Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 1–16 1 Hommage au Père Servais-Théodore Pinckaers, OP The Significance of His Work ROMANUS C ESSARIO, O. P. St. John’s Seminary Brighton, Massachusetts Reverend Fathers, Distinguished Ladies and Gentleman: I T IS CUSTOMARY for speakers in my position to express their gratitude to those who invited them. I must acquit myself of a double obligation. First, to Father Michael Sherwin and Professor Craig Titus, who graciously arranged this tribute in honor of Father Pinckaers, and to the Dominican Fathers at the Albertinum, and its other Swiss sponsors, whose customary largesse has made this celebratory gathering possible. In addition, I owe a debt of gratitude to the aforementioned persons, both individual and corporate, because their generosity affords me an occasion to return to my alma mater. Since October 1976, when as a young priest I came here to study, Fribourg, the place and the school— they are difficult to distinguish for those who love both—has done admirably what one expects “dear mothers” to do, namely, to shape a man’s life in significant ways.1 And so I say, simply, “Thank you!” Who in my position, I now ask you, would not recollect what Aristotle, in the Nicomachean Ethics, affirms—admittedly to explain its inadequacy as the ultimate good for man—about honor: “Honor depends more on those who confer than on him who receives it.”2 The person whose merits we recognize today deserves great honor, and to be candid, I consider myself unequal to the task of conferring it. So this evening, I stand before you as a spokesman—a stand-in, if you will—for the many 1 For example, see my “Theology at Fribourg,” The Thomist 51 (1987): 325–66. 2 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, bk 1, ch. 5, 1095b25, trans. J. A. K. Thomson, The Ethics of Aristotle, (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1955), 30. 2 Romanus Cessario, OP persons throughout the Catholic world and beyond who, better than I am able, would fittingly confer honor on this university professor and Dominican priest, Servais Pinckaers. During this weekend, his work, son travail, gladly will occupy our attentions.3 I am sure that our honoree, who elucidates and exemplifies both the Christian virtue and gift of piety, will pose no objection to my expressing his appreciation to each of you, and especially to the Dominicans at Fribourg. Since Father Pinckaers’s arrival here in 1973, his Dominican brothers have supplied the spiritual and temporal support that have enabled him to complete the better part of the labors for which we do rightly honor him under the sign of Ephesians 1:10,“Making all things new in Christ.”4 The Roman historian and stylist Livy wrote,“Favor and honor sometimes fall more fitly on those who do not desire them.”5 To whom does this classical adage better apply than to our dear friend, Servais Théodore Pinckaers, revered theologian, holy priest, and exemplary Friar Preacher? Friar Preacher The Dominicans first arrived at Fribourg during a particularly stressful period in their modern history: the last quarter of the nineteenth century. The order’s numbers were in decline such that from 4,562 in 1844, membership fell to 3,474 in 1876, the lowest it had been since the thirteenth century. Is it not paradoxical that after twenty-two years of reformminded leadership inspired by Henri-Dominic Lacordaire, the Dominican Master Alexandre-Vincent Jandel (1850–1855–1872) left an almost extinct order well-organized and vigorous.6 Moreover, the situation in Europe made Dominican governance difficult to conduct until, in 1879, Joseph M. Larroca (1879–91) was chosen by mail-in balloting to lead the order.7 He 3 Webster’s New Dictionary of Synonyms reports on the English cognate:“Travail carries a stronger implication of painful effort or exertion than does labor; that connotation is often so strong that the term tends to denote suffering rather than labor.” 4 See Eph 1:10: “In dispensationem plenitudinis temporum instaurare omnia in Christo quae in caelis et quae in terra sunt in ipso.” 5 Titus Livius, The History of Rome, Bk. 4, 57. 6 See William A. Hinnebusch, OP, The Dominicans:A Short History (New York:Alba House, 1975), ch. 10. In 1850, Father Jandel was named vicar general of the order directly by Pope Pius IX, and then in 1855, master general of the order. See Catholicisme, vol. 6, 310. 7 Dominican historian Guy Bedouelle observes in a private communication with the author: “[C]e n’est pas l’election de Larroca qui a rendu le gouvernement de l’ordre plus facile. C’est le fait que Pie IX a aboli en 1872 la bulle de 1804 qui soustrayait les provinces espagnoles de la juridiction du Maitre de l’Ordre, à la suite de quoi Jandel a choisi Larroca comme socius, puis est venue l’election de Larroca, comme espagnol, ce qui a en effet stabilisé l’unité de l’ordre.” Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 3 was the first master general since before the French Revolution to be elected by all of the Dominican provinces. It was under his leadership that the Dominican general chapter of Louvain in 1885 launched the École Biblique in Jerusalem and accepted the request of the government of Fribourg to staff the theology faculty of its new university.Today, it is gratifying to discover mention, on the faculty of theology’s Web site, of the international reputation of alma mater Fribourg that Dominicans since 1890 have helped to build.8 This weekend, we will discover additional warrant for this claim as scholars from Switzerland and abroad describe the contribution to this “rayonnement international” made by one of our contemporaries, a certain Dominican from Belgium. Belgium The Dominicans were established in Ghent as early as 1228. It should come as no surprise to learn that Flanders and Wallonia enjoy prominence in the history of the Dominican Order.And not only for Flemings and Walloons. In 1658, the English Dominican Philip Thomas Howard (who in 1675 became “Cardinal of Norfolk”) acquired the Convent of the Holy Cross at Bornhem, a Flemish town situated a few miles southwest of Antwerp. He took this initiative for the purpose of giving new life to the English province, which in the 1650s, the period of the Commonwealth and the Protectorate governments in England (1649–60), had come perilously close to extinction.9 This Bornhem cloister originally built for, but never inhabited by, Franciscans would serve for 167 years the needs of expatriate English Dominicans.10 8 University of Fribourg Web site, Faculty of Theology, “L’Université de Fribourg–Bref aperçu historique,” www.unifr.ch/theo/presentation/index.html. 9 The English Commonwealth and Protectorate were republican governments of England introduced after the English Civil War during the Interregnum (1649–60). The Commonwealth (1649–53) was founded on the execution of Charles I in 1649, and was followed by the two Protectorates of Oliver Cromwell (1653–58), and his son Richard Cromwell (1658–59). The Commonwealth was briefly revived (1659–60), before the restoration of the monarchy in the person of Charles II in May 1660. For more information on this work of Father Thomas Howard, see C. F. Raymund Palmer, The Life of Philip Thomas Howard, OP, Cardinal of Norfolk, Grand Almoner to Catherine of Braganza, Queen-Consort of King Charles II., and Restorer of the English Province of Friar-Preachers or Dominicans. Compiled from Original Manuscripts, with a Sketch of the Rise, Missions, and Influence of the Dominican Order, and of Its Early History in England (London: Thomas Richardson and Son, 1867), 98–107. 10 For a good account of the English College at Bornhem, see Raymund Palmer, OP, “Bygone Colleges: Bornhem and Carshalton,” Merry England 12 (1889): 310–24; ibid., Merry England 12 (1889): 370–97.This article appears in this literary journal 4 Romanus Cessario, OP One of these expatriates was Thomas Williams, a native of Monmouthshire.11 This young Englishman made his way in 1685 to East Flanders, and there when he was only seventeen took the Dominican habit at Bornhem. In 1740, he died a bishop, having been consecrated by the Dominican Pope Benedict XIII (1724–30) to serve as vicar-apostolic of the northern district of England, a posting that reflects the gradualness of the restoration that the Catholic hierarchy underwent in the British Isles. Since the appointment of Thomas Williams involved Catholic affairs in England, the Holy See sought to obtain the pleasure of the Old Pretender, James Edward Stuart (1688–1766), who was recognized in Rome as James III.This same James Stuart, it is said, lodged on his southward journey from France to Rome in the structure that today houses the Albertinum. The significance of this event is left to the professional historians to decipher, especially in light of the evolution of European politics that required this Stuart prince to leave France after the Treaty of Utrecht in 1713. During the eighteenth century, the English Dominicans set up a study house in Louvain, the “College of St. Thomas Aquinas of the English Friar-Preachers,” located on the Krakenstraat. As a young priest,Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire arrived there from Rome, where he had been sent for studies, to organize the new project. While at Louvain, he wrote and printed three scholastic theses: the first on God (1701), the second on the Trinity and the Incarnation (1703), and the third, in 1705, on a subject that occupies the energies of all intellectually alert Dominicans, especially after a papal cease-fire order in 1607 returned to theologians the discussion of issues left unsettled during the Congregatio de Auxiliis:“Thomismus ex Thomistis assertus & contra Novos ejus impugnatores vindicatus, seu Theses Theologicæ de Scientiâ,Voluntate et Providentiâ Dei, Juxta inconcussa tutissimaque dogmata Angelici & Quinti Ecclesiae Doctoris D. Thomae Aquinatis.”12 We find ourselves face-toface with the Thomism of the Late Baroque, an age that in Flanders falls under the rubric, “The Collegian.” Also see, Godfrey Anstruther, OP, A Hundred Homeless Years: English Dominicans 1558–1658 (London: Blackfriars Publications, 1958). 11 Information on Thomas Williams is drawn from another article by Raymund Palmer, OP, “A Consecrated Life,” Merry England 10 (1887): 411–28; ibid., Merry England 10 (1888): 480–95. 12 The inscription continues: “Quas Præside F. Dominico Williams, S. Theologiae Præsentato, necnon Collegii et Studii FF. Prædicat.Anglorum Rectore, Defendet F. Ambrosius Burgis, eiusd. Ord. Lovanii in Conventu Majori Ord. FF. Prædicatorum, die 12 Maii, horâ 9 ante merid. Lovanii, apud Ægidium Dènique. Anno 1705. In 4to, 18, num.” Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 5 under the artistic shadow of Peter Paul Rubens (1577–1640) and his successors, including Anthony Van Dyck (1599–1641), whose painting, Charles I Dismounted, displays the ill-fated English king (1600–49) in a posture of self-assurance that in retrospect evokes the political and religious instability that compelled English and Irish Catholics to seek a safe haven in Flanders.13 Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire illustrates what English and other Dominicans were doing in Flanders at the start of the eighteenth century. They made the doctrine of St.Thomas Aquinas available to the many who were prepared themselves to receive it. This apostolic work continued in one way or another until the end of the eighteenth century. Indeed upon the papal suppression of the Jesuits in 1773, the Belgic-Austrian authorities prevailed on the English Dominicans to take charge of the two colleges conducted by the English Jesuits in Bruges—the former Jesuit teachers themselves being led off as prisoners. When the Dominicans demurred pleading scarcity of men in their ranks, down came an imperial edict from Maria Theresa (d. 1780), Dowager Empress of the Austrian Netherlands: “Vénérable, Cher, et Bien Aimé, . . . Nous vous ordonnons. . . .”14 Her English guests acceded, of course. Friends of the Jesuits, meanwhile, acted to facilitate the withdrawal from the “Great College” of students who protested with unruliness its change of directors and, within a few days, the Dominicans were absolved of responsibility for it. One Bornhem Dominican, however, Father Augustine Noel, did take charge of the “Little College” where younger boys studied. Within a few months, however, these students also dwindled in number, and Father Noel returned to teaching theology at Louvain, remaining there until 1792 when he moved back to Bornhem.15 Shortly thereafter, forces other than and hostile toward Thomism became startlingly active in Flanders. In 1794, French revolutionary troops invaded the Antwerp region, and eventually spread out into the countryside. Most English Dominicans were forced to flee Bornhem and to seek passage across the English Channel, where no commodious welcome was assured them. Among those who remained to guard the college and convent buildings was a young American from St. Mary’s County, Maryland (a colony named after the queen consort of Charles I, the French princess Henrietta Maria 13 This oil on canvas, which dates from about 1635, now hangs in the Louvre in Paris. For an account of the precarious status of the Dominicans in England from the death of Queen Mary I in 1558 until the execution of Charles I in 1649, see Palmer, The Life of Philip Thomas Howard, 70–78. 14 Palmer, “Bygone Colleges,” 375. 15 Ibid., 374–77. Romanus Cessario, OP 6 [1609–69]), who had been ordained a priest the year before.16 Although briefly imprisoned by the French revolutionary forces, Father Fenwick was released, I am happy to report, when he protested that he was a bona fide citizen of the United States of America. Edward Fenwick (1768–1832) left his native land when he was only sixteen and joined the Dominicans in 1790 at Bornhem, just as Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire had done a century before. Like Williams, who took the name Dominic at his religious profession, Edward Dominic Fenwick also died a bishop, the first of Cincinnati in the state of Ohio.17 This missionary priest is recognized as the founder of the Dominicans in the United States, specifically of the province of St. Joseph, which celebrates its two-hundredth anniversary this year [2005]. (Only Dominicans in California claim another beginning.) Father Fenwick’s departure from England for the United States in 1804 preceded the sale of the English College at Bornhem in 1825, which never recovered from the political disruptions of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries.18 The United States The province that Edward Dominic Fenwick founded eventually sent members back to both Belgium and Fribourg. One of them, the Louvain-trained Daniel Joseph Kennedy (d. 1930), formed part of the early professorial corps at Fribourg. He did not remain long, however, having taken exception to the policy that stipulates his salary belongs to the Albertinum instead of his home province.19 To the present day, other Dominicans from the United States have come to study and to teach at alma mater Fribourg.They also returned to Belgium. In the 1950s,American Dominicans (unlike the French we have no adjectival form for the United States) returned to study theology at the studium, Notre Dame de la Sarte, which since 1929 had been the location of a house of philosophy, and since 1941, of a faculty of theology for the Belgian province.20 It was here at La Sarte, close to Huy, that two years after his ordination our honoree began in 1953 his teaching of “moral theology in its entirety,” 16 Ibid., 382. 17 For a recent presentation of his life, see Loretta Petit, OP, Friar in the Wilderness, Edward Dominic Fenwick, OP (Chicago, IL: Project OPUS, 1994). 18 The buildings fell into the possession of Cistercian monks, who turned them into a parish school. For further information, see Benedictus van Doninck, Het voormalig Engelsch Klooster te Bornhem (Leuven: Peeters, 1904, 1986). 19 See Reginald M. Coffey, OP, The American Dominicans (New York: Saint Martin de Porres Guild, 1970), 510–11. 20 For information on this place of pilgrimage, see Corneille Antoine Halflants, Histoire de Notre Dame de la Sarte lez-Huy (Liège: H. Dessain, 1864). Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 7 as he recounts in an interview given in the year 2000.21 When, to respect linguistic differences in Belgium, the Province of St.Thomas in Belgium was established in 1958, the study house at La Sarte was recognized as a studium generale, a designation then with special significance in the Dominican Order.The suspension of theological teaching at La Sarte in 1964 providentially opened the way for Father Pinckaers’s arrival at Fribourg in 1973. Last month, The Tablet of London published Alasdair MacIntyre’s review of a posthumous book by the English Dominican Herbert McCabe (1926–2001) titled The Good Life: Ethics and the Pursuit of Happiness.22 At the end of the review, Professor MacIntyre observes that “this introduction to philosophical ethics points us towards a theological ethics, in which the narrative of our lives is understood in relation to the narrative of God’s self-giving.”23 He further describes McCabe’s vision of theological ethics as follows: “The life of friendship with others, a life of concern for their and our flourishing through growth in the virtues needed for human happiness, becomes through grace a life in which God shares his friendship with us.”24 There are very strong reasons to suppose that Alasdair MacIntyre would not have composed such an appreciation of Herbert McCabe and his English brand of Thomism—one, I should add, that careful analysis would show to exhibit the same theological underpinnings as those Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire defended three hundred years ago at Louvain in 1705—unless the distinguished Scottish philosopher had been introduced to and had come to appreciate deeply the moral theology of Father Pinckaers. One recent piece of evidence that favors this opinion comes from what Alasdair MacIntyre wrote in his preface to Father Michael Sherwin’s “impressive” translation of La morale catholique published in 2001 as Morality:The Catholic View.25 “Father Servais Pinckaers, op, is an extraordinary author, and this is an extraordinary book. The extraordinariness lies in Father Pinckaers’s rare 21 Interview with Carlo Leget, “Aquinas, a Revolutionary in Morality?” Newspage (2000), the Thomas Instituut te Utrecht, www.thomasinstituut.org/thomasinstituut/ scripts/nws_show.php?id=35. 22 Alasdair MacIntyre,“Fully Alive, Informed by Virtue,” Tablet (September 10, 2005): 22. 23 Ibid. 24 Ibid. 25 The original French edition was published by Les Éditions du Cerf, Paris, 1991 and the English edition by Saint Augustine’s Press, South Bend, IN, 2001, with a preface by Alasdair MacIntyre, vii–viii. Romanus Cessario, OP 8 ability to know precisely what needs to be said and when and how and to whom to say it.”26 As you may be aware, Professor MacIntyre is not given to glibness. Whence comes this extraordinariness? In July 1999, Father Pinckaers was invited to the University of Notre Dame in Indiana, and there he gave an interview that later was published in the American edition of Communio under the title “My Sources.”27 The man we honor tonight tells us of two principal influences on his theological work:The Blessed Eucharist and the Bible as the Word of God. The Eucharist Father Pinckaers offers testimony plain and straightforward: “I have felt the attraction of the Eucharistic presence since my infancy.”28 He in part attributes this grace to the mediation of the thirteenth-century Blessed Juliana of Mont-Cornillon (1192–1258) and thus to his native city, Liège on the Meuse. It is, furthermore, to the city of Liège that historians trace the origins of the Feast of Corpus Christi.This pious and liturgical observance arose about the time St. Thomas Aquinas was living close by in Cologne (1248–52), a student under St.Albert the Great.29 What is more significant, the young Dominicans of Liège, so Father Pinckaers assures us, rallied to the cause of introducing a special liturgical commemoration in honor of the Blessed Eucharist, which the Prince-Bishop of Liège authorized to be celebrated in his ecclesiastical state as early as 1246.The practice became popular, and spread elsewhere. In 1264, Pope Urban IV extended the solemnity to the universal Church and promulgated the Officium de festo Corporis Christi, which, it is now agreed,Aquinas composed during his period of service to the papal court in Orvieto (1261–65).30 The Bible His discovery of the Bible as the Word of God, Father Pinckaers identifies with the mediation of another religious person, Dom Olivier Rousseau (1898–1984), Benedictine monk of Chevetogne, who in 1945 preached 26 Alasdair MacIntyre, preface to Servais Pinckaers, OP, Morality:The Catholic View, trans. Michael Sherwin, OP (South Bend, IN: Saint Augustine’s Press, 2001), vii. 27 Servais Pinckaers, OP, “My Sources,” Communio 26 (1999): 913–15. 28 Ibid., 913. 29 For this dating see, Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1, The Person and His Work, trans. Robert Royal (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America, 1996), 24–35. 30 Torrell, Thomas Aquinas, 357, and ch. 7. Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 9 the novitiate retreat to the young Servais, now Brother Théodore, Pinckaers. Again, his testimony is arresting for its simplicity:“The awareness that the Word of God is superior to any human word was for a time . . . so strong in me that I did not want to read anything other than the Bible.”31 Dom Olivier Rousseau belonged to an innovative experiment in monasticism. The monastery of Chevetogne was founded in 1925 by Dom Lambert Beauduin (1873–1960), who resigned in 1928 after the Holy See sounded a cautious note on ecumenical “enterprises.”32 The monks of Chevetogne are liturgically organized in two groups, one celebrating according to the Western tradition, the other according to the Eastern Byzantine tradition. This arrangement has been in place from the beginning of the monastery, the two rites having been adopted for ecumenical reasons, and in view of the reconciliation between the Christian East and West.33 Within this setting, Dom Olivier Rousseau produced the Sources chrétiennes edition of Origen’s homilies on the Song of Songs.34 The early exposure to the theological accents of Chevetogne helps to explain why Father Pinckaers, following the practice of the Fathers of the Church, privileges the “spiritual” meaning of the Scriptures, one that develops out of a prayerful beholding of the Word of God. The monastery at Chevetogne occupies a place in both the ecumenical and the liturgical movements that, along with biblical studies, dominated the work of theology during the period between the two world wars.35 The then-Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, upon being received into 31 Pinckaers, “My Sources,” 913. 32 Pope Pius XI’s 1928 encyclical letter, Mortalium Animos, “On Religious Unity,” was the occasion for this initiative; see especially, no. 8. the Web site for the Monastère de Chevetogne at www.monaster echevetogne.com. 34 Origéne, Homélies sur le Cantique des Cantiques, 2nd ed., trans. Dom Olivier Rousseau, OSB (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1966). 35 The same year that Dom Olivier was giving his retreat to novice-brother Servais Théodore Pinckaers, this Benedictine monk also published Histoire du mouvement liturgique; esquisse historique depuis la début du XIXe siècle jusqu’au pontificat de Pie X (Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 1945).An English translation appeared six years later: The Progress of the Liturgy; an Historical Sketch from the Beginning of the Nineteenth Century to the Pontificate of Pius X, trans. Benedictines of Westminster Priory, Vancouver, B.C., (Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1951). The work offers a point of view on the development of the liturgical movement until 1903 that is respectfully critical of the styles of worship fostered by the nineteenth-century Solesmes Benedictine, Dom Prosper Guéranger (1805–75). For a different view of the legacy of Dom Guéranger judged from the present moment of liturgical practices, see Jonathan Gaspar and Romanus Cessario, OP, “ ‘Worthy of the Temple’: Liturgical Music and Theological Faith,” Nova et Vetera (English) 3 33 See 10 Romanus Cessario, OP the Pontifical Academy of Sciences during its plenary session November 8–11, 2002, remarked: “I did my philosophical and theological studies immediately after the war, from 1946 to 1951. In this period, theological formation in the faculty of Munich was essentially determined by the biblical, liturgical and ecumenical movement of the time between the two world wars.”36 Father Pinckaers, it is clear, finds himself formed within the same theological currents as those that shaped the current Roman Pontiff. At the same time, whereas Pope Benedict XVI devoted his early intellectual labors to the Franciscan tradition, our young Dominican from Belgium took up the intellectual tradition of his order, which had flourished in the region of Liège since 1232. I refer of course to Thomism, and to the distinctively Dominican mandate to make the doctrine of Aquinas available to the many. Thomas Aquinas From the references to Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire, one easily could take away the impression that Thomism in Belgium awaited the arrival of expatriate Englishmen to make a foothold there. On the contrary.Think of Dominic of Flanders (d. 1479) and Peter Crockaert of Brussels (d. 1514), to cite examples from the early modern period. In the eighteenth century, European Dominicans in Belgium who published scholarly texts explaining the doctrine of St. Thomas Aquinas numbered seventeen.37 Among them is the celebrated theologian and apologist, Charles René Billuart (1685–1757), whose Le thomisme vengé was published in Brussels in 1720. Father Pinckaers inserted himself into a tradition that, despite the diversity of interpretation on specific topics that it comprises, remains capable of creating a fellowship of common discourse that still sustains Dominican and Catholic intellectual life.38 (Dominicans who eschew Thomist fellowship in favor of here-today-gone-tomorrow intellectual fads miss out on the graces that make them reliable witnesses in (2005): 673–88. For some general observations on the present-day outcomes of the modern liturgical movement, see my forthcoming article,“The Sacraments of the Church in Sacrosanctum Concilium,” in Vatican II: Renewal within Tradition, ed. Matthew L. Lamb and Matthew Levering (forthcoming). 36 For the complete text of his remarks, see Pontifical Academy of Sciences, The Cultural Values of Science (Vatican City: Pontificia Academia Scientiarum, 2003), 50–52. 37 See Leonard A. Kennedy, CSB, A Catalogue of Thomists, 1270–1900 (Houston: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1987), 133–34. 38 For further explanation, see my A Short History of Thomism (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2005). Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 11 the Church.) Father Pinckaers expresses it best: “St. Thomas was my principal initiator in theology during my formation as a Dominican and especially later as I prepared courses based upon the texts of the Summa.”39 He claims as his own the style of historical Thomism that had been inherited by the studium at La Sarte from professors at Louvain.Those teachers who transmitted the thought of Aquinas to Father Pinckaers include his Dominican confreres: dogma professor (later cardinal of the Holy Roman Church [1985]) Jean Jérôme Hamer (1916–96), the Saulchoir-trained moralist Bernard Maximillian Olivier (1920–), and, at least indirectly, a founding figure of the studium at La Sarte, Louis Charlier. (The latter’s 1938 L’Essai sur le problème théologique found its way onto the “Index” because of certain untoward remarks on theological method, with the result that Father Charlier was affected for a period of time by the Roman sanctions of 1942.)40 Whoever may be tempted to conclude that Thomism imposes a monochromatic view of reality, natural or supernatural, should read more of the mainline Thomists. To announce that Servais Pinckaers brings luster to the Thomism practiced in the Order of St. Dominic is to do something that is obviously superfluous. It is like carrying coals to Newcastle, to borrow a British expression. (Newcastle is a city in northeast England where coal is mined.) Still, no commemoration of Servais Pinckaers would be complete without mentioning the retrieval of St.Thomas’s moral theology that this Belgian Dominican undertook in the period after the Second Vatican Council. His early essays published in the collection, Sein und Ethos in 1963, and, the next year, his first book, Le renouveau de la morale, demonstrate that he had escaped “from the prison of Kantian rationality”—“Thanks to Saint Thomas,” adds Father Pinckaers almost forty years later.41 St.Thomas also helped Servais Pinckaers escape from a prison whose bars, by the mid-1960s, were soon to be sundered in any event.Today, hardly a well-trained theology student in the United States does not realize that the four-hundred-year reign of textbook casuistry came to an abrupt end about 1965, and that the only credible replacement for this mode of moral argument unfolds from the moral theology 39 Pinckaers, “My Sources,” 914. 40 For a brief commentary, see Roger Aubert, “La théologie catholique. A. Durant la première moitié du XXe,” in Bilan de la Théologie du XXe Siècle, eds. R.V. Gucht and Herbert Vorgrimler, vol. 1 (Paris: Casterman, 1969), 443. For a more extended treatment, see R. Guelluy, “Les antécédents de l’encyclique ‘Humani generis’ dans les sanctions romaines de 1942: Chenu, Charlier, Draguet,” Revue d’histoire ecclésiastique 81 (1986): 421–97. 41 Pinckaers, “My Sources.” 12 Romanus Cessario, OP of Thomas Aquinas.42 They learned this historical lesson from reading Father Pinckaers, who himself best explains his program for renewal: The theology of St. Thomas and that of the manuals constitute two different moral systems, both of which have their own inner logic. Consequently, the way to renew moral theology is by returning to St. Thomas, as one who represents the best of the tradition nourished by the Scriptures and the Fathers of the Church.43 We sense the shadow of Dom Olivier Rousseau. No wonder Alasdair MacIntyre considers the work of Servais Pinckaers “extraordinary.” It would be difficult to estimate the influence that Father Pinckaers has exercised on the renewal of moral theology in the Catholic Church. One thinks of the Catechism of the Catholic Church and of the 1993 encyclical letter Veritatis Splendor that followed the initial publication in December 1992 of the Catechism. Those who have studied with Father Pinckaers, or have read carefully his works, recognize that these magisterial documents bear indisputably the stamp of his moral theological outlook.The same documents also set about to redress widespread errors in moral theology that gained ascendancy in the immediate aftermath of the Second Vatican Council, especially after the equally widespread negative reaction to the 1968 encyclical letter, Humanae Vitae, and which perdured thereafter for a quarter century. Before I left Boston for Zurich, I inquired of Father Pinckaers’s American publisher, Dr. David McGonagle at Catholic University of America Press, about the cumulative sales of The Sources of Christian Ethics.44 He replied that since its publication in 1995, the book, which is a translation of the 1993 third French edition, has sold more than 6,500 copies. “It remains,” wrote the publisher, “one of our best-selling books each year.”45 At this juncture, it would be remiss of me not to mention the work of Sister Mary Thomas Noble, Dominican nun of the Buffalo Monastery. More than any other person, Sister Mary Thomas has labored selflessly to make Father Pinckaers’s work 42 The manuals of the Flemish Dominican Benedict Merkelbach (1871–1942) represent this tradition, although they are thought to differ in important respects, for example, by placing an emphasis on virtue, from the prevailing casuist paradigms of the first half of the twentieth century. 43 Pinckaers, “My Sources,” 914. 44 Servais Pinckaers, OP, The Sources of Christian Ethics, trans. Sr. Mary Thomas Noble, OP, (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1995). 45 Private communication of October 3, 2005, from Mrs. Elizabeth Benevides to the author. Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 13 available to the English-speaking world.46 Alasdair MacIntyre deems her translation of Les sources “excellent.”47 For all his knowledge of and love for the Catholic tradition, Servais Pinckaers is not a theological antiquarian. His is not the project of restorationist theology that occupies the energies of some of our contemporaries, and that others are tempted to think provides the only way out of the impasse that Catholic theology at the start of the twenty-first century arguably finds itself bogged down in. Father Pinckaers supplies commentary on Fides et Ratio as much as on Veritatis Splendor. His own testimony speaks for itself: “Firm in my faith [from Eucharist, Bible, Aquinas], I was able to undertake the study of ancient and modern philosophers . . . a study that is necessary if one desires to be enriched by experience and to acquire a mind that is open to all that is human.”48 His broad reading in philosophy strengthened his practice of Thomism.“The engagement with modern and contemporary authors,” he attests, “is necessary in order to render the teaching of St. Thomas current for our own time.”49 If due allowance is made for rhetorical differences, this counsel displays a form of spiritual communion with Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire:“Thomismus ex Thomistis assertus & contra Novos ejus impugnatores vindicatus.” In 1993 Father Pinckaers published an essay in the Revue Thomiste which that indefatigable contemplative Dominican, Sister Mary Thomas Noble, translated for The Pinckaers Reader, itself a work of piety by professors John Berkman and Craig Titus. “Dominican Moral Theology in the 20th Century” reports mainly on the moral theology taught in the European French-speaking Dominican Houses of Study and at Fribourg.50 In this article, Father Pinckaers situates himself within the company of men who contributed to the making of moral theology during the preceding century. He tells his own story, as it were.The present encomium aims to locate Father Pinckaers within the big picture of Catholic and Dominican intellectual life. It is clearly impossible to acknowledge every figure 46 In addition to numerous articles that Sister Mary Thomas has translated, she also is responsible for Father Pinckaers’s The Pursuit of Happiness—God’s Way. Living the Beatitudes (New York: Alba House, 1998). 47 MacIntyre, preface to Pinckaers, Morality, viii. 48 Pinckaers, “My Sources,” 915. 49 Ibid., 915. 50 Originally published as “L’Enseignement de la théologie morale à Fribourg” Revue Thomiste 93 (1993): 430–42; the English translation appears in Servais Pinckaers, OP, The Pinckaers Reader: Renewing Thomistic Moral Theology, eds. John Berkman and Craig Steven Titus (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2005), 73–89. 14 Romanus Cessario, OP in this long tradition—although you will allow me, for personal reasons, to mention the exquisite contribution to moral theology made by the Provençal Dominican Michel Labourdette. So I have constructed, citing the historical warrants, a spiritual genealogy for Father Pinckaers that favors my own linguistic background. Jingoism does not dictate taking this tack. Rather I cite the huge success that Father Pinckaers has enjoyed in the English-speaking world, and in particular the United States. I leave it to other of his admirers to plot the course of his intellectual bilander as it glides along the coasts of other regions, linguistic and national. No easy way presents itself to bring to a conclusion this tribute to a man whose accomplishments are so rich and diverse. I have said nothing specific of Father Pinckaers’s regular contributions to journals such as Nova et Vetera, Sources, and Kerit, nor of his preaching in Liège (1964–73) and retreats given to laity and religious, nor indeed of his many other priestly ministrations over more than half a century. I am persuaded, however, that the man who has done so much to remind us of the telic perfection that befalls those who await “our blessed hope, the appearing of the glory of our great God and Savior Jesus Christ” (Tit 2:13) does not mind. Measured against this divine Beatitude that, please God, will meet us all, what significance do human words possess? This Sunday marks Father Pinckaers’s eightieth birthday, October 30, 1925–2005. The best expression of our gratitude that we can offer him will be effected around the altar of the Eucharist and the proclamation of the Word of God. The graces that set Servais Pinckaers on his way to scholarship and blessedness and which have sustained him over these four score years are also the pledge of his reward for service to Christ’s Church. Bible and sacraments express in a human mode the plan of divine predestination that works itself out inexorably in the world. By a double birthright from Dominic Guzman and Thomas Aquinas, Dominicans commit themselves to upholding the priority of this divine initiative in the drama of salvation.To my mind, all that Father Pinckaers has taught us supplies a contemporary commentary on what Aquinas teaches about the knowledge, the will, and the providence of God.What matters in the Christian life above all, is that the believer comes to rely on the intrinsic efficacy of divine grace. When this first principle of the moral life is compromised (as Dominicans believe to happen in theories that emphasize divine foreknowledge and human freedom), Christian life loses its sweetness and all is lost.The doctrine of predestination is not easy for students of theology to master. Happily, Father Pinckaers helps us to learn about divine prevenient love from the bottom up, so to speak. His return again and again to Beatitude lulls us into sound Thomist teaching Hommage au Pére Servais-Theodore Pinckaers, OP 15 on predestination.That is why I chose Thomas Williams of Monmouthshire as a figure for this laudatio. In Louvain 300 years ago, this expatriate Englishman taught the right theses. So today, does our brother Servais Théodore Pinckaers. And I am willing to wager that our Belgian friend N&V does it better. Ad multos annos, dear Father Pinckaers!51 51 The author wishes to acknowledge his gratitude to Rev. Msgr. Laurence W. McGrath, Rev. Dominic Langevin, OP, and Brother Thomas Joseph White, OP, for reading a draft of this essay and offering many helpful corrections and suggestions. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 17–40 17 Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? Sources and Innovation in Summa theologiae I, Question 1, Article 1* WAYNE J. H ANKEY Dalhousie University Halifax, Nova Scotia Introduction I N 1968, the influential American neo-Calvinist theologian and cultural historian Francis Schaeffer published a small book, Escape from Reason. He located the origin of this disastrous modern “escape” in the division between nature and grace made by Thomas Aquinas, and in his placing grace above nature. By this account, Thomas draws a horizontal line and places grace above it and nature below.This hierarchical division is what Schaeffer calls “the real birth of the humanistic Renaissance,” and of the autonomy of the human intellect.The reader is told that “from the basis of this autonomous principle, philosophy also became free and was separated from revelation.” Establishing the reality and goodness of the natural was a good thing, but by doing it as he did,“Aquinas had opened the way to an autonomous Humanism, an autonomous philosophy, and once the movement gained momentum, there was soon a flood.”1 This was a bad thing. Schaeffer declares that “[a]ny autonomy is wrong” in respect to Christ and the Scriptures.2 Humans, created in the image of God to whom all belongs, demand by nature a rational whole. Once Aquinas made the division, step by step the autonomous rational ate up * This paper was delivered as a public lecture for the Institute of Medieval Philoso- phy and Theology of Boston College, October 19, 2004. I am grateful to Stephen Brown and Eileen Sweeney for their invitations and hospitality. 1 Francis Schaeffer, Escape from Reason (London: InterVarsity Press, 1968), 10, 11, 13. 2 Ibid., 84. 18 Wayne J. Hankey what was above the line, rendering it either empty or irrational. The result is what Schaefer calls the Line of Despair; he tries to show, by way of a dialectical somersault, how by traveling down that line we arrive at a loss of confidence in reason—the escape from reason. In 1998, Pope John Paul II published the encyclical Fides et Ratio, whose purpose is indicated by the title of a book that translates, comments on, and discusses it, namely Restoring Faith in Reason.3 Evidently, the pope, like Schaeffer, is troubled by the despair about reason. He writes that: philosophical research [now] wanders around in the uncertain soil of universal skepticism, . . . everything is reduced to opinion. . . . Hence not just some philosophers, but the men and women of our time have been subject to an increasing distrust and lack of confidence in the existence of the great cognitive capacities of the human mind.A certain false modesty has made them content with partial and provisional truths so that they no longer strive to pose radical questions about the meaning and ultimate foundation of human life.4 However, the pope’s diagnosis of the cause of the disease is diametrically opposed to that of Schaeffer; he writes: “[H]uman reason has its own proper domain from where it can inquire and comprehend, being restricted by nothing else except its own finite nature before the infinite mystery of God.”5 For the pope, a separation of faith and revealed theology from philosophy and the work of human reason is good and necessary:“Faith does not interpose itself in order to destroy the autonomy of reason [autonomiam rationis] or to reduce the area of its activity.”6 For the pope, in distinction from Schaeffer, from its beginnings, the Christian proclamation of the gospel has been linked with philosophy. In that history as the pope tells it, as also for Schaeffer’s account of history, Aquinas has an important place, however, Thomas is praised by the pope precisely for what the Calvinist lays to his blame. John Paul II writes that Aquinas “had the great merit of bringing to the fore the harmony between reason and faith.”7 For him, the Thomistic harmonization is connected to the foundations of the university and involves the autonomy of both faith and reason.The pope maintains that St.Thomas is “an authentic exemplar” 3 Laurence Paul Hemming and Susan Frank Parsons, eds. Restoring Faith in Reason: A New Translation of the Encyclical Letter of Pope John Paul II Together With a Commentary and Discussion (London: SCM Press, 2002). 4 John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, no. 5; Hemming and Parsons, Restoring Faith, 11–13. 5 Ibid, no. 14; 26. 6 Ibid., no. 16; 33. 7 Ibid., no. 43; 71. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 19 “precisely because he radically protected the particularity of Revelation, without at the same time diminishing the proper course of reason.”8 According to him:“Although St. Albert the Great and St.Thomas insisted on the existence of a close link between theology and philosophy, even so they were the first learned men to admit the necessary autonomy that philosophy and the sciences needed, so that each should depend upon arguments belonging to their own sphere.”9 Moreover, the pope agrees with Schaeffer that, having drawn this line of difference, Aquinas subordinates natural reason to the faith that perfects it: “Illumined by the light of faith, reason is rescued from the frailty and limitation that arise from sin.”10 Nonetheless, John Paul insists again and again on the autonomy of philosophy:“[P]hilosophy rightly assumes its autonomy, acts according to its own laws, and depends on its own strengths” and demands that respect must be had for “a valid autonomy of thought.”11 In contradistinction from Schaeffer, for the pope, differentiation, hierarchy, and autonomy are good and necessary.The problem arises not because of these, but because of too great a separation. John Paul II writes: [S]ome rationalists took such an entrenched position in pursuit of certain arguments that they developed a philosophy that was separate from and autonomous of the truths of faith. Among the different consequences of this separation was the gradual existence of a greater distrust of reason itself . . . [the profoundly unified] structure [created by the Fathers and the medievals] was totally destroyed through teachings that favored the defense of a rational knowledge both separated from faith and taking its place.12 The consumption of what is above the line by what is below it pointed to by both theologians has much the same consequences for both men. Although certainly not agreeing with Schaeffer that giving an autonomy to philosophy, which he says has its own “proper object,” that is,“nature,”13 is either avoidable or evil, the pope is clear that it is dangerous, that it has led to “the increasing separation of faith from philosophical reason,”14 and that this has been destructive both of philosophy and of reason itself. 8 Ibid., no. 78; 127. 9 Ibid., nos. 43 & 45; 69 & 75. 10 Ibid., no. 43; 71. 11 Ibid., no. 75; 121. 12 Ibid., no. 45; 77. 13 Ibid., no. 43; 71. 14 Ibid., no. 48; 79. 20 Wayne J. Hankey Before going on to look at Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 1, in light of these opposed evaluations of the structure it imposes on Sacred Doctrine and gives to Christian intellectual and spiritual life, it is worth noting that the pope’s characterization of what Aquinas did has been general in the modern Catholic Church. Indeed, even if the dangers of Thomas’s treatment of the relations of philosophy and sacred doctrine were strongly felt by the ecclesiastical authorities right from the beginning when it provoked condemnation, his praise of precisely what Schaeffer finds destructive echoes past positive judgments. Particularly important is the use made of Aquinas’s division of the work of natural reason from what is given by the light of faith by the great Jesuit Cardinal Bellarmine in the seventeenth century and by Pope Leo XIII under Jesuit influence in the nineteenth. Some scholars continue to defend what Bellarmine drew out of Aquinas as Thomas’s own doctrine on the relation of the secular and the priestly power.15 I side instead with those who maintain that this Jesuit doctor of the Church either exploited a contradiction in Thomas’s texts on the relation of the political and ecclesiastical powers, or used something implicit in his treatment of philosophy to draw a conclusion opposite to that actually drawn by St. Thomas. My view is that Aquinas combined a logic derived from the pseudo-Dionysius, strongly modified when transmitted by Hugh of St.Victor, with Aristotelian political notions to produce a strongly papalist doctrine. His papalist centralism served the interests of the mendicant orders in their struggles against the secular clergy. However there is another side to Aquinas. His notion of an imperfect philosophical and moral happiness that humans can achieve by natural reason and the moral virtues in this present life is the “secular humanism” that I think his thought contains.This notion of an imperfect philosophical felicity is essential to Thomas’s thought and is part of what made it revolutionary in the thirteenth century. It has, in fact, the potential to give an integrity to secular political authority. Bellarmine used it 350 years later to limit papal authority, maintaining that the pope had only indirect, not direct, power in temporal matters.16 Earlier thinkers attempted to lead Thomas’s positions on the papal power vis-à-vis the temporal power to Bellarmine’s judgment. I doubt that either 15 For example, Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP, Saint Thomas d’Aquinas maitre spirituel. Initi- ation 2, Pensée antique et médiévale (Paris/Fribourg, Suisse: Cerf/Éditions Universitaires de Fribourg, 1996), 399. 16 See my “ ‘Dionysius dixit, Lex divinitatis est ultima per media reducere’:Aquinas, hierocracy, and the ‘augustinisme politique,’ ” in Tommaso D’Aquino: proposte nuove di letture. Festscrift Antonio Tognolo, ed. Ilario Tolomio (Padova: Editrice Antenore, 1992), 129, 142. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 21 they or Bellarmine himself cited or interpreted Thomas’s texts accurately. The developed doctrine of the mature Aquinas is that in order for humans to obtain the supernatural end of eternal life, the royal priesthood of the God-man Jesus Christ must have an earthly embodiment in a regale sacerdotium, ordering the earthly to the heavenly, the secular to the spiritual, and thus all the kings of the Christian people are subject to the Roman Pontiff, the Vicar of Christ, as to the Lord Jesus Christ himself. Moreover, this fullness of papal power extends throughout the whole Christian commonwealth although the priestly authority does not usually exercise the secular power directly.17 Certainly both Bellarmine, and his predecessors who found the doctrine of the potestas indirecta in Aquinas, earned papal displeasure for their efforts. It is significant both for understanding Thomas’s adversaries in the thirteenth century, and for understanding the present discussion about Aquinas and secular humanism, that the doctrine opposed to Bellarmine’s is known as “Political Augustinianism.” For “Political Augustinianism,” natural reason and moral power are so weak or perverse that the secular authority must function “at the nod (ad nutum)” of the priestly authority. Whatever Thomas’s position on the relations of the priestly and the temporal powers may in fact have been, and, however disagreeable the limitation of papal authority to the potestas indirecta by Bellarmine and his predecessors may have been in earlier periods, 130 years ago, when the papacy was losing direct power even over its Italian territories, it accepted the Jesuit approach. In Fides et Ratio John Paul II quotes often the encyclical Aeterni Patris of Pope Leo XIII, which mandated the revival of Thomistic philosophy in the Catholic Church, and which was written under close Jesuit influence. Leo’s purposes in Aeterni Patris were, in part, the opposite of John Paul’s in Fides et Ratio, but there is much in common. Leo’s most urgent concerns were political:The territorial existence of the papacy was threatened, and the Church continued to suffer as a result of the totalitarian tendencies of the revolutionary and national states of the nineteenth century. In respect to these, Leo wanted more to limit philosophy than to lift it from false modesty and despair.18 17 See Aquinas, Contra Impugnantes (Leonine [1970], 41), pars 2, cap. 2, ad 10: patet quod ordinare de studio pertinet ad eum qui praeest reipublicae, et praecipue ad auctoritatem apostolicae sedis, qua universalis Ecclesia gubernatur, cui per generale studium providetur. See pars 2, cap. 3, co. et ad 6, ad 7, ad 8, ad 21, ad 23, ad 24. 18 See my “Pope Leo’s Purposes and St. Thomas’s Platonism,” in S. Tommaso nella storia del pensiero, Atti dell’ VIII Congresso Tomistico Internazionale, vol. 8, ed. A. Piolanti (Città del Vaticano: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1982), 40–41. 22 Wayne J. Hankey For him the problems that had befallen Church and State, and which he was experiencing immediately, resulted from philosophical innovations at the origins of modernity: “It pleased,” he wrote, “the struggling innovators of the sixteenth century to philosophize without any respect for faith, the power of inventing in accordance with his own pleasure and bent being asked and given in turn by each one.”19 Nonetheless, Leo also worries about the collapse of the gigantic new edifices philosophy has constructed for itself: From a mass of conclusions men often come to wavering and doubt; and who knows not how easily the mind slips from doubt to error? . . . For, a multiform system of this kind, which depends on the authority and choice of any professor, has a foundation open to change, and consequently gives us a philosophy not firm, and stable, and robust like that of old, but tottering and feeble. And if, perchance, it sometimes finds itself scarcely equal to sustain the shock of its foes, it should recognize that the cause and the blame lie in itself.20 Thus Aeterni Patris, like Schaeffer and John Paul II, is troubled by philosophy separate from revelation both arrogantly consuming the whole realm of knowledge and also falling into despair. Leo sought from a renewed Thomism that by which the Church could, on the one hand, speak to an intellectual world in which science and philosophy were independent of and even opposed to ecclesiastical theology, and, on the other hand, bring philosophy, and the political and social life supposed to be based thereon, back within the control of and subordination to sacred doctrine and ecclesiastical authority.The scholasticism that was to provide for these aims thus had the exact characteristics to which Schaeffer objects: Philosophy is separated from theology and subordinated to it. In his most important quotation from Aeterni Patris on the work of St.Thomas, John Paul II lays stress on the distinction, close association, and dignity, which, according to Leo,Aquinas gives the two forms of knowledge: He “correctly distinguished reason from faith, yet he also united them in friendship, and he protected the rights and respected the dignity of both.”21 Although John Paul II is just as insistent as Leo had been on the mutual need of reason and faith for each 19 Leo XIII, Aeterni Patris, “On the Restoration of Christian Philosophy,” no. 24, www.vatican.va/holy_father/leo_xiii/encyclicals/documents/hf_l-xiii_enc_ 04081879_aeterni-patris_en.html. 20 Ibid. 21 Aeterni Patris, no. 18, quoted in John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, no. 57; Hemming and Parsons, Restoring Faith, 97. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 23 other, he is less insistent on the subordination of philosophy to theology than was Leo, judging that at this moment it is better to put the stress on the proper autonomy of philosophy.22 In the course of Aeterni Patris, Leo continually refers to the First Vatican Council, which had hurriedly finished its work just nine years before this his first encyclical ( John Paul II also refers to it positively).23 Vatican I also had established the work of philosophy as necessary, but the most important passage in this regard in the Dogmatic Constitution On the Catholic Faith, Dei Filius, occurs not in Chapter 4, “On Faith and Reason,” but in the chapter “On Revelation,” which begins with this affirmation based in a Thomistic interpretation of Romans 1:20:24 God, the source and end of all things, can be known with certainty from the consideration of created things, by the natural power of human reason: ever since the creation of the world, his invisible nature has been clearly perceived in the things that have been made.25 This leads to an anathema: If anyone says that the one, true God, our creator and lord, cannot be known with certainty from the things that have been made, by the natural light of human reason: let him be anathema.26 In the De Veritate,Aquinas tells us that “the study of philosophy for its own sake, is both allowable and praiseworthy, because the truth which the philosophers grasp, is revealed to them by God, as the epistle to the Romans 1:20 says.”27 The same authority demands for him that the existence of God “is proved by the philosophers with unbreakable reasons.”28 Without this, he tells us at Summa theologiae I, q. 2, a. 2, Romans 1:20, which 22 John Paul II, Fides et ratio, no. 77; Hemming and Parsons, Restoring Faith, 125. 23 Ibid., no. 52ff., no. 55; 87. 24 See É. Zum Brunn,“La ‘métaphysique de l’Exode’ selon Thomas d’Aquin,” Dieu et l’être, Exégèses d’Exode 3, 14 et de Coran 20, 11–24, ed. Centre d’Études des Religious du Livre, CNRS (Paris: Études augustiniennes, 1978), 253. 25 Vatican I, Dogmatic Constitution on the Catholic Faith, Dei Filius, ch. 2, no. 1, www.ewtn.com/library/COUNCILS/V1.htm. 26 Ibid. 27 Aquinas, Summa theologiae (Piana, Ottawa, 1941), II–II, q. 167, a. 1, ad 3:“Studium philosophiae secundum se est licitum et laudibile, propter veritatem quam philosophi perceperunt, Deo illis revelante, ut dicitur Ad Rom. 1.20.” 28 Aquinas, Questiones disputatae de veritate (Leonine [1972–75], 22/2), q. 10, a. 12, co., 340, lines 137–39: “rationibus irrefragabilibus etiam a philosophis probatum”; and ST I, q. 2, a. 2, s.c.; see John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, no. 22. Wayne J. Hankey 24 holds that the invisible things of God are understood from creation, would be false because we cannot understand anything unless we can demonstrate that it is.29 An interpretation of Aquinas that both understands him to recognize philosophy as having a proper autonomy in respect to what humans can come to know by their own power and can do by moral virtue, and also embraces this as necessary and good for the life of faith, is well established in the Catholic tradition. In contrast, let me add to the partisans of something like Schaeffer’s judgments, before drawing us to the text of St. Thomas by way of a recently published book whose author is almost certainly the most creative and influential present French scholar of medieval philosophy, Alain de Libera. Radical Orthodoxy is a movement in contemporary theology and philosophy founded by three English thinkers at Cambridge University, who describe themselves as High Church Anglicans. It has attracted some Catholics, but Catholic criticism of the movement is very sharp indeed.30 More recently evangelicals on this side of the Atlantic have been attracted by its trenchant antiphilosophical stance, notable among these is a young member of the philosophy department at Calvin College, James K. A. Smith, a Canadian who gained his Ph.D. at Villanova University under John Caputo.31 The movement has made enough headway in the AngloAmerican world to get it a short piece in Time magazine reproducing a claim that Radical Orthodoxy is the “biggest development in theology since Martin Luther nailed his ninety-five theses to the church door.”32 Its founder John Milbank has fashioned what he called a “postmodern critical Augustinianism.”33 Absolutely essential to its program, and enabling it to overcome the oppositions and contradictions of modernity, is ridding theology of all connection to an independent or autonomous philosophy. Milbank writes: 29 ST I, q. 2, a. 2, s.c. 30 See L. P. Hemming, ed., Radical Orthodoxy? A Catholic Inquiry (Aldershot:Ashgate Publishing, 2000). 31 James K. A. Smith, Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation (London and New York, Routledge, 2002); for another evangelical with similar views see Jens Zimmerman,“Radical Orthodoxy:A Reformed Appraisal,” Canadian Evangelical Review 26–27 (2004): 65–90; for trenchant criticism there is Paul D. Janz, “Radical Orthodoxy and the New Culture of Obscurantism,” Modern Theology 20 (2004): 362–405. 32 The Chronicle of Higher Education, quoted in “God as a Postmodern,” Time 158 (December 17, 2001): 61. 33 John Milbank,“ ‘Postmodern Critical Augustinianism’:A Short Summa in FortyTwo Responses to Unasked Questions,” Modern Theology 7 (1991): 225–37. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 25 An independent phenomenology must be given up, along with the claim, which would have seemed so bizarre to the Fathers, to be doing philosophy as well as theology. . . . [P]hilosophy as autonomous, as “about” anything independently of its creaturely status is metaphysics or ontology in the most precisely technical sense [a very bad thing, according to Radical Orthodoxy, whose judgments owe much to Heidegger in this regard]. Philosophy in fact began as a secularizing immanentism, an attempt to regard a cosmos independently of a performed reception of the poetic word. The pre-Socratics forgot both Being and the gift, while (contra Heidegger) the later Plato made some attempt to recover the extracosmic vatic logos. Theology has always resumed this inheritance, along with that of the Bible, and if it wishes to think again God’s love, then it must entirely evacuate philosophy, which is metaphysics, leaving it nothing (outside imaginary worlds, logical implications or the isolation of aporias) to either do or see, which is not—manifestly, I judge—malicious.34 At the cost of a thoroughly tendentious reading,35 Truth in Aquinas by Catherine Pickstock and Milbank dissolves Aquinas’s Aristotelian noetic into intellectual intuition and Augustinian illumination in order to reduce philosophy to what they call “theology proper.” Metaphysics is collapsed into sacred doctrine. What makes this new Augustinianism resemble that of those who opposed, and were opposed by Aquinas, and who were victorious in the condemnations of the 1270s and 1280s is that, by destroying the autonomy of philosophy, Radical Orthodoxy supposes that it will get philosophy back again but now identical with Christian theology. A strategy has been discovered by which philosophy is reduced to nothing, and then retrieved as a new ontology and a new metaphysics. This would be a Christian neo-Platonism transformed by the Nietzschean critique of Platonism. In the demand that philosophy be reduced to theology so that its content is the same as that of faith, we recognize Bonaventure and the so-called Augustinians of the late thirteenth century.36 Alain de Libera’s Raison et Foi:Archéologie d’une crise d’Albert le Grand à Jean-Paul II is a complex and convoluted book. It spills a great deal of ink 34 John Milbank, “Only Theology Overcomes Metaphysics,” New Blackfriars 76 (1995): 340–41. 35 See N. Lash, “Where Does Holy Teaching Leave Philosophy? Questions on Milbank’s Aquinas,” Modern Theology 15 (1999): 433–44; W. J. Hankey, “Why Philosophy Abides for Aquinas,” Heythrop Journal 42 (2001): 336–45; and Wayne J. Hankey and Douglas Hedley, eds., Deconstructing Radical Orthodoxy: Postmodern Theology, Rhetoric, and Truth (Aldershot: Ashgate Press, 2005). 36 Alain de Libera, Raison et Foi: Archéologie d’une crise d’Albert le Grand à Jean-Paul II (Paris: Seuil, 2003), 221–22. Wayne J. Hankey 26 analyzing John Paul II’s encyclical and other papal pronouncements, but it is by no means a work of piety. One of its principal aims is to drive a wedge of difference between Aquinas and his teacher Albert the Great on the question of the autonomy of philosophy. Their positions are treated as the same by the pope in Fides et Ratio. De Libera contends that John Paul II’s position is in fact that of Albert and not of Aquinas. He sums up Thomas’s most disputed and most difficult to understand teaching in a single remarkable sentence that distinguishes him from Averroes. I think it to be correct and to be the heart of Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 1: The paradoxical task which Thomas assigns ultimately to reason is the mark of a rationalism very different from that of Averroes: to show by the resources of reason that reason is not able by itself to attain the goal which constitutes its ultimate end: the vision of God.Without contest this opposes Thomas to Averroes, for whom the task is more to show by means of the resources of the revealed text that Revelation is not able without philosophy to attain the objective constituting its ultimate end: the establishment of a universal human community founded in the Koranic Revelation.37 In fact, the self-transcendence of man, as expressed in reason as well as in faith, is a constant theme of Fides et Ratio, although the encyclical does not attribute this doctrine specifically to Aquinas.38 Nonetheless, ultimately, de Libera embraces the pope’s purposes within his own. This book is part of de Libera’s larger endeavor to use the study of the religious and intellectual culture of the Middle Ages, a period in which Judaism, Christianity, and Islam met through the medium of philosophy, to illumine both their meeting with one another and the clash of secular institutions with them in our contemporary societies. His last chapter is titled “Les enfants de Billy Graham et de Mecca-Cola.” De Libera sees an intolerance accompanying the religious revival that is taking place in the twentyfirst century. He judges that this intolerant religiosity is a threat both to what the French call laïcité, “secularism,”39 and also to the university, which de 37 Ibid., 255. 38 John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, nos. 15, 17, 22, etc. 39 “Laïcité” has a widely varying group of meanings resulting from its long evolution within Western Christendom generally and in France particularly; at its harshest it is a notion that exceeds the American separation of church and state, being used by the French republic at present to assert the absolute autonomy of the secular power and excludes Catholic clergy and religious from teaching in the state schools or universities and recently persons who display religious symbols from state institutions. See “Laïc/laïcat,” Dictionnaire critique de théologie, dir. Jean-Yves Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 27 Libera calls, institution de chrétienté. He writes: “[T]he institution which has made the autonomy of research and science its founding charter sees itself reproached today because of its tolerance.”40 Les enfants de Billy Graham et de Mecca-Cola are analogues of Bishop Tempier, and those who worked with him to have the positions of the Masters of Arts in Paris, of Albert the Great, and of Aquinas condemned.They threaten the university and laïcité in a way analogous to the way the Bishop threatened the university in the thirteenth century. He pictures the twenty-first century as “sleepwalking towards a censure worse than any which the Middle Ages experienced.”41 In the course of this long book, besides the analysis of the pronouncements of John Paul II, de Libera exposits and compares Albert the Great, Thomas Aquinas, and Averroes on faith and reason. He shows that the conflict of Averroes with the Islamic Kalam ˜ had a entirely different problematic than the conflict of faith and reason within the thirteenthcentury Christian university. He argues that Aquinas’s polemic against the Parisian Aristotelians invented the notion of Latin Averroism and the doctrine of double truth with which its Parisian adherents came to be associated and for which they were condemned. For him the condemnations, which ultimately encompassed the positions of Albert and Aquinas, pushed scientific autonomy toward the separatism Pope Leo XIII and Pope John Paul II find so destructive. He concludes: The paradox is that the vision of John Paul II in regard to the relations between faith and reason, philosophy and religion, erects as a model the strategy and principles of autonomy condemned by the Magisterium in 1277 . . . the condemnations of 1277 have been the most formidable measure of ideological control taken by the Church in respect to philosophy.They forbad Albert the Great’s conception of the autonomy of the sciences, inviting by the same act the movement of separation Lacoste, 2nd ed. (Paris: Quadrige/Presses Universitaires de France, 2002), 639. For its effects on the university and scholarship, see my One Hundred Years of Neoplatonism in France: A Brief Philosophical History, published with Levinas and the Greek Heritage, by Jean-Marc Narbonne, Studies in Philosophical Theology (Leuven/ Paris/Dudley, MA: Peeters, 2006), 131–32. De Libera’s argument in Raison et foi neither justifies, nor seems to intend to justify, the extreme exclusion and control of religion currently associated with laïcité. In appropriating the teachings of John Paul II, his interest does not seem to go further than the protection of the autonomy of research and teaching in the university from religious intolerance in a way that the pope might well support. 40 De Libera, Raison et foi, 358. 41 Ibid., 359. Wayne J. Hankey 28 which the Magisterium proposes today to arrest in making its own the position condemned.42 Within this context, let us look at the text of Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 1. Summa theologiae I, Question 1, Article 1 In my view the most radical and stunning feature of Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 1, is the question itself:“Whether it is necessary besides the philosophical disciplines to have another teaching?” The question assumes a true knowledge based in the natural powers of reason, asks whether this is all humans should know or could know, and whether there is need, and room, for any other knowledge.The question and the objections speak of disciplina rather than “scientia.” Disciplina is the wider term and includes the moral side of philosophical work as well as other parts of philosophy, like logic, which are not sciences treating kinds of natural being.43 In consequence, sacred doctrine here sets herself the task of finding a place and a necessity for herself relative to human knowledge and virtues that enable humans to construct a world aiming for and achieving the human end of happiness.The arguments in the objections establish what Aquinas assumes: what we might call a secular humanism provided by philosophy. Theology as revealed doctrine must justify herself in the face of a philosophically constructed world. Since we generally assume what at present corresponds to these philosophical disciplines, it is almost impossible for us to appreciate the shocking character of this question to the Western Christian in the thirteenth century.Augustine had spoken of Christianity itself as “true philosophy.”44 Following him, when philosophy is identified with intellectus or wisdom, an identification Eriugena explicitly made on Augustine’s authority, and when fides gives us the same content but in a form inadequate to reason, we arrive at Anselm’s fides quaerens intellectum, which is silently quoting Augustine.45 Intellectus surpasses what we know on authority but, crucially, it aims for identity with faith. When, in its inward and upward quest for God, the soul finds its deiform rationality, it knows through the structure of its own reasoning the content of faith according to rationes necessariae. 42 Ibid., 358. 43 See my God in Himself:Aquinas’s Doctrine of God as Expounded in the Summa theolo- giae (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987, 2000), 25–26. 44 Augustine, Contra Julianum 4.14.72; see De vera religione 5.8. 45 Eriugena, De divina predestinatione I, PL 357–358 (Treatise on Divine Predestination, trans. Mary Brennan [Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998], cap. 1, nos. 1, 7–8); and Anselm, Proslogion, cap. 1. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 29 The existence and attributes of God, the Trinity, and the Incarnation become a series of intelligibilia known independently of faith.46 For the Augustinianism world to which the Aristotelian philosophical science came in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, there was no question of an account of reality established independently of Christian faith, which might have a content different from faith, and relative to which faith would have to find a place and a justification for itself. The first objection, the first argument in the whole system, proposes that whatever is not above reason is fully (sufficienter) treated in the philosophical disciplines. “Therefore, besides them, there is no need of any further knowledge.”47 The philosophical sciences providing this complete account are usually attributed to Aristotle, and indeed, the “Philosopher” is spoken of in the second objection where significantly his Metaphysics is cited to the effect that there is a philosophical science of God. In fact, it is because of the systematization of philosophical sciences in the Peripatetic and neo-Platonic schools of later Antiquity, on the one hand, and, because of the Islamic Arabic mediation of Aristotle to the Latins, on the other, that the philosophical world is established as a totality over against what is made known by religious revelation. As Alain de Libera puts it, the Arabs mediated the texts of Aristotle to the Latins as “a total philosophic corpus, into which the whole of Hellenistic thought, profoundly Neoplatonized, had surreptitiously crept.”48 Within the Islamic Arabic world the greatest defender of the need for and totality of this philosophical knowledge of all things was Averroes, so, even if the problematic within which Averroes functioned was quite different from that of Aquinas, he must come to mind at this point. That Aquinas not only accepts as established a philosophical account of reality, but also wishes to see it established, is suggested by the text quoted in the first objection. We are told that Ecclesiasticus warns us not to inquire into things that are too high for us.Aristotle also confronts this objection from the inspired theologians (in his case poets) when he is introducing his liberal science of wisdom in the second chapter of the Metaphysics. This wisdom is God’s knowledge; it is too high for us; the 46 See Anselm, Proslogion, cap. 4, in respect to the existence of God; the Monologion deduces the Trinity and the Cur Deus Homo the Incarnation. For method, see the Prooemium of the Monologion; in the Prooemium of the Proslogion the requirement of deiformity is made. 47 ST I, q. 1, a. 1, obj. 1; for th\e significance of this beginning within Thomas’s world, see Fergus Kerr, After Aquinas:Versions of Thomism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), 12–14. 48 Alain de Libera, Penser au Moyen Âge (Paris: Seuil, 1991), 20. For brief description of this Aristotelianism, see idem, La querelle des universaux: De Platon à la fin du Moyen Age (Paris: Seuil, 1996), 117 and 68–124. Wayne J. Hankey 30 poets warn that seeking it will provoke the divine jealousy and bring misfortune. In his commentary on Metaphysics, Aquinas sides entirely with Aristotle against this error of Simonides and other poets. He says that the root of their argument is falsissima. Thomas supplies from Plato what Aristotle would have needed in order to demonstrate his position from the notion of divine perfection.49 That Aquinas accepts and wills the existence of a complete philosophical account of reality, including philosophical theology or metaphysics, is confirmed by the second objection, which argues, citing Aristotle silently (verum quod cum ente convertitur) or explicitly, that all the parts of being, including God, have philosophical disciplines that treat them. The response to this objection does provide for another teaching; it does so, however, not only without negating the truth and completeness of the human sciences as human, but also by further establishing them. First, it grants that the same things can be treated from two different perspectives without one negating the other; thus there can be two different sciences of God. Second, it provides the basis for the two sciences: One functions through the power of the light of natural reason, the other through the light of divine revelation. Moreover, they can, at least to some extent, keep out of each other’s way because they differ secundum genus; sacred doctrine is fundamentally different from the theology that is part of philosophy. Most interesting and powerful about Thomas’s treatment of sacred doctrine in this article is that, after granting all this territory to philosophy, he refuses to solve the problem he has set for sacred doctrine by establishing the room and necessity for another kind of teaching with the surrender of the field of knowledge and reason to philosophy. Attending to this aspect of Thomas’s respondeo, I shall avoid speaking about that aspect de Libera calls Aquinas’s paradoxical rationalism.50 Seven hundred years of often increasing controversy about how nature and grace are related when Aquinas made reason seek, and in some way apprehend, a perfect end it could not attain, does not encourage attempting to deal with this subject briefly. I have attempted to demonstrate elsewhere, against Pierre Hadot, that, for Aquinas, although nature must be perfected by grace, philosophy 49 Aquinas, In duodecim libros metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio, liber 1, lect. 3 (Turin: Marietti, 1964), nos. 61–63. 50 For the grave problems involved in this paradox and why it is central to the impossibility of constructing a Thomistic philosophical ethics, see Denis J. M. Bradley, Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good: Reason and Human Happiness in Aquinas’s Moral Science (Washington, DC: The Catholic University Press, 1997); Kerr, After Aquinas, 119–20 (a summary of Bradley). Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 31 continues to be a way of life for Christians.51 Essential to my argument is that Aquinas places moral virtue and philosophical reason within systematic structures derived from Porphyry and Iamblichus. I concluded that, even when contained within theological and religious structures which enable what philosophy cannot attain, for Thomas as well as for pagan neoPlatonists, philosophy “is still a way of life which transforms us towards deiformity.”52 It is not, however, Thomas’s connections to neo-Platonism that I want us to consider but those to Moses Maimonides (while noting my judgment that many of the same differences that separate Maimonides and Aquinas from Aristotle and that are usually credited to what they derive from biblical revelation are in fact derived for them from neo-Platonism).53 A moment’s attention to the respondeo shows the debt of Aquinas to the Jewish theologian who shared life in the city of Cordoba (and much else) with Averroes. The debt is most obvious when Aquinas writes of the reasons we are in need of instruction by divine revelation “even in respect to those things about God which human reason is able to investigate”: that is, its being known to a few, after long study, etc.54 Aquinas does not tell us either here or in the Summa contra Gentiles (I, 4) from where he gets this list. However, in the Disputed Questions de Veritate, when he is considering whether it is necessary to have faith, he acknowledges his debt to “the five reasons which Rabbi Moses gives” and which we can find in the Guide of the Perplexed.55 The De veritate shows the necessity of faith by an argument which is a fuller version of what is found in ST I, q. 1, a. 1. It speaks not only of the ordering of humans to the perfect cognition of God, but also of a difference between that of which we cannot have perfect cognition in this life because it totally exceeds the power of reason, and that at which we can arrive with perfect knowledge now,“because they are things about God which we can prove demonstratively (sicut illa quae de Deo demonstrative probari possunt).”56 51 W. J. Hankey,“Philosophy as Way of Life for Christians? Iamblichan and Porphyr- ian Reflections on Religion,Virtue, and Philosophy in Thomas Aquinas,” Laval Théologique et Philosophique 59 (2003): 193–224. 52 Ibid., 223. 53 See on this in respect to Maimonides, Marvin Fox, Interpreting Maimonides: Studies in Methodology, Metaphysics, and Moral Philosophy (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 122, 244, 245, 310; for an instance in respect to Aquinas, see my God in Himself, 5–6. 54 ST I, q. 1, a. 1, co. 55 De Veritate, q. 14, a. 10 (Leonine 22/2, 467, lines 188–201); Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed, trans. S. Pines (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963), liber I, cap. 34. 56 Ibid., lines 186–187: sicut illa quae de Deo demonstrative probari possunt. 32 Wayne J. Hankey In their judgments about the difficulty of theology and about the necessity of keeping it from all except mature students who have had a long period of preparation both moral and intellectual, Aquinas and Maimonides were following Plato, Aristotle, and the curricula of the neoPlatonic schools. The abstractness of philosophy generally, and of metaphysics particularly, the weakness of our minds which must be strengthened by mathematical and other studies, the extent of the ground which must be covered to reach it, the length of time traversing this takes, the need for developed moral virtues and the proper temperament, are all reasons why we require the gift of faith.57 These reasons do not make philosophy any less necessary to the true understanding of Revelation, even if, by itself it is insufficient for the knowledge that leads to salvation. Moses Maimonides follows the Arabic Islamic philosophers in teaching that philosophy is necessary for the restoration of the knowledge of the unity and incorporeality of God possessed by those through whom we were given revelation. This knowledge was subsequently lost by the faithful.Thus, for him,Abraham only broke away from the idolatry of his time by means of profound scientific and metaphysical study.58 Marvin Fox judges, correctly I think, that in the Guide of the Perplexed, and elsewhere, “Maimonides’s greatest concern is to eliminate every vestige of the belief that God has corporeal properties” and that he is aware (as were the Arabic Islam philosophers) that “a problem is caused by the language of Scripture in which God is frequently spoken of in corporeal terms.”59 When bringing philosophy to Scripture, Fox concludes that Maimonides “is casting himself as the Abraham of his generation.”60 In a similar way, Aquinas, while also agreeing with Maimonides that philosophy is acquired with much difficulty, makes it subordinately necessary for sacred doctrine. Aquinas never tires of reminding us that the knowledge of sensible particulars is natural to us. It belongs to our “natural perfection” not to know God except ex creatura and so by abstraction from sensible things.61 He asks how, with a form of knowing the complete contrary of God’s own, shall we understand his speech to us? How shall we understand speech from and about separate simple incorporeal substance? He answers 57 See also Aquinas, Sententia Libri Ethicorum, liber 6, lect. 7 (Leonine [1969], 47/2, 358–359); Super Boetium de Trinitate, q. 3, a. 1 (Leonine [1992], 50, 108); ST I, q. 1, a. 1; Super librum de Causis Expositio, ed. H.D. Saffrey, OP, 2nd ed. (Paris:Vrin, 1954), prooemium, 2. 58 Fox, Interpreting Maimonides, 261; and Maimonides, Guide, liber III, cap. 29. 59 Fox, Interpreting Maimonides, 157. 60 Ibid., 264. 61 De Veritate, q. 18, a. 2. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 33 that revealed theology needs philosophy, not because of what God’s knowledge lacks, but because of our human deficiency. Like his neoPlatonic predecessors, Thomas is always aware that our theology, though valid because it participates in higher forms of knowledge, belongs to human reason. By its labor of abstraction, human science exercises our minds in the necessary knowledge for theology of intellectual objects separated from matter. In the fifth article of question 1, Aquinas tells us that despite its limits, without philosophy, we would not understand divine speech.62 When arguing against Anselm and Franciscan Augustinians in the thirteenth century that God’s existence is not self-evident, he reminds us that humans have even thought that God was a body.63 It is significant that question 3, De simplicitate Dei, begins with the question Utrum Deus sit corpus and starts its answer by reference to God as primum movens immobile.64 Aquinas is close to Moses Maimonides not only about the limits and difficulty of philosophy, but also about its necessity for us, and by following the Aristotelian way in philosophy. However, Moses Maimonides contributes still more than this to ST I, q. 1, a. 1. Essential to Thomas’s teaching is that faith knows truths which philosophical reason unaided by grace cannot know. As he writes in ST I, q. 1, a. 1, “We must know an end before we direct our intentions and actions toward that end.Therefore, it is necessary for human salvation that some truths which exceed human reason be known through divine revelation.” His system involves a fundamental quid pro quo: in return for giving philosophy an autonomy, as also with Moses Maimonides, faith for Aquinas now knew things philosophy could never reach. In making this division between philosophical and revealed truths, Aquinas is exactly following the criticism by Moses Maimonides of the Kalam. ˜ Against the so-called Augustinians of his time, he is equally refusing to allow that what philosophy and what faith teach are identical. Maimonides praises the intentions of those who use the method of dialectical philosophical theology called Kalam, ˜ but he finds their solutions radically flawed. They are atomists of the divine will who, as Maimonides puts it, “abolish the nature of that which exists” (Guide, II, 19). Maimonides represents Aristotle as fighting opponents of the same kind: “those of his predecessors who believed that the world has happened to come about by chance and spontaneously” (Guide, II, 20). With Kalam, ˜ against positions he represents as Aristotelian, for example, that the world is eternal, and that creation proceeds by a necessary 62 ST I, q. 1, a. 5, ad 2. 63 ST I, q. 2, a. 1, ad 2. 64 ST I, q. 3, a. 1. See De Veritate, q. 10, a. 12. 34 Wayne J. Hankey emanation of a chain of single intellectual substances as much alike one another as possible, Maimonides asserts particular acts of the divine will by which the world had a real temporal beginning, variety enters creation, and miracles occur. Emanation and its law (“from the one and simple comes nothing but unity”)65 need to be supplemented. Because even with “thousands of degrees [of emanation], the last intellect would indubitably still be simple” (Guide, II, 22), another cause is required, namely, “a purpose and a will directed toward this particular thing” (Guide, II, 21),“the will of the one who wills” (Guide, II, 22).66 Nonetheless, Maimonides wants no reduction to will alone. He also strongly opposes the notion of Kalam ˜ that the temporal creation of the world can be proved by reason, and thus the assimilation of revelation to reason or reason to revelation. Following the argument of Maimonides exactly—even if his list of differences in content differs from that of Maimonides—Aquinas maintains that the demand of his Augustinian adversaries that things only faith could know—the temporal beginning of the world; the Trinity; a universal, individual, and immediate providence; the Incarnation—be rationally proved was not only impossible to satisfy but destructive. Like the arguments about the limits of philosophy, he found this argument in Maimonides and indicates this in his very early Commentary on the Sentences. When refusing to ascribe rational necessity to the doctrine that creation has a temporal beginning, Thomas reproduces, in both reasoning and content, the position of Maimonides on this point. Aquinas shares his judgment that the endeavor of theologians to claim necessity for what cannot be demonstrated only serves to bring contempt on theology and to undermine trust in the rational demonstrations on which divine science does and must rely.67 On this basis, can we regard Thomas as simply having taken over his strategy for relating philosophy and revelation from Rabbi Moses? I think not. 65 Maimonides, Guide, liber II, cap. 19, and following; liber III, cap. 13. 66 See A. Hyman, “From What Is One and Simple only What Is One and Simple Can Come,” Neoplatonism and Jewish Thought, ed. L. E. Goodman (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 117; L. E. Goodman, Jewish and Islamic Philosophy: Crosspollinations in the Classic Age (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999), 97–98. 67 Maimonides, Guide, lib. 2, cap. 15ff.; Aquinas, Scriptum super Sententiis, lib. 2, dist. 1, q. 1, a. 5, c., and ad s.c. 6.The editors of the Leonine edition of the De aeternitate mundi judge that Aquinas follows the exact position of Maimonides whom he cites twice in the article but “semble bien présenter une thèse de théologiens latins, appuyée, dit-il, sur un texte de saint Grégoire”: De aeternitate mundi (Leonine [1976], 43), 55. See T. B. Noone,“The Originality of St.Thomas’s Position on the Philosophers and Creation,” The Thomist 60 (1996): 295–99. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 35 For Aquinas, knowledge of God is what faith possesses so as to enable it to seek its end, namely union with God by the vision of his essence. I sometime think that too much is made of Thomas’s doctrine of analogy, but it cannot be doubted that his conviction on its basis that we rightly make affirmative and proper predications of God, is essential to his system. He reasons that our predications are true because God possesses the qualities predicated most properly, and in this he sets himself against both Maimonides and Dionysius for whom the qualities are ascribed to God only as the cause of what is in creatures.68 The Divine Names refers the unknowability of God to the fact that God is “beyond being” and thus “above and beyond speech, mind and being itself.” Union beyond illumination, and in contrast to knowledge—not union by intellectual activity—is what enables theology, and this union is the perfection theology seeks.69 Although Maimonides is central to the transformation of Judaism in the Middle Ages, which makes it more a doctrinal religion than it was previously, he unites the Jewish judgment that God is unnamable with neo-Platonic negative theology to arrive at a position that Aquinas regards as far too apophatic. According to Aquinas, for Maimonides human language about God is equivocal.70 Furthermore, for Aquinas, knowledge of God is for the sake of union, and the union it brings is so intimate that he is required to take measures to prevent the dissolution of the human into the divine essence.71 His understanding of our end in terms of union comes to him most strongly from Dionysius. There is a great deal of Dionysian negative theology in Aquinas. He asserts that it is better to say that we know of God what he is not than what he is (ST I, q. 3, prol.), and he teaches that “in this present life our intellect is not so joined to God as to see his essence but so that it knows of God what he is not.”72 Nonetheless, Aquinas is far along in a tradition of the interpretation of Dionysius that assimilates union and knowing, something neither Dionysius nor Plotinus, who is the source for Dionysius on this, will do.73 In fact, Thomas will not allow that for Dionysius 68 ST I, q. 12, a. 4; ST I, q. 13, a. 1, co, ad 2, and ad 3; ST I, q. 13, aa. 2, 3, 5, 6, and 12; see Hankey, God in Himself, 88–95. 69 Dionysius, Divine Names, I, 1 [588A]. 70 On Maimonides, see Fox, Interpreting Maimonides, 306–21. For how Aquinas understood him, see ST I, q. 13, a. 2; I, q. 13, a. 5. 71 This is how I understand the ST I, q. 12, a. 5, ad 3; see Hankey, “Philosophy as Way of Life,” 223. 72 Aquinas, In librum Beati Dionysii de divinis nominibus expositio, cap. 13, lect. 3 (Marietti [1950]), no. 996. 73 See A Thirteenth-Century Textbook of Mystical Theology at the University of Paris:The Mystical Theology of Dionysius the Areopagite in Eriugena's Translation with the Scholia 36 Wayne J. Hankey God is beyond esse.74 Explaining why essentia Deitatis est occulta for Dionysius,Aquinas separates him from the Platonici.Their causa prima is unknowable because it “exceeds even ipsum ens separatum.” In contrast, secundum rei veritatem, a position which always includes Dionysius, “the first cause is above being insofar as it is ipsum esse infinitum.”75 For Aquinas, despite the Dionysian negative theology, his first is a form of esse. In fact, the ultimate account of human knowing for Aquinas comes not from Dionysius but from Augustine and the doctrine of the beatific vision he bequeathed the Latin church. Aquinas argues that both philosophy and faith demand human vision of the essence of God. Without face-to-face knowledge, faith would be nullified because its purpose is human beatitude: “Since the final happiness of man consists in his highest activity, reasoning, if no created intellect could see God, either it would never achieve happiness, or its happiness would consist in something other than God.This is foreign to faith.”76 Reason, in turn, would be denied. It is fulfilled in the knowledge of the principles and causes. This frustrated, man’s natural desire would be vain. Both faith and reason require that “the blessed see the essence of God.” Thomas’s doctrine of created grace explains how we can have the demanded knowledge of God’s essence. It is determined by Thomas’s desire to preserve the integrity of human nature, even when we are united to God. Just as angels have a natural capacity for knowing God as the subsistent act of being, humans have some capacity for knowing separate substance, and to this a gracious addition can be made: Since the created intellect has an innate natural capacity for apprehending individualized form and the concrete act of being in abstraction by means of a certain power to separate out, it is able through grace to be raised so that it can know subsisting separated substance and the separated subsistent act of being.77 Translated by Anastasius the Librarian and Excerpts from Eriugena's Periphyseon, ed. and trans. L. Michael Harrington (Paris/Leuven/Dudley, MA: Peeters, 2004), 12–26. Eriugena is an early member of this intellectualist tradition, although Aquinas misses this because Eriugena's inferior angels do not see the essence of God, see Aquinas, Super Epistolam ad Hebraeos Lectura, in Super Epistolas S. Pauli Lectura, vol. 2 (Marietti [1953]), cap. 1, lect. 6, no. 85. 74 See Hankey, “Aquinas and the Platonists,” in The Platonic Tradition in the Middle Ages: A Doxographic Approach, eds. Stephen Gersh and Maarten J. F. M. Hoenen (Berlin/New York:Walter de Gruyter, 2002), 317–19. 75 Aquinas, Super librum de Causis, prop. 6, 47, lines 8–22. 76 ST I, q. 12, a. 1. For a complete treatment of the issues involved in the relation of faith and reason here, see Bradley, Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good. 77 ST I, q. 12, a. 4, ad 3. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 37 Divine grace gives a power to the creature in order, by an addition, to raise its natural created capacity beyond its natural limit. Grace continues, even at this absolute limit of creaturely existence, to conform itself to the specific nature of the rational creature and to strengthen its intellect. In asserting the necessity of direct vision of God’s essence for human happiness, Aquinas sets Augustine against Dionysius. If philosophical science draws us toward deiformity, theology as sacra doctrina returns the gift by strengthening reason. Sacred doctrine has its origin in a light added to our lumen naturalis rationis, the lumen divinae revelationis.78 The reception of this additional light—not inherent but conferred by grace from outside—increases ratio by giving to it what lies beyond its scope.Aquinas does not save sacred doctrine from the scientific completeness of philosophy, by placing her in the sphere of affectivity and charity. This is where Franciscans, who belong in the tradition of Dionysian interpretation that makes union with God experiential—the alternative to the intellectualist tradition where Aquinas is situated—typically place it.79 Rather, he makes her a science which addresses a knowledge to human reason and will in order that we can direct ourselves with rational freedom toward the end which both exceeds our natural knowledge and power and also assimilates union to intellection. We are related to an end beyond reason in such a way as to strengthen our reason and will by giving to them truths to know and goods to love higher than their natural capacities reach. As Thomas writes, the infusion of grace perfects the rational power: “The gifts of grace are added to nature in such a way that nature is not destroyed but is greatly perfected. Hence, even the light of faith, which flows into us by grace, does not destroy the light of the natural reason divinely bestowed on us.”80 The light of nature is divinely given to us.The whole massive pars secunda of the Summa theologiae, which describes the human in its desire for happiness, both in terms of what nature understands, seeks, and does, and also in terms of what grace might give, is set under the idea of the human as suorum operum principium because it is imago Dei. 78 ST I, q. 1, a. 1, ad 2. 79 See ch. 7 of Bonaventure's Itinerarium mentis in Deum; and Harrington's intro- duction, in Harrington, A Thirteenth-Century Textbook of Mystical Theology, 15. 80 Super Boetium de Trinitate, q. 2, a. 3, c., 98, lines 114–18: “Dicendum, quod dona gratiarum hoc modo nature adduntur, quod eam non tollunt set magis perficiunt; unde et lumen fidei, quod nobis gratis infunditur, non destruit lumen naturalis rationis diuinitus nobis inditum.” 38 Wayne J. Hankey Having introduced my discussion of ST I, q. 1, a. 1, in terms of secular humanism by reference to the pope’s justification of the good of an autonomous philosophy, and of Alain de Libera’s endeavor to learn something from the development of the autonomy of philosophy in the Middle Ages that might be applied to the present conflicts between Jews, Christians, and Muslims, and having brought out in my commentary what Aquinas owes to Averroes and Moses Maimonides, it is appropriate to conclude with a description of an ideal moment in the Middle Ages. In his essay “Mediaeval Jewry in the World of Islam,” Mark R. Cohen shows how Greek philosophy provided a space within which religious groups could both preserve their differences and find community: Philosophy was studied by Jews, Muslims, and Christians in interdenominational settings, where the particularities of each religion hardly made a difference. In fact, the Jews . . . participated in this as well as other intellectual endeavors as near-equals with Muslims in what has long been called “the Renaissance of Islam” in the tenth century. In the words of Joel Kraemer, “[c]osmopolitanism, tolerance, reason, and friendship made possible the convocation of these societies [of learning], devoted to a common pursuit of the truth and preservation of ancient wisdom, by surmounting particular religious ties in favor of a shared human experience.”. . . This world of shared intellectual discourse could exist because, in origin and content, much of it was neither Islamic nor Jewish nor Christian: it was Greek. Moreover, Arabic was not just the language of the dominant, and hostile, majority religion, but also the linguistic medium of mathematics, logic, and medicine, subjects that we call (and they felt were) secular.81 In the light of this picture of the Middle Ages and in light of the problematic of our present situation, I conclude that a foundation for secular humanism can be found in Aquinas and that it is a good thing. Of course, locating a foundation in Aquinas for human powers of reason and will to seek the human good in this present life, and thus for the secular state, does not justify regimes, theories, and actions that actually destroy the human good.That much contemporary humanism is selfcontradictory in this way cannot be doubted. Human freedom is asserted in such a way as to destroy not only the human good but also human 81 Mark R. Cohen, “Medieval Jewry in the World of Islam,” in The Oxford Hand- book of Jewish Studies, ed. Martin Goodman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 204. Aquinas at the Origins of Secular Humanism? 39 nature itself.This problem John Paul II has also confronted.82 The moral and intellectual dilemmas of secular humanism press urgently upon us N&V but are beyond my reach. 82 See Veritatis Splendor (Vatican City: Liberia Editrice Vaticana, 1993), no. 46: “Human nature . . . could be reduced to and treated as a readily available biological or social material. This ultimately means making freedom self-defining and a phenomenon creative of itself and its values. Indeed, when all is said and done man would not even have a nature, he would be his own personal life-project. Man would be nothing more than his own freedom!” Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 41–66 41 The Vision of Virtue and Knowledge of the Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas K EVIN E. O’R EILLY Milltown Institute Ireland I N THIS article I wish to offer an interpretation of Thomas Aquinas’s natural law theory that at once respects the fact of its historical development while arguing that such respect does not negate the claims of natural law to universality.1 Central to my argument is a correct understanding of the role emotion plays in practical judgment for Thomas, a role that is not that of a mere psychological support or prop but rather is integral to the process of reasoning itself.This point is quite easily missed if one reads Thomas’s treatment of law in isolation from the rest of his ethical teaching. In order to facilitate an appreciation of this connection, I have chosen to concentrate primarily on the Summa theologiae, a work in which he offers a systematic treatment of all aspects of his ethical teaching, along 1 The limitations of this essay require that I prescind from the wider theological context in which Aquinas develops his natural law theory, concentrating instead on purely philosophical issues. While the view presented here is incomplete, it nevertheless constitutes a necessary propaedeutic to any adequate theological discussion of the subject, for as any student of Thomas knows, grace does not abolish nature, but rather perfects it. In the conclusion I will indicate the significance of this basic tenet for further theological reflection on the themes that I discuss throughout the course of this article. For a discussion of the natural law as a participation in the eternal law, see Pauline C.Westerman, The Disintegration of Natural Law Theory: Aquinas to Finnis (New York: Brill, 1998), 21–47. For a treatment of the Old Law as a restatement of the natural law—a restatement required because of the obscuring effects of sin on human perception of the natural law—as well as of the insufficiency of the Old Law and of the necessity for the New Law, as the law that enables union with God, see Pamela M. Hall, Narrative and the Natural Law: An Interpretation of Thomistic Ethics (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994). 42 Kevin E. O’Reilly with all the necessary ontological supports. Indeed, as Pamela M. Hall correctly points out,“the very structure of the Summa itself, dialectical in nature, hinges on the relationship and interdependence of its many parts.”2 The same could be said of Thomas’s entire intellectual edifice. Failure to appreciate this fact inevitably leads to a distortion of Thomas’s teaching on the natural law.3 The role that the emotions/passions4 play in reason’s constitution of the natural law is a case in point as I have already stated. In contrast to the conception of Thomas’s thought as predominantly intellectualist, a careful reading of his work reveals a sensitive appreciation of the role our emotions play both in our perception of moral reality and in our reasoning about the same. The following words of Martha Nussbaum would, I believe, receive approbation from Thomas:“Emotions are not just the fuel that powers the psychological mechanism of a reasoning creature, they are parts, highly complex and messy parts, of this creature’s reasoning itself.”5 2 Hall, Narrative and the Natural Law, 23. 3 On this point, see also Daniel Mark Nelson, The Priority of Prudence: Virtue and Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas and the Implications for Modern Ethics (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992), 27–28. This distortion of Thomas’s teaching on natural law, arising from a failure to situate it in the context of his overall system of thought, is quite widespread in contemporary Catholic moral theology. Obviously lacking familiarity with the philosophical anthropology that undergirds his thought, Charles Curran, for example, notes in Thomas “a definite tendency to identify the demands of natural law with physical and biological processes,” Directions in Fundamental Moral Theology (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1985), 127. Curran believes that Thomas relies too much on Ulpian, who thought of humanity as being layered on top of animality (ibid., 130). A critique of this kind of misunderstanding of Thomas’s natural law theory would lead us far away from the concerns of this article. It will nevertheless become clear as the arguments presented here unfold that the notion of humanity as being layered on top of animality is completely alien to Thomas. He in fact regards the human person as a unitary composite being. It is precisely this view of human nature that explains the dynamic of reciprocity that obtains between reason and the emotions, a dynamic we are at pains to elucidate in this essay. 4 Throughout this essay I employ both “emotion” and “passion” as translations of the Latin passio. It ought to be borne in mind, however, that the term “passion” does not connote the same degree of intensity as it does in contemporary English. For a brief discussion of the problems in translating passio into contemporary languages, see Paul Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul in the Theology of St.Thomas Aquinas (Münster: Aschendorff, 2002), 30–33. 5 Martha C. Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought:The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 3. It must be admitted nevertheless that Thomas’s conception of the precise nature of the relationship obtaining between reason and emotion differs from that of Nussbaum. It does not however fall within the scope of this article to discuss these differences. Virtue and Natural Law 43 If this assertion is true then the implications for ethical theory in general, and natural law theory in particular, are quite obvious. In short, they cannot be ignored in the manner in which they have been by philosophy for so long, since they color in a fundamental way our perception of reality and, consequently, our moral deliberations concerning the same. In particular I argue here that for Thomas affectivity is integral to the perception of what constitutes the human good, which perception provides the starting point for the practical reason as it deliberates about the means to attain this good.6 It ought to become clear in the course of this essay that in Thomas’s scheme of things perception of the natural law can never be divorced from the agent’s affective constitution. As such this perception is intrinsically bound up with habit and therefore inevitably narrative in structure. Hence the fluctuations in appreciation of the various natural law precepts throughout the course of history, a phenomenon I attempt to account for in the case of one particular group mentioned by Thomas, namely the Germans, among whom “formerly, theft, although it is expressly contrary to the natural law, was not considered wrong.”7 Natural Law Reason is central to Thomas’s definition of law. He describes law as “an ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community, and promulgated.”8 After explaining the different elements of his definition of law, Thomas proceeds to show how this definition is worked out in the case of eternal law, natural law, human law, and divine law. Eternal law is clearly the core form of law for Thomas, from which the other forms are derived.9 Given that the world is ruled by divine providence, as Thomas has shown elsewhere,10 we can say that it is governed by divine reason. It follows therefore that “the very Idea of the government of things in God the Ruler of the universe, has the nature of a law.”11 Indeed, since the divine reason’s conception of things is not subject to time, but is 6 Nussbaum would, I suspect, be surprised to see the view that emotions are inte- gral to the process of reasoning itself applied in support of Thomas’s natural law theory. For in her estimation any system that advocates rule following (“deductivism”) understands reasonable and moral action to be independent of desires; in such systems, according to her, reason is taken to be self-motivating. See her “Practical Syllogisms and Practical Science,” in Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium, trans. Martha C. Nussbaum (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978), 165–220. 7 Summa theologiae I–II, q. 94, a. 4. 8 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 4. 9 ST I–II, q. 93, a. 3. 10 ST I, q. 22, aa. 1 and 2. 11 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 1. 44 Kevin E. O’Reilly rather eternal, this kind of law must also be eternal.All things are ruled and measured by the eternal law in that they receive their respective inclinations to their proper acts and ends from its being imprinted on them.They may therefore be said to partake of the eternal law. Human beings however enjoy a unique position in material creation, for they partake in divine providence by being provident both for themselves and for others because of their sharing in the divine reason, whereby they have a natural inclination to their proper act and end. It is precisely this participation of the eternal law in the rational creature that is called the natural law. Thomas underscores the centrality of reason in the natural law when he states that, because the rational creature shares in eternal reason in an intellectual and rational manner,“the participation of the eternal law in the rational creature is properly called a law, since law is something pertaining to reason.”12 Nussbaum’s contention that any ethical system that is characterized by rule-following necessarily deems moral action to be independent of desires seems initially, at least, to have some validity in the case of Thomas’s natural law theory, for emotions have a role to play only insofar as they are ruled by reason, in which case they too belong to the natural law.13 When we proceed to examine the determination of natural law, which determination we call human law, the force of reason does not flag. Indeed, the analogy between practical reason and speculative reason further emphasizes the role of reason in natural law. Just as speculative reason, on the basis of naturally known indemonstrable principles, draws the conclusions of the various sciences, so too practical reason, on the basis of the precepts of the natural law—which are general and indemonstrable principles in the practical domain—proceeds to the more particular determination of matters.14 Thomas is, however, aware that practical reason is concerned with singular and contingent matters, unlike speculative reason, which deals with necessary things. Human laws, consequently, do not enjoy the kind of inerrancy that belongs to the demonstrated conclusions of the sciences.15 The usefulness of a law does nevertheless extend beyond a single act, for “if there were as many rules or measures as there are things measured or ruled, they would cease to be of use, since their use consists in being applicable to many things.”16 12 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, ad 3. 13 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2, ad 2. 14 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 3. 15 ST I, q. 91, a. 3, ad 3. 16 ST I–II, q. 96, a. 1, ad 2. Virtue and Natural Law 45 These assertions concerning human law mirror what Thomas states elsewhere concerning natural law.The natural law is the same in all men with regard to general principles,“both as to rectitude and as to knowledge.”Yet when one descends into those details “which are the conclusions, as it were, of those general principles,” the natural law, although “it is the same for all in the majority of cases, both as to rectitude and as to knowledge,” may in some few cases fail. It may fail “as to rectitude, by reason of certain obstacles (just as natures subject to generation and corruption fail in some few cases on account of some obstacle),” while it may fail “as to knowledge, since in some the reason is perverted by passion, or evil habit, or an evil disposition of nature.”17 As a concrete illustration of this point,Thomas cites the example of the Germans who formerly, according to Julius Caesar (De Bello Gall. vi), did not consider theft to be wrong. Elsewhere Thomas tells us that the secondary precepts, which are derived by practical reason from first principles, “can be blotted out from the human heart . . . by vicious customs and corrupt habits, as among some men, theft, and even unnatural vices, as the Apostle states (Rom 1) were not esteemed sinful.”18 Practical Reason as Constitutive of the Natural Law The foregoing brief account serves to highlight the centrality of reason to Thomas’s conception of natural law.The natural law can be understood only in relation to what he terms the “order of reason” (ordo rationalis).19 It is important however to offer some clarification here, for Thomas distinguishes between the theoretical intellect and the practical intellect. By this distinction,Thomas does not mean that we possess two intellects, one theoretical and the other practical. Stated very simply, there is one mind that operates theoretically when it is a question of attaining to the truth of a particular reality—or indeed of reality itself—and operates practically when the subject seeks to realize his desired ends in action. While paradigm cases of purely theoretical or purely practical intellectual activity doubtless exist, most of our thinking is a mixture of both kinds.20 17 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4. 18 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 6. 19 See Frank J.Yartz,“Order and Right Reason in Aquinas’ Ethics,” Mediaeval Studies 37 (1975): 407–18. 20 See John Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 11. The reader will note that the understanding of the relationship obtaining between the practical reason to the speculative reason presented in this present article differs radically from that espoused by Finnis, Grisez, and others who follow their cue. Among the various problems that the natural law theory developed by these authors presents is that of intuitionism, for they argue not only that it is self-evident that certain things are good, but also that some goods are basic while others are 46 Kevin E. O’Reilly In the words of Ralph McInerny,“as often as not we are interested in the truth because of some practical aim we have.”21 Apart from whatever motivation we may have for acquiring theoretical knowledge, however, it is clear that for Thomas a relationship obtains between the theoretical reason and the practical reason, which goes beyond simply crossing over into one another’s territory. In Thomas’s understanding the practical reason includes and asserts the theoretical. The former is an extension of the latter: intellectus speculativus per extensionem fit practicus (theoretic reason becomes practical).22 The practical reason presupposes the theoretical and is rooted in it. It becomes clear, therefore, that Aquinas’s conception of the intellect is profoundly unitary. The intellect is a single faculty that manifests two different modes, theoretical and practical, but which are so related that the practical is an extension of the theoretical.This understanding of the intellect is crucial in Thomas’s ethical realism, for the practical reason is the measure of right action precisely because it has received this measure from objective reality by way of the speculative intellect of which it is an extension. For Thomas ethical imperatives are founded upon ontological indicatives, that is to say, upon the way things are. Because of the ontological unity of the intellect, there can be no disjunction between “is” and “ought.” not.The fact that many dispute these claims certainly calls into question their selfevidence. Their method, moreover, fails to offer any guidance beyond personal experience and social conventions on how one can judge whether something is only apparently good or is indeed truly so.The position that I outline with regard to the Germans later in this article requires the presence of theoretical knowledge, that is to say, it demands a grasp of the facts. For, as Ralph McInerny states, “The judgment that something is good presupposes and depends upon theoretical knowledge of the thing judged to be good and of the one for whom it is judged to be good” (Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Practice [Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America, 1992], 192).This assertion does not preclude the fact that theoretical knowledge can more often than not be “confused, vague, and susceptible to all but endless refinement and addition” (ibid.). If I have a headache I do not have to be a medical doctor in order to take appropriate steps to deal with it. If I need to get better immediately I can administer some medication to myself in the full knowledge that it will relieve my pain; I most certainly do not require the expertise that a pharmacist or a chemist has concerning pain relievers. If I so choose, however, I can try to acquire that kind of expertise. For a concise and insightful critique of the position taken by Grisez and Finnis, see Russell Hittinger, “After MacIntyre: Natural Law Theory,Virtue Ethics, and Eudaimonia,” International Philosophical Quarterly 29 (1989): 449–61. See also McInerny, Aquinas on Human Action, 184–206. 21 McInerny, Aquinas on Human Action, 185. 22 ST I, q. 79, a. 11, s.c. Virtue and Natural Law 47 The practical reason simply translates the knowledge of being, gained by the theoretical reason, into the realm of action.23 The penetrating insight of Goethe thus becomes more intelligible to us, namely that “in our doing and acting everything depends on this, that we comprehend objects clearly and treat them according to their nature.”24 Having delayed briefly on the relationship between the theoretical and the practical intellect, it is necessary at this point to highlight a fundamental aspect of the constitution of the latter, an aspect central to the argument of this essay: Unlike speculative reason, practical reason is appetitive in its condition, that is to say, the principle of practical reason is the “desirable” (appetibile). As St. Thomas states, “the practical intellect is said to move because the starting point of its deliberations, namely the object desired, moves.”25 We can agree with Rhonheimer’s description of practical reason: It is, he states, “embedded” in “seeking” and depends upon it.26 For, as Thomas notes,“good is the first thing that falls under the apprehension of the practical reason, which is directed to action: since every agent acts for an end under the aspect of good.”27 In the words of Pamela M. Hall, “one cannot act intelligibly, that is, deliberately and 23 This analysis differs from that of those who argue that the question of “ought” does not arise from the experience of being but rather from the subjective experience of our goal-directed nature that manifests itself in seeking, choosing, and doing. It is this experience, they opine, that provides the foundation for the systematic reflection that is proper to moral philosophy proper. Hence Martin Rhonheimer maintains that “such judgments as ‘All striving is guided to some goal’ and ‘That toward which everything strives we call the good,’ are not derived from metaphysics, but represent an original experience that is sui generis” (Rhonheimer, Natural Law and Practical Reason:A Thomist View of Moral Autonomy, trans. Gerald Malsbary [Bronx: Fordham University Press, 2000], 23). Here we witness the influence of John Finnis who asserts that the good that guides ethical reflection is not preceded by—in fact is independent of—any theoretical knowledge, Fundamentals of Ethics (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1983). 24 Quoted in Josef Pieper, Living the Truth, trans. Lothar Krauth and Stella Lange (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1989), 108. Pieper offers an analysis of the structure of the extension of reason from the sight of the good to the command that is directed toward action (ibid., 145–51). He does not, however, deal with the problem of bad choice or with the aporia of the apparent good. For a very fine treatment of the same, see Rafael-Tomás Caldera, Le jugement par inclination chez saint Thomas d’Aquin (Paris:Vrin, 1980). 25 “Propter hoc dicitur intellectus practicus movere, quia scilicet eius principium, quod est appetibile, movet.” In III De anima, in Opera omnia, vol. 24, ed. Stanislas Eduardus Fretté (Paris:Vivès, 1875), lect. 15. My translation. 26 Rhonheimer, Natural Law and Practical Reason, 27. 27 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2. 48 Kevin E. O’Reilly rationally, without acting purposively, for the sake of some end understood as good.”28 Indeed, it is precisely because of its appetitive condition that the acts of the practical reason are necessarily experienced as preceptive: Good is to be done and pursued and evil is to be avoided.29 This precept refers of course to goodness under its formal aspect, the ratio boni. As we will see, however, it is possible to be mistaken at the level of this first principle about the true nature of the particular good that confronts one, for at this level all the force of subjectivity comes to bear on the perception of reality.This contention is of course at odds with an understanding that treats the rules of natural law as if they were intuitively knowable or evident a priori to reason. Our position does seem to cohere much more with common experience and the testimony of human history. Knowledge of self-evident truths is attained by laborious acquisition through reflection on human experience30; and the formulation of rules on the basis of this experience is meant to facilitate us in securing the goods of human life—although it is very possible to misinterpret experience and to formulate erroneous rules on this basis, thereby actually undermining the attainment of these goods. Notwithstanding this possibility, however, the natural law can be said to be teleological in its very nature, that is to say, it has as its end or purpose human flourishing or fulfillment.31 Human fulfillment is of course nothing other than the fruit of a life lived virtuously, and so it becomes clear that natural law theory and virtue theory do not constitute two completely disparate approaches to moral reality; they are rather intimately connected with each other.The arguments offered here aim to substantiate this claim. In this regard, I seek to show that a life of virtue does not so much lead to a discovery of the rules that truly conduce to a flourishing existence as being the very process of discovery itself, while these rules in turn guide us in our efforts to fulfill ourselves as human beings and thus they culti28 Hall, Narrative and the Natural Law, 30. 29 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2. 30 This assertion may seem confused, but we must bear in mind Thomas’s distinc- tion between truths that are self-evident secundum se (“in themselves”) and those that are self-evident quoad nos (“in relation to us”). Thus, he states that “certain axioms or propositions are universally self-evident to all; and such are the propositions whose terms are known to all, as Every whole is greater than its part, and, Things equal to one and the same are equal to one another. But some propositions are self-evident only to the wise, who understand the meaning of the terms of such propositions: thus to one who understands that an angel is not a body, it is selfevident that an angel is not circumscriptively in a place: but this is not evident to the unlearned, for they cannot grasp it,” ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2. 31 See ST I–II, q. 90, a. 2. Virtue and Natural Law 49 vate a life of virtue.32 On the one hand, moral perception is a function of virtue; on the other hand, one’s store of moral knowledge furnishes the matrix within which consequent virtuous activity unfolds.This dynamic, which obtains between virtue and law, means however that the natural law is not something given once and for all to human beings; it is rather something that stands in constant need of reappropriation by means of rational reflection and virtuous living.33 In the remainder of this article, evidence is adduced to support these claims. It is important to bear in mind that it is only by the reflection of practical reason on its own act that we attain the linguistic formulation of this experience of practical judgment “good is to be done and pursued and evil to be avoided.” It is quite possible that one might never adequately succeed in formulating it—or indeed any of the basic and self-evident 32 This view is clearly opposed to that of those who argue either for the primacy of law or for that of virtue in the ethical doctrine of Thomas. In this regard Nelson, who argues for the primacy of prudence over natural law in Thomas’s ethical theory, has surely got it wrong. He is right, nevertheless, when he argues that the standard account of Thomas’s natural law theory, “which begins with intuited moral knowledge and then proceeds to the virtues,” is an erroneous interpretation (Nelson, The Priority of Prudence, 37).What is required is a synthesis of these two misinterpretations in the manner that Hall proposes: “[F]or prudence to operate effectively, the inclinationes must come into play—those specific directednesses which are the core of natural law for Aquinas. Without acknowledgement of this teleology, one cannot locate in Aquinas any notion of natural human flourishing” (Hall, Narrative and the Natural Law, 20). For a succinct portrayal of some versions of the standard (erroneous) account of Thomas’s natural law theory, see Nelson, The Priority of Prudence, 8–11. Nelson is himself, however, guilty of misinterpretations of Thomas.The scope of this article does not permit a treatment of these misunderstandings, but I might perhaps be allowed to quote one instance: “Thomas’s perspective, therefore, leaves very little room for a full-fledged ethics of natural law. The foundations of such a theory seem to have been drastically undermined by Thomas’s portrayal of a human nature created in such a way that it is oriented by nature only to its final end and is unavoidably free to direct itself to more particular ends.” What, one might therefore ask, are we to make of the basic inclinations listed in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2, inclinations that constitute the core of the natural law for Thomas? On this point, see Hall, Narrative and the Natural Law, 23–44. 33 Pamela M. Hall makes a similar point in stressing the narrative nature of the natural law: “We discover the natural law through a process of reflection on the goods of our nature and on what conduces to those goods. This reflection is characterized as a kind of practical reasoning within experience; we reason about our actions and, more comprehensively, our lives as proceeding towards those goods which constitute our flourishing. In doing this, we appropriate more and more the directednesses which are the core of the natural law,” Narrative and the Natural Law, 50. 50 Kevin E. O’Reilly principles of practical reason. As Clifford G. Kossel puts it, however,“one knows well enough to employ them in rational discourse and in practical life.”34 What we encounter here is in effect, as Thomas Ryan points out, an instance of affective knowing in “the form of primordial moral awareness.”35 The judgment “good is to be done and pursued and evil to be avoided” itself cannot be derived from a prior judgment; it is absolutely primary. The first principle of practical reason conditions everything else that is recognized in a universal sense as good or that is to be concretely realized hic et nunc in action by way of prudence. The recognition of universal goods expresses itself in the precepts of natural law, while those goods to be realized concretely here and now are expressed by the precepts of prudence.36 The Truth of the Practical Intellect We have emphasized the appetitive condition of the practical reason. For St. Thomas, indeed, “the truth of the practical intellect depends on conformity with right appetite.”37 This conformity does not of course concern necessary matters that can in no way be affected by human will; it pertains rather to contingent matters, for such matters alone can be effected by us, whether these be matters of interior action or the products of external work. Hence, concludes Thomas,“it is only about contingent matters that an intellectual virtue is assigned to the practical intellect, namely, art, as regards things to be made, and prudence, as regards things to be done.”38 Here it is human action, namely, the things to be done, that is in question.The relevant virtue in this domain is prudence, the subject of which is the practical intellect in its relation to the right will. Thomas describes prudence as “the right reason of things to be done.”39 Just as man is rightly disposed to the principles of speculative truth (such as the principle of contradiction) by the natural light of the active intellect, so too is he rightly disposed to the principles of the reason of things to be done—principles that are provided by the ends to which man is rightly disposed—by the 34 Clifford G. Kossel, SJ,“Natural Law and Human Law (Ia IIae, qq. 90–97),” in The Ethics of Aquinas, ed. Stephen J. Pope (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2002), 173. 35 Thomas Ryan, S.M., “Revisiting Affective Knowledge and Connaturality in Aquinas,” Theological Studies 66 (2005): 52. 36 Rhonheimer, Natural Law and Practical Reason, 32. 37 ST I–II, q. 57, a. 5, ad 3. 38 Ibid. 39 ST I–II, q. 56, a. 3. Virtue and Natural Law 51 rectitude of the will.40 Thus the principles of the reason of things to be done, that is to say, of prudence, are fundamentally determined by the constitution of a person’s will. For a person’s affective condition either facilitates or impedes his prudential reasoning, dictating the degree to which the latter is in conformity with truth.This dynamic obtains regardless of which species of prudence is in question: that which is directed to one’s own good (prudence simply so called), that which is directed to the common good of the home (domestic prudence), or that which is directed to the common good of the state or kingdom (political prudence).41 I argue that the impact of the affective constitution of an individual on the operation of his practical reason is fundamental in Thomas’s ethical thought and in his natural law theory in particular, a claim that I hope to substantiate in the remainder of this essay and one central to appreciating the dynamic which, I posit, obtains between virtue and law.As already stated, this dynamic means that the natural law is not something given once and for all to human beings, but is rather something that stands in constant need of reappropriation by means of rational reflection and virtuous living. Affectivity and the Perception of Moral Truth The important place that the passions occupy in the moral life for St. Thomas is indicated by the fact that he foregoes any systematic treatment of them in the treatise on the soul in the Summa theologiae, I, questions 75–79, choosing instead to devote a treatise to them in the secunda pars, that part of the Summa theologiae that deals with moral concerns. He adopts this course of action in spite of his assertion in the prologue to the treatise on the soul that he intends to discuss the operations of the soul, which operations include the passions.42 The choice to defer any inquiry into the passions until the secunda pars bears witness, according to Paul Gondreau to “the wholly integral role that affectivity plays in the moral life.”43 This role cannot be understated.As Gondreau remarks, the passions are for Thomas “integral and indispensable features of the moral life, since 40 Ibid. 41 ST II–II, q. 47, a. 11.Thomas’s assertion that there are three species of prudence points to his understanding that our knowledge of human nature and of what contributes to its flourishing is acquired on both an individual plane and a communal plane. The latter plane leads us to human law, a kind of law from which the natural law can never be wholly separated. See Hall, Narrative and the Natural Law, 41–42. 42 ST I, q. 75, prol. 43 Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul, 108. Kevin E. O’Reilly 52 one’s emotional disposition figures largely in determining whether the human thrust for the good has indeed been attained.”44 Although the passions furnish the necessary first step in the moral life, however, the fulfillment of the human desire for perfection requires, as we shall see, the overseeing command of reason—or imperium, to employ Thomas’s term. At the beginning of the secunda secundae pars, Thomas observes that “General remarks about moral matters are of little use because human actions are about particular things.”45 When the moralist comes to discuss particular concrete cases, he encounters the fact that human beings are moved by passions.As Gilson points out,“the study of the passions, therefore, must precede any discussion of moral problems.”46 In adopting this approach,Thomas displays his moral realism; as Gondreau points out,“the moral quality of human life begins for him in the most concrete of human experiences: the movements of sensitive affectivity, the passions.”47 For Thomas our choices and intentions do not exist in the realm of abstraction; rather, a man desires this object, he fears that outcome, and so on. One of the principal reasons Thomas views human affectivity in such a positive light is because of his hylomorphism, that is to say, the theory of form and matter that he inherited from Aristotle, albeit adapting it according to his own purposes.According to Thomas’s hylomorphic metaphysics of human nature, the human person is a unitary composite being, comprising both body and soul. In keeping with this view, he recognizes that one cannot separate the sensible dimension of human life from the psychic. Thus, as Judith A. Barad comments, “the psychic and corporeal elements of emotional experience are not characteristic of two entities; together they make up one affective experience.”48 Sensibility therefore is integral to affectivity and cannot be ignored in any treatment of the moral life, for just as emotion has both psychic and physical components, so too moral judgment includes rational and emotional elements. The intrinsic connection between the various dimensions of the human person will be illustrated in the following summary of Thomas’s account of the emotions insofar as they have an impact on the life of reason. It will become evident that a hylomorphic metaphysics of human nature requires that any affec44 Ibid., 264. 45 ST II–II, prol. My translation. 46 E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St.Thomas, trans. L. K. Shook (New York: Random House, 1956), 271. 47 Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul, 108. 48 Judith A. Barad, “Aquinas on the Role of Emotion in Moral Judgment and Activity,” The Thomist 55 (1991): 399. Virtue and Natural Law 53 tive movement be informed by and integrated into the life of reason; a synergy therefore obtains between affectivity and the life of reason. The moral life engages the entire human person.49 According to Thomas, all the soul’s powers are rooted in the one essence of the soul; in other words, they emanate from one and the same spiritual principle, although it must be emphasized that they remain distinct from one another, having different formal objects.50 This connection between the soul’s powers means that when the exercise of one power becomes more intense, that of another is weakened or perhaps even altogether impeded.There obtains among the various powers of the soul a spiritual equivalent of the principle of conservation of energy; “in the operations of the soul,” therefore,“a certain attention is requisite, and if this be closely fixed on one thing, less attention is given to another.”51 The rational appetite or will is not immune from the dynamism we have just described for, as Thomas states, “by a kind of distraction, when the movement of the sensitive appetite is enforced in respect of any passion whatever, the proper movement of the rational appetite of will must, of necessity, become remiss or altogether impeded.”52 More pertinent to our discussion is the second way in which Thomas argues that a passion of the sensitive appetite can move the will indirectly. This influence has its source in the will’s object, namely the good apprehended by reason. It is clear that the judgment and apprehension of reason in those who are deranged is impeded on account of “a vehement and inordinate apprehension of the imagination and judgment of the estimative power.”53 Just as the judgment of the sense of taste is conditioned by the disposition of the tongue—the disposition of the tongue of one affected by illness might, for example, make even perfectly good food seem bitter to the sense of taste—so too “the apprehension of the imagination and judgment of the estimative power follow the passion of the sensitive appetite.”54 Consequently, the imagination of one overtaken by a fit of passion is consumed with the object of his emotion, finding it difficult to divert his attention elsewhere.As a result,Thomas tells us,“the 49 See Servais Pinckaers, “Les passions et la morale,” Revue de sciences philosophiques et théologiques 74 (1990): 381–86. 50 Thus sight has color as its object; hearing, sound; and so on. 51 ST I–II, q. 77, a. 1. 52 Ibid. 53 Ibid. For Aquinas imagination “is as it were a storehouse of forms received through the senses” (ST I, q. 78, a. 4).The estimative power apprehends “intentions that are not received through the senses” (ibid.)—that something is good or harmful, for example, or that something is useful. 54 ST I–II, q. 77, a. 1. 54 Kevin E. O’Reilly judgment of the reason often follows the passion of the sensitive appetite, and consequently the will’s movement follows it also, since it has a natural inclination always to follow the judgment of reason.”55 In other words, the passion of the sensitive appetite informs the judgment of reason, which in turn gives a certain direction to the movement of the will. It is not difficult to see how a person’s ability to engage in moral reasoning is impaired when he is in the grips of emotion.As Barad points out,“being overtaken by a strong emotion, our reasoning ability becomes centered on the object of the emotion to such a degree that we do not consider the advantages of alternative courses of action.”56 In this regard it ought to be noted that whether the object of the will be a true good or merely an apparent good, there is always an affective influence on reason, an influence that issues from the sensitive appetite. Given the ontologically unitary nature of the human being there can be no such thing as pure, detached reason in the sense of reason that prescinds completely from emotion.The question on any particular occasion is: Given the appetitive condition of the practical reason that we have already noted, to what extent does affectivity facilitate or impede an objective perception of reality on the part of reason? To what extent is the affective response in accord with the very constitution of the reality at hand and therefore allow reason to accomplish its work in fidelity to the demands of truth? Aquinas himself notes that “the fact that something appears good in particular to reason, whereas it is not good, is due to a passion.”57 This influence of passion on reason can even lead to a situation in which a man fails to consider in particular what he knows in general; passion in effect fetters the reason and hinders it from arguing from the appropriate premise. An incontinent man, for example, may well know that fornication is wrong, but on account of passion fails to see that this particular act is one of fornication and therefore immoral.This state of affairs arises because, instead of reasoning from the universal premise “No fornication is lawful,” the incontinent man employs the premise “Pleasure is to be pursued.” Man in effect reasons about the universal proposition that is “suggested by his the inclination of the passion,”58 and reasons to his 55 Ibid. 56 Barad, “Aquinas on the Role of Emotion,” 406. 57 ST I–II, q. 77, a. 2, ad 2. Elsewhere he states that “a man is changed as to his disposition according to the passions of the sense appetite. Hence something seems fitting to man when experiencing a certain passion which would not seem so with the passion absent; for example, something seems good to a man when angry which does not seem so when he is calm. In this way, on the part of the object, the sense appetite moves the will,” ST I–II, q. 9, a. 2. 58 ST I–II, q. 77, a. 2, ad 4. Virtue and Natural Law 55 conclusion accordingly.Thomas explicitly refers to this argument, which occurs in his treatise on the passions, when he comes to expound his theory of the natural law. Although the general principles of the natural law, in the abstract, can in no way be blotted out from human hearts, they can be blotted out in the case of a particular action, “in so far as reason is hindered from applying the general principle to a particular point of practice, on account of concupiscence or some other passion.”59 In order that the conclusion of his practical reason may in fact be in accord with the objective reality confronting him, a man must enjoy “a right appetite of the end” so that reason “may hold itself aright in respect of principles, that is, the ends, on which it builds its argument.”60 It ought to be borne in mind with regard to all that we have said thus far that reason always remains the first principle of human acts; all other principles of human acts are subordinate to reason, but in various ways. Some, such as healthy members, obey reason without resistance,“for as soon as reason commands, the hand or the foot proceeds to action.”61 In contrast to healthy limbs, “the appetitive faculty obeys the reason, not blindly, but with a certain power of opposition.”62 Referring to Aristotle,Thomas cites the analogy of the exercise of political power, whereby a man rules over free subjects who enjoy a certain right of opposition, in order to elucidate the relationship obtaining between reason and the passions. Reason, for example, might demand that one adhere to a special diet in order to regain or to maintain one’s health; this demand, however, will have no effect unless the sensitive appetite approves of it and translates it into actual practice. Insofar as the passions do not obey the lead of reason, therefore, but rather lead an unruly existence, they impede the judgment of reason. Or, as Thomas expresses it elsewhere, they “drag the reason down with them.”63 59 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 6. This idea is echoed in Thomas’s treatment of the Old Law. Thus in ST I–II, q. 99, a. 2, ad 2, he states: “Now human reason could not go astray in the abstract, as to the universal principles of the natural law; but through being habituated to sin, it became obscured in the point of things to be done in detail.With regard in fact to the other moral precepts, which are like conclusions drawn from the universal principles of the natural law, the reason of many went astray so that it judged certain things to be good which in themselves are bad.” (My translation.) Thomas maintains that the habit of sinning gave rise to a progressive ignorance of the natural law; hence the necessity for the Old Law, which clarified the natural law, knowledge of which habitual sin had obscured. 60 ST I–II, q. 58, a. 3, ad 2. 61 ST I–II, q. 58,a. 2. 62 Ibid. 63 ST III, q. 15, a. 4.The translation is from Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul. The original Latin reads “trahunt rationem.”The Blackfriars translation is “deflect the reason.” Kevin E. O’Reilly 56 When however they do follow the judgment of reason, as though commanded thereby, they facilitate the execution of its command since they are inclined to the good that is in accord with reason. Moreover, as Mark D. Jordan puts it, “so far as the passions are brought under right reason, they increase the exercise of reason and so nearness to the good.”64 It is precisely this inclination of the appetitive faculty to the good that is in accord with reason, which constitutes moral virtue. Moral virtue is not simply the appetitive condition that inclines a man to what is in accord with right reason; in order to count as moral virtue it must be joined with right reason. Moral habits are “to be considered as virtues in so far as they are in conformity with reason.”65 The movements of passion constitute the matter of moral virtue, while moral virtue itself is effected by the habitus of choosing informed by the rule of right reason. In the words of Gondreau, “reason’s penetration into sensibility helps the concupiscible and irascible powers engage actively in the work of virtue, whereby they desire themselves the good of reason and where they exercise their proper activity within the arena of virtuous duty.”66 Virtue and Habit The notion of moral virtue necessitates a brief examination of habitus, for Thomas’s treatment of virtue must be understood in relation to the preceding treatise on habit.Virtue itself denotes a certain perfection of a power.Thus, for example, the ability to see with 20/20 vision can be said to be the perfection of the power of sight in human beings. The active natural powers, such as sight, are however determinate to their acts; thus sight is determinate to the act of seeing. In contrast the rational powers proper to man alone are not determinate to one action, but are rather inclined indifferently to many. In order to determine the acts of the rational powers habits are required. Thus, concludes Thomas, “human virtues are habits,”67 for as we have just seen, an appetitive inclination must be joined with right reason in order to constitute a virtue. Further specifying what he means by human virtue, St.Thomas points out that it “cannot belong to the body, but belongs only to that which is proper to the soul.”68 In other words, human virtue does not refer to the body, which man shares in common with other animals; neither does it 64 Mark D. Jordan, “Aquinas’s Construction of a Moral Account of the Passions,” Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie 33 (1986): 92. 65 ST I–II, q. 58, a. 2. See I–II, q. 61, a. 2; also, II–II, q. 141, a. 6. 66 Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul, 281. 67 ST I–II, q. 55, a. 1. 68 ST I–II, q. 55, a. 2. Virtue and Natural Law 57 pertain to the forces common to the soul and body for the same reason. Since the soul is related to the body as form to matter, the former being the act of the latter, it becomes evident why Aquinas refers to human virtue as an operative habit. For form is the principle of action,“since everything acts in so far as it is in act,”69 and human virtue implies reference to act. In addition to being an operative habit, human virtue is also a good habit. If we take any power whatsoever if it either fails to reach or exceeds the limits of its power, it is defective.Thus, for example, in human beings short-sightedness is a defect, while to possess the eyesight of an eagle is also defective. In a like manner,“moral virtue observes the mean,”70 this mean being established by the rule of reason. In establishing its rule, reason resists the lower powers exerting themselves in opposition, for the perfection of a lower power entails a falling away from reason.71 In contrast,“reason is shown to be so much the more perfect, according as it is able to overcome or endure more easily the weakness of the body and of the lower powers.”72 In his commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics,Thomas explains that the virtuous man is a sort of living rule and measure of human actions because on each occasion he correctly discerns that which is good and that which is bad. His virtue puts him in harmony with the true good since virtue consists in this harmony. In each case therefore he sees what is truly good because that which is proper to each habit, that is to say, that which is in agreement with it, naturally appears to it as delightful. In other words, the proper objects of the virtues naturally seem delightful to the virtuous man on account of habit.73 We encounter the same doctrine in the Summa theologiae.There Thomas tells us that in the same way the sense of taste discerns tastes according to its habitual disposition, so too man judges the object of his actions according to his habitual disposition. This is so because habit makes what is agreeable to him seem good, and what is repugnant to him seem bad.This fruit of habituation is what Aristotle is referring to, Thomas states, when he says, “according as someone is, so does the end appear to him.”74 69 Ibid. 70 ST I–II, q. 64, a. 1. 71 ST I–II, q. 55, a. 3, ad 2. 72 ST I–II, q. 55, a. 3, ad 3. 73 Aquinas, In Ethic., III, lectio X (no. 494). 74 ST II–II, q. 24, a. 11. In response to the charge of relativism—that is really good that seems to me to be good—I direct the reader to the metaphysical account of the good offered in Rafael-Tomas Caldera, Le jugement par inclination chez saint Thomas d’Aquin (Paris:Vrin, 1980), 31–58. As always, Aquinas steers a via media between objectivism and subjectivism.The ontological constitution of an object is such that it is good insofar as it is perfect, and this is so independently of human 58 Kevin E. O’Reilly Habit therefore makes that which is in agreement with itself seem good.This is so even in the case of evil, when the habit of the subject is a vice and not a virtue.Thus, for example, injustice “may spring from a gust of passion, namely anger or lust.”When however it proceeds from choice and the doing of wrong affords pleasure, it issues from a corresponding habit, “for whatever befits a habit is, of itself, pleasing to the one who possesses it.”75 This experience of an appetitive inclination that does not participate in the life of reason, an experience with which we are all familiar, is one that has perhaps not received as much attention as it merits, given that it results in an all-too-common human experience, namely immoral action. The mediation of habit in the discernment of good is a constant in Aquinas’s doctrine concerning judgment in moral matters. Correct discernment in matters of virtuous action is a direct function of the habit of virtue; thus, for example, a chaste person decides aright on issues affecting chastity.76 Thomas constantly describes the manner of this discernment as an intuitive judgment analogous to the judgment of the senses or, again, analogous to the intellect’s discernment of the first principles of speculative reason: “Just as a person assents to the first principles through the inborn light of natural reason, so also a virtuous person, through the disposition given by virtue, has a right judgment about what is in keeping with his virtue.”77 Thus, whatever is in agreement with a person’s habit appears spontaneously to him as good, and whatever is repugnant to it appears spontaneously to him as bad. Discernment is spontaneous because the individual’s habit is in consonance (or dissonance) with the objects of perception.These objects therefore, when apprehended by perception, are immediately grasped as delightful (or repugnant). The Germans and Theft The same observations can be made, mutatis mutandis, concerning erroneous perceptions of the good on the part of the vicious.The barbarian apprehension. A habit will incline a faculty to that which is truly good in so far as the habit itself is proportioned to the good; it will incline the faculty to that which is lacking in goodness in so far as it lacks due proportion to the good: qualis unusquisque est, talis finis videtur ei. The objective ontological constitution of the object, however, remains unaffected by human apprehension. The goal of the moral life, when viewed in these terms, is to achieve a right proportion between our internal subjective constitution and the objective constitution of external reality. 75 ST II–II, q. 59, a. 2, emphasis added.The translation offered here departs slightly from that in the Blackfriars edition of the Summa theologiae. 76 ST II–II, q. 60, a. 1. 77 ST II–II, q. 2, a. 3, ad 2. Virtue and Natural Law 59 Germans’ ignorance of certain precepts of natural law is a case in point. Because of their long-standing practice of raiding other communities they lost an awareness of the wrongness of this custom.78 Instead, this practice afforded them a certain pleasure, a pleasure that fettered both their communal and individual reason. Instead of reasoning from the premise “One ought not to steal,” they employed some other premise— perhaps “Material comfort ought to be pursued.”79 The starting point for deliberation about human action, namely, the end, was therefore defective. Prudence was consequently also vitiated, for it cannot exist without moral virtue that rectifies the appetite—which in turn has due regard for the end of human action.80 The affective pleasure afforded by reaping the material benefits furnished by the time, labor, and skill of others gradually blinded them to the wrongness of stealing and led them to adopt the second premise as the normal point of departure in their practical reasoning. Reason, in the course of this moral decline, retreated increasingly from its exercise of political dominion over the passions; and there prevailed the dual ignorance of which Thomas S. Hibbs speaks: “ignorance of the good and ignorance of one’s own ignorance.”81 One can imagine young men being educated in this environment. Growing up in a society in which raiding the possessions of other communities was accepted to some degree or other, the youngest generation of such men would naturally have regarded it in the same light.The impression they formed could then easily be translated into a premise in a practical syllogism, stating in effect that raiding the possessions of other communities is a legitimate way of sustaining life and pursuing material comfort.The sense that this stealing was a morally legitimate pursuit would have grown gradually stronger over a period of time; it did not happen 78 As E. A. Goerner points out, the Germans obviously did not think that all robbery was just.“They only thought it good if practiced against people outside the community of the raiders, as is clear from the passage in Caesar to which Thomas referred,” Goerner, “On Thomistic Natural Law: The Bad Man’s View of Thomistic Natural Right,” in Political Theory 7 (1979): 114–15.The passage in question is as follows: “Latrocinia nullam habent infamiam quae extra finis cuiusque civitatis fiunt,” De Bello Gallico (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951), vi, 23. 79 According to Caesar’s interpretation, the Germans valued raiding because it “exercised the youth and diminished sloth,” De Bello Gallico, vi, 23. 80 Thomas would say that the Germans at this stage possessed false prudence: “For since a prudent man is one who disposes well of the things that have to be done for a good end, whoever disposes well of such things as are fitting for an evil end, has false prudence, in so far as that which he takes for an end, is good, not in truth but in appearance,” ST II–II, q. 47, a. 13. 81 Thomas S. Hibbs, “Divine Irony and the Natural Law: Speculation and Edification in Aquinas,” International Philosophical Quarterly 30 (1990): 426. Kevin E. O’Reilly 60 overnight.The demise of a sense of right and wrong surrounding the practice of theft could therefore be described as narrative in character. Expressing this notion otherwise, we could say that it was the result of habituation: Long-standing practice over several generations led to an impairment of the functioning of practical reason and to an eclipse of a sense of right and wrong in relation to stealing from neighboring societies. The more the Germans failed to enact the natural law, the more stunted became their prudential ability to discern and to apply it.Any attempt at reasoning with them would have doubtless been in vain for, as Nancy Sherman points out in commenting on Aristotle’s theory of virtue, for “those who have already been corrupted by a life of pleasure and immoderate feeling, rational persuasion and dialogue are no longer viable means of effecting reform.”82 Their reason having been fettered by unruly passion explains why this would have been so. Indeed, the Germans would have come to regard their activity as an almost “natural” part of their life because, as Thomas notes, “custom (consuetudo) becomes a second nature, and produces an inclination similar to a natural one.”83 In making this assertion,Thomas recognizes that reason cannot escape the influence of the social practices that furnish the context in which it necessarily operates. Such practices as that of the Germans can therefore stifle knowledge of the natural law.We witness here, from a negative perspective, the importance of community and tradition. The depletion of the surrounding communities’ resources led to a reversal of the dynamic just outlined for, no longer in a position to live parasitically at their expense, the Germans themselves were forced to adopt a more self-sustaining mode of existence.84 In so doing, one might reasonably speculate that they experienced life in a more stable community along with the virtues that such a life necessarily entails. In its early phase this radical change in organization and conduct of German society no doubt occasioned widespread discomfort—emotional discomfort predicated upon the deliverances of the speculative intellect with regard to attendant circumstances.85 Once 82 Nancy Sherman, The Fabric of Character:Aristotle’s Theory of Virtue (Oxford: Claren- don Press, 1989), 165. 83 ST I–II, q. 58, a. 1. As Kossel notes, we witness here a progression from consue- tudo to habitus. See “Natural Law and Human Law,” 188, note 51. 84 See Goerner, “On Thomistic Natural Law,” 115, for a brief account of how this process might have worked itself out. 85 See note 19 above.The observation of Goerner is pertinent here: “The kind of training through punishment that the natural law imposes would seem to be just the sort of slow social process whereby Germanic, northern Europeans, who liked nothing better than a good raid, had been painfully and imperfectly learning for a millennium that robbery, as a way of life, doesn’t pay for technically developed societies living together,” Goerner,“On Thomistic Natural Law,” 116. Virtue and Natural Law 61 again, however, time allowed them to become habituated to the new state of affairs.The pleasure that attended this habituation allowed them to appreciate in a new light not only the fruits of their labor but also the virtues that were necessary in order to produce these fruits.They would have come to understand how the advantages that life in a well-ordered society, in which justice reigned supreme, could be completely destroyed by the kind of activity in which they themselves had once engaged. Such a realization might well have occasioned a certain horror on their part with regard to their past activity, activity that was incompatible with the good of human nature considered as a totality; their affective reaction would certainly have resulted in an unfettering of their reason so that they were once again capable of proceeding from the premise “One ought not to steal” in their practical deliberations concerning their dealings with other communities. Doubtless, too, many other premises that had previously been cast into oblivion were now reactivated because of the relocation of spiritual energy effected by their newfound life of virtue, that is to say, because of the transition from a life characterized by the prevalence of unruly passion to one in which the effective political exercise of reason predominated. Being forced to live a life that happened to be in accord with right reason led, by way of habituation, to an existence actively informed by right reason; in other words experience of the benefits of their new way of life—experience, needless to say, informed by an attendant affective pleasure—provided the necessary conditions for reason to be able to see the connection between this new way of behaving and the fact that they were now flourishing to a greater degree as human beings both on an individual and a communal basis.86 A rectified appetite, albeit helped initially by coercive conditions, facilitated prudence in reasoning on the basis of correct premises to appropriate means (practical conclusions) ordered toward acquiring the goods of human existence. Now, if faced with depleted resources, the Germans would size up the situation in the light of past experience, a sizing up that would, of course, be informed by an appropriate imaginative and affective feel for how this experience was related to what was at hand and their response would be more in accord with the objective demands of the natural law than previously had been the case. Once again we must emphasize that growth in appreciation of the natural law among the Germans would necessarily have been a gradual affair: 86 Here there is a recognition that desires are preceded and prepared by perception. If this were not so it would not be possible to progress from a state of affairs in which desires were in accord with right reason to one in which they were joined with it. 62 Kevin E. O’Reilly Growth in virtue would have resulted in greater pleasure in fulfilling the demands of the natural law, while this increase in pleasure would itself have facilitated rational appreciation of the demands of the natural law. In turn a heightened awareness of the demands of the natural law, when accompanied by actions fulfilling these demands—actions chosen for their own sakes and performed from a firm and unchanging character87—would have produced an experience of even more intense pleasure, thereby facilitating further progress in rational understanding of the natural law.And so on.The fact that that neighbors’ resources had been completely depleted and that there was, therefore, nothing material to be gained from raiding them could not automatically evoke actions performed for their own sakes and from an unchanging character.The passage of time and the habituation to action in accord with right reason which it allowed was necessary for all the conditions for virtuous action to be actualized, action that was the fruit of a personal appropriation of the demands of the natural law. The Germans became ever more a living rule and measure of virtuous actions because they themselves were increasingly conformed to the demands inherent in the very constitution of reality itself—a reality of which their own human nature and circumstances were a part—as expressed in the natural law. Conclusion It seems reasonable to argue that the forms of community in which we participate condition in a fundamental way (speculative) reason’s perception of what constitutes the human good. Given that the natural law is an opus rationis, a work of reason, it cannot escape the influence of particular cultural forms and social practices that furnish the context in which the life of reason unfolds; knowledge of the natural law is in fact nurtured or stifled through such forms and practices.88 Nobody can argue with the 87 The astute reader will have noticed that here I have drawn on Aristotle’s condi- tions for actions performed from mature virtue:“The agent . . . must be in certain conditions when he does them; in the first place he must have knowledge, secondly he must choose the acts, and choose them for their own sakes, and thirdly his action must proceed from a firm and unchangeable character,” Niomachean Ethics 1105a30–4. 88 Recent work in epistemology has devoted attention to the social dimensions of knowledge. See, for example, Frederick Schmitt, ed., Socializing Epistemology:The Social Dimensions of Knowledge (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994).W. Jay Wood summarizes well the influence of the attendant societal context on our careers as intellectual and moral agents: “Family, friends and social institutions contribute mightily toward shaping the framework within which our development takes place.What goals are worth pursuing, what goals should be subordinated to others, what practices ought to be avoided and which pursued, and what Virtue and Natural Law 63 fact that the goods of family, friendship, intellectual inquiry, and so forth are sought in different ways in different societies; indeed, a variety of ways of pursuing any one of these goods may exist within a particular social community. These social expressions of the fundamental inclinationes are, however, open to revision if they do not promote human flourishing. Natural law theory is therefore not an unchanging body of moral knowledge that is mediated from one generation to another—in the sense that it is up to each generation to attempt to reach conclusions concerning which cultural forms and social practices are conducive to human flourishing and which ones impede or even destroy it. Our delineation of the way in which habit and passion affect human functioning for either good or bad precludes any charge of relativism being leveled against us. The objective conditions required for human flourishing do not change over the course of time, although the manner in which they are fulfilled is of course subject to the conditioning of social, political, and cultural context.What can fluctuate, however, is our ability to perceive these conditions and to mold our choices accordingly. This fluctuation is a function of the subjective factors we have discussed, namely habit and passion. These factors can either help or hinder right perception of what constitutes suitable means to the attainment of the goods of human life. The example of the Germans’ practice of raiding serves as an illustration of how accepted norms of behavior in a particular society can impede perception of the human good and of the most suitable means to the realization of this good. Moral obscurity is occasioned by habituation—with its attendant affective constitution—to modes of conduct that do not conduce to human flourishing.Thus while social practices express a community’s understanding of what constitutes human flourishing, this understanding may be distorted because of the epistemic impact of accepted norms of conduct that serve to undermine rather than to promote human well-being. For a reciprocity of influence obtains between understanding what promotes human flourishing and accepted mores: A particular society’s understanding of flourishing expresses itself in particular norms of behavior, while concrete expressions of these resources are available to assist us in moral and intellectual growth are matters shaped in large measure within families, churches, schools and other social frameworks. Imagine how the complexion of your intellectual life might vary as you were alternately a part of traditions whose chief goals were world economic domination, the biblical concept of shalom, aesthetic sensitivity, the dissolution of the self and union with God,” Epistemology: Becoming Intellectually Virtuous (Leicester: Apollos, 1998), 20. 64 Kevin E. O’Reilly norms reinforce the common perception of flourishing. Unfortunately, as the example of the Germans indicates, the only way out of moral obscurity is furnished by the disastrous effects it occasions.This fact, however, ought to be a source of encouragement for those who despair at the moral fabric of contemporary western society, as also should the anthropological explanation offered by Thomas as to why improvement is always possible. To Thomas’s understanding of how we (re)discover the natural law may be applied the following words that Nancy Sherman employs with regard to learning virtue: It is “neither a mindless nor a purely intellectual matter, and . . . the process requires practical reason and desire working in tandem throughout.”89 It thus becomes clear that virtue theory and natural law theory cannot be two alternative and mutually exclusive approaches to ethics; they are, rather, mutually implicative and depend upon one another for their elucidation. What I have termed the “vision of virtue” can never stand outside the conditioning context of society and culture. (A fundamental flaw of modern conceptions of practical reason is to think that it can do so, it being sufficient that agents be armed with rules for right conduct.) Aquinas would certainly agree with Russell Hittinger’s contention that “deliberations and judgments are shaped by character and virtue, or lack thereof.”90 Indeed this dynamic is clearly operative in Thomas’s ethical thought, as I hope to have clearly shown in this paper. Nevertheless, he would also commend Hittinger for his realization that “deliberations and judgments not only flow from character, but are made in the light of universals. And by universals we mean not only propositions about conduct, but a knowledge of the world and other human beings.”91 Viewing virtue and law as twin components in a dialectical process enables us to transcend the limiting perspectives of particular societies and epochs in the light of what is good for man while, on the other hand, preventing us from doing violence to what are legitimate particular expressions of universal precepts of the natural law. In this essay I have confined myself to the realm of philosophical reflection on the epistemic impact of the life of virtue—or lack thereof— on our ability to know the natural law.What I have argued does, however, 89 Sherman, The Fabric of Character, 199. 90 Russell Hittinger, “After MacIntyre,” 455. Hittinger adds that “by universals we mean not only propositions about conduct, but a knowledge of the world and other human beings.” Unfortunately, to explicate what this contention would mean in the context of Aquinas’s thought would take us well beyond the confines of this article. 91 Ibid. Virtue and Natural Law 65 have great significance for any adequate theological treatment of the relationship obtaining between virtue and law, for grace builds on nature. Man enjoys the theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity as a result of the life of grace that is operative in him, the very grace that heals the obscuring effects of sin occasioned by the Fall. By grace the nature of the soul is transformed so as to “participate in the Divine Nature, after a manner of likeness, through a certain regeneration or re-creation,”92 enabling him in his intellective power to participate in the divine knowledge through the virtue of faith and in his power of will to participate in the divine love through the virtue of charity. Of course the illuminating effects of grace are often undermined because of the same kind of factors discussed throughout the course of this article: Human nature is not destroyed by grace, but rather is perfected; as such, it always remains ontologically unitary in its constitution. Nevertheless, given the sanitary effect of grace on the life of reason, it is not difficult to appreciate how ultimately the most exalted grasp of the natural law is reserved for those who are animated by a living faith. A substantiation of this assertion however must await treatment in a future article. N&V 92 ST I–II, q. 110, a. 4. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 67–80 67 Book Symposium The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters by Lawrence Feingold (Rome: Apollinare Studi, 2001) Steering Clear of Charybdis: Some Directions for Avoiding “Grace Extrinsicism” in Aquinas H ARM G ORIS Catholic Theological University/Thomas Institute Utrecht, the Netherlands I N HIS masterful, very clearly written study on the Thomistic doctrine of the natural desire to see God, Lawrence Feingold offers us a wealth of textual evidence and conceptual analyses, covering the entire history of the interpretation of Aquinas’s view on the relation between nature and grace, ranging from Aquinas himself to Henri de Lubac. One if its major achievements, I think, is that it revives the somewhat dormant debate over nature and grace. The heart of this debate has always been to find the right balance between, on the one hand, the axiom that “grace perfects nature,” which suggests some intrinsic connection between nature and grace, and, on the other hand, the gratuity and novelty of grace. In the past decades the scale tipped in the direction of the first alternative, that is, grace perfecting nature, but Feingold’s work adds more weight to the other side. Or to put it negatively: The debate has been about avoiding the Charybdis of “grace extrinsicism” and the Scylla of naturalizing grace (or supernaturalizing nature). Feingold warns us rightly that the course has been too much in the direction of Scylla. In this essay I shall first give a brief sketch—which also reflects my personal experiences as a student—of the basic sentiments evident in 68 Book Symposium theological anthropology since the 1960s. Next I will summarize the core of Feingold’s position. Finally I will make suggestions as to how Aquinas’s theology may help to avoid falling prey to Charybdis. The Nature–Grace Debate Since the 1970s Feingold’s study raises very serious questions about some deeply felt convictions in mainstream (late-) modern theological anthropology. For me and many of my colleagues, who received their training in theology during the 1970s and 1980s, the topic of nature versus grace was no longer the issue it had been in the previous decades (and centuries). De Lubac’s sharp criticisms on Cajetan’s merely obediential potency for grace and on Suárez’s construct of a “state of pure nature” (status naturae purae), his own alternative view that our very being is created for union with God, and its modified version of Karl Rahner’s “supernatural existential,” were already so deeply ingrained in the mind of our professors, that as students we could only shake our heads at those sixteenth-century debates and the rearguard actions fought by old-fashioned neo-Thomists. Had not the nouvelle théologie, Rahner, Edward Schillebeeckx, and many others shown that the theology of Thomas Aquinas had been distorted from Cajetan onward? In fact, Cajetan bashing had become more or less something de rigueur, whether it concerned his classification of analogy, his metaphysical interpretation of analogia entis, or his insistence on a merely obediential potency for grace. Furthermore, the view of de Lubac and Rahner that each human being actually longs to see God, offered a more fruitful basis for interreligious dialogue and, allegedly, it influenced the fathers of the Second Vatican Council.1 Also with the Second Vatican Council, the salvation history perspective had become dominant, and this did not foster a climate favorable for speculative theology about possible worlds in which possible rational beings were not called by God; neither did existentialist philosophy with its profound criticism of an essentialist conception of human being, implied by the very notion of “the human nature.” The same went for social constructivism (in whatever form), which so prevailed in the social sciences (for example, the nature vs. nurture debate) that it made us theology students even more reluctant to talk—or even think—about something like human nature or human essence. And last, but certainly not least, many Roman Catholic theologians—at least in Germany and in the Netherlands—were impressed by the dialectical theology of Karl Barth, who scorned any consideration of 1 Cf. Ilaria Morali, La Salvezza dei non cristiani. L’influsso di Henri de Lubac sulla dottrina del Vaticano II (Bologna: Editrice Missionaria Italiana, 1999). Book Symposium 69 humanity apart from the salvific works and person of Christ and labeled such considerations as idolatry. Against the background of all these developments, the only possibility for a truly theological anthropology seemed to be a reflection on concrete human existence in its historical relation of salvation to God. This allegedly was the formal object of theological anthropology—if not of theology tout court.When the relation to God was left out, theology had as little to say about human beings or human nature as it has to say about the periodic system of the elements: It would be none of its business. In consequence, any speculation about a “pure nature” was considered beyond the scope and competence of theology. Declaring “pure nature” not to belong to the subject matter of theology was also the remedy against what Maurice Blondel labeled an “extrinsicist” view of grace, or what we as students referred to as “Suárez’s cream cake.” It is the well-known picture of nature and grace as two tiers, one on top of the other, without an intrinsic connection between the two. Human nature is complete in itself, and it might very well do without grace, that is, without a personal relation to God.Without the cream of grace, it would be a little dry and less tasty, but the cake of nature is not really affected by the cream topping. However, from a religious, and hence also from a theological perspective, such a view was completely unacceptable. It alienated grace and faith from our personal, concrete, everyday life and from the larger reality of society and the world by promoting a flight into a distinct spiritual realm. It domesticated and isolated theology, confining it to the little, sheltered niche of the supernatural, fully disconnected from the humanities and sciences. The only way out from this imprisonment and trivialization of theology seemed to be to reclaim a specifically theological interpretation of human nature, such as offered by de Lubac or Rahner. That is, to reclaim an approach of the human being as actually created by God and destined for participating in the inner life of the Triune God. Faith teaches that God made us for the supernatural end of the beatific vision. He intended our existence to be perfected by sharing his own divine life. If the supernatural is to be our perfection, the perfection of us human beings, then it seems to be obvious that our humanity must be constituted in such a way that it somehow “fits” this destination: There must be some kind of coherence or continuity between “our nature” and “God’s grace,” otherwise we could not be intrinsically perfected by it. Precisely such an internal affinity seems to be denied by assuming a merely obediential potency for grace or by accepting the possibility of a state of pure nature having its own natural destination and beatitude and not in need of any further perfection. The conclusion looked inevitable. The 70 Book Symposium classical interpretation of the Thomistic commentators had to be abandoned: it created fatal problems and offered no way out. Feingold: The Classical Thomistic Position Contrary to the general impression sketched above, it becomes clear from Feingold’s study that it was precisely for internal theological reasons that Cajetan applied the notion of the potentia oboedientialis to the reception of grace and that Suárez developed his theory of the status naturae purae. Both Cajetan and Suárez were trying to further explicate and spell out the consequences of what Aquinas had said about the natural desire to see God but had not really elaborated in unambiguous terms. It would take me too far to summarize the whole of Feingold’s presentation, but the key question in interpreting Aquinas’s texts on the natural desire to see God is this: Granted, Aquinas speaks about an elicited and conditional natural desire of the human will to see God, but does that desire also correspond with an innate and absolute desire of human nature for this supernatural vision of God? The classical interpretation is that human will has a natural desire to see the divine essence, but that this desire is only a consequence of three other things. First, it originates from the underlying innate orientation the will has toward the perfection, not only of itself, but also of all other human powers and of the human being as a whole. Just as heavy objects are pulled down to the earth by the force of gravity, the will has an innate tendency (also called pondus naturae) to its goal, that is, beatitude in general, and, on top of that, also to the natural perfections of other human powers: to knowledge, as the perfection of the intellect, to health as the perfection of the body, and so on. Having an innate tendency as such is not yet something proper or peculiar to the human will (though the goal itself is specific to the will).The pondus naturae the will has is an instance of the general Aristotelian–Thomistic principle that each nature or natural power has its goal; in other words, the innate tendency is just the way in which the will exemplifies the appetitus naturalis, the universal teleological structure of “nature” in general. It is situated on a potential, preintentional, and preconscious level; it is an orientation that does not change and is always there, as long as the will as a natural power exists (whether it is in act or not). However—and this is the second presupposition to the natural desire for the beatific vision—when we consider the will not only as “a nature,” but precisely as “will,” that is, as appetitus intellectualis, we move to the level of actuality, of knowledge, and of intentionality. For peculiar to the will Book Symposium 71 as appetitus intellectualis is its own mode of actually striving toward its goal; it strives to something that has been understood or apprehended by the intellect as a good, and has been presented as such to the will.These acts of the will in response to what the intellect presents as a good are called “elicited” acts. Thirdly, elicited acts can occur in two ways.The elicited act may regard the desired object as a good just in and by itself, taken in isolation or abstractly.Technical Thomistic terminology for this kind of elicited act is abundant: It is called the “antecedent will” or, somewhat confusingly, “will as nature” (voluntas ut natura; not to be identified with the pondus naturae of the will), velleitas, “conditional,” “inefficacious,” “imperfect,” or “incomplete willing”. This means that if something is presented to the will as good by itself in all respects, then necessarily the will wills it, but as yet only “conditionally”. Next, the elicited act may also desire the object as it concretely exists in reality, that is, by taking into account what my intellect knows about the object’s relation to other goods, all its relevant circumstances, and its feasibility.This is the full-blown act of the will, called “consequent will” or “will as reason” (voluntas ut ratio), “unconditional,” “efficacious,” “perfect,” or “complete willing”. Now, we may desire something by our antecedent will without desiring it by our consequent will.This can happen for several reasons. Something may be understood as a good in itself and in itself be desired, but in a concrete, given situation may be forsaken for a greater good. For example, when I am sick, I may give up the good of carnal pleasure, which in itself I desire, and take a bitter medicine for I think my physical health to be a greater good. Martyrs may even forsake the good of life for the greater good of testifying to the faith. Likewise, I may wish for something that in itself is desirable, but when my intellect reasons that it is not feasible, I shall not desire it fully and pursue it. I can think of how desirable it would be to fly like a bird, or to know intuitively like an angel, but as these things cannot actually be realized (neither by myself, nor by someone else on my behalf), they will remain merely as a dream wish (velleitas). The classical interpretation of Aquinas’s teaching, that a human being has a natural desire for the supernatural end of seeing God, is that this desire is neither an innate appetite (pondus naturae), nor a perfect, unconditional elicited act, but only an imperfect, conditional elicited act. The argument goes like this. Our intellect can present to the will the vision of God as a desirable good.The act of apprehending the beatific vision as a good and of presenting it as such to the will is the result of the intellect’s natural tendency for its own perfection. By its very nature, the intellect aims at knowledge of essences and causes. Having reasonably established 72 Book Symposium the existence of a First Cause from observed effects by way of some kind of proof of God’s existence, the intellect can conclude that knowing the essence of this First Cause (which is the beatific vision) is a good, even that it is the highest good imaginable. And the intellect can propose this absolutely perfect good to the will. Next, by its very nature, the will cannot not desire the perfect good of seeing God: Upon the proposal of the beatific vision by the intellect, the will necessarily and naturally has an elicited act of desiring it. But the human intellect also knows that essential knowledge of God is not feasible or attainable by humans. Seeing God is beyond what can be realized by any creature—even the angels. Therefore, we shall not have a perfect, unconditional desire for the supernatural end:The condition that the end can be realized by natural powers is not fulfilled.This means that the desire itself for this end remains at the level of velleitas, of a mere dream wish that does not really affect our actual striving or our efforts. In other words: the beatific vision is not a goal that is proportionate to our nature, and therefore our natural desire for it remains imperfect. The crucial point of the classical Thomistic reading is that the natural desire to see God does not belong to the pre-intentional “innate appetite” (pondus naturae). The latter position is the one taken by Duns Scotus, Domingo de Soto, and Henri de Lubac, among others. As Feingold points out, there is some textual evidence in the writings of Aquinas for this position, but it is not convincing. However, apart from the question of what is the correct interpretation of Aquinas’s texts, there is a more pressing theological problem for the view that we have an innate appetite for the beatific vision. It runs the risk of falling prey to Scylla: how to account for the gratuity and for the novelty of grace—not only with regard to the means of realizing the end, but also with regard to desiring the very end, telos, itself. If we have a positive orientation or unconditional desire toward the supernatural end by our very nature, then grace seems to be a debitum naturae, something that belongs and is due to our nature: Grace is no longer a completely gratuitous gift from God.At the same time, grace seems to be merely a kind of prolongation or continuation of our own nature, with which we are so familiar: Grace is no longer something novel and unprecedented. De Lubac and Rahner try to meet these problems either by stating that we naturally desire the supernatural vision precisely as a gift (de Lubac) or by introducing a kind of constant, but not natural, freely bestowed attraction toward the supernatural good (the “supernatural existential” of Rahner). Feingold argues that neither solution is satisfying.2 It seems to 2 Cf. Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Rome:Apollinare Studi, 2001), 618–20, on de Lubac and note 311 on pp. 623–24 on Rahner. Book Symposium 73 me that his criticism of de Lubac is convincing, but that his discussion of Rahner is too succinct to make a well-balanced assessment of the Rahnerian position.3 However, it would be beyond the scope of this essay, which focuses in particular on Thomas Aquinas, to give a detailed account and interpretation of Rahner’s texts. Avoiding Grace Extrinsicism in Aquinas In order to avoid the Charybdis of “grace extrinsicism,” de Lubac and Rahner want to redefine the distinction between nature and grace.4 But for both the result seems to be that the very distinction tends to be blurred or to disappear. Joel Garver characterizes the two positions “roughly and schematically” as follows:“[W]hile Rahner’s thought tends to naturalize the supernatural, de Lubac tends to supernaturalize the natural.” 5 One might then draw the conclusion that in avoiding “grace extrinsicism” we will find ourselves confessing “tout est grâce” (or “tout est nature”) or with accepting the radical consequence of abandoning the very expressions and concepts of “nature” and “grace” altogether in theological anthropology.After all, the distinction as such is not found in Holy Scripture (unlike, for example, the distinction “law” and “grace”), and one could argue that it is given only within a specific, historically conditioned, philosophical context, namely, of an Aristotelian–Thomistic substance metaphysics. However, I think that each of these two “ways out” is too easy and that discriminating between the concepts of nature and grace remains a very valuable means for expressing fundamental data of faith concerning the relation of us, human beings, to God. 3 Feingold characterizes Rahner’s notoriously vague “supernatural existential” as a disposition (with or without quotation marks, like Rahner himself who speaks of Anlage) on 624, note 311. However, Stephen Duffy, following William Shepherd, interprets it not as a disposition for the offer of grace but as the enduring offer itself of justifying grace: Stephen Duffy, The Grace Horizon: Nature and Grace in Modern Catholic Thought (Collegeville, MN: Health Policy Advisory Center, 1992), 206–18. But on this interpretation the question is how the offer of grace can become something human prior to and independent from its actually being accepted by the human person. 4 Hans Urs von Balthasar and Max Seckler are two other influential theologians who proposed similar redefinitions of the distinction between nature and grace. Edward Schillebeeckx has an excellent critical review of Seckler’s Instinkt und Glaubenswille nach Thomas von Aquin, in “Het niet-begrippelijke kenmoment in de geloofsdaad,” pt. III, ch. 3 of Openbaring en theologie (Bilthoven: H. Nelissen, 1964), 233–61. As far as I know, this text of Schillebeeckx has never been translated. 5 Joel Garver,“Rahner and de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” www.joelgarver.com/ writ/theo/naturegrace.htm. 74 Book Symposium Leaving aside the easy ways out, there are several possible strategies. One could continue criticizing the opposite position: the classical Thomist warning de Lubac and Rahner that they are heading for Scylla, and vice versa the Rahnerian telling the Thomist that she is falling into the clutches of Charybdis. But instead of criticizing the other party, I think it will be more fruitful to listen to their warnings. So we could try to show that the Rahnerian position (maybe in a modified form) is both coherent and keeps a clear distinction between nature and grace. Or one should try to argue that the Thomistic position—in its classical interpretation—does not necessarily entail an extrinsic conception of grace.The latter is the course I will take here by presenting some basic lines of thought from Aquinas that could help us to steer away from Charybdis, that is, from grace extrinsicism. First we have to keep in mind that for Aquinas “human nature” is a double abstraction. It is not only a universal concept, abstracted from concretely existent, individual human beings, but it also abstracts from the actual history of salvation of this world, in which all humans are gratuitously called by God to share in his life—a call that may or may not be answered. Every human being stands in a relation of grace—or its opposite, the broken relation of (original) sin—to God, and we cannot be in a neutral position toward God’s call to the supernatural end. A state of pure nature (status naturae purae) does not exist in reality.6 This does not mean that the notion of a pure nature would not concern the existent human beings in this concrete economy of salvation and would only apply to hypothetical intelligent beings in some possible but not actualized world, as de Lubac stated.7 The concept of a pure nature remains very useful and maybe even indispensable for articulating the gratuity of the gift of grace we have received, but it remains a concept that is abstracted from the ontologically prior concrete human being in the state of grace or of sin. Both de Lubac and Rahner are correct in insisting that we should start our theological reflection with the concrete human beings in this actual history of salvation. The ontological priority of the graced (or sinful) human being in historical reality is mirrored by the intentional priority in the divine mind of our supernatural end. Talking about the “order of divine decrees” is a tricky business, but at least we should not think of God first deciding to create intelligent beings and next ordering them to the supernatural end. 6 Apart maybe from the souls in limbo, but I shall not go into this. 7 Cf. Feingold, Natural Desire, 393–95, 620–25. Book Symposium 75 Sharing his own inner life is what God intends first and foremost.8 Intelligent beings, both humans and angels, are only and uniquely created for this supernatural beatitude. Free, intelligent beings having their own nature and natural powers are so to say a necessary condition of possibility for God to share his life. In this sense the order of Quesnel’s infamous statement should rather be reversed: natura est sequela glorificationis.9 Because God wants to elevate free creatures to participate in the uncreated life of the Three Persons, He “has to” endow them with their own nature. It is logically impossible for God to create intelligent beings that by nature would share the divine life.Then God would create gods, and God is by definition unique and uncreated. Only the divine Persons share the divine life by their own nature. Keeping in mind the priority of grace, the first important question is how to describe or characterize theologically the nature of intelligent creatures without invoking directly the category of grace. For that would blur, if not annul, the very distinction between nature and grace. Aquinas describes nature, in particular the substantial form, as what constitutes something in its own being. According to that form, each nature has its natural potencies (both active and passive) and corresponding natural desires or goals. In the case of human beings, the distinctive natural powers are the rational intellect and will; while the corresponding goals that fulfill these powers are their formal objects: truth, in which reason comes to rest, and the good, which puts an end to the striving of the will. Knowing truth and loving the good is what fulfills human nature and what makes a person happy. Equally important is the question of how to describe grace, but this can only be done with reference to nature. For if we do not relate grace directly to nature, we shall keep a clear distinction between nature and grace, but we shall push it too far into a separation of the two, that is, into grace extrinsicism.Apart from this theological motive, there is also a metaphysical reason why a definition of grace implies a relation to nature. Sanctification is not a creation de novo; it is a transformation of an existing subject. It is a change, a movement, not on the level of the natural, substantial form of the subject (generatio), but on level of the accidents (alteratio).10 8 This is associated with the Pseudo-Dionysian axiom “bonum est diffusivum sui,” cf. In III Sent. d. 24, q. 1, a. 3, qc. 1, ad 2. 9 Cf. Quesnel’s proposition, condemned in the constitution Unigenitus of Septem- ber 1713, Denz. no. 2435: “Gratia Adami est sequela creationis et erat debita naturae sanae et integrae.” 10 Aquinas, Summa theologiae I–II, q. 110, a. 2. 76 Book Symposium It is therefore misleading to speak about “supernature,” for there is only the “supernatural” as a qualification of a subsisting nature.11 In what way do grace and the consequent theological virtues change or qualify human nature? According to Thomas, grace and the theological virtues make us participate directly in the divine life. In the Summa theologiae I–II, question 110, article 4, he states: For through his intellective potency, the human being participates in divine knowledge by the virtue of faith; and according to the potency of his will, [he participates in] divine love by the virtue of charity; likewise through the nature of the soul, [he participates] according to a certain similitude in the divine nature by a certain regeneration or recreation.12 Aquinas is somewhat reluctant to speak of a direct participation in the divine nature through grace, and he prefers more cautious formulations about a participation “according to a certain similitude in the divine nature” or a participation “in a certain similitude of the divine being”.13 It is likely he wants to avoid the suggestions of a substantial change and of an essential deification of creatures—even when they are sanctified. But with regard to the supernatural virtues of faith and of charity, Aquinas is more straightforward. In his view, it is rather by operating, namely, by knowing and loving God supernaturally, than by being, that we reach God himself directly.14 The (formal) object of faith is God as the Highest or First Truth (veritas prima), while charity regards God as the Highest Good (summum bonum).15 And it is in knowing and loving the divine essence that human beings find the perfect happiness. 11 The expression “supernature” seems to have been introduced in the nineteenth century. Cf. Michael Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade. Über die Beziehung des Menschen zu Gott nach Henri de Lubac (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verl, 1979), 13, note 1. 12 “Sicut enim per potentiam intellectivam homo participat cognitionem divinam per virtutem fidei; et secundum potentiam voluntatis amorem divinum, per virtutem caritatis; ita etiam per naturam animae participat, secundum quandam similitudinem, naturam divinam, per quandam regenerationem sive recreationem.” 13 ST III, q. 62 a. 2: “gratia, secundum se considerata, perficit essentiam animae, inquantum participat quandam similitudinem divini esse.” 14 Cf. In II Sent. d. 1, q. 2, a. 2, ad 4: “Creatura autem intellectualis non attingit ad eam secundum suum esse ut ipsa sit summum bonum, sed secundum operationem intelligendo et amando eam.” Cf. also Summa contra Gentiles II, c. 46, no. 3; ST I, q. 8, a. 3; and q. 43, a. 3. 15 In III Sent., d. 26, q. 2, a. 3, qc. 1, ad 1: “Ad primum ergo dicendum, quod idem secundum rem est objectum omnium virtutum theologicarum, sed differt secundum rationem: quia inquantum est primum verum, est objectum fidei; inquantum est summum bonum, est objectum caritatis.” See ST II–II, q. 1, a. 1, for veritas prima as the formal object of faith. Book Symposium 77 In comparing the Thomistic description of nature with the one of grace, we find that the same words occur: being, happiness, truth and the good. However, what I would like to suggest is that, in accordance with a basic feature of Thomistic theology, these terms should not be interpreted univocally. Speaking about “perfect” happiness, “first” truth, and “highest” good might suggest that there is only a quantitative difference with happiness, truth, and good, or that perfect happiness, first truth, and the highest good are but instances or exemplifications of happiness, truth, and good in general. But that is not the case. Our natural life and desire for truth, goodness, and happiness do not by themselves include a participation in the divine life and a desire for the First Truth, the Highest Good, and perfect happiness. But, on the other hand, neither do they contradict the very possibility of these supernatural perfections. Or in other words: Human nature insofar as it is a rational nature has an intentional directedness toward the transcendentals of truth and goodness, but the transcendentals are not to be understood univocally and they do not include God as the First Truth and Highest Good—yet they do not exclude God and the supernatural perfections either. The human spirit has a kind of natural openness or “natural aptitude” for knowing and loving God supernaturally.This is what being imago Dei means, according to Thomas.16 Thomas never speaks of a potentia oboedientialis for grace, but only of a natural capacitas, aptitudo, habilitas, and the like.17 However, Thomas does not identify this capacitas with any natural (active or corresponding passive) human potency. An interesting illustration of Thomas’s view that the capacitas Dei is not a natural human potency can be found in his discussion whether men are more “image of God” than women. Recently, Klaus Krämer has argued that while in his earlier works Thomas locates the imago Dei in the rational potency of the human soul with the consequence that men are more an image of God than women—because naturally man’s reasoning power exceeds that of woman—he abandons this idea in his mature works. Endorsing a more 16 ST I, q. 93, a. 4. Cf. also ST III, q. 9, a. 2, ad 3. 17 However, other thirteenth-century theologians, including Albert the Great and the authors of the Summa Halensis, used the expression potentia oboedientialis or potentia oboedientiae in relation to grace: cf. Feingold, Natural Desire, 214–15. In the twentieth century the distinction between a “generic” and a “specific” potentia oboedientialis was introduced: ibid., 216–20. “Generic” potentia oboedientialis concerns miracles like changing stones into bread, where stones lose their substantial form. The “specific” potentia oboedientialis of intelligent creatures for grace does not imply a loss of their substantial form. 78 Book Symposium radical, Augustinian view on grace, Thomas identifies the imago Dei no longer with an active (or corresponding passive) natural potency, but with the mere natural openness or aptitude for grace; as a consequence man is no longer more imago Dei than woman, although Aquinas does hold on to the Aristotelian idea that by nature men reason better than women.18 It may be clear then that in Aquinas’s theological language “happiness”—“perfect happiness,” “truth”—“First Truth,” “good”—“Highest Good” are not to be considered as cases of univocal use of identical terms. But neither are the terms used purely equivocally. It is more in accordance with Aquinas’s general theological framework to interpret them as terms that are used analogically. Like “wisdom” is said analogically of God and of creatures, so “truth” is called analogically the object of our intellect in its natural state (“truth in general”) and of our intellect in the state of grace, that is, of faith, whose object is the First Truth.The same goes for “good,” used analogically for both the object of natural human will (“good in general”) and the object of our supernaturally perfected will, charity, whose object is the Highest Good.The same interpretation applies to the relation between our natural desire for happiness in general and our supernatural desire for perfect happiness.19 It is beyond the scope of this paper to elaborate on Aquinas’s theory of the analogy of divine names.20 Taken together with Pseudo-Dionysius’s threefold way of knowing God, namely, through affirmation, negation, and eminence, Aquinas’s view on and his use of analogy in theology permit a balanced usage of both positive and negative theological language, which reflects our understanding of the incomprehensible mystery of God—an understanding that is grounded in a similarity of creatures with God that entails an even greater dissimilarity. God is truly wise, but he is not wise in 18 Cf. Klaus Krämer, Imago Trinitatis. Die Gottebenbildlichkeit des Menschen in der Theologie des Thomas von Aquin (Freiburg: Herder, 2000), 305–8. 19 For “being” it may be more complicated. As noted above Aquinas seems reluc- tant to correlate the being we have through our natural form with the being we have through grace (“through a certain similitude”) in exactly the same way he correlates truth as object of our intellect in its natural state and the first truth as object of faith. 20 An excellent study of analogy in Aquinas is Gregory Rocca, Speaking the Incomprehensible God:Thomas Aquinas on the Interplay Between Positive and Negative Theology (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2004). The similarity or continuation between nature and grace that includes an even greater dissimilarity or discontinuation is to be seen along the same lines as Sokolowski’s “Christian distinction” between Creator and creature: Robert Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason: Foundations of Christian Theology (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982). Book Symposium 79 the way of a creature. God’s wisdom differs not just in degree, but in mode. In creatures wisdom is only an accident, not a subsistent reality, and, moreover, wisdom in creatures is really distinct from other perfections like power or love. God’s wisdom, on the other hand, is identical with his being and with all the divine perfections. He is wise supereminenter, in a way we cannot express or understand.What I am suggesting is that the supernatural realities of the “First Truth,” “Highest Good,” and “perfect happiness” constitute real modes of truth, goodness, and happiness, but modes that we can no longer comprehend. Interpreting the relation between nature and grace with the help of the doctrine of the analogy of divine names offers a way to allow for a certain similarity, continuation, or intrinsic relation between nature and supernatural grace, while at the same time maintaining a radical dissimilarity and discontinuity between the two. Grace perfects our nature, our natural desire for truth and goodness, but in a way we could never have imagined. Grace transforms our natural life into a participation in the divine life, our desire for truth into a desire for the First Truth, our desire for the good into desire for the Highest Good, our desire for happiness into the desire for perfect happiness. That is a radical transformation, a regeneration, a N&V recreation into “what no eye has seen and no ear has heard.” Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 81–132 81 Desiderium Naturale Visionis Dei— Est autem duplex hominis beatitudo sive felicitas: Some Observations about Lawrence Feingold’s and John Milbank’s Recent Interventions in the Debate over the Natural Desire to See God R EINHARD H ÜTTER Duke University Divinity School Durham, North Carolina M AN IS PERFECTED by virtue, for those actions whereby he is directed to happiness, as was explained above (q. 5, a. 7). Now man’s happiness is twofold [Est autem duplex hominis beatitudo sive felicitas], as was also stated above (ibid., a. 5). One is proportionate to human nature, a happiness, to wit, which man can obtain by means of his natural principles.The other is a happiness surpassing man’s nature, and which man can obtain by the power of God alone, by a kind of participation of the Godhead, about which it is written (2 Pt 1:4) that by Christ we are made partakers of the Divine nature. And because such happiness surpasses the capacity of human nature, man’s natural principles which enable him to act well according to his capacity, do not suffice to direct man to this same happiness. Hence it is necessary for man to receive from God some additional principles, whereby he may be directed to supernatural happiness, even as he is directed to his connatural end, by means of his natural principles, albeit not without Divine assistance.1 1 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I–II, q. 62, a. 1, c.“Per virtutem perficitur homo ad actus quibus in beatitudinem ordinatur, ut ex supradictis patet. Est autem duplex hominis beatitudo sive felicitas, ut supra dictum est. Una quidem proportionata humanae naturae, ad quam scilicet homo pervenire potest per principia suae naturae.Alia autem est beatitudo naturam hominis excedens, ad quam homo sola divina virtute pervenire potest, secundum quandam divinitatis participationem; secundum quod dicitur 2 Petr. 1, [4], quod per Christum facti sumus consortes divinae naturae. Et quia huiusmodi beatitudo proportionem humanae naturae excedit, principia naturalia hominis, ex quibus procedit ad bene agendum secundum suam proportionem, non sufficiunt ad ordinandum hominem in beatitudinem praedictam. 82 Book Symposium The reason and will are naturally directed to God, inasmuch as He is the beginning and end of nature, but in proportion to nature. But the reason and will, according to their nature, are not sufficiently directed to Him in so far as He is the object of supernatural happiness.2 Others destroy the gratuity of the supernatural order, since God, they say, cannot create intellectual beings without ordering and calling them to the beatific vision.3 Introduction: “What Is the Human Being?”— The Two Types of Answers One might propose that the fulcrum on which theology is balanced is an answer to the question, or some version of it,What is the human being? Or, in more precise theological terms, What is the ultimate end of the human being, and in which way and to what degree is this end constitutive of human nature? The answers theologians offer to this question belong largely to one of two overarching types. One type of answer begins with a statement, for some of almost canonical status, from Augustine’s Confessions:“Inquietum est cor nostrum, donec requiescat in te.”4 Resting in God is the ultimate end of humanity and, short of reaching this end, human life will remain essentially unfulfilled Unde oportet quod superaddantur homini divinitus aliqua principia, per quae ita ordinetur ad beatitudinem supernaturalem, sicut per principia naturalia ordinatur ad finem connaturalem, non tamen absque adiutorio divino.” For consistency’s sake, all citations from the Summa theologiae (ST) in English are taken from the translation of the Fathers of the English Dominican Province, St.Thomas Aquinas Summa theologica (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1948).The Latin original offered in the notes is taken from Sancti Thomae de Aquino, Summa theologiae, 3rd ed. (Turin: Edizioni San Paolo, 1999), which offers an improved version of the Leonine edition. 2 Ibid., q. 62, a. 1, ad 3.“Ad Deum naturaliter ratio et voluntas ordinatur, prout est naturae principium et finis, secundum tamen proportionem naturae. Sed ad ipsum secundum quod est obiectum beatitudinis supernaturalis, ratio et voluntas secundum suam naturam non ordinantur sufficienter.” 3 Pope Pius XI, encyclical Humani Generis [August 12, 1950], no. 26. “Alii veram ‘gratuitatem’ ordinis supernaturalis corrumpunt, cum autument Deum entia intellectu praedita condere non posse, quin eadem ad beatificam visionem ordinet et vocet.” Heinrich Denzinger, Enchiridion symbolorum definitionum et declarationum de rebus fidei et morum. Kompendium der Glaubensbekenntnisse und kirchlichen Lehrentscheidungen. Lateinisch-Deutsch. Ed. Peter Hünermann, 40th ed. (Freiburg/Basle/Vienna: Herder, 2005), no. 3891; this latest edition will subsequently be cited as DHfollowed by the section number.The 1975 edition, edited by Adolf Schönmetzer, will be cited as DS followed by the section number. 4 St. Augustine, The Confessions, trans. Maria Boulding, OSB (Hyde Park, NY: New City Press, 1997), 39: “Our heart is unquiet until it rests in you.” Book Symposium 83 and, in the end, pointless. For rational creatures such a resting in God can be nothing short of “seeing God face to face,” that is, contemplating the infinite ocean of God’s essence forever, which constitutes the rational creature’s perfect felicity. Hence for some theologians human beings are creatures hardwired by God for communion with God such that theology has to stipulate a fundamental obligation for God to fulfill this destiny which human beings as creatures, by definition, cannot reach on their own. But such an exigency placed by creation on the Creator might very well go too far—and indeed, such a problematic version of Augustinianism as contended by the sixteenth-century Louvain theologian Michael Bajus was condemned by the Church’s magisterium.5 If, however, the Augustinianism of Bajus went too far in stipulating a divine obligation, might it at least be the case that the ultimate end of human fulfillment in the beatific vision is anticipated in the form of an inmost desire for this end, a desire rooted deeper in human nature than intellect and will? Might it be the case that this very desire is ontologically constitutive of what it means to be human in all respects, that is, constitutive of the human being as rational soul or spirit (Geistseele) and thus constitutive of the inner dynamic of intellect and will? Might this desire, without entailing any exigency for God to fulfill it, form the essential human élan for transcendence, the profundity of which can only be grasped in the inchoate moments of a completely gratuitous fulfillment, when the desired end begins to inform the human being from above as faith, hope, and love? Is the human being always made essentially for communion with God, such that the incarnate Son, the eternal God-Man, not only represents the prototype of the ultimate end of humanity, of genuine human fulfillment in the beatific vision, but also anticipates the destiny of indeed all creatures, the universal apokatastasis? Is human nature, due to its constitutive end being genuinely transcendent, already originally graced in a way such that the inchoate dynamic fulfillment of this end must be understood as an intensification—albeit an infinite intensification—of this original grace to its eventual fulfillment and vice versa, the original grace as nothing else than the very anticipation of the eventual fulfillment? In short, isn’t it all a matter of fundamentally the same grace, just of gradations in intensity? Isn’t human nature itself most fundamentally but a function of grace? This type of answer, which takes its 5 One of the theses condemned in Pope Pius V’s bull “Ex omnibus afflictionibus” (1567) claims: “Humanae naturae sublimatio et exaltatio in consortium divinae naturae debita fuit integritati primae condicionis, et proinde naturalis dicenda est, et non supernaturalis.” DH, no. 1921. 84 Book Symposium patronage from Origen of Alexandria and Gregory of Nyssa, finds its most brilliant Eastern-Orthodox voice in the twentieth century in Sergei Bulgakov, is most prominently represented in the Western Catholic tradition in a highly nuanced form in the theology of Henri de Lubac, and has been recently radicalized by the Anglican theologian John Milbank in his Bulgakovian reading of Henri de Lubac’s theology. Another type of answer, however, begins with Psalm 8: “What is man that thou art mindful of him and the son of man that thou dost care for him?” (Ps 8:4 RSV) The human being is a fragile creature with a limited life span, prone to all kinds of deficiencies of a physical, moral, and intellectual kind, surely a rational creature, but one whose intellect even in its highest flights of abstraction and speculation remains earthbound, limited by the exigencies of space, time, the deliverances of the senses, and the corruptibility of the body. Moreover, human beings are creatures whose nature is deeply wounded by original sin and whose concrete life is burdened and diminished by a dense web of personal and systemic sin. According to this type of answer, Christ became incarnate first and foremost because of and in response to human sin, for the sake of salvation and not primarily to perfect creation by inchoately ushering in its transcendent end. And what about a natural desire for the vision of God? Like Abraham having not the slightest inkling about his eventual calling and surely no desire for it, but being unexpectedly and inexplicably called and following the call, like Israel being created out of the “nothingness” of Egyptian slavery and being called to something for which it had no antecedent desire whatsoever of its own (Lv 19:2),“the many” (Mk 10:45) from Israel and the nations are called to a supernatural destiny categorically transcending the range of human imagination and hence desire, a destiny that grants its own supernatural desire with the call to it, and a fulfillment of the destiny in a glory of such utter transcendence that human nature can only be elevated by God to such a state. “ ‘What no eye has seen, nor ear heard, nor the heart of man conceived, what God has prepared for those who love him,’ God has revealed to us through the Spirit” (1 Cor 2:9–10a RSV). Because the human being has been made capable for this end (capax Dei) by God, human nature is in no way transmuted into something else by such an end. However, since this end so utterly transcends every aspect of created human nature, there can be no innate natural desire whatsoever in the human being for this end. Heavenly beatitude is as categorically different from earthly felicity as is God from creation. Hence the desire for the former cannot be innate in human nature (whereas desire for the latter indeed is) but must be in and of itself a gift from above. However, in order to perfect human nature instead of transmuting it, this Book Symposium 85 gift from above must indeed be met by a corresponding conditional desire, hence a desire not innate to human nature itself, but elicited. This unique, conditional openness to the supernatural, the attainment of God, has been understood as a specific obediential potency, specific because of the very constitution of the human rational soul and its intellective and volitional faculties. This type of answer finds its patronage in the late Augustine, was deepened and nuanced by Thomas Aquinas, was developed variously as well as controversially by the Thomist commentatorial tradition (partially in reaction to Bajanism as well as Jansenism), and has deeply informed Catholic theology until the middle of the twentieth century. The Controversy over la nouvelle théologie These variant types of answers to the question concerning the “nature and destiny of man” informed the most significant and intense theological battle among Catholic theologians in the middle of the twentieth century. The argument erupted between what was at the time a dominant neoscholastic Thomism (predominantly the French Dominican Thomism of Marie-Michel Labourdette6 and the “Thomism of the strict observance,” represented at the Angelicum in Rome first and foremost by Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange)7 and an emerging movement, dubbed very early on by its adversaries as la nouvelle théologie, which after a period of marginalization in the wake of the encyclical Humani generis (August 12, 1950) became the avant-garde and eventually with and after Vatican II the dominant theological movement.8 Arguably, the very center of the debate, the eye of the storm, was formed by the collision of two variant overall theological visions, the one informed by Gregory of Nyssa’s reception of Origen, and the other by Thomas Aquinas’s reception of the late Augustine. However, many other complex issues informed the controversy and contributed to its acrimonious nature.A tightly interconnected set of questions were (and continue to be) involved, including: 6 For a commemorative volume of his largely forgotten contribution, see “Un maître en théologie: Le Père Marie-Michel Labourdette, OP,” Revue Thomiste 92 (1992). 7 See now for a very accessible introduction to the person and work, Richard Peddicord, OP, The Sacred Monster of Thomism:An Introduction to the Life and Legacy of Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, OP (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine Press, 2005). 8 For a helpfully nuanced account of this historically as well as theologically complex controversy, see Aidan Nichols, OP, “Thomism and the Nouvelle Théologie,” The Thomist 64 (2000): 1–19. 86 Book Symposium 1. the nature and method of theology and its proper discourse; 2. the role of metaphysics (Thomistic, Scotist, or Suarezian) in the constitution of theological arguments and a. the philosophical question of a natural teleology and its theological interpretation, as well as b. the relationship between philosophical and theological knowledge; 3. the role and method of the interpretation of Scripture as informing theological discourse; 4. the role of the patristic Western and especially Eastern theological tradition for contemporary theology; 5. the interpretation of the genesis of “modernity,” its subtle influence on Baroque scholasticism and hence also on neo-scholastic theology; 6. the place and role of the nouvelle théologie in general and Henri de Lubac’s theology in particular before, during, and after Vatican II, as well as the specific issue whether Pope Pius XII’s encyclical Humani generis indeed aimed at Henri de Lubac’s early work;9 and, underlying all of the previous questions, 7. the correct method of interpreting and receiving the theological as well as philosophical thought of Thomas Aquinas.10 This struggle had its root and beginning in pre-WWII France and focused initially on two projects launched by the French Jesuits, the two series Sources Chrétiennes and Théologie. Both series, each in its own particular way, were seen to question and challenge more or less directly the principles and methods of neo-scholastic theology.The book, however, around 9 Feingold and Milbank agree in the judgment that the encyclical indeed did, while Henri de Lubac and many de Lubac scholars think the encyclical, as a matter of fact, did not aim at his work. See on this question the instructive introduction by David L. Schindler to the 1998 edition of the English translation of Henri de Lubac’s The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Herder & Herder/The Crossroad Publishing Company, 1998), esp. xxi ff, as well as Henri de Lubac himself in his At the Service of the Church: Henri de Lubac Reflects on the Circumstances That Occasioned His Writings, trans. Anne Elisabeth Englund (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993), 60–79, 89–90. 10 There was indeed also a political context to this conflict accounting in part for its particularly acrimonious nature. See Nichols, “Thomism and the Nouvelle Théologie,” 8ff. Book Symposium 87 which the theological conflict became most intense, was Henri de Lubac’s monograph Surnaturel,11 which appeared in 1946 in the series Théologie. The contended issues that came to a head with the publication of Surnaturel and the subsequent theological conflict are far from dead and bygone. That they remain quaestiones disputatae is plainly documented by numerous noteworthy publications, including two from 2001, one from 2002, and another from 2005: Surnaturel: Une controverse au coeur du thomisme au XXe siècle [Actes du colloque organisé par l’Institute Saint-Thomas-d’Aquin les 26–27 mai 2000 a Toulouse] (Toulouse: Revue Thomiste, 2001); Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Rome:Apollinare Studi, 2001); Georges Cottier, Le Désir de Dieu: Sur les Traces de Saint Thomas (Paris: Éditions Parole et Silence, 2002); and John Milbank, The Suspended Middle: Henri de Lubac and the Debate concerning the Supernatural (Grand Rapids, IN: Eerdmans, 2005). The following remarks are as fragmentary as they are preliminary in their refusal, in such a limited space, even to gesture toward a conclusive interpretation of Thomas Aquinas, a detailed reconstruction of the debate elicited by de Lubac’s Surnaturel, or a comprehensive engagement of de Lubac’s own work.To do justice to any one of these worthy goals would require nothing less than an extensive monograph.12 Rather, I shall have to confine myself to submitting some observations about the most recent interventions into this debate. Observation 1: Lawrence Feingold’s Provocations, or Why Feingold Is Not Feinberg and Why the Former Should Receive a Serious Hearing The present symposium has been elicited by the recent work of Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Rome: Apollinare Studi, 2001). His study constitutes a contribution of rather far-reaching historical and doctrinal implications, sufficiently controversial to amount to a serious scholarly provocation. To put it in the briefest way: Feingold, in a study more extensive in scope than Surnaturel itself, substantially challenges the charge of Henri de Lubac—now 11 Henri de Lubac, Surnaturel: Études historiques. Nouvelle édition avec la traducion inté- grale des citations latines et grecques (Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1991). For a very instructive introduction to Surnaturel and the ensuing conflict, see Bernard Sesboüé, SJ, “Le Surnaturel chez Henri de Lubac,” Recherches de Science Religieuse 80 (1992): 373–408. 12 See the recent extensive study by Éric de Moulins-Beaufort, Anthropologie et Mystique selon Henri de Lubac: “L’esprit de l’homme” ou la présence de Dieu en l’homme (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 2003). 88 Book Symposium widely accepted—that much of the Thomistic commentatorial tradition, first and foremost Cajetan, introduced “renaissance distortions” into their interpretation of Thomas Aquinas and so rather profoundly obfuscated the authentic teaching of the doctor communis, especially regarding the relation between human nature and the vision of God. For de Lubac and his Jesuit confrères, as Aidan Nichols aptly put it, “the true ‘nouvelle théologie’ was the late Scholasticism defended à l’outrance by Garrigou and with much more nuance by Labourdette. This was the upstart theology alien not only to the Fathers but the Golden Age of the thirteenth century itself.”13 Feingold’s challenge of this widely received and settled notion is indeed not a minor provocation. In his recent opuscule, The Suspended Middle: Henri de Lubac and the Debate concerning the Supernatural, John Milbank characterizes Feingold’s work as “arch-reactionary,” “written to reinstate a Garrigou-Lagrange type position,” and his exegetical method as “much like that of the proof-texting of a Protestant fundamentalist,” hence representing the “die-hard,” “palaeolithic” neo-Thomism. Moreover, in a less than subtle form of invective, Milbank denies his interlocutor the honor of being named correctly by consistently misnaming him throughout as “Feinberg.”14 The readers of Milbank’s treatise—most of whom in all likelihood are neither experts in the thought of Thomas Aquinas, Henri de Lubac, or Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange in particular nor of Catholic theology in general—are thus invited to entertain the suspicion of some sinister right-wing ecclesiastical conspiracy. And since Feingold’s tome is, quite unfortunately, virtually impossible to lay hands on as well as (should one succeed in getting hold of it) a much more demanding read than Milbank’s opuscule, very few of Milbank’s readers will be able to double-check the all too quick dismissal of a serious piece of theological scholarship the implications of which are, however, unsurprisingly, less than supportive of Milbank’s own project. But why should anyone care about the truth of the charge if one of the presently leading opinion formers of contemporary Anglo-American Protestant theology has sent out such weighty signals as “arch-reactionary, die-hard, palaeolithic neo-Thomism”? The associations seem to be all too clear to leave any doubt about the purpose of such antecedent rhetorical disqualification. Anyone willing seriously to consider Feingold’s arguments (and for 13 Nichols, “Thomism and the Nouvelle Théologie,” 17. 14 Milbank, Suspended, 26, 79, 84.The possibility, however, that the consistent use of the misnomer “Feinberg” simply reflects a neglect of contingent details, cannot be definitively excluded, since, after all, the reader has to recognize behind “Jacques Maintain” the Thomist philosopher Jacques Maritain (25, note 9). Book Symposium 89 that matter Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange’s interpretation of Thomas Aquinas), by the sheer dynamic of the connotations entailed, must be a supporter of the Spanish Inquisition, a defender of the Papal States, and an admirer of the Franco-, Vichy, and Pinochet regimes in addition to anything else implied by association as arch-reactionary. It is sad to see such an astute and critical mind as Milbank’s submit in such an unnuanced and uncritical way to the thoroughly modern political geography of “left” and “right” in order to situate and prejudice matters doctrinal and theological, a habit, surely by now as widespread in contemporary theology as it is thoughtless, and achieving nothing else than comfortably condemning matters of theological enquiry and discourse to the Procrustean bed of a policing political correctness and hence of the final domestication of matters ecclesial and theological under the extrinsically superimposed rubrics of political liberalism. Because of this unfavorable treatment, if not to say simply unjustified dismissal of Feingold’s work in Milbank’s footnotes, in the following I will give generous space to Feingold’s own voice, probably more than should be regarded as useful, were the book easily available.What has elicited Milbank’s ire? Three questions are indicative of a larger dispute: (1) whether de Lubac’s critique of key Thomist commentators, especially Cajetan, obtains; (2) the correct interpretation of Thomas Aquinas’s thought on the exceedingly complex subject of the desiderium naturale visionis Dei; and (3) how theology itself is to be done and how it relates to philosophy. Milbank has a high stake in all three questions insofar as he is interested in presenting de Lubac as “along with Sergei Bulgakov, one of the two truly great theologians of the twentieth century,”15 (the former’s Surnaturel is “arguably the key text of the twentieth century”)16 and in drafting both for his own particular project— in marked contrast to Hans Urs von Balthasar17—into a vision that, like 15 Ibid., 104. 16 Ibid., 3. 17 The student, close friend, and translator of de Lubac’s works into German who, according to Milbank’s intimations, never fully understood de Lubac’s vision, and therefore—again for Milbank a regrettable theological deficiency—made more substantive concessions to the encyclical Humani Generis than his mentor de Lubac was ever willing to do. According to Milbank, von Balthasar’s capitulation to Humani Generis can be clearly discerned “in the way von Balthasar’s dogmatics seems to float free of ontological conceptualizations into a ‘mythical’ realm that is highly voluntarist and personalist, and in the end at times only tendentiously orthodox” (13). One not only wonders what the normative point of reference of Milbank’s use of the term “orthodox” is (“Radical Orthodoxy”?), but also whether the deep and explicitly acknowledged indebtedness of Hans Urs von Balthasar to 90 Book Symposium Sergei Bulgakov’s,18 is ultimately indebted to Origen of Alexandria, a vision “at once more strictly orthodox and more radically humanist.” In short, de Lubac is assigned the role of forerunner to the self-proclaimed movement of Radical Orthodoxy and its continuation of “Origen’s vision of apokatastasis: the universal Christological salvation of spirits and through this, the eternal re-establishment of all things.”19 It is precisely Milbank’s consistently Bulgakovian reading of Henri de Lubac and his tendency to receive Aquinas’s thought in as neo-platonic or Dionysian a way as possible that makes Feingold’s book so irritating for him. While Milbank’s project is neither guided nor framed by the norms and criteria of Catholic theology, his reaction is nevertheless indicative of how not a few contemporary Catholic theologians might react to Feingold’s book as well. For Feingold indeed challenges numerous assumptions received and settled in the first three decades after Vatican II. The first is methodological: In the wake of neo-Marxist sociology, the linguistic turn in Anglo-Saxon philosophy, and the hermeneutical and poststructuralist developments in continental philosophy, theology for many a contemporary Catholic theologian can only be conceived as defensible and intelligible in a thoroughly historical-contextualist and constructivist mode. Every theological claim must needs be advanced, read, and assessed in light of the historical, communal, and political context in which it is produced and to which it is addressed. The only way to forward arguments is by situating and out-narrating opponents as well as offering rhetorical and aesthetic appeals leading to the volitional as well as conceptual conversion of the interlocutor. Propositional discourse as informed by metaphysical realism and discursive, conceptual argumentation is therefore at present widely dismissed as a suspiciously disembodied and philosophically outdated mode of speculative theology, oblivious to the historical, pragmatic, and practiceoriented nature of theology itself and thus vulnerable to being constantly the metaphysics of being as advanced by the two twentieth-century, Thomist philosophers Gustav Siewerth and Ferdinand Ulrich, must have been a form of subtle self-deception, not to mention the form of self-deception exercised in his small, but weighty book on de Lubac. For a critique as concise as devastating of Milbank’s reading of von Balthasar’s theology, see the instructive review essay by Edward T. Oakes, SJ,“On Milbank’s The Suspended Middle,” Nova et Vetera (English) 4 (2006): 667–96, esp. 682ff. 18 Bulgakov’s theological vision—thoroughly impressive in its systematic coherence, comprehensive scope, and speculative penetration—can possibly be best appreciated in his late work, The Bride of the Lamb, trans. Boris Jakim (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2002). 19 Milbank, Suspended, 108. Book Symposium 91 co-opted by deeply entrenched as well as concealed discourses of power and interest. This wholesale rejection of what was seen as the ossified discourse of textbook neo-scholasticism was accompanied—in the wake of Heidegger as well as Wittgenstein—by hailing the “end of metaphysics” in general and the Aristotelian Thomist metaphysics in particular.And since— on the basis of Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni Patris—Thomas Aquinas had again been instantiated as the loadstar of a renewed Catholic philosophy, according to an understanding that interpreted Vatican II as the license to break with that very tradition, he had to be put aside as outmoded too. Yet in recent years, there has occurred a remarkable revival of interest in Thomas Aquinas’s thought (a revival to which Milbank himself has contributed). However, this revival, for the most part, is eager not to steer again a course of confrontation with the meanwhile well-established nouvelle théologie. Rather, this Thomist renewal—in the wake of Chenu and Torrell—characteristically draws on the very best of the historical reconstruction of an authentic Thomas behind the interpretative discourse of the once greatly esteemed, but now equally widely despised Thomist commentatorial tradition, a Thomas whose theology is properly foregrounded and again linked to its original “Sitz im Leben” in the contemplative tradition of Dominican spirituality. At the same time, an increasing philosophical interest in Aquinas has reemerged, but one much more attentive to the historical and social embeddedness of philosophical discourse (Alasdair MacIntyre), in dialogue with analytic philosophy of religion (Norman Kretzmann, Eleonore Stump, et al.) as well as post-Wittgensteinian philosophy of language (Victor Preller, Cornelius Ernst, Herbert McCabe, Fergus Kerr, David Burrell). A large part of Feingold’s provocation rests in the fact that he advances his enquiry and arguments as if none of the above had ever happened. There are no nods of even the slightest acknowledgment into the directions of any of these more recent forms of Thomism. Rather, he concentrates exclusively on Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus (as well as some Scotists), the Thomist commentators (including Suárez) up to GarrigouLagrange and Henri de Lubac. The reason for what seems to be a narrow-minded obsession with the “Thomism of the strict observance,” its interlocutors, and critics is that the scope of his enquiry corresponds with quite appropriate precision to the one in which de Lubac advances his critique of most of the Thomist commentatorial tradition on the question of nature and the supernatural. Moreover and possibly more importantly, Feingold provokes by operating in a mode of discourse very unfamiliar to theological readers by now largely unaccustomed to the conceptual precision and rigor once cultivated 92 Book Symposium by the “schoolmen.” Differently put, Feingold’s mode of discourse is highly mimetic of the virtually forgotten tradition of Thomist commentators. Hence his modus operandi can arguably be understood, precisely by way of his eventual engagement of de Lubac, to continue and thereby help reinstate a particular tradition of discourse (MacIntyre), a move that can be described as “arch-reactionary” or as “prophetically proleptic” or even as “radically orthodox” depending on what one thinks to be at stake in the very recovery of such a discourse of scholastic enquiry and argumentation. Surely the macro-issue ultimately is whether to interpret what is properly Augustinian and properly Thomist by way of an Origenist and Bulgakovian vision (like Milbank) of the eternal God-Man (entailing, by a Bulgakovian “necessity” of love, that is, of ultimately irresistable sophianization, the apokatastasis ton panton),20 or whether to receive what is properly Augustinian and properly Thomist on the predestination of the saints as well as on gratuitous, efficient grace by way of the theology of the late Augustine as received by the Second Synod of Orange (529),21 as confirmed in the late theology of grace in Thomas Aquinas, and as reconfirmed by the Council of Trent.22 The more proximate, but also more implicit dispute between Feingold and de Lubac, however, is over how to access and interpret the interpretation of the Thomist commentators itself. What makes Feingold so provocative is that the form of his discourse—in stark contrast to de Lubac’s way of reading the commentators—is shaped not by a historical hermeneutic but by reconstructing and thus entering their own way of conducting a speculative theological enquiry, a mimetic exercise reconstructing and thus continuing the commentators’ discursive mimesis of Aquinas. In his own very attempt of retrieving an even older form of 20 Bulgakov, in logical consequence, applies what he calls “the necessary principles of universal salvation” (518) to Satan: “Satan’s very being, his createdness by the omniscient God, is, so to speak, an ontological proof of the inevitability of his future salvation. Even Satan in his madness does not have the power to overcome the fact of his own being, its divine foundation, that is, the sophianicity of all creation, by virtue of which ‘God will be all in all.’ Satan cannot fail to be convinced by his own nature of the insanity of seeking freedom in self-willfulness rather than in knowledge of truth, which alone can give true freedom.‘Liar and the father of lies’ who ‘abode not in the truth’ ( Jn 8:44), he will end up by subordinating himself to the truth, and evil will thereby disappear completely from God’s creation.” Bulgakov, The Bride of the Lamb, 517. 21 See DH, nos. 370–400. 22 “Hoc concilium, utpote solummodo provinciale plurimis ignotum et mox per saecula oblivioni traditum, disputationibus demum Concilii Tridentini memoriae redditum est.” Denzinger-Schönmetzer, Enchiridion Symbolorum, 36th ed., 131. Book Symposium 93 theology, de Lubac, on the contrary, transposes the speculative theological discourse of the commentators into a historical-hermeneutical frame of inquiry (this transposition ironically forming nothing but a quite characteristic move of critical scholarship in a genuinely modern sense, and as such completely extrinsic and foreign to the modus operandi of the commentators). Hence what might look to a reader uninitiated into the discursive habits of the commentators like the equivalent of “Protestant fundamentalism” and its propositionalist proof-texting (a charge that the modern liberal Protestant theologians in the Enlightenment tradition liked to place onto the threshold of the scholasticism of Lutheran and Reformed Orthodoxy) represents in Feingold’s case his way of entering the commentatorial tradition with its propositional-discursive mode of operation and, moreover, turning this mode of operation consistently and cogently against de Lubac’s interpretation of the commentators as well as his interpretation of Aquinas. In other words, Feingold refuses to engage de Lubac in the discursive mode by way of which the latter chose to critique the commentators, that is, by way of a primarily historical exegesis of theological language, its development and use, and the related development and flux of theological ideas.23 Rather, Feingold insists on engaging de Lubac’s own account by way of the metaphysical realism (which makes his work a “Garrigou-Langrange type position”)24 and its rigorous discourse in which the Thomist commentators conducted their interpretation and enquiry.25 This particular conflict opens up wide-ranging questions on the nature of the relationship between thought and language and more specifically on what the relationship between the broadly historical (of ideas, concepts, motives) and the strictly speculative and discursive should be in the interpretation of the oeuvre of Thomas Aquinas. Feingold provokes by returning to and, by implication, rehabilitating an older discursive tradition (albeit, and here the nouvelle théologie is unquestionably right, not the 23 One of the most paradigmatic studies in which this approach comes clearest to the fore is de Lubac’s Corpus Mysticum: L’Eucharistie et L’Eglise au Moyen Age (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1949). 24 Milbank, Suspended, 26, note 10. 25 Most recently the Aristotelian Thomist realism of how world, concepts, and language relate (implicitly shared by Feingold with the Thomist commentators and a set of assumptions to which indeed de Lubac’s work is submitted in Feingold’s engagement of it) has been very ably reconstrued and defended in relation to philosophy’s “linguistic turn” by John P. O’Callaghan, Thomist Realism and the Linguistic Turn:Toward a More Perfect Form of Existence (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2003). 94 Book Symposium oldest way of doing theology) and submitting de Lubac’s theology to the conceptual rigor of this tradition. Feingold is so irritating because he picks up the ball where it was dropped—with the broad acceptance of the theological approach advanced by Henri de Lubac and other representatives of the nouvelle théologie—without signaling awareness of what has happened in Catholic theology since. For a doctoral dissertation this is a forgivable sin; if Feingold ever were to consider publishing a version of this work in the form of a book for a wider audience, he would do well to find a way to acknowledge, if not engage, at the least the reemergence of a Thomism in many instances significantly different from the one Reginald GarrigouLagrange represented. However, although Feingold’s approach is for sure “untimely,” I can see no prima facie reason simply to dismiss him as intellectually unworthy of anything but less than subtle forms of scorn and contempt. On the contrary, in light of the fact that Pope John Paul II’s encyclical Fides et Ratio has pointed out that the historical-hermeneutical approach is not sufficient for the full task of Catholic theology, but that Catholic theology’s commitment to the truth requires a genuine speculative mode of operation,26 Feingold’s approach might not be exactly as untimely as it could seem at firsthand to those deeply shaped by the intellectual conventions of the last forty years. Moreover, it should be noted that, one might say, ironically, Feingold displays a historical consciousness sui generis, one present in Milbank (in significant contrast to de Lubac’s de facto operation) only in form of its negation. Both de Lubac and Feingold, in their very dispute over the right interpretation of the Thomist tradition, are highly aware of the conceptual as well as speculative exigencies caused by Bajanism as well as Jansenism and their condemnation, in addition to other developments up to and including the encyclical Humani Generis. De Lubac and Feingold occupy the same ecclesial ground, with a shared, even if variously interpreted, set of doctrinal norms and magisterial decisions. 26 “With regard to the intellectus fidei, a prime consideration must be that the divine Truth ‘proposed to us in the Sacred Scriptures and rightly interpreted by the Church’s teaching [Aquinas, ST II–II, q. 5, a. 3, ad 2] enjoys an innate intelligibility, so logically consistent that it stands as an authentic body of knowledge.The intellectus fidei expounds this truth, not only in grasping the logical and conceptual structure of the propositions, in which the Church’s teaching is framed, but also, indeed primarily, in bringing to light the salvific meaning of these propositions for the individual and for humanity. . . . For its part, dogmatic theology must be able to articulate the universal meaning of the mystery of the One and Triune God and of the economy of salvation, both as a narrative and, above all, in the form of argument.” Pope John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, no. 66; cf. also nos. 95–98. Book Symposium 95 Milbank’s interpretation of de Lubac is, on the contrary, to say the least, notably unencumbered by the normative doctrinal commitments that inform the horizon shared by de Lubac and Feingold, unencumbered to the degree that he interprets de Lubac’s modification, in light of the concerns expressed in the encyclical Humani Generis, of his early Surnaturel in the later two volumes The Mystery of the Supernatural 27 and Augustinianism and Modern Theology 28 as a purely extrinsic form of deference to magisterial pressure.29 Simultaneously, Milbank’s dismissal of von Balthasar’s theological project is largely fueled by the impression that, allegedly unlike de Lubac, the former took the encyclical Humani Generis too seriously to heart by presumably submitting to some version of nature-grace extrinsicism.30 However, it might never have really occurred to Milbank that neither Henri de Lubac nor Hans Urs von Balthasar nor Lawrence Feingold, nor for that matter any of the Catholic theologians and philosophers adverted to in his small book, would want to take the stance that a happily unencumbered oppositionalism to the Church’s magisterium and the normative dogmatic tradition is intrinsic to the role and vocation of the Catholic theologian. (In the case of Milbank’s own criteriology, it remains utterly unclear by what normative criteria Hans Urs von Balthasar should be understood as only marginally orthodox, Henri de Lubac fully, or even radically, orthodox, and Reginald GarrigouLagrange, by implication, heterodox—other than those subjectively entertained by the author.) The struggle between the sets of concerns that de Lubac stands for and the ones Feingold represents, however, only become fully visible and truly weighty in a theological context in which the First Vatican Council as well as the Second Vatican Council matter normatively and in which the encyclicals Aeterni Patris, Humani Generis, and Fides et Ratio as expressions of the pope’s ordinary magisterium continue to inform the work of theology, its methods and modes of discourse. Hence, the wider question, not only but especially for Catholic theology, which Milbank’s situating of Henri de Lubac in his own project and his all too facile dismissal of Feingold’s defense of the commentatorial tradition opens up, is the question in which way and to what degree theology’s 27 The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Herder and Herder, 1965) [Le mystère du surnaturel (Paris: Aubier, 1965)]. See the instructive introduction by David L. Schindler in the new 1998 edition. 28 Augustinianism and Modern Theology, trans. Lancelot Sheppard (New York: Herder and Herder, 1969) [Augustinisme et théologie moderne (Paris: Aubier, 1965)]. 29 Milbank, Suspended, 35ff. 30 See Edward T. Oakes’s trenchant critique of this aspect of Milbank’s construal. 96 Book Symposium formal object is deeply informed by the normative dogmatic tradition as well as the pope’s magisterium. Theologians who operate under the presupposition that the dogmatic tradition as well as the living magisterium constitutively inform theology’s formal object will indeed assume that the concerns expressed in the encyclical Humani Generis about the enduring importance of maintaining a hypothetical state of pure nature, and hence the theonomic principle of nature, are of ongoing relevance for the task of theology and will indeed assume that the magisterial rejection of Bajanism and Jansenism has lasting implications for the way the gratuity of the supernatural order is theologically conceived. If there is indeed an ongoing, legitimate difference possible about the above questions, a productive theological conflict and tension, the mode of discourse in which such an engagement takes place might lean more to the historicalhermeneutical mode as advanced by the nouvelle théologie or more to the speculative-discursive mode as advanced by the Dominican Thomism that engaged and criticized the nouvelle théologie, but in either mode it will want to take account of the Church’s doctrinal tradition as well as the living ordinary magisterium. It seems that Henri de Lubac and Hans Urs von Balthasar occupy a terrain of normative doctrinal and theological commitments shared with Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange and Lawrence Feingold that Milbank can only dismiss as the regrettable submission to the purely extrinsic pressures of dogma and magisterium, the truth claims of which consequently make little if any difference in his reconstruction of Henri de Lubac’s theological project. Observation 2: The Aquinas of Milbank’s Radicalized Bulgakovian Lubacianism Made Strange, or Aquinas the “Other” The question whether, and if so, to what degree Milbank’s intensification of de Lubac’s theology along Bulgakovian lines is legitimate cannot be pursued at this point. However, some remarks are in order pertaining to the reading of Thomas Aquinas he advances to foster such an intensification. Appealing to recent French philosophers of religion and philosophical theologians Courtine, Boulnois, Marion, Schutz, and Lacoste, Milbank stresses three motives, which in their combined force presumably give Thomas Aquinas himself a rather Bulgakovian appearance: “first, spirit as intrinsically linked to grace, second, the entire cosmos as drawn through humanity to beatitude; third, grace as gratuitous because a gift can be a gift without contrast to gift.”31 A bit further on, a fourth moment emerges, this 31 Milbank, Suspended, 88. Book Symposium 97 time unequivocally negative:“the regime of pure nature.”32 While Milbank rightly emphasizes that, according to Aquinas,“Adam was created from the outset with the reception of grace,”33 the very rendition “regime of pure nature” signals a profound misunderstanding: For Aquinas as much as for any other of the scholastic theologians there could never have been some “regime” that would not simply be identical with the execution of divine providence, that is, divine governance. Hence, either the state of pure nature is assumed (as it is not in Aquinas) to belong—even as an instance— to the extant providential order as it coincides with the economy of salvation, or “pure nature” is assumed as hypothetically obtaining in another order of divine providence (as it is in Aquinas). Because of frequent confusions regarding this latter topic, I will take it up first. Next, I shall turn to the question of the fundamental and indispensable difference between nature and grace, the ensuing double gratuity, and finally, by drawing upon St.Thomas’s teaching on predestination, address the Bulgakovian dynamic of the entire cosmos being drawn through humanity to beatitude. Finally, I will briefly address the question whether the rational creature is “intrinsically linked to grace.” In the course of my remarks I am going to consider texts primarily of the later Aquinas, that is, of his Roman period and of his second Parisian regency in order to make strange the Aquinas proposed by Milbank’s radicalized Bulgakovian Lubacianism. During his Roman period St. Thomas, for the first time, had direct access to the full text of such important treatises of the late Augustine as De gratia et libero arbitrio, De correptione et gratia, De dono perseverantiae, and De praedestinatione sanctorum, and possibly came across echoes of the widely lost and forgotten canons of the Second Synod of Orange—an encounter with a salutary impact on his late theology of grace that ever so subtly promotes the new, contingent, and supernatural gratuity of grace above and beyond the ontological thrust of the exitusreditus scheme.34 These texts from Aquinas serve as pointers to a significant strand of thought in his later theology on the specific gratuity of grace, texts that strongly suggest that the commentators first and foremost 32 Ibid., 89. 33 Ibid. 34 For detailed accounts of this rather complex matter, see Henri Bouillard, Conver- sion et Grace chez S.Thomas d’Aquin (Paris: Aubier, 1944), 97–102; Max Seckler, Instinkt und Glaubenswille nach Thomas von Aquin (Mainz: Matthias Grünewald, 1961), 90–98; Joseph P.Wawrykow, God’s Grace and Human Action: “Merit” in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), 266–76. 98 Book Symposium continue conceptually to unfold the implications of his theology of grace. Moreover, these texts paradigmatically represent central strands in Aquinas’s theology that strongly resist an adoption of the doctor communis into an overarching theological scheme shaped by the visions of Origen and Bulgakov. 1.The hypothetical state of pure nature as entailed in the notion of differing orders of divine providence: De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 15 While St. Thomas never assumed an extant state of pure nature, he explicitly entertained as a legitimate thought the possibility of a state of pure nature in a different order of divine providence. Such an assumption, however, presupposes the relative integrity of the principle of nature, both ontologically as well as epistemically. We find these matters quite instructively addressed by St.Thomas in De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 15. In De malo, q. 5, a. 1,35 St.Thomas treats the question “Is Privation of the Vision of God a Fitting Punishment for Original Sin?” and defends the position that indeed the privation of the vision of God is a fitting punishment for original sin. He does so by arguing that if two things belong to something’s perfection—the first being capable of a great good but with significant external help, the second needing no or little help but being a small good—then the first is still far better than the second. Hence it is much better to attain a great good with much help than to attain a little good with little or no help at all. “Therefore, rational creatures surpass every other kind of creature in being capable of the highest good in beholding and enjoying God, although the sources from their own nature do not suffice to attain it, and they need the help of God’s grace to attain it.”36 Thomas emphasizes up front that to attain the perfect end of the beatific vision, every rational creature—be it angel or human—is in need of a particular divine help, sanctifying grace. However, due to the particular constitution of the human nature, it being an essentially composite nature of soul and body, an additional help is necessary, namely original justice: 35 As is often the case so also here, Aquinas addresses in the first article of a partic- ular question the most central issue and lays it out in such a way that it provides the basic structure of how the rest of the articles tackling other aspects of the question are ordered. 36 De malo, q. 5 a. 1, c.: “Creatura ergo rationalis in hoc preeminet omni creature, quod capax est summi boni per diuinam uisionem et fruitionem, licet ad hoc consequendum nature proprie principia non sufficiant, sed ad hoc indigeat auxilio diuine gratie.” The De malo of Thomas Aquinas, trans. Richard Regan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 408. In the following, this edition will be refered to as De malo, Davies edition. Book Symposium 99 If the body and the senses be left to their nature, as it were, they burden and hinder the intellect from being able freely to attain the highest reaches of contemplation. And this help was original justice, by which the mind of human beings would be so subject to God that their lower powers and their very bodies would be completely subject to them, nor would their reason impede them from being able to tend toward God. . . . [T]his help, whereby the body is under the control of the soul, and sense powers under the control of the intellect, is almost a disposition for the help whereby the human mind is ordained to see and enjoy God.37 Original justice, being gratuitously given to what has been created and hence to be distinguished from human nature per se, is a quasi-disposition for the help of sanctifying grace. Hence, sanctifying grace acts upon a human nature readily fit for such an operation, the one being neither intrinsic nor extrinsic to the other, but of a perfect and perfectly gratuitous fittingness (convenientia). Original sin, however, destroys this quasidisposition, the help of original justice, as the result of which sanctifying grace—that is,“the help, whereby the human mind is ordained to see and enjoy God”—is withdrawn as the fitting punishment. And when persons by sinning cast away the means whereby they were disposed to obtain a good, they deserve that the good that they were disposed to obtain be taken away.And the very taking away of the good is a fitting punishment for the sin. And so the fitting punishment of original sin is the taking away of grace and thereby of the vision of God for which grace ordains human beings.38 Thomas clearly distinguishes in this question among (1) a composite nature, that is, a reality to be intellectually grasped according to its proper constituents, that is, as species, irrespective of the particular state—original justice—this composite nature is to be found in at the beginning, (2) the specific gratuitous help of original justice, being not integral to human nature, but rather constitutive of the particular state in which created humanity originally existed according to the given providential order, this original justice being the disposition for (3) the help of sanctifying grace, both helps being categorically different from the created nature and also different in kind from each other. Let us consider now objection 15. This important objection denies that the privation of the vision of God is a fitting punishment for original sin, which goes like this: If human beings had been endowed with just 37 Ibid., 409. 38 Ibid. 100 Book Symposium natural powers (homo naturalibus constitutus) and had never sinned, they would have been indeed without the vision of God (which in any case can only be attained by grace). But since punishment is rightly owed for sin, the deprival of the vision of God cannot be called punishment for original sin. Thomas responds to this objection that humans endowed with only natural powers (homo in solis naturalibus constitutus) would indeed be without the divine vision if they were to die in such a supposed state (precluding hence any further divine agency before the separation of body and soul); however, this lack of the divine vision would in no way be punitive, since “the debt of not having it” would not apply to them: “For it is one thing, not to be bound to have, which does not have the nature of punishment but of defect only, and it is another thing to be bound not to have, which does have the nature of punishment.”39 Aquinas is unquestionably entertaining here the concept of a hypothetical state of pure nature, hypothetical because under the present order of providence such a state clearly never obtained.40 The obtaining order of providence, on the contrary, coincides with the economy of salvation, according to which the human being, as created, was originally gifted with the help of original justice and elevated by sanctifying grace.To put it differently, according to Aquinas—and as Milbank rightly emphasizes—humanity was originally created immediately in a state of grace. However, another order of providence seems for St. Thomas hypothetically entertainable in a perfectly legitimate way, and under such an order the non-attainability of the divine vision seems also to be perfectly thinkable. What seems, by entailment, also to be perfectly conceivable in his answer to the objection is the continuity of the self-same human nature under different orders of providence. Consequently, the state of graced nature presupposes an anterior created nature, the latter never de facto 39 This translation, which I prefer to the one offered by Richard Regan in the Davies edition is to be found in St. Thomas Aquinas, On Evil, trans. John A. Oesterle and Jean T. Oesterle (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), 214. “Aliud est enim non debere habere, quod non habet rationem pene set defectus tantum, et aliud debere non habere, quod habet rationem pene.” De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 15; De malo, Davies edition, 412. 40 De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 1: “Human beings would have been created uselessly and in vain if they were to be unable to attain happiness, as would be the case with anything that cannot obtain its ultimate end. And so, lest human beings begotten with original sin be created uselessly and in vain, God from the beginning of the human race intended a remedy for them by which they would be freed from such frustration, namely, Jesus Christ, the very mediator between God and human beings. And the impediment of original sin could be removed through faith in him.” Davies edition, 409. Book Symposium 101 obtaining without the former, however being an ontological principle with its own integrity, the two being related to each other by way of a supreme fittingness, but without any intrinsic continuity between each other. For different orders of providence do not entail an ontological transmutation of the human being, nor is the rational soul—while capax Dei—becoming something else in a hypothetical order in which the human being is ordered to a lesser felicity than the vision of God. Hence, for Aquinas, the creation of a rational soul, capable of the vision of God, yet destined to a lesser felicity does not seem to be a contradiction in the very created nature itself, nor to constitute a punishment per se. However, in comparison to the de facto obtaining providential order, such a lesser felicity can still be characterized by Aquinas as a defectus, to be understood rather neutrally as the absence of that which simply was never supposed to be there in the first place. Reflection about a hypothetical state of pure nature seems rather clearly to have its root in Aquinas’s own thought rather than to be a retrospective projection of the Thomist commentators. Such reflection, however, entails that God’s creative activity insofar as it results in a subsistent reality, in distinct species, obtains ontologically and is hence epistemically accessible as well as intelligible in a multitude of created “natures,” including the human nature, quite independently from superadded divine helps and gifts to that nature.This is the case even though in the de facto obtaining providential order these helps and gifts were indeed given, according to Aquinas, from the first instance of human existence; one of which (original justice) was destroyed by the fall and the other (sanctifying grace) withdrawn in consequence of it.While human nature remains a constant, subsistent reality under a variety of hypothetical divine providential orders, the superadded divine helps and gifts belong to the de facto economy of grace known solely by divine revelation. Moreover, it is indeed important to emphasize that for Aquinas human nature under the condition of sin in the present order of providence is emphatically not to be understood as the result of a fall into some state of “pure nature.” Rather, original sin has affected human nature in such a way that in the present order of providence, after the loss of original justice, human nature is wounded.That is, because of the first sin, human nature is now continuously marked by the deficiency of a disordered disposition (peccatum naturae), which antecedes the free exercise of the will (ST I–II, qq. 82–83). Hence, St. Thomas consistently differentiates between the concrete historical condition of human nature sub conditione peccati, which belongs to the extant order of providence as it coincides with the economy of salvation on the one hand, and on the other hand 102 Book Symposium a hypothetical state of pure nature.What is presupposed by such a nuanced and theologically indispensable differentiation is the relative integrity of the principle of nature, ontologically as well as epistemically. Put differently, the relative integrity of the principle (or the order) of nature is the necessary condition for the possibility of differentiating properly between the realities of creation, creation sub conditione peccati, and redemption. Failing to do so would inevitably lead to deficient theological positions, such as doctrines denying sin’s impact on human nature, or doctrines defending the essential corruption (allegedly due to original sin) or the essential transmutation (presumably due to deification) of human nature. Hence, it is not accidental at all that St.Thomas defends the necessity of the sacraments as a healing remedy after sin based on this principle: “Man’s nature is the same before and after sin, but the state of his nature is not the same. Because after sin, the soul, even in its higher part, needs to receive something from corporeal things in order that it may be perfected: whereas man had no need of this in that state.”41 2. Desiderium naturae versus desiderium gratiae: St.Thomas on 2 Corinthians 5, 5–10 For Aquinas, as for all Christian theology, everything that is, is God’s gift (creatio ex nihilo). However, there is—in the present order of providence as coinciding with the economy of salvation—a second gift. Because God is the giver of both gifts and because the second (sanctifying grace) has to come by way of the first (being), there indeed cannot obtain an essential heterogeneity between them in respect of their origin. At the same time, however, what we might arguably call the donum primum and the donum ultimum do not simply represent two aspects of the self-same gift. Rather, there obtains a significant difference between both gifts: While God is the omnipotent first cause of both gifts, God, being the sole cause of the first gift, creation, grants the rational creature proper secondary causality in the comprehensive realization of the second gift, beatitude. While the first gift brings about free will by constituting it via God’s exclusive creative agency, the second gift involves the proper actualization of free will in the realization of the gift (not, however, in a constitutive, 41 ST III, q. 61, a. 2, ad 2, emphasis added: “Ad secundum dicendum quod eadem est natura hominis ante peccatum et post peccatum, non tamen est idem naturae status. Nam post peccatum anima, etiam quantum ad superiorem partem, indiget accipere aliquid a corporalibus rebus ad sui perfectionem: quod in illo statu homini necesse non erat.” Book Symposium 103 but in an appropriately accompanying way).42 Moreover, the second gift is to be differentiated from the first gift in that (1) the second gift necessarily presupposes the first gift (not in the chronological order, but in the logical as well as ontological orders) while the second gift is not necessarily entailed by the first; (2) the second gift brings the first gift, in the case of the human being, to a gratuitous, ultimate supernatural perfection and fulfillment; (3) the second gift discloses in the case of the rational creature—by initially ordering the first gift, created human nature, to the supernatural end and secondly perfecting it—the intrinsic ontological openness of the first for the second gift as well as the former’s surpassing fittingness for such a supernatural perfection; and (4) the second gift is all of this without canceling out the connatural, proportionate end that comes with the prior gift, created human nature. A quite remarkable instance of how St. Thomas distinguishes such a connatural end and the respective desire directed to it from an end that is infinitely disproportionate to human nature and hence requires the distinct supernatural desire that corresponds to such an end, can be found in one of Aquinas’s commentaries on the Pauline corpus of letters: 2 Corinthians 5:5–1043. In lectures 1 and 2 of his commentary on 2 Corinthians 5, Aquinas distinguishes between a desiderium naturae and a desiderium gratiae,44 and displays the subtle dynamic between the two in this difficult passage of St. Paul’s text. St.Thomas begins his second lecture (on vv. 5–10) with the 42 I regard Bernard Lonergan’s early study Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St.Thomas Aquinas, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran, vol. 1 of Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000) still to be the benchmark analysis of Aquinas’s profound treatment of this utterly complex topic. 43 2 Cor 5, 1–10 RSV:“(1) For we know that if the earthly tent we live in is destroyed, we have a building from God, as house not made with hands, eternal in the heavens. (2) Here indeed we groan, and long to put on our heavenly dwelling, (3) so that by putting it on we may not be found naked. (4) For while we are still in this tent, we sigh with anxiety; not that we would be unclothed, but that we would be further clothed, so that what is mortal may be swallowed up by life. (5) He who has prepared us for this very thing is God, who has given us the Spirit as a guarantee. (6) So we are always of good courage; we know that while we are at home in the body we are away from the Lord, (7) for we walk by faith, not by sight. (8) We are of good courage, and we would rather be away from the body and at home with the Lord. (9) So whether we are at home or away, we make it our aim to please him. (10) For we must all appear before the judgment seat of Christ, so that each one may receive good or evil, according to what he has done in the body.” 44 In order to make the same distinction, he also uses the pair naturalia desideria versus supernaturalia desideria. 104 Book Symposium observation that in this section of his letter the apostle shows us that the author of the desire for the heavenly habitation is, in a very specific way, God, and that this desire is quite different from, indeed in contradiction to, the desiderium naturae: Hic ostendit auctorem supernaturalis desiderii de habitatione caelesti. Causa enim naturalis desiderii quod nolumus expoliari est, quia sc. anima naturaliter unitur corpori, et e converso. Sed hoc, quod caelestem inhabitationem superindui cupiamus, non est ex natura, sed ex Deo.45 Since the human being is a composite nature, the soul is naturally united with the body (being the sole substantial form) such that there is a natural desire to abhor the separation of the two, which is natural death. Hence, the desiderium naturae is an innate, necessary desire for the ongoing integrity of the human composite nature. It is a desire that reflects the very constitution of human nature per se in its relative integrity as an ontological principle with perfect epistemic intelligibility. However, the desire “to put on our heavenly dwelling” does not come from our nature, but from God in a distinct and quite specific way. Most interesting here is the contrasting use of ex natura and ex Deo. Ex natura is, of course, nothing else than the singular effect of God’s creative agency (creatio ex nihilo as well as creatio continuans). In contrast, ex Deo must refer here to an act (1) categorically distinct from the former, (2) in no way in any prospective intrinsic continuity with it, (3) but rather in a surprising, newly gratuitous relationship with and hence in clear distinction from the former: Cuius ratio est, quia quamlibet naturam consequitur appetitus conveniens fini suae naturae, sicut grave naturaliter tendit deorsum, et appetit ibi quiescere. Si autem sit appetitus alicujus rei supra naturam suam, illa res non movetur ad illum finem naturaliter, sed ab alio quod est supra naturam suam. Constat autem quod perfrui caelesti gloria, et videre Deum per essentiam, licet sit rationalis creaturae, est tamen supra naturam ipsius, non ergo movetur rationalis creatura ad hoc desiderandum a natura, sed ab ipso Deo, qui in hoc ipsum efficit nos, etc. Sed quomodo hoc efficit subdit, dicens: Qui dedit pignus, etc. Circa quod sciendum est, quod Deus efficit in nobis naturalia desideria et supernaturalia. Naturalia quidem 45 S.Thomae Aquinatis in omnes S. Pauli Apostoli epistolas commentaria, vol. 1, (Turin: Marietti, 1929), 449.“Here he discloses the author of the supernatural desire for a heavenly dwelling. For the cause of a natural desire that we be not despoiled is that the soul is naturally united to the body, and vice versa. But the desire to be clothed upon with a heavenly dwelling is not from nature but from God.” (Translation by Fabian R. Larcher, OP) Book Symposium 105 quando dat nobis spiritum naturalem convenientem naturae humanae. Inspiravit in faciem ejus, etc. [Gen 1]. Supernaturalia vero dat quando infundit in nobis supernaturalem spiritum, sc. Spiritum Sanctum. Et ideo dicit: Dedit nobis pignus spiritus, id est, Spiritum Sanctum causantem in nobis certitudinem hujus rei qua desideramus impleri. Signati estis Spiritu promissionis Sancto, etc. [Eph 1].46 This text speaks for itself. According to Aquinas, God effects in us natural as well as supernatural desires: Deus efficit in nobis naturalia desideria et supernaturalia. The former are understood in this context strictly per se (as integral to a distinct species in its natural constitution), that is, not exclusively as desires as they might characterize the human being extant sub conditione peccati, but as desires of a composite, mortal nature irrespective of the providential order in which it is found. Because of their natural spirit (spiritus naturalis), as it is fitting for human nature, human beings are endowed with naturalia desideria. The supernatural desires are, on the contrary, given by God, ab ipso Deo over and above the naturalia desideria. Categorically different from the former, the supernatural desires are the distinct effect of the Holy Spirit’s mission, desires that indeed are the very pledge of the Spirit himself. Most decisive, however, is the explicit statement: Si autem sit appetitus alicujus rei supra naturam suam, illa res non movetur ad illum finem naturaliter, sed ab alio quod est supra naturam suam. Constat autem quod perfrui caelesti gloria, et videre Deum per essentiam, licet sit rationalis creaturae, est tamen supra naturam ipsius, 46 Ibid. “The reason for this is that upon every nature follows a desire suited to the end of that nature, as something heavy naturally tends downward and seeks to rest there. But if a thing’s desire is above its nature, that thing is not moved to that end naturally, but by something else, which is above its nature. Now it is evident that to enjoy eternal glory and to see God by his essence, although it is appropriate to a rational creature, is above its nature.Therefore, the rational creature is not moved to desire this by nature, but by God himself,‘who prepared us for this very thing.’ How this is accomplished he adds, saying, ‘who has given us the Spirit as a guarantee [pledge].’ In regard to this it should be noted that God produces natural desires and supernatural desires in us: the natural, when he gives us a natural spirit suited to human nature:‘God breathed into his nostrils the breath of life’ [Gn 2:7]; but he gives the supernatural desires when he infuses in us the supernatural spirit, that is, the Holy Spirit.Therefore he says, who has given us the Spirit as a guarantee, that is, the Holy Spirit producing in us the certainty of this thing, with which we desire to be filled:‘You were sealed with the Holy Spirit, which is the guarantee of our inheritance’ [Eph 1:13–14]” (Translation by Fabian R. Larcher, OP). 106 Book Symposium non ergo movetur rationalis creatura ad hoc desiderandum a natura, sed ab ipso Deo.47 Aquinas operates here very clearly with the distinction between an appetite or desire proportionate and connatural to human nature and being capable of directing human beings toward their connatural end, and a supernatural desire, given from above, directing human beings to their ultimate, supernatural end. Although the fruition of heavenly glory and the vision of God’s essence is a permitted end (licet!) for the rational creature, because it utterly transcends human nature the rational creature cannot be moved naturally to this end but must be moved to this end by God by way of a supernatural desire given by the Holy Spirit. Hence it hardly amounts to a retrospective projection of a deplorable Baroque severance between nature and grace back into Aquinas when the seventeenth-century French Dominican theologian and Thomist commentator Jean Baptiste Gonet claims that “innate appetite is from God as Author of nature, and as the Creator of natural forms. However, the desire for the clear vision of God cannot be from the Author of nature.Therefore, there cannot be an innate appetite for it.”48 In order to confirm Gonet’s thesis, Feingold rightly draws upon Aquinas’s commentary on 2 Corinthians 5 and states: According to this text, nature herself does not give a natural desire for an end that is above the nature of the creature. Such a desire directly for a supernatural end must be infused directly by God, working above the natural order, through the gift of grace. De Lubac claims that this distinction between “God as Author of the natural order” and “God as Author of the supernatural order,” or between “God as the object of natural beatitude” and “God as the object of supernatural beatitude,” is not found in St.Thomas.49 47 Ibid.“But if a thing’s desire is above its nature, that thing is not moved to that end naturally, but by something else, which is above its nature. Now it is evident that to enjoy eternal glory and to see God by his essence, although it is appropriate to a rational creature, is above its nature.Therefore, the rational creature is not moved to desire this by nature, but by God himself ” (Translation by Fabian R. Larcher, OP). 48 Feingold’s translation from Gonet, Clypeus theologiae thomisticae contra novos ejus impugnatores, 6 vols. (Bordeaux 1659–69; Lyons 1681; Paris 1875) vol. 1 in I, q. 12, disp. 1, a. 5, §2, n. 86, 224, cited in Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Rome: Apollinare Studi, 2001), 655. 49 Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 656f. Book Symposium 107 Feingold displays a significant number of texts by Aquinas that prove the contrary.50 He concludes: Thus it is clear that for St. Thomas, the natural love of God above all, which man has in common with all creatures, is not directed to God insofar as He can be seen in the beatific vision. Instead it is directed to God as the source and end of natural perfections, which generates a ‘natural friendship’ with God (In I Cor, c. 13, v. 13, lect. 4).The love or desire for God (or conversion to God) insofar as He can be participated in through grace, and seen face to face, is spoken of by St.Thomas as charity, a love which is exclusively the product of grace. . . .Therefore, it is clear that for St.Thomas, it would be very wrong to say that there is an innate natural desire or love for God insofar as He can be participated in only through grace. Such a love or inclination directed towards God as He can be possessed supernaturally in the beatific vision must itself be the product of a supernatural intervention of God, infusing the theological virtues.51 Feingold’s correct emphasis on the sole efficient causality of God’s supernatural intervention in eliciting the supernatural desire, however, does not per se invalidate the insistence upon a natural desire for the vision of God. We find in this text two clearly distinguished operations of God—and corresponding gifts from God—one being the very constitution of human nature as a subsistent reality (with an end proportionate to this nature and its corresponding natural desires), the other being God’s sovereign salvific operation in relationship to extant human beings, a second gift drawing the first beyond the confines of its original giftedness and thus not destroying but perfecting it in a way prospectively as inconceivable as unanticipatable, yet retrospectively to be understood as perfectly fitting the first gift as it has been created for and is intrinsically open to the reception of the second gift.The necessary precondition for the fitting reception of the second gift, however, must be a readiness in the first gift for the second, a potential in the first gift that allows for a transnatural expansion (elevation), an expansion infinitely disproportionate to human nature. However, because it is a genuine potential of the first gift, its infinitely disproportionate expansion does not transmute the particular constitution 50 Ibid., 658f, note 72: ST I, q. 60, a. 5, ad 4; ST I, q. 62, a. 2, ad 1; ST I, q. 63, a. 1, ad 3; ST I–II, q. 62, a. 1, ad 3; ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3, ad 1; ST II–II, q. 26, a. 3; Quodl., I, q. 4, a. 3 [8], ad 1; De car., q. un., a. 2, ad 16; De spe, q. un., a. 1, ad 9; In I Cor., c. 13, v. 13, lect. 4; De malo, q. 16, a. 4, ad 14 and 15; De malo, q. 5, a. 3, ad 4; Comp. theol., I, q. 174, n. 2; In II Sent., d. 3, q. 4, ad 1; In II Sent., d. 33, q. 2, a. 2, ad 5; In III Sent., d. 27, q. 2, a. 2, ad 4. 51 Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 659f. Book Symposium 108 of the first gift, its specific nature, into another nature. That is, in the beatific vision, human beings remain human beings. (They are not, in an Eckhartian sense, “melted” into the divine essence itself.) Would such a specific natural potential of the first gift (the technical term in the Thomist tradition became “specific obediential potency”),52 however, not require a corresponding, proper natural desire? While such a desire would need to correspond in potency to the second gift (hence a desire for the vision of God), it could not be a desire innate to human nature itself (that is, a desiderium naturae), because such a desire would necessarily reflect the connatural end of the composite human nature. Rather, this natural desire for the ultimate supernatural end would need to be elicited by the same faculties by way of which the second gift is received: intellect and will. And precisely in the vicinity of this elicited desire, quasi-preparing and undergirding it, we find the proper instantiation of that ontological élan so often emphasized by Milbank as the comprehensive dynamic of the creation’s reditus to God. Such an élan indeed plays a fundamental and indispensable role in the thought of the doctor communis. This élan, however, is treated by Aquinas in a highly nuanced way that Milbank fails to recognize. For it falls, first and foremost, under the category of “natural love” and, more precisely, comprises the equivalent of what Jacques Maritain, in his brilliant analysis of the four necessary loves (developed by Aquinas in the treatise on the angels in his Summa theologiae) has identified as the first and the second love.The first is a love, by which every creature naturally loves the supreme Whole more than itself with a radical élan consubstantial with its essence. . . . It naturally exists in every creature, with or without sense or reason, and is not free. It is inamissible; a being cannot lose it except by losing its nature and ceasing to exist. It continues to exist in the sinner and in the demon.53 The second love is a version of the first, namely the love through which every creature capable of knowledge loves the supreme Whole more than itself, instinctively or by a spontaneous élan and not because it knows Him, due solely to the fact that it loves necessarily, and with an elicited love, whatever is its good of nature. . . . Here there is no knowl- 52 See Steven A. Long’s astute treatment and defense of this concept in his contri- bution to this volume. 53 Jacques Maritain, The Sin of the Angel:An Essay on a Re-Interpretation of Some Thomistic Positions, trans.William L. Rossner, SJ (Westminster: Newman Press, 1959), 20. Book Symposium 109 edge of God properly speaking, no idea of God from which an elicited love for God might proceed.54 These first two loves, according to Thomas, cannot fail; they endure even in hell. Not so the next two.The third is the “elicited love of nature” which, before any option or election, arises at once in every intellectual creature as a spontaneous, immediate movement of the rational appetite at the instant and by the mere fact that the intellect knows the existence of the Principle of all good, the Selfsubsisting Good which is the common good of all.55 While a movement necessary in itself, this love depends indirectly on the free will,“insofar as it can be prevented by free will, like any other indeliberate motion of the elicited appetite.”56 Finally, “in every intelligent creature there exists a natural inclination . . . to love the supreme Whole more than himself with an elicited love of free option.The intelligent creature is inclined by his nature to this love which is essentially free in its very mode of emanation.”57 Hence, de Lubac’s famous dictum from Surnaturel that “the spirit is the desire for God”58 is indeed correct—on the ontological level of natural love.As will become sufficiently clear later, for Aquinas neither the innate ontological love pure and simple, nor the intra-elicited ontological love of God above all, translates into an innate natural desire for the vision of God. For, as Maritain rightly stresses, according to Aquinas, the human being, as composite nature fundamentally different from the angel, receives all knowledge by way of the senses. Hence, since there is no innate knowledge of God,59 the human being’s natural desire for the vision of God, if it is an intellective desire (which, according to Aquinas, it is), must be called forth via the senses by the first gift, creation, as it points, by way of its causal order, not ineluctably, but consistently, to its primal origin, the Giver of the gift. It must, hence, be an elicited desire, intending a transnatural and ultimately infinitely disproportionate end that, however, because of the 54 Ibid., 20–22. 55 Ibid., 23. 56 Ibid., 24. 57 Ibid., 26. 58 Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 500 (“L’esprit est donc désir de Dieu,” Surnaturel, 483). 59 The intellectus agens, pace Milbank, does not provide such a knowledge, even most implicitly. 110 Book Symposium nature of the intellect, remains integral to the connatural human end as proportionate to human nature—short of the gift of sanctifying grace.60 3. Double Gratuity Milbank, in his Bulgakovian radicalization of de Lubac and by entailment of Aquinas argues that the two gifts, the second in a unique way perfecting the first, are to be seen in a continuum, a seamless dynamic of varying intensity, reflecting a fundamental ontological élan drawing the entire cosmos through humanity to beatitude. Can St. Thomas’s theology be drafted for a project that assumes a single non-contrastive gratuity, seamlessly connecting creation and deification in a comprehensive unitary and universalistic vision? On the contrary, Aquinas’s theology of grace entails a clear double gratuity; moreover, his doctrine of predestination forestalls any attempt to claim his patronage for such a theological project. In his profound and, in light of the widespread contemporary theological confusions about Christology, highly relevant treatise on the hypostatic union in the tertia pars of the Summa theologiae, questions 1–15, Aquinas dedicates the second quaestio to the problem of the precise mode of the union of the Incarnate Word with the human nature. Relevant for our particular problem is article 10 of question 2, where he asks whether the union of the incarnation took place by grace. In his response,Aquinas first offers a crisp summary of his definition of grace originally submitted in question 110, article 1 of the prima secundae:“Grace is taken in two 60 This elicited desire indeed needs to be satisfied supernaturally for an absolutely perfect human felicity to occur.The Thomist who, according to my lights, got the matter exactly right ad mentem S.Thomae is Jacques Maritain—and Feingold’s long analysis is in substantive agreement with Maritain on this point:“Beatitude signifies perfect felicity, ultima perfectio rationalis seu intellectualis creaturae (the ultimate perfection of the rational or intellectual creature) [ST I, q. 62, a. 1]. And the very notion of perfect felicity might well be understood in various senses which are more or less strict, from the eudaimonia of the sage of antiquity, to the joy which surpasses all that the mind of man has ever conceived. As far as I am concerned, I do not much like the expression ‘natural beatitude,’ for I do not think that there is any absolutely perfect felicity as long as the natural (trans-natural) desire to see God (a desire which in the Angel must be still much more profound than in man) is not supernaturally satisfied. Nevertheless, I shall use the expression ‘natural beatitude’ . . . because quarrels over words are uninteresting, and because St.Thomas himself does not hesitate to use the word beatitude [‘Quodammodo beatitudo . . . dicitur,’ ST I, q. 62, a. 1] in order to designate the state of pure natural happiness . . . in which the Angel was created.” Maritain, The Sin of the Angel, 97. Book Symposium 111 ways: first as the will of God bestowing something; secondly, as the free gift of God.”61 First, according to this definition, one might want to assume that St. Thomas regards creation itself as the first grace, since it surely is the first and foremost of all gifts.62 However, quite interestingly, St.Thomas does not mention creation in this context at all. Rather, he immediately relates grace to human nature, a principle of relative but distinct ontological integrity and hence relative but distinct epistemic accessibility: “Now human nature stands in need of the gratuitous will of God in order to be lifted up [elevetur] to God, since this is above its natural capability.” Second, a crucial term—if not the crucial term—in the above quote is the verb “to be lifted up,” in the Latin passive elevari (active: elevare; noun: elevatio). Human nature—notice that Thomas does not say here, the “human person”—stands in a passive relationship to a specific agency of God, an agency fundamentally distinct from creatio ex nihilo and creatio continuans, in that it is an agency that presupposes human nature (notice, however, not a subsistent “state of pure nature”) as a distinct species, sufficiently conceptually penetrable in its distinction from other natures in order to make relevant ontological claims about it and in relationship to which grace operates qua elevatio, because hoc sit supra facultatem naturae suae. Third, St. Thomas distinguishes between two ways of elevatio, one per operationem, another per esse personale. The first, by operation, occurs “as the saints know and love God.”The second, by personal being, occurs only in Christ, “in Whom human nature is assumed so as to be in the Person of the Son of God.”As St.Thomas reminds his readers in the tertia pars of the Summa theologiae, question 4, article 1, ad 2, the elevation bringing about a union by operation is indeed possible because of “the likeness of image [. . .] found in human nature.”This likeness consists in human nature being capax Dei, namely, “by attaining to Him through its own operation of knowledge and love,” which are the essential characteristics of the intellectual soul. And it is precisely this capax Dei, this inherent potentiality in human nature that grace reduces to act, to unitive knowledge and love, whereby human nature is elevated to God per operationem. Both ways of 61 “Respondeo dicendum quod, sicut in Secunda Parte dictum est, gratia dupliciter dicitur: uno modo, ipsa voluntas Dei gratis aliquid dantis; alio modo, ipsum gratuitum donum Dei.” 62 For a profound metaphysical meditation of creation as gift (long before the presently as fashionable and as tiring debate over whether a gift can be given set in), see Kenneth L. Schmitz, The Gift: Creation (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1982). 112 Book Symposium elevation presuppose the integrity of the prior gift, even sub conditione peccati, and by entailment the supplementary nature of the second gift. It is not explicitly denied by Aquinas in this place that the second gift, quasi by infinite intensification of the first, extends efficaciously and hence infallibly to all rational creatures. However, it is by no means accidental that Aquinas chose his sed contra in question 2, article 10, preparing his response in light of the objections, from St. Augustine’s late work De praedestinatione sanctorum, where Augustine argues that it is a mystery why faith is given to some and not to others and that the elect are not called because they believe, but that they may believe. The quote from the sed contra itself is taken from book 15 in which Augustine argues that the incarnation provides the supreme example of grace’s specific gratuity, for Christ’s human nature could have done nothing to deserve to be united to the Word.63 What is clearly presupposed in this article, namely a distinct double gratuity, is constitutive of the whole architecture of Aquinas’s mature theology of grace. The clear and categorical distinction between the first gift of creation and the grace of elevation is rooted deeply in Aquinas’s doctrine of God, and especially in his Trinitarian reflections. In his discussion of the missions of the Son and Spirit in the prima pars of the Summa theologiae, question 43, article 3, he starts with the axiomatic distinction between two kinds of God’s presence: First, “God is in all things by his essence, power, and presence, according to his one common mode, as the cause existing in the effects which participate in his goodness.” There is, however, a second, special, and superior mode according to which God is present, a mode characterized by Aquinas with the terms “above and beyond” (super) and “in a new way” (novo modo): Above and beyond this common mode, however, there is one special mode belonging to the rational nature wherein God is said to be present as the object known is in the knower, and the beloved in the lover. And since the rational creature by its own operation of knowledge and love attains to God Himself, according to this special mode God is said not only to exist in the rational creature, but also to dwell therein as in his own temple (ST I, q. 43, a. 3). And the latter, St.Thomas states, happens by sanctifying grace:“The Holy Ghost is possessed by man, and dwells within him, in the very gift itself 63 “Ea gratia fit ab initio fidei suae homo quicumque Christianus, qua gratia homo ille ab initio suo factus est Christus” (cap. 10; Patrologia latina 44, 982). Thomas continues: “Sed homo ille factus est Christus per unionem ad divinam naturam. Ergo unio illa fuit per gratiam.” Book Symposium 113 of sanctifying grace.” It is the latter claim, that the Holy Spirit dwells within the human being in the gift of sanctifying grace (in ipso dono gratiae gratum facientis) that perfectly justifies that, while human nature qua rational soul is surely capable of it, this “indwelling” of the Spirit by way of elevating human nature through sanctifying grace is infinitely beyond and categorically different from God’s presence in the first mode, the presence of the Creator in the creation. If one turns to St. Thomas’s discussion of the mission of the divine persons, it might indeed be perfectly defensible to call the very indwelling in the mind of the Trinity by sanctifying grace (ST I, q. 43, a. 5) a donum ultimum since by this very gift “the soul is made like to God” (ST I, q. 43, a. 5, ad 2: anima per gratiam conformatur Deo), resulting in an ultimate beatitude to be obtained “by the power of God alone, by a kind of participation of the Godhead, about which it is written (2 Pt 1:4) that by Christ we are made partakers of the Divine nature” (ST I–II, q. 62, a. 1). Different from this donum ultimum, the gift of union with God by the indwelling of the Trinity by sanctifying grace, is the very precondition for it, a first and fundamental gift, which we might want to call the donum primum, creation as the gift of a relation to God that issues in a procession of creatures caused and upheld by the triune God’s exemplar, efficient, formal, and final causality, a relation, however, that subsists in its own relative, but proper integrity: For God is in all things by his essence, power, and presence, according to his one common mode, as the cause existing in the effects which participate in his goodness. Above and beyond this common mode, however, there is one special mode belonging to the rational nature wherein God is said to be present as the object known is in the knower, and the beloved in the lover.And since the rational creature by its operation of knowledge and love attains to God Himself, according to this special mode God is said not only to exist in the rational creature, but also to dwell therein as in his own temple. So no other effect can be put down as the reason why the divine person is in the rational creature in a new mode, except sanctifying grace.64 64 ST I, q. 43, a. 3, emphasis added:“Est enim unus communis modus quo Deus est in omnibus rebus per essentiam, potentiam et praesentiam, sicut causa in effectibus participantibus bonitatem ipsius. Super istum modum autem communem, est unus specialis, qui convenit creaturae rationali, in qua Deus dicitur esse sicut cognitum in cognoscente et amatum in amante. Et quia, cognoscendo et amando, creatura rationalis sua operatione attingit ad ipsum Deum, secundum istum specialem modum Deus non solum dicitur esse in creatura rationali, sed etiam habitare in ea sicut in templo suo. Sic igitur nullus alius effectus potest esse ratio quod divina Persona sit novo modo in rationali creatura, nisi gratia gratum faciens.” 114 Book Symposium Let us now move further back in Aquinas’s doctrine of the Trinity in the prima pars of the Summa theologiae, question 38, article 1, where St.Thomas asks whether “gift” is a personal name. For here again we encounter the sheer absence of a simple seamless continuity of infinite intensification between the two forms of divine presence as well as of some kind of intrinsic dynamic leading from the one to the other in a way already “inscribed in” or “anticipated by” the first. Rather, we encounter a twofold differentiation, the first by now being quite familiar:There obtains a crucial difference between the nature of the rational creature, on the one hand, and all other creatures, on the other hand. For only rational creatures can enjoy a divine person by being united to God.“Other creatures can be moved by a divine person, not, however, in such a way as to be able to enjoy the divine person, and to use the effect thereof.” There is, however, a second crucial differentiation to be made regarding the donum ultimum, now pertaining specifically and exclusively to the rational creature. For “the rational creature does sometimes [quandoque] attain thereto; as when it is made partaker of the divine Word and the Love proceeding, so as freely to know God truly and to love God rightly.”65 The rational creature qua rational is endowed with the albeit purely passive capability of being united to God by way of its own powers acting according to their proper secondary causality; this capability is reduced to act by the Holy Spirit himself, who is given from above by way of sanctifying grace that simultaneously elevates human nature for the reception of such an infinitely disproportionate gift. However, unlike the gift of creation that is perfectly universal and by way of which God is present by essence, power, and presence, the enjoyment of the divine persons occurs quandoque, sometimes. That the qualification quandoque is far from being a casual side remark finds its possibly clearest expression in St.Thomas’s treatment of predestination in the prima pars of the Summa theologiae, question 23, wherein he answers affirmatively the question whether human beings are predestined by God, resting his response to the objections on a sed contra in which he cites Romans 8:30 (RSV): “And those whom he predestined he also called.” The opening sentence of his response is crucial: Deo conveniens est homines praedestinare. It is fitting for God to predestine human beings.The convenientia or fittingness refers to the end to which predestination pertains. As Aquinas argued in the preceding question 22, divine providence directs all things to their proper ends (ST I, q. 22, a. 1 and 2). However, regarding the human being Aquinas distinguishes between a twofold (duplex) end, 65 “Ad quod quandoque pertingit rationalis creatura; ut puta cum sic fit particeps divini Verbi et procedentis Amoris, ut possit libere Deum vere cognoscere et recte amare.” Book Symposium 115 one which exceeds all proportion and faculty of created nature; and this end is life eternal, that consists in seeing God which is above the nature of every creature. . . . The other end, however, is proportionate to created nature, to which end created being can attain according to the power of its nature. . . . Hence, properly speaking, a rational creature, capable of eternal life, is led towards it, directed, as it were, by God. Here again we have the clear distinction between an end proportionate to created nature (something that must be perceptible in its own right and makes sense ontologically as a subsistent principle with a respective end proportionate to it) and an end “which exceeds all proportion and faculty of created nature” (qui excedit proportionem naturae creatae et facultatem). Moreover, the use of the term convenientia signals that the relationship between the two ends cannot be captured by the all too simple alternatives “intrinsic” or “extrinsic.” There is no continuity from the first end to the second, a continuity that might suggest some kind of innate and inchoate anticipation of the second in the first; nor is the first “closed up” to the second, such that it can only be “opened up” for the second gift by being miraculously transformed by the latter into something essentially foreign to its specific natural constitution. Convenientia rejects these alternatives by referring the matter to the mystery of God’s goodness, which is identical with God’s justice as well as mercy, utterly unfathomable in the glorious simplicity of the divine perfection. The ineradicable difference, however, between the first gift and the grace of predestination is marked by an echo of the oblique quandoque in two other instances. First, in question 23, article 2 (with a sed contra from Augustine’s De dono perseverantiae, chapter 14) Aquinas returns to Rm 8:30 in his response to the question whether predestination places anything in the predestined. Denying the question he emphasizes that providence is not anything in the things provided for; but is a type in the mind of the provider, as was proved above (22,1). But the execution of providence which is called government, is in a passive way in the thing governed, and in an active way in the governor.Whence it is clear that predestination is a kind of type of the ordering of some persons [aliquorum] towards eternal salvation, existing in the divine mind. The execution, however, of this order is in a passive way in the predestined, but actively in God.66 66 ST I, q. 23, a. 2, c.:“Providentia autem non est in rebus provisis; sed est quaedam ratio in intellectu provisoris, ut supra dictum est. Sed executio providentiae, quae gubernatio dicitur, passive quidem est in gubernatis; active autem in gubernante. Unde manifestum est quod praedestinatio est quaedam ratio ordinis aliquorum in salutem aeternam, in mente divina existens.” 116 Book Symposium Second, in question 23, article 7, where on this particular matter St.Thomas stands in clear agreement with the late St. Augustine:“The number of the predestined is certain . . . not only by reason of his knowledge, because, that is to say, He knows how many will be saved . . . ; but by reason of his deliberate choice and determination.”67 The reason for the quandoque as well as the aliqui is the mystery of God’s principal preordination.68 And it is at this particular place where the irresolvable differentiation between God’s loves becomes most pertinent. In his treatise on grace, Summa theologiae I–II, question 110, article 1, St. Thomas distinguishes between two aspects of God’s love to the creature: For one is common [dilectio generalis], whereby He loves all things that are (Wis 11:25), and thereby gives things their natural being. But the second is a special love [dilectio specialis], whereby He draws the rational creature above the condition of its nature to a participation of the Divine good; and according to this love He is said to love anyone simply, since it is by this love that God simply wishes the eternal good, which is Himself, for the creature.69 67 That this account is far from some type of “blue print” statically and quasi-mech- anistically imposed upon thing-like rational creatures is implicitly addressed in q. 8, ad 3, where he makes the crucial metaphysical distinction between the first universal cause and secondary causes:“Secondary causes cannot escape the order of the first universal cause . . . , indeed, they execute that order. And therefore predestination can be furthered by creatures, but it cannot be impeded by them.” 68 Thomas does not avoid the difficult question of reprobation either. It is important, however, to note that he implicitly follows the canons of the Second Synod of Orange in rejecting any notion of an active divine reprobation. Rather, God permits some [aliquos] to fall away from the ultimate end (which entails the reality of sufficient grace); (“Unde, cum per divinam providentiam homines in vitam aeternam, ordinentur, pertinet etiam ad divinam providentiam, ut permittat aliquos ab isto fine deficere. Et hoc dicitur reprobare.” ST I q. 23, a. 3, c.). However, as divine providence entails both the divine intellect (providence in the narrow sense) and the divine will (divine governance as the execution of providence), the divine permission not only entails the divine knowledge of such a falling away but includes the will to permit a person to fall into sin: “Sicut enim praedestinatio includit voluntatem conferendi gratiam et gloriam, ita reprobatio includit voluntatem permittendi aliquem cadere in culpam, et inferendi damnationis poenam pro culpa” (ibid.). 69 ST I–II, q. 110, a. 1, c.: “Una quidem communis, secundum quam diligit omnia quae sunt, ut dicitur Sap. 11, [25]; secundum quam esse naturale rebus creatis largitur. Alia autem est dilectio specialis, secundum quam trahit creaturam rationalem supra conditionem naturae, ad participationem divini boni. Et secundum hanc dilectionem dicitur aliquem diligere simpliciter: quia secundum hanc dilectionem vult Deus simpliciter creaturae bonum aeternum, quod est ipse.” Book Symposium 117 Hence,Thomas explains,“grace” can signify something that is bestowed by God on the human being.Then he emphasizes again the logic of the quandoque: “Nevertheless the grace of God sometimes signifies God’s eternal love, as we say the grace of predestination, inasmuch as God gratuitously and not from merits predestines or elects some.”70 The very fact that St. Thomas describes the efficacious elevation of some to the beatific vision as the grace of predestination is a clear indication that in his theology there obtains an explicit and distinctive double gratuity such that the first gift, created human nature, originally gifted with the help of original justice and through sanctifying grace ordained for the vision of God differs categorically from the ontological élan reflected in the four necessary loves, according to Maritain’s analysis, as mentioned above.These four necessary loves, however, indicate an antecedent fittingness of the first for the second gift, as becomes increasingly clear by reflecting upon the first gift, the rational creature qua particular nature in its proper integrity, in light of the second gift, the elevation of human nature per operationem to personal communion with the triune God. Passages like the above suggest that St.Thomas was intent upon preserving the strict gratuity of the grace of predestination by operating with the logic of a double gratuity, first the gift that constitutes its own reception (creation), then the gift that infallibly, though entailing the proper secondary causality of free will, constitutes communion with God, the Giver of both gifts. In the course of this brief excursion we encounter an Aquinas who thoroughly resists Milbank’s attempt of assimilating his theology into the latter’s radicalized Bulgakovian Lubacianism for at least two reasons: First, while St.Thomas never assumed a state of pure nature in the present order of providence, he clearly assumes the principle of nature—and hence a hypothetical state of pure nature—with its own relative but proper integrity as an entailment of creation that ontologically obtains and is accessible to the intellect. Second, Aquinas’s doctrine of the grace of predestination makes it impossible—despite the very prominent role of the ontological exitus-reditus scheme in the overall architectonic of his thought—to press his theology into the service of an overarching Origenist-Bulgakovian vision of universal apokatastasis. The ontology of the exitus-reditus is a necessary precondition entailed in the first gift in order for grace “to 70 ST I–II, q. 110, a. 1, c.: “Quandoque tamen gratia Dei dicitur ipsa aeterna Dei dilectio: secundum quod dicitur etiam gratia praedestinationis, inquantum Deus gratuito, et non ex meritis, aliquos praedestinavit sive elegit.” 118 Book Symposium come on the way of being,”71 that is, to elevate human nature to a supernatural perfection without its transmutation into another species. The complexity of this position (ontological élan as well as grace of predestination) is precisely reflected in the question of the rational creature and its natural desire for the vision of God to which we now turn. Observation 3: Is the rational creature “intrinsically linked to grace”? Or, What is ultimately at stake in Feingold’s Thomist engagement of Henri de Lubac’s position? For a detailed discussion of the crucial texts in Aquinas regarding the natural desire of the vision of God72 I happily refer to the excellent and cogent discussion in Steven A. Long’s contribution to this symposium. I could at best only reproduce his precise argumentation, which I regard as a correct interpretation of Aquinas and the Thomist commentators. Moreover, his interpretation convincingly invalidates the critique raised by Milbank that Feingold only cites paragraphs 11–13 of Summa contra Gentiles, book III, question 25, while “the ontological and neoplatonizing prelude is omitted from his discussion entirely!”73 Long’s precise interpretation of Aquinas shows plainly that even without an explicit treatment of Summa contra Gentiles III, question 25, articles 1–10—which indeed should have been explicitly treated—Feingold’s overall analysis of the broad coherence between Aquinas and the Thomist commentators obtains. Rather than repeating Long’s excellent analysis, I regard this as the opportune place to give voice to Feingold himself. As mentioned earlier, I choose this approach because Feingold’s book is very hard to track down, and therefore the subsequent extended quotations may be the only way to gain an initial appreciation of the utterly serious and substantive nature of Feingold’s engagement of Henri de Lubac’s position. 1. Feingold’s reconstruction of Henri de Lubac’s position on the desiderium naturale visionis Dei a. De Lubac’s fundamental concern:The intrinsic nature of a spiritual creature’s finality De Lubac argues that the finality of a spiritual creature is intrinsic and cannot be changed without changing the nature. . . . 71 Ferdinand Ulrich, Homo Abyssus: Das Wagnis der Seinsfrage, 2nd ed., ed. Martin Bieler and Florian Pitschl (Freiburg: Johannes Verlag, 1998), 333. 72 De Veritate, 14; Summa contra Gentiles III, 25; Compendium Theologiae, 103–7 et al. 73 Milbank, Suspended, 26, fn. 10. Book Symposium 119 De Lubac’s fundamental concern is to remove an “extrinsicist” view of man’s relation to his supernatural end, which he thinks is inherently linked with the theory of the possibility of a state of pure nature, as put forward by Suárez, and with the way the natural desire to see God was interpreted by authors such as Cajetan, Báñez, Suárez, and those who followed them. For de Lubac, the “essential finality” of man is the vision of God. This finality cannot be changed without changing our nature. Man as he is today has only one end that is in harmony with his nature as it now exists—the vision of God.This end, therefore, is “inscribed” or “imprinted” on man’s nature as he concretely exists (prior to any gift of grace) (491). b. De Lubac’s central philosophical argument: The actual final end of a concrete nature This conception is based on a fundamental philosophical notion, central to de Lubac’s position, according to which the actual final end of a thing is necessarily something which determines its nature ontologically, from within. Since we know by faith that we have been destined to a supernatural end, it follows that even before we receive the gift of grace, our nature must be intrinsically determined by our destination to this supernatural end. One and the same “concrete nature” cannot have two distinct possible finalities, one natural and the other supernatural, which God could assign by an external decree, without changing the nature itself. Such a notion implies a “watered-down idea of what finality is.” Rather, two different finalities determine two different natures (or two different “concrete natures” or “historic natures”). In other words, the actual finality of a thing is always the “essential finality” of a thing, postulated by its very essence. Thus de Lubac opposes the idea that our supernatural end is something “superadded” by God on top of and distinct from a “natural end,” to which our nature would be directed in virtue of its own intrinsic principles. . . . It is precisely this possibility of a divergence between actual finality and natural (or essential) finality, with regard to the spiritual creature, which de Lubac rejects, as a notion that is philosophically and religiously unacceptable, contrary to the authentic notion of finality (493ff, emphasis added). c. The finality of the spiritual creature expressed in the natural desire to see God, understood as the innate inclination for the actual final end De Lubac’s interpretation of the natural desire to see God is intimately connected with his understanding of finality in the 120 Book Symposium spiritual creature. Natural desire is understood as the innate inclination of a being for its actual final end, or as the “expression” of the finality of a thing. This corresponds with the notion of appetitus naturalis or inclinatio naturalis in St.Thomas as applied to inanimate creatures and the faculties of the soul. According to St.Thomas, this natural appetite is “determined to one” by nature. The natural end of a thing always determines a natural appetite for that end. Therefore, the fact that man actually has a supernatural finality necessarily determines a natural desire for that supernatural end, according to de Lubac. The natural desire to see God, therefore, is nothing other than the necessary attraction of spiritual beings to the end imprinted on their nature by God. It is precisely the presence in us of our finality, inscribed within us, for the vision of God. . . . [see the important section from The Mystery of the Supernatural, 70–72, cited at this point.] De Lubac is affirming here a natural appetite for beatitude in the particular object in which it actually consists, and not just for beatitude in general. Since the end for which God has ordained us is quite determinate in the mind of God, consisting in the beatific vision, de Lubac concludes that our natural desire must be equally determinate, since natural desire and final end are correlative terms.We must have a concrete natural desire for our concrete final end, as it has been actually determined in the mind of God. Since we are actually destined for the vision of God, we must have a specific natural desire for this vision.This natural desire will be the desire of our nature (desiderium naturae) for its true and specific finality, in the actual plan of God’s providence (495ff). Therefore, de Lubac can assert both (a) that a state of pure nature is impossible for human nature as we now possess it (that is, for man as we know him, who possesses a natural desire to see God), and (b) that God could perhaps create other rational creatures without ordering them to the vision of God (and without giving them a natural desire for that vision).Thus the possibility of a state of pure nature for other rational beings is left open, neither being asserted nor denied. However, the possibility of a state of pure nature is clearly denied with regard to men possessing the same (concrete) nature as ourselves (507). 2. Feingold’s characterization of the central metaphysical issue at stake between Thomas Aquinas (and the commentators) and Henri de Lubac a. Thomas Aquinas: The metaphysical principle “form determines end” and the supernatural finality superadded by the principle of grace and the supernatural virtues Book Symposium 121 For St. Thomas, the possession of a certain form determines a relation to a given natural end that is called for by that form. In CG, III, c. 150, n.5, St.Thomas states that “each thing is ordered to the end that is fitting to it according to its form: to different species there belong different ends.” From this he concludes that a new supernatural form—grace—must be “super-added” to human nature so that it can be ordered to an end that is “above human nature”: “Sed finis in quem homo dirigitur per auxilium divinae gratiae, est supra naturam humanam. Ergo oportet quod homini superaddatur aliqua supernaturalis forma et perfectio, per quam convenienter ordinetur in finem praedictum.” [“But the end to which man is directed by the help of divine grace is above human nature. Therefore, some supernatural form and perfection must be superadded to man whereby he may be ordered suitably to the aforesaid end.”] 74 This clearly implies that human nature in itself without grace is not naturally or essentially ordered (and cannot be fittingly ordered) to an end that is above human nature, precisely because “each thing is ordered to the end that is fitting to it according to its form,” proportionate to its nature (521f). b. Henri de Lubac:The imprinting of a supernatural finality upon human nature prior to the gift of grace For de Lubac, on the contrary, the “imprinting of a supernatural finality” upon our nature is prior to the gift of grace, and is involved in the very constitution of our nature, as it concretely exists in us.The first fundamental problem with de Lubac’s position is how the denial that our nature is ordered to the vision of God prior to grace can be reconciled with his repeated assertion that a supernatural finality has been imprinted on our nature, prior to grace. Being ordered to an end according to one’s nature, and having a finality imprinted on one’s nature seem to be equivalent notions. It seems therefore that de Lubac’s position entails a fundamental contradiction, and that he must logically choose between (a) his repeated affirmation that our nature itself is intrinsically determined by having received a supernatural finality (also referred to as an “essential finality”), prior to the reception of grace, and (b) the affirmation (which is the constant teaching of St.Thomas) that our nature itself is not ordered to a supernatural end without grace (523f). De Lubac presupposes that the actual or de facto end must necessarily be the end “essential” to the nature, or inscribed upon that nature, as it concretely exists. 74 Translation from Summa contra Gentiles. Book Three: Providence, Part II, trans. Vernon J. Bourke (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975), 232. 122 Book Symposium However, we cannot conclude that because God has destined man for an end that is above his nature, transcending the natural inclination of his faculties, that such an end is therefore necessarily a finality “imprinted on the nature” itself, or an “intrinsic” or “ontological” end, or an “essential finality.”All that we can conclude is that if God destines us to a supernatural end, it is fitting that He give a new form, added to our nature (superadditur), by which we are fittingly ordered to that supernatural end. This new (accidental) form must necessarily be above our nature (sanctifying grace), so as to make us proportionate to an end which is above our nature, connatural only to God. If this new form which determines us to a supernatural end is above our nature, then this supernatural finality cannot be said to be “imprinted in our nature itself.” Nor can the finality that is generated by this supernatural form be considered to be an “essential finality.” It is ultimately contradictory to suppose that our nature itself—without the addition of a supernatural principle—could be intrinsically determined by a supernatural finality, or have a supernatural finality inscribed upon it, or have an “essential finality” that is supernatural. If this were the case, our nature itself would be in some sense supernatural, in virtue of St. Thomas’s axiom that everything is ordered to its end in virtue of its form, as well as the principle invoked by de Lubac that “finality is something intrinsic, affecting the depths of the being.” However, a “supernatural nature” is a contradictory notion. An end that is actually imprinted on our nature itself (an “essential finality”) can never truly be “supernatural.” If the end is supernatural, it cannot be imprinted on our nature prior to our reception of grace, for grace alone is sufficient to order the intellectual creature to a supernatural end (526–29). c. The different meanings of “grace superadded” in de Lubac and in Aquinas [F]or de Lubac, grace should be conceived as “super-added” to our nature only insofar as it renders us properly disposed and capable of achieving the end which was already inscribed in our nature prior to the gift of grace. It should not be conceived as “super-added” in the sense of giving us a “new finality.” However, for St. Thomas, grace is not conceived only as a necessary means to achieve an end to which our nature is already essentially ordered. On the contrary, grace is necessary first for us to have a being and dignity such that the vision of God is a fitting and proportionate end for us.The infused moral virtues are necessary so that we may operate for that supernatural end, but grace is situated by St.Thomas on a different level. It makes Book Symposium 123 present within us a supernatural finality by giving us a mysterious proportionality with the divine nature. Thus it can be said that for St. Thomas, our supernatural finality is “imprinted on our being” first by sanctifying grace (529ff). 3. Feingold’s characterization of the central tension in Henri de Lubac’s account of the desiderium naturale: the created spirit a. The innate appetite or natural inclination being necessarily directed to the actual final end The vision of God is certainly not “proportionate” to human nature without grace, as de Lubac also recognizes. [The Mystery of the Supernatural, 111–12: “However profound, however lofty it may be, created spiritual nature is in no way ‘proportionate’— except ‘as the effect to the cause, or the potency to the act’—to what infinitely surpasses it.”] However, de Lubac fails to draw the necessary conclusion from this. According to St. Thomas, the natural inclination of our will is directed to the end that is proportionate to our nature, and not to the actual end to which God has destined us, which is supernatural. This is a direct consequence of the fact that our actual end is supernatural. A supernatural end necessarily exceeds the proportionality of the nature which has been elevated to it, by definition.Therefore, it necessarily also exceeds the natural inclination (or innate appetite) of the faculties of that nature, since natural inclination is based on proportionality and similarity. De Lubac’s fundamental deviation from St. Thomas in this matter consists in supposing that natural inclination or innate appetite is necessarily directed to the actual final end to which God has destined a creature, and not rather to the end proportionate to the nature of the creature (534). b. The natural inclination or innate appetite generated by the natural form according to Thomas Aquinas Natural inclination or innate appetite must be based on the nature of the creature, since, being prior to knowledge, it can only be generated by the natural form that is possessed. However, it is clear that there is nothing in the natural form of the creature, prior to the gift of grace, such that it could generate a natural inclination or innate appetite for the vision of God. A natural desire for the vision of God, prior to grace, can only be an elicited desire caused by some knowledge of God’s effects, and thus it will be directed to a knowledge of God’s essence as First Cause, according to the profound interpretation of Sylvester of Ferrara. The presence of sanctifying 124 Book Symposium grace, on the other hand, generates a new “super-added” precognitional inclination directly for the vision of God, as the object of our supernatural beatitude. This new inclination follows on grace, “per modum naturae.” In short, there is no basis for the thesis that the end to which God actually destines a creature—if that end is supernatural—necessarily generates a corresponding innate appetite or natural inclination for that end (and only for that end) in the creature, prior to the reception of grace (535f ). c. The unresolved tension in de Lubac’s account:The natural desire to see God—purely natural, or also somewhat divine? There is an unresolved tension, in fact, in de Lubac’s thought as to whether the natural desire to see God should be conceived as purely natural, or as also somehow divine. According to the logic of his system, there are strong reasons for both affirmations. It must be considered as natural, on the one hand, insofar as it is identified either with the nature itself, or with its foundation and depths. On the other hand, however it must be considered to be somehow divine or supernatural for it to accomplish the role that de Lubac assigns to it. The imprinting of a supernatural finality on our nature, creating an innate inclination to our supernatural end, understood as God’s “call,” can only be the result of the gift of a supernatural form added to our nature (539f ).75 If our nature can make no claim to the supernatural finality that has been imprinted on it, and does not in itself imply that finality, then the imprinting of that finality cannot properly be understood to belong to the nature itself, for otherwise my nature would “claim” it and “imply” it, as an essential constituent element. For example, our nature itself “claims” and “implies” the presence of reason, hands and feet, ordination to a fitting final end, etc. St. Thomas expresses this through the notion of debitum naturae.Therefore, this finality, if it is truly not claimed by the nature, must logically be something added to our nature (at least insofar as the nature is considered “abstractly”). This implies that what de Lubac refers to as our “concrete” or “historical” nature should really be conceived—in order to 75 Page 540 note 68: “It is basically for this reason that Karl Rahner introduces his ‘supernatural existential,’ for he reasons that a principle which intrinsically orders us to a supernatural end must itself be supernatural. In this he is quite coherent. St. Thomas agrees that we are ordered to our supernatural end by supernatural principles: grace and the supernatural virtues. However, for Rahner, this principle is not grace, but something prior to the reception of grace.” Book Symposium 125 be coherent—as a composite formed by two elements: (a) our nature itself, as such (referred to by de Lubac as our “abstract” or “generic nature”), with the addition of (b) a supernatural finality imprinted on that nature which determines in us a natural desire to see God (an “imprint” which would logically itself be a supernatural element). [note 78: This is essentially the solution of K. Rahner] (542f ). 4.The resolution of the tension in de Lubac’s account: Either Thomist or Bulgakovian/Milbankian One ironic outcome of Feingold’s critique and Milbank’s modification of de Lubac’s position is that Milbank’s radicalized Bulgakovian Lubacianism constitutes precisely the other side of Feingold’s Aristotelian Thomism. Both Feingold and Milbank agree that (a) the concern expressed in Humani Generis was indeed aimed at de Lubac, and (b) that the later de Lubac’s way of responding to the encyclical’s concern was not fully satisfying—for both because de Lubac never jettisoned the fundamental assumption about the constitution of the created spirit for a single supernatural end expressed in the innate natural desire for the vision of God. a. The tension summarized In order to coherently hold that our supernatural finality is “essential” to us, de Lubac would logically have had to eliminate the distinction of abstract and concrete human nature altogether, and maintain that human nature as such is necessarily determined by a supernatural finality, which thus is essential to it and would be included in man’s definition itself, in any hypothesis or economy of salvation.According to this solution, an “uncalled” rational nature (if it is possible) would not be human nature at all, but would be a completely different nature or species, having a different definition, with a different essential finality. This would mean discarding the possibility of an abstract human nature different from our concrete human nature in not containing a supernatural finality imprinted on it. Although this solution would be philosophically more coherent in certain respects, and is supported by several passages of Chapter 4 of The Mystery of the Supernatural (in which de Lubac implies that members of a hypothetical “uncalled” humanity would really have a different nature), such a solution poses great theological problems, defining a created nature, as such, by a supernatural end. In any case, the mature de Lubac did not wish to take this step in an unambiguous way, so as not to turn our supernatural end into a mere sequela creationis, and also perhaps 126 Book Symposium so as not to be in conflict with the teaching of Humani generis. In fact, such a solution would render impossible de Lubac’s threefold distinction, seen above, between (1) the creation of a spiritual nature, (2) the imprinting of a supernatural finality, and (3) the offer of grace, so that the first does not imply the second, and the second does not imply the third (546ff). b. The alternative resolutions In conclusion, de Lubac is in perfect harmony with St.Thomas and with the Christian tradition in denying that our nature itself, as it actually exists, has the slightest supernatural element. However, this cannot be reconciled with his interpretation of the natural desire to see God as the expression of a supernatural finality imprinted on our nature in creation itself, prior to the reception of grace, determining us to an inevitably supernatural end. A choice must be made. Either the supernatural finality imprinted on our nature must be recognized to flow from a supernatural element given with our constitution itself (as K. Rahner affirms); or one must reject altogether the thesis that a supernatural finality has been imprinted on our nature, prior to grace, opting instead for the thesis that an ordination to our supernatural end is impressed on our being first by sanctifying grace. Clearly the principles of St. Thomas and the Christian tradition demand the latter option (550). c. Feingold’s rejection of “grace extrinsicism”: the specific obediential potency of the rational creature, that is, the rational creature’s natural openness to the supernatural For St.Thomas, the existence of an elicited natural desire to know the essence of God shows that a call by God to the beatific vision is tremendously fitting, since it is the only end in which we can find perfect beatitude and in which all natural desire can come to rest (emphasis added) In addition, St.Thomas combats a certain type of “extrinsicism” by showing that our ordering to a supernatural end is realized through principles which are truly possessed by us in a continuous way in the form of supernatural habits which generate a new inclination, so that our supernatural end is attained in a way that is “connatural” in a certain sense. Although these principles ordering us to the vision of God remain extrinsic to our nature (for they are supernatural and thus “super-added” to the nature), they are not extrinsic to the person who possesses these supernatural habits. The difference is that for St. Thomas, this intrinsic ordering and inclination comes through “super-added” (supernatural) principles, whereas for de Lubac, it comes through the Book Symposium 127 nature itself, as it is historically realized in us, bearing an innate and absolute natural desire for its actual end (551f ). It is certainly true, as de Lubac emphasizes, that rational creatures constitute a special case with regard to their finality. St. Thomas notes that a great dignity of the rational creature lies in the fact that it can be raised to an end exceeding its natural faculties and proportionality; it alone is naturally open to the supernatural, in virtue of the very nature of the faculties of intellect and will.Thus it can be elevated through the gift of grace to receive a new finality to which its nature itself is not ordered. This has been analyzed above as a specific obediential potency of the rational creature (553). d. The novelty or paradox of de Lubac’s position: The idea of an innate natural desire for the vision of God The novelty or paradox of de Lubac’s position lies in his claim that a desire can be absolute or unconditional, and at the same time still remain inefficacious and imperfect (558). [On the contrary, St. Thomas’s] position is based on the axiom that innate appetite, since it derives directly from the natural form possessed, is always directed to an object proportionate to the nature of the creature. . . .An elicited (imperfect) natural desire, on the other hand, is not limited by the proportionality of the creature, because it is based on knowledge, and something can be known to be desirable even though it exceeds the proportionality of the creature, as is manifestly the case with regard to the vision of God. I hold that the latter line of interpretation, represented by Suárez, is correct, and that the former line of interpretation, represented most prominently by de Lubac, contradicts many texts and principles of St.Thomas.The idea of an innate natural desire for the vision of God—although it may appear plausible at first sight—is fundamentally incompatible with the Thomistic synthesis (636). e. Avoiding the paradox; or, the philosophical and theological necessity of the possibility of a state of pure nature [T]he existence of an innate appetite for the vision of God logically implies the impossibility of a state of pure nature. However, the possibility of a state of pure nature is necessary for both philosophical and theological reasons, and has been taught by the Church’s Magisterium. It is philosophically necessary for the coherence of the natural order, and theologically necessary to preserve the full gratuitousness of grace. If there is only one final end (or only one beatitude) that is possible for man’s nature as such—the vision of God—then 128 Book Symposium that end, together with the means necessary to obtain it, will be due to human nature. In such a case, the vision of God, together with grace and the theological virtues, would no longer be gratuitous in the sense in which St.Thomas understands these gifts to be gratuitous (666f ). 5. St.Thomas transcending the alternatives of the “extrinsicism” and “intrincisism” of grace Finally, it must be noted that Feingold captures with admirable nuance the intriguingly complex as well as precise position of St.Thomas and the Thomist tradition over against the rather crude alternatives of the alleged Thomist submission to a “grace-extrinsicism” on the one hand and the proposed panacea of the intrinsicism of a “grace-continuum of infinite intensification” on the other hand: It should be noted that the assertion of the “possibility of a state of pure nature,” (which should be understood as the possibility or non-absurdity for an intellectual nature to be created, and yet not to be called to a supernatural end) does not imply that it would be equally fitting for God to elevate an intellectual creature, as not to elevate him. On the contrary, St. Thomas shows that it is more fitting to our nature and its natural (elicited) aspirations, for God to elevate us to the supernatural end of the vision of God.This is shown by means of the natural desire to see God. Perfect beatitude is possible only in the vision of God, for only this can bring to rest all natural desire. Nevertheless, despite the fittingness of our elevation, it is very important to assert that it would not be absurd or incoherent (that is, it would not be impossible with regard to the order of God’s providence) for human nature to exist without being elevated to a supernatural end, in which case it could only attain an imperfect beatitude. However, the existence of a truly innate natural appetite for the vision of God (which thus would be absolute), would make it not merely less fitting for human nature to exist without being elevated to a supernatural end, but also ultimately absurd, as was affirmed by Jansenius and his followers, together with the Augustinian theologians Noris, Bellelli and Berti, and finally by de Lubac and those who follow him. Therefore, in order to coherently affirm the possibility of a state of pure nature, one must reject the existence of an innate appetite for the vision of God, as Suárez maintained in opposition to the earlier solution of St. Robert Bellarmine, Toledo and Soto (as well as Scotus), which maintained an innate appetite for the vision of God without rejecting the possibility of a state of pure nature (667). The subtle and nuanced argumentation of this last section gives the lie to Milbank’s characterization that Feingold resurrects an “arch-reactionary,” Book Symposium 129 “die-hard,”“palaeolithic” neo-Thomism intent on defending a “regime of pure nature.” Moreover, Feingold himself advances at this very point the kind of aesthetic argument of ontological fittingness, based on convenientia, that Milbank hails as the latest achievement of what he characterizes as only a very recent Fribourg-Toulouse Thomism, presumably chastened by the nouvelle théologie. Hence it is not really surprising that Milbank fails to recognize that for Feingold, convenientia in this section has nothing whatsoever to do with the mere “epistemological likelihood,” which according to Milbank is Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange’s (and by implication Feingold’s) understanding of convenientia.76 Finally, in light of this particular passage, it becomes clear that the question of whether there exists in the human being an innate natural desire for the vision of God is a question debated in highly nuanced ways long before the days of Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, OP, and Henri de Lubac, SJ, and hence in all likelihood a question that will continue to be debated long after them, though now in light of the concern expressed in Humani Generis. Coda It has become clear, first, that how the question of nature and grace is resolved has in at least some cases a subtle, but nevertheless immediate, impact on resolutions to the question of the nature and scope of salvation. In other words, if, as the early de Lubac states in Surnaturel and as Milbank likes to take him, spirit indeed is the desire for God, then Bulgakov’s universal apokatastasis is indeed the logical explication of a fundamental entailment of de Lubac’s theological vision of a Christian humanist universalism. It has become furthermore clear that it is ultimately unconvincing on the question of nature and grace to drive a consistent and comprehensive wedge between the thought of Thomas Aquinas on the one hand and the tradition of the Thomist commentators on the other hand. In other words, the Thomist position that the natural desire to see God is an elicited natural desire is by no means a Renaissance or Baroque distortion of a presumably “original,” more or less Areopagite Aquinas, but a faithful and consistent interpretation of the comprehensive position of the doctor communis. Finally, it has become clear that the reading of St.Thomas’s theology of grace as exclusively reconstructed in light of an Areopagite ontology of participation, in order to help warrant the vision of a Bulgakovian Lubacianism, simply is untenable.The humanism St.Thomas advances is integrally united with an Augustinian theological position on predestination 76 Milbank, Suspended, 84ff. 130 Book Symposium and grace as stated in the Second Synod of Orange and reconfirmed at the Council of Trent. I should add, nevertheless, that while the universal apokatastasis was never adopted as a comprehensive dogmatic position by East or West,77 universal human salvation remains a legitimate theological expression of the infused, supernatural virtues of hope and charity and hence a matter of fervent prayers of intercession, as consistently argued by Hans Urs von Balthasar.78 Transposing universal salvation, however, from the scope of Christian hope and prayer to the core of Christian doctrine and theology would at the very least be a grave mistake of categories, if not the unwarranted anticipation of divine judgment in the form of theological speculation, even be it a Christological speculation as brilliant and gospelcentered as in the case of Karl Barth’s doctrine of election.79 Hence, to return to the beginning of these observations, the first type of answer to the question,What is the human being?, in all its profound humanist attraction suffers from the speculative excess of a premature systematic closure, precisely at the point where theology has to practice the askesis of leaving the end to God. Although, obviously, the second 77 Indeed, it was explicitly rejected by the Fifth Ecumenical Council, that is, the Second Council of Constantinople, 553, in a first, formally preconciliar, anathema, a statement issued by the assembly of bishops, in which they confirmed in an elaborated version the anti-Origenean canon promulgated by the Synod of Constantinople in 543. (For the anti-Origenean canon of 553, see Acta Conciliorum Oecumenicorum [Berlin, 1914ff], vol. IV/1, 248ff.) The statement can be interpreted minimalistically as a rejection of the idea that one can know certainly that no one will be eternally damned; more straightforwardly and less minimalistically read, it seems simply to condemn any position that would want to deny the concrete possibility of eternal damnation for some, as argued already by Augustine in De Civitate Dei XXI, 17. 78 See for a discussion more accessible than the sprawling Theo-Drama, Hans Urs von Balthasar, Dare We Hope “That All Men Be Saved”? with a Short Discussion on Hell (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1988); and the insightful discussion of von Balthasar’s nuanced position by Geoffrey Wainwright, “Eschatology,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hans Urs von Balthasar, ed. Edward T. Oakes and David Moss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 113–27. 79 Karl Barth, Die kirchliche Dogmatik II/2 (Zürich: Theologischer Verlag, 1942), 1–563.The remarkable sophistication of Barth’s speculative Christological anticipation consists in the very fact that he stops short of stating explicitly what is clearly entailed by the logic of the argument itself for, as Barth himself acknowledges, there indeed is no explicit biblical warrant for universalism. To which degree Barth’s restraint at this point remains a merely dialectical, rather than eschatological, reserve, however, depends on whether one reads the long concluding exegetical excursus on Judas Iscariot (508–63; esp. 551 and 563!) as a question mark or rather as an exclamation mark to his whole doctrine of election! Book Symposium 131 type of answer does not follow by necessity from the argument thus far advanced80—an argument primarily pertaining to the correct interpretation of Thomas Aquinas—I shall nevertheless insist upon submitting that it is indeed in the second type of answer where we find such askesis most properly practiced. And in order to sustain the proper theological askesis this side of the eschaton, it strikes me to be indispensable as well as of eminent convenientia not only to acknowledge the proper difference that obtains realiter between nature and grace, in order to do justice to the specific gratuity of the grace of predestination, the donum ultimum, but moreover, and presently more importantly, to develop a coherent account of the relative and limited integrity of the principle of nature, which preserves the proper gratuity of the first gift, the donum primum, and hence does justice to the ineluctable double gratuity entailed in the economy of salvation. Where everything is grace all the way down in one and the same way, albeit of infinitely differing intensity, everything that has been brought into being, must have its end in God, by necessary ontological entailment. While undoubtedly a grandiose speculative vision, it, however, is neither the teaching of the Scriptures nor of the Church.81 N&V 80 Moreover, the two types of answers do not cover all, albeit by far the most, posi- tions taken by Christian theologians. One such answer not addressed by the two types submitted—a nuanced form of Augustinianism—indeed combines two particular features of both types by defending the possibility of a divinely permitted ontological self-annihilation of the persistently evil rational soul.This answer does indeed entail neither the apokatastasis ton panton nor the doctrine of the eternal punishment of souls as defended by St.Augustine in De Civitate Dei XXI, 17. For a forceful and brilliant defense of a version of this third type of answer, see Paul J. Griffiths,“Self-Annihilation or Damnation? A Disputable Question in Christian Eschatology,” forthcoming in Pro Ecclesia 16 (Fall 2007). 81 I am indebted to Kent Dunnington and Nancy Heitzenrater Hütter for attending to the prose of this essay and to Paul J. Griffiths and Bruce Marshall for pressing me in most incisive ways regarding the fundamental conceptual, logical, and normative question underlying this particular effort as well as the larger theological question itself. Only by way of a subsequent essay can I hope to do at least some initial justice to their questions and concerns. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 133–184 133 On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature as a Theonomic Principle: Reflections on the Nature/Grace Controversy* S TEVEN A. L ONG Ave Maria University Naples, Florida Introduction D R . L AWRENCE F EINGOLD is to be thanked for the comprehensive, instructive, and irenic character of his work The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters.1 The doctrinal and historical intricacy, the sympathy, indeed, the sheer largeness of intent of this book, merits extensive consideration. Hence insofar as mastery of a teaching implies critical command of the contrary case, the publishing of this book marks a potent challenge for those who assume—on the warrant of de Lubac’s claim—that most of St. Thomas’s commentators have preferred “Renaissance corruptions” to the genuine teaching of Aquinas. Considering this claim in detail, this volume establishes both systematically and exegetically that the case is otherwise. The Natural * In what follows I have liberally availed myself of the Corpus Thomisticum, S. Thomae de Aquino opera omnia, made available online by the University of Navarre (www.unav.es/filosofia/alarcon/amicis/ctopera.html#OM), although rarely I have preferred to use either the Ottawa edition of the Summa theologiae, or a different edition (as indicated). Also, I would like, from the start of this essay, to enter a demurrer to the view that to criticize de Lubac’s controversial thesis regarding nature and grace is by that fact alone to traduce his considerable merits as a lover and servant of the Church. One would have thought that no one would be inclined to question these. Nor should criticism of his approach to the nature/grace issue imply derogation of the contemplative profundity of his wider body of work. The neuralgia of past disputes need not be our own whereas the light one may find in them should be.Yet, all this being said, there is much at stake doctrinally in this issue, which is the reason why its reconsideration is exigent. 1 Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Rome: Apollinare Studi, 2001). 134 Book Symposium Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters merits careful attention for this historical, exegetic, and doctrinal contribution, as also for helping a generation of theologians and philosophers to appreciate the importance of this controversy and the profundity of the Thomistic commentatorial tradition. Likewise, this essay is penned with one eye focused on John Milbank’s recent work The Suspended Middle.2 This work—which rightly discerns the profundity of the questions pursued by de Lubac and the importance of their implications for theology—nonetheless fails to discern the larger stage on which the loss of nature as a theonomic principle has been played, and the distortive results it has both in prejudicing the nature/grace question, and for theology as a whole. As the third section of this present essay is devoted to articulating, the relative and limited integrity of nature within the actual teaching of St.Thomas has been the casualty of a deific view of freedom.This view of freedom was bound to separate God from the natural world of human action, and equally bound to suggest efforts at retrieval by dissolving nature into supernature and contradicting Thomas’s clear teaching that there is a proximate natural end inferior to the supernatural end.3 2 John Milbank, The Suspended Middle (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2005). 3 To be quite clear, Milbank argues (The Suspended Middle, 63) that “[i]ndeed, it can now be seen that the Surnaturel of 1946 was almost as important an event of cultural revision as Being and Time or the Philosophical Investigations.”With this judgment one may wholly concur, save that one might think it even more important than these.Yet, his explanation of how this is so fails. In the ensuing lines he writes: “For it revealed that the space of modern philosophy and culture was paradoxically created by a dubious scholastic theology, which reinvigorated the primitive pagan ontological assumption that ‘capacity’ or ‘power’ rather than ‘desire’ will disclose reality to us.” But, to the contrary, the space of modern philosophy and culture have been created by erroneous notions of will in Scotus and ensuing philosophers, and most critically and foundationally by Molina, whose implicit removal of will and human agency from Divine Providence evacuated the scholastic theology of its profound theocentricity, and destroyed natural order as theonomic.To these innovative errors commentators such as Cajetan stood opposed. Radicalizing created will to hotwire it to the Trinity is hardly the way beyond this impasse, but is understandably inspired by what happens to natural order—including the order of volition—once it is no longer seen as participating by efficient causality the ordering wisdom of God.What is lost to the metaphysical dependence of creature to Creator must then be regained by the triumph of the will—a nature whose theocentricity has been denied, must then be dissolved into supernature to regain it. But however tempting such a solution may be, it is not Thomistic, and even more vitally, it is not true. In short, Milbank has identified the wrong “dubious scholastic theology.”The “pure nature” of the possibility that man might have been created “in puris naturalibus” as Thomas puts it (Quod. I, q. 4, a. 3, resp.) is wholly Book Symposium 135 In this essay, it is my intent to contribute to the project of facilitating a renewed appreciation of St. Thomas’s profound teaching—explored so rigorously by the commentators—on the character of the relation between the natural and the supernatural. I shall try to achieve three things. First, this essay will survey the general speculative dimensions of the controversy about the character of the natural desire for God, so closely related to the question of the natural end; second, it will explore in particular the contours of what I take to be the common error of de Lubac and Gilson respecting the obediential potency for grace and glory; third, it will argue that despite what I shall argue to be its doctrinal deficiency, that de Lubac’s account of the natural desire for God is rooted in a genuinely profound theological need to overcome the loss of natural order as a theonomic principle. I will conclude by observing the protean implications of these issues for the effort to understand, and to transcend, an invertebrate postmodern theological pluralism that itself presupposes the loss of natural order as a theonomic principle. While the first objective of this essay speaks for itself, the second and third considerations require a preliminary gloss. St. Thomas’s clear and classical teaching is that human nature is defined in its species in relation to the natural and proximate end as distinct from the supernatural beatific end. Further, he teaches that man possesses a purely passive obediential potency for grace—a potency that exists only in relation to the active agency of God—a teaching that explicates how supernatural acts are simultaneously our own yet enacted only through the grace of God.Yet a unilateral stress upon certain aspects of St.Thomas’s teaching about the natural desire for God led de Lubac to deny the existence of a proportionate natural end as opposed to the supernatural finis ultimus. And both de Lubac and Gilson4 came to think of obediential potency as a mere theocentric and in no way compatible with “a debased autonomous humanism.” A better candidate for meriting this dubious distinction is found in those who separate the will from Divine Providence and their voluntarist progenitors. The metaphysics of the total dependence in being and act of the ens creatum cannot be rejected in part, without gradually rejecting the whole teaching of St. Thomas. Regarding Thomas’s affirmation of the proximate natural end as definitive of species and distinct from the supernatural end, see ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1; and Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10, the second quoted in detail in note 5 below. 4 For example, see Henri de Lubac, Surnaturel Étude historiques (Paris: Aubier, 1946); idem, Augustinisme et theologie modern (Paris: Aubier, 1965), 242–51; idem, Le Mystère du surnaturel (Paris:Aubier, 1965), 87–88, 142, 179–89 (noteworthy for its criticism of the Dominican commentator tradition). Along similar lines, note also J. Laporta, La destinée de la nature humane selon Thomas d’Aquin (Paris: J.Vrin, 1965). Laporta devotes an appendix to arguing that St.Thomas does not use the 136 Book Symposium generic susceptibility to miracle, denying the distinct, specific sense of obediential potency as applied by St. Thomas Aquinas to the relation of nature to grace. The motivating reason for these departures from the teaching of St.Thomas appears to repose in a wider theological concern springing from the loss of nature as a theonomic principle and from a creative yet defective strategy for recovery of this loss.This wider concern is of course not irrelevant to the present situation of theology (and of philosophy as well). Before turning to these points, however, a rather extensive word is owed to the general consideration of the nature/grace problematic, and simultaneously to the synthesis of St. Thomas’s actual texts, inclusive of those which, given the profundity of de Lubac’s influence, it has become customary to pass over in silence. Only after this extensive general treatment will the focus narrow, first, to address the decisive loss for theological anthropology of the classical conception of obediential potency; and, second, to consider the defective theological problematic faced by de Lubac—a problematic for whose loss of nature as a theonomic principle a “natural desire” for supernatural beatitude could seem to be—while yet not being—a sufficient cure. At the start of this essay, I beg the privilege of an author to request that those for whom the first two sections of this argument may be uncongenial consider the wider treatment of the third section before assessing its success or failure. For only the third section of the essay offers an interpretation of the strategic derailment of theology—rooted in the loss of natural order as a theonomic principle—to which de Lubac’s nature/grace thesis constituted a creative but flawed response. Because this loss persists through much contemporary thought, it becomes all the more vital to correct it at its root rather than merely to extemporize responses to effects that occur further on in the chain of implications. Dimensions of the Controversy The distinction between nature and grace is a foundational distinction for Christian life.This distinction is helpfully approached through the interpretative schools that, prior to la nouvelle théologie, successfully articulated and indeed safeguarded this vital distinction.The doctrinal analysis of this language of obediential potency in his account of the supernatural destiny of man (133–46). See also Gilson’s letter to Henri de Lubac, dated June 20, 1965, in which he indicates complete unawareness of the very idea of specific obediential potency, saying of obediential potency that “strictly speaking, it is applicable only to miracles.” Etienne Gilson, Letters of Etienne Gilson to Henri de Lubac (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1988), 81. Book Symposium 137 distinction is rich with implications both for the contemplative and the practical life, and indeed systematically inflects theology such that a wrong emphasis on this question will generally lead to the symbiotic evils on the one hand of fideism, and on the other, of rationalism: twin aberrations. Yet weighty theological considerations motivated great scholars and lovers of the Church such as Henri de Lubac to read St. Thomas’s texts with an exclusory eye, neglecting texts which clearly rendered his own account problematic.These considerations remain with us today—all the more so inasmuch as the texts overlooked by de Lubac, and the antecedent commentatorial tradition, are little known. It helps to put to rest the exegetic difficulty. It is without doubt true that there is a problem in the very texts of Aquinas, and a problem which seemingly does not allow much room for maneuver with respect to its solution: because the doctrinal points which constitute the elements of the problem—one is almost tempted to say “constitute the contradiction”—are starkly and clearly stated in St.Thomas’s text.Yet the realization that there are indeed two sets of texts, one of which was not merely an interposed corruption, itself marks a decisive advance toward correct interpretation of Thomas’s teaching. So, there are two sets of texts. On the one hand, we have St.Thomas’s arguments that to know God is the end of every intelligent substance (Summa contra Gentiles III, 25); that there is indeed a natural desire for God (ScG III, 25; and Summa theologiae I–II, q. 3, a. 8); and that no natural desire may be in vain (ST I, q. 75, a. 6; Compendium 104). On the other hand, we have his clear affirmation that human and angelic nature are distinguished based upon their differing natural and proximate ends whereas their supernatural beatific end is the same (ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1; Quaestiones de anima, a. 7, ad 10:“Those beings whose proximate and natural end is one and the same are one in species. However, eternal beatitude is a final and supernatural end.”);5 further, that “in the very beginning of creation human nature was ordained to beatitude, not as to an end proper to man by reason of his 5 Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10:“Ad decimum dicendum quod ea quorum unus est finis proximus et naturalis, sunt unum secundum speciem. Beatitudo autem aeterna est finis ultimus et supernaturalis.” So much for the claim that the natural end—whence the human species is derived—is one and the same with the supernatural end. Obviously there cannot be at once two ultimate finalities, but God need not have elevated man to the supernatural finis ultimus, but could have ordered man exclusively to his natural end whence the species of human nature is derived (see note 7 below). In the present order, this natural end is retained while the entire order of nature is causally further ordered in grace to supernatural beatitude. 138 Book Symposium nature, but given him solely by divine liberality”;6 that man could have been created in a state of pure nature lacking any supernatural aid of grace;7 and that had man been created by God in such a state, that the absence of the beatific vision would not have been a punishment, because there is a difference between “necessarily not to have” and “not necessarily to have,” and that it is the second of these that would apply had man been created outside of sanctifying grace (De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 15). Regarding this last, if the natural desire for God were formally a desire for supernaturally beatific vision, it would follow that to be perpetually deprived of this end proper to nature would be a punishment.Yet St.Thomas teaches exactly the contrary.8 Finally, among this second set of texts, one finds that St.Thomas clearly argues in Summa theologiae I, question 62, article 2, that only grace can direct the movement of the will toward beatitude: 6 Quaestiones Disputatae de Veritate, q. 14, a. 10, ad 2: “Ad secundum dicendum, quod ab ipsa prima institutione natura humana est ordinata in finem beatitudinis, non quasi in finem debitum homini secundum naturam eius, sed ex sola divina liberalitate. Et ideo non oportet quod principia naturae sufficiant ad finem illum consequendum, nisi fuerint adiuta donis superadditis ex divina liberalitate.” 7 Quod. I, q. 4, a. 3, resp.: “But because it was possible for God to have made man in a state of pure nature, it is useful to consider how far natural love could be extended” (“Sed quia possibile fuit Deo ut hominem faceret in puris naturalibus, utile est considerare ad quantum se dilectio naturalis extendere posit”). Note that this refers to the state of nature, while nature is present in any case, and natural order is impressed upon man even when he is further ordered in and by grace from the first moment of his creation: Something which de Lubac thought not possible. Cf. ch. 4 of The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Herder and Herder, 1967), where de Lubac writes of natural order that “To convince me that I might really have had this humbler destiny—humbler, but note also less onerous—you need only show it to me, even momentarily, as something really imprinted upon me, in my nature as it is. Most people would agree that this is precisely what is, by hypothesis, impossible.” But it is possible: What is impossible in this given order of Providence is for the natural order to be in a state wherein it is not either fallen from grace or elevated within it. But ends proportionate to human nature still are recognizably distinct from ends proportionate only to God. 8 This last point from De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 15, is arresting: “Man endowed with only natural powers would be without the divine vision if he were to die in this state, but nevertheless the debt of not having it would not be applicable to him. For it is one thing not to be bound to have, which does not have the nature of punishment but of defect only, and it is another thing to be bound not to have, which does have the nature of punishment” (“Ad decimumquintum dicendum, quod homo in solis naturalibus constitutus careret quidem visione divina, si sic decederet; sed tamen non competeret ei debitum non habendi. Aliud est enim non debere habere, quod non habet rationem poenae, sed defectus tantum; et aliud debere non habere, quod habet rationem poenae”). Book Symposium 139 The angels needed grace to turn toward God insofar as He is the object of beatitude. For as was explained above [q. 60, a. 2], the will’s natural movement is the source [principium] of all the things we will. But the will’s natural inclination is toward what is naturally fitting for it.And so if something is beyond its nature, then the will cannot be moved toward it without the assistance of some other principle that lies beyond its nature [ab aliquo alio principio supernaturali]. For instance, it is clear that fire has a natural inclination to produce heat and to generate fire; however, it lies beyond fire’s natural power to generate flesh, and so fire does not have an inclination toward generating flesh except insofar as it is moved as an instrument by the nutritive soul. Now it was shown above, in the discussion of our knowledge of God [q. 12, a. 4], that to see God through his essence—which is what the ultimate beatitude of a rational creature consists in—lies beyond the nature of any created intellect. Hence, no rational creature can have a movement of will that is ordered to this sort of beatitude unless he is moved by a supernatural agent; this is what we call the assistance of grace. And so one has to claim that an angel could not have turned with his will toward this sort of beatitude except through the assistance of grace.9 The second set of texts hedges about, and delimits, the possible signification of the first set, and vice versa.That is, on the supposition that we do not wish to suppose St. Thomas’s texts to exhibit raw incoherence, then we need to read these texts in relation one to another. This is clear, for example, with texts such as that of the Summa theologiae I–II, question 3, article 8, which addresses the question “Whether man’s happiness consists in the vision of the divine essence?” In this article St.Thomas affirms that man naturally desires to know the essence of any cause once he knows it to be, and that only knowing the essence of God can bring to rest the natural desire of the intellect to know the 9 ST I, q. 62, a. 2:“Dicendum quod angeli indiguerunt gratia ad hoc quod convert- erentur in Deum, prout est obiectum beatitudinis. Sicut enim superius dictum est, naturalist motus voluntatis est principium omnium eorum quae volumus. Naturalis autem inclinatio voluntatis est ad id quod est conveniens secundum naturam. Et ideo si aliquid sit supra naturam, voluntas in id ferri non potest, nisi ab aliquo alio supernaturali principio adiuta. Sicut patet quod ignis habet naturalem inclinationem adcalefaciendum et ad generandum ignem, sed geerare carnem est supra naturalem virtutem ignis, unde ignis ad hoc nullam inclinationem habet, nisi secundum quod movetur ut instrumentum ab anima nutritiva. Ostensum est autem supra, cum de Dei cognitione ageretur, quod videre Deum per essentiam, in quo ultima beatitudo rationalis creaturae consistit, est supra naturam cuiuslibet intellectus creati. Unde nulla creatura rationalis potest habere motum voluntatis ordinatum ad illam beatitudinem, nisi nota a supernaturali agente. Et hoc dicimus auxilium gratiae. Et ideo dicendum est quod angelus in illam beatitudinem voluntate converti non potuit, nisi per auxilium gratiae.” Book Symposium 140 essence of the cause of finite things. So, he affirms with respect to perfect happiness that it can be brought about only by the vision of God. One observes, however, that the desire in question is elicited (it is compared with desiring to know the cause of an eclipse, which clearly presupposes prior knowledge). Note also that the question concerns that in which, simpliciter and absolutely speaking, perfect happiness consists.There is no reference to whether this is possible, or not possible, although St. Thomas seems to be writing with the theological assurance of its possibility (a possibility that as Feingold reminds us10 St. Thomas elsewhere identifies as flowing from divine faith, as in Summa contra Gentiles III, question 153: “Fides autem, quae causatur ex gratia, declarat possibilem esse unionem hominis ad Deum secundum perfectam fruitionem, in qua beatitudo consistit”). Nor does St.Thomas deploy here any argument regarding the impossibility of natural desire being in vain.11 He seeks only to determine what constitutes perfect happiness. Likewise, whether there is a lesser felicity proportioned to human nature as such he does not here address, and certainly does not here deny. Since St.Thomas does affirm it elsewhere, for example in contradistinguishing human and angelic natural 10 See pp. 102–6 of Natural Desire for Feingold’s helpful early treatment of this arti- cle, in particular p. 104. 11 Of course, elsewhere there is seemingly such argument: for example, ST I, q. 12, a. 1; or ScG, III, 51, which last argues that “Since it is impossible that a natural desire be frustrated, which would happen if we could not arrive at the understanding of the divine substance that all minds naturally desire, it is therefore necessary to affirm that it is possible to see the divine substance by way of the intelligence.” But apart from all other interpretative issues—which here abound— one must point out that even were this taken in the strongest and most prima facie sense, and as unlimited by other ad extra textual considerations, it would indicate only the possibility of such a vision, and is indeed perfectly compatible with considering the natural desire, as such, both to be a velleity and to be radically disproportionate to the divine essence as such in precision from grace. Such a reading is perfectly in accord with Cajetan’s proposition that this teaching is offered from the vantage point of the theologian: For only through Revelation do we know that through the active agency of God the beatific vision is proximatelypossible for the believer (and one might think this is also true even of the purely abstract possibility or mere “thinkability” of seeing God, again on the grounds that St.Thomas writes in ScG, III, 51, as a theologian—but even if this were not true there would remain an enormously important distinction between proximate possibility and mere abstract possibility). It is of course a further question whether the steep gradient between mere abstract possibility and what is, with divine aid, proximate obediential potency mirrors the distinction between simple logical or conceptual possibility and real possibility. But in any case, only Revelation seems to assure the possibility of the divine vision in the second sense of proximate possibility, such that the natural desire becomes unconditional. Book Symposium 141 ends (every end has the nature of the good—so one is speaking of some measure of felicity) as opposed to the unity of the supernatural finis ultimus; or in distinguishing imperfect from perfect felicity (ST I–II, q. 5, a. 5), it is clearly not a text establishing that seeing God is the properly natural end of man. Indeed, in the Summa theologiae I–II, question 5, article 5, ad 3, St. Thomas insists that the species of the imperfect operation subject to man’s natural power is distinct from the species of the perfect operation which is man’s happiness (“Imperfecta autem operatio, quae subiacet naturali hominis potestati, non est eiusdem speciei cum operatione illa perefecta quae est hominis beatitudo, cum operationis species dependeat ex obiecto”). Thus, while there is more to be said about this text, the Summa theologiae I–II, question 3, article 8, establishes precisely what it set out to establish: that perfect beatitude for man can be found only in the vision of God. Manifestly, reading such texts within their precisely delimited reference, and refusing to extend them beyond, requires a knowledge of the text, an understanding of the reasoning of St.Thomas, and an intellectual asceticism that refuses to lose sight of the whole for the sake of exuberance with the part. De Lubac’s argument stresses the first set of texts, and more or less passes by the second (save when generically suggesting that these and other sources of Thomist reservation regarding his thesis are Renaissance corruptions concocted by Cajetan). I do not recollect de Lubac anywhere commenting extensively upon the second set of texts—in particular either with regard to the teaching of Aquinas that the absence of beatific vision for man in a state of pure nature would not constitute a punishment or in relation to St.Thomas’s clear teaching that human nature is defined by its natural and proximate end, which he says is distinct from the supernatural finis ultimus.The error of the historian who treats speculative propositions from without, thus failing theoretically to reconcile component parts of the doctrine to which they belong, forms part of this story, as does also the unfortunate mistrust of the scientia required to distill the meaning of these texts. That the pedagogic and heuristic limits of the scholastic project to which he was exposed may accidentally have contributed to kindling such mistrust in a mind as cultured and learned as de Lubac’s constitutes a tragedy within the twentieth-century history of Thomism.Yet, the omission to which this mistrust led is, with the distance of time, difficult to deny.12 12 Those who argue on the force of numerous other speculative assertions of St. Thomas that he cannot have meant what the face value of some propositions may suggest are gently—and sometimes not so gently—mocked by de Lubac, as witness his commentary on Gilson’s letters. In this and other respects the Letters of Etienne Gilson to Henri de Lubac proves a helpful source, as de Lubac’s notes establish that at 142 Book Symposium The rediscovery of the needed scientia is a necessity for contemplating the distinctions in Thomas’s texts and articulated by the commentators to enable a felicitous contemplation of the Gospel.As an illustration one notes the distinction between the mode of being and the mode of realization of a divinely caused effect—as visible for example, in the distinction between raising a body from the dead (restoring its natural life) by miracle, and achieving an effect whose being is intrinsically supernatural (for example, supernatural charity, the lumen gloria, the Incarnation of Christ). Perhaps equally helpful is the realization that the putative Renaissance corruptions13 the end of his career his position, despite varied refinements, had not fundamentally changed. Owing perhaps to overriding issues of perspective, Thomas’s fully theological use of the doctrine of specific obediential potency is never fully engaged by the great churchman.Yet this coincides with a proliferate citation of authors to assert that on this point, as de Lubac quotes Canon Balthazar from the 1928 Criterion 4:473:“One asks oneself how Cajetan had the nerve to propose his exegesis, and why it was, in point of fact, taken seriously for such a long time” (110), or as he cites Francisco Tolet, that Cajetan’s reading of obediential potency in relation to grace and nature “destruit testum” (103). But, St.Thomas himselfdirectly denies that man’s nature is actually in itself ordered to beatific vision (and surely it should not be averred that natural desire for supernatural beatitude is other than a “natural ordering”—natural desire is a sign of natural order). Quoth St. Thomas (Quaestiones Disputatae de Veritate, q. 14, a. 10, ad 2):“In the very beginning of creation, human nature was ordained to beatitude, not as to an end proper to man by reason of his nature, but given him solely by divine liberality. Therefore, there is no need for the principles of nature to have sufficient power to achieve that end without the aid of special gifts with which God in his generosity supplements them.” Further, Thomas expressly affirms a natural and proximate end distinct from the supernatural end that distinguishes man from the angel even though both are called to supernatural beatitude (cf. Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10):“Those beings whose proximate and natural end is one and the same are one in species. However, eternal beatitude is a final and supernatural end.”This point is of special pertinence for those critics who suppose that only lower, physical beings possess a natural end, for here Thomas is clearly distinguishing any angelic species from the human species by their different natural ends, which are distinct from supernatural beatitude. Add to this Thomas’s teaching that man might have been created without any supernatural aid—in short, with nothing but nature and the natural order to the natural end (Quaestiones quodlibetales I, q. 4, a. 3, resp.: “it was possible for God to make man with purely natural endowments”)—and the theological difficulties caused by such speculative omission in the historical insight of the scholars of la nouvelle théologie becomes conspicuous. 13 De Lubac notes (Gilson, Letters, 31, note 4) about Cajetan, citing his earlier work for emphasis, that “There is no doubt that the ‘commentator’ assigned another orientation to his master’s work.” Cf. H. de Lubac, Augustinism et théologie moderne (Paris:Aubier, 1965). Further (Gilson, Letters, 101, note 3) while de Lubac notes his own efforts to soften Gilson’s description of Cajetan’s work as “corruptorium Thomae,” he nonetheless takes great pains to relay several other charges of this sort Book Symposium 143 interposed by allegedly rationalizing scholastic interpreters exist within the very texts of St.Thomas himself—something that the astute critic may be disinclined to perceive as evidence for time travel.After all, if human nature has its species in relation to its natural end, which is distinct from the supernatural end, then this teaching of Thomas alone destroys the proposition that for Thomas supernatural beatific vision is the natural end (and this formulation that beatific vision is the natural end by contrast occurs nowhere in Thomas’s text: Yes, God is the natural end, but God as First Cause of these effects, not God precisely as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit). Likewise, if supernatural beatitude were the natural end of man, then to be perpetually deprived of it by God would necessarily constitute a punishment:While according to Thomas (and in a different way also according to de Lubac, who with all believers admitted the gratuity of grace and of the call to beatitude—it is the compatibility of this belief with his thesis that poses the difficulty), were man to die in the hypothetical state of pure nature and so not attain to the beatific vision, the inaccessibility of this vision would not be a punishment. Failure to attend to such texts naturally inclines one to read the first set of texts about natural desire for God as in the lines that follow, for example, from Soto (whose Scotistic treatment of the will in terms of pondus naturae is famed, but noting that would hardly have dignified Soto’s quoted remark about Cajetan’s account that “Haec glossa destruit textam, est tortuosa”). In general, the identification of Cajetan as imposing a “modern” reading of St.Thomas’s texts that is somehow distant from its original sense would carry more conviction if the actual texts of St. Thomas that seem to contradict the idea of supernatural beatitude as natural end had been cited and critically engaged. No historical scruples here, however: For is not (as Gilson, for example, tended to express it) a historian always and necessarily the better philosopher? Insofar as a priori this is held necessarily to be so, the commentators—whose emphasis is principally scientific and systematic as was their master’s—come to be instinctually distrusted.Yet Henri de Lubac knew he was arguing for an account, and in this respect—although fully capable of waxing poetic about the superiority of the historical habitus—seems never to have assumed the on-again/off-again pose of superior and dominating indifference to speculative contradiction within theology achieved by Gilson. Granted that the element of mystery must prevail in theology, contradiction is contradiction—something that when Gilson wished to note he would note, and when he did not, he would cast aspersions of “fanaticism.” Cf. Gilson (Gilson, Letters, 40):“[I]t’s perfectly all right to cling to another system as long as you don’t use your pet theology to oppose Saint Thomas’s. They all do it. And they themselves, no less than certain people who call themselves Thomists, are fanatics, too.” But perhaps such figures, whether Thomist or not, consider certain divergences amongst teachings to be of greater speculative weight than did Gilson—hardly a ground for the aspersion of fanaticism. A gifted and profound historian and reader of St.Thomas, his own particular combination of habitus could veil from his sight the validity of other combinations of the same. 144 Book Symposium straightforward and unproblematic, whereas in Thomas they exist within a wider philosophic and theological context necessary to their interpretation: A context of scientia that requires actual mastery of a body of natural distinctions. Hence those whose theology rests exclusively within a broadly theistic, historicized, cultural hermeneutic will tend to lack the metaphysical entry capital to commence interpretation of Aquinas on these points, and so tend to make scant sense of the controversy that so divided de Lubac from the consensus of the Thomistic commentatorial tradition. The truth is that any full regard for the complexity of St. Thomas’s teaching would suggest at the very least a certain reluctance to import into the first set of texts conclusions, which are incompatible with many unimpeachably clear and unquestionable formulations of Thomas elsewhere. For instance, the teaching that to know God is the end of every intelligent substance, apart from St. Thomas’s wider teaching might be read as suggesting that man lacks a proportionate natural finality (something Thomas expressly denies), and so in the absence of other texts might seem to suggest that the beatific finality is indeed properly speaking the natural end of man. The difference between an ontologically imperfect end proportionate to nature, and the perfect beatific end achieved solely through divine aid, requires advertence not alone to more texts, but to distinct aspects of the real. Yet as regards texts, even if one ignores the second set of texts, what should one make of those such as the following from the Summa contra Gentiles, III, chapter 25, titled “That to Know God Is the End of Every Intellectual Substance” (rather a different title than “intrinsically supernatural beatitude is the end of every intelligent substance” one should note): “Thus however slight may be the knowledge of God to which the intellect can attain, this will be the intellect’s last end, rather than a perfect knowledge of lower intelligibles.” What function does the “however slight” play, save to accommodate the manifest difference between a natural end perfect in its order with all the ensuing natural limits, and the supernatural end, which is absolutely ontologically perfect and transcendent of all natural limit? Natural understanding of God—if taken seriously and straightforwardly—is necessarily limited with respect to God because conditioned by finite evidence.Yet this natural desire and natural understanding constitutes a purely passive obediential potency, which under the active agency of God renders man capable of the supernatural vision of God. Nonetheless the first set of texts emphasized by de Lubac raises genuine problems of prime importance. Without doubt the question of natural desire is profound. What is the natural desire for God, and what is its object? Is this desire equivalently a natural desire for supernatural beat- Book Symposium 145 itude? And how could the natural desire for God not target supernatural beatitude—for is not the object of supernatural beatitude God in his essence, and is not the natural desire for God a desire to know God in his essence? That this desire reaches God only as cause of finite nature and under a formality infinitely inferior to supernatural beatitude—attaining God as a function of the natural desire to know the essence of any cause once it is known to exist, rather than as specified directly by the inner being of God14—requires insight into the requisites of natural teleology. Likewise, when we speak of “natural” desire for God, what is the sense of “natural”? Do we mean to refer to the voluntas ut natura or to what is the naturally befitting object of the will as such, and so to claim that the hidden reality of God is the natural befitting object of the will? Is the will as nature (voluntas ut natura) and in precision from grace naturally proportioned to the hidden substance of God—is it expressly and explicitly a deific faculty ordered apart from grace to the intrinsically supernatural vision of God? Or is the befitting natural object of the will not instead good in general, the universal good? The natural inclination clearly is for Thomas that toward which the thing naturally tends, which involves action and movement. Surely Thomas teaches that “the natural movement of the will is the principle of all things that we will. But the will’s natural inclination is directed towards what is in keeping with its nature” (ST I, q. 62, a. 2, emphasis added). Hence the will cannot be moved toward something beyond its nature such as supernatural beatitude without 14 See the Summa contra Gentiles III, 25, wherein St.Thomas expressly refers to the natural desire for God as a desire to know the cause of whatever one sees, and to know the cause of any effect including the cause of the effect of universal being. Clearly both these are elicited desires and both formally a function of the natural desire to know causes rather than of a desire whose formal object is supernatural beatitude as such. Further, to desire God as cause of universal being is to desire God under an infinitely lesser denomination than as he is in himself intrinsically independent of finite being: as though one were to desire to know God as “First Cause of goldfish.” That this natural desire may be elevated within the graced desire for essentially supernatural beatitude does not establish its formal identity with graced desire for God. Further, that contemplation of God is definitive of man’s natural end does not equate with this contemplation of God occurring through free and gratuitous supernatural Revelation.There is an intrinsic disproportion between a desire sparked by God’s own direct self-revelation in Christ, and a desire sparked by finite nature to know the Cause of this nature—as there is a formal difference between merely wanting to meet the man in the raincoat, and wanting to meet the same man in the raincoat because he is Einstein and has invited you to discuss physics with him. Materially the object is the same, but the formal specification of the desire is quite different. Clearly, also, the second includes the first, the greater includes the lesser, but not the other way around. 146 Book Symposium extrinsic supernatural assistance—about which last he states that “this is what we call the assistance of grace” (ST I, q. 62, a. 2). If the natural desire of the will in the sense of voluntas ut natura is not ordered to supernatural beatitude, must it not then be the case that the natural desire for God is a desire elicited by prior knowledge of the existence of God?15 Cajetan’s “hypothesis” of pure nature is often scorned as suggesting a “layer cake” of nature and grace.Yet his famed commentatorial treatment seems to suggest that the natural desire for God is modalized by the state in which nature exists, so that this desire would be found in one way had God not created man from the beginning within the privileged life of sanctifying grace, and is found in another in the context of man’s creation in the state of grace and of the data of supernatural Revelation. Conjoinedly, the scholastic consensus quo ante—that the natural desire for God is of itself an inefficacious desire within the ambit of the general desire for knowledge of being, and is a conditional desire save in relation to the promises of Revelation—seems enhanced in a remarkably subtle way by Cajetan’s contextualizing of natural order within the life of grace.16 15 It should be added that a similar analysis pertains to the intellect as nature, or in other words to the issue of what the befitting object of the intellect is. For this is the true in general, and perhaps more particularly the truth of quiddity in corporeal matter that is the proper object of the intellect of man as a composite knower, rather than specifically the divine truth. As we have seen, there is a proximate natural end from which the species is derived, and this proximate natural end clearly is not the inner reality of God—the human intellect is not simply and of itself proportionate to the infinitely transcendent God, but to the true in general. 16 Of course, Cajetan did not hold that the hypothetical state of pure nature had ever existed, knowing full well St.Thomas’s teaching that man is created in sanctifying grace. This does not mean that nature never existed, but that it never existed outside an order of Providence in which it was causally further ordered by grace: that is, from the very beginning nature is called to a higher destiny than the natural end whence the species is derived.The Fall of Man is indeed a sign of this further ordering, because man does not rebound to the order of pure nature, but rather nature is wounded: having been causally further ordered, its motion toward the purpose of that ordering cannot be stopped without harm. Of course, it also is true that the idea of defining the doctrine of the Incarnation without the conception of pure nature is impossible: What is it that would be assumed? This is of course too simple an observation for those who paint with broad strokes, but broad strokes often fail to depict intricate scenes. It is also inconsistent with the cottage industry of Cajetan-vilification, which devolves from a failure to consider all the pertinent texts in Aquinas, much less to entertain the idea that Cajetan was (as is manifest) a brilliant and subtle reader of St. Thomas: perhaps not always correct, but rather more positively engaged with the doctrine (and the implications of the doctrine) of St.Thomas than suggested by de Lubac in Augustinianism and Modern Theology and elsewhere. Book Symposium 147 The following points articulate St. Thomas’s teaching regarding the natural desire for God: • The arc of natural desire for God (viewed in itself and apart from grace and Revelation) is specified by natural knowledge, and so cannot formally reach to the essence of God as such howsoever much it reaches it materially. 17 17 Cf. St.Thomas Aquinas, Super Sent., lib. 3, dist. 23, q. 1 a. 4, qc 3 co., a passage of whose full extent I was reminded by Christopher Malloy of the University of Dallas, and about which I have also profited from the erudition of Prof. John Boyle, of the University of St.Thomas:“To the third question it must be said that in all things which act for an end there must be an inclination to the end, a certain ‘inchoation’ of the end, otherwise, they would never do something for an end. But the end towards which the divine generosity has ordained and predestined man, namely, the fruition of himself [of God], is in every way elevated above the faculty of created nature, for “neither has the eye seen, nor the ear heard, nor has there arisen in the heart of man what things God has prepared for those who love him” (1 Cor 2:9). Therefore, by his natural powers alone, man does not have a sufficient inclination to this end, and thus it is necessary that something be superadded to man through which he would have the inclination to that end, as by his natural powers he does have an inclination to the end that is connatural to him. And those things that are superadded are called the theological virtues for three reasons. First, as to the object: For, since that end to which we are ordained is God himself, the inclination that is prerequisite [to this end] consists in an operation that regards God himself. Second, as to the cause: For as that end is ordained for us by God not by our nature, so the inclination to the end is worked in us solely by God; thus it is that these virtues are called theological, as though created in us by God alone.Third, as to knowledge:“The inclination to this end is not able to be known by natural reason but rather by divine revelation; therefore, the virtues are called theological since by the divine word they are manifest to us, for the philosophers knew nothing of them.”—“Ad tertiam quaestionem dicendum, quod in omnibus quae agunt propter finem oportet esse inclinationem ad finem, et quamdam inchoationem finis: alias nunquam operarentur propter finem. Finis autem ad quem divina largitas hominem ordinavit vel praedestinavit, scilicet fruitio sui ipsius, est omnino supra facultatem naturae creatae elevatus: quia nec oculus vidit, nec auris audivit, nec in cor hominis ascendit, quae praeparavit deus diligentibus se, ut dicitur 1 corinth., 2, 9. Unde per naturalia tantum homo non habet sufficienter inclinationem ad illum finem; et ideo oportet quod superaddatur homini aliquid per quod habeat inclinationem in finem illum, sicut per naturalia habet inclinationem in finem sibi connaturalem: et ista superaddita dicuntur virtutes theologicae ex tribus. Primo quantum ad objectum: quia cum finis ad quem ordinati sumus, sit ipse deus, inclinatio quae praeexigitur, consistit in operatione quae est circa ipsum deum. Secundo quantum ad causam: quia sicut ille finis est a deo nobis ordinatus non per naturam nostram, ita inclinationem in finem operatur in nobis solus deus: et sic dicuntur virtutes theologicae, quasi a solo deo in nobis creatae.Tertio quantum ad cognitionem, inclinatio in finem non 148 Book Symposium • The natural desire for God is a desire consequent on the natural ordination of intellect to being, a desire to know the essence of a cause once that cause is known to exist. • This desire is elicited by the acquired knowledge that God is, rather than being equivalent to the voluntas ut natura (or for that matter the intellectus ut natura)—because what the will naturally desires as its befitting object is the good in general and not specifically the essence of God (howsoever much it be true that God is the subsisting universal good).18 potest per naturalem rationem cognosci, sed per revelationem divinam: et ideo dicuntur theologicae, quia divino sermone sunt nobis manifestatae: unde philosophi nihil de eis cognoverunt.” 18 This is of course one of the most longstanding confusions affecting the entire question of the natural desire for God.Thomas writes of the will as nature or voluntas ut natura that “each power desires by the natural appetite that object which is suitable to itself ” (ST I, q. 80, a. 1, ad 3: “Unde unaquaeque appetit obiectum sibi conveniens naturali appetitu”). This is distinguished from animal appetite and likened to “sight for seeing or sound for hearing” (“utpote visio ad videndum et auditio ad audiendum”). But what is suitable to the will by its nature in this sense is intelligible good in general. It must be noted that what the nature is ordered toward and suitable for simply by its nature is that from which Thomas maintains the creature derives its species. But in this sense human nature is not defined by its capacity to be uplifted by God’s grace to supernatural beatific vision—which is shared also by the innumerable species of angels—but by what St.Thomas calls the proximate and natural end, the end that might have been the end simpliciter had God created man in a state of pure nature and not gratuitously ordered man to the beatific vision.To say that by nature the human will directly aspires to the hidden life of God is to define it as the divine will alone may be defined. All creation is ordered to God as End, but through the medium of the proportionate natural end for each creature, which is nothing other than a mode of being like unto God. In the human case, of course, this is constituted by the most exalted contemplation of God within the ambit of natural capacity. But, as Thomas points out, the beatific vision exceeds every purely natural capacity whether of man or angel (cf. ScG III, ch. 52), exceeding all natural capacity to know. Since the desire for God is specified by natural knowledge of God (for the will is—cf. Quaestiones quadlibetales, quodlibet VI, q. 2, a. 2—nothing other than inclinatio sequens formam intellectam), it follows that natural desire for God does not truly know what it desires, whereas graced desire (even while man yet is remote from the beatific vision) is rooted in the reality of God itself (and hence one can know more of God by grace than by nature, even in this life). One notes the words of Jacques Maritain from his work Approaches to God, trans. Peter O’Reilly (New York: Harper, 1954), 109–10: “But this desire to know the First Cause through its essence is a desire which does not know what it asks, like the sons of Zebedee when they asked to sit on the right and on the left of the Son of Man.‘Ye know not what ye ask,’ Jesus replied to them. For to know the First Cause in its essence, or without the intermediary of any other thing, is to know the First Cause otherwise than as First Cause; it is to know it by ceasing to attain it by the very means by which we attain it, by ceasing to Book Symposium 149 • The natural desire for God is not of itself efficacious.That is, we have no natural capacity to know the essence of the First Cause quidditatively.Although we do indeed naturally move toward contemplation of God as First Cause, this motion cannot reach the divine essence. Indeed, this desire is thoroughly conditioned by the finite evidence whence it arises, such that it is not proportioned to God, but rather is proportioned to the intellective desire to understand the world in general which gives rise to it.19 But to desire to know God in himself under the ratio of “cause of the world” is somewhat like the desire to know Einstein under the ratio of “man wearing a raincoat.” As “man wearing a raincoat” is an accidental denomination vis-à-vis Einstein, so to desire God as cause of the world is strictly speaking not truly to desire God, who is infinitely more than cause of the world. Indeed, for God to be cause of the world signifies something in the world, whereas God infinitely transcends the world. Whether the hypothetical but immutable divine will should will the universe to be, or not, does not alter the infinite goodness of God. Creation is an utterly free and gratuitous act of divine generosity. • There are diverse ways in which this natural desire for God can exist. For example, the natural desire would exist in one way had man never been assisted with supernatural aid;20 it exists in another way exercise the very act which bears us up to it.” See also p. 112:“It is necessary that there be in man an “obediential potency” which, answering to the divine omnipotence, renders him apt to receive a life which surpasses infinitely the capacities of his nature.”This “neo”-Thomist earned the adverse adjective by conforming to the actual teaching of St.Thomas—a paradox he savored. 19 Some authors have supposed that, had God created man in a state of pure nature, the separated soul would have enjoyed a knowledge of the universe both comprehensive in itself and reflective of all that can be known through the universe of God as in a mirror, by way of infused divine species. But St.Thomas is silent about such reflections inasmuch as his focus is upon the actual providential synthesis—wherein grace moves us to the infinitely higher goal of personal union with God transcending all created species—rather than upon the mere hypothesis of pure nature. 20 Within this zone of the purely natural, the natural desire to know God as Cause of finite being, as this knowledge principally defines purely natural felicity, is to be distinguished from the natural quasi-velleity to know God as he would be known through himself were this to be attainable. For the former is proportionate to nature and naturally attainable, whereas that which the latter confusedly seeks is disproportionate to any finite nature and attainable only insofar as God elevates us to a share in divine life: It knows not what it asks, and naturally speaking amounts simply to a desire for more and higher knowledge were this possible (while yet still being conceived on the pattern of a knowing infinitely lesser than 150 Book Symposium in the actual order of Providence wherein man is created in sanctifying grace and where the real possibility of the beatific vision is divinely revealed. Where Revelation makes the real possibility of beatific vision known, this renders the otherwise conditional desire to know God to become unconditional. Apart from Revelation the desire would be conditional—“were it possible” one would will it. Just as one might wish to live forever, or never to make a mistake— both logically but seemingly not really possible—so one would wish to know the essence of the First Cause, save that in this case one genuinely would not know what one is wishing for. After Revelation, the desire becomes unconditional. Once God reveals himself and his gift of divine life, the natural desire thus elevated and supernaturalized in grace inclines toward it absolutely by inclining toward the infinitely higher end of union with the Uncreated Persons of the Holy Trinity. For the object of the natural desire for God under the ratio of “Cause of these effects” is incorporated within the graced desire of God as God. This idea of the modalization of the natural desire according to the states in which it may be found contextualizes it in relation to grace. Because St. Thomas’s focus is upon the given providential synthesis, his principal treatment of the natural desire is a treatment that takes it up as it actually is to be found in this present order, and not merely as it would be found in the hypothetical state of pure nature (although the phrase from ScG III, q. 25—“however slight may be the knowledge of God to which the intellect can attain this will be the intellect’s last end”—seems a nod of the head to the state of the natural desire apart from Revelation, since it expressly considers a state in which the last end of the intellect is the wisdom about God as First Cause which does not reach the divine essence: “however slight”). • Finally, specific obediential potency is not a mere susceptibility to miracle but represents what a nature is capable of with the assistance of the active power of God. Hence while it remains true that grace is an extrinsic principle vis-à-vis human nature—human nature is not grace, nor is it law, which is why St. Thomas in the prologue to his treatise on law in the Summa theologiae identifies grace and law as extrinsic principles—nonetheless, grace does work within human nature as such whose rational character makes it with divine assistance to be elevable to supernatural life, action, and merit. Grace thus elevates human nature and works within it, enabling the Christian to perform genuinely supernaturalized acts meritorious of beatitude. Book Symposium 151 The convergence of both Dominican and Jesuit commentatorial authors—Sylvester of Ferrara, Cajetan, Báñez, John of St.Thomas, Suárez— around themes such as these within St. Thomas’s work is all the more remarkable for having fallen off the map of a generation of theologians. Of course, these commentators do not all agree (and some would dissent from certain of the elements above): yet, for none of them is the natural desire for God a desire for intrinsically supernatural beatitude.21 This is an arresting theological consensus, whose density and ascetic rigor contrasts markedly with the loss of awareness of texts, contexts, and doctrinal implications that has come to dominate accounts of the relations of nature and grace, or—for that matter—of theology and philosophy. Correct doctrine with respect to the relation of grace to nature is of the greatest strategic import for theology, by reason of the theological synthesis it sustains. By contrast, a teaching that renders human nature to be a vacuole or pure nought lacking proportionate created integrity and unknowable apart from the beatific vision seems to make the doctrine of Nicea to be unintelligible. For what is assumed in the Word is defined in precision from the datum of its assumption. One does not say, “The Person of the Word assumed the nature that is defined by its being assumed by the Person of the Word”—for that would render hypostatic union a necessary function of finite human nature. The idea that the natural end of man—the end from which human nature derives its species—is that divine good directly known and loved by God alone seems to imply that man is naturally deific. But the connatural and direct knowledge and love of God is verified in God alone, howsoever much it is the case that all creation is indirectly ordered to God as End.22 that of beatific vision). The status of this confused, conditional, elicited desire clearly changes when elevated in grace and ordered to the supernatural beatific vision that revelation instructs us to be proximately attainable with divine aid. 21 For the map of this convergence, as of the differences among these commentators, we now have no better compendium than Feingold’s book.Whereas he stresses the central and formative contributions to the tradition of Sylvester of Ferrara, and of Suárez, the emphasis above, stressing Cajetan’s contribution, is my own. While there are other readings of Cajetan, it seems to me that the one which most keeps the intelligible sense of his account is that which I suggest above. 22 Cf. ScG III, 17, whose title is “That All Things Are Directed to One End,Which Is God.” One notes that this reasoning is based upon the order of agents toward God as the Supreme and Common good of the universe, and naturally pertains to “all things” for “there can be nothing that has not its being from Him” (Omnia autem entia sunt huiusmodi: nam, sicut in secundo probatur, nihil esse potest quod ab ipso non habeat esse. Omnia igitur ordinantur in Deum sicut in finem). 152 Book Symposium What defines human nature, as St.Thomas Aquinas expressly and everywhere affirms, is the proximate and natural end rather than the supernatural end.23 Hence, for example, these words of Fr. Brian Shanley regarding the text of Aquinas are simply false:“It needs to be emphasized at the outset that Aquinas holds that man has one and only one end or telos: the beatific vision of God.There are not two human ends, one natural and the other supernatural, as was thought in older, erroneous versions of two-tiered Thomism.”24 If he had written that for Thomas there is but one finis ultimus, which is beatific vision, or that there are not two “coequal” ends, this would be true. But while there is only one finis ultimus, which is supernatural, this does not rule out an end proportionate to nature that is further ordered in grace to the ultimate supernatural finality. Already we have cited, above, the words of St.Thomas:“Those beings whose proximate and natural end is one and the same are one in species. However, eternal beatitude is a final and supernatural end.”25 Clearly, then, for St.Thomas there is a proximate and natural end, definitory of the species, which is distinct from and inferior to the final end of supernatural beatitude. Further, nature is the preamble to grace and not merely its postscript. Yet lacking natural finality distinct from supernatural beatitude, nature does indeed become merely a placeholder for grace, as though the manifestation of what man is capable of with divine grace did not presuppose nature; or, as though in order to be theocentric, nature must already be ordered to supernatural beatitude apart from grace. Speech about nature anticipating grace is utterly vain in a context within which the order of nature is not distinguished from the order of grace. Since powers are distinguished by acts, and acts by objects, and objects by ends, to distinguish the two orders is to acknowledge that the natural end is distinct from, and less perfect than, the supernatural end. Nor is this to free nature from God, because natural order is theonomic, the impress of the ordering wisdom of God. Indeed, natural law obligates man to receive whatsoever God deigns to reveal. Further, man’s creation in sanctifying grace orders nature to a higher end—it is causally efficacious—such that sin itself does not put man into a state of “pure nature” but rather does harm to nature (not, of course, substantially, but accidentally, in lessening 23 Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10. 24 See p. 555 of Fr. Brian Shanley’s “Pagan Virtue,” The Thomist 63 (1999): 553–77. 25 Again, see Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10, quoted in full in note 3 above, or ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1, with respect to human nature being defined by the proximate and natural end as distinct from the supernatural end. Human nature is not defined by a non-existent natural end, albeit the natural end is not, from the very creation of man in grace, man’s final end. Book Symposium 153 the strength of the motion toward the end). Just as a man who climbs up the Empire State Building and then jumps loses something more than the height he had attained (namely, his life), so nature as concretely further ordered in grace is profoundly harmed when grace is lost (although, again, accidentally, in regard to the vigor of its motion to the end, and not essentially: Fallen man is yet human) precisely because it has itself been ordered through grace toward the more exalted beatific end. But the very idea of the supernatural is not the idea of a merely natural completion. The attempt to argue that if nature and grace are distinct that therefore no natural harm should ensue upon the loss of grace is an argument that implicitly fails to accept the causal efficacy of grace. Once ordered in and by grace at creation, thereinafter human nature will be vain and frustrated apart from the supernatural end. That is, human nature, as created in sanctifying grace, is as such remotely ordered to the supernatural end by this fact—the very reason why St. Thomas, in the Summa theologiae I–II, question 89, article 6, will argue that the first morally significant act of a boy who has not been baptized is either damnific or salvific (because, implicitly, he either seeks the due good as such—which requires grace—or does not, which is damnific).26 That the two orders are distinct hardly voids the causal efficacy of grace. Nor is the causal efficacy of grace transmutative of species, because the natural end remains in its integrity as further ordered to the supernatural end—just as knowledge of and desire for God merely as cause of finite creation is in grace ordered to knowledge of and desire for God as he is in himself. Further, human nature is such that with divine aid it is capable of supernatural beatitude—the nature itself need not be transmuted, but rather only aided and elevated by the active agency of God.While Scotus implies that the appetite for supernatural beatitude is in substance natural, Aquinas pronouncedly and clearly denies this proposition.27 26 ST I–II, q. 89, a. 6:“Now the first thing that occurs to a man to think about then, is to deliberate about himself. And if he then direct himself to the due end, he will, by means of grace, receive the remission of original sin: whereas if he does not then direct himself to the due end, and as far as he is capable of discretion at that particular age, he will sin mortally, for through not doing that which is in his power to do.” 27 Note the teaching of Scotus on this matter (Ordinatio I [Vatican ed.], distinction 3, 113–14; III, 70–71) arguing that if grace were to elevate the human intellect beyond its natural capacity this would mutate the intellect, whereas in his view an accidental quality can perfect the capacity of an already existing power but not change its nature. Thomas by contrast (ScG, III, 53–54) holds that the divine elevation and emendation of the ontological limits of the human intellect via the lumen gloriae does indeed transcend the natural use of the intellect, rendering it capable of an 154 Book Symposium With St. Thomas one may hold that the way in which the higher creation of man and angel is naturally ordered to God as End is infinitely lesser than the way in which supernatural grace, elevating and redirecting nature and enabling it to participate in the very love of God, orders the creature to God as End.The ontological reditus incorporates a natural element (and its epistemic requisites) within the life of grace. Human and angelic nature are indeed ordered to God in precision from grace, but along an infinitely lower trajectory than that of supernatural grace, so that only with divine aid may these natures be elevated within the higher arc that passes into the very mystery of God himself. Further, the natural is not an arena of autonomy from God: All created being and action derive from God as First Cause. Thus what frequently is presented as unhistorical novelty is paradoxically the teaching not only of Aquinas but of the consensus of the Catholic theological tradition.This is not merely a historically curious vindication of great commentators become obscure, but a rediscovery of the genuine synthesis of St.Thomas: a synthesis wherein the natural mode of participation in eternal law is transcended by the nobler participation of the eternal law in supernatural grace.That the teloi of these participations are distinct, are materially but not formally the same—God as principle of created nature as opposed to God revealed in himself (for there is infinitely more in God than merely being “principle of created nature,” just as there is more in Einstein than being a “man wearing a raincoat”)—is essential to the integrity of St.Thomas’s teaching. Likewise, that the natural desire for God represents an obediential potency whereby the active agency of God may elevate man to achieve distinctive supernatural friendship indicates that the lower participation of the eternal law is presupposed to the higher. Nonexistent natures obviously are not elevated by grace, and a nature lacking a proportionate end would be a nature lacking any actual natural tendency whatsoever: for actual motion is only known in relation to the end to which it tends. Now, every orthodox Catholic—as de Lubac insisted—considers that nature has no claim on grace (as de Lubac put it,“in my view, which is that of every Catholic, any idea of a claim of created nature in relation to the supernatural should be absolutely excluded”)28 and that man cannot really intrinsically supernatural act while not altering or annulling its nature.That is, nature is elevated to a supernatural capacity by a supernatural grace. 28 Henri de Lubac, Augustinianism and Modern Theology (Paris: Aubier, 1965), at the close of the first chapter regarding Baius. Book Symposium 155 move toward supernatural beatitude without grace. It follows that since man cannot under any circumstances move toward supernatural beatitude without grace that no purely natural motion toward such an end apart from grace and Revelation is possible. This is true quite apart from sin: Even had man been created without the supernatural aid of grace and had done no evil, he still would not be able to actually move toward intrinsically supernatural beatitude inasmuch as this infinitely transcends finite nature29 (which is not to deny that man naturally would have been able to move asymptotically toward God as causal principle of created nature). But in the absence of natural motion (howsoever accidentally impeded) toward X, X is not said to be the natural end. One recollects the words of Summa theologiae I, question 62, article 2: “But the will’s natural inclination is toward what is naturally fitting for it. And so if something is beyond its nature, then the will cannot be moved toward it without the assistance of some other principle that lies beyond its nature [ab aliquo alio principio supernaturali].” Just as reading Shakespeare does not finalize the motion of the Tulip because the Tulip naturally exhibits no actual tendency or motion toward reading Shakespeare, and the Tulip is defined not by reading Shakespeare but by the end toward which it actually moves; so human nature is defined in relation to the end proportionate to that nature and toward which it actually moves as from its natural inclination. As he puts it in Summa contra Gentiles IIIb, question 150: Also. Everything is directed to a suitable end in proportion to its form: since different species have different ends. Now, the end whereto man is directed by the assistance of divine grace is above human nature. Therefore man needs, over and above, a supernatural form and perfection, so as to be suitably directed to that same end. Besides. It behooves man to reach his last end by means of his own actions. Now, everything acts in proportion to its form. Therefore, in order that man may be brought to his last end by means of his own 29 It must be remembered, however, that man is created in sanctifying grace, and that natural law itself dictates that whatever God reveals be received and obeyed. What is proper to nature as such is not simply tantamount to what remains within this order of Providence when grace is lost. But the very idea of the supernatural is not the idea of a merely natural completion.The attempt to argue that if nature and grace are distinct therefore no natural harm should ensue upon the loss of grace is an argument that implicitly fails to accept the efficacy of grace in further ordering nature. But that the two orders are distinct hardly voids the causal efficacy of grace. 156 Book Symposium actions, he needs to receive an additional form, whereby his actions may be rendered effective in meriting his last end.30 There is simply no doubt that this is Thomas’s teaching.31 Perhaps the understanding of the natural desire for and motion toward God as distinct from the graced desire for and motion toward God has lapsed so very much precisely because theologians no longer consider themselves in need of understanding natural motion and natural teleology.32 Yet if ever there were a question that 30 ScG IIIb, ch. 150, nn. 5 and 6: “Amplius. Unumquodque ordinatur in finem sibi convenientem secundum rationem suae formae: diversarum enim specierum diversi sunt fines. Sed finis in quem homo dirigitur per auxilium divinae gratiae, est supra naturam humanam. Ergo oportet quod homini superaddatur aliqua supernaturalis forma et perfectio, per quam convenienter ordinetur in finem praedictum. Item. Oportet quod homo ad ultimum finem per proprias operationes perveniat. Unumquodque autem operatur secundum propriam formam. Oportet igitur, ad hoc quod homo perducatur in ultimum finem per proprias operationes, quod superaddatur ei aliqua forma, ex qua eius operationes efficaciam aliquam accipiant promerendi ultimum finem.” 31 Note, again, Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10; and ST I, q. 62, a. 2. 32 Indeed, this may be widened to include understanding of the whole ontology of nature, and of the distinct discipline of metaphysics. Hence one finds many authors today advancing the old, and radically erroneous, view according to which there are strictly speaking no “demonstrations” of the existence of God.This unfortunate inversion of Thomas’s teaching—in truth a hoary old misreading and stock answer perpetually recycled by fideist authors—is unfortunately resuscitated in the work of Milbank and Pickstock (cf. John Milbank and Catherine Pickstock, Truth in Aquinas [London: Routledge, 2001], 28: “ ‘demonstrations’ of God’s existence can only be meant to offer weakly probable modes of argument and very attenuated ‘showings’ ”). One may agree that the “showing” is attenuated (one does not demonstrate the existence of God in the manner that one demonstrates one’s battle scar) without implying that the demonstration is only “weakly probable”—an expression contrary to Thomas’s teaching regarding the nature of demonstration. Of course,Thomas holds not only that the truth of the proposition that “God is” is demonstrable: He also holds (Scriptum on the Sentences, II, dist. 1, q. 1, a. 2) that the truth of creation is demonstrable: “I answer that not only does faith hold that there is creation but reason also demonstrates it.”The present author has heard it said more than once by theologians that natural theology “makes atheism possible”—as though, if only we pretend that the existence of God is self-evident to everyone, we can avoid the need to contemplate the evidence of creation’s dependence upon its transfinite Cause. One supposes in the same way that the principle of non-contradiction makes falsity possible—but one trusts that the fact that truth may be contradicted hardly constitutes sufficient reason for abandoning truth.The degree of unaffected innocence of the knowledge of natural ontology and metaphysics among contemporary theologians is perhaps rivaled only by the singular remotion of many contemporary analytic philosophers from the theoretic Book Symposium 157 requires natural teleology—of the sort that Thomas develops with exquisite philosophic care—surely it is the question of the natural desire for God. Further, there is no reductionist aspect to this consideration. It is because human nature in its spiritual character is such as to be able to be further aided by God to enjoy divine friendship—further aided to know God not merely as principle of nature but as he is in himself—that human nature is said to manifest an obediential potency for grace and glory in relation to the active agency of God.This is indeed not a natural potency, but a purely passive potency of a given nature in relation to the active agency of God. The obediential potency enables the creature to receive from God an actuation radically disproportionate to its unassisted nature and natural potencies. Here again the truth is manifest that only those who discern the profundity of the gift of created nature see how far grace and Revelation transcend it: Far from naturalism, it is the exaltation of the supernatural order that follows from these considerations. These reflections, while dispensing in principle with the conundrums of a created nature putatively hotwired into supernatural beatitude, imply and indeed invite a complementary project. That complementary project consists in seeing how it is that the theological intention of de Lubac might most fittingly have been fulfilled not by the hypothesis of a creature whose natural desire is deific, but by the very notion of obediential potency itself. Further, this complementary project needs to explain the historical and doctrinal elements that remotely but really condition the theological stage, leaving Henri de Lubac and others such as LaPorta with only the narrowest apparent interpretative margins for safeguarding and developing a certain legitimate Christian intention which that antecedent theological problem-situation seemed to endanger. This complementary consideration constitutes a veritable Rosetta stone in deciphering the intelligible causes and narrative of postmodern, pluralist theological fragmentation: the loss of the sacramentality of the Word, the evisceration of anthropology and moral theology, and the dangerous proliferation of historicist fideisms and ideologized rationalist modes of thought. This complementary project, to which I should now like to turn, pursues not only a deeper awareness of the context that molded de Lubac’s creativity in the directions in which it flowed—largely positive, but in this significant point regarding nature and grace, deeply problematic—but also seeks a strategic viewpoint for understanding the problem situation canon of two millennia of Catholic philosophy for the sake of the theoretic canon of the past seventy-five years. Interesting years, it is true: but perhaps not quite that interesting? In any case, it is within such circumstances that fideist and rationalist impulses may begin to run amuck. 158 Book Symposium of theology, and the impediments and challenges to Catholic thought, at the start of the new millenium. For the contrapositions that defined the horizon of theology for de Lubac and called forth his teaching have not been corrected as he hoped.These contrapositions persist today in structuring theological contemplation apart from the requisites of Catholic doctrine and culture.To these points I shall now turn. First I will address the misconstrual of St. Thomas’s doctrine of obediential potency by de Lubac and Gilson, and their consequent loss of the idea of specific obediential potency as thematized in St. Thomas’s account of nature and grace.33 Then I will try to identify the critical deprivations within the theological situation as he inherited it that tempted so profound a Catholic intelligence to the solution he adopted in Surnaturel. The Immediate and Proximate Context: Error Regarding Obediential Potency The immediate context for assessing de Lubac’s thought about nature and grace is of course that of the loss to theological anthropology represented by the misconstrual and rejection of the classical conception of specific obediential potency. Insofar as de Lubac refers to obediential potency, he seems to depict it chiefly as susceptibility to miracle, and as in any case not pertinent to the fundamental question of the relation of nature to grace. This is a view, of course, largely associated with the Franciscan school. It demarcates a common if erroneous judgment, which has been shared by such notable Thomistic figures in the twentieth century as Etienne Gilson (in his later work), for whom obediential potency in relation to grace was tantamount to the idea of a mere extrinsic and miraculous transmutation of nature. As noted above, de Lubac did not significantly advert to the texts that militate against his reading of the natural desire and obediential potency, and tended more and more to attribute opposition to his account 33 It must be noted that de Lubac’s orthodoxy, profound love for the Church, and desire to resolve the impasse suggested by the horizon defining his vision, all make his treatment of this issue a more favorable place to confront the distortion of the understanding of the relation of nature to grace than that of others. For example, one thinks of authors such as Rahner, whose conclusion is in this respect nonetheless quite close to de Lubac’s in excoriating the antecedent consensus (as he once put it, the purpose of his work was to make “scholasticism” to be impossible in the future). But for Rahner this required invention of an overgeneric and unclear conception of a “supernatural existential” to replace the intelligible principles of nature and grace, whereas de Lubac aims to retain these principles as properly foundational. Book Symposium 159 merely to “fanatical Suarezians and intransigent Thomists.”34 He was inclined to conflate insistence upon the distinction between the end proportionate to nature and the supernatural finis ultimus with a naive naturalism, as these remarks indicate: The great traditional texts on man’s destiny and blessedness were to be systematically refuted in favor of a natural plan that distorts them.They were to be understood from this point on as nothing but affirmations of purely natural philosophy. The “perfection” of human nature to which these very texts apply . . . was itself going to be, in the same way, a fully natural perfection; pure philosophy was supposed to furnish the concept of natural perfection, etc. This concern lest the idea of “natural perfection” enter Christian thought is paradoxical, inasmuch as human nature in its integrity is precisely a perfection, and one without which the mystery of the Incarnation is impossible. Further, how would God himself distinguish nature and supernature were it not the case that between the divine nature and the nature of the created person there are naturally diverse ends? A natural end is that toward which a being naturally tends as to the perfection proportionate to it and from which its species is distinguished:35 And 34 Gilson, Letters, 102, note 3 (carried on from p. 101). An interesting conjunction, which should have served as a warning: How could all the interpreters of St. Thomas on this point be completely in error? Of course, such is not impossible. But it is not a likely supposition, nor is it reasonable to discard generations of theological and philosophic work on the force of such a supposition. Both Thomists and Suarezians read the Angelic Doctor as holding for obediential potency as pertaining to the relation of nature to grace.Their in-house disputation about the sense of “obediential potency” cannot obscure the datum that, at bottom, each views it as a passive potency of a very particular sort, the sort involving a specific range of actuation to which a nature is amenable solely through the active agency of an extrinsic cause. Today, many persons who have read neither Thomas, nor Thomistic commentators, nor Suárez, nor Suarezians, are equally convinced that all are incorrect on this point, and also are convinced that the scholastics were ahistorical. But sed contra: It seems that they were correct, and that however ahistorical their work, at least they did not judge authors without first reading them. 35 One directs the attention once more to Quaestiones de Anima, a. 7, ad 10, which is of course duplicated in ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1, and elsewhere. Bluntly:There is precisely no doubt in Thomas’s text that what defines human nature is precisely the natural end as distinct from the supernaturally beatific end. Recollect the text from De Anima:“Those beings whose proximate and natural end is one and the same are one in species. However, eternal beatitude is a final and supernatural end.” This—absolutely in itself—would be sufficient to destroy the thesis of Surnaturel and Augustinianism and Modern Theology with respect to the actual teaching of Aquinas. It is also enough to indicate that Cajetan did not invent this teaching. 160 Book Symposium clearly this definition does not describe the supernatural beatific vision (for only the divine nature is defined by intrinsically supernatural and deific felicity—even in beatitude, the creature’s knowledge does not comprehend God but rather is measured by God). It follows that the philosophic definition of “end” was to be surmounted with a different conception, for which the only justification was its putative efficacy in saving the Christian intellect from the danger of naturalism. But it is precisely in relation to the end proportionate to human nature that the supernatural end comes properly into view: The Triune God who moves us to himself in beatific vision is not merely the maraschino cherry on a purely natural sundae.36 Why should specific obediential potency be equated with mere miraculous transmutation? In one of his letters Gilson well articulates the position he came to share with de Lubac: Yet in fairness, the animating quest was perhaps less to engage St.Thomas’s teaching than to achieve a symbiosis of certain aspects of the teaching of the Angelic Doctor—perhaps “corrected” of certain of its actual traits—with non-scientific conceptions of theology.This suggests a parallel between de Lubac and Heidegger. As Heidegger identifies the font of metaphysics and ontology as scientia in the work of Aristotle, and accuses this Aristotelian understanding of science with being the origin of the positivist and reductionist spirit regarding being; so de Lubac seems to consider the ideal of scientia assimilated by St. Thomas to theological purpose, as naturalist and intrinsically prone to rationalist desiccation and the flight from mystery. Of course, de Lubac separates out from Thomas’s work elements that he prefers, a speculative reconstruction that loses what Thomas says about nature and natural end.Yet one may argue that genuine mystery does not entail the evisceration of the natural, and that obediential potency does not, for Thomas, reduce to its most generic meaning of mere susceptibility to miracle. If Thomas’s teaching offers a hermeneutical principle for the reading of the Fathers, this suggests the presence in his work of a supervening excellence. Ironically, the genius of de Lubac—his profound gift for appreciating the Fathers in their own terms—may partially account for his misdoubts regarding basic elements of St.Thomas’s stress on theology as science. 36 It should not be forgotten that the position of Henri de Lubac bears some comparison to that of Scotus insofar as the capacity for beatific vision is a natural capacity aided by grace, as opposed to being what it is for Aquinas: a strictly supernatural capacity that requires the supernatural strengthening of the lumen gloriae to render the human creature even capable of receiving the supernatural vision of God. Hence it transpires that while the concern is avoiding Aristotelian “naturalism” that this concern seems likely to give way precisely to a species of naturalism that Aquinas directly and unwaveringly opposed through his texts and for all his life: that naturalism that would claim that there is a strictly natural desire and natural capacity for supernatural beatific vision that requires merely extrinsic supernatural aid for its accomplishment, rather than seeing that the desire and capacity for supernatural beatific vision is as such itself an effect of supernatural grace. Book Symposium 161 I don’t think either of us has ever found a set of terms adequate to define the Thomist position, and that’s quite to be expected, since he himself could not find one either. In fact, his terminology is somewhat loose, because he never throws away an expression if it is possible to justify it in some sense. Potentiality subject to obedience is an instructive example of what I’m talking about. He came upon the term ready-made; strictly speaking, it is applicable only to miracles, where nothing in matter either prepares for, expects, or makes the phenomenon possible [emphasis added]; in general (your excellent quotes on page 244), all nature is in a state of potentiality subject to obedience to whatever it may please God to do with it, provided that this is not, in itself, contradictory or impossible.37 Henri de Lubac of course thought the same: In the order of finality itself, so as to avoid any confusion between the supernatural gift and the mere fulfillment a nature receives from some natural agent, we may join some of the moderns—without in any way departing from the spirit of the past—in specifying that the “passive potentiality” which characterizes human nature in relation to that supernatural gift can be called “specific obediential power”—“potentia obedientialis specifica hominis”—or “passive obediential power.” But it remains quite clear, from the explanations he has given us, that for St. Thomas particularly, the simple idea of potentia obedientialis conceived not “to express the condition in which God’s gift places us of being able to become children of God,” but to account for the possibility of miracle, is not adequate as a definition of the relationship of human nature to the supernatural. It does not lay sufficient stress on the “absolutely special case of spirit.”38 Of course, it is true that obediential potency conceived as mere susceptibility to miracle is insufficient with respect to the fittingness of human nature to receive the divine aid (human nature is such that it may be uplifted by grace to the supernatural knowledge and love of God, whereas irrational natures cannot, insofar as irrational, be so aided).Yet it is clear that the common view of de Lubac and Gilson that for Thomas “obediential potency” refers only to the generic susceptibility to divine miracle falls short of Thomas’s text: Only the well-merited reputation of Gilson with respect to other aspects of Thomas’s synthesis, and the incredible depth of de Lubac’s knowledge and love of the Church Fathers, could impart some semblance of life to it. In fact, de Lubac’s above-cited reasoning should 37 Gilson, Letters, 81–82. 38 Henri de Lubac, The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Herder and Herder, 1967), 184–85. 162 Book Symposium have led him to the realization that “obediential potency” was not to be confined to the case of mere generic transmutability.This discovery—to which he is so close in the above-cited text—would necessarily have realigned his account of nature and grace with the commentatorial consensus. For in what would the obediential potency for grace and glory consist, if not in the rational character and in the natural desire for God as distinct from this same desire as supernaturally elevated within the graced desire for beatific vision? In fact, the most conspicuous “modern” defender of the view that Thomas’s notion of obediential potency is not confined to mere transmutability but also extends to “specific obediential power” is Suárez. Compare de Lubac’s contrary view with the express teaching of St. Thomas—the very words to which Gilson supposed the historically inclined were more sensitively disposed than the mere philosophers with their “superficial” and “scholastic” preoccupations (critics of Gilson, too, were waved off by de Lubac as symptomatic of “superficial philosophizing endemic to the Church from the beginning but which has infested Scholasticism since the thirteenth century”).39 St.Thomas writes: When a passive subject is by nature constituted to receive various perfections from diversely ordered agents, the diversity and order of the passive powers in the patient will correspond to the diversity and order of the active powers in the agents, for an active power will correspond to each passive potency. For example, water or earth have some potency whereby they are naturally apt to be changed by fire; and another potency whereby they are naturally apt to be changed by a heavenly body; and still another, whereby they are naturally apt to be moved or changed by God. Just as from water or from earth something can be made by the power of a heavenly body which cannot be made by the power of fire; so, from the same elements something can be formed by the power of a supernatural agent which no natural agent can produce. For this reason we say that in the whole of creation there is a certain obediential potency whereby every creature obeys God by receiving into itself whatsoever God wills.40 39 Gilson, Letters, 110–11, note 10. 40 De Virtutibus, q. 1, a. 10, ad 13: “Ad decimumtertium dicendum, quod quando aliquod passivum natum est consequi diversas perfectiones a diversis agentibus ordinatis, secundum differentiam et ordinem potentiarum activarum in agentibus, est differentia et ordo potentiarum passivarum in passivo; quia potentiae passivae respondet potentia activa: sicut patet quod aqua vel terra habet aliquam potentiam secundum quam nata est moveri ab igne; et aliam secundum quam nata est moveri a corpore caelesti; et ulterius aliam secundum quam nata est moveri a Deo. Sicut enim ex aqua vel terra potest aliquid fieri virtute corporis caelestis, quod non potest fieri virtute ignis; ita ex eis potest aliquid fieri virtute supernaturalis agentis quod non potest fieri virtute alicuius naturalis agentis; et secundum hoc Book Symposium 163 Here one observes St. Thomas affirming that a diverse range of actuation corresponds to the purely passive potency of each nature in relation to a distinct, active agency—including the active agency of God. Hence human nature may be aided by God to act in a fashion that a stone may not be aided. This is the very notion of specific obediential potency—whatever terminology be used to articulate it—and clearly it is neither a Renaissance corruption nor “modern” (unless the middle ages are “modern”). Moreover, this passage manifests that St. Thomas’s well-articulated conception of obediential potency is decidedly not reducible merely to a susceptibility to miraculous transmutation. Susceptibility to miraculous transmutation (as water may be changed to wine by divine agency) may, however, perhaps be described as the most generic and lowest sense of obediential potency: the floor, rather than the ceiling, of the concept. But the specific sense of obediential potency with regard to grace is an aptness of human nature— an aptness that exists only in relation to the active power of God and is simply speaking disproportionate to finite nature—whereby, with divine aid, man may be elevated to supernatural life and to agency meritorious of Heaven. Hence man may be elevated to the higher life of grace and divine friendship, because the spiritual nature is such that with divine aid it may be so uplifted, whereas a rock cannot be uplifted to acts of supernatural knowledge and love precisely because it lacks rational nature. If a rock were uplifted to the divine friendship in knowledge and love of God, it would by that fact cease to be a rock (although there is a wide sense of “love” in which we may say that all creation loves God: But here we are speaking specifically of love as it pertains to rational will). Just as earth and water have diverse passive potencies in relation to different active agencies, so human nature possesses a passive potency for that which can only be achieved in it through the active agency of God. It is this conception of obediential potency that expounds acts of infused virtue as truly acts of the human agent, without thereby implying that human nature can perform supernaturalized acts apart from divine aid. Indeed, properly understood, this doctrine of obediential potency involves the realization that human nature is itself elevated and perfected by God, while the perfection is in substance supernatural and human nature is not even capable of this perfection save in relation to God. Had they but seen, Gilson and de Lubac would have realized that St. Thomas and his commentators were, in their exposition of obediential potency, describing the contours of the very mystery that they themselves dicimus, quod in tota creatura est quaedam obedientialis potentia, prout tota creatura obedit Deo ad suscipiendum in se quidquid Deus voluerit.” 164 Book Symposium sought to understand. For man’s nature is not transmuted but elevated, and so must first be elevable by divine grace: the very meaning of specific obediential potency as opposed to generic obediential potency. Here again one discerns the need not alone for historical erudition, but for scientific penetration of natural distinctions—a cautionary tale for those for whom theology and philosophy have become mere ancillary functions of historical erudition. It is also this conception of obediential potency that most profoundly answers to the language of Vatican II with regard to God “revealing man to himself ” (Gaudium et Spes, note 22). For the higher capacities of man aided by grace are not knowable apart from the gift of grace, yet it is these capacities to which man is called: Human nature is created in sanctifying grace, and the order of nature is efficaciously further ordered in grace (and so if man sins he rebounds, not into a purely natural order, but into an order of nature as accidentally wounded).As I have elsewhere attempted to express this point: The similitude of the stained-glass window illumined by the sun’s rays well bespeaks the character of the doctrine of obediential potency as applied to the relation of nature and grace. The stained-glass window, were it cognizant, could not “know what it was missing” were it never to irradiate its bright colors under the influence of the sun. It would be a window, still, and function as part of the structure—though it would, in a given respect, not be fulfilled. It would be what it is, not fail to be part of the whole structure of which it would form an integral part, nor lack its own participation in the good of the whole as a specific perfection. Yet its nature stands properly revealed only under the extrinsic causality of the sun’s illumination: seeing it so illumined, we know what stained glass truly is for.41 Yet, were one to adopt the more generic conception of obediential potency as its exclusive sense, missing the more specific sense of obediential potency as revealed in passages such as that of St. Thomas from De Virtutibus above, then it would be necessary to reject obediential potency and to deem it wholly inapplicable to man’s elevation in grace and achievement of supernatural beatitude. For just as water transmuted to wine is no longer water, so if obediential potency “in the strict sense” is taken to refer only to miraculous transmutation of nature, it follows that fulfillment of the obediential potency for supernatural life is the transmutation and loss of human nature. Thus would it follow that no human person would be redeemed (for to be redeemed would then mean to lose human nature). 41 “On the Possibility of a Purely Natural End for Man,” The Thomist 64 (2000): 236. Book Symposium 165 This would indeed be an extrinsic and odd conception of grace as destructive of human nature rather than uplifting and redeeming it. Given such a reading of “obediential potency” it follows as a matter of course that one must reject the application of obediential potency to the nature/grace relation. De Lubac and Gilson must be given credit—as manifesting integrity of theological intention—for opposing this sort of monstrosity. They were right that the specter of a generic obediential potency, as though grace came to man not only extrinsically but through supernatural transmutation (like the changing of water to wine), needed to yield to a sense that God’s first creation of human nature made it such as with divine aid to be able to attain to supernatural life and action.Yet these latter words properly describe the conception of specific obediential potency as Thomas applies it to the relation of nature to grace: the very idea that they failed to acknowledge. A good theological intention is not enough: Because everything moves to its end according to its form, the formal account must be adequate. On this score de Lubac and Gilson’s reading of obediential potency appears not only exegetically but theologically erroneous. It is after all St. Thomas Aquinas who writes of supernatural beatitude that “[t]here is another good of man that exceeds the proportion of human nature because the natural powers are not sufficient for attaining, or thinking, or desiring it.”42 If natural powers are of themselves insufficient for desiring the supernatural good that exceeds the proportion of human nature, might not this mean that the natural desire for God is in itself a desire specified not by uncreated nature—which is literally unknowable apart from Revelation—but by that created nature in relation to whose existential dependence the reality of God is discovered? A natural desire for God not qua God but qua Cause of finite being, whereas there is infinitely more in God than being the cause of finite being? A rock cannot know and love God without ceasing to be a rock—it cannot even be “helped” to know and love because it lacks any such faculties that might so be helped.43 By contrast while a human person cannot know and love God in direct vision and embrace without supernatural aid, with such aid the human person may partake in intrinsically supernatural divine friendship: and this is the specific notion of obediential potency as applied to the relation of grace to nature. It is a wholly passive potency that yet presupposes as its subject some determinate nature that 42 De Veritate, q. 14, a. 2. 43 Perhaps there is some way in which the nature of a rock can be distinctively aided by God to radiate glory—but it surely cannot achieve knowledge without an intellective power, nor love in a proper spiritual sense without the rational power of will. 166 Book Symposium is such that when aided by the active agency of God it may achieve a certain specific range of actuation. It is because of man’s essentially spiritual nature that he has an obediential potency to the supernatural life. Thomas even uses the language of a “twofold capacity”—one of nature simply, and one of nature “according to the order of divine power”—to explain the incarnation,“the grace of union which is the greatest grace.”44 Clearly then, the overgeneric and extrinsicist account of obediential potency—which reduces it to the lowest instance of mere capacity for natural transmutation and does not acknowledge specific obediential potency— misses something essential.The fear of extrinsicism harbored by Gilson and de Lubac indifferently targeted both a legitimate object of aversion (the proposition that nothing in man is truly elevated and perfected by grace, so that grace would become a vermiform appendage) and an illegitimate object of aversion (the proposition that supernatural beatitude cannot as such be targeted by a purely natural desire). This fear obstructed their reading of St. Thomas’s text. Yet, since virtually all commentators of St. Thomas’s work preceding them did acknowledge the specific sense of obediential potency applicable to the nature/grace question, it seems that other factors should be discerned as moving them to this undifferentiated preoccupation with the avoidance of extrinsicism (whereas it is not grace as extrinsic principle—for that is what grace is, since grace is not nature— but grace as transmutative principle, that constitutes a deformation of Christian teaching). Clearly, the decisive points were not missed from any ordinary nescience nor from bad will, but rather from a diverted attention preoccupied with profound and necessary theological purpose. It is to the nature of this diversion and that purpose that we now turn. 44 ST III, q. 1, a. 3, ad 3:“A double capability may be remarked in human nature: one, in respect of the order of natural power, and this is always fulfilled by God,Who apportions to each according to its natural capability; the other in respect to the order of the Divine power, which all creatures implicitly obey; and the capability we speak of pertains to this. But God does not fulfill all such capabilities, otherwise God could do only what He has done in creatures, and this is false, as stated above (I, q. 105, a. 6). But there is no reason why human nature should not have been raised to something greater after sin. For God allows evils to happen in order to bring a greater good therefrom; hence it is written (Rm 5:20): ‘Where sin abounded, grace did more abound.’ Hence, too, in the blessing of the Paschal candle, we say:‘O happy fault, that merited such and so great a Redeemer!’ ”While the specific phrase “obediential potency” is not used here, clearly the general idea is congruent with that articulated in De Virtutibus, cf. note 34 above, which undeniably expresses the conception of specific obediential potency.The idea is that of a potency in relation to the divine power “which all creatures implicitly obey”— what is this, but obediential potency? Book Symposium 167 Behind It All: The Loss of Natural Order as a Theonomic Principle It is clear that de Lubac’s reading of Aquinas with respect to obediential potency is erroneous, and that indeed time has only deepened and intensified the consequent divorce of theological formation and method from natural truth (although Pope John Paul II’s Fides et Ratio stands in marked contradiction to this tendency). But likewise it is clear that de Lubac—a great scholar and lover of the Church, blessed with a subtle and powerful intellect—misprised this teaching neither from any common nescience nor from malice. Rather, the need to safeguard a profound theological intention in an inhospitable intellectual climate seemed to point toward the argument that the object of the natural desire for God must be intrinsically supernatural beatific vision.The nature of this animating intention requires greater consideration. No theologian worthy of the name should fail to affirm the theocentric character of reality as such.Yet, from the Enlightenment period on, the view that nature constitutes a separate jurisdiction from divine authority and governance—one utterly separable from the theistic account, and only dubiously related to the truth of the Gospels—gained in influence and prestige.The Enlightenment spawned secular theories of progress, and a reductive naturalism that happily banished the very knowledge of God from the realm of natural truth to one of (at best) a shadowy noumenal existence. Indeed, this tendency is discernibly present today in the insistence of many philosophers and commentators on science that the realm of physical causes must be considered to be “causally closed” and so putatively impermeable to any immaterial cause whatsoever, including God. Kant, Hume, Comte, and in the twentieth century the movements of scientism and positivism, all tended to reduce natural knowledge in such a way as to minimize or seemingly render impossible the project of metaphysical scientia and knowledge of God. Ethics, too, was to be confined within the realm of a secular and non-metaphysical reason alone. Even when theories maintained speculative trajectory or theistic nomenclature, too often the trajectory was immanentist or the terms merely placeholders within doctrines remote from theism and more distant still from traditional Christianity. In this light, one thinks, of course, of Hegel. To make matters worse, however, within Catholic life itself, there had been a gradual but nonetheless crucial disengagement of Catholic theology from the metaphysical realism of St.Thomas Aquinas.The history of this unfortunate and retrograde motion together with the tracing of its speculative influence remains to be written. But it is here that we need 168 Book Symposium pause to recollect the role of Molina in this story. For it is manifest that beginning with Molina’s teaching in the sixteenth century it became acceptable to view free human action as standing outside of divine governance and causality: and this idea is incompatible with the understanding of nature as a theonomic principle.This tendency has only intensified and grown, such that it is frequently the case that when a theologian speaks of “freedom” it is assumed that the proper definition of a cause as contingent or necessary is a function of that cause’s relation to God.That is, it is assumed that to be free a cause must possess liberty of indifference with respect to divine causality. Yet it is the teaching of St. Thomas that no created cause possesses a liberty of indifference with respect to divine causality, and that a cause is denominated as contingent rather than necessary solely owing to its proportion to the contingency of its terrestrial effects. In short, created liberty is not defined in relation to God, but in relation to the nature of the proximate cause. Thus Thomas writes in De malo: And therefore necessity and contingency in things are distinguished not in relation to the divine will, which is a universal cause, but in relation to created causes which the divine will has ordered proportionately to the effects, namely in such a way that the causes of necessary effects are unchangeable, and of contingent effects changeable.45 St.Thomas further articulates the dependence of the created human will on God when he writes: It should be said that when it is said that God left man to himself, this does not mean to exclude man from Divine Providence, but merely that he has not a prefixed operating power determined to one as with natural things; because they are only acted upon as though directed by another towards an end—for they do not act of themselves, directing 45 De malo, q. 16, a. 7, ad 15 (Leonine ed.): “Et hoc quidem quantum ad scientiam patet ex his que supra dicta sunt: sic enim se habet diuina scientia ad futura contingentia sicut se habet oculus noster ad contingentia aue in presenti sunt, ut dictum est; unde sicut certissime uidemus Sortem sedere dumsedet, nec tamen proper hoc sit simpliciter necessarium, ita etiam ex hoc quod Deus uidet omnia que eueniunt in se ipsis, non tollitur contingentia rerum. Ex parte autem uoluntatis considerandum est quod uoluntas diuina est uniuersaliter causa entis et uniuersaliter omnium que consequntur , unde et necessitatis et contingentie; ipsa autem est supra ordinem necessarii et contingentis sicut est supra totum esse creatum. Et ideo necessitas et contingentia in rebus distinguitur non per habitudinem ad uoluntatem diuinam que est causa communis, set per comparationem ad causas creatas, quas proportionaliter diuina uoluntas ad effectus ordinauit, ut scilicet necessariorum effectuum sint cause intransmutabiles, contingentium autem trnasmutabiles.” Book Symposium 169 themselves towards an end, as do rational creatures through free choice whereby these take counsel and make choices. Hence it is significantly said: In the hand of his own counsel. But because the same act of free choice is reduced to God as to a cause, it is necessary that whatsoever happens from the exercise of free choice be subject to Divine Providence. For the providence of man is contained under the providence of God, as a particular cause under a universal cause.46 And, even more clearly: “When anything moves itself, this does not exclude its being moved by another, from which it has even this that it moves itself.Thus it is not repugnant to liberty that God is the cause of the free act of the will.”47 Whereas Molina strove with all his power to do justice to freedom and Providence—falling as it were by accident into the error whereby freedom is defined with respect to God rather than with respect to its finite and contingent effects—it is without doubt true today that the libertarian account of freedom as an absolute capacity outside of the governance of the omnipotent God is prevalent even among believers.Whereas Thomas held that no terrestrial finite good could coerce the will, so that the rational will is free,48 it is common today to suppose that the creature must somehow also be able to stand outside the divine causality for it to be free.Yet this view treats the divine causality like that of a creature, neglecting the dependence of all created reality in being and action upon God. 46 ST I, q. 22, a. 2, ad 4 (Ottawa ed.): “Dicendum quod in hoc quod dicitur Deum hominem sibi reliquisse, non excluditur homo a divina providentia; sed ostenditur quod non praefigitur ei virtus operativa determinata ad unum, sicut rebus naturalibus; quae aguntur tantum, quasi ab altero directae in finem, non autem seipsa agunt, quasi se dirigentia in finem, ut creaturae rationales per liberum arbitrium, quo consiliantur et eligunt. Unde signanter dicit: “In manu consilii sui.” Sed quia ipse actus liberi arbitrii reducitur in Deum sicut in causam, necesse est ut ea quae ex libero arbitrio fiunt, divinae providentiae subdantur; providentia enim hominis continetur sub providentia Dei, sicut causa particularis sub causa universali.” 47 De malo, q. 3, a. 2, ad 4 (Leonine ed.): “Similiter cum aliquid mouet se ipsum, non excluditur quin ab alio moueatur a quo habet hoc ipsum quo se ipsum mouet. Et sic non repugnat libertati quod Deus est causa actus liberi arbitrii.” 48 St.Thomas teaches that the object of the will as a rational appetite is the universal good, the good in general. Since every finite good is a limited good, no finite good is universally good or good in every respect (were it so, it would not be a finite or limited good). It follows that no finite good may coerce the will. Even at the very moment of choice, the intellect presents the finite good to the will as finite, as limited and hence not universally good—as, in some respect, really not good, even if it be not the respect pertinent to our moral fulfillment.Thus, even at the moment of choice, the rational will retains a dominating indifference with respect to any finite good. Cf. ST I, q. 82, a. 2, ad 2. Book Symposium 170 The formulation of Molina has sadly outlived the profound Christian context of his work, which limited the ill effect of this formulation and prevented its worst implications from being drawn. It is certainly true as Molina writes in the Concordia, “that the will is free only when, all requirements being retained, the will could indeed act otherwise”49— provided we refer solely to terrestrial requirements. But if we include the hypothetical but immutable divine will as a requirement, then this proposition is impossible. For, owing to the divine simplicity, it is not God who changes but rather only the world: If God ordains from all eternity that the creature shall freely (in the sense of not coerced by any terrestrial good) choose X, and the creature is moved freely to choose X, what changes is not God but the creature. The creature is really related to, and dependent upon, God, but not vice versa. Between God efficaciously willing a created effect and God not efficaciously willing some created effect, the sole difference is that the efficaciously willed effect actually is.Thus one cannot retain the requirement that God cause the creature freely to act while the creature is not caused freely to act because this is a contradiction in terms. The Molinist account unwittingly carries the implication that the domain of human action is outside Divine Providence insofar as outside divine causality.Thomas makes the connection quite patent in the Summa theologiae I–II, question 91, article 2, teaching that since all things subject to Divine Providence are ruled and measured by the eternal law, as was stated above (I–II, a. 90, q. 1); it is evident that all things partake somewhat of the eternal law, in so far as, namely, from its being imprinted on them, they derive their respective inclinations to their proper acts and ends. The implication here is not that there is some recondite class of things which are not subject to Divine Providence while still being ruled and measured by eternal law. Rather, if the human will is not subject to Divine Providence, then it is not ruled and measured by the eternal law. As Thomas teaches, providence extends so far as power:50 he will cannot be subject to Divine Providence if it lies outside divine causality. Hence, if we affirm a theonomic conception of natural law, we need also to affirm that the human will is autonomous neither in being nor in action, but is moved to its act from without, yet in such a manner that this motion is truly its own motion: which is to say that the very motion that 49 Cf. Molina’s Concordia, q. 14, a. 13, disp. II. 50 See ST I, q. 22, a. 2. Book Symposium 171 is received by the will from God is that whereby it moves itself in free self-determination. Like existence itself, the positive substance of my action is most my own, yet also most a gift. In Molina the emphasis is upon scientia media or middle knowledge— the doctrine that God knows all the varied circumstances in the light of which the creature will act or not act—a teaching that some critics speak of as a determinism of circumstance.51 For why should circumstances alter how one would be inclined to act unless they exercise some causality, a causality seemingly denied to God by the Molinist account. Why then should what is denied to God be attributed to finite circumstances? But it is in any case not this aspect of his teaching that has prevailed. What is arresting about the Molinist account is not the emphasis on circumstance, which is but an ineffective brake placed on the turning of the wheel, but the logic of the turning of the wheel itself, in the direction of separating human agency from divine causality. And indeed, this is the effect that Molinism seems concretely to have had—not to move people to accept scientia media, which seems fraught with contradiction, but to move toward the rejection of the subjection of human agency to divine causality.Apart from the question of Molina’s full theological position, his negative treatment of the dependence of human freedom on divine causality seems in historical terms to be one large stride in the direction of undifferentiated libertarianism of a sort that implies that the created will is a being a se. What thus ensues in the common imagination as well as in ensuing academic interpretations is an immense and insupportable freedom—as though the finite creature were characterized by a divine aseity of will. A separate jurisdiction of human liberty is thus created that is literally beyond divine governance, so that it becomes difficult to imagine what difference even divine Revelation could make to the situation—for why should a will whose act is a se to require or seek aid of any kind? If its act is a se, it follows that its being is a se (operatio sequitur esse). And a being a se is intrinsically independent of every other being—the very logic whereby God is affirmed to be intrinsically independent of any created cause.52 51 In the twentieth century, one thinks of the extensive criticism offered by Norbert del Prado, De Gratia et Libero Arbitrio, 3 vols. (Friburgi Helvetiorum: Ex Typis Consociationis Sancti Pauli, 1907) and Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, God: His Existence and His Nature, 2 vols., trans. Dom Bede Rose (St. Louis: Herder, 1934). 52 The idea that the separation of freedom from providential government could be accepted without its implications being harvested has proven deficient. Granted that the idea of the directive authority of natural law is chiefly cognitive, still for such directive authority to be even potentially effective it is a necessary condition that the finite agent be susceptible of direction. But if the finite agent’s will is 172 Book Symposium Hence intra-Catholic meditations on freedom as well as philosophic tendencies rooted in the Enlightenment each carved out a dominion for natural human agency as absolutely independent of God.The convergent effect is that of secular and intra-Catholic tendencies of thought each of which tend toward making the natural realm—and particularly the natural realm of human agency—an utterly separate jurisdiction sealed off from Providence. In this light, the continued insistence upon the nature/grace distinction could seem to be an insistence upon maintaining an artificial and destructive divorce between God and the world, and a fortiori between God and the human world. Within such a world, natural law, far from being what it was for St.Thomas—namely, nothing other than the rational participation of the eternal law—becomes instead the demarcation of a realm outside the governance of the eternal law. Natural law becomes, as it were, the “stalking horse” of secularism and naturalist reductionism. A more complete inversion of the character of the doctrine of the natural law cannot be imagined—indeed a transvaluation of all values. Even more arresting is that these two complementary motions retreating from the theonomic character of nature and natural order end by insisting on similar judgments. The advocate of absolute autonomy for the rational creature must deny the subjection of man’s will to divine causality and Providence—ruling out the “interference” of God with a will either supposed to be purely in act or else mysteriously able to move itself from potency to act without first receiving this motion from God. Likewise, the contemporary physicalist or materialist advocate of “causal closure” amongst physical causes must deny the subjection of any physical agency whatsoever to the higher causality of God. Hence the physicalist or materialist also must rule out the “interference” of God with the natural world and with the nature of human agency. In one case the motive is the preservation of absolute freedom; in the other case, the motive is the preservation of causal closure (and, for some authors, absolute necessity) not only independent vis-à-vis all merely terrestrial causality but stands outside of divine causality as well, then it follows that the finite agent’s willing is a se and so not susceptible to governance by any extrinsic agent. Thus we end with the temper tantrum construed as a metaphysical principle, with an incapacity on the part of the modern and postmodern to receive directive governance in the moral, social, and political orders, and with a fixed strategic resistance of governance with respect to the supernatural life itself.This shows itself not merely in antinomian glosses on natural law (for example, one notes Bernard Häring and Josef Füchs), but in the supposition that the Church must, herself, accommodate the absolute requisites of ecclesial communion to the a priori supremacy of pluralism and autonomy: an insistence in reason impossible yet socially widespread and hardly unknown even within the Church. Book Symposium 173 amongst exclusively physical causes. One may well note that it seems that for Kant both of these motivations simultaneously hold sway—the categories of phenomenal necessitation just as much as the nature of human freedom require the denial of any knowable providential government of world and will. But in either case, the effect is the same: the banishing of God from the natural world and especially from the natural world of human agency.53 What was to be Henri de Lubac’s response to the distinction of nature from grace as it functioned within the anomalous context of the exile of God from the natural world and from the nature of human agency? Reading the de Lubac of The Drama of Atheist Humanism, it becomes perfectly clear that he was well acquainted with antitheism and the banishing of God from history through the unreasoning exaltation of matter, or will, or reason. He was also intimately aware of the dilemma of human freedom in a world that, like a mausoleum, enclosed its inhabitants in a lofty and impenetrable solitude or, alternately, offered release solely through alienating extroversion. To a Christian man of such profound vision and cultural sensitivity as well as historical awareness, it cannot have been other than ravishingly tempting utterly to contradict the naturalist reduction with one working in a different and Christian direction, asserting a natural desire for intrinsically supernatural beatitude. The dynamism of man, himself, would be taken not only as pointed ad Deo but as aspirationally projected within the Triune life of God Himself.54 Neither positivism nor 53 It is also possibly pertinent that Molina strongly influenced the thought of many of his brethren within the Society of Jesus, which historically has been associated with some measure of support for the Molinist account. It may not be wholly accidental that the effort to reinstate the theonomic character of nature by supernaturalizing the natural telos should derive from a gifted and creative theologian formed within this order and sensitive to the onset of naturalism. 54 Of course, de Lubac would have denied that the natural desire for God—which he took to be a desire for supernatural beatitude—had any psychological corollary whatsoever. Nonetheless, if to aspire is to seek to attain a goal, then quite literally de Lubac’s position must countenance that the voluntas ut natura aspires to supernatural beatitude whether this has a psychological correlate or not. It is this position itself that, the Thomist will discern, defines the created nature as deific by skipping over the proximate and natural end altogether. Of course, there is also the question whether it makes sense that so profound a metaphysical orientation as de Lubac claimed for the will can be intelligible in the absence of any psychological correlate—especially inasmuch as movement of the will is depicted as follows by St. Thomas (Quaestiones Quadlibetales, quodlibet VI, q. 2, a. 2): “motus voluntatis est inclinatio sequens formam intellectam.”That is, it is impossible that there be any natural volition that is not first specified by intellect, and this natural specification is necessarily infinitely less than that which specifies the intellect 174 Book Symposium scientism nor any of the other “isms” seeking to confine man within the terrestrial cage and to reduce the human mystery to a problem of naturalist flow-dynamics would gain any purchase over this starting point for the Christian apologetic, for this apologetic would be nothing other than the answer to the question “What is man?” In the face of such crushing cultural, ideological, and philosophic adversity, the distinctions contemplated and honed within baroque scholasticism—that Revelation reveals man to himself with respect to his deeper destiny in grace, but not primarily or properly with respect to human nature as such (of which one has connatural awareness and potential natural wisdom) but rather medicinally—could hardly seem decisive. Against the antitheists—Marx, Nietzsche, and the rest—de Lubac would rely upon teleology. Almost alone amidst contemporaries for whom teleology defined nothing, de Lubac would overstress teleology, making of the finis ultimus of intrinsically supernatural beatific vision the very natural end of man, and denying that human nature is placed in its species— as Aquinas expressly asserts that it is—by its natural and proportionate end as distinct from the supernatural beatific end.55 The convergent implication of secular and Molinist thought seems indeed to be the loss of nature and natural order as theonomic principles, and the loss of natural law as nothing else than a participation of eternal law. Once this theonomic character of natural order and natural law are lost, then sustaining the distinction of nature and grace simply formalizes the boundaries consequent upon the loss of God. One may say safely, from this repose of distance in time, that de Lubac was correct in seeking the answer in teleology, and correct again in seeking an answer that would once more establish the theonomic character of natural order. While he was incor- in beatific vision. It follows that all natural willing is only distributively rather than simultaneously universal, and that likewise all natural willing is specified by created realities. God ineluctably is then to be known and desired as “Cause of finite effects”; and while for St. Thomas “each power desires by the natural appetite that object which is suitable to itself ” (ST I, q. 80, a. 1, ad 3), what is suitable to the will is the intelligible good in general.The universal good is the aspect under which the will desires whatever it seeks, but it is no more to be identified with the universal subsistent Good in God than the befitting adequate object of the intellect as universal being is to be confused with the being of God: as though the metaphysician seeking to study being qua being were, by that fact and in precision from grace, naturally seeking the beatific vision. 55 Once again, one notes texts such as Quaestiones de anima, a. 7, ad 10; and ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1, remembering such texts of de Lubac, for example, as the fourth chapter of The Mystery of the Supernatural (see note 7 above). Book Symposium 175 rect in supposing that natural teleology in itself could be shoehorned into or equated with a supernatural trajectory, it was precisely his instinct that the theonomic character of nature needed to be preserved that led him to attempt this defense in a manner that unwittingly falsifies nature itself. This turning of nature into a vacuole fit only for supernatural beatitude even apart from grace and Revelation paradoxically completed the ontological evacuation of nature to which de Lubac was in part responding. Perhaps this is the clearest theological instance of “destroying the village in order to save it”—but it still does not constitute a sufficient answer to the negation of the theonomic character of natural law and, more widely, of natural order. It also manifests a lack of that radical providentialist trust in the specifically natural that demarcates the theological vision of St. Thomas from those who are prone to assume that the natural in its own right must be a zone without the divine governance and so needing to be as theologically minimized as possible. That is, it manifests despair in seeking to reachieve the theonomic character of natural order by draining the natural of its own distinctive finality and intelligibility. It is not the first time that a physician unintentionally has communicated the plague he nobly sought to resist. The persistent refusal to see the limited but dignified fashion in which not only all creation, but man specifically, is naturally ordered to God, is explicable only within a context wherein it has already been decided as an initial postulate that sublunary natural order has no efficacy or essential role within theological method. But all of creation is ordered ad Deo, and man naturally desires God as Cause and Principle of finite nature—a natural desire that is not by its essence formally a desire for supernatural beatific vision. Rather it is a real but limited created dynamism toward God as Cause of finite being, reflective of that spiritual dignity in man that constitutes a potency of obedience for what God may bring forth through his grace. Nonetheless, if one’s project is to cut short the very possibility of rationalist misconstrual of nature as a separate and absolutely autonomous jurisdiction; if one is wary of the distinct character of the natural within the theological synthesis; and if one stands historically downstream from the abandonment of St. Thomas’s doctrine of providence, then the hotwiring of nature to grace becomes all too alluring. That a correct judgment of the relation of nature to God is required by theology itself—such that error here is liable thoroughly and in multifarious ways to denature theology—may quickly appear of secondary importance by comparison with safeguarding the pertinence of Revelation in an increasingly naturalist world. It is ironic that the very medicine actually required for this latter purpose—the purpose of safeguarding the 176 Book Symposium pertinence of Revelation from the irrelevance to which naturalism would consign it—is itself principally a function of the truth regarding the relation of nature and grace. One grants that at the moment of the composition of Surnaturel, it must have seemed—for contingent yet pressing reasons—unlikely that Thomism would prove up to the challenge posed by the cultural confluence of Catholic and secular tendencies promoting the autonomy of nature and of human agency from God. In fact, insofar as elements of Thomas’s synthesis persisted in riding the waves long after the strategic rejections of divine providential governance of human agency and of theistic metaphysics had occurred, these might appear as of merely residual importance.Worse, the distinction of nature and grace might then be construed simply as formalizing the evacuation of God from creation: a wall of demarcation excluding God from the world. But the evisceration of the richness of created human nature guarantees an eviscerated theology. A small error in the beginning is a large one in the end. And the loss of the theonomic character of natural order and law in its own right and not merely by analogy of attribution with supernatural order is an error of decisive importance. Far from natural truth constituting a metaphysical Berlin Wall keeping man in, and God out, of man’s world, such truth is by its own character essentially ordered toward God. By its own character, that is, as naturally ordered toward God with all the limits this suggests—that is, nature is essentially ordered toward God, but is not of itself ordered toward supernatural beatitude. It is against these natural limits that the sublimity of the supernatural becomes manifest. The grandeur of man’s supernatural calling reveals the higher end and acts of which human nature is capable with the assistance of grace, revealing these loftiest capacities and perfections of man so aided to himself. Dostoevsky’s Grand Inquisitor is wrong in picturing human natural desire as essentially antagonistic to God in Christ, albeit this famous literary image is compelling as a depiction of sinful nature. But distinct from supernatural charity is natural love, and Thomas rightly affirms that man by natural love loves God above himself insofar as natural love—with which man is created—is not perverse: The good we receive from God is twofold, the good of nature, and the good of grace. Now the fellowship of natural goods bestowed on us by God is the foundation of natural love, in virtue of which not only man, so long as his nature remains unimpaired, loves God above all things and more than himself, but also every single creature, each in its own way, that is either by an intellectual, or by a rational, or by an animal, Book Symposium 177 or at least by a natural love, as stones do, for instance, and other things bereft of knowledge, because each part naturally loves the common good of the whole more than its own particular good.This is evidenced by its operation, since the principal inclination of each part is towards common action conducive to the good of the whole. It may also be seen in civic virtues whereby sometimes the citizens suffer damage even to their own property and persons for the sake of the common good.Wherefore much more is this realized with regard to the friendship of charity which is based on the fellowship of the gifts of grace.56 Natural love is not perverse, it prefers God to self, and it is essentially inferior to supernatural charity.To cite St.Thomas again to this effect, he writes: Accordingly, since God is the universal good, and under this good both man and angel and all creatures are comprised because every creature in regard to its entire being naturally belongs to God, it follows that from natural love angel and man alike love God before themselves and with greater love. Otherwise, if either of them loved self more than God, it would follow that natural love would be perverse, and that it would not be perfected but destroyed by charity.57 Elsewhere St.Thomas makes clear that the restoration of natural love after sin requires grace: in the state of integral nature man did not need the gift of grace added to his natural endowments in order to love God above all things naturally, although he needed God’s help moving him to it; but in the state 56 ST II–II, q. 26, a. 3: “Respondeo dicendum quod a Deo duplex bonum accipere possumus, scilicet bonum naturae, et bonum gratiae. Super communicatione autem bonorum naturalium nobis a Deo facta fundatur amor naturalis, quo non solum homo in suae integritate naturae super omnia diligit Deum et plus quam seipsum, sed etiam quaelibet creatura suo modo, idest vel intellectuali vel rationali vel animali, vel saltem naturali amore, sicut lapides et alia quae cognitione carent, quia unaquaeque pars naturaliter plus amat commune bonum totius quam particulare bonum proprium. Quod manifestatur ex opere, quaelibet enim pars habet inclinationem principalem ad actionem communem utilitati totius.Apparet etiam hoc in politicis virtutibus, secundum quas cives pro bono communi et dispendia propriarum rerum et personarum interdum sustinent. Unde multo magis hoc verificatur in amicitia caritatis, quae fundatur super communicatione donorum gratiae.” 57 ST I, q. 60, a. 5: “Quia igitur bonum universale est ipse Deus, et sub hoc bono continetur etiam Angelus et homo et omnis creatura, quia omnis creatura naturaliter, secundum id quod est, Dei est; sequitur quod naturali dilectione etiam Angelus et homo plus et principalius diligat Deum quam seipsum. Alioquin, si naturaliter plus seipsum diligeret quam Deum, sequeretur quod naturalis dilectio esset perversa; et quod non perficeretur per caritatem, sed destrueretur.” 178 Book Symposium of corrupted nature, man needs, even for this, the help of grace healing his nature.58 Yet the significant point here is that sin itself is defined as deprivation visà-vis the theonomic role of nature, and that restoration of the natural love is only part—and the lesser part—of the effect of the redemption. Indeed, paradoxically, the attainment of the natural end will require medicinal grace, but not because it is itself supernatural, but because nature is itself further ordered in grace from its creation and is thus harmed by the loss of grace. For the restoration of natural integrity and rectitude forms part of a loftier motion that rises past the merely natural proximate end to the finis ultimus of supernatural beatitude. And thus—because to desire, know, and love God as principle of all being is something quite different than to desire, know, and love God as object of supernatural beatitude—Thomas writes that: “[I]t must therefore be said that to love God as the principle of all being pertains to natural love, but to love God as the object of beatitude pertains to the gratuitous love in which merit consists.”59 Conclusion: The Protean Implications If our aim is countering the loss of the normativity of nature as a theonomic principle, the first impulse of de Lubac—the prime resort to teleology—is condign, but this resort must be to genuinely natural teleology as conditioning our reception of Revelation. For this natural conditioning, like the preparation of Israel by the prophets, is part of the divine economy itself and not something alien or extrinsic to the divine governance. Yet this in itself will not avail for so long as the realm of nature—and especially the realm of human agency—is supposed to be a separate jurisdiction immunized and utterly independent from providential government. For the loss of natural order as a theonomic concept that transpires upon the subtraction of human agency from divine order is an irreplaceable loss. Consequently, the greatest need of contemporary thought is to rediscover the theonomic character of natural law, and more extendedly of natural order as such—which will require a vigorous return to meta58 ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3:“Et ideo dicendum est quod homo in statu naturae integrae non indigebat dono gratiae superadditae naturalibus bonis ad diligendum Deum naturaliter super omnia; licet indigeret auxilio Dei ad hoc eum moventis. Sed in statu naturae corruptae indiget homo etiam ad hoc auxilio gratiae naturam sanantis.” 59 Quod. I, q. 4, a. 3, ad 1: “Ad primum ergo dicendum, quod diligere Deum prout est principium totius esse, ad naturalem dilectionem pertinet; sed diligere Deum prout est obiectum beatitudinis, est gratuitae dilectionis, in qua meritum consistit.” Book Symposium 179 physics, natural theology, and ontology of nature. The natural character of—and need for—metaphysics as sapiential science is thus exhibited. Such a project is in all frankness a great and perhaps overmastering challenge for an age in which philosophers have preponderantly retreated to logical and linguistic preoccupations remote from nature, whilst many theologians drift in historicist or textual currents seemingly permanently outside the orbit of reference to natural order or, alternately, dwell within intricate dialectical fictions. The perhaps unintended radicalization of de Lubac’s position itself by prominent and distinguished theological minds;60 60 One notes the work of David Schindler, who has at least on occasion suggested that nature is objectively undefinable apart from grace. This is rather a different proposition than to say that medicinal grace is needed—owing to the Fall—in order to attain the proximate natural end that is indeed naturally knowable, or even than the proposition that medicinal grace may be needed by some to cognize that which is nonetheless objectively defined in precision from grace. Cf. David Schindler, “Christology, Public Theology, and Thomism: de Lubac, Balthasar, and Murray,” in The Future of Thomism, ed. Deal W. Hudson and Dennis W. Moran (Notre Dame, IN: American Maritain Association, 1992), 253–54, note 9.Yet one also notes this author’s arguments stressing the metaphysical principle of form with respect to the dangers of reductionism in genetic engineering, in which he strongly affirms the proportionate natural principles without that objective reference to revelation that one would think necessary were it true that nature is indefinable apart from grace. See his “A Response to the Joint Statement ‘Production of Pluripotent Stem Cells by Oocyte Assisted Reprogramming,’ ” Communio 32 (2005). With respect to the radicalization of de Lubac’s position, one also thinks of theologians in the East. For example, see the work of John D. Zizioulas, whose bibliography includes two books and some sixty articles published in a variety of languages. His main publication, L’Etre ecclésial (Geneva: Labor et Fides, 1981), is a collection of six previously published articles; the English edition, Being as Communion (London: Darton, Longmann and Todd, 1985), is somewhat modified to include later materials. Zizioulas now serves as an Orthodox bishop. In his theology, being and history outside of Christ are so unintelligible that philosophy as a purely rational investigation seems capable of holding little of worth for the Christian believer. Paul McPartlan wrote a thesis, The Eucharist Makes the Church: Henri de Lubac and John Zizioulas in Dialogue (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1993), comparing Zizioulas’s theology of the Church with that of Henri de Lubac, noting a certain degree of convergence. Zizioulas argues that Latin theology as manifest in the teaching of popes, councils, and bishops, fails to appreciate the radically relational and existential character of creation renewed in Christ, causing consequent deformations with respect to participation in the Eucharist and understanding of the mystery of the Church.The similarity of such reasoning with the radical view that the creature is a subsistent relation—something properly predicable of the Divine Persons of the Trinity alone, but which certain eminent scholars assert with respect to the created human person—is doctrinally remarkable. See, for example, the work of W. Norris Clarke, Person and Being (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press,1993), 180 Book Symposium the widespread despair of natural truth regarding God, the soul, and the moral life, proceeding from the distinct sources of nihilism, fideism, and rationalism; the substitution of ungrounded and relativized dialectics, historicist reflections, textualism, or logicism for metaphysics, natural teleology, and ontology of nature; and the danger (to which the Church has responded in Dominus Iesus) that the relativized dialectical context may go so far as to infect the concrete affirmation of the mysteries of faith itself; the radical miscasting of the doctrine of natural law outside of its proper theistic context; and the more or less ideologized movements resulting from the vacuum of teaching: All this constitutes an enormous welter of danger and confusion. It is tempting to outline the most conspicuous errors and challenges— proceeding from the evacuation of natural norms within theology—within each of the component disciplines of theology and philosophy itself, as well as within the more general life of the Church and of society. Such an undertaking would constitute a project to itself, and doubtless one worthy of the effort in detailing the disorientations consequent on the theological retreat from nature. Such a list might include: a causal role in engendering fideist, rationalist, and nihilist impulses; excessive autonomism in ethics (and, implicitly, in philosophic anthropology); the divorce of the practical from the speculative to which it is naturally wedded (for naturally speaking, all knowing has a speculative component, with practical knowing adding only a relation to action and so a distinct end);61 the loss of unified teleology and of the material continuity of natural proximate end with the supernatural end (God as principle and cause of nature as distinct from as alike his essay “Person, Being, and St. Thomas” in Communio 19 (1992); and Kenneth Schmitz, “The First Principle of Personal Becoming,” Review of Metaphysics 47 (1994), together with my criticism, Steven Long, “Personal Receptivity and Act: A Thomistic Critique,” The Thomist 61 (1997); and his answer “Created Receptivity,” 339–72, published with my brief “Reply,” 373–76, alongside in The Thomist 61 (1997). 61 One notes the following illustrative lines about this from De Veritate, q. 2, a. 8, which also track Aquinas’s more forthright definitions of the speculative and practical elsewhere—but the formulation here is arresting: “But the knowledge that an artist has about something that can be made is of two kinds: speculative and practical. He has speculative or theoretical knowledge when he knows the intimate nature of a work but does not have the intention of applying the principles to the production of the work. His knowledge is practical, properly speaking, when by his intention he ordains the principles of the work to operation as an end. In this way, as Avicenna says, medicine is divided into theoretical and practical. It is clear that the practical knowledge of an artist follows his speculative knowledge, since it is made practical by applying the speculative to a work. But when the practical is absent, the speculative remains.” [Emphasis added.] Book Symposium 181 God as revealing himself in supernatural beatitude); the denial that God is necessary to the doctrine of natural law; a certain desacramentalization of nature; the epistemic radicalization of de Lubac’s position represented by the claim that nature is utterly unknowable in precision from Revelation;62 and the kindred claim that the treatise De Deo uno is not presupposed by and necessary to the treatise De Deo trino. This last thesis—that the treatise on the One God is not presupposed by and necessary to the treatise on the Triune God—is embraced by many genuinely Catholic scholars. Nonetheless it truly represents theology walking off into thin air: as though the Revelation of God in Christ does not invite and presuppose a natural doctrine of God as a condition for the intelligibility of the truth that Christ is God.When we affirm that Christ is God and man, the obvious question is, Quid sit Deus? The effort either to resituate this query, or—at the worst—to suppress it, seems not to be a theological effort, albeit it might be construed as theoplastic: yet another sign of the loss of nature as a normative principle within theology. That no theologian would wish to stop with natural theology, or to lose the sense of its continuity with the mysteries of faith within the providential synthesis of Revelation and grace, is perfectly reasonable. But that one should wish to subtract the natural ordering of creation to God from the inception of theology, or to treat the doctrine of God this implies as though it were not methodically presupposed by and necessary to revealed theology, indicates misalignment in one’s understanding of nature and grace, and perhaps also with respect to the humble epistemic roots of man’s contact with the real.The first creation is presupposed by and taken up within the contemplation of the new creation in grace: It is not a separate dead residue from which revealed theology can happily detach itself without losing both divine and human nature.To use a hallowed but valid formula (De Veritate II, q. 14, a. 9, ad 8):“grace presupposes nature.” One might also include in the list of consequences of the loss of natural order as a theonomic principle the loss of regard for principled conformity to the moral teaching of the Church as necessary for ecclesial communion and participation in the sacramental life of the Church. For the moral law dissociate from eternal law is construed as a zone of absolute personal autonomy, and nature so dissociate no longer yields connatural certitudes but merely more or less provisional “points of view.” Here the evacuation of nature and the dissociation of natural from eternal law keep pace, pari passu, yielding a conclusion so antinomian as to leave nothing standing of the Catholic sense of the moral life. Even the most crass and 62 Cf. note 60 above. 182 Book Symposium destructive type of autonomy often is defended as compatible with communion with the Church (witness those for whom no degree of dissent—even regarding the wrongful homicide of millions of innocent unborn children—is sufficient to warrant exclusion from the sacraments). Yet the supernatural unity of the Church is not the unity of mere wellwishing and social fellowship, it is a supernatural society, participation in whose source and summit—the eucharistic sacrifice—presupposes conformity to the teaching of the Church and places one within an order of governance (and that not merely canonic, but substantive). Indifference to the Church’s doctrine of faith and morals displayed by persons and groups who then elevate and honor contingent issues of social prudence and party politics to the same level argues both a grotesque lack of assimilation to the supernatural life in Christ and a serious confusion between natural social assimilation to a secular group and abandonment to God and his Church. Yet doubtless the path to transcend these doctrinal difficulties and errors, so as to achieve an organic development of Catholic life and doctrine, is illumined by the instruction of papal encyclicals such as Pope John Paul II’s Fides et Ratio and Veritatis Splendor. This same path is also highlighted by works of retrieving scholarship such as Dr. Feingold has given us in The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters. It is profoundly highlighted in the work of de Lubac himself, the whole purpose of whose controversial account of nature and grace was to affirm the theonomic character of natural order albeit at the cost of a certain confusedly volatile conflation of supernatural and natural dynamisms.The judgment that this path is erroneous because it denies the distinct manner in which created natural order is theonomic does nothing whatsoever to negate the ineluctability of the prior judgment: the judgment that the theonomic character of natural order needs strongly and effectively to be reaffirmed. In this sense, the most important element of the teleology of de Lubac’s own account truly is achieved (to be sure, in a radically distinct way) in the doctrine of St. Thomas Aquinas and of the Thomistic commentatorial tradition that de Lubac critically misapprehended. It is of course true that the medicinal grace that restores natural integrity also to some degree enables the assent of faith to compensate for the absence of the knowledge of natural truths.Yet clearly what may be known in service to theological contemplation, ought to be known.The tendencies that elsewise may be expected to hold sway and fill the vacuum in the realm of thought, culture, and sensibility are either unhelpful or positively harmful to the task of explicating and promoting Christian life. Book Symposium 183 It is perhaps the final salute that a Thomist owes to the efforts of de Lubac on this score to see to it that the chief effect of emending his error about the natural desire for God is not merely to throw us back to the status quo ante. For that status quo ante already was deeply marred and impaired by the grievous attrition of the tradition’s emphasis upon nature as a normative principle in theology—a theonomic principle—and the consequent harboring in germinus of the praxeological obsessions and autonomist tendencies that became the chief divagations of the postconciliar era. Rather—if truth is holographic—the task is to see to it that the shards of right reason are reunited within a rich and realistic metaphysic translucent to the further ordering of grace and Revelation, and at the service of sacra doctrina. Such a treatment—clarifying the manner in which human nature with divine aid may achieve supernatural friendship and beatific fruition, and bringing all creation into the service and under the dominion of Christ—is a fitting response to an error whose doubtless genuine and profound theological motivation it more truly fathoms N&V and fulfills. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 185–198 185 Lonergan on the Natural Desire in the Light of Feingold G UY M ANSINI , OSB Saint Meinrad Seminary Saint Meinrad, Indiana T HIS ESSAY will measure Bernard Lonergan’s understanding of the natural desire to see God asserted by St.Thomas against that provided by Lawrence Feingold.1 Feingold does not refer to Lonergan. Fr. Lonergan’s treatment of the natural desire has been important for many North American theologians, however.2 Moreover, it has recently received renewed and detailed attention from Michael Stebbins.3 Feingold finds the structure of the issues surrounding the natural desire to see God in three questions, where the answer to the first governs the answer to the second, and the answer to the second that of the third. First, is the desire to see God innate or elicited? Second, is it a conditional or an unconditional desire? Third, is it probative of the possibility of seeing God, and even of the actual offer by God of that end, or not? 1 Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Rome: Apollinare Studi, 2001). 2 See principally (1) Bernard Lonergan, SJ, De Ente Supernaturali. Supplementum schematicum, ed. Frederick E. Crowe (Toronto: Regis College, 1973), thesis IV, scholion I, “De naturali desiderio videndi Deum per essentiam,” 35–42, which first appeared in 1946 and without knowledge of the Surnaturel; (2) in the appendix to the De ente, note to section 83, 84–85, added 1951–52; (3) idem, “The Natural Desire to See God,” in Collection, ed. Frederick E. Crowe (New York: Herder, 1967), 84–95, first published in 1949; and (4) two short book reviews, the first, idem, review of The Eternal Quest by William R. O’Connor, Theological Studies 9 (1948): 125–27; and the second, idem, review of Man’s Last End by Joseph Buckley, Theological Studies 10 (1949): 578–80. 3 J. Michael Stebbins, The Divine Initiative: Grace,World-Order, and Human Freedom in the Early Writings of Bernard Lonergan (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1995), 142–82. Book Symposium 186 Answers are related as follows. If the desire is innate, an inclination of the will or the nature itself, a preconscious inclining and tending to quidditative knowledge of God that is prior to knowledge, then the desire is also unconditional and absolute.4 Further, if the desire is unconditional, an absolute inclination of the nature itself, then the vision of God will certainly be possible and more, it will be the actual destiny to which humanity is ordered, for it will be debitum naturae.5 On the other hand, if the desire is not innate but elicited, a conscious desire of the will that follows upon the knowledge that God exists, then although naturally following from the innate desire of intellect to know the causes and principles of reality, it will, apart from faith, be an imperfect desire, as for an object beyond the proportion of the human way of knowing, and so a conditional desire, as for something impossible to attain by our own active powers. Further, if the desire is elicited and conditional, it can at most indicate the fittingness that man see God, but not demonstrate its possibility and much less its actuality as the destiny God ordains for us. Let us turn to Lonergan, and begin with the third question, the probative value of the desire to see God.A very quick reading of his texts would tell us that the natural desire to see God is not probative of the possibility of vision, much less of its actual offer.6 As for the second question, we would gather that the fulfillment of the desire is conditioned on freely given supernatural helps of grace and the supernatural virtues, not to speak of the light of glory.7 Further, the potency for fulfillment of the desire is obediential, and so by definition is conditioned on the divine will to elevate man to the supernatural order.8 Should we expect to read in Lonergan and in conformity with Feingold’s analysis that therefore the desire to see God is an elicited and imperfect desire, however, we will be disappointed. Rather, according to Lonergan, the desire is very explicitly not an elicited desire but an innate desire, an innate tendency, and one moreover not of the will, but of the intellect.9 It is the desire or inclination or 4 Feingold, Natural Desire, 23. 5 Ibid., 25. 6 Lonergan, De Ente, 40, no. 78. 7 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 86. 8 Lonergan, De Ente, 36, nos. 69–70; 38–38, no. 75. 9 Stebbins, Divine Initiative, 151–52: For Lonergan, the “natural” of the “natural desire,” in addition to being set off from the supernatural, “conveys the notion of something that ‘is opposed not to the supernatural but to the elicited: that is, it is not an act elicited in an appetitive potency but is the very order of the potency to act, the natural tendency of the potency itself.’ ” Stebbins here translates De Ente, 35, no. 67.According to Feingold, by contrast, the “natural” of the “natural desire” is to be set off not from the elicited (and not only from the supernatural), but from Book Symposium 187 tendency of the intellect just as such.10 “There exists a natural desire to understand. . . .This natural desire extends to understanding God.”11 So for the second and third questions, we must have read Lonergan too rapidly. Let us go more slowly. For the third question, no, the natural desire for the vision of God is not probative of the possibility of vision, but more, the desire cannot even be known unless we know the actual ordination of man to vision by faith.12 The conclusion that there is a natural desire of the intellect to see God, Lonergan says, “is theological,” and “can be thought only because one has the faith, knows the fact of the beatific vision, and so must accept its possibility.”13 According to Feingold’s Thomas, to the contrary, the desire is known because elicited, and so available to our consciousness of our own acts, as soon as we know the existence of the First Cause.14 To be sure, Lonergan reports Summa theologiae I, question 12, article 8, according to which St. Thomas teaches us that, knowing the existence of God, we want naturally to know what he is. But this conscious and elicited desire to know the essence of God is for Lonergan but a “corollary” of what the “natural desire” really refers to, namely, the inclination of intellect itself.15 the deliberated; it is a desire elicited necessarily, immediately, and without discursive reasoning upon the knowledge that God exists, as opposed to an elicited desire that does follow upon a process of reasoning; see Feingold, Natural Desire, chs. 2 and 3, esp. 63, and 319–21 (Sylvester of Ferrara). 10 Lonergan, De Ente, 36, nos. 68–69; 37, no. 71: the natural desire of the intellect is the “tendentia intellectus in quaerendum et sciendum,” but “antecedit haec tendentia omnem explicitam quaestionem”; ibid., 37, no. 72:“exsistit tendentia intellectus humani in quidditatem Dei cognoscendam, in ipsum Deum intelligendum.” 11 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 87. It was Durandus of St. Pourçain who first characterized the desire to see God as an innate tendency of the intellect; see Feingold, Natural Desire, 147, 321, and see 634–35, note 8, for moderns who embrace this position. Remember, for Scotus the natural desire to see God is an innate desire of the will, not the intellect. See Lonergan’s review of O’Connor, 125, praising him for making the desire a desire of intellect, not of will. 12 Lonergan, De Ente, 42, no. 83:“Naturale desiderium visionis cognoscitur postquam theologus factum visionis cognovit et inquantum eius convenientiam explicare conatur.” In speaking of the desire, St. Thomas speaks as a theologian, Lonergan says, De Ente, 40–41, nos. 79–80, and this holds for the argument from reason in ST I, q. 12, a. 1, c. 13 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 87. 14 See Feingold, Natural Desire, 109, and 143, where he points out that the appeal to the natural desire loses its apologetic value if, as an innate desire, it cannot be known independently of revelation. 15 Lonergan here reads as does Henri de Lubac and Domingo Soto, taking the elicited desire as a sign of an innate desire to see God, a reading Feingold, Natural Desire, 335–36, shows wanting. 188 Book Symposium He writes: “the [conscious] question quid sit Deus, expresses a desire that arises naturally as soon as one knows the existence of God [and so, is an elicited desire].” And he continues: “This is but a corollary of the twofold affirmation that the desire to understand is natural [innate] and transcendental.”16 Evidently, we do not need revelation to know the existence of the elicited desire that “arises naturally” once we know the existence of God. No, but we do need revelation to know the existence of the innate desire of intellect, the tendency of intellect itself, unto the vision of God.Why does not the elicited desire, the conscious and wakeful desire to know what God is once we recognize the existence of a first cause, tell us all by itself of the innate desire of the intellect? Why does not the elicited desire—itself something “natural”—tell us of the inclination of nature to the vision of God? Presumably, because whatever the natural desire of the intellect may be, it is something constitutive of the intellect. Innate desires are, as it were, structural. And therefore the innate desire to see God must be of something possible, else the very nature of intellect is self-contradictory and badly constructed. So, unless we know that quidditative knowledge of God is possible, we do not know whether there really is an innate natural tendency toward it constitutive of the intellect. And we do not know it is possible apart from Revelation.There can be no desire of nature, innate, for something impossible where the author of natures is the infinitely wise and good God. Human natural and innate appetite, although it does not proceed from human knowledge yet proceeds from some knowledge, namely God’s.17 Only with Revelation do we know the fact of our supernatural end, however, and so the real possibility of seeing God; and so only with Revelation could we know that the natural desire, the innate tendency, of the intellect were to such an object. Apart from Revelation, Lonergan says, the philosopher must be content with “paradox,” not knowing what the (“naturally” arising) elicited desire really indicates about our innate natural desire.18 We can have the elicited desire, whether or not the thing is possible, and just as Feingold points out, following Suárez, but we could not have the innate desire unless the thing were possible.19 16 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 86. 17 See the text in Feingold, Natural Desire, 641. 18 See similarly Francisco de Toledo, in Feingold, Natural Desire, 343. 19 Ibid., 436. This elicited desire is conditional, not perfect or efficacious; perfect elicited desire depends on knowing the object possible, and this knowledge here depends on Revelation.The elicited and imperfect desire manifests, not an innate desire for vision, but an innate desire for knowledge, for truth—in short, for the universal object of the faculty, ibid., 338–440. Book Symposium 189 As to the second question, the fulfillment of the desire remains conditional, but that does not mean for Lonergan that the desire itself is conditional, and certainly not in the way an elicited desire for an object impossible of attainment is conditional because dependent on a knowledge of the conditions of fulfillment. Lonergan grants that the elicited desire, as expressed by some such words as “I would like to know what God is,” and as spoken prior to faith, is not efficacious, for he holds that the meritorious and efficacious desire to see God is an act of supernatural charity or hope.20 Still, the innate desire, the preconscious tendency of the intellect is absolute. “There is an inclination of the human intellect to know the quiddity of God.”21 The fulfillment is conditioned on grace and glory, but the desire is not conditioned. It is a natural desire; and natural desires, natural tendencies, are “on” under any condition in which the nature exists, and so are “unconditioned,” absolute. They are structural, built-in to the edifice as long as it stands. In other words, the natural desire of the power cannot be conditioned as is a velleity or some imperfect act of will, where the desire is elicited. As a natural desire, a tendency of the faculty, it is unconditional in the sense that it really and truly is a tendency—full, complete, perfect as such, and in its own order—to quidditative knowledge of God. Innate appetite is always absolute.22 Even so, Lonergan thinks it need not be fulfilled. Feingold shows that (1) natural desire, or inclination, or tendency, and (2) the principles by which to attain the end, and (3) ordination to the end all belong together.23 If we are not ordered to vision except by grace, and if the principles of attainment are grace and the theological virtues, then there is no natural desire for vision, no innate inclination to it. So also inclination, finality, and ordination all belong together.24 For St.Thomas, vision exceeds natural inclination, innate inclination, as witness the many texts that Feingold assembles.25 There is therefore no natural inclination of the intellect to vision.26 There can be a natural inclination only to what is proportionate, and the natural inclination of the intellect to its proportionate object works through naturally given first principles; therefore, if the intellect is to be inclined to a supernatural end, 20 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 90. 21 Lonergan, De Ente, 37, no. 72: “exsistit tendentia intellectus humani in quiddi- tatem Dei cognoscendam.” 22 Feingold, Natural Desire, 563. 23 Ibid., 305, apropos of Sylvester of Ferrara. 24 Ibid., 524. 25 Ibid., 299–300. 26 Ibid., 357–58. Book Symposium 190 it must be enhanced by a supernatural gift, another set of first principles, namely, the articles of faith. So Summa theologiae I–II, question 62, article 3: The theological virtues order man to supernatural beatitude in the way that man is ordered to the end connatural to him through natural inclination.This happens in two respects, however: first, according to reason or intellect, insofar as it contains the first universal principles known to us by the natural light of the intellect, from which reason sets forth in both the speculative and the practical orders; second, by the rectitude of the will naturally tending to the good of reason. But these two are not sufficient for the order of supernatural beatitude, according to 1 Corinthians 2:9,“Eye has not seen nor ear heard nor has it entered into the heart of man what God has prepared for those who love him.” Whence it is necessary that in both respects something be added to man supernaturally so that he be ordered to a supernatural end. And first, indeed, as to the intellect, certain supernatural principles are added to man, which are received by divine light, and these are the articles of faith [credibilia] about which is faith. Second, however, the will is ordered to that end both as to the motion of intention, tending to it as to what is possible to attain, which pertains to hope, and as to a kind of spiritual union, through which it is in some way transformed unto that end, which occurs through charity. For the appetite of each and every thing is naturally moved and tends unto the end connatural to it, and this motion proceeds from some conformity of the thing to its end.27 Just as de Lubac makes an innate desire of the will do the job for which St.Thomas says charity or habitual grace are necessary, giving man a real inclination to a supernatural end, so Lonergan has an innate desire of intellect doing the job for which St.Thomas says the articles of faith are necessary, inclining the intellect to the vision of God.28 This problem with the innate and so absolute character of the desire can be seen from another point of view. For notwithstanding its innate character, Lonergan characterizes the potency for its fulfillment, as has been indicated, as obediential. So, what St.Thomas keeps together, namely (1) a natural inclination, (2) of a natural passive potency, (3) the fulfillment of which is debitum, Lonergan breaks up: He wants a natural inclination, but in an obediential potency, whose fulfillment is not owed.29 To make the potency obediential fits with his denying that the desire constitutes an 27 See Feingold’s use of this text in the important concluding section, ibid., 641–43, and also 305 and 532. 28 Ibid., 549–50. Since it functions as does charity, the very status of the desire as “natural” thus comes into question, as Feingold points out in this section of his book; see esp. 538, 548–49. 29 Ibid., 207, 229, 234, 241, 647–48. Book Symposium 191 “exigence” for fulfillment, but not with saying the desire is innate.30 It is Scotus and de Lubac, of course, who want an inclination to vision; but also, more congruently with Thomas’s usage, they want the potency to be characterized, not as obediential, or only as obediential, but as natural.31 For Lonergan, the natural desire is an innate natural desire for a supernatural state of affairs, a natural appetite for a supernatural fulfillment.32 Like Scotus, Lonergan asserts a non-exigent inclination of intellect to all intelligible objects, not just those it has the natural active power to make inform the possible intellect.33 Lonergan, holding to a natural and innate inclination to vision, and holding also that man’s nature is defined by God on the supposition of his being called to a supernatural end (about which, see below), is therefore much closer to Henri de Lubac than to St.Thomas as Feingold gives us to understand him. If Feingold is correct, therefore, Lonergan’s position is misleading as an expression of the thought of St.Thomas, and the remark Lonergan made apropos of William O’Connor’s work could be made about Lonergan’s work:“I do not think that the author has evaluated adequately the significance of Aquinas’s views on natural desire.”34 Lonergan’s position is difficult to evaluate, however, and this is because of two ambiguities that push it in the direction of what Feingold would recognize as a correct exposition of St.Thomas. First, in the discussion of a desire that he explicitly denies is elicited, he sometimes nevertheless slides quite unmistakably into a discussion of what can be nothing but an elicited desire to see God. So, he writes:“The natural desire is to know what God is.That natural desire neither includes nor excludes the Blessed Trinity. It supposes knowledge that God is.”35 Therefore, it is an elicited desire. And just here, Lonergan invokes the solution of Sylvester of Ferrara to remove the paradox of having a natural desire for a supernatural state of affairs: The naturally elicited desire has for its object to know the essence of God and nothing else; it is not the desire for this knowledge as constituting our happiness; that desire is the 30 The desire, Lonergan says, indicates a “capacity,” not an “exigence”; see his review of Buckley, Man’s Last End, 580. 31 Feingold, Natural Desire, 242, points out that for Scotus a natural potency with a natural inclination for a perfection can also be obediential, if only God can supply the perfection; and see his concluding remarks on this matter, ibid., 280–81. 32 See Feingold’s exposition of the position of Jansenius and Arnauld, ibid., 460. 33 Ibid., 228–29. 34 Lonergan, review of O’Connor, The Eternal Quest, 126. 35 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 90, emphasis added. 192 Book Symposium desire of vision as supernaturally beatifying, and that elicited (and perfect) desire depends on revelation and grace.36 It is just this distinction for which Lonergan praises O’Connor.37 Second, there is another ambiguity about exactly what Lonergan refers to in speaking of “natural desire.” If the desire is not elicited, it is innate. But is it really an innate desire for the vision of God as the perfective act of the intellect, as for Scotus the desire is the innate pondus of the will toward vision as constituting beatitude? Lonergan speaks of the natural desire to see God—which seems determinate enough—as in fact something rather more indeterminate. So, he tells us, the desire and its fulfillment have the same material object, but not the same formal object: “[T]hus, the object of the natural desire is transcendental; but the object of the fulfilling vision is supernatural.”38 Again, the knowledge of God is presented, not as a determinate object to which there is an innate inclination, but as simply included within the scope of an intellect whose adequate object is the transcendental ens.39 Writing in this context, the elicited desire to know God is just a “corollary” of a natural and transcendental desire to understand whatever there is.40 Again, the natural and innate desire to understand is said to “extend” to understanding God.41 In this way, we seem very close indeed to Feingold’s presentation, and perhaps it is useful to recall Lonergan’s remark to the effect that the natural desire to see God is rather ill-named.42 Indeed it is if, as innate, it is really the natural and transcendental desire “to understand.” It is understandable that one so concentrated on the natural and transcendental desire to understand, so alive to the virtualities of the pure and unrestricted desire to know in understanding ourselves, God, and the world—it is understandable, I say, that such a one would find there a central element in understanding St.Thomas’s assertion of a natural desire to see God.43 In this regard, Fr. Lonergan cannot be faulted. 36 See Feingold, Natural Desire, 310, 313–14. 37 Lonergan, review of O’Connor, The Eternal Quest, 125. 38 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 90. 39 Ibid., 86. See also idem, De Ente, 84–85, where the natural and innate desire to know “extends” to the quiddity of God. 40 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 86. 41 Ibid., 87; also idem, De Ente, 84–85, where the natural and innate desire to know “extends” to the quiddity of God. 42 Lonergan, De Ente, 36, no. 68. 43 In this respect, what Lonergan expressly says about the natural desire to see God can be found in quite another form in Insight: A Study of Human Understanding (New York: Philosophical Library, 1957, 1970), ch. 19, “General Transcendent Knowledge.” Book Symposium 193 Notwithstanding the invitation latent in Lonergan’s text to distinguish the natural desire to know the truth, the natural desire whence naturally arises the elicited desire to know God once we know he exists, from a determinately characterized desire to know the essence of God, there remains a last matter which is not, it would seem, amenable to such a negotiation. To be sure, this is the issue of “pure nature.” Lonergan thinks its possibility a “marginal theorem.” It is a marginal theorem if it cannot be strictly demonstrated from the gratuity of grace.44 Feingold, evidently, adheres to the view that it is to be demonstrated from the gratuity of grace and so is not marginal at all. For the gratuity of grace implies that there can be no innate and natural desire for vision;45 it is just such a desire, however, that implies the impossibility of a state of pure nature.46 So, the impossibility of such a desire, following from the gratuity of grace, means that a state of pure nature is possible. For an innate appetite, Feingold reminds us, is determined to one end; if the end is natural, there is no innate desire for vision, and if there is a desire for vision, there is no innate desire for a natural end.47 No innate desire for vision means innate desire is for a natural end, and this implies the possibility of “pure nature.” Lonergan inclines to the possibility of a world and a humanity without grace, but thinks the affirmation of such possibility unimportant.This view, that the affirmation of the possibility of a purely natural world is marginal to Catholic dogmatics, he thinks follows from what he calls the priority of world order to individual natures.As it were, the controlling element of the divine ordering wisdom is the order of all things in the world and their ordination to him. Granted the determination of this order and how things are ordered to him, there follows the determination of the specific natures of the things of the world, together with the natural desires that constitute these natures.48 Nature, and so natural desire, is a function of world order. In fact, world order is supernatural, and we are destined to see God as the perfecting beatitude of our natures.Therefore, we are given the nature we have, together with its natural desire, in view of this end. Lonergan does not say in so many words that the natural desire to see God is a function of our 44 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 94. 45 Feingold, Natural Desire, 668. 46 Ibid., 666. 47 Ibid., 662; and see 620–25. 48 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 88, 93.The question of the priority of world order arises also for Lonergan from the fact that while the natural law is naturally knowable, it cannot be kept without grace; ibid., 90. Note that the distinction between world order and finite natures does not occur in the De Ente of 1946. 194 Book Symposium being called to a supernatural end, of the supernatural character of the existing “world order.” But if it means anything in the context of discussing the natural desire to see God, his emphasis on the priority of world order to nature means that because we are ordered to a supernatural end, therefore God has built into us the desire of nature, the innate and natural tendency (absolute, in fact) to see God. This is exactly like de Lubac, it seems: I am what I am only because God has called me to himself.49 Moreover, it seems to follow for Lonergan that some “concrete possibility” relative to this, that, or the other nature and its end is determinable only according as a world order is “concretely” determined, which is to say “complete down to its least historical detail.”50 In the absence of our being able to think out a world order to that degree of concreteness— which in fact is possible only for the divine mind—we cannot say with certainty whether man as we know him could exist puris in naturalibus. If this is the upshot, and I say “if ” because Lonergan moves very fast here and his text is very compressed, I can think of four problems. First, it seems to imply that not every created intellect, just as such, would have the “transcendental” scope our intellects do in fact have. For the natural desire to see God is strictly a function for Lonergan of that transcendental scope. This would mean that it is really possible to have an intellect whose adequate object is not being, an intellect that would not include the First Cause in its scope, an intellect that would not naturally ask “What is God?” upon the knowledge that God exists. For recall, the conscious question manifests the natural desire; if there is no natural desire to see God, then there is no manifestation of it. I do not believe this could be countenanced by one for whom “the pure notion of being is the detached, disinterested, unrestricted desire to know,” the idea of being “the content of an act of understanding that grasps everything about everything,” the primary component of which is “identical with the unrestricted act” itself of understanding everything about everything, and for whom “it is one and the same thing to understand what being is and to understand what God is.” 51 Second, and following on this first problem, we are led by Lonergan’s argument to determine a quite “concrete possibility” on the supposition that a world without a supernatural ordination is possible, namely the possibility of an intellect whose scope does not extend to wondering what God is.This is not the certain knowledge that man might exist puris in naturalibus, which knowledge as certain Lonergan forbids us. But it is the certain knowledge 49 Henri de Lubac, The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Crossroad, 1967, 1998), 64, 77–81. 50 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 93. 51 Lonergan, Insight, 642, 644, 646, 658. Book Symposium 195 that some intellectual or rational creature might so exist, and it seems to be a knowledge such as he forbids us to have, that is, a certain knowledge of a nature in the absence of the knowledge of the concrete world order, complete down to its last atom, in which such an intellect would exist. Third, and following on the last, the conception of such an intellect is in fact impossible. If the questions for judgment and understanding—Is it? What is it?—really do define the intellect and tell us what it is, what its scope is, what its end is, then an intellect for which there could be a reality of which we would not ask “What is it?” is an impossibility and an impossibility most certainly according to Fr. Lonergan’s lights.52 These considerations by no means imply that Lonergan’s point about the priority of world order to the exact shapes of natural kinds in the world is to be gainsaid. We may well grant that the divine practical wisdom, as John Wright puts it, is “first concerned with the divine goodness itself: in which of the many possible ways open to Him was it to be shared.”53 But the above considerations appeal to the sort of, shall we say, transcendental analysis of intellect that Lonergan was himself so adept at. In any possible world, intellect, under whatever specifying determinations, must be such as to have as its adequate object just what Lonergan says it does. From this it will necessarily follow that, knowing God exists, such persons will naturally want to know what he is. In other words, the “principal parts of the universe,” those intellectual or rational creatures to whom the divine goodness is to be manifested and in which manifestation the end of the universe is to be found, have a sort of density of generic nature according to which some things must be true of them in any possible arrangement of creation.This in fact Lonergan seems almost to envisage. He says that for the argument from a finite nature and the necessarily finite character of its proportionate end to be sound, we should have to assume “that the parts in question [men and angels] determine the whole, that finite natures are prior to and determine world order.”54 The argument here so far is to the effect that, while the generic nature of created mind need not be taken to determine everything about world order, it does indeed determine some things about world order. For instance, the existence of rational creatures would seem to require that non-rational creatures serve them.55 For St. Thomas, and on Feingold’s 52 Cf. Feingold, Natural Desire, 576; and for Lonergan, the immediately preceding note. 53 John H.Wright, SJ, The Order of the Universe in the Theology of St.Thomas (Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1957), 191–92, note 2.This dissertation was directed by Lonergan. 54 Lonergan, “Natural Desire,” 93. 55 Wright, Order, 156ff., 193. Book Symposium 196 showing, because intellectual and rational natures must naturally desire to know God, once his existence is known, these natures also indicate the supreme and most beautiful fittingness that the order of the world be a supernatural one, the order of this world.56 Fourth and last, prior to idea of world order there is the idea of world itself, that is, creation.That whatever is created, moreover, cannot have an exigence for or be owed what is proper to the uncreated would seem to be a principle for whatever world order there is. Therefore, there can be no innate desire for the vision of God that belongs to any created nature in any order of things. Is whatever glitter such an argument has a function of vicious abstraction? “Concrete possibility” is not to be asserted from a simple consideration of nature and its exigencies, Lonergan writes. Feingold agrees and notes that every consideration of natures is “abstract.”The “concrete” belongs to individuals in history.57 Even so, the concrete and the historical are functions of the material and the accidental, and do not determine innate natural desires, which are part of the “abstract” nature itself.58 Therefore, they cannot determine what is debitum naturae or destroy the possibility of a beatitude proportionate to the nature. I am concerned in pointing out this fourth problem, however, to put things in terms of creation itself.The possibility of a purely natural order, inscribed in the idea of nature, is inscribed also in the idea of creation, and rests squarely on the adequacy of the distinction between uncreated and created reality, or, to put it otherwise, on the assertion of the transcendence of God. As Feingold abundantly shows, what is innately and naturally desired is owed.This thought can be developed.What is owed, we might say, belongs to the thing, and what belongs to a thing is a sort of part of the thing.59 Therefore, to say that God’s own understanding of himself or his own happiness is innately desired by a creature, is tantamount to saying that it is a part of the created order, just as such. It is to say, as it were, that God can create some world order of which he is a part.Which is to say that just by the act of creation, just by the act of distinguishing what is not him from himself, he makes himself a part of what is not him. The distinguishing is not therefore successful; and he is both a part of creation (because owed to the desire of the creature) and not a part of it (because 56 Feingold, Natural Desire, 607. 57 Ibid., 545. 58 Ibid., 545–46. 59 Cf. St. Thomas, In librum beati Dionysii de Divinis Nominibus expositio, IV, lect. 9, no. 406 (Marietti). So to speak, God would be owing to human nature as are hands, parts of the nature. Book Symposium 197 transcendent Creator).The act of creation seems as it were to self-destruct. But no. What is owing to a created nature is of the earth, earthly, and cannot be anything proper to heaven, however characterized—whether the divine love or the divine understanding or the divine happiness, all of which things are the divine nature itself.Therefore, the very transcendence of God, or otherwise expressed, the very adequacy of the distinction between creature and Creator, requires that vision be gratuitous, and therefore an innate natural desire for vision be impossible, and therefore that whatever created order there be comprise a natural beatitude proportionate to rational and intellectual creatures. This point can be put in a different way. Suppose with Plotinus one thinks the world and the human soul necessarily proceed from God, the One-Good, as it were, by necessity of nature.60 Then, whatever one may say about the transcendence and unknowability and unnameability of God, it will be true to say also and paradoxically that there is a sort of continuity of nature between God and the world, such that the soul’s ascent to God and its union with God will be just as “natural” as its procession from God.Therefore, if the soul proceeds from the One-Good by necessity of nature, so its end will be by nature—which is to say, by its origin and by the content it brings from that origin—union with God. For Plotinus, after all, the higher part of the soul remains in some fashion always with the Divine Mind.61 In the very establishment of what is not the One, there is established both the desire and the power of return.62 To the contrary, “it must be said that, since the creature proceeds from God in diversity of nature, God is outside the order of the whole of creation, nor is it from his nature that he has a relation to creatures. For he 60 There is still justice in this formulation, even if the world follows from what the One is only because the One has first (eternally) willed himself to be what he is, the undiminished source of the world. See John Rist, Plotinus:The Road to Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), 82–83; and earlier, Jean Trouillard, La Procession Plotinienne (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1955), 76–80. An especially good treatment of the freedom and necessity of Plotinian procession is A. Hilary Armstrong’s “Two Views of Freedom:A Christian Objection in Plotinus, EnneadsVI.8 [39] 7, 11–15?” in Studia Patristica, vol. 17, pt. 1 (New York: Pergamon Press, 1982), 397–406. 61 A. Hilary Armstrong, “Salvation, Plotinian and Christian,” Downside Review 75 (1957): 132–34. More, that the soul know and desire God supposes an already established likeness to God; see René Arnou, Le Désir de Dieu dans la philosophie de Plotin (Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1921, 1967), 148–53. Note in St. Thomas, ST I–II, q. 62, a. 3, c, quoted above, where just such a likeness, correlative with ordination unto God, is likewise posited, but is supernatural, and see Feingold, Natural Desire, 650–53. 62 Armstrong,” Salvation,” 128. Book Symposium 198 does not produce creatures from necessity of his nature, but by intellect and will.”63 So, St.Thomas further concludes, there is no real relation of God to the creature. Furthermore and from the other side, while this diversity of nature does not of course exclude a real relation of dependence of the creature on God, it does mean that what belongs to the divine nature as such cannot belong to the creature, and that the creature can have no natural operation that naturally possesses it of what belongs to God. The gratuity of creation, then, a part of the Christian adjustment of neo-Platonism, just of itself implies also the distinct and so double gratuity of sharing the beatitude of God. The One is hardly to be conceived apart from what (willingly) flows from him, but the doctrine of creation requires us to think the possibility that the world might not exist.64 The liberality of the One is such as of itself to bring to pass the overflow of being and the world, and of itself to install into what overflows the capacity to return. It must be (not by chance, but neither by coercion) that God create, and likewise it must be that we return. Neither of these necessities, however, survives the first article of the creed.65 So, if gratuity of grace shows the possibility of pure nature as Feingold argues, and if it as tied to the transcendence of God and the very meaning and gratuity of creation as I have tried briefly to indicate, it is no marginal theorem. Writing in 1949 on the question of man’s end and the question of pure nature, Lonergan said: If the history of the matter is becoming clearer, the speculative issues are so complex that a generous lapse of time will have to be granted, I suspect, before all concealed suppositions have been detected and a sound judgment can be passed upon the relative merits of the medieval and the Renaissance positions.66 A very just prediction of Fr. Lonergan, very justly fulfilled by Lawrence N&V Feingold. 63 ST I, q. 28, a. 1, ad 3. 64 Robert Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), 31–33. 65 Trouillard expressly likens the neo-Platonist view of the relation of the natural and the supernatural to that of Blondel (and so of de Lubac); see his “Procession néoplatonicienne et création judeo-chrétienne,” in Néoplatonisme: mélanges offerts à Jean Trouillard, Cahiers de Fontenay 19–22 (Fontenay-aux-Roses, 1981), 13–15. 66 Lonergan, review of Buckley, Man’s Last End, 579. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 1 (2007): 199–226 199 Book Reviews Faith, Reason and the Existence of God by Denys Turner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 292 pp. F OR T HOMAS AQUINAS, the limitations of ancient philosophy—limitations to its views on, say, the eternity of the world, the state and activity of the intellectual soul apart from the body, the nature of divine life and God’s relationship to the created order, and the account of human happiness—are most evident in the greatest achievements of pagan philosophy.To see the limits clearly, we must see the successes. Although he does not speak in detail about the role of ancient philosophy in Aquinas’s writings, Denys Turner, in his book Faith, Reason and the Existence of God, aims to explicate and defend Aquinas’s account of natural reason, particularly his assertion that natural reason can reach the existence of God. Not one to shy away from controversy,Turner wants to defend not just Aquinas but the precise teaching of Vatican I on the demonstrability of the existence of God by natural reason. In the opening,Turner apologizes for what he calls the “intentionally narrow” focus of the book (ix), but the book is in fact remarkably, at times frustratingly, diffuse in its treatment of topics.The breadth of treatment is at once a vice and virtue of the book. It makes it difficult at times to discern the continuing thread in the argument, but it also allows the reader to make connections between the underlying issue of faith and reason and a number of other discussions, for example, concerning language in contemporary continental thought and the nature of musical expression. Turner’s book thus offers more than simply a persuasive case for the significance of proofs for the existence of God; it points us in the direction of a rehabilitation of the role of philosophy in Aquinas’s life and thought that contemporary theology, as Turner amply demonstrates, is in danger of forgetting. From the beginning,Turner wants to be clear about precisely what the teaching of Vatican I is and what it is not.The Church does not claim that we currently possess a valid proof from natural reason for the existence of 200 Book Reviews God. It does not advocate on behalf of a particular proof. (Turner himself does not offer a fully worked out proof, although he devotes a good bit of time to clearing a path for such a proof.) One might wonder: If we cannot point to a precise proof, what is the point of the teaching? On Turner’s reading, the teaching itself is a deliverance of faith, not reason:The possibility of such a proof is not to be denied on the grounds of faith.Turner’s most succinct way of putting the issue is this. The proof is something of which “reason must be capable of in its terms if it is to serve its purpose within faith’s self-exploration as quaerens intellectum” (5). What is striking and instructive about Turner’s approach is the way it meets the opponents of natural theology on their own terms.There is not even the slightest suggestion in Turner that defending natural theology entails abandoning or bracketing faith or adopting a neutral standpoint of pure reason. Of course, that description of the practice of natural theology owes as much to the postmedieval conception of natural theology as it does to the Barthian critique of rational proof. At various points in the book, Turner is preoccupied with the Barthian critique and with the recent revival of neo-Barthianism in the popular theological movement known as Radical Orthodoxy.With the Barthian objection that natural theology involves adopting the standpoint of creation in utter independence from our election in Christ, Turner teases out the key issue—whether the approach to God through natural reason must in every case entail a normalization of the relation between creature and Creator.Turner argues that, in the case of the approach of Aquinas at least, it does not. Aquinas’s ways to God underscore the poverty of human reason in the face of the divine. But human reason is, as Plato puts it in the Symposium, the offspring not just of poverty, but of plenty.Thus, the claim, universally affirmed by Aquinas, that we do not know what God is does not entail that we know no truths about God or that we have no way of removing falsehoods from our understanding of God. One of the most significant philosophical and theological consequences of the proofs is that they make palpable the distance that separates our intellect from the divine. Under the influence of Derrida, a certain trend in contemporary theology celebrates otherness and detects idolatry in any attempt to reach God by reason. One of the unusual features of Turner’s defense of natural theology is the way it engages this trend.Turner dismisses as nonsense Derrida’s statement that “every other is totally other”—a claim that would undercut not just metaphysics but ethics as well, unless ethics is to be founded on “blank anonymity.”Yet Turner’s discussion here is not just critical or simply negative. He finds grounds for engagement with continental thought on the topic of music, a topic he takes up as a basis for an analy- Book Reviews 201 sis of absence and presence in Eucharistic theology. Music signifies the “body in the condition of ecstasy” (115) and is symbolic of the limits of reason.The sadness that typically attends great music,Turner thinks, arises from our experience in it of “what one has caught some glimpse of but cannot yet possess” (116). In this and other contexts, reason itself points to an otherness that it cannot know. Here Turner identifies both the key insight concerning the limits of reason and the potential self-destruction of reason in the post-Nietzschean epoch. On this view, there is nothing to guarantee that beyond reason there is anything but a “vacuous, empty nothingness, an endless prolongation of postponements” (119). The only way out of this nihilism is for reason to be able to “name the otherness,” to justify the existence of God as that to which it points (see 119). The way natural reason points beyond itself and the way we are to distinguish the pointing toward God in philosophy from the pointing done in theology are important issues for Turner’s project. Setting aside as a later accretion to the reading of Thomas the contrast between the formal and material objects of knowledge, Turner holds that Aquinas’s way of distinguishing the philosophical from the theological knowledge of God is to speak, in Aristotelian terms, of the same object less and more distinctively known. Seen from afar, we might discern only that what is approaching is a human being; as we come closer, we realize that the human being is Peter.Turner here touches upon, but does not develop, a pervasive principle of method in Aquinas, both in philosophy and in theology: dialectical engagement of received opinions. How is that germane to the debate over natural theology? From Aristotle,Aquinas inherits a conception of dialectic as providing a path to the principles, a sorting through of received opinions and salient examples from ordinary experience in order to reach insights about the nature of things. The dialectical method involves, in part, the appraisal of the strengths and weaknesses, the truth and falsity, of various opinions. Without being naïvely irenic, the approach involves crediting, wherever possible, one’s interlocutors with a partial apprehension of truth. Aquinas, of course, stresses that the philosophers reached these truths about God only after much effort and with an admixture of error. But Aquinas is characteristically modest in his assessment both of the achievement and of the limitations or failures.“Admixture of error” does not mean utterly riddled with falsehood. Indeed, the critics of natural theology replace Aquinas’s sense of degree and scale with an all-or-nothing dichotomy more characteristic of later Christian thinkers such as Pascal or Kierkegaard, who, it is important to add, were reacting to a very different and much more audacious conception of the power and scope of natural reason. 202 Book Reviews Here is another way of putting this point. Without a commendation or affirmation of the achievements of pagan philosophy, it is hard to see how theology could have the status, which Aquinas attributes to it, of architectonic science. The notion of an architectonic science or art that rules over and directs other, subordinate sciences and arts is not a Christian invention. It comes from Aristotle. If there is no real learning, let alone wisdom in ancient philosophy, then theology’s architectonic status is earned by default.As theologian,Aquinas maintains a positive, ongoing dialogue with reason and philosophy precisely because, as Turner nicely puts it, “reason, in the exercise of its own native powers, in some way ‘replicates’ or ‘anticipates’ this shape of faith” (75). Thomas calls the truths proffered by faith but available to reason preambles of the faith.These truths can be found in both the speculative and the practical orders. In the former, the preambles inform us about the existence of God and other truths immediately derived from God’s existence as unmoved mover. In the latter, the natural law partially overlaps with the Decalogue and gives human beings access to the starting points of the ethical life. Since Aquinas says explicitly that sin has a greater effect on the will than on the intellect and he holds that sin has not made us completely oblivious to the principles of the practical order, it would seem odd for him to hold that we are utterly deprived of access through natural reason to the great truths of the speculative order, such as God’s existence. Of course, the latter truth is not a self-evident precept as are the founding principles of the natural law. But the seeds of the knowledge of the existence of God are, according to Aquinas, latent within ordinary experience, in our desire for happiness and in our apprehension of order in the universe. Of course, the comparison of the speculative and practical orders raises an important question about natural knowledge of God, namely, whether the knowledge is efficacious for a good life or for salvation. Sometimes the objection to natural theology is that such knowledge is impossible apart from faith; or that, even if such knowledge is available, it is not efficacious for salvation; or that such knowledge does not reach the trinity of persons. Aquinas would certainly concur with the last two, and, for the case of most human beings, with the first as well. But this does not mean that, where it is held as a valid argument, a proof for the existence of God provides no knowledge. Indeed, on some versions of the objection, it would seem that the Jews did not, and do not have, knowledge of God. Of course,Aquinas’s account of the preambles reposes in part on the claim of a partial overlap between what the philosophers were able to achieve and what God revealed to the Jews in Exodus, concerning both our naming of God and our conduct toward God and others in the commandments.The extreme Book Reviews 203 anti natural theology position, which holds that there is no knowledge of God apart from faith in Christ and the Trinity, would for Aquinas create difficulties in our understanding of the Jewish faith. That is one way of stating the problem for faith of the critique of natural reason. Another way, one explicitly articulated by Turner, is this. If we stress the apophatic to the exclusion of the cataphatic, silence to speech, one wonders how we can give “due weight . . . [to] the positive revelation of God in Jesus Christ” (50).The Word is speech, after all, not silence. In contemporary theology, Turner worries, the “delicately constructed tension between the apophatic and the cataphatic within both reason and faith has been readjusted into a polarity between the negative possibilities of reason and the positive possibilities of faith” (75). Turner’s defense of reason on behalf, or from the perspective, of faith does not mean that reason is simply instrumentalized. Indeed, that is one of the dangers with the hasty and wholesale repudiation of natural theology; nothing is left of reason but to play an instrumental role.Turner objects to the growing popularity in theology of a “generalized skeptical negativity concerning reason, combined with a theological positivism concerning faith” (75). Reason loses the rich, ample significance that it had in antiquity and takes on a strikingly modern sense. In his concluding comments, Turner captures Aquinas’s sense of reason both as partly constitutive of the human and as crucial for faith: “The believer who . . . refuses to stand on the ground of the atheists’ denials and to challenge them on shared rules of contest concedes the territory of reason, and so of the human, at a price which in the end will be paid in the quality of faith itself ” (262). N&V Thomas Hibbs Baylor University Waco,Texas Reason, Community and Religious Tradition: Anselm’s Argument and the Friars by Scott Matthews (Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, 2001), ix + 238 pp. Simon Tugwell nicely defined the difference between the early Franciscan and Dominican ideals. Dominicans sought to recover the apostolic life; Franciscans the apostolic life. The Friars Preachers emphasized apostolic mission; the Friars Minor, personal renewal. Scott Matthews explores the difference in how the Friars approach Anselm’s argument for the existence of God in the Proslogion. He begins with Anselm’s monastic context. Anselm writes for monks and for his female patrons, his purpose private and devotional, not evangelistic. 204 Book Reviews Summarizing the Monologion and Proslogion chapter by chapter, Matthews emphasizes a focus not on definition, but on the divine ineffability. The reader is to recognize, as Anselm says, that “I was made for the purpose of seeing you, and I have not yet been able to do that for which I was made.” When Gaunilo translates the negative “that than which nothing greater” to “a being greater than everything,” he exactly misses the point: Anselm emphasizes that we do not know God. His aim is not philosophical proof, but compunctio cordis, an upward spiral of knowledge and love. Following Anton Pegis, Matthews emphasizes the role of participation, hierarchy, and presence—rather than definition—in Anselm’s argument. Matthews next reviews the history that separates Anselm from the friars. The rise of wandering religious movements challenged Christendom to establish a greater unity ad intra: New schools provided literary tools for centralized government, and the friars gave papal access to the provinces. Ad extra, Christendom was challenged to show its vitality visà-vis Judaism and Islam, and above all vis-à-vis the Philosophy those religions had assimilated. These challenges fostered a theology “judicial rather than contemplative, professional rather than aristocratic” (31). No longer a text to be pondered in one’s cell, Anselm’s argument became a weapon for debate.Thus Alexander Nequam used it to prove to the Jews that God could become man, and William of Auxerre, teacher of the first great scholastic friars, Alexander of Hales, and Hugh of St. Cher used it to prove the necessity of faith for true philosophy. The four central chapters of the book consider the transposition of Anselm’s argument, first by the early Franciscan and Dominican schools, and then by their greatest flowers, Bonaventure and Thomas. Summarizing manuscripts from Oxford, Paris, Bologna, and Assisi, Matthews details the development of the two schools. Again, he puts the Franciscan school in the context of challenges from within and from without: the question of studies in the poverello’s order, and the question of beggars in the schools. In Alexander of Hales, Odo Rigaud, three disciples of Odo, and the Summa Minorum (fratris Alexandri), Matthews finds a consistent theology. St. Francis rediscovered the primacy of conversion from sensual love to the love of Christ. For the early Franciscan theologians, this conversion expressed itself intellectually in the turn from contemplating creatures to contemplating the ground of their existence. Anselm’s argument served to show that true thought necessarily sees through creatures to their most perfect exemplar—only the fool says there is no God. Reread in a new context, Anselm’s argument now showed both that theology is a part of Franciscan conversion and that Franciscan conversion is necessary for theology. Book Reviews 205 While Francis’s friars cultivated an experience of God’s presence, Dominic’s battled heresy, emphasizing authority over interiority. Among the early Dominicans, then, the first emphasis was on the authority of Scripture, as with Hugh of St. Cher. Their first Summa, Roland of Cremona’s, arose in the missionary battles of Toulouse. By the time of Albert the Great, says Matthews, reason was clearly set out, not as a tool within faith, but as a means of discourse with the infidel. Albert focused on solid proofs of God’s existence and his unity. Anselm is significant precisely for his absence:Though aware of his argument, the Dominicans replaced this interior way with concrete arguments from causality. The two orders toyed with various approaches, but it became clear that there were distinctly Franciscan and Dominican ways of doing theology. Before turning to the central characters of his book, Matthews devotes half a chapter to the vicissitudes of Oxford. Here, Robert Grosseteste, friend of the Franciscans, filled out their theory of illumination with a greater emphasis on the senses, while the Dominican Richard Fishacre gave greater space to an illuminationist reading of Anselm. In contrasting the order of causality and the order of knowledge, the Franciscan Richard Rufus sounds distinctly like a Dominican. But—and this seems to be the point—Rufus’s confreres drove him from Oxford in shame. Experimentation with opposing viewpoints only proved the deepening commitments of each school. Early Franciscan thought culminates in Bonaventure’s exemplarism. Matthews summarizes parts of Bonaventure’s Sentences commentary, the De Trinitate, and the Itinerarium. Because God causes everything that is, nothing is understood properly apart from him. Moreover, because God causes knowledge itself, the mind can find him without venturing beyond itself.Thus for Bonaventure, only willful malice, never ignorance, prevents one from knowing God.Again,Anselm’s argument shows that all thought is false and illogical unless it acknowledges God.The argument need not pass as a proof; it shows that God’s existence is self-evident, beyond proof. For Bonaventure, only Franciscan conversion reveals the existence and presence of God.Theological argument is a way of ascent, not proof. In contrast, for the great Dominican,Thomas Aquinas, theology works not to edify, but to defend the faith. Matthews reviews Thomas’s commentary on Boethius’s De Trinitate and the De ente et essentia, but his primary focus is on the Summa contra Gentiles.Thomas’s primary goal, he says, is to establish an account of God’s unity that is totally acceptable to his primary opponents, the Muslims, so that he can teach them the truth of the Trinity. The mission of preaching to the unconverted requires equal access to the sources of knowledge; if only the converted can understand, then there 206 Book Reviews is no reason to preach. Thus Thomas uses an Aristotelian proof for God’s existence and discards the Franciscan reading of Anselm. In so doing, Thomas has no interest in the historical Anselm and his monastic world. His concern is to find a more accessible argument for preaching—and to reject the Franciscan priority of the will over the intellect. Matthews shows Thomas’s affinity with his confreres Peter of Tarentaise, Annibald d’Annibald, and the obscure and totally unconnected Bombolognous of Bologna. In his final substantive chapter, Matthews reviews later intellectual developments within the two orders.The Dominicans Robert Kilwardby, Thomas Sutton, Robert D’Orford, and Bernard of Trilla continued to discuss and debate the principles of Thomas and Dominican spirituality. Ulrich of Strasbourg is particularly interesting for his German variations on the Dominican theme—far from the missions and from scholastic debate. Among the Friars Minor, John Peckham and Matthew of Acquasparta developed Bonaventure’s argument in response to Thomist critiques. Richard of Middleton,William of Ware, and Duns Scotus, however, gradually shifted the Franciscan argument away from Bonaventure’s vulnerable illuminationism toward a greater emphasis on the will—a significant move because it shows their commitment not to Bonaventure’s theology but to a spirituality of conversion. Matthews draws two conclusions. First, Thomas and Bonaventure are not the last word in Dominican and Franciscan theology. Second, the theological schools of thought that developed within the two orders reflect not parochialism, but the fundamental religious interests of the two communities. Matthews calls his book Reason, Community and Religious Tradition: Anselm’s Argument and the Friars, and the title reveals the two levels on which the book operates. On one level, the book is an essay in historical theology: Anselm’s argument and the friars. On another level, it argues that reason is necessarily contextualized in community and religious tradition—a critique of modernity’s penchant for objectivity. This critique seems to be Matthews’s primary concern. To Matthews, the transformation of Anselm’s devotional argument in the scholastic world of the friars, and the further opposition between Franciscan and Dominican, reveals the importance of philosophical context. The supposed rational objectivity of Anselm’s argument breaks down under the weight of different presuppositions. Thus reason can never be purely objective. This argument addresses an important concern for students of scholastic theology. Lovers of Anselm know the significance of his monastic context.They will appreciate Matthews’s critique of modern anthologies. Those who read Bonaventure and Thomas appreciate certain irreducible Book Reviews 207 contradictions: among others, the primacy of will versus intellect and illumination versus knowledge of the senses. Matthews helps to clarify these contradictions and their roots in religious commitments. But Matthews does not seem to have theologians in mind. His opening remarks are about the philosophy of religion. Locke looms large in the first few pages. In the wake of the wars of religion, says Matthews, the seventeenth century strove to establish the “common core of religions” through the pure objectivity of reason.“It is assumed [among Enlightenment thinkers] that rationality is everywhere the same, and that the issues discussed by philosophers are ‘eternal questions’ ”; philosophy is “the disinterested pursuit of truth separable from context.” (Aeterni Patris, he says, falls into this camp.) Set in this context by its opening and concluding remarks, Matthews’s book is not about medieval theology at all. It is rather a case study,“to illustrate the ways in which reason constructs itself in the course of its operations.” Matthews believes he has proved that “enquiry does not begin by removing difference and particularity, but proceeds upon and creates it.” The goal of philosophy, he shows, is not only rational consensus but also a greater understanding of difference. Such an argument betrays, perhaps, the fundamental irony of postmodernism. Matthews is at pains to disprove the rational objectivity of the Enlightenment, yet his enquiry retains the Enlightenment’s critical distance. He contradicts Enlightenment hope, but wholeheartedly accepts its sense of detached superiority. The problem, perhaps, consists in putting ultimate questions at the service of secondary ones. Matthews’s historical erudition can illuminate vital questions of conversion, knowledge, and God. Theologians of the last century have gained much from a deeper appreciation of the fundamental assumptions of great thinkers—das Ungesagte, says Josef Pieper. Seeing these presuppositions helps us to appreciate the full value of a theology, and even of contradicting theologies, like those of Bonaventure and Thomas. The modern project, however, has often reduced ultimate questions to historical curiosities, putting the master at the servant’s service. Thus Matthews’s introduction and conclusion strive not to understand the truth of things, but to prove reason’s inability to transcend commitments. Significantly, this reversal clouds his full appreciation of the historical. Arguing that religious commitments are prior to rational inquiry, Matthews sides with the Franciscans, but relativizes their search for the true God. He correctly shows the missionary impulse of the Dominicans, but his eagerness to set them against the Franciscans neglects their contemplative piety. Bernard Gui’s official Legenda remembers Thomas, the great theologian of the missions, not for his missionary zeal, but for 208 Book Reviews his prayer and simple charity. Fra Angelico shows his founder lost in prayer beneath the cross.The preachers were first of all pious friars. And so perhaps we best return to Tugwell’s distinction between the apostolic life and the apostolic life, a distinction that recognizes unity in difference—unity of friars caught up in the love of Christ. Only at the service N&V of this fundamental commitment does history truly come to life. Eric M. Johnston The Catholic University of America Washington, DC Sexual Ethics:The Meaning and Foundations of Sexual Morality by Aurel Kolnai, translated and edited by Francis Dunlop (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate Publishing, 2005), xviii + 316 pp. I N RECENT YEARS some theologians have promoted the image of the exile as a model of Christian life.The image is meant to convey that the Christian has no home save in Christ.This aspect of the image is wonderful, biblical, and true. Less positively, the image would have us separate ourselves from earthly loyalties, perhaps even to contemn the world, but certainly to nourish low expectations of the world. The world and its secular polities are only the Bible’s “principalities,” and the order and forms of life offered there are little better than thralldom. Defenders of the Christian-as-exile idea believe the Church is better served by this than the older (but not really old) idea of the Christian of national loyalties who has made accommodations with a particular ordering of secular life.The personal story of Kolnai is a refutation of this claim. Aurel Kolnai, later Aurel Thomas Kolnai upon his conversion to Catholicism, was an exile much of his life. Born Aurel Stein (1900–73) to a banking family of liberal Jews, Kolnai, a truly cosmopolitan man and eccentric of the first order, fled Europe in his late thirties to live in poverty for the rest of his life, landing occasional academic grants and university positions. After living in America and Canada, he settled in England, a country he loved. There he remained for the rest of his life teaching as an adjunct at Bedford College, one of the colleges of the University of London. Kolnai was not just brilliant, he was probably one of the greatest Catholic minds of the last century. Any reader of his Sexual Ethics will agree with this statement. Readers should not fear that a book on sexual ethics written seventy-odd years ago will be laughably naïve. Kolnai lived in the pluralistic Austro-Hungarian Empire before and after its cataclysmic end in World War I. His book has philosophical explorations not merely of marriage but a host of perversions and sexual pathologies.True, there is Book Reviews 209 no mention of gay marriage nor had abortion yet been woven into European sex lives; but otherwise the sexual landscape is little different now than when Kolnai wrote. Found in the book are fascinating analyses of fetish, prostitution, masochism, homosexuality, and other perversions of sex values.Yet why has the Church been deprived of the ideas of this book for more than seventy years? As a personalist belonging to the school of Scheler, Kolnai’s book ought to have earned a readership because of the huge interest in John Paul II’s work. But it is only now, some thirty years after his death, that Kolnai’s works are being edited and published: For the first time Kolnai is gaining the readership he deserved all along. I suggest that his living an impoverished exile not only forced constant disruptions in his work,1 but robbed him of a stable national academic community that could claim his work for itself. It is quite easy to be an intellectual whose books are read when one has produced graduate students who enter the academy and when one is able to build a network of colleagues who ensure your books are published and promoted.And thank goodness this is true! If the Church needs ideas then she also needs a stable secular order with its academies and economic production and distribution networks to disseminate those ideas. The Church has not been well served by Kolnai’s exile. Let us rejoice, however, that now his contributions can start to be felt. Enormous praise must be given to Francis Dunlop who has been tireless in editing and translating Kolnai’s largest works.The Church must also be grateful to intellectuals who have no especial connection with her. Thinkers like David Wiggins, Roger Scruton, and Bernard Williams, doyens of the English philosophical world, have all supported or expressed great admiration for Kolnai’s work. It is easy to see why despite the unfashionable quality of his ideas. There is an “ethical precariousness” to sex, says Kolnai. Every civilization recognizes that there is an inherent tendency in sex toward evil, and this because sexual pleasure destroys personal values. Sex is a depersonalizing power (49). Hence Kolnai’s comment, “the idea that the ‘infamous’ forms of sex should be treated as ‘imperfect’ forms of an ideally perfected and ennobled form of Eros, is utterly mistaken” (90). Persons are spiritual bearers of intrinsic value and will.As each person has intrinsic value so each person is separate one from another, and the structure of value reality is a protection of this distinctive distance. However, whilst the intentionality of sexual pleasure, a topic handily ignored by those who would valorize sex, is always an intending of the 1 Kolnai’s magnum opus, a work on phenomenological ethics, was delivered in manuscript form to the German publisher around the time he fled Europe and was probably destroyed in a bombing raid.The manuscript is lost at any rate. 210 Book Reviews other sex, it is also an abandonment of the persons involved. Sex is an abandonment of the person because in orgasm the person becomes “all sex,” and every sex act is structurally directed to orgasm. Stepping back into human appetite is also removing oneself from the moral order, and John Paul II’s later reflection on the strange intermingling of sex and homicide is here structurally announced with great phenomenological precision.The morally problematic center of sexual pleasure is not only that it opens and then closes off access to the other but that there is a diminishment of the self as well as the self is absorbed into the “matter” of sex.This “matter” is voluptuousness, and its antipersonalist feature is its subjection of the person to the homogeneity of vital bodiliness (45 & 65).Voluptuousness trivializes the person:There is no engagement with a person but merely the use of a person as an instrument of “diversion” (44). Those familiar with Kolnai’s seminal essays in political theory from the late 1940s will recognize the theme of privilege. The person is a site of privilege ever threatened in sex by a tendency of appetite toward collectivism. Announced here are the lineaments of John Paul the Great’s shocking claim in Evangelium Vitae (no. 20) that the sexual politics of contemporary liberal democracy is a “form of totalitarianism,” However, sex is also a good for “conjugal love is already anticipated in all sexual love” (131).The intentionality of sexual pleasure might be inherently problematic but it is subtended by the intentionality of sexual love, which aims at an overcoming of its own voluptuousness. Sexual love imposes a limit on itself, for it has a peculiar devotional structure “radically exalting” the beloved over others (131).That is, sexual love is selective and privilege generating. There is thus a continuity—albeit problematic— between sexual love and conjugal love. Moreover, voluptuousness interiorly ordered to orgasm is also interiorly ordered to the affirmation of persons: persons created by sex. Marriage is the form of life that does “justice to both nature and the person” (92). Marriage transforms the human devotion of sexual love into “a principled conception of the partner as an ‘equal’ possessor of value and will” (123). Thus sex inside marriage is taken up into a form of life that privileges persons: spouses and children. If sexual pleasure is morally precarious because of its depersonalizing power marriage fosters the “more real presence” of persons (125). Kolnai was not a moral theologian nor even a Thomist in any strict sense. His work is a largely phenomenological reflection on sexuality and so in a language of public reason.To Kolnai’s mind, the language we use to describe the moral world closely tracks the natural order, or what he liked to call “ordinary moral consciousness.”What might strike some as a philosophical populism was, for Kolnai, an anchor for an exile and all his Book Reviews 211 cosmopolitan credentials and many fluent languages (he wrote philosophy in Hungarian, German, French, Spanish, and English!) never sundered his conviction that a broad moral consensus existed; one that had to be protected from ideological perversion. Kolnai must, of course, be read for his intrinsic worth but it should be obvious by now that his Sexual Ethics is essential reading alongside Wojtyla’s work on the same subject. I have touched upon only a few of the riches of this book. Even with the themes addressed here, I have not conveyed the subtleties of the analyses nor their thoroughness. (The book’s 300 pages do not convey just how long the book is:The typeface is very small.) There is every reason to expect that this translation of Kolnai’s brilliant 1930 book will help return the school of Scheler to some prominence in Catholic ethical reflection.And perhaps there are grounds for a deeper hope. Could a claim made in Roger Scruton’s preface to the text yet come true? Scruton says something rather remarkable. He speculates that had Kolnai’s work been common currency in humanities departments around the time of the Kinsey Report that document would have been rejected for the obvious nonsense it is. Given the pernicious consequences that report helped generate in American life we must hope that Kolnai may yet have decisive influence. It is very frustrating that the book is so expensive, making it impossible for classroom use! Still, this book should be read by every serious Catholic intellectual.The Church and her mission would be N&V well served were this to happen. G. J. McAleer Loyola College in Maryland Baltimore, Maryland The Nuptial Mystery by Angelo Cardinal Scola, translated by Michelle K. Borras (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans, 2005), xi + 405 pp. T HE ENCYCLICAL of Pope Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est has something in common with Angelo Cardinal Scola’s book, The Nuptial Mystery. They both draw on the pioneering work of John Paul II, who was in turn inspired by Vatican Council II (especially, Gaudium et Spes) to illuminate human, especially spousal, love as a path to divine love and the fulfillment of the commandment to love.The encyclical emphasizes the importance of incarnating love in all aspects of the Church’s charitable activity. Scola proposes the nuptial mystery of love, sexual difference, and procreation as the analogatum princeps of all reality, both ascending and descending, and a legitimate “key to the intellectus fidei of revelation” (393). It provides, in his view, a basis for the renewal of philosophical and theological studies in 212 Book Reviews seminaries (345), as well as a new, much needed perspective in systematic theology. Such a bold claim alone from a papabile, currently patriarch of Venice, merits a careful reading of this book. Like the future Pope Benedict XVI, Scola collaborated in the founding of the journal Communio, in the English edition of which several chapters of this book originally appeared. He was educated in the Venegono seminary, where he came under the influence of Luigi Giussani, founder of the ecclesial movement Communion and Liberation. Scola’s work is stamped with the emphasis on foundations and experience that mark the Venegono school of theology. His subsequent career combined pastoral work with two periods teaching at the John Paul II Institute for Studies on Marriage and Family in Rome, becoming president in the 1990s. His most formative work flowed from this teaching. Scola’s background as a teacher, in fact, dictates the style of The Nuptial Mystery. Several chapters were originally given as lectures or papers at conferences. “Fundamental human experiences” are for Scola the inescapable ground for exploring the nuptial mystery, which includes the inseparable and intertwining factors of sexual difference, love (a relation to the other as gift), and fruitfulness. The dual unity of man and woman constitutes the starting point and also the nuptial mystery’s horizontal dimension. Analogy allows one to pass from the horizontal to the vertical dimension reaching ultimately to God himself in the Trinity. From this starting point the nuptial mystery can find new depths in the Christian mysteries of Jesus Christ, the Church, and the sacraments.Why this new articulation now? The culture, from rejecting Humanae Vitae and the perennial doctrine of the inseparability of the unitive and procreative dimensions of conjugal intercourse, has progressed to endorsing a form of androgyny that brings about a veritable “anthropological mutation.” Scola posits that a return to the fundamental human experience of marriage and family, which contains within itself the original structure of being, can reinstate reasoned argument on the human being and at the same time show how nuptiality is a constitutive part of God’s plan revealed in Scripture. Scola presents his argument in four parts with the first given to the dual unity of man and woman and the meaning of sexual difference. The second fleshes out the nuptial mystery from a theological perspective, and the third looks at its implications in family and society.With the accent on the word “mystery,” section four considers sacramental theology in light of the nuptial mystery. The three chapters devoted to fatherhood and motherhood in relation to God the Father, Christ as Bridegroom of the Church, and the Holy Spirit as the “principle of nuptiality,” are particularly rich in new insights on both consecrated celibacy and the sacrament Book Reviews 213 of marriage.The seven articles included in the appendices are by no means marginal. In fact it is here in numbers 4 and 7 that Scola proposes that all that has gone before constitutes a new perspective for systematic theology. From the outset Scola makes clear that pontifical teaching is his point of departure, not studies in theology, philosophy, or the human sciences. To discover the meaning of identity and difference his primary texts are John Paul II’s apostolic letter Mulieris Dignitatem and the Wednesday catecheses on the theology of the body, both of which draw heavily on Scripture. In the Genesis texts John Paul II identifies four essential features, Man exists always as either masculine or feminine; sexual difference must be understood ontologically, and their union is asymmetrical, not two halves of a whole; sexual difference belongs to the image so that sexuality is neither purely animal nor spiritual. Finally “spousal love is the analogatum princeps of every kind of love” (9). The foundation of their dual unity is the mystery of Christ (cf. Gaudium et Spes, no. 22) whose incarnation is a spousal relation of his divine and human natures and issues from the heart of the Trinity. Briefly, difference is for the sake of unity, which is realized in reciprocity. The unity of Christ and the Church is the fulfillment of the mystery and the origin of the original man–woman pair, Adam and Eve.The union must be fruitful; Mary’s motherhood corresponds to Eve’s with motherhood itself tied to the woman’s very nature. The important innovation in all this, proposed by the magisterium, is the raising of sexuality to the level of the imago Dei (34). It means that either the gender difference has its ultimate foundation in the Trinitarian, Christological, and ecclesial mysteries of Revelation or it simply has reference to human reproduction and its moral requirements. Chapter four takes up the way sexual love in marriage, far from being debased by passion is the paradigmatic form of love. Scola draws on Aquinas to show how amor naturalis, which depends on voluntas ut ratio, is a constituent of all love, even the highest mystical union. The human being’s potential for choosing does not take place from a tabula rasa but from a specific inclination to the good. Love then is the fruit of a choice arising from a desire already within the person.“If the love of desire is an affective passio, the love of election is an effective choice.” In summary the way lies open for eros to be assumed into agape, which John Paul II describes in the theology of the body as eros and ethos meeting in the human heart.With the redemption of the body the conjugal love of the human spouses, instead of being a barrier to holiness in a Manichaean interpretation of sexuality, is on a continuum with consecrated virginal and divine love. Benedict XVI says in Deus caritas est, “eros and agape— 214 Book Reviews ascending and descending love—can never be completely separated” (Deus caritas est, no. 7). He takes this to its logical conclusion by positing erotic love in God himself. “God loves, and his love may certainly be called eros but it is also totally agape” (Deus caritas est, no. 9). Chapter five then draws all these threads together to describe the nuptial mystery at all its different levels analogically. Even though modern man, as Scola says, takes a utilitarian approach to sexual pleasure, it is easier to welcome the new emphasis on the goodness of conjugal union than the Church’s insistence on the openness to procreation. Fruitfulness is central to the nuptial mystery. Procreation essentially belongs to the conjugal act. “Sexual difference as difference (duality) in unity, inscribing difference in the ‘I’ itself, shows that fruitfulness is the full ‘face’ of asymmetrical reciprocity.’ ” Conjugal union is not and can never be a search for an androgynous union of two halves.That is to deny the internal difference of the masculine and feminine “I.”The other always remains other, and it is only out of dual unity that a third “I” issues, in an analogy of the perfect communio personarum, in the Trinity.The Son is begotten by the Father and the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son.The conjugal act is a spiritual act because it brings forth a child who is an imago Dei. Having outlined the nuptial mystery, Scola proceeds to engage the culture. Here he finds a crisis of freedom and value. Freedom of choice has become the whole of freedom detached from any relation to the natural law. Modern man has lost the capacity for truth as adaequatio intellectus et rei. Scola shows brilliantly how freedom unhinged from the real and from God ends in nihilism and relativism with disastrous consequences for the family, especially fatherhood and motherhood. While theology and philosophy are not the point of departure for Scola’s study, he states in chapter twelve, that the various aspects of the nuptial mystery need to be explored with the criteria of the human sciences, philosophy, and theology. He proceeds to critique contemporary philosophical views, particularly “scientific universalism,” which subscribes to an absolute subjectivism and at the same time claims to explain all human reality from an empirically measurable perspective. No room remains for the domain of “mystery,” which Scola defines not as something unknowable but rather as a place where the infinite somehow makes itself present (85). In this sense sexual difference is a privileged place for the domain of mystery. This section of the text is important for understanding Scola’s methodology. In explicating the insuperable sexual difference, he refers both to the Heideggerian theme of ontological difference and Aquinas’s distinctio realis, which Scola shows overcomes the deficiency in Heidegger. From this and other comments it is clear that Scola’s meta- Book Reviews 215 physics are firmly based on Thomism (he wrote his doctoral dissertation on Aquinas), although he does coin a new category,“symbolic ontology,” to account for what he calls the dramatic nature of reality. Truth has a “symbolic character.” Being itself cannot be encompassed by man so that technically it is indeducible but it communicates itself in a sign, which Scola calls an “e-vent.” Being discloses itself to the subject so that the subject can cleave to it. In order for man to adhere to the being that is disclosed in the sign, man must choose it in freedom.Yet he cannot resolve the difference that lies at the heart of the being disclosed. The other always remains a mystery. It is that difference that allows relationship. In the ontological difference there is a continuous interplay between the gift and freedom. Sexual difference always presents itself to the other as an invitation to form its identity, and it is always fruitful (226–27). On the theological plane “the logic of the Incarnation,” says Scola, “allows us to experience Jesus Christ as an event and not as an abstract idea” (262).The ontological difference appears most fully in the God-man relation. The difference allows for the gratuitous nature of the gift and man’s freedom in responding. The Sacrament of the Eucharist underlines both this difference and man’s response. The unity of body and soul, indeed, calls for the logic of the sacrament, since the body is the “sacrament of the person.”The relation between Christ and the Church is the form of spousal love and possesses within it the ultimate significance of the relation between man and woman. The Christ–Church union is actualized in a unique way in marriage as an indissoluble communion of persons, which becomes an efficacious sign and sacrament. At the same time consecrated virginity is the summit of nuptiality in loving the other exclusively in Christ (270). Through the concept of analogy Scola concludes that the spousal analogy of sexual difference functions as a privileged path to explore the nuptial mystery and the whole of reality as ordered to communion on the basis of a prior gift. Scola recognizes that the whole concept of analogy since St. Thomas has undergone criticism as well as evolution. He holds that Von Balthasar’s notion of the analogia libertatis is able to overcome the critical objections. For those who read this book, the centrality of analogy as both a theological and a philosophical method is likely to influence their judgment on its conclusions. For Scola every encounter with the nuptial mystery both vertical and horizontal “must always pass through a new act of testimony on the part of the individual” calling to his freedom (403).Thought must always become experience. He believes the very openness of the perspective of the nuptial mystery as a foundation “offers a systematic perspective—but one never to be taken for granted or possessed—for the 216 Book Reviews intellectus fidei.”Whether one accepts the methodological premises or not, Scola in The Nuptial Mystery has presented a compelling synthesis of the truths of the faith and a Christian anthropology both inspiring and necessary to meet the challenges to the humanum today. N&V Mary Shivanandan John Paul II Institute for Studies on Marriage & Family at the Catholic University of America Washington, DC The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ by Bernard J. F. Lonergan, SJ, edited by Michael G. Shields and Frederick E. Crowe, SJ (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2002), 350 pp. E VEN THOUGH the shiny white cover with gold and black type invites one to open Bernard Lonergan’s The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ, one might wonder what his 1964 Latin text and new English translation by Michael Shields has to say for today. Plenty. First, as we seek to construct a theological view of Christ that highlights the human and the personal, we need to see the value of those first 600 years of tradition, when the faithful, theologians, and emperors, each with his own agenda, battled over how to speak about Christ. Lonergan does. He sees this tradition as a given of faith. Nonetheless he is aware that unless he shows the possibility of Christ being human as well as divine, and of being a single subject capable of growth and personality, he will likely hear the Athenians saying, “We’ll speak of this some other time”! To meet this challenge Lonergan closely adheres to the methodological requirements of theology and of philosophy to come to a creative understanding of Christ. He was known to be human but one person with God. He had a consciousness of himself and knowledge of God, yet lived an experiential life like our own. In order to see how this is possible, it is necessary to trace Lonergan’s thought as he moves between subjective and objective points of view, between a theological and a scientific methodology, and between the “what is” of consciousness and the “what is” of knowledge. While Lonergan’s book is divided into six parts, his actual frame of reference is twofold. Because psychological operations arise from a person’s being, he first discusses the ontological constitution of Christ in parts I to IV, before examining Jesus’ consciousness in parts V and VI. Of Christ’s constitution Lonergan asks,“Why is the assumed nature of Christ not a human person?”And, if he is not a human person, how then can “Christ as God and as man” be “one and the same, divided only in reflective thought, but one supposit, one being, one reality?(5)” Book Reviews 217 Lonergan reveals his approach to this question in Part I. Holding that knowing is by identity, he addresses the subject seeking to know before addressing the object to be known. Anticipating his functional specialty “foundations,” he examines the notion of “existenz,” that is, the subject knowing (19ff). He holds that in order to know the being of Christ, who as man is known by reason and as God known by faith, one’s own being must have the same configuration. One must be conscious, knowing, and committed in faith (31). As for the object to be known, Christ is a person, the highest form of being. Not only is “person” one, subsistent, and distinct, but it is intelligent, that is, capable of performing the highest of operations (31ff). So, in Part II, before dealing with the person of Christ Lonergan examines what constitutes a finite person. However, since “constitution” refers to causality, Lonergan first discusses that which exerts “an influence on the existence of something” (47). Using the principle that “things that differ in intelligibility differ in reality,” Lonergan establishes that a thing has distinct causes, extrinsic and intrinsic (53). If one said that “extrinsic cause” is a mental construct, one would have to say that contingent beings have no extrinsic cause, which is absurd.Also, just as to understand what a thing is is distinct from judging that it is, that is, a reality born of evidence and not a fantasy of the mind, so the being that is known is constituted by distinct causes. One accounts for its essence and the other for its existence! A finite being is that which has an essence that is not its act of existence and has its existence from a self-existing extrinsic cause. Lonergan then moves to discuss what constitutes a finite person. As it is, a “distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature,” it needs the essence of an intellectual nature, otherwise it would not be a being that is intelligent. It needs an act of existence, otherwise it would not be a subsistent being. Its existence must be received by the human essence, otherwise one is dealing with God whose essence is its existence. The act of existence must be proper to that essence, otherwise it would be another’s act of existence, and thus not a human person (59–61). In Part IV, Lonergan considers Christ. First he lays out what is of faith, “the Dogma of the Incarnation” (107ff).Then to understand Christ, he uses philosophical methodology to resolve his being as human into its “causes,” and theological methodology to resolve his being as divine into its “reasons.” Since the Incarnation refers to God, one’s deeper understanding of it cannot be attained through resolving a thing into its causes, for God has no causes. One must use reason to take what God reveals and formulate principles of reason by which one can better understand it.Thus, of the revelation that Christ is God, one can reason that as he has every power 218 Book Reviews he is able to assume a contingent reality to himself, namely human nature (83, 87). As man, however, Christ has causes.To better understand him, therefore, one resolves his being into its causes. These are two: One is the essential human nature and the other is its act of existence. As essential human nature is in potency for an act of existence, it can be either proportionate to that nature or exceeding it. But as being God Christ’s act of existence exceeds what is proportionate to human nature. He is, then, not a finite person, as having a proportionate existence, but a human nature whose act of existence belongs to another, God (113). The problem is to explain how these truths of faith and reason come together into a unity. Working with the notion that one can know the being of God only analogously, Lonergan judiciously rejects “what we naturally know about the composition of a finite being” and turns to what “we naturally know about God” (131).We know that the being of God is not “some kind of material principle that always acts the same way by blind necessity” (133ff). Rather God’s existence acts the way God’s understanding does. Just as God can think and will, that is, terminate in, what is contingent as well as in what is necessary, so also can God’s act of existence. First one can say that Christ’s human nature, known and willed by God, can be related to God as term of God’s act of existence. Second one can say that since God can think and will that this contingent reality of Christ’s human nature be related only to the Son, so it is related to the Son and not to the Father and/or Holy Spirit. Next, Lonergan discusses Christ’s consciousness. In Part VI, he considers human consciousness. Consciousness is of one’s self, the “subject,” and of one’s acts. It is not introspection or knowledge about one’s self, as these refer to the “object.” Consciousness is presence to one’s being and one’s acts, but not the being of one’s self as it is an object of knowledge (157–65). To get this knowledge one must go beyond experience to acts of understanding and judgment.Thus to come to a knowledge of one’s self as sentient, one would have to experience one’s self as sensing, understand what sensing is, and then judge whether one’s experience matches one’s understanding. If there is a match, one knows one’s self as sentient. One would have to go through a similar process regarding acts of understanding and judgment. Lonergan’s theorem is that the way one understands consciousness seriously affects the way one understands Christ. On the one hand, if one understands consciousness as experience, one can say that Christ was humanly conscious of his divine person, when he was seeing, under- Book Reviews 219 standing, and willing various things. On the other hand, if one understands consciousness as perception, then one has to make the very odd statement that when Christ did not have himself as an object of perception he was not humanly conscious of himself! In Part VI, Lonergan examines the consciousness of Christ. First, how is Christ, as God, conscious? To answer this question, Lonergan leads the reader from understanding that God is conscious of himself through his acts, to seeing that these acts can be shared in common by the persons of the Trinity and then to seeing that there are notional acts that are proper to each person (195ff). Then Lonergan asks,“Are they conscious not just of their notional acts but of themselves as distinct subjects?” More specifically,“Is the person of Christ as person . . . conscious?” Yes. As the notional acts of each of the three persons are different, so is the consciousness of these acts. As these notional acts give rise to relations that are given subsistence through God's act of existence, then what is constitutive of person is present. So the Son, though his notional act of being begotten, is conscious of his own person (201–3). As to the human consciousness of Christ, Lonergan recalls that consciousness is awareness of both one’s being and one’s acts. Since Christ the man is constituted by his human nature and the act of existence of his divine person, Christ is conscious of both his human nature and his person, since his person is identified with his act of existence. He becomes conscious of his person when he performs his human operations. Consequently Christ, like us, was able to experience life in its complexity, seeking to understand that experience, checking that understanding with further evidence, and making decisions. Should he stay in his Father’s house talking and asking questions or leave in obedience to his mother and father. Such operations are the basis for forming one’s personality. Lonergan makes another assertion. Christ knows himself as the natural Son of God and true God. For this to happen, two things are required, consciousness of self and beatific vision. One can only judge who one is by grasping the match between what is known and what one is conscious of.To know what God is in himself and to know what others are in God, beatific vision of the divine essence is required.To be humanly conscious of his divine person, Christ has to perform his human operations.When these two requirements are met, Christ can match them and thus conclude that he is natural Son of God and true God (215–19). In such an analysis, it is possible to see that just as a concept of some thing does not preclude a concept of another thing, so the concept of God’s essence, which is beatific vision, does not preclude other self-concepts, 220 Book Reviews those that Christ gained from his own reading of the Scriptures and his own self-reflection.When the gift of vision was given, it gave a higher unity to these other concepts, analogous to how the concepts of the Christological councils gave a higher unity to the scriptural designations of Christ. Lonergan concludes his work by linking what is of faith with what one says philosophically and theologically. One’s belief that the Son of God became man and really experienced what it was to be a human being must be connected with what one says theologically. If one understands consciousness as experience,“this truth of the Catholic faith follows immediately.” However, if consciousness is understood as perception, this same truth that Christ experienced what it is to be a human being “is overlooked by those who . . . take for granted that consciousness is perception” (287). From this, Lonergan draws two philosophical conclusions which show how Christian faith can help philosophy. First, for faith reasons about Christ, the notion of consciousness-as-perception must be abandoned. Second, knowledge as some form of duality must be abandoned as well. If one does not do this, then when one says God knows himself, one would be saying there are two Gods! Rather than Church teaching being a straightjacket for theology, Lonergan shows that by a close attention to the methodologies proper to what is of reason and what is of faith one’s Christology can be creative and offer much to human thought.Whether one agrees with his ChrisN&V tology or not, one has a fine example to follow. W. Jerome Bracken, C.P. Seton Hall University South Orange, New Jersey Aquinas’s Summa: Background, Structure, and Reception by Jean–Pierre Torrell, OP, translated by Benedict M. Guevin, OSB (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2005), vii + 156 pp. T HE WORK of Jean–Pierre Torrell, OP, displays a renewed understanding of St. Thomas Aquinas that goes well beyond arguments for God’s existence or the atheological natural law theory that are all too often packaged as Thomism. In the concluding salvo, Torrell describes the “most common and damaging error” in approaching the great Summa is to “have considered Thomas first of all as a philosopher and to have believed it possible to isolate certain parts of the Summa as ‘philosophical’ ” (133). To overcome this defect in appreciating St.Thomas and his greatest work, Torrell insists that his reader “give all of his attention to Thomas as a theologian, a disciple of the Fathers of the Church and an interpreter of Book Reviews 221 the Bible” (133).Torrell is a master at accentuating the theological impetus and structure of Aquinas’s greatest work—the Summa theologiae. This book is dedicated to that task. The book is structured around six chapters that present the biographical details of Thomas’s life, the structure, content, genre, and sources of the Summa, and the history of its reception. Torrell begins Aquinas’s Summa with a sketch of Aquinas’s life. He uses this first chapter to unearth important elements of Thomas’s formation that help one to better understand the various influences to which Aquinas was exposed during his early education and Dominican formation. Torrell even delightfully attempts to reconstruct “with a minimum of certainty” (6) what a normal day at St. Jacques would have been like for a magister in sacra pagina during Aquinas’s first teaching tenure in Paris from 1252–59. Perhaps the most important contribution in this biographical section is the way Torrell interweaves the major periods of Aquinas’s life with his teaching assignments and the writings that he produced at each stage. One can use this chapter as a reference point for discovering what Aquinas wrote and when he wrote it, thus leaving a genealogical means for situating any particular work of Aquinas within his whole corpus. In the second and third chapters,Torrell offers an analysis of the structure and content of the Summa. It is here that he is at his best.Torrell reads the Summa and explains its content by adhering to the internal structure or ordo established by Aquinas.“Thomas is clear on this,”Torrell explains,“he will speak of God (I), then of the movement of the rational creature to God (II), and finally, of Christ who, in his humanity, is the way that leads to God” (18). Failing to recognize Thomas’s plan in organizing his great work contributes, Torrell contends, to the difficulty that contemporary readers have in understanding the Summa. For those of us who marvel at the socalled “novices” for whom Thomas is writing the text,Torrell assures us: No doubt he [Thomas] was thinking less about the level of difficulty of the material taught than about its organization into a body of doctrine that would offer them not simply a series of questions juxtaposed haphazardly, but rather an organic synthesis in which the internal connections and coherence of these questions might be grasped. (19) Crucial to understanding this internal coherence is Torrell’s attentive reading of the first question of the Summa, “a kind of discourse on method” (19), in which Aquinas lays forth his theological intention. In this first question Aquinas defines the discipline of the Summa as sacra doctrina, which is 222 Book Reviews broader than the modern understanding of theology because “the term [sacra doctrina] includes all forms of Christian teaching, beginning with what God says to us in Sacred Scripture” (19).The discipline of sacra doctrina is thus affirmed by Aquinas to be a science insofar as it advances “the reasoned knowledge that we have of God by placing in relation the diverse truths that we believe” (20). However, Torrell significantly adds that sacra doctrina is not simply one discipline or science among many. Rather, Aquinas sees this discipline in terms of its sapiential dimension: “[M]ore than ‘science,’ ”Torrell clarifies,“sacred doctrine is ‘wisdom,’ that is, knowledge by the supreme cause” (20). Consequently, “God presents himself as the first subject of theology, and it is with respect to him that all of the rest is situated, not in the sense of being juxtaposed to him, but rather dependent on him and explained by him” (20).Torrell remains consistently mindful of the parameters that Thomas establishes in this first question, and he draws on the concept of sacra doctrina in his explanation of each part of the Summa, and in showing the contribution that each part makes to the project of sacra doctrina as a whole. In Prima pars of the Summa, Aquinas presents God and the procession of creatures from God. St.Thomas divides his treatment of God into two parts: first, a consideration of the divine essence (qq. 2–26), and second, a consideration of the distinction of persons (qq. 27–43).Torrell notes that the first division is often referred to as a philosophical treatment of God, but he quickly adds that the reduction of Aquinas’s treatment of the divine essence to philosophy is not in keeping with the intentions of the author. He is writing a Summa of theology and the God about whom he speaks has nothing in common with that spoken of by the deist philosophers but is instead the living God of the Bible, who has revealed himself in salvation history. Knowledge of him is not attained until he has been understood as a trinity of persons. . . .The break between the two sections serves only a pedagogical function; it should not be understood as a separation. (21) As a segue between his treatment of the Prima and Secunda partes and in his introduction to the third part,Torrell weighs in on the long debated issue of the place of Christ within the plan of the Summa. St. Thomas’s placement of the moral life between the Treatise on God in the Prima pars and the Treatise on Christ in the Tertia pars has left thinkers pondering the importance of Christ within the Summa’s overall structure. Following a vast body of literature on this issue,Torrell identifies a circular plan that governs the whole of the Summa. With this in mind, the reader is not tempted to treat the Secunda pars independent of God or Christ, because Book Reviews 223 the circular plan, starting from and returning to God, “is like a subterranean current that unifies, by tying together the three parts and their multiple treatises” (27). Torrell, therefore, summarizes Aquinas’s exposition of the moral life in terms of the end—beatitude—and the means for attaining beatitude, which include the vast content found in the whole of the second part. Directly addressing the debate about the place of Christ in the Summa,Torrell explains: [T]he end will not be achieved without grace and without following Christ who came to show us, in his humanity, the way to happiness. . . . Between the study of human action described in the Second Part and that of the happy life which concludes the Summa,Thomas will insert, in the Third Part, a study of Christ—“the unique mediator between God and humanity” (1 Tim 2.5)—and the sacraments which are part of the “means” left to his followers to assist them in reaching their end. (29) When Torrell begins his presentation of the Treatise on Christ in the Tertia pars, he insightfully argues that the tripartite structure announced by Aquinas at the beginning of the Summa “corresponds to real internal necessities” (48–49). However, standing above the three parts of the Summa: God, Moral Theology, and Christology, is a “superimposed” “bipartite” vision which “retrieves a distinction that is familiar to the Fathers of the Church between ‘theology’—the consideration of God in himself. . . .— and ‘economy’—the work of God as it is accomplished in time, that is, salvation history” (49).This superimposed bipartite reading of the Summa’s narrative brings to full relief the organic and irreplaceable role that Christ has in Aquinas’s moral vision and in the ordering of the work as a whole. For Aquinas, the rational creature returns to God only under the headship of Christ, who “takes the lead in this movement for he alone is able to bring it to completion” (49). Torrell carries this theologico-Christological reading of the moral life throughout his exposition of Aquinas’s position on human action and the life of virtue, pointing out that since the happiness of beatitude cannot be achieved through actions “on a purely human level” (33), God infuses into man a means of acting proportionate to the end for which he was created—namely, the gift of supernatural grace.Torrell gently reminds the modern reader of Aquinas that the various branches of theological specialization that we use to label the parts of the Summa: dogma for the first and third parts; morals and spirituality for the second part, are not labels that Aquinas would have recognized. “All of his theology,” Torrell explains,“is, at one and the same time, concrete and speculative, dogmatic and moral and, we might add, spiritual as well” (36). 224 Book Reviews The study of Christ, therefore, taken up after the moral life in the third part, is not some afterthought for Aquinas.“Christ,”Torrell points out,“is the one who allows access to beatitude.Thomas cannot be more clear: the study of Christ is necessary to achieve the goal of his theological enterprise” (50). After a detailed examination of the mysteries of Christ’s life Thomas offers a general treatment of the sacraments and a specific examination of Baptism, Confirmation, Eucharist, and Penance.Torrell keenly points out that the sacraments are strategically placed by Aquinas immediately following his treatment of Christ.The sacraments are part of God’s salvific economy, and “their efficacy comes from the efficacy of the God-man. Thomas’s study of the sacraments does not come, therefore, until after he has dealt with Christ in his being and action as the ultimate form under which comes to us the salvation begun by the earthly acts of Christ” (59). Following his rich presentation of the Summa’s theological structure, Torrell again draws upon his historical skills to offer a presentation of the “literary and doctrinal milieu” in which the Summa was born. Torrell begins the fourth chapter by noting that among the four primary literary genres of medieval theological literature (biblical and other commentaries, commentaries on the Sentences, disputed questions and quodlibets, and the Summa), the Summa was the only genre not tied directly to oral teaching. As a result, the Summa allowed the author to forge a synthesis of various topics and sources that the other literary genres could not support. Drawing on quantitative research to support his theological reading of the Summa, Torrell provides a summary of the major sources in Aquinas’s work.Torrell points out that of the “38,000 explicit citations in the Summa theologiae and the Summa contra Gentiles . . . 25,000 come from the Bible, almost two-thirds” (72). Another “8,000 come from Christian authors” while “4,300 are from the Philosopher, namely,Aristotle” (74).Torrell does not downplay the importance of Aquinas’s use of Aristotle. He simply wishes to “not overemphasize Aristotle’s contribution to such an extent as to push into the background other sources that, statistically and doctrinally, are even more important” (74). Torrell then summarizes each of Aquinas’s major non-Christian sources: Aristotle, Medieval Platonism, the Stoics, Avicenna, Averroës, and Maimonides.This section does not do full justice to each source, but Torrell does a balanced job of highlighting both what Aquinas retained from each thinker and what he saw fit to correct. He also briefly sketches how Aquinas’s use of each thinker evolved as his life went on. In the final two chapters, Torrell offers an analysis of the “Summa through History,” treating the reception and polemics surrounding the Summa as well as the history of Thomism vis-à-vis the vast tradition of Book Reviews 225 commentators and the renewal associated with Leo XIII’s encyclical letter Aeterni Patris.Those who wish to study specific thinkers, works, and phases in the history of Thomism will find this rapid account a helpful appetizer. Torrell’s balanced presentation of Cajetan, Vitoria and the School of Salamanca, John of St. Thomas, the Jesuits and Carmelites, while brief, pinpoints several areas of interest and needed research. The reader will also find interesting Torrell’s identification of the various journals, publications—including the English edition of Nova et Vetera—and institutions dedicated to the study of St.Thomas Aquinas. However familiar one is with the work of Fr. Jean–Pierre Torrell, it is certain that his warm contemplative approach to theology and to his elder Dominican confrere will leave the reader with both an appreciation for his continued contribution to Thomistic studies and a desire to read N&V or reread Aquinas—prayerfully and theologically. Roger W. Nutt Ave Maria University Naples, Florida Mary,“Mediatress of Grace.” Mary’s Universal Mediation of Grace in the Theological and Pastoral Works of Cardinal Mercier. Supplement of “Mary at the Foot of the Cross” IV by Manfred Hauke (New Bedford, MA:Academy of the Immaculate, 2004), 183 pp. M ANFRED H AUKE has produced a well-researched study of the Mariological thought and initiatives of the “Great Cardinal” of Malines, Belgium, Désiré Joseph Cardinal Mercier (1851–1926). Cardinal Mercier is known for his philosophical acumen and for his pastoral zeal, having hosted ecumenical dialogues long before the Vatican encouraged them (the “Malines Conversations”). Further, he founded an institute for experimental psychology. Surprisingly, he is almost unrecognized—in the general scholarship—for what he took to be the very heart of his pastoral mission, to promote a dogmatic definition of Mary as “Mediatrix (or Mediatress) of all Graces.” In a letter to fellow prelate Cardinal Vico, he confides, “The proclamation of the dogma must remain the goal of all our efforts” (76). Despite both his theological and pastoral efforts in this regard, Mercier’s thought has been much neglected. The entry for the latest edition of the ODCC does not even mention his passion for Mary. Long overdue, then, is this fine study of the Great Cardinal’s Mariological work. The book is historical in approach, though the author brings his wellknown excellence in systematic theology to the task. Copiously documented in the notes while easily understood in the main text, it is available 226 Book Reviews to educated readers and well-suited for historians, who, if enkindled with Mercier’s love of Mary, may wish to follow up with studies of their own. Such studies are needed, as the author himself attests, since not all materials are yet available, especially the archives of the so-called “Roman Commission,” one of three commissions established to examine the theological background, systematic content, and practicality of a definition on Mary as Mediatrix of all graces. Here, Hauke lays groundwork upon which others can build. The book closes with an exhortation: One of the more important virtues needed for those supportive of a dogmatic definition is— patience. That, prayer, and hard theological work. A dogmatic definition requires much painstaking discussion and clarification. Any reader of Mary, Mediatress will benefit by learning about a number of the major players, theological and hierarchical, in the early twentiethcentury debates, including such theologians in favor of a definition as Garrigou-Lagrange and Lebon, as well as such theologians opposed to a definition (for various reasons) as De la Taille and Billot. The careful reader will encounter some of the subtleties of the issues at stake.There is no demonizing at play here. Further, readers unfamiliar with this issue will witness the wide palette of Mercier’s approaches. For one, Mercier almost single-handedly obtained permission for the celebration of the Feast of Mary, Mediatrix of All Graces (May 31) in his diocese. Over 400 other dioceses soon joined in this annual celebration. About the same number of bishops (coincidence?) joined Mercier’s efforts to petition Rome on behalf of a definition. Perhaps no small number of readers will be surprised to discover that there was, in the early 1900s, a general consensus that Mary was in fact the Mediatrix of all actual graces after her Assumption (a doctrine, now defined, also universally held at the time). There were, of course, numerous disputes:Was this physical dispensation or moral intercession; does her intercession include also habitual grace? Still, few theologians disputed the basic kernel of what Mercier wanted defined: Mary’s universal mediation.The sensus fidei was clear on this point. Of great significance in this book, also, is the important role of Mary’s cooperation with Jesus’ redemptive work. Hauke underlines Mercier’s emphasis on the canonical unity between Jn 19:26 (Mary at the foot of the Cross) and Gen 3:15, the Proto-Evangelium (the first “good news” after the fall). In assenting to the Incarnation, Mary assented at least implicitly to the crucifixion of her Son (later, for certain, explicitly). Her assent gained merit congruously (fittingly, that is, not condignly or according to strict right) for the redemption of the whole human race. Garrigou-Lagrange, some of whose reflections Hauke translates here, Book Reviews 227 underscores the effective character of Mary’s “congruous” merit, for God is no exacting tyrant but a Father of “Gentle Providence.” There is a tantalizingly passing reference to the opinion of Lebon (one of Mercier’s theological collaborators) that Mary, having a right to prevent her Son’s death, cooperated in giving him over to sinful men—hence the title, CoRedemptrix (feminine for Co-Redeemer). If shocked by this claim, the reader might recall the words of Irenaeus, who said of Mary that she became the “cause of salvation to herself and to the whole world.” Often given to misunderstanding, the title “Co-Redemptrix” does not situate Mary and Jesus on the same plane, as though she were “making up” for what was essentially lacking in Christ’s sufferings. Rather, the title is grounded in the participatory character of Mary’s sufferings in and with her Son. She but participated (yet effectively!) in her Son’s sufferings, being utterly without sin and, thus, rightfully exempt from any suffering. In short, Mary became a genuine instrument within the mediation of the one mediator between God and man, the man Jesus Christ (1 Tim 2:5). Lebon’s opinion seems to me tenable at least, though as Hauke rightly notes, Lebon’s excesses in some of his other opinions prevented fruition of Mercier’s desire. Sharing this perspective on the Christo-centric character of Mary’s role but critical of a definition at the time, Grabmann cautioned that the Church must first clarify and define Christ’s role in mediation, particularly, his universal vicarious satisfaction. A background theme, rhythmically coming to the fore as the book progresses, is that of total consecration to Mary. By total consecration is meant a complete surrender to Mary’s will for oneself, now and forever. It rests on absolute trust in this humble woman who by grace was made Mother of God and of all the Church. The Catholic practice of total consecration, especially promoted by John Paul II, hinges on Mary’s universal mediation of all graces. Mercier and his supporters understood that. Does not the continued growth of this practice, indebted not only to St. Louis-Marie de Montfort but also to St. Maximilian Kolbe (a contemporary of Mercier) bode well for some future definition? Yet, will sufficient theological labor and pastoral zeal prepare the way? Hauke salutarily closes, Deus providebit. This book is also available in the original German (2004) and, with a small supplement, in Italian (2005). Finally, readers can look forward to the completion of Fr. Hauke’s work in progress: a systematic text on N&V Mary’s maternal mediation of grace. Christopher J. Malloy University of Dallas Irving,Texas 228 Book Reviews St.Thomas Aquinas and the Natural Law Tradition edited by John Goyette, Mark S. Latkovic, and Richard Myers (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2004), xxiii + 307 pp. T HIS COLLECTION provides perhaps the best introduction to contemporary discussions of natural law available. Its essays treat virtually all major topics and areas of discussion in contemporary natural law scholarship, including the relationship of natural law to theology and specifically Christian belief, the philosophical debates about the exact sense in which natural law is “natural” and the derivation of natural law, and the plausibility and applicability of natural law to contemporary political and philosophical debates. The book developed out of a conference by the same name sponsored by Sacred Heart Major Seminary and Ave Maria Law School in June of 2000, at which many of the most influential and prominent advocates of natural law were participants. The editors have divided the book into four parts.The first addresses the philosophical foundations of natural law, in particular the meaning of “nature” in natural law as explored in essays by Benedict Ashley, OP, Janet Smith, and Ralph McInerny. The next section contains essays by David Novak, Martin D. Yaffe, John Goyette, Romanus Cessario, OP, Robert Fastiggi, and Earl Muller, SJ, and focuses on the theological context of St. Thomas’s natural law teaching.The third part, in essays by William E. May, Mark S. Latkovic, and Steven A. Long, discusses the new natural law theory espoused by Germain Grisez and John Finnis and the hotly debated question as to whether the “new natural law” theory is genuinely Thomistic. Finally, Christopher Wolfe,William Mathie, Robert P. George, and Russell Hittinger discuss natural law and contemporary legal/political issues. This volume will be useful for those seeking a snapshot of the ongoing discussion of numerous crucial issues among experts within the natural law tradition. A number of the essays explore the relationship of theoretical and practical reasoning, of revelation (as interpreted in Christian and Jewish tradition) and ethical first principles, and of politics and natural law. Although at times the various contributors appear to misunderstand one another, or confusing historical questions about fidelity to the thought of St.Thomas with philosophical ones about the truth of the matter, the discussion for the most part succeeds in a fruitful engagement. Most essays tackle matters of inter-Thomistic interpretational dispute. However, some essays (such as Ashley’s and George’s) tackle objections and misunderstandings that a non-expert might have, objections against the Thomistic project itself. Those who do not specialize in natural law might also benefit especially from essays like that of Christopher Wolfe. Book Reviews 229 In his contribution, “Thomistic Natural Law and the American Natural Law Tradition,” Wolfe summarizes natural law in way that, with perhaps a few quibbles, would be acceptable to all major parties in the disputes over natural law. He then compares and contrasts this understanding with the views of the American founding fathers as well as adding a section on natural law in contemporary American life. It is of course not possible, within the limits of a short review, to give an overview of these 16 essays and responses, but most contributions are of high quality. For both those well-schooled in natural law as well as the curious beginner, St. Thomas Aquinas and the Natural Law Tradition provides a valuable take on the contemporary debates on this subject. N&V Christopher Kaczor Loyola Marymount University Los Angeles, California