an object to God’s eternity “is only a necessary condition for the certitude of God’s knowledge, but in no way a reason for that certitude.”98 He thus concludes as follows: “[H]ere is the gross objection, the antinomy that I do not see how to resolve: (1) The creature is the first cause of evil as such; (2) Nothing created can be the cause of the knowledge that God has of it.”99 One could only wish that every objector in a debate would pose as trenchant a difficulty as this one is with as much clarity and grace! 94 Maritain, letter no. 138 (February 19, 1926), 369–371. 95 Ibid., 369. Maritain had mentioned this problem to Journet (note 66, above) before reading the second article. 96 Ibid. 97 Ibid. 98 Ibid. 99 Ibid., 370. God’s Permission of Evil 75 Having raised the objection, Maritain then admirably suggests that Marín-Sola may have offered its possible solution, namely, by affirming that the creature is the cause of God’s knowledge of this deficiency, but that this does not render God’s knowledge dependent on things, for the created object is for it only a term materially attained. . . . One would thus say that God knows the good in his decree and the evil in this good itself (and in the decree ut aeternus), modified in fact by the first causality in the line of evil.100 In other words, he wonders whether the idea of a term “materially attained” does not answer his new objection concerning the independence of God’s knowledge, as well as his first objection concerning its determination. The former does not suffer any more than the latter, because what is at issue is no being or form, but an absence of being and form, a defect in being. Maritain regards this solution as “risky,” but he sees no other way of defending the thesis.101 This is the last we hear of Maritain’s response to Marín-Sola’s views in these letters.The exchange thus ends on a positive note. For, despite his strong initial misgivings, which have not entirely been removed, he is inclining toward the latter’s position (even if it is “risky”). He asks his forgiveness for writing him so freely, and hopes he will see in this “only a mark of the powerful interest I have in your work and of the excellent souvenir I retain of our conversation in Fribourg.”102 Maritain here acknowledges his intellectual debt. In his next letter, Journet indicates that he has passed his letter on to Marín-Sola, although he has not seen him since then (and we never do gather from him whether he sent a personal reply).103 Journet thinks Maritain has raised a good objection; he admits that he is unable to decide between Marín-Sola’s position and that of Garrigou-Lagrange, both of which seem to contain a contradiction (in the case of MarínSola, the idea of a creature modifying the divine motion); and he worries again about the outcome.104 That very month gave him further cause, for 100 Ibid. Maritain refers to Gonet’s passage quoted in note 80 above. It is more accu- rate to say that God’s knowledge of vision supposes the term materially attained: It makes no sense to say that God “sees” a creature, if no creature exists (at some time) to be seen.That the creature does exist, with whatever being it may possess, is caused by God’s formative idea of it and his creative will. 101 Ibid. 102 Ibid. 103 Journet, letter no. 139 (March 8, 1926), 371. 104 Ibid., 372. 76 Michael Torre Garrigou-Lagrange was not mollified by Marín-Sola’s second article, and he published a second article against it, in the March–April issue of the Revue Thomiste.105 Curiously, neither Journet nor Maritain ever refer to this second article. Perhaps that is simply because their surviving correspondence from this time is very thin.106 Marín-Sola, however, responded to it in the next issue of La Ciencia Tomista. Since he had already written his next article, he merely adds an appendix, replying to the further difficulties raised.107 In this article and appendix, he also responds to Maritain’s concerns. He begins the article by addressing a concern that Maritain had raised with Journet. (We cannot tell from the correspondence whether the latter passed this one on to Marín-Sola. If not, then he is responding to others who had the identical concern.) Marín-Sola had argued that sufficient grace gives man the power not to sin in easy (not difficult) matters, and for a limited time.This led to an objection, which he reports as follows: [T]hey believe that this distinction is proper to casuists, that it considers these questions from a moral or practical point of view, which is improper to Thomistic metaphysicians or theologians, who always have founded their theory on an ontological point of view.108 In reply to this difficulty, he points out that, for Thomas, fallen man is neither healthy nor whole, but sick; that is, he has the capacity to do some moral good—but not the difficult moral good—and for some time—but not for long. Since the actual graces remotely preparatory to justification109 105 Garrigou-Lagrange,“La grâce infalliblement efficace et les actes salutaires faciles,” Revue Thomiste 31 (1926): 160–73. 106 There is a “lull” in the published exchange at this point: Maritain writes no letters in March, one in April (no. 140), one (no. 147) and a postcard (no. 146) in May, and none in June; Journet writes only three letters in April and one in May (no. 141 and nos. 143–145): thus, there is an exchange of only seven letters over four months (March 8–July 11). 107 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones”; the appendix is 384–97. 108 Ibid., 321. For Maritain’s concern on this point, see note 67, above. 109 Marín-Sola’s theory should not be confused with that of González d’Albeda (later adopted by Henri Guillermin), who held that sufficient grace not only was an impedible motion, but that it could cause the proximate preparation for justification (my emphases). Marín-Sola holds that the latter is caused only by efficacious grace, the infusion of a new (and sanctifying) form. (On this point, see Marín-Sola,“Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 7 note 1.) For a later, more historically based, account of Thomas’s own teaching on actual, preparatory grace, see Guérard des Lauriers, OP, “La théologie du saint Thomas et la grâce actuelle,” L’Année Théologique 6 (1945): 277–300. For a similar type of analysis of what God’s Permission of Evil 77 are received in man’s fallen nature, they move him to do some (easy) goods and to avoid sin (for example, not impede God’s grace) for some time (not long). In speaking thus about “sufficient grace,” he is speaking of the capacity of man’s nature (that is, from an ontological point of view), but in its fallen state. Later, in a footnote to the substantive portion of his article, he replies directly to Maritain’s difficulty (and perhaps that of others, as well). He reports it as follows: [I]n reading our first article, some Thomists became alarmed, believing that our solution destroyed the infallibility of the divine knowledge. After our second article, they now concede that it saves the aforesaid infallibility; but they object that they see even less clearly how it saves the independence of the divine knowledge, which requires that it not have any created thing as a ratio cognoscendi.110 Marín-Sola first answers this difficulty by reference to the following text from Godoy: Objicies primo: “nihil creatum potest esse Deo ratio cognoscendi; alias eius scientia dependeret a rebus: sed si malum aut privatio cognosceretur a Deo per bonum creatum esset illi ratio cognoscendi privationem; ergo Deus non cognoscit mala per bonum creata.” Respondeo: ratio cognoscendi posse quadrupliciter sumi. Primo, ex parte cognoscentis, per modum speciei aut verbi. Secundo, per modum objecti motivi. Tertio, per modum objecti formalis terminativi. Quarto, ut objectum in quo materiale.Tribus illis modis nihil creatum potest esse Deo ratio cognoscendi, ne illius cognitio a creatura dependeat. Quarto modo potest aliquid creatum esse illi ratio cognoscendi, nec ex illo sequitur dependentia cognitionis divinae a creatura, sed tantum dependentia objectorum: et solum hoc modo malum per bonum creatum ab intellectu divino cognoscitur.111 It is ever typical of Marín-Sola not to take credit for someone else’s idea: His own idea is obviously that of Godoy. His central idea is thus not new; he does, however, provide the following commentary: [T]he reason of knowing follows the reason of being.Thus just as it would be impossible—according to the teaching of Saint Thomas (Summa Thomas himself meant by “sufficient,” see M. D. Chenu, OP, “Sufficiens,” Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques 22 (1933): 251–59. 110 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 360. 111 Ibid., 360–61. Godoy’s text is from his De Scientia Dei, disp. 26, no. 307, book I, 282. Godoy (and Gonet and Billuart) are defending Thomas’s teaching of ST I, q. 14, a. 10, ad 4 noted earlier: See the text in note 40, above. Michael Torre 78 Contra Gentes I, 71)—that God know the essence of sin, were He to know only his own essence, without knowing the essence of the creature, so it would also be impossible for God to know the existence of sin were He to know only his own will or action, without knowing the will or action of the creature. In both cases, the creature must enter as a medium or as a reason of being and thus as a reason of being known. In the first case, the essence of the creature; in the second, the action of the creature. . . . Thus, to us it appears evident that, according to the doctrine of Saint Thomas, to put in God alone the futurition of sin or the truth of sin or the divine knowledge of sin, is to put in God alone the reason of being of sin. If the creature enters, as it must enter, in the reason of being of formal sin, because it—and not God—is its first cause, there is no other remedy than to make it also enter in some manner in the reason of being known of sin, at least “per modum objecti in quo materialis,” without this interfering either with the infallibility or with the independence of the divine knowledge.112 Marín-Sola here argues not that this doctrine is perfectly “clear,” or that it removes the mystery for us of “how” God knows sin, but that it is the truth we are left with when other alternatives are eliminated as impossible. From his first article on, he argues that this is to place the mystery in these matters in the right place. In his third article, he appeals to John of St. Thomas: “Hoc est ergo maximum et obscurissimum mysterium hujus attributi et in quo humanus intellectus omnino caliigat.”113 His is a salutary reminder that mystery is no weakness in theology, especially when it results from avoiding an absurd contradiction. Garrigou-Lagrange had equally worried that, if God’s knowledge supposed anything created, this would render it dependent or passive. In his appendix, Marín-Sola supplies this decisive remark: The essential or metaphysical relations of things, and, therefore, the infallibility of these relations, are not born of the will or efficient causality of God or of pure Act, but are supposed by it. Well then: in all existing being, even in the case of its existing by a fallible causality, there is an essential metaphysical property, supposed and not caused by the free will of pure Act.This essential property is the “infallibility of fact,” expressed many times by Saint Thomas in the formula that “all that exists, while it exists, exists infallibly. . . .” In virtue of this essential principle that “all the existent or caused (whether caused infallibly or fallibly) exists infallibly while it exists,” it results that the effect of a fallible causality can be the object of an infallible knowledge. In this case, the infallible knowledge 112 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 361. 113 Ibid., 360, note 1. John of St.Thomas’s text is from his De Deo, q. 10, disp. 9, art. 3, num. 1 (Vives, book 2, 80). God’s Permission of Evil 79 of vision supposes something in the created object, without receiving anything of the created object. That which the knowledge of God supposes is something essential (the essential law of “infallibility of fact”) and, as all the essential—although it is supposed by the free will of God, and therefore, by the knowledge of vision—is a formal effect of the divine intelligence or simple intelligence, exemplary cause of all the essential, we hold that the science of vision of pure Act can suppose something in known objects; but this is something that, in its turn, comes from the very essence or simple intelligence of pure Act. One can affirm a supposition of something, without any divine dependence or divine passivity.114 He again takes no credit for this reply, pointing out that Cajetan had given a similar reply to an objection of Scotus (in a passage he had earlier cited).115 Finally, his third article also provides a metaphor for his doctrine on sufficient grace. The electric company supplies electric current to his house and gives him two keys with which he can turn it off: One that turns off one floor only, the other that turns off both.Although he cannot light his house (that is the work of the electricity supplied by another), he can darken it (either partly—the sin of commission—or wholly—the sin of omission). All that is in his hand, as first cause, is something negative: to turn off the light (that is, not to use the power that is in his hand, not to use his intellect to consider the rule that he could consider).116 This is a modern equivalent of Thomas’s metaphor that we close our eyes to the light or close the shutters of our house to the sun:117 Again, our responsibility as first cause is purely negative. Just as neither Journet nor Maritain refer to Garrigou-Lagrange’s second article, neither do they refer to Marín-Sola’s reply to it. Instead, Journet’s next reference to the controversy is to a further piece Garrigou-Lagrange 114 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 386–87. Marín-Sola indicates that he is preparing a book on these questions. This is the first volume of his Concordia Tomista, dealing with God’s knowledge. (It runs to over one thousand portfolio pages.) He finished it in 1928, in Ocaña, the year after leaving Fribourg, together with a reply to Garrigou-Lagrange’s final piece written against his position: See note 118, below. The third volume of the Concordia Tomista, on God’s will, was then worked on during his return to Manila in 1929, but was left incomplete at his death in 1932. It runs to over six hundred portfolio pages. 115 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 387. Cajetan’s text is In I, q. 14, a. 13, no. 14 (Leonine, t. 4, 188–189) and was cited in Marín-Sola, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 47. 116 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 375, note 1. 117 For an example of Thomas’s first use of the metaphor of shutting our eyes to the light, see 1 SN, 40, 4, 2, and ad 4; for that of the shutters, see 3 SN, 33, 2, 1, 1 and obj. 4.Thomas uses these metaphors throughout his career. 80 Michael Torre wrote against Marín-Sola.118 While he thinks many of its difficulties could be avoided, he still thinks it “hits home” (“cela porte”).119 He does not find Marín-Sola’s solution to the divine knowledge “solid”; and, while he is not satisfied with Garrigou-Lagrange’s solution either, he thinks it is “better to put obscurity on sin than on the divine knowledge.”120 He also mentions that Marín-Sola has asked him if Maritain had received his (third) article. In reply, Maritain indicates that he has, but asks Journet to excuse him from answering further: He “no longer is able to,”121 apparently wishing to honor the silence the Master General is imposing on this controversy.122 He comments that Garrigou-Lagrange is content with this action. While perhaps “politic,” he himself can imagine “more noble solutions,” and says there still is need of a profound study of the permission of evil.123 (Some thirty-five years later, he himself would attempt to supply this.) Journet’s last comment on this controversy is not very even-handed, for the difficulty in each position concerns something of God. While Marín-Sola must explain God’s knowledge of sin, the other position must explain God’s will in relation to sin: not just sin itself, but the divine 118 Journet, letter no. 148 ( July 11, 1926), 388. Garrigou-Lagrange’s piece was titled “Principia Thomismi cum novisimo congruismo comparata:Thomismi renovatio an eversio?” This was to have been published in the Angelicum; since the Master General imposed a silence on this controversy in the summer of 1926, it came out instead as a fascicule of that publication ([1926]: 121–75). Marín-Sola wrote a line-by-line reply to it (that runs to over twelve hundred portfolio pages, forming the actual second volume of his Concordia Tomista). 119 Ibid., 388. 120 Ibid., 389. 121 Maritain, letter no. 149 ( July 15, 1926), 390. Given the warmth and depth of their previous exchange, it is difficult to interpret his words (“Je n’en peux plus”) as deriving from any other source than a desire to be sensitive to the silence that the Master General was “about to impose on all the world” (“le P. General va imposer silence à tout le monde”).This silence would not have applied to Maritain, a layman with no formal affiliation to the Dominicans, much less to his private correspondence. Yet, as the Journet correspondence itself makes very clear, Maritain was much involved with many Dominicans at this time of his life. (Indeed, this was to be true throughout his life.) Given that Garrigou-Lagrange was a close personal friend, Maritain seems to have felt it was politic to avoid a further exchange at this time with Marín-Sola. 122 Ibid. This imposed silence explains both why Marín-Sola ceased publishing his series of articles and also why the first volume of his Concordia Tomista, although a complete book, was not then published.When Marín-Sola also wrote his reply to Garrigou-Lagrange, he must have known that it, too, was not likely to be published at that time. Seventy-five years later, it still awaits publication. 123 Ibid. God’s Permission of Evil 81 permission of it.This is often pointed out by Marín-Sola, and never more eloquently than in these words: Really, if one notices the phrases, more than the mind, of certain theologians, one would gain the impression that—under the pretext of saving the infallibility of divine knowledge—they are intent on establishing an infallible connection between divine causality and sin, making sin or the impediment be known by the sole means of a decree, even though disguised with the name of permissive decree, and that the premotion or beginning of the act leaves the most holy and most loving hands of God already infallibly connected with sin. No, no, and a thousand times no!124 Rarely has a Dominican been willing to express so forcefully the objection of many other Catholics when faced with what has to them seemed a necessary implication of the “Thomist” view! When confronted with Jansenism, many Dominicans attempted to elucidate how grace could truly be “sufficient” and sin could thus truly be our responsibility.125 Yet, because God’s permission itself limited that grace to be only a capacity, which God (by his permission) chose not to activate, the word “sufficient” again seemed little more than a disguise. Here are Marín-Sola’s eloquent words on this development: All those who admit in God no more providence than the infallible nor more decrees than the infallible nor more premotions or graces than the infallible appear to us to rest on that theory that there is no more will in God than the infallible or consequent, and thus that the antecedent will (with the decrees, motions, and graces that correspond to it, and that are called sufficient) is a will of pure name, a will of sign, not a real, true, and 124 Marín-Sola, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 38, note 1. 125 As Marín-Sola argues throughout his articles, the Dominican position on these questions is framed by two controversies: on one side by that of de auxiliis and on the other by that of Jansenism. Both prior to the first and after the second, Dominicans make a strong use of God’s antecedent will and man’s resistance to it in order to explain man’s responsibility for sin. But Bañez regarded that will as one of “sign” only, and his systematic use of that idea in the controversies on grace led to a “hardening” of the Dominican position, for a brief time.Yet, due to the nature of the de auxiliis controversy, aspects of that position became “enshrined,” as “the” Thomist view on these issues, and it was difficult for Thomists responding to Jansenism (for example, Gonet and after) to free themselves entirely from those aspects, even though these no longer accorded with their own teaching on God’s antecedent will. Marín-Sola saw himself as attempting this “liberation,” and as, thereby, returning the Dominican view to positions and principles also held prior to the de auxiliis controversy. 82 Michael Torre sincere will of beneplacito.126 It is true that this is not said clearly, and that the names of antecedent will and will of beneplacito are conserved.Yet, in reality this antecedent will is then destroyed in one of two ways: either by converting it into a will of pure sign, which is the equivalent of saying that it does not suffice in fact for anything, nor certainly for not placing an impediment in easy things and for a little time, and this way affirms that sufficient grace is a pure potency; or by transforming it into the consequent will and saying that it serves for something, but all that one has one has infallibly, and this is the theory that admits that sufficient grace is a premotion, but an infallible premotion, which is the equivalent of saying that there are no more true divine decrees than the infallible. Both theories are going to end up the same, that is, in denying the antecedent will of God: either by reducing it to so little that it serves in fact for nothing or by augmenting it to so much that there are no more ways than the infallible or irresistible in fact, with which one converts it into the consequent [will]. No, no, and a thousand times no!127 126 The author of this invention within Thomism (that the antecedent will is one of “sign” only) would appear to have been Cajetan. For a summary of diverse scholastic views of the antecedent will, see Albert Michel OP,“Volonté de Dieu, salvifique universelle,” in the Dictionnaire du Théologie Catholique, vol. 15, 2nd part (Paris: Letouzey et Ané, 1950), 3368. Scotus had argued the antecedent will was one of sign only (see his In 1 SN, 46, 1), following both Alexander of Hales and Bonaventure. In adopting this view, Cajetan incorporated a typically Franciscan position into that of Dominicans. A Thomist might suppose that he had some ground for this view, since in the Summa theologiae,Thomas himself describes the antecedent will as more like a “velleity” or mere wish (ST I, q. 19, a. 6, ad 1) than an absolute will; that is, it is like an inefficacious will, such as the desire “I wish I could fly,” which gives rise to no further action. However, this is to forget the supposition of Thomas’s text, which is that God (the just judge) is confronted with a sinner (a hardened criminal deserving of death). On that supposition, namely of a sinner with an impediment to his grace or who has resisted his conditioned will to save him, such a will may indeed be inefficacious. But that is because the sinner, not God, has first placed an impediment to it, and because God—in his absolute will—chooses not to overcome this impediment. The entire mistake of some Thomists on this point is to forget Thomas’s supposition that grounds his use of “velleity,” and thus to make it universally applicable: to those in sin and those not in sin. This error is the complement to the error of holding that God’s permission infallibly entails sin on any supposition, rather than for someone in sin: See note 52, above. 127 Marín-Sola, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 43. Another reason for this error, as he remarks later, is that “some theologians, even Thomists, want to give a universal extension to many Augustinian formulas on infallibly efficacious grace (67).”The “logical-mindedness” of Dominicans thus led to the curious situation of their placing a greater emphasis on God’s efficacious grace and decree (and his knowing sin by virtue of his decree) than Augustinians (who held differently regarding the grace of Adam). I say “curious,” because Thomas himself was initially criticized by some Franciscans (who regarded themselves as “truer” to God’s Permission of Evil 83 Again, those who have in the past been critical of the way Dominicans have interpreted sufficient grace could hardly articulate a stronger objection. Indeed, one of the characteristics of Marín-Sola’s treatment of this matter is to indicate how the Thomist interpretation he is offering makes the Dominican position much more acceptable to other Catholic positions, especially that of St. Alphonsus Ligouri.128 He not only notes this in relation to Augustinians129 and to “Sorbonic congruism,” but also in relation to some Jesuit theologians (for example, Billot), who tend toward the more traditional Dominican view.130 (He never mentions St. Robert Bellermine’s theory of “negative determination,” but it bears an obvious relation to his view: What Bellermine had applied to man’s freedom, he limits to the fallible mode of that freedom, or to man’s fallibility.)131 Furthermore, since Marín-Sola is intent on showing that his theory accords in its essentials with the solid “Thomistic edifice” of Bañez, and thus on distancing himself from the errors of Molina,132 he does not Augustine) for not taking this view, and the very first Dominicans to defend Thomas did so precisely in relation to the importance of his doctrine concerning the physical presence of created things to God’s eternity! (See John Quidort’s Correctorium corruptorii circa, ed. Jean Pierre Muller, OSB [Rome: Herder, 1941], a. 3, 26.) Thomas ameliorates Augustine’s position through Damascene’s antecedent will. In making this inefficacious (either a will of “sign” only or an idle “velleity”), later Dominicans become even more “rigorous” than Augustine. 128 See Marín-Sola, “El sistema tomista,” 14 and 31, note 1; and especially idem, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 17–20. For a study of Ligouri’s position that brings out their agreement fully, see Jose Fidel Hidalgo, Doctrina Alfonsiana acerca de la gracia eficaz y suficiente (Rome: Angelicum, 1951). 129 For the Augustinians’ view, see Winifried Bocxe,“Introduction to the Teaching of the Italian Augustinians,” Augustiniana 8 (1958): 356–96. In a remarkable series of articles in the Revue des Études Augustiniennes (1960–1966), the modern Augustinian Athanase Sage,A.A., applies Augustine’s ideas on Adam’s grace to those who are returned to a state of grace but still remain in via. He develops therein the Augustinian position in a way that accords perfectly with the Thomist position defended by Marín-Sola. See, especially, Sage’s “Augustinisme et théologie moderne,” Revue des Études Augustiniennes 12 (1966), 134–56. 130 See Marín-Sola, “El sistema tomista,” 14 and 31, note 1. 131 For an exposition of Bellarmine’s theory, see J. M. Hellin, SJ, “Determinación negativa en S. Belarmine,” Estudios Eclesiásticos 10 (1938): 161–99. In English, a good article is R. Z. Lauer,“Bellarmine on Liberium Arbitrium,” Modern Schoolman 33 (1955–1956): 61–89, esp. 79–89. 132 See Marín-Sola,“Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 71–73. Marín-Sola argues that Bañez and his companions held (against Molina) that grace was efficacious ab intrinseco and that predestination was completely free or “ante praevisa merita.” In defense of those theological positions, they advanced two philosophical ideas: the divine decrees and physical premotion (both as necessary to cause free acts). He defends Bañez on each of these points. 84 Michael Torre underline that it also saves his “intent behind the error”; for God’s “general concursus” can be modified by the creature (but only negatively, and as a subordinate cause—not a coordinate one), and God does not know sin in his decree alone (but because creatures are present to his eternity—not because of a scientia media).133 Marín-Sola even acknowledges that some “Molinists” have raised a telling difficulty: How could God know a defect “in his permissive decree,” if the latter supposed a knowledge of that same defect, which impedes sufficient grace?134 His own distinction between man’s actual defect of non-consideration (which precedes sin and God’s permission of that) and sin itself (which supposes a final permission) is crafted in part to overcome this objection. Finally, since “negative reprobation” is one of the most controversial ideas of the Thomist position, this text seems worth quoting at length: Some Thomistic novices, in reading phrases where St. Thomas clearly says that the unique motive of negative reprobation is the greater good of the universe, thereby imagine that negative reprobation cannot suppose the foreknowledge of actual sins, as though “being uniquely for the greater good of the universe” and “supposing the foreknowledge of sins” were incompatible things, whereas, on the contrary, they are things that can be united. Let us take a common example to make this clear. Let us suppose that Peter has committed a crime, punished by the laws of the nation with the penalty of death. Let us also suppose that the prince of the nation so loves Peter that he has a true and most sincere will to pardon him and free him from death, but it is a will conditioned 133 Marín-Sola argues that Molina also defends two theological positions: predesti- nation “post praevisa merita” and “versatile grace” (Marín-Sola,“Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 70). Marín-Sola’s view likewise “saves” truths contained in these theological positions. For God’s gift of final perseverance, while free and in no way “due” to previous merits, can still suppose them; and God’s sufficient grace can be impeded or not (and is “versatile” in that sense).Thomas himself expressly taught that predestination could suppose the foreknowledge of futures, both in the Summa theologiae (III, q. 1, a. 3, ad 4) and in a late quodlibet question (5, 5, 1): that is, in late and most authoritative texts. 134 Marín-Sola mentions this difficulty in “El sistema tomista,” 50 and note 1. He says it was brought against Gonet first by Johannes Baptist Cardinal Franzelin (De Deo uno [Rome: Typographia Polyglotta, 1876], 458–59) and then is repeated later by a defender of the scientia media, Francis Zigon, in Divus Thomas, arbiter controversiae de concurso divinae (Gorizia, 1923), 148. Zigon was later to offer a critique of Marín-Sola’s own view from his “Molinist” viewpoint in “MarínSola, OP, de motione divina,” Ephemerides Theologicae Lovaniensis 8 (1931): 17–46 and 51–72. Herman Lange, SJ, was also to give a Molinist “critique” of his views in “Marín-Sola, Bañez und Molina,” in Scholastik 1 (1926), 533–65. For an effort to reply to these objections, and to other objections later advanced by diverse theologians to Marín-Sola’s view, see my “God’s Permission of Sin,” 413–533. God’s Permission of Evil 85 by one sole condition: by the condition that the pardon does not oppose the good of the republic. Let us suppose, finally, that the prince, after studying the case well, sees that to pardon Peter would be against the greater good of the republic, and in consequence, he decrees two things: (a) not to pardon him, but (b) to surrender him to the law and that he be hanged. In this case, a current and common one every day, two things are clearly evident: (a) the true and unique cause of not forgiving Peter (negative reprobation) is not the crime, but the greater good of the republic, since even after and despite the crime, the prince has the true and sincere desire to pardon him; (b) on the other hand, the true cause of hanging him ( positive reprobation), is the crime committed.Thus are verified two affirmations of the doctrine of St. Thomas: first, that the motive of positive reprobation is sin; second, that the motive of negative reprobation is the greater good of the universe, but a good of the universe that supposes sin, because without sin the salvation of a person would never be opposed to the good of the universe.135 Marín-Sola’s work in these articles is nothing less than an attempt to exorcise from Thomism the idea of “negative reprobation ante praevisa demerita.” So much does his position open itself to the other schools of Catholic theology on these issues that it has well been said to have brought an end to the quarrel generated by de auxiliis.136 Despite his last comment noted, Journet clearly continues to be uncertain about these issues. Thus, over two years later, he makes a final mention of Marín-Sola.137 He indicates that he is now in Manila; he notes Franzelin’s objection that Marín-Sola had acknowledged and admits that he continues to find Garrigou-Lagrange’s “solution” to it unsuccessful;138 and he asks Maritain to work “to shed a little light on 135 Marín-Sola, “Nuevas observaciones,” 370–71, note 1. 136 See Illytd Trethowan, OSB, “St. Thomas and the Problem of Evil,” Dublin Review 212 (1943): 176.This is a review article of Maritain’s book by the above name, and thus as he articulated Marín-Sola’s position. One can take this idea further. The recent declaration on justification between Catholics and Lutherans holds that “personal consent [to grace] . . . is itself an effect of grace” and yet that “a person can reject the working of grace” ( Joint Declaration on the Doctrine of Justification by the Lutheran World Federation and the Catholic Church, 4.1, nos. 20 and 21): This exactly follows the “directive line” of his thought. And, in emphasizing Damascene’s antecedent will, his position is equally consonant with that of Orthodoxy. 137 Journet, letter no. 276 ( January 11, 1929), 658–75. 138 Ibid., 661. Garrigou-Lagrange’s solution applies the adage “causae ad invicem sunt causae” to this problem, but Journet here, as previously (for example, letter no. 139, July 15, 1926, 372) finds this to be a misapplication; for the same aspect is considered as both previous and posterior to the permission: There is thus a vicious circle. In other words, he acknowledges that Garrigou-Lagrange fails to answer Cardinal Franzelin’s objection. 86 Michael Torre the question of premotion, above all on the points of resistance to grace” and how God can know this in his permissive decree.139 Much later, he himself would attempt to shed some light on these difficulties.140 Given Maritain’s avid interest in Marín-Sola’s views, the degree to which he vanishes from his correspondence following his last letter is remarkable. He makes only one other reference to him, almost two years later, and this in relation to a matter raised in Marín-Sola’s Evolution (which he had by then read), and not in relation to God’s permission.141 Nevertheless, his interest in the questions raised remained strong. As Cottier notes in his appendix to the correspondence, Maritain dedicated his course on metaphysics at the Institut Catholique, in 1936–1939, to “questions of freedom in God and in man”142 (thereby fulfilling Journet’s request). It seems, then, that he followed Marín-Sola in fixing his position only after a thorough examination of Thomas’s text. The evident consequence of this study was to put to rest his lingering doubt about MarínSola’s position. His own writings on this subject come increasingly to defend ideas and distinctions that derive directly from that position. We can see the parentage of his position from his very earliest writing on this subject. In his “A Philosophy of Freedom,” he insists that man is the first cause of sin, specifically of “the mutilation that deforms my act,”143 and this is something that he can do “without God, by withdrawing myself, as if by an initiative emanating from my nothing, from the 139 Journet, letter no. 276 ( January 11, 1929), 661. 140 See his Le mal, essai théologique (Paris: Desclee, 1961), in English, The Meaning of Evil (New York: Kenedy and Sons, 1962), 176–82. He there indicates his clear sympathy for Maritain’s views, as he had gone on to elaborate them in Existence and the Existent and in On the Philosophy of History. Journet had already endorsed Maritain’s positions in Entretiens sur la grâce (Paris: Desclee, 1959), in English, The Meaning of Grace (New York: Kenedy and Sons, 1960), 25–31, a series of talks first given in 1956. Indeed, he had communicated to Maritain that, after attentively reading Existence, he found it “marvellous,” (vol. 3 of their correspondence, letter no. 937, November 26, 1947). 141 Maritain, letter no. 237 (May 6, 1928), 566. (The editors also annex some texts, on the matter of Catholic faith and doctrine [749–56] that Journet had supplied him in September 1927, and which make much use of Evolution.) Maritain ends by accepting Marín-Sola’s views on the development of doctrine, as can be seen from a letter in vol. 2 of their correspondence, no. 306 ( January 4 or 11, 1930), 21 and 24. In the same volume, he also expresses to Journet how very pained he was to learn of Marín-Sola’s death (no. 419, July 31, 1932, 256). 142 Cottier, “La liberté,” 746. 143 Maritain, “Une philosophie de la liberté,” in Du regime temporal et de la liberté (Paris: Desclée, 1933):The English is from “A Philosophy of Freedom,” in Freedom in the Modern World (London: Sheed and Ward, 1936), 27. God’s Permission of Evil 87 current of divine causality.”144 Maritain here adopts Marín-Sola’s very own metaphor. Not surprisingly, he also adopts other elements of his position: God’s (final) permission supposes our “refusal,” but “does not will to prevent”145 its effect; history is the result of “concordant or discordant initiatives”146 of Creator and creature (of being and non-being, respectively); and God’s knowledge of the creature’s first causality in sin is secured by virtue of His eternity “where all the moments of time are indivisibly present.”147 We also find here his first characteristic exegesis of John’s “without me you can do nothing.”148 Maritain’s position regarding sin is altogether brief, but its directive lines are clearly set. Two years later, he expands on these ideas. He now uses the word “nihilate” to refer to man’s first initiative in evil, which he here identifies as the creature’s “free non-attention to the rule of action.”149 This word (“nihilation”) is unique to Maritain, but he here indicates that it is identical in concept to the “non-consideration of the rule” to which MarínSola had earlier called attention: to the creature’s initial free defect that causes sin.150 Maritain also again argues that God knows this defect because it is present to his eternity; but he now further insists that “evil cannot be known save in the same instant when it thus wounds existence”151 (thus in the creature’s will, and not in God’s will or decree). Maritain here clearly accepts Marín-Sola’s solution to the difficulty of God’s infallible knowledge of sin. He goes even further, answering his own initial worry that this would “determine” God’s knowledge, by giving us Marín-Sola’s very own response! Thus, to one so worried (as he had once been), he responds by asking: “Do you believe that created beings are for divine knowledge anything else but a secondary term attained as a mere ‘material’ or factual 144 Maritain, “A Philosophy of Freedom,” 27 (my emphasis). 145 Ibid., 27. 146 Ibid., 28. 147 Ibid. 148 Ibid., 27. 149 Maritain, “La clef du chant,” published first in the Nouvelle Revue Française 5 (1935): 778–809; and then as chapter five of Frontières de la poesie et autres essais (Paris: Rouart, 1935); the English is from “The Freedom of Song,” in Maritain, Art and Poetry (New York: Philosophical Library, 1943), 85. Journet writes Maritain his strong approval of this article. He does not miss its parentage, saying he believes that “Father Marín-Sola would have been ravished” by Maritain’s work (vol. 2, letter no. 518 [May 29, 1935], 466). 150 In his next treatment of this subject, he explains that “nihilate” merely describes this initial defect “in picturesque present-day language”: Maritain, St.Thomas and the Problem of Evil (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1942), 24. 151 Maritain, Art and Poetry, 83–84. Michael Torre 88 datum, in no way formative or specifying?”152 It may be remembered that Maritain had initially regarded this answer as “risky”; he is now ready publicly to embrace that risk. World War II brought Maritain to America, and it was there that he was to present a “rough draft” of his entire position in his Marquette lecture of 1942. Here, he even more clearly insists on the real distinction between sin and the initial defect that is its defective cause, now relying on the same text of De malo (1, 3) that Marín-Sola had earlier noted: One must “consider as prior” (“praeintelligitur”) to sin a defect in the will, and one need seek no further than the will itself for its reason.153 Maritain also notes that Thomas specifies that this defect is not yet sin or a privation, but the cause of sin or a “negatio pura.”154 In this he is original, for Marín-Sola had not quoted this text. However, since Thomas divides defects between privations and negations and since Marín-Sola had expressly affirmed that the will’s prior failure to use the intellect to consider the rule was not a sin (and hence not a privation), he had said virtually as much. Pointing out this text does have the merit, however, of demonstrating the consistency of Thomas’s position. There is again nothing more than a verbal novelty in the way Maritain now chooses to speak of the divine motion or grace that is resisted by the creature: it is one that is “merely ‘sufficient’ or breakable (‘brisable’).”155 There is no real or conceptual difference between a motion that is “impedible” and one that is “breakable.” Maritain himself later acknowledged this, saying that he had “proposed this expression ‘breakable motion or actuation’ as a kind of philosophical equivalent of the theological expression ‘sufficient grace.’ ”156 He also now uses MarínSola’s words of “the lines of good and evil,” pointing out that there is a “dissymmetry” between them (since the creature is first cause only of an impediment to God’s motion).The word “dissymmetry” is new, but not the concept. All of the distinctions Maritain has been developing hang together and are aspects of Marín-Sola’s theory.To this point, the remarks Maritain has made on the subject are embedded in longer works and do not tackle at length the relation between the divine motion and free will. He does this 152 Ibid., 84. 153 Maritain, St.Thomas and the Problem of Evil, 24. Marín-Sola quotes the text in “El sistema tomista,” 46, note 1. 154 Ibid., 29.Thomas’s text is De malo, 1, 3, ad 13 (although it is mistakenly printed as “ad 3” in his lecture). 155 Ibid., 37. 156 Maritain, On the Philosophy of History (New York: Scribners, 1957), 120, note 3. God’s Permission of Evil 89 first following World War II in the fourth chapter of Existence and the Existent. In this work, he now makes the following points, all made previously by Marín-Sola: that the creature’s “non-impediment” adds nothing to the divine motion;157 that a breakable motion moves the free creature according to the fallible mode proper to its nature;158 that there are two divine permissions: one that makes sin possible (by moving the creature in an impedible way), and the other that infallibly entails sin (supposing that the creature impedes the motion by his defect);159 that the order of motions that is sufficient or breakable derives from God’s antecedent will, which is an active will of beneplacitum and not an idle velleity;160 and that God’s providence “takes into account” the “nihilations” of the creature, as first cause.161 The latter is clearly just another way of saying that God’s predestination can suppose a knowledge of our defect (a position MarínSola again expressly defends).162 With Existence and the Existent, Maritain commits himself to MarínSola’s position, both in its directive lines and in its details. On one point, however, he seems to differ from him slightly. In a lengthy footnote, he argues that—supposing a creature does not impede the divine motion— it then receives a new, infallibly efficacious motion that is specifically different and that effects the good election.163 It seems evident that Maritain is here trying to accommodate the earlier concern of GarrigouLagrange; for, with him, he here holds that an infallibly efficacious motion is necessary to cause any good choice. (Or, to put the point differently, he here appears to be ontologizing Marín-Sola’s sufficient and efficacious graces, making both types of motions be proper to every choice.) Yet his thought is murky here. For he also says that, should we not impede the divine motions, then they “fructify by themselves into the unshatterable divine activation.”164 This is Marín-Sola’s view. In any case, Maritain was later to repudiate certain aspects of this footnote and to 157 Maritain, Court Traité de L’Existence et de L’Existant (Paris: Paul Hartmann, 1947); the English is from Existence and the Existent (New York: Pantheon, 1948), 92. See also page 100 and its note 10. 158 Ibid., 93–94. 159 Ibid., 110. 160 Ibid., 102. 161 Ibid., 118. 162 Marín-Sola, “El sistema tomista,” 32–40. He is mainly concerned to defend that predestination supposes the knowledge of sin; as he says (44), the idea that predestination can also suppose the existence of non-persevering merit is secondary and not necessary to defend the first proposition. 163 Maritain, Existence and the Existent, note 9, 94–99; see especially 95 and 97. 164 Ibid., 94. 90 Michael Torre maintain that its attempted distinctions were “to a large extent incidental” to his main thesis.165 Marín-Sola had himself anticipated the type of reservation that Maritain apparently had felt. In a footnote, he observed that some Thomists might “become frightened” by the idea of man’s defect modifying the divine motion and thus want to hold that it is God himself who modifies His own motion.166 He says that “this accidental change of formula is to us of little importance”:167 What is essential is that God never causes the activity in sin unless man’s defect is supposed as ontologically prior. Now, what is accidental in regard to an impediment is likewise so in regard to a nonimpediment.The essential point is that God permits a free creature to be moved to the honest good in a way that can or cannot be impeded, and that his defect or failure derives from his will alone, not God’s permission. Given the extraordinary degree to which Maritain follows MarínSola, it is remarkable that he does not mention him further. His involved footnote may supply the reason: He was still mindful of GarrigouLagrange and his former strong opposition to this view. Perhaps Maritain felt that he was trying to stake out a “middle ground” between the two positions. More likely, he simply did not want to find himself in contention with his old “mentor.”168 He was evidently not the only one to proceed in this manner. For, in his notes to volume 1 of the Spanish bilingual edition of the Summa theologiae published that same year, Francisco Muñiz, OP, advocates Marín-Sola’s position on these matters . . . without ever once mentioning his name!169 He acted the same way 165 Maritain, God and the Permission of Evil, viii. In that same work, he says that his thought in that footnote involved a “complementary distinction badly arrived at” (55). 166 Marín-Sola, “Respuesta a algunas objeciones,” 64, note 1. 167 Ibid. 168 He would not have been wrong to be mindful of Garrigou-Lagrange! The latter saw not only the likeness between Maritain’s views and those of González d’Albeda and Guillermin, but that Maritain had gone “much further” (“beaucoup plus loin”) than they, precisely in allowing that the initial defect in sin does not infallibly follow a divine permission (my emphasis). He tells Maritain that such an admission will lead “much further than he thinks,” and he expresses his “deep regret” that he had published these pages: See vol. 3, letter no. 957 (April 18, 1948), 639. Maritain replies, briefly defending his position, and again without mentioning Marín-Sola. 169 Francisco Muñiz, OP, Suma teologica de santo Tomas de Aquino, vol. 1 (Madrid: Biblioteca de Autores Cristianos, 1947), appendix 2, 979–1055.That Muñiz’s views were those of Marín-Sola did not go unnoticed; see José Sagües, SJ, “Reflexiones teológicas: Crisis en el Bañecianismo?” Estudios Eclesiásticos 22 (1948): 699–749. God’s Permission of Evil 91 when he later supplied the notes to the volume on God’s grace.170 Given that he was a younger colleague of Garrigou-Lagrange at the Angelicum, his behavior is not altogether surprising: The latter was still a powerful figure in Rome. Maritain may likewise have felt that it was wise for him to distance himself from this “Dominican quarrel.” If so, he was not entirely successful. To begin with, his position gave rise to a series of articles in the Revue Thomiste, with many Dominicans “weighing in” (mostly favorably) on the ideas he had presented in Existence and the Existent.171 And then Jean-Hervé Nicolas, OP, wrote a sustained article that was pointedly critical of his views.172 During this period, Maritain had continued to meditate on ideas related to this matter.173 He was thus prepared to reply to Nicolas, clarifying his views 170 Francisco Muñiz, OP, Suma, vol. 5 (1956), appendix 1, esp. 757–81. Jesus Valabuena, OP, likewise followed Marín-Sola, and acknowledged as much, in his appendix 2, in vol. 3b of the Suma (1959), “El influjo de la causa primera en el obrar de las causas segundas,” 1117–1183. 171 See M.-J. Nicolas, OP, “La liberté humaine et le problème du mal,” Revue Thomiste 48 (1948): 191–217; C. J. Geffré, “La possibilité du péché,” Revue Thomiste 57 (1957): 214–45; G. Bavaud, “La doctrine du Père Marín-Sola sur la grâce: est-il une concession au Molinisme?” Revue Thomiste 58 (1958): 473–83; and M.-J. Nicolas,“Simples réflexions sur la doctrine thomiste de la grâce,” Revue Thomiste 58 (1958): 645–53. 172 J.-H. Nicolas, “La permission du mal”: For the full reference, see note 3, above. This gave rise to further articles in the Revue Thomiste, mostly supportive of Maritain. See G. Bavaud, “Comment Dieu permit-il et connaît-il le péché?” Revue Thomiste 61 (1961): 226–40; M. Corvez,“Où commence le péché?” Revue Thomiste 64 (1964): 53–62; L. M. Antoniotti, “La volonté antécédente et conséquent selon S. Jean Damascène et S. Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue Thomiste 65 (1965): 52–77; J. P.Arfeuil,“Le dessein sauveur de Dieu, le doctrine de la prédestination selon S.Thomas d’Aquin, Revue Thomiste 74 (1974): 591–641; and M. L. Guérard des Lauriers, “Le péché et la causalité,” in the Bulletin Thomiste 11 (1960–1962): 553–637. It is ironic that J.-H. Nicolas defended the same line as Garrigou-Lagrange . . . but while at Fribourg; whereas Muñiz defended MarínSola’s views . . . while he was at the Angelicum! (And Maritain also developed his “defense” of Marín-Sola while he was in Rome!) 173 In “Le péché de l’ange, essai de ré-interpretation des positions thomistes,” Revue Thomiste 56 (1956): 197–239, English: The Sin of the Angel (Westminster, MA: Newman, 1959), esp. 5–15, Maritain applied the structure of the free fallible act to the angel. And, in Neuf leçons sur les notions premières de la philosophie morale (Paris:Tequi, 1951), 174–76, English: An Introduction to the Basic Problems of Moral Philosophy (New York: Magi, 1990), 195–97, he begins to reflect on what in God is resisted by our sin, reflections that would later reach their culmination in one of his last essays,“Réflexions sur le savoir théologique,” Revue Thomiste 69 (1969): 5–27, esp. 14–26; English, “For an Existential Epistemology II: Reflections on Theological Knowledge,” in Untrammeled Approaches. Michael Torre 92 and giving his final and definitive position, in Dieu et la permission du mal.174 In this work, he returns to Marín-Sola’s position, affirming that a “shatterable” motion infallibly effects a tendency toward a good act, yet “can non-attain the final object to which it tends.”175 These are just different words for what Marín-Sola had earlier taught: that the divine motion infallibly effects the beginning of the good act, but that it may not reach its final term (due to an impediment). And Maritain further follows Marín-Sola in holding that the divine motion continues to the act of sin, but now as deformed by the defect: “[A]ll ordination to the moral good being suppressed by the fact of nihilation of the creature, the shatterable motion towards the moral good gives way to a simple premotion to all that there is of the ontological in the act of election.”176 Again, the difference between them is only verbal, not conceptual or real. It is even more remarkable that Maritain does not mention Marín-Sola in his reply to Nicolas, since the latter had distinguished his view from that of Marín-Sola. Here was the perfect opportunity to “set the record straight”! Yet he does not do this.This unfortunately allowed Nicolas’s characterization to stand.Thomists had to await the Journet–Maritain correspondence to see the degree to which it was inaccurate. (Nicolas, of course, had no access to that correspondence when he wrote. It was only published thirtyfive years later.) Maritain does here refer to Garrigou-Lagrange precisely as one who had “advanced” the traditional Dominican position in the right direction!177 This remark becomes a little less puzzling if one remembers that Maritain then goes on to criticize this position in no uncertain terms. Nevertheless, it does not clarify the parentage of his own views. Perhaps he felt that certain of his distinctions importantly distinguished his views from those of Marín-Sola. For he suggests that he may have made an “effective contribution” to philosophy more on this matter than anywhere else in his work.178 He does engage in certain “baroque” reflections on some of the finer points involved in the theory,179 and he was fond of such points, such as were often made by his favorite commentator, John of St.Thomas. Specifically, as I noted earlier, Maritain had called attention to the fact that Thomas describes the voluntary non-consideration of the rule as a 174 Maritain: in English, God and the Permission of Evil (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1966). 175 Ibid., 56. 176 Ibid., 57–58. 177 Ibid., 19. 178 Ibid., foreword, viii. 179 Specifically, see his “schemas” no. 2 and no. 3 in chapter II/II, regarding the “ulti- mate time” of deliberation and the “moments of nature” involved in the sinful act: God and the Permission of Evil, 47–54. God’s Permission of Evil 93 “negatio pura.” This term suggests that Thomas is thinking of a nonconsideration during the time of deliberation. In fact, when we deliberate about what we should do, we may consider many things. While we are considering, for example, the pleasure that might come from acting a certain way, we are then not considering the moral rule that should govern all our action (and that may prohibit our acting for this pleasure). Yet this non-consideration is clearly no fault, nor is it even connected to sin, as its defective cause, since we can go on to consider that rule before we act, and can choose in accordance with it (rejecting the pleasure considered). Thus, prior to the final judgment that terminates deliberation, any non-consideration is clearly nothing more than a negation, an absence that is not due; for we need only consider the rule when we proceed to make our choice. However, from the viewpoint of a faulty final practical judgment, we can and should rightly say, “this judgment was my fault, because I did not consider the rule (that should govern my action), as I could have.”Thus, we can and should also say,“that voluntary non-consideration was prior to and the cause of this judgment being defective”; as Thomas says, we can “pre-consider” the non-consideration in the intellect (and we can likewise pre-consider the voluntary non-use of the intellect by the will). Maritain, in noting that the voluntary non-consideration is a “negatio pura,” emphasizes the time of deliberation that precedes the final practical judgment. In this, as earlier noted, he is original. Marín-Sola, on the other hand, emphasizes the final practical judgment itself that establishes the connection between the non-consideration of deliberation and the subsequent inconsiderate and sinful election.180 Yet these emphases are in truth perfectly complementary:They are mutually related aspects of an identical theory. Perhaps Maritain felt that his own speculations helped explicate and defend a theory he had come to regard as deeply important, and that his “effective contribution” lay chiefly in its defense.Whether he did or not, it was through Maritain that Marín-Sola’s position was to affect French and English Thomists181 (as it was to affect Spanish Thomists through the work of Muñiz and Valabuena). Marín-Sola, as he himself said, 180 Maritain speaks of this, without identifying it as the final practical judgment. In his analysis, this is the first “moment of nature” involved in sin, a moment subsequent to the time of deliberation and prior to the sinful choice itself: a moment in which the prior “negatio pura” (non-consideration) now is sin’s negative cause. 181 To take only one instance, I myself came to take an interest in Marín-Sola’s view after having first become acquainted with it through the work of Maritain (and the critique of J.-H. Nicolas to which he makes reference). 94 Michael Torre had a real “veneration” for Maritain; he had “thought constantly” of him as he presented his doctrine; and he was obviously very much concerned to know how he had received his last articles.There is something fitting, then, that it was through Maritain (a far more famous figure than he) that his doctrine was to have a worldwide impact and to receive the attention it so clearly deserved. I think it must please him that God in his providence arranged matters this way. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 4, No. 1 (2006): 95–200 95 Book Symposium The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: A Constructive Conversation by Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz, SJ (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2002) The Future of Christian Biblical Scholarship R ICHARD B. H AYS The Divinity School, Duke University Durham, North Carolina I AM PLEASED that Nova et Vetera has invited me, as a Protestant biblical scholar, to join the “constructive conversation” that Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz seek to initiate, a conversation about future directions for biblical interpretation. While their book addresses itself explicitly to the future of Catholic biblical scholarship, its preface implies the hope that their proposals might be of more general relevance.1 Their diagnosis of the present situation is indeed pertinent for other ecclesial communities, and many features of their constructive program will prove instructive for interpreters outside the Roman Catholic Church. I want to begin this response, therefore, by emphasizing the substantial common ground between this book and my own perspective. Finding Common Ground Johnson’s diagnosis of the problems that we face hits the mark at numerous points.2 I concur with him that biblical scholarship within the 1 “Others can help us discover whether what we say on these things . . . applies also to other spheres.” Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz, SJ, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: A Constructive Conversation (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2002), viii. 2 I refer here particularly to the book’s opening chapter, written by Johnson, “What’s Catholic about Catholic Biblical Scholarship? An Opening Statement,” in ibid., 3–34. Book Symposium 96 professional guilds has frequently been overdetermined by certain postEnlightenment tendencies: a distaste for theology; a predisposition for highlighting disunity among the biblical witnesses; a hankering to reconstruct hypothetical layers, sources, and origins “behind” the biblical texts (even where there is no real evidence) and to assign privileged authority to these hypothetical earlier materials over the canonical witnesses; and an assumption that the Church’s history of interpretation is chiefly a history of misreading the original (and therefore “real”) meaning of the texts. Johnson’s description accurately characterizes the state of affairs in many sectors of the New Testament guild: “In short, the study of the Bible (not understood as “Scripture”) is increasingly an academic activity that is not merely secular but often actively antireligious in character” (26).3 Johnson correctly observes that this Tendenz of scholarship has had its impact even on interpreters who teach in seminaries and church-related colleges: While they may privately hold to traditions of Christian faith and piety, their actual teaching of the Bible is constrained by professional allegiance to illusory ideals of scientific objectivity and intellectual neutrality, and their understanding of the historical data may be shaped by critical paradigms that are implicitly anti-ecclesial.Thus, for example, courses on the Old Testament—even in seminaries—may teach students to eschew Christological interpretations of Isaiah or the Psalms and may insist that “Hebrew Bible” texts must be understood only within their hypothetically reconstructed historical context in ancient Israel. Or, to take a couple of New Testament examples, the hypothetical “Q” may be regarded as a more reliable source for understanding Jesus than the Gospel of John; and the Pastoral Epistles and Catholic Epistles may be treated as having lesser value than the seven undisputedly authentic Pauline letters.4 Such tendencies are widespread in Protestant scholarship no less than in the Catholic scene that Johnson describes; indeed, one of his claims is that these tendencies infected Catholic scholarship because “second generation” Catholic biblical scholars uncritically reproduced characteristics of the Protestant historical criticism that they sought to emulate. The result has been that biblical scholarship—Catholic and Protestant alike—finds itself alienated from theology and distanced from the prayer and practice of the Church. As I shall suggest below, Johnson’s portrayal of the situation is selectively and unsympathetically drawn. Nonetheless, the difficulties to which 3 Ibid., 26. Subsequent parenthetical page numbers in this essay, unless otherwise noted, refer to Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship. 4 These examples are mine, not Johnson’s, but I think they fairly illustrate the point he seeks to make. Book Symposium 97 he points are not imaginary.Anyone who surveys the field of professional biblical scholarship at the beginning of the twenty-first century will readily recognize that Johnson has identified tendencies and forces that do in fact exercise powerful influence in the academic world. In light of this diagnosis of the problem, Johnson and Kurz offer a number of prescriptive proposals, all of which are to be welcomed.They call for a recovery of biblical interpretation as a properly ecclesial activity that seeks not merely the acquisition of knowledge (scientia) but also the formation of wisdom (sapientia). Interpretation so conceived must conduct its business in open and sympathetic conversation with the Church’s liturgy, with theology, and above all with the history of interpretation, in the expectation that interpreters today stand to learn much from skilled Christian readers in the past. As Johnson and Kurz rightly indicate, such an approach to interpretation will necessarily open itself to figurative senses of Scripture, as well as literal ones, recognizing that a text’s meaning is not exhausted by its initial historical reference. Both authors are careful to stipulate that “the doing of history must remain a permanent aspect of biblical study” (18).Their chief concern, however, is to summon biblical scholars to a new and edifying dialogue with the Church’s rich tradition of scriptural interpretation. To their credit, Johnson and Kurz offer us not merely prescriptive declarations but actual examples of the sort of interpretation they advocate: Kurz through several chapters expounding passages from the Gospel of John, and Johnson through two incisive chapters on Origen and Augustine as biblical interpreters.These two chapters in particular are so strong that this reader finds himself wishing for more; perhaps Johnson will favor us in the future with further studies of patristic exegesis. One fears that the fine insights of Johnson’s treatment of Origen and Augustine may not receive the attention they deserve, since they are tucked away within a book that is chiefly a programmatic manifesto. As I read The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, I was immediately struck by the intellectual and spiritual convergence between this book and several other recent scholarly proposals. One thinks, for example, of the pioneering efforts of Brevard Childs to recover the history of exegesis, including premodern exegesis, as an integral element of biblical interpretation.5 Or one recalls Hans Frei’s influential argument, in The Eclipse 5 See, for example, Brevard S. Childs, The Book of Exodus: A Critical, Theological Commentary (Philadelphia:Westminster Press, 1974); idem, Biblical Theology of the Old and New Testaments:Theological Reflection on the Christian Bible (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1993); idem, The Struggle to Understand Isaiah as Christian Scripture (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2004). 98 Book Symposium of Biblical Narrative, that biblical interpretation in the German academy during the Enlightenment and afterward lost its bearings by its inability to read biblical texts as coherent narratives that must be read figurally.6 To cite more recent examples, one thinks of the work of New Testament scholars, such as Francis Watson and Stephen Fowl, who have sharply challenged some of the same aspects of the prevailing historical-critical paradigm that Johnson and Kurz identify; in different ways, each calls for a robust recovery of theological exegesis.7 Or, to mention one particularly striking instance, one thinks of David Steinmetz’s widely cited 1980 essay, “The Superiority of Pre-Critical Exegesis,” which concludes with the following provocative assessment: The medieval theory of levels of meaning in the biblical texts, with all its undoubted defects, flourished because it is true, while the modern theory of a single meaning, with all its demonstrable virtues, is false. Until the historical-critical method becomes critical of its own theoretical foundations and develops a hermeneutical theory adequate to the nature of the text which it is interpreting, it will remain restricted—as it deserves to be—to the guild and the academy, where the question of truth can be endlessly deferred.8 Certainly Steinmetz’s view of things ought to be profoundly congenial to Johnson and Kurz’s program. Finally, as a participant in an initiative called the Scripture Project, sponsored during the years 1998–2002 by the Center of Theological Inquiry in Princeton, I am impressed by the very substantial convergence of Johnson and Kurz’s agenda with the findings of our research group, published in a collection of essays called The Art of Reading Scripture.9 The members of the Scripture Project—a group of fifteen scholars, both Protestant and Catholic, spanning the disciplines of Old Testament, New Testament, theology, Church history, and the practice of ministry—articulated their agreement in a set of “Nine Theses on the Interpretation of Scripture” that envision a future for biblical interpretation that closely 6 Hans W. Frei, The Eclipse of Biblical Narrative:A Study in Eighteenth- and Nineteenth- Century Hermeneutics (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1974). 7 Francis Watson, Text and Truth: Redefining Biblical Theology (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1997); Stephen Fowl, Engaging Scripture: A Model for Theological Interpretation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998). 8 David C. Steinmetz,“The Superiority of Pre-Critical Exegesis,” in The Theological Interpretation of Scripture: Classic and Contemporary Readings, ed. S. Fowl (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 26–38.The quotation is found on p. 37. 9 E. F. Davis and R. B. Hays, eds., The Art of Reading Scripture (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2003). Book Symposium 99 parallels Johnson’s five “Premises of Premodern Interpretation” (47–60) and four “essential elements in recovering a scriptural imagination” (131–42). The Scripture Project’s nine theses insist that Scripture is chiefly about the triune God and call for, inter alia, reading Scripture in and for the Church, in light of the Church’s rule of faith and the hermeneutical example of the saints.10 Thus, a good case can be made that Johnson and Kurz are speaking in chorus with an impressive cloud of witnesses, not only in the Church’s past but also in the present moment. They are not lonely voices in the wilderness; rather, they stand within the ranks of a widespread reforming movement in biblical studies. Questions and Puzzlements And yet, despite my appreciation for the work of Johnson and Kurz, and despite my fundamental agreement with key aspects of their program, I come to the end of their book with certain nagging questions and puzzlements.These may be enumerated briefly as follows: (1) Why is their proposal formulated in a way that seems unnecessarily uncharitable toward Protestant interpreters? (2) What, if any, criteria enable us to decide when it might be appropriate to disagree with interpretations that have become traditional within the Church? and (3) Are Johnson and Kurz proposing a common vision, or do their distinct sections of the book embody materially different prescriptions for biblical interpretation? In the following remarks, I shall address each of these questions in turn. Polemic Against Protestantism First, is it really necessary for Catholic biblical scholarship, at the beginning of the twenty-first century, to define its task in polemical opposition to Protestantism? Throughout The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, one stumbles over careless caricatures of Protestantism and a puzzling tendency to conflate Protestant biblical interpretation with Enlightenment worldviews. We read that the deleterious aspects of the historicalcritical paradigm are a result of certain “mental reflexes” of “the Protestant form of Christianity from which the model derived” (15).The “reflexes” to which Johnson refers are then explained as follows: “In contrast to the conjunctive ‘both/and’ that I have suggested expresses the spirit of Catholicism, the Protestant ethos is expressed in terms of the disjunctive ‘either/or’ ” (15–16).The Lutheran slogan Sola Scriptura is said to entail the consequences that Scripture and Tradition can never be in dialectical 10 For the nine theses, see Davis and Hays, Art of Reading Scripture, 1–5. Book Symposium 100 harmony, that “the development of Christianity must be regarded as opposed to the spirit of its origins,” and that “the literal sense of Scripture must be opposed to figurative interpretations” (16). It must be admitted that Johnson’s sweeping caricature of Protestantism has some basis in historical reality—as caricatures usually do— and that some Protestant scholarship has exhibited the tendencies that Johnson deplores. Nonetheless, Lutheran interpreters would surely reply that Luther’s own understanding of the relationship between Scripture and Tradition was far more nuanced than Johnson’s bumper-sticker dichotomies would allow: Luther believed that authentic Christian tradition was in fact harmonious with Scripture, while Scripture provides the criteria whereby one can identify inauthentic and abusive developments of tradition, such as the selling of indulgences.11 The simplistic polemic against Protestant interpretation reaches its climax in Kurz’s chapter, “Voices in the Church: Preunderstandings in Applying Scripture” (182–202), which mounts a critique of the chapter on abortion in my book, The Moral Vision of the New Testament.12 The difference between Kurz’s position and my own is said to present a contrast between Protestant and Catholic hermeneutical preunderstandings, in which my argument allegedly reflects “a Sola Scriptura insistence that something has to be expressly treated in Scripture to be binding,” whereas Kurz’s argument represents a Catholic way of interpreting Scripture “within our broader Catholic context of Revelation” (187). I shall return later in this essay to reply specifically to Kurz’s assessment, which I believe represents an unfortunate misreading of my book—a misreading seemingly fostered by his reading of my work through the lens of this Protestant/Catholic dichotomy. For now, I simply register the question whether “the future of Catholic biblical scholarship” requires this kind of aggressive posture toward Protestant interpreters. It seems to me that it is Johnson and Kurz who are pressing a disjunctive “either/or” mentality that disregards the complexity of hermeneutical debates within Protestantism and threatens to undermine some of the goodwill built up during the past forty years of ecumenical conversation.13 ( Johnson notes in a humor11 See D. C. Steinmetz, Luther in Context, 2nd ed. (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Acad- emic, 2002). 12 Richard B. Hays, The Moral Vision of the New Testament: Community, Cross, New Creation (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1996), 444–61. 13 One notes with gratitude in the book’s concluding chapter a brief affirmation of the importance of ecumenical conversation in biblical interpretation (267). While welcoming this affirmation, I find it somewhat dissonant with the features of the book noted above. Book Symposium 101 ous aside [5] that his own dichotomous characterization of Protestantism and Catholicism embodies precisely the disjunctive reflex against which he is polemicizing, but he excuses this disconcerting fact by observing that “Catholics also have a high tolerance for paradox!”) The antagonistic stance of The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship toward Protestant biblical interpretation is particularly strange in light of the developments I described above: Some very influential Protestant interpreters have for the past generation been engaged in sustained efforts to reclaim precisely the hermeneutical approach that Johnson and Kurz advocate: respect for the history of premodern exegesis, openness to figural readings, the recovery of theological interpretation, and efforts to inhabit Scripture’s imaginative world.14 (Has anyone achieved the last of these aims more impressively than Karl Barth?) It is perhaps worth remarking that the publisher of The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship is not one of the traditional Roman Catholic publishing houses but rather William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, a publisher traditionally identified with the Reformed branch of Protestantism.This is surely a fact worth pondering. Johnson describes himself as “a Catholic whose professional training as a New Testament scholar took place at Yale, the very belly of the Enlightenment beast” (4–5). Presumably this is another attempt at humor. I, for one, find the humor in dubious taste; it gratuitously dishonors the work of Christian scholars such as Childs, Frei, and George Lindbeck, all of whom were members of the Yale faculty during Johnson’s years as a student and junior faculty member there.15 Surely Johnson’s characteristic emphases on narrative hermeneutics and recovery of the history of tradition must have been encouraged by his Yale environment more than he acknowledges in this book. 14 I note, for example, that twelve of the fifteen scholars who participated in the Scripture Project were Protestants, who found much common ground with— and were richly instructed by—the three Catholic participants: Gary Anderson, Brian Daley, and Robin Darling Young (all three of whom are now members of the faculty at Notre Dame). I think it would be fair to observe that The Art of Reading Scripture is free of the “Catholic vs. Protestant” polemic that appears in The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship. 15 Admittedly, none of these scholars taught specifically in the field of New Testament, Johnson’s own discipline. Perhaps there is a more complex story to be told here; some clues may be detected through reading Wayne Meeks’s stringently anti-theological presidential address to the Studiorum Novi Testamenti Societas in Barcelona in 2004 (now published as “Why Study the New Testament?” New Testament Studies 51 [2005]: 155–70). But even in the field of New Testament, one can hardly avoid recalling the work, in an earlier generation, of Yale’s Paul Minear, a scholar whose life work might aptly be summed up in Johnson’s phrase, “imagining the world that Scripture imagines.” 102 Book Symposium In short, one of my first impulses after reading The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship was to pick up the phone, call the authors, and say, “Hey, Luke and Bill, hold your fire; we’re on the same side!” I did not do that. But this essay represents my attempt to re-establish diplomatic relations between interpretive forces that ought to be allies.The real enemy of Johnson and Kurz’s hermeneutical project is not Protestantism but Enlightenment secularism and its strange postmodern derivatives. My point here can be made simply: I would find their book more generous, and wiser, if they had chosen to imagine and write about The Future of Christian Biblical Scholarship.16 A corollary of The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship’s antagonism toward Protestantism is Johnson’s searing indictment of “biblical theology.” In Johnson’s view, the enterprise of “biblical theology” seeks to impose “a false harmony” on the diverse witnesses of Scripture “by means of some extrinsic category.” (Would it be fair to ask how such procedures might differ from Augustine’s insistence on the unity of Scripture, his explicit attempts to harmonize the Gospels, and his use of “charity” as the material hermeneutical norm for all scriptural interpretation?) Or, to state a different accusation, biblical theology seeks “to close the gap between historical criticism and the Bible” simply through “the use of more history.” But this attempt is doomed, because “Biblical theology manages to keep the world of Scripture firmly in the past.” Biblical theology, according to Johnson’s account, “derives neither inspiration nor authority from the life of the Church, and it does not address itself to the transformation of human existence within a community that imagines itself living within the world imagined by Scripture” (129–30).This is an astonishing charge. I am at a loss to identify the actual targets of Johnson’s polemic against biblical theology. Perhaps Johnson’s harsh judgments are, to some limited extent, true of the exponents of the “Biblical Theology Movement” of the 1950s and 1960s, but it is very difficult to see how such charges can be sustained against the interpreters I have listed above, including Watson, the most articulate recent advocate of “biblical theology.” (Consider the concluding sentence of Childs’s most recent book: “By reviewing the 16 I might also raise the question of whether Johnson’s polemic does justice to the Christian motivations and contributions of the Catholic biblical scholars of what he calls the “second generation.” Kurz is characteristically more cautious on this point and more appreciative of the positive pastoral contributions of the “second generation” (see, for example, 146). I am sure, however, that this question has already been vigorously debated within the Catholic Biblical Association, and perhaps it would be wiser for me to stay out of this family dispute. Book Symposium 103 history of the Church’s biblical interpretation, we can derive new confidence in confessing with the creed: I believe in the one holy catholic and apostolic Church.”)17 It is simply baffling that Johnson seeks to document his case by referring in a footnote to Wayne Meeks’s The Origins of Christian Morality as an illustration of the alleged tendency of biblical theology to devolve into “an exercise in the history of ideas, or an ethnography of ancient culture.” (130, note 21) In fact, there is no more adamant foe of biblical theology than Wayne Meeks.18 Johnson is once again firing at the wrong target.19 This is perhaps the place to state my puzzlement about a powerful ambivalence that runs through Johnson’s discussion. Does he or does he not see himself living within the world imagined by Scripture? Or to use Johnson’s own metaphor, is Scripture for him a lost city or a living city? On the one hand, he is fiercely critical of biblical theologians and historical critics who no longer inhabit the scriptural world and who must therefore “approach” Scripture from “somewhere else” (127–28). On the other hand, within the very same chapter, he can describe himself as a postmodern person who is “estranged from the world of Scripture, but . . . not contemptuous of it.” He can declare that “the greatest difficulty our 17 Childs, Struggle to Understand Isaiah, 323. 18 “[W]e should start by erasing from our vocabulary the terms ‘biblical theology’ and, even more urgently,‘New Testament theology.’ Whatever positive contributions these concepts may have made in the conversation since Gabler, we have come to a time when they can only blinker our understanding” (Meeks, “Why Study the New Testament?” 167–68). 19 Equally strange is Johnson’s complaint (129, note 19) that my book The Moral Vision of the New Testament makes “ ‘the historical Jesus’ a key element of New Testament theology.” As even the casual reader of my book will see, the problem of the historical Jesus is treated in a ten-page excursus following a much more extensive discussion of the individual Gospel witnesses. This excursus begins with a lengthy explanation of my decision not to make the historical Jesus central: “the historian’s re-imagining of Jesus, however informative and interesting, can never claim the same normative theological status as the four diverse canonical accounts” (Moral Vision, 160). Further, the excursus leads to this judgment in the final paragraph: “Thus, in one sense, the reconstruction of the historical Jesus adds nothing new to New Testament ethics. If it adds anything at all, it is merely what Luke calls asphaleia, a confidence in the truth of the things about which we have been instructed by the storytellers who wrote the Gospels” (167).When my book moves in its last section to the treatment of specific ethical problems (Moral Vision, 313–470), “the historical Jesus” plays virtually no role at all. Johnson has elsewhere articulated other criticisms of Moral Vision that are more substantive, but on this point his critique is misplaced. It appears that my book has simply gotten caught in the crossfire of Johnson’s indiscriminate assault on Protestant biblical theology. 104 Book Symposium generation has in doing theology is our distance from the imaginative world of Scripture, which means, our distance from the God revealed by the world as imagined by Scripture” (122). And he can describe his own hermeneutical project in the following language:“I argue that the peculiar challenge to faith today is to oscillate creatively between worlds constructed by secular analyses and the world constructed by Scripture” (132, note 24). Is that not precisely what Rudolf Bultmann did in his day? And is it not very much the same thing attempted by the “biblical theologians” for whom Johnson expresses such dismissive contempt? The dizzying rhetorical reversals enacted within these few pages rival the dialectical self-accusations performed by that master of theological dialectics, the Apostle Paul, in Romans 7: “I do not understand my own actions, for I do not do what I want, but I do the very thing I hate.” At the very least, in light of this complex hermeneutical situation, Johnson ought to consider adopting a more charitable posture toward other interpreters who grapple with very similar problems. Criteria for Discernment We turn now to a different issue. On what basis might we as interpreters of Scripture take positions that differ from the received traditions of the Catholic Church? Johnson explicitly indicates that respectful and receptive reading of the tradition does not necessitate agreement with it: “Closer examination of these ancient interpreters will reveal the ways in which we can and should disagree with them” (61).20 But on what grounds? Johnson never offers an explicit, focused answer to this question, but as the discussion unfolds, several examples of such disagreement—or development—come to the surface. First, Johnson evidently believes that late modernity has developed an understanding of narrative meaning that is more sophisticated than, and at least in some respects superior to, the hermeneutical theories accessible to patristic interpreters. This point emerges particularly in Johnson’s critique of Augustine:“Augustine lacked a theory of language that would enable him to find a place between allegory and literal-as-referential as a mode of truth-telling in Scripture.” This theoretical deficiency left Augustine caught in a bind in his attempts to respond to Faustus the Manichaean: In order to defend the truth of the Gospels’ witness to Jesus, he was forced to fall back on literalistic attempts at harmonization. “Trying to prove too much, he falls into the danger of the very vice he 20 One looks in vain for any such suggestion in Kurz’s contributions to the book. This is one of the significant differences to which we shall return below. Book Symposium 105 despises, namely of manipulating the evidence in order to achieve the desired result” (104–6). Johnson’s critique—a critique surrounded by much appreciative exposition of Augustine’s underlying concerns—is exactly correct:“His anxiety concerning the historicity of the Gospels . . . led him to downplay the very real critical problems presented by their differences” (108). Indeed, Augustine’s Harmony of the Gospels is replete with strained and unpersuasive attempts to explain away these differences, while at the same time remarkably oblivious—from our point of view— to the literary and theological distinctiveness of each of the four witnesses. Augustine’s literalistic harmonizing, which finds its modernist counterpart in fundamentalist apologetics, offers no real solution. Scholars in modernity who did recognize “the very real critical problems” presented by the differences among the Gospels, however, plunged almost inescapably into the realm of historical speculation that so absorbed Johnson’s “second generation” of Catholic scholars, as they attempted to reconstruct the historical events behind the Gospels and the processes of composition and editing that yielded the texts as we now have them. Johnson also regards this sort of explanatory effort as a hermeneutical dead end. The alternative, in Johnson’s view, is a “theory of ‘narrative truth’ ” (106) that allows us to escape from the conundrum posed by Augustinian literalism on one hand and historical criticism on the other. He articulates this constructive approach to narrative in a couple of brief paragraphs near the end of the book, in his “Response to Bill Kurz”: Patristic and medieval interpreters rarely if ever saw compositions whole. The premise of contemporary literary criticism, that narratives bear meaning immanently in and through the composition as such and as a whole, is only rarely spotted in antiquity. Patristic and medieval interpreters had much more of an atomistic approach to narratives, seeing them in more oracular terms. The development of literary criticism within biblical scholarship is . . . to be applauded because it enables us to ask the question about the truth of narratives in ways that are more creative and flexible than were available, for example, to Augustine.We can think of the Gospels as rendering the figure of Jesus truly even if they disagree in their telling and cannot be harmonized as historical sources. They speak truth precisely as witnesses and interpretations, in and through the form of narrative (250–51). Once again, I find myself, broadly speaking, in agreement with Johnson at this point.21 The problem, however, is that The Future of Catholic Biblical 21 Here again Johnson’s work is strikingly convergent with the proposals of The Art of Reading Scripture. 106 Book Symposium Scholarship offers very little explicit development of this extremely important claim.What precisely does it mean to say that the Gospels render the identity of Jesus “truly” even if they are not referentially factual? Is the correspondence between narrative and history a matter of complete indifference for theological interpretation? If not, how do we understand the relationship between them? And why is Johnson’s literary-critical theory of narrative truth preferable to Augustine’s? These are not novel questions, and—to be fair—Johnson has addressed them to some extent in other books.22 Nonetheless, one comes away from The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship with the slightly uneasy sense that Johnson and Kurz are tying the future of Catholic biblical scholarship to a particular hermeneutical proposal about narrative that is decidedly underdeveloped in the present volume. If they hope to rally Catholic (or, as I would prefer, Christian) scholars around their proposal, they owe us a more expansive account of these matters. The closest Johnson comes in The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship to addressing these questions is in his final substantive chapter, “Imagining the World That Scripture Imagines” (119–42). Here he sketches the outlines of a sapientia that will enable us to interpret the Bible more faithfully. His proposal, in brief, has four components: (1) We must learn to apprehend Scripture not as a descriptive or propositional text but as a fountainhead of imaginative vision,“as a vast collection of interconnected and internally coherent images” (133). (2) We must read Scripture together in “communities of practice” (134), small reading communities dedicated to Christian discipleship. (3) We must learn anew to read Scripture imaginatively, moving beyond the literal/historical to grasp “the rich world of image and metaphor within Scripture’s compositions” (136).23 (4) We must read Scripture in dialogical interaction with “close and obedient attention to actual human experience in the world” (141). The last of these “four essential elements in recovering a scriptural imagination” (131), though it receives the briefest development (141–42), seems to be singled out as particularly important. (Note that in contrast to the first three elements, it receives a new bold heading in the text.) Johnson wants us to attend, precisely in our reading of Scripture, to “the work of the 22 L. T. Johnson, The Real Jesus: The Misguided Quest for the Historical Jesus and the Truth of the Traditional Gospels (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1996); idem, Living Jesus: Learning the Heart of the Gospel (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1999); idem, The Gospel of Luke (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1991). 23 The difference between Johnson’s first and third points here is not immediately evident; clearly, they are closely related. In any case, I eagerly endorse at least the first three of Johnson’s four desiderata. Book Symposium 107 Living God in the world” as it is encountered through “human stories.” Johnson suggests (remarkably) that contemporary theology has been inattentive to human experience24 and argues that “the human drama of idolatry and sin, grace and faith” can be “if properly heard, revelatory.” Johnson’s recommendation at this point is strongly reminiscent of a powerful strain of Protestant liberalism, running from Schleiermacher to Bultmann to some contemporary feminist theologies. It would be illuminating for Johnson to clarify how his program parallels or differs from these sorts of experientially centered theologies—whose besetting weakness is a tendency to turn theology into anthropology. One worries slightly about Johnson’s mandate that we give “obedient attention” to human experience.What might it mean to owe “obedience” to the many and varied narratives of human subjectivity? (I confess that, upon encountering this phrase, I could not get out of my mind the advertising slogan for the soft drink 7-Up: “Obey your thirst!”) Of course, much hinges on the qualifier:“if properly heard.” Experience is hardly an unambiguous teacher.25 I believe that Johnson must have in mind—as Kurz certainly does in his chapters—a way of interpreting experience that is given normative guidance by the Rule of Faith, by the Church’s historic creeds, and by the Church’s liturgy. But—at least in his chapter on “Imagining the World that Scripture Imagines”—Johnson does not clearly say so.To the contrary, “experience” seems to be revelatory in its own right; indeed, it becomes—alongside a modern theory of narrative truth—a second sort of criterion that might provide leverage for critique or revision of Christian tradition—as Johnson has elsewhere proposed.26 If I am reading Johnson rightly at this point, what response would he give to those interpreters, whose voices have grown more insistent in the 24 I can only assume that Johnson means to refer here to certain types of Roman Catholic theology. Protestant theology, both in its liberal and evangelical forms, has been awash in the seas of human experience for the past two hundred years. This would be particularly true of my own Wesleyan tradition. 25 Interestingly, in his “Response to Bill Kurz,” Johnson reacts warily to Kurz’s argument that the experience of repentant postabortion women supports the Catholic teaching against abortion, because the counterargument made by proponents of abortion also “uses the criterion of experience to make the exact opposite point.” Consequently, Johnson reminds both his colleague and himself that the criterion of experience “is as slippery as Scripture itself and must be discerned as carefully” (254). It is a salutary reminder. The question of criteria for discernment looms, unresolved. 26 For the outworking of this revisionary function of “experience” with regard to the Church’s teaching on human sexuality, see L. T. Johnson, Scripture and Discernment (Nashville,TN: Abingdon Press, 1996). 108 Book Symposium academy, who read “human experience” as the definitive evidence that the Bible and the Christian gospel are inherently violent and oppressive? How are such experientially based claims to be evaluated? One of the surprising features of Johnson’s chapters is that he expends so much energy in his polemic against the historical criticism of a generation that is passing away, while mostly ignoring the much more pressing challenges posed by the postmodern hermeneutics of suspicion and the polarizing hermeneutics of various identity-group theologies.27 Surely the future of Catholic biblical scholarship depends much more on how it will answer these challenges faithfully than on how successfully it fights rear-guard battles against the generation of Raymond Brown and Joseph Fitzmyer.28 Kurz does devote about two pages to the hermeneutics of suspicion, in which he concludes flatly that, whatever its value for “the domain of history and sociology,” it has no value for discovering the spiritual sense of Scripture (226–28). Johnson addresses the issue briefly in his response to Kurz, with a wise cautionary remark that the concerns of “those who have been hurt badly by readings of Scripture . . . that justify intolerance or oppression of humans” cannot be so lightly dismissed. His prescription for response to this situation is the formation of a community of reading that “empowers all readers” (254). If I may be permitted to speculate, it seems to me that Johnson is relatively uncritical of experientially based theologies because they are methodologically congenial, at least in crucial aspects, to his own program: They are indeed giving obedient attention to human experience and expecting to find a revelation of the Living God there, precisely within the messy human drama. I do not doubt that we stand to learn much that is theologically valuable by careful listening to human stories, and I join Johnson in affirming that human experience provides significant input for theological reflection.The crucial question, once again, is how one processes and evaluates the reports of human experience.What criteria enable us to distinguish the work of the Living God from the claims of idols and the self-deceptive desires of the 27 The topic is not entirely absent from Johnson’s field of vision: on p. 130, he offers a couple of sentences sharply critical of “ideological criticism within the academy that only makes more explicit the assumed moral superiority of the contemporary reader to the world imagined by Scripture.” On this issue, see my essay, “A Hermeneutic of Trust,” in R. B. Hays, The Conversion of the Imagination (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2005), 190–201. 28 At recent meetings of the AAR/SBL, one is hard-put to find papers doing the sort of old-fashioned reconstructive historical work that Johnson frets about; however, one finds numerous papers about reading the text from particular social locations, or through the eyes of various marginalized groups. Book Symposium 109 human heart? With regard to these questions, I find Kurz’s more forthrightly tradition-bound position far clearer than Johnson’s—even while I find Johnson the more hermeneutically subtle of the two authors. A Common Vision? This comparison between Johnson and Kurz can serve as a transition to the third big question I have about The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: To what extent are these two authors really advocating the same program of interpretation? To what extent do they share a common vision? To be sure, Johnson and Kurz share many common concerns, as I indicated in my initial outline of the book’s key programmatic emphases. The more closely one reads their constructive discussions, however, the more one wonders whether they may be on divergent paths. Kurz is, from start to finish, committed to performing biblical interpretation within the framework of Catholic teaching, as mediated through the Church’s magisterium. He champions the Catechism of the Catholic Church as an appropriate guide to reading Scripture, and his sample exegetical probes unfailingly support contemporary Catholic doctrine and practice, whether the issue is Christology, abortion, Eucharist, or the sacrament of reconciliation.At no point does he entertain the notion that Scripture might play a critical role in relation to tradition, or that received ecclesiastical interpretations might be in need of some correction. He comes across, in these chapters at least, as a good company man, who strongly believes that the institution of the Catholic Church provides comprehensive and satisfying guidelines for interpreting Scripture. This gives his chapters the virtue of clarity and consistency, but one never has the sense that Kurz is actually learning anything through his exegesis or that Scripture might have the capacity to surprise the Catholic reader. Rather, his exegesis consistently reinforces preestablished beliefs and practices—and vice-versa. Many of the examples that he chooses to illustrate the value of reading Scripture from a Catholic perspective are obvious and unilluminating. For instance, it is not exactly a hermeneutical breakthrough to show that the prologue of John’s Gospel is consonant with the Nicene Creed (178–81). Kurz could hardly have chosen a less illuminating text to show how Catholic interpretation goes “Beyond Historical Criticism” (the title of his chapter on the Johannine prologue).29 A more interesting challenge 29 Kurz states: “Recently, under the unexamined influence of historical criticism, teachers and preachers have often seemed to go out of their way to minimize connections between this biblical prologue which Christians read and the Creed which they recite and doctrines which they believe. Consequently, many Catholics seem intimidated into not allowing themselves to recognize their 110 Book Symposium would have been to show how, for example, the Gospel of Luke—which is often thought to manifest a “low” or “prophetic” Christology— expresses a Christology consistent with the Church’s creedal traditions.30 Johnson, by contrast, is edgier and more hermeneutically adventurous. He shares Kurz’s commitment to read within Catholic tradition, but for him that seems to mean engaging in direct conversation with patristic primary sources, not with contemporary official ecclesial documents and structures. He believes that to read within the tradition is to be inspired to “imagine the world” afresh in the way that earlier readers did.As we have seen, such reading may lead to unexpected conclusions, even to a posture that is directly critical of the present Church’s teachings and practices. The contrast between the two is elegantly illustrated by one instance where these two colleagues permit themselves a relatively clear expression of difference: the interpretation of John 20:19–23 and its application to the practice of forgiveness of sins within the Church. This is the passage in John’s Gospel in which the risen Jesus appears to the disciples in Jerusalem on the evening of the day he was raised from the dead. Jesus shows them his hands and his side, pronounces peace upon them, and tells them that he is sending them just as he was sent by the Father.Then, the narrator tells us,“he breathed on them and said to them,‘Receive the Holy Spirit. If you forgive the sins of any, they are forgiven them; if you retain the sins of any, they are retained.’ ” Kurz discusses this text as a test case for “applying Scripture with the Catechism” (237–48). First he notes that the Catechism of the Catholic Church replaces John’s reference to “disciples” with the statement that Jesus conferred this authority on the “apostles.” Kurz describes this terminological substitution as an “actualization” of the text. This “actualization” is hermeneutically crucial for what follows. The fourth Gospel’s generic “disciples” are read as ciphers for ordained clergy who alone are authorized to pronounce forgiveness. Kurz writes: Trinitarian and Christological beliefs as being expressed in this prologue” (165). Because Kurz offers no citations in support of this claim, I find myself at a loss to know what he is talking about. In fact, there is really nothing in Kurz’s own reading of the prologue that is not supported, as Kurz’s own footnotes indicate, by Raymond Brown’s commentary—generally acknowledged for the past forty years as the preeminent historical-critical commentary on the fourth gospel in the English language. Raymond E. Brown, The Gospel according to John I–XII (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1966). 30 For an important engagement of this issue, see C. Kavin Rowe, “Luke and the Trinity: An Essay in Ecclesial Biblical Theology,” Scottish Journal of Theology 56 (2003): 1–26. I cannot resist observing that Rowe is (a) a Protestant; and (b) a strong advocate of biblical theology. Book Symposium 111 in John 20, the recipients of Jesus’ commission to judge sins are undoubtedly the group of “official” disciples who would later be the Church leaders. . . . This kind of judgment can obviously not be entrusted to every individual believer or private member of the Church but necessarily only to its leaders, whose authority to judge sins of Catholics furthers their mission to lead and direct the Catholic Church. [242–43, emphasis added] The italicized words and phrases highlight the several ways in which Kurz has superimposed a hierarchical, institutionalized understanding of Church and ordination on a text that notably lacks such an ecclesiology.31 The foil against which Kurz sets his reading is some unidentified group of “Bible Christians [that is, Protestants?] who do not believe in confession to a human minister” (240). My copy of The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship is strewn, on these pages, with numerous marginal question marks, exclamation points, and other more vivid expressions of dismay. Not only as a historical critic but also as a reader formed by a “believers’ church” tradition that strongly encourages all Christians to see themselves as recipients of the Holy Spirit and as commissioned by the Risen Lord to confess their sins to one another and to proclaim God’s forgiveness, I found Kurz’s reading tendentious and unpersuasive. I was therefore delighted to discover, a few pages later, that Luke Johnson found Kurz’s treatment of this material nearly as problematical as I did. Johnson suggests, in an artfully interrogative sentence, that by confining the authority to forgive sins to ordained clergy, the Catechism of the Catholic Church has “achieved an institutional shrinkage of the scriptural witness.” Rather than directly challenging Kurz’s exegesis of John 20, Johnson cites a counter-text, James 5:14–20, which calls the whole community to “mutual confession of sins and mutual prayer within the community, as well as mutual correction of wrong doing.” Thus, Johnson finds within the New Testament itself “a richer understanding of an ecclesial practice of forgiveness and healing than that presented by the Catechism of the Catholic Church” (258). I would add that Johnson’s side of this argument could be supported also by more careful critical exegesis of the Fourth Gospel itself, in which the disciples are not Church authorities but representative figures for all believers who in subsequent generations find themselves in union with Jesus. 31 On this point, see particularly the helpful remarks of Raymond E. Brown, The Churches the Apostles Left Behind (New York: Paulist Press, 1984), who comments on the “egalitarianism” of Johannine ecclesiology and finds no sign in the text that the Johannine community had an ordained priesthood, or even clearly established structures of authority (99–101). 112 Book Symposium The issue here is larger than the exegesis of one text or the justification of one sacramental practice. As Johnson rightly frames the matter, there is a “necessarily dialectical relation between tradition and Scripture.” Not only on this point but also more generally in his contributions to The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, “Father Kurz has properly emphasized the positive pole of that dialectic, the way in which tradition can be seen as legitimately developing and deepening the sense of Scripture,” but he has unfortunately “given less attention to the negative pole of the dialectic, which is the way in which Scripture also must challenge the tradition” (257). And with these words, near the end of the book, Johnson suddenly sounds—dare I say it?—like a Protestant. Or, rather, more precisely, he articulates a hermeneutical stance that I take to be healthy and necessary for Protestant and Catholic Christians alike. Perhaps Johnson and Kurz would say that their differences represent complementary viewpoints within a cordial conversation between colleagues engaged in a common project. Perhaps each requires the balancing influence of the other in order to represent the scope of Catholic hermeneutics faithfully. Perhaps it is so. But surely “the future of Catholic biblical scholarship” will have to choose to some extent between the options represented by their different assessments of the Catechism of the Catholic Church’s handling of John 20:19–23. Is the task of Catholic biblical scholarship chiefly to show how the Bible authorizes the Church’s “official” practices and pronouncements? Or is the task of biblical scholarship to bring Scripture and Church into a conversation that is mutually edifying, mutually critical, and open-ended? Johnson clearly advocates the latter, while Kurz, at least for the most part, represents the former. In my judgment, the future of the Church lies with Johnson’s approach. The ninth and final thesis of the Scripture Project reads as follows:“We live in the tension between the ‘already’ and the ‘not yet’ of the kingdom of God; consequently, Scripture calls the Church to ongoing discernment, to continually fresh re-readings of the text in light of the Holy Spirit’s ongoing work in the world.”32 This kind of eschatologically chastened hermeneutics is profoundly consonant with Johnson’s proposals about how to read Scripture. Preunderstandings and the Issue of Abortion William Kurz devotes one entire chapter of the book, as I have noted, to elucidating his Catholic hermeneutical perspective by setting it in contrast to my chapter on abortion in The Moral Vision of the New Testa32 Davis and Hays, The Art of Reading Scripture, 5. Book Symposium 113 ment. Readers will perhaps therefore forgive me if I bring this review essay to a close by responding briefly to Kurz’s critique of my position. I hope that this response will serve not merely as an exercise in self-defense but also as a further clarification of the issues that The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship seeks to raise. I must begin by emphasizing that on this particular issue—as on the wider issue of the appropriate agenda for biblical scholarship—there is extensive agreement between Kurz and me. Kurz and I agree that the Bible contains no explicit prohibition of abortion. We agree that it is therefore necessary to address the question by looking for a broader biblical framework: as I described it in Moral Vision,“placing the problem in the broader context of the New Testament’s symbolic world.”33 In view of this broader biblical framework, we agree that “[t]hough the New Testament gives no explicit prohibition, its portrayal of God as the author and giver of life creates a general presumption against any human decision to terminate life.”34 We agree that “the New Testament example and words of Jesus lead to a much more radical and complete rejection of killing” than is to be found in the Old Testament (197).We agree, further, that “Christians are to obey the commandments, even to a heroic degree, in imitation of Christ’s self-sacrificing obedience and supported by the Church” in caring for the weak and helpless (198).We agree that the evidence of Christian tradition speaks strongly against the practice of abortion—even to the extent of citing precisely the same texts from the Didache and the Epistle of Barnabas. And finally, we agree that Christians ought not to choose to abort unborn children, even in a society where such practices are legal. As I concluded, “My own judgment in this case is that the New Testament summons the community to eschew abortion. . . . The New Testament envisions a more excellent way.”35 In view of this wide-ranging agreement, I must register my own sense of saddened puzzlement that Kurz has singled out my book to illustrate what is wrong with contemporary biblical interpretation and how Catholic biblical interpretation overcomes the “ ‘either/or’ mentality” that afflicts Protestantism (183). Perhaps, though, the basic similarity between our positions may serve, as Kurz intends, to shed even brighter light on important hermeneutical questions where we diverge. Let us then, attend more carefully to Kurz’s bill of complaints against my work and seek to identify where in fact we do differ. 33 Hays, Moral Vision, 450. 34 Ibid., 455–56. 35 Ibid., 457. 114 Book Symposium First of all, to get this matter out of the way in the beginning, it seems to me that Kurz has misread my chapter in a way that causes him to overlook many of the fundamental agreements I have listed above. A reader unacquainted with my book who learned of it only through Kurz’s account would never know how significant the areas of agreement are. Kurz makes one passing remark that my treatment “shares several pro-life sympathies” (188), but otherwise his references create the impression that my chapter on the topic is driven by a narrow, fundamentalist logic that looks for specific prohibitions of abortion, finds none, and therefore functions as “a kind of Sola Scriptura justification, in an argument from silence, for treating abortion as something much more contingent on circumstances” (190). I can only protest that this is a serious misrepresentation of my position. The purpose of my chapter on abortion, within the larger argument of my book, is precisely to show how the New Testament can be understood to provide moral guidance on a question on which it offers no explicit teaching.36 In short, it is exactly the opposite of the “Sola Scriptura insistence that something has to be expressly treated in Scripture to be binding” (187)—the caricature with which Kurz associates my work.37 As I have indicated above, my method for doing this bears important similarities to Kurz’s discussion; particularly striking is the fact that both of us appeal to “a more inclusive canonical horizon” (191) to address the issue—to say nothing of the fact that both of us conclude that the force of the New Testament’s teaching is to call Christians to bear witness against abortion. Kurz, however, seems to ignore this. It is almost as though he read the first five pages of my chapter, in which I survey a few biblical passages sometimes wrongly used as proof texts38 and then stopped, without reading my constructive argument against abortion.39 Having lodged that protest against Kurz’s disappointing misconstrual of my book, I turn now to three issues on which there really is a serious difference between us, three points at which Kurz helpfully identifies how his Roman Catholic preunderstanding (his term) shapes his response to the question of abortion and his reading of the biblical evidence in relation to it.The three issues are: (1) whether it is appropriate to speak of a “right to life”; (2) the role of the Roman Catholic magisterium in provid36 Ibid., 313–15, 455–57. 37 I am grateful at least for the paragraph on p. 183 in which Kurz recognizes some- thing of the larger purpose of my book, before he opines that my chapter on abortion represents an unconscious slippage into a different viewpoint. 38 Hays, Moral Vision, 444–48. 39 Ibid., 449–61. Book Symposium 115 ing moral and hermeneutical guidance; and (3) whether abortion belongs to a class of actions prohibited by an absolute divine command to which there can be no exceptions.We take these points in turn. Is There a “Right to Life”? Kurz correctly observes that “Hays categorically denies the notions of the sacredness of human life and the biblical relevance of rights language” (189). My position here is based not only on the fact that “human rights” language is absent from the Bible and emerged in Western intellectual history only at the time of the Enlightenment,40 but also on a more fundamental theological point: Life is always a gift of God. From a theological perspective, we have no inalienable right to life; we possess life only as a contingent gift from our Creator. Kurz of course does not deny this, but he argues that “once God has freely given the gift of life to a human, that particular human as God’s image now has a right to life which other humans must respect” (189). In explicating this right, Kurz is willing to speak of the “sacredness” or “sanctity” of life. My concern is that such language often is used to speak of human life as an end in itself, as the source and center of autonomous meaning, quite apart from the Jewish and Christian conception of human beings as created in the image of God. I continue, therefore, to agree with my colleague Stanley Hauerwas that “[t]he Christian prohibition of abortion derives not from any assumption of the inherent value of life, but rather from the understanding that as God’s creatures we have no basis to claim sovereignty over life.”41 It is simply a matter of getting the theological accent in the right place. Underlying this difference of opinion, there probably is, as Kurz suggests, a difference between Catholic and Protestant sensibilities. I would suggest, though, that the issue here may be related to differing theological judgments about “natural law,” a concept long embraced in Catholic/ Thomist circles and regarded with wariness by many Protestant theologians. I do not suppose that I can settle that argument in a paragraph or two, so I merely name the difference as one background element in the hermeneutical argument. To the extent that this is so, Kurz is correct to highlight different “preunderstandings” as a factor in our dispute. Patient theological conversation might ultimately show this dispute to be more a matter of rhetoric than substance. Kurz and I agree that God 40 For the best defense known to me of “human rights” in biblical perspective, see C. D. Marshall, Crowned with Glory and Honor: Human Rights in the Biblical Tradition (Telford, PA: Pandora, 2001). 41 Stanley Hauerwas, A Community of Character:Toward a Constructive Christian Social Ethic (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), 225. 116 Book Symposium is the giver of life and that human beings do not have a “right” to take it away.We also agree that human beings have distinctive value and dignity in God’s eyes, though I hesitate to use the word “sacredness” to describe this divinely given status. The Magisterium as Hermeneutical Guide Another central difference between us, unsurprisingly, hinges on the authority of the teaching office of the Roman Church. I quote at length from an important paragraph that expresses Kurz’s view: Further, when we read the Scriptures as Catholics, the Church’s rich moral tradition (handily summarized in the Catechism of the Catholic Church and Vatican II) and explicit magisterial treatments of abortion (such as The Gospel of Life [Evangelium vitae] ) can be used as a “rule of faith” analogously to how the early patristic authors used the creeds as criteria for whether a biblical interpretation was acceptable or heretical. . . . Although one should not claim that all of these are explicitly biblical teachings, for Catholics they are legitimate traditional helps in interpreting and applying the evidence which Scripture does provide about the meaning of human life in relation to our creator God. [197–98] This paragraph clearly articulates one of the admirable strengths of traditional Catholic biblical hermeneutics: There is not only a strong tradition of teaching but there is actually an institutionally embodied magisterium that can resolve disputes and provide authoritative guidance for the community. Protestantism, on the other hand, always faces the danger of radical individualism and communal incoherence, of having every interpreter of the Bible do “what is right in his own eyes.” Kurz is careful to state that the magisterial statements “can be used” in a way that is analogous—not equivalent—to the early Church’s rule of faith and the ecumenical creeds. I applaud the caution of this formulation, and I am quite glad to acknowledge the status of such sources as “legitimate traditional helps” in biblical interpretation. If that is all that Kurz really means to assert, then the difference between his position and mine is insignificant. I might say, for my part, that the rich moral tradition of Luther, Calvin,Wesley, and Barth informs my moral reflection in a similar way. Indeed, I would gladly include in this list of sources key theological voices of the Catholic tradition. Surely my treatment of abortion in Moral Vision would have been richer had I included Evangelium vitae as one of the “legitimate helps” to my interpretation of the biblical witness on this issue. With the wisdom of ten years’ hindsight, I wish I Book Symposium 117 had done exactly that. In point of fact, however, my book’s treatment of abortion gives only the briefest attention to the Church’s tradition, and it looks very Protestant in its concentration on direct interpretation of the biblical texts. Two of the Scripture Project’s nine theses speak to these matters, affirming that “faithful interpretation of Scripture invites and presupposes participation in the community brought into being by God’s redemptive action—the Church” and that “The saints of the Church provide guidance in how to interpret and perform Scripture.”42 These affirmations are meant to counteract the dangers of individualistic interpretation, and to emphasize the importance of reading Scripture from within ecclesial tradition. The key question, however, is whether the statements of the Catholic magisterium are more than “helps.” Do they have a binding claim on the work of subsequent biblical interpreters? Kurz never quite puts it so baldly, but as I noted earlier, his position is unlike Johnson’s in that he never offers any example of a question on which he would disagree with Catholic tradition or argue for its correction. And, if I understand him correctly, he regards the magisterium’s prohibition of abortion as a definitive application of “moral absolutes” to a particular ethical issue. This would seem to foreclose any possibility for biblical interpreters to challenge the magisterium or to undertake fresh, corrective readings that appeal directly to exegesis of the Bible to open up room for what I call “humility about our claims and convictions concerning abortion.”43 Once again, this difference of opinion on the weight of magisterial teaching would seem to be a traditional Catholic-Protestant dispute. On this point, however, I note that Johnson seems to be, in principle, on my side! As he puts it later in the book,“Catholic biblical scholarship, therefore, should be critically loyal to the teaching of the hierarchy but also loyally critical” (277). Would Kurz accept that formulation? If so, the difference between us is perhaps not insurmountable. Is the Prohibition of Abortion a Moral Absolute? Finally, Kurz writes disapprovingly of “Hays’s refusal to allow any moral absolutes that may be applicable to the treatment of abortion” (190, original emphasis). Because of my willingness to treat “hard cases” as at least morally debatable, Kurz offers this judgment: “His approach does not sound like a question of discovering what God commands in this case, nor like an application of an absolute divine command or an absolute 42 Davis and Hays, Art of Reading Scripture, 3–4. 43 Hays, Moral Vision, 445. 118 Book Symposium moral principle to this decision” (190). In one respect Kurz is quite right. The central argument of Moral Vision of the New Testament is that the New Testament should not be read chiefly as a source of moral rules or absolute principles; rather it should be read as a source of narrative paradigms that shape the Church’s moral action analogically or metaphorically. (Kurz makes an argument of this type also, when he points to the self-sacrificial example of Jesus as part of his argument against abortion [197–98].) The rhetorical pressure in Kurz’s chapter toward the quest for “absolutes” clearly indicates his discomfort with the greater flexibility and contingency of my approach to New Testament ethics and hermeneutics. There is no doubt that on that point the difference between us is both real and significant. I do think it is unfair, however, for him to say that my approach is not interested in discovering what God commands. I am urgently interested in discovering precisely that, but I approach the question in a different way. I will leave it to readers of my book to adjudicate this disputed point for themselves. The basic problem with Kurz’s argument, as I see it, is the considerable slippage between his desire for absolute moral commands about abortion and the rather fuzzy way that he derives his knowledge of such commands. At several points in the chapter, he describes his discernment of such matters as “instinctive.” For example, after admitting that “the commandment ‘you shall not kill’ does not answer the question whether abortion is included in the prohibition of killing,” he goes on to assert that “the step to including abortion as a species of killing which is forbidden by the fifth commandment is a rather instinctive one” (200–201). Indeed! But surely Kurz’s “instinct” on this matter has been tutored, as he affirms, by his particular ecclesial community. He rightly describes his own methodology when he says, “if one reads the Bible as a convinced member of the Catholic Church, one will spontaneously fill in biblical silences and gaps such as the non-mention of abortion with fundamental Catholic moral principles and the historical tradition of Catholic practice” (200, emphasis added). In the concluding summation of his chapter, he describes such acts of filling silences and gaps as a way to “actualize” and “apply” biblical passages to “new and different situations, like abortion, which are admittedly beyond those original concerns and situations discovered by historical-critical exegesis” (202). This description is a precisely accurate account of Kurz’s hermeneutical procedure. But if Kurz’s Catholic position on abortion is derived through such intuitive acts of filling gaps and silences, of imaginatively actualizing texts Book Symposium 119 by applying them to questions and situations unimaginable to the original authors (a necessary process that I call “Moral Judgment as MetaphorMaking”),44 how is it possible to claim absolute moral certainty for his findings? It seems to me that Kurz simply refuses to face the epistemological problem raised by his own description of his process of moral reasoning. Surely any process of intuitive “actualization” is fallible and not capable of yielding absolute knowledge of God’s will. If, then, we cannot attain absolute certainty about such matters, surely we must at least entertain the possibility that our conviction about the wrongness of abortion—a conviction, I repeat, that I share with Kurz— might be open to certain qualifications.We might, for example, have a serious argument among Christians about whether there can be exceptional circumstances that allow for abortion as a tragic but justifiable option. Such an argument, of course, would require us to explore carefully the contingent circumstances of particular human lives—that is to say, to take human experience into account as a factor in moral deliberation. It is a final irony that Kurz castigates me for giving “so much weight to economic and social considerations, which are more closely related to historical and social-scientific than to theological approaches, in an abortion decision” (183). This is, I am sure, the first time I have ever been criticized by a Catholic interpreter for paying too much attention to concrete human experience in the process of ethical discernment—the very thing that Johnson highlights as the climactic essential element in the Catholic project of imagining the world that Scripture imagines (141–42).This is one of many indications that the deeper issue to which The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship points may not be a dispute between Catholics and Protestants, but between the substantially different hermeneutical perspectives represented by Kurz and Johnson themselves. Conclusion At the end of the day, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship places me in a very unusual position.This is a book that caricatures and gratuitously attacks my own ecclesial community as the source of mischief and error in modern biblical interpretation. It also contains a chapter that singles me out as a polemical target and seriously misrepresents what I wrote on a topic of urgent moral concern in our time. And yet I find myself in enthusiastic agreement with nearly all of its fundamental concerns and constructive proposals. I therefore warmly commend the book to the community of Catholic theologians and biblical scholars. 44 Ibid., 298–306. 120 Book Symposium My commendation is subject, however, to the substantial qualifications expressed in this rather lengthy critical review. Johnson and Kurz’s work should be read alongside The Art of Reading Scripture and some of the other recent hermeneutical works mentioned at the beginning of this essay.When it is so contextualized, it can be seen as a stimulating contribution to the revitalization of biblical interpretation as an ecclesial practice that offers both intellectual challenge and spiritual nourishment. I want to reiterate that the fundamental purpose of this essay is to join the “constructive conversation” that Johnson and Kurz propose and to seek to bridge the gulf they seem to perceive between Catholic and Protestant interpreters of the Bible. In our time, it is urgently important that we make common cause and see one another as brothers and sisters within the Church of Jesus Christ, seeking to read Scripture carefully, faithfully, and imaginatively for the sake of the Church’s mission. If I have responded to their sharp criticisms with serious criticisms of my own, it is in the hope that truthful conversation will enable us all in the end to N&V glorify God with one voice. The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: Balance and Proportion F RANK J. M ATERA The Catholic University of America Washington, DC Introductory Remarks T HE TITLE OF THIS ESSAY presents a minor semantical problem since it might seem that I am trying to prognosticate. Or it may appear that I am dictating what the future of Catholic biblical scholarship should be. My purpose, however, is more modest. I have adopted the title from the work of Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, in order to suggest some ways in which Catholic biblical scholarship can become even more fruitful.1 Like Johnson and Kurz, I do this in a spirit of entering into “a constructive conversation” about the future of our discipline. According to Luke Timothy Johnson the future of Catholic biblical scholarship is to rejoin a long conversation with our patristic and medieval ancestors, not so much to do what they did as to learn how they 1 Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz, SJ, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: A Constructive Conversation (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2002). Book Symposium 121 approached and appropriated the sacred text.2 Johnson’s suggestion has a great deal of merit, for even if we disagree with the exegesis of patristic and medieval writers on particular points, we cannot but admire the reverence and awe with which they approached the sacred text and the manner in which they conceived of Scripture as a unified word of God. Thus, there is a paradoxical sense in which the way forward is to retrace our steps and discover anew where we have been. It must be acknowledged, however, that the riches of patristic and medieval exegesis do not belong solely to Catholics. Orthodox and Protestants can and do lay claim to these treasures as well. According to William S. Kurz, the future of Catholic biblical scholarship is to make greater use of our Catholic preunderstanding.3 Since modern hermeneutics has taught us that we always approach texts with a certain preunderstanding and social location, Catholic biblical scholarship should make more explicit use of its own preunderstanding and social location in its interpretation of texts.This point is well taken, and to his credit Kurz provides several essays that exemplify this approach. There are times, however, when our preunderstanding can mislead us, a point made by the Pontifical Biblical Commission. All preunderstanding, however, brings dangers with it. As regards Catholic exegesis, the risk is that of attributing to biblical texts a meaning that they do not contain but which is the product of a later development within the tradition.The exegete must beware of such a danger.4 This said, I agree with the general direction Kurz provides for Catholic biblical scholarship:There is no need to be embarrassed by our Catholic preunderstanding of the text, provided we remain critically aware of how we are employing that understanding. Unlike Kurz and Johnson, I do not have a single formula that points the way forward for Catholic biblical scholarship. Perhaps this is due to 2 Johnson makes this point in chapter 2,“Rejoining a Long Conversation,” 35–63. 3 Kurz makes this point in all of his essays. See especially pages 159–66 in the essay titled, “Beyond Historical Criticism: Reading John’s Prologue as Catholics.” 4 The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church, 4th ed. (Washington, DC:The United States Catholic Conference, 1994, 2001), 24.The text, with commentary, can also be found in Joseph A. Fitzmyer, The Biblical Commission’s Document “The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church”:Text and Commentary (Rome: Editrice Pontificio Istituto Biblico, 1995), 133. For a recent commentary on the text that tries to identify the Catholic principles for interpreting Scripture that this text presupposes, see Peter S. Williamson, Catholic Principles for Interpreting Scripture: A Study of the Pontifical Biblical Commission’s The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church (Rome: Editrice Pontificio Istituto Biblico, 2001). Book Symposium 122 my social location. I teach at a Catholic university where the university’s Catholic identity is discussed, but, in my view, not seriously in jeopardy. I work within a vibrant Catholic tradition and find no need to justify my scholarship to the wider university community.Thus, my social location may make me naïve as to what is happening elsewhere and more sanguine about the present situation of Catholic biblical scholarship. This said, I would like to take up a point that Johnson and Kurz make about the inclusive nature of the Catholic spirit, what they call the “both/and” emphasis of Catholicism and what Johnson identifies more specifically as “a spirit of inclusion and generosity.” 5 Here, I heartily agree. When most true to itself, Catholicism is a big tent that embraces diverse points of view. In this sense, Jesus’ image of the kingdom applies to Catholicism: “But once it is sown, it springs up and becomes the largest of plants and puts forth large branches, so that the birds of the sky can dwell in its shade” (Mk 4:32).6 Because it is inclusive, Catholic biblical scholarship can and should embrace a variety of methods without claiming any particular one as distinctively its own. There is room for patristic and medieval exegesis, and a variety of modern approaches to the text—provided we maintain a sense of balance and proportion. As Kurz and Johnson remind us, it is not “either/or” but “both/and.” The following statement of the Pontifical Biblical Commission is apropos: Catholic exegesis does not claim any particular scientific method as its own. . . . What characterizes Catholic exegesis is that it deliberately places itself within the living tradition of the Church, whose first concern is fidelity to the revelation attested by the Bible.7 There are moments, however, when Catholic biblical scholarship can lose its sense of balance and proportion by focusing on one method to the exclusion of others, or by emphasizing one aspect of a question to the detriment of another. In what follows, I discuss four areas where it will be helpful for Catholic biblical scholarship to maintain a sense of balance and proportion: (1) The role of history and theology in exegesis; (2) the relationship between the theology and the theologies of the Bible; (3) the relationship between the Old and the New Testaments; and (4) the ecclesial and academic dimensions of exegesis. 5 The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 265. 6 Scriptural quotations are taken from The New American Bible. 7 The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church, 24; Fitzmyer, The Biblical Commis- sion’s Document, 132. Book Symposium 123 The Role of History and Theology in Exegesis One of the most vexing issues in contemporary biblical scholarship is the relationship between history and theology in exegesis. Is exegesis a form of historical study, or is it a theological discipline? Is it faith seeking understanding, or is it history looking to reconstruct the past? Can one be true to both the historical method and theological truth, or must one choose between the two? It is possible, of course, to conceive of exegesis as a purely theological discipline in which history plays little or no role, just as it is possible to conceive of exegesis as a purely historical discipline from which theology is excluded.The future of Catholic biblical scholarship, however, does not belong to such extremes that would compel exegetes to choose between interpreting the text apart from history or apart from theology. Consider for a moment how dangerous it could be to read the Gospel of John with its multiple references to “the Jews”—many of which are quite hostile—without some understanding of the historical situation that occasioned that writing.To be more specific, consider the fierce polemic between Jesus and “the Jews” in John 8 that comes to a highpoint when Jesus says to them,“You belong to your father the devil and you willingly carry out your father’s desires” ( Jn 8:44). Or, consider the cry of the people in Matthew’s Gospel (and only in Matthew’s Gospel) at Jesus’ trial, “His blood be upon us and upon our children” (Mt 27:25). The reader who is unaware of the historical context that gave rise to these texts might think that the Jewish people are indeed the progeny of the devil, a people eternally guilty of the Messiah’s death. By taking into consideration the historical circumstances that gave rise to these texts, however, contemporary exegesis has shown that these statements derive from the redactional work of the Evangelists and echo the polemics of a debate between synagogue and church in a period after Jesus’ death, a debate in which we can no longer participate.8 Read apart from their historical contexts, texts such as these can foster sentiments of anti-Jewishness, if not outright antiSemitism. Read in light of their historical setting, it becomes apparent that they must be interpreted in light of their historical background. 8 Contemporary Johannine scholarship has shown that the fourth Evangelist often employs the expression “the Jews” to signify the unbelief of “the world.” It argues that the particularly harsh episode in chapter 8 reflects the debates between the Johannine community and the synagogue of its day rather than the actual debates between Jesus and the Jewish people of his day. Similarly, contemporary Matthean scholarship, which accepts the priority of Mark, attributes the cry of the people in the Matthean Passion narrative to Matthew’s redactional work. It is a comment that reflects the struggle between the Matthean congregation and the synagogue rather than an historical account of what the people actually said. 124 Book Symposium Conversely, consider the results of reading the infancy narratives for the sole purpose of determining the historical events surrounding Jesus’ birth. Although the task is legitimate, the final result would surely miss the theological richness of the Matthean and Lukan narratives.The historian might well conclude that the infancy narratives are of little historical value since Matthew and Luke apparently contradict each other at several points. For example, according to Luke, Joseph and Mary must travel to Bethlehem because they are residents of Galilee (Lk 2:4) but according to Matthew they already reside in Bethlehem where they appear to have a home (Mt 2:11). Only later do they move to Galilee in order to escape Herod’s son, Archelaus (Mt 2:22–23). A purely historical approach might be correct in its historical conclusions, but it would miss the theological depth of the Matthean and Lukan infancy narratives, which provide rich theological commentary on the person of Jesus, presenting him as the climax of his people’s history and his birth as the fulfillment of the promises made to David. My point is simply this: We are no longer in a position—if ever we were—to do exegesis apart from history. But this does not mean that exegesis is merely an historical discipline. Exegesis is also an act of theology. Exegesis is faith seeking understanding, and this act of theology requires the assistance of historical investigation. For example, when contemporary Catholic exegetes come to the texts of John 8:44 and Matthew 27:25 mentioned above, they are faced with a problem. In its Declaration on the Relation of the Church to Non-Christian Religions, the Second Vatican Council declared: Even though the Jewish authorities and those who followed their lead pressed for the death of Christ (see Jn 19:6) neither all Jews indiscriminately at that time, nor Jews today, can be charged with the crimes committed during his passion. It is true that the church is the new people of God, yet the Jews should not be spoken of as rejected or accused as if this followed from holy scripture.9 How, then, should the exegete interpret Jesus’ words to “the Jews” that the devil is their father and the cry of the people who call guilt upon themselves and their children? This is a case where historical research into the background of the Johannine community and an understanding of 9 Nostra Aetate, no. 4.The translation is taken from The Basic Sixteen Documents:Vati- can Council II: Constitutions Decrees Declarations:A Completely Revised Translation in Inclusive Language, ed. Austin Flannery, OP (Northport, NY: Costello Publishing Company, 1996), 573. Book Symposium 125 how Matthew edited his Markan source in the Passion narrative can assist exegetes to interpret what they believe about Jesus and God’s faithfulness to Israel. If Catholic biblical scholarship is to nourish the Church, it must be concerned with theology as well as with history, and with history as well as with theology—history in order to clarify the meaning of the text in its historical setting; theology to understand the text in light of the Church’s faith. Exegesis, then, is a discipline that involves both history and theology. To be sure, there will be moments when scholars will emphasize one more than the other, but at some point both must come into play.Theology must listen and learn from history, and history must leave room for theology to interpret. The Relationship between the Theology and Theologies of the Bible Catholic biblical scholarship has long been aware of the different theologies in the Bible. For example, the canonical text of the Old Testament includes diverse strains of tradition such as the Priestly document and the Deuteronomistic history, which represent differing and sometimes competing theological voices. More importantly, the canonical writings themselves testify to God’s revelation in a multiplicity of ways. Consider, for example, the distinctive manners in which the Book of Proverbs and the Book of Job present God. In the former, there is a rhyme and reason to God’s ways in the world; in the latter, God’s ways are puzzling and disturbing. The same phenomenon occurs in the New Testament, even though its writings were composed within sixty to seventy years after Jesus’ death. New Testament specialists speak of the theologies of the Synoptic Gospels, the Johannine writings, the Pauline and the deuteropauline letters, not to mention Hebrews, James, Revelation, 1 and 2 Peter. The recognition of the diverse theologies of, and in, the biblical writings has led to a deeper appreciation of the biblical witness to God’s revelation. It reminds believers that God’s self-revelation is a profound mystery that cannot be captured in a single formula.This is why the biblical writings portray God and the salvation God brings in diverse ways. It is why Genesis offers two accounts of creation, and why the Book of Job takes up the question of suffering and evil in a new way. It is why John begins with the incarnation and Paul with Christ’s death and resurrection. It is why the Synoptic Gospels focus on Jesus’ proclamation of the kingdom of God, whereas the fourth Evangelist speaks of the Son’s revelation of the Father. It is only by listening to the diverse voices of the biblical writings that exegesis hears the full richness of God’s revelation. 126 Book Symposium The presence of so many voices, however, presents biblical scholarship with a vexing question.What is the relationship between these different theologies? Are the many theological witnesses of the Old Testament related to each other in any way? Can the variety of theologies in the New Testament be brought together in a coherent way? In other words, can we speak of the theology of the Old Testament or the theology of the New Testament, as well as the theologies within the Old and the New Testament?10 The answer to this question depends, in large measure, upon how one approaches the text. The historian of Israelite religion or of early Christianity approaches the Bible as a diverse collection of writings that provide a window into the past. Consequently, the question of whether or not there is a unifying principle that justifies collecting these writings into what is now called the Old and the New Testament is an historical problem that needs to be solved.The historian does not and should not begin by positing the unity of the biblical witness. Whether or not there is a principle that unites these diverse writings is a problem to be resolved by careful historical analysis.At the end of this analysis, the historian may even decide that there is no unifying principle apart from historical development. The situation is, and it ought to be, quite different for the exegete who works within the living tradition of the Church. The very concept of revelation presupposes unity, unless the God who discloses himself purposely seeks to conceal himself—in which case it would be better to speak of concealment than of revelation. Put another way, it would be strange for a believing community to affirm on the one hand that its Scriptures witness to God’s revelation but on the other hand to be unconcerned about the inner unity of that revelation. Consequently, whereas the historian need not and should not begin by positing unity, the believer can and must. Although faith posits unity because it believes in the truth and unity of God’s self-revelation to which the writings of Scripture testify, Catholic exegesis must continually seek out that unity, first within each of the Testaments, and then between the Testaments, a point I will consider below. The purpose of seeking the unity in the Old and the New Testaments, however, is not to do away with the diversity of theologies in each, or to find a principle to control and tame the biblical witnesses. The purpose is more profound because the subject matter of exegesis is so profound. Searching for the unity of Scripture is another 10 This question is examined by James Barr, The Concept of Biblical Theology:An Old Testament Perspective (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1999). Book Symposium 127 way of searching for God. Who is the God to whom the law, the prophets, and the writings testify in such diverse ways? Who is the God to whom the Synoptics, John, Paul, Hebrews, James, Peter, and Revelation witness in a multiplicity of ways? For the believer, this diverse witness paradoxically points to the unity of the mystery, and the unity of the mystery paradoxically requires a multiplicity of witnesses. At the present moment in Catholic biblical scholarship, the goal of most studies is to investigate the diverse witnesses of both the Old and New Testaments. This is quite understandable. Having emerged from a period when any suggestion of diversity was suspect, Catholic biblical scholarship turned to a neglected area of research: diversity within the Bible. Catholic exegesis is now aware that before one can grasp the whole, it is necessary to understand its parts. But there should also be a moment when some seek the inner unity of this diverse witness. There should be a moment when some scholars address the question of the theology of the Old Testament and the theology of the New Testament, asking what is the unity of the diverse witnesses to God’s revelation in Israel and Jesus. Given the mystery of the God whom biblical scholarship confronts, no scholar can present the definitive answer to this question. But the question needs to be addressed again and again by those who appreciate the rich diversity of the biblical witness. The Relationship between the Old and New Testaments The relationship of the Old and the New Testaments is analogous to the question of the relationship between the theology and theologies of the Bible. Ultimately, however, it is a question about the faithfulness of God. For, if the two Testaments are not related to each other in a meaningful way—if the New Testament does not illuminate the Old, or if the Old Testament does not foreshadow and prepare for the New—then the God and Father of Jesus Christ is not the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. Furthermore, to the extent that the Old Testament is the Scripture of the Jewish people, the question of the relationship between the testaments is a question about the Church’s relationship to the Jewish people.The relationship between the testaments then is the most vexing of all questions, and how Catholic biblical scholarship addresses it reveals a great deal about its understanding of God and the covenant people of Israel. Although most Catholic scholars, like their Protestant colleagues, tend to work in either the Old or New Testament, there is a growing sense that the relationship of the testaments needs to be addressed anew. In this country, Brevard Childs has engaged the issue, and in Germany, Peter Stuhlmacher, Ferdinand Hahn, and Hans Hübner have done the same, 128 Book Symposium though in different ways.11 Moreover, the Pontifical Biblical Commission has recently considered the issue in its 2002 publication The Jewish People and their Sacred Scriptures in the Christian Bible.12 That document notes that “the Christian Bible is not composed of one ‘Testament,’ but of two ‘Testaments,’ the Old and the New, which have a complex dialectical relationships between them” (42). It goes on to say, “This relationship is also reciprocal: on the one hand, the New Testament demands to be read in the light of the Old, but it also invites a ‘re-reading’ of the Old in the light of Jesus Christ” (43). There are a number of reasons why it has become difficult for contemporary biblical scholars to address the issue of the unity of the testaments. First, most scholars are specialists in one testament or the other, and they rarely venture outside their discipline except when the exegesis of a particular text requires it. Second, a lack of familiarity with the early Church’s Bible, the Septuagint, means that some New Testament scholars do not read the same Bible the authors of the New Testament did. Consequently, the linguistic unity between the Old and New Testament is not always as apparent to them as it might be if they were working from the Greek as well as from the Hebrew text of the Old Testament.The question of how the testaments are related to each other, however, is of vital importance since it is ultimately a question about God and the faithfulness of God to his covenant people. The first Christians were already aware of the problem raised above, though they framed it in another way since the New Testament did not yet exist. For the authors of what would eventually be the New Testament, the crucial question was the relationship between what God did in Jesus of Nazareth and God’s covenant promises to Israel. If Jesus was the Messiah, in what sense was he the Messiah? How did Jesus fulfill the covenant promises God made to Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob? How was his life and ministry related to God’s will as revealed in the Mosaic law? Because those who first confessed Jesus as the Messiah belonged to the people of Israel, or were closely related to the chosen people, they answered these questions by re-reading Israel’s Scriptures in light of Christ’s life, death, 11 Brevard S. Childs, Biblical Theology of the Old and New Testament:Theological Reflec- tion on the Christian Bible (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1993). Peter Stuhlmacher, Biblische Theologie des Neuen Testaments, 2 vols. (Göttingen:Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1992, 1999). Ferdinand Hahn, Theologie des Neuen Testaments, 2 vols. (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2003); Hans Hübner, Biblische Theologie des Neuen Testaments, 3 vols. (Göttingen:Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1990, 1993, 1995). 12 Pontifical Biblical Commission, The Jewish People and Their Sacred Scriptures in The Christian Bible (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2002). Book Symposium 129 and resurrection. It is not surprising, then, that Matthew begins his Gospel with a genealogy that portrays Jesus as the culmination of Israel’s history, that the fourth Evangelist sees Jesus as the Son who reveals the Father to the world, that Paul argues that Christ is the singular descendant of Abraham, and that the author of Hebrews portrays Christ as a high priest who entered into the true holy of holies, the sanctuary of heaven, when he died on the cross.The New Testament struggles again and again to make a single point in a variety of ways: God’s revelation in Christ is in continuity with God’s revelation to Israel. Jesus’ death brings a new creation not a rupture with the past. The God whom Jesus reveals in a new and striking way as his Father is the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. Because the mystery is profound, the answers the New Testament writers provide are sometimes in tension with each other. For example, Matthew certainly has a greater sense of the enduring validity of the law than does Paul (compare Mt 5:17 and Rom 10:4), and Luke is more concerned to show that Jesus is the Davidic Messiah than is Mark (compare Lk 1:32–33 and Mk 12:35–37). But all agree that Jesus is the Messiah—even though the nature of his messiahship requires massive redefinition in light of his death and resurrection.And all concur that the law has found its fulfillment in Jesus, even when there are varying views about its enduring validity. In effect, each of the New Testament writers tries to “inscribe” the story of Jesus into the story of Israel. Indeed, one could say that the major narrative writings of the New Testament (the four Gospels and the Acts of the Apostles) seek to bring Israel’s story, as recorded in the Scriptures, to closure by telling the story of Jesus and, in the case of Acts, the story of the Church.This is most apparent in Luke-Acts, which comprises nearly one-fourth of the New Testament. In this work, which begins as if it were an Old Testament narrative, Luke shows how the events that have recently transpired among those who believe are, in fact, the culmination of Israel’s history. In Stephen’s speech (Acts 7:1–53) and in Paul’s inaugural sermon in the synagogue at Pisidian Antioch (Acts 13:16–41), Luke recounts the story of Israel in such a way as to show that Israel’s history finds its climax in the coming of the Messiah, Jesus of Nazareth. For Luke, there is continuity between old and new, and God has been faithful to Israel. The point I am making is quite simple. Before there was a New Testament, those who composed the writings of what would eventually constitute the New Testament already affirmed the continuity between God’s revelation to Israel and God’s revelation in Jesus of Nazareth. It was inconceivable to these writers that it could be otherwise since God is faithful. From the perspective of the New Testament, the two testaments 130 Book Symposium are intimately related to each other, and their unity is apparent. A fruitful direction for Catholic biblical scholarship, then, would be to examine anew the relationship between Old and New Testaments. The relationship between the testaments is analogous to the relationship between the theology and theologies of the Bible. Just as faith posits that there is a unity to God’s revelation, so it posits that there is an inner unity between the testaments, even if scholarship cannot perfectly express that unity in a single formula upon which all agree.This unity, however, should be second nature to Catholics nurtured by the Church’s liturgy in which texts from Old and New Testaments are regularly juxtaposed in order to mutually illumine each other. Consider, for example, the Church’s Liturgy of the Hours, which moves so easily between the texts of Old and New Testaments to show the believing community the intimate relationship between its story and the story of Israel. Here, as Kurz notes, the Church’s life of faith flows from its life of prayer.13 There is, of course, a difference between scholarship and prayer, but they are not mutually exclusive. Those who live in a liturgical world that moves so easily between Old and New Testaments understand, at least at the level of worship and faith, that it is not a matter of Old or New Testament but both: the Old in the New and the New in the Old. Ecclesial and Academic Dimensions of Exegesis There has been a subtext to this essay that can be stated in a question: Can Catholic biblical scholarship be ecclesial and academic? The answer depends, in large measure, upon how one defines the terms. By ecclesial, I mean scholarship that is done within the context of the Catholic tradition for the sake of the Church. By academic, I mean scholarship that can receive a hearing within the university because it makes a significant contribution to human knowledge. The proper starting point for understanding what is “Catholic” about Catholic biblical scholarship is the statement of the Pontifical Biblical Commission:“What characterizes Catholic exegesis is that it deliberately places itself within the living tradition of the Church, whose first concern is fidelity to the revelation attested by the Bible” (24). Catholic exegesis does not depend upon a particular exegetical method, nor does it require one to teach in a specifically Catholic environment. The determining factor is that exegetes place themselves within the living tradition of the Church, a tradition whose first concern is to remain faithful to the revelation to which the sacred writings testify. Such an exegetical stance 13 The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 264–265. Book Symposium 131 accepts the biblical writings as the Church’s Scripture, which is intended to nourish and strengthen the community of believers. It believes that these writings witness to God’s revelation, first to Israel, then in Jesus Christ. Consequently, it approaches the writings as the Word of God from a stance of faith seeking understanding. This said, Catholic biblical scholarship is also academic because God’s Word is clothed in human words, thereby mirroring the mystery of the incarnation. John Paul II noted this in his address on the occasion of the publication of the Pontifical Biblical Commission’s document, The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church: The strict relationship uniting the inspired biblical texts with the mystery of the incarnation was expressed by the encyclical Divino afflante Spiritu in the following terms: “Just as the substantial Word of God became like men in every respect except sin, so too the words of God, expressed in human languages, became like human language in every respect except error” (EB, 559). Repeated almost literally by the conciliar constitution Dei Verbum (no. 13), this statement sheds light on a parallelism rich in meaning.14 It is not surprising then that the Biblical Commission’s document reserves its harshest critique for biblical Fundamentalism stating:“The basic problem with fundamentalist interpretation of this kind is that, refusing to take into account the historical character of biblical revelation, it makes itself incapable of accepting the full truth of the incarnation itself ” (19). A rigorous academic approach to the text, then, is not alien to Catholic biblical scholarship that remains within the living tradition of the Church. Anything less would be unacceptable.Within the context of the university, Catholic scholars should work with the same academic standards required of their colleagues in other disciplines of learning, thereby establishing a fruitful dialogue between the academy and the Church. This, of course, does not mean that biblical study belongs only to the professional exegete, or that only the professional exegete can understand the text. It simply indicates that Catholic biblical scholarship can and should be both ecclesial and academic. To summarize, Catholic biblical scholarship will discover its identity by finding its place “in the mainstream of the great Tradition,”15 not by withdrawing from the academy or ecumenical dialogue.The future of Catholic biblical scholarship will be found in the present as well as in the past: in the 14 Pope John Paul II, address, “On the Interpretation of the Bible in the Church,” in Fitzmyer, The Biblical Commission’s Document, 4. 15 Ibid., 7. 132 Book Symposium past inasmuch as it must rejoin a long conversation as Johnson maintains, in the present inasmuch as it must live within the liturgical life of the Church as Kurz reminds us. Catholic biblical scholarship, however, will not find its identity by retreating behind closed walls. Conclusion Luke Timothy Johnson and William Kurz have invited us to enter into a constructive conversation about the future of Catholic biblical scholarship. Following their lead, I have tried to do this in a way that takes into account four aspects of the discipline, arguing that it is not a matter of history or theology but both. Nor is it a question of the theology of the Bible or the theologies in the Bible but both. The Old and the New Testaments are not to be read in isolation from each other but together. It is not a choice between ecclesial or academic exegesis but both. This Catholic spirit is found in the great Tradition we share, a Tradition that embraces many methods and approaches to Scripture and in which Catholic exegesis has its home.The future of Catholic biblical scholarship belongs to those who live in and out of this Tradition, within and for the N&V sake of the Church. The Text of the Bible and Catholic Biblical Scholarship S TEPHEN D. RYAN, OP Dominican House of Studies Washington, DC L UKE T IMOTHY J OHNSON and William S. Kurz, SJ, have written a timely book, one that delves deeply into the past in order to assess the current state of Catholic biblical scholarship in the United States.1 Since the book has already been reviewed appreciatively by my colleague Jody Vaccaro Lewis in the pages of this journal, and since its import has been assessed elsewhere, I will address myself to the “future” featured in the book’s title, specifically to the future of the text of the Old Testament. I will seek to relate a rather specific discussion about the form of the text of the Old Testament to larger questions this discussion raises for ecumenism, for the doctrine of biblical inspiration, and for the future of 1 Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz, SJ, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: A Constructive Conversation (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2002). Book Symposium 133 Catholic biblical scholarship. It is my hope that these remarks will add both an Old Testament complement to the work of Johnson and Kurz, both of whom are New Testament scholars, and a new dimension to the larger discussion about the future of Catholic biblical scholarship. The text of Scripture is generally regarded as fixed and stable and we are seldom tempted to add to or subtract from it. But establishing the text of Scripture has become slightly more complicated in the last fifty years. For example, when the New Revised Standard Version was published in 1989, one can imagine that relatively few readers noticed that the translation of the Old Testament was slightly longer than that found in the Revised Standard Version of 1952. The reason for this change had nothing to do with new theories of translation or even with the use of inclusive language, but can be traced rather to the momentous textual discoveries at the Dead Sea some fifty years ago. In the books of Samuel, for instance, the New Revised Standard Version restored four sentences to 1 Samuel 10:27 on the basis of new Hebrew evidence from Qumran. In the book of Tobit, the New Revised Standard Version chose to translate the longer and more original textual form of the book, again on the basis of evidence from Qumran, adding some seventeen hundred words to the Revised Standard Version translation, which had used the shorter Greek text.And this is only the tip of the iceberg.The quiet and generally unnoticed revolution in textual studies generated by the Dead Sea Scrolls has revealed that for several books of the Old Testament the traditional Masoretic Hebrew text represents only one of several textual forms that have a claim to representing the earliest recoverable or “original” form of the book. Jeremiah is a case in point. Here the Greek text, which in several chapters differs significantly from the Hebrew, arguably represents in certain chapters a different and earlier literary form of the book. Similar examples could be added.Adrian Schenker has argued recently, for example, that in large sections of the book of Kings, the Old Greek text represents an earlier form of the text than that preserved in the Masoretic text.2 This raises several related questions about the goals of textual criticism and how one determines the textual form to be translated. Johnson and Kurz discuss the question of the textual form of the Bible only in passing. Johnson notes that authors like James, Paul, and Luke “read 2 A. Schenker, OP, Älteste Textgeschichte der Königsbücher, Die hebräische Vorlage der ursprünglichen Septuaginta als älteste Textform der Königsbücher (Fribourg: Academic Press, 2004); see also the theoretical discussion in Schenker’s earlier article, “Was übersetzen wir? Fragen zur Textbasis, die sich aus der Textkritik ergeben,” in Die Übersetzung der Bibel-Aufgabe der Theologie, eds. J. Gnilka and H. P. Rüger (Bielefeld: Luther-Verlag, 1985), 65–80. 134 Book Symposium and interpreted the Greek translation of Torah called the Septuagint (LXX)” (47), and goes on to observe that some Hellenistic Jews regarded the Greek text to be divinely inspired (48). Later, having observed that Kurz signals the importance of the Septuagint as the intertext for New Testament authors (167–69, 215–16), Johnson writes, The richness of this exposition presses the issue of the status of the Septuagint for Catholic biblical interpretation. Everyone acknowledges that the New Testament itself is unintelligible without reference to the Septuagint. But this recognition has no effect on anything else. Catholics who do not have Greek have no sense of these interconnections. But even when they are pointed out by scholars, ordinary Catholics cannot find them in their Bibles, or hear them in the liturgy, for all modern translations are from the Hebrew (256). Without doing so explicitly, Johnson seems to argue in favor of facilitating wider popular access to the form of the Old Testament used by many of the writers of the New Testament, namely the Septuagint. While this is in itself a laudable goal, recent developments in the field of Old Testament textual criticism raise even broader issues about the early biblical versions and their status. Below I will briefly raise four questions dealing with the text of the Bible that I should like to propose for the future agenda of Catholic biblical scholarship. 1. Multiple literary editions. Eugene Ulrich has written recently about the phenomenon of multiple literary editions of some books of the Old Testament.3 The discoveries at the Dead Sea have helped scholars like Ulrich to recognize more clearly that several books of the Old Testament circulated in more than one literary form. Examples of this phenomenon are found in certain chapters of the books of Exodus, 1–2 Samuel, 1–2 Kings, Jeremiah, and Daniel. In some cases two Hebrew forms are preserved, while in other cases one form is preserved in Greek and another in Hebrew.Textual criticism itself is not always equipped to determine which of these forms was earlier. In the beginning, it seems, there was multiplicity. And this multiplicity seems to have continued long past what scholars used to refer to 3 E. Ulrich, “Double Literary Editions of Biblical Narratives and Reflections on Determining the Form to be Translated,” in The Dead Sea Scrolls and the Origins of the Bible, ed. E. Ulrich (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company; Leiden: Brill, 1999), 34–50.Angela Kim Harkins explores some of the theological implications of textual pluriformity in a forthcoming article titled, “Theological Attitudes towards the Scriptural Text: Lessons from the Syriac Exegetical Tradition and Qumran.” Book Symposium 135 as the period of the stabilization of the biblical text.4 The editors of a new critical edition of the Hebrew Bible known as the Oxford Hebrew Bible have correctly decided in such cases to print two Hebrew texts in parallel synoptic columns.5 It will not be long before popular translations follow suit, printing translations of both Hebrew texts side by side. In addition to the questions such plurality might elicit from lay readers, Catholic biblical scholars will no doubt be forced to consider more closely the editorial decisions underlying popular diplomatic editions of the Masoretic text such as the Biblia Hebraica Stuttgartensia.This editio minor, which prints one of the best complete Masoretic manuscripts and adds a modern, critical apparatus, is often cited as if it represented “the Bible” in some pristine and normative form.While the Biblia Hebraica Stuttgartensia, its text and critical apparatus, represented the best standards of scholarship of its day and continues to provide convenient access to one early form of the Masoretic text, the manner in which the texts have been chosen, edited, and presented, and the readings proposed in the critical apparatus, give evidence of unarticulated historical and theological presuppositions. The result is that editions such as the Biblia Hebraica Stuttgartensia, though useful, can hardly be assumed to give us the definitive text of the Old Testament. The Oxford Hebrew Bible critical edition will undoubtedly likewise contain very provisional and personal scholarly interpretations. In effect it will approximate an original that should have been but never was. But the simple fact that this edition will make occasional use of synoptic parallel columns will help to awaken greater awareness of the limitations of textual criticism and of the difficulties in the seemingly simple task of establishing the text of the Bible.6 4 For a different view, one that would see textual uniformity associated with the Jerusalem temple alongside of textual pluriformity elsewhere, see A. S. van der Woude, “Pluriformity and Uniformity, Reflections on the Transmission of the Text of the Old Testament,” in Sacred History and Sacred Texts in Early Judaism, ed. J. N. Bremmer and F. García Martínez (Kampen: Pharos, 1992), 151–69. 5 Similarly T. Nicklas and C.Wagner (“Thesen zur Textlichen Vielfalt im Tobitbuch,” Journal for the Study of Judaism 34 [2003]: 141–59), who have argued that it is impossible to reconstruct an Urtext of the book of Tobit and call for a synoptic presentation of the extant texts, suggesting that only such plurality can do justice to the “riches of the reception and interpretation history of the book of Tobit” (159). 6 See the important reflections on the task and limits of textual criticism in James A. Sanders, “Stability and Fluidity in Text and Canon,” in Tradition of the Text, Studies offered to Dominique Barthélemy in Celebration of his 70th Birthday, eds. G. Norton, OP, and S. Pisano, SJ (Freiburg: Universitätsverlag, 1991), 203–17; and 136 Book Symposium 2. The ancient versions. One of the major trends in Old Testament studies in the past twenty years has been a growth of interest in and appreciation of the major biblical versions (LXX, Peshitta,Vulgate). While the versions have traditionally been used by text critics as resources for reconstructing the original Hebrew text, increasingly they are studied and appreciated as precious literary and theological texts in their own right. The Spanish textual critic N. Fernández Marcos, demonstrating a Catholic preference for the “both/and,” has observed: “The procedure adopted by the Polyglot Bibles has something to teach us today: to edit the different ancient texts that circulated among the distinct communities and which constitute sensu pleno the Books, ta biblia.”7 The Septuagint in particular has been increasingly recognized to have played an instrumental role in the formation of Christian culture. The late Dominique Barthélemy, OP, who devoted most of his scholarly life to the establishment of the critical Hebrew text of the Old Testament, called repeatedly for the recognition of a Christian Old Testament in two columns: one containing the Septuagint of the first centuries of our era, the second the Hebrew text canonized by the scribes of Israel.8 A preliminary step in this direction has been taken already in the case of the translation of the book of Esther. A 1969 agreement between the United Bible Societies and the Vatican Secretariat for Promoting Christian Unity allows for this book to be translated twice, based on both the Hebrew (in the Hebrew canon idem,“The Task of Text Criticism,” in Problems in Biblical Theology, Essays in Honor of Rolf Knierim, eds. H. T. Sun and K. L. Eades (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1997), 315–27; for a popular discussion of the differing approaches to textual critcism underlying forthcoming editions of the Hebrew Bible, see James A. Sanders,“Keep Each Tradition Separate,” Bible Review 16 (2000): 40–49, 58. 7 Fernández Marcos, “The Use of the Septuagint in the Criticism of the Hebrew Bible,” Sef 47 (1987): 59–72. 8 Dominique Barthélemy, OP, “La place de la Septante dans l’Église,” reprinted in D. Barthélemy, Études d’histoire du texte de l’Ancien Testament (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires, 1978), 126; see also Adrian Schenker, OP, “L’Ecriture Sainte subsiste en plusieurs formes canoniques simultanées,” in L’interpretazione della Bibbia nella Chiesa, Atti del Simposio promosso dalla Congregazione per la Dottrina della Fede (Città del Vaticano: Libraria Editrice Vaticana, 2001), 178–86; and the expanded German version of Schenker’s article, “Die Heilige Schrift subsistiert gleichzeitig in mehreren kanonischen Formen,” in Studien zu Propheten und Religionsgeschichte, ed. A. Schenker, OP (Stuttgart: Verlag Katholisches Bibelwerk, 2003), 192–200. Book Symposium 137 section) and the Greek (in the deuterocanonical section).9 This practice has been adopted by the NEB, REB, New Revised Standard Version, GN, and the French TOB translations. It is to be hoped that in the future consideration will be given to printing both versions synoptically in parallel columns. Several major international projects are now underway to provide not only translations but also commentaries on the Septuagint and the Syriac Peshitta.10 This is a welcome development and one that will make the rich heritage of the Eastern churches accessible to Western audiences. As Brian Daley, SJ, has recently noted, “Christian exegesis must not only become more theological but more theologically ecumenical, if it is to nourish the Church.”11 The inter-faith (Christian-Jewish) and ecumenical gains involved with the use of a critical Hebrew text based on the work of the Masoretes have been significant, especially with regard to the increasing convergence of lectionary practice in North America. One might anticipate similar ecumenical gains to be had with a greater accessibility of the Greek and Syriac Bibles in English translation, though the widespread use of these versions in the Western liturgies is not likely.12 The Catholic Church, with its supra-national organizational structure, long history of utilizing non-Hebrew versions of the Old Testament, and its theoretically multi-cultural and multi-lingual nature, is the Church best equipped to foster the use of the versions alongside of critical and scholarly editions based on the earliest recoverable texts. As the pioneering Catholic biblical scholar Richard Simon 9 United Bible Societies Executive Committee and the Vatican Secretariat for Promoting Christian Unity, “Guiding Principles for Interconfessional Cooperation in Translating the Bible,” The Bible Translator 19 (1968): 103. 10 The three Septuagint projects are known as the New English Translation of the Septuagint; La Bible d’Alexandrie, and Septuaginta Deutsch. The New English Annotated Translation of the Syriac Bible is sponsored by the Peshitta Institute in Leiden. 11 Brian E. Daley, SJ,“Is Patristic Exegesis Still Usable?: Reflections on Early Christian Interpretation of the Psalms,” Communio 29 (2002): 213. 12 At a conference on the interpretation of the Bible held in Romania in 1998, Orthodox and Western scholars identified the questions of the status of the Septuagint and of Christological reading of the Old Testament as related questions and as open issues remaining to be resolved; see the editor’s comments in “Konvergenzen und offene Fragen,” in Auslegung der Bibel in orthodoxer und westlicher Perspektive, Akten des west-östlichen Neutestamentler/innen-Symposiums von Neamt vom 4.–11. September 1998, eds. J. D. G. Dunn, H. Klein, U. Luz, and V. Mihoc (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2000), 219. 138 Book Symposium noted long ago, “L’Église Romaine reçoit toutes ces nations avec leurs Bibles.”13 The preservation of an ecclesial role for the Septuagint, Vulgate, and Peshitta, and perhaps for other important early translations as well, would manifest in a clear way that the Bible of the whole Church, East and West, has been inspired by the Holy Spirit in radically rich and diverse ways. Though the Catholic Church clearly calls for modern biblical translations to be based on the original scriptural languages, there is a growing body of official teaching on the role the biblical versions are to play alongside the original Aramaic, Greek, and Hebrew texts. Dei Verbum, number 22, for example, refers to the honor with which the Church holds these versions, even while going on in the next sentence to call for translations to be based on the original texts:“For this reason the Church, from the very beginning, made her own the ancient translation of the Old Testament called the Septuagint; she honors also the other Eastern translations, and the Latin translations, especially that which is called the Vulgate.”14 The recent instruction Liturgiam authenticam suggests a similar concern for preserving the riches of the biblical versions when preparing liturgical translations: [O]ther ancient versions of the Sacred Scriptures should also be consulted, such as the Greek version of the Old Testament commonly known as the ‘Septuagint,’ which has been used by the Christian faithful from the earliest days of the Church. . . . Finally, translators are strongly encouraged to pay close attention to the history of interpretation that may be drawn from citations of biblical texts in the writings of the Fathers of the Church.15 This official ecclesial sanction for the use of the versions may be understood as another expression of a Catholic predilection for “both/and” inclusivity. 13 R. Simon, Réponse au livre intitulé Défense des Sentiments de quelques Theologiens de Hollande sur l’Histoire Critique du Vieux Testament (Rotterdam: 1699), as quoted in D. Barthélemy, “L’enchevêtrement de l’histoire textuelle et de l’histoire littéraire dans les relations entre la Septante et le texte massorétique,” in De Septuaginta, Studies in Honor of John William Wevers on his Sixty-Fifth Birthday, eds.A. Pietersma and C. Cox (Mississauga, ON, Canada: Benben, 1984), 37. 14 Dei Verbum, in Vatican Council II: The Conciliar and Post Conciliar Documents, ed. Austin Flannery, OP (Northport, NY: Costello, 1987), no. 22. 15 Congregatio de Cultu Divino et Disciplina Sacramentorum, Liturgiam authenticam, March 28, 2001 (Washington, DC: United States Conference of Catholic Bishops, 2001), no. 41. Book Symposium 139 3. The history of interpretation based on non-Hebrew versions of the Old Testament.Attention to the various early translations of the Bible can have a pastoral impact in that it can facilitate access to the history of biblical interpretation in the Church. Johnson (256) notes that even when readings and interpretations based on the versions are pointed out by scholars, people cannot find them in their own Bibles. A fine example of how the treasures of the biblical versions and the patristic tradition can be exploited in popular commentary can be seen in Pope John Paul’s recent commentaries on the psalms and canticles of Morning Prayer. There the pope occasionally cites interpretations of the Psalter based on the text of the Vulgate and the Septuagint alongside of his comments on the Hebrew text.16 In this way the pluriform nature of the Word of God is highlighted and the richness of the history of interpretation in both the Western and the Eastern traditions, particularly spiritual and Christological interpretation, is made accessible to a new generation.17 4. Textual pluriformity and biblical inspiration. Finally I would suggest that the developments in textual criticism outlined above make even more urgent the call for a renewal of the study of biblical inspiration by Catholic biblical scholars and theologians.18 The fundamental idea behind the doctrine of inspiration is the secure link between God’s words as delivered by the prophets and sacred authors and the Scripture preserved by the Church. In the not too distant past prominent Catholic biblical scholars have suggested that inspiration is to be located at the level of particular textual forms of Scripture. George 16 I have consulted an English translation of the pope’s commentaries on the psalms and canticles of morning prayer titled, Psalms & Canticles, Meditations and Catechesis on the Psalms and Canticles of Morning Prayer (Chicago: LTP, 2004). In this edition examples of the pope’s use of the Vulgate and Septuagint alongside rather than in place of the Hebrew can be found on p. 94 (Ps 150:1), p. 108 (Ps 43:4), p. 177 (Ps 96:10), and p. 189 (Ps 86:2). The pope’s practice is similar to that of Jerome, who likewise commented on both Greek and Hebrew lemmas in his Old Testament commentaries; on Jerome’s practice see Adrian Schenker, OP, “Septuaginta und christliche Bibel,” Theologische Revue 91 (1995): 461. 17 One might also note in this context that the first volume of the Church’s Bible (The Song of Songs, Interpreted by Early Christian and Medieval Commentators, ed. R. A. Norris [Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2003]) prints complete translations of the Vulgate and Septuagint at the beginning of each unit of commentary. 18 D. Janthial (“Livre et révélation: le cas d’Isaie,” Nouvelle Revue Théologique 126 [2004]: 16–32) has suggested that recent developments in biblical research require a new articulation of the Church’s teaching on biblical inspiration. Book Symposium 140 Montague, SM, for example, has referred in the case of Judith to “the superiority of the Greek text in determining the Word of God to the Church.”19 In this particular case, Montague’s position is defensible, given the textual history of this particular book. But one wonders if the recovered Semitic texts of Ben Sira would require H. Duesberg, OSB, and P. Auvray, who argued in 1958 that it is specifically the Greek text of Ben Sira that enjoys inspiration, to revise their opinion.20 L. Hartman, CSSR, specifically identified the inspired biblical text with “the original manuscript of the inspired author.”21 P. Benoit, OP, and other Catholic scholars went so far in the opposite direction as to argue explicitly for the inspiration of the entire Septuagint, an argument made particularly in the 1950s and 1960s, but one that seems to have been largely abandoned.22 I would suggest that these arguments could be included in a more general theory of a multiform inspired Bible. It seems more prudent, and more in keeping with the textual evidence, to locate inspiration at either the level of the book or of the Bible as a whole, rather than at the level of particular textual forms, particular manuscripts, or particular authors. E. Ulrich has preferred to speak of canonicity at the level of the book.With regard specifically to canonicity, Ulrich notes, “Both in Judaism and in Christianity it is books, not the textual form of the books, that are canonical.”23 Since canonicity and inspiration are related, one might infer that Ulrich would locate inspiration at this level as well. It is not clear that this particular formulation is entirely a happy one, for books, of course, have content; they are not empty shells. The question of the textual form remains. In Judaism there is clear evidence that it is specifically the Masoretic text itself that has a sacred status not shared by the textual forms of books in the early biblical translations such as the Septuagint. Other scholars, such as Norbert Lohfink, SJ, argue that inspiration should be located at the level of the Bible as a whole.24 Lohfink bases his argument on the function of the canon.When an individual book 19 G. Montague, SM, The Book of Judith (NY: Paulist, 1973), 13. 20 H. Duesberg, OSB, and P.Auvray, La livre de l’Ecclesiastique, La Sainte Bible, 2nd ed. (Paris: Cerf, 1958), 22. 21 L. Hartman, CSSR, “Sirach in Hebrew and Greek,” Catholic Biblical Quarterly 23 (1961): 444. 22 For a recent discussion, see M. Müller, The First Bible of the Church:A Plea for the Septuagint (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1996). 23 E. Ulrich,“The Canonical Process,Textual Criticism, and the Latter Stages in the Composition of the Bible,” in Ulrich, The Dead Sea Scrolls, 57. 24 N. Lohfink, SJ,“The Inerrancy of Scripture,” in The Inerrancy of Scripture and Other Essays (Berkeley: BILBAL, 1992), 24–51. Book Symposium 141 is taken into the canon its context is radically reshaped and its meaning necessarily modified.This reception into the canon that gives a book its final form can be understood as a new act of authorship, and Lohfink would locate the final act of authorship, and inspiration, here at this level. The many individual books, as part of the canon, become one inspired book, the Bible.As Hugh of St.Victor put it:“The whole divine Scripture is one book, and this one book is Christ.” While Lohfink’s interpretation of inspiration is not without problems, it nicely emphasizes the formative role of the Church in shaping the biblical text and avoids speaking of inspired textual forms of individual books. Throughout their book both Johnson and Kurz demonstrate a concern that Catholic biblical scholarship maintain the highest academic standards while also building up the Body of Christ. Scholarly reflection on the pluriformity of the text of the Word of God may contribute to these goals in two ways. Firstly, such reflection may help the Church’s teaching on biblical inspiration to mature and to avoid the seductive certainties of enlightenment forms of biblical literalism. Secondly, maintaining a role for the early biblical versions alongside the original texts in the liturgical and intellectual life of the Church may also help safeguard the ecumenical catholicity of the Church and provide it with greater access to the rich tradition of the saints and scholars who have gone before us.25 N&V 25 I am grateful to Angela Kim Harkins, Jody Vaccaro Lewis, Francis Martin, James A. Sanders, Adrian Schenker, OP, and Gregory Tatum, OP, for reading earlier drafts of this paper. 142 Book Symposium “La Bible en ses Traditions” The New Project of the École biblique et archéologique française de Jérusalem Presented as a “Fourth-Generation” Enterprise O LIVIER -T HOMAS V ENARD, OP École Biblique Jerusalem, Israel “We might do a number of creative things.” —L. T. Johnson1 S UCH A REFRESHING approach to biblical scholarship as Johnson and Kurz’s has, of course, struck us here in Jerusalem at the École biblique. For a long time indeed several of us have been involved in a reflection on a recasting of the Bible de Jérusalem, taking into account the requirements of a comprehensive exegetical agenda that has been emerging since 1956, the date of the first one-volume edition.2 It should include: the discovery of the irreducibility of several versions of the same book (or of the same passages of a book); the new importance given to the history of the reception in literary studies, that matches up with the rediscovery of patristic commentaries in exegesis; a greater awareness of the literary aspect of biblical texts, besides their plain historical or doctrinal meaning. In brief, we aim at producing an edition of the Catholic Bible presenting the texts themselves in their diversity, framed by an enriched annotation divided into three main registers. The first, “Text,” will include all the notes dealing with the linguistic and literary description of the text, from points in textual criticism to more literary remarks. “Background” will group notes dealing with archaeology, history, geography, realia or texts of the ancient worlds and cultures, relevant to the production of biblical texts. “Reception” will be the largest zone of annotation; it is to comprise the most important readings of the text throughout history, starting from possible intertextual 1 L. T. Johnson, in Luke Timothy Johnson and William S. Kurz The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: A Constructive Conversation (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 2002), 90. 2 La sainte Bible, traduite en français sous la direction de l’École biblique de Jérusalem (Paris: Cerf, 1956), later called by the public La Bible de Jérusalem. For the history of its making, since the first sketches of 1943, see our “Cultural Backgrounds and Challenges of La Bible de Jérusalem,” in Essays in Honour of Dom Henry Wansbrough OSB, ed. P. McCosker (Oxford: Continuum, forthcoming 2006). Book Symposium 143 Reception Header Header Translations of the biblical texts Meaningful variant Cross references Proposed reading Cross references Variable height Pattern of two pages of the opened Bible en ses Traditions main version (e.g. MT) other version (e.g. LXX) Proposed reading Reception Biblical intertextuality Jewish traditions Christian traditions Theology, dogmas Liturgy Iconography Art and literature Background Text Text Key-words Key-words … Textual criticism Philology Literary devices Background History and geography Social background Ancient texts Fixed width echoes in parallel texts (in the canonical Bible, in Jewish tradition, or in apocryphal works), and continuing to some of the most important modern readings, including the Church Fathers and medieval theologians.The top corner of each page will present the reading proposed by the exegetes in charge of the book as a result of all preceding notes. In this contribution, in gratitude to our lucid authors and in thanks to our clear-minded colleagues, I would like to describe our project as a possible answer to some of their most challenging propositions.3 It gives me the opportunity to share with English-speaking exegetes and theologians some aspects of the “scientific project” we worked out two years ago to serve as a vade mecum for our scholarly undertakings in the years (or decades) to come.4 Permit me to insist on the fact that the following pages are not an official presentation of our project: If any of the views proposed in the next pages shock the reader, let him/her evaluate the project itself and eschew my opinions. Throughout their book, our authors express judgments or make suggestions that eventually depict what “The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship” could be, granted the rise of a new awareness of what it is 3 I shall not quote many of Kurz’s proposals, as far as they are mostly concrete examples attempting to actualize this theory by studying a series of texts with a view to revealing how they speak to certain contemporary concerns. 4 See “La Bible en ses Traditions, projet scientifique,” available at the École biblique de Jérusalem. See also the proceedings of one of the conferences preparing this scientific undertaking: J.-M. Poffet, dir., L’autorité des Écritures (Paris: Cerf, 2002). 144 Book Symposium to be a catholic exegete among the fourth (or a fifth?) generation of biblical scholars. These would be very much postmodern scholars,5 but according to a Christian version of postmodernity, which inverts the general relativism of postmodern thinkers into the conscious “second naivety” provided by an illuminated faith regarding our possibility to know the truth.6 Indeed, postmodern relativism can be of great help for us, to get rid of the exaggerated assumption of being “scientific”—the adjective meaning here objective and close to fact—an assumption that triggered the divorce between biblical exegetes and the life of the Church. Now, we do know that penser est toujours phraser (Lyotard) and that every discourse, scientific though it might claim to be, implies a rhetoric, a tradition, and many preconceptions. La Bible en ses Traditions was not purposely conceived of as a postmodern undertaking. Nevertheless, it is possible to underline several aspects of this undertaking that happen to fit best with the renewed, humble enthusiasm allowed to biblical interpreters by the postmodern softening of the modern “scientific” pattern.That is what I would like to do in the next pages, by following The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship in its both postmodern and Catholic celebrations of language, diversity, otherness, culture, and faith. Celebration of Language “In the beginning was the Word”: both the Bible and postmodernity invite us to renew our literary sensitivity.To better relate to one another the biblical text and the ways in which it was read, it is worth studying its literary conditioning in all its dimensions: Sometimes a full theological tradition begins with a minute literary variation that might be perceptible in “original” languages, and blurred in different translations. Annotation That is the reason why much attention will be paid to a precise linguistic description of the actual text in the first zone of notes. These notes should embrace the literary phenomenon on all its scales, from the smallest (that of utterances) to the largest (that of the work as a whole). From lexicological particularities to meta-literary teachings, including the 5 As Johnson puts it, “as soon as we are able to use the term ‘modernity,’ we find ourselves, willy-nilly, in the posture of postmodernism.” 6 On all this, see both J. Milbank’s and C. Pickstock’s works (see also Gavin Hyman’s critical analysis of the way both authors deal with postmodernity: Gavin Hyman, The Predicament of Postmodern Theology. Radical Orthodoxy or Nihilist Textualism? (Louisville, London, Leiden,Westminster: John Knox Press, 2001). Book Symposium 145 identification of literary genres or figures coming from rhetoric (either traditional or new), narratology or semiotics, and the detection of strategies of enunciation, the main significant features relevant to the interpretation of the text should be observed. Among the five functions that linguistics classically attributes to language, only one—namely the referential—has been really taken into account by exegetes, insofar as that for a long time their main aim has been reaching “historical facts” behind their literary and theological rendering. But there are four others: the “poetic function” related to the signifier considered as a value in itself; the “conative” and the “phatic” one to the pragmatic relationships surrounding utterances (language may be used as a means to draw someone’s attention, or to sustain it); and the “meta-linguistic” one (language may speak about itself—a phenomenon particularly frequent in literatures coming from orality). Once texts have been worked out in all these dimensions, some exegetical reasonings may collapse, while some traditional readings may appear to be more relevant than expected. Indeed, form criticism was often imbued with cultural prejudices coming from the neo-classical rhetorical mould common to most biblical scholars of the first three generations, concerning the “natural” way of expressing one’s thoughts or the very nature of the act of writing.7 Redaction criticism too has very seldom tried to surpass the wholly literary mindset inherited from the culture of the book8—which led scholars to interpret doublets sometimes too systematically, for example, in terms of editorial layers, without even imagining that some of them might be remnants of the oral compositions preceding the written texts. Interestingly enough, the sophisticated celebration of the cultural shaping of all knowledge owed to postmodern thinkers meets with the 7 Postmodern thinkers have rightly stated that to compose or to write a text does not mean simply to try to communicate one’s thoughts; what goes on when human beings write is not only a sort of translation of pure preceding thought into words. Indeed, thought is formed only once it has been worded. Moreover, in the very act of speaking or writing lies an implicit assent to the general rules of human communication—including its difficulties, impossibilities, and other phenomena related to a “murkiness” of human relationships. Insofar as they are expressed, one’s ideas are always more than one’s ideas, at least because of the very structure of linguistic signification:The meaning of one word is determined by that of all other words in the language in question; to speak is also to yield to those connotations. 8 As J. Dunn stated it a few months ago: “We here are all children of Gutenberg and Caxton. We belong to cultures shaped by the book.” J. D. G. Dunn, “Altering the Default Setting: Re-envisaging the Early Transmission of the Jesus Tradition,” New Testament Studies 49 (2003): 142. 146 Book Symposium teachings of patristic exegesis. The way in which ancient interpreters dealt with texts fits well with the insistence upon textuality as productivity. For example, Johnson reminds us that Origen seizes on the distinction between what happened in the past and the textual character of Scripture. Scripture was inspired by the Holy Spirit (so the Church teaches). Therefore in its language it inevitably teaches; in the way it is stated, it is meant for our instruction, whatever its relation to ‘what might have happened’ (Princ. 4, 1.12–13).9 Hence, according to Origen, “our contention with regard to the whole of Scripture is that it has all a spiritual meaning, but not all a bodily meaning; for the bodily meaning is often proved to be an impossibility” (Princ. 4, 1.20). Moreover, Origen seems to be sometimes more critical than modernity when the question of the relation between history and theology is raised.10 Translation Such a renewed interest in the literary dimension of our texts will have consequences for the art of translating. Linguistic reflection upon truth has taught us an operative conception of signification, instead of the resultative one inherited from the (neo-)classical times.As far as we are now aware that the way leading toward the meaning is itself part of the meaning, we should no longer equate the art of translating with a technique of rendering the same signified with other signifiers. Signification is a journey—not only the end of a way:Translating a text should be building up in the targeted language an analogous linguistic and literary path.The translation we would like to propose ought not only to inform the reader of the “conceptual” content of the biblical text, but also enable him to take an analogous literary itinerary to discover the treasure hidden in the field of the words.Translators should mobilize all sorts of literary devices and all levels of language in order to achieve this ideal goal—which supposes poetic imagination and, sometimes, even audacities toward any classical rhetorical canon. 9 Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 72, emphasis added. Origen is here commenting on 1 Cor 10:11: “These things happened to them typologically, but they were written for our instruction.” 10 As Johnson puts it,“Events of the past are past (see Mt 12:36).They are, like their actors, dead. But the text is living since it is inspired by the Holy Spirit ([Origen,] Hom. 1 Sam. 28, 4, 2)—the meaning the Spiritus wishes to teach is found precisely in the literary shaping, whether figurative or not ( Jn 10:4). . . .To read the text as a means of recovering the past is to prefer the dead to the living.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 83. Book Symposium 147 By no means should one equate this plea in favor of free literary imagination with a call for futility. On the contrary, it is deeply rooted in a theological account of reading as such.11 The close link between the sometimes intricate or painful (literary) way to the meaning of the text and the preparation for God’s grace12 is the main reason why the original text ought to be scrupulously respected. Ignoratio scripturarum est ignoratio Christi,13 a kind of “physical” continuity from the body of flesh of Jesus to the body of the biblical text,14 explains why those who believed that, thought even of the slightest details of the written texts.15 Therefore, just as many phrases or locutions that were understood beforehand in a purely metaphorical way came to be endowed with a proper meaning with the historical coming of Christ—in Jesus, yes, God does have arms and legs—a human being may be sown in the world as well as a word in the heart. I allude here to a passage of Matthew I worked out last year in the perspective of La Bible en ses traditions: Permit me to enlarge a little upon it. In the so-called “explanation” of the parable of the sower, the Greek presents a striking logical discrepancy. Whereas everything was made by the redactor to make us identify the sower and Jesus, in the telling of the parable itself, though such an identification held at the beginning of the “explanation,” suddenly in the hyperbaton of verse 19 the hearer, not the word is identified with the seed: “This is he that was sown by the way side.”16 Because for decades the exegesis of parables has mainly consisted in trying to recover Jesus’ words, the general trend among commentators is to lessen the importance of the fact, for example by evoking former 11 According to the ancient theology of inspiration, “God’s Spirit is at work not only in the ancient author, but at work also in the present reader, prodding and guiding human reason into the wisdom that God seek to reveal here and now about the present and future world.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 57. 12 The traditional discipline of lectio divina rests upon this link, especially the passage from its third to its fourth steps (oratio, contemplatio). See Guigues II le Chartreux, Epistola de vita contemplativa (scala Claustralium), in Lettre sur la vie contemplative (ou échelle des moines): Douze méditations, eds. and French trans. E. Colledge and J. Walsh (Paris: Cerf, 1970). See also the context of the famous phrase divina eloquia cum legente crescunt in Gregory the Great, Homilies On the Book of the Prophet Ezekiel, quoted on Homélies sur Ezéchiel, t. 1, ed. and French trans. Ch. Morel (Paris: Cerf, 1986), 244–45. 13 Saint Jerome, Commentarii in Isaiam, “Prologus,” (CCL 73), 1; or (PL 24), 17. 14 That “the Bible” as a whole and the real Jesus are in dialectic relationship might be argued from the viewpoint of the history of canon. 15 Mt 5:18. 16 Mt 13:19 (ASV). 148 Book Symposium (oral?) layers of composition, in which (Aramaic?) speakers used holistic ways of expression. In French, they did it up to the point of altering the text in the translation.17 In fact, what the text means literally is both: that the seed is the word (and the sower is Jesus), and that the seed is the hearer of the word (and the sower is God the Creator)—which ambiguity results in suggesting an enigmatic relationship between Jesus and God and between Jesus and his words.Agreeing with this supposes that not having already set one’s mind on the literary genre of verses 18–23: As much as an explanation, it appears as a mere retelling of the parable (neither the identity of the sower, nor the nature of fructification are allegorically elucidated), complicated by enigmatic features. In the narrative, Jesus does not begin “hear, ye, the meaning, nor my explanation of the parable of the sower,” but “Hear then ye the parable of the sower.”18 Actually, what he is doing in these verses is applying to the disciples the general rule he gave at verse 12: “For whosoever hath, to him shall be given, and he shall have abundance.” Indeed, by asking Jesus why he is speaking to them in parables,19 the disciples act as if they had understood. Therefore, although they do not really need any explanation, as far as they “have” (a certain knowledge of what Jesus intended to mean),20 they deserve to “be given” (more).That is what Jesus does in these verses: He gives them more symbolic teaching (which, we shall suggest later on in this article). Here again, a postmodern celebration (namely, that of the signifier over against the essentialist overvaluing of the signified) merges with ancient practices: Did not Jerome coin a sort of new Latin language by wishing to respect sometimes even the word order of the biblical text? 21 17 Thus, the literary feature was completely erased in the first edition of La Bible de Jérusalem, which translated “tel est celui qui a reçu la semence au bord du chemin” (Mt 13:19b; ed. 1956).The text was restored in the second edition: “tel est celui qui a été semé au bord du chemin” (ed. 1973), but Fr. Benoit chose to maintain in note the following value judgment: “cette tournure étrange vient d’une certaine confusion dans l’interprétation de la parabole etc” (note b ad loc.), rather than try to go further in interpretation. 18 Mt 13:18 (ASV). 19 Cf. Mt 13:9–11 (ASV):“ ‘He that hath ears, let him hear.’And the disciples came, and said unto him ‘Why speakest thou unto them in parables?’ And he answered and said unto them: ‘unto you it is given to know.’ ” 20 In fact, more than that! cf. v. 11 (ASV): “Unto you it is given [or: it has been given: dedotai] to know the mysteries of the kingdom of heaven, but to them it is not given.” 21 See A. Michel, In hymnis et canticis, culture et beauté dans l’hymnique chrétienne latine, “Philosophes médiévaux,” vol. 20 (Paris, Louvain:Vander-Oyez, 1976), 41–43. Book Symposium 149 Celebration of Diversity To stress the legitimacy of the love of our generation for diversity and the opportunity it gives to spread authentic Christianity among them, Johnson draws attention to the first 350 years of Christianity. It was, according to him, a time of religious and cultural pluralism like our age: In that time, skeptical of received certitudes, Christianity appeared as one way among many others.22 Texts A similar love for diversity appears in our choice concerning the very texts we shall translate. As regards textual criticism, this Bible will show a preference for a diplomatic way of editing the texts. Indeed, in her wisdom, the Catholic Church never canonized texts, but only books. As Pope Pius XII taught some sixty years ago, the traditional primacy of the Vulgate is a “juridical,” not a “scientific,” one. Recent discoveries in the history of texts, especially those provided by the Dead Sea Scrolls, prevent scholars, from now on, to be satisfied with the old stratification that considered the Hebrew masoretic text as the oldest, the Septuagint coming next, and the different (Latin, Syriac, Coptic, etc.) versions after. We do know that the Greek texts reflect sometimes a Hebrew version older than the Masoretic one. In some cases,23 one should consider each version as an original text, sometimes with its own theological agenda, rather than to try to elaborate an “original” text by comparing them and mixing them up—which resulted in publishing, in modern languages, biblical texts never read before! According to a first evaluation by Fr. Maurice Gilbert, nearly 30 percent of the Old Testament appears in two or three different, irreducible versions. Rather than producing one more eclectic text, we wish to present the different ways a same work resonated (like a bow) in the echo chambers of the different communities and periods that transmitted it to us. Concretely speaking, it means that the reader will be given the possibility of reading different texts, either in synoptic columns, or in special frames included in the text, or in notes in the register called “Text,” each time multiple versions with significant variations of meaning occur. By restoring the polyphony of text traditions within the Old Testament itself, we 22 As Johnson puts it, “in important ways, we are closer to the earliest Christian interpreters than we might at first imagine, and it is this closeness that enables a conversation across centuries” (63):“we are in a post-Constantinian era”;“we live in a world that is intensely and explicitly pluralistic” (62) in which we are “forced to make [our] way as an intentional community” (63). 23 For example Jeremiah, or some parts of Sirach. 150 Book Symposium shall echo the practices of Origen portrayed by Johnson.24 As regards the New Testament, besides the Alexandrine text—epitomized at best by the Nestlé-Aland critical edition—attention should be given to the Byzantine text, the Vulgate, and other versions important in the history of reception. Annotation Giving great importance to the depiction of the literary conditioning of biblical texts enables us better to take into account different and sometime contradictory interpretations that were made in the history of its reception. We wish to enlarge and “open” the reading, rather than close or restrict it on the pretext that one knows exactly what the text (or worse, its author) means. In addition, this fits well with the “both/and” approach to the Bible illustrated by Johnson and Kurz.25 Against a “scholarly” either/or ethos, according to which choosing one option in interpreting a text necessarily means rejecting the others, the analytical presentation of the notes will greatly help to retain all the possibilities and to combine them in the most generous way possible. It means that notes should focus on facts, not on hypotheses (consensual though they might be among scholars), in order to give the largest space to the description of textual facts and to the interpretations that they actually brought about in history. Celebration of the Otherness In the context of La Bible en ses Traditions, such a celebration is nothing less than a theoretical stance:The otherness characterizes the very making of this new edition, which collaborators will have to engage other fields of knowledge and specialists with other mindsets. Other Fields Obviously, the making of this new kind of Bible requires new skills from the exegete, in comparison with the type of training delivered by present-day institutions, either secular or ecclesiastical (both are indebted to the modern confrontations of rationalism and apologetics). Part of the 24 “Rather than seek to discard readings in favor of the quest for a simple proto- type—the instinct of modernity—Origen uses such textual variations as a means of honoring local textual traditions and entertaining new possibilities of meaning.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 80. 25 With respect to the relationship with pagan wisdoms, Judaism, and early Christianity as well, La Bible en ses Traditions hopes to expose “both continuity and distinctiveness (not the same as uniqueness, please note), [which] is congenial to Catholic historiographical and theological instincts.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 22. Book Symposium 151 exegete’s work will be the (usual) scientific one, but part of it should be a more creative (literary, poetic) one. The appreciation of otherness will appear in the option for more literal translations, better attuned to the “exoticism” of biblical cultures, especially to the oral matrix of many of our texts. Against the schoolteacher’s prejudice that condemns repetition, a prejudice more widely spread in French than in any other language, repetitions, plays on words, symmetries should be better preserved than in past translations, which often simplify, in order to fit with the modern concept of clarity. We shall become more inventive not only as translators, but also as administrators of the general balances among the different registers of notes—which will be, like a poetical composition, a question of ingenious wisdom as much as of science. Other People Hardly any scholar masters all the fields of knowledge required by the annotation, so that the work on each book of the Bible may be an opportunity to gather several people with various viewpoints and priorities. Indeed, among the difficulties we have to face is the fact that we belong to different generations26 and cultural spheres. My language in this paper 26 I particularly enjoyed Johnson’s sociological analysis of the history of Catholic biblical scholarship. Yes, at the beginning of the use of historical-critical approaches in the Church, the catholic structure of minds was robust enough to let the exegetes make use of these new tools without being fascinated by them. Indeed Father Lagrange, founder and still inspirer of the École biblique, would be a good example of the fruitful synergy of a reliable (Thomist) theology and classical training in the humanities with historical criticism.Yes, from 1943 onward, catalyzed by authoritative invitations to make use of it, the historical-critical pattern became omnipotent not only in biblical studies, but also in other theological fields. But it was not merely a lack of scientificity that was fortunately filled out: Catholic biblical scholars were tempted to forget who they really were meant to be, especially in relationship with the pastoral needs of the Church. Many exegetes of this second generation lost the awareness that historical-critical reading was nothing but one option among others in understanding the sacred text. Since that time the historical-critical dominion over biblical studies began to decline, because at last no real certainty emerged, neither about ancient Israel nor about the origins of Christianity out of two centuries of research. Those interested in reading and transmitting the Bible as Word, the believers, could not be satisfied with this way of dealing with Scriptures.Therefore, the third generation is now striving to recover a better sense of what it is to be a Catholic scientific reader of the Bible: “We would like to find a way to think about biblical interpretation within the church that is not totally defined by academic conventions yet truly has a scholarly quality.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, viii.The fourth one could be that of La Bible en ses Traditions! 152 Book Symposium may surprise readers from cultures other than the “Parisian” one, either exegetes fond of Deutsche Wissenschaft or simply exegetes from previous generations; even among my generation, some of us are more sensitive to the reconstruction of the historical meaning, some others to the creativity of the reception.The challenge is to work together without reducing the biblical symphony of diverse divinely inspired voices into a cacophony of rival scholars inspired by generational conflict!27 We shall work together and agree to debate on disputed points. For my part, I have begun to work on the first Gospel. My assistant and I prepare a first draft of notes for all the registers, taking special care for our own specialties.Then we submit our work to specialists in patristics, ancient Judaism, history of the liturgy, iconography or dogmatics.They are invited to modify our proposals, to correct or even to suppress them, to rewrite them in a more effective way according to the specialty, to add better references. . . .At the end of the process we shall obtain a rich annotation, both unified (insofar as it was first planned by the very few in charge of the book), and diverse (insofar as each register will have been reworked by a specialist of its field according to his own discipline’s standards). As a result, this Bible should be able to attract all kinds of readers. The analytical annotation facilitates different sorts (hopefully complementary) of readings. Even non-believers should be able to state that faith does not prevent the believers from respecting the fields in which they work and does not break up the community of those who honestly search for the Truth.28 Celebration of Culture Fundamentally, with all thinkers of our time, we are “deeply aware of the constructed character of human meaning, how much it is connected to faith commitments, how profoundly it is rooted in community traditions.”29 Postmodernity, once deprived of its nihilist postulates, can help biblical 27 This paper is to be read simply as a collection of remarks on the reasons some- one with a mindset such as mine has had to collaborate with La Bible en ses Traditions, and to promote it as something that many cultured believers as well as biblical scholars dream about. None of my remarks are normative. 28 Here again postmodern thinkers should agree with Catholic theologians on the “both/and” ethos. Contemporary hermeneutics has taught us that both tradition and criticism are at work in any reading:“Loyalty is not the opposite of criticism, but its condition,” since reading a text means always interpreting it according to the premises and practices of a specific reading community. . . . It does not demand the sacrifice of any critical questioning, it demands rightly, from an hermeneutical viewpoint, “the affirmation of that Tradition as the starting point of any inquiry.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 27. 29 Ibid., 63. Book Symposium 153 scholars recover confidence in cultural mediation: From the outset, cultural, social, literary, philosophical, and theological prejudices shape every thought, and this is not fate, but fact—and should simply be taken into account. Epistemological Shift The stress put by La Bible en ses Traditions on the linguistic shaping and the historical reception of our texts fits quite well with Johnson’s definite stance against a “commitment to the notion of an original and pure good news, a moment of revelation so uniquely untouched by human influence that it is self-evidently divine.”30 This notion is a romantic prejudice, inherent in the historical-critical method, which would never have appeared without the classical, rationalist reduction of language to a noetic tool or a mere means of expression. In ancient oral or semi-oral civilizations language was not the scanty instrument modern Western thought has construed: For speakers or hearers of oral circles, language reveals rather than represents. As N. Frye beautifully showed it in his famous book,31 the linguistic practice inherent the Bible is not the objective application “signifier/signified” or “word/thing” to which we have been accustomed by the dualist ontology of sign promoted by modern linguistics. In the world of Scripture, events, undetectable without texts that beforehand sharpen the attention of those who live them, come to enlighten these very texts. Inhabitants of this world experience the mutual illuminations of being and letter. These observations might have frightened believers at the time of positivism, as mere excuses not to be engaged with critical historians, but the situation is now reversed. On one side, any honest thinker of our time should wonder if the circle of preknowledge and knowledge that is working throughout the biblical revelation is different from the hermeneutic circle of the most commonplace knowledge. On the other side, traditional themes like the “fulfillment of Scriptures” now appear first as consequences of the poetical and narrative structure of knowledge, in communities that bore, produced, and handed over the Bible,32 30 Ibid., 20. 31 N. Frye, The Great Code.The Bible and Literature (Toronto:Academic Press Canada, 1982). 32 In modern times, to quote the Scriptures means to open books and concordances to make an erudite composition. Such was not the case in the Jewish culture of the first century, for example. In those times, one was taught to read and sometimes to write with (and within) the Bible, so that the Bible itself became a sort of language.The rediscovery of the Jewish art of memory could provide the real hinging upon one another of historicity and “literarity” in the evangelical recitatives. Indeed, it could avoid reducing intertextuality to a persuasive device used a 154 Book Symposium so that many critical arguments against historicity grounded in the literary shaping and the scriptural perspectives drawn by allusions and quotations fall short. Efforts should be made to recover at least a little of the ancient sense of language so that historical effectiveness should be detected no longer against, but through the cultural mediations of knowledge. Between the crisis of historical reason and the invading of literary thought, may not fresh studies of the biblical practice of “the fulfillment of Scriptures” open paths for new insights to theologians who do not agree with any reduction of revelation to anything immanent, be it historical or literary? Theology of Inspiration By helping to appreciate the cultural conditionings of human communication in the making of the Bible, La Bible en ses Traditions could eventually bring about a deeper comprehension of the traditional account of oeconomia revelationis taking place “gestis verbisque intrinsece inter se connectis.” 33 The gesta in question refer as much to the bearing and shaping of the verba throughout time, as to the very events told in texts. From the plain lacuna to the most illogical passage, passing through all kinds of textual corruptions and other accidents in the oral or written handing over of the text, what French literary theorists in the 1960s and 1970s called the “rustling” of the text34 do share in “the Word of God in its historical communication,” to speak in the magisterial way.35 These cultural “events,” unspectacular though they may be, belong to the historical communication of God’s Word. Celebration of Faith The next convergence of the project La Bible en ses Traditions with Johnson and Kurz’s wishes that might be stressed is the role devolved to faith inside the scholarly work of exegetes. posteriori by a writer, by granting it a concrete basis in actual practices of the ancient times. See beautiful insights on this point in “The Tradition,” ch. 8 of J. D. G. Dunn, Jesus remembered,“Christianity in the Making,” vol. 1 (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2003), 173–254. 33 Dei Verbum, no. 2. 34 Cf. R. Barthes, The Rustle of Language, trans. R. Howard (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989), French: Le bruissement de la langue (Paris: Seuil, 1984). 35 That is one of the greatest reasons for relativizing an overly romantic vision of inspiration as a psychological or noetic phenomenon. Book Symposium 155 Be it only for preparing patristic or theological notes, exegetes should not overlook the teaching of the Church, even under “methodological” grounds. On the contrary, it should be a key part of their agenda, as an invitation to deepen their philological, rhetorical, or semiotic study of the text and its reception, so as to link (the possibility of) their belief with the very text. At least, it should enlarge one’s context of reading and provide new challenging hypotheses. The so-called “literary methods” supply many tools to assess the continuity or the discontinuities between the biblical text and the traditional teachings of the faithful communities. As Kurz shows in his essays about the prologue of John or about John 6, some theological truths that were developed a posteriori may help the reader notice textual facts or literary peculiarities that otherwise would have seemed without interest. Here again, Church fathers like Origen or Augustine may be of great help, to appreciate that truth is not merely meaning. Beyond the historical meaning/literal sense determined by the historico-critical method, a multifaceted approach of the text should take into account a wide variety of factors deriving from the tradition of the church centered on Christ. Couldn’t we apply to literary richness in general what Origen said about the inspiration? The divine inspiration of prophetic words and the spiritual dimension of Moses’ Law appeared in full light when Jesus came. It was not really possible to put forward clear examples of the divine inspiration of the ancient Scriptures before the coming of Christ. But the coming of Jesus led all those who might have supposed the Law and the Prophets not to be divine to state definitely that they had been written with the help of a celestial grace.36 If one strives to detect literary links between the linguistic shaping of the texts and the dogmatic teaching of the Church, many amazing “effects of meaning” may be brought to light. Going back for a while to the parabolical discourse of Jesus in Matthew: Isn’t it striking to discern a rather unified theology of the Word and of language as a medium of revelation through the enlarging upon the theme of the Word as a seed,37 specifically 36 Origen, De Principiis, IV, 1, 6–7; quoted in Origène, Traité des Principes, eds. and French trans. H. Crouzel and M. Simonetti (Paris: Cerf, 1978 and 1980), 252. 37 Usually considered as a theologoumenon in the earliest apostolic traditions, it might be related to Jesus’ preaching itself, as far as no Jewish assimilation of the Word to a seed can be found before him. Cf. M. E. Boismard, review of Siegfried Schulz, Komposition und Herkunft der Johanneischen Reden, Revue Biblique 69 (1962): 422. 156 Book Symposium expressed in the discourses of John38 and only hinted at in the narrative of Matthew?39 Our stress on the fruitfulness of faith might be related to the postmodern celebration of the irrational, but it inverts its logic. For Christians, reason is not so much determined by infra-rational factors, than by a supra-rational call to reach the very Principle of all possible reason by faith, hope, and love. Ideally our abbreviated “talmud” is to be Christian not only in its content, but also in its very organization: It should not look like a compilation of pieces of information or opinions connected by associations of ideas, as in school discussions, but like an analytical, logical collection attuned to the religion of the Logos—logikè latréia— which Christianity pretends to be.40 Numerous though they will be, 38 Jesus is the Word of God straight from the Prologue.To his disciples, he gives the Word, not only through his words considered as static performances to be repeated, but also through a competence to say even greater words. Cf. Jn 14:12: “Verily, verily, I say unto you, he that believeth on me, the works that I do shall he do also; and greater [works] than these shall he do.” In the context, the works are Jesus’s words. Cf. Jn 14:10, “the words that I say unto you I speak not from myself: but the Father abiding in me doeth his works.” 39 The narratological framing of Jesus’ discourse by the only two passages where his familial origins are put into question in Matthew (compare Mt 12:46–50 with Mt 13:53–58) raises in the reader’s mind the question of who Jesus is. The rhetorical discrepancy in the “explanation” of the parable (is the seed the word, or the one who hears it?) raises the question of the identity of the sower (is he Jesus—sower of the word—or the Creator—sower of men who might hear and listen to the word?) and that of the relation between these two possible “sowers.” Finally, the relationships between Jesus, his word, his disciples, and their words implied in the concluding dialogue between Jesus and the disciples is very similar to that implied in Jn 14:12 (cf. preceding note). “ ‘Have ye understood all these things?’ They say unto him: ‘Yea.’ And he said unto them: ‘Therefore every scribe who hath been made a disciple to the kingdom of heaven is like unto a man that is a householder, who bringeth forth out of his treasure things new and old.’ ” (Mt 13:51–52 [ASV], emphasis added.) This dia touto refers to the very answer of the disciples.As far as they have understood, they shall be able to speak in a way similar to that of Jesus, and to devise means to tell all “these things” by combining not only new interpretations with ancient Scriptures, but also new developments with Jesus’ words. 40 Against the growing (postmodern) defiance of reason, J. Ratzinger reiterates this ancient pretence of worship according to the Logos. See, for example, J. Ratzinger, The Spirit of the Liturgy (Der Geist der Liturgie; Verlag: Herder, 2000), trans. J. Saward (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2000), read in the French trans., L’esprit de la liturgie, trans. G. Catala and G. Solari (Genève: Ad solem, 2001), 38–41. God’s Logos—both Intelligence and Word—who grants human being as well as angels intelligence and word,“incorporated” in the Scriptures, incarnated in Jesus of Nazareth, leads the whole humankind to resurrection in his paschal Book Symposium 157 comments on the text will look like a verbal galaxy moving around an invisible center which is the mystery of Christ. Invitation I would like to end with what I find one of the most challenging propositions of L. T. Johnson: “Catholics should be concerned not only with the world that produced the New Testament, but as well with the world that the New Testament itself produced.”41 To be even more challenging, let us put the last verb in the future: Catholic scholars have to be concerned with the world that the New Testament and the Bible in general will produce. Indeed, biblical scholars are cultural agents: not only because they bring preconceptions, either linguistic/literary or philosophical or theological, from their social and intellectual milieu, but also because they themselves take part in the ongoing process of culture. They produce works and books, which in their turn influence that surrounding milieu. The most fruitful relationships between the Bible and the cultures that read it in the past were oriented from the Bible to culture.42 It is only the spreading of the positivist historical paradigm over all fields of knowledge, which overturned the direction of this relationship by judging the Bible only by secular standards. To reconstruct the “historical” original context and audience of the texts, scholars tended to reduce them to other ideas, customs, or phenomena known beforehand through other ancient documents or scholarly studies.Thus, the creativity of the authors or their addressees, the newness of the text, the fruitfulness of its effects (in brief, its revelatory function) tended to be blurred.43 mystery. In the Christian rite, the human logos is reached, purified, and magnified by the eternal Logos of the Creator. 41 Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 23. 42 The promoters of a new French translation of the Bible three years ago badly missed this point by contending that every generation in the past had adapted the sacred Book to its own needs. On the contrary, past generations changed their cultural habits-sometimes even their language to receive the Bible. Cf. O.Th.Venard,“La culture de la Bible Bayard,” Képhas 1 (2002): 129-40, esp. 138-40. 43 Therefore, it is of tremendous importance to recall that “the historical moment does not exhaust the process of criticism.” Johnson, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 28. “Criticism has philosophical, theological, moral and aesthetic dimensions that are as least as legitimate and important as the historical.” Ibid. “Historical knowledge”-especially built up as it is since the modern concept of historical fact was invented, “plays a limited role within a complex conversation enacted by a faith community.” Ibid. 158 Book Symposium In fact, as a keystone of the whole Bible, the New Testament is not a pure mnemonic device conserving the archives of the Founder and the beginnings of his community. To describe itself, the primitive Christian literature uses mainly two words: testimony and seed.44 Perceiving truth as exactitude and correspondence, the first leans upon the past (and calls for historical reconstitutions and historiographical debates). Envisaging truth as fruitful dynamism, the second is turned toward the future (and invites to spiritual experiment, ethical commitment, and creative engagements). Biblical texts are as much places to live nowadays as sources of information about ancient times. Taking into better account the fecundity of the text may mean to depart from a severe “scientific” attitude inherited from the Protestant world; but it will certainly bring us closer to our Judaic roots.45 Once achieved—in fifteen, thirty, or sixty years46—La Bible en ses Traditions could greatly help our contemporaries to embrace the holistic approach to Scripture that Johnson and Kurz promote: produced by a 44 In the New Testament, sperma that may have symbolized first the Mosaic law ( Jas 1:23-25), designates the whole revelation, especially that coming from Jesus ( Jas 1:18-22; 1 Pt 1:23-25; synoptic parables of sowing), and finally Jesus himself ( Jn 1:13; Jn 12:24).Very significantly, kokkos (grain) is used only to symbolize the faith (Mt 17:20 and par.), Jesus' body in the Easter mystery ( Jn 12:24), the believers' bodies sowed on earth and destined to rise up again (1 Cor 15:37). Sowing and harvesting become usual metaphors for the future fruitful mission of the disciples, suggesting both innovation (one grain has to produce many others) and faithfulness (from one sowing to the other, the grain must hold its nature and quality). 45 “Luther was surely right when he saw Catholicism as closer to Judaism than to Protestantism. An observant Jewish community is structured by halakah. So is Catholicism. Jewish scholars are freed by the strong identity formation accomplished by halakah to engage Torah haggadically, that is, not only as a collection of rules, but above all as a source of wisdom. So are the Catholic biblical scholars free to engage Scripture in a variety of imaginative ways as a source of transforming wisdom.” Johnson and Kurz, The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship, 31.At the same time, we should not reduce text reading to elaborating moral rules. Literary imagination should retain its own value as part of a contemplative life. “By no means every reading of the text within the church, however is for the purpose of deciding halakah. Much reading is for wisdom and delight, for the transformation of the mind and the conversion of the heart. In such reading both communities and individuals can enter into the imaginative world constructed . . . by the Bible.” Ibid., 32. 46 Please do not be discouraged! Like the first Bible de Jérusalem, each book of the Bible will be released separately, both in French and in the original modern language of scholars who will have prepared it, as soon as it is finished and approved by the Steering Committee.Thus, it will be possible to improve them thanks to readers' criticisms before collecting them in “the” Bible (which should not be more than three times larger than the present-day Jerusalem Bible). Book Symposium 159 Christianity once more facing towards its Origin, it could even “incarnate” it, as a sort of “Christian Talmud.”All biblical scholars or scholars of other fields touched by the annotation we project will be very welcome to share in the imagining and—Deo iuuante—realization of this future. Re-Entering the Scriptural World DAVID S. Y EAGO Lutheran Theological Southern Seminary Columbia, South Carolina I T SHOULD BE SAID from the beginning that this book accomplishes what its title promises: It does present a genuinely “constructive” conversation on the future of Catholic biblical scholarship by two leading Catholic biblical scholars. It is, moreover, an important conversation, and one that opens toward the future in a promising way, not only for Roman Catholics. Though I am going to proceed now to raise some questions about the conversation as it has developed so far, I should not like anything I say to obscure my gladness that these issues are being discussed along these lines, nor my gratitude to the authors for their work. In their attempt to envision a distinctively Roman Catholic approach to biblical scholarship, the authors take a path that my colleague Michael Root has called “oppositional self-definition.”That is to say, they identify a paradigm of biblical study that they take to be undifferentiatedly Protestant and historical-critical (more will be said later about this assumption) and define their “Catholic” paradigm by the ways in which it would contrast with this “Protestant” approach.The Protestant-Catholic division is taken entirely for granted, as a fixed and unquestioned feature of the landscape.Thus Professor Kurz writes: Since it is intuitively obvious that Catholics differ from Christians of other denominations in how they worship, pray, and emphasize sacraments, it stands to reason that Catholics will always have at least some significantly different beliefs from members of other denominations or religions, as well as from nonbelievers, no matter how ecumenical they endeavor to be. (264) Notice here the acceptance of the ecumenical status quo as axiomatic:“it is intuitively obvious. . . . It stands to reason.” No awareness is displayed of a century of ecumenical discussion that has worked with great intensity to break down the “obviousness” of many perceived differences 160 Book Symposium between Catholics and Protestants. For example, one could not tell from this that there is now a mutually recognized “consensus in the basic truths” of the doctrine of justification among Lutherans and Roman Catholics, a doctrine described by both parties as “more than just one part of Christian doctrine, . . . an indispensable criterion that constantly serves to reorient all the teaching and practice of our churches to Christ.”1 It is unfortunately no surprise to ecumenists when theological scholarship in all fields and on all sides ignores the ecumenical dialogues; but one might have hoped for more in a book calling for a more ecclesially grounded biblical scholarship, especially given the teaching of Pope John Paul II that ecumenism is not “some sort of appendix” added on to the essential work of the Church, but is rather “an organic part of her life and work, and consequently must pervade all that she is and does.”2 Notice too how in Professor Kurz’s formulation there is no recognition of any “hierarchy of truths” or any other way of sorting out and weighing differences among Christians. Indeed, he simply lines non-Catholic Christians up with adherents of non-Christian religions and non-believers, and describes the relationship of Catholics to all three groups with the same term: “significantly different beliefs.” I am quite sure that Professor Kurz does not intend the implications of what he has written here; in the fact that he did write it, however, we see the power of the status quo of Christian division that can make it seem natural to lump together with nonChristians those fellow Christians with whom Catholics share “some, and even most, of significant elements and endowments which together go to build up and give life to the Church itself.”3 Furthermore, even with regard to intra-Christian relations, the notion of “significant differences” is left entirely unanalyzed. Are all such differences equally significant? And just how significant are they for biblical study in comparison with what Catholics and other Christians believe in common? When Professor Johnson comes to discuss ecumenism explicitly a few pages on, the picture does not brighten appreciably. Catholic biblical scholarship should be “ecumenical,” he says, in four ways: (1) It should renounce triumphalism, and (2) cooperate with Protestant scholarship on 1 The Lutheran World Federation and the Roman Catholic Church, Joint Declara- tion on the Doctrine of Justification (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2000), par. 18. 2 Pope John Paul II, Ut unum sint, no. 20. 3 Second Vatican Council, Unitatis redintegratio, Decree on Ecumenism, no. 3, in Decrees of the Ecumenical Councils, vol. 2, ed. Norman Tanner (London: Sheed and Ward, 1990). Book Symposium 161 “tasks which can be carried out in relatively neutral fashion.” Further, Catholic scholars should (3) have “deep respect for different faith perspectives” operative in biblical study, but also (4) “celebrate the sensibilities that are distinctively Catholic” (267). One could, I believe, describe this as an essentially “multi-culturalist” version of ecumenism. Difference is taken to be the bottom line; no real reconciliation or synthesis is envisioned: “Ecumenism does not demand the removing of differences.” Each party should rather respect the otherness of the “other” while at the same time insisting on remaining “other,” on retaining its own distinct “sensibilities.” This emphasis on “sensibilities” is, I fear, revealing. Johnson does not speak of “celebrating the truths of which we are confident” but of celebrating a set of attitudes and sympathies that make “us” the way we are. In other words, it is the identities we have formed in our divisions from one another that are finally sacrosanct, and for their sake the divisions have to be maintained. We may, perhaps, exchange gifts across the lines of divisions—Americans can learn to like couscous without becoming Moroccans—but the other must nonetheless remain other, so that we may remain the same. Doubtless I exaggerate unfairly, as far as either author’s intentions and conscious attitudes go. But rhetoric has its own dynamic, and the absence of countervailing impulses in the book makes it legitimate, I believe, to ask in what direction the force of this rhetoric would take Catholic biblical scholarship. Already in the book itself there are problematic indications. Thus, in the paragraph I have been criticizing, Professor Johnson writes: Catholics cannot find in Paul’s language about justification by faith the same depth of significance that Lutheran scholars do. Reformed readers cannot appreciate Paul’s language about sanctification in the same manner as Catholics. (267) What is the force of the “cannot” in these sentences? Does it express a normative principle: “Catholics, as Catholics, cannot be as taken with Pauline language about justification by faith as Lutheran scholars are”? If so, then how odd for the Catholic Church to affirm together with Lutherans that the scriptural message of justification “directs us in a special way toward the heart of the New Testament witness to God’s saving action in Christ”!4 Or is Professor Johnson registering this lesser appreciation on both sides as a fact so massive that it must simply be taken for granted? That would, it seems to me, raise difficult questions about just what defines 4 Lutheran World Federation and the Roman Catholic Church, Joint Declaration, no. 17. 162 Book Symposium “distinctively Catholic sensibilities,” for it would suggest that Professor Johnson’s Catholic sensibilities are quite different from those of St.Augustine or St. Thomas Aquinas, who show no signs of finding less “depth of significance” in the Pauline language of justification than Lutherans do, even though they may not always find precisely the same significance. Likewise, if I as a Protestant “cannot” appreciate Pauline language about sanctification as Catholics do, then it would seem that my Protestant sensibilities are vastly different from those of the Puritans or John Wesley, not to mention (in my own tradition) untold numbers of Lutheran Pietists over the centuries.5 Who then is the real Catholic, Augustine or Professor Johnson’s “Catholics”? Who is the real Protestant, the “Reformed readers” whom Professor Johnson has in mind, or the Puritans and Pietists? The truth is that ecumenism has everything to do with the removal of differences, not to be sure all differences, which would be insane, but those differences that prevent us from living the life of the Church together as one visible people.6 As reading Scripture together is an integral part of the Church’s life, it follows that ecumenism does aim at removing those differences that render Catholic and Protestant biblical scholarship separate enterprises that converge on secular ground but remain divided theologically and spiritually. Ecumenism classically conceived certainly aims to conserve and integrate the truths perceived by the various parties, but it is intentionally rather hard on “sensibilities” all round, especially insofar as those sensibilities have themselves been formed by the distorted situation of institutionalized disunity.7 There is an aspect of being “Catholic” or “Lutheran” that stands in the same relation to being “one in Christ” as being “slave or free, Jew or Greek, male and female” (Gal 3:28). Not the 5 And, I would argue, different from those of Luther himself, though I cannot make that case here. See my article “Martin Luther on Renewal and Sanctification: Simul Justus et Peccator Revisited,” in Sapere teologico e unità della fede: Studi in onore del Prof. Jared Wicks, eds. Carmen Aparicio Valls, Carmelo Donato, and Gianluigi Pasquale (Rome: Editrice Pontifica Università Gregoriana, 2004), 655–74. 6 See on this Michael Root, “Identity and Difference:The Ecumenical Problem” in Theology in Dialogue: Essays in Conversation with George Lindbeck, ed. Bruce D. Marshall (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), 165–90. For a recent attempt to restate the rationale and goals of classic visible-unity ecumenism, see In One Body Through the Cross:The Princeton Proposal for Christian Unity, eds. Carl E. Braaten and Robert W. Jenson (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2003). 7 Recall here the statement in Unitatis redintegratio, no. 4, that in the wake of Christian divisions, “the Church herself finds it more difficult to express in actual life her full catholicity in all its bearings.” That would seem to suggest the possibility that “Catholic sensibilities” in their present state are not necessarily adequate to the catholicity of the Church. Book Symposium 163 whole of being Catholic or Lutheran, not even every difference of sensibility, is called into question by unity in Christ, but convergence in Christ will not leave us as we are, and it is most likely to be our “sensibilities” that take the brunt of the change. Oppositional self-definition imposes on those who adopt it an imperative to be “distinctive” at all-costs the consequences of which can be both strange and debilitating. R. R. Reno has in a brilliant essay described the dynamic of this debilitation with both Roman Catholic and Protestant illustrations.8 In the Roman Catholic case, he argues that the nowlamented ecclesiological “juridicism” of the post-Reformation period is grounded in the logic of oppositional self-definition. In order to distinguish Roman Catholicism cleanly from the Protestant “other,” it became necessary to center Roman Catholic identity on features of Roman Catholic life not shared with Protestants (or the Orthodox), which turned out to be most clearly the papacy and the institutional and legal structures that bound the Roman Catholic Church to the papacy. Commenting on the late nineteenth-century fundamental theology of John Brunsmann, Reno writes: Brunsmann’s analysis shifts the focus or Roman Catholic theology and ecclesial life away from the primary apostolic tradition (because that which is shared is unable to identify the church), and in so doing, greases the skids toward cultural captivity.The power of jurisdiction is easily assimilated to the logic of modern bureaucracies: commercial, military, and governmental.Thus at the very moment that the Roman Catholic Church is clearly distinguished from all other churches, it blurs into the landscape of modern life. Reno is not suggesting that Catholics should surrender what they believe to be true about the right order of the Church; the issue is rather the consequences of defining Roman Catholic identity in this way rather than, say, by reference to the faith of the Apostles’ Creed. In our present context, juridicism is not the issue, nor is my purpose a general criticism of post-Reformation Roman Catholic thought. Indeed, I would willingly stipulate that the outworking of the same dynamic in Protestantism has brought about far more abject forms of cultural captivity than Roman juridicism. I draw attention rather to the pattern Reno describes, because I suspect that the dynamic of oppositional self-definition has weakened our authors’ proposal in a very different but perhaps isomorphic way. 8 R.R. Reno, “The Debilitation of the Churches,” in The Ecumenical Future, eds. Carl E. Braaten and Robert W. Jenson (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2004), 46–72. 164 Book Symposium It is, at any rate, rather disappointing when “what’s Catholic about Catholic biblical scholarship” turns out to be that “to be Catholic is to think inclusively rather than exclusively,” to “tend toward the ‘both/and’ rather than the ‘either/or’ ” (5). Can “being Catholic” in biblical scholarship really be summed up in a formula so bland and empty of content? Is this formula really expressive of the heart and soul of Roman Catholicism, of what makes liturgy and devotion and public witness and the lives of the saints and martyrs tick? Or is this formula not rather drastically overdetermined by the imperative of distinguishing Catholics from the Protestant-historicist other, in the context of a scholarly field in which substantive agendas very often come disguised as methodological axioms? And could not a case be made that this “methodologism” is itself a significant cause of the theological vacuity in biblical studies, that is, of the very problem the authors are attempting to address? Reno suggests that in defining ourselves over against other Christians, we lose the power of distinguishing ourselves from the world around us, “greasing the skids toward cultural captivity.” I wonder if we cannot see the beginnings of such a slide in Professor Johnson’s proposals, in chapter 5, for a retrieval of elements of pre-critical exegesis.Amidst much that is insightful in that chapter, there are some jarring notes. For example: People act on the basis of the imagined world in which they dwell. By acting on what they imagine, they help establish their worlds as real. . . . [T]hose who act on the basis of the world Scripture imagines . . . make it less ‘imaginary’ and more ‘real.’ . . . Living in any of these imaginary worlds requires a fundamental acceptance of its premises, an adjustment of vision according to its perceptions, and a decision to act as though these premises and perceptions were not only real but valid. Because Scripture imagines the world in which we live and move as having its source and meaning in an Other who enables us to move and live, we are able to perceive the world this way and decide to live according to this premise. So perceiving and so acting, we incrementally transform the world imagined by Scripture into the physical world in which we live and move. (121–22) It is of course true that Scripture calls us to a new way of imagining the world. But there is a great difference between an imagined world and an imaginary one. What are we to make of the notion that we “make” the scriptural world “less ‘imaginary’ and more ‘real’ ” when we “decide” to act “as though its premises were not only real but valid.” Can we really imagine any premodern exegete speaking of the Scriptures as providing an “imaginary world” which it is our task to make “more real”? Surely the Book Symposium 165 classic view was that of John Henry Newman,“that we are in a world of mystery, with one bright Light before us, sufficient for our proceeding forward through all difficulties.” Take away this Light, and we are utterly wretched—we know not where we are, how we are sustained, what will become of us, and of all that is dear to us, what we are to believe, and why we are in being. But with it we have all and abound.9 For Newman and the tradition, we do not make the scriptural world real; Scripture sets forth to us the reality of the world to which our foolish minds have been darkened by sin (Rom 1:21). The scriptural world is antecedently the real world; Scripture itself is the lamp whose light shows us the reality with which we have to do, so that we do not crash and burn on its hard surfaces and sharp corners. Professor Johnson himself has described this classic view quite well in his descriptive account of premodern exegesis, one of whose premises is “that the Bible, as the Word of God, is authoritative” (55), which means that readers are to view Scripture as “a text that can reveal the mind of God” (56). But surely when the mind of God is revealed to us, we are not presented with imaginative possibilities that we are then called to “make more real,” but with the bedrock of reality itself. Johnson describes his talk of Scripture’s imaginary world as “postmodern,” and he is undoubtedly correct in this. But just how is postmodernism more properly “Catholic” than modernism? Reno’s pattern begins to seem uncomfortably pertinent: By defining himself contrastively over against Protestant modernism, has Professor Johnson “greased the skids” toward a captivity in which “Catholic,” remarkably enough, turns out to coincide with a now culturally acceptable soft postmodernism?10 Doubtless I am again overstating as regards Professor Johnson’s own intentions. But again, the rhetoric has consequences. Having adopted a 9 John Henry Newman, “Mysteries in Religion,” in Parochial and Plain Sermons (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987), 361. 10 “Soft” in the meritorious sense that it resists following the logic of postmod- ernism to its violent conclusion, in which there can be only more or less regulated warfare between different ways of imagining the world. For a critique of postmodernism, see David Bentley Hart, The Beauty of the Infinite:The Aesthetics of Christian Truth (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2003), part 1.An Orthodox with an uncommonly generous attitude to the Western Christian tradition, Hart offers much in this book that could be brought fruitfully to bear on questions of biblical interpretation, if those questions are framed at a properly theological and metaphysical level. 166 Book Symposium postmodernist stance, is it really possible to indwell the scriptural world? Despite its anti-metaphysical pretensions, does not postmodernism already carry with it its own construal of the world as a “darkling plain, where ignorant armies clash by night”? Can we genuinely live in a world that we regard as an imaginary construct that we are to make real? Or are we not as postmodernists always already living somewhere else, in the implied empty space from which we look out upon the scriptural world and decide to live “as though” it were real? Will the postmodernist starting point therefore not inevitably perpetuate “the greatest difficulty our generation has in doing theology . . . our distance from the imaginative world of Scripture” (122)? Another closely related critical point needs to be made. As mentioned at the beginning, the authors define their Catholic approach against what they take to be a single other, made up indiscriminately of Protestantism and historical-critical rationalism.That they would see things in this way is rendered immediately understandable by Professor Johnson’s insightful description of American Catholic biblical scholars as “immigrants” to a “world of scholarship previously inhabited by Protestants” (11). Catholic scholars entering into the mainline biblical disciplines, first after Divino Afflante Spiritu, and then in increasing numbers after Vatican II, would of course feel themselves to be in a “Protestant” world, where issues were framed and professional identity defined in terms of three centuries of conflict over historical criticism in the Protestant communions. Nevertheless, by thus collapsing Protestantism into modernism, the authors fail, I believe, to describe clearly the cultural politics out of which the present situation in biblical studies has emerged, and therefore have not assessed quite accurately the strategic situation in which theology, including biblical scholarship, finds itself today. The authors tell the story of the relationship between Protestantism and historical criticism exactly as Protestant historical critics have liked to tell it; it is the winners’ version, the story as told by the modernist victors in the great Protestant ecclesiastical and academic battles over the Bible. In that narrative, there is a straight line between Luther and, say, Wellhausen or Bultmann. Released from ecclesiastical tyranny, the study of the Bible was liberated to become Wissenschaft; and the sola scriptura mandates that such “scientific” study of the biblical texts become the basis for a reconstruction of the Christian religion to which, in principle, no limits can be set.The plausibility of this picture depends, however, upon resolutely ignoring the period between the Reformation and the Enlightenment, and in particular ignoring the biblical interpretation of that period, which is, in fact, hardly ever studied, particularly from a theo- Book Symposium 167 logical angle of interest. One could not tell from reading most standard histories, for example, that one of the most significant biblical scholars in Germany at the beginning of the eighteenth century was the Pietist August Herman Francke (1662–1727), who combined philological expertise with the lifelong hermeneutical project of a unified Christocentric reading of the whole Bible, not only in the dogmatic mode promoted by confessional controversy, but also as a spiritually transformative enterprise.11 My point here is neither to defend nor to commend precritical Protestant exegesis, though I do consider it a shame that it has been allowed to fall so completely down the memory hole.The point is rather that by accepting the standard narrative, Johnson and Kurz have not seen clearly enough that historical-critical biblical scholarship, as it exists today, is not simply a Protestant phenomenon, but a synthesis of Protestant motifs with something else, with the secularism that arose in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries as a reaction to a lamentable joint “achievement” of Catholics and Protestants, the physical and moral devastation of Europe by the wars of religion. Secularism, as John Milbank and others have described it, was the cultural and political construction of a world in which Christianity was defined as “religion,” inward and private, and thus banished from the public realm, where it was deemed to have proven itself incurably destructive.12 Such a project could not succeed without breaking down the precritical tradition of scriptural exegesis in which Scripture was read, in Ephraim Radner’s terms, as “the providential exponent of the world’s divine order.”13 The modern secularity project was not a demonic upsurge of incomprehensible hostility to the faith; it was in large measure the attempt of 11 See August Herman Francke, Schriften und Predigten, Band 4: Schriften zur biblis- chen Hermeneutik I, ed. Erhard Peschke (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2003). For insightful reflection on early-modern Anglican exegesis, see Ephraim Radner, Hope among the Fragments:The Broken Church and its Engagement with Scripture (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos, 2004), 79–108. 12 See John Milbank, Theology and Social Theory: Beyond Secular Reason (Oxford: Blackwell’s, 1990). This book is the classic description of secular rationality as a deliberate cultural construct, though Milbank tends to reduce history to the history of ideas and thus misses the crucial relationship between the public fact of ecclesial schism and the rise of modern secularism, presenting the latter as though it were simply an organic outgrowth of late medieval voluntarism. On the way in which this problem plays out in Milbank’s very problematic constructive proposals, see R. R. Reno,“The Radical Orthodoxy Project,” in idem, In the Ruins of the Church: Sustaining Faith in an Age of Diminished Certitude (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos, 2002), 63–79. 13 Radner, Hope among the Fragments, 103. 168 Book Symposium decent minds to cope with the chaos public Christianity had wrought in the wake of the Reformation.The incapacity of Christians to live together in charity in the biblical world subverted the cultural plausibility of that world and motivated the urgency with which the secularist project strove to get the Bible under control.14 Indeed, precisely in order to liberate their faith from complicity in violence and murder, Christians of all ecclesiastical parties took part in the establishment of the secular culture, in which “religion” would be private, and secular rationality firmly in charge of the public square. The historical-critical movement cannot be understood apart from its ideological roots in secularist thinkers like Hobbes and Spinoza, but scholars in the churches (mostly, but not only, Protestants) took up both the critical challenge and much of the ideological motivation of these great skeptics in the interests of producing a “purified” Christianity, that is, one that limited its claims to the proper sphere of “religion,” the moral and spiritual life of the inner person.15 The pertinence of these remarks to the hermeneutical enterprise of Professors Johnson and Kurz is twofold. First, I would suggest that we cannot re-enter the scriptural world from which we are all in various 14 This motivation is placed squarely on the table by Spinoza in chapter 7 of the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus: “Ambition and unscrupulousness have waxed so powerful, that religion is thought to consist, not so much in respecting the writings of the Holy Ghost, as in defending human commentaries, so that religion is no longer identified with charity, but with spreading discord and propagating insensate hatred disguised under the name of zeal for the Lord, and eager ardor.” Trans. R. H. M. Elwes (New York: Dover Books, 1951). Such terms appearing in 1670 have very specific and bloody referents. 15 On the Catholic side, while Richard Simon’s motivations continue to be controversial, his work and its reception cannot be understood except in the politicalreligious context of the late seventeenth century. Some of the issues about Simon are raised and a sense of his context is communicated by Justin I. A. Champion, “ ‘Acceptable to inquisitive men’: Some Simonian contexts for Newton’s Biblical Criticism, 1680–1692” (www.rhbnc.ac.uk/~uhra026/simon1.html), and idem, “Pere Richard Simon and English Biblical Criticism, 1680–1700” (www.rhbnc.ac.uk/~uhra026/simon2.html).Though Professor Johnson is rather dismissive of the role of Spinoza and Simon (15, note 16), they were in fact important influences on the German developments to which he points. For example, Simon’s Histoire Critique was published in German in 1776, with preface and notes by Johann Salamo Semler (1725–1791), among the most significant figures in the rise of German historical criticism. Spinoza too had a profound influence in Germany, especially by way of the notorious Pantheism Controversy of the 1780s. Spinoza’s apparent influence on Lessing is testimony enough to his importance for the development of German Protestant biblical scholarship, given Lessing’s immense role in framing the questions that dominated (and in some ways still dominate) that scholarly tradition. Book Symposium 169 ways estranged without facing head-on the issue of secularism. Bluntly put, are we ready to reckon straightforwardly with divine providence as a factor shaping the real world, just as surely as we reckon with the law of supply and demand or the force of gravity? As a recent study by R. R. Reno and John J. O’Keefe makes abundantly clear,16 faith in divine providence is at the heart of the classical Christian engagement with Scripture, that one providence that has enfolded the whole world in an “oikonomia for the fullness of the times, to recapitulate all things in Christ, things in heaven and things on earth” (Eph 1:10), and has likewise designed in the literary “economy” of the scriptural canon an unsurpassably rich representation of the Christologically centered order of reality. Thus St. Irenaeus of Lyons, who laid out more clearly than anyone else in the patristic period the theological contours of the common Christian exegetical tradition, writes: Anyone who reads the Scriptures with attention will find in them a discourse about Christ, and a prefiguration of the new calling.17 For Christ is “the treasure hidden in the field” (Mt 13:44), that is, in this world (for “the field is the world,” Mt 13:38), but he is also hidden in the Scriptures, since he was signified by types and parables which could not be understood, humanly speaking, before the consummation of those things which were prophesied as coming, that is, the advent of Christ.18 St. Irenaeus here captures precisely the understanding of the relationship between Scripture and reality that is operative in the whole premodern Christian theological tradition. Christ is the treasure hidden in the world, the world’s secret meaning, the one in whom God intends in the mystery of his will to “recapitulate all things.” That world-ordering “economy” is mirrored and revealed in the complex literary economy of Holy Scripture, in the providentially designed interconnections of the whole with the parts and of the parts with one another as they converge on the skopos, Jesus Christ, the one toward whom both Scripture and reality move. Professor Johnson describes quite clearly the theological premises that led Christians of the past to treat the Bible as an utterly singular book, taking its divine authorship as a reality with which interpreters must reckon in very concrete and practical ways (47–60). But in his subsequent reflection on these premises (60–63), he does not really address their challenge as truth-claims, as assertions about what is the case. By taking the 16 John J. O’Keefe and R. R. Reno, Sanctified Vision: An Introduction to Early Christ- ian Interpretation of the Bible (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 2005). 17 That is, of the gentiles. 18 Irenaeus, Against Heresies, IV, 26, 1. 170 Book Symposium postmodernist route, he effectually transforms these premises into imaginative possibilities rather than claims about the real world. Ever since Auerbach, however, it has been a commonplace of the literary study of the Bible that the Scriptures do not present their world to us as simply an imaginative possibility:“The Scripture stories do not, like Homer’s, court our favor, they do not flatter us that they may please us and enchant us— they seek to subject us, and if we refuse to be subjected we are rebels.”19 I do not therefore believe that there is any way to ease ourselves into the scriptural world by a postmodernist side door; one does not enter that world by deciding to act “as though” it were real, but rather by acknowledging the hand and voice of God in particular present, public phenomena. Catholics and Lutherans, at least, are familiar with the idea of acknowledging God’s public “real presence” in worship, but we need to think through more explicitly what would be involved, and how drastic a break with the scholarly norms of our public culture would be required, were we to approach Scripture with the Fathers as a divinely authored book.20 The other issue raised by my remarks on secularism has to do with Christian unity. The inability of European Christians to live together in peace within the scriptural world was the most potent factor that brought the Bible into public discredit in the early modern period. I would suggest that we will not overcome our estrangement from the Scriptures until we find them gathering us together from our divisions into unity in Christ—until we submit to the power of the Holy Spirit who strives through the Scriptures to bring us all into communion under the rule of the one Christ. Scripture must reassert its power to order the world at the point at which it once lost that power, by and through the reconciliation of Christians under one Lord in one shared scriptural world. No more than anyone else can I offer a “roadmap” to Christian unity. I am convinced however that if we define ourselves contrastively right from the start, if we accept our divisions as one of the premises of our enterprise, and so construe the theological-exegetical task that our own 19 Eric Auerbach, Mimesis:The Representation of Reality in Western Literature (Prince- ton: Princeton University Press, 1953), 15. 20 Writing in a Thomist journal, I should perhaps say that while there is certainly a metaphysical aspect of the encounter with secularism, it cannot stand alone. Indeed, it may be that the loss of a “scriptural mind” in the modern Church is one of the reasons Thomist philosophy has not had the culture-transforming effects at which it has aimed. Philosophical refutations of secularism do not by themselves teach people how to live in a non-secular universe; in the Christian tradition, the latter was precisely the task of scriptural interpretation. Book Symposium 171 identities and “sensibilities” are protected from disturbance, we will not find our way into the real world that Scripture sets before us. I do not, let me repeat, advocate compromises of truth; but though the truth is not up for grabs, we ourselves must be ready to die to our present “identities” if we are to inhabit the scriptural universe where Christ is Lord. I suspect therefore that entering again into the scriptural world will involve for us far greater humiliation, the experience of a far greater disorientation, the confession of a far more profound ignorance, than anything postmodernism is equipped to imagine. It will not be a matter of deciding to make the scriptural world real, but rather a realization in the presence of the scriptural Christ that we are not only blind, but unreal—like the shades in C. S. Lewis’s Great Divorce, who find that even on the distant outskirts of the City of God, the very grass underfoot is so much more solid than they that it hurts their feet to walk upon it. What Christian unity would look like, what we ourselves would look like as inhabitants of a shared scriptural universe, is impossible to say in advance of arrival. But the starting point and road forward have been pointed out with great clarity by the Holy Father, in words that have the greatest relevance to the necessary reformation (if I may be permitted the word) of theology and the study of Scripture alike: All of us who are Christ’s followers must therefore meet and unite around him. . . .We can and must immediately reach and display to the world our unity in proclaiming the mystery of Christ, in revealing the divine dimension and also the human dimension of the Redemption, and in struggling with unwearying perseverance for the dignity that each human being has reached and can continually reach in Christ.21 Due to limitations of space, I have not been able to balance my criticisms with due appreciation of the many excellent features of this book. I should not however like to leave unmentioned Professor Johnson’s forthright and cogent critique of contemporary “establishment” biblical studies, Professor Kurz’s illuminating readings of the Gospel of John, and the example both authors set of amicable discourse within a shared scriptural universe on the part of two rather different Roman Catholics—an ecumenical achievement in its own right. Despite my criticisms, Professors Johnson and Kurz are moving the conversation about biblical interpretaN&V tion in the right direction, and for that they deserve our thanks. 21 Pope John Paul II, Redemptor Hominis, no. 11. 172 Book Symposium Conversation, Conversion, and Construction L UKE T IMOTHY J OHNSON Emory University Atlanta, Georgia I T IS IN A SPIRIT of gratitude that I respond to the five essays that colleagues have written as part of the constructive conversation concerning the future of Catholic biblical scholarship. Bill Kurz and I recognize that the efforts of Michael Dauphinais and Matthew Levering have already played a significant role in making our book a part of this conversation. We are grateful for this issue of Nova et Vetera dedicated to the topic, as well as for the lengthy and positive review by Jody Vaccaro Lewis already published in its pages. The experience of this symposium also recalls for me the colloquium on the book that Thomas Levergood and the Lumen Christi Institute organized at the University of Chicago Divinity School on April 26, 2003. At that session, Bill and I had a chance to “extend and amend” the positions we had taken in the book, and heard vigorous responses from Gary Anderson, Carolyn Osiek, and Paul Griffiths.We learned on that occasion that by no means did all Catholic scholars agree either with our diagnosis or with our proposed remedies.The lack of unanimous praise and universal plaudit dismayed us less than it might have, for the tone of that conversation was civil, and the conversation was indeed constructive. We can scarcely complain if readers actually respond with what we said we wanted! The same sense of gratitude extends to the work of the five colleagues who wrote essays for this journal. We understand the generosity it requires to enter into projects other than one’s own, and are impressed by the energy and seriousness of the essays. Not only do they raise important issues, they do so in the same spirit of collegial conversation that we had hoped would mark this entire enterprise. Some respondents (as well as reviewers) have noted the ways in which Bill and I differ on significant points, if not in substance, surely in emphasis and style. This is no surprise to either of us, for we have genially been disagreeing in perfect amity for many years. Indeed, we both regard such pluralism of perspective—within an even deeper commitment to common faith and practice—to be thoroughly catholic in character. Equally important, we do not regard our individual or common “correctness” to be at all the point.The point is rather the cultivation of a conversation that will bear fruit for the passionate and prophetic reading of God’s Word within the church and for the world. Bill and I have Book Symposium 173 not, therefore, consulted or collaborated in our essays of response, and may, characteristically, go in several different directions. I will respond individually to the essays in the order in which they reached me (this is the “conversation” part of my title), and then add some thoughts on “conversion and construction.” The Text of the Bible and Catholic Biblical Scholarship Stephen D. Ryan, OP, helpfully identifies four issues pertaining to the text of Scripture that present significant challenges to scholarship within the church. Three of the issues touch on the question of what we actually regard as Scripture. What is the status of the Septuagint, of multiple editions of the same book, of the early versions? If biblical scholarship were simply something carried out in the academy, these complexities would only represent the delights of literary and historical study. The scholar can embrace them all. But if biblical scholarship is in and for and by the church, then difficult decisions must be made, and these decisions are of an ecclesial and theological character, rather than of a literary and historical character. Ryan is certainly on the right track when he suggests that the fundamental ecclesial decision is made at the level of canonization, and that what is canonized is a book rather than a form of the text. He is also surely correct that inspiration must be connected to the work of the Holy Spirit in the entire process of composition, tradition, and reading, rather than in the production of a single, putatively original, form of the text—and that the plurality of texts and versions help the church avoid “enlightenment forms of biblical literalism.” And it is impossible not to agree that maintaining a role for early biblical versions safeguards the ecumenical catholicity of the church, enabling it to sustain conversation across the centuries with earlier saints and scholars. Still, even more discernment is necessary, and it is my hope that Catholic scholars will be able to encourage and participate positively in these properly ecclesial and theological conversations. Most important, I think, is the question of the status of the Septuagint in the life of the church. Should it be regarded simply as another version? Here, the use of the Septuagint by the New Testament, and by one continuous tradition within Christianity (Orthodoxy), would seem to give it special status. Ryan’s report on the complexity of the Old Testament textual history only makes the issue more urgent. It is, moreover, a question that cannot be settled by textual critics as such, for the issues are not merely textual, but are ecclesial and theological. 174 Book Symposium The issue, after all, is not simply whether Christians should have access to the readings of the Septuagint as a means of enrichment; it is whether the Septuagint should have first claim to be regarded as the Christian Old Testament, with the authority in ecclesial and theological debates that goes with such status. Precisely here is where a scholarship of and for the church makes a difference. I have already applauded the sentiments expressed by Ryan in his final paragraph. But I would like to make a distinction between two things that he apparently treats as one. He speaks of maintaining the versions alongside the original texts “in the liturgical and intellectual life of the church.” Concerning the last, I am in full agreement. There is every reason within the academy to keep diversity alive without discrimination, because the point of such scholarship is knowledge. When it comes to the “liturgical,” however, we are in a realm other than the scholar’s study where parallel texts can endlessly be compared and weighed; we are in the realm of ritual performance and spiritual transformation. In this realm, a pluralism of texts may do more harm than good. This is why a decision about the scriptural status, inspiration, and authority of the Septuagint would make a profound difference, for a positive decision would (could? should?) lead logically to the use of a translation from the Septuagint for the Old Testament readings in liturgical celebrations. I do not pretend to know whether such a conclusion would be appropriate or not, but I am convinced that conversation about the grounds even of our present liturgical practice with respect to Scripture is necessary. Such are the quaestiones disputatae that Ryan’s essay introduces. They are genuine questions. They should be actively discussed and disputed within a biblical scholarship concerned not only for the advancement of learning but for the theological life of the church. “La Bible en ses Traditions” One could scarcely imagine a response to the book more positive or generous than that offered by Olivier-Thomas Venard, OP, especially since he engages the conversation from the perspective of a project already in process. Rather than defensively state, as he might have done, “but everything you call for, we are already doing,” he has rather entered into the spirit of a collegial effort by presenting the recasting of the Bible de Jerusalem, in which he is involved, as a “fourth-generation enterprise,” and one that seeks truly to be a form of biblical scholarship in service to the life of the church. By so doing, he and his colleagues at the École Biblique truly do walk in the footsteps of their “founder and inspirer,” Père LaGrange. There are many specific aspects of the project that deserve a full and positive response. I state here only my appreciation for the way in which Book Symposium 175 not only the “world that made the Bible” (background) finds a place in the notes, but even more, “the world that the Bible made.” The place given to the versions, to textual variants as part of the history of reception, and to moments in the interpretive tradition—in liturgy and doctrine as well as in commentaries—is impressive. Both in the design of its pages and in its contents, the project does resemble a “Christian Talmud.” It is perhaps also worth observing that the project seeks a way of honoring the multiple editions and versions and text traditions to which Ryan refers in his essay. The sensibility brought to the translation and notes on language are also impressive. I agree that the rhetorical and poetic dimensions of the biblical text are as important to celebrate as its historical referents. And Venard’s example from his work on Matthew shows how a creative struggle with the original language not only opens up new possibilities of meaning, but also deeply suggestive intertextual connections (as in the nuances of seed/word in the Gospels of Matthew and John). I don’t know how well it will work in practice, but Venard’s vision of a collegial effort in annotation, with a main author receiving feedback and helpful leads from experts in fields other than the author’s own, is an attractive ideal. Even as I see this project as making concrete so many of the ideas expressed in our book, I would prefer to see it as an aspect, even an important one, of a renewed Catholic biblical scholarship rather than as the full or necessary expression of that renewal. My caution is connected entirely to the fact that the Bible de Jerusalem is not only a book, but a long series of books, that will appear in full only after “15, 30, or 60 years.”The time lapse is not worrisome, but the monumental character of the project is. Now, given the ambitious ideals of the authors, and given the number of biblical books, and given the natural tendency of scholarship to expand, there is no avoiding the fact that the new Bible de Jerusalem, if carried out as Venard describes, will be a “monument.” And there are plusses and minuses attached to all such monuments. On the positive side, a monumental publication embodies in an impressive form the values to which it ascribes; there can be no mistaking a commitment to the history of interpretation when it forms such a prominent feature of a multi-volume work. Such a sprawling publication can also provide a fine framework for the study of others, placing at the disposal of less learned readers the riches of scholarly research, in a format that emphasizes the reciprocal and dialogical relationship among the original text and the reception of it in the church. As such, the work can serve to invite others into the conversation that it enables. On the negative side, such monumental ventures, simply because of their size and 176 Book Symposium impressive erudition, might be taken as having already accomplished the interpretive conversation and packaged it for readers. It is very difficult to break out of the package, once it has been completed. Similarly, anthologies devoted to “Rabbinic Tradition” and “Patristic Thought” both have the same liability: They can seduce those who do not know such traditions firsthand into thinking that they have actually engaged those realms, when in fact they have only been exposed to a small portion of it, not on its own terms, but as selected by the biblical passage under discussion. Despite the limitations and dangers of a publication so monumental, it deserves recognition and support, not only for the values it espouses and seeks to realize, but because the process of writing and publication devoted to such values will itself have a transforming effect on the scholars who are involved, and a transforming effect on their students, and through them have the possibility of transforming the church. A Future of Balance and Proportion Frank J. Matera embraces the theme of “both/and” in Catholic biblical scholarship and develops it according to four topics. By so doing, he illustrates precisely the very balance and proportion that we would all like to consider a distinctively, if by no means uniquely, Catholic sensibility. Before responding to his major observations, with which I substantially agree, I want briefly to address the possible implications of two opening statements. First, he suggests that Bill and I each had “a single formula” with which to address the present situation. I would resist that characterization, as I think Bill would as well. Certainly I do not think that engagement with patristic and medieval interpreters is alone sufficient or can stand apart from all the other dimensions of recovering a scriptural imagination that I sketch in my first and fifth chapter. Second, Father Matera says that his social location within a Catholic University may make him naïve as to what is happening elsewhere and “more sanguine about the present situation of Catholic biblical scholarship.” I can see ways in which that can be so, but I caution against an inference that working within a Catholic university automatically ensures the sort of balance and proportion in scholarship that he advocates. Each of Father Matera’s categories opens an important and difficult arena of conversation, none more difficult or important than the relation between history and theology, both in general and with respect to the interpretation of Scripture. It is a topic too vast and complex to take on in this brief response. But briefly, I agree that an understanding of the historical circumstances giving rise to texts can be important, and in Book Symposium 177 general subscribe to the proposition that the more history we know the better and more responsible readers we can be. There is, to be sure, an important distinction between doing history in order better to understand and engage the texts, and manipulating the texts in order to do history. This is the bone I picked with the quest for the historical Jesus, which in some versions was content to deconstruct the Gospel compositions in order to reconstruct Jesus. Although I recognize the value of “historical correction and clarification,” I think it would be an exaggeration to say that it is always sufficient or helpful. Rightly, then, Father Matera puts the theological element in the texts in balance with the historical.As he points out, there is not much history in the Gospel infancy accounts, but there is much theology. Here again, though, we must also recognize that there are cases when the “theology” of a text itself needs to be challenged. But most of all, I want to issue the reminder that between history and theology is the literary texture, the rhetoric of the text itself.The failure to take the New Testament writings seriously enough as literary compositions, and to engage them at that level, has tended to distort the doing both of history and theology. The relationship between the “theologies” and “theology of the Bible” is equally vexed. I agree with Matera that contemporary scholars have done a better job of describing the “theological voice” (my own phrase) of the respective biblical compositions than they have at addressing the ways in which those voices join in a unified chorus.To describe the theological voice—or worse, the “theology,” as if it were a set thing±of a specific writing, however, is not yet necessarily to engage that voice theologically, to struggle not only with its meaning but also with its claims to truth. Biblical scholars have largely resisted that task, preferring the more modest exercise of description. It is not entirely clear, moreover, how the descriptive exercise can move to that more dialogical (even agonistic) one. This is the real, and as yet largely unmet, challenge to those of us who wish to read Scripture theologically. It is in this light that I am also cautious concerning the “theology of the New Testament” or “theology of the Bible.” My remarks here anticipate my response to Professor Hays below. I like Father Matera’s formulation,“Searching for the unity of Scripture is another way of searching for God.” Exactly. But just as the search for God is not a matter of tying all the elements of the world together in a final and satisfying whole, but is rather a process of engaging each dimension of the world that is thematically given while at the deepest level also responding to the one who is never thematically available as the world is, so the quest for the unity of Scripture is best carried out, I think, athematically, or extra-thematically. 178 Book Symposium I agree, therefore, that one extreme to be avoided is the fragmentation of Scripture into a loose assemblage of ancient writings that are read, each one, only with reference to their original historical settings. But I ask whether we need to construct and make explicit the ways in which all these writings, gathered into a single collection through canonization, can converse with each other, and with all the centuries of their readers, in a single, complex conversation that is, from beginning to end, revelatory. Does the effort to fix those points of unity—especially when it is done in books—not tend inevitably to suppress elements of diversity within the voices, and worse, render static what works best precisely as a dynamic element in canonical reading? Father Matera correctly notes that the question of the relation of Old Testament to the New is analogous to the question of theologies/theology. He is further correct in noting that the question of the Christian Bible is made more acute by the ecumenical recognition of the Hebrew Bible as the Scripture of the Jewish people. On this question, I want to make only three brief points. First, as with the question of “New Testament Theology,” I consider the best approach to be not through the construction of a single systematic biblical theology but through enabling and enlivening the multiple and complex conversations that can take place among all the compositions of Scripture. The model for such conversation, in fact, is found in creative preaching on lectionary texts. Second, the question of the unity of the Scriptures and the character of the “Christian Bible” once more presses us to consider the role of the Septuagint as the Christian Old Testament. Third, as an example of “balance and proportion,” the consideration of the two testaments must give due consideration both to the compositional voice of the respective Old Testament texts in the own right, and to the ways in which the appropriation of those texts by the New Testament represents for Christians a privileged though not exhaustive reading of them. With regard to Matera’s final category, the balance is far easier to state than it is to realize.The kind of deep loyalty and critical engagement that I think should characterize an ecclesial biblical scholarship has to resist, on one side, an anti-intellectualism and suspicion of scholarship among many in the church, including some leaders, and on the other side, an academic environment that sometimes holds itself aloof from the concerns of faith communities, and sometimes is even hostile to those concerns. At the same time, those seeking that middle ground of critical loyalty must acknowledge the partial validity of the extreme positions. They recognize that not every reading of Scripture must be mediated through experts, and that experts have often done little to nurture the life Book Symposium 179 of faith, even as they also recognize that the life of the mind can legitimately have disinterested moments and that not all learning needs to have an immediately obvious pragmatic or pastoral yield. I will try to say a few more words on this subject in my closing subject, but I want to basically agree with Matera that the balance (which may be collegial and reciprocal rather than necessarily located in each scholar at every moment) is the ideal, however difficult it is to achieve. Re-Entering the Scriptural World Some considerable delicacy is required in my response to the essays so generously contributed by two Protestant colleagues, just as considerable delicacy was required of them to make those contributions to a conversation that was from the beginning a call to Catholics to consider what they were about when they studied Scripture. Both Professor David S. Yeago and Professor Richard B. Hays say positive things about the book, for which I am grateful. Perhaps understandably, they are also more critical in their review of our efforts. And to some extent, they touch on the same or very similar points. Some of my response to Yeago, therefore, will also serve as a response to Hays. Although Bill also used some of the same language, I clearly am the main target for both reviewers’ criticism of what they regard as a polarizing Protestant/Catholic language. My rhetoric is regarded as hostile, inaccurate, and an affront to a proper ecumenical spirit. Some time spent examining if not salving this sore spot may therefore be appropriate. First, let me hasten to admit that this sort of rhetoric, which as Professor Yeago notes, has as its goal a certain identity formation, always involves, as Hays observes, a certain amount of stereotyping. I am as aware as my colleagues that Luther and Calvin read Scripture within a theological framework very different than that of David Strauss and F. C. Baur. And I know, as they do, that the difference was the way in which enlightenment principles were at work in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries in a way they were not in the sixteenth century. I am aware that Wesley and Pietists had strong doctrines of sanctification. So let me take their respective corrections concerning overstatement and oversimplification as read. But having acknowledged the oversimplification of my language, I want to point out that the intention of the contrast I drew was to have Catholic biblical scholars look to what precious aspects of their own tradition they may have too quickly abandoned, rather than to criticize Protestant scholars for being consistent with their own theological principles. Professor Yeago can object to the strategy of identification by 180 Book Symposium contrast, but in the present case, I not only think it was appropriate, I find it hard to conceive how else the necessary points could be made. Although I agree, furthermore, that the historical-critical approach was, from the nineteenth century forward, a quintessential project of modernity, driven by enlightenment premises, I do not think it a caricature (to use Professsor Hays’s term) to observe that a not inconsiderable amount of Protestant theology—in particular the Protestant theology most comfortable with critical biblical scholarship—over this same span of time was equally affected by modernity. E. Brooks Holifield has masterfully demonstrated the point in his Theology in America (Yale University Press, 2003). Within critical NT scholarship, it is not inaccurate to observe that an insistence on the literal sense rather than the figurative, a consistent application of sachkritik—not least with regard to those writings thought to be “catholic” in their tendencies, and a privileging of origins over development, are not derived so much from enlightenment historiography as from specifically Protestant convictions. By no means am I the first to point this out. In the book, I make reference to two Jewish scholars, Jon Levenson and Jonathan Z. Smith, who have explicitly spoken of “protestant presuppositions” within critical biblical scholarship, as a way of locating a preoccupation with history as the vehicle of theology on one side (Levenson), and a privileging of origins over development on the other (Smith). Such designations, furthermore, are not a matter of bias.They are derived from Protestant scholars themselves. In his Drudgery Divine (University of Chicago Press, 1990), Smith massively documented the use of the phrase “pagano-papism” by Protestant scholars. A superficial survey would quickly show how even recent Protestant theologians such as Paul Tillich could use the phrase “Protestant Principle” precisely as an instrument to reject tendencies regarded as specifically Roman Catholic (see, e.g.,Tillich, Systematic Theology I, 37, 227; III, 176). If Professors Yeago and Hays are (understandably) sensitive to Protestant scholarship being made to appear as a foil for the positive presentation of a Catholic scholarship, I would ask them to place themselves in the position of Roman Catholic scholars who have, from their first initiation into critical New Testament scholarship, been schooled to regard development as a decline from the truth of the Gospel, if not its actual distortion, and to regard “early Catholicism” as the best way to characterize such development.The reason I quoted Hans von Campenhausen on this point in the book (20, note 21) is that he was the first author Bill and I were assigned to read in our first month of Ph.D. study at Yale. In short, if I stipulate that my rhetorical rendering of the Protestant principles in historical-critical scholarship is lacking nuance, I would ask Book Symposium 181 whether Professor Yeago would be willing to stipulate that it does not, in fact, lack substance. Further, I would ask whether Protestant biblical scholars might not usefully engage in a similar exercise to the one Bill and I have suggested for Catholic scholars: If the privileging of origins— to take one example—is not intrinsic to Protestant Christianity, then it can be asked why it has played such a key role; if it is intrinsic and even essential to the Protestant way of being Christian, then ought it not to be embraced and celebrated, as this tradition’s distinctive gift within a broader ecumenical conversation? Having spent so much space on this question, I must too briefly respond to a number of other provocative and important points raised by Professor Yeago. On the issue of ecumenism, I have reread my statements on this carefully, and think they represent exactly my position as well as my disposition. I also stand by the substantial accuracy of my statement that a Catholic “cannot find in Paul’s language about justification by faith the same depth of significance that Lutheran scholars do. Reformed readers cannot appreciate Paul’s language about sanctification in the same manner as Catholics.” Professor Yeago refers to official ecumenical treaties. I am talking about deep cultural realities. Is my statement prescriptive? No. Is it descriptively accurate? I think so, and have had that view strengthened over and over in (ecumenically populated) doctoral seminars on Pauline letters, as well as in Bible study sessions (more than I can remember) in Catholic, Lutheran, Presbyterian, and Methodist congregations. Finally, Professor Yeago poses two interrelated questions concerning my phrase “imagining the world that Scripture imagines.”With Professor Hays, he wonders whether I inhabit that world or not. Intellectual honesty requires me to respond that I don’t, certainly not in the manner that patristic and medieval interpreters inhabited it, or in the manner I once inhabited it when I was a very young Benedictine monk. Like all my colleagues, I have passed through and am still tremendously influenced by modernity. To be postmodern in the sense I have used the term—not as a personal affectation but as a cultural condition—requires having been modern in some fashion. Do I wish to imagine that world and dwell within it? The best part of me does, and seeks to embody that world in action. Do large parts of my life not succeed in that endeavor? Yes, on one side because of sin, and on the other side because of the ways in which I am aware of multiple ways of imagining the world and collude, knowingly or not, in their construction as well. Professor Yeago also worries that speaking of “the world Scripture imagines” might be taken to mean an “imaginary world.” He makes the valuable point that Scripture claims that its construal of the world is real 182 Book Symposium and true, and that Christians also take up a public position in the world by their profession of faith that derives from that construal. I agree, and make an extended argument to that effect in my book, The Creed:What Christian Believe and Why it Matters (Doubleday, 2003). Furthermore, I regard the argument in my book on the creed and the statements I have made about the world that Scripture imagines as complementary rather than contradictory. The Future of Christian Biblical Scholarship My response to Professor Richard Hays will be relatively short because, as I noted above, he has identified some of the same issues as were raised by Professor Yeago. I am pleased that Hays likes a number of our proposals and even some of our diagnosis. I am delighted that he recalls the names of Brevard Childs, Hans Frei, Francis Watson, Stephen Fowl, David Steinmetz, and the members of the Scripture project with which he is involved (and which included three Roman Catholics) as a reminder that Bill Kurz and I are not—just in case we were tempted so to characterize ourselves— “lonely voices in the wilderness,” but speak in chorus with “an impressive cloud of witnesses” who form a “widespread reforming movement in biblical studies.” I gladly acknowledge that the footnote (129, note 19) that caused him pain was more accurate with respect to its main referents, Caird and Hurst, than it was with respect to his Moral Vision of the New Testament. In my previous response to Yeago, I have tried to address what Hays calls an “unnecessarily uncharitable” and “antagonistic stance” toward Protestant interpreters, as well as the question of whether I really inhabited “the world imagined by Scripture,” and whether I knew there was a difference between the scriptural sensibility of the great reformers and the tendencies of enlightenment scholars who happened also to be Protestant.There is no need, I think, to address the obvious fact that Bill and I, although both Roman Catholic, have different perspectives and emphases, since we have cheerfully acknowledged this, both in the form and the substance of our conversation. I will leave aside entirely as deeply uninteresting to anybody but old Yalies a discussion of whether I have failed in piety toward my alma mater. This leaves two substantial objections to things I said in the book—I will leave to Bill a response to any statements made about his contributions. The first substantial issue is biblical theology. I have already touched on this point in my response to Father Matera. I think it is important to distinguish three distinct exercises, which are frequently, and unfortunately, lumped together under the rubric “biblical theology.” One is the description of and (too seldom) engagement with the “theological voice” Book Symposium 183 of the respective biblical compositions. I not only think this is important, I have actually done more than a little of it. I think this is what Augustine did in his homilies on the First Letter of John and what Childs did in his commentary on Isaiah.Another is the use of Scripture in the doing of theology within the church.This also is legitimate and necessary. I have also done some of this. In this exercise the point is less the meaning of the text than it is the meaning of the mystery of faith.This is what Augustine did in his anti-Pelagian tractates or in De Trinitate. In distinct ways, both Professor Hays and I have done some of this. I therefore have no issues with these two enterprises, except concerning whether they are done well and with integrity. I do have some questions about how the first exercise might aid or hinder the second, but that is another discussion.And I resist calling them “biblical theology” because of the way in which that term has been connected to the third exercise. My criticism is directed solely to the distinct intellectual exercise that grew up precisely within the frame of the enlightenment and has called itself since the time of Philip Gabler “New Testament Theology.” As embodied by books with that title (including those by Brevard Childs), this exercise suffers from the faults I have attributed to it, and should be abandoned, precisely in the name of theology and the theological engagement with Scripture. The second issue is the role of experience in interpreting Scripture. I should mention immediately that my stress on this element owes not a little to my own immersion in a Methodist context at Candler School of Theology. I have found the Wesleyan Quadrilateral to be a wonderful explication of hermeneutical principles that are deeply consonant with Catholic sensibilities. I should also note that my emphasis is not on experience of any sort but on the experience of the living God, and that I have derived this emphasis, not from some philosophical or ideological position, but from the careful reading of the New Testament. Since Hays refers to my book Scripture and Discernment, he must also know that I fully acknowledge there the difficulties that accompany taking religious experience seriously, and that I devote considerable attention to the question of criteria for discernment. By no means can the church say yes to everything claimed to be an experience of God.The church must say yes only to what builds it in holiness. As Hays notes, moreover, my call for attention to the experience of the living God in the fabric of human existence goes together with a call for close and disciplined practices of reading within communities.This is far from a call for subjectivity or individualism. Perhaps what Hays cannot grasp is the way in which Roman Catholic 184 Book Symposium scholars always assume (and find no need constantly to reaffirm) the presence of the magisterial teaching function, the formal practices of liturgy, the framework of the canon, the profession of the creed, the practices of piety, the witness of the saints, the entire weight of tradition, as realities that are massively given, and constantly serving as checks and balances to excessive subjectivity. It is, in fact, important to appreciate the experiential element in interpretation from a perspective other than that of the problematic. God’s Holy Spirit, after all, works at every moment in human experience for growth in holiness and wisdom.Without the witness of the saints—a witness that is always based in their experience—the church does not grow in the understanding of Scripture that is, in the most proper sense, sapiential. Conversion and Construction As grateful as I am for this continuation of “conversation,” I want to conclude this response by reminding my colleagues as well as myself that the process of scholars talking among themselves, however enjoyable and even profitable, is not by itself sufficient to enliven a future Catholic biblical scholarship. Insofar as such conversation stays at the level of theory and position-taking, in fact, it can come dangerously close to an academic exercise that serves its own ends but does not necessarily build the church. If the participants agree on most of the positive ideals that the authors have identified in their book, the question arises how those ideals might find embodiment and not merely intellectual agreement. It is my conviction that those of us who espouse these convictions need to engage a process of conversion and construction, or, to use other terms, to apply ourselves seriously to the politics and pedagogy of scholarship. By conversion, I mean precisely the turn from theory to practice, and within the academy and the church, practice always involves politics. Those of us in major graduate programs, for example, are in a position to fundamentally affect the way Scripture is read in the church, first through our education of ministers, and second, through our training of professors. If values are going to find embodiment, then hard curricular debates and decisions must be made. It will not be enough to gather at conferences and workshops with like-minded folks, we must engage and try to persuade colleagues in specific institutions whose views do not line up with ours. In ministerial programs, how much Scripture should be studied, and how does such study serve to enrich the theological imagination of the pastor? In Ph.D. programs, what role shall be given to the history of interpretation, both at the level of seminars and as a necessary aspect of dissertations? How much shall we encourage, as part of our enterprise, Book Symposium 185 scholarship that is explicitly theological and ecclesial? By construction, I mean pedagogy, which is closely connected to politics. Curricular decisions, after all, are, or ought to be pedagogical in character. But there is also a politics embedded in the specific pedagogy of a course. Again we might ask how our manner of teaching the New Testament in seminary provides students with a living laboratory of ecclesial practice. And in our training teaching associates in Ph.D. programs, we can similarly ask how the forms of pedagogy that we communicate both explicitly and implicitly embody the values that we espouse verbally. It is fairly easy to criticize the manner in which others have exercised their scholarship, and also fairly easy to imagine a utopian alternative.The hard work comes in the way in which we must change and work for N&V change with others, if we want that alternative to become real. Response to the Respondents W ILLIAM S. K URZ , SJ Marquette University Milwaukee,Wisconsin R EADING THE FIVE thoughtful responses by scholarly colleagues to Luke Johnson’s and my book awakened a grateful experience of our project being honored and vindicated. These responses constructively “continue the conversation” to which our book aspired to contribute.The three responses by Catholic scholars placed appreciative focus on the positive intent and implications of our dominant model of inclusive, generous “both/and” Catholic approaches, and mainly disregarded possibly negative comparisons to alternative “either/or” tendencies.The two scholars from other denominations expressed displeasure at what they perceived as the unfairness of our comparison. I will address their concerns, but my initial and overall response is to emphasize the positive and important insights in the inclusive approaches that we are recommending Catholic scholarship continue to foster, and to withdraw focus on possibly negative comparisons, at least with the approaches of other Christians. Frank Matera’s response was generally appreciative, especially of our inclusive turning to tradition when interpreting Scripture and of our declining to be embarrassed by our Catholic preunderstandings, but with critical awareness of how we apply them. His constructive contributions to the continuing conversation focused on “balance and proportion,” in the inclusive “both/and” direction we had taken. He reminded us that there is no special “Catholic method” of exegesis. What characterizes Book Symposium 186 Catholic exegesis and interpretation is that it is consciously and forthrightly practiced within a living tradition and with the aim of fidelity to the basic revelation of Scripture.1 His four areas in which balance and proportion in biblical interpretation are especially needed move the conversation forward by emphasizing the constructive application of Catholic exegetical predilections. In calling for a balance between the theology and history, he reminds us that there is even theological value in the historical approach in situating and relativizing the implications of some sharp controversies with Judaism in John and Matthew. I find especially helpful his characterization of Catholic exegesis as theological, as faith seeking understanding with the aid of historical investigation.2 Matera’s second inclusive balance and proportion between an overall theology and the particular theologies of Scripture remind us that the mysteries of God are too profound for any single theology and require the multiple kinds of explanations in the various biblical books. He also makes a helpful distinction between a historical judgment that the Bible has many quite different theologies, and the necessity, from the perspective of belief, to posit unity to God’s revelation in Scripture. Believers, in doing so, are in fact searching for God through the Scriptures.3 Regarding Christian balance between Old and New Testaments, Matera recalls the instruction of the Pontifical Biblical Commission’s 2002 document on the Jewish people and Scriptures in the Christian Bible. Particularly pertinent to my concerns were his reminder that the Father of Jesus is identical to the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, and that Catholics who pray the Liturgy of the Hours “live in a liturgical world” that seamlessly integrates Old Testament and New Testament texts.4 His final balancing suggestions between ecclesial and academic approaches to Catholic exegesis primarily furthered Luke Johnson’s observations in our book. The contributions of Stephen Ryan, OP, and Olivier-Thomas Venard, OP, mainly presupposed the many book reviews about our book. They focused less on our book than on moving the conversation forward in two fascinating and constructive new directions, beyond the topics we raised. As a specialist in Old Testament, Stephen Ryan made some intriguing observations about how the pluriformity both of variant biblical manuscripts and of the major ancient versions (particularly the Greek, 1 Matera, “The Future of Catholic Biblical Scholarship: Balance and Proportion,” Nova et Vetera 4:1(2006): 122. 2 Ibid., 124. 3 Ibid., 127. 4 Ibid., 130. Book Symposium 187 Latin, and Syriac) provide a further application of the inclusive “both/ and” principle. Ryan mentioned very encouraging developments for the future of Catholic biblical scholarship. Current projects of providing translations and commentaries on the Septuagint and Syriac Peshitta will make the rich Eastern interpretive tradition accessible to the Western readers. Interfaith cooperation between Catholics and Jews on the Hebrew Scriptures is complementing the ecumenical gains and goals of recent interdenominational biblical scholarship.The Oxford Hebrew Bible, a new critical edition that prints synoptic Hebrew parallels for passages that survive in more than one significant form, will enlighten readers to the realities of the pluriformity of many Old Testament texts.A 1969 ecumenical agreement between the United Bible Societies and the Vatican Secretariat for Promoting Christian Unity allows for Esther to be translated twice, the Hebrew text in the canon section, the Greek in the deuterocanonical section. Ryan draws attention to the incentives that such significant pluriformity of manuscripts provides for reconceptualizing the meaning of divine inspiration of the Bible.This in turn should provide a needed corrective to the “seductive certainties” of post-Enlightenment literalism (that affect both critical and fundamentalist forms of interpretation).5 Ryan celebrates the hope that the increasing ecclesial role of early biblical versions alongside the original texts will promote the ecumenical catholicity of the Church and better access to rich interpretive traditions of patristic and medieval saints and scholars.6 Another fascinating further stage in the conversation is the account by Olivier-Thomas Venard of how “fourth-generation” Catholic scholars (successors to Johnson and my “third generation”) are at work through the École Biblique to produce a “Christian Talmud” under the title La Bible en ses Traditions. This complete recasting of the next version of the Bible de Jérusalem plans to incorporate the irreducibility of several versions of the same book or passage (which Ryan also discussed). It plans to address the new importance of the history of reception in literary studies, which in turn is intimately related to renewed appreciation of patristic exegesis. It combines appreciation of the literary aspects with plain historical or doctrinal meaning of biblical texts.7 5 Ryan, “The Text of the Bible and Catholic Biblical Scholarship,” Nova et Vetera 4:1(2006): 141. 6 Ibid., 141. 7 Venard, “ ‘La Bible en ses Traditions’: The New Project of the École biblique et archéologique française de Jérusalem. Presented as a ‘Fourth-Generation’ Enterprise,” Nova et Vetera 4:1(2006): 142. 188 Book Symposium I find especially promising the prospect that the new edition will be structured analogously to the layout of the Talmud. At the center, on facing pages will be translations of the biblical texts (in synoptic parallelism with translations of any important irreconcilable variants). The “Text” register will supply the usual historical-critical notes on textual criticism, philology, and literary devices. “Background” will provide history and geography, social background, and parallel ancient texts.The largest section of annotation will be “Reception,” on biblical intertextuality, Jewish and Christian traditions, theology, dogmas, liturgy, iconography, art, and literature. Such an ambitious project is being implemented by a large interdisciplinary team of scholars. Venard than illustrates exciting ways in which his “fourth-generation” project is furthering our book’s “postmodern and Catholic celebrations of language, diversity, otherness, culture, and faith.”8 Venard’s project will further Origen’s insight (cited by Johnson) that it is the language of Scripture that teaches, whatever its relation to what happened.9 The close link between literary textual meaning and God’s revelation requires scrupulous respect for the original text, as Venard illustrates by his work on the parable of the sower in Matthew, in which he shows that in the Matthaean text the seed refers to both the word sown by Jesus and the hearer of the word sown by God the Creator.10 Diversity will be respected, for example, by consulting important translations like the Vulgate along with the original New Testament Greek. Otherness will be celebrated by the very interdisciplinary nature of this project, and by adding to the usual scientific exegesis a more creative literary one.Appreciation for otherness will also appear in choosing more literal translations more attuned to “exotic” biblical and oral cultures.11 Venard’s work on Matthew begins with his and his assistant’s draft of notes for all the registers, based especially on their own expertise. These drafts they submit to specialists in “patristics, ancient Judaism, history of the liturgy, iconography, or dogmatics” to modify, correct, or even suppress their proposals and to add better references.12 The collaborators in this Bible respect how human meaning is constructed, connected to faith commitments, and rooted in community traditions.They recognize in biblical interpretation the same kind of circle of preknowledge and knowledge that characterizes most commonplace 8 Ibid., 144. 9 Ibid., 146. 10 Ibid., 147, esp. 148. 11 Ibid., 151. 12 Ibid., 152. Book Symposium 189 knowledge.They hope that their Bible will deepen understanding of how the “economy” of revelation occurs by means of “deeds and words intrinsically interconnected.”13 Another area of convergence between the proposals of our book and their new Bible will be the explicit incorporation of faith into their scholarly exegetical work.They intend to consult Church teaching as an invitation to deepen their philological study of the text and its reception, enlarge the context of their reading of the text, and allow truths that were developed later to help readers notice textual facts or peculiarities.14 Finally, Venard envisages biblical scholarship as helping in the future to produce a biblical world that is, to be an agent changing the culture, especially its irrational and nihilistic foundations.15 Venard proposes making biblical texts places where our contemporaries can live today. Because they came primarily in the form of challenges, the responses of David Yeago and Richard Hays proved especially productive for my own attempts to “continue the conversation.” When I tracked down Yeago’s references I found some especially useful writings and suggestions that were being written about the same time as Luke Johnson and I were composing our book, most of them not available to us at the time of writing. Many of my own current further steps toward reading Scripture more theologically and spiritually are relying heavily on both Yeago’s own articles and David Steinmetz’s analogy between reading Old and New Testaments and reading a mystery story, which appeared after our book in The Art of Reading Scripture co-edited by Hays.16 In fact, responses to our book have included practical guidance to excellent proposals and writings that run parallel to Johnson’s and my concerns. Before attempting answers to particular criticisms of Yeago and Hays, I want to acknowledge that I consider their concerns and those of many others to be quite parallel to ours. I regard them not only as brothers in Christ but as significant partners in the conversation toward the future of both Catholic and Christian biblical scholarship. The following writings exemplify contributions to the ecumenical and Catholic search for theological and religiously helpful exegesis as an alternative to interpretation heavily indebted 13 Dei Verbum, no. 2;Venard, 154. 14 Venard, 155. 15 Ibid., 157. 16 David Steinmetz, “Uncovering a Second Narrative: Detective Fiction and the Construction of Historical Method,” in The Art of Reading Scripture, ed. E. F. Davis and R. B. Hays (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2003). Book Symposium 190 to modernism and postmodernism. Most of these publications appeared at about the same time or after our book and were not available to us. I recommend that many of these be read in conjunction with our book, to supplement, complement, and at times correct some of our emphases. Perhaps the most evidently parallel work to ours is the set of published essays resulting from the Duke University ecumenical Scripture Project, co-edited by Ellen Davis and Richard Hays, The Art of Reading Scripture. Their “Nine Theses on the Interpretation of Scripture,” complement our suggestions.17 I intend to incorporate them into my Scripture classes and to recommend them as a fine starting point for all who share our common desire for interpretation more attuned to the Bible as God’s Word. For my present search for something like the patristic overarching biblical narrative, I find particularly helpful Richard Bauckham, “Reading Scripture as a Coherent Story”18 and even more so, David C. Steinmetz, “Uncovering a Second Narrative: Detective Fiction and the Construction of Historical Method,”19 along with Brian Daley’s essay on “Is Patristic Exegesis Still Usable?”20 Yeago’s response alerted me to a 2005 book by John J. O’Keefe and R. R. Reno, Sanctified Vision: An Introduction to Early Christian Interpretation of the Bible.21 It provides an extraordinarily helpful introduction to patristic interpretation.Also quite helpful is Christopher R. Seitz, Figured Out:Typology and Providence in Christian Scripture.22 Especially productive for my search for a more theological method have been the following essays in The Theological Interpretation of Scripture: Classic and Contemporary Readings: Henri de Lubac, “Spiritual Understanding”; David C. Steinmetz, “The Superiority of Pre-Critical Exegesis”; and especially David S.Yeago, “The New Testament and the Nicene 17 Davis and Hays, The Art of Reading Scripture, 1–5. 18 In Davis and Hays, The Art of Reading Scripture. 19 See note 16 above. 20 A variant of Communio 29 (2002): 185–216. 21 John J. O’Keefe and R. R. Reno, Sanctified Vision: An Introduction to Early Christ- ian Interpretation of the Bible (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2005). 22 Christopher R. Seitz, Figured Out: Typology and Providence in Christian Scripture (Louisville: Westminster John Knox, 2001). A seminal book for understanding how patristic interpretation relates to Greco-Roman rhetoric, philosophy, and culture is Frances M.Young, Biblical Exegesis and the Formation of Christian Culture (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 1997, 2002). A classic development of especially Irenaeus’s recapitulation theory that deserves more attention is Paul M. Quay, The Mystery Hidden for Ages in God (New York: P. Lang, 1995). A short accessible version of de Lubac’s classic four volumes on the four senses is Henri de Lubac, Scripture in the Tradition (New York: Crossroad, 2000). Book Symposium 191 Dogma:A Contribution to the Recovery of Theological Exegesis.”23 The readily available classic St. Athanasius on the Incarnation nicely illustrates this theological approach.24 Catholic contributions that overlap many of the concerns of our book (perhaps more my emphases than Johnson’s) are Peter S. Williamson, Catholic Principles for Interpreting Scripture: A Study of the Pontifical Biblical Commission’s The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church;25 and David M.Williams, Receiving the Bible in Faith: Historical and Theological Exegesis.26 Lutheran systematic theologian David Yeago expressed misgivings about Luke Timothy Johnson’s recommendation of “imagining the world as the Scripture imagines it.” He was primarily concerned about Christians using a postmodern approach without sufficient acknowledgement of how dangerous postmodernism’s proclivities can be to Christian faith. I share Yeago’s concerns about “the imagined world” of postmodern approaches being equated with an “imaginary” world. From his explicit faith perspective,Yeago argues that Scripture reveals the true meaning of the world, to which we tend to be blinded by sin. Despite rhetorical differences, I doubt that Johnson would disagree with Yeago’s insistence that it is not merely a matter of a postmodern (and arbitrary) choice to imagine the world in the way the Bible does. In faith we accept the reality of that biblical world.To this I would add that according to my own experience and study, the biblical worldview in fact makes more rational sense of reality than any modern or postmodern alternative views of reality that I know. And Venard’s proposal that biblicists actually help build a biblical world that we can live in today also contributes to this topic. On the other hand,Venard emphasizes that there can be “a Christian version of postmodernity, which inverts the general relativism of postmodern thinkers into the conscious ‘second naivety’ provided by an illuminated faith regarding our possibility to know the truth.”27 Postmodern relativism 23 Stephen E. Fowl, ed., The Theological Interpretation of Scripture: Classic and Contempo- rary Readings (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1997): Henri de Lubac, “Spiritual Understanding,” 3–25; David C. Steinmetz, “The Superiority of Pre-Critical Exegesis,” 26–38; and especially David S. Yeago, “The New Testament and the Nicene Dogma: A Contribution to the Recovery of Theological Exegesis,” 87–100. 24 St.Athanasius on the Incarnation:The Treatise De Incarnatione Verbi Dei (Crestwood, NY: St.Vladimir’s Orthodox Theological Seminary, rev. ed., 1944, 1953, 1982). 25 Peter S.Williamson, Catholic Principles for Interpreting Scripture:A Study of the Pontifical Biblical Commission’s The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church (Rome: Editrice Pontificio Istituto Biblico, 2001). 26 David M. Williams, Receiving the Bible in Faith: Historical and Theological Exegesis (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2004). 27 Venard, 144. Book Symposium 192 can help dispose of an exaggerated assumption of criticism being “scientific,” which triggered the divorce of exegesis from the life of the Church. We now appreciate with Lyotard that every discourse, including scientific, “implies a rhetoric, a tradition, and many preconceptions.28 After removal of its nihilist postulates, postmodernity “can help biblical scholars to recover confidence in cultural mediation.”That is, various cultural and other “prejudices shape every thought, and this is not fate, but fact—and should be simply taken into account.”29 Venard also celebrates the epistomological shift away from the romantic prejudice in historical criticism that there was an original, pure good news that became progressively corrupted throughout Church history. He argues that in ancient semi-oral civilizations language reveals, rather than represents.30 “In the world of Scripture, events, undetectable without texts that beforehand sharpen the attention of those that live them, come to enlighten those very texts. Inhabitants of this world experience the mutual illuminations of being and letter.”31 One effect of this is to render invalid many critical judgments against historicity in narratives because of their literary shaping and intra-biblical allusion. Historical effectiveness has to be judged “no longer against, but through the cultural mediations of knowledge.”32 Questions remain about how one can live in a scriptural universe in the twenty-first century. I continue to look to premodern exegesis in the hopes that it can reintroduce some approaches and principles that would be viable today. One productive patristic paradigm is the importance of combining both philosophical and purely rational approaches with living within a biblical worldview.Yeago has astutely remarked that in addition to the philosophical alternatives of secular versus scriptural worldviews, it is important to remember the culture-transforming effects of a scriptural mind set.33 This recalls the more fundamental and critically important need for both faith and reason to be able to live within a biblical worldview. Faith believes in the God revealed in Scripture, a God who both creates and redeems and who exercises providential care for us creatures. Reason 28 Venard, 144. 29 Ibid., 152–53. 30 Ibid., 153 31 Ibid., 153. 32 Ibid., 154 33 See somewhat comparable comments by Venard mentioned above. Especially helpful is the treatment of how rhetoric, philosophy, culture, and the biblical vision mutually influence each other in patristic interpretation in Young, Biblical Exegesis and the Formation of Christian Culture. Book Symposium 193 applies considerations of the dignity of persons and human rights, natural law and the common good, and justice, within the pluralistic realities among which we live.34 In addition, as Catholics and other Christians reading Scripture today, we demonstrate the reasonableness of our faith in the loving, biblical God who created all things good and who rescues humans from our sinful misuse of our God-given freedom. Concern for the reasonableness of our faith reminds us that the biblical worldview requires that we respect the dignity and rights of the other human images of God. It requires us to live morally and justly, in ways that use material creation wisely and avoid mistreating or misusing it selfishly. Yeago, Hays, and others have expressed intense ecumenical uneasiness and some personal offense taken with what Yeago calls our “oppositional self-definition,” and with some of our characterizations of Protestantism (undifferentiated and often linked to Enlightenment presuppositions). I certainly apologize for any offense I have given. In most cases, I believe upsetting statements on my part or their implications resulted either from my overgeneralizing from individual writings or actual pastoral or teaching experiences, or from insufficient care to specify the precise authors or settings of statements or methods that concerned me. In some cases, I think I was simply misunderstood. I cannot speak for Luke Johnson, but from my personal experience of his extraordinarily friendly personality and ecumenical openness, I think some of his rhetoric and expressions were likewise misunderstood. As both Yeago and Hays agree, ecumenism does not mean reducing discussions to “least common denominator” concerns and theologies. In fact, I characterize even what seemed to me to be their sharpest criticisms as offered in a spirit of ecumenical dialogue and respect, and I accept them in that spirit. As they both recognized, I have never hidden my Catholic presuppositions and loyalties (some of which differ also from Luke’s, as Hays especially pointed out). In turn I am happy to be reminded of their differing personal presuppositions and loyalties. I had already discovered some negative aspects and results of the “leastcommon-denominator” approach to dialogue as a graduate student at Yale, from an orthodox rabbi friend who was a fellow student there. He emphasized to me how offensive and condescending he found it when 34 Although Hays provides reasonable arguments for finding substitutes for “rights language,” I find such terms too important components of long-standing Catholic social teaching to surrender. Cf. Pope John Paul II, encyclical letter “Faith and Reason” (Fides et ratio; 1998), www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/ encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_15101998_fides-et-ratio_en.html. 194 Book Symposium Christians talked to him about Christ in reductionistic ways, as if they, like he, were Jewish in their beliefs about Jesus. He expected me as a Christian to believe in the divinity of Christ, and to acknowledge that belief in conversations with him. “Least-common-denominator” dialogue was not only not helpful, but was actually dishonest. Still, neither Johnson nor I ever wanted to emphasize oppositional self-definition as our program or as a desideratum. My remarks simply began from what abundant personal, professional, pastoral, and teaching experience indicated are noticeable differences that in fact occasion different interpretive perceptions and approaches between Catholics and Christians of other denominations. I believe the best ecumenical contribution I can make to any dialogue is to speak with both respect for others’ views and a desire to learn from them, but also without apology for my personal Catholic presuppositions and beliefs—all of them, even those with which some other Catholics might disagree. When I emphasized that there exist factual differences between Catholics and other Christians, I was not ignoring ecumenical efforts or concerns, but simply expressing my extensive experiential awareness of how seriously such differences influence both behavior and biblical interpretation. I was referring to grassroots teaching and exegetical experience, not the level of organized ecumenical discussions. On that level of ordinary give-and-take, I find it more productive simply to begin ecumenical exchange by having all parties speak from their actual current beliefs, opinions, and preferences, in which there happen to be not inconsiderable differences among them. Convergences come afterward, from listening to and learning from the views of others. Both Yeago and I want to remove as many differences between Christian groups as possible, but for me the most effective starting point is honest acknowledgement of our current positions and consequently their differences from positions of our dialogue partners. As each participant explains her or his reasons for their position, more areas of common concern and conviction can emerge, and more differences can be either overcome or relativized in their significance. This process may also give promise of eventually including denominational differences alongside social, ethnic, and sexual differences as overcome in the unity of the one Christ (cf. Gal 3:28), as Yeago hopes. I furthermore concur with generally wanting to find common ground and to emphasize more fundamental points on the hierarchy of truths where Christians and other believers can agree, rather than to focus excessively on differences that divide us. Still, there are also important values that are contained within our very differences.We can learn from Book Symposium 195 the differing perspectives from other individuals and other denominations if we both listen to others’ outlooks and express our own diverging values honestly and respectfully. Sometimes we may simply have to “agree to disagree.” But more often we find complementarity in the differing views and approaches that can be mutually enriching. The extraordinary productiveness (and enjoyableness) of respectful but open and frank ecumenical discussion, in which each participant in the conversation speaks from her or his personal faith and differing denominational perspectives, have been amply demonstrated in my recent large ecumenical seminars on Luke-Acts and on Johannine writings at Marquette.As I have become more aware of how our Catholic, Lutheran, Orthodox, Pentecostal, Episcopalian, Evangelical, Presbyterian, and other perspectives do influence what we notice, bring to, and read in biblical texts, I have begun testing my developing hypotheses that our differing denominational preunderstandings bring positive contributions and not merely limitations to our common efforts at exegesis. I have begun encouraging students to exegete biblical passages not only using the standard historical, critical, and literary methods, but also acknowledging to the whole class any special emphases or insights their particular denominational and religious background, training, and experience suggested to them. Each student was encouraged to express honestly his or her opinion on the topic or passage as well as any particular disagreement with anyone else’s opinion, including the professor’s. The only basic ground rule in this mutual give-and-take was that it always be respectful of others and their suggestions, and never resort to personal attacks or to insulting the views of others. Both the graduate students and I found these class sessions with their sharing and mutual critiques of exegetical papers and studies enormously enjoyable as well as profitable. Both they and I were especially proud when a pair of exegetical papers produced in the seminar, both of which explicated Lukan treatments of “breaking of bread,” were accepted by a scholarly journal for publication explicitly as a pair. They were regarded as examples of how differing Baptist and Catholic presuppositions in exegeting the same biblical passages can lead to varying and often complementary emphases, in this case the Baptist stressing the communal aspects and the Catholic the Eucharistic facets of “breaking of bread” in Luke and Acts. Regarding the hierarchy of truths, I agree with both Yeago and Hays that on such fundamental levels as creedal belief in central doctrines like Trinity and Incarnation we are primarily on common ground. This common ground extends more than I previously realized also to our 196 Book Symposium parallel searches and converging general principles for ways of doing biblical exegesis that are more attuned to Scripture as God’s Word. I am happy to come to know and learn from them as brothers and allies in our common desires and efforts for the future of biblical scholarship. I think that both Catholics and other Christians, including Johnson and me, have for some time been earnestly cultivating such areas of common convictions. Sometimes, however, very significant disagreements remain among us on the level of truths that are not toward the top of the hierarchy of truths. I suggest that the serious disagreement expressed between Hays and me relates mostly to debated propositions that belong lower down in this hierarchy. I am sorry if I did not sufficiently emphasize the extensive areas of agreement between Dr. Hays’s chapter on abortion and my chapter critiquing his position. The main reason I chose the case history of his chapter was to avoid setting up a “straw man.” It was to grapple with a book, a scholar, and a position for whom I had genuine respect, and whose overall agreement in general moral and interpretative principles allowed me to illustrate where our remaining real differences lay. The way that I applied the “both/and” and “either/or” contrast was unfortunate and now regretted, but we both agree with my main point that our differences are primarily related to differing denominational preunderstandings and preferences when it comes to how we apply extra-biblical reasoning to our interpretation. (As Matera had remarked, there are no particularly Catholic methods of exegesis, but what characterizes Catholic interpretation is their doing it explicitly from within their tradition.) Our areas of agreement extend to most of the fundamental methodological priorities for reading Scripture as the Word of God and seeking guidance from it in areas that we both agree are not explicitly treated in Scripture, like abortion. Our respective chapters also agree in our strong aversion to abortion and in how the worldview and narratives of Scripture strongly discourage it. I also regret and apologize for not clearly enough acknowledging that not only Hays’s fundamental approaches but also his ultimate conclusion from his exegetical and interpretive quest for biblical guidance about abortion come to an analogous basic judgment. As he puts it, “My own judgment in this case is that the New Testament summons the community to eschew abortion and thus to undertake the burden of assisting the parents to raise the handicapped child.”35 Further, as someone with pastoral experience 35 Richard B. Hays, The Moral Vision of the New Testament: Community, Cross, New Creation (San Francisco: Harper-SanFrancisco, 1996), 457, emphasis added. Book Symposium 197 myself, I too acknowledge the difference between giving an unambiguous ethical directive (for me it would be against abortion in any circumstances) and dealing pastorally with the imperfect and even sinful decisions people actually make. I also agree that the Church should assist people in keeping difficult moral commandments, but that does not completely absolve the actual parents from their own responsibility. The point of clear divergence between us is that ultimately I have to characterize the choice that this fortyish couple made to kill their preborn baby who had Downs Syndrome as morally wrong, not merely a tragedy. From my belief that God has a plan for every human being in creating each human soul, I cannot see that God approves killing one’s handicapped baby in the womb for any reason.This personal conviction stems both from the general biblical worldview on which I think Hays and I mostly agree and from my denominationally influenced attitudes to using traditions such as natural law and moral absolutes. (This particular instance does not happen to result particularly from my tendency to show more dependence than others on magisterial teachings.) The conclusion of my argument from Scripture and rational reflection and reasoning is confirmed by extensive personal experience in helping women and men who bitterly grieve over and repent of aborting their child in even significantly worse circumstances than the example under discussion. The key to their healing was their honestly acknowledging their guilt and repenting of what they have done, as in the biblical pattern exemplified in Psalms 32 and 51. The main reason I may be seeming to belabor this difference is that I believe such ethical concerns extend far beyond the narrow purview of hard cases concerning abortion. I believe the churches are going to need biblical and traditional guidance for many critical recent ethical questions that are not mentioned in Scripture but that have enormous ethical, economic, scientific, and cultural ramifications. I am alarmed by current bioethical developments that seem to be headed in the direction described in Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World, in which “mother” is a dirty word, babies sorted according to genetically graded abilities are produced in factories, and sex is reduced to trivialized pleasure.36 I believe there is an ecumenical urgency to find in Scripture and tradition, with helping guidance from ecclesial leaders, orientations for sorely needed ethical principles in such financially lucrative but morally problematic biomedical areas as cloning, artificial creation of human embryos, and embryo experimentation and harvesting for stem cells, not to mention end-of-life 36 Aldous Huxley, Brave New World (Cutchogue, NY: Buccaneer Books, c1946, 1997). 198 Book Symposium concerns exacerbated by developing medical technologies. In these areas, I believe Catholic scholars, tradition, and magisterium have achieved many pioneering results that are of potential value to all Christians and moral people of good will. I also regret that my disagreement about discernment was experienced as judgmental. Because Hays alluded to St. Ignatius Loyola and discernment in reference to this decision, I was merely trying to insert a necessary distinction about Ignatian practices of discernment, in which I have been steeped throughout my Jesuit life. The misapplication of Ignatian discernment that I was addressing is a common one, not in any special way focused on Dr. Hays. According to my Ignatian training and experience, ethics is in critical ways different from discernment: Ethics seeks to know what God has commanded as right or wrong, to be done or to be avoided. Ignatius would tend to seek answers to these ethical questions in the commandments, Scripture, Catholic teaching, tradition, and the magisterium.Then one would determine what to do and how to do it by applying the resulting general principles with prudence to one’s particular circumstances. This approach would not tend to seek answers to whether something is ethically right or wrong in prayer over one’s interior movements or one’s options and individual circumstances. A much more common kind of Ignatian discernment in prayer is to seek the Spirit’s guidance among multiple choices that are evidently morally good or neutral—for example, is God guiding me to be a doctor or a teacher, to seek marriage or a single life dedicated to extraordinary availability and service. In my Ignatian experience, a question about abortion would be an ethical question of right or wrong, and therefore not a matter of discernment in the usual Ignatian sense. Ultimately, I do not think it is surprising that on some points, Hays and I may have to “agree to disagree,” but even in these matters I believe we can disagree respectfully. Longstanding differences and deeply held convictions regarding natural law, moral absolutes, magisterium, and various hard ethical cases, such as those regarding abortion, are not able to be overcome in the small space of our interchange here. These particular disagreements need not hinder us from together searching among our abundant common convictions, beliefs, values, and exegetical priorities for a future for Catholic and Christian biblical scholarship that is more explicitly addressed to the needs of the Church and of believers. Despite the positive reception most Catholic reviewers and respondents have given to our promotion among Catholics of an inclusive “both/and” approach to interpretation, this image also occasioned signif- Book Symposium 199 icant objections.Yeago, Hays, and several reviewers have registered particular dismay and criticisms of Luke Johnson’s contrast, which I also used extensively, between a more characteristically Catholic “both/and” approach and a more typically Protestant “either/or” approach to biblical interpretation. Probably the majority of reviewers found our fundamental contrast between “both/and” and “either/or” exegetical predilections illuminating and corresponding to their own experience. However, I now think that linking the latter so explicitly to a generalized Protestantism was unfortunate. I regret any impression that our book was glorifying our Catholic proclivities at the expense of those of other denominations, or that it seemed to lump all denominations together as generically Protestant, or that it too closely equated Protestant predilections with those of the Enlightenment and secularistic mindsets. As I recall, our descriptions came about from our actual and painful experience of this “either/or” emphasis especially in the German and post-Bultmanian critical tendencies reigning during our graduate studies in the early 1970s. The tendency to emphasize dichotomies, along with some anti-Catholic nuances disguised in such standard exegetical constructs as “early Catholicism” to exemplify decline from the pristine Pauline-Johannine gospel, were so apparent to us that it even elicited our protests, mere graduate students though we were. I am convinced that such exegetical mindsets were common to most mainstream graduate programs at the time, and perdure among some of the more secularistic approaches to Scripture to this day. However, perhaps our linking this legitimate contrast between dichotomizing and inclusive exegetical approaches to a contrast between Catholic and Protestant owed too much to our personal, painful, but now long-past experiences as a Catholic, graduate-student minority in the face of some alienating exegetical presuppositions. For purposes of the ongoing constructive conversation about the future of both Catholic and ecumenical biblical scholarship, I believe that the three Catholic responses in this journal and the majority of book reviews both confirm that our emphasis on inclusive exegetical and interpretive approaches has merit, and also suggest reasonable ways to implement it. Stripped of the possibility of negative implications regarding other Christian denominations, we can pursue what is valuable in convictions about inclusive manners of interpreting Scripture, especially with acknowledged consultation of tradition. Cautions against eisegesis and simply reading one’s presuppositions into the text will always be important and necessary. We must also allow the biblical text to change and correct our presuppositions and traditions when necessary. In these 200 Book Symposium matters, not only our “separated brothers and sisters” but also Catholic practitioners from earlier “generations” who continue to emphasize mostly critical exegesis will have important contributions to make to this N&V ongoing conversation about biblical scholarship. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 4, No. 1 (2006): 201–22 201 Book Reviews Trinity in Aquinas by Gilles Emery, OP (Ypsilanti, MI: Sapientia Press of Ave Maria College, 2003), xxix + 361 pp. C LAIMING MERE COMMONPLACES to be the teaching of Thomas Aquinas is a frequent failing in works on the Angelic Doctor. In contrast, Trinity in Aquinas, by Fr. Gilles Emery, OP, professor of dogmatic theology at the University of Fribourg, is particularly adept at highlighting the unique features of Thomas’s Trinitarian theology. Deeply versed in the writings of Thomas’s contemporaries, Fr. Emery proves a superior guide to the Angelic Doctor’s voluminous writings on the Trinity, from the pertinent distinctions of the Scriptum super libros Sententiarum, to their expansion in the Summa contra gentiles and Summa theologiae, and finally to their exegetical flowering in the Super Evangelium S. Ioannis lectura. Along the way, the reader is treated to detailed discussions of the unity and triunity of God, the relationship of the Holy Trinity to creation, the proper account of processions, relations, and persons in the Holy Trinity, the infamous Trinitarian “analogies,” the controversy surrounding the procession of the Holy Spirit a Filio, and the “long and vast debate” about the relative priority of essentialism or personalism in Aquinas. Fr. Emery explains these rather difficult topics briskly, but with unparalleled ease and lucidity.What makes Trinity in Aquinas shine, however, is the way Fr. Emery finds passages that illuminate the distinctive aspects of Thomas’s Trinitarian theology. Trinity in Aquinas, which is a collection of seven independent studies, begins with a survey of Trinitarian theology from the twelfth through the fourteenth centuries. After patient examinations of Roscellinus, Abelard, Anselm, Gilbert de la Porrée, Peter Lombard, and Joachim of Fiore, Fr. Emery turns his attention to the role of rationes necessariae in medieval Trinitarian theology. It turns out that Thomas, for all his speculative brilliance, is more cautious than his contemporaries when assessing the capacities of reason to investigate the mystery of the Trinity. Unlike 202 Book Reviews Anselm, Richard of St. Victor, Bonaventure, and other Franciscans, Thomas is particularly wary of using rationes necessariae to demonstrate aspects of the mystery of the Trinity once it has been revealed, relying solely upon probable arguments. In fact, the caution displayed by Thomas in his commentary on Lombard’s Sententiae becomes the methodological theme of the entire collection. Not satisfied with any treatment of the Holy Trinity that threatens to diminish its mystery,Thomas will likewise safeguard the contemplative and speculative order that wisdom alone provides. Consequently, faith and Scripture are the only sources for the analogies and plausible reasons that invite us to contemplate the mystery. Such concerns allow the reader to feel the force of Thomas’s unique attribution of exemplarity to the procession of persons as a whole in his account of the relationship of the Holy Trinity to creation, which is the subject of the second chapter. Thus, for Thomas, the procession of the divine persons as persons is the cause of the procession and multiplicity of all creatures (67). One can imagine no better antidote to the common misconception that the medieval theologians thought of creation simply in terms of the One God! Fr. Emery elaborates further on the methodological importance of plausible reasons in his third chapter, which takes up the complex structure of the Trinitarian treatise in the Summa contra gentiles. Here too, Fr. Emery treats the reader to a detailed account of Thomas’s exegesis of Scripture and the various hermeneutic principles that shape his treatment of the Holy Trinity (esp. 90–91). Of particular importance, too, is the fact that Thomas abandons the theme, beloved by Augustine and the Victorines, of the Holy Spirit as the mutual love of the Father and the Son in the Summa contra gentiles in favor of an exploration of the essential love by which God loves himself (102, 216–17). Such a forward-looking decision allows Thomas to develop his mature position in the Summa theologiae on the Trinitarian persons as subsistent relations in contradistinction to the generally Franciscan emphasis on the Father as fontalis plenitudo, a teaching which Aquinas judges rather harshly: “hoc non videtur verum” (147, although cf. 197–98). Running like a red thread through all these essays is Thomas’s emphasis on the Trinitarian persons. By the time that Fr. Emery addresses, in his fifth chapter, the charges of Théodore Régnon and Karl Rahner that Latin and Greek theology lay opposed by virtue of their alleged essentialism and personalism, he has amassed a seemingly endless series of quotations, all expertly explained, as evidence in favor of dismissing the charges outright. Indeed, so thoroughly does Fr. Emery make his case, that the fifth chapter seems almost anticlimactic. Even so, Fr. Emery does not shy away from some of Thomas’s less than Book Reviews 203 flattering remarks about Greek theologians who denied the procession of the Holy Spirit a Filio, nor from Thomas’s claim that procession a Filio is “necessary for salvation’ (de necessitate salutis) (263–64, 267). Fr. Emery crowns Trinity in Aquinas with an analysis of Aquinas’s speculative exegesis of Trinitarian passages in Thomas’s lectures on the Gospel of John. Certain themes, such as the unity of will between the Father and the Son and the actions of the divine persons in the world, are more developed in Thomas’s lectures on John than elsewhere, and Fr. Emery wastes no time explaining them in the context of Thomas’s other works. Of crucial importance here is Emery’s claim that the doctrine of the economic Trinity in Thomas is in no way limited to a description of the works of the persons in Scripture. Rather, the proper understanding of the Trinitarian works ad extra requires a robust metaphysics of participation and order not unlike the reductio so dear to St. Bonaventure (292–93).This is a fitting place to conclude Trinity in Aquinas, since it returns to the themes so impressively outlined in Fr. Emery’s previous work, La Trinité créatrice: Trinité et Création dans les commentaries aux Sentences de Thomas d’Aquin et de ses précurseurs (Paris:Vrin, 1995). Cataloging the virtues of Trinity in Aquinas is almost as difficult as summarizing it. Fr. Emery certainly knows his way around both medieval and modern sources; primary and secondary sources pack his study, and Latin quotations abound so that specialists can follow his complex arguments. As an interpreter of Thomas, Fr. Emery stands firmly in the tradition of Marie-Dominique Chenu: The exitus-reditus scheme figures heavily in his presentation of Thomas’s thought, especially when discussing the relationship of the Holy Trinity to creation (53–59, 65–69, 77, et al.), as does Fr. Chenu’s emphasis on rationes verisimiles (75). Like his great predecessor, Fr. Emery also has a fine eye for rarely discussed aspects of Thomas’s thought, such as his innovative concept of “transcendental multitude” (multitudo secundum quod est transcendens; 30–31); his early description of God as artist (the metaphor that so exercised Étienne Gilson; 59); Thomas’s use of conciliar and patristic sources, which was quite advanced for its day (111, 240, 269); and the importance of Trinitarian theology for understanding Thomas’s doctrine of participation (42–43, 124, 288–89, 295, et al.). With such a wealth of information, it may be unfair to criticize Fr. Emery’s work for failing to address another aspect of Thomas’s Trinitarian theology. Since Trinity in Aquinas addresses Rahner’s criticism of medieval Trinitarian theology, I would have liked to see a discussion of the fifth article of the third question of the tertia pars, where the Angelic Doctor asks whether any of the divine persons could have assumed human nature. 204 Book Reviews When Thomas answers that the unity of the divine power would be threatened if the Father and the Holy Spirit could not do what the Son in fact did, he seems to imply that the unity of the divine nature is more important than the Trinitarian taxis in deciding the question. If so, this raises questions about many of the philosophical and theological concepts that appear in Professor Emery’s essays. Particularly important in this regard are the concepts of necessity and fittingness, for it appears, at least in this article of the Summa theologiae, that the relationship between the immanent and economic Trinities is established merely ex convenientia.This is an issue of great historical and theological significance, since Thomas— at least at first glance—seems to have departed from both the Greek and earlier Latin traditions, which stressed the incompatibility of the Father’s innascibility and his being sent. (In all fairness to Aquinas, this confusion can be traced to Augustine’s agnosticism in De Trinitate concerning the exegesis of Genesis 3:8: “et cum audissent vocem Domini Dei deambulantis in paradiso ad auram post meridiem.”) This is not merely a question of the contingency of creation and salvation—a point upon which all agree— but rather a question of the relative priority of nature and will in God’s revelation of himself. If all agree that God could have revealed his nature in any number of contingent ways, no one would deny that when God reveals his nature he does not reveal another, since were God to reveal his nature to be other than it is, he would no longer be God. If, however, God is Triune and his Trinity of persons consists in subsistent relations determined by their relations of origin, it would seem that the Trinitarian taxis cannot be compromised. In any event, I think it a point of honor for Thomists (and followers of other scholastics who shared this position) to explain the thought of the Angelic Doctor in such a way that he sufficiently answers Rahner’s charges. I do not raise this issue to question Fr. Emery’s findings, which are truly edifying, but rather because I hope that he might devote his numerous talents and vast erudition to a detailed study on necessity and contingency in Thomas’s Trinitarian theology—perhaps in a study not unlike his confrère Gilbert Narcisse’s Les raisons de Dieu. In the meantime, anyone interested in medieval theology or contemporary discussions of the Holy Trinity should purchase a copy of Fr. Emery’s work at his earliest convenience. A work that promises to repay diligent study with profound insight, Trinity in Aquinas should rest close at hand for anyone N&V who takes the thought of St.Thomas Aquinas seriously. R.Trent Pomplun Loyola College in Maryland Baltimore, Maryland Book Reviews 205 Denying and Disclosing God: The Ambiguous Progress of Modern Atheism by Michael J. Buckley, SJ (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 2004) I N D ENYING and Disclosing God, Michael Buckley builds on his earlier work, At the Origins of Modern Atheism (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1987), that received such justly deserved acclaim.Whereas the earlier book ran nearly four hundred pages, the current book, derived from his D’Arcy lectures, spans less than half the length of the previous book. Despite its comparative brevity, Denying and Disclosing God will not disappoint devotees who expect the erudition and care that marks all of Buckley’s work. The book reads like a series of lectures insofar as each chapter, though related, could be consumed on its own. The first two chapters recapitulate much of what the first book argued—namely, that the mechanics of Newton first gains their independence from faith and then presumes to give faith a more valid foundation. Theologians resorted to philosophical apologetics that bracketed religious experience while relying on mechanics to prove the existence of God. In their attempt to appeal universally, theologians ceded the particular expertise of theology. This strategy proved disastrous when Diderot and d’Holbach envisioned dynamic matter that no longer needed any God to set things in motion. Paradoxically, concludes Buckley, Atheism . . . did not arise in its strength primarily from a purported opposition of science or from the rich discoveries of that period or from the intellectual movements skeptically antagonistic to any claim for certainty. It arose from the contradiction immanent within . . . its apologetic strategies. (46) Of course, Christianity has a long history of hiding its hand. Already when St. Paul goes to Athens, he appeals initially not to the crucified Christ, but to the Athenians’ “unknown God.”This tradition would also include such early apologists as Justin Martyr and the long list of Christian intellectuals who would claim a universally accessible, natural knowledge of God. Though Buckley makes a persuasive argument about theology’s contribution to atheism, he does not explain how the fact of this ironic contribution should or should not inform Christian use of the spolia Aegyptorum. The hero of the book turns out to be John of the Cross, but the reader may well ask, why not Karl Barth? Buckley approaches some of these questions retrospectively in the third chapter, where he defends Aquinas against the charge that the Summa theologiae, 206 Book Reviews with its employment of the inference of the quinque viae to demonstrate the existence of God and to buttress philosophically the self-revelation of God, with its reliance upon metaphysics in its treatment of the nature of God and of the trinity itself before any consideration of the mysteries of Christ, (47) encourages a strategy similar to that of early modern apologists.As Buckley reads the first response to question 2, article 1 of the prima pars, the question of the self-evidence of God’s existence is crucial for a defense of Aquinas against such critics as Paul Tillich. For St. Thomas, God emerges in self-consciousness like a figure in the distance.The teleological urge for authentic happiness is implanted in each person, but is known in an “inchoate” manner. Such knowledge is not its own kind, but instead is an early stage of what one hopes will become a richer knowledge. As Buckley puts it, “When human beings naturally long for happiness, they are actually and naturally longing for God” (54). In this sense, as one comes to know God as the telos of one’s desire, “one cannot help feeling that [one] has always known God” (56, quoting Gilson). Still, this reading does not explain why Aquinas waits until the tertia pars to treat Christ. Pace Chenu and other Thomists, Buckley argues that Aquinas’s Christology cannot be viewed as an appendix unrelated to the first two parts. Here the care of Buckley’s reading proves insightful: In the prologue to the tertia pars, Aquinas writes that the consideration of Christ serves as a “consummatio.” Buckley points out that in the Aristotelian tradition, “one only knows something in its completion” (65). Following J. P.Torrell, Buckley states,“Christology is the consummation of theology because Christ is the consummation of the divine action of uniting the world with himself.”The goodness of God manifested in creation reaches its completion in the self-gift of Christ’s life and death. For Aquinas then, the gradual sense of the longing for happiness that exists in each person is only completed through a knowledge of Christ as the consummate selfrevelation of the Trinity. Rather than providing the foundation for natural theology as a separate branch of theology, Aquinas “charted a radically different course from the one taken by the rationalist tradition traced in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries” (69). In the following chapter, “God as the Anti-Human,” Buckley untangles the militant atheism of Feuerbach, Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud. Echoing Henri de Lubac’s Drama of Humanistic Atheism, Buckley proposes that nineteenth-century atheism considered God to be an imaginary force against which humanity fought to liberate itself. Before treating these militant atheists, Buckley argues that the stage was being set first by Book Reviews 207 Locke and then Kant. Locke issued a shift in what Buckley calls “fundamental thinking,” which, in this case, meant shifting “foundational thinking from ‘things’—from the realities given in nature or the ideas confronting the thinking subject—to the actual capacities of thinking subjects themselves” (75).This epistemological shift became more widely accepted on the Continent with Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. As Buckley puts it, Kant did not originate this flood; he augmented and sanctioned it for the century that was to follow. Under his blessings, these waters become holy. Disciplines bearing such names as epistemology or criticism or phenomenologies of spirit or cognitional theory became prevalent and foundational in the nineteenth century. (78) The historical narrative is skeletal compared to the work of an historian of ideas like Frederick Beiser, but Buckley’s account of the “turn to the subject” agrees with mainstream histories of philosophy. Following Richard Niebuhr, Buckley labels Schleiermacher “the Kant of modern Protestantism” for instituting a turn to the subject in theology. One can certainly trace the influence of Kant on Schleiermacher, but here Buckley’s narrow focus leaves something to be desired. He argues that Schleiermacher does for theology what Kant does for philosophy:“the human becomes . . . the criterion for what we know of God— since we never know God in Himself but only what God is for us” (80). But this pro nobis appeal links Schleiermacher to Kant only insofar as they were both heirs to Luther. Buckley’s reading of On Religion also overlooks the deeper thread of Spinozist monism that runs through much of the text, a monism pervasive among the Romantic crowd to which Schleiermacher belonged, and these Romantics, though not entirely dismissive of Kant, reappropriated monism as an alternative to Kant’s analytic tendency to separate rather than bring together. Though Buckley’s reading of the nineteenth century feels narrow, the argument that the later militant atheists built on foundations laid by Locke, Kant, and Schleiermacher manages to persuade. God and the human become bitter enemies.Writes Buckley,“It was only a question of time until the centrality of the human saw itself threatened by the very God whose ex professo existence it was explicitly to sustain. . . .This inherently vicious antinomy between the divine and the human led inexorably to the elimination of the divine” (96). The final two chapters constitute Buckley’s suggested remedies for the problem of disbelief. Buckley makes an interesting case that the Christian 208 Book Reviews apophatic tradition anticipates many of the problems about religious consciousness articulated by militant atheists. As Buckley explains, apophatic theology is not a fuzzy agnosticism; rather, it seeks to develop “a faith that points beyond experience and concepts, a process through negation into the infinite mystery that is God, a reality that beggars language” (110). Instead of throwing the search for God into reverse after the realization that one’s consciousness of God involves a certain projection, the apophatic theology of John of the Cross and Gregory of Nyssa implores the seeker to move toward a richer sense of a God who is, paradoxically, both accessible and beyond our grasp. Buckley also makes the point that religious experience has been omitted from much critical theological reflection. In short, the experience of Christian saints has not been considered viable data; Buckley laments this fact and asks rhetorically:“Is it not a lacuna . . . that theology neither has nor has striven to forge the intellectual devices to probe in these concrete experiences the disclosure they offer of the reality of God and so render them available for so universal a discipline?” (130). The experiences of holy and good people should not be cognitively empty. One could have hoped for a thicker book that filled in the details of each lecture more exhaustively, but Denying and Disclosing God should still be of interest to anyone concerned about the crisis of belief and the history of ideas in modernity. And even the well-versed scholars will no doubt reconsider some of their positions if they encounter the text sincerely. Instead of offering theological cotton candy—easily consumed, but not overly nourishing—Buckley provides the wholesome nutrients of a coconut that one must arduously engage before its richness can be digested. Buckley has done historians of ideas and theologians a great favor by providing an original and compelling account of how God has N&V been lost, and how we might gain a glimpse again. Grant Kaplan Loyola University New Orleans, Louisiana John Paul II and the Legacy of Dignitatis Humanae by Hermínio Rico, SJ (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2002), 273 pp. J OHN PAUL II and the Legacy of Dignitatis Humanae is published as part of the Moral Tradition Series of Georgetown University Press edited by James F. Keenan, SJ. The author, Fr. Hermínio Rico, SJ, is editor of the Jesuit cultural monthly journal Brotéria—Cristianismo e Cultura and a guest lecturer of theology at the Universidade Católica Portuguesa in Book Reviews 209 Lisbon. In his preface, Fr. Rico reveals that the present study is “the conclusion of a course of studies of theology at Weston Jesuit School of Theology, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and Boston College.” Accordingly, Fr. Rico expresses his particular gratitude to Fr. David Hollenbach, SJ, who directed the research that led to the published work. There is much impressive scholarship in this study. Rico provides many details related to the background and composition of Vatican Council II’s 1965 Declaration on Religious Freedom (Dignitatis humanae). Of particular interest is the debate between the followers of the American Jesuit, John Courtney Murray, who wanted the declaration to have a limited juridical focus, and the followers of “the French school,” who were convinced that the document “needed more compelling and complete theological grounding” (29). Rico offers some valuable insights on this tension within the document itself, and he carefully examines a 1976 study of Philippe André-Vincent, who was concerned to distinguish the teaching on religious freedom of the council from various modern understandings of individualistic freedom. The main heuristic framework employed by Rico for understanding Dignitatis humanae is that of three historical moments.The first moment he understands as the result of a doctrinal development away from the nineteenth-century papal ideal of the Church possessing “a juridically privileged status in a confessional state” (4). Thus, after a long period of resistance, the Catholic Church accepted religious freedom in civil society as a human right not to be denied. The second moment Rico describes as the “freedom of the Church against atheistic communism” (9). It was this historical dimension that greatly informed the interventions of Pope John Paul II (as Bishop Wojtyla) at Vatican II with respect to religious freedom. Here, it was primarily a concern of the freedom of the Church within politically hostile regimes. It was also a matter of upholding the obligations of all human beings toward the truth in settings where the freedom to articulate the truth was being suppressed. The third moment identified by Rico is one that is still unfolding. It is the challenge faced by the Church in democratic and pluralist societies where there is an emerging effort “to reduce religion to a purely private affair” and resist any efforts of the Church to influence “social and political issues” (13).The challenge, of course, is for the Church to establish credibility as a public voice in such political settings, which are becoming the norm in Europe, North America, and, to some extent, in Latin America. The interpretative framework of the three historical moments is helpful in many respects. Rico, though, makes use of this framework to present 210 Book Reviews persistent criticisms of John Paul II’s interpretation and application of the teachings of Dignitatis humanae within his pontificate. He understands John Paul II as being overly influenced by the second historical moment (that is, the confrontation with communism) but lacking an effective strategy for the third (that is, engagement with pluralistic democracies). Rico accuses the pontiff of “rhetorical exaggerations” and “lack of nuance” (163),“a topdown obedience-to-authority approach to moral formation within and by the Church” (169), “a biased approach to the interpretation of Dignitatis humanae” (196, note 205), and an outlook toward the modern secular world that may be “tendentiously pessimistic” (206). Of all the writings of John Paul II, the encyclicals Veritatis splendor (1993) and Evangelium vitae (1995) are signaled out for their excessively pessimistic views of modern secular culture. Rico believes the pope is correct to worry about the dangers of moral relativism and religious indifferentism, but he fears that John Paul II’s overly negative estimation of “the contemporary culture of freedom” (225) will undercut effective efforts at dialogue and moral persuasion on the part of the Church. He likewise is afraid that the pontiff ’s approach of “prophetic denunciation” (226) will rekindle old fears of “attempts to impose Catholic views upon the whole society” (234). In the final analysis, Rico believes that Dignitatis humanae was seeking a fine balance between truth and freedom. John Paul II, however, is hindered by “a constant insistence on the priority of truth over freedom” (221), a priority which puts the pope in “clear tension with the view of Murray and others inspired by him” who understand freedom as “a value to be respected always even when it regards people in error and evil” (ibid.). To be fair to Fr. Rico, he does not favor moral relativism or religious indifferentism. His concern, ultimately, is to establish credibility for the Church’s voice by means of “dialogue and search for common ground in cultural transformation” (176). He favors efforts at persuasion with complete respect for freedom and the building of consensus according to the democratic model. He believes this posture is more in line with Dignitatis humanae than that of John Paul II, who evokes “echoes of paternalistic views of political power,” especially by his “direct appeals to political authorities to heed the voice of the Church and enforce demands of the objective moral order upon society through legislation” (222). While Rico’s analysis will resonate with some, I find it deficient in several ways. First, he does not seem to appreciate the gravity of abortion as a moral evil. Indeed, he complains about the “disproportionate importance” being given “to a particular issue,” that is, abortion (180). Just as in the nineteenth century too much importance was given to the issue of Book Reviews 211 “religious freedom,” now abortion has become “the make or break criterion of all judgments and the focus of totally one-sided extremist positions” that can weaken the social influence of the Church and drive it into “the isolation of dead-end doctrinal immobility” (180). At one point, Rico indirectly suggests that John Paul II, in seeking to overturn laws permitting abortion, is promoting Catholicism as “the one true morality” entitled to “legal enforcement” (241, note 41) But, for Rico, to understand the protection of unborn human life as simply a “Catholic” issue plays into the hands of the secularists who want to isolate the prolife doctrine as simply sectarian. Another weakness of Rico’s analysis is his failure to recognize that John Paul II’s call for the legal protection of innocent human life is in complete accord with Dignitaitis humanae, number 7, which teaches that in the exercise of their freedom human beings are “bound by the moral law” and “the rights of others” (including the unborn it would seem!). Moreover, Dignitatis humanae, number 11, supports the pontiff ’s “prophetic denunciation” of abortion by praising the apostles “who were not afraid to speak out against public authority when it opposed God’s holy will.” It should also be noted that John Paul II’s main appeal in Evangelium vitae is for Catholic legislators to work for the legal protection of the unborn.The pontiff does not need to dialogue with members of his own flock since he assumes that they already accept Catholic moral teaching. For those who are not Catholic, he assumes an awareness of the natural law that stands in stark contrast to the evil of abortion. This leads to the last weakness of Rico’s book: his reduction of John Paul II to simply one interpreter of Vatican II rather than its authoritative interpreter. Fr. Rico presents many valuable details of John Paul II’s personal involvement with the council’s discussions on religious freedom. It would seem that the Holy Father, who was personally present for these conciliar deliberations, should have a better understanding of what Dignitatis humanae actually taught than later commentators like Hollenbach and Hehir. Beyond this, Rico should manifest greater deference to the teachings of the Roman pontiff, who, according to Lumen gentium, number 22, N&V is “the Vicar of Christ and shepherd of the whole Church.” Robert Fastiggi Sacred Heart Major Seminary Detroit, Michigan 212 Book Reviews The Wisdom of Aristotle by Carlo Natali, translated by G. Parks (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2001), xii + 259 pp. T HIS IS A VERY GOOD translation of a book Carlo Natali published in Italian ten years ago. The English version, appropriately, includes an afterword that is meant to fill the ten-year gap by summarizing the most recent debate on the Nicomachean Ethics. Natali proves to be very competent, not only in the Italian scholarship on Aristotle’s ethics, but also in the contemporary German, French, and American literature.The expert reader of Aristotle will appreciate the author’s constant and careful use of Aristotle’s original Greek terms, and his ability to always frame the discussion of the ethics into the overall context of Aristotle’s thought and writings. It is worth mentioning the book’s critical apparatus, which counts many detailed and useful footnotes, the list of “Texts Cited,” an “Index of Greek Terms,” an “Index of Names,” an “Index of Passages Cited,” and a “Subject Index.” The book is entirely dedicated to Aristotle’s concept of phronêsis— which Natali identifies with practical knowledge and reasoning—and counts four chapters, respectively, “Virtue or Science?” “Ends and Means,” “The Practical Syllogism,” and “Aristotle’s Conception of Happiness.” Strictly speaking, the key chapters are the first three, in which it is explained how moral knowledge originates choice and action. However, by concluding the book after those chapters “the reader would have received a slightly distorted image of ” practical knowledge, running “the risk of limiting wisdom’s field of action to individual choices, and to particular moments of human life” (111).We might add that the fourth chapter appears less systematic and well organized than the former, and not perfectly integrated in the overall structure of the book; as if Natali had originally conceived it independently on the other chapters. The first chapter introduces and states the main theses of the book: namely, that phronêsis is not science (epistêmê) due to its intrinsic connection with the right desire (that is, with the ethical virtues); this connection is the specific trait of practical knowledge as practical.Two other key theses of the book, which align Natali with some recent trends in the interpretation of Aristotle’s ethics, are: (1) the thesis that phronêsis interacts with the ethical virtues in determining the ends of the action; and (2) the thesis that practical syllogism concludes with the actual action, but it is only symbolically a syllogism as it involves many middle terms, and in the last analysis, it cannot be said to have a major and a minor premise. But let us go back to the first chapter. Natali begins by criticizing von Arnim, who argued that Aristotle, in the Topics, identified phronêsis and epistêmê. Natali thinks that the Topics Book Reviews 213 does not contain a definite doctrine of phronêsis. However, it defines phronêsis as a virtue (“the virtue of the rational part of the soul”; 2) and outlines a conceptual difference between virtue and science—as “a science, unlike a virtue, can also produce evil” (6). “In the Topics, Aristotle had not yet formulated the concept of aretê dianoêtikê, that is, a virtue of the intellect, a concept applicable even to the most rigorous science” (3). In the Magna moralia as well “it is certain that a virtue cannot be science, but it is not certain what phronêsis is” (10). The solution comes with the Eudemian Ethics and the Nicomachean Ethics, where phronêsis is featured as a virtue of the rational part of the soul devoted to taking decision (logistikon), and the ethical virtues are featured as the virtues of the irrational part of the soul. It follows that “truth is an essential aspect of practical knowledge” (12) because truth is the function (ergon) of the entire rational part of the soul. Truth is not enough, though, as practical knowledge is about the good action to perform. Phronêsis, therefore, necessarily contains within itself an element of personal and emotional participation, of good desire; this makes it a different kind of knowledge from pure science. . . . If one possesses phronêsis, one’s desire naturally tends towards the good and cannot be directed toward anything else, not even by accident, without causing phronêsis itself to disappear. For this reason, of all the intellectual virtues it is the one closest to the ethical virtues. (12–13; see also 16, 19, and 26) We should certainly praise Natali for underlining that phronêsis is about truth and that, as the virtue of the good moral reasoning, it must be intrinsically connected to the right desire. However, there are two things that should raise our suspicion. One is the hasty identification of phronêsis with practical knowledge, which might involve a reductive view of practical knowledge that finally leaves phronêsis’s truth ungrounded.The other is the translation of Aristotle’s “logon” and “alogon” as, respectively,“rational” and “irrational,” which might irremediably relegate the ethical virtues to a part of the soul that is, in our sense of the word, intrinsically irrational.The two points are dangerously connected as Natali agrees that phronêsis is basically about reasoning (16–19), and that, even if there is an interaction, the primacy in giving the ends to moral action lies on the side of the ethical virtues. The feeling is therefore strong that, notwithstanding the author’s statements to the contrary, his account of moral action will end up being essentially irrational. The remaining part of chapter 1 (19–37) is devoted to a more detailed distinction between phronêsis, on the one hand, and “science” (or “sophia”) and “technique” (“skill, or art”), on the other (19 and 25). All 214 Book Reviews the specific features of phronêsis are “due to the fact” that it is “linked to a habitual state of desire” (26). Unlike teknê, phronêsis does not aim to results that “are tools for something else” (24). Unlike episteme and sophia, phronêsis: (a) “is not an exact science”; (b) “deals with things that can be otherwise”; (c) in this, it is similar to physics; (d) but its end is “action, not knowledge”; (e) therefore, “in it, particular propositions”—or the minor premises, which deal “with particular cases”—“are more important than universal propositions”; (f) for the same reason, it requires experience of life; (g) it allows for predictability, as “there is a certain consistency in human events” that permits “inferences and generalizations”; and (h) it is different than the treatise of ethics given by the philosophers (like the Nicomachean Ethics). Natali’s discussion is very useful but this part of the chapter is not very systematic, and the reader needs to make an effort to orderly identify phronêsis’s main traits. The reason is probably that the author is always too close to an exegetical approach to Aristotle’s texts, and sometimes the exegetical exposition prevails over a clear systematic treatment of the relevant concepts. It is worth mentioning the author’s emphasis on Aristotle’s theory requiring freedom. “Practical actions do not happen of necessity” as “by nature, man is capable of behaving in contrary ways”:“Wrong, or morally unacceptable, behavior is thus more frequent than exceptions to the laws of nature, which are rare and monstrous” (32–33). At page 24 there is something of which I cannot make sense. Natali puts together praxis and teknê by calling them both “practical knowledge,” and by saying that “practical and technical reason require that true judgment and correct desire should be made to agree.” A few lines later he says that “the two types of practical knowledge differ in genus”—but how can two species of the same genus (that is, practical knowledge) differ in genus?—and he adds that “teknê” can also be purposely distorted and used for a bad end. Now, this last statement is definitely correct but it clearly seems to contradict the previous line on “correct desire.” The second chapter aims at explaining Aristotle’s thesis that, in moral action, the ends are provided by ethical virtues (desire) and the means by phronêsis (reason). Natali adds two main qualifications: (1) that the search for the means requires desire, too, and this is why deliberation is different than mere justification; and (2) that determination of the ends requires reason, too, and this is ultimately why moral action is not irrational. For Natali (interpreting Nicomachean Ethics, 6, 1144b1–17), ethical virtues without logos are “blind,” as they do not know “how to achieve [the good] in practice” (52); this is why phronêsis is essential to the determination of the ends. So far so good; but, pace Natali, this is not enough to Book Reviews 215 make the action rational.That the ethical virtues without phronêsis do not know “how to achieve the good in practice” does not mean, strictly speaking, that they are “blind” with respect to the good or end.And even if phronêsis were to ethical virtues as good glasses are to a near-sighted person, we could not say that phronêsis provides the seen object but just the capacity to see it.To be sure: Natali really thinks that, as far as moral action is concerned, ethical virtues and desire are on the irrational side and that the rational side is all about phronêsis. This is why he interprets all Aristotle’s references to the (practical) nous (not only Nicomachean Ethics, 6, 1144b12) as related just to the grasping “of the minor premise of the syllogism” (53); and he says that there is no such a thing as a (practical) nous grasping the good and the first principles of practical reasoning at the level of the major premise (see 59). Let me say that this is a strange Aristotle, in whom a train of reasoning can start without first principles known by the intellect. Natali thinks that there is no vicious circle in his interpretation of Aristotle because “phronêsis and virtue belong to two different parts of the soul, and their collaboration poses no logical problem” (55). Does he not see that this separation is exactly the reason why his interpretation cannot logically work? If the ends are not known as such by the part of the soul endowed with intellectual power, reasoning about them will never start. As Descartes with res extensa and res cogitans, Natali, in order to give the ends to the logos, has to create a link between rational and irrational parts of the soul, and his solution is astounding: “Our hypothesis, then, is that, according to Aristotle, virtue in general can, in a given situation, take some non-practical, pre-existing doxa as a practical principle, making it into an object of desire, and therefore, turning it into an end” (60). If this were so, the choice of one doxa instead of another would not be a choice at all but an instinct-like event, and our practical principles would be radically irrational. But why should our intellect accept this event as the principle of its own activity in the first place? Let me add that there is a formal contradiction between maintaining: (1) that logos grounds the rationality of desire by making the virtues see “how to achieve the good in practice” (here logos grounds the rationality of desire); and (2) that desire gives the start to logos by transforming a doxa into a (rational) practical principle (here desire grounds the rationality of logos). At any rate, given this approach, we should already expect Natali to give an account of the practical syllogism in which the major premise is substantially deprived of any real role. Let us see. Chapter three starts with a defense of the formal syllogistic structure of the practical syllogism that, in turn, determines the main organization of 216 Book Reviews the chapter itself:“The Major Premise” (section 2),“The Minor Premise” (section 3),“The Link Between the Two Types of Premise” (section 4), and “The Conclusion Is an Action” (section 5). As for the major premise, Natali locates it in the calculative part of the soul (see esp. 69); this is his basic way to reduce the major premise to the minor premise. He repeats at length that the first principles of practical reasoning are not acquired by “noetic intuitions” but by “habits” due to social education, rewards, and punishments (73–75). I think Natali missed a distinction here between the (very) first principles of practical reasoning—which depend on experience but must precede reasoning—and major premises (first principles of the syllogisms), which depend on both experience and (scientific) reasoning (dianoia). As for the minor premise, Natali identifies it with “deliberation” (“the search for the middle term”). This leads him to portray three cases in which, having no need for searching the middle term, there is supposedly a practical syllogism without minor premise: namely, (1) in the case of “exact and autonomous science” such as grammar, as “we are in no doubt about how to write”; (2) when “akrasia [weakness of the will] is the result of impetuosity,” and “one passes directly from the perception of a particular situation to action”; and (3) when “the minor premise is so obvious it need not be formulated” (76–78). Of course, if we conceptually distinguish “middle term” from “search for the middle term,” cases 1 and 3 fall immediately apart because case 1, to be sure about the right means, does not make the knowledge of it (that is, the middle term) unnecessary to the action, and case 3, not to formulate the minor premise, does not mean that we do not know what we do while acting—as when we say “Too late!” we know that time cannot go backward even if we do not focus on this truth explicitly. As for case 2, it is very difficult to say that there is anything there resembling a practical syllogism at all. In any case, the identification of minor premise and deliberation process explains why Natali talks finally about “middle terms” in the plural (for example, 97) and reduces the practical syllogism to be no more and no less than practical reasoning (95–96). In the end, in Natali’s account, there is no real distinction between major and minor premises; actually, there is no minor premise at all. Practical syllogism is a reasoning process in which a practical premise (that is, a mix of doxa and desire) is the more and more specified until becoming so concrete that it leads automatically to action. Desire is the engine of the whole process. Sometimes no step is required, sometimes many are:This does not change its nature. But . . . is this Aristotle? In chapter four, Natali offers a useful survey of the dominant-vs.inclusive-end debate and an interesting comparison between Aristotle’s Book Reviews 217 position and the positions held in Plato’s Academy (111–24). He gives special importance to the distinction between (component) “parts” and “necessary conditions” of happiness, because the definitions given by Aristotle “mention only the component parts and not the necessary conditions” (126). For Natali, “Aristotle’s theory of happiness has [a] a formal part, which consists in the identification of happiness with” active life and “in the distinction between the component parts and the necessary conditions”; and [b] a “substantive” part, which “provides indications regarding what the most important of all the virtues activity is” and “what is the most important amount of external good or necessary conditions of happiness” (165). Natali’s main goal, in this chapter, is to harmonize the two main definitions of happiness given by Aristotle: namely, “activity in accordance with complete virtue” and “activity in accordance with the best and most perfect virtue” (117). He apparently does so by reducing the first to the second: that is, by saying that “the most perfect virtue” is “the virtue of the most important part of the rational soul,”“it includes both sophia and phronêsis,” and “it is not at all just theoria” (151). Is this the prelude to a watered-down concept of ultimate end? Actually, this seems to be the case if we just look also at pages 141 and 143, where Natali suggests that “honor, pleasure, knowledge, and every virtue” are “chosen for their own sake” in the sense that they can be chosen “only” for their own sake and not necessarily “also” for happiness—here happiness ceases to be an ultimate end formally necessary to action. Natali’s book, notwithstanding some questionable theses and interpretations, must definitely be read carefully by every scholar who works on Aristotle’s ethics. It would have been a more pleasurable reading, though, if it had had a little less of an exegetical approach and a little more of a N&V systematic approach. Fulvio Di Blasi University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana Common Calling: The Laity and Governance of the Catholic Church edited by Stephen J. Pope (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2004), 272 pp. T HE BOOK Common Calling was put together after the scandals over a number of priests being found to be involved in homosexual activity (which is not referred to specifically in the book which is an interesting fact in itself) and child abuse. There is understandable anger over the scandal, 218 Book Reviews and in the book, this is, not unreasonably, attributed to a failure in the governance of the Church. But what is interesting is the premise of the book, as it is formulated by Stephen Pope in his introduction, which says: “How the current system of ecclesial governance might be improved and made more responsive to the needs of believers,” (1) which is actually a different question. More about this further on. The other authors also want to change the leadership structure in the Church. Some of the motivations, at least as they are presented, are very reasonable. For example, Michael J. Buckley, SJ, says of the choice of bishops by the clergy and people in the eleventh century: “I think that if we were to follow this practice we would get better bishops in greater numbers” (74). One would of course wonder how this logically follows from acclamation. So there is at least the expression of a longing for “better bishops.”Then there are the more problematic formulations, such as those of Lisa Sowle Cahill, who claims that “the historical interpretations of Jesus that have formed official Catholic views of women participate in the sexism of centuries of cultural patriarchy” (136). These two views illustrate the real nub of the problem with parts of the book, and that is that the theology of history, which is being used, is itself flawed. This is probably the most fundamental difficulty with the book. Let me explain what I mean: Several of the authors offer “historical” studies that are then used with various nuances to argue for changes in the leadership structures of the Church.The studies such as the ones on “Cyprian on the Role of the Laity in Decision Making in the Early Church” (Francis A. Sullivan, SJ), the “Laity and the Development of Doctrine: Perspectives from the Early Church” (Francine Cardman), and “Resources for Reform from the First Millennium” (Buckley), and R. Scott Appleby’s examination of the lay trusteeship issue in the U.S., raise a web of issues, but really the fundamental question is what does history mean? Then more specifically, what does it mean to say that the Church is a phenomenon in history. Some of the authors are aware that the past cannot simply be transposed into the present. For example, Sullivan says “one cannot simply repeat history” (48). But the more radical and extremist views, such as those of Cahill, presuppose that modern Western authors have some special situation in history—as a radical feminist, for example—that supersedes any other particular moment in history and any office in the church. Historicity is an inescapable feature of human ontology, but the historicity of the Church is of a different order. It is a history within the action of the Holy Spirit. According to the Second Vatican Council, the key signs of the Church are the Scriptures and Tradition, the People of Book Reviews 219 God, the Apostolic Succession, the hierarchy, and the sacraments. But not every one of the other elements, such as events and practices, let me call them historical artifacts of the Church, is simply “there” for future use. There is a way in which the complex of the Church moves on, even as the key elements remain. While the Church never forgets that once, for example, bishops were appointed by acclamation, at the same time it is the authentic practice of the Church at this point in time that bishops are appointed by the Congregation for Bishops after surveys of a number of different groups in the Church.This is authentic practice, which is to say that it fits the mandate of Christ as exercised by the present day authorities in the Church. This brief consideration brings us to the shift in project that was alluded to above. The book starts with a totally justifiable complaint about the occurrence of the scandal and the poor handling of the scandal. The leap is then made that the structure of the Church must be changed.The notion of moral failure of individuals is not fully addressed. The further leap is that, of course, laity should have more of a hand in the leadership of the Church. I did not find any justifications for any of these leaps of logic in the book except the prevailing presupposition that this is obvious. What has happened is that current left-wing agendas are being trotted out because the Church has been wounded. Having said this, there was one chapter that, to my mind, attempted to really identify the problem and suggest a logically consequent response. In his chapter titled “Weathering ‘the Perfect Storm’:The contribution of Canon Law,” John Beal, correctly in my view, identifies the convergence of problems that one sees in the scandal.These are (1) the resentment of the faithful and the lower clergy at the “lack of accountability, transparency, and opportunities for participation in church governance” (165); and (2) the “allegedly arbitrary and capricious treatment of [laity and clergy] by diocesan bishops” (166). This book itself is a product of the convergence of these currents. However Beal does make a further positive contribution by explaining how the Catholic Church in America developed its structures, on the one hand, to accommodate to civil requirements and how it also resisted Vatican pressure “to impose cathedral chapters, which would have provided for genuine co-responsibility in diocesan administration” (170). Then on the other hand, the church also adopted “made for business models” (170) of administration.This is a telling point and from my reading, not one that is addressed substantially elsewhere in the literature. Whatever one finally concludes about Beal’s argument, he at least sets up a historically and theologically coherent proposal, and that is that 220 Book Reviews “canon law suggests that the church might begin by abandoning the wholly uncanonical corporation sole model for diocesan organization, and the corporation sole mentality” that goes with it (171). He has tried to identify the historical accretion—the corporation sole structure—and has done the more theologically valid task of returning to the kernel of the structure of the Church. It would take a canon lawyer to analyze his proposal further, but epistemologically his chapter is way ahead of the others in the volume. The other chapters are more of a patchwork of genuine expressions of concern, of complaints about clericalism, and thoughts about changes in structure, and these are then mixed with forlorn hopes such as Mary Jo Bane’s:“I personally believe that a process of collective discernment, guided by the Spirit, would come to a different position on birth control than the one currently held officially by the Church” (187). Another example is Terence L. Nichol’s criticism of the Conferencia Episcopal de Latino América for not putting clerical celibacy on the agenda for the conference (123). The authors tend to leap out of the theological framework to embrace politically correct positions based on no more than a fond hope. There are a number of theological problems scattered through the text. Let me just offer a few examples. Either one claims the mandate for completely rewriting Scripture (Cahill, above) or one demonstrates a problematic grasp of the context of Scripture itself. Witness Pope’s trotting out the old saw that the distinction between the clergy and the laity emerges only in the second century (4).The fact is that even though the words “clergy” and “laity” do not appear in the Scriptures, the acts of Jesus that gave rise to the distinction are clearly laid out in the New Testament (for example, Lk 6). Let me call Pope’s error an error in the theology of foundation. He does not grasp the completeness of the deposit of faith in the revelation of Jesus Christ.The distinction between clergy and laity then becomes a merely historical development. The erroneous implication is then that what has developed can be changed. The same lack of proper categories arises when Pope tries to shift the clergy-laity distinction to something that he wants to base on “the equal dignity of baptism” (5). When he looks at Vatican II, the same undifferentiated “something,” because it certainly is not the Church, is supposed to be apparent in the Church’s description as a “mystery” and a “sacrament” (6).The same appeals to undoubted common features, which then are presumed to override the distinctive features in the theological complex of the Church, appear in the chapter by Appleby and his appeal to “collegiality at every level” (105) and Nichol’s claim to a “participatory hierarchy” (111). Book Reviews 221 This latter view apparently was the “kind of hierarchy Jesus practiced” (115). Now, while it is clear in the Scriptures that Jesus saw that “authority is service” (117), this does not describe the whole of Jesus’ presence, it is also clear that Jesus also said:“Teach them all that I have commanded you” (Mt 28:20), which is an authoritative act, and it is commanding others to act with authority since holding people to the truth is indeed a service. It is the slipperiness with categories that is the most disturbing feature of the book since terms in theology have meanings, they indicate certain relations. Without this most basic commitment, dialog is impossible. A healthy consequence of the scandals should be a serious reflection on the Church and how it operates, but serious reflection requires taking the epistemological categories seriously! N&V Bevil Bramwell, OMI Ave Maria University Naples, Florida