Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 231–48 231 “Nature and Grace” in the Encyclical Deus Caritas Est S ERGE -T HOMAS B ONINO, OP Dominican House of Studies Toulouse, France N ATURE AND GRACE : Might this be the cryptic theme of Pope Benedict XVI’s first encyclical, which was made public on January 25, 2006?1 Of course not.The precise subject of Deus Caritas Est is one that could not be more clearly specified right from the beginning: “I wish in my first encyclical to speak of the love which God lavishes upon us and which we in turn must share with others” (no. 1). Consequently, the pontifical document is subdivided in two parts, which are distinct in many aspects but unified by the common reference to divine love, envisaged first in and of itself, and then considered as participated in the community of believers and the source of the community’s charitable energy. The goal of the first part is to “clarify some essential facts concerning the love that God mysteriously and gratuitously offers to man, together with the intrinsic link between that Love and the reality of human love” (no. 1). The second part “treats the ecclesial exercise of the commandment of love of neighbor” (no. 1), which is to say, the diakonia or service of charity (no. 19, original emphasis).The practical goal of this teaching is to “call forth in the world renewed energy and commitment in the human response to God’s love” (no. 1). This being said, it quickly becomes apparent to the theologian that, in the treatment of the encyclical’s questions, Benedict XVI uses a well thought-out and precise conception of that which is classically called “the question of the relationship between nature and grace.” In truth, even 1 This article first appeared as “ ‘Nature et grâce’ dans l’encyclique Deus Caritas Est,” trans. Shannon Gaffney, Revue Thomiste 105 (2005): 531–49. 232 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP though the concept of nature is well-attested to in the encyclical,2 it would be distorting the thoughts of the pope to force them, at any cost, to fit into the problematic, and the “Thomistic” categories, of the relationships between nature and grace. Benedict XVI does not focus as much on abstract essences as on concrete, historical situations, in such a way that the problematic of the relationships between nature and grace takes on, for him, the analogical form of a reflection on the encounter between, on the one hand, the event that is the grace of Christian revelation3—in its twofold dimension of light for the intelligence and dynamism for the will, and on the other, the historically determined human realities, personal and communal.4 For Benedict XVI, the archetype—which is constantly a subject of meditation—of this encounter is that which took place at the beginning of Christianity between Christian faith and the Greco-Latin culture of Antiquity.5 There is nothing surprising about the fact that the meditation on love that opens the encyclical is constructed on the encounter between eros, as understood in Greco-Latin culture, and agape, which defines Christian love according to the New Testament. It is also not surprising that the encyclical is full of references to the wisdom of antiquity:This comes not from a mania of an erudite German, but rather 2 Benedict XVI, encyclical letter Deus Caritas Est, January 25, 2006. The term “nature” appears at least a dozen times in the encyclical. Once it is used simply to translate the Latin, indoles (no. 28). Most of the time, it refers to the essence of a reality, that is to say to the elements and the dynamisms that define it.Thus, it concerns the nature of love (nos. 7 and 18), that of eros (no. 7), of the Church (nos. 25 and 29), and of faith (no. 28). Concerning human nature, Benedict XVI explains that God revealed to Israel “man’s true nature” (no. 9).This nature is the source and the normative justification of certain fundamental givens of human existence. It founds the natural law that manifests “what is in accord with the nature of every human being” (no. 28). In the same way,“eros is somehow rooted in man’s very nature” (no. 11) and “the command of love of neighbor is inscribed by the Creator in man’s very nature” (no. 31). 3 Cf. Benedict XVI, encyclical letter Deus Caritas Est, January 25, 2006, no. 1: “Being Christian is not the result of an ethical choice or a lofty idea, but the encounter with an event, a person, which gives life a new horizon and a decisive direction.” 4 These “human realities” are the expression of human nature defined by a constant ensemble of active and passive powers; but, as realities concretely situated in the history of Salvation, they also carry the double mark of the initial vocation of man to the supernatural, which coincides in fact with creation as the first act of the history of Salvation, and of sin that refuses this vocation and warps human nature in the sinner. 5 Cf. for example Joseph Ratzinger’s recent explorations of this theme in Values in a Time of Upheaval (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2006); and idem, On the Way to Jesus Christ (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2005), ch. 3. Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 233 from the desire to think within a horizon of the intimate relationship between the classical, pre-Christian culture and the Christian faith. The manner in which Benedict XVI envisages the encounter between Christian faith and human realities—its modalities and the causes of its success or failure—constitutes a theological structure that underlies the entire encyclical and that does not fail to contribute greatly to its unity. It effectively governs the principal problematics at play in the encyclical. In the first part, the meditation on the relationship between eros and agape clearly shows this vision of the encounter between Revelation and the order of human realities. In the second part, this same vision is at the heart of the reflection on the relationship between justice and charity, as well as on the relationship between the State and the Church as subjects of social activity with the purpose of doing good. This article aims to be a theological homage to Benedict XVI at the dawn of his pontificate. It proposes to explain, in a small way, this theological structure.To do so, two paths are possible. An inductive route, according to the ordo inventionis, would begin from different analogical realizations of this structure of the encounter in order to show, little by little, the ratio or the analogically common notion. In this article, I will follow a more deductive route, according to the ordo expositionis, which consists in first expressing the general laws of this encounter of faith and human realities, in order then to illumine the various applications that the encyclical sets forth. The General Laws of the Encounter Between Faith and Human Realities The order of natural human realities and the order of grace are two distinct orders. For example, concerning the State and the Church, the pope affirms that “the two spheres are distinct, yet always interrelated” (no. 28). Human realities are the deployment of the capacities of human reason, in the theoretical order (philosophy, science) or the practical order (justice, political life), as well as in the dynamisms of human love.The order of grace comes from a more profound gift of God: It consists on the one hand in the objective revelation of the Mystery, received in faith, and on the other hand in the dynamism of charity as participation in the love with which God loves himself and loves his spiritual creatures. In relation to nature, grace is irruption and newness: It opens “new horizons”6 to human existence. As distinct as they may be, these two orders are not called to be purely juxtaposed or to be contented with a peaceful coexistence. On the 6 Cf. Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, no. 1 and no. 28:“Faith by its specific nature is an encounter with the living God—an encounter opening up new horizons extending beyond the sphere of reason.” 234 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP contrary, they must imperatively enter into and stay in an intimate relationship with one another. A successful articulation between these two orders is characterized by three traits. First, it assumes at the very least a unity according to the analogy between the two orders. If there were no relationship between the natural human realities (for example, human love) and the supernatural realities (charity), there would be two parallel universes that never meet.7 This gets to the heart of the very pertinence of Christianity, which is to say its inscription in the real life of men. If the order of grace were “another world,” without a relationship to the historic realities of human cultures, Christianity would be reduced to a gnosis, an evasion. On the contrary, human realities offer themselves to grace as a surface of incarnation. Second, grace ripens, heals, and purifies natural human realities. This is something upon which the encyclical greatly insists.There exists in natural human realities, a sort of initial indetermination that must be lifted up in the course of their development by an encounter with faith.This makes emerge, not without suffering at times, that which is the best and most authentically human within them.8 By contrast, when they are left to themselves, that is to say, when man refuses to enter into the paschal steps that are implied in the encounter with Christian faith, these human realities can only degenerate. But, when man opens himself to grace, man becomes aware of his own mystery, which is to say the integral reality of his nature; and he can fully and truly exercise the dynamisms that constitute this nature. Third, the irruption of grace at the heart of human realities brings newness and rupture: Grace cannot be reduced to a homogenous deployment of nature.9 Nonetheless, beyond the rupture, grace also fulfills, in an 7 Cf. ibid., no. 7: “Were this antithesis [between the Greek eros and the Christian agape ] to be taken to extremes, the essence of Christianity would be detached from the vital relations fundamental to human existence, and would become a world apart, admirable perhaps, but decisively cut off from the complex fabric of human life”; and no. 8: “biblical faith does not set up a parallel universe, or one opposed to that primordial human phenomenon which is love, but rather accepts the whole man; it intervenes in his search for love in order to purify it and to reveal new dimensions of it.” 8 Cf., for example, ibid., no. 8: “Fundamentally, ‘love’ is a single reality, but with different dimensions; at different times, one or other dimension may emerge more clearly.” 9 The encyclical insists, for example, on the newness of the image of God brought by Revelation in comparison to that which circulated in ancient religions or even in Greek philosophy. This newness was not without rupture. Between Greek philosophy and Christian faith, there is not a simple homogenous development. Cf. ibid., no. 9: “The divine power that Aristotle at the height of Greek philosophy sought to grasp through reflection, is indeed for every being an object of desire Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 235 unexpected fashion, the profound wishes of human nature and carries its dynamisms to their full completion. In fact, Revelation brings certain still confused hopes which, by nature or already by grace—this question will not be discussed here—inhabit and agitate the human heart, a response that is both disconcerting and fulfilling.10 In opposition to this logic of complementarity and accomplishment are the mortifying logics of substitution and separation. In the first case, the autonomy of temporal realities is denied by religious overdetermination. Religion refuses the constituent dialogue with reason, which leads to its own degradation, to a deformation of the image of God, and in the sociopolitical arena, to a fanaticism that does not hesitate to have recourse to violence. In the second case, the logic of separation leads to the secularization and the social marginalization of Christian faith, which is denied any influence over the real life of men. A certain “gnostic” tendency in the interior itself of Christianity can, by advocating a spirituality of evasion or disengagement, favor this movement of secularization to the highest degree. Religious values, confined to a strictly private sphere, appear, in this way, to be more and more ethereal and without real interest. As for the human values which were brought by Christianity, they are, one may think, reintegrated or reabsorbed into the structures of natural order. Thus Revelation is reduced to a mere anticipation of the conquests of reason, and the charitable works of the Church to a rough sketch of the pure rationality of the providence of the State. The consequences of this separation are no less noxious to human realities than they are to Christian faith.To describe the situation that is created in nature when it is cut off from grace, the encyclical many times uses words such as degradation, debasement, and demeaning: Nature degrades itself when it closes itself off from the beneficial influences of grace.11 In and of love—and as the object of love this divinity moves the world—but in itself it lacks nothing and does not love: it is solely the object of love.The one God in whom Israel believes, on the other hand, loves with a personal love.” 10 The encyclical uses the concept of “dream” two times to indicate this type of confused hope. Cf. ibid., no. 10: “man can indeed enter into union with God— his primordial aspiration [somnium]. But this union is no mere fusion, a sinking in the nameless ocean of the Divine; it is a unity which creates love, a unity in which both God and man remain themselves and yet become fully one”; and no. 13:“The ancient world had dimly perceived [antiqui somniaverunt] that man’s real food—what truly nourishes him as man—is ultimately the Logos, eternal wisdom: this same Logos now truly becomes food for us—as love.” 11 Cf. ibid., no. 4: “An intoxicated and undisciplined eros, then, is not an ascent in ‘ecstasy’ towards the Divine, but a fall, a degradation [imminutio] of man”; no. 5: 236 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP fact, the opening to grace is not an optional possibility, but an intrinsic requirement of nature, whose refusal is equivalent to mutilation.This is to say, for example, that eros that thwarts the movement, which brings it to go beyond itself toward agape and which divinizes itself, becomes its own caricature.12 Similarly,“neutral” reason—reason that desires to be nothing but reason—easily allows itself to be subverted by particular instincts or interests that are, however, inferior in dignity.13 In particular, reason cut off from faith ends up easily losing the dynamism that should open it to the totality of reality in all of its complexity. The price that is paid for this withdrawal into ourselves is reductionism, which consists in taking the part for the whole, and reducing the real to that which reason—a reason voluntarily lacking in fullness—thinks it grasps. From this comes a truncated vision of God that has produced at least three venomous fruits in contemporary culture. “Here we are actually dealing with a debasement [depravatio] of the human body: no longer is it integrated into our overall existential freedom”; no. 7: “The element of agape thus enters into this love, for otherwise eros is impoverished [decidit] and even loses its own nature”; no. 37:“A personal relationship with God and an abandonment to his will can prevent man from being demeaned [prolabatur homo].” 12 Cf. ibid., no. 8: “Yet when the two dimensions are totally cut off from one another, the result is a caricature or at least an impoverished form of love.” 13 Joseph Ratzinger has a great interest in the thought of St. Bonaventure. In an era during which philosophy tended to claim its independence, Bonaventure firmly denounced this pretension of philosophical reason as a degradation of reason. Cf. St. Bonaventure, Collationes de septem donis Spiritus sancti, Collatio IV, no. 12: “Philosophical science is a path toward other sciences, but those who claim that we can stop there [ibi stare, such was the ideal of certain members of the faculty of arts] fall into darkness [Philosophica scientia via est ad alias scientias; sed qui vult ibi stare cadit in tenebras]”; and ibid.: “The first light, that of philosophical science, is great in the opinion of the men of the world, but it is easily eclipsed if one is not on guard against the head and the tail of the dragon. If between it and the sun of justice something is interposed, it suffers the eclipse of foolishness. . . . The one who trusts in philosophical science and is appreciated, and because of this he believes he is better, he becomes stupid. That is to say, when he believes he grasps the Creator through this science, without an ulterior light, it is like a man trying to look at the sky or the sun with candles [Prima claritas, scilicet scientiae philosophicae, magna est secundum opinionem hominum mundialum; sed de facili eclipsatur, nisi homo caveat sibi a capite et cauda draconis. Si aliquid interponatur inter ipsum et solem iustitiae, patitur eclipsim stultitiae. . . . Qui confidit in scientia philosophica et appretiatur, se propter hoc et credit se esse meliorem, stultus factus est, scilicet quando per istam scientiam sine ulteriori lumine credit se apprehendere Creatorem, sicut si homo per candelas vellet videre caelum vel corpus solare].” Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 237 The first fruit of rationalist reductionism is materialism. The encyclical denounces, above all, the social effects of materialism, such as the reduction of the person to his economic needs, which goes hand-inhand with forgetting the necessary interpersonal and spiritual dimension of aid to the destitute.14 The second fruit is dualism, which, incapable of conceiving of the unity of reality in reference to the Creator and the unifying presence of original reason (the Logos), divides the world into two universes that are strangers to each other: that of the body, abandoned to the materialist interpretation, and that of pure spirits. Benedict XVI indicates two major consequences of this dualism. First, applied to the human person, it pulverizes unity;15 it decomposes the human person into one part to which is reserved the exclusivity of rationality and to another part, consequently purely material, which no longer has rational and human meaning on its own. From this point on, it is up to each person’s subjectivity to impose a meaning on the foreign and insignificant mass of the body that each person technically manipulates in a way that treats it as a purely physical and exterior reality.16 This vision of things is evidently destructive for authentic love: It disconnects the spiritual dimension of love, often reduced to a chaste amorous feeling, from sexuality, which is reduced to a purely biological function, ceasing to be the sacrament of love.17 Second, the same dualism is at the root of the ideology of progress and betterment, which is many times denounced in the encyclical.18 It is certainly not the case that the pope is against progress or 14 Cf. Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, no. 28:“In the end, the claim that just social structures would make works of charity superfluous masks a materialist conception of man: the mistaken notion that man can live ‘by bread alone’ (Mt 4:4; cf. Dt 8:3)—a conviction that demeans man and ultimately disregards all that is specifically human.” 15 Cf. ibid., no. 5: “Should he aspire to be pure spirit and to reject the flesh as pertaining to his animal nature alone, then spirit and body would both lose their dignity. On the other hand, should he deny the spirit and consider matter, the body, as the only reality, he would likewise lose his greatness.” 16 Cf. ibid.: “On the contrary, he now considers his body and his sexuality as the purely material part of himself, to be used and exploited at will. Nor does he see it as an arena for the exercise of his freedom, but as a mere object that he attempts, as he pleases, to make both enjoyable and harmless.” 17 Cf. ibid.: “Here we are actually dealing with a debasement of the human body: no longer is it integrated into our overall existential freedom; no longer is it a vital expression of our whole being, but it is more or less relegated to the purely biological sphere.” 18 Cf. ibid., no. 31:“The modern age, particularly from the nineteenth century on, has been dominated by various versions of a philosophy of progress whose most radical form is Marxism”; no. 33: “they [Christians] must not be inspired by 238 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP amelioration of the conditions of the life of humanity, but he diagnoses in this common belief—which holds that men radically modify their condition by their action—an illusion that flows from the forgetting of God and his providential action. If, in fact, as dualism claims, the world is not the work of the Logos, if it is not governed by him with strength and wisdom, then man, instead of fitting into the world as a humble instrument in the work of this mysterious governance, is tempted to impose, even by revolutionary violence, the pseudo-clarity of his “scientific materialism.”19 However, this ideology, because it takes its support from a truncated vision of man, can only lead to inhumane practices.20 The failure of the bloody experiment of Marxism sounded the knell of this dualist and promethean approach toward the amelioration of the world by “pure reason.”21 The third venomous fruit of rationalist reductionism is, on the sociopolitical level, totalitarianism. Having no vis-à-vis to remind it of its relativity, political reason, incarnated in the State, can easily take itself to be everything, as we will discuss later. But, here again, the pretense that neutral reason can suffice in and of itself leads, in fact, to its pledging allegiance to infrarational interests, which is to say to ideologies. Eros and Agape In this perspective of a necessary and fecund interaction between natural human realities and Christian faith, the first part of the encyclical teaches ideologies aimed at improving the world, but should rather be guided by the faith which works through love (cf. Gal 5:6)”; no. 35: “we are helped by the knowledge that, in the end, we are only instruments in the Lord’s hands; and this knowledge frees us from the presumption of thinking that we alone are personally responsible for building a better world. In all humility we will do what we can, and in all humility we will entrust the rest to the Lord.” 19 State bureaucracy (cf. ibid., no. 28) is another expression of this will toward excessive rationalization. In fact, the desire to master everything in the social body is born from the lack of knowledge—which is characteristic of this rationalist dualism—of the immanent rationality of the natural communities anterior to the State. 20 An example of this would be sacrificing, in the name of a “generic, abstract, and undemanding expression of love” (ibid., no. 15), the concrete and truly present person, for the utopia of a perfectly organized society. Cf. no. 31:“What we have here, though, is really an inhuman philosophy. People of the present are sacrificed to the moloch of the future—a future whose effective realization is at best doubtful. One does not make the world more human by refusing to act humanely here and now.” 21 Cf. ibid., no. 27:“Marxism had seen world revolution and its preliminaries as the panacea for the social problem: revolution and the subsequent collectivization of the means of production, so it was claimed, would immediately change things for the better.This illusion has vanished.” Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 239 that a just appreciation of nature and the value of human love becomes possible only in the climate of an openness to supernatural Revelation, filled with the love that is in God. Only in the coming together of eros and agape can the full truth of human love be shown. Love considered as a gift of self to the person loved is not a perfection that belongs exclusively to the love of God or to his participation in man, which is supernatural charity:This is already a constituent dimension of human love. At the same time, this dimension, virtually present from the beginning in eros—which is the “worldly” form of love (cf. Deus Caritas Est, no. 7)—seems to be concealed by the initial predominance of the possessive dimension of this love. It only fully emerges in the light of the revelation of the divine form of love, agape. This is an eloquent illustration of the thesis that only grace can fully reveal nature to itself. There exists, therefore, in eros, as the human form of love, whose archetype is the love of man and woman, an internal dynamism that pushes it not to deny itself in charity but to come to its fulfillment in charity. It contains two types of elements. Some come from its initial imperfection, for example, its selfish, possessive, primarily sensual character, or the fact that sexual instincts or feelings of love develop in a savage fashion without being integrated into a properly spiritual and unifying plan. If eros were defined by such properties, it is clear that it could never be assumed into the Christian form of love. Eros and agape would, in this case, be two contradictory and irreconcilable realities.The victory of one would be the death of the other. However, eros also contains, and more essentially, an oblative, spiritual dimension. The passage from an eros that is predominantly possessive to an eros that is predominantly oblative, assumed by agape, is, therefore, not so much a rupture, but rather a maturation, a healing, and a purification.22 Little by little, these accidental elements of eros, which could be parasites to the essential reality of human love and limit its dynamism, are abandoned, and the secondary elements are integrated into the global plan.This passage, which is in the very logic of authentic human love, nevertheless does not happen without death to itself. But, this is in order to attain, in a paschal logic, to a fulfillment where love becomes capable of integrating the diverse components of the person and unifying them. In this fulfillment the promises of the absolute and of 22 Cf. ibid., no. 5:“Purification and growth in maturity are called for; and these also pass through the path of renunciation. Far from rejecting or ‘poisoning’ eros, they heal it and restore its true grandeur.” The concept of “purification” is omnipresent in the encyclical: It expresses an essential aspect of the action exercised by grace in natural human realities. 240 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP happiness, which are confusedly present like a foretaste in the experience of human love, are finally realized.23 A completely opposite logic of separation between the human experience of love and the revelation of divine love in Christ would lead here to a two-fold impasse. On the one hand, human love that rejects the illuminations and purifications that come from grace would lower itself to an infra-human form of love—sentimentalism or eroticism. Eros, being intrinsically ordered to its assumption by agape, degrades and denies itself when it opposes this.The perversions of eros in the cultures of antiquity and the reduction of eros to “sex” in contemporary culture show evidence of this problem.24 On the other hand, a divine love of charity that would come to juxtapose itself in a purely extrinsic fashion to the experience of human love would not only lose its pertinence for man, but would be purely and simply incomprehensible:The very term “love” would be equivoval. Without using the term, Benedict XVI has recourse here to the classic thematic of analogy. On the one hand, a “categorical” analogy unifies the different meanings of love on the human level by using the first and unifying analogate, the love of man and woman, which finds its fulfillment in marriage.25 On the other hand, a “transcendental” analogy 23 Concerning the “promises” that human love contains, without being able to real- ize them by itself, cf. ibid., no. 2: “love between man and woman, where body and soul are inseparably joined and human beings glimpse an apparently irresistible promise of happiness”; no. 5:“love promises infinity, eternity—a reality far greater and totally other than our everyday existence”; no. 6: “How might love be experienced so that it can fully realize its human and divine promise?”; no. 7: “Even if eros is at first mainly covetous and ascending, a fascination for the great promise of happiness, in drawing near to the other, it is less and less concerned with itself, increasingly seeks the happiness of the other.” Along the same line, human love gives a foretaste of full happiness; cf. DCE, no. 3: “the joy which is the Creator’s gift offers us a happiness which is itself a certain foretaste of the Divine”; no. 4: “Evidently, eros needs to be disciplined and purified if it is to provide not just fleeting pleasure, but a certain foretaste of the pinnacle of our existence, of that beatitude for which our whole being yearns.” 24 Cf. ibid., no. 4: The Old Testament “in no way rejected eros as such; rather, it declared war on a warped and destructive form of it, because this counterfeit divinization of eros actually strips it of its dignity and dehumanizes it”; and no. 5, “Eros, reduced to pure ‘sex,’ has become a commodity, a mere ‘thing’ to be bought and sold, or rather, man himself becomes a commodity.” 25 Cf. ibid., no. 2:“Let us first of all bring to mind the vast semantic range of the word ‘love’: we speak of love of country, love of one’s profession, love between friends, love of work, love between parents and children, love between family members, love of neighbor, and love of God. Amid this multiplicity of meanings, however, one in particular stands out: love between man and woman. . . .This would seem Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 241 permits us to think of the “intrinsic link” (cf. Deus Caritas Est, no. 1) between, on one side, these different forms of human love and, on the other, divine love. These two loves clarify each other: Revelation of the love of God for men is expressed through human love, and human love receives from this revelation an unsuspected depth and discovers the fullness of its meaning.The link, which biblical scholars know well, between the deepening of monotheism and the emergence of monogamous marriage illustrates this reciprocity perfectly.26 This understanding of the fullness of the truth of human love, made possible by the light of Revelation, reflects back on the idea that one can have of love in God. The authentic perfection of human love must eminently be found in God, but free of its created modalities. Can eros then be attributed to God? Is eros a divine Name?27 If eros is taken in the restricted sense, in which it defines a sensual and passionate love, or even a love of the possessive sort, it is clear that it cannot in any manner be attributed to God. St. Thomas comes to our aid in this question. In the Summa theologiae, he explains how the will and love of God that extends first to the infinite Good, God himself, extends also to his creatures. In doing this, St. Thomas leads us deeply into the contemplation of the mystery of love. Using physical beings as his starting point, because for us they are the most familiar, the Angelic Doctor draws out a first transcendental metaphysical law: Each being, he says, has a natural inclination toward his own good, his own perfection, whether it be to acquire it (if he does not have it), or to rejoice in it (if he has it). But this is only one aspect, the most apparent one for us, of the dynamism of the appetite. St.Thomas also discerns in each being another natural inclination: the tendency to communicate his own good, to have others participate in his own perfection, to “shine” with a kind of gratuitous superabundance. Such is the law of the generosity of being, which defines in its source the mystery of causality: “Hence we see that every agent, in so far as it is perfect and in to be the very epitome of love; all other kinds of love immediately seem to fade in comparison. So we need to ask: are all these forms of love basically one, so that love, in its many and varied manifestations, is ultimately a single reality, or are we merely using the same word to designate totally different realities?” 26 Cf. ibid., no. 11:“Corresponding to the image of a monotheistic God is monogamous marriage. Marriage based on exclusive and definitive love becomes the icon of the relationship between God and his people and vice versa.” 27 Benedict XVI, who, concerning the love of God for his people, declares that “his love may certainly be called eros, yet it is also totally agape” (ibid., no. 9), indicates in number 9, note 7 that this was the position of Dionysius:“Cf. Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, who in his treatise The Divine Names, IV, 12–14 (PG 3, 709–713) calls God both eros and agape.” 242 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP act, produces its like.”28 The Dionysian influence can be seen here (bonum diffusivum sui).This law of the generosity of being applies analogically to God:“Hence, if natural things, in so far as they are perfect, communicate their good to others, much more does it appertain to the divine will to communicate by likeness [that is to say: by communicating its likeness] its own good to others as much as possible,” that is to say, as much as the other things are susceptible to receive it.29 The perfection of love consists, therefore, in giving, in giving oneself. Thus, on the human level, deeper than the love that desires (a sign of the imperfection of our “needy” nature) there is the love that gives (a sign of a certain already possessed perfection). However, for us, the two aspects are indissociable:The love that gives does not exist without the love that desires and acquires the good that it communicates. Consequently, eros cannot be defined without this reference to desire. It remains intrinsically linked to need and to lack, and thus to the potentiality that characterizes the condition of the creature. In this case, it appears difficult to see in eros a pure perfection that one could attribute analogically to God.The love of God is supremely “liberal”: God does not want creatures in order to fill a lack or a need that he has, but rather to communicate to them his goodness in a manner of superabundance.30 The attribution of eros to God can, therefore, only be along the lines of a metaphor, which clearly does not mean that it has nothing to teach us about God’s way of being toward his creatures. Justice and Charity The same logic of the fulfillment of natural human realities through their encounter with grace, which is fully at play in the meditation on the rela28 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I, q. 19, a. 2. 29 Cf. ibid.:“Deus non solum se vult, sed etiam alia a se. Quod apparet a simili prius introducto. Res enim naturalis non solum habet naturalem inclinationem respectu proprii boni, ut acquirat ipsum cum non habet, vel ut quiescat in illo cum habet; sed etiam ut proprium bonum in alia diffundat, secundum quod possibile est. Unde videmus quod omne agens, in quantum est actu et perfectum, facit sibi simile. Unde et hoc pertinet ad rationem voluntatis, ut bonum quod quis habet, aliis communicet, secundum quod possibile est. Et hoc praecipue pertinet ad voluntatem divinam, a qua, per quandam similitudinem, derivatur omnis perfectio. Unde, si res naturales, inquantum perfectae sunt, suum bonum aliis communicant, multo magis pertinet ad voluntatem divinam, ut bonum suum aliis per similitudinem communicet, secundum quod possibile est. Sic igitur vult et se esse, et alia. Sed se ut finem, alia vero ut ad finem, inquantum condecet divinam bonitatem etiam alia ipsam participare.” 30 Cf. ST I, q. 44, a. 4, ad 1: “Et ideo ipse solus est maxime liberalis, quia non agit propter suam utilitatem, sed solum propter suam bonitatem.” Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 243 tionship between eros and agape, is still at work in the second part of the encyclical about the relationship between social justice, as a rational requirement in the relations between people, and charity.31 Benedict XVI affirms both the necessary distinction between justice and charity, and their no less necessary complementarity. It follows that charity has not to substitute for human justice and that human justice has not to do without Christian charity.32 On this last point, the pope vigorously responds to the Marxist objection, according to which, in a society that is finally rational like the post-revolutionary society, social justice should substitute for charity.33 This Marxist absorption of charity into justice, which is the fruit of a logic of separation, betrays a double error. First, narrow rationalism, which inescapably flows from the separation of reason and faith, disfigures and humiliates human nature by reducing it to its material, economic dimension. Narrow rationalism does not understand that the human person aspires to things beyond the abstract love due to this abstraction, which is the ens oeconomicum.The human person wants concrete love, which is manifested in quality, interpersonal relations and especially in the gift of self.34 Second, Marxism does not understand that, without Christian charity, human justice can only degrade itself. In fact, if it is not animated by charity, the pursuit of social justice loses its most efficacious moral spirit, and, in the face of difficulties becomes a prey to the discouragement that lies in wait for those who adhere to the ideology of promethean progress.35 31 Cf. Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, no. 26. 32 Cf. ibid., no. 28: “There is no ordering of the State so just that it can eliminate the need for a service of love. Whoever wants to eliminate love is preparing to eliminate man as such.” 33 Cf. ibid., nos. 26 and 31. 34 Cf. ibid., no. 18: “Going beyond exterior appearances, I perceive in others an interior desire for a sign of love, of concern. This I can offer them not only through the organizations intended for such purposes, accepting it perhaps as a political necessity. Seeing with the eyes of Christ, I can give to others much more than their outward necessities; I can give them the look of love which they crave.” The same principal according to which a merely “technical” (objective and abstract) relationship is insufficient to truly come to the aid of a concrete human person is applied to the work of caregivers (no. 31):“Individuals who care for those in need must first be professionally competent: they should be properly trained in what to do and how to do it, and committed to continuing care.Yet, while professional competence is a primary, fundamental requirement, it is not of itself sufficient.We are dealing with human beings, and human beings always need something more than technically proper care. They need humanity. They need heartfelt concern.” 35 Cf. ibid., no. 35: “There are times when the burden of need and our own limitations might tempt us to become discouraged. But precisely then we are helped 244 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP The State and the Church The question of the relationship between Church and State is, along with the analogous question of the relationship between faith and reason, one of the classic forms of the issue of the relationship between grace and nature. In Deus Caritas Est, this question is raised by the pontifical teaching on the necessary harmonization between, on the one hand, charitable works that are proper to the Church as an autonomous social subject, and, on the other hand, the workings of the requirements of justice and solidarity in which the State is invested. Benedict XVI intends here to warn against the temptation of a gentle secularization of the Church’s works of social charity, which would lead to their absorption into the tentacular structures of the providence of the State. As must be done, Benedict XVI reminds us of the importance of the distinction between the two social communities that are the Church and the earthly city: Fundamental to Christianity is the distinction between what belongs to Caesar and what belongs to God (cf. Mt 22:21), in other words, the distinction between Church and State, or, as the Second Vatican Council puts it, the autonomy of the temporal sphere. . . . The two spheres are distinct. (Deus Caritas Est, no. 28) According to its essential goals, the State, which is to say the political authority, aims to promote a social justice that guarantees to each member of the civil society his share of the common good.36 In order to determine this just order, the political leaders use the support of the fundamental givens of natural law and, making use of reason, create laws that are adapted to the desired end. As for the Church, she is not an invisible communion of pure spirits, but rather the “social expression of Christian faith.” She is an autonomous social subject endowed with institutions that are necessary for the realization of her own ends. Consequently, she “has a proper independence and is structured on the basis of her faith as a community which the State by the knowledge that, in the end, we are only instruments in the Lord’s hands; and this knowledge frees us from the presumption of thinking that we alone are personally responsible for building a better world.” 36 Cf. ibid., no. 26:“It is true that the pursuit of justice must be a fundamental norm of the State and that the aim of a just social order is to guarantee to each person, according to the principle of subsidiarity, his share of the community’s goods. This has always been emphasized by Christian teaching on the State and by the Church’s social doctrine”; and no. 28: “Justice is both the aim and the intrinsic criterion of all politics.” Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 245 must recognize” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 28).The Church works directly to procure the eternal salvation of men:This consists for them in communion with God, who realizes at the same time their full humanization. Thus, in accord with the main concerns of the encyclical, Benedict XVI affirms that “the entire activity of the Church is an expression of a love that seeks the integral good of man” (ibid., no. 19). It follows from this distinction between “two spheres” that the Church must respect the “legitimate autonomy” (ibid., no. 29) of the political order: She must not seek to exercise political power nor even to intervene directly in concrete determinations of the political order.37 Similarly, the State must abstain from intervening in religious subjects as such and must respect the structures that are proper to religious communities.38 However, there is nothing more arduous for the State, considered not as a philosophical abstraction but as a real institution composed of men who are marked by egoism and sin, than to resist the temptation to totalitarianism. The State has a tendency almost spontaneously to free itself from any relationship with the religious institution, which, in reminding the State of its relative status, would hinder it from erecting itself as the absolute. Little by little the State absorbs and governs every aspect of social life. The “laity,” when it is conceived as a reduction of religion to an individual option of the strictly private order, without inscription in the social or political order, becomes, in this way, a decisive step in this process of absolutization of the State. Against this, Benedict XVI claims for the Church the status of a proper social subject, as much in the order of charitable action as in the order of social and cultural life.To be faithful to the integrality of her mission, the Church possesses and must possess her own charitable works, which insert themselves into the social network of the civil community.39 Thus, the wave of secularization (or 37 Cf. ibid., no 28: “The Church cannot and must not take upon herself the polit- ical battle to bring about the most just society possible. She cannot and must not replace the State”; ibid.: “The Church’s social teaching . . . recognizes that it is not the Church’s responsibility to make this teaching prevail in political life”; no. 29: “We have seen that the formation of just structures is not directly the duty of the Church, but belongs to the world of politics, the sphere of the autonomous use of reason.” Lay Christians have a specific mission to fulfill on this concrete level of political life; cf. ibid., no. 29: “The direct duty to work for a just ordering of society, on the other hand, is proper to the lay faithful.” 38 Cf. ibid., no. 28: “The State may not impose religion, yet it must guarantee religious freedom and harmony between the followers of different religions.” 39 Cf. ibid., no. 29:“The Church’s charitable organizations, on the other hand, constitute an opus proprium, a task agreeable to her, in which she does not cooperate collaterally, but acts as a subject with direct responsibility, doing what corresponds 246 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP self-secularization) that desires to put certain ecclesial institutions (hospitals, schools, universities, youth movements, and so forth) under the more or less direct tutelage of the State, far from closing an abnormal bracket during which the Church would be provisionally substituted for the State, which is weak in these domains, represents a vital loss for the Church and for society. In addition to this, it constitutes a danger for civil society that finds itself with its hands tied and given up to the deadly embraces of the State hydra.40 Historically, this process of secularization could have been favored by a false theological conception that unilaterally insisted on the autonomy of the temporal realities, while making the beneficial influence of grace, which allows for the full blossoming of nature, go unnoticed. A certain neo-Thomism—that which categorically refused the notion of Christian philosophy, and, always in the name of strict separation of orders, came to justify the “purely political” adhesion of Catholics to Maurrassisme and then to communism—carries its weight of responsibility here. Deus Caritas Est teaches, on the contrary, how vital it is for natural human realities to be exposed to the purifying influences of grace. Concerning this “Christian philosophy,” Jacques Maritain judiciously distinguished, inspired perhaps by the Thomist theology of angelic illumination, a dual influence of faith on the opus rationis that is and must remain philosophy. In concrete human history, faith, on the one hand, brings certain objective givens to philosophy, which stimulate it, and, on the other hand, subjectively comforts the philosopher in permitting him to practice philosophy in a propitious moral and spiritual climate.41 This is also, mutatis mutandis, the role that Benedict XVI attributes to faith vis-à-vis politics. In fact, to her nature. The Church can never be exempted from practicing charity as an organized activity of believers”; and no. 32: “the true subject of the various Catholic organizations that carry out a ministry of charity is the Church herself.” 40 On the merely political level, secularization of ecclesiastical institutions manifests a serious misunderstanding of the principle of subsidiarity, which nevertheless protects personal and communal freedoms against the absolutist temptation that always exists for the State. Cf. ibid., no. 28:“The State which would provide everything, absorbing everything into itself, would ultimately become a mere bureaucracy incapable of guaranteeing the very thing which the suffering person— every person—needs: namely, loving personal concern. We do not need a State which regulates and controls everything, but a State which, in accordance with the principle of subsidiarity, generously acknowledges and supports initiatives arising from the different social forces and combines spontaneity with closeness to those in need.The Church is one of those living forces.” 41 Cf. Jacques Maritain, De la philosophie chrétienne (conference given in 1931), in Oeuvres complètes, vol. V (1933; Fribourg: Éditions universitaires, 1982), ch. 3, “L’état chrétien de la philosophie,” 245–58. Nature and Grace in Deus Caritas Est 247 politics is more than a mere mechanism for defining the rules of public life: its origin and its goal are found in justice, which by its very nature has to do with ethics. The State must inevitably face the question of how justice can be achieved here and now. But this presupposes an even more radical question: what is justice? (Deus caritas Est, no. 28) In this ethical determination of what is just, a work of practical reason, Christian faith intervenes on the level of “objective contributions” thanks to the social doctrine of the Church, which, arguing “on the basis of reason and natural law, namely, on the basis of what is in accord with the nature of every human being” (ibid.), reminds us of and confirms the fundamental principles of ethics.The Church contributes in this way to the “formation of consciences in political life” (ibid.). Faith also intervenes on the level of “subjective considerations.” Indeed, if practical reason can, by right, discover what is “just,” it is actually fragile, precarious, and menaced: “The problem is one of practical reason; but if reason is to be exercised properly, it must undergo constant purification, since it can never be completely free of the danger of a certain ethical blindness caused by the dazzling effect of power and special interests” (ibid.). Grace, by purifying the heart, places practical reason in the best conditions to accomplish its proper ethical work. Thus, faith is “a purifying force for reason itself ”: “From God’s standpoint, faith liberates reason from its blind spots and therefore helps it to be ever more fully itself. Faith enables reason to do its work more effectively and to see its proper object more clearly” (ibid.). What is more, still on the level of subjective considerations, the purification accomplished by grace not only ameliorates the capacity for discernment, but also gives the moral strength to put into practice, whatever the costs may be, the demands of justice that one perceives. Grace thus nourishes and keeps alive the spiritual and ethical motivation of the members of civil society:The Church “has to reawaken the spiritual energy without which justice, which always demands sacrifice, cannot prevail and prosper” (ibid.). In sum, grace gives a “soul” to action for social justice and brings it to its perfection. Deus Caritas Est is addressed “to the bishops, priests, and deacons, men and women religious, and all the lay faithful.” It nevertheless contains a powerful and well-defined message for all men of good will. Benedict XVI is convinced that the recognition of the primacy of God and of spiritual values is not an option but a vital necessity for the life of people and communities. Integral humanization passes through the opening to grace that does not destroy anything, but rather purifies and fulfills everything that is good in human realities. Likewise—and this is the obscure side of 248 Serge-Thomas Bonino, OP the same principle—our societies self-destruct by marginalizing Christian faith and hiding their spiritual roots. Thus, Benedict XVI, in his homily for the inaugural Mass of his pontificate, April 24, 2005, restated with fervor the famous words of his beloved predecessor: “Do not be afraid! Open wide the doors for Christ!”42 Benedict XVI explained that John Paul II was addressing the mighty, the powerful of this world, who feared that Christ might take away something of their power if they were to let him in, if they were to allow the faith to be free.Yes, he would certainly have taken something away from them: the dominion of corruption, the manipulation of law and the freedom to do as they pleased. But he would not have taken away anything that pertains to human freedom or dignity, or to the building of a just society.43 Then Benedict XVI enlarged his meditation and, going beyond the political order alone, applied to the whole of human reality the necessity of being open to grace: If we let Christ into our lives, we lose nothing, nothing, absolutely nothing of what makes life free, beautiful, and great. No! . . . Only in this friendship is the great potential of human existence truly revealed. . . . [Christ] takes nothing away, and he gives you everything.When we give ourselves to him, we receive a hundredfold in return.Yes, open, open N&V wide the doors to Christ—and you will find true life. Amen.44 42 Pope John Paul II, homily at the Mass for the inauguration of his pontificate (October 22, 1978), www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/speeches/1978/ documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_19781022_inizio-pontificato_it.html. 43 Pope Benedict XVI, homily at the Mass for the inauguration of his pontificate (April 24, 2005), www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/homilies/2005/ documents/hf_ben-xvi_hom_20050424_inizio-pontificato_en.html. 44 Ibid. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 249–66 249 Bonaventurian Resonances in Benedict XVI’s Theology of Revelation A ARON C ANTY Saint Xavier University Chicago, Illinois O F THE RECENT evaluations of Pope Benedict XVI’s theology, few have examined at any length the influence of St. Bonaventure on his thought. There are a number of surveys or brief descriptions of his encounter with Bonaventure as Benedict wrote his habilitation, but what analysis of Bonaventure’s influence that does exist tends to focus on Benedict’s ecclesiology or his interest in history and eschatology.1 These emphases are no doubt justified, since these themes arise throughout Benedict’s career, but they fail to capture one of his primary interests during his early career, namely revelation. History, eschatology, and the Church are, of course, bound up with the concept of revelation, but 1 See, for example, John L. Allen, Jr., Pope Benedict XVI: A Biography of Joseph Ratzinger (New York-London: Continuum, 2000), 36–38, 99–100; Andrea Bellandi, Fede cristiana come “Stare e comprendere.” La giustificazaione dei fondamenti della fede in Joseph Ratzinger (Rome: Editrice Pontifica Università Gregoriana, 1996), 90–92; Maximilian Heinrich Heim, Joseph Ratzinger–Kirchliche Existenz und existentielle Theologie unter dem Anspruch von “Lumen Gentium.” Ekklesiologische Grundlinien (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2004), 149–52; Dorothee Kaes, Theologie im Anspruch von Geschichte und Wahrheit. Zur Hermeneutik Jospeh Ratzingers (St. Ottilien: EOS Verlag, 1997), 62–63; Paolo Martuccelli, Origine e natura della chiesa. La prospettiva storico-dommatica di Joseph Ratzinger (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2001), 305–20, 330–33; Aidan Nichols, The Thought of Benedict XVI:An Introduction to the Theology of Joseph Ratzinger:An Introductory Study (New York/London: Burns and Oates, 2005), 51–65; Andrea Tornielli, Ratzinger. Custode della fede (Casale Monferrato: Piemme, 2002), 36–39; and Thomas Weiler, Die Ekklesiologie Joseph Ratzingers und ihr Einfluss auf das Zweite Vatikanische Konzil (Mainz: Grünewald, 1997), 125. There are some exceptions to this trend in the studies by A. Bellandi and D. Kaes. 250 Aaron Canty Benedict’s theology of revelation is the larger conceptual sphere in which his ecclesiology, theology of history, and eschatology develop. Revelation was also among his first theological interests, and the theology of revelation that he articulated was also among the first elements of his overall theological project that took a definite shape. In the formation of this theology, Bonaventure played a significant role. It was Bonaventure’s theology of revelation that initially interested the young Joseph Ratzinger as he began research for his habilitation.Although Benedict was forced to omit his study of Bonaventure’s theology of revelation from the final draft of his habilitation, as he recounts in his memoirs, he claimed that what he learned from Bonaventure regarding revelation was “very important for me at the time of the conciliar discussion on revelation, Scripture, and tradition.”2 This interest in Bonaventure’s theology of revelation is the background for Ratzinger’s published studies on Bonaventure’s ecclesiology and theology of history. It is also important to note that however much Bonaventure’s theology of revelation and his salvation-historical mode of theology appealed to Benedict, the latter’s appraisal of Bonaventure’s ecclesiology was not entirely positive, nor was his evaluation of Bonaventure’s theology of history and eschatology entirely free from criticism. Nevertheless, there are significant connections between the two men on these topics. This essay will describe several aspects of Bonaventure’s theology of revelation and attempt to show parallels between Bonaventure’s and Benedict XVI’s understanding of revelation and history and its significance for the Church. Aspects of Bonaventure’s Theology of Revelation Although Joseph Ratzinger was clearly influenced by Thomas Aquinas’s understanding of revelation,3 Bonaventure’s articulation of this teaching, especially in the Collationes in Hexaëmeron, was particularly important for 2 Joseph Ratzinger, Milestones: Memoirs, 1927–1977, trans. Erasmo Leiva-Merikakis (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1998), 109. 3 For Ratzinger’s interpretation of Thomas on revelation and salvation history, see his Principles of Catholic Theology: Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology, trans. Mary Frances McCarthy (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987), 178–79; and idem, Pilgrim Fellowship of Faith:The Church as Communion, ed. Stephan Otto Horn and Vinzenz Pfnür, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2005), 21–28. See also Leo Scheffczyk, “Der neuscholastische Traktat De revelatione divina, die dogmatische Konstitution Dei Verbum und die Lehre des hl. Thomas,” in La doctrine de la révélation divine de saint Thomas d’Aquin, ed. Léon Elders (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1990), 13–26; and Leo Elders,“Aquinas on Holy Scripture as the Medium of Divine Revlation,” in Elders, La doctrine de la révélation divine, 132–52. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 251 Benedict.4 In the works of Bonaventure, Benedict found that the Franciscan master never treated the concept of revelation in a systematic way, in the manner of nineteenth- and early twentieth-century neo-scholasticism. Bonaventure’s interest, rather, lay primarily in “the many individual revelations which have taken place in the course of history.”5 Bonaventure’s writings address “the individual acts of revelation which can be repeated, and which in fact are often repeated by God. In these acts, God turns toward the individual recipient of the revelation.”6 This emphasis on a dynamic model of revelation necessarily touches on how revelation is perceived in faith and in Scripture and how humans respond to God in salvation history. In the Collationes in Hexaëmeron, Benedict discovered that Bonaventure’s understanding of revelation had three primary significations.The first signification consists of an unveiling of the future.7 When Bonaventure uses “revelation” in this sense, it usually refers to Old Testament figures and events representing Christ in some way.The second signification consists of 4 Joseph Komonchak has rightly noted Benedict’s initial interest in Bonaventure, although his characterization of Bonaventure as “anti-philosophical” and “antiintellectual” requires significant qualification at the least, if not outright rejection. See his “The Church in Crisis, Pope Benedict’s Theological Vision,” Commonweal 132 ( June 3, 2005). For more nuanced appraisals of Bonaventure’s philosophy and his estimation of human reason, see Efrem Bettoni, Saint Bonaventure, trans.Angelus Gambatese (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1964), 119–27;Vincenzo Cherubino Bigi, Studi sul pensiero di S. Bonaventura (Assisi: Edizioni Porziuncola, 1988), 325–29; Elisa Cuttini, Ritorno a Dio. Filosofia, teologia, etica della mens nel pensiero di Bonaventura da Bagnoregio (Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino, 2002), 121–81; and Alfonso Pompei, “Cosmologia: scienza e fede in Bonaventura da Bagnoregio,” Doctor Seraphicus 47 (2000): 5–42. Perhaps the best study of the relationship between Bonaventure and Aristotle is Jacques Guy Bougerol’s “Dossier pour l’étude des rapports entre saint Bonaventure et Aristote,” Archives d’Histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age 40 (1973): 135–222. Benedict himself acknowledges Bonaventure’s suspicion of Aristotle not only in The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, trans. Zachary Hayes (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1971, 1989), 134–62; but also in a lecture given at the College of St.Thomas and St. John Vianney Seminary,“Faith, Philosophy, and Theology,” in Pope John Paul II Lecture Series (St. Paul, Minnesota: College of St.Thomas, St. John Vianney Seminary, 1985), 11, 13. 5 Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, 57. 6 Ibid. 7 Ibid., 58.This dimension of revelation is brought out most clearly in Bonaventure’s Collationes in Hexaëmeron, ed. Pp. Colegii S. Bonaventurae, in Opera omnia, vol. 5 (Quaracchi: ex Typographia Collegii S. Bonaventurae, 1891), 14, 25, where Bonaventure uses the term “prophetical revelation” to show how Old Testament figures and events represent Christ.The other references Benedict cites (13, 17; 14, 7; 14, 10) do not stand by themselves as easily, but must be placed side by side one another in order to corroborate the understanding of revelation given in 14, 25. 252 Aaron Canty a “spiritual” understanding of Scripture. For Bonaventure, this authentic understanding of Scripture, which is a type of revelation, occurs only in the sixth age of human history after the life and mission of Jesus Christ.8 Bonaventure is clear that revelation does not pertain to the letters of Scripture, or the literal sense, but revelation instead consists of God’s communication of the spiritual understanding of Scripture. Using the Gospel story of Jesus turning water into wine, Bonaventure claims that the “Holy Spirit does not give spiritual understanding unless man provide the jar, that is, his capacity, and the water, that is, the understanding of the literal sense.”9 When the literal sense is turned into “wine” or the spiritual understanding, the “jar” or human capacity remains, but the literal understanding is turned into the spiritual understanding.10 The third spiritual signification of “revelation” can refer to “that imageless unveiling of the divine reality which takes place in the mystical ascent.”11 This dimension of revelation emphasizes the importance of love in uniting the individual with God in such a way that the concepts and the activity of the intellect cease to operate and only “the affective power keeps vigil and imposes silence upon all other powers.”12 Bonaventure’s threefold understanding of revelation allows him to outline three forms of wisdom that are made possible only by means of revelation: sapientia multiformis, sapientia omniformis, and sapientia nulliformis. Sapientia multiformis is the wisdom that Scripture communicates under various figures and signs.13 Sapientia omniformis is the wisdom that can be found in all things.14 Wisdom, in its most penetrating reach into the human soul, has no form, hence the designation sapientia nulliformis. 8 See Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 16, 29. 9 Ibid., 19, 8. 10 Benedict will use similar language when discussing the creation narrative of Genesis. He claims that the Old Testament can be read only in light of Christ, who provides the unity of Scripture. Any interpretation of the creation account, or the legal precepts for that matter, without reference to Christ would be concerned only with the literal sense of Scripture; it is Christ who “frees us from the slavery of the letter.” Benedict, In the Beginning:A Catholic Understanding of the Story of the Creation and the Fall, trans. Boniface Ramsey, O.P. (Huntington, IN: Our Sunday Visitor, Inc., 1990), 26. On faith as a hermeneutic lens that “opens” the Scriptures, see his essay “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: On the Question of the Foundations and Approaches of Exegesis Today,” in Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: The Ratzinger Conference on Bible and Church, ed. Richard John Neuhaus (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1989), 1–23. 11 Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, 59. 12 Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 2, 30. 13 See ibid., 2, 12. 14 On the idea of “natural” revelation, see Henri de Lubac, The Discovery of God, trans. Alexander Dru (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1996), 7–13. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 253 The soul attains this height of wisdom by grace, turning away from sense perceptions and images and gazing only at God.15 The fact that revelation is operative in all of these manifestations of wisdom implies that revelation is not consigned to the past, nor identified only with the writing of Scripture, but is an ongoing process that occurs throughout salvation history, eliciting a response of faith both in individuals and in the Church as a whole. The subjective dimension of revelation, that is, what pertains to an individual’s penetrating vision of the intelligible world, is bound up with prophecy and contemplation. The objective dimension of revelation, that is, what pertains to the content of revelation, is found in Scripture and the understanding of Scripture as articulated by the Fathers of the Church. In both the subjective and objective dimensions of revelation, what allows the individual and the Church to respond to divine revelation is the gift of faith. Faith is an attitude or disposition of the will that allows the individual and the Church to understand the content of Scripture, the “spirit” veiled by the “letter.” As the individual and the Church witness God’s revelation of himself, they articulate in human language what they “see” or perceive. Scripture is one result of this effort to describe the ineffable, but so too is any work in which the understanding of Scripture is communicated. Scripture is the privileged source because it contains the “mysteries” that both reveal and conceal the mystery of Christ,16 but the non-scriptural reception and communication of the mysteries of the faith is also “revelation,” as well. For Bonaventure what matters is not so much the written text of Scripture, the “letter,” but the understanding of it that is received and passed on in the Church. One may read Scripture but still not believe or understand what it says. Likewise, someone may never be able to read Scripture and still understand what it says through the preaching and oral exposition of others.The inseparability of the text of Scripture and the understanding of Scripture explains not only the equation of sacra scriptura and theologia in the thirteenth century and the designation of scholastic theologians as doctores sacrae scripturae,17 but it also suggests the need for a corporate reception and 15 This description of wisdom is slightly different from that found in Bonaventure’s Sentences commentary, where he distinguishes four kinds of wisdom. See his Commentaria in IV Libros Sententiarum Magistri Petri Lombardi, vol. 3 , ed. Pp. Collegii S. Bonaventurae (Florence: Collegium S. Bonaventurae, 1934–49), d. 35, a. 1, q. 1. 16 See Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 2, 11–12. 17 See Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, 67; and Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1, The Person and His Work, trans. Robert Royal (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1996), 54–58. Aaron Canty 254 understanding of Scripture and the development of the understanding of Scripture over time. Because God’s revelations to the individual and to the Church throughout history have the same source there is a harmony among them. Since God is the source of the spiritual understanding of Scripture, there should also be a harmony of interpretations between the individual exegete and the Church, as well.This fact does not mean that theologians do not disagree in their understanding of certain passages in Scripture or in their understanding of certain teachings (the record of scholastic disputations and ecclesial condemnations from the thirteenth century confirms that), but it signifies that both the individual and the Christian community receive revelations from the same source and respond to it with the same faith, regardless of its articulation. The fact that revelation and the response to revelation that is faith both occur in time and space implies that both revelation and faith grow over time.This process is true both for the individual believer and for the Church as a whole. As the individual advances in contemplation, the soul perceives more profoundly the truths that Scripture contains; likewise in the Church, the contemplative part of the Church learns more and more about the revelation contained in Scripture. Scripture contains an infinite number of “seeds” or interpretations that require time to unfold them.18 Only constant contemplation on the truths of the faith can make these seeds bear fruit. But how does this growth of revelation take place throughout history? As indicated above, God reveals himself to the prophets and apostles who write most of the books of Scripture.19 The spiritual meaning is revealed progressively by the Fathers of the Church, who interpret Scripture through the lens of faith, and whose writings, because of their close relationship to the truths of the faith, are not completely separate from Scripture. Characterizing Bonaventure’s view of the relationship between Scripture and patristic exegesis, Benedict claims that the Fathers are “bearers of a new spiritual ‘revelation,’ without which the Scriptures simply would not be effective as revelation.”20 Revelation does not end with the age of the Fathers, however. In fact, for Bonaventure, it increases and intensifies over time, so that his own age shares in this process, as well. Bonaventure notes that the sixth age of the Old Testament, from Hezekiah to Zerubbabel, was one of prophecy, and it parallels the sixth age of the New Testament, which began with the 18 See Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 13, 2. 19 On the canonical status of biblical books not written by the prophets and apos- tles, see Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, 78–79. 20 Ibid., 80. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 255 pontificate of Adrian I and continued up to Bonaventure’s own day.21 The fact that Bonaventure was living in the time of prophecy before the seventh and final age is significant for his understanding of the process of revelation.The gift of prophecy allows for the “contemplative Church”22 to have a greater understanding of Scripture than existed in earlier stages of salvation history. According to Bonaventure, however, the Church has not only a contemplative dimension, but an “active” dimension and a “mixed” dimension (comprising activity and contemplation), as well.Although the distinction between action and contemplation had long been used by Christian writers to describe the various modes of Christian life, Bonaventure recasts this distinction in light of historical developments in the thirteenth century (and also with a desire to have any earthly ordo align with the ninefold angelic hierarchy of Pseudo-Dionysius and the threefold “hierarchy” of the Trinity).The active part of the Church is made of three groups of laypeople (people, masters, and leaders), and the “mixed” part of the Church consists of clerics, whose way of life involves contemplation but service in the world, as well.23 The contemplative part of the Church has three groups. The first consists of those who pray, namely monks. The second group consists of those who “speculate” or study Scripture: the Dominicans and the Franciscans.24 The final group consists of those whose contemplation has led to rapture or ecstasy, and here Bonaventure lists only Francis. The fact that the two most recognized mendicant orders comprise the penultimate stage of the contemplative dimension of the Church precisely because of their study of Scripture is significant. Francis, the one who occupies the highest plane of contemplation, is the one whom God chose to rebuild the Church of that time. Francis’s prophetic role was revealed to him, and it involved a life of following the Gospel quite literally. In his Legenda maior, Bonaventure ensures that his master is both apostolic, in the 21 See Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 16, 29. 22 “Ecclesia contemplative”: Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 13, 7. See also ibid., 16, 29. 23 The clerics also are divided into three groups: ministers, priests, and pontiffs.The “ministers” consist of porters, readers, exorcists, acolytes, subdeacons, and deacons; the “priests” consist of both priests and bishops; the “pontiffs” category includes Christ, Peter, the pope, and the patriarchs of the four other patriarchates. Further discussion of Bonaventure’s understanding of the structure of the Church would take us too far astray from Bonaventure’s theology of revelation. 24 Even here Bonaventure cannot resist placing the Franciscans above the Dominicans, because while the Dominicans emphasize study, the Franciscans emphasize love. See Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaëmeron, 22, 21. 256 Aaron Canty sense of living an apostolic life and being devoted to the apostles (especially St. Peter), and prophetic.25 Both dimensions involve following the truths of the Gospel, and preaching those truths. In order to preach the Gospel, his followers would have to do more than live a life of poverty; they would have to study Scripture and imitate what they studied. Only then would Franciscan preaching be effective. Francis’s literal imitation of the Gospel, which was the fruit of his mystical experiences, was both the historical and the theological foundation for the Franciscans’ study of Scripture. Following Francis meant looking back to Christ, the apostles, and the Church Fathers, and toward the eschatological elements of the Gospel, which were in the process of unfolding. Although Bonaventure situates his own time just before the seventh age of the New Testament, and so gives his own time an apocalyptic coloring, he was convinced that the infinite seeds of Scripture were not close to sprouting and blooming.The full revelation was in the process of unfolding and would be consummated in the seventh age, but the mendicants (and the Franciscans in particular) played an important role in preparing for the full revelation that God would bring about. For Bonaventure, the mendicant orders not only followed the Gospel more literally than the monks did, but their following of the Gospel coincided with a renewed interest in Scripture. Indeed the scientific examination of Scripture, emphasizing the literal sense, was rooted in St. Francis’s decision to follow the Beatitudes literally. For Bonaventure, Francis was an eschatological figure, whose self-giving response to God’s Revelation in the form of poverty pointed the way to a new manner, not only of living the Gospel, but also of interpreting Scripture, as well.The scriptural studies of the Franciscans and Dominicans during the first half of the thirteenth century led to renewed interest in the transmission of scriptural texts, the creation of study tools, such as concordances and lists of variant readings of the Vulgate text, changes in the method of dividing the text, and drawing from contemporary theologians and spiritual writers, and not only the Fathers or “doctors” of the Church. Bonaventure’s theory of revelation, then, gives a priority to God revealing himself to human beings throughout history. Knowledge of God is communicated to people as individuals, such as Abraham, but also to people as whole. “Scripture” is one means of communicating God’s revelation, but the actual act of revelation is in some sense prior to writing the text of Scripture or to people’s reading Scripture or hearing its exposition.This priority is manifested when faith accompanies the read25 See Bonaventure, Legenda Sancti Francisci, ed. Pp. Colegii S. Bonaventurae, in Opera omnia, vol. 8 (Quaracchi: ex Typographia Collegii S. Bonaventurae, 1898), ch. 3. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 257 ing of Scripture, since without it no knowledge of God may be received. The collective reading of Scripture in the Church, that is, the place where Scripture is read and heard, builds up the spiritual understanding of Scripture over time in such a way that the Church as a whole gains deeper insights into God and his plan of salvation. Bonaventure’s appreciation for the transmission of revelation throughout history and the increasing deepening or penetration of revelation over time anticipated in some ways modern approaches to fundamental theology. Benedict’s Discovery of Bonaventurian Resonances in Vatican II As theologians in the middle of the twentieth century gained a greater appreciation for the historical context of revelation and the response to that revelation, they increasingly focused on God’s plan of salvation in history and the human potential to receive and understand revelation. The Second Vatican Council’s Constitution on Divine Revelation, Dei Verbum, was written with some of these interests in mind; and Benedict, then a professor of fundamental theology at the University of Bonn, contributed to the theological discussion that shaped the schemata of what eventually would become Dei Verbum. Benedict’s previous study of Bonaventure, completed in 1957, had allowed him to reflect on the nature of revelation; and it proved valuable in the ongoing discussions of the schemata, which proved to be highly controversial.26 In the final text of the Constitution on Divine Revelation, Benedict found profound similarities between high scholastic models of revelation and what the council fathers taught in Dei Verbum. One similarity was the understanding of revelation as a process, and another was its eliciting faith in individuals and in the receiving community.27 It is precisely this dynamic understanding of revelation and faith that attracted Benedict to Bonaventure’s model of revelation. Benedict was intrigued by it, because, in contrast to certain neo-scholastic models, the scholasticism of the thirteenth century understood revelation to be an act of God. The neoscholastic models that dissatisfied Benedict understood revelation to be 26 See Benedict’s reflections on these discussions in Ratzinger, Milestones, 124–30. 27 Shortly after the council, René Latourelle, who saw Dei Verbum as a possible “char- ter of fundamental theology,” described the task of fundamental theology to be understanding the Word of God “in its mysterious being, in its historical unraveling, in the signs of this unraveling, in the objective forms by which it expresses itself and perdures through the centuries (tradition and Scripture), and in its authentic interpreter (the magisterium).” “Dismemberment or Renewal of Fundamental Theology?” trans.Anthony M. Buono, in The Development of Fundamental Theology, ed. Johannes B. Metz (New York-Paramus, NJ: Paulist Press, 1969), 31. Aaron Canty 258 what resulted from that action, namely Scripture and Tradition. According to Bonaventure, Scripture could not exhaust God’s revelatory selfcommunication; God’s revelation always transcends what gives witness to it. This theological approach to the question of revelation found favor with those modern theologians, like Benedict, who thought it important to consider how the receiving subject or subjects of revelation shared in the act of revelation. Benedict summarizes the findings of his research in his Milestones: The word [“revelation”] refers to the act in which God shows himself, not to the objectified result of this act. And because this is so, the receiving subject is always also a part of the concept of “revelation.” Where there is no one to perceive “revelation,” no re-vel-ation has occurred, because no veil has been removed. By definition, revelation requires a someone who apprehends it.These insights, gained through my reading of Bonaventure, were later on very important for me at the time of the conciliar discussion on revelation. Because, if Bonaventure is right, then revelation precedes Scripture and becomes deposited in Scripture but is not simply identical with it. This in turn means that revelation is always something greater than what is merely written down.And this again means that there can be no such thing as pure sola scriptura (“by Scripture alone”), because an essential element of Scripture is the Church as understanding subject, and with this the fundamental sense of tradition is already given.28 This understanding of revelation that Benedict found in Bonaventure implies that revelation is not only historical, it is also intrinsically dialogical. It begins with God who reveals himself, but he reveals himself to a “receiving subject,” whose being is conditioned by time and space. Benedict describes this process further in his commentary Dei Verbum, where he describes the council’s articulation of revelation in terms very similar to what he discovered in the Seraphic Doctor (although he never mentions him). Benedict, for example, emphasizes the differences in the articulation of revelation between Vatican I and Vatican II, and several emerge: Whereas Vatican I starts from the natural knowledge of God and considers “supernatural” revelation only in close connection with this idea, in order to proceed immediately to the question of its transmission in scripture and tradition, here the question of natural knowledge of God is put at the end and God’s revealing activity described within a comprehensive survey of salvation history. . . . Here, instead of the 28 Ratzinger, Milestones, 108–9. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 259 abstract values “sapientia et bonitas” we first have reference to God himself “in his wisdom and goodness,” thus giving a far greater emphasis to the personal and theocentric starting point when compared with Vatican I: it is God himself, the person of God, from whom revelation proceeds and to whom it returns, and thus revelation necessarily reaches—also with the person who receives it—into the personal center of man, it touches him in the depth of his being, not only in his individual faculties, in his will and understanding.29 What Benedict here calls the “personal and theocentric starting point” is precisely what he discovered in Bonaventure.30 God communicates himself in a unique way at certain moments in salvation history. Criticizing again what he calls “neo-scholastic intellectualism” that understood revelation to be “a store of mysterious supernatural teachings,” Benedict believed that Dei Verbum tried to show how revelation was a “totality, in which word and event make up one whole, a true dialogue which touches man in his totality, not only challenging his reason, but, as dialogue, addressing him as a partner, indeed, giving him his true nature for the first time.”31 Benedict noted that this dialogical dimension of revelation, the fact that God’s act of revealing necessarily involves individual recipients, including the Church in some sense, has profound implications. Most obviously, it entails that this action of revelation initiated by God invites or elicits a fully human response, a response that not only originates within time and space, but also is directed toward the eternal and thus what is in humanity’s future. This human response occurs only because of the human openness toward the divine and the receptivity latent in that openness, and the response of faith is possible only because one has heard God. Indeed Benedict believed that the emphasis on listening in Dei Verbum was one of its strengths over earlier drafts of the document that were in danger of “ecclesiological positivism.”32 If the earlier schema had prevailed (in particular text C), 29 Ratzinger, “Dogmatic Constitution on Revelation: Origin and Background,” in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler, trans. William Glen-Doepel, et al. (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969), 170. 30 See also Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra Gentiles I, c. 6; and Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 6. 31 Ratzinger, “Dogmatic Constitution on Revelation,” 172. Although Benedict here describes the receptive subject of revelation primarily in anthropological terms, in his commentary on ch. 2 of Dei Verbum the Church plays a more significant role as the partner in God’s revelatory act. See ibid., 181–98. Benedict also notes in passing the influence of neo-scholastic theological emphases on earlier versions of the text: see 157–66. 32 See ibid., 162. Aaron Canty 260 The Council would otherwise have risked falling victim to a kind of ecclesio-monism in its texts, whereas the Constitution on Revelation now stressed the importance of listening, thus moving beyond everything that was said at the Council in order to take up an attitude of listening, an attitude in which the Church transcends itself, for it is not there for its own sake, but only to lead him to whom all honor is due, God the Lord.33 Revelation thus conceived includes both God’s self-communication and the human response simultaneously. This understanding is exactly what Benedict found in Bonaventure’s theology of revelation. Just as revelation is not “a store of mysterious supernatural teachings,”34 so too “faith is not a system of knowledge, but trust.”35 This trust is an existential orientation, a direction of life that one manifests concretely within history, but that always is open toward the future, which is “where” the Church and each believer await the fulfillment of God’s promise.36 Bonaventurian Themes in Benedict’s Writings After the Council After the council, Benedict developed the understanding of revelation and faith that he found in Dei Verbum and that he described in his commentary on it. He continued the idea that revelation is an ongoing process initiated by God, but he recast that teaching into more existential terms. Although Benedict returns to this theme in numerous places, making an exhaustive study here impossible, it will suffice to point out a few places where Benedict develops his theology of revelation. In Benedict’s recent work, Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions, he echoes Bonaventure’s understanding of revelation as individual acts of God’s self-communication, initiated throughout history, and translates it into existential terms. In contrasting what he calls “mysticism” with monotheistic religion, Benedict argues that mysticism is a religious system in which the ultimate reality is a spiritual experience that the individual achieves through a purifying ascent into a passive and impersonal God. Monotheism, as Benedict understands it, stands in near opposition to this view of religion and necessarily requires God’s initiative. Monotheism views God as the primary agent in the historical relationship and sees 33 Ibid., 162. 34 Ibid., 172. 35 Joseph Ratzinger, Faith and the Future (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1971), 24. 36 For a summary of the early conciliar debate on revelation, see Joseph Ratzinger, Theological Highlights of Vatican II, trans. Henry Traub and Gerard C. Thormann (New York: Paulist Press, 1966), 20–26. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 261 union as occurring between a personal God and individuals. Revelation occurs when “something not ours, not to be found in what we have, comes to me and takes me out of myself, above myself, creates something new.”37 It is a “call from God,” which is the ultimate reality in human existence.38 This call, initiated by God, goes out to all people, people embedded in historical and cultural contexts; and it requires a response. The positive response, the response that allows each human to be an “actor in divine history,”39 is faith. Even in his understanding of faith, however, Benedict begins with an existential approach. In his early Introduction to Christianity, he describes the most basic characteristic of faith as an openness toward what is not visible, that is, an acknowledgment that what we experience through sense perceptions may not be all there is to reality. He explains that “belief signifies the decision that at the very core of human existence there is a point that cannot be nourished and supported on the visible and tangible, that encounters and comes into contact with what cannot be seen and finds that it is a necessity for its own existence.”40 This attitude is a “conversion” in some sense because humanity possesses a natural inclination toward what is sensible. The acknowledgment of what is not sensible, the acknowledgment of something that undergirds and supports sensible reality, is an authentic step toward the truth of reality in its fullness. From this basic attitude of openness toward Another to the God of Jesus Christ seems to be quite a leap. How is the chasm bridged? Benedict finds in the enigmatic figure of Abraham a clue to expanding the understanding of what faith means.What is important for Benedict is not so much that Abraham was unaware of Jesus Christ or that he may have had a polytheistic religion.The first important element of Abraham’s faith is that the God of all, the Creator, was a family God, even a personal God. This fact implies that the Creator was not only outside the created order, but somehow inside it, as well. The transcendent Creator was a God of history and in history, a God who entered into relationships, covenants with humanity.The second important fact about Abraham’s faith was that this God called to Abraham, and Abraham responded to that call by leaving his homeland and going into unknown lands and an uncertain future. This step from the known into the unknown, this leap of faith in response 37 Joseph Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), 89. 38 Ibid., 36. 39 Ibid., 42. 40 Joseph Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity, trans. J. R. Foster (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), 51. Aaron Canty 262 to God’s call (however that call was perceived), represents a remarkable commitment: [Abraham] gave up the present for the sake of what was to come. He let go of what was safe, comprehensible, calculable, for the sake of what was unknown. And he did this in response to a single word from God. He had met God and placed all his future in God’s hands; he dared to accept a new future that began in darkness. The word he heard was more real to him than all the calculable things he could hold in his hand. He trusted that which he could not yet see, and thus became capable of new life, of breaking out of rigidity.The center of gravity of reality, indeed the concept of reality itself, changed. The future took precedence over the present, the word heard over comprehensible things. God had become more important to him than himself and than the things he could understand. This response to God’s call marks Abraham’s freedom: Attachment to the accustomed world came to an end, and man’s true destination appeared—not his immediate environment, but the whole world, the whole of creation that knows no frontiers, but allows itself to be explored until the ultimate foundation of everything has been discovered. . . . Abraham is on the way. He no longer belongs to any fixed place, and is therefore a stranger and a guest wherever he goes.41 Abraham’s faith is not merely openness but an attitude of trust in a personal God.The trust is elicited because of God’s promise to Abraham, a promise whose fulfillment lay in the distant future.The trust also implies a renunciation, a conversion from what is known to what is unknown. Although this faith is clearly different from a mere openness to Another, insofar as trust in the promise of a personal God becomes operative, how does it relate to the faith of Christianity? Abraham’s belief in God’s promise of future posterity and a future homeland and the Christian faith in the God of the resurrected Jesus seem very different. Christianity seems to care very little about blood ties and a hope for a future homeland on earth. Nevertheless, for Benedict, the person of Jesus Christ is the fulfillment of God’s promise to Abraham. In Christ, “the promise of a future, of the country of the future, has acquired a full and clearly defined form. Faith in the risen Christ is nothing other than the faith of Abraham—the promise of a future and of a country.”42 41 Ratzinger, Faith and the Future, 30–31. 42 Ibid., 39–40. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 263 The difference between belief in God before and after the event of Christ is the person of Christ himself. Before Christ, those who had faith (Abel, Melchizedek, Abraham, the people of Israel) trusted God with their future. Abraham’s faith is so strong that he could be prepared to sacrifice Isaac, his son, the embodiment of Abraham’s future, because of his trust in the Lord.43 Those who had faith in God believed that they would have a place of rest and a time of peace in the future. With the advent of Christ, the “place” and “time” of the future are made present. Christ himself is the future of humanity because “Faith in the God of Jesus Christ means faith in the God who still opens up, really and truly, a future behind the wall of death.”44 The resurrection of the crucified Christ shows the similarity between Abraham and Christ, namely that both entrusted their entire being to God; the difference between Abraham and Christ is that the promise to Abraham has been fulfilled in the Word-made-flesh, in whom the future has been made eternally present. The exodus or “cultural break,”45 that is, the journey in which Abraham and the people of Israel left behind what was familiar for something new, is, in Christianity, “now interiorized as the readiness to allow oneself to be changed.”46 The promise of a glorious future, which Abraham believed, is revealed fully in the resurrected Christ. The life represented by the Resurrection is eternal and one of communion with God. It redeems humanity from what is so familiar—namely sin, suffering, and death—and allows the believer to share in that eternal life. It implies the eradication of sin and death in general and the forgiveness of personal sins and their consequences as well. Benedict’s more existential description of faith allows him to address contemporary concerns better than if he had retained more traditional language. He believes that it is important that Christian faith be a trust directed toward “that which has not been made by oneself and never could be made and which precisely in this way supports and makes possible all our making.”47 It means that this trust lies outside the realm of practical or scientific knowledge. Drawing from Heidegger’s distinction between “calculating” and “reflective” thought, Benedict argues that trust belongs to the realm of reflective thought, the dimension of humanity that pertains to the “realm of basic decisions that man cannot avoid making.”48 43 See Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance, 94. 44 Ratzinger, Faith and the Future, 42. 45 Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance, 87. 46 Ratzinger, Faith and the Future, 46. 47 Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity, 70. 48 Ibid., 71. Aaron Canty 264 In responding to the fundamental questions that pertain to the very meaning and existence of each human person, humanity can find the meaning of existence in what it makes or in what it receives from beyond itself. If humanity looks for the meaning of existence in what it makes, it must put its trust in the future that it is preparing and will accomplish. For Benedict, the archetypal model of this form of belief is Marxism.49 Since it does not acknowledge the reception of human existence and the meaning bestowed on it apart from itself, it is a monological belief system, or perhaps better, a solipsistic belief system.True dialogue can exist for humanity only when it responds to what it hears from outside itself. Although Benedict cites Marxism as a particularly acute danger because of the “impression it evokes of harmony with practical knowledge,”50 he also asserts that the danger of calculating thought eclipsing reflective thought is present in every age. Benedict cites as an example Bonaventure’s response to the increasing interest in the natural world that developed in the thirteenth century. The problem according to Bonaventure was not so much the growing autonomy of philosophy or natural science. What Bonaventure encountered was a certain type of amnesia.According to Benedict, “Bonaventure felt obliged to reproach his colleagues of the philosophical faculty at Paris with having learned how to measure the world but having forgotten how to measure themselves.”51 How should humanity “measure” itself? A clue to discovering how to measure oneself is the restlessness within each person. Augustine, in the famous opening passage of The Confessions, prayed, “You have made us and drawn us to yourself, and our heart is unquiet until it rests in you.”52 The restlessness that one feels existentially invites the kind of reflective thought to which Bonaventure exhorted his colleagues at the University of Paris. Ultimately that restlessness is a deeper invitation, not only to reflective thought, but to a radical orientation and trust in the Creator. This reflective thought can liberate humanity and allow it to realize its yearning for authentic freedom, which is conceived not as the ability to act in autonomous fashion, but rather as the acceptance of love.53 Ultimately it is faith or trust in God that will allow humanity to find the true measure of itself. Benedict notes the significance of faith in his 49 See Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity, 72. See also his comments regarding Marxism in Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, nos. 26, 31. 50 Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity, 72. 51 Ibid., 71. 52 Augustine, The Confessions, trans. Maria Boulding (New York: New City Press, 1997), I, 1, 1. 53 See Ratzinger, Behold the Pierced One, 33–34; and idem, Salt of the Earth, 282–83. Bonaventure and Pope Benedict XVI 265 commentary on part of Gaudium et Spes:“Faith does not diminish man but leads him in the direction which alone the endless restlessness which impels him can find satisfaction. Man’s measure is infinity, everything else is too little for him. Consequently only God can be man’s measure.”54 This capacity for God is a gift, something received and not something manufactured by humanity. Faith is the human response to that gift and “to the meaning” that supports humanity and the world.55 In “more traditional language,” Benedict describes faith as “a response to the word, the logos, that upholds and maintains all things.”56 It is clear, however, that there is nothing impersonal about this response to “the word.”This faith is a trust in the Word-made-flesh, a person, who makes existence intelligible to humanity: Christian faith lives on the discovery that not only is there such a thing as objective meaning but that this meaning knows me and loves me, that I can entrust myself to it like the child who knows that everything he may be wondering about is safe in the “you” of his mother.Thus in the last analysis believing, trusting, and loving are one, and all the theses around which belief revolves are only concrete expressions of the allembracing about-turn, of the assertion “I believe in you”—of the discovery of God in the countenance of the man Jesus of Nazareth.57 Faith, then, as an attitude of trust, begins with openness to what is not perceived by the senses, and it moves toward a realization that this imperceivable reality beyond itself communicates meaning to each individual. What gives meaning to human beings, precisely, is love, a love that is manifested in action. Here is where the revelation of God in Jesus Christ becomes the starting point of the people’s realization of just how much this “imperceivable reality,” namely God, loves them. Although Benedict’s less traditional language, especially in his later writings, may make his theology of revelation seem rather distant from that of Bonaventure, Benedict has retained most of the essential themes of Bonaventure’s thought. First, Benedict gives priority to God’s initiative in revealing himself to humanity. Second, this revelation transcends the text of Scripture in such a way that faith must precede its reading for it 54 See his commentary on Gaudium et Spes “The Dignity of the Human Person,” in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 5, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler, trans. W. J. O’Hara (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969), 159.The sentiment articulated there is expressed in the context of human freedom in idem, Behold the Pierced One, 34. 55 Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity, 73. 56 Ibid. 57 Ibid., 80. Aaron Canty 266 to be transformative.58 Third, faith, that is, humanity’s response to God, necessarily possesses a corporate dimension. Revelation is given to individuals, who, because of their faith, form a community that continually communicates God’s revelation. An ongoing dialectic of reception and communication continues throughout history so that “the individual authors [of the Bible] are inspired, and thus the Church is active in speaking through them, and God is speaking through the Church.”59 Throughout history then, revelation continues and even grows, both in the individual and in the Church.60 Fourth, Benedict’s theology of revelation maintains a strong historical and even eschatological orientation, which involves not only an emphasis on God’s plan of salvation within history, but also on the very theological significance of history and its relationship with the future.These elements of fundamental theology, all central to Benedict’s thought, have close parallels with the theology of the Seraphic Doctor. Although in Benedict’s later writings Bonaventure is cited less frequently than he was in the earlier part of his career, and although Benedict clearly developed what he had learned from Bonaventure, Bonaventure’s theology of revelation remains a foundational source of Benedict’s own theology and his view of God’s revelation to humanN&V ity within history. 58 See Joseph Ratzinger, God and the World, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2002), 152–59. 59 Ibid., 155. Heinrich Schlier, who wrote about revelation at the time of the Second Vatican Council, expresses it this way: “the communication of God by Jesus Christ to the world merges into communication of Him by the tradition of those who experienced it. God’s self-disclosure to the world is disclosed precisely as such in history, in the explanatory speech of those who have opened themselves to it.” The Relevance of the New Testament, trans. W. J. O’Hara (New York: Herder & Herder, 1968), 49. (The original edition, Besinnung auf das Neue Testament, was published in 1964.) 60 See Ratzinger, God and the World, 154. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 267–70 267 The Theological Heritage of Pope Benedict XVI ROMANUS C ESSARIO, OP St. John’s Seminary Brighton, Massachusetts The Pope Theologian N O POPE in modern times has come to the Chair of Peter with as copious a body of published theological writings as did Joseph Ratzinger. He has written more than eighty-five books as well as over five hundred articles and occasional essays. Although Pope Benedict XVI is knowledgeable in many fields, the majority of his writings exhibit his professional competence as a theologian. Upon being received into the Pontifical Academy of Sciences, thenCardinal Ratzinger remarked in 2002:“I did my philosophical and theological studies immediately after the war, from 1946 to 1951. In this period, theological formation in the faculty of Munich was essentially determined by the biblical, liturgical, and ecumenical movement of the time between the two World Wars.”1 Joseph Ratzinger engaged the theological disciplines that prepared him to meet the challenges that the Church would face in the twenty-first century. It is easy to discern in this This short essay, which draws on published reflections by the Irish priest-student of Joseph Ratzinger Vincent Toomey, originally appeared as an introduction to Benedictus, ed. Peter John Cameron (San Francisco: Ignatius Press/Magnificat, 2006).This volume of day-by-day meditations taken from the writings of Pope Benedict XVI offers to those who do not have the time to read everything that the pope has written a way to benefit from his richly textured insights into divine truth. Father Peter John Cameron, O.P., who is a long-time student of the pope’s writings, has assembled excerpts from the pope’s writings that may serve, among other purposes, as a source for daily reflection. 1 For the complete text of Pope Benedict’s remarks, see Pontifical Academy of Sciences, Scripta Varia 105, The Cultural Values of Science (Vatican City: Pontificia Academia Scientiarum, 2003), 50–52. 268 Romanus Cessario, OP program of studies the hand of divine providence at work early in the life of a man who would become pope. Professional theologians will come to recognize what the pope himself has described recently as the “unfinished character” of his complete works. The unfinishedness that Benedict XVI ascribes to his lifelong theological accomplishment does not signal a failure, however. He contemplates what might have been the case if he were not asked to assume responsibilities other than those of a university professor. Joseph Ratzinger was called to assure pastoral service in the Church, first as cardinal archbishop of Munich and shortly thereafter as prefect of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. He was not afforded the opportunity to complete the kind of overall systematic account of Catholic theology that, for example, finds an original model in the Summa theologiae of St.Thomas Aquinas.The pope considers nonetheless that his writings do “amount to something like a single whole.” Pope Benedict XVI makes these remarks on his own writings in his 2005 book Values in a Time of Upheaval: How to Survive the Challenge of the Future.2 The Pope’s Theology Pope Benedict XVI has been occupied with theological studies and discussion for more than half a century. No wonder that he has found the occasion to write on nearly every topic that one expects from the pen of an authentic Catholic theologian.This massive accomplishment provides the pope’s blueprint for doing theology. One way to identify some general themes that emerge in the theological reflections of Joseph Ratzinger is to recall what he reports as the influences that surrounded his own early theological studies: the Holy Bible, the Sacred Liturgy, and Catholic ecumenism. The Sacred Scriptures introduce Christ. Joseph Ratzinger takes seriously the Church Fathers’ insistence on the unity of the Old and New Testaments.This unity illuminates the central place that Jesus Christ holds in the salvation of the world. No one is saved without at least implicit faith in the One Mediator between God and men, which in some way associates them with the worldwide communion that we call the Church. The Liturgy of the Church finds its source in the Eucharist. It is said that Pope Benedict had to be persuaded to hold his inaugural Mass as pope in St. Peter’s Square. He would have preferred to offer the Mass within the Vatican basilica to make it visually clear that Christ stands at 2 Pope Benedict XVI, Values in a Time of Upheaval: How to Survive the Challenge of the Future (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2005). The Theological Heritage of Benedict XVI 269 the center of every efficacious liturgical action that the Church celebrates. Each human being is called to participate in the worship that Christ offers to the Father of glory and that is preeminently commemorated in the Catholic Mass. Ecumenism is ordered to reveal that the one Church of Christ exists in order to communicate the gift of salvation to the whole human race. There is only one saving communion. People of God and God’s House in Augustine’s Doctrine of the Church is the title of the pope’s doctoral dissertation.3 From his earliest student days, a principal concern of Pope Benedict XVI has been to point out the legitimate place that the Church holds among the nations; he wants to capture for his contemporaries the important reflections that St. Augustine first aired in his chapters on the City of God and the City of Man. The Pope’s Mission In accord with one’s personal vocation, each Catholic is obliged to make the mission of the pope his or her own. Like the great pontiffs who are his predecessors, Benedict XVI considers it incumbent on a Catholic bishop to address the well-being of both the Church and the political community. He recognizes that the original rebellion of the human race still makes its adverse influence felt among even the most enlightened of our contemporaries. “The outcry in favor of anarchy,” writes the pope, “is the reaction to a threatening feeling of dependency that creates a new form of non-liberty in the middle of our social liberties.”4 The pope offers more than a social critique. He has an exit strategy. Benedict XVI proclaims that God has provided a remedy for mankind’s ancient curse: Christ, the Eucharist, the Church. The Incarnation of the Son of God ennobles every human being. In Christ, each believer receives his mandate to make things new. It is no wonder that Benedict XVI returns again and again to the Fiat spoken by the Blessed Virgin Mary. He sees that her submission to God effectively brings tranquil order, happy surrender, and true freedom to the world. Those who want to share in these liberating qualities are invited 3 Joseph Ratzinger, Volk und Haus Gottes in Augustinus Lehre von der Kirche (Ph.D. diss., University of Munich, 1954). 4 In Pope Benedict XVI, Theologische Prinzipienlehre. Bausteine zur Fundamentalthe- ologie, 2nd ed. (Donauwörth:Verlag Erich Wewel, 2005): “Der wachsende Schrei nach Anarchie ist die Reaktion auf das bedrängende Gefühl totaler Anhängigkeit, die eine neue Form totaler Unfreiheit mitten in den bürgerlichen Freihalten erschaffen könnte.” English trans: Principles of Catholic Theology: Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology, trans. Sr. Mary Frances McCarthy, S.N.D. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987). 270 Romanus Cessario, OP to enter into her Magnificat. Those who implement, according to their capacities, what Pope Benedict XVI says about Christ, the Eucharist, and the Church will contribute to completing in their own lives and vocations what for reasons known only to God Joseph Ratzinger has left N&V “unfinished.” Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 271–84 271 A Note on Joseph Ratzinger and Contemporary Theology of the Priesthood M ATTHEW L EVERING Ave Maria University Naples, FL I N HIS ESSAY “On the Essence of the Priesthood,” originally delivered at the opening of the Synod of Bishops on the priesthood in October 1990, Joseph Ratzinger begins by depicting the current mainstream viewpoint regarding leadership in the earliest Christian communities. According to this mainstream scholarship,“Above all there is no sign that these offices were empowered for cultic worship: nowhere are they explicitly connected with the celebration of the Eucharist. Indeed, their content appears to be principally the proclamation of the Gospel and, in second place, the ministry of love among Christians, along with functions of a more practical sort within the community.”1 Lacking the aspect of cultic worship, no hierarchical priesthood would be needed, since teaching and service require no unique priestly participation in Christ beyond that which all Christians receive. As Ratzinger observes, this mainstream position leads to a functional rather than ontological/sacramental account of Christian priesthood: “All of these data arouse the impression that these offices were seen, not sacrally but in purely functional terms, that is, that they were administered entirely according to considerations of practical utility.”2 Corresponding to this functional account of the priesthood, he goes on to say, is a non-cultic understanding of Jesus’ Cross, which becomes an exemplar of love that radically overturns every “cultic” 1 Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, “On the Essence of the Priesthood,” in Called to Communion: Understanding the Church Today, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1996 [German 1991]), 105–31, at 107. 2 Ibid. 272 Matthew Levering system and thereby frees human beings from sacrificial worship.3 In this light it is not surprising that many Catholic theologians now seek to go beyond both Trent and Vatican II’s teaching on the priesthood, so as “to abandon the ancient conceptions of cult and priesthood and to seek a Church at once biblical and modern that would resolutely take up the challenge of the profane world and would be organized solely according to functional considerations.”4 Is Ratzinger’s description of the contemporary situation correct, and if so how might theologians reclaim an understanding of the cultic priesthood? The two sections of my brief essay seek an initial answer to these questions. First, in order to flesh out Ratzinger’s depiction of the contemporary situation, I summarize the views of the sacramental theologian David Power. Second, I suggest that Ratzinger’s essay offers an exemplary path for moving beyond the current mainstream view that Jesus abolishes the cultic/hierarchical priesthood. 3 Ratzinger challenges the notion that such exegetical conclusions are “objective,” arguing instead that they are “the fruit of the fundamental hermeneutical options developed in the Reformation of the sixteenth century. The central point of these options was a reading of the Bible based on the dialectical opposition of law and promise, of priest and prophet, of cult and promise.The mutually coordinated categories of law, priest and cult were classified as the negative aspect of the history of salvation: the law, it was maintained, leads man to self-righteousness; cultic worship presupposes the error that man stands on a sort of equal footing with God and can establish a relationship of justice between himself and God by offering certain gifts; priesthood, on this reading, is, so to say, the institutional expression and the permanent instrument of this perverted relationship with God.The essence of the gospel, which is said to appear at its clearest particularly in the major Pauline epistles, would then be the overcoming of this structure raised by man’s destructive self-righteousness.The new relationship to God rests entirely on promise and grace, and it finds expression in the figure of the prophet, who is accordingly construed as strictly opposed to the cult and the priesthood. Catholicism appeared to Luther as the sacrilegious reinstatement of the cult, of sacrifice, priesthood and law. He therefore saw it as the negation of grace, as apostasy from the gospel, as a return behind Christ to Moses” (108). Ratzinger adds, however, that “there were countertendencies even at the time of the Reformation, even within Lutheranism and Luther’s own works. In spite of everything, ordination was soon understood as much more than a purely functional decree that could be revoked at any moment but was conceived as having at least a certain analogy to a sacrament. Its connection with the celebration of the Eucharist quickly reemerged, and it was even seen once more that the Eucharist and preaching are not to be disjoined. . . . Accordingly, it was precisely the branch of Protestantism tracing itself back to Luther that also developed a strong cultic tradition, whose deepening in the liturgical spring of the twentieth century made possible fruitful ecumenical encounters” (109–10). 4 Ibid., 109. Joseph Ratzinger and Theology of the Priesthood 273 David Power on the Priesthood David Power’s The Eucharistic Mystery: Revitalizing the Tradition bemoans the loss of a proper understanding of “sacrifice” in the early Church, a loss that in his view led to the development of a strict distinction between the ordained priesthood and the common priesthood, as well as to the deformation of the Church’s understanding of the Eucharist. In the early Church of Justin Martyr,“sacrifice” in Christian worship meant not a bloody sacrifice, or a cultic (unbloody) reenactment of Jesus’ bloody sacrifice, but rather a spiritual sacrifice, a “sacrifice” of praise and thanksgiving. In this way, the pagan and Jewish emphasis on the need for the shedding of blood in the worship of God was transcended. Early Christianity, Power notes, provided a “way to God that eliminated cultic sacrifice from the picture and placed the grateful memory of the cross in its stead and replaced the rites of sacrifice with the table of Christ’s body and blood.”5 By sharing a meal with the risen Lord and giving thanks for what the Lord did on the Cross, the early Christians indicated that pagan and Jewish bloody sacrifice, the need for violence in the relationship with God, no longer had a place after Jesus. Jesus’ death and resurrection made possible an entirely new way of relating to God, namely, relating to the risen Lord in table fellowship and praise. The contrast between friends sharing a transformative meal in a spirit of rejoicing and priests slitting the throats of animals and sprinkling their blood upon the altar is clear. Power remarks that by continuing to use the term “sacrifice,” however, the early Christians risked that their metaphorical understanding of “sacrifice” (as a spiritual sacrifice of praise and thanksgiving) would be misunderstood by later Christians. More importantly for the development of the priesthood, the early Christians risked that the pagan and Jewish forms of cultic priesthood—built around ritual slaying of animals so as, among other things, to purify the people before God—would return in the Christian community. Where Eucharistic worship is a meal between friends who are rejoicing and giving thanks together, there need be no strict distinction between the friends; although one may preside, nonetheless such presiding need require no cultic consecration (cf. Exodus 29) that sets apart priests for the service of God, and that leads to a two-tiered relationship of the community with God. If all the friends are equally equipped to offer thanksgiving at the meal, then all the friends relate to God together, on the same level. By contrast, if some of the friends are consecrated priests, then the other friends have to relate to God in worship through the mediation of the priests. 5 David N. Power, O.M.I., The Eucharistic Mystery: Revitalizing the Tradition (New York: Crossroad, 1992), 320. 274 Matthew Levering The latter situation, Power holds, came about due to negligence in the early Christian community as regards the words “priest” and “sacrifice.” He explains the original situation:“As is well known, in earliest times no cultic vocabulary was attached to presiding at the Eucharist. The one pronouncing the prayer and blessing the table was given only a functional designation.Words like presider, supervisor, or bishop were enough to designate the officiant, just as they designated the ministerial role of leadership in the church.”6 Such words referred to a function, but not to an ontological status that elevated some Christians above others in the relationship to God accomplished in worship. Unlike pagans and Jews, these early Christians did not depend upon priestly, cultic intercession; Jesus had removed this barrier. He did not remove the barrier, Power emphasizes, by offering on the Cross the perfect sacrifice.This would be to place the Cross in a continuum of sacrifice, so that it would differ only in degree from other bloody sacrifices. Rather, in Jesus, an entirely new way of relating to God becomes possible. Christ’s supreme love in sharing his life with us, a life that overcomes death by his resurrection, makes us friends of God, no longer burdened with the weight of offering bloody sacrifice to God so as to propitiate and be acceptable to an alien God. Power states, “All ritual offerings ceased because of the way in which the Word Incarnate had wrestled with humankind’s alienation from God in death and sin.”7 Lives filled with love are henceforth the path of relationship with God, rather than requiring the mediation of priestly and cultic sacrifice. Thus, as Power observes, “The religious awe and power associated with cultic sacrifice was transferred to the memorial Eucharist, to the death remembered, to lives lived in obedience to this gospel, and to the witness of the martyrs.”8 The pagan and Jewish habits, however, remained close to the surface, and the early Christian effort to redefine the old words ultimately failed. This failure occurred gradually, making the Eucharist a particularly “poignant” instance of the tendency of human beings to reify what is originally a metaphor.9 Power remarks, “When the presider was in time called a priest, at first this meant nothing more than what was meant by designating the prayer or the blessed gifts a sacrifice.”10 A “priest” was not a cultic priest, no more than the “sacrifice” was a cultic sacrifice. On the contrary, the words simply evoked metaphorically the “religious awe and 6 Ibid., 321. 7 Ibid. 8 Ibid. 9 Ibid., 320. 10 Ibid., 321. Joseph Ratzinger and Theology of the Priesthood 275 power” that pagans and Jews had associated with the cultic worship; the metaphors served to show that Christian worship had taken up and fulfilled the goals of pagan and Jewish worship, but no longer with the need for consecrated priests devoted to offering bloody intercessory sacrifice to God. As Power puts it, “When Justin Martyr said that Christians did indeed have a sacrifice but that it was no other than the thanks rendered for redemption in the death of Christ, his words recast religious reality in a new mould.”11 Even when the priest’s sacramental action began to be seen as action “ex persona Christi,” this meant solely that Christ’s power, not the priest’s, infused the sacrament.12 What happened, in Power’s view, to finally overpower this fragile “new mould” for religious thinking, this transformation of worship into a meal of friendship and thanksgiving? By the fourth century the “new mould” was showing severe strains:“Already in John Chrysostom’s relation of the action of the bishop to Christ’s heavenly liturgy there is a tendency to employ the words sacrifice and priest in a more mythical than metaphorical sense.”13 What had happened, Power says, was that the understanding of the Eucharist as a memorial meal—“Do this in remembrance of me” (Lk 22:19)—had changed.The act of remembering Jesus’ gift of his body and blood now was understood to insert participants into Jesus’ very act of sacrificial self-offering. Instead of a memorial, the Eucharist thus became a representation or reenactment in the sense of enabling participants to share in Jesus’ very act. Instead of the linear horizon of time within which participants remembered Jesus’ past actions with hope for the future consummation of the kingdom, the Eucharist now inserted time into eternity in such a way as to enable the present to participate, ontologically, in the past and in the future. Power describes with dismay the resulting collapse of the early Christian attempt to move beyond the traditional religious framework of priestly sacrifice: “In this context, the language of sacrifice assumed anew something of its cultic and mythic character.The sacrificial act of Eucharist was again given propitiatory and cultic power. It appealed anew to the cultic shedding of blood and the offering of victims as a way of escaping evil and making retribution for sin.”14 Once the Eucharist came to be understood as a cultic sacrifice, Christian priesthood underwent a similar retrogression to the pagan and Jewish model of consecrated intercessors standing between the people and their (wrathful) God. 11 Ibid., 320. 12 Ibid., 321. 13 Ibid. 14 Ibid., 321–22. 276 Matthew Levering According to Power, although this radical distortion of Christian ecclesiology and worship has largely held sway for over 1600 years (in the Catholic Church at least), the present moment offers a propitious time for carrying forward once again the early Christians’ rejection of cultic worship and cultic priesthood. He observes, “As things stand at present, the language of priesthood and sacrifice needs to be once more demythologized.”15 In order to accomplish this, he suggests, one needs first to understand why the mythical understanding of the humankind’s relationship to God, in which God is seen as requiring bloody sacrifice from consecrated intercessors, has proven to be so resilient.The answer is evident as regards rural people who depend upon the seasonal cycles of life:“If the spirits were propitious, the cycles themselves were benevolent. Angering spirits or showing them neglect was hazardous to the lifeworld.”16 Among rural Christians, this worldview was transposed so that it seemed that Christ’s “suffering appeased God and so rendered the surrounding world benevolent.”17 Cultic participation in Christ’s sacrificial Cross enabled such Christians to think that they had appeased God and would therefore be blessed. Although it is less clear why the sacrificial worldview holds attraction even for modern, urban people, Power speculates that the reason is that cultic sacrifice appears “to offer a means of overcoming the disorder caused by injustice and division and offense against rule.”18 Cultic sacrifice, on this view, reestablishes “order.” How then can this notion be “demythologized,” in accord with early Christian faith and practice? Power argues that once more the early Christian “reversal” of the pagan and Jewish bloodletting must be heard. (Holding that Judaism became less and less a cultic religion during the time of the prophets, Power adds the caveat that he wishes to make his point not “by way of comparison with Old Testament worship, which in its own way is a story of reversal, but by way of contrast with what appears to be a rather universal human instinct to want to ‘make sacrifice.’ ”)19 God is not a wrathful God who desires victims. Rather, God loves us and desires us as friends with whom he shares fellowship. Since everything is God’s gift, God is not so needy as to require that sacrificial offerings from us. In faith, we can recognize God’s infinitely gifting love, and we can thereby emerge from the cycle of cultic sacrifice. God need not be propitiated at special times or through special acts of worship; all 15 Ibid., 322. 16 Ibid. 17 Ibid. 18 Ibid. 19 Ibid. Joseph Ratzinger and Theology of the Priesthood 277 God asks, instead, is that we share his love. Above all, God completely renounces violence. Love is the opposite of violence, although love may at times be called to non-violent martyrdom. As Power says, Christ “reverses the attempt to set aside special times and acts of worship by revealing that the people freed in Christ are themselves ‘sacrifice,’ that true worship is a life lived in faith and according to the gospel and in the Eucharist celebrated as such. In the cross of Christ believers have been freed once and for all from evil powers, sin, and death.”20 For Power, then, sacrifice in its “demythologized” sense is a “language of reversal.”21 What is sacrificed in Christ’s death is the old worldview of pagans and Jews (the latter to varying degrees). Gone is the notion of the God who seeks our offerings and the blood of victims. In its place, Christ makes fully manifest the God of love, already active in the Old Testament. This God wants us to join him in love and friendship.Whereas the God of sacrifice emerges from our fears about our fragility in a world of suffering and death, the God of love proclaims good gifts and resurrection from the dead. Communion in loving fellowship, rather than sacrifice to a needy God, constitutes the real import of Christ’s death. In this “reversal of values,” the false god and the false religion are “sacrificed.” Power states that Christ’s “love proclaimed reverses the order of religion in which the judgment of God demands satisfaction to one in which a communion with a forgiving and loving God is possible.To celebrate this reversal, recourse can be had to some of the images other than sacrifice that tradition supplies.”22 Among these images are God’s vindication of the just and the release of those in bondage. The resurrection, not the crucifixion, thus comes to stand at the heart of Eucharistic theology. The Eucharist invites people to the liberation from evil, sin, and death that God reveals and accomplishes through Christ’s resurrection, and that forms the basis of our eschatological hope. Against the view that the Eucharist represents and reenacts Christ’s Passion, Power remarks that the Eucharist promotes the kingdom of God “not by a mythic reenactment of a primordial sacred event, but by a retrieval of the eschaton into the story. In the story, the image of Christ’s return figures as judgment upon malevolence and as a reversal of values.”23 Similarly the Eucharist, properly understood, should not for Power inspire self-sacrifice or mortification, but rather should inspire intensified communion in self-giving love and mercy. The Eucharist 20 Ibid., 322–23. 21 Ibid., 322 and 323. 22 Ibid., 323. 23 Ibid. 278 Matthew Levering stands for the justice of communion (the God of love) rather than the justice of sacrifice (the God of fear). Power affirms, “It is the demythologization of sacrifice, the predication that relates it to Christ’s love, to thanksgiving, to a life of obedience to the gospel, that offers a new paradigm for justice.”24 Christians thus should seek communion with each other in love, confident that “[i]n the bread and wine of the people there is the presence of a God who is revealed by being veiled under these symbols, just as the divine love continues to be revealed under the veil of Christ’s suffering.”25 Clearly, this vision has an impact on how one should understand the Christian “priesthood.” Rather than a two-tiered system in which consecrated priests offer up Christ’s sacrifice on behalf of the people, the community that gathers for the common meal of thanksgiving in memory of Jesus enjoys an unqualified unity “in the communion of a common table that knows of no discrimination.”26 The task of the leaders of the community is to make manifest this unity in the gospel as received by the community and in the “common table.” God’s gifts of life and healing are for everyone, and do not require sacrificial or cultic priestly mediation. When Power discusses the priesthood, therefore, he emphasizes its transparency to the community rather than anything that sets it apart within the community. In his view,“The role of the priest has too often been spoken of as a power received. It is properly understood in what it says of the reality of church communion.”27 The priesthood should be understood, in other words, not as a power to consecrate the Eucharistic sacrifice in the divine worship, but as a service of communion:“Ordination to ministry in fact expresses the ecclesial reality of inner 24 Ibid. 25 Ibid., 324. Power later summarizes his understanding of God’s presence in the Paschal mystery: “It is proclaimed in the story of the death and resurrection of Jesus Christ that even in suffering the power of God prevails in the history of the world. In his death, Jesus is presented as eschatological judge in whom the triumph of God’s power will prevail. . . . In the paschal narrative, the hearers of the word hear of their own future hope and expectation.The force of God’s love prevails amid all the discontinuities of history and keeps hope alive.The memory of all who suffered is taken into the memory of Christ.This dangerous memory stands as judgment on human injustice and as promise of freedom. It liberates from prejudice and fear. It offers a critique of human ideologies and institutions, political and religious. In faith and anticipative memory, Christian peoples can always give testimony to an alternative world, in which love and justice prevail” (347). 26 Ibid. 27 Ibid., 346. Joseph Ratzinger and Theology of the Priesthood 279 unity, Catholic communion, and apostolic foundation. The role of the presider is to let speak and work those realities that presidency serves.”28 In particular, Power identifies three such realities: the power of the word, the community’s apostolic witness, and the communion table.The priest/presider serves “the power of the word” through the homily, which is best understood as “a community action” rather than as the work of the priest.29 The community’s apostolic witness possesses a preeminence recognized, Power says, in the Didascalia’s “image of the bishop yielding his chair to the beggar,” an image that should inspire like actions.30 Third, the priest/presider’s role at the communion table finds true expression “[w]hen the ritual performance of the communion rite is such as to express the bonding in Christ of members with each other in the sharing of Christ’s own gift.”31 In these three realities, the existing communion of believers in Christ’s love, not priestly cultic achievement of such communion through sharing in Christ’s sacrifice, is affirmed and celebrated by the priest/presider, whose role is strictly functional rather than ontologically differentiated from other members of the community. Joseph Ratzinger on the Priesthood: Three Principles How might one respond to Power’s position? As a beginning step, I think that one can find in Joseph Ratzinger’s “On the Essence of the Priesthood” principles for challenging Power’s viewpoint. I will identify three of them here. 1. Jesus Christ is the bearer of power to heal the world. A fully developed Christology and soteriology, Ratzinger suggests, finds in Jesus Christ both the newness of the gospel and the unity of the Old and New Covenants.Thus it will not suffice to conceive of Jesus “as the great ethical teacher who frees man from the constraints of cultic ritual and places him directly before God with his personal conscience.”32 Nor is Jesus the great liberator from institutional oppression, notably that of priestly institutions. Rather, “In all the Gospels, he appears as the bearer of a power received from God (Mt 7:29, 21:23; Mk 1:27, 11:28; Lk 20:2, 24:19, et passim).”33 28 Ibid. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid. 31 Ibid. 32 Ratzinger, “On the Essence of the Priesthood,” 111–12. 33 Ibid., 112. 280 Matthew Levering 2. The Gospels show that Jesus shares his power with the disciples/apostles. By configuring the twelve as the new Israel, after his Resurrection “Jesus confers his power upon the apostles and thereby makes their office strictly parallel to his own mission. ‘He who receives you receives me’, he says to the Twelve (Mt 10:40; cf. Lk 10:16; Jn 13:20).”34 Could this power simply be the power to teach and serve, and thus a power that would not seem to require a hierarchical priesthood among Christians? Against this view, Ratzinger argues that the “power” is the power of divine gifting:“How could they [the disciples/apostles] possibly say ‘I forgive you your sins’? How could they conceivably say ‘This is my body’ or impose their hands and pronounce the words ‘Receive the Holy Spirit’? Nothing that makes up the activity of the apostles is the product of their own capabilities.”35 Since their power is one of divine gifting, it must be uniquely received from God. It is received from God as a participation in Jesus’ own relation of total receptivity to the Father. As witness to this point, Ratzinger cites two texts from the Gospel of John: “The Son can do nothing of himself ” ( Jn 5:19, 30) and “Without me you can do nothing” ( Jn 15:5). The disciples/apostles receive all from the incarnate Son, just as the Son receives all from the Father. By receiving a share in Christ’s power of divine gifting—manifested in the forgiveness of sins, the Eucharist, baptism, and so forth—the disciples/apostles enjoy a power that goes beyond, while including, teaching and service. This power to communicate the divine gifting is rooted, as Christ’s power is, in radical receptivity, and so the power itself is a “sacrament” received from Christ. 3. Paul makes clear the structure of gifting/receptivity that belongs to kenotic power. In 2 Corinthians 5, Ratzinger notes, Paul emphasizes the connection between his work and Christ’s: All this is from God, who through Christ reconciled us to himself and gave us the ministry of reconciliation; that is, God was in 34 Ibid., 113. In this regard Ratzinger also cites other texts from the Gospels:“Perti- nent here is the whole string of texts in which Jesus transmits his own ‘power’ (authority) to the disciples: Matthew 9:8; 10:1; 21:23; Mark 6:7; 13:34; Luke 4:6; 9:1; 10:19. For its part, the Fourth Gospel goes on to complete in especially clear terms the parallelism between the form of Jesus’ mission and the form of the mission of the apostles: ‘As the Father has sent me, so I send you’ (13:20; 17:18; 20:21)” (113–14). 35 Ibid., 114. Joseph Ratzinger and Theology of the Priesthood 281 Christ reconciling the world to himself, not counting their trespasses against them, and entrusting to us the message of reconciliation. So we are ambassadors for Christ, God making his appeal through us.We beseech you on behalf of Christ, be reconciled to God. (2 Cor 5:18–20) Paul’s “ministry of reconciliation” communicates to others the reconciliation accomplished by Christ. Put another way, it communicates the power of Christ’s Cross. As Ratzinger says, “Since as a historical happening it [the Cross] belongs to the past, it can be appropriated only ‘sacramentally’, though Paul does not explain in detail here how this takes place.”36 Most importantly, Paul’s power itself is “sacramental”—that is, a participation in Christ’s power— because it is a distinct ministry belonging to Paul as an ambassador, or steward (1 Cor 4:1), of Christ. For Ratzinger, such apostolic power serves to carry “forward that dialogical structure that pertains to the essence of revelation,”37 by inscribing a structure of receptivity within which the divine gifting operates. Arguing that this dialogical structure of gifting/receptivity belongs intrinsically to the Church, Ratzinger cites Paul’s farewell exhortation to the “elders” (presbyteroi) of the Ephesian Church as recorded in Acts 20:28:“Take heed to yourselves and to all the flock, in which the Holy Spirit has made you guardians [episkopoi], to feed the church of the Lord which he obtained with his own blood.”These “presbyter-bishops,” Ratzinger observes, “are successors but are not themselves apostles.”38 Their task, like Paul’s, is to communicate the divine gifting so that the universal priesthood of Christ may be nourished.39 36 Ibid., 118. 37 Ibid., 120. 38 Ibid., 123. 39 Ratzinger presents this point by quoting Jean Colson’s words about the Old Testament priesthood: “ ‘It is the chief function of the kohanim (i‘eqei~y) to keep the people aware of its priestly character and to work so that it might live in accordance with it, so that it might glorify God with its entire existence’ ” (127, quoted from J. Colson, Ministre de Jésus-Christ ou le Sacerdoce de l’Évangile [Paris: 1966], 185). Ratzinger comments on this quotation: “This statement is unmistakably close to the already-cited formula in which Paul speaks of his mission as leitourgos of Jesus Christ; the only difference is that the dynamic, missionary character of this expression now comes much more clearly to light as a consequence of the bursting open of the boundaries of Israel by the Cross of Christ.The ultimate end of all New Testament liturgy and of all priestly ministry is to make the world as a whole a temple and a sacrificial offering for God” (127). 282 Matthew Levering Concluding Reflections What then are the main differences between Ratzinger’s and Power’s positions? First, as regards Jesus Christ, Power understands him as the one who liberates human beings from the perceived need to placate an alienated god through sacrificial worship. Jesus reveals instead that God desires to unite us to himself in a shared celebratory meal. By contrast, Ratzinger denies that Jesus is primarily a teacher who frees human beings from the irrationalities of cultic worship. For Ratzinger, Jesus bears life-changing power from the Father. Jesus’ power changes the world through his total self-giving on the Cross. His power, when applied to us, changes us from self-centered to self-giving. Second, as regards Jesus’ sharing of his power with the disciples/apostles, Power argues that all human beings are equal in the celebratory meal, a meal that exposes God’s triumphant and everpresent love. Since God does not need cultic propitiation, there is no need for anything but a functional distinction between the presider at the meal and the other partakers. For his part, Ratzinger holds that Jesus’ sharing of his power with his disciples/apostles ontologically changes them and gives them a distinct role in the community. They receive a power that is beyond merely human capacities, a power to give the divine gift.Third, as regards the witness of Paul, Power emphasizes that the apostolic generation preached the triumph of love over fear and the recognition that everything is God’s gift.There is thus no need for setting apart special acts of worship.We worship rightly when, freed from the myth of an alienated God, we recognize that God’s gifting takes place all around us. Ratzinger’s position again is quite different. He holds that Paul, with the other apostles, receives a “ministry of reconciliation” in which Paul serves as a “steward” of the power of divine gifting.The ecclesial hierarchy instantiates a structure of gifting and receptivity (a participation in the Son’s relation to the Father) that is the opposite of the sinful human tendency to claim autonomous self-construction and self-sufficiency. In short, Ratzinger’s three principles suggest a path toward reclaiming the theology of the cultic priesthood.The first step is to affirm that Jesus’ Pasch, as the supreme manifestation of his “power” from the Father in the Holy Spirit, brings about a real change in the relationship of human beings to God, rather than simply revealing God’s unchanging love.The second step is to identify the apostles as receiving an ontological share in Jesus’ Paschal “power” that enables them to bestow Jesus’ sanctifying gifts upon the whole community. The third step affirms that Jesus thereby constitutes a community built upon a structure of gifting/receptivity, which reverses the human sinful desire for autonomous self-sufficiency. Joseph Ratzinger and Theology of the Priesthood 283 By contrast to Power’s depiction of Jesus as the revealer of the omnipresence of God’s beneficent gifting, Ratzinger presents Jesus as answering, by the power of his embodied self-giving love, the need of fallen human beings to be liberated from their sinful pride and rejection of God. Jesus establishes hierarchical sacramental mediation in his Church because human beings need more than a celebratory meal that assures them of the omnipresence of God’s love. Given the sinful tendency to cleave to self, human beings require ongoing formation in receptivity to Jesus’ healing and elevating power. For Ratzinger, hierarchical sacramental mediation exists to form human beings in this cruciform image of radical receptivity. Ratzinger’s approach thus provides a model for a N&V renewed theology of Catholic priesthood. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 285–314 285 Joseph Ratzinger, Benedict XVI, on Biblical Interpretation: Two Leading Principles F RANCIS M ARTIN John Paul II Cultural Center Washington, DC T HE BASIC principles governing Joseph Ratzinger’s understanding of biblical hermeneutics can be reduced to two under which many other aspects of his approach can be subsumed. In this short study of his teaching on the understanding of the Bible, I will concentrate on these two principles, which can be expressed as: (1) The subject of biblical interpretation is the Church, the Whole Christ; (2) Scripture is a privileged instrument of Divine Revelation, which means that it mediates supernatural knowledge to those who approach it with faith. In this essay I will try to develop briefly the thinking of Benedict XVI on these two principles. In each case I will describe his position and then reflect on it theologically and philosophically. I offer this as a contribution that can help elucidate his thought as well as honor a theologian who has striven his whole life long to serve Jesus, the Word of God. The First Principle: The Subject of Interpretation A Brief Presentation of Joseph Ratzinger’s Thought In concluding his address of May 10, 2003, commemorating the onehundredth anniversary of the Pontifical Biblical Commission, Cardinal Ratzinger, its president, made the following statement that expresses both principles I have isolated for consideration in this essay: 286 Francis Martin Faith itself is a way of knowing.Wanting to set it aside does not produce pure objectivity, but comprises a point of view which excludes a particular perspective while not wanting to take into account the accompanying conditions of the chosen point of view. If one takes into account, however, that the Sacred Scriptures come from God through a subject which lives continually—the pilgrim people of God—then it becomes clear rationally as well that this subject has something to say about the understanding of the book.1 In another essay dedicated to “The Spiritual Basis and Ecclesial Identity of Theology,” Ratzinger further discusses the Church as the subject of theology thus opening up its interior mystery: The Church, moreover, is not an abstract principle but a living subject possessing a concrete content.This subject is by nature greater than any individual person, indeed than any single generation. Faith is always participation in a totality and, precisely in this way, conducts the believer to a new breadth of freedom. On the other hand, the Church is not an intangible spiritual realm in which everyone can pick what suits him. She is endowed with a concreteness rooted in the binding Word of faith. And she is a living voice which pronounces itself in the organs of faith. . . . But how exciting exegesis becomes when it dares to read the Bible as a whole. If the Bible originates from the one subject formed by the people of God and, through it, from the divine subject Himself, then it speaks of the present. . . . Without the living subject, either one must absolutize the letter, or else it vanishes into indefiniteness.2 “Subject” as the term is being used here may be defined as “the locus of agential receptivity and active engagement.” Employed this way the primary reference must be to a person, predicated analogously of divine and human persons.3 There is also the use of the term to apply to collective entities as “subjects,” the state, a family, a race, and so forth, which can be loci of receptivity and engagement but whose unity is found in a bond that is external to the persons who make it up.There is, however, a third way of being a subject, and this is the way of the Church, the Body of 1 “Relationship Between Magisterium and Exegetes,” address to the Pontifical Biblical Commission, L’Osservatore Romano (English), July 23, 2003. 2 Joseph Ratzinger, The Nature and Mission of Theology: Essays to Orient Theology in Today’s Debates, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995), 61, 64–65. 3 For a brief but clear treatment of “person” in theological predication, see Josef Ratzinger, “Concerning the Notion of Person in Theology,” Communio 17 (1990): 439–54. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 287 Christ that is neither a person, defined as “the incommunicably proper existence of spiritual nature,”4 nor a collectivity. In Thomas Aquinas’s opinion, the Church, which is the Mystical Body of Christ, may be considered as a “quasi person” united to Christ, its Head.5 It is this “mystical person” that is the subject of Revelation and its interpreter. In a 1997 essay Joseph Ratzinger addressed the issues of Revelation, Christology, the role of office in the Church, and the notion of the Church as subject:6 For the believer, however, the Church is not a sociological subject created by human agreement, but a truly new subject called into being by the Word and in the Holy Spirit; and precisely for that reason, the Church herself overcomes the seemingly insurmountable confines of human subjectivity by putting man in contact with the ground of reality which is prior to him.7 The Second Vatican Council teaches the historical continuity between the Church founded by Christ and the Catholic Church in the now-famous paragraph 8 of Lumen gentium: “This Church constituted and organized as a society in the present world subsists [subsistit] in the Catholic Church, governed by the Successor of Peter and by the bishops in communion with him, although outside of her structure, many elements can be found of sanctification and truth which, as gifts properly belonging to the Church of Christ, impel toward catholic unity.”8 If belief “in the body” of the Church is taken away, the Church’s concrete claims regarding the content of the faith disappear along with her bodiliness. . . . Subsistere is a special case of esse. It refers to existence in the form of an individual subject.That is exactly what it means here. The council wanted to say that the Church of Jesus Christ, as a concrete subject in the world, is found in the Catholic Church.9 4 “Spiritualis naturae incommunicabilis existentia.” Richard of St.Victor, cited in ibid., 449. 5 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae III, q. 49, c.: “Sicut enim naturale corpus est unum, ex membrorum diversitate consistens, ita tota Ecclesia, quae est mysticum corpus Christi, computatur quasi una persona cum suo capite, quod est Christus.” (ST III, q. 19, a. 4, c.: “Grace was in Christ, . . . not simply as in an individual man, but as in the Head of the whole Church, to whom all are united as members to the head, forming a single mystical person.” Also, ST III, q. 48, a. 2, ad 1: “The head and members form as it were a single mystical person.” 6 Joseph Ratzinger,“Deus Locutus Est Nobis in Filio: Some Reflections on Subjectivity, Christology, and the Church,” in Proclaiming the Truth of Jesus Christ: Papers from the Vallombrosa Meeting (Washington, DC: United States Conference of Catholic Bishops, 2000). 7 Ibid., 23. 8 Ibid., 24. 9 Ibid., 27. Francis Martin 288 In the same essay Cardinal Ratzinger goes on to state that in the Catholic Church the subsistence of the one subject of the Church is the work of God alone, and it continues to be true “despite the discrediting failures of the members of the Church.”10 The sin and disunity of the Church hinders and obscures Christ’s action in his body, namely unity of faith, which speaks both to the faith by which one believes and faith as that which is believed. As people mature in their progressive and personal faith assimilation to Christ, the shadows of their personality give way to the light of truth and the energy by which they yield and cling to revealed reality becomes more personal and less idiosyncratic. This is a process that is never complete but it does bring about a deep spiritual unity in those who are being moved by the same Spirit.The result is that there is unity as well at the meeting point of faith, that is, God himself and a knowledge of his plan of salvation.11 The Church is a mystical Person, a mystery as well as an agent. The Scriptures have been entrusted to the Church as a source of life, the life that consists of a transforming knowledge of Jesus Christ,“the leader and perfecter of faith” (Heb 12:2). Such a faith vision is expressed by Thomas Aquinas, who, while he does not use the word “subject,” expressed the same truth:“The formal objective of faith is the First Truth as this is made known [manifestatur] in Sacred Scripture and in the teaching of the Church which proceeds from the First Truth” (ST II–II, q. 5, a. 3, c). Or again in the same question, “Faith adheres to all the articles of faith because of one reason [medium], namely because of the First Truth proposed to us in the Scriptures understood rightly according to the teaching of the Church [secundum doctrinam Ecclesiae]” (ST II–II, q. 5, a. 3, ad 2). And to cite but one more text:“The formal role [ratio] of object in faith is the First Truth made known through the teaching of the Church” (De caritate, q. 13, ad 6). In the three texts from St.Thomas we have just seen, we may note that the Church is described as the active, that is, the mediating subject of Revelation. Before continuing to consider this aspect in the thinking of Joseph Ratzinger, we should consider his understanding of a prior truth, namely, that of the Church as receptive subject of Revelation. Joseph Ratzinger approaches this question primarily in terms of the relation between Reve10 Ibid., 28. 11 See Vatican Council II, Dei Verbum, no. 2: “It pleased God in his goodness and wisdom to reveal Himself and to make known the mystery of his will (see Eph 1:9) by which men have access in the Holy Spirit to the Father, through Christ, the Word of God made flesh, and become sharers in the divine nature (see Eph 2:18; 2 Pet 1:14).” Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 289 lation, Scripture, and Tradition.12 In his 1964 study, published along with a study by Karl Rahner, Ratzinger considers the question in just these terms, proceeding in part by a series of five “theses.”13 The first thesis, “Revelation and Scripture,” begins by stating that the fact that “tradition” exists derives from the non-identity of “Revelation” and “Scripture.”14 The non-identity lies in the fact that Revelation is more than Scripture to the extent that the reality exceeds its verbal expression, and also because there can be Scripture without Revelation as when a non-believer reads Scripture.“For Revelation always and only becomes a reality when there is faith. . . . It is a living reality which calls for the living man as the location of its presence.”15 Ratzinger expresses the same principle elsewhere by saying that for St. Bonaventure,“Revelatio refers not to the letter of Scripture, but to the understanding of the letter; and this understanding can be increased.”16 In the second thesis Ratzinger discusses the Old and New Covenants and the writings of each stage, maintaining that for the New Testament “Scripture” refers to the Old Testament.This position probably needs to be nuanced in the light of some recent studies that point to indications that the Gospel writers were aware of continuing the Scriptures.17 Nevertheless, it is still true that the Old Testament “can only subsist within the spiritual reality of Jesus Christ.”18 The third thesis examines“Christ, the Revelation of God,” which means that “The actual reality which occurs in Christian Revelation is nothing and no other that Christ himself.”19 Thus, “faith is equivalent to the indwelling Christ”20 (this is expressed in Eph 3:17), which implies that by faith “the individual encounters Christ and in him enters the sphere of influence of his 12 This is, in fact, the title of an article he wrote in 1958: Joseph Ratzinger,“Offen- barung–Schrift–Überlieferung,” Trierer theologische Zeitschrift 67 (1958): 13–27. 13 Joseph Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” in idem, Revelation and Tradition (Montreal: Palm Publishers, 1966). 14 Ibid., 35. 15 Ibid., 36. 16 Joseph Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, trans. Zachary Hayes (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1971, 1989), 68. 17 D. Moody Smith,“When Did the Gospels Become Scripture?” Journal of Biblical Literature 119 (2000): 3–20; Francis Moloney,“The Gospel of John as Scripture,” Catholic Biblical Quarterly 67 (2005): 454–68. 18 Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” 39. 19 Ibid., 40. 20 This statement can find a remarkable echo in the work of some Lutheran theologians who maintain that this is Luther’s position as well. See Karl Braaten and Robert Jenson, eds., Union with Christ: The New Finnish Interpretation of Luther (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998). Francis Martin 290 saving power.”21 On a broader scale it also means that the Pauline expression “Body of Christ” implies that the community of the faithful, the Church, represents Christ’s continued abiding in this world in order to gather men into, and make them share, his mighty presence. . . . It also follows that the presence of Revelation is essentially connected with the two realities “faith” and “Church,” which themselves, as is now clear, are closely connected.22 The fourth and most fully developed thesis has to do with “the nature of tradition.” The basic principle stems from the fact that the reality of Revelation is in excess (Überhang) of Scripture.23 Revelation itself, the explicitation of the Christ reality, has its double yet single enduring presence in faith and in the Church; and it occurs in the preaching that is an unfolding of what is presented, first in the Old Testament and then in the New Testament: It is also an interpretation of the Christ-event itself on the basis of the Pneuma.“But it is precisely in this Church that Christ is living and present; in the Church which is his Body in which his Spirit is active.”24 The move to include the Gentiles, thus moving from “Kingdom” to “Church,”“opened out that new interpretation of the message of Christ which is the essential message of the Church.”25 After discussing the “Old Testament theology of the Old Testament” (a series of new readings of older texts),26 the “New Testament theology of the Old Testament” (basically its “spiritual sense”),27 and the “New Testament theology of the New Testament” (established by looking at successive expressions of the Mystery), Ratzinger arrives at what he calls the “Church theology of the New Testament.” By this latter he means the continuation of that successive process already begun in the New Testament itself but now no longer 21 Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” 41. 22 Ibid. 23 Ibid., 45. 24 Ibid., 42. 25 Ibid. For an appreciation of this initiative of the Holy Spirit, see F. Bovon, De Voca- tione Gentium: Histoire de l’interprétation d’Act. 10:1–11:18 dans les six premiers siècles, vol. 8 of Beiträge zur Geschichte der biblischen Exegese (Tübingen: Mohr [Siebeck], 1967); and Brant Pitre, Jesus, the Tribulation, and the End of the Exile: Restoration Eschatology and the Origin of the Atonement (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck/Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2005). 26 For an excellent account of this procedure, see Michael Fishbane, Biblical Interpretation in Ancient Israel (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985). 27 See Francis Martin,“The Spiritual Sense (Sensus Spiritualis) of Sacred Scripture,” in Sacred Scripture:The Disclosure of the Word, Francis Martin (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2006). Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 291 canonical. Ratzinger calls this “dogmatic theology” and then goes on to specify that “in a precise sense we could designate only dogma as such as the Church’s theology of the New Testament.”28 Finally, the essay develops here the three “sources” (Wurzeln) of tradition.The first we have already seen:The excess of the reality of Revelation over Scripture. The second is: “The specific character of New Testament Revelation as pneuma as opposed to gramma and, consequently, what one might call in Bultmann’s terminology the impossibility of objectifying it.”29 From this comes the fact that the Rule of Faith has a guiding priority in interpretation.The return to this position, notably on the part of several evangelical scholars, challenges the opinion that the Scriptures can be understood from within any context provided that the correct methods are rigorously applied. This challenge is multiform. It comes from those who appeal to the Rule of Faith as the ultimate, interpretive norm,30 or more generally, to the role of the Holy Spirit in the Church,31 or finally to the multiform presence of the Word in the Church.32 The third source is given as: The character of the Christ-event as present and the authoritative enduring presence of Christ’s Spirit in his Body the Church and, connected with this, the authority to interpret Christ yesterday in relation to Christ today, the origin of which we have observed in the Church’s reinterpretation by the apostles of the message of the kingdom.33 Ratzinger goes on to enumerate the “levels” of tradition: 1. the original paradosis made by the Father of his Son who continues this action as judgment and gift of salvation and remains in the whole of his mystery in the Church. This superabundant tradition remains “the decisive fundamental reality which is antecedent to all particular 28 Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” 45. 29 Ibid. 30 For example, see Robert W. Wall, “Reading the Bible from Within Our Tradi- tions:The ‘Rule of Faith’ in Theological Hermeneutics,” in Between Two Horizons: Spanning New Testament Studies and Systematic Theology, eds. Joel B. Green and Max Turner (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2000), 88–107. 31 David S.Yeago, “The Bible,The Church, and the Scriptures: Biblical Inspiration and Interpretation Revisited,” in Knowing the Triune God:The Work of the Spirit in the Practices of the Church, ed. James J. Buckley and David S.Yeago (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2001), 49–93. 32 Leo Scheffczyk,“Sacred Scripture: God’s Word and the Church’s Word,” Communio 28 (2001): 26–41. 33 Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” 45. Francis Martin 292 expressions of it, even those of Scripture, and which represents what in fact what has been handed down.”34 2. The presence in faith of the indwelling Christ. 3. The organ of tradition is the authority of the Church, that is, those who have authority within it:These are the “apostles, prophets, evangelists, pastors, and teachers” spoken of in Ephesians 4:11 whose authority is diverse but real. 4. The expression of tradition as the Rule of Faith. Finally, we must consider exegesis, or interpretation, whose basic principle is that “Revelation becomes present through preaching” and therefore that “tradition by its very nature is always interpretation, does not exist independently, but only as exposition, interpretation ‘according to the scriptures.’ ”35 In another place, commenting on Dei Verbum, Joseph Ratzinger has this to say about tradition: We can see here how little intellectualism and doctrinalism are able to comprehend the nature of Revelation which is not concerned with talking about something that is quite external to the person, but with the realization of the existence of man, with the relation of the human “I” to the divine “thou,” so that the purpose of this dialogue is ultimately not information but unity and transformation.36 This must, of course, be balanced by the insistence that the Church’s witness is linked to an exegesis that “investigates the literal sense, and so guards the link with the sarx of the Logos in opposition to all gnosis . . . defending the sarx of history against the caprice of gnosis which perpetually seeks to establish its own autonomy.”37 The Church performs this function in virtue of the right of prescriptio: The Church is the rightful owner of Scripture (Tertullian).This raises the issue of the delicate balance between the Rule of Faith, and the historically ascertainable literal sense of Scripture in confrontation with those types of gnosis that seek either to claim a “higher” knowledge on the basis of modern historical study or to bypass such historical work in the name of a “spiritual” understanding. The key is a restored understanding of human cognition and of faith as a 34 Ibid. 35 Ibid., 47. 36 Joseph Ratzinger, “Revelation Itself,” commentary on chapter 1 of the Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation Dei Verbum, in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969), 175. 37 Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” 48, 49. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 293 way of knowing. Some approaches to this were made by Dei Verbum, but the crucial question of how the Church uses Scripture to correct the exuberances of “tradition” has yet to be thoroughly considered.38 The Church as “I” There is, moreover, one other aspect of the Church as subject that must be considered here, and that is the relation between the individual “I” and the “I” of the Whole Christ. Perhaps the best place to appreciate this aspect of Ratzinger’s thought is the essay we have considered already: “The Spiritual Basis and Ecclesial Identity of Theology.”39 In that essay, the starting point is Galatians 2:20,“It is no longer I who live, but Christ who lives in me,” whose meaning is expanded as follows: It is a death-event. In other words, it is an exchange of the old subject for another. The “I” ceases to be an autonomous subject standing in itself. It is snatched away from itself and fitted into a new subject.The “I” is not simply submerged, but it must really release its grip on itself in order then to receive itself anew in and together with a new “I.”40 The new “I” spoken of here is the una persona mystica. It is the Christ who, through baptism, is “put on” with the result that now “[t]here is neither Jew nor Greek, there is neither slave nor free, there is not male and female, for you are all one [singular masculine] in Christ” (Gal 3:8). This “one man” can be called “the Christ”: “For just as the body is one and has many members, and all the members of the body, though many, are one body, so it is with the Christ” (1 Cor 12:2, see also 1:13). This one man both possesses and receives the form (typos) of teaching to which we are entrusted and to which we give obedience from the heart (Rom 6:17). Jesus Christ is the one who as God incarnate is the Source of the Body’s life, he is the one who animates our prayer and understanding, and who prays for us. As Augustine declares: 38 Though it is not our matter here, it is worthwhile pointing out that Ratzinger appreciates the fact that Vatican II did not advance the discussion as to how tradition can be criticized: “On this point Vatican II has unfortunately not made any progress, but more or less has ignored the whole question of the criticism of tradition.” (Ratzinger, “Revelation Itself,” 185). In another study, I have tried to point out that, in fact,Vatican II did redirect tradition but without offering any theoretical basis. See “Dei Verbum: Revelation and Its Transmission” to appear in Vatican II: Renewal Within Tradition, ed. Matthew L. Lamb and Matthew Levering (Oxford University Press, forthcoming). 39 In Ratzinger, The Nature and Mission, 45–72. 40 Ibid., 51. Francis Martin 294 When we speak to God, praying, we do not separate the Son from Him; and when the Body of the Son prays, it does not separate its head from itself.Thus it is he, the one Savior of his Body, our Lord Jesus Christ, the Son of God, who prays for us and prays in us and is prayed to by us. He prays for us as our priest, he prays in us as our Head, he is prayed to by us as our God. Let us then, recognize our voice in his and his voice in ours.41 In bringing this section to a close, I wish to give here a striking paragraph, found as the concluding statement to the remarkable study by Emile Mersch, The Whole Christ. It is, as far as I can judge, a perfectly adequate way of expressing Joseph Ratzinger’s understanding of the Church, and the Church as the subject of biblical understanding: The message is this: in the Church, which is the continuation of Christ, there exists between the Incarnate Word and each Christian more than any bond of love, however ardent, more than relation of resemblance, however close, more than the bond of total dependence that binds to their one Savior all men who have received the grace of pardon and sanctification. There is something more than the union of subjects to any king, more than the insecure incorporation of members in an organism, more than the closest moral union. There is a “physical” union, we should say, if the very term itself did not appear to place this bond in the category of mere natural unions. At all events it is a real, ontological union, or, since the traditional names are still the best, it is a mystical, transcendent, supernatural union whose unity and reality exceed our powers of expression; it is a union that God alone can make us understand, as He alone was able to bring it into being.42 The Church as Subject in the Letter to the Ephesians It will be useful at this point to turn briefly to a New Testament writing that speaks of the Church, the Body of Christ, in terms that can reinforce the teaching of Joseph Ratzinger and help us to understand the Church as a knowing subject. I will concentrate on the first sixteen verses of chapter 4 of the Letter to the Ephesians since it is there particularly that we can be instructed on the intimate relation between Revelation and unity. Ephesians 4:7–16 This passage is the second paragraph in a major section (Eph 4:1–6:20) titled by Rudolf Schnackenburg,“Realising Christian Existence in Church 41 In Psalm 85, 1 (Corpus Christianorum Latinorum 39, 1176 [Turnholt: Brepols, 1956]). 42 Emile Mersch, The Whole Christ: The Historical Development of the Doctrine of the Mystical Body in Scripture and Tradition, trans. John R. Kelly (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1938), 584. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 295 and World.”43 The passage we are going to consider (4:1–16) is titled “The Church as the Sphere of Christian Existence.” Its first part (4:1–6) addresses the urgent question of Church unity, which it ultimately grounds in the Trinity itself.The second part, which we will reflect upon (4:7–16), speaks of the variety of gifts bestowed on the Body by the ascended Christ, then of the danger of division as well as its remedy: arriving “at the unity of faith and knowledge of the Son of God, unto the Perfect Man, unto the measure of the stature of the Fullness of Christ” (v. 13). Ephesians 4:7–16 applies the Trinitarian foundation of Church unity, set forth in Ephesians 4:1–6, to the multiplicity of gifts in a way similar to the development in 1 Corinthians 12:7–30. However the accent here is on the resurrected Christ being the source of the gifts and his action in bringing about unity through joining all believers more closely to himself. The text begins with a principle: “To each of us is given grace according to the measure of the gift of Christ” (v. 7). It goes on to unveil for us the source of that donation of life-giving activity: Therefore it says:“Going up to the height, he captured captives, he gave gifts to men.” This, “he went up,” what is it except that he also descended to the lower part of the earth? The one who descended is also the one who went up, above all the heavens, that he might fill all things. (vv. 8–10) The “grace” mentioned in the enunciation of the principle, it is generally agreed, refers to those special graced endowments given to each believer for the building of the Body. They are distributed by Christ himself according to the measure he wills. In order to explicate how Christ distributes these and other blessings, Paul appeals to the authority and fruitfulness of the transformed Christ, now “divinized” in his humanity by the resurrecting power of the Father: “the surpassing greatness of his power, for us the believers, in keeping with the operation of the might of his strength which he carried out in Christ, raising him from the dead and seating him at his right hand in heaven” (Eph 1:19–20).We celebrate this ineffable mystery on the feast of the Ascension.44 43 Rudolf Schnackenburg, The Epistle to the Ephesians: A Commentary, trans. Helen Heron (Edinburgh:T&T Clark, 1991), 5. 44 For a study of the mystery of the humanity of Christ now present to God in a new way, see Pierre Benoit, “The Ascension,” in idem, Jesus and the Gospel, vol. 1 (New York: Herder & Herder, 1973). For another understanding of this text, see W. Hall Harris, The Descent of Christ: Ephesians 4:7–11 and Traditional Hebrew Imagery (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker, 1996). 296 Francis Martin Paul presents the risen Jesus as the source of “grace” in the Church by adapting a Jewish interpretation of Psalm 68:19.The notion of ascending on high and thus being able to confer gifts on men is contained explicitly in the targum on this psalm verse:“You ascended the firmament, prophet Moses, you took captivity captive, you learned the words of the law; you gave them as gifts to the sons of man.” The actual text of the targum of the Psalms is late, probably fourth or fifth century, but some form of this targum must have been known to Paul who cites it nearly verbatim. Moreover, a text that so perfectly corresponds to the Christian use made of it by Paul and other parts of the New Testament can hardly have been forged or even retained by Judaism unless it were already firmly fixed in the tradition.45 The tradition concerning Moses going up to heaven to receive the law is a development of the biblical notice (Ex 19, 32, 32–34) that relates Moses’ special meetings with God that resulted in his coming down from the mountain with the gift of the law.46 It is this tradition that forms the basis for the targumic text just cited, and that is utilized in Romans 10:6–8.The same image lies behind Acts 2:33 whose theme is close to that here in Ephesians:“Exalted to the right hand of God, receiving the promise, the Holy Spirit, from the Father, he poured him out: that is what you see and hear.” The explanation of the use of this Jewish tradition is given now by Paul, using the two key words “ascend” and “descend.” Jesus’ ascension according to Paul is not from the foot of a mountain, but from the abode of the dead:“[W]hat is it except that he also descended to the lower part of the earth?” (Eph 4:9).Thus is it that the ascension is not to the top of a mountain but “above all the heavens” (v. 10).The consequence is not a carrying back of the gift of the Torah but “that he might fill all things” μ (v. 10). This allusion to the theme of pleroma, refers to the fact that in Ephesians, the Church, the Body of Christ, is the recipient of the divinizing activity of the Risen Christ: It is the place of union and action. In 45 For instance, TgNe of Dt 30, 12–14, reads: “The law is not in the heavens, that one should say: Would that we had one like Moses the prophet who go up to heaven and fetch it for us, and make us hear the commandments that we might do them. Nor is the law beyond the great sea that one should say:Would that we had one like Jonah the prophet who descend into the great sea and bring up the law for us, and make us hear the commandments that we might do them. For the word is very near to you, in the word of your mouths and in your hearts, that you may do it” (compare Rom 10:5–10). 46 There are some developments of this tradition, in which it is said that God “inclined the heavens and came down” to speak to Moses (See Pseudo-Philo, Biblical Antiquities, 15, 6; 4 Esd 3:18). Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 297 brief it is the subject, the receiver of and active participant in, Christ’s action as both God and man. And it is he who gave some [to be] apostles, some [to be] prophets, some [to be] evangelists, some [to be] pastors and teachers, with a view to equipping the holy ones for the work of service, for the building of the Body of Christ until we all arrive at the unity of faith and knowledge of the Son of God, unto the Perfect Man, unto the measure of the stature of the Fullness of Christ. So that we might be children no longer, wave-tossed and carried along by every wind of teaching through men’s trickery, in [their] cunning ability for the scheming of error. Rather, being truthful in love, let us in every way grow unto him who is the Head, Christ; from whom the whole Body being fitted together and connected through every joint which gives it support, in keeping with the effective action, done in the measure of each individual part, is bringing about the growth of the Body, for its own upbuilding in love. (Eph 4:11–16) The Graces Conferred by Christ It is extremely important to note that the five “graces” mentioned in Ephesians 4:11 all have to do with what Joseph Ratzinger calls “the organs of faith”: apostles, prophets, evangelists, pastors, and teachers.The object of these ministries is “to equip the holy ones for the work of service,” each person having their own endowment “for the building of the Body of Christ.”47 Thus, from the outset there is order in the Body of Christ and ministerial gifts that have a directive role in regard to the activity of the whole Body.This “building” activity of the risen Christ continues until we all arrive at the unity of faith; the knowledge of the Son of God; the Perfect Man, unto the measure of the stature of the Fullness of Christ.This corresponds to the description in Dei Verbum, article 8, which, as we have seen describes the “progress” of the Apostolic Tradition taking place by contemplation, study, and experience on the part of the whole Church, and the particular role of the successors of the apostles. The atmosphere created by the unity of faith produces the second effect: “knowledge of the Son of God.” The process of coming to this knowledge on both a personal and ecclesiastical level is traced out in the 47 Several commentators wish to see in the notion of “equipping” and “building” an extension of the original ministry of the five expressly named leaders rather than a description of the effect of their activity in regard to the rest of the community. This is not necessary, makes it difficult to understand why the author says that this activity continues “until we all arrive . . . ,” and renders the expression in verse 16, that the Body is “building itself up in love,” difficult to understand. Francis Martin 298 concluding lines of the first part of the letter, Ephesians 3:14–21, especially the first six verses in which Paul speak of his prayer to: The Father from whom every family, in heaven and on earth, is named, that he give to you, in keeping with the riches of his glory, to be strengthened with power through his Spirit unto the inner man; that Christ dwell, through faith, in your hearts, rooted and grounded in love; so that you may be strong enough to comprehend, with all the holy ones, what [is] the width and length and height and depth; thus to know the love of Christ surpassing knowledge, that you may be filled unto all the Fullness of God. (Eph 3:14–19) The prayer is to the Father from whom every family is named, accenting his all powerful will to confer life.The object of the prayer is twofold: that we be strengthened interiorly48 by the power of the Holy Spirit, and that Christ dwell in our hearts by faith; thus enabling us to be rooted and grounded in love.The passage speaks of “power” because this is the means by which our wounded and weak nature is actually transformed as we yield to the interior action of the Holy Spirit.As Cardinal Ratzinger says: “It is here that the poles of human subjectivity and the uniqueness of the person of Christ are resolved in the concrete subject of the Church.”49 A further goal of the action of the holy ones mentioned in Ephesians 4:13 is that we, as Church, arrive at being “the Perfect Man, unto the measure of the stature of the Fullness of Christ.” In terms of the prayer in Ephesians 3:19, it means that we come to know the love of Christ surpassing knowledge and to be filled unto all the Fullness of God. The phrase in Ephesians 4:13, “the stature of the Fullness of Christ,” refers to becoming fully Church, an eschatological reality when the Church will receive all the divine life and gifts that flow into it from its Head, Christ. The phrase in Ephesians 3:19, “be filled unto all the Fullness of God” looks at the same reality from the viewpoint of Christ himself who is “the Fullness of God,” the divine and infinite recipient of the gift the Father makes of himself within the life of the Trinity. Now, by the mystery of the incarnation, Jesus Christ himself is in some mysterious way the Fullμ ness (Pleroma) of the Father, as the one in whom the Ple μroma of the Deity dwells bodily (Col 2:9), and the Church, his Body, is the created recipient of that divine life. The final two verses of this section portray, on the other hand, the role of truth in bringing the whole Church to maturity. 48 A determination of the exact meaning of eso μ anthro μpos exceeds our needs in this present context. 49 Ratzinger, “Deus Locutus Est,” 23. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 299 Rather, being truthful in love, let us in every way grow unto him who is the Head, Christ; from whom the whole Body being fitted together and brought into connection, through every sustaining juncture according to the action, [done] in the measure of each individual part, is bringing about the growth of this [same] Body, unto the building of itself up in love. (Eph 4:15–16) μ The participle aletheuontes, translated as “being truthful,” refers on one level to truthful speech and action that flows from union with Christ. It is here contrasted with the falsehood that is keeping Christians immature and μ divided.The full meaning of the phrase aletheuontes en agape μ refers to a deep 50 yielding to “the truth in Jesus” (Eph 4:21), and letting him actually become the living source of our energy and life.The nature of that activity is now described by a partial comparison between the activity of the head in a human body, as this was then understood, and the action of Christ as head of his Body. Going beyond the physiology of the day Paul speaks of a causality that flows from the risen Christ (see already Phil 3:21) that confers growth on the Body, that provides life and movement though in such a way that it is working “within each individual part.” Maturity, therefore, is the work of the Spirit conferred by Christ upon each believer bringing each one into a deeper union with the risen Son of God in such a way that the Body builds itself up in love. Mystical awareness of this process is what Paul means by “knowledge of the Son of God.” Such a knowledge belies in its own way the non-transcendent bias of much modern reflection on cognition, and it is to that aspect of Joseph Ratzinger’s thought that we now turn. The Second Principle: Faith Is a Way of Knowing “The act of faith essentially consists in an act of knowing; that is its formal or specific perfection; this is clear from what its object is.”51 This splendidly dense statement of Aquinas may be made clear by the remark of 50 J. Armitage Robinson, St. Paul’s Epistle to the Romans, 2nd ed. (London: MacMil- lan and Co., 1922), 107: “Paul uses the name ‘Jesus’ by itself when he wishes emphatically to point to the historic personality of the Christ.And this is plainly his intention in the present passage.The message which he proclaimed was this: The Christ has come: in the person of Jesus—the crucified, risen, and ascended Jesus—He has come, not only as the Messiah of the Jews, but as the hope of all mankind. In this Jesus is embodied the truth: and so the truth has come to you. You have learned the Christ; him you have heard, in him you have been taught, even as the truth is in Jesus.” 51 Thomas Aquinas, De veritate, q. 14, a. 2, ad 10: “Ad decimum dicendum, quod actus fidei essentialiter consistit in cognitione, et ibi est eius perfectio quantum ad formam vel speciem; quod patet ex obiecto, ut dictum est; sed quantum ad finem perficitur in affectione, quia ex caritate habet quod sit meritoria finis.” 300 Francis Martin Joseph Ratzinger that, “To know the person of Christ is the foundation of theology.”52 Applied to the topic at hand, we see that the understanding of Scripture is the work of faith seeking understanding; and that is something that far exceeds that kind of biblical criticism that is, to use George Steiner’s expression,“words about words.”53 Dei Verbum, article 8, presupposes that “faith is a way of knowing” and at the same time places this principle in the context of the growth of Tradition the growth of which, as has been already observed, it understands to be a combination of the increased knowledge of all the members of the Body of Christ and the preaching of those with the episcopal charism.54 It is important to note in this text how Vatican Council II places this reality within the life of the Whole Christ that is presented as the subject of interpretation: The Tradition which is from the Apostles makes progress in the Church under the assistance of the Holy Spirit.55 There is a growth in understanding, both of the realities as well as of the words that have been handed on.This takes place as a result of the contemplation and study of the believers who ponder these things in their heart (see Lk 2:19, 51), as well as by the intimate knowledge of the spiritual realities which they experience, and by the preaching of those who have received with episcopal succession, the sure charism of truth.Thus, as the centuries advance, the Church continually moves toward the plenitude of divine truth until the words of God reach their fulfillment in her. (Dei Verbum, no. 8) The ministries enumerated in Ephesians 4:11 as “apostles, prophets, evangelists, pastors, and teachers,” ultimately derive from, are sustained by, serve, and direct that whole body of the faithful whose growth in understanding, achieved through “contemplation and study” and an “intimate knowledge of the spiritual realities which they experience” is the source of the growth of Tradition. 52 Ratzinger, “Deus Locutus Est,” 21. 53 George Steiner, Real Presences (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989, 1991). Elsewhere in the same study he says, “It is the break of the covenant between word and world which constitutes one of the very few genuine revolutions of spirit in Western history and which defines modernity itself ” (93). 54 It will be helpful here to return to Ratzinger’s statement to the effect that, “Tradition then exists concretely as presence in faith, which again, as in the indwelling of Christ, is antecedent to all its particular explicit formulations and is fertile and living, thus developing and unfolding throughout the ages.” Revelation and Tradition, 46. 55 See Vatican I, Dogmatic Constitution on the Catholic Faith, Dei Filius, ch. 4 (Denz. 1800 [3020]). Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 301 I wish now to reflect briefly on what is meant by the words “understanding” (perceptio),“intimate knowledge” (intima intelligentia), and “experience” (experiuntur). All of these expressions are a forthright rejection of that theological attitude once described by Romano Guardini as “a liberalism kept in check by obedience to dogma,”56 and which are indebted to a Kantian understanding of cognition. The council has reiterated the fact that faith is a way of knowing, and this obliges us to look more deeply into the questions of knowledge and language. I will first present a few lines in order to elucidate Joseph Ratzinger’s frequently reiterated position that “faith is a way of knowing,” and then proceed to look at knowledge as both imitation and word, that is, as the reality itself transposed through the act of knowledge and communication. In order to accomplish this, I will reconsider the ancient understanding of knowledge as this has been recovered and advanced in the modern appreciation of language and knowledge. Ratzinger on Modern Cognition Theories and Biblical Interpretation One of Joseph Ratzinger’s most trenchant criticisms of the cognition theories that lie at the root of much biblical interpretation is to be found in his 1989 essay, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” published the same year in German and in English.The occasion for the English text was the Ratzinger Conference on Bible and Church.57 Early in his presentation, Ratzinger observes that historical criticism of the Bible labors under many of the erroneous presuppositions of modern historical investigation, especially the notion that history is a “science” in the same way as the empirical sciences.58 A diachronic analysis of the results of the method can show unmistakably that, after two centuries, contrary to the positive sciences, there are few if any assured results that have become a common basis for progress.59 In addition, modern fascination with an understanding of history as temporal linear succession has eliminated the biblical vision of history as the working out of God’s plan of salvation: 56 Romano Guardini, Berichte über mein Leben:Autobiographische Aufzeichnungen (Düssel- dorf: Patmos Verlag, 1984, 4th edition), 33, cited by Ratzinger, The Nature and Mission, 47, n. 5. 57 Joseph Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: On the Question of the Foundations and Approaches of Exegesis Today,” in Biblical Interpretation in Crisi:. The Ratzinger Conference on Bible and the Church, ed. Richard John Neuhaus (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1989). 58 Ibid., 6. 59 Ibid., 8. 302 Francis Martin If we are to understand modern exegesis and critique it correctly, we simply must return and reflect anew on Luther’s view of the relationship between the Old and New Testaments. In place of the analogy model which was then current, he substituted a dialectical structure.60 We must also note that, while there has been a continuity in the historical analysis of the biblical text, it lies not so much in a settled body of agreed upon results as in the perdurance of philosophical presuppositions at work in what is called historical reason.61 The real philosophic presupposition of the whole system seems to me to lie in the philosophic turning point proposed by Immanuel Kant. According to him, the voice of being-in-itself cannot be heard by human beings. Man can only hear it indirectly in the postulates of practical reason, which have remained, as it were, the small opening through which he can make contact with the real, that is, his eternal destiny.62 In theological terms, this means that Revelation must recede into the pure formality of the eschatological stance, which corresponds to the Kantian split. As far as everything else is concerned, it all needs to be “explained.”What might otherwise seem like a direct proclamation of the divine can only be myth, whose laws of development can be discovered. It is with this basic conviction that Bultmann, along with the majority of modern exegetes, read the Bible. He is certain that it cannot be the way it is depicted in the Bible, and he looks for methods to prove the way it really had to be.To that extent there lies in modern exegesis a reduction of history into philosophy, a revision of history by means of philosophy.63 I recognize, of course, that many exegetes would object that they do not practice their scholarship under the aegis of a Kantian epistemology. Some, through loyalty to the Church tradition, have intuitively gone beyond the limits and presuppositions of their method, but they have not directly confronted the challenge offered here in Joseph Ratzinger’s assessment. One reason, perhaps, is that the whole field of cognition theory has itself been dominated by Kantian thinking as well as reactions to it that do not manage to shake themselves free from the image of the knower as 60 Ibid., 12. On the importance of the ancient understanding of the “spiritual sense” of Scripture and the view of history it implies, one might consult Martin, “The Spiritual Sense.” 61 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 14. 62 Ibid., 15. For an account of Marburg neo-Kantianism and its influence on Bultmann, see Roger A. Johnson, The Origins of Demythologizing: Philosophy and Historiography in the Theology of Rudolph Bultmann (Leiden: Brill, 1974). 63 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 16. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 303 an isolated unit responsible for the forging of personal meaning.64 Another reason is the vastness of the enterprise: The scholarly search to find a better synthesis between the historical and critical methods, between higher criticism and Church doctrine is hardly a recent phenomenon.This can be seen from the fact that hardly anyone today would assert that a truly pervasive understanding this whole problem has yet been found. . . . At least the work of a whole generation is necessary to achieve such a thing.65 In the few lines that follow I wish to contribute to this work of a generation by reflecting on two realities that have suffered a false separation, namely knowledge and language and by proposing that knowledge is not effected by a determining subject knowing a passive object, and that consequently language is not the naming of a private acquisition. Knowledge as Imitation Because God’s “motive” in creating is agape,μ there is present in creation what Jacques Maritain calls “the basic generosity of existence.”66 Aquinas reflects this intuition when he states that,“From the very fact that something exists in act, it is active.”67 In a remarkable passage, obviously indebted to Denys’s treatise on The Divine Names, Aquinas moves from the observation of the “generosity” of all beings to an understanding of the generosity of their Source. Note how this vision of reality follows upon the biblical teaching that God’s act of creation is totally free and adds nothing to God:68 For natural things have a natural inclination not only toward their own proper good, to acquire it, if not possessed, and if possessed, to rest therein; but also to diffuse their own goodness among others as far as possible. . . . Hence if natural things, insofar as they are perfect, communicate their goodness to others, much more does it pertain to the divine will to communicate by likeness its own goodness to others as far as possible.69 64 See, for instance, Kenneth Schmitz, “Postmodern or Modern-Plus?” Communio 17 (1990): 152–66. 65 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 5–6. 66 Jacques Maritain, Existence and the Existent (New York: Doubleday, 1957), 90. 67 Summa contra Gentiles, 2, 7. 68 In this section I am using material that can be found in chapter 6 of my study, The Feminist Question: Feminist Theology in the Light of Christian Tradition (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1994). 69 ST I, q. 19, a. 2, quoted in W. Norris Clarke, “Person, Being, and St. Thomas,” Communio 19 (1992): 604. All quotations of St.Thomas in this section are translations of W. Norris Clarke from his article. 304 Francis Martin If we apply this notion to the act of knowledge, we may say that the very act of existing is a communicable perfection that is bestowed on the knower by what is known. This understanding of the manner in which all entities can imitate God not only eliminates the isolation of foundationalism, which leaves to the knowing subject the sole task of conferring intelligibility, it also shows the universe to be a place characterized by relation: “Communication follows upon the very intelligibility [ratio] of actuality. Hence every form is of itself communicable.”70 There is a certain generosity in effective activity; it is sharing, not coercion.This is especially noticeable in the act of knowing.The mind is not a dominating principle imposing intelligibility from its own resources, nor is the object known through an act by which it coerces the mind to produce its “representation.”There is a “nuptial relation.”Truth is not primarily in the proposition, but rather in the “original concord between thing and intellect,” in the “resonant symmetry of knower and known.”71 Rather, knowing takes place in the receptive and creative imitation of reality effected by the mind. Being shares in the generosity of God, it is diffusive of itself. Mind, while it fashions the entity according to its own energy, can only do so as fecundated by the entity itself, which, far from passively receiving intelligibility, actively imparts its reality to the mind.There is no “foundation” either in the subjectivity of the knower, deriving all certitude from a seemingly unassailable experience, or in the thing known that requires to be known in order to be actually intelligible. Both are principles communicating actuality, and both are receivers needing union in order for truth to exist. The original truth, spoken of previously, the union between the mind and what is known, is only possible because what is known is “imitated” by the mind.To imitate is to transpose a reality to another plane of existence. If, in response to a request that I imitate the chair in my room, I make another chair, I have not imitated—I have reproduced. To imitate the chair I must transpose it to the level of word or line and color or some other and different mode of being.Thus, in the act of knowledge, the energy by which being is imitated derives both from the dynamism 70 SCG 3, 64. As W. Norris Clarke expresses it: “It turns out, then, that relational- ity and substantiality go together as two distinct but inseparable modes of reality. Substance is the primary mode, in that all else, including relations, depend on it as their ground. But since ‘every substance exists for the sake of its operations,’ as St. Thomas has just told us, being as substance, as existing in itself, naturally flows over into being as relational, turned toward others by its self-communicating action. To be is to be substance in relation.” Clarke, “Person, Being,” 607, original emphasis. 71 Kenneth Schmitz, “Neither With Nor Without Foundations,” Review of Metaphysics 42 (1988): 15. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 305 of the substance in relation and that particular way in which I, as a knower, share in the dynamic light of God, a light that, even apart from faith, St.Thomas does not hesitate to call “a certain imprint of the divine light.”72 It should also be noted that, while this action takes place in the mind, it is the whole body person who knows, who imitates. Thus, from the two points established, the dynamic and relational character of being, on the one hand, and the mutually active and receptive nature of the act of knowing, we are able to appreciate that knowledge is neither with nor without foundations. The bias to replace commonality by a systemic totality swallows the irreducible nature of the individual in context by making it correspond to a prefabricated structure. Furthermore, the bias to replace being by thought sacrifices a confidence in creation to the anxiety of isolation. When these biases are surrendered, logic’s need for a starting point is recognized as both valid and limited, but it is clearly recognized as pertaining to second-order discourse. Clarity in this regard has been achieved not in spite of, but precisely because of the turn to the subject. It is a metaphysical achievement nurtured by a biblical sense of the manner in which all that is created shares in the dynamism and generosity of the Creator.The act of knowledge is thus, under this aspect, an imitative sharing in the creating act of God. But there is more, it is, in a profound sense an imitation of the procession of the Word: “The Word of God comes to man everyday, present in the human voice.”73 Knowledge as Word “When the verbum cordis is constituted the intellect actively thinks what it knows; the internal word is knowledge come to life in the mind.A still further dimension is reached in external speech, the audible use of language, whose function is to express publicly the verbum cordis.”74 This statement of Robert Sokolowski contains most of the key notions necessary for the reestablishing of what, as we have seen, George Steiner referred to as “the covenant between word and world.”75 In the preceding section, I analyzed knowledge as an imitative act performed by the person in and through the mind. I now wish to look more closely at the 72 ST I, q. 12, a. 11, ad 3; I–II, q. 91, a. 2. 73 Hugh of St.Victor, The Word of God, I, 2–3 (Paris: Sources Chrétiennes, 155, 60). 74 Robert Sokolowski, “The Agent of Truth: Phenomenology of the Human Person” (2006).This section of my own study is deeply indebted to Sokolowski’s, and I thank him for allowing me to use and cite his work, still in copyrighted manuscript, as I attempt to apply his insights to the task of biblical exegesis. 75 George Steiner, Real Presences, 93. 306 Francis Martin act of imitation itself and observe how this act is intrinsically linked to language, to word.76 General Considerations Building upon his own understanding of the Platonic principle that “good is diffusive of itself,” St. Thomas reasons that since the act of existence is the foundation of all other perfections, indeed “the actuality of all acts and the perfection of all perfections,”77 the diffusiveness of the good is rooted in the existence of a being; and it is thus that whatever exists manifests itself in the act of its existing.78 Disclosure, therefore, involves both the created reality manifesting itself in and through the act of its existence and the creative receptivity of the mind that receives the act of the reality and gives it intelligibility, transposing it to the level of the knower.This energy, the capacity to receive and transpose, is what the ancient thinkers meant by the light of the mind. As we have already noted, Aquinas says of this interior light of reason that it is itself a “certain participation in divine light” (ST I, q. 12, a. 11, ad 3); it is, in fact, “nothing else but the imprint of the divine light in us” (ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2). He also says that the intensification and elevation of this light, which is the heart of sacra doctrina, the reception and transmission of prophetic knowledge, is also “a certain imprint of the divine knowledge” (ST I, q. 1, a. 3, ad 2). From the side of the mind itself, according to Aquinas, there are three dimensions of our knowing that can be manifestations of God.The first of these is the knowledge implicit in every act of knowing: “All knowing beings implicitly know God in whatever they know. For just as nothing is desirable except as it bears a likeness to the First Goodness, so nothing is knowable except as it bears a likeness to the First Truth.”79 76 In the paragraphs that follow I am utilizing material that can be found in my article, “Revelation as Disclosure: Creation,” in Wisdom and Holiness, Science and Scholarship, ed. Michael Dauphinais and Matthew Levering (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, forthcoming). 77 De potentia, q. 7, a. 2, ad 9. Translation is from W. Norris Clarke, “Action as the Self-Revelation of Being:A Central Theme in the Thought of St.Thomas,” in his Explorations in Metaphysics (Notre Dame, IN/London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), 45–63. 78 Later in the same essay (“Action as the Self-Revelation,” 63, n. 11), Clarke cites Karl Rahner: “Our first statement which we put forward as the basic principle of an ontology of symbolism, is as follows: all beings are by their very nature symbolic, because they necessarily ‘express’ themselves in order to attain their own nature.” Quoting Karl Rahner, “Theology of the Symbol,” in Theological Investigations, vol. 4 (Baltimore: Helicon Press, 1966), 221–52. 79 Aquinas, De veritate, q. 22, a. 2, ad 1. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 307 The second dimension of knowledge is intuition or intellectus. It consists in the presence of the thing known to the knower. In the very first article of De veritate, Aquinas, who is asking the question, “Quid sit veritas?” discusses the relation of being to the intellect. He makes the following statement: True [verum] expresses the correspondence [convenientia] of being to the knowing power [intellectus], for all knowing is produced by an assimilation of the knower to the thing known, so that assimilation is said to be the cause of knowledge [assimilatio dicta est causa cognitionis]. Similarly, the sense of sight knows a color by being informed with a species of the color. 80 The first reference [comparatio] of being to the intellect, therefore, consists in its agreement with the intellect [ut ens intellectui correspondeat]. This agreement is called “the conformity of thing and intellect” [adaequatio rei et intellectus], and in this conformity is found the formal constituent of the true [et in hoc formaliter ratio veri perficitur], and this is what the true adds to being, namely, the conformity or equation of thing and intellect [conformitatem seu adaequationem rei et intellectus]. As we said, the knowledge of a thing is a consequence of this conformity [ad quam conformitatem, ut dictum est, sequiter cognitio rei]; therefore it is an effect of truth, even though the fact that it is a being is prior to its truth [Sic ergo entitas rei praecedit rationem veritatis; sed cognitio est quaedam veritatis effectus]. (De veritate, q. 1, a. 1. c.) “Assimilation is the cause of knowledge.” And again, “knowledge of a thing is a consequence of the conformity of thing and intellect.” And since truth is precisely the “assimilation of the knower to the thing known,” it follows that “knowledge is a certain effect of truth.” It is at the ontological level that the act of knowing imitates, in a created manner, the procession of the Word in the Trinity, with this difference: In the Trinity, the Father produces the Word totally from within himself, he is the principium Deitatis,81 whereas the human being must first receive before 80 It is important to advert to another principle of Aquinas:“veritas fundatur in esse rei magis quam in ipsa quidditate” (In I Sent d. 19, q. 5, a. 1, sol.).As David Bentley Hart remarks: “the adequation that truth is consists in an assimilation of the esse of any given thing, whereby it accepts each thing as it is.” David Bentley Hart, The Beauty of the Infinite:The Aesthetics of Christian Truth (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2003), 247. 81 For a discussion of this and similar expressions, see Yves Congar,“The Father, the Absolute Source of Divinity,” in I Believe in the Holy Spirit, vol. 3 (New York: Seabury, 1983). 308 Francis Martin producing a word, for, as we have just seen, beings give themselves to us and modify us, thus establishing us in truth whose effect is knowledge.82 The third dimension of knowledge is, then, reasoning (ratiocinatio), which is a movement of the mind made in the power of the original intuition by which new truth is acquired and consciously assimilated in judgment. It is a movement from what is less determinate to what is more determinate; from a determination of actuality to a determination of form. But this must not be understood as a unidirectional movement. What is acquired by reasoning can itself become another intellectus, for, as Aquinas says elsewhere, intellectus is not only the principle of reason, but also its term or goal.83 Word Robert Sokolowski has correctly observed that the act of knowing transpires as a linguistic act. Thus, by the fact that knowing takes place in and through a commonly held medium, namely, language, it is of its nature a public performance. The establishing of this fact and its relevance to the modern problem of cognition is one of the bases of Sokolowski’s whole study. I will use some of his fundamental notions in order to untie the Kantian knot, which, as we have seen in Ratzinger’s analysis, is the principal obstacle to a “synthesis between the historical and critical methods, between higher criticism and Church doctrine,”84 that is, between an integration of the manner in which the Church as interpreting subject understands and lives Scripture and the proposals of modern historical reason.The key, as I understand it, is to show that words are not labels we give to an interior possession most often called “concepts.” This understanding of “concept” leaves us with the insoluble problem of explaining the relation between these interior entities and the world in which we live. In terms of exegesis this split between word and world licenses one to interpret the word of the text as bearing all the meaning, while the “event” remains in the unknowable territory of the past, or is reinterpreted according to the reconstruction of the commentator. In this view, the account of the death and resurrection of Jesus, for instance, can be interpreted by the evangelists who express their interpretation based on their preoccupations and prejudices, and we have the right to do the same: Matthew or Crossan, take your pick. 82 Thus, it would seem that that knowledge which is the effect of truth must first be considered as intellectus, as Aquinas says in the Summa contra Gentiles (1, 57): “That which is supreme in our knowledge is not reason, but intellectus which is the source of reason.” 83 In III Sent. d. 35, q. 1, a. 3, sol. 2:“Intellectus est rationis principium et terminus.” 84 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 5. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 309 It is essential, then, as one of the first steps in integrating the ancient expressions of biblical reality with our historical reason to resolve the Kantian understanding of the act of knowledge, and its influence on much of the neo-scholastic interpretation of Aquinas. We have already ascertained that knowledge is a “nuptial event”: It involves the imparting to the knower something of the being of the other and the reception of that gift by the knower in an initial act.“For all knowing is produced by an assimilation of the knower to the thing known, so that assimilation is said to be the cause of knowledge. Similarly, the sense of sight knows a color by being informed with a species of the color” (Aquinas, De veritate, q. 1, a. 1. c.).This “assimilation” is what Aquinas calls elsewhere species intelligibilis. Besides being potential as receptive, the intellect is potential in the sense of being capable of acting, that is, it can generate an internal word. It needs, however, to be enabled to do so by being informed by an intelligible species. . . . Once it has been so formed the intellect can form its own conception or word: formatus format. The intellect therefore, is potential in being both receptive and active.85 The key in understanding Aquinas’s teaching on knowledge is to grasp his attribution to the intellect of an energy by which what has been received and to which the intellect is assimilated achieves its reality of knowledge by being worded. This word, however, is not protolanguage; it is language: It is a statement formed by syntax that expresses a form of being.At the level of assimilation, there is presence, but not, strictly speaking, knowledge. For this to exist, there must be what Aquinas, following Augustine, calls a verbum interius or verbum cordis (also called a conceptus or conceptio). It is at this point that there is language and communicability, though all the activity is as yet immanent:“The internal word of the heart is what is signified by the exterior word. But the exterior word does not signify the intelligible species.”86 The reason for Aquinas’s distinction regarding what the exterior word signifies lies in the difference in the mode of being of the internal word and the intelligible species: Knowledge takes place in and through an expression that has syntax, that is, one in which there is expressed explicitly or implicitly the notion of “to be.”87 85 Sokolowski, “The Agent of Truth,” 209. 86 Quodlibet V, q. 5 a. 2, sc.This whole paragraph is indebted to Sokolowski, “The Agent of Truth,” 205–7. 87 It should be noted that the “word” need not be merely a simple statement, it may be an abundant reality either actually expressed by several statements or virtually containing them as occurs in a significant insight. 310 Francis Martin Having forged a union once again between word and world—thanks to the teaching of Aquinas and others regarding the manner in which being gives itself to the knower who receives it and who gives it a properly human existence as word—we should turn our attention now to the modern contribution made by an understanding of syntax as such, since the “word” of which we speak is precisely the reality given a human level of existence because of syntax. With this step we will be enabled once again to receive the word of Scripture as communicating to us in a human way the divine realities that give life. Syntax In elaborating his understanding of syntax, Robert Sokolowski acknowledges the important influence of the work of Derek Bickerton.88 After observing the four levels of language—protolinguistic, normal word use, declarative, and philosophical—Sokolowski notes, “Protolanguage is speech deprived of syntax, or speech that has not attained syntax. It is what we call ‘baby talk.’ In it the speaker indicates things, but only episodically.”89 One of the characteristics of protolanguage is the paucity of verbs and thus of the linguistic markers that indicate and effect a specific intelligibility. Syntax, on the other hand, is the means by which reality in all its multiple and layered complexity presents itself to be known: It is not represented by concepts that are in turn represented by verbal expression, it is rather revealed in and through words. I wish to present now a long passage in Sokolowski’s study, with its passages from Bickerton, because this text can convey an intuitive understanding of how reality is mediated through language and serve as a response to the aporia created by subject-dominated cognition theory. Language is an entirely different thing from protolanguage. It is not the case that protolanguage is only a more primitive stage of language; it is something else, an alternative to language, and not a simpler version of it: “The faculties of protolanguage and language are disjoint,”90 Bickerton says, and “there can be no plausible intermediate stage between the two.”91 The difference between protolanguage and language is discrete 88 Derek Bickerton, Language and Species (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990); Derek Bickerton, Language and Human Behavior (Seattle: University of Seattle Press, 1995);William H. Calvin and Derek Bickerton, Lingua ex Machina: Reconciling Darwin and Chomsky with the Human Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2000). 89 Sokolowski, “The Agent of Truth,” 22. 90 Bickerton, Language and Species, 118. 91 Ibid. 165. Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 311 and decisive: “Between protolanguage and language we find nothing.”92 The major difference between them lies in the fact that language incorporates syntax and protolanguage does not:“Syntax is the magic key that unlocks the floodgates of language. . . .”93 It is “the Rubicon.”94 Moreover, syntax is not just linear concatenation; what is special about it is its hierarchic and nesting structure: “The really crucial relationships in language are not horizontal but vertical. . . .”95 Through syntax, phrases can be embedded inside other phrases, not just strung along one after the other.This embedding, this Russian-doll structure, permits the exquisite articulation that is radically different from the “one by one” sequencing of protolanguage. . . . In language, “phrases are not as they might appear to be, strung together serially, like beads on a string. Phrases are like Chinese boxes, stacked inside one another.”96 And Bickerton rightly concludes this remark by saying, “The importance of this point cannot be overestimated.” In protolanguage we have sequences of ideas; but in language we have thoughts, and thoughts occur as embedded in larger thoughts.97 If faith is a way of knowing, then faith is a way of wording. By returning to a more solid understanding of cognition and deepening this through an appreciation of the role of syntax in human-language expression, we have articulated, in regard to the Scriptures, what every believer knows by experience: that in all genuine, verbal communication what is mediated is the reality itself, not a notion of the reality.The stage is now set for a beginning in the work of synthesis called for by Joseph Ratzinger. To conclude, I would like to reflect on what lies ahead in this effort. Concluding Reflections The act of knowing is an instance of the “generosity of existence,” by which creation participates in the nature of God and is, in its own way, diffusivum sui. Created reality thus calls out, as it were, to be known, not only by its Creator, but also by its fellow creatures. Man, through the whole activity of his spiritual/physical being, receives this call and, by a mysterious alchemy, accepts the gift of other creatures, transforms it by a process of imitation into something of himself, and then gives another 92 Bickerton, Language and Human Behavior, 71. 93 Calvin and Bickerton, Lingua ex Machina, 52. 94 Bickerton, Language and Human Behavior, 65. Calvin and Bickerton, Lingua ex Machina, 24: “In fact, as was apparent nearly two decades ago, the real Rubicon, unpalatable as it may be to the philosophically minded, is syntax not symbols.” 95 Calvin and Bickerton, Lingua ex Machina: Reconciling Darwin and Chomsky with the Human Brain, 140. 96 Bickerton, Language and Species, 60. 97 Sokolowski, “The Agent of Truth,” 23. Francis Martin 312 level of being to what he knows through an act of wording, in an act by which, like Adam, the creature’s being and identity are named and placed in the interlocking net of all being. If this were not enough, God, who willingly allows himself to be known in this way and thus to enter the world of his creatures, has raised man to faith, to the ability to share, though darkly for now, in the knowledge God has of himself, and which he shares ineffably with the blessed.98 The challenge that faces us now is to apply what has been gained in the area of knowing and wording, to the revelation God makes of himself in Christ, and in his Body, the Church, instructing us constantly through our share in the divine light that we call faith. Since biblical interpretation is a matter of understanding the realities mediated to us by a text, we must attend to the public nature not only of discourse, but of the very act of wording itself which takes place by language. Understanding the thoroughly public nature of the process by which the worded reality reaches us in an act of communication remains a primary task of biblical interpretation, and provides insight into the fact that the Whole Christ is the subject of interpretation.99 We must, moreover, remember that God teaches us uniquely through the Scriptures. Commenting on 2 Timothy 3:16, Aquinas asks why only the Scriptures should be considered divinely inspired since, according to Ambrose, “anything true, by no matter whom said, is from the Holy Spirit.” His response is that God works in two ways, one that is immediate and this pertains to him alone (such as is the case with miracles), and one that is mediate, that is through the mediation of lesser causes (as is the case with natural operations). He then says: “And thus, in man, God instructs the intellect both immediately through the sacred letters and mediately through other writings.”100 There is further the very model of all “wording” in which by the grace of the “mission” of the Word, he proceeds in a participated way within us. It will be important in the future to imitate Augustine and Aquinas and look to what we can become in our knowing in order to understand knowledge itself, especially our knowledge of revelation. Think, for instance, of how our understanding of cognition is stretched when the word that proceeds in us is the Word himself. It is necessary that the soul be conformed or assimilated to that Person (who is sent) through some gift of grace. . . .The Son, for his part, is the 98 See ST I, q. 1, a. 2. 99 I have hardly touched upon this important aspect of Sokolowski's contribution. 100 In 1 Tim 3, lect. 3 (Marietti ed. §812). Joseph Ratzinger on Biblical Interpretation 313 Word—and not just any word but a Word breathing forth love. Thus Augustine (bk. 9 of De Trinitate) says that “the Word we intend to make known is a knowledge filled with love.” For it is not by just any perfection of the intellect that the Son is sent, but only of that instruction by which it bursts forth in an affection of love as it says in John 6:45, “Whoever has heard from the Father and accepted his teaching comes to me.” . . .Augustine plainly says that the Son is sent when he is known and perceived. The word “perceived” signifies a kind of experiential knowledge.101 And finally, let us consider this text of Henri de Lubac when reflecting on what is available to us in the gift of the Sacred Scriptures: Since Christian mysticism develops through the action of the mystery received in faith, and the mystery is the Incarnation of the Word of God revealed in Scripture, Christian mysticism is essentially an understanding of the holy books. The mystery is their meaning; mysticism is getting to know that meaning.Thus, one understands the profound and original identity of the two meanings of the word mystique that, in current French usage, seem so different because we have to separate so much in order to analyze them: the mystical or spiritual understanding of Scripture and the mystical or spiritual life are, in the end, one and the same.102 N&V 101 ST I, q. 43, a. 5, ad 2. I suspect that this teaching of Augustine is one of the places from which Aquinas drew, and because of which, in contradistinction to Aristotle, he posited the notion of wording in every act of knowledge, in much the same way as, in his teaching on our knowledge of God, (ST I, q. 12) he concentrates on beatific knowledge. 102 Henri de Lubac, “Mysticism and Mystery,” in idem, Theological Fragments (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1989), 58. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 315–24 315 Pleasure: A Reflection on Deus Caritas Est G. J. M C A LEER Loyola College in Maryland Baltimore, Maryland T HERE IS a strange peculiarity in the history of Catholic ideas. Thomas is the only truly great Thomist, but there are a number of great Augustinians.At least this is true of philosophy. Most philosophers would accept three Catholics after Thomas amongst the absolute giants of the discipline: Malebranche, Pascal, and Scheler. All three were Augustinians. It seems that when Catholic philosophy replenishes itself it does so either with a renewal of Thomism or with original thinkers who draw upon Augustine.To the philosopher, it is interesting that there are no references to Thomas in Pope Benedict XVI’s encyclical Deus Caritas Est, but quite a few to Augustine. Of course,Thomas spoke about love—indeed he has a fascinating theory of love—but for Augustine love is basic to the analysis of man and human action. It is quite fitting then that Augustine is a substantial presence in Pope Benedict’s encyclical on the distinctiveness of Christian love. Media pundits found something very reassuring about Benedict’s choice of love as the topic of his first encyclical. It is such a “nice” subject and one that everyone can agree on.The Church and our media elite agree: Love is good! Benedict’s choice, however, is subtle. He is well aware that humanitarian love is not at all the same as Christian love (see the remarkable nos. 36–37) and that these two loves are the difference between the culture of death and the culture of life. Perhaps he even means to signal this difference with his preference for the phrase “social charity” rather than “social justice” (nowhere used) for the latter, as anyone familiar with American Catholic colleges knows, is readily coopted by a “diversity” agenda antithetical to Christian morals. But love has also been a “wedge issue” inside Catholic Christianity itself.There are at least four distinctively Augustinian theses that medieval 316 Graham McAleer philosopher-theologians of various stripes used when disputing with Thomists. St. Augustine said of his stealing pears one night that “if any part of one of those pears passed my lips, it was the sin that gave it flavor.” About that night, he reflects, “the evil in me was foul, but I loved it.”1 Thomas argued that the will requires no virtue to order it internally because the will is structurally responsive to the good.2 Augustine’s example raises the possibility of will unmoored from the good, having as its object not a good, nor even an apparent good, but evil. Scotus finished Augustine’s thought for him arguing that it is possible to love and take pleasure in hate.3 Augustine chillingly described the City of God and the city of man as two loves: the one marked by a love of God, the other by a self-love contemning God and others.The first is a love of generosity, the other a love of domination where government, though intent on building security for the enjoyment of the “lowest goods,” does not stop at crime being inspired by “diabolical envy.”4 This powerful vision of the city of man makes Thomas’s conviction that secular government is part not of a fallen but natural order seem naïve. For Augustine’s analysis of government suggests that even if there is a “pull” in the will toward the good, it is fatally compromised by man’s destructive ambition and joy in domination. Quite apart from diabolical grip, the good are beset by their own lower nature. While wayfarers, the good will have to fight against the wicked but they will even fight amongst themselves “as a result of that part” that makes a man fight against himself.5 Importantly, it is not Augustine’s position that this struggle is a simple consequence of the Fall. The Fall exacerbates a structural tension within human nature.6 Whereas Aquinas argues that sensuality in relation to reason is like the “freemen 1 St. Augustine, The Confessions (London: Penguin, 1961), 49 and 47. 2 J. Capreolus, On the Virtues, ed. K. White and R. Cessario (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2001), 265. Capreolus’s text is a remarkable compilation of passages from Thomas and his detractors arranged as a series of arguments. Readers who want to find the exact references for the texts of Thomas, Durandus, and Scotus will find them cited in Capreolus. 3 Ibid., 331. Respecting the damned, Scotus claims, “they, simply speaking, hate God with pleasure and without remorse of conscience. It is clear, therefore, from these points that the right dictate can be, simply speaking, present in the intellect without the right choice of that dictate being present in the will.” 4 St. Augustine, The City of God (London: Penguin, 1984), 593, 599 and 601. 5 Ibid., 601. 6 For the late thirteenth-century Augustinian Giles of Rome on this point, please see my “Sensuality: An Avenue into the Political and Metaphysical Thought of Giles of Rome,” Gregorianum 82 (2001): 129–47. Pleasure: A Reflection on Deus Caritas Est 317 in cities who have the right and the means” of opposing their royal ruler,7 Augustine says reason rules sensuality,“the irrational desire which submits to rule,” despotically.8 Thus Aquinas argues that there is a continuity of freedom between the three principles of human action—intellect, will, and sensuality.9 If the actus voluntarius is to reflect the man, this continuity of freedom is necessary. Augustine’s restriction of freedom to man’s “higher part” echoes in Scotus’s idea of the will as the only free power and the principal site of the virtues.10 The question raised here is—and it is of enormous significance for philosophical anthropology, and so for apologetics, ecumenism, and pastoral theology—to what degree can sensuality be a constituent of an act of love? These three theses are related and relevant to the principal topic of this reflection, the fourth of Augustine’s theses: his stunning, and surely true, phenomenology of sexual pleasure.11 There are a number of aspects to this description, some a Thomist has little difficulty accepting. But Augustine’s description of the orgasm’s assault on the integrity of the person proves deeply troubling for Thomism. Famously, Augustine describes sexual pleasure as a “mental emotion” mingling with a “physical craving” that ends in “an almost total extinction of mental alertness.”The excitement of sexual pleasure culminating in orgasm, “disturbs the whole man,” says Augustine.12 Troubling to the Thomist is the implication that an aspect of the natural order is (now) depersonalizing.Augustinians are less perplexed than Thomists by the sense that nature and grace relate with a certain degree of antagonism; they are less surprised by the role dialectal antagonism plays generally. Benedict writes, for example, of God’s forgiving love being so great that “it turns God against Himself, his love against his justice” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 10, see also no. 12). I do not know if this formulation is inspired by Augustine, but it certainly runs counter to Aquinas’s conceptual “serenity” (Gauthier). Aquinas can only marvel at Augustine’s image of the married man, a “friend of wisdom,” overwhelmed by the (now) “perverted emotions.”13 To the Thomist, sacramental conjugal love is a supernatural perfecting of sexual love and expressive of a certain continuity between nature and grace:After all, Thomas 7 Capreolus, On the Virtues, 249. 8 Augustine, The City of God, 584 and 586. 9 Capreolus, On the Virtues, 248–49. 10 Ibid., 256–57. 11 Augustine, The City of God, 577–81. 12 Ibid., 577. 13 Ibid., 577 and 580. 318 Graham McAleer argues that natural love can have God as its primary object; were it otherwise the general principle that grace perfects nature fails.14 Augustine’s phenomenology makes one wonder whether there might be a problem not merely with sexual pleasure but pleasure as such. It is something of a commonplace in contemporary theological circles that many of today’s woes can be traced to the nominalism that swept the Christian universities in the fourteenth century. Is it well-appreciated that Augustine stood warranty for some of nominalism’s essential ideas? An early fourteenth-century Dominican (d. 1332?), Durandus of St. Pourçain argued that pleasure is indeed morally problematic and so much so that it raises a problem with Thomas’s naturalistic ethics in toto. Scotus certainly disagrees with Thomas that God because “by essence goodness, cannot be displeasing to any will.”15 Durandus is skeptical for another reason: He argues, and the argument will come to have a principled role in modern thinking, that pleasure is always self-referential and that a naturalist or eudaimonistic ethics is only ever a metaphysical egoism.16 According to Durandus, Thomism holds that the good satisfies human appetite, and this is just to say that the good is what satisfies our love of concupiscence, a love that has man as its object. Durandus is not just some medieval contrarian—he agrees with Benedict, “whoever wants to eliminate love is preparing to eliminate man as such” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 28)—but he thinks ethical naturalism is precisely the elimination of love. Benedict and Durandus agree with Scheler when he writes that “the important thing is not the amount of welfare, it is that there should be a maximum of love among men.”17 Benedict thinks Durandus completely wrong, however.The encyclical has as one of its aims to clarify the unity between eros and charity.There is no fundamental break between these two loves: eros, a human love capable of giving a “foretaste . . . of that beatitude for which our whole being yearns” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 4) and the love that God is, has him as its object, and him as its source, charity. Benedict says eros is a love between a man and a woman, “where body and soul are inseparably joined” (no. 2), and, of course, what he means is, as Aurel Kolnai puts it, “mature people are absolutely never in love without also being sexually attracted.”18 So when he says that “human beings glimpse an apparently 14 Capreolus, On the Virtues, 165. 15 Ibid., 355. 16 Kant objects to an ethics expressing desire for this is, as Spiegelberg puts it, to “subordinate all our actions to the rule of self-love and happiness, hence our lower nature.” H. Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982), 289. 17 M. Scheler, Ressentiment (Milwaukee,WI: Marquette University Press, 2003), 62. Pleasure: A Reflection on Deus Caritas Est 319 irresistible promise of happiness” in eros (no. 2), that love is refracted through sexual pleasure and we quickly return to the problem posed by Augustine’s analysis. Benedict wants to argue that there is a unity in love, but we must wonder both whether there really is a continuity between sexual love and charity and what this can mean for Thomism where sensuality is significantly valorized. Some of Augustine’s theses on love cut against the hope of the encyclical respecting the unity of love. The stakes are high for Benedict reaffirms the basic direction of Catholic theoretical engagement with the world: “The Church’s social teaching argues on the basis of reason and natural law, namely, on the basis of what is in accord with the nature of every human being” (no. 28). But how is Durandus’s criticism blocked? What matters here is to get clear about the intentionality of pleasure. In Capreolus’s treatment of hope he reviews a dispute between Thomas and Durandus. Durandus denies that hope, at least as explained by Thomas, is a theological virtue. In Thomas’s account, hope is a perfection of the irascible appetite19 because it seeks an “arduous good” difficult to secure: eternal life.20 The theological virtue of hope helps establish an inclination in the will for an “eternal good,”21 and Thomas argues blessedness or happiness “enters into the definition of hope” because it is “the aggregation of all goods.”22 If a virtue is a theological virtue, God must be the object; but if human happiness is the object of hope, then it appears to collapse into a love of concupiscence, and such a love always has the human agent as its principal object. Durandus argues that the Thomistic analysis makes hope have the pleasure of eternal life as its immediate object, though he concedes God may appear as a remote object within this pleasure. That is, “created blessedness,” a state of human happiness, is the immediate object of hope23 and not the uncreated living God. In a love of concupiscence, says Durandus, we always will “a good for ourselves.”24 18 A. Kolnai, Sexual Ethics: The Meaning and Foundations of Sexual Morality (Alder- shot, UK: Ashgate, 2005), 129. 19 Spiegelberg’s classic essay on medieval and modern conceptions of intentional- ity confines medieval interest in intentionality to acts of the intellect and denies the idea was connected with acts of love, joy, and other emotions and appetitive states.This is not right: See H. Spiegelberg “ ‘Intention’ and ‘Intentionality’ in the Scholastics, Brentano, and Husserl,” in his collection of essays The Context of the Phenomenological Movement (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981), 4 and 12. 20 Capreolus, On the Virtues, 124–25. 21 Ibid., 126. 22 Ibid., 127. 23 Idem. 24 Ibid., 128. 320 Graham McAleer About this argument, Capreolus says a Thomist can accept that a love of concupiscence is a love of self, but must reject Durandus’s claim that because hope is a hope for blessedness God is not an immediate object of a love of concupiscence.25 Capreolus argues that Thomas shows that a love of concupiscence is not exclusively a love of self: that God and the self can both be immediate objects of such a kind of love.Thomas argues that eternal blessedness is an intentional pleasure double in object having the use-experience of blessedness and the contemplative-experience of the essence of God.26 Even if we love God only with a love of concupiscence, God is still an immediate object of that love.Thomas denies, therefore, that pleasure is uniform. Pleasure may be self-seeking but this does not warrant the assumption that my use of an object is the full content of the pleasure; rather, besides my use, there stands the object, immediately experienced, and so not merely an object refracted through my useexperience.There is, if you like, an estoppel on the use-experience by a contemplative, disinterested aspect of the pleasure. Hope as a virtue that perfects human desire generates a pleasure double in object then. The formal object of the pleasure generated by hope is God; the material object, created blessedness.27 Put otherwise, hope ordering appetite in relation to God has a complex intentionality with one object being God as “Himself in Himself ”28 and another object being God as benefactor. Since it is Thomas’s position that objects give the species of acts,Thomas argues that hope is a genuine theological virtue because it has God as an immediate (formal) object. As Capreolus puts it, a Thomist can concede to Durandus that God is not the total immediate object of hope but one of two partial objects of hope. This subtlety is enough to save Thomas’s position—and therewith eudaimonistic ethics!—because Durandus is right to point out that every pleasure has, as at least a partial object, an operation and this must needs belong to the one having the pleasure.29 The example used by Thomas to clarify this point is that of drinking wine. Because of the position he wants to hold, Durandus is forced to argue that taking pleasure in a glass of wine has but one object, the pleasure I have from the use of the wine. Aquinas had argued that besides this pleasure object there is also the object of the wine itself: One can take pleasure in the wine and not merely from it.30 Pleasure can rest in the 25 Ibid., 127–28. 26 Ibid., 140. 27 Ibid., 139. 28 Ibid., 128. 29 Ibid., 137. 30 Ibid., 140. Pleasure: A Reflection on Deus Caritas Est 321 wine as its intentional object and not only upon the effects of the wine. Of course, Aquinas has also to argue that these two partial objects of pleasure in wine stand in a hierarchy, the contemplative-experience standing as the formal object of the pleasure and the use-experience of the wine as the material object. The example is interesting because it seems that Thomas’s analogy between pleasure in wine and pleasure in God is weak. Even if Aquinas is right about the wine example and that our appetites expressed in love of concupiscence can genuinely rest in objects, Durandus is nevertheless right about the crucial example. Our pleasure in wine is not a compelling analogy to our pleasure in God, for Benedict is certainly correct that the personal love of marriage is a better analogy for the personal love of God. Pope Benedict argues with plenty of scriptural warrant that the pleasure of conjugal love offers a “glimpse” of a “promise of happiness” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 2): Conjugal love is a “joy which is the Creator’s gift [and] offers us a happiness which is itself a certain foretaste of the Divine” (no. 3). Conjugal love certainly has the double intentionality of partial objects that Aquinas seeks. Marriage is a relationship in which a man and a woman have a useexperience of one another, but also experience a genuine beloved, not merely someone loved but someone privileged in the field of my experience.These two partial objects also stand in a hierarchy, but sexual pleasure appears to rupture the relationship between the formal and material objects and to invert the intentional order within conjugal love.The wine analogy is weak because taking pleasure in wine is not an analogous pleasure to the peculiar nature of sexual pleasure. Durandus did not believe that marriage was a sacrament and perhaps on account of this inversion: If marriage is an affirmation of sexual love then marriage cannot be a sacrament, for sexual love expresses a pleasure that is, inevitably, one of egoism; namely, where the use-experience takes precedence over and occludes the contemplative, affirmational aspect of pleasure. As Augustine puts it, excitement and orgasm overwhelm the “intellectual sentries.”31 Aquinas rejected the Augustinian (and later Scotist) position that perversity is a love of an evil object.Aquinas had a number of explanations for the phenomenon of perversity,32 but one regards the inversion of values. Scheler and Karol Wojtyla held that an inversion of value was the mark of an evil will,33 and Aquinas agrees: Perversity 31 Augustine, The City of God, 577. 32 His use of the idea of velleity is especially interesting. See On Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), q. 16, a. 3. 33 M. Scheler, Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973), 25; and K.Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1981), 159. 322 Graham McAleer is the turning away from a high good towards a preferred low good.34 Built into sexual love is perversity.This is not meant to be shocking, but an explanation for the phenomenological evidence of what Kolnai calls the “ethical precariousness” of sex.35 The phenomenology of sexual pleasure favors Durandus’s position that pleasure is always a love of concupiscence and thus a matter of use. Even if sexual pleasure is a perverse pleasure, the role it has in conjugal love will be enough to derail Pope Benedict’s hopes for the unity of love. Kolnai accepts Augustine’s analysis of sexual pleasure, but argues nonetheless that sexual love is rather Thomistic than not.The depersonalizing quality of sexual pleasure is not only because of the domination of the partner implicit in Augustine’s analysis,36 but also a “drowning” of the person in a homogeneous, anarchistic “stream of life.”37 Drowning in sexual pleasure is phenomenologically the eclipse of the person, for distinction between person and object all but disappears:There is, says Kolnai, a “quasi-absolute pervasion of the object.”38 Sexual pleasure is morally a problem, “something which extremely easily and quickly becomes sinful,”39 because the pervasion of excitement and orgasm is an experience happening within one, an abandonment.Wojtyla identified the experience of efficacy as opposed to something happening in one as a basic fault line in the experience of our personhood.40 Sexual pleasure is not only not experienced as efficacy, but precisely as pervasion. Benedict writes: “[I]t is man, the person, a unified creature composed of body and soul, who loves. Only when both dimensions are truly united, does man attain his full stature. Only thus is love—eros—able to mature and attain its authentic grandeur” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 5).The unity of love—wherein eros and charity both affirm the person—is lost if eros is not an act of the person or, to use Wojtyla’s terms, efficacy is replaced by activation. Sexual pleasure is a threat to the person but one framed by, and in continuity with, sexual love, and so not a decisive threat. Sexual pleasure structurally is found with sexual love—which is not to deny the two can be separated—and whilst sexual pleasure is a felt narrowing of intentional life, sexual love is a felt expansion. Even within sexual pleasure there is a definite intentional structure wherein essentially a union with the other sex is 34 Capreolus, On the Virtues, 352–53. 35 Kolnai, Sexual Ethics, 45. 36 Ibid., 44. 37 Ibid., 45 and 49. 38 Ibid., 42. 39 Ibid., 43. 40 K.Wojtyla, The Acting Person (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1979), 87. Pleasure: A Reflection on Deus Caritas Est 323 sought.Two poles exist in sexual pleasure: Pulled toward irresponsibility by the binding power of excitement and orgasm,41 sexual pleasure is also a response to the concrete value of someone of the opposite sex.42 This value response is (normally) initiated by sexual love and magnified by marriage, an institution that, amongst other things, serves for the personalizing of sex. To use Thomas’s double-object analysis of the intentionality of pleasure: Sexual love has for one of its two partial objects the use of the other as an instrument of diversion,43 the occluding of the “beloved” amidst the pervasion of voluptuousness; but the other partial object of sexual love is human devotion, a reaching out for personal closeness,44 what Kolnai calls the “proximity-intention.”45 This second object is the “intrinsic ennoblement” of sex, while the first is its innate moral precariousness.The “proximity-intention” of sexual love is an expression of an appetite for “the more real presence of the person possessed”46 and “an intention which embraces the two lives [of the man and the woman] in their entirety.”47 As Scheler has it, all love, including sexual love, is a response to the value-saturated essence of a particular person48 abstracted from the utility value of the person.49 Indeed, conjugal love is anticipated in sexual love as the latter already “radically exalts” the beloved.50 There is then “an emphatic and thoroughgoing moralization of sexuality” from within sexual love as it places sexual pleasure, despite all its precariousness, within “the sphere of feeling,”51 the site of the cognition of value. Kolnai’s analysis of the intentionality of sexual love shows that Augustine is right about sexual pleasure. The use-experience of sexual pleasure is, however, only one of the two partial objects of pleasure initiated by sexual love. It is by returning to Aquinas’s treatment of the intentionality of beatitude that helps make this point. Sexual love has a double intentionality with an object fixing use and another fixing the affirmation of the beloved, a devotional encounter with her value-saturated essence. 41 Ibid., 237–38. 42 For why homosexuality does not refute this essential structure of sexual pleas- ure, see Kolnai, Sexual Ethics, 46, 186–94. 43 Ibid., 44. 44 Ibid., 122. 45 Ibid., 131. 46 Ibid., 124, original emphasis. 47 Ibid., 125, original emphasis. 48 Ibid., 128, n. 1. 49 Ibid., 130. 50 Ibid., 131. 51 Ibid., 132. 324 Graham McAleer This reflection wanted to show that Benedict’s interest in the unity of love can only claim in Augustine an ambiguous filiation. I reviewed the Thomas-Durandus debate to show that in the history of Catholic ideas an Augustinian heritage had been used to counter what I take to be a signature Thomist theme:That there is a deep continuity in human and divine love because there is a continuity between nature and grace. Returning to this old debate helps better explore the essential thesis of the encyclical in its full richness. To appreciate the double intentionality of eros with its problematic object of use and its ennobling object of devotion is to identify a connective tissue between eros and charity. Benedict’s unity of love thesis is thoroughly defensible on Catholic grounds, but these grounds are not naïve. They show, as Kolnai puts it, that the sacrament of marriage “fulfils a double goal, to affirm and seal the goodness laid down in nature itself, and also to complete it supernaturally and to fence it off from the evil and anarchic powers of natural reality with the help of a special grace.”52 In marriage the devotion of sexual love is elevated into promises of commitment to the good of the other, and to the good of others who will issue from sexual love; these promises craft donations that then serve as a substructure of sexual love and orders that love to the generosity of the hour known by a Mother and her Son (Deus Caritas Est, no. 41) and N&V definitively away from egoism. 52 Ibid., 147, emphasis added. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 325–58 325 Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology: The Four Last Things F RANCESCA A RAN M URPHY University of Aberdeen Aberdeen, Scotland I N 1960, Joseph Ratzinger remarked that, with respect to Protestantism, one could “invert a saying of Saint Augustine’s: that an old schism becomes a heresy.The very passage of time alters the character of a division, so that an old division is something essentially different from a new one.”1 Ratzinger had a hand in Pope John Paul II’s encyclical Ut unum sint (1995) and pushed through the Lutheran-Catholic Joint Declaration on the Doctrine of Justification in the summer of 1998.2 This essay will describe just his responses to Protestant thought, not his ecumenical work or the ecclesiology from which it springs.3 His engagement with Protestantism is characteristically ad hoc. Where there is disagreement, Ratzinger, as the original South Park Catholic, simply says,“You’re wrong.” He is coruscating about Luther’s reduction of justification by faith to hope for myself, for this entails the “exclusion of love” from justification: “[I]n Luther’s view faith is no longer, as it is for Catholics, . . . a sharing in faith with the entire Church; for him . . . the Church can neither assume the guarantee of certainty for one’s personal salvation nor decide in a . . . binding manner 1 Joseph Ratzinger, The Meaning of Christian Brotherhood, 2nd English trans. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1960, 1993), 88. 2 John L.Allen, Pope Benedict XVI:A Biography of Joseph Ratzinger (London: Contin- uum, 2005), 232–34; and, for a scholarly account, Daphne Hampson, Christian Contradictions: The Structures of Lutheran and Catholic Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 215–21. 3 We discuss both in “De Lubac, Ratzinger, von Balthasar:A Communal Adventure in Ecclesiology,” in Ecumenism in the 21st Century: Reflections on Ut Unum Sint, ed. Chris Asprey and Eric Puosi (Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, forthcoming). 326 Francesca Aran Murphy about the content of faith.”4 There is also an ironic side, exposed in the adverse comparison of Catholic behavior with that of Protestant. As against some 1970s Catholic catechisms, Ratzinger remarks that Luther’s catechisms were based on clear doctrinal loci, not on complex theological programs;5 having flattened another cardinal’s fleet of local churches, he capped the devastation with a citation from Rudolf Bultmann.6 There are a few straight lifts, such as his use of Barth’s notion of the election of all humanity in Christ to address the question of the relation of Christians to non-believers:“Just as Christ the chosen one,” Ratzinger says, became “the one rejected for us in order to confer on us his election,” so “this exchange relationship occurs constantly in salvation history following him.”The few are elected in service to the many.7 His theology also contains some give and take with recent Protestant theology. Since Protestants have always looked to Augustine, one might imagine the interchange begins from Ratzinger’s doctoral thesis on Augustine. His habilitation on Bonaventure’s theology of history led him nearer the mark.There are two reasons why taking the measure of Bonaventure put Ratzinger foursquare with Protestant thought. In the first place, Bonaventure’s “unique individuality” consists in his being the sole scholastic writer to consider Scripture, not in a “conceptual-abstract” way, but in terms of its historical symbolism.8 Bonaventure built “a new theory of scriptural exegesis which emphasizes the historical character of the scriptural statements in contrast to the exegesis of the Fathers and the Scholastics which had been more clearly directed to the unchangeable and the enduring.”9 A Bonaventurian approach to Scripture has sufficient parallels with Protestant methods to create openings for dialogue. One way of resolving the problem of how Scripture relates to history has been to conceive Revelation as a salvation-history: For Ratzinger, Bonaventure got there 4 Joseph Ratzinger, Church, Ecumenism and Politics: New Essays in Ecclesiology, trans. Robert Nowell and Fridesiwide Sandeman, O.S.B. (Slough: St Paul Publications/New York: Crossroad, 1988), 111–13. 5 Joseph Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology: Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology, trans. Mary Frances McCarthy, S.N.D. (Ignatius: San Francisco, 1982, 1987), 130–31. 6 Joseph Ratzinger, “The Local Church and the Universal Church,” America 185 (November 19, 2001): 11. 7 Ratzinger, The Meaning of Christian Brotherhood, 79. Here, as so often in his references to Barth in the 1960s, Ratzinger refers us both to Barth’s Church Dogmatics and to Hans Urs von Balthasar’s The Theology of Karl Barth. 8 Joseph Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, trans. Zachary Hayes (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1959, 1971, 1989), 4. 9 Ibid., 7. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 327 before Barth and Oscar Cullmann.With the Protestant writers, salvationhistory replaces metaphysics as a category of theological understanding. Bonaventure’s notion of salvation-history and his belief that “wisdom is unthinkable . . . without reference to the historical situation in which it has its place” enter into Ratzinger’s conversation with modern Protestantism.10 He allows that history has a place in metaphysics, and complements the concession with the profession that metaphysical insight is a creative force in history. In the second place, for better and for worse, the accentuation of the historical character of knowledge in both Bonaventure’s thought and that of Protestant theologians is linked to a focus on eschatology, and even to apocalyptic leanings. Luther’s appropriation of a “linear” sense of history, the “greater value” that the Reformer placed on the “individual historical event” led Lutherans to perceive their era “as moving very quickly toward the edge” of historical time.11 Ratzinger had discerned the same slant in his favored medieval theologian. Luther expressed his eschatological sensibility in a doctrine of once-for-all justification. By separating justification from temporal sanctification, he divested Lutheran Christianity of the need for an historical Church. Ratzinger traces the “anecclesiality” of Lutheranism to Augustine’s having distinguish[ed] with a sharpness until then unknown between the theological greatness of the Church as a salvific reality and her empirical existence; many who seem to be in the Church are outside her; many who seem to be outside her are in her.The true Church is the number of the predestined who . . . transcend the visible Church while . . . the reprobate are present at her very center. With Luther, the concept of the Church was limited, on the one hand, to the local community; on the other hand, it embraced the community of the faithful throughout the ages who are known only to God. But the community of the whole Church as such is no longer the bearer of a positively meaningful theological content.12 It is not easy for a Catholic theologian to find a solid point of contact in writings from which a theological notion of the Church is absent.Taking 10 Ibid., 6. 11 Robin Bruce Barnes, Prophecy and Gnosis:Apocalypticism in the Wake of the Lutheran Reformation (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1988), 100, 102, and 114. 12 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 196–97. 328 Francesca Aran Murphy a different tack from the Anabaptists and Lutherans, Calvin sublimated eschatology into dual predestination.When Barth wrote in his Commentary on Romans that a “Christianity which is not wholly eschatology and nothing but eschatology has nothing to do with Christ,” he was taking Protestantism back to the Reformation.13 In his Church Dogmatics, Barth transformed Calvin’s idea of predestination into the eternal predestination of Christ to damnation and salvation on behalf of all.The first volume of his Church Dogmatics declares that “theology is a function of the church.”14 Here a point of conversational contact is established.Where Ratzinger uses Luther and modern Lutherans like Bultmann to support ideas he already holds, he assimilates the Swiss Calvinist’s Christocentricity into the positive content of his theology.At the same time—agreeing with Barth that plausibility to secular reason is not a criterion of theology—he retains the right to say,“You’re wrong.” Barth had not so much eliminated eschatology from his theology as he created an eschatological doctrine of the Church. He fills out his notion of the Church by affirming that “the being of the Church is identical with Jesus Christ.” For Barth, the subject of theology takes three forms: Revelation (flowing from the Father), Word (corresponding to the Son), and Proclamation (deriving from the Holy Spirit). The Word is said to be the history-making act of God. When he states that the Word is the criterion of Christian dogma, Barth means that Christ is.15 The Church exists from the Word of God. Ratzinger acknowledges the value of this when he states his relief that, following the intervention of Paul VI,Vatican Council II’s Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation, Dei Verbum, was not absorbed into that on the Church: “The council would otherwise,” he considers, have risked falling victim to a kind of ecclesio-monism in its texts, whereas the Constitution on Revelation now stressed the importance of listening, thus . . . tak[ing] up . . . an attitude in which the Church transcends itself, for it was not there for its own sake, but only to lead to him to whom all honor is due, God the Lord.16 13 Karl Barth, Commentary on Romans, 4th ed., 314, cited in Nicholas J. Healy, The Eschatology of Hans Urs Von Balthasar: Being as Communion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 8. Anyone who can get to page 314 of Barth’s Commentary on Romans has a higher eschatology threshold than I. 14 Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, The Doctrine of the Word of God, trans. G. W. Bromley, 2nd ed. (Edinburgh:T&T Clark, 1932, 1936, 1975), 3. 15 Ibid., 41, 43, 137, and 144. 16 Joseph Ratzinger,“Origin and Background,” in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler, trans. William Glen-Doepel (London/New York: Burns & Oates/Herder & Herder, 1967, 1969), 162. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 329 The first phrase in article 1, “Dei verbum religiose audiens et fidenter proclamans” is “one of the happiest formulations in the text: the dominance of the word of God, its sovereign supremacy above all human eloquence and activity . . . is given due prominence.The Church itself is depicted in the double role of listening and proclaiming.”17 This elucidates the link between the Constitutions on the Church and on Revelation: The “life of the Church is . . . opened upwards and its whole being gathered together in the attitude of listening, which can be the only source of what it has to say.”18 Ratzinger seems to proceed in the same deferential direction when he notes that the third article of Dei Verbum affirms the historical character of Revelation, which comes to man not as a timeless idea but as the historical operation of God in our own time. So far we can see here a certain approximation to the position of Cullmann and his school without necessarily speaking, in a technical sense, of a theology of salvation history.19 But he is actually moving toward a sting in the tail. For, as Walter Brueggemann observes, the “notion of salvation history and what Enlightenment scholarship understood by history are quite distinct matters.This distinction . . . has haunted . . . the enterprise of Old Testament theology through the twentieth century.”20 All the better that Dei Verbum was not tied to it. Two of the obstacles to the coupling of the understanding of “history” in Protestant biblical scholarship and in secular scholarship are the hermeneutical gap a modern person must cross to grasp the meaning of an ancient text, and the question of how a history in which God acts overlaps with data acceptable to a secular scholar. Brueggemann notes that, although nineteenth-century developmentalism is very different from eighteenth-century rationalism and empiricism, it is in continuity with them in practicing an epistemology of the human knower as an unencumbered objective interpreter who was understood to be a nonpartisan, uninvolved reader of the data.21 17 Ratzinger,“Preface,” in Vorgrimler, Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, 167. 18 Ibid. 19 Ibid., 172–73. 20 Walter Brueggemann, Theology of the Old Testament: Testimony, Dispute, Advocacy (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1997), 11. 21 Ibid., 13, original emphasis. Francesca Aran Murphy 330 Barth’s declaration that faith is the only objective lens through which the Bible can be understood was intended to abridge this hermeneutical difficulty. His followers in the field of Old Testament studies sought to shore this up by demonstrating that a gulf exists between the attitudes evinced in sacred Scripture and those exhibited in the texts of other Near Eastern Religions. Albrecht Alt argued that “very early, even from its inception, Mosaic Israel operated with distinct theological assumptions.” 22 Claiming that Israelite law codes differ from other Near Eastern codes in issuing “absolute commands and prohibitions,” Alt argued that this apodictic command . . . is based on the absolute sovereignty of YAHWEH , the God of Israel. Thus the form of the law is taken as evidence of the . . . monotheism that was already present in Israel and decisive at the Mosaic beginning of Israel. Martin Noth followed Alt’s insight with the claim that it is YAHWEH ’s “exclusive sovereignty” that is the bedrock of Israel’s self-understanding as a community under the command of YAHWEH .23 The “Biblical Theology” school from Alt to Noth to von Rad, in Germany, and G. Ernst Wright in America intended to echo Barth’s hermeneutical “fideism” by finding marks of Israel’s unique character in its texts. But, after Vatican II, the second problem in the Protestant agenda for linking sola Scriptura to Scripture’s demonstrable uniqueness came home to roost: “The principal criticism of von Rad and his ‘recital of God’s mighty deeds’ is that neither von Rad nor anyone else has found a way to relate salvation history . . . to secular history as it could be recovered by secular scholarship.”24 The point at issue in both the hermeneutical question and that of whether both Christian and secular historians understand history in the same way is whether the Bible makes most sense within the Church. Where Brueggemann finds with the Council of Trent,25 Ratzinger notes that Vatican II improved on Trent’s notion of two sources of Revelation, Scripture and tradition. For this distributes Revelation in a mechanical way between two vessels of Revelation that are independent of each other and thus again fails to recognize its true nature, which is not a collection of propositions that 22 Ibid., 21, original emphasis. 23 Ibid. 24 Ibid., 43. 25 Ibid., 4. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 331 can be . . . sheered out between two different compilations, but a living, organic unity.26 But the council’s effort to create a single-source, Catholic notion of sola Scriptura irritated Protestant observers. Ratzinger saw that the route of appeasement in dialogue with Protestantism often boomerangs; as one seems to approach convergence, more deep-seated Protestant convictions emerge to reject the apparent kinship. Moreover, the common ground may turn out to be quicksand, out of which a biblical theology like Cullmann’s has no escape. The dual dilemma of mid-century biblical theology came down to proving in all scientific credibility that one’s historical findings come up to one’s faith. At the time, writers like Cullmann and J. Jeremias were convinced that biblical exegesis would approach ever closer to the truth of history. Others, like Bultmann and Ernst Käsemann were not: “[I]t seems to me safer to walk through a minefield blindfold[ed],” Käsemann wrote, than to rely on historical exegesis.27 Although Ratzinger appreciated that, materially, sound scholars like Jeremias sometimes made good findings, nonetheless he recognized that Bultmann and Käsemann had seen the basic formal problem: Historical research has done away with the Reformation idea that Scripture itself has one clear meaning. . . . This means that an opposition between Scripture and the Church is ultimately not possible. . . . When Cullmann tells us to put our trust in the exegetes, that is, in their being led by the Holy Spirit, then we must say that fear of the terrifying possibilities of the teaching office can equally be dispelled only through confidence in the Spirit that guides his Church.28 With Barth clearly in view, Ratzinger notes that in Dei Verbum: “[O]nly Scripture is defined in terms of what it is: it is stated that Scripture is the word of God consigned to writing.Tradition . . . is described only functionally, in terms of what it does: it hands on the word of God, but is not the word of God.”29 As his perception of the meaning of the contingency of Revelation deepened, Ratzinger will argue that Luther’s excision of “man-made traditions” from the interpretation of Scripture left him with just “the pure power of reason, the immediate access to the 26 Ratzinger, “Chapter II: The Transmission of Divine Revelation,” in Vorgrimler, Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, 191. 27 Ibid., 193. 28 Ibid., 194. 29 Ibid., original emphasis. 332 Francesca Aran Murphy word of God.”Tradition, he will later say, “is not the adversary of reason but its handiwork . . . and the contingency on which it is founded.”30 At the turn of the twentieth century, two Protestant biblical scholars, Johannes Weiss and Albert Schweitzer, dismantled the nineteenth-century belief that biblical scholarship had recovered the historical Jesus. They argued that Jesus was not a pious liberal but a pious Jew who preached the imminent end of the world. A generation later, von Balthasar could accurately comment that eschatology was now the “storm-zone” of modern theology.31 Pre-Reformation Christians had set eschatology in stone, in the architecture of their cathedrals. But, since the seventeenth century, both magisterial Protestantism and Catholicism had put the lid on the apocalyptic fervor that preceded the Reformation;32 only sectarian Protestants like the Plymouth Brethren took eschatology or apocalyptic as central to their life and worship.The rediscovery of eschatological themes in Jesus’ own preaching reopened a question educated people imagined had been closed: If eschatology belonged to Jesus’ self-understanding, it should have some role in Christian theology—but what? Bonaventure had already raised this problem. The Franciscan general broke with the lapidary formation of medieval orthodoxy and went some way in hand with Joachim of Fiore’s use of Scripture to predict an eschaton that is both imminent and overlaps with the “Sixth Day” in which history has remained since the advent of Christ. As Ratzinger put it in his habilitation,“Bonaventure believes in a new salvation in history, within the limits of this time. This . . . must be seen as the central historico-theological problem of the Hexaemeron.”33 Following Augustine, a standard medieval opinion was that nothing very new will happen before the end of time; history replays variations on the plan mapped out in the Book of Revelation. As in the liturgy, so in history—but with less calendrical regularity—the map depicted in Revelation simply circulates.34 By laying the sevenfold movement of history (corresponding to the seven days of Creation) from Adam to Christ alongside a chart of historical events, Bonaventure was able, in Joachim’s footsteps, to note equivalences between 30 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 91. 31 Hans Urs von Balthasar, “Eschatologie,” cited in Joseph Ratzinger, Eschatology: Death and Eternal Life, trans. Michael Waldstein (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1977, 1988), 1. 32 Walter Klaassen, Living at the End of the Ages: Apocalyptic Expectation in the Radical Reformation (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1992), 19–24. 33 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 14. 34 I discuss this in more detail in “The Book of Revelation:The Apocalypse of St. John the Divine,” in The Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible, ed. Kevin Vanhoozer (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic/SPCK, 2005), 680–87. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 333 the scriptural “septacet” and the era after Christ.Where the equivalences between the two lines have yet to be balanced out, he was able to discern which events will arrive before the “Seventh Day,” or the Second Coming of Christ: As yet missing are a second Charlemagne and, parallel to the Babylonian exile, a second tribulation for the Church.Abandoning a reading of Scripture and history that went back to Augustine, Bonaventure decided that there will be an intersection in the as-yet-uncharted territory of the Sixth Day, the last days of mankind, and the Seventh Day, the Last Judgment: The eschaton and the “new salvation” it harbors will occur within history. Bonaventure’s belief in the imminence of the end is tied to a conviction that Francis was the “seventh seal,” the “Angel who ascends from the rising of the sun” (Rev 7:2).35 This is not, according to Ratzinger, the most ground-breaking feature of the Seraphic Doctor’s theology of history; but it is there and helped to prepare the German theologian’s response to the means by which modern Protestant theologians attempted to navigate the “storm-zone.” In Barth’s 1919 Romans Commentary, eschatology had been the category that depicts God’s “vertical” difference from human, horizontal history, the way in which God miraculously erupts into history. Considering the “antiseptic task” of the Commentary completed, the Church Dogmatics modifies its category-break by asserting that the reality of the Revelation of Jesus Christ is also what we call the lifetime of a man. It is also a section of what we call “historical time” or world history. . . . Revelation in the sense of Holy Scripture . . . is an eternal, but not therefore a timeless reality. . . . Revelation will never be discovered by anyone who undertakes to arrive at a kind of timeless core by abstracting from all times or from specific times, or who attempts to rise from the human to the divine.36 Within Barth’s hermeneutics, “what we call ‘historical time’ ” is known theologically, and hence some Anglican critics have questioned whether “history” is for Barth a reality independent of God.37 The autonomy of historical time is not the matter that Ratzinger sees as problematic in Barth’s eschatology. His concern is that the post-Romans Calvinist keeps 35 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 33; see also 20–32. 36 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 50. 37 See Richard Roberts, “Karl Barth’s Doctrine of Time: Its Nature and Implica- tions,” in Karl Barth: Studies of His Theological Method, ed. Stephen W. Sykes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 88–146; and Richard Roberts, “The Ideal and the Real in the Theology of Karl Barth,” in New Studies in Theology I, ed. Stephen Sykes and Derek Holmes (London: Duckworth, 1980). Francesca Aran Murphy 334 the “Last Things” at arm’s length, outside of time. As a theological and thus Christological category, for Ratzinger, eschatology involves indwelling as well as inbreaking. He complains that, with Barth, the “word ‘eschatological’ no longer qualifies time.”38 Barth’s negotiation of the eschatological question can be seen synoptically with that performed by Bultmann, and Ratzinger does this, taking the one as the converse side to the other. Where Barth reinstated eschatology as the ever-possible act of God, Bultmann took eschatology as the Christian’s act of “breaking through to authenticity in an encounter-event.”39 Ratzinger is no more satisfied by the Lutheran than the Calvinist: Bultmann’s “solution is,” he feels, “purchased at too dear a price. For it depends on displacing Christianity from its home in the midst of reality and resettling it on the pinhead of the present moment.”40 Chiliasm repeatedly resurfaces in Western history because it is religiously attractive. Ratzinger considers that Barth’s apparent withdrawal of eschatology from “real time” leaves an all too theological Christianity defenseless against the appeal of religion. Ratzinger is familiar with Eric Voegelin’s accounts of National Socialism and Marxism as secularized versions of chiliastic and Joachimite religiousity.41 As Ratzinger sees it, the “attack on God” launched by Marxist thought fosters a religious pathos which attracts the often deracinated religious energies of numerous contemporary men and women to itself, as a magnet draws ore.This pathos also affects theology, which detects in it the opportunity to fill the eschatological message with a tangible, realistic content. It is curious, and yet, in the light of Barth’s violent separation of faith and religion, also understandable that when theology is thus placed before the alternatives of faith in God and a religious pathos directed to futurity, it is willing to choose religion over against God.42 One of Ratzinger’s objections to liberation theology is that transmuting eschatology into futurity creates an inner-historical “new salvation”: As a 38 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 48. 39 Ibid., 49, original emphasis. 40 Ibid., 50. 41 In conversation with Voegelin’s literary executor, Paul Caringella, Ratzinger assured him that he owned shelf-loads of Voegelin’s writings.The briefest exposition is to be found in Eric Voegelin. Science, Politics and Gnosticism (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1968). Ratzinger may have had a sufficiently high eschatology threshold to attempt Hans Urs von Balthasar’s Apokalypse der deutschen Seele: Studien zu einer Lehre von letzten Haltungen (1937–39). It has some relevance to German history between 1932–1945. 42 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 3–4. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 335 terminus for humanity, this is what Barth would call an idol. Ratzinger encountered this maneuver in the Lutheran Jurgen Moltmann’s Theology of Hope. Where Barth and Bultmann seemed to derealize eschatology, Moltmann made it a function of a human future to be earned by political means. Moltmann had regained the future connotation that eschatology had for Joachim, for Bonaventure in part, and for the Anabaptists, and installed at its heart a “political utopianism.” Ratzinger argues that a political interpretation of the category of eschatology both rationalizes faith— by making eschatological hope intelligible in political terms—and fideizes reason—by requiring politicians to take Jesus’ preaching of the Kingdom as a direct criterion of practical action.43 Ratzinger’s work on Bonaventure prefigures his later doubts about liberation theology: He criticizes Bonaventure’s belief in the imminence of the end in the same way that he will censure Moltmann’s “futurity,” finding that, here,“a new, second end is set up next to Christ.”44 Hence, when he states that “[t]he setting asunder of eschatology and politics is one of the fundamental tasks of Christian theology,”45 one may think that this is his last word. But when Ratzinger writes that “every interpretation of Franciscanism which abstracts from its original determination with regard to . . . eschatology . . . misses” its “essence,”46 he does not mean that Franciscanism was a dead end.The vicissitudes of modern Protestantism make evident the omission in which Catholic and Protestant thought had colluded:We cannot maintain the polite, post-Anabaptist silence about eschatology, for forgetting that we are “ever before” the eschaton had sent theology into a tailspin when Jesus’ eschatological preaching was rediscovered. Ratzinger makes good the omission in three ways, which, as it happens, are mirrored in Pope John Paul II’s encyclical Ecclesia de Eucharistia (2003). Most obviously, he seeks to reawaken the medieval art of making worship a living exegesis of Revelation: “The cosmic imagery of the New Testament cannot be used as a source for the description of a future chain of cosmic events.” For “these texts form part of a description of the mystery of the Parousia in the language of liturgical tradition. . . . The Parousia is the highest intensification and fulfillment of the Liturgy. And the Liturgy is Parousia, a Parousia-like event taking place in our midst.”47 Second, just as Ecclesia de Eucharistia affirms that “the Christian vision . . . increases rather then lessens our sense of 43 Ibid., 58–60. 44 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 114. 45 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 60. 46 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 40. 47 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 202–3; cf. John Paul II, Ecclesia de Eucharistia, nos. 18 and 19. 336 Francesca Aran Murphy responsibility for the world today,” so Ratzinger insists that eschatology is more effective in “moral theology” than in practical politics.48 The significance of the sacramental and moral signposts is that, third, they disturb our this-worldly complacency: Martin Heidegger remarked that, in the face of the situation into which mankind has blundered, only a god could save us. Our one possibility, he considered, was “to prepare the way for the readiness to receive the appearing of the god.” In this dictum of a post-Christian pagan, there is a genuine insight into the depths of our subject. The “readiness to expect” is itself transforming. The world is different, depending on whether it awakens to this readiness or refuses it.49 Bonaventure acknowledged this “ever-beforeness.” He realized that the Franciscan order is “not yet the true order of Francis,” but, rather, poised on the edge of eschatological perfection. Bonaventure’s gesture of waiting, to “preserve whatever could be preserved” of the “radically eschatological character” of Francis’s life and testament,50 is an immanent sign of the eschaton and one which Ratzinger appreciates. He finds this sense of immanence wanting in Barth’s theology. He intended to create a theology that does just silence the Protestant dilemmas. Moltmann’s 1970s “futurism” was built on German biblical scholarship going back to the immediate postwar years. It was at this time that biblical scholars sought the uniqueness ascribed to Scripture by Barth in the attention that it pays to history.Thus, Cullmann found that Hebrews defined faith in temporal terms:The “assurance of things hoped for” refers to “things which are future.” This accentuation of temporality made it impossible to avoid “futurism” by entwining eschatology with the liturgy. For what is unique about the biblical conception of time, according to Cullmann, is that it does not rotate but follows a straight line: In the primitive Christian preaching . . . salvation, in keeping with the Bible’s linear understanding of time, is conceived . . . in terms of a time process. . . . Because time is thought of as a progressing line, it is possible here for something to be “fulfilled”; a divine plan can move forward to a complete execution; the goal which beckons on the end of the line can give to the entire process which is taking place all along the line the impulse to strive thither.51 48 John Paul II, Ecclesia de Eucharistia, no. 20; Ratzinger, Eschatology, 59. 49 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 201; John Paul II, Ecclesia de Eucharistia, no. 20. 50 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 51; see also 50. 51 Oscar Cullmann, Christ and Time: The Primitive Christian Conception of Time and History, trans. Floyd V. Filson (London: SCM Press, 1948, 1951), 37, 53–54. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 337 This linearity is evidence for the thesis that, unlike other near-Eastern texts, Scripture refers to a saving history. Cullmann seeks to show that Barth’s notion of the uniqueness and hence God-givenness of faith is exegetically accurate: For Barth, “revealed reality” is a “temporally limited, unrepeated, and quite unrepeatable event.” Both Barth and, he thinks, the “Bible” place “extraordinary stress on the historicity of the Revelation recorded by it because by Revelation it does not mean a creation of man.”52 For these thinkers, the liturgy cannot reflect the immanence of the eschaton because liturgy is eminently repeatable. Cullmann’s most famous exegetical claim is that Scripture makes Christ define the “mid-point” of temporal space: Once time is perceived in its full linearity, “the decisive mid-point, the Christ-deed, can be the firm hold which serves as a guide point for all the process that lies behind and for all that lies ahead.”53 Barth had exposited the same idea theologically: [T]he real temporal pre-existence of Jesus Christ in prophecy and his reality post-existence in witness are identical with this once-for-all existence of his as the mid-point of time. The mid-point of time— which, after all, belongs to time—is the fulfillment of time.That is what distinguishes it from all other times.That is what it has common with the end (and . . . with the beginning) of time.54 The topical feature of Ratzinger’s habilitation was the claim that Bonaventure situates Christ at the “mid-point” of time. Bonaventure achieved this innovation partly through his “charting” of the seven days of creation against the history from Adam to Christ and post-apostolic history. For this leads him to break with the normative, Augustinian picture of Christ as inaugurating the Sixth, and historically final, Day of creation—which situates Christ at the eschatological closure of biblical time rather than in the midst of salvific time. As Ratzinger puts it, For the Augustinian scheme, Christ is the end of the ages; for the Bonaventurian schema, Christ is the center of the ages.55 The coming of the Son of God marks the fullness of time: not because time ends with his coming, but because the hidden prophecies of all ages have been fulfilled. . . . It belonged to Him . . . as the true Mediator, to come mid-way, some of his elect preceding and others following Him.56 52 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 12, and 329. 53 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 54. 54 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 12. 55 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 17. 56 Ibid., 109–10. Francesca Aran Murphy 338 Bonaventure reinterprets plenitudo temporum, the “fullness of time,” to mean “the center of time”: Thus, “the figure of Jesus Christ, the middle person in the Trinity as well as the mediator and middle between God and man . . . becomes the synthesis of everything that is expressed for Bonaventure in the concept of center. Christ becomes the center.”57 Joachim lies behind this new conception, for Bonaventure achieved it by assimilating something of Joachim’s “futurism,” and “baptizing” it. It was because Joachim saw the Old and New Testaments as “parallel”“halves” of history that he set Christ literally in medias res:“For the first thousand years of Christian theology,” or, after Augustine and before Joachim, “Christ is not the turning point of history at which a transformed and redeemed world begins. . . . Rather, Christ is the beginning of the end. He is ‘salvation’ in as far as in him the ‘end’ has already broken into history.”58 By setting Christ at the mid-point of time,“Joachim became the path-finder within the Church for a new understanding of history which to us today appears to be so self-evident that it seems to be the Christian understanding.”59 This is Joachim’s “true significance.” Joachim’s influence on the Franciscan movement is “important above all because it brought about the acceptance of this new historical consciousness. . . . The Church and redemption are rendered historical in an entirely new way which cannot be a matter of indifference for the history of dogma nor for systematic theology.”60 Where Augustinian tradition stressed Christ’s finality, Joachim and Bonaventure stressed his centrality.Thomas Aquinas’s objection to the apocalypticist side of Joachim was that Old Testament signs and miracles do not forewarn of similar crises in New Testament and post-apostolic time but, rather, prefigure Christ himself.61 Bonaventure retains Joachim’s idea that the Old and New Testaments run parallel to each other in their entirety but keeps apocalypticism at bay by repudiating the notion of a “third age” of the Spirit that supersedes the era of Christ. Here as elsewhere, Ratzinger says,“Thomas is more an Augustinian than is Bonaventure.” Bonaventure is able to baptize Joachim’s ideas because his goal is Christocentism.Where Joachim was concerned with bringing out the movement of the second age to the third, Bonaventure’s purpose is to show, on the basis of the parallel between the two ages, that Christ is the true center and the turning 57 Ibid., 110. 58 Ibid., 106. 59 Ibid., 107, original emphasis. 60 Ibid. 61 Thomas Aquinas, IV Sent., d. 43, q. 1, a. 3, qc. 2, ad 3. Near identical remarks occur in the Summa theologiae III, q. 77, a. 2, ad 3. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 339 point of history. This is the basic concept of Bonaventure’s historical schema, and it involves a decisive rejection of Joachim. In the final analysis, he is closer to Thomas than to Joachim.62 This aspect of Ratzinger’s comeback to biblical theology indicates that it is possible for a scholastic and Catholic thinker to place Christ at the “ ‘axis of world history,’ the center of time.”63 But this does not resolve the opposition implicit in the Protestant theologians’ emphasis on biblical linearity.The “symbol of time for primitive Christianity as well as for biblical Judaism,” Cullmann wrote, “is the line, while in Hellenism it is the circle.”64 He defined “biblical thought” as against “Greek thought,” and thus against metaphysics. It remains common in Protestant milieux to contrast the abstract and atemporal thinking of the Greeks with the historicity of Scripture. In order to tackle this objection, Ratzinger draws on Bonaventure’s deep sense of the historicity of Revelation. Once he has laid the specter of Catholic abasement before “Greek” metaphysics to rest, Ratzinger will be able to show that, in the liturgy as in “the prayer of the early Church,” eschatology is “personalized. Its focus is not space and time, . . . ‘Where?’ and ‘When?’ but relationship with Christ’s person and longing for him to come close.”65 The question arising from the crossover of time and eschatology in Jesus’ self-understanding seemed to be, where do they overlap in Christian history? But a better question may be, who is the juncture? “The Christian,” Ratzinger writes, “lives in the presence of the saints as in his own proper ambiance,” amongst the persons who indwell the frontier between time and eternity,“and so lives ‘eschatologically.’ ” The saints “count for something not as the past but as the present of the Lord’s power to save.”66 Ratzinger has claimed that because, for Luther, “ontology is the basic philosophical expression of the concept of continuity” between Christ and the Church,“it is opposed first as a Scholastic and later as a Hellenistic perversion of Christianity and is contrasted with the idea of history. In modern histories of theology, the concept of salvation history is treated as a Protestant antithesis to the ontological assessment in Catholic theology.”67 Before we consider Ratzinger’s treatment of this “antithesis,” we should note a difference between what Cullmann and Barth mean by 62 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 117–18. 63 Ibid., 118. 64 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 51. 65 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 8. 66 Ibid., 9. 67 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 158, original emphasis. Francesca Aran Murphy 340 “salvation history.” When they stressed the linear temporality of Scripture, the salvation historians wanted to uncover in Scripture something that, in Barth’s own doctrine of Revelation, is more elusive than chronological time. For Barth, the contact of Revelation with the passage of time is a metaphor for its quality as event. Even the idea of the “mid-point of time” exposed in the first volume of the Church Dogmatics is too static to capture what Barth means by the Christ-event. Where the biblical theologians pointed to historicity as against Greek, metaphysical circularity, Barth argued that God’s acting is not a thing, but an event. The efforts of the biblical theologians to supply textual evidence for a Barthian Weltanschauung goes against the grain in that the purpose of Barth’s theological method is to deliver Christians from reliance on any kind of evidence, including not only the metaphysical but also the historical. Moreover, for Barth, Revelation never materializes in a text as such. The text of Scripture is not Revelation in its verbal content: It becomes Revelation if and when God chooses to make it a revelatory event. Scripture becomes concurrent with Revelation when it becomes the focus of God’s action. Barth writes that, The concept of truths of Revelation in the sense of Latin propositions given and sealed once for all with divine authority in both wording and meaning is theologically impossible if it is a fact that Revelation is true in the free decision of God which was taken once for all in Jesus Christ, that it is thus strictly future for us, and that it must always become true in the Church in the intractable reality of faith.The freely acting God Himself and alone is the truth of Revelation. Hence, the direct identification between Revelation and the Bible which is in fact at issue is not one that we can presuppose or anticipate. It takes place as an event when and where the biblical word becomes God’s Word, that is, when and where the biblical word comes into play as a word of witness. . . .Thus in the event of God’s Word, Revelation and the Bible are indeed one, and literally so.68 There is a tension between this and Cullmann’s proposition that the “Christian absolute norm is itself also history and is not, as is the philosophical norm, a transcendent datum that lies beyond all history. The primitive Christian norm . . . consists . . . in a temporally connected historical series of a special kind, namely, the biblical history.”69 Ratzinger’s 68 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 15 and 113. 69 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 21–22. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 341 rejoinder will, in a sense, play the two positions off against each other: If Christian Revelation really is eschatological, then it must be historical, and this “is” is then an ontological or metaphysical datum. Cullmann and Barth share the belief that the priority of history or event over ontology is rooted in the fact that God is “for us.” Christians must describe God in terms of “act” and “deed” because God’s primary reality in relation to us is salvific. God does before we know anything about him. Barth also asserts that God is a doer or actor in relation to us because his very being is act or deed. Ratzinger rejects one feature of these proposals but also goes some way toward greeting Barth’s insight. To say that truth is yielded only by time is to make deeds or occurrences the sole source of truth. If one takes the notion that “truth is a function of time” as a principle—and we have seen that the biblical theologians inadvertently reinstated a first principle to underlie revealed theology— then one will have to take it as a matter of principle that Christ’s temporal doing exhausts his being. For Cullmann, only the “salvation historical” creeds of the early Church, the formulae that describe what he has done for us, appropriately name him. But Christ does not remain within history: He acts creatively in relation to it and changes its course. In order to affirm the leap from historical being into Resurrection, one must affirm that there is something beyond time—eternal life.There is no need to consider the latter as a lifeless and inactive concept. As Ratzinger notes, the primitive Christian creeds were both nominal and verbal:The first, such as “Jesus is Lord,” denote what Christ is; the second, such as “God has raised him” refer to what he has done—risen from death.70 But, precisely as a deed, the resurrection reveals Jesus’ ontological identity with the life of God: The Resurrection is but the most extreme concretization of this statement: God is. It shows that God is in-deed (wirklich), for being is doing and God’s being is the life that overcomes death. That God is in-deed means that there is a truth of man in which the goals of his intellectual inquiry find their limits and their measure.71 The resurrection is a quintessential event, so that, in it, being and doing are at one. Likewise, the “is” of Chalcedon, which affirms that, in the incarnate Logos, God is man, is no abstract, a-temporal concept, but embraces the event of God’s becoming man, the Incarnation.72 70 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 16, 19–21. 71 Ibid., 99. 72 Ibid., 182. 342 Francesca Aran Murphy In the Incarnate Christ, the deed of service to us, the role as savior, is identical to Christ’s being; he puts his entire being at our service. Ratzinger has written that “the Trinity becomes . . . recognizable for us through the fact that in his Son as man God Himself has become witness to Himself and thus his personality has taken actual concrete shape in the radical anthropomorphism of ‘the form of a servant’ in ‘the likeness of men’ (Phil 2:7 . . . ).”73 Aidan Nichols interprets such statements by reference to Ratzinger’s affirmation that, in Christ, the “person is the office, the office is the person”:There is in Christ “no private area reserved for an ‘I’ which remains in the background behind the deeds and actions, and thus at some time or other can be ‘off duty.’ Here there is no ‘I’ separate from the work: the ‘I’ is the work, and the work the ‘I.’ ”74 For Barth, the person of Christ is his work because the immanent Trinity itself is act or deed before our need for salvation: Unlike Cullmann’s equation of Christ with his temporal function, Barth’s formula proceeds from a theological principle. Ratzinger’s treatment recalls Barth’s proposition that “ ‘Christ’s being as man is his work’: the importance of the whole section had been brought home to Ratzinger by von Balthasar.”75 Ratzinger’s development of a Christology of “being and service” is intended to overcome, to the degree possible, the polarity between a Christology of the Incarnation, on the Johannine and patristic model, and a Christology of the Cross, of the sort found in Paul and the sixteenthcentury Reformers.The being of Christ—the predominant concern of a Christology of the Incarnation—is a continuous exodus. It is not a resting in self, but the permanent act of being Son, of being servant. Conversely, this act, for which we need verbs, “doing” words, and whose supreme manifestation is the Cross, is not simply doing, but is also being. A Christology of the Incarnation and a Christology of the Cross require each other.76 Ratzinger lays aside both a Christology that functionalizes Christ at the requirement of human justification, and a Christology so metaphysical that it is blind to the fact that, within the Trinity, action or being is 73 Ratzinger, Church, Ecumenism and Politics, 34–35. 74 Aidan Nichols O.P., The Thought of Benedict XVI:An Introduction to the Theology of Joseph Ratzinger (London: Continuum, 1988, 2005), 123, original emphasis, quoting Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity (London: 1969), 149. 75 Nichols, The Thought of Benedict XVI, 123, citing Karl Barth, Kirchliche Dogmatik (1948), III.2, 66–69; and Hans Urs von Balthasar, “Zwei Glaubensweisen,” in Spiritus Creator (1967), 76–91. 76 Nichols, The Thought of Benedict XVI, 125–26. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 343 acting toward, or relating. The primary historical “action toward” is the resurrection. Hence, “all Christian theology,” as Ratzinger considers must be first and foremost a theology of Resurrection. It must be a theology of Resurrection before it is a theology of the justification of the sinner; it must be a theology of Resurrection before it is a theology of the metaphysical sonship of God. It can be a theology of the Cross but only as and within the theology of Resurrection. . . .The core of the Gospel consists . . . in the good tidings of God’s action, which precedes all human doing. . . . For if it is true that the prae of God’s action is significant for theology, that faith in an actio Dei is antecedent to all other declarations of faith, then the primacy of history over metaphysics, over all theologies of being and existence is “obvious.”77 The “concept of God is” thereby removed from the realm of a mere . I believe that it was here that the definitive boundary between the biblical and the Greek concept of God became obfuscated, that this obfuscation was the crux of the repeated patristic attempts to combine Greek thought with biblical faith and that from this arose for Christian theology a task that is still far from being accomplished. Decisive for the Greek concept of God was the belief in God as a pure and changeless being of whom . . . no action could be predicated; his . . . changelessness meant that he was . . . selfcontained and referred wholly to Himself without any relationship to what was changeable. For the biblical God, on the other hand, it is . . . relationship and action that are the essential marks; creation and Revelation are the two basic statements about him, and when Revelation is fulfilled in the Resurrection, it is . . . confirmed . . . that He is not just one who is timeless but also one who is above time, whose existence is known to us only through his action.78 The Reformation disjunction between metaphysics and saving history is based on the belief that God is only known in his saving act. If one accentuates the word “known,” God’s “saving act” is subordinated to our knowledge and reception of it:The error of Lutherans like Cullmann lies here; but those Catholic critics who reduce Protestant belief to this are also missing something. For if, with Barth, one stresses the “saving act,” then one is simply a realist. To say that God is his doing is to affirm that God is before we theoretically formulate his being. Ratzinger concludes that,“the prae of God’s action means . . . that actio is antecedent to verbum, 77 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 184–85. 78 Ibid., 185. Francesca Aran Murphy 344 reality to the tidings of it.”79 Theological realism is a good way to avoid Pelagianism: “It is not works that are vivifying, but faith” because “Only by handing oneself over to truth and rightness does one find that communication which is life.”80 Ratzinger extensively embraces Barth’s notion of God’s being as event. But he also sees a value in the more prosaic conception underlying the evidentialism of the biblical scholars: This event really does materialize in history. An eschatologically oriented theology must include ontology because, in the Resurrection, eschatology is history—the “is” of metaphysics is inescapable. As Ratzinger puts it, the definitive transformation that eschatology underwent by virtue of Christian belief in the Resurrection is its transposition into history. For late Judaic expectation, eschatology lay at the end of history.To believe in the Resurrection of Jesus means, on the contrary, to believe in the eschaton in history, in the historicity of God’s eschatological action.81 The ancient world imagined the philosopher as one to whom “death is always present.” This pre-Christian “philosophy gave the [Christian] faith its first concrete,” imaginative “expression”:“This means that Christian art finds one of its roots in coming to grips with death.”82 The early Church imagined the “Christian philosopher” in an analogous yet “different” way.The difference is a new contact with reality:“[H]e carries in his hand the Gospel, out of which come facts, not words. He is the true philosopher because he is understands the mystery of death.”83 The art of the Catacombs often presents Christ as the philosopher, and a favorite scene is the raising of Lazarus: “Christ appears as the true philosopher because he has the answer: he changes death, and he changes life.”84 Within the history of philosophy, as Ratzinger sees it, the upshot of Luther’s opinion that metaphysics is an intellectual “justification of works” is the “rejection of ontology” by the post-Kantian philosophers.85 If one is to converse with Protestants about the usage of philosophy within theology, a Bonaventurian idea of the creative Logos is an apt opener. Historically, Barth’s objections to the Catholic use of metaphysics in theology refer to the practice of most Thomists of his era of making 79 Ibid., 186. 80 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 99. 81 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 187. 82 Joseph Ratzinger, “Faith, Philosophy and Theology,” Communio 11 (1984): 350. 83 Ibid., 351. 84 Ibid. 85 Ibid., 356–57. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 345 philosophy the antecedent foundation of theology.Whence his assertion that there is no anthropological or metaphysical “prius” for theology. What Barth found fault with in the Thomist theology he knew was its methodological insistence on foregrounding philosophy. Ever “since Descartes,” he complains, this has entailed deploying “a comprehensively explicated self-understanding of human existence which may also at a specific point become the pre-understanding of an existence in the Church or in faith, and therefore the pre-understanding and criterion of theological knowledge.” As Barth sees it, God’s action is the only antecedent condition of theology: “The Word of God always tells us something fresh that we had never heard before from anyone. The rock of a Thou . . . is thrown in our path here. This otherness which is yet related to us and made known to us . . . stamps it . . . as the Word of God.” The criterion that goes before theology is not the anonymous objective truth of metaphysics but the divine subject: The personalizing of the concept of the Word of God, which we cannot avoid when we remember that Jesus Christ is the Word of God, does not mean its deverbalizing. But it . . . means awareness of the fact that it is person rather than thing or object even if . . . it is word, word of Scripture and word of preaching.To be person means to be subject, not merely in the logical sense, but also in the ethical sense: to be free subject, a subject . . . able to control its own existence and nature . . . and also able to select new possibilities of existence and nature.86 Ratzinger thinks that Barth’s idea of Revelation as a personal action influenced Vatican II’s move away from the notion of revealed truth as congealed in two separate “sources,” conceived as material objects: “One of the most important events in the struggle over the Constitution on Revelation” was, he says, the liberation from this narrow view and the return to what actually happens in the positive sources, before it was crystallized into doctrine, when God “reveals” Himself. . . . Only by going back to the comprehensive reality of the deeds and words of God is it possible to do away with the positivisitic idea of the duplex fons; only by going back to the common foundation of all Christian discourse, could the question of the individual elements of the passing on of Revelation be removed from the field of controversy and placed within the appropriate framework. If one compares the text of article 2 with what was said at Vatican I (DS 3004 f.), it becomes clear how much Catholic theology has benefited in the last fifty years from the theology of Karl Barth, which 86 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 36, 138, 141. Francesca Aran Murphy 346 itself was influenced by the personalistic thinking of Ebner, Buber, and others. . . .Whereas Vatican I starts from the natural knowledge of God and considers “supernatural” Revelation only in close connection with this idea, in order to proceed . . . to the question of its transmission in Scripture and tradition, here the question of the natural knowledge of God is put at the end and God’s revealing activity described within a comprehensive survey of salvation history.87 If starting from God’s “revealing activity” could help to defrost the notion of Revelation as a solidified “deposit,” so the notion of philosophy as an antecedent foundation of theology can attain more flexibility if one considers philosophical questions historically. Barth rejected philosophy as a static, Cartesian basis for theology because this foundation lacks the ultimacy of a person-to-person “dialogue”: [T]he Word of God . . . aims at us and smites us in our existence. No human word has the competence to aim at us in our existence. . . .The only word that may aim at us in our existence and can smite us in our existence is one which questions and answers us in . . . the same way as death might question and answer us at the end of our existence. But death is dumb. It neither questions nor answers. It is only the end.88 For Ratzinger, metaphysical conceptions of immortality, like that of Plato, are not the antecedent foundation of Christian faith in resurrection: The philosopher, we might say, is Peter on the lake, wishing to step beyond mortality and glimpse life but not succeeding, indeed sinking beneath the waves. For all his capacity to speculate about immortality, in the end he cannot stand. . . . Only the Lord’s outstretched hand can save sinking Peter, that is, humankind.That hand reaches out for us in the saying, “Blessed are the pure in heart, for they shall see God” [Mt 5:8]. Philosophical understanding remains a walking on the waters: it yields no solid ground. Only God incarnate can draw us out of the waters by his power and hold us firm.89 Once given a “Christological transformation, the Platonist notion of the life which flows from truth is . . . made the vehicle of a ‘dialogical’ concept of humanity: Man is defined by his intercourse with God.”90 Although it accords with the Platonic conception, the 87 Ratzinger,“Chapter I: Revelation Itself,” in Vorgrimler, Commentary on the Docu- ments of Vatican II, vol. 3, 170. 88 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 141. 89 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 152. 90 Ibid. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 347 starting point of the Christian understanding of immortality is the concept of God, and from this it draws its dialogical character. Since God is the God of the living, and calls his creature, man, by name, this creature cannot be annihilated. In Jesus Christ, God’s action in accepting humanity into his own eternal life has . . . taken flesh: Christ is the tree of life whence we receive the food of immortality. Immortality cannot be accounted for in terms of the isolated individual existent and its native capacities, but only by reference to that relatedness which is constitutive of human nature.91 The “constitutive” “relatedness” of human beings is brought about by their creatureliness:Their Creator sets them in relation to himself as creatures.Whereas, for the creature, relatedness is conferred by another, to be God is to be relationship, for God is love. So it is wrong to think of God as an inactive metaphysical condition of theology: “knowing and believing in God,” Ratzinger states, is an active-passive process, not a philosophical structure . . . ; it is an act in which one is first touched by God and then responds. . . . It is only from this perspective that we can understand what it means to call God a “Person” or to speak of “Revelation”: in our knowledge of God there occurs also—and, indeed, first—something from God’s side.92 Presented in terms of a doctrine of creation, a theocentric personalism can interpret immortality as a property of human nature. Using Teilhard de Chardin’s idea that evolution produces “ever better eyesight” as a metaphor for spiritual vision, Ratzinger remarks that the human person is the creature . . . for whom the vision of God is part and parcel of his very being. Because this is so, it also belongs intrinsically to his being to participate in life. . . . it is not a relationless being oneself that makes a human being immortal, but precisely his . . . capacity for relatedness, to God. . . . such an opening in one’s existence is not a trimming, an addition to a being which really might subsist in an independent fashion. . . . It constitutes what is deepest in man’s being. It is . . . what we call “soul.” . . . A being is the more itself the more it is open, the more it is in relationship.93 Hence, it is the man who makes himself open to all being, in its wholeness and in its Ground, and becomes thereby a “self,” who is truly a person. Such 91 Ibid., 157–58. 92 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 69. 93 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 154–55. Francesca Aran Murphy 348 openness is not a product of human achievement. It is given to man; man depends for it on Another. But it is given to man to be his very own possession. That is what is meant by creation, and what Thomas means when he says immortality belongs to man by nature.94 As in “Thomas’s theology of creation: nature is only possible by virtue of a communication of the Creator’s, yet such communication both establishes the creature in its own right and makes it a genuine participator in the being of the One communicated.”95 But if relatedness is simply a spelling out of createdness, how was it that this insight gave over to a notion of metaphysical “natures” as rationally self-founding entities? Why did Catholic theology need Karl Barth to remind it of the implications of the doctrine of creation? And was it because of any overlaid feature of Catholic theology that Protestant salvation historians complained that the “ ‘Hellenization’ of Christianity” had “created a static style of thought that cannot do justice to the dynamism of the biblical style?”96 Such “questions had a strong influence” on Ratzinger, and he wrote his habilitation on Bonaventure in order to “make a contribution toward answering them.”97 As he notes, the idea of history that the Scholastics took from Augustine denies that, as a series of accidental occurrences, history can be a “science”: “for science treats precisely of the universal.” Hence, despite the importance of biblical typology to the medieval, “the predominant impression remained that history lay outside the limits of that which is properly intelligible and thus below the proper area of concern for theology.”98 Since any sequence of moments is “mere[ly] accidental,” the idea that an infinite series of moments could lie behind us is not illogical. Once it is assumed that “history is the realm of chance,” one can entertain the hypothesis of the eternity of world.99 “With keen perception,” Ratzinger says, “Bonaventure sees that this concept of history is incompatible with the Christian view.”100 Bonaventure rejected the thesis of the eternity of the world not because it was Aristotelian but because it ran counter to his own “theology of history”101 within which history is not a chronicle of 94 Ibid., 155. 95 Ibid. 96 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, xi 97 Ibid., xii. 98 Ibid., 76, 119. 99 Ibid., 140. 100 Ibid., 141. 101 Ibid., 119. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 349 chance occurrences, but “illumined by the same divine order which is the unifying law of all reality.”102 Ratzinger seems to consider that a Bonaventurian sense of history as the arena of God’s action is a natural complement to the Thomist appetite for metaphysics. For, without the sense of dynamism and concrete contingency that history lends to metaphysics, philosophy neglects its other-bound reference, becoming a self-referential science of pure rationality, not the rationality of things, and thus loses the sense of relationality in creation, which theology perfects. Something similar can happen to faith. Just as a theoretical commitment to philosophical rationality can end up “reasoning about rationality,” so a programmatic determination to make faith propel theological discourse can turn into believing in one’s belief. Commenting on the odd fact that it was “Thomas the metaphysicist” who both “brought about the rejection of the salvation-historical concept” and “took the first critical step toward the age of history,” Ratzinger remarks that “[f]ortunately, theology has always been richer in its achievements than in its programs.” The theological “revolution” attendant on a literal rather than allegorical “hermeneutic method” can be assessed “positively and negatively (yes, negatively!).”103 Ratzinger is an unprogrammatic thinker, a Church man who is more interested in responding to the lay of the land than in driving a theory to its logical conclusion. For the man of the Church, neither Plato, Aristotle, nor Thomas “is philosophy or the philosopher. It is in the multivalent message of the entire history . . . that truth is disclosed and with it the possibility of fresh knowledge.”104 The question of philosophy and theology is not a matter of either giving priority to faith or making reason the foundation but of “put[ting]” both “into dialogue with one another.”105 Barth said that theology is “rational wrestling with the mystery” of God’s action. “But all rational wrestling with this mystery . . . can lead only to its fresh . . . interpretation and manifestation as a mystery. For this reason it is worth our while to engage in this rational wrestling with it.”106 Ratzinger was disconcerted that a recognition of God’s mysterious “invisibility” is absent from Lumen Gentium’s two articles on atheism: “[P]ass[ing] over the essentials of the via negativa,” the council ignored the attention that Catholic theologians had paid to this “since Karl Barth’s 102 Ibid., 19. 103 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 181. 104 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 24. 105 Ratzinger, “Faith, Philosophy and Theology,” 358. 106 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 368. 350 Francesca Aran Murphy criticism of the analogia entis.”107 Rather than regarding the necessity of acknowledging God’s “invisibility” as an admission of the ultimate blindness of conceptual reason, Ratzinger treats it as the space that creates the possibility for dialogue between philosophical questions and theological answers: “Must not the answers . . . by their very nature leave room for the unexpressed and inexpressible? Might it not be that such answers give the ultimate questions of life and death their real depth and dramatic character?”108 Theology creates the possibility for concrete, realistic, and dramatic philosophical speech because “if faith speaks about the resurrection from the dead, then we are not dealing with some abstruse utterance about some unknown place in some unknown future.”109 Earlier twentieth-century students of Bonaventure had been divided between those who followed Etienne Gilson in viewing him as an antiAristotelian Augustinian, and those like van Steenberghen who saw Bonaventure as an eclectic, Augustinian Aristotelian. Gilson and van Steenberghen differed for half a century, not only about whether Bonaventure was a pure Augustinian or an Aristotelianizing one, but about the possibility of “Christian philosophy.” Whilst finding that van Steenberghen’s view of Bonaventure as an eclectic Aristotelian is more on the mark, Ratzinger observes a certain irony in the fact that this requires van Steenberghen to regard the Seraphic Doctor as a “Christian philosopher.”110 Ratzinger does not point out a second irony: Both medievalists exchanged places in the two controversies, for Gilson’s 107 Joseph Ratzinger, “Introductory Article and Chapter I: The Dignity of the Human Person,” in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 5, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler, trans. W. J O’Hara (London/New York: Burns & Oates/Herder & Herder, 1969), 154–55. 108 Ratzinger, “Faith, Philosophy and Theology,” 354. 109 Ibid., 358. 110 Ratzinger declares that “Van Steenberghen is . . . inconsistent with the results of his own studies when he defines Gilson’s concept of ‘Christian philosophy’ and when he expressly affirms the fundamental possibility of separating philosophy and theology in Bonaventure; for his own presentation of the history of philosophy indicates that the so-called Augustinianism arises from the problem of the relation of philosophy and theology and that it is the result of a process of development in which this philosophy is actually being formed. . . . His own presentation of the history of this period . . . indicates that the real question in the great disputes of the thirteenth century was not simply a philosophical fight within an already existing philosophy. Rather it was a question of Christian philosophy and Christian wisdom as such. . . .The problem of Augustinianism and Aristotelianism is not a purely philosophical problem. It cannot be treated at all if we abstract from theology, and every presentation that attempts to do so overlooks the decisive point at issue.” Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 131. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 351 notion of Christian philosophy is at least as Bonaventurian as it is Thomist. Ratzinger mentions, in his book on Bonaventure, Gilson’s famously annoying lecture on the future of Scholasticism, in which he argued that Scholastic philosophy can only survive if, like the philosophy of the medieval doctors and saints, it needs theology like some fish need “warm water.”111 Two decades on, when Ratzinger tackled the ThomistFranciscan debate over whether theology is primarily a speculative or practical science, he finds with the Thomists, simply because God is and does before human theologians can act and do. But, he says, this does not mean Bonaventure’s insight can be disposed of. This is because the assumption that God, and thus the scriptural word of God, is the subject of theology that lies behind it: The writers of Holy Scripture speak . . . as men, and yet . . . in doing so, they are “theologoi,” those through whom God as subject, as the word that speaks itself, enters into history. What distinguishes Holy Scripture from all later theology is thus . . . safeguarded, but, at the same time, the Bible becomes the model of all theology. . . . In this way, Bonaventure achieved in his later works the synthesis he had sought in his earlier ones, where he had affirmed the ontological character of theology and thus the proper rank of the theoretical and yet had spoken . . . of the necessary self-transcendence of contemplation into the practice of the faith.112 A good theologian is not a career intellectualist, for “just as we cannot learn to swim without water, so we cannot learn theology without the spiritual praxis in which it lives.”113 Ratzinger’s response to the protest against the presence of metaphysics in theology is to take up a Bonaventurian, that is, Gilsonian, notion of philosophy as Christian wisdom. A Christian wisdom will relate philosophy to history. For instance, it will not think of Platonism as an ahistorical “essence,” but as a precise response to a historical and political crisis in the development of human thought about human nature.114 For Ratzinger “the whole question of the relation of faith and reason” is related to the issue of history. For it can hardly be disputed that as a consequence of the division between philosophy and theology established by the Thomists, a juxtaposition has gradually been established which no longer appears adequate.There 111 Etienne Gilson, “Historical Research and the Future of Scholasticism,” Modern Schoolman 29 (1951): 10. 112 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 321. 113 Ibid., 322. 114 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 77–78. 352 Francesca Aran Murphy is, and must be, a human reason in faith; yet conversely, every human reason is conditioned by the historical standpoint so that reason pure and simple does not exist.115 As Ratzinger notes, “the terminology established by St. Thomas” entailed that “philosophy and theology were distinguished as the study of the natural and the supernatural. . . .These distinctions received a particular sharpness in the modern era.” Even if the “distinction” was later presented “in a more radical manner than the texts themselves would justify,” one cannot go back to the thirteenth century or make the tradition just end there:“Once this distinction is drawn, the question inevitably arises: can philosophy and theology be brought into a methodological relationship?”116 The means of reconnection between nature and the supernatural that Ratzinger takes links up with a historical fact: Historically, philosophy has always responded to religion.This link can be surprising, not only because one may think of philosophy as timeless reasoning, but because Ratzinger himself can be as critical of religiosity as any Lutheran or Barthian. He constantly deems the innovations of Socrates and Plato as an “enlightenment” with respect to earlier religious and mythical thinking.117 Nonetheless, unless it wants to be ontologically empty, philosophy needs “a priori concepts”:“philosophy has always thrived on critical dialogue with . . . religious traditions.”“[R]eligious traditions” form “the starting points in its struggle to find the truth.”118 What calls for enlightened criticism in religion is the localism of myth, its inability to proclaim one universal God. This is where the philosophical impulse joins forces with the Revelation of the unique God of Israel: The assertion of a God who creates and redeems the entire world goes far beyond any individual religious community. . . . It is an assertion about reality. . . .The impact of this “God-thought” . . . is quite clear in the critique of other religions made by the prophets of Israel and the Wisdom literature.When the self-made gods are ridiculed and the one true God is placed in opposition to them, we see the same movement at work as we do in the pre-Socratic thinkers of the early Greek enlightenment. . . . The faith of Israel gives rise to a . . . claim whose universality is linked to its reasonability.119 115 Ratzinger, “Introductory Article and Chapter I,” 120. 116 Ratzinger, “Faith, Philosophy and Theology,” 353. 117 See, for instance, Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 327 and 339; and idem, Eschatology, 77–79.The deepest discussion is in Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2003, 2004), 82–83 and passim. 118 Ratzinger, “Faith, Philosophy and Theology,” 355. 119 Ibid., 355. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 353 When John calls Christ the Logos “he stands in the clear Wisdom tradition.”120 Although biblical theologians like Gerhard von Rad grasped the significance of biblical typology, it took him a while to admit that Scripture does not only proclaim history, but also creation.Von Rad arrived at this conclusion late in life, through the study of Old Testament parables and proverbs.121 Ratzinger uses the example of the parable to explain what Christian wisdom is. Jesus taught in parables not just because “faith reveals itself only in parables” but also because “the parable makes clear the core of reality itself.This is possible because reality itself is a parable. Hence, it is only by way of parable that the nature of the world and of man himself is made known to us.”122 Parables are not extrinsic to our natural or historical “experience of the world” for the parable . . . gives this experience its proper depth and reveals what is hidden in things themselves. Reality is self-transcendence, and when man is led to transcend it, he not only comprehends God but, for the first time, also understands reality and enables himself and creation to be what they were meant to be. Only because creation is parable can it become the word of parable.That is why the material of daily living can always lead beyond itself; that is why a history can take place in it that both transcends it and is profoundly conformable to it.123 Christian wisdom is historically instantiated because to be human is to be historical: Man is temporal as a traveler along the way of knowing and loving. . . . His specific temporality also derives from his relationality—from the fact that he becomes himself only in being with others and being toward others. Entering upon love, or . . . refusing love, binds one to another person and so to the temporality of that person, his “before” and “after.” The fabric of shared humanity is a fabric of shared temporality.124 120 Ibid., 359. 121 Gerhard von Rad began his defense of the reading of Christological typology in the Old Testament by remarking that typological thinking is present in all human thought, especially in proverbs and in poetry: “Typological Interpretation of the Old Testament,” in Essays on Old Testament Hermeneutics, ed. Claus Westerman, trans. James Luther Mays (Richmond,VA: John Knox Press, 1964).Von Rad elaborated on this at length in Wisdom in Israel, trans. James D. Martin (London: SCM, 1970, 1972). 122 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 344. 123 Ibid., 345, original emphasis. 124 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 183–84. Francesca Aran Murphy 354 This insight, spurred in part by Barth’s perception that we gain our humanity by how we are addressed and respond, leads into the question of whether “tradition takes place . . . as the growing insight, mediated by the Holy Spirit, into Revelation that has been given once and for all”: The question of the historicity of inspiration is “the crux of the difference between Catholic and Protestant theology in the question of tradition.”125 During the Second Vatican Council, both literal-minded Thomists and Protestants like Cullmann found it difficult to articulate the value of tradition because they ignored our deeper knowledge of the problem of historical understanding, which is no longer adequately expressed by the simple ideas of a given fact and its explanation, because the explanation, as the process of understanding, cannot be clearly separated from what is being understood.126 Bonaventure had made no such clean-cut distinction between Revelation and inspiration, text and interpreting mind: For him, Revelation is the ongoing deepening of our understanding of Scripture.127 Ratzinger carries this line of thought through by declaring that “subsequent history belongs intrinsically to the inner momentum of the text itself. . . . It does not . . . provide retrospective commentary on the text. Rather, through the appearing of the reality which was still to come, the full dimensions of the word carried by the text come to light.”128 Because Scripture becomes spiritually intelligible in history, the Gospel does not confront the Church as a self-enclosed Ding-an-Sich. Herein lies the . . . methodological error of trying to reconstruct the ipsissima vox Jesu as a yardstick for Church and New Testament alike. . . . Jesus’ message becomes intelligible for us through the echo effect it has created in history. In this echo, the intrinsic potential of that message, with its various strata and configurations, still resounds. Through its resonance, we learn more about the real than we shall ever do from free-floating critical reconstructions.129 The sense of “either/or”-ness upon which Protestant spirituality turns can be appropriated by Catholics as the real historicity of the human creature. But where, in Protestantism, the “either/or” is conceived as a decision and thus related to the future, for the Catholic, human history 125 Ratzinger, “Revelation Itself,” 179. 126 Ratzinger, “The Transmission of Divine Revelation,” 187–88. 127 Ratzinger, Bonaventure, 64–69. 128 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 42. 129 Ibid., 41. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 355 includes not only the present and future, but also the past. Barth both uses the philosophers and thinks philosophically for himself: He does not so much denigrate philosophy or reason as he underplays the consideration that reality “remembers” what God has done in it. Ratzinger claims that human time is “memoria-time,” time as recapitulated and made meaningful in memory.130 Barth believed that To be in the Church . . . is to be called with others by Jesus Christ.To act in the Church is to act in obedience to this call.This obedience to the call of Christ is faith. . . . Faith grasps the promise that we shall be led into all truth ( Jn 16:13). Faith knows God. Faith is the determination of human action by the being of the Church and therefore by Jesus Christ, by the gracious address of God to man.131 For Ratzinger, the ecclesiality of Christian faith entails that, as a “transhistorical subject,” a subject that is in but not of time, the “communio Ecclesiae . . . is the mediator between being and time.”132 This memory generates tradition, the creative ability to take history forward.Within the communal litany of the saints, the “eschatological question becomes the question of my own dying,” rather than “temporal expectation of the world’s end.” But “this is possible . . . because the individual has found shelter in a history filled with salvific energy.”133 The prerequisites for Ratzinger’s reply to Barth’s understanding of the Incarnation as the revelatory act of the Trinity were, first, his discovery of a similar pattern in Bonaventure, for whom “Christ is the medium distantiae, the defining center, in his Crucifixion,”134 and second, that he “in due course” became “sympathetic to the principal prophet of a renewed Christocentricity in Catholic theology: Hans Urs von Balthasar.”135 Von Balthasar’s work on Barth’s theology was one means through which Ratzinger learned that “for pursuing the dialogue with Protestant theology, Catholic theology requires that there be, despite all divisions and antitheses, a common theological motive”136 and that “Catholic theology must not . . . be afraid to learn from its partner.”137 The pre-Barthian Catholic understanding of the work of Christ was not really centered on 130 Ibid., 184. 131 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 17. 132 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 23. 133 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 11–12. 134 Nichols, The Thought of Benedict XVI, 63. 135 Ibid., 63–64. 136 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 180. 137 Ibid., 180–81. Francesca Aran Murphy 356 death. In Being and Time, Heidegger had summed up human historicity as a being toward death. Barth appropriated this historicizing of human “nature” into his Christocentric anthropology. For him, the human being is a being toward the eschatological act of God—Christ. Barth created an opening for others to enable philosophy to recapture its bonds with the deep religious desires of humanity, and thus with faith. Ratzinger affirms that for “human life, death is the only real question” and yet that, “we have also to reckon with the openness” of divine “Love for history.”138 Barth concurs. The critical difference between the two is the place of human philosophy in this “reckoning.” For the Thomists of Barth’s time the only dialogue possible with Barth was a “dialogue of the deaf ” (we need not pretend that the recent maneuver of pretending that Thomas was a Barthian is a better solution). Ratzinger draws on Bonaventure instead, because unlike Thomas the “saint . . . admits that there is a certain violence in reason which will not be harmonized with faith.”This is the violence of irreligious, technological rationality. But Bonaventure says that there is a question that emerges from another source: perhaps faith should be understood in terms of the love to which it gives its assent. . . .To love means wishing to know, and so the search for insight can be an inner drive towards love. . . .There is a link between love and truth, which is significant for both philosophy and theology.139 For the Swiss Calvinist, Revelation . . . does not differ from the person of Jesus Christ nor from the reconciliation accomplished in him. . . .When in the word Revelation we say “The Word was made flesh and dwelt among us” then we are saying something which can have only an inter-Trinitarian basis in the will of the Father and the sending of the Son and the Holy Spirit, in the eternal decree of the triune God, so that it can be established only as knowledge of God from God.140 Ratzinger modulates Barth’s programmatic forte :The “means of salvation history—the death and Resurrection of the Lord” is “truly present” in the ecclesial act of faith. This means, which is inseparably bound to the act of “faith in” . . . introduces us into the dynamic circle of Trinitarian love. . . . Because this creative love is . . . love as meaning and meaning as love, because it is 138 Ibid., 39; and idem, Eschatology, 190. 139 Ratzinger, “Faith, Philosophy and Theology,” 361. 140 Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, 119. Joseph Ratzinger and Protestant Theology 357 the creative reason of all reality, it cannot be reciprocated without logic, without thought and word. But because true reason makes itself known, not in the abstraction of thought but in the purification of the heart, it is linked to a way, the way followed by him of whom it may be said: He is the Logos. This way is death and resurrection; to the Trinitarian communio there corresponds the sacramentally real communio of a life lived in faith for which we are purified in the death and resurrection of conversion.141 Ratzinger complements Barth’s theological Christocentricity with a firm recognition that “in the man Jesus God has bound himself permanently to human history.”142 As he reads it, the “act of faith . . . is essentially an act of union”143 because “the real interdependence of all men and of all creation” entails that the end of history is not for any man . . . something which has ceased to concern him. . . .“The Body of Christ” means that all human beings are one organism, the destiny of the whole the proper destiny of each. . . . The decisive outcome of each person’s life is settled in death. . . . But his final place in the whole can be determined only when the total organism is complete, when the passio and actio of history have come to their end. And so the gathering together of the whole will be an act that leaves no person unaffected. Only at that juncture can the definitive general judgment take place, judging each man in terms of the whole and giving him that just place which he can receive only in conjunction with all the rest.144 Human history is the gestalt form of the Lord.“History is still real” after Christ, “it really continues and its reality is suffering.”145 The way in which Ratzinger applies a “renewed Christocentricity” to eschatology fills certain lacunae in Protestant and earlier Catholic thought. He understands the Last Things historically, by reference to the person of Christ. “Justification by works means that man wants to construct a little immortality of his own,”146 and hence, “Purgatory is understood in a properly Christian way when it is grasped Christologically, in terms of the Lord himself as the judging fire which transforms us to his own glorified body.”147 141 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 26–27. 142 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 187. 143 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 328–29. 144 Ratzinger, Eschatology, 190. 145 Ibid. 146 Ibid., 99. 147 Ibid., 229. Francesca Aran Murphy 358 It does not replace grace by works, but allows the former to achieve its full victory . . . as grace.What . . . saves is the full assent of faith. But in most of us, that basic option is buried under a good deal of wood, hay, and straw. . . . Man is the recipient of the divine mercy, yet this does not exonerate him from the need to be transformed. Encounter with the Lord is this transformation.148 Just as purgatory is not a “supra-worldly concentration camp,” so heaven is not a place, but Christ: One is in heaven when, and to the degree, that one is in Christ. . . . Heaven is thus primarily a personal reality. . . . Heaven, as our becoming one with Christ, takes on the nature of adoration. All cult prefigures it, and in it comes to completion. Christ is the temple of the final age; he is heaven, the new Jerusalem; he is the cultic space for God. . . .This is what the theological tradition calls the vision of God.149 N&V 148 Ibid. 231, original emphasis. 149 Ibid., 234. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 359–74 359 Benedict XVI on the Holy Images A IDAN N ICHOLS, OP Oxford University Oxford, England Introduction A POPE who is at once a theologian by métier and a man of wide personal culture is likely to address at some point or other the topic of holy images. For this topic exists at the intersection of two vital lines: the presentation of the economy of creation and redemption through divinely elected signs and the human practice that is visual art or—if the word “art” has acquired excessively virtuoso associations—then, at any rate, painterly craft. As Cardinal Ratzinger, Benedict XVI has addressed these issues from two perspectives that broadly correspond to my proposal of two (intersecting) “lines.” In his Christology, he considers holy images as a continuation of the divine presentation of salvation through the incarnate Word, Jesus Christ, who is the living Icon of God and his human Face—a Face the traits of which can still be captured iconographically, by a meta-empirical seeing, through visionary painting. In his study of the liturgy he takes holy images to belong with the way the Church, in her worshipping spaces, allows the divine signs issuing from Revelation to be themselves signaled and thus transmitted through human art. In the first case, the emphasis lies on the holiness of the image: It is continuous with the divine action. In the second case, the stress lies rather on the image-character of sacred art: It is a sign that is humanly constructed, though for a God-given purpose. We can call these two perspectives, then, Christological and liturgiological, respectively.While we may employ the two perspectives alternately in quick succession—as we shall see, Benedict does not keep them hermetically sealed from each other, the distinction between them is plain. Though the material content discussed in one or the other perspective Aidan Nichols, OP 360 will overlap, the formal entertainment of that content is proper to each. At the same time, as Ratzinger handles these matters, other major themes of philosophical and theological importance also make their appearance. The Christological Perspective The Christological perspective is well-evidenced in Ratzinger’s essay on “The Face of Christ in the Holy Scriptures,” which takes as its starting point the Johannine saying, “He who has seen me has seen the Father” ( Jn 14:9). Ratzinger underlines the Old Testament background of Jesus’ conversation with St. Philip in the immediate aftermath of the Last Supper Discourse in St. John’s Gospel. The primordial human longing to see God had taken the Old Testament form of “seeking the Face of God.” The disciples are men who seek the face of God.That is why they came across Jesus and followed him. Now Philip brings this seeking before the Lord and receives a surprising answer, in which the novelty of the New Testament—the new thing that is coming through Christ—seems gathered up as if in a crystal:Yes, man can see God.Whoever sees Christ sees Him.1 But just how are we to look at Christ in such a way that we can see the Father? Ratzinger refers us back to the earlier incident in the Fourth Gospel where pagan Greeks had approached Philip—himself from a strongly Hellenized region of Palestine—asking to see Jesus, to which the reply, from Jesus himself, is a riddling reference to the fruitfulness of his Passion ( Jn 12:24). The Hellenic world—indeed, the pagan world as a whole—will see Jesus (and through Jesus, the Father), but only via his Passion. The Passion is glorification, whereby he will come to them in the risen power of the Holy Spirit, and do so in such a manner that there is “a new seeing, which happens in faith.”2 Ratzinger emphasizes that this never leaves the Passion behind. “The seeing happens in discipleship. Discipleship is a life in that place where Jesus stands, and this place is the Passion. In it and no place other is his glorification a present reality.”3 In the pregnant saying of the Johannine Passion narrative, which finds here the fulfillment of a prophetic prediction (Zec 12:10),“They shall look on him whom they have pierced” ( Jn 19:37). Ratzinger admits that the Old Testament vocabulary of “the face of the Lord” does not in fact recur in St. John. But he holds stoutly nonetheless 1 Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus (Augsburg: Sankt Ulrich Verlag, 2003), 12. 2 Ibid., 13. 3 Ibid., 14. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 361 to a deep underlying continuity between that motif of the Hebrew Bible and Johannine thought. If that is disputed, then at least there is one Pauline text that can support his thesis for the New Testament more generally, since in Second Corinthians St. Paul makes the connection quite explicit: “It is the God who said, ‘Let light shine out of darkness’ who has shone in our hearts to give the light of the knowledge of the glory of God in the face of Christ” (4:6). Over a quarter of all uses of the word panim, “face,” in the Old Testament Scriptures refer to the divine face, rather than human (or angelic) countenances.That amounts to an astonishing total of one hundred texts. Ratzinger comments on the thought-provoking fact that this plethora of references to seeking God’s face issues from an aniconic religion. Were the divine face to be found embodied in a cult-object, this pervasive vocabulary would be understandable. But no. “The image is prohibited, yet the seeking of the face remains.”4 That is certainly curious.The divinity ceases to be objectified yet its face endures. Precisely as the One who must never be imaged, God can, it seems, be seen. The materialization of the divine in cult is abolished and yet its innermost direction emerges clearly as never before. Relation to the divine personality:That is what the Old Testament holds out to us, and vividly so, in this paradoxical concatenation.5 Ratzinger finds it unsurprising that, as biblically derived discourse mutates linguistically in its passage through Greek to Latin, panim becomes in the first prosopon and then, in the second, persona. The face brings us to the mystery of the person. God is ein uns zugewandtes Wesen, an “Essence turned toward us.” And Ratzinger hints strongly that the notion of sensuous perception that “face” suggests ought not to be eliminated—just as it was not so eliminated for Israel’s experience of the face of the Lord in the rich cultus of the Jerusalem Temple (compare Ps 24:6 and the “liturgical calendars” of Ex 23, Ex 34, and Deut 16). That is so even if the prophets and the psalmists alike emphasize the moral and spiritual preconditions of such seeing in right living and purity of heart— and even if a key text for his account, the beautiful fragment that is Psalm 17:15b, the seeing in question is eschatological, lying beyond our historical existence: “[W]hen I awake, I shall be satisfied with beholding thy form.” For other texts again (for example, Ps 4:7b), the “light” of God’s face means life for Israelites here and now. In any or all of these senses, 4 Ibid., 16. 5 Ratzinger points out there is an analogy here with Old Testament talk of the “Name” of God, referring his readers to his Einführung in das Christentum, 2nd ed. (Munich: Kösel, 2000), 122–24. Aidan Nichols, OP 362 for God to “hide” his face is penalization.The deprivation of God is the contrary of flourishing; it is tiefstes Unheil, “deepest woe.”6 The Pauline passage from Second Corinthians, in which Ratzinger found a safe anchor for his claim to New Testament relevance for this Old Testament material, invokes a more particular comparison: between Moses and Christ. In the dramatic encounter of Moses and the Lord that follows the deviant worship of the Golden Calf in Exodus 32, we are told, seemingly contradictorily, that Moses “spoke with the Lord face to face” (33:11), and yet was warned by God, “You cannot see my face, for man shall not see me and live” (33:20), a statement whose opening prohibition is solemnly repeated three verses later. The New Testament writers, so Ratzinger explains, find here a significant ambiguity. Putting together various disparate passages from the proto-martyr Stephen’s speech to the Sanhedrin in the Book of Acts, the Letter to the Galatians (at 3:13) and the First Epistle of St. John (at 2:1), Ratzinger concludes that the Son stands always face to face before the Father.“He could see the Face of God and on his face is the glory of God visible for us.”7 If Moses were told only the Lord’s “back” might be seen, for St. Gregory of Nyssa in his Life of Moses that is because we can only encounter God when we follow “behind” in the manner of disciples. Ratzinger makes this more concrete: Gregory should have written “in the manner of disciples of Jesus.”8 What is new about the New Covenant in this regard is not new themes, but a new person: Jesus, the face of God for us. At this juncture one might say that what Ratzinger is carrying out may usefully be called, in the words of Kevin Mongrain about Balthasarian thought, an “Irenaean retrieval.”9 According to a key expression of St. Irenaeus’s Adversus haereses, the Son is the visibility of the Father. What we have heard so far in “The Face of Christ in the Holy Scriptures” is a biblically informed defense of this claim.And Ratzinger’s summary conclusion on the difference the New Testament makes to the Old—“not new themes, but a new person”—seems a verbal reminiscence from book 4 of Irenaeus’s great treatise:“Know that he brought all novelty by bringing himself who had been announced.”10 Out of this awareness, writes Ratzinger, there arose the art of the icon, which cannot of course claim to be the end of our quest for the face of 6 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 22. 7 Ibid., 24. 8 Ibid., 25, with reference to Gregory of Nyssa, De vita Moysis (PG 44, 408D). 9 K. Mongrain, The Systematic Theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar.An Irenaean Retrieval (New York: Crossroad, 2002). 10 Irenaeus, Adversus haereses, IV, 34, 1. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 363 God, not even when the icons concerned are miraculous icons, the acheiropoeitai or images “not made by hands.”11 The crucial question to emerge from the iconoclast dispute for Ratzinger is, Do the icons “carry the dynamic of transcendence”? Can they “point beyond themselves”? Are they an “invitation that brings us onto the [right] road in the search for the Lord’s face”?12 If so, they lead us further on the path of discipleship which in this life has no end. The icons are seen justly only when they are seen in terms of this eschatological aim.The love of neighbor and the Eucharistic cultus furnish us with anticipations of the Kingdom we hope for. But we need the holy icons to remind us that the “true healing and the true repletion” will be looking on God’s face.13 The Christological perspective—readily sanctioned by a work to which Ratzinger has elsewhere made laudatory reference, Christoph von Schönborn’s L’Icône du Christ—has the possible disadvantage of concentrating an account of the origin and meaning of the cult of icons on the central Figure of Christianity, to the detriment of the wide iconographic range of early Christian art—unless, that is, the additional themes (Mariological, hagiological, sacramental, and the like) are treated as aspects of a wider Christological constellation.14 Where, however, Ratzinger differs from his fellow cardinal lies in the way he underscores the subjective, rather than objective, significance of iconic making and perception. Whereas Schönborn emphasizes the dogmatic foundations of the icon in the Greek patristic Christology of dual nature and single hypostasis, Ratzinger stresses the transformed subjectivity that alone can allow us to grasp and profit by the new Image of God in Jesus Christ. In Balthasarian terms, within the unity of the entire perceived Gestalt, always both objective and subjective together, it is the “subjective evidence” (which is far from “subjective” in any pejorative, self-referential sense of that word) he prefers, in this context, to explore. Ratzinger returned to the topic—still in what I am calling the “Christological perspective”—in an essay titled “Wounded by the Arrow of the Beautiful: the Cross and the New ‘Esthetic’ of Faith,” which, among other things, shows his debt to the theological aesthetics of Hans Urs von Balthasar just mentioned. He begins from the liturgical use of Psalm 45, the Epithalamion psalm for the marriage of an Israelite king, but applied in the Lenten Psalter to the nuptial relation of Christ and the Church. The 11 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 26. 12 Ibid. 13 Ibid., 29. 14 C. von Schönborn, O.P., L’Icône du Christ. Fondements théologiques élaborés entre le Ier et le IIe Concile de Nicée (325–787), 2nd ed. (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires, 1976). 364 Aidan Nichols, OP acclamation “You are the fairest of men and graciousness is poured upon your lips” (v. 3) is not, so Ratzinger points out, simply an act of praise of the outer loveliness of the Redeemer. For what appears on his “lips” is “the inner beauty of his word, the splendor of his message.” What “appears” in him is, accordingly, “the splendor of truth, the splendor of God Himself, which carries us away, which so to say inflicts on us the wound of love.” This is the “holy eros” whereby in and with the Church we can respond to the love that calls us.15 But in Holy Week the same psalm, when used in the liturgy, is qualified by juxtaposition with an antiphon that radically changes its sense. The antiphon is drawn from the Servant Songs of the Book of Isaiah: “He had no form or comeliness that we should look at him . . . ” (53:2).The contrast cannot but strike the attentive worshipper.16 The fact to which it draws attention certainly struck one attentive reader: Augustine of Hippo, who concluded from the marring of the Passion, itself the most admirable of events, that in the events of the Great Week the entire Hellenic aesthetic is Christologically called in question. Both Old Testament texts, applied to Christ, are breathed out by the same Spirit. Their contrasting sounds, which lack all audible harmony (so prized by the Greeks), are what place before us the true beauty. The suffering Christ tells us that “the beauty of truth includes wounding, pain, and even the dark mystery of death itself.”17 Actually, the Greeks were not without some distant surmise of this. In the Phaedros Plato showed his awareness that beauty has the power to draw us out of our contentment with the everyday, and by unsettling us makes us uncomfortable. Ratzinger goes so far as to say, on Plato’s behalf, that “the arrow of longing strikes man, wounds him, and in this way gives him wings and draws him upward.”18 In his treatise Life in Christ, the Byzantine theologian Nicholas Cabasilas baptizes this thought. People who have a longing that outstrips their nature are those “the Bridegroom has wounded; he has dispatched to their eyes a ray of his beauty.”19 That is how God awakens them to their highest destiny. Ratzinger denies that all this is superficial aestheticism, much less irrationality.“Beauty is knowledge—yes, a higher kind of knowledge, because 15 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 31. 16 The alternation of unlovely and lovely in the Christusbild of the Fathers was noted in A. Grillmeier, S.J., “Die Herrlichkeit Gottes auf dem Antlitz Jesu Christi,” in idem, Mit ihm und in ihm. Christologische Forschungen und Perspektiven (Freiburg: Basel,Wien, 1975), 19–75, but without the use of Ps 45. 17 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 32–33. 18 Ibid., 33. 19 Nicholas Cabasilas, Das Buch vom Leben in Christus, 3rd ed. (Einsiedeln: Johannes, 1991; in English Life in Christ), 79. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 365 it brings home to man the full magnitude of truth.”20 Contrasting knowledge through true report with knowledge through direct experience of things, Cabasilas, unsurprisingly, privileges the latter, which is a being touched by reality, and in the case of the Gospel, by the personal presence of Christ himself. In Ratzinger’s words: “[B]eing overwhelmed by the beauty of Christ is a more real and profound kind of knowledge than would be mere rational deduction.”21 Through the impact of such beauty, “reason is freed from its stupor, Betäubung, and made capable of action.”22 Ratzinger warns that this should not be taken to devalue careful theological reflection.Yet the latter is of secondary importance compared with the encounter of the heart with beauty.This Ratzinger takes to be the central claim of Hans Urs von Balthasar in the opening volume of his theological aesthetics.23 Ratzinger regrets that so little response has been made to this central claim, not only in dogmatics but also in pastoralia—for the Church public, and the unevangelized too for that matter, need to meet the Lord in his beauty. People think theological reason is a wax nose; one can make of it any shape one likes. Being wounded by the Lord’s beauty gives one a measuring rod for judgments in matters of discourse about revelation, and the capacity to weigh arguments in contemporary theology and, by this criterion, find them, if need be, wanting. In the art of the Byzantine icon, in the creations of the Romanesque and Gothic periods, one finds oneself vis-à-vis what the palpable power of the beautiful truth of God has made present in the inspiration of the artist. The artist has rendered the reality he experienced something in which we too can partake. This will make demands on us. Ratzinger seconds the proposal of the Russian Orthodox lay theologian Paul Evdokimov that the icon calls for a “fast of seeing,” a going beyond ordinary sense perception, the learning through prayer and asceticism of a “new, deeper seeing,” since what shines through the sensuous matrix is the radiance of divine glory.24 What can be said so confidently of the icon can be affirmed of all “the great images of Christian art.”The beauty our faith has generated forms its chief apologia—along with the reality of the saints.These are our greatest treasures. 20 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 34. 21 Ibid., 35. 22 Ibid., 37. 23 H. U. von Balthasar, Herrlichkeit. Eine theologische Ästhetik. I. Schau der Gestalt (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1961). 24 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 36–37. Cf P. Evdokimov, L’Art de l’icône. Théologie de la beauté (Paris: Desclée Brouwer, 1970), 153–65. 366 Aidan Nichols, OP Some will say, beauty may provide positive experiences in spots of time, but in the long run reality is more likely to be largely wretched. After Auschwitz who can write lyric poetry? For Ratzinger that objection is to “Apollo,” to the Hellenic aesthetic of beautiful harmony, not to the aesthetic embodied in the glory of the Cross, the thorn-crowned beauty of Christ for which the Shroud of Turin may stand as symbol.This is the beauty of the charity that loved us to the end. Here Ratzinger returns to the starting point of the Epithalamion psalm and its fruitful liturgical ambiguity. The icon of the Crucified liberates us from the prison-house of believing the “lie” that would make the denial of beauty’s ultimacy the last word.The splendid Passion likewise frees us from that other lie offered us by an aesthetic of hedonistic possession, whose artists would content us with the here and now, stifling rather than stimulating the movement of transcendence to go beyond. When in Dostoevsky we hear that beauty will save the world, we can too easily forget that the beauty concerned is specifically the “redemptive beauty of Christ.”25 The Liturgiological Perspective When we turn from the primarily Christological to the chiefly liturgiological perspective, we discover that Ratzinger’s liturgical iconology remains distinctly Christocentric, just as his Christological iconology bears significant reference to the liturgy—whether Jewish, for the cultic context of seeking God’s face, or Christian, as in the stimulus he found to such reflection in the use by the Roman Office of the theme of the marred splendor of Jesus, the suffering King. He sets out from where we would normally expect a theology of images to begin—from the issue of Israelite aniconicism, the anti-iconic commandments in the Hebrew Bible. He points out how, in the making of the golden cherubim to flank the Tabernacle’s mercy seat (Ex 25:22), the Book of Exodus transgresses the very command it elsewhere (Ex 20:4) asserts. I note that to speak here, as he does, of an “exception,” Ausnahme, assumes the prohibition of the Decalogue to strike unconditionally at all graven images and not simply those intended to represent the divine.26 Be that as it may, by using philosophical dialectic, he coun25 Ratzinger, Unterwegs zu Jesus Christus, 40. 26 See the recent discussions in O. Keel and C. Uehlinger, Gods, Goddesses and Images of God in Ancient Israel (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1998);T. N. D. Mettinger, No Graven Image? Israelite Aniconicism in Its Ancient Near Eastern Context (Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell, 1995).There is a substantial review article prompted by the latter study:T. J. Lewis, “Divine Images and Aniconism in Ancient Israel,” Journal of the American Oriental Society 118 (1998): 36–53. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 367 ters that to render the guardians of the divine mystery visible is precisely to underline the invisibility of the mystery itself.27 The question of the original intent of the anti-iconic commandment is raised again when Ratzinger calls the thoroughgoing aniconicism of rabbis contemporary with the high patristic era a “radical” interpretation of the Torah, in contrast to the more moderate understanding that permitted the rich synagogue art of Dura-Europos, our fullest surviving example of a sacral figurative art in the synagogues of the early centuries of the common era. The frescoes of the Dura synagogue come with no handy manual of textual interpretation. Ratzinger offers a “high” theology of these paintings, accommodating them to the Jewish haggadah of the period as its visual equivalent. In so doing he produces a Jewish counterpart for the way the Second Council of Nicaea (the seventh ecumenical council) would treat the icons as the visual counterpart to the New Testament Scriptures—themselves, of course, a “reading” of the Scriptures of the Israel of old.The representations of Old Testament scenes on the walls of the Dura synagogue are not just “images of past events.” Rather, they participate in the liturgical re-presentation of the original happenings. That is an ontological possibility since those happenings were not merely moments in human development but “God’s action in time.”28 The images in the Christian catacombs, so Ratzinger holds, take this sort of synagogue art into a “new kind of presence.” That “presence” is “new” because it depends on the Incarnation and the inauguration of the sacramental era.And it is really a “presence” because the biblical events in which, through sacred art, Christians were sharing are now inserted into the reality of the risen Lord as he masters time through his exaltation to the Father’s side. It is from there that he dispenses his life-giving sacraments—in catacomb art so often typologically indicated—via their human ministers in the Church. This prise de position enables Ratzinger to establish a distinctive theology of the image, which he does by treating all Christian images as being in some way Easter-oriented, ordered to the Session when Christ receives universal Lordship. He can make good his claim that early Christian art, whatever its limitations of technique, always furnishes “images of hope,” Hoffnungsbilder, if the entire iconology of the Church consists in fact of Auferstehungsbilder, “images of the Resurrection.”29 27 Ratzinger, Der Geist der Liturgie. Eine Einführung (Freiburg:Verlag Herder, 2000), 99. 28 Ibid., 100. 29 Ibid., 101. Aidan Nichols, OP 368 A more obvious Christological framework for the discussion of sacred art is surely that provided by the Incarnation itself—which would, no doubt, include a reference to the Resurrection mystery but not necessarily keep its focus there.30 In fact, Ratzinger cannot do without some more pervasive appeal to the sheer entry of the Logos into the sensuous realm—prescinding, then, from the Word’s eventual destiny in the return, his humanity glorified, to the Father. The early painterly or sculptural images of Christ as teacher, Christ as shepherd, speak of the wisdom of the Logos now entering the human world, and his pastoral guardianship of the human creation that he carries “home” on his shoulders, the Church of Jews and Gentiles.31 One reason for Ratzinger’s anxiety to deflect the iconological center to the Resurrection soon becomes plain. It is those excessive claims for the continuity of the image with the Incarnation made in the context of images believed to be “not made by human hands.”The appearance of the acheiropoeitai—Ratzinger thinks especially of the Cappadocian image called the Camuliana and of the mandylion of Edessa whose (controversial) identification with the Shroud of Turin he seems to favor—led the faithful to ascribe to (at any rate, certain) images, a capacity to yield communion with the Savior, and indeed the gift of his real presence, thus rendering the holy images competitors and rivals of the Eucharistic mysteries themselves. After all, the affinity in causal origination between the achieropoeitai and the Babe of Bethlehem was, to say the least, striking. These “true” icons no more had a human artist as their author than the Word incarnate himself had a human father as his progenitor. Ratzinger thinks that images modeled on the acheiropoeitai—whose supernatural provenance, incidentally, he nowhere denies—became the very “midpoint of the entire canon of images,” die Mitte der Bilderkanon.32 He sees here a twofold danger: that icons could usurp the role of sacraments, and that they might be taken as loci of direct vision of God here and now. In the circumstances the Iconoclast controversy might be called a cruel necessity. Ratzinger recognizes the role of non-theological factors in the official adoption by the Isaurian dynasty of Iconoclasm (though where a theological position is concerned every other consideration necessarily takes on a theological coloring). Essentially, however, the crisis enabled the Byzantine church to grasp the nature of the icon as a vehicle for evangelical faith by teasing out the notion of a new kind of looking, 30 See for instance, A. Nichols, O.P., The Art of God Incarnate:Theology and Image in Christian Tradition (London: Darton, Longman, and Todd, 1980). 31 Ratzinger, Der Geist der Liturgie, 102. 32 Ibid., 103. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 369 a looking that penetrates through the sensuous to the Christological center of the supersensuous realm beyond. In Ratzingerian terms, the Iconoclast dispute enabled the Church to grasp the Resurrection character of all Christian images. “The icon wants to draw us onto an inner path, the path ‘to the East,” ’ toward the Christ who will return.”33 As my use of the neologism “Ratzingerian” suggests, this account reproduces neither the language of the dogmatic definition of Nicaea II, nor that of the Iconophile fathers who worked for the vindication of the icons.34 It is a contemporary theological re-presentation, a kind of Roman Catholic equivalent to the Eastern Orthodox theology of the icon that flourished in Russian Orthodoxy in the late nineteenth century (for Russia itself) and the early twentieth century (for the Russian diaspora in the West). In particular, echoing the iconological essays founded on a Christological perspective described earlier, Ratzinger does not hide his admiration for Evdokimov’s theology of the icon, which is cited liberally in Der Geist der Liturgie. Whereas in the neo-Orthodox appropriation of the patristic sources (not least for Evdokimov), the icon is dependent—ontologically and epistemologically—on the paradigmatic moment of Christ’s Transfiguration as reiterated references to the “Light of Thabor” make plain, for Ratzinger the key mystery in which to see the icon is the Resurrection. And yet the manner of his appeal to the Easter event is entirely Evdokimovian in feel. In both cases the crucial consideration is the “unity of creation, Christology and eschatology,”35 the coincidence of the light of the “first” day and the light of the “eighth” day in the illuminated countenances of Christ and his saints. Both Evdokimov and Ratzinger are suspicious of an excessively or unilaterally apophatic theology.The radiance of God streaming forth from the glorified form of the Easter Jesus is—in a phrase of Evdokimov’s adopted by Ratzinger—the “apophatic ‘Yes,’ ” ein apophatisches Ja.36 The reason Ratzinger prefers, in the liturgiological perspective, a Resurrection-centered iconology to an Incarnation-centered one, is not only that it fits better his wider emphasis on the eschatological orientation of 33 Ibid., 105. 34 A. Nichols, O.P.,“The Horos of Nicaea II: A Theological Evaluation,” Annuarium Historiae Conciliorum 20 (1988): 171–81. 35 Ratzinger, Der Geist der Liturgie, 107. 36 Ibid., 106. On Evdokimov, see P. C. Dinh Phan, Culture and Eschatology:The Icono- graohical Vision of Paul Evdokimov (Berne: Peter Lang Pub Inc, 1985). I have provided a brief entrée in my essay, “Paul Evdokimov and Eschatology,” in A. Nichols, O.P., Light from the East:Authors and Themes in Eastern Orthodoxy (London: Sheed and Ward, 1995), 194–204. 370 Aidan Nichols, OP the liturgy itself. It is also because through that very congruence we are able to discern the peculiar pertinence of a Paschal iconology to the ultimate goal of the Incarnation, which is not to draw the Logos down here to where we are but to take us up with him to his home. It is at “human ascent” that “divine descent” aims. Of course, to maintain continuity with the theological doctrine of the image offered in the Christological perspective, we shall have to remind the reader that the Resurrection is precisely the Resurrection of the Crucified. Ratzinger makes the same point the other way round when he says of even the most anguished Late Gothic images of the Passion that, by finding and communicating consolation even in such horror, they “carry within them the message of the Resurrection.”37 That doctrinal suture forms part of an interesting analytic survey of the chief periods of Western Christian art—issuing in some prescriptions for the future. Ratzinger regards the Romanesque as, despite its emphasis on sculpture, Latin Byzantinism. He considers that Early and High Gothic art, owing to its admirable fidelity to the unity of the Testaments, reproduces much in the ethos of Eastern Christian iconography even if, with the relativization of Christian Platonism in the high medieval West, salvation history now strikes people rather as “Historie” than as “Sakrament.”38 We have seen how he deals with the often agonized Passion paintings of the Late Gothic period, maintaining by a bold inversion of more conventional interpretations, that these are covertly Paschal images, since only by tacit reference to the Resurrection can ghastliness console. It is curious that he does not mention the well-documented fact that the practice of depicting the dead Christ on the Cross is a tenth-century Byzantine innovation subsequently received in the West through early Franciscanism. (The making in Byzantium of images of the Christus patiens—showing the Crucified with eyes closed, head sagging to one side—figured among the charges against the church of Constantinople brought there in 1054 by the papal legate Humbert of Silva Candida.) Ratzinger offers a glowing testimonial to medieval glass, the “iconostasis of the West,” where the church walls, in interplay with the sun, become an image sequence in their own right. As a Bavarian Catholic, he naturally defends the Baroque at least in its “best” forms, which he describes as a visual equivalent to the jubilation of a melismatic alleluia from the Latin chant. His coldest comments are reserved for the Renaissance, in which he joins hands not only with modern Eastern Orthodox critics but with also internal dissenters in the 37 Ratzinger, Der Geist der Liturgie, 110. 38 Ibid., 109. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 371 Western tradition. Not for nothing did the nearest English Victorian equivalent to the Nazarene school call itself the “Pre-Raphaelite Brotherhood.” Ratzinger excoriates the Church art of the Renaissance. It made no proper distinction between the world of meaning of the Gospels and that of ancient myths. It excluded fear of sin and the pain of the Cross. It pronounced an apotheosis of beauty for its own sake. It is curious, then, that at the first synod of bishops at which he presided as pope, namely the Synod on the Holy Eucharist, which met at Rome in October 2005, Ratzinger arranged for an image from the art of Raphael, the Disputation on the Sacrament, to be projected on a large screen above the presider’s table in the synod aula. He likewise commissioned the American-born, Florence-based art historian Father Timothy Verdon to provide an authoritative commentary on the painting in L’Osservatore Romano for October 12, 2005. Though the painting appears to confirm Ratzinger’s strictures on Renaissance art (notably, it presents its Eucharistic subject in parallel with a companion painting on a patently pagan theme, The School of Athens), Verdon’s commentary rescues it from the theological dumping ground to which, prematurely, it might have been consigned.Verdon argues that the principal message of Disputation on the Sacrament concerns eschatology anticipated by the liturgy—absolutely in line, then, with Ratzinger’s own theology of the image.The center of this fresco, after all, is the glorified Christ displaying his wounds—a reminder of the general judgment (compare Apocalypse 1:7), with, below him, the dove of the Holy Spirit fluttering above the Eucharistic altar and the Host to whose conversion from bread to the Body of the Lord the Spirit’s work is crucial. (Verdon thinks Raphael intended here an irenic reference to the Greek theology of the Mass, not long previously adumbrated at the abortive reunion Council of Florence.) Even the pagan companion piece contributes to the full effect of this image of the Church gathered in the presence of the Trinity in Eucharistic adoration. Raphael, so Verdon argues, wished to emphasize the intellectual fascination the Eucharistic mystery has aroused.The Christian doctors shown in the one painting are no less animated in their search for truth than are the pagan philosophers portrayed in the other, while the latter have laid some vital conceptual foundations for the work of the former.When the two paintings are seen together, as was intended, they show how even the pagans share in the Church as unwitting co-travelers in her pilgrimage to God. Evidently, here is one Renaissance image that could be taken to embody, rather than traduce, the prescriptions for sacred art that Ratzinger offers. How in his own conclusion does he sum them up? Briskly. First, iconoclasm is not a Christian option: It is tacit denial of the Incarnation 372 Aidan Nichols, OP of God. Second, the principal topic of sacred art (that is, a doctrinally informed art capable of serving as a monument of Tradition) is the salvation history of the two Testaments, seen as ordered to “the day of the Resurrection and the Second Coming” of Christ. That by no means excludes as a secondary topic the saints, since they are corporately or individually an “unfolding of the history of Jesus Christ.”39 Third, the images qua sacred art are essentially connected to the sacramental liturgy, which is the enduring visibility of the mystery of Christ on earth. That in turn means the center of iconography is Jesus Christ in the unity of his Passion and Resurrection—since this is the center of the liturgy itself. Ratzinger reiterates his claim that all images must be in some way images of Easter— hinting at the Christ who suffered, rose, will come again, and now reigns hiddenly in and over time. Fourth, the holy images are born of contemplation and issue in contemplation. The eyes of faith they require—and inspire—are the eyes of the Church herself, the primary subject of Christian vision. Fifth and finally, the Church of the West must make her own the common dogmatic formulation owed in practice, at the seventh ecumenical council, to the Church of the East.The theology of the icon proposed at the council is absolutely normative—even if stylistically a variety of iconographic manners may be compatible with its affirmations. Conclusion Pope Benedict is to be lauded for the rapid way in which, on assuming the office of bishop of Rome, he sought to put into effect his high view of the place of holy images in Christian catechesis and mystagogy. The fourteen sacred images included in the Compendium of the Catechism of the Catholic Church, presented by Benedict XVI on June 28, 2005, were, the pope insisted, not merely illustrations but an integral part of the new text. Each image receives a detailed commentary in the Compendium with generous citations from the Bible and the Fathers of the Church.The new pope had learned from the fate of the 1992 Catechism issued by his predecessor, John Paul II, whose far more modest total of illustrations (here probably the word was apt) suffered the indignity of mutilation, replacement, or elimination in some translations. For the Compendium, all translations must reproduce the holy images exactly, and in the position indicated. As patriarch of the West, Benedict XVI has the right and duty to act as overseer of the iconographic patrimony of the Latin Church. Writing as Cardinal Ratzinger, he was correct to draw attention to the continuing importance of the Second Council of Nicaea for Catholics of the West as 39 Ibid., 113. Benedict XVI on the Holy Images 373 well as of the East. His statement that its theology of the image is normative sits rather oddly, however, with a certain lack of zeal in investigating that theology in its historical context.The dogmatic definition of Nicaea II and the theological doctrine of the iconophile Fathers are not the same, after all, as the neo-Orthodox theology produced by Russian devotees of the art of the icon, however gifted, in the modern period. Actually, I think Ratzinger might have gone further and declared Byzantine practice (and not simply Greek conciliar thinking) to enjoy a normative significance likewise.40 The Byzantine church is the only ritual church in Christendom to have worked out with full liturgical and dogmatic coherence an iconographic scheme for the decoration of church interiors, the setting of the Eucharistic action.That alone grants it a special status that could usefully act as a criterion for the re-conceiving of iconographic schemes in a Latin Catholicism too often haphazard or, more recently, minimalistic in this respect.The Byzantine is, furthermore, the only church whose art shows so consistently (albeit not entirely consistently) a “Paschal aesthetic” in the stylistic manner iconographers employ, combining austere Good Friday and lavish Easter Sunday qualities in a unity of asceticism and salvific fullness. Latins, and other Easterners, would do well to note. Meanwhile, we can take courage and consolation from the magnificent words Benedict used at the ceremonial presentation of that compendium of the Church’s faith, when he declared: Image and word illuminate one another in turn. Art always “speaks,” at least implicitly, of the divine, of the infinite beauty of God, which finds its reflection in the icon par excellence: Christ the Lord, the image of the invisible God. Sacred images, with their beauty, are also heralds of the Gospel and express the splendor of Catholic truth, showing the supreme harmony between the good and the beautiful, between the via veritatis [way of truth] and the via pulchritudinis [way of beauty]. While they give witness to the age-old and prolific tradition of Christian art, they encourage all, both believers and non-believers, to discover and contemplate the inexhaustible wonder of the mystery of redemption, continually providing a new impulse for the lively process of its inculN&V turation in time.41 40 A. Nichols, O.P., “On Baptising the Visual Arts: A Friar’s Meditation on Art,” in idem, Scribe of the Kingdom. Essays on Theology and Culture, vol. 2 (London: Sheed and Ward, 1994), 183–96. 41 Pope Benedict, speech upon presentation of the Compendium of the Catechism of the Catholic Church ( June 28, 2005), n. 5.“Occasione publicae exhibitionis Compendii Catechismi Catholicae,” Acta Apostolicae Sedis XCVII, 6–7 (2005), 829. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 375–402 375 Reflections on Deus Caritas Est A Tour Through the Casbah M ICHAEL S HERWIN, OP University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland T RAVELERS TO Algeria have long been captivated by the narrow streets and exotic inhabitants of the ancient district in the heart of Algiers known as the Casbah, a word synonymous with mystery.1 Those who study the nature of love enter a similarly ancient and exotic inner fortress: the Casbah of human culture, a place where the attentive traveler encounters all the varied realities that commonly bear the name of love. In his brief encyclical, Pope Benedict does not explore all the twisted lanes of love’s topography. Instead, he introduces its essential features. Benedict is an experienced guide who chooses the points of interest with care.2 He traces his itinerary by means of the questions he asks, explicitly posing twelve of them (six in each of the encyclical’s two parts). It is the answer he gives, however, to an unexpressed thirteenth question—Why write an encyclical on charity?—that reveals the encyclical’s particular relevance for Christians today. Indeed, in relation to the pope’s implied question, the experience of Algeria offers more than a mere metaphor for love. It can serve to illustrate the pope’s primary concern. Specifically, the witness of the Trappist monks of Tibhirine, who were martyred during Algeria’s most recent civil war, embodies Benedict’s conception of Christian love. This essay will consider the pope’s questions and sketch the theology of charity he develops in answer to them. It will then offer in 1 An earlier version of this essay was delivered as the Charles Cardinal Journet Lecture, April 7, 2006, at Ave Maria University, Naples, Florida. 2 See, for example, his encyclopedia article on the history of love: Joseph Ratzinger, “Liebe: III. Geschichte der Theologie der Liebe,” in Lexikon für Theologie und Kirche, vol. 6, eds. Josef Höfer and Karl Rahner (Freiburg: Herder, 1961), 1032–36. Michael Sherwin, OP 376 conclusion the example of Algeria’s martyred monks as a model of the charity Pope Benedict is calling us to live. I The First Question: Love’s Plurality The pope begins his exploration of charity by posing the age-old question of love’s plurality.We speak of loving God and of loving our neighbor. There is romantic love and also the physical act of “making love.” People even speak of loving their dogs or a horse or a good glass of wine. In light of this plurality, Benedict asks:“[A]re all these forms of love basically one, so that love, in its many and varied manifestations, is ultimately a single reality, or are we merely using the same word to designate totally different realities?”3 Josef Pieper calls this question the “true difficulty” confronting the student of love.4 The pope will subsequently answer his first question on the side of unity, discerning a single reality underlying all our loves.5 Before doing so, however, Benedict focuses on two types of love, employing the Greek terms eros and agape to distinguish them.This narrowing of focus is justified because these loves seem to signify opposite extremes.6 Indeed, some authors even present them as mutually exclusive.7 Eros signifies the passive aspect of love, which is proper to romantic love and is conveyed by such expressions as “falling in love” or being “love sick.” It is powerfully experienced in the “love between man and woman which is neither planned nor willed, but somehow imposes itself upon human beings.”8 Agape, on the other hand, expresses the active aspect of love proper to the biblical conception of love and conveyed in such expressions as “love seeks not its own” (1 Cor 13:5).While eros is a desire to possess the other, agape is a concern for the other that seeks the other’s good even to the point of renunciation and self-sacrifice. Although some accuse Catholi3 Deus Caritas Est, no. 2. 4 Josef Pieper, Faith, Hope and Love (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1997), 145. In the early sections of Deus Caritas Est, the pope follows Pieper’s analysis closely. 5 Deus Caritas Est, no. 8. 6 Josef Pieper explains his own focus on eros and agape in words that Pope Bene- dict could have used to explain his similar focus on them:“Eros and agape remain more important, as the words that with presumably mutually exclusive intent rally the sides and determine the character of the philosophical and theological disputation in which we mean to intervene vigorously in the course of the following pages.” Pieper, Faith, Hope and Love, 156–57. 7 Anders Nygren, Agape and Eros (London: SPCK, 1953), 51–52. 8 Deus Caritas Est, no. 3. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 377 cism of corrupting biblical agape by mixing it with pagan eros, Benedict first addresses the opposite critique: that Christianity denigrates and suppresses eros.This leads Benedict, even before he has answered his first question concerning love’s plurality, to ask another. The Second Question: Christianity’s Attitude Toward Eros Pope Benedict cites Friedrich Nietzsche’s aphorism that “Christianity gave Eros poison to drink—but he did not die of it. He degenerated into a vice.”9 The pope then asks,“But is this the case? Did Christianity really destroy eros?”10 To answer this question he turns to the pagan experience of eros, which enables him to clarify further the distinction between eros and agape. Although the Greeks recognized the presence of eros in the passionate love between a man and a woman, they never reduced eros merely to sex.11 They regarded it as a phenomenon similar in its effects to intoxication and as a reaction provoked by the beauty and goodness of the beloved. Eros draws the lover out of himself toward union with the beloved and ultimately toward union with the divine—toward the source of the beloved’s beauty and goodness. The promise of eros, therefore, is happiness through union with the divine. It is the love that inspires the poet to search for his ideal of beauty, and the mystic to search beyond created things for their creator.12 Benedict notes, however, that pagan 9 Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, part 4, no. 168. 10 Deus Caritas Est, no. 4.The pope describes the notion that Christianity destroys eros as a “widely held perception” expressed in questions such as: “Doesn’t the Church, with all her commandments and prohibitions, turn to bitterness the most precious thing in life?” (Deus Caritas Est, no. 3); “Doesn’t she blow the whistle just when the joy which is the Creator’s gift offers us a happiness which is itself a certain foretaste of the Divine?” (ibid.). The pope’s own second question is thus a summary of these concerns. 11 Josef Pieper cites with approval the following observations by Rollo May: “The curious thing to our ears is how rarely the Latins speak of sexus. Sex, to them, was no issue; it was amor they were concerned about. Similarly, everyone knows the Greek word eros, but practically no one has ever heard of their term for ‘sex.’ It is phýlon . . . a zoological term” (Rollo May, Love and Will [New York: Norton, 1969], 73); “We are in flight from eros—and we use sex as the vehicle for the flight” (ibid., 65). See Pieper, Faith, Hope and Love, 157–58. Although anyone who has read Ovid might hesitate to affirm too great a distinction in the Roman mind between amor and sexus, May’s point is well taken and accords well with the pope’s critique of the contemporary tendency to reduce eros to sex. See also C. S. Lewis’s observations on the relationship between sex and eros, especially the patently obvious but often overlooked fact that the former can exist without the latter. C. S. Lewis, The Four Loves (London: Harper Collins, 1960), 111–40. 12 See, for example, St. John of the Cross’s description of his bittersweet encounter with created things, all of which whisper to him, “Pouring out a thousand 378 Michael Sherwin, OP religion too often expressed this insight by means of fertility cults and “sacred” prostitution, thereby misunderstanding the true nature of the divine fellowship that eros desires. Human experience teaches that eros must be purified if it is to attain its goal: “[E]ros tends to rise ‘in ecstasy’ towards the divine, to lead us beyond ourselves; yet for this very reason it calls for a path of ascent, renunciation, purification, and healing.”13 Benedict offers here his initial response to the notion that Christianity destroys eros. Although there have been currents in Christian history that have denigrated the bodily aspects of eros, the true goal of the Gospel message is to purify, not destroy eros. “Purification and growth in maturity are called for; and these also pass through the path of renunciation. Far from rejecting or ‘poisoning’ eros, they heal it and restore its true grandeur.”14 Up to this point Pope Benedict has said nothing that Plato, Plotinus, or any of the neo-Platonists could not have said as well. They too were dismayed by the vulgarities of pagan ritual.They too sought to purify eros and ascend to union with the divine.15 The uniquely Christian contribution to our understanding of eros emerges when one considers the nature of the purifications that eros requires. It is in this context that Benedict introduces his third and fourth questions. The Third and Fourth Questions: Christianity and the Purification of Eros After affirming the need to purify eros in its ecstatic assent toward the divine, the pope asks two related questions: “Concretely, what does this path of ascent and purification entail? How might love be experienced so that it can fully realize its human and divine promise?”16 Benedict dedicates the bulk of the remaining first half of his letter to addressing these graces,/he passed these groves in haste;/and having looked at them,/with his image alone,/clothed them in beauty,” which only leaves John desiring God all the more, and no longer satisfied by his created messengers: “Do not send me/any more messengers;/they cannot tell me what I must hear” (Spiritual Canticle, vv. 5 and 6, in The Collected Works of St. John of the Cross, trans. Kieran Kavanaugh, O.C.D., and Otilio Rodriguez, O.C.D., rev. ed. [Washington, DC: ICS Publications, 1991]). John’s description of his experiences is also influenced by the Confessions, where Augustine affirms that whoever cultivates internal silence will hear the transient things of this world whisper: “We did not make ourselves, but He made us who abides forever.” Confessions, 9.10. 13 Deus Caritas Est, no. 5. 14 Ibid. 15 See John Rist, Eros and Psyche: Studies in Plato, Plotinus and Origen (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1961). 16 Deus Caritas Est, no. 6. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 379 two questions. He first turns to a literal reading of the Song of Songs. As “love-songs” written “to exalt conjugal love,”17 the book contains insights into the nature of marital love. Here again we find two different words for love.There is the overtly sexual word, dodim, with which the book begins (Sg 1:2:“Let him kiss me with kisses of his mouth! More delightful is your love [dodim] than wine”), and there is the more general biblical term for love (ahabah) that is often used to express God’s love for his people and is employed here in such key texts as “stern as death is love [ahabah], relentless as the nether world is devotion” (Sg 8:6).The pope sees these poems as portraying passionate love in the context of a mutual self-revelation that leads the lovers to seek each other’s good, even to the point of renunciation and self-sacrifice.This aspect of love’s dynamism reveals the true sense in which love is an ecstasy. It is an ongoing and liberating journey from “the closed inward-looking self ” toward a self-giving concern for the other. As such, it is also a movement toward “authentic self-discovery and indeed the discovery of God.”18 In this movement, love becomes “finalized,” in the sense that it attains a definitive object and duration. It is an exclusive and unending love for this particular person.19 In his analysis of love’s purification Benedict is simply summarizing the experience of faithful lovers throughout history. Their love often begins with romantic infatuation that leads the lovers together. The beloved becomes the all-consuming object of the other’s attention; yet at this stage the lover’s knowledge of the beloved remains superficial. In a sense, the lovers are in love with being in love, and the beloved is viewed in many ways from the perspective of the pleasure he or she produces in the lover. In other words, romantic love often begins with a powerful element of self-love (even though this element may be unperceived by the lovers themselves):The beloved holds me enthralled partly because of the joy she brings me, because of the ways in which she completes what in me is lacking.There is much in this initial stage that is illusion.We are in love with an ideal type that no creature can fulfill. The very force of romantic infatuation, however, pushes the lovers toward learning more about each other and, thus, toward a truer understanding of the other. Eventually, through the crises and trials of the relationship the lovers come to see each other more truly, and a shift occurs.While romance will always have a place, an element that was present in the beginning begins to grow in prominence. It is the celebration of the other: the affirmation through word and deed that “it is good that you exist, that you are in this 17 Ibid. 18 Ibid. 19 Ibid. Michael Sherwin, OP 380 world.”20 There is also that element of finalization, where each is led to choose the other as an exclusive partner for life. Once again another shift in emphasis occurs, and an element that was already present acquires new prominence. Mature human love is not so much two gazing into each other’s eyes, as two people shoulder to shoulder focused on the common object of their love.21 In the economy of the family, this entails the lovers’ common concern for their children. Their love, however, also naturally tends toward a common concern for the ultimate source of their love, which is in God. Like spokes on a wheel that converge at the center, the lovers draw closer as they focus on God by making him the center of their lives. In all of this, the romance and power of eros leads faithful lovers to the mature celebration of the other in the affirming love of agape. At this point in his analysis, the pope answers his first two questions. He begins by sharpening the distinction between eros and agape. Eros signifies a “worldly,” “possessive,” and “ascending” love, while agape is a faith-shaped, “oblative” (that is, sacrificial), and “descending” love.22 Benedict notes that both in theology and in philosophy the distinction between these two loves has often been radicalized to the point of establishing “a clear antithesis” between pagan eros and Christian agape.23 The logical consequence of this antithesis would be to detach Christianity from the fundamental relationships and experiences of human life.24 The pope counters that “eros and agape—ascending love and descending love—can never be completely separated. The more the two, in their different aspects, find a proper unity in the one reality of love, the more the true nature of love in general is realized.”25 Thus, just after he has contrasted these two loves most sharply, Benedict begins to blur the distinction between them. First, true eros always contains an element of agape. Second, true agape always also has an element of receptive eros. Even if eros is at first mainly covetous and ascending, a fascination for the great promise of happiness, in drawing near to the other, it is less and less concerned with itself, increasingly seeks the happiness of the other, is concerned more and more with the beloved, bestows itself and wants to “be there for” the other.The element of agape thus enters into 20 See Pieper, Faith, Hope, Love, 167–69. 21 Antoine de Saint-Exupéry, Terre des Hommes (Paris: Gallimard, 1939); Lewis, The Four Loves, 73. 22 Deus Caritas Est, no. 7. 23 Ibid. This is no doubt a reference to the views of Anders Nygren in his classic study Agape and Eros (London: SPCK, 1953). 24 Deus Caritas Est, no. 7. 25 Ibid. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 381 this love, for otherwise eros is impoverished and even loses its own nature. On the other hand, man cannot live by oblative, descending love alone. He cannot always give, he must also receive.Anyone who wishes to give love must also receive love as a gift.26 Through affirming the interconnectedness between eros and agape, the pope is able finally to answer his first question concerning love’s plurality by affirming an underlying unity: Fundamentally, “love” is a single reality, but with different dimensions; at different times, one or other dimension may emerge more clearly.Yet when the two dimensions are totally cut off from one another, the result is a caricature or at least an impoverished form of love.27 The recognition of this underlying unity also enables Pope Benedict to respond to his second question concerning Christianity’s attitude toward eros: “Biblical faith does not set up a parallel universe, or one opposed to that primordial human phenomenon which is love, but rather accepts the whole man; it intervenes in his search for love in order to purify it and to reveal new dimensions of it.”28 Although Benedict has already begun to sketch answers to his third and fourth questions, it is only when he turns to “the newness of biblical faith” that he develops the features of these answers. Thus far in his analysis, even though he has frequently included proleptic references to the role of Christ and the theology of the early Church, the pope has remained close to the general human experience of love. Now, however, his “somewhat philosophical reflections” have led us “to the threshold of biblical faith.”29 It is by crossing this threshold that we discover the deeper meaning of the relationship between eros and agape. The Newness of Biblical Faith Biblical faith brings to the human experience of love the radical discovery that God loves us with a personal and passionate love. God is not merely the object of eros, as Aristotle held; he is also a lover. He loves humanity with eros.To understand what this means for Benedict, we must turn to the work of the patristic author whom he cites to justify this claim. PseudoDionysius was a sixth-century theologian who attempted to convey the Christian message to the pagan and neo-Platonic culture in which he lived. 26 Ibid. 27 Ibid., no. 8. 28 Ibid. 29 Ibid., no. 7. 382 Michael Sherwin, OP In a work dedicated to studying the divine names, he asserts that both agape and eros are proper names for God.30 Although he recognizes that eros appears nowhere in the New Testament, Pseudo-Dionysius affirms that the two terms are synonymous.31 The goal of this identification is not to reduce agape to eros, but to reveal in neo-Platonic language an essential and revolutionary feature of God’s love that is at the heart of biblical revelation.32 The pagan philosopher Proclus had already developed the view that there was a “descending eros” exhibited by a particular group of gods in their providential care for humans.33 Moreover, Plotinus had already characterized the first principle of all things as Eros.34 As such, Eros provoked ecstasy in all things, an ecstatic eros whereby they moved toward the Eros/One because of its beauty. Pseudo-Dionysius reworks these neoPlatonic elements to make a very un-neo-Platonic affirmation: God himself is an ecstatic eros. Unlike Plato’s notion of eros, which always implied a lack, God’s eros springs from the superabundance of his goodness.35 God, freely from the riches of his goodness, loves and cares for his creation.36 Thus, as the pope underlines, God’s eros is entirely agape.37 It is gratuitous in the sense that it is unmotivated and freely given. It is not a response to the beauty and goodness of creation, but is the cause of it. God’s love is said to be passionate by analogy with the intensity of human passion. Divine passion, however, is not based on a lack existing in God, but rather on the unfulfilled character of human existence. God passionately desires that we attain the fulfillment for which the human community was created: perfect union with him in the community of the Trinity. Ultimately, the character of this passionate love is revealed in the Incarnation and cross of Jesus who suffers to make this fulfillment possible.38 The cross also points to the second agapic feature of God’s eros, a feature already 30 In this identification he is following the example of Origen (Commentary on the Song of Songs, prologue [PG 13, 70D]), who also cites Ignatius of Antioch’s affirmation in an apparent reference to Christ: “My Eros is crucified.” Letter to the Romans, 7, 2. 31 Pseudo-Dionysius, On the Divine Names, 4.12 (709B). 32 See John Rist,“A Note on Eros and Agape in Pseudo-Dionysius,” Vigiliae Christiane 20 (1966): 235–43; A. H. Armstrong, “Platonic Eros and Christian Agape,” Downside Review 79 (1961): 105–21. 33 Proclus, Commentary on Alcibiades, 56, 2–6, p. 25 (Westerink). Rist, “A Note on Eros and Agape,” 239. 34 Plotinus, Enneads, 6.8.15. Rist, “A Note on Eros and Agape,” 239. 35 See Plato, Symposium, 211. Rist, “A Note on Eros and Agape,” 243. 36 Pseudo-Dionysius, On the Divine Names, 4.13 (712A and B). Rist, “A Note on Eros and Agape,” 241. 37 Deus Caritas Est, no. 9. 38 Ibid., no. 10. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 383 revealed by the Old Testament prophets: God’s love is forgiving. God not only loves us, he overcomes our infidelity by forgiving us our sins. It is here that the Song of Songs emerges in a new light.39 According to their fuller meaning (sensus plenior), the book’s poems describe God’s love for his people and the Church’s response of love.As such they point to the deeper interconnection between eros and agape.The people’s desire for God leads them to a mature worship of God whereby they affirm his goodness, and love and desire what He loves and desires.At the same time, however, their generous and sacrificial love is possible only because of the love God himself has poured into their hearts. Benedict notes that biblical revelation not only offers a revolutionary understanding of God’s love, it also reveals the unique beauty of human love.As a created participation in God’s eros, eros is a positive and holy part of human nature that is called to grow ever more deeply agapic in character.This occurs in a unique way through marriage. Human eros “directs man towards marriage,” which by its monogamous character is a visible sign of God’s permanent and faithful love for his people. From this perspective, family life and the daily ordinariness of marital love acquire a dignity and a relationship to God that “has practically no equivalent in extra biblical literature.”40 In the sacrament of marriage, couples are called to love each other in ways that reflect and participate in God’s generous and forgiving love. Jesus Christ—The Incarnate Love of God Benedict underlines, however, that God reveals the fullness of his love for humanity in the Incarnation. The life, death, and resurrection of Christ give “flesh and blood” to the biblical conception of love.41 It is especially by Christ’s death on the cross that we encounter “love in its most radical form.”42 Indeed, it is by “contemplating the pierced side of Christ” that the Christian learns what it means to affirm that “God is love.”43 Benedict even goes so far as to assert that the cross of Christ is the true starting point of the Christian definition of love. It is here that the pope offers his fullest answer to his third and fourth questions. Initially the pope affirmed, in answer to the fourth question, that it is by living “a life of fidelity to the one God”44 that love can fully realize its human and divine 39 Ibid. 40 Ibid., no. 11. 41 Ibid., no. 12. 42 Ibid. 43 1 Jn 4:8; Deus Caritas Est, no. 12. 44 Deus Caritas Est, no. 9. Michael Sherwin, OP 384 promise. The pope has also, in answer to his third question, traced the general features of the purifications required of human love. Now he portrays the cross of Christ as the concrete path of ascent and purification through which Christian love must pass. “In this contemplation [of the pierced side of Christ] the Christian discovers the path along which his life and love must move.”45 When the pope portrays Christ as the way by which the ascent of love must pass, he is echoing the famous passage from the Confessions where Augustine describes how his attempts at mystical ascent failed because they were not rooted in the humility and charity of Christ.46 Augustine describes how, following the advice of the Platonists, he was able to ascend to a fleeting mystical union with God, but fell back because of his weakness. Lasting ascent only becomes possible by embracing Christ who is the “Mediator between God and Man” and “the way, the truth, and the life.” It is by descending with Jesus that we are able to rise to the heights with his rising.Augustine confides that this led him to see the vast difference between seeing the goal and seeing the way to it.47 In a passage that will subsequently shape Dante’s description of his own plight at the beginning of the Divine Comedy, Augustine concludes: It is one thing to see the land of peace from a wooded mountaintop, yet not find the way to it and struggle hopelessly far from the way, with hosts of those fugitive deserters from God, under their leader the lion and the Dragon, besetting us about and ever lying in wait; and quite another to hold to the way that leads there, a way guarded by the care of our heavenly General, where there are no deserters from the army of heaven to practice their robberies—for indeed they avoid that way as a torment.48 The delights of human eros are like the heights of a wooded mountaintop. They offer a glimpse of our goal, but not the way to it. C. S. Lewis explains the implications of Augustine’s analogy by distinguishing between “near45 Ibid., no. 12. 46 Augustine, Confessions, 7.9–21. For an excellent analysis of this experience at Milan and a comparison of it in relation to Augustine’s experience at Ostia (ibid., 9.10), see Thomas Williams, “Augustine vs Plotinus: The Uniqueness of the Vision at Ostia,” in Medieval Philosophy and the Classical Tradition in Islam, Judaism, and Christianity, ed. John Inglis (New York: Curzon Press, 2002), 169–79. 47 Augustine, Confessions, 7.20.The pope also portrays St. Benedict as having passed through an analogous purification and assent. See Joseph Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), 159–61. 48 Augustine, Confessions, 7.21. Cf. Dante, Inferno, 1.1–60. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 385 ness-by-likeness” and “nearness-of-approach.”49 All human loves are near to God by likeness, for God is love. This is especially true in their most noble expressions as in family affection, friendship, or devotion to one’s community. These loves are near to God the way one mountain peak is near the next, through a nearness-by-likeness. Being on the top of one is like being on the top of the other. It is not, however, the same as being on that other peak. To be there requires “that slow and painful approach which must be our (though by no means our unaided) task.” This nearness-of-approach, Lewis explains, is “an imitation of God incarnate.”50 The pope has long placed “great weight” on this section of the Confessions not only because of its focus on Christ, but also because of the way Augustine presents the centrality of Christ in an ecclesial and Eucharistic context.51 The Christ who strengthens Augustine is the Eucharistic Christ: “who brought into union with our nature that Food which I lacked the strength to take: for ‘the Word was made flesh’ that Your Wisdom, by which You created all things, might give suck to our soul’s 49 Lewis, The Four Loves, 5. Lewis reworks Augustine’s metaphor, making it a more prosaic mountain walk where one is close to the village while above it on an outcrop, but to arrive there one must follow a long trail (ibid., 5–7). 50 Lewis draws his study to a close through words that mirror the pope’s teaching closely and also reveal some hint of the sufferings Lewis had recently experienced during the first onset of his wife’s cancer:“Man can ascend to Heaven only because the Christ, who died and ascended to Heaven, is ‘formed in him.’ Must we not suppose that the same is true of a man’s love? Only those into which Love Himself has entered will ascend to Love Himself. And these can be raised with Him only if they have, in some degree and fashion, shared his death; if the natural element in them has submitted—year after year, or in some sudden agony—to transmutation.The fashion of this world passes away.The very name of nature implies the transitory. Natural loves can hope for eternity only in so far as they have allowed themselves to be taken into the eternity of Charity; have at least allowed the process to begin here on earth, before the night comes when no man can work. And the process will always involve a kind of death.There is no escape. In my love for wife or friend the only eternal element is the transforming presence of Love Himself.” Lewis, The Four Loves, 165–66. 51 With regard to this passage, Aidan Nichols in his 1988 study of Joseph Ratzinger’s thought affirms that,“Ratzinger places great weight on a text of the Confessions where Augustine laments that a momentary vision of God which once came to him could not be sustained or re-created in memory, owing to human ‘infirmity.’ Because of such weakness some means of help beyond the self must be sought. . . . Since he cannot bear the divine ‘food’ in its pure form, the divine Word has mingled itself with flesh so that man may be able to enjoy it. In the Church, the divine humility has provided a medicine by its own example for the sickness from which none is immune.” Aidan Nichols, The Theology of Joseph Ratzinger (London:T&T Clark, 1988), 32. Michael Sherwin, OP 386 infancy.”52 Not surprising, therefore, the pope links our following of Christ to the Eucharist and develops its ecclesial implications. Echoing the language of St. Augustine, the pope affirms that Jesus gave his sacrificial love “an enduring presence through his institution of the Eucharist at the Last Supper. He anticipated his death and resurrection by giving his disciples, in the bread and wine, his very self, his body and blood as the new manna.”53 Once again, the pope underlines how God’s action is the fulfillment of the deepest aspirations of the human heart: “The ancient world had dimly perceived that man’s real food—what truly nourishes him as man—is ultimately the Logos, eternal wisdom: this same Logos now truly becomes food for us—as love.”54 The Eucharist is not something static that we receive passively. Instead, through the Eucharist “we enter into the very dynamic of [Christ’s] self-giving.”55 Here we find the pope’s fullest response to his third question. Our love is purified through the “sacramental mysticism” of the Eucharist, which exceeds both in height and in breadth anything that human culture could imagine on it own. Not only does this sacramental mysticism raise us “to far greater heights than anything that any human mystical elevation could ever accomplish,”56 it also goes out to all people, uniting us in the one bread, the body of Christ. As such, the Eucharist was rightly called agape by the early Church, because “there God’s own agape comes to us bodily, in order to continue his work in us and through us.”57 This means on the one hand that the Church’s good works can never be separated from the life of grace, faith, and the sacraments, while on the other hand the reception of the sacraments always implies an ethical commitment to works of charity. As a consequence, “Faith, worship, and ethos are interwoven as a single reality which takes shape in our encounter with God’s agape. Here the usual contraposition between worship and ethics simply falls apart.”58 In language reminiscent of Dom Virgil Michel’s insistence on the social implications of the Eucharist,59 the pope explains that “ ‘worship’ itself, 52 Augustine, Confessions, 7.18. 53 Deus Caritas Est, no. 13; cf. Jn 6:31–33. 54 Deus Caritas Est, no. 13. 55 Ibid. 56 Ibid. 57 Ibid., no. 14. 58 Ibid. 59 See Virgil Michel, “The Liturgy the Basis of Social Regeneration,” Orate Fratres 9 (1934–35): 536–45 (reprinted in American Catholic Religious Thought:The Shaping of a Theological and Social Tradition, ed. Patrick W. Carey [Marquette: Marquette University Press, 2004], 424–33). Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 387 Eucharistic communion, includes the reality both of being loved and of loving others in turn.”60 Consequently,“a Eucharist which does not pass over into the concrete practice of love is intrinsically fragmented.”61 Through living the reality of the Eucharist in our lives, Christian love extends out to all people. All people become our “neighbor” through a love that “is now universalized, yet remains concrete.”62 It is here that Pope Benedict poses the last two questions of the encyclical’s first part. The Fifth and Sixth Questions: On Loving God and Neighbor The pope’s fifth and sixth questions enable him to probe more deeply what it means to love God. He first ponders whether we can “love God without seeing him.” Then, in reference to the biblical commandments to love God and neighbor, he inquires whether love can be commanded.63 The pope begins with the observation that although no one has ever seen God as he is in his essence, nevertheless, “God is not totally invisible to us.”64 First, he became visible to a particular historical generation in Israel through the incarnation of Christ. Second, the incarnate Christ remains visible to us in word and deed through the Scriptures and the Sacraments, especially the Eucharist. Third, God is visible to us through the lives and example of the people we meet who share his love. “In the Church’s Liturgy, in her prayer, in the living community of believers, we experience the love of God, we perceive his presence, and we thus learn to recognize that presence in our daily lives.”65 This encounter with God’s love enables us to love God in return: “He loves us, He makes us see and experience his love; and since He has ‘loved us first,’ love can also blossom as a response within us.”66 Notice that Benedict does not proceed here in the way one might have expected. In responding to the question of how to love an invisible God, the pope refuses to reduce the love of God to the love of neighbor. Although he accepts the Johannine insight that we cannot love God if we hate our neighbor, he refuses to say that the way to love the unseen God is simply and solely by loving the neighbor we can see. Instead, the pope 60 Deus Caritas Est, no. 14. 61 Ibid. 62 Ibid., no. 15. 63 Ibid., no. 16: “[C]an commanded?” 64 Ibid., no. 17. 65 Ibid. 66 Ibid. we love God without seeing him? And can love be 388 Michael Sherwin, OP keeps the focus on God by partially denying his question’s premise.We can love the unseen God, because God has in a certain sense made himself visible. He reveals his love for us, and it is by experiencing this love that we can learn to love him in return. In his description of how we grow in the love of God, the pope considers the ways in which love is a choice. As we have seen, the pope follows a long tradition of employing the term eros to describe those aspects of love that do not seem to be voluntary. It is a passion that comes over us or something we fall into.As love grows, however, an element of freedom enters into it. Indeed, at the core of love’s purification is its deepening presence in the spiritual heart of the person: in his intellect and will.The experience of being loved by God “engages our will and our intellect,”67 and thus empowers us freely to love him in return. In a free act we both acknowledge God and accept his will for us in an act that “unites our intellect, will, and sentiments in the all-embracing act of love.”68 Moreover, all mature human love entails a union of wills over the essentials, and our love for God is no exception.“The love-story between God and man consists in the very fact that this communion of will increases in a communion of thought and sentiment, and thus our will and God’s will increasingly coincide.”69 The result of this affective communion is that God’s will and his commandments are no longer experienced as “an alien will” or as “something imposed on [us] from without.”70 These two features of our mature love for God—its freedom and interiority—are what make love something that God can command of us. He can command it because by loving us he both gives us the ability to fulfill the command and the desire to do so.71 As the pope states in the encyclical’s introduction, “Since God has first loved us (cf. 1 Jn 4:10), love is now no longer a mere ‘command’; it is the response to the gift of love with which God draws near to us.”72 We can thus make Augustine’s prayer our own: “Give what you command, and command what you will.”73 67 Ibid. 68 Ibid. 69 Ibid. 70 Ibid. 71 Ibid., no. 18. Benedict develops this theme in subsequent sections of his letter. First,“the command of love of neighbor is inscribed by the Creator in man’s very nature” (ibid., no. 31). Second, for those who have encountered the love of God in Christ, “love of neighbor will no longer be for them a commandment imposed, so to speak, from without, but a consequence deriving from their faith, a faith which becomes active through love (cf. Gal 5:6)” (ibid., no. 31). 72 Ibid., no. 1. 73 Augustine, Confessions, 10.29. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 389 It is only at this point, after considering how the mature love for God involves the whole person (intellect, will, and emotion) and entails a communion of heart and mind with God, that the pope sketches how the love of neighbor is “possible in the way proclaimed by the Bible.”74 Because of God’s loving initiative, which is communicated to us through the liturgical and communal life of the Christian community, we can begin to see all people as our neighbors whom we are disposed to love— even those whom we do not “like,” do not know personally, or even those who are our enemies. In the gift of faith we can see them “with the eyes of Christ,” and in the gift of charity we can love them with the love of Christ.75 The patristic aphorism that “His friend is my friend,” becomes true to such an extent that we can even treat our enemies from God’s perspective: as those called to be our intimate friends in heaven.76 This last feature of our love of neighbor has important implications for how Christians organize their charitable acts and their social and political engagement in the world, which is the subject of the encyclical’s second part. II Although it is true that the second part of the encyclical draws on material already in preparation before Joseph Ratzinger’s election as pope, the final product is very much crafted according to his own deepest concerns.77 In his 1954 doctoral dissertation on the ecclesiology of St. Augustine, Ratzinger already emphasized that works of charity are an 74 Deus Caritas Est, no. 18. 75 The pope also underlines how the two objects of our love interact:“The saints— consider the example of Blessed Teresa of Calcutta—constantly renewed their capacity for love of neighbor from their encounter with the Eucharistic Lord, and conversely this encounter acquired its realism and depth in their service to others” (ibid., no. 18). In other words, our love for God pushes us to love our neighbor and our encounters with our neighbor deepen our love for God. 76 Ibid., no. 18. 77 Pope Benedict explains elsewhere that, “A first reading of the Encyclical could possibly give the impression that it is divided into two parts that are not very connected: a first part, theoretical, which speaks about the essence of love, and a second, which speaks of ecclesial charity and charitable organizations. I was particularly interested, however, in the unity of the two themes that are well understood only if seen as a whole.” “Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI to the Participants at the Meeting Promoted by the Pontifical Council Cor Unum” (Monday, 23 January 2006), www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2006/ january/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20060123_cor-unum_en.html. 390 Michael Sherwin, OP essential feature of the Church’s mission.78 The pope reiterates this truth in the introductory sections of the encyclical’s second part. By means of a quick historical sketch of ecclesial practice that begins with the Acts of the Apostles and continues to the Church at Rome under Gregory the Great, the pope underlines “two essential facts.”79 First, “ecclesial charity,”80 which Benedict describes as a “well-ordered love of neighbor” administered communally,81 is an expression of the “Church’s deepest nature.”82 Specifically, in an activity that flows from the Triune economy of God’s action in the world, the Church expresses itself in the threefold activity “of proclaiming the word of God [kerygma-martyria], celebrating the sacraments [leitourgia], and exercising the ministry of charity [diakonia].”83 Benedict emphasizes that the ministry of charity is as essential to the Church’s life as is the celebration of the Eucharist and has consequently always been associated with it.84 Second, ecclesial charity has a twofold character: It is directed toward the needs of its visible members (because no Christian should go without the essentials of life), and it is a universal love that goes out beyond the visible Church to all those in need.85 After these introductory remarks, Benedict considers charity’s relationship to justice. The Seventh Question: What Is Justice? In his study of Augustine’s ecclesiology, Ratzinger underlined the role of faith and the role of charity in the Church’s life.86 Pope Benedict does the same here. First, he emphasizes the importance of faith in helping secular society discern the requirements of justice.The Church acknowledges the “autonomy of the temporal sphere,” and thus also the distinction between Church and State. The State must not impose a particular religion upon its citizens, but neither must it exclude the legitimate freedom of religion to exist within society.87 Moreover, the just ordering of society is the responsibility of politics. Secular society, therefore, cannot 78 Joseph Ratzinger, Volk und Haus Gottes in Augustins Lehre von der Kirche (People and House of God in Augustine’s Doctrine of the Church) (Munich: Herder, 1954). See, Nichols, The Theology of Joseph Ratzinger, 27–50. 79 Deus Caritas Est, no. 25. 80 Ibid., no. 23. 81 Ibid., no. 21. 82 Ibid., no. 25. 83 Ibid. 84 Ibid., nos. 22 and 32. 85 Ibid., no. 25. 86 See Nichols, The Theology of Joseph Ratzinger, 32–33. 87 Deus Caritas Est, no. 28. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 391 avoid the question of Justice. “What is justice?”88 The issue here is not the definition of justice, but its application to particular situations. Each society is faced with the question,What does justice entail in this specific situation? Benedict does not intend to answer the question, but to underline that the answer requires a judgment of practical reason. Reason, however, is constantly threatened by the temptations of power and selfinterest. To function properly, practical reason must continually be purified. This is where the contribution of faith emerges. The gift of faith purifies and strengthens reason, enabling reason “to do its work more effectively and to see its proper object more clearly.”89 From this perspective, the Church’s role in political life is not to control the State or to takes its place. Instead, through its social teaching, which appeals to reason and the natural law, it seeks to persuade the citizens of secular society concerning the requirements of justice. This process of persuasion seeks both to form consciences and to instill a “greater readiness” to act according to the dictates of conscience.90 The pope is concerned to show, as he has argued elsewhere, that Christian faith is not irrational but seeks to strengthen reason in its quest for truth and justice.91 Far from being a threat to society, the Church’s efforts to form consciences about the requirements of justice can help society protect itself from irrational enthusiasms and destructive special interests. Nevertheless, even the most just society needs charity.92 This is true because even when material needs are satisfied people still experience suffering and loneliness, challenges that can only be met through a “loving personal concern” that offers them “refreshment and care for their souls.”93 This leads the pope to ask his eighth question. The Eighth Question: On Christian and Ecclesial Charity The pope begins his analysis of ecclesial charity by distinguishing it from the charity that animates the political engagement of individual Christian citizens. Although “charity must animate the entire lives of the lay faith88 Ibid. 89 Ibid. 90 Ibid. 91 See, Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance, 138–258.This was also a theme in the pope’s controversial address at Regensburg. “Meeting with the Representatives of Science: Lecture of the Holy Father, Aula Magna of the University of Regensburg” (September 12, 2006), www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/ speeches/2006/september/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20060912_universityregensburg_en.html. 92 Deus Caritas Est, no. 28. 93 Ibid. Michael Sherwin, OP 392 ful, and therefore also their political activity,” this activity is not the sum total of the Church’s charitable action. There is also “ecclesial charity” administered by the Church’s “charitable organizations” as an “organized activity of believers” and constituting an “opus proprium” of the Church.94 After considering some features of the current situation in which ecclesial charity is lived, the pope asks, “what are the essential elements of Christian and ecclesial charity?”95 The pope answers this question by identifying three such elements. First, Christian charity is a response to immediate needs in specific situations:“feeding the hungry, clothing the naked, caring for and healing the sick, visiting those in prison, etc.”96 Moreover, this response entails not merely professional competence on the part of these workers of charity, but also “a formation of the heart” that enables them to lead those whom they help to “experience the richness of their humanity.”97 Thus, in order to respond to the integral needs of those whom they serve, these workers must themselves receive a formation that, through an encounter with Christ, “awakens their love and opens their spirits to others.”98 Second, “Christian charitable activity must be independent of parties and ideologies.”99 Ecclesial charity is neither a means of “changing the world ideologically” or of preserving the status quo. Instead, in imitation of the Good Samaritan, charity flows from “a heart that sees.” It is a heart that “sees where love is needed and acts accordingly.”100 Third, Christian charity is not a means of engaging in “proselytism,”101 by which the pope means that charity is not a stratagem for persuading individuals to convert. Those who practice charity in the Church’s name will never seek to impose the Church’s faith upon others. They realize that a pure and generous love is the best witness to the God in whom we believe and by whom we are driven to love. A Christian knows when it is time to speak of God and when it is better to say nothing and to let love alone speak. He knows that God is love (cf. 1 Jn 4:8) and that God’s presence is felt at the very time when the only thing we do is to love.102 94 Ibid., no. 29. 95 Ibid., no. 31. 96 Ibid. 97 Ibid. 98 Ibid. 99 Ibid. 100 Ibid. 101 Ibid. 102 Ibid. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 393 As a personal love, charity is never a means to a further end except in the sense of being ordered to love God. Charity is a free gift of love for one’s neighbor springing from the neighbor’s inherent dignity. This does not mean that charity excludes God from its activity or sees the acceptance of Christian Revelation as an unwanted byproduct of its activity. Ecclesial charity always bears witness to Christ. It does so, however, as a free gift and through quiet acts of service, speaking about God with words only when the moment is right.103 After identifying these three essential elements of ecclesial charity, Pope Benedict turns to those who administer this charity. Although the Holy See and the bishops have a unique responsibility for administrating ecclesial charity, the duty of charity is “a responsibility incumbent upon the whole Church.”104 In this context, the pope reiterates the traits of character that workers of charity should have: “[T]hey must not be inspired by ideologies aimed at improving the world, but should rather be guided by the faith which works through love.”105 Since it is through experiencing Christ’s love that love of neighbor is awakened within us, the deepest requirement for those who practice ecclesial charity is that they be “moved by Christ’s love.”106 The inspiration underlying their activity should be St. Paul’s affirmation that “the love of Christ urges us on.”107 In essence the pope is affirming that those who administer the Church’s organized good works must be animated in their actions by the agape described in the first part of his letter. It is not enough simply to want to do good.As an expression of ecclesial love, their actions must flow from “a love nourished by an encounter with Christ.”108 One who loves with this agape recognizes with St. Paul that “if I give away all I have, and if I deliver my body to be burned, but do not have love, I gain nothing.”109 Pope Benedict even goes so far as to assert that “[t]his hymn must be the Magna Carta of all ecclesial service; it sums up all the reflections on love which I have offered throughout this encyclical letter.”110 Ultimately, as this agape grows within us, we are inspired by the example of Christ “to live no longer for ourselves but for him, and, with him, for others.”111 The pope, however, recognizes the everpresent danger of discouragement before the overwhelming needs that 103 Ibid. 104 Ibid., no. 32. 105 Ibid., no. 33; cf. Gal 5:6. 106 Deus Caritas Est, no. 33. 107 2 Cor 5:14; Deus Caritas Est, no. 33. 108 Deus Caritas Est, no. 34. 109 1 Cor 13:3; Deus Caritas Est, no. 34. 110 Deus Caritas Est, no. 34. 111 Ibid., no. 33. 394 Michael Sherwin, OP confront us and the seemingly insignificant results that we are able to attain. This leads Benedict to pose a series of questions that confront our relationship with God in the context of human suffering. Questions Nine Through Eleven: The Question of God Pope Benedict acknowledges that the immensity of the needs confronting us can give rise to two powerful temptations. We can either be drawn toward an ideology that offers the illusory promise of “doing what God’s governance of the world apparently cannot: fully resolving every problem,” but which comes at the price of an “arrogant contempt for man,” or we can succumb to a resigned inertia, “since it would seem that in any event nothing can be accomplished.”112 Benedict explains that during such times of temptation “a living relationship with Christ is decisive if we are to keep on the right path.”113 Yet, how to cultivate such a relationship? The pope poses this question by quoting the words of Blessed Teresa of Calcutta:“We need this deep connection with God in our daily life. How can we obtain it?” Mother Teresa’s answer is decisively simple: “By prayer.”114 It is a response that summarized the answer the pope had already begun to develop. Benedict appeals to the reader to see that “prayer, as a means of drawing ever new strength from Christ, is concretely and urgently needed.”115 Countering the danger of a restless activism, the pope contends that “people who pray are not wasting their time, even though the situation appears desperate and seems to call for action alone.”116 Once again Benedict offers Mother Teresa as an example. The balanced life of prayer and service that she practiced and that her sisters continue to live illustrates that “time devoted to God in prayer not only does not detract from effective and loving service to our neighbor but is in fact the inexhaustible source of that service.”117 Indeed, time spend in prayer protects us from a form of discouragement that Benedict regards as closely linked to the secular rejection of God. It protects us from the disappointed rejection of God because of God’s seeming indifference to human suffering. “An authentically religious attitude” that the life of prayer sustains within us “prevents man from presuming to judge God, accusing him of allowing poverty and failing to have compassion for his creatures.”118 It is poignantly 112 Ibid., no. 36. 113 Ibid. 114 Ibid. 115 Ibid. 116 Ibid. 117 Ibid. 118 Ibid., no. 37. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 395 in this context that the pope asks his tenth question, a question he leaves his readers to answer for themselves:“[W]hen people claim to build a case against God in defense of man, on whom can they depend when human activity proves powerless?”119 In a manner reminiscent of Augustine’s argument with the Stoics, the pope is inviting non-believers to recognize the powerlessness of human effort before the mystery of death. He makes this invitation with the confidence that in God’s grace an honest recognition of human limitation will open the non-believer to seek the ultimate meaning of his existence in the God who cries out to him. Although the pope rejects the case against God, he acknowledges that human suffering nevertheless confronts the believer with a deep and painful mystery. The suffering of the innocent and the apparent inactivity of God are mysteries that the believer will never fully understand in this life.The human heart, however, cannot help but question God about this. Thus, although the pope asks a question of non-believers, he proposes a question for believers to ask their God. It is a question drawn from the Book of Revelation: “Lord, holy and true, how long will it be?”120 The pope regards this question as the equivalent of Jesus’ agonized words from the cross: “My God, my God, why have you forsaken me?” (Mt 27:46).These words themselves hold the key to interpreting Jesus’ attitude from the cross, because they are the initial words of Psalm 22. Although this psalm begins by describing the agony of the psalmist, it ends with the psalmist proclaiming God’s praises:“I will tell of your name to my brethren; in the midst of the congregation I will praise you” (Ps 22:22). The experience of the psalmist is that God “has not despised or abhorred the affliction of the afflicted; and He has not hid his face from him, but has heard, when he cried to Him” (Ps 22:24). By citing this psalm from the cross, Jesus reveals this confidence to be his own.The pope invites us to do the same. By embracing a question from the Book of Revelation, we are called to have the same confidence that the book itself symbolically proclaims: that “in spite of all darkness [God] ultimately triumphs in glory.”121 Those who live the Church’s charity, therefore, question God in the midst of the sorrows of their ministry, but do so in faith, hope, and charity. United to the suffering Christ, their acts of charity are a light revealing the God whom they serve.122 As we shall see, the pope offers Mary as an example of one who lives this charity. First, however, before turning to Benedict’s twelfth and final question— 119 Ibid. 120 Rev 6:10; Deus Caritas Est, no. 38. 121 Deus Caritas Est, no. 39; cf. Rev 21:1–22:21. 122 Deus Caritas Est, no. 39. Michael Sherwin, OP 396 the question of Mary—we should address the unexpressed question that has, in a certain sense, guided the pope’s entire letter. The Unexpressed Question: Why Write an Encyclical on Charity? Pope Benedict famously introduces his encyclical with the Johannine affirmation that “God is love, and he who abides in love abides in God, and God in him.”123 Benedict describes this affirmation as “the heart of the Christian faith.”124 Christian faith is about a personal encounter with God who reveals himself as love.The fundamental act of faith is thus “to believe in God’s love.”125 The consequence of faith in God’s love is eternal life: “God so loved the world that whoever believes in Him should . . . have eternal life.”126 The pope begins, therefore, by affirming that since God is love the object of Christian faith is love. It is in relation to this core message that the pope explains why he chose charity as the topic of his first encyclical. In a world where the name of God is sometimes associated with vengeance or even a duty of hatred and violence, this message is both timely and significant. For this reason, I wish in my first encyclical to speak of the love which God lavishes upon us and which we in turn must share with others.127 The pope wishes to speak to us about God’s love because of the ways in which God, and by implication religion, have been associated with vengeance, violence, and hatred. The pope returns to the theme of violence when he addresses the danger of ideology. As we have seen, Pope Benedict underlines that Christians must avoid the ideological temptation. Benedict offers the historical example of Marxism. Through its strategy of viewing charitable works as something that delays the advent of the liberating revolution, Marxism sacrificed the people of the present “to the moloch of the future,” a revolutionary future that Marxism was itself never able to inaugurate. The lesson the pope draws from this historical example is that, “one does not make the world more human by refusing to act humanely here and now.”128 An integral part of Benedict’s conception of ideology 123 1 Jn 4:16; Deus Caritas Est, no. 1. 124 Deus Caritas Est, no. 1. 125 1 Jn 4:16; Deus Caritas Est, no. 1. 126 Jn 3:16. Deus Caritas Est, no. 1. 127 Deus Caritas Est, no. 1. 128 Ibid., no. 31. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 397 is that ideologies always paradoxically entail “an arrogant contempt for man.”129 In their misguided attempts to serve God or save humanity, ideologies lose sight of the individual humans we are called to love and respect. As we have seen, the pope regards prayer and a personal experience of Christ’s love as what keeps us from succumbing to ideology. In arguing for the priority of prayer, Benedict introduces two further concepts, “fanaticism and terrorism.” By associating these terms to ideology, the Holy Father reveals that he intends ideology to signify something more contemporary than Marxism. In a passage that counters the assumptions of radical religious fundamentalism as well as those of radical secularism, the pope asserts that “a personal relationship with God and an abandonment to his will can prevent man from being demeaned and save him from falling prey to the teaching of fanaticism and terrorism.”130 If the pope is here making (at least in part) a veiled reference to violent forms of Islam, his remarks cut in two directions. First, they pose a challenge to the consciences of pious Muslims.The reference here to “an abandonment to his will” is not without import, since the literal meaning of the word “islam” is “surrender” or “abandonment.”131 As every Muslim knows, Islam is a call to “surrender to the will of God.”132 Essentially, the pope is saying here that true Islam should reject the ways of fanaticism and terrorism. Moreover, the pope is inviting Muslims to deepen their “personal relationship with God” as a way of avoiding the demeaning effects of ideology. At the same time, however, the pope’s remarks counter the secularist view that religion by its very nature promotes intolerance and violence.Throughout his encyclical the pope takes pains to affirm that the goal of biblical religion is to promote an “integral” or “true” humanism.133 At the deepest level, however, the pope’s primary audience is neither Islam nor secular society.The pope is primarily addressing his remarks to Christians themselves.134 Benedict’s references to the Roman emperor 129 Ibid., no. 36. 130 Ibid., no. 37. 131 It is worth noting that the Latin version of the encyclical employs the word dedi- tio, which literally means “surrender.” In German, it is Hingabe (“devotion” or the act of “giving oneself to”), which is also closer to the literal sense of “islam” than “abandonment.” 132 The word “islam” derives from the Arabic word salama, which actually means both surrender and peace. A Muslim is one who surrenders to God’s will and thereby finds inner peace. 133 Deus Caritas Est, nos. 9 and 30. 134 Note that the Holy Father does not, as is often the current practice, include among the intended recipients of the encyclical “all men and women of good will.” The letter is addressed “to the bishops, priests and deacons, men and 398 Michael Sherwin, OP Julian the Apostate are instructive in this regard. The Holy Father could have described Julian in any number of ways, but he chooses to portray him as follows: As a child of six years, Julian witnessed the assassination of his father, brother, and other family members by the guards of the imperial palace; rightly or wrongly, he blamed this brutal act on the Emperor Constantius, who passed himself off as an outstanding Christian.The Christian faith was thus definitively discredited in his eyes.135 The pope explains that the one aspect of Christianity that Julian admired was its organized works of charity. It is worthy of note that the pope chooses this example—the reaction of one who rejected Christianity because of the violence he had suffered at the hands of publicly professed Christians—to underline the importance of Christian charity. Whatever one may think of the legitimacy of the West’s interventions in the Islamic world over the last sixty years, it is an undeniable fact that a growing number of Muslims have shared Julian’s experience. They too have witnessed the death of their loved ones at the hands of Christians or their surrogates. From this perspective, the pope’s encyclical offers a concrete proposal for how Christians should live in an environment increasingly shaped by Islam, by which I mean Europe. Muslims are a growing presence in Europe, and if the demographic projections are correct, this trend will continue and accelerate. Whether Christians wish to or not, therefore, we shall be forced to formulate a response to this Islamic presence— both individually and collectively as a Church.What will be our attitude before our Muslim neighbors? This, I believe, is the unexpressed question that guides the Holy Father’s analysis of charity. His encyclical is nothing short of a pastoral plan for living among those who have been shaped by experiences analogous to those that formed the anti-Christian views of the Emperor Julian.136 women religious, and all the lay faithful” (an die bischöfe, an die priester und diakone, an die gottgeweihten personen, und an alle christgläubigen). 135 Deus Caritas Est, no. 24. 136 Shortly after the publication of Deus Caritas est, Pope Benedict explained that he chose to write an encyclical on love because our understanding of love needed to be purified, especially in its relation to faith. Faith informed by love changes us and configures us to Christ. Benedict explicitly linked this renewed conception of faith and love to the violence of our contemporary culture:“In an epoch where hostility and greed have become superpowers, an epoch where we support the abuse of religion to the point of deifying hatred, neutral rationality alone cannot protect us. We need the living God, who loved us even to death. And so, in this Encyclical, the themes ‘God,’‘Christ’ and ‘Love’ are fused together Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 399 The pope offers us what he describes as a “sacramental mysticism.” It is a mysticism centered on Christ and dedicated to loving our neighbor with the love of Christ. As noted above, this sacramental mysticism is deeply influenced by the theology of St. Augustine. Augustine develops this theology, however, in relation to martyrdom. He describes the martyrs as those who have followed the admonition to “observe carefully all that is set before you, for you also must prepare such a banquet.” Augustine then explains that the banquet is none other than the Lord of the table himself. No one has his guests feed upon himself, and yet this is precisely what Christ our Lord does; though host, he himself is both food and drink.The martyrs recognized the food and drink they were given, in order to make repayment in kind. But how can they make repayment, unless he first spends his riches on them and gives them the means to repay? . . .The Lord of the heavens directed their minds and tongues; through them he overcame the devil on earth and crowned them as martyrs in heaven.137 Augustine was writing in the context of the collapse of Roman culture in North Africa and the pastoral challenges this raised for his suffering flock. Augustine responded both by engaging his pagan contemporaries (telling them that the cause of this collapse was not the Christian religion) and by offering the Christian faithful a vision of how to live in their violent world: through a sacramental mysticism ready to die for the love of Christ. Pope Benedict, as a student of Augustine, is offering a similar proposal to his Christian flock throughout the world, a flock that—ever since September 11—finds itself in an analogous situation. In this context, the example of the Trappist monks at Tibhirine acquires special relevance. The Christian theology of martyrdom does not focus on the dying, but on the living that led to it. A Christian becomes worthy of the title “martyr” only because his violent death is the culmination of a life as the central guide of Christian faith.”“Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI to the Participants at the Meeting Promoted by the Pontifical Council Cor Unum” (Monday, 23 January 2006). Benedict developed this theme further in his address at Regensburg where he underlined that neither secular rationality nor religious fundamentalism can preserve and renew our contemporary cultures, but only the charity that flows from the eternal Logos, which renders our life and worship a “ ‘kocivg kasqeía,’ worship in harmony with the eternal Word and with our reason.” “Meeting with the Representatives of Science: Lecture of the Holy Father, Aula Magna of the University of Regensburg” (September 12, 2006). 137 Sermo 329 (PL 38, 1454–56). 400 Michael Sherwin, OP configured to the love of Christ.The murdered monks at Tibhirine were truly martyrs in this sense. Their manner of living among their Muslim neighbors offers a concrete model of the charity Pope Benedict wishes to promote. Indeed, the words of one monk to his Muslim friends well encapsulates the pope’s message: The only thing I have to say to you is the “I love you” that Jesus said to the Church. This “I love you” is not simply for us [Christians] but for the whole world—for you Mohammed, Ahmed. . . . This “I love you” is for everyone.We all need the love of God to live.138 This is not the place to relate the history of that particular North African monastery or to tell the full story of the events that led up to the monks’ deaths during Algeria’s violent civil war. I wish only to note that a small community of very diverse personalities was quietly and collectively dedicated to living lives of prayer and Christian charity in the midst of their humble Muslim neighbors. Cardinal Duval had described the Church’s vocation in Algeria as a ministry of presence, prayer, and sharing (la présence, la prière, et le partage).139 This is what the monks lived.They took care of their neighbors’ medical needs (old Brother Luc had helped at the births of several generations of villagers), helped alleviate their material poverty, attended their celebrations, shared their joys and sorrows, and prayed for them continually.The community’s prior, Christian de Chergé, also made the monastery a place of intellectual and spiritual dialogue, where Christians and Muslims met regularly to discuss their differences and prayerfully celebrate what they shared in common. The monks had no illusions about their situation. Although they were given ample warning of what might befall them, they decided to stay. A deciding factor was that the local Muslim population repeatedly begged them to remain. During the violence of that time, one Muslim villager told the monks, “If you go away, you will rob us of your hope, and we’ll loose ours.”140 Later, this same villager would simply say of the monks,“you are the branch and we are the birds.”141 In his last testament, which was to be 138 These words were expressed by Fr. Christophe Lebreton on the day of his ordi- nation. See John W. Kiser, The Monks of Tibhirine: Faith, Love, and Terror in Algeria (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 2002), 74. For a study of Fr. Lebreton’s thought, see Marie-Dominique Minassian, “La Spiritualité de Frère Christophe moinemartyr de Tibhirine: éléments d’une théologie du don” (University of Fribourg, STD dissertation in preparation). 139 Kiser, The Monks of Tibhirine, 81. 140 Ibid., 156. 141 Ibid., 163. Reflections on Deus Caritas Est 401 read in the event of his murder, Christian de Chergé forgave his executioners and expressed the wish that “Insha Allah” he and they, “like happy thieves,” would one day meet in heaven as friends. He also explained that although he did not wish to die this way, he would be grateful to them because “my death will satisfy my most burning curiosity.” At last, I will be able—if God pleases—to see the children of Islam as He sees them, illuminated in the glory of Christ, sharing in the gift of God’s Passion and of the Spirit, whose secret joy will always be to bring forth our common humanity amidst our differences.142 The pope’s encyclical invites us to begin to see this way now.We are to see even our enemies “with the eyes of Christ.”143 What would it mean for us to see our Muslim neighbors as Christ sees them? What would it mean to love them as he loves them? The pope is aware that the greater threat to Christianity than Islamic violence is a disordered Christian response to it. During his community’s discernment over whether they should remain in Algeria, Brother Paul Favre-Miville wrote home,“How far does one go to save his skin without running the risk of losing his soul?”144 In our post-9/11 world, this is a question that all Christians must face. The Twelfth Question: The Example of Mary Our Lady of the Atlas Mountains, which is what Tibhirine’s Trappist monastery is called, lies only sixty miles south of the ancient heart of Algiers known as the Casbah. To this day the vandalized statue of the Lady, whom the Muslim villagers call “Lalla Mariam,” Mother Mary, watches over the monastic compound from the nearby hilltop. A keen chronicler of the events at Tibhirine relates that “over the years, Muslim women from the surrounding villages had worn a path to her feet through the dense cork-oak forest to seek her aid and blessing.”145 It is 142 Ibid., 245. Christian de Chergé’s death brought his life to full circle. He had first come to Algeria as a French soldier during Algeria’s war of independence. A Muslim friend with whom he had many discussions once asked him,“you Christians don’t know how to pray.We never see French soldiers praying.You say you believe in God. How can you not pray if you believe in God?” (ibid., 8). That friend was subsequently murdered in retribution for having saved de Chergé's life. Fr. Christian dedicated his life to answering his friend's question. He returned to Algeria to be a witness of Christian prayer. 143 Deus Caritas Est, no. 18. 144 Kiser, The Monks of Tibhirine, 198. 145 Ibid., 82. 402 Michael Sherwin, OP appropriate, therefore, that after listing “the entire monastic movement” as bearing clear witness to the character of Christian charity, the pope ends his letter by offering the example of Mary. He describes her as “a woman who loves,” and asks his final question: “How could it be otherwise?”146 She, more than any other creature, embodies the love of God and neighbor. She was the first to be configured to the love of Christ; in her role as our mother, which Christ entrusted to her from the cross, she continues to love her neighbor with a mother’s love. As a woman honored by all three of the faiths that trace their lineage to Abraham, she can teach us how to love our neighbor as Christ does. In the grace of her son, this humble daughter of Sion is the best guide through the twisted lanes of love’s Casbah. N&V 146 Deus Caritas Est, no. 41. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 403–30 403 A Remedy for Relativism: The Cosmic, Historical, and Eschatological Dimensions of the Liturgy according to the Theologian Joseph Ratzinger G EOFFREY WAINWRIGHT Duke University Divinity School Durham, North Carolina I N HIS ADDRESS to the college of cardinals on the eve of his election as bishop of Rome, Joseph Ratzinger spoke critically of the contemporary “dictatorship of relativism.” Such relativism manifests itself not only in philosophy and in society but also in the arts. It runs counter to the Christian faith, for which truth, goodness, and beauty are permanently and universally grounded in the triune God who is the maker of all things and who has a final purpose for his human creatures.The relativist challenge summons Christians to a response that will ultimately benefit humankind.The answer may draw on resources that are intellectual and ethical but are also lodged in the liturgical tradition of the Church. Crucial to the theological vision of Joseph Ratzinger, now Pope Benedict XVI, are the cosmic, historical, and eschatological dimensions of Christian worship.These I will now explore as he sets them in relation to the crisis of late modernity. As a theologian, Joseph Ratzinger often touched on liturgical matters in the course of more general reflections. More specifically, he devoted occasional thematic pieces to the liturgy, gathered especially in the collections Das Fest des Glaubens (1981) and Ein neues Lied für den Herrn (1995).1 1 Joseph Ratzinger, Das Fest des Glaubens: Versuche zur Theologie des Gottesdienstes (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1981), in English, The Feast of Faith: Approaches to a Theology of the Liturgy, trans. Graham Harrison (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1986); and Ein neues Lied für den Herrn Christusglaube und Liturgie in der Gegenwart 404 Geoffrey Wainwright All these find some synthesis in Ratzinger’s single most systematic work in this area, Der Geist der Liturgie (2000); and this book will therefore constitute my standard reference.2 Its title—which is a reprise of the admired classic text by Romano Guardini, Vom Geist der Liturgie (1918)— may be taken as a hint that Cardinal Ratzinger judged the Catholic Church itself and its liturgical practice to be in need of a recovery of certain qualities, and even particular features, that had been lost to “the spirit of the age” in an over-hasty rush to reform on the alleged basis of the Second Vatican Council.3 The Crisis in Contemporary Culture Not surprisingly—since treatment of the liturgy entails such things as iconography and service music—Ratzinger sometimes frames his analysis of modernity in terms of the arts.We shall look first at the visual arts and what Ratzinger calls today’s “iconographic crisis of the West.”4 Then we shall hear the challenge posed to music by “the cultural revolution of recent decades.”5 Absurdity in Art A theological foundation for his critical reading of contemporary art is borrowed by Joseph Ratzinger from the Orthodox thinker Paul Evdokimov: “The light of the first day and the light of the eighth day meet in the icon. Present already in the creation is the light that will shine in its full brightness on the eighth day in the Resurrection of the Lord and in (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder, 1995), in English, A New Song for the Lord: Faith in Christ and Liturgy Today, trans. Martha M. Matesich (New York: Crossroad, 1996). 2 Joseph Ratzinger, Der Geist der Liturgie: Eine Einführung (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder, 2000), in English, The Spirit of the Liturgy, trans. John Saward (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2000). 3 In order to declare my own fundamental sympathy with the vision of Joseph Ratzinger, I hope I may be allowed to cite at the outset, without mentioning them again, some of my own writings at the intersection between systematic theology and liturgy: Eucharist and Eschatology (London: Epworth Press, 1971; 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 1981); Doxology:The Praise of God in Worship, Doctrine, and Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 1980); For Our Salvation (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1997); Worship with One Accord (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997);“Babel, Barbary, and the Word Made Flesh: Liturgy and the Redemption of the World,” Antiphon: A Journal for Liturgical Renewal 3 (1998): 5–14; “Christian Worship: Scriptural Basis and Theological Frame,” in The Oxford History of Christian Worship, ed. Geoffrey Wainwright and Karen Westerfield Tucker (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006), 1–31. 4 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 120. 5 Ibid., 147. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 405 the new world, the light that enables us to see the splendor of God.”6 In the history of Christian art, right up to the end of the Romanesque period,“there is no essential difference between East and West with regard to the question of images. . . . It is always the risen Christ, even on the Cross, to whom the community looks as the true Oriens.”7 “With the emergence of Gothic,” however,“the depiction is no longer of the Pantocrator, the Lord of all, leading us into the eighth day. It has been superseded by the image of the crucified Lord in the agony of his passion and death.”8 Again Evdokimov is cited for the view that “the turn from Platonism to Aristotelianism during the thirteenth century” played a part in this shift: Platonism sees sensible things as shadows of the eternal archetypes. In the sensible we can and should know the archetypes and rise up through the former to the latter. Aristotelianism rejects the doctrine of Ideas.The thing, composed of matter and form, exists in its own right. Through abstraction I discern the species to which it belongs. In place of seeing, by which the supersensible becomes visible in the sensible, comes abstraction.The relationship of the spiritual and the material has changed and with it man’s attitude to reality as it appears to him.9 Admittedly, late medieval art both drew upon and further nourished a popular devotion to the suffering of the incarnate God; and Ratzinger, in his reading of the historic West, does not wish either to forget “the glorious art of Gothic stained glass”: The windows of the Gothic cathedrals keep out the garishness of the light outside, while concentrating that light and using it so that the whole history of God in relation to man, from creation to the Second Coming, shines through.The walls of the church, in interplay with the sun, become an image in their own right, the iconostasis of the West, lending the place a sense of the sacred that can touch the hearts even of agnostics.10 The Renaissance, however, “did something quite new. It ‘emancipated’ man”:“Now we see the development of the ‘aesthetic’ in the modern sense, the vision of a beauty that no longer points beyond itself but is content in the end with itself. . . . Man experiences himself in his autonomy, in all his 6 Ibid., 123. 7 Ibid., 124, 125, original emphasis. 8 Ibid., 125–26. 9 Ibid., 126. 10 Ibid., 128–29. Geoffrey Wainwright 406 grandeur.”11 The Baroque, inspired by the Council of Trent, prompted an “interior renewal . . . [in] seeing”:“The altarpiece is like a window through which the world of God comes out to us. The curtain of temporality is raised, and we are allowed a glimpse into the inner life of the world of God. This art is intended to insert us into the liturgy of heaven.”12 This respite ended with “the Enlightenment [that] pushed faith into a kind of intellectual and even social ghetto. Contemporary culture turned away from the faith and trod another path, so that faith took flight in historicism, the copying of the past, or else attempted compromise or lost itself in resignation and cultural abstinence.”13 So, “today we are experiencing, not just a crisis of sacred art, but a crisis of art in general of unprecedented proportions,” and “the crisis of art for its part is a symptom of the crisis of man’s very existence”: The immense growth in man’s mastery of the material world has left him blind to the questions of life’s meaning that transcend the material world.We might almost call it a blindness of the spirit.The questions of how we ought to live, how we can overcome death, whether existence has a purpose and what it is—to all these questions there is no longer a common answer. Positivism, formulated in the name of scientific seriousness, narrows the horizon to what is verifiable, to what can be proved by experiment; it renders the world opaque. . . . Art turns into experimenting with self-created worlds, empty “creativity,” which no longer perceives the Creator Spiritus, the Creator Spirit. It attempts to take his place, and yet, in doing so, it manages to produce only what is arbitrary and vacuous, bringing home to man the absurdity of his role as creator.14 Mayhem in Music Ratzinger’s reading of the history of liturgical music, and of Western music more generally, runs parallel to his reading of iconography and the visual arts. In both East and West, vocal music rightly subserved the primordial and evangelical Word—until the point at which, in the West, “artistic freedom increasingly assert[ed] its rights, even in the liturgy”: Music was no longer developing out of prayer, but, with the new demand for artistic autonomy, was heading away from the liturgy; it was becoming an end in itself, opening the door to new, very different ways 11 Ibid., 129. 12 Ibid., 130. 13 Ibid. 14 Ibid., 130–31. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 407 of feeling and of experiencing the world. Music was alienating the liturgy from its true nature.15 Trent intervened to “make it a norm that liturgical music should be at the service of the Word; . . . and the difference between secular and sacred music was clearly affirmed.”16 A high point was reached, in both the Catholic and Protestant worlds, with Bach, Haydn, and Mozart. But danger signs were already apparent: Subjective experience and passion are still held in check by the order of the musical universe, reflecting as it does the order of the divine creation itself. But there is already the threat of invasion by the virtuoso mentality, the vanity of technique, which is no longer the servant of the whole but wants to push itself to the fore.17 Philosophically, the cosmic character of music was grounded in the Pythagorean theory—still held by St. Augustine—whereby the cosmos “was constructed mathematically, a great edifice of numbers,” and “beauty comes from meaningful inner order.” Still for Goethe, “the mathematical order of the planets and their revolutions contains a secret timbre, which is the primal form of music,” and “the music made by man must . . . be taken from the inner music and order of the universe.”18 Modern physics, from Kepler, Galileo, and Newton onward, retains a “mathematical interpretation of the universe, [which] has made possible the technological use of its powers”;19 but, among the philosophers, the nineteenth century moved away from “metaphysics” as “outdated”: Hegel now tried to interpret music as just an expression of the subject and of subjectivity. But whereas Hegel still adhered to the fundamental idea of reason as the starting point and destination of the whole enterprise, a change of direction took place with Schopenhauer that was to have momentous consequences. For him, the world is no longer grounded in reason but in Wille und Vorstellung. The will precedes reason.And music is the primordial expression of being human as such, the pure expression of the will—anterior to reason—that creates the world.20 15 Ibid., 145–46. 16 Ibid., 146. 17 Ibid. 18 Ibid., 152. 19 Ibid. 20 Ibid., 154. Geoffrey Wainwright 408 The result is the triumph of the “Dionysian” over the “Apollonian,”21 epitomized in “Rock”: “Rock” . . . is the expression of elemental passions, and at rock festivals it assumes a cultic character, a form of worship, in fact, in opposition to Christian worship. People are, so to speak, released from themselves by the experience of being part of a crowd and by the emotional shock of rhythm, noise, and special lighting effects. However, in the ecstasy of having all their defenses torn down, the participants sink, as it were, beneath the elemental force of the universe.22 In sum, we confront today an “anarchistic” theory and practice of “art,” which coincides philosophically with “deconstructionism.” Optimistically considered, the very “dissolution of the subject” might help contemporary people to “overcome the unbounded inflation of subjectivity.”23 But in the face of contemporary culture, so analyzed in terms of the arts, a more active requirement is surely made of Christians, if people are to be led again to recognize that “a relationship with the Logos, who was at the beginning, brings salvation to the subject, that is, to the person, . . . and puts us into a true relationship of communion that is ultimately grounded in Trinitarian love.”24 One urgent need is to “identify the principles of an art ordered to divine worship.”25 Logically, the prior and fundamental task is to understand and practice worship as the focal point and effective enactment of the entire nature, calling, and destiny of humankind and the world in which we are set. That is precisely how the theologian Joseph Ratzinger in his writings interprets, expounds, and promotes the rites and signs of the Christian liturgy in terms of what he calls a “symbolic theology.”26 The Three Dimensions of Christian Worship Ratzinger takes the framework for his theology of worship from the structure of the Bible and its overarching narrative; and within that general frame he interprets and expounds particular scriptural events, episodes, sayings, and gestures that bear a more or less direct reference to the liturgy, bringing out always their correspondence to the overall and 21 Ibid., 150. 22 Ibid., 148. For more on music, see Ratzinger, The Feast of Faith, 97–126 (“On the Theological Basis of Church Music”); and idem, A New Song for the Lord, chs. 6–8 (pp. 94–146). 23 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 155. 24 Ibid., 155. 25 Ibid., 131. 26 See ibid., 60–61. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 409 recurrent pattern. That pattern has three dimensions: the cosmic, the historical, and the eschatological. The themes of creation, redemption, and consummation are constantly interwoven. According to St. Irenaeus, “the glory of God is man alive, and the life of man is the vision of God”;27 and “cult,” says Joseph Ratzinger, “exists in order to communicate this vision and to give life in such a way that glory is given to God.”28 In the midst of the world, humankind is made in the image of God, and (to borrow a formulation from a different part of the Christian Tradition, the Westminster Catechism of the Reformed family) “man’s chief end is to glorify God, and to enjoy him for ever.”29 The course of human history is both conducted and corrected by the triune God, the crucial and decisive event being the incarnation, life, death, and resurrection of the Son. The story stretches from Adam through Abel, Melchizedek, Abraham and Isaac, Moses and the Exodus, Joshua and David, the Promised Land, the Exile, and the Return, to Jesus, born of Mary, crucified, risen, and again awaited. Foreshadowed by the Old Testament, the Church of the New fits in the overlap of “image” and “reality,” where the End is anticipated but still “through a glass darkly.” Against any overly realized eschatology, Ratzinger points to the sufferings and pain, and indeed the sin, guilt, and futility, in the world of the “not yet.” But hope is in place, since the “new world” has begun with the Resurrection of Christ while the promise of God’s finally being “all in all” is secure. Our author fixes on two major signs with liturgical (and intrinsically Christological) reference that bring the three dimensions—cosmic, historical, eschatological—comprehensively together: the sun and the Cross. In each case, the range is both temporal and spatial. The Sun Ratzinger makes much of orientation as the traditional Christian direction of prayer. A biblical basis is found in Psalm 19:6–7, where “the sun comes forth like a bridegroom leaving his chamber. . . . Its rising is from the end of the heavens, and its circuit to the end of them.” Christians interpret this psalm of “creation” and “law” in terms of “Christ, who is the living Word, the eternal Logos, and thus the true light of history, who came forth in Bethlehem from the bridal chamber of the Virgin Mother and now pours out his light on all the world.”30 Moreover, the Christ 27 Irenaeus, Adversus haereses, 4.20.7, quoted in Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 18. 28 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 18. 29 From the opening exchange of the Shorter Cathechism of the Westminster Assembly (1647–48). 30 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 68. Geoffrey Wainwright 410 who “rose” in his Resurrection will also return “from the east” (cf. Mt 24:27–31).Thus, liturgically: The fact that we find Christ in the symbol of the rising sun is the indication of a Christology defined eschatologically. Praying toward the east means going to meet the coming Christ.The liturgy, turned toward the east, effects entry, so to speak, into the procession of history toward the future, the New Heaven and the New Earth, which we encounter in Christ. It is a prayer of hope of the pilgrim as he walks in the direction shown us by the life, Passion, and Resurrection of Christ.31 In fact, orientation in prayer signifies that “cosmos and saving history belong together”: “The cosmos is praying with us. It, too, is waiting for redemption. It is precisely this cosmic dimension that is essential to Christian liturgy. It is never performed solely in the self-made world of man. It is always a cosmic liturgy.”32 Practically, Cardinal Ratzinger deeply regretted the post-Vatican II move to the priest’s celebrating the liturgy versus populum, attributing the priest’s westward volte-face to the misunderstood consequence of an accident of terrain in the Roman basilica of St. Peter’s.33 He appealed to the liturgical historians Joseph Jungmann, Cyrille Vogel, and Louis Bouyer for the view that the important thing, traditionally and theologically, was that the priest and the entire congregation be “facing in the same direction, knowing that together they were in a procession toward the Lord.They did not close themselves into a circle; they did not gaze at one another; but as the pilgrim people of God they set off for the Oriens, for the Christ who comes to meet us.”34 As history and the cosmos cohere in Christ, so do time and space intertwine in the Christian calendar, where once again the sun serves to symbolize Christ through temporal rhythms just as it did in spatial direction.The Gospel accounts insist on “the first day of the week” as the day when the Lord’s Resurrection was discovered;35 Justin Martyr might have been quoted for the weekly Eucharistic assembly as occurring on “the day called after the sun, because it is the first day, the day on which God transformed darkness and matter, and made the world, and Jesus Christ our Savior rose from the dead.”36 Then, too, Sunday is the “third 31 Ibid., 69. 32 Ibid., 70. 33 Ibid., 76f. 34 Ibid., 80. 35 Mt 28:1; Mk 16:2, 9; Lk 24:1; Jn 20:1. 36 Justin Martyr, First Apology, 67. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 411 day” (cf. 1 Cor 15:4), when “seen from the Cross”; Ratzinger notes that “in the Old Testament the third day was regarded as the day of theophany, the day when God entered into the world after the time of expectation.”37 Finally, Sunday, in relation to the whole preceding week, is the “eighth day”38 and thus, according to the patristic designation, the “new time that has dawned with the Resurrection,” “looking toward the final consummation.”39 Sunday thus embodies “a unique synthesis of the remembrance of history, the recalling of creation, and the theology of hope.” It is “the day on which the Lord comes among his own and invites them into his ‘liturgy,’ into his glorification of God, and communicates himself to them.”40 In the annual rhythm, cosmos and history have their most charged encounter at Easter, “the Christian Passover,” where lunar calculations— with the moon a “symbol of transitoriness”41—also play a part. At the Exodus from Egypt, Israel began “its own journey in history as the People of God.”42 Christ defined his paschal death—which would have “a significance for history, for mankind, for the world”43—as his “hour.”44 The theologian Ratzinger cites Pope Gregory the Great as pointing out that “according to the Bible, Easter should fall in the first month, . . . the time when the sun is passing through the first part of the Zodiac—the sign of Aries [the Ram]”: “The constellation in the heavens seemed to speak, in advance and for all time, of the Lamb of God, who takes away the sins of the world ( Jn 1:29).”45 At Easter, “transitoriness is taken up into what never passes away. Death becomes resurrection and passes into eternal life”:46 “The ‘hour’ of Jesus makes its appearance, again and again, within the unity of cosmic and historical time. Through the feast we enter into the rhythm of creation and into God’s plan for human history.”47 In connection with Christmas also, the other focal point of the calendar (for Christians confess the one Christ inseparably as the Incarnate Son 37 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 96. 38 Ibid. 39 Ibid., 97. 40 Ibid., 95. Chapter 4 of Ratzinger, A New Song for the Lord, is devoted to “the meaning of Sunday for Christian prayer and life” and includes a current reflection on “weekend culture and the Christian Sunday.” 41 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 101. 42 Ibid. 43 Ibid., 98. 44 Ibid., 101. 45 Ibid., 100. 46 Ibid., 101. 47 Ibid., 103. Geoffrey Wainwright 412 and Redeemer), factors to do with solstice and equinox played their part in fixing the festal celebration (scholars differ over the details). St. Jerome is cited for a Christmas sermon: “Even creation approves our preaching. The universe itself bears witness to the truth of our words. Up to this day the dark days increase, but from this day the darkness decreases. . . . The light advances, while the night retreats.”48 The corresponding date of the Annunciation—March 25—matches an ancient reckoning of the day of creation. In these ways, the cosmic serves the historical. Only in history is the cosmos given its center and goal. To believe in the Incarnation means to be bound to Christianity’s origins, their particularity, and, in human terms, their contingency. Here is the guarantee that we are not chasing myths; that God really has acted in our history and taken our time into his hands. Only over the bridge of this “once for all” [ephapax/semel] can we come into the “forever” [aiônios/semper] of God’s mercy.49 Seasonally, the world’s spring and autumn are connected by Christ. St. John’s Gospel and the Epistle to the Hebrews interpret Christ’s “hour” not only with a reference to Passover (spring) but also in light of the Day of Atonement (autumn):“The autumn of declining time becomes a new beginning, while the spring, as the time of the Lord’s death, now points to the end of time, to the autumn of the world, in which, according to the Fathers, Christ came among us.”50 The lectionary readings concerning “the sowing of the seed”—“which is [also] a metaphor for the spreading of the Gospel”—can be accommodated in both spring and autumn, for “in both seasons the mystery of hope is at work and reaches its proper depth in the waning year, which leads beyond decline to a new beginning”: It would be a great work of inculturation to develop this approach and to bring it into the common consciousness of Christians in the two hemispheres, southern and northern.The South could help the North to discover a new breadth and depth in the mystery, thus enabling us all to draw afresh on its richness.51 With regard to the solar and related symbolism thus recalled by Ratzinger, it must be admitted, sociologically, that it is difficult in late 48 Ibid., 108. 49 Ibid., 104; cf. 56. 50 Ibid., 104. 51 Ibid., 105. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 413 modernity to feel with quite the same force as earlier generations the impact of the sun and the seasons.Technology brings us indoor living, artificial lighting, year-round provision of an entire range of foods. But amid this redeployment of space we are still dependent on the created “cosmos” in many ways, as ecological concerns about global warming and the depletion of earthly resources demonstrate; we have an inheritance from the past and a responsibility for the future. Moreover, the passage of time remains an ineluctable experience for every human being, and “history” is no less real for having assumed geopolitical proportions. The universal frame is still there that allows and requires these matters to be considered in a consistent, coherent way; and the Christian liturgy provides a place and an occasion for such attention and an inspiration and guide for appropriate living. The Cross “The most basic Christian gesture in prayer,” says Joseph Ratzinger, “is and always will be the sign of the Cross”: It is a way of confessing Christ crucified with one’s very body, in accordance with the programmatic words of St. Paul . . . [1 Corinthians 1:23f.; 2:2]. To seal oneself with the sign of the Cross is a visible and public Yes to him who suffered for us; to him who in the body has made God’s love visible, even to the utmost; to the God who reigns not by destruction but by the humility of suffering and love, which is stronger than all the power of the world and wiser than all the calculating intelligence of men.52 A recurrent picture in Ratzinger’s writings is that of the pierced heart of Christ on the Cross (cf. Jn 19:34–37). From the opened side flow with the water and the blood, according to a patristic interpretation, the constitutive sacraments of Baptism and Eucharist.53 The image of the wounded Christ stays to the end, for “they shall look on him whom they pierced” (Rev 1:7). “And I,” said Jesus, “when I am lifted up from the earth, will draw all men to myself ” ( Jn 12:32). Ratzinger cites Lactantius from the fourth century:“In his Passion God spread out his arms and thus embraced the globe as a sign that a future people, from the rising of the sun to its setting, would gather under his wings.”54 A Methodist may think of Charles Wesley’s words: 52 Ibid., 177. 53 Cf., for example, ibid., 84 and 222. 54 Ibid., 182–83. Geoffrey Wainwright 414 The arms of love that compass me Would all mankind embrace.55 The cosmic scope of the Cross is already found in St. Irenaeus,“the real founder of systematic theology, in its Catholic form,” who in his Demonstration of the Apostolic Preaching echoes St. Paul’s teaching in Ephesians 3:18ff.The crucified Christ is the very Word of Almighty God, who penetrates our universe by an invisible presence.And for this reason he embraces the whole world, its breadth and length, its height and depth, for through the Word of God all things are guided into order. And the Son of God is crucified in them, since, in the form of the Cross, he is imprinted upon all things.56 St. Justin Martyr, in his First Apology, found a “prophecy of the Cross” already in Plato’s “idea of a cross inscribed upon the cosmos,”57 as Ratzinger explains: Plato took this from the Pythagorean tradition, which in its turn had a connection with the traditions of the ancient East. First, there is an astronomical statement about the two great movements of the stars with which ancient astronomy was familiar: the ecliptic (the great circle in the heavens along which the sun appears to run its course) and the orbit of the earth. These two intersect and form together the Greek letter Chi, which is written in the form of a cross (like an X). . . . Plato, again following more ancient traditions, connected this with the image of the deity.58 Our author recalls also the idea from Indian religions of “the cross-shaped tree of the world that holds everything together.”59 From all these signs he concludes that “the cosmos speaks to us of the Cross, and the Cross solves for us the enigma of the cosmos. . . .When we open our eyes, we can read the message of Christ in the language of the universe, and conversely, Christ grants us understanding of the message of creation.”60 In late modernity, the natural sciences offer us speculative accounts of beginnings and endings—and of apparently universal structures at the macroscopic and microscopic levels—that seem to be grounded in obser55 From the hymn “Jesus! the Name High over All” by Charles Wesley. 56 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 182. 57 Ibid., 180; cf. Timaeus, 34ab and 36bc. 58 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 180–81. 59 Ibid., 182. 60 Ibid., 181. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 415 vations and calculations not available hitherto. But our common human questions of direction and purpose, of suffering and moral evil, remain. Here certainly are pistes de recherche for theologians to pursue in company with interested natural scientists if, with the aid of the Christian liturgy, we are to find (as Joseph Ratzinger does) the sacrificial love of God inscribed in the universe and offering us the way of salvation. It must and may be hoped that poets, musicians, and visual artists, working within the semantic context set by the faith, teaching, and liturgy of the Church, will find timely ways to embody valid new insights so as to grip the minds and imaginations of the contemporary communities at worship. Matter and Spirit Our location in the universe, our temporal existence as embodied creatures, our calling to an eternal destiny with the transcendent God: All these things raise questions about matter and spirit, which find the offer of an answer in a Christian liturgy that bears cosmic, historical, and eschatological dimensions. Joseph Ratzinger’s fundamental understanding of worship is that of logikê latreia—the “reasonable service” of God.61 In the light of Christ, the notion found in Romans 12:1 achieves two things: First, it resolves the Old Testament paradox epitomized in Psalm 51:15–19, with its tension between animal sacrifices at the temple-altar and the spiritual sacrifice of heart and lips;62 and second, it borrows from the Greek mind “the idea of a mystical union with the Logos, the very meaning of all things,”63 while yet avoiding the Hellenistic temptation that “allows the body to fall into insubstantiality.”64 On those terms, “spiritual worship”—a Christologically grounded “worship in spirit and in truth”65—became “the Christian response to the cultic crisis of the whole ancient world.”66 It continues to offer a means to contain and counter the disorder of relativism at all levels: The sacrifice is the “word,” the word of prayer, which goes up from man to God, embodying the whole of man’s existence and enabling him to become “word” ( logos) in himself. It is man, conforming himself to logos and becoming logos through faith, who is the true sacrifice, the true glory of God in the world. . . . 61 Cf. especially ibid., 45–50. 62 Cf. also Ps 50:12–15. 63 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 46. 64 Ibid., 47. 65 Jn 4:23; cf. 7:39; 14:6. 66 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 45–46. 416 Geoffrey Wainwright The idea of the sacrifice of the logos becomes a full reality only in the Logos incarnatus, the Word who is made flesh and draws “all flesh” into the glorification of God.When that happens, the Logos is more than just the “meaning” behind and above things. Now he himself has entered into flesh, has become bodily. He takes up into himself our sufferings and hopes, all the yearning of creation, and bears it to God.The two themes that Psalm 51 (50) could not reconcile, the two themes that throughout the Old Testament keep running toward one another but do not meet, now really converge. Now “word” is no longer just the representation of something else, of what is bodily. In Jesus’ self-surrender on the Cross, the Word is united with the entire reality of human life and suffering.There is no longer an Ersatz cult. Now the vicarious sacrifice of Jesus takes us up and leads us into that likeness with God, that transformation into love, which is the only true adoration. In virtue of Jesus’ Cross and Resurrection, the Eucharist is the meeting point of all lines that lead from the Old Covenant, indeed from the whole of man’s religious history. Here at last is right worship, ever longed for and yet surpassing our powers: adoration “in spirit and truth.”67 The mention of the Eucharist suffices to hint at the sacraments proper, which will figure in our discussion later, but first we shall look more generally at “the psychosomatic unity of man,” which “express[es] itself in the bodily gesture” as “the bearer of spiritual meaning” in worship.68 Ratzinger devotes the final section of The Spirit of the Liturgy to “the body and the liturgy”; and there he writes in his most catechetical style, occasionally anecdotal, sometimes autobiographical, and here and there (it 67 Ibid., 46, 47; cf. 57, 61. One may just wonder whether, in insisting so strongly and persuasively on Christian worship as what the Roman canon calls oblatio rationabilis, Joseph Ratzinger has been led to underplay, both historically and theologically, the “meal” character of the rite that Protestants have ecumenically learned to call “the Eucharist” but which they have more customarily designated “the Lord’s Supper.” It is surely well within scriptural and traditional bounds to understand (“dogmatic content”) and practice (“liturgical form”) the sacrament as importantly—albeit not exclusively—a foretaste of the heavenly banquet, the marriage supper of the Lamb (cf., for example, Mt 26:29; Rev 19:7–9). Again, the present sacramental anticipation of the communion to be lived and enjoyed in the pax of the City of God provides a context in and from which to begin the overcoming of—this time—social relativism. Ratzinger’s brief (and, to my mind, unnecessary) critical remark on the “meal” question in The Spirit of the Liturgy, 78ff., derives from his much fuller arguments in favor of eucharistia as the governing category of the rite in “Form and Content in the Eucharistic Celebration,” in The Feast of Faith, 33–60 (“Gestalt und Gehalt der eucharistischen Feier,” in Das Fest des Glaubens, 31–54). 68 Cf. Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 190. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 417 will be thought today) even mildly idiosyncratic.69 Among liturgical postures and gestures, it is kneeling and bowing which receive most attention from our author. The key passage from Scripture is “the great hymn of Christ in Philippians 2:6–11”:70 All bend the knee before Jesus, the One who descended, and bow to him precisely as the true God above all gods. . . .The Christian liturgy is a cosmic liturgy precisely because it bends the knee before the crucified and exalted Lord. Here is the center of authentic culture—the culture of truth.The humble gesture by which we fall at the feet of the Lord inserts us into the true path of the life of the cosmos.71 The supplices—our being “bowed low”—is the bodily expression, so to speak, of what the Bible calls humility (cf., “he humbled himself,” Phil 2:8). . . . Humility is the ontologically appropriate attitude, the state that corresponds to the truth about man, and as such it becomes a fundamental attitude of Christian existence. St. Augustine constructed his whole Christology, indeed I would say his entire apologetics for Christianity, upon the concept of humilitas. He took up the teaching of the ancients, of the Greek and Roman world, that hybris—self-glorifying pride—is the real sin of all sins, as we see in exemplary form in the fall of Adam. Arrogance, the ontological lie by which man makes himself God, is overcome by the humility of God, who makes Himself the slave, who bows down before us.The man who wants to come close to God . . . must likewise learn to bend, for God Himself has bent down. In the gesture of humble love, in the washing of feet, in which He kneels at our feet—that is where we find Him.72 Our author is well aware that learning again to kneel and to bow will not come easily to “modern man.”73 Even post-Vatican II liturgists may have undervalued such “a physical reminder of the spiritual attitude essential to faith.”74 “In our times,” observes Ratzinger,“in a variety of forms, the fascination of Gnosticism is at work.”75 Attitudes toward the human body are tell-tale in this respect. If I may just this once quote myself: 69 See, for example, ibid., 214–16, in favor of an occasional quasi-silent recitation of the canon of the Mass. 70 Ibid., 192. 71 Ibid., 193. 72 Ibid., 205–6. 73 Ibid., cf. 194, 206. 74 Ibid., 206. 75 Ibid., 32. Geoffrey Wainwright 418 The transformation of our senses by the Word of God takes on a particular poignancy in our contemporary North American and West European culture.We live in a very sensate and sensualist society.We are in some ways absorbed in our senses, a people defined by materialism and sexuality.Yet in other ways we are curiously detached from our bodies, as though we were not really affected by what happens to us in our bodies or what we do in them. The contradiction between indulging our senses and disowning our bodies is only an apparent one. If our bodies are not us, then we are not responsible in and for them; and that irresponsibility may assume the character of license or, indeed, of withdrawal. The same phenomenon occurred in the Gnosticism of the second century. Saint Irenaeus countered its threat to Christianity by retelling the authentic biblical tale of the divine Word’s history ad extra as the single sweep of universal creation, the making of humankind, the incarnation in Jesus the Christ, the constitution of the Church, the institution and practice of the sacraments, and the awaited resurrection of the body.76 “The body,” says Ratzinger, “must be trained . . . for the resurrection.”77 “Laid hold of by the Logos and for the Logos in our very bodies,” we meanwhile learn to cooperate with the will and action of God:“The true liturgical action is the deed of God, and for that very reason the liturgy of faith always reaches beyond the cultic act into everyday life, which must itself become ‘liturgical,’ a service for the transformation of the world.”78 It is noteworthy that twentieth-century Orthodox theologians took to speaking of “the liturgy after the Liturgy.” For human beings, as corporeal creatures, the body is the point of contact with the rest of material creation. We apply matter to ourselves, we take it into ourselves, we work outwardly upon it. Matter is neither to be absolutized nor to be despised. In conjunction with the words of the Word, material elements—which “the Lord himself chose”—serve as sacramental signs: water, (olive) oil, (wheaten) bread, and wine: Whereas water is the common element of life for the whole earth and is therefore suitable in all places as a door of entry to communion with Christ, in the case of the three other elements we are dealing with the typical gifts of Mediterranean culture. We encounter this triad in explicit association in the glorious psalm of creation, Psalm 104, where the Psalmist thanks God for giving man the food of the earth and “wine to gladden the heart of man, oil to make his face shine, and bread 76 Geoffrey Wainwright, For Our Salvation, 18. The first five chapters of that book are devoted—indulging in a pun—to “The Senses of the Word.” 77 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 176. 78 Ibid., 175. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 419 to strengthen man’s heart” (v. 15). These three elements of Mediterranean life express the goodness of creation, in which we receive the goodness of the Creator Himself. And now they become the gift of an even higher goodness, a goodness that makes our face shine anew in likeness to the “anointed” God, to his beloved Son, Jesus Christ, a goodness that changes the bread and wine of the earth into the Body and Blood of the Redeemer, so that, through the Son made man, we may have communion with the triune God Himself.79 Thus both universality and particularity are respected—“geographically,” culturally. “In the interplay of culture and history,” however, “history has priority”: The elements become sacraments through connection with the unique history of God in relation to man in Jesus Christ. . . . Outwardly, that history may seem fortuitous, but it is the form of history willed by God, and for us it is the trustworthy trace that he has imprinted on the earth, the guarantee that we are not thinking up things for ourselves but are truly touched by God and come into touch with Him. Precisely through what is particular and once-for-all, the here and now, we emerge from the “ever and never” vagueness of mythology. It is with this particular face, with this particular human form, that Christ comes to us, and precisely thus does he make us brethren beyond all boundaries.80 That brings us to the personal and social constitution of humanity, which we may follow out first in the structures of the world and then in the structures of the Church. Once more we see how these are envisaged by Joseph Ratzinger in terms of liturgy. A Social Covenant In retelling the story of the Exodus,81 Ratzinger insists that Israel’s deliverance from Egypt was for the sake of worship, in order to “serve God.”82 In “the wilderness of Sinai” (Ex 19:1), Israel “discovers the kind of sacrifice God wants.”83 From the mountaintop, God speaks and makes his will known to the people in the Ten Commandments (cf. Ex 20:1–17) and, through the mediation of Moses, makes a covenant with them (cf. Ex 1)—“a covenant concretized in a minutely regulated form of worship”; “cult, liturgy in the proper sense, is part of this worship, but so too is life according to the will of 79 Ibid., 223. 80 Ibid., 224. 81 Cf. ibid., 15–23. 82 So, Ex 7:16; 8:1, 25–27; 9:1, 13; 10:3, 24–26. 83 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 17. Geoffrey Wainwright 420 God.”84 This service of God was to be maintained in the land across the Jordan first promised to Abraham, for the land will be given to the people as “a place for the worship of the true God,”“the place where God reigns,”“the realm of obedience, where God’s will is done and the right kind of human existence developed.”85 Ratzinger draws broad conclusions from the covenant ordered on Sinai.“Law and ethics do not hold together when they are not anchored in the liturgical center and inspired by it”:86 On Sinai the people receive not only instructions about worship, but also an all-embracing rule of law and life. Only thus can it become a people.A people without a common rule of law cannot live. It destroys itself in anarchy, which is a parody of freedom, its exaltation to the point of abolition.When every man lives without law, every man lives without freedom. . . . In the ordering of the covenant on Sinai, the three aspects of worship, law, and ethics are inseparably interwoven. . . .When morality and law do not originate in a God-ward perspective, they degrade man, because they rob him of his highest measure and his highest capacity, deprive him of any vision of the infinite and eternal. This seeming liberation subjects him to the dictatorship of the ruling majority, to shifting human standards, which inevitable end up doing him violence.87 In “the modern age,” says Ratzinger, we witness “the total secularization of the law and the exclusion of any God-ward perspective from the fashioning of the law.”88 On the ethical front, Ratzinger, in another context,89 recalls Goethe’s Faustian recasting of the Johannine “In the beginning was the Word” to “In the beginning was the Deed”: In our own times this continues in the attempt to replace “orthodoxy” by “orthopraxy”—there is no common faith any more (because truth is unattainable), only common praxis. By contrast, for Christian faith, as Guardini shows so penetratingly in his masterly early work, The Spirit of the Liturgy, logos has precedence over ethos. When this is reversed, Christianity is turned upside down.90 84 Ibid. 85 Ibid. 86 Ibid., 20. 87 Ibid., 18–19. 88 Ibid., 18. 89 Ibid., 154–55. 90 Ibid., 155. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 421 It seems that “Christendom” needs to hear (again) the warning contained in the story of the golden calf (Ex 32): The cult conducted by the high priest Aaron is not meant to serve any of the false gods of the heathen.The apostasy is more subtle. . . .And yet it is a falling away from the worship of God to idolatry. This apostasy, which outwardly is scarcely perceptible, has two causes. First, there is a violation of the prohibition of images.The people cannot cope with the invisible, remote, and mysterious God. They want to bring Him down into their own world, into what they can see and understand. Worship is no longer going up to God, but drawing God down into one’s own world. He must be there when He is needed, and He must be the kind of God that is needed. Man is using God, and in reality, even if it is not outwardly discernible, he is placing himself above God. . . . [Second,] the worship of the golden calf is a self-generated cult. When Moses stays away for too long, and God Himself becomes inaccessible, the people just fetch Him back.Worship becomes a feast that the community gives itself, a festival of self-affirmation. Instead of being worship of God, it becomes a circle closed in on itself: eating, drinking, and making merry. The dance around the golden calf is an image of this self-seeking worship. It is a kind of banal self-gratification. . . . Ultimately, it is no longer concerned with God but with giving oneself a nice little alternative world, manufactured from one’s own resources. Then liturgy really does become pointless, just fooling around. Or still worse it becomes an apostasy from the living God, an apostasy in sacral disguise. All that is left in the end is frustration, a feeling of emptiness.There is no experience of that liberation which always takes place when man encounters the living God.91 This is the background against which to see Cardinal Ratzinger’s insistence on the “givenness” of instituted and traditional rites in face of the “creativity” (or, more sharply, the “Beliebigkeit”) of some sophisticated contemporary pastors and congregations.92 Churches are summoned to permanent vigilance concerning what is required of them by the divine covenant that makes them—and their liturgical assemblies—the place in which, under God, persons and societies are shaped for life in this world and beyond. The Ecclesial Community The contemporary search for personal and social “identity”—often individualistically and divisively conducted—is offered an available response in 91 Ibid., 22–23. 92 Cf., for example, ibid., 80 and 159–70. Geoffrey Wainwright 422 baptism as insertion into the paschal mystery of Christ and membership of his Body, the Church. Joseph Ratzinger brings these things together thus: In the light of Easter, Christians see themselves as people who truly live. They have found their way out of an existence that is more death than life. They have discovered real life: “And this is eternal life, that they know You, the only true God, and Jesus Christ whom You have sent” ( Jn 17:3). Deliverance from death is at the same time deliverance from the captivity of individualism, from the prison of self, from the incapacity to love and make a gift of oneself.Thus Easter becomes the great feast of Baptism, in which man, as it were, enacts the passage through the Red Sea, emerges from his own existence into communion with Christ and so into communion with all who belong to Christ. Resurrection builds communion. It creates the new People of God.The grain of wheat that dies all alone does not remain alone but brings much fruit with it.The risen Lord does not remain alone. He draws all mankind to himself and so creates a new universal communion of men.93 A Protestant Christian may express gratitude for two liturgical gifts in particular from Catholicism over the last sixty years: first, the revitalization of the Paschal Vigil, begun already under Pius XII, with its rehearsal of the biblical story of salvation, and as an occasion for baptisms and baptismal renewals; and then the Rite of the Christian Initiation of Adults, created after Vatican II, which has contributed to a recovery of catechesis, whether initial or remedial, in an era of needed reevangelization. It may be significant that these two features largely escaped strictures from Cardinal Ratzinger in his concerns over some developments in recent Catholic practice. One might just regret that he did not actively welcome the ecumenical scope of the Easter Vigil and a strengthened initiatory practice, for his commitment to the cause of authentic Christian and ecclesial unity in the truth of the Gospel is not in doubt. Meanwhile, here is a pastoral word that all Christians may hear from the theologian who is now bishop of Rome: When we make the sign of the Cross, we accept our Baptism anew; Christ from the Cross draws us, so to speak, to himself (cf. Jn 13:32) and thus into communion with the living God. For Baptism and the sign of the Cross, which is a kind of summing up and re-acceptance of Baptism, are above all a divine event: the Holy Spirit leads us to Christ, and Christ opens the door to the Father. God is no longer the “unknown god”; He has a name.We are allowed to call upon Him, and He calls us.94 93 Ibid., 102. 94 Ibid., 178. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 423 Or again, concerning the adoption of the orans posture in prayer,“one of the primal gestures of man in calling upon God and found in virtually every part of the religious world”: By extending our arms, we resolve to pray with the Crucified, to unite ourselves to his “mind” (Phil 2:5). In the arms of Christ, stretched on the Cross, Christians see a twofold meaning. In his case, too, this gesture is the radical form of worship, the unity of his human will with the will of the Father, but at the same time these arms are open toward us— they are the wide embrace by which Christ wants to draw us to himself ( Jn 12:32).Worship of God and love of neighbor—the content of the chief commandment, which sums up the law and the prophets—coincide in this gesture. To open oneself to God, to surrender oneself completely to Him, is at the same time—the two things cannot be separated—to devote oneself to one’s neighbor.This combining of the two directions of love in the gesture of Christ on the Cross reveals, in a bodily and visible way, the new depth of Christian prayer and thus expresses the inner law of our own prayer.95 Finally, the ecclesial and human community, we are not surprised to read, has for Ratzinger not only a synchronic but also a diachronic—and ultimately eschatological—range. Gathered in the Holy Spirit (though, with the notable exception of the chapter on “Music and Liturgy,” epiclesis is more an implicit than an explicit category in Ratzinger’s writing— despite the title of our principal book!), the liturgical assembly embodies and enacts the anamnesis of Christ, which has past, present, and future reference. Ratzinger speaks often of “the communion of the saints.” Of icons, he writes that “the images of biblical history have pride of place in sacred art, but the latter also includes the history of the saints, which is an unfolding of the history of Jesus Christ, the fruit born throughout history by the dead grain of wheat.”96 Or of the Eucharist:“Eucharistic personalism is a drive toward union, the overcoming of the barriers between God and man, between ‘I’ and ‘thou’ in the new ‘we’ of the communion of the saints. . . . Only the true Body in the Sacrament can build up the true Body of the new City of God.”97 Recalling his own priestly and episcopal ordinations, and the singing of the Litany of the Saints by the whole congregation, Joseph Ratzinger wrote: The fact that the praying Church was calling upon all the saints, that the prayer of the Church really was enveloping and embracing me, was 95 Ibid., 203–4. 96 Ibid., 132. 97 Ibid., 87–88. Geoffrey Wainwright 424 a wonderful consolation. In my incapacity, which had to be expressed in the bodily gesture of prostration, this prayer, this presence of all the saints, of the living and the dead, was a wonderful strength—it was the only thing that could, as it were, lift me up. Only the presence of the saints with me made possible the path that lay before me.98 And his own unforeseen election to the chair of Peter gives a special poignancy to what he wrote, in historical and theological vein, about the location of that chair in the basilica of the Vatican: In St. Peter’s, during the pontificate of St. Gregory the Great (590–604), the altar was moved nearer to the bishop’s chair, probably for the simple reason that he was supposed to stand as much as possible above the tomb of St. Peter.This was an outward and visible expression of the truth that we celebrate the Sacrifice of the Lord in the communion of saints, a communion spanning all times and ages. The custom of erecting an altar above the tombs of the martyrs probably goes back a long way and is an outcome of the same motivation. Throughout history the martyrs continue Christ’s self-oblation; they are like the Church’s living altar, made not of stones but of men, who have become members of the Body of Christ and thus express a new kind of cultus: sacrifice is humanity become love with Christ.99 Ratzinger cites St. Augustine for the view that “the true ‘sacrifice’ is the civitas Dei, that is, love-transformed mankind, the divinization of creation, and the surrender of all things to God: God all in all (1 Cor 15:28). That is the purpose of the world. That is the essence of sacrifice and worship.”100 We come thus to a final reading of the liturgy in the three dimensions of cosmos, history, and consummation. A Universal Prospect History is conceived by Joseph Ratzinger as the cosmic story of created humankind en marche toward the City of God and the New World that has already dawned in Christ. Within the great “arc from exitus to reditus,”101 the “great historical process by which the world moves toward the fulfillment of God being ‘all in all,’ ”102 the smaller units “carry within themselves the great rhythm of the whole, give it concrete forms that are 98 Ibid., 188. 99 Ibid., 76. 100 Ibid., 28. 101 Ibid., 33. 102 Ibid., 59. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 425 ever new, and so provide it with the force of its movement.”103 These include “the lives of the different cultures and communities of human history, in which the drama of beginning, development, and end is played out.”104 Given “the Christ-event and the growth of the Church out of all the nations,”105 Christian liturgy is a liturgy of promise fulfilled, of a quest, the religious quest of human history, reaching its goal. But it remains a liturgy of hope. It, too, bears within it the mark of impermanence. The new Temple, not made by human hands, does exist, but it is also still under construction.The great gesture of embrace emanating from the Crucified has not yet reached its goal; it has only just begun. Christian liturgy is liturgy on the way, a liturgy of pilgrimage toward the transfiguration of the world, which will only take place when God is “all in all.”106 In this universal historical context a recurrent liturgical trope of Ratzinger’s is “the procession of the nations.”107 The feast of the Epiphany celebrates, among other things, the arrival of the Magi as “the beginning of the Church of the Gentiles, the procession of the nations to the God of Israel (cf. Is 60)”: The narrative of the adoration of the Magi became important for Christian thought, because it shows the inner connection between the wisdom of the nations and the Word of promise in Scripture; because it shows how the language of the cosmos and the truth-seeking thought of man lead to Christ. The mysterious star could become the symbol for these connections and once again emphasize that the language of the cosmos and the language of the human heart trace their descent from the Word of the Father, who in Bethlehem came forth from the silence of God and assembled the fragments of our human knowledge into a complete whole.108 How, in this (liturgical) light, are we to distinguish between legitimate diversity, problematic pluralism, and the castigated “relativism” in matters of religion and culture? It is clear that the test must be Christological (and, derivatively, ecclesial); and that is precisely what we find stated in the declaration Dominus Iesus emanating from the Congregation for the Doctrine of 103 Ibid., 29. 104 Ibid., 30. 105 Ibid., 54. 106 Ibid., 50. 107 See, for example, ibid., 76, 110. 108 Ibid., 110. 426 Geoffrey Wainwright the Faith in the year 2000 while Cardinal Ratzinger was its prefect: “On the Unicity and Salvific Universality of Jesus Christ and the [Catholic] Church.” While “the Catholic Church rejects nothing that is true and holy” in non-Christian religions (no. 2, citing Vatican II, Nostra aetate, no. 2), Dominus Iesus declares that “the Church’s constant missionary proclamation is endangered today by relativistic theories which seek to justify religious pluralism, not only de facto but also de iure,” so as to lose “the definitive and complete character of the revelation of Jesus Christ”: The roots of these problems are to be found in certain presuppositions of both a philosophical nature and theological nature, which hinder the understanding and acceptance of the revealed truth. Some of these can be mentioned: the conviction of the elusiveness and inexpressibility of divine truth, even by Christian Revelation; relativistic attitudes toward truth itself, according to which what is true for some would not be true for others; the radical opposition posited between the logical mentality of the West and the symbolic mentality of the East; the subjectivism which, by regarding reason as the only source of knowledge, becomes incapable of raising “its gaze to the heights, not daring to rise to the truth of being” [John Paul II, Fides et ratio, no. 5]; the difficulty in understanding and accepting the presence of definitive and eschatological events in history; the metaphysical emptying of the historical Incarnation of the Eternal Logos, reduced to a mere appearing of God in history; the eclecticism of those who, in theological research, uncritically absorb ideas from a variety of philosophical and theological contexts without regard for consistency, systematic connection, or compatibility with Christian truth; finally, the tendency to read and to interpret Sacred Scripture outside the Tradition and magisterium of the Church.109 Our question in this essay has to be: How is all that to be properly dealt with, and countered, in the realm of liturgy—and, through liturgy, in the realm of an entire culture? How are Christian worship—and the entire faith—to cope with a culture and its intellectual, social, and religious components? How, at our particular time and place, are the distinctions to be drawn between diversity-in-unity and an ideologically affirmed pluralism that amounts to relativism? The theologian Joseph Ratzinger stated some principles, and gave some examples, of his own discernment in the book to which we have been devoting our principal attention. In principle, he detects an early Christian realization that “the paths of religious history converged on Christ, . . . that philosophy and religion gave faith the images and concepts in which alone it could understand itself.”110 Yet 109 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Dominus Iesus, no. 4. 110 Ratzinger, Spirit of the Liturgy, 183. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 427 he is very suspicious of what recent and contemporary liturgists have meant by “inculturation”;111 and he proposes an alternative: The first and most fundamental way in which inculturation takes place is the unfolding [Entfaltung] of a Christian culture in all its different dimensions: a culture of cooperation, of social concern, of respect for the poor, of the overcoming of class differences, of care for the suffering and dying; a culture that educates mind and heart in proper cooperation; a political culture and a culture of law; a culture of dialogue, of reverence for life, and so on. This kind of authentic inculturation of Christianity then creates culture in the stricter sense of the word, that is, it leads to artistic work that interprets the world anew in the light of God.112 “In the religious sphere,” says Ratzinger,“culture manifests itself above all in the growth of authentic popular piety.”113 He instances devotion to the Passion of Christ among suffering peoples, and “Marian devotion, in which the whole mystery of the Incarnation, the tenderness of God, the participation of man in God’s own nature, and the nature of God’s saving action are experienced at a profound level.”114 And thence into liturgy: Popular piety is the soil without which the liturgy cannot thrive. . . . One must love it, purifying and guiding it where necessary, but always accepting it with great reverence, even when it seems alien or alienating, as the dedicated sanctuary of faith in the hearts of the people. . . . Tried and tested elements of popular piety may pass over, then, into liturgical celebration, without officious and hasty fabrication, by a patient process of lengthy growth.115 Two further remarks are in order here. First, our author himself recognizes that it was freely composed poetry and music that “provided the point of entry for Gnosticism, that deadly temptation which began to subvert Christianity from within”—and conciliar control (as in the fourth-century “Canons of Laodicea”) was needed to “save the identity of biblical faith”; so that in fact “the very rejection of false inculturation opened up the cultural breadth of Christianity for the future.”116 And second, the mention of “purifying,” “guiding,” “trying,” and “testing” in the previous passage confirms the need for magisterial control (as Pope 111 Cf., for example, ibid., 200ff. 112 Ibid., 201. 113 Ibid. 114 Ibid., 202. 115 Ibid. 116 Ibid., 144–45. Geoffrey Wainwright 428 Pius XII stated in his encyclical of 1947, Mediator Dei, in a neat twist on a familiar dictum: ut lex credendi legem statuat supplicandi ). Since religion, in one shape or form, seems always to be woven into culture, the question of “religious pluralism” must always arise in the presentation of the Gospel and in the regulation of Christian worship. According to Joseph Ratzinger, “one of the great realities in the history of religion” is that “man is always looking for the right way of honoring God, for a form of prayer and common worship that pleases God and is appropriate to his nature.”117 From the revelation communicated in Christ certain criteria must be brought to bear. In the context of our current discussion, two detailed applications made by the theologian Ratzinger are of some significance. First, he notes that “the lotus position of Indian religiosity, which is regarded as the proper posture for meditation,” is “again being practiced, in different ways, by some Christians.” He does not “want absolutely to rule out” its use for Christians, recognizing that “the Christian tradition is also familiar with the God who is more interior to us than we are to ourselves”; yet “the sitting position of oriental meditation” has no proper place in the liturgy of the Church:118 With all of today’s empiricism and pragmatism, with its loss of soul, we have good reason to learn again from Asia. But however open Christian faith may be, must be, to the wisdom of Asia, the difference between the personal and the a-personal understandings of God remains. We must, therefore, conclude that kneeling and standing are, in a unique and irreplaceable way, the Christian posture of prayer—the Christian’s orientation of himself toward the face of God, toward the face of Jesus Christ, in seeing whom we are able to see the Father.119 The second application concerns dance. “Dancing,” Ratzinger judges, “is not a form of expression for the Christian liturgy.” It was, in fact, rejected by the Church when, around the third century,“certain GnosticDocetic circles [attempted] to introduce it into the liturgy” in place of “the liturgy of the Cross, because, after all, the Cross was only an appearance.”120 More generally, “the cultic dances of the different religions have different purposes—incantation, imitative magic, mystical ecstasy—none of which is compatible with the essential purpose of the liturgy of the ‘reasonable sacrifice.’ ”121 The “dancing pantomimes” currently fashionable in “creative 117 Ibid., 159. 118 Ibid., 197 119 Ibid., 198. 120 Ibid. 121 Ibid. The Liturgy according to Joseph Ratzinger 429 liturgy” are a far cry from what occurs in “the [traditional] Ethiopian rite or the Zairean form of the Roman liturgy [officially since 1988]” as “a rhythmically ordered procession very in keeping with the dignity of the occasion, . . . provid[ing] an inner discipline and order for the various stages of the liturgy, bestowing on them beauty and, above all, making them worthy of God.”122 That last remark about beauty and worth is a reminder, too, that authentic cultural achievements in the broader sense—“whatever is true, honorable, just, pure, lovely, gracious” (Phil 4:8)—may find a proper place among “the glory and the honor of the nations” that will in the end adorn the City of God (cf. Rev 21:22–27). Conclusion To adapt H. Richard Niebuhr’s classic Christ and Culture (1951): Instead of taking his five “typical” attitudes as fixed and divergent stances historically manifested by different Christian believers toward all human culture as such, it may be appropriate to see them as indicating the possibility of, and need for, a discriminating attention on the part of all Christians toward every human culture whatever the time and place.Whereas a particular cultural configuration may appear as predominantly positive or negative in relation to the saving purposes of God, it is likely that most cultures will contain some elements to be affirmed; some to be negated, resisted, and even fought; some to be purified and elevated; some to be held provisionally in tension; and some susceptible to a radical and profound transformation toward God’s kingdom. The liturgy can function not only to sift but also to inspire a surrounding public culture. As a theologian, Joseph Ratzinger has argued that the Church’s liturgy— as divinely instituted and responsibly celebrated—has the potential to operate in those ways toward a contemporary culture that is marked by a false and debilitating relativism at the intellectual, social, moral, and religious levels. His argument has been conducted with intelligence, learning, and art. Now, as Pope Benedict XVI, he is in a position as never before to use pastoral and magisterial powers of persuasion. His skills as a preacher and his grace as a presiding priest—both evident to many millions at the funeral of Pope John Paul II and at his own installation Mass—are cause for hope. My use of the word “remedy” in the title of this essay would be quite contrary to Joseph Ratzinger’s character if it were taken to imply merely a “quick fix” that would leave people unchanged. He rightly understands himself at the service of a liturgy that, by serving God, will work for the redemption and transN&V formation of humankind toward its true nature, calling, and destiny. 122 Ibid., 198–99; cf. 169f. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 431–44 431 Discussion Acts Amid Precepts:The Aristotelian Logical Structure of Thomas Aquinas’s Moral Theory by Kevin Flannery, SJ (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2001) L AWRENCE D EWAN, OP Còllege Dominicain Ottawa, Canada T HIS IS A STUDY of practical reasoning, and the shape proper to it, as taught by St.Thomas. Father Kevin Flannery, dean of philosophy at the Pontifical Gregorianum University in Rome, provides us with a searching investigation, showing a most impressive familiarity with a wide range of scholarship. Anyone who reads this work carefully will benefit hugely. I say this quite apart from any incidental disagreements one might have with the author. In his first chapter, Flannery provides an argument for the existence of absolutely fixed principles of practical reasoning according to Aristotle, tied to the doctrine of Motion of Animals.1 This challenges Martha Nussbaum’s interpretation of Aristotelian ethics and is very effective. Flannery neatly shows that the role of the ends, the first principles in Aristotelian ethics, for our conduct is akin to that of the immobile starting point that Aristotle discerned in animal movement, a source of “leverage” as Flannery says (24). 1 Cf. p. 21. In his note 44 there, Flannery mentions the commentator Michael of Ephesus as seeing the products of crafts as to be identified with the end of practical reason. Flannery, later in the book, uses the products of crafts as a principle for understanding double-effect reasoning in morals (chs. 7 and 8). 432 Lawrence Dewan, OP Rather than go through the book chapter by chapter, I will here focus on two important points where I have some disagreement.The first point occurs in Flannery’s chapter 2, a presentation of the precepts of natural law. Flannery is in the course of presenting a stratification of practical reason analogous to that found in theoretical reason. He places first the apprehension of the intelligibility of “the good,” and second the first principle of practical reason.Third come the “common precepts” (42). On this level Flannery points to such precepts as (1) “ill is to be done to no one,” (2) “one should act rationally,” and (3) “love of God and (4) neighbor.” This leads him to explain how these four “common precepts” are parallel to the “common axioms” of theoretical reason. I am concerned here only with his discussion of “love of God” in this context (44). The love of God is described by Thomas as a first and common precept of natural law, known by virtue of itself to human reason, either by nature or by faith; it is related to all Ten Commandments as principle to conclusions.2 Flannery takes into consideration the teaching of St. Thomas that the existence of God is a demonstrable conclusion rather than a proposition per se nota quoad nos. How, then, can the precept “love God” be so known? Flannery’s solution amounts to substituting for the precept “love God” the precept “love happiness” or “seek happiness,” on the basis of the teaching of St.Thomas that the existence of God is thus known in a way, in that we have a natural desire for happiness and God is in fact happiness.3 This is hardly satisfactory.We are, after all, speaking of the best-known items in the domain of practical reason. Consider what is said about the precept to love God above all else. For example: “That which is maximally and firstly natural to man is that he love the good, and most especially the divine good and the good of one’s neighbor.”4 Moreover, it is natural to love God more than ourselves by a friendly love, not merely a concupiscible love; and our love for happiness is merely concupiscible.5 Flannery claims to be taking his cue from Thomas’s comments on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, as follows: And it can be said that all men have appetite for the same delight in virtue of natural appetite, though not, nevertheless, according to their 2 Cf. ST I–II, q. 100, a. 3, ad 1, referred to by Flannery at 43, note 54. 3 Flannery refers us, in nos. 57 and 58, to ST I, q. 2, a. 1, ad 1; In Boet. De trin. 1.3, ad 4; and to De veritate 22.2. 4 ST II–II, q. 34, a. 5: “Id autem quod est maxime et primo naturale homini est quod diligat bonum, et praecipue bonum divinum et bonum proximi.” 5 On friendly natural love for God more than for ourselves, cf. ST I, q. 60, a. 5; whereas the love of God involved in his being our happiness is presented by Thomas as concupiscible love, at ST I–II, q. 2, a. 7, ad 2. On Kevin Flannery, SJ’s Acts Amid Precepts 433 own judgment; for not all reckon in their heart nor say orally that the same delight is best; still, nature inclines all to the same delight as to the best, namely, to the contemplation of intelligible truth, inasmuch as all men by nature desire to know. And this happens because all have naturally within themselves something divine, namely, the inclination of nature which derives from the first principle; or else, namely, the very form which is the principle of this inclination.6 Now this involves moving from whatever people judge and say they find supreme pleasure in to their actually finding supreme pleasure in the contemplation of intelligible truth. However, that move does not take us from what is humanly known intuitively (we desire happiness) to what is known only through demonstration or reasoning (happiness is to be found in God). Thus, it does not really provide a model for what Flannery is doing with “love happiness” standing in for “love God.” However, Flannery also makes reference to the Summa contra Gentiles, book 3, question 38 (2161), though he does not quote it.7 This, in fact, is quite a different doctrine from the one he has featured. It is not about an implicit knowledge of God through an actual knowledge of happiness. It is about a remarkable dimension of our natural life, namely, a natural 6 In Ethic. Nic. 7.13.14, where Thomas is explaining Aristotle at 7.13 (1153b31–32): “Et potest dici quod omnes homines appetunt eamdem delectationem secundum naturalem appetitum, non tamen secundum proprium iudicium; non enim omnes existimant corde, neque dicunt ore eamdem delectationem esse optimam, natura tamen omnes inclinat in eandem delectationem sicut in optimam, puta in contemplationem intelligibilis veritatis, secundum quod omnes homines natura scire desiderant. Et hoc contingit, quia omnia habent naturaliter in se ipsis quiddam divinum, scilicet inclinationem naturae, quae dependet ex principio primo; vel etiam ipsam formam, quae est huius inclinationis principium.” 7 In no. 58, he refers to SCG, bk 3, ch. 38. In no. 57, he mentioned in more detailed fashion ST I–II, q. 89, a. 6. I notice that Flannery presents the topic of ST I–II, q. 89, a. 6, as whether it is possible for a youth to sin venially before sinning mortally.The topic is rather whether one can have only original sin and venial sin on one’s soul (no mortal sin).The answer is no.The idea is that before one can commit a venial sin one must either get rid of original sin or one will commit a mortal sin. Thus, it is quite possible, according to the doctrine, to sin venially before sinning mortally.This is so, if one first turns to God, thus eliminating original sin, and then sins venially.The doctrine in this text, with its reply to objection 3 about the obligation to turn to God at the very start of the moral life, I would say should be read in the light of the doctrine of natural reasoning that I mention below. However, Cajetan read it as requiring one to recognize, through deliberation, only the bonum honestum as such (as one’s proper end), rather than actual knowledge of and turning to God; cf. my paper “Natural Law and the First Act of Freedom: Maritain Revisited,” Études Maritainiennes/Maritain Studies 12 (1996): 3–32, in the section on Cajetan, ca n. 27. 434 Lawrence Dewan, OP reasoning to a conclusion that God exists. We should not envisage the natural dimension of our cognitive life merely in terms of simple apprehensions of such items as being, unity, act, and potency.8 We should not even limit the picture to the primary axioms, such as the impossibility for the same thing to be and not be.9 Rather, a further dimension of what is naturally conferred on us is our natural reasoning. Three texts come to mind.There is the just mentioned Summa contra Gentiles item.There is the Summa theologiae II–II, question 85, article 1, on natural law as requiring the offering of sacrifice to God, and, least known of all, there is Thomas’s commentary on Psalm 8, a text from his final activity in Naples.10 The Summa contra Gentiles text occurs in a context where it is already clear that ultimate human happiness consists in a knowledge of God. Thomas is beginning a series of chapters in which various modes of human knowledge of God are considered as possible candidates for such happiness, a series beginning with the most imperfect knowledge.Thus, Thomas speaks of a knowledge had by pretty well everyone, the sort of knowledge of God that has led some thinkers to say that such knowledge is per se notum. He himself holds that it is really the result of natural reason (naturali ratione) proceeding from our experience of the order of natural 8 Thomas Aquinas, Sententia libri Ethicorum Aristotelis 6.5 (ed. Leonine, t. 47–2, Rome, 1969:Ad Sanctae Sabinae, lines 102–106 (concerning Aristotle at 1141a12–17) (ed. Pirotta, no. 1181): “existimamus quosdam esse sapientes totaliter, idest respectu totius generis entium . . . illa quae est sapientia simpliciter est certissima inter omnes scientias, inquantum scilicet attingit ad prima principia entium, quae secundum se sunt notissima, quamvis aliqua illarum, scilicet immaterialia, sunt minus nota quoad nos. Universalissima autem principia sunt etiam quoad nos magis nota, sicut ea quae pertinent ad ens inquantum est ens: quorum cognitio pertinet ad sapientiam sic dictam, ut patet in quarto Metaphysicae” (emphasis added). And Thomas, In Meta., prologue: “illa scientia maxime est intellectualis, quae circa principia maxime universalia versatur. Quae quidem sunt ens, et ea quae consequuntur ens, ut unum et multa, potentia et actus.” 9 St.Thomas describes this as the maximally first principle: cf. In Meta. 3.5.6. 10 This work is presented by James Weisheipl, Friar Thomas D’Aquino: His Life,Work, and Thought (Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Co., 1974), 368–69 and 302–4, as Postilla super Psalmos. Ps. 1–54 (Naples, 1272–1273). He explains that the given title reflects the use of the psalms in the liturgy of the Church, but that Thomas is really writing what would be more properly and simply described as Super Psalmos (incomplete) (Friar Thomas, 303). Speaking of the period September 29, 1272, to December 6, 1273, from the beginning of the academic year 1272–1273 to the moment in the following term when Thomas stopped writing, Fr. Weisheipl says that “this is the only academic work that can be attributed to this period with certainty” (Friar Thomas, 302). By “academic work” here is meant actual lecturing; the Super Psalmos is a reportatio by Reginald of Piperno,Thomas’s personal secretary. On Kevin Flannery, SJ’s Acts Amid Precepts 435 things to an orderer of natural things.The stress is on the imperfection of the knowledge, the “confused” character of the knowledge. One should note particularly, in the same chapter, that a person who does not have such knowledge is morally blameworthy. Thus, it is knowledge very much linked to our common membership in the moral order. While the Summa contra Gentiles text relates the reasoning to our experience of “the order of natural things,” the Summa theologiae II–II text is more closely linked to our experience of our own imperfection.We read: natural reason [naturalis ratio] declares forcefully [dictat] to man that he is placed under some superior [being], because of the defects which he experiences in himself, with regard to which he needs to be aided and directed by some superior. And whatever that [superior] is, this it is which among all [men] is called “a God.” But just as, in natural things, the lower are naturally placed under the higher, so also natural reason strongly declares to man, in accordance with natural inclination [naturalis ratio dictat homini secundum naturalem inclinationem], that he [should] exhibit, in a way in keeping with his own self, submission and honor to that which is above man.11 Here the resulting precept is not precisely the love precept, but rather pertains to the virtue of religion, the highest form of justice.12 Nevertheless, what interests us is the nature of the knowledge of God that is involved, the fruit of natural reasoning. And it is seen as universal, that is, pertaining to man by his very nature. Lastly, and in many ways most impressively, we have the comment on Psalm 8, speaking of the manifest character of the divine greatness, seen by mere “infants.”There had previously been mention in the psalm of the majesty of God.Thus,Thomas says: Then, when he says: “Out of the mouth” [ex ore], he shows that it [the majesty of God] is maximally manifest. And firstly he shows the manifestness; secondly the reason for it, there [where he says]:“Because I will see” [Quoniam videbo]. That it is manifest he proves: because that is manifest which is placed within [inditum] all, no matter how simple [they are], as by a sort of natural knowledge [quasi quadam naturali cognitione]. For there are two sorts of men who follow natural and right instinct [naturalem et rectum instinctum], namely, the simple and the wise. That the wise know God is no great matter; but that the simple do is [a great matter]. But there are some who pervert the right instinct, and these people reject knowledge 11 ST II–II, q. 85, a. 1 (ed. Ottawa, 1861b48–1862a6). 12 Cf. ST II–II, q. 122, a. 1. 436 Lawrence Dewan, OP of God. Cf. Psalm 81: “They have not known,” that is, they willed not to know, “nor have they understood” etc. Cf. Job 22: “They have said to God: Go away from us; we do not want your ways.” But God has brought it about that through them, that is, through the simple people who follow the natural instinct, are confounded those who pervert the natural instinct. By “infants” the simple are signified, cf. 1 Peter 2:“Like new-born infants, reasonable, without guile.” Therefore he [the Psalmist] says:“Your name is admirable”; but in such a way that “out of the mouth of infants and nurselings you have brought praise to perfection,” [you] who interiorly instigate to this; and this “because of your enemies,” who oppose your science and knowledge. Cf. Philippians 3: “Enemies of the cross of Christ” etc. . . . This takes place when the simple recognize God, and others pervert the study of natural knowledge, lest they know God himself.13 Though Thomas speaks of a “natural knowledge” had by the simple, and of them following “natural instinct,” he still sees this phenomenon as having its reason, its source, in a grasp of the cosmic situation.14 He sees the common man as spontaneously sizing things up, somewhat as in the Summa contra Gentiles and the Summa theologiae II–II texts. 13 Emphasis added.The commentary continues, speaking of the celestial phenomena as the ground of the natural reasoning, in keeping with the text of the psalm: “Next, he subjoins the reason for this manifestness, saying ‘Because’ [Quoniam]. Tully says in the book De natura deorum, and it was said also by Aristotle, though in those books of his that we have among us it is not found, that if some man were to enter a palace, which he would see [to be] well disposed, none is so lacking in intellect [amens] that, even though he would not see how it had been made, he would not perceive that it had been made by someone. And this the order of the celestial bodies especially shows. For there were some who, erring, attributed the causes of things to the necessity of matter: hence, they said all had been made because of the warm, the cold, the dry, and the wet: as by the elements which have these properties. But this, if it can have an appearance [of truth] regarding other things, can in no way [have such appearance] in [the case of] the celestial bodies; for they cannot be attributed to the necessity of matter, where one is so distant from the other, and they take so great a time to complete their course.That cannot be traced back to anything but an intelligent cause.And so Scripture, when it wants to manifest the power of God, directs us to a consideration of the heavens.” 14 Clearly the presentations in the SCG and the In Psalm. relate to Thomas’s “fifth way” of proving the existence of God (ST I, q. 2, a. 3). It is also notable that it is this line of thinking, purpose as opposed to chance as a source of the cosmos, which is presented in Thomas’s popular sermons on the Apostles’ Creed, concerning the existence of a God. Cf. In Symbolorum Apostolorum expositio, in Opuscula theologica, t. II, ed. R. Spiazzi, O.P. (Rome and Turin: Marietti, 1954), no. 869. Here Thomas insists on the regularity of the celestial movements.This work also dates from 1273, in Naples. And once again, Thomas speaks of the rarity and stupidity of people who do not believe that the cosmos is governed. On Kevin Flannery, SJ’s Acts Amid Precepts 437 It seems to me perfectly acceptable that the natural love that man has for God more than for his own self be seen as following from this natural knowledge of God that man has by a spontaneous, inborn reasoning to the existence of God. I think this is better than attempting to see such a primary precept as “love God above all else” merely in the way it is present in the desire for happiness. The natural love for God above all else is present in every creature, but in each according to its own mode or measure. In the rational creature, that is, angels and man, it is “in the mode of will.” Such natural love presupposes natural intellectual knowledge of God.15 In the angel such knowledge is a mediated intuition.16 In the human being, it is a natural conclusion, the fruit of a spontaneous, universally inborn discursive operation. Our intellectuality is “rational,” as possessed of a weaker light than the angelic.17 Notice that it is inasmuch as God is known as the author of being, life, and intelligence that he cannot be hated, but must be loved.18 That we need a commandment concerning such love stems from the possibility (through habituation to sin) of our not living according to it in particular choices.19 My understanding is, then, that Thomas presents the existence of God as naturally known to all, even though naturally reasoned to.That someone 15 In ST I, q. 60, a. 1, it is seen that natural love is present in each creature accord- ing to its own mode, and that for angels and men, this is secundum voluntatem. In ST I, q. 59, a. 1, it was seen that will is the most perfect mode of inclination toward the good, in that it follows upon the intellectual vision of goodness, considered universally. In ST I, q. 60, a. 5, ad 1, it is seen that all naturally love God more than themselves, each in its own mode (and notice that the sed contra there links this love to the natural law). 16 Cf. ST I, q. 56, a. 3. 17 Cf. ST I, q. 58, a. 3. 18 Cf. ST II–II, q. 34, a. 1. 19 Cf. ST I–II, q. 99, a. 2, ad 2:“It is to be said that it was fitting for the divine law that it provide for man not only as to those matters which are beyond the capacity of reason, but also as to those concerning which it does occur that human reason suffer impediment. Now, human reason concerning the moral precepts, as regards the most common precepts of the natural law, could not err, taking them universally, but nevertheless, because of habituation in sinning, it has been obscured regarding particular things to be done.” Cf. also ST I–II, q. 100, a. 5, ad 1, as to why the ten commandments speak of our duty to God and to our neighbor, but not of our duty to ourselves: “The precepts of the Decalogue are related to the precepts of love. But a precept had to be given to man concerning the love of God and neighbor because in that respect the natural law had been obscured because of sin; not as regards the love of himself, because in that respect the natural law was still in vigor.” Cf. also ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3, on our natural love for God above all else, and the effect of original sin. 438 Lawrence Dewan, OP professes ignorance of the existence of God stems from moral disorder (as the Psalms commentary as well as the SCG text asserts). I would say that this natural knowledge would fill out the picture of the commandment of love as known by virtue of itself to all. Given that one has knowledge of God as the author of being, one has knowledge of him as lovable by us, indeed as more lovable that ourselves.20 My second main point of difference with Flannery concerns the principle of double effect and fixed paths. In his introduction (cf. xiii), Flannery tells us that the problem of the morally right action that one does, knowing that its outcome will be bad in certain respects, is what generated the book.The text of St.Thomas that most immediately relates to the principle of double effect is that on the licitness of self-defense, Summa theologiae II–II, question 64, article 7. There Thomas explains that an act can have two effects, only one of which is intended.This is the case with selfdefense, where it is natural and good to defend one’s own life, even though this requires, in a particular instance, killing the adversary.21 Even with a good intention, the act will be illicit if one uses more force than necessary. One cannot, moreover, have the intention of killing the adversary, since that is exclusively the responsibility of the public authority. Flannery mentions at the outset of the relevant chapter (ch. 7, pp. 167 ff.) that he wonders how the public authority can intend to kill the criminal, since that has the appearance of an action that opposes a basic human good. He promises to return to this. His discussion features some modern issues related to the principle of double effect.The problem is, as it seems, that in some situations one can treat the bad feature of the situation as unintended whereas in other situations this is not acceptable. A hypothetical case to illustrate this is “the fat potholer.”This member of a group of spelunkers becomes fixed in the only escape-hole, thus constituting a threat to the lives of the group. Is it licit for the group to blow the person away in self-defense? The case was 20 As I have often pointed out, the first level of natural inclinations spoken of in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2, is the natural inclination common to all creatures; it is not ordered merely toward the preservation of the individual self. It covers everything spoken of in ST I, q. 60, as natural love: love of the individual self, love of one’s species more than the individual self, and love of God more than oneself or any creature. The second level of inclination in that text is not about reproduction, for that is common to all substances, but about the perfect animal mode of reproduction. The third level is not about love of God, but about seeking the truth about God, as well as living in society: The rational animal by nature desires to know, and especially to know the truth concerning God. 21 “The act” has two effects, taken as a physical act; the moral act is simply “saving one’s own life.” Cf. ST I–II, q. 1, a. 3, ad 3. On Kevin Flannery, SJ’s Acts Amid Precepts 439 designed to show that, while the answer is “no,” it is not easy to say why this is so. (Some discussants even said “yes.”) More actually encountered situations are the surgical treatments of pregnant women. It has been held that the removal of a cancerous uterus (“hysterectomy”) is acceptable, even though this inevitably means the death of the fetus, whereas crushing the skull of a fetus (“craniotomy,” for short) in order to save the life of the mother is unacceptable. Finding in discussions such descriptions of one victim as “close” and another as “more distant,” or “direct” and “indirect,” Flannery expresses dissatisfaction, and the conviction that the disputes, so presented, can never be settled. He suggests that there is something missing from the discussion, something that was present of old, namely a context of fixed human practices. Having noted appeals along these lines in Plato and Aristotle, he focuses on the practice of medicine as something with definite procedures. The hysterectomy procedure has its place in medical practice, whereas the “craniotomy” case has not. Flannery explains this in terms of what constitutes treatment of the patient; he sees the fetus in the craniotomy case as a very badly treated patient. Flannery, in this line of thinking, is now obliged to say what fixed practice Thomas is involved with in his self-defense article. His answer is law.Thus, he calls to our attention the references to law as characterizing the context of Thomas’s discussion. In answer to the possible objection that this is a “legalistic” solution, he recalls the way positive law in Thomas’s doctrine flows from natural law. I cannot say I am happy with this treatment. It seems to me that nature and the natural should have been given more prominence. Flannery’s difficulties stem in part, I would say, from not reading the Summa theologiae II–II, question 64, article 7, as part of the whole question 64. I am concerned that so little attention has been given to the pedagogy of the question.The first article, establishing our right to kill plants and animals, begins with the premise that no one sins in treating a thing in accordance with its purpose.22 The first thing we learn, after the case of plants and animals, is about the justification of the public authority killing the criminal.The second thing is that the private person cannot kill the criminal. The third is that the killer of the criminal cannot be a cleric (who, of course, can have public responsibility; his ministers must perform the 22 In speaking of the natural purpose of plants and animals, Thomas even makes reference to Aristotle, Politics 1.8 (1256b15). This text falls in with Flannery’s appeal to arts as fixed paths, though modern readers might not like to see war presented as an art of acquisition (of slaves). 440 Lawrence Dewan, OP execution: cf. the ST II–II, q. 64, a. 4, ad 3).The fourth is that one cannot kill oneself:This applies even to the ruler who is a criminal, since no one is to judge oneself.We then come to the case of the killing of the innocent: It is altogether forbidden. Only then do we come to that problematic figure, the attacker of the private citizen. No judgment will be made as regards his state of soul, but the person attacked has the right to take the necessary steps to save himself, even though this sometimes must result in the death of the attacker. Lastly, we have the case of accidental killing. This rich context first sees the criminal as analogous to the beast, and as analogous to the diseased bodily member; all are cases of the imperfect being for the sake of the perfect.The human individual who menaces the community may have to be “used” for the well-being of the community, even to the point of being executed. Article 3, forbidding the killing of the criminal by a private person, makes clear the reason for this: The killing of the criminal is for the sake of the common good only, and thus it is for those responsible for that good to make the necessary judgment about the criminality of the criminal.The reply to objection 2 should be especially considered: The man who is a sinner is not naturally distinct from just men.Therefore, there is need of the public judgment, in order to discern whether someone is to be killed for the common welfare. The insistence is on the need for right discernment concerning the public need and the moral condition of the accused, in inflicting such great harm on a person.23 This need for public judgment throws great light on the situation of the private self-defender. His act simply cannot be a killing of the attacker as a malefactor. In this same line, the lesson for us from the anti-suicide article is that even a supreme judge, himself a criminal, cannot, having come to condemn himself personally, do away with himself. Public judgment is a matter for “someone else.” How important, then, is the absolute rejection of all killing of the innocent! First we have the obligation to love the nature that God has made and which is destroyed by killing: Thus, no one, just or sinner, is a killable 23 The question on homicide leads the discussion of vices violating the justice of exchange, and in particular involuntary exchanges:This is to say that some harm is visited upon one’s neighbor against his will, either as to deed or word, and among deeds, those that harm the person or the associate of the person, or the property. Homicide comes first as maximally harming one’s neighbor. Cf. ST II–II, q. 64, prol. On Kevin Flannery, SJ’s Acts Amid Precepts 441 object, just in himself. Second, we have the case of the public authority to kill the public enemy: Since the innocent primarily constitute the community (which is essentially a school of virtue), killing the innocent is analogous to amputating the head to save the arm. It is with these premises in view that we come to the self-defender. He is faced with an attacker, but has no right to judge that attacker to be a criminal, a public enemy; no right to kill a criminal. Nor has he any right to kill an innocent human being. He has no right to kill at all. Here I believe it would be helpful to recall the distinction between the physical act performed by the human being and the moral act. Thomas explained this very early in the Summa theologiae I–II.24 One same species of physical act, that is, killing a human being, can be two different species of moral act, namely, murder and capital punishment.The moral act gets its species from the intention. Here in the Summa theologiae II–II, question 64, with self-defense, we are still dealing with a physical act of homicide. St. Thomas teaches that it cannot be a moral act of killing at all: Morally, it is neither justified nor unjustified homicide. The “craniotomy” case Flannery speaks of is a killing of an innocent; thus, it is simply not available for any motive. The “fat potholer” case is, again, a killing of the innocent.The “hysterectomy” described is an amputation; the resultant death of the fetus is a “letting die,” not a killing at all.25 The true private self-defense case is one where there is obviously a menacing human being.What makes it a special moral matter is the inappropriateness of privately judging the attacker. Thus, also, the public authority’s “intention to kill” relates directly to that authority’s power of discernment. Flannery is quite right in arguing that this “intention to kill” cannot be a seeking of the death of the culprit in the way that an act of hatred toward the culprit would be. As St. Thomas teaches in the article rejecting all killing of the innocent, the human being, considered just in himself, is not a possible candidate for homicide, since even in any evildoer whatsoever we ought to love the nature that God has made and that is destroyed by killing; it is only when taken relative to the well-being of the community that the public authority can rightly judge that a person is too great a menace to let live. In so judging, it is considered that the good to be gained is greater than the bad to be endured.That is Thomas’s rationale for all punishment. It is only in such a per accidens way that the bad is intended. There must be no hatred for the executed person; on the contrary, one 24 Cf. ST I–II, q. 1, a. 3, ad 3. 25 It is not my intention to brush off the question of a mother’s responsibility as easy to resolve. 442 Lawrence Dewan, OP must act charitably toward that person. It is definitely a judgment favoring human life, not opposing it.26 The responsible act of the society is thus morally specified as an act of homicide, in that the killing is deliberately employed in the interest of the community.The private act of self-defense is, when the adversary dies as a result, physically an act of killing, but morally not a homicide, not an “act of killing a human being” at all. Flannery focused on law as the practice to be considered in Thomas’s discussion of both private and public licit killing.There is no doubt that in the article on private self-defense law is referred to. The sed contra is taken from the Old Law (though there is here not merely the element of a human practice but the authority proper to revelation). There is also reference to canon law.This is a significant use of legal authority. Nevertheless, I do not like Flannery’s contention that in the teaching of the licitness of private self-defense, but without intention to kill, “law is simply basic here” (192). Flannery immediately adds that “neither is this law without sense.There is good reason for a society not to allow private, intentional killing. If such intentional personal self-defense were licit, how could private executions for defensive purposes be prohibited?” Thomas’s article is not about a law against intention to kill. That is rather a matter of personal conscience. It is true that excessive use of force might be a sign that the intention has been to kill. However, that is not said. It is said that the use of excessive force will make even an act done 26 I quote from my paper,“Thomas Aquinas, Gerard Bradley, and the Death Penalty: Some Observations,” Gregorianum 82 (2001): 162, quoting Thomas:“God does not will the damnation of someone under the aspect of damnation, nor the death of someone under the aspect of death, because he ‘wills that all human beings be saved’ [1 Tim 2:4], but he wills these under the aspect of justice. Hence, it is sufficient regarding such matters that the human being will the preservation of the justice of God and of the natural order.” This implies that, in the case of private self-defense, what is forbidden is the intention ‘justice through execution.’ No one (whether a public official or a private person) is ever allowed to ‘intend the death of this person,’ in the way that that involves pleasure in that person’s suffering, or hate of that person as possessed of human nature. But the private person has not the right even to restore the order of justice through any sort of punishment. Notice that even in punishment, what is bad, such as the death, is willed only per accidens. Since we say, as well, that in private self-defense the death of the adversary is per accidens, it seems to me that “intending the death” in the case of capital punishment must be a mode of the per accidens closer to the per se than in the case of private self-defense, where the death of the adversary is per accidens in the way that the physical species of the act is per accidens relative to the moral species of the act. Cf. ST I–II, q. 1, a. 3, ad 3. On Kevin Flannery, SJ’s Acts Amid Precepts 443 with good intention illicit. And it is concluded that an act done with moderate violence will be licit. Here the law is quoted as explicitly permitting moderate force in self-defense. Moreover, I am not happy with the translation of licet and related terms by “lawful.” For example, there is no law, human or divine, against a venial sin as such, and yet such sins are “illicit.” Flannery’s use of the word “lawful” (also found in the old English Dominican translation of ST II–II, q. 64, a. 7) is deceptive.27 Thomas makes it sufficiently clear that he is basing his judgment on nature: Actus igitur huiusmodi ex hoc quod intenditur conservatio propriae vitae, non habet rationem illiciti, cum hoc sit cuilibet naturale quod se conservet in esse quantum potest. [Such an act, therefore, as intending the preservation of one’s own life, does not have the character of the illicit, since it is natural for each being whatsoever that it preserve itself in being to the extent this is possible.] It seems to me that the practices Flannery refers to have their basis in long experience with nature. Thus, there is good sense in Flannery’s caution that one should look at the context. One might consider the use Thomas makes of the doctrine that art imitates nature in his prologue to the Commentary on Aristotle’s Politics. In order to effect the highest of human reason’s products, the very order of the human community, the science must proceed by imitation of nature. Lastly, I will mention a particular claim of Flannery’s, concerning the date of De malo 6. He argues that it predates De veritate. I think the Leonine editors dating, namely, 1270, is correct. However, this is not central to his project. An appendix contains a text and translation of De malo 6. Footnote 1 stresses the literalness of the translation, following even the Latin word order as much as possible. However, what I immediately note is the translation of: Cum ergo voluntas se consilio moveat, consilium autem est inquisitio quaedam non demonstrativa, sed ad opposita viam habens, non ex necessitate voluntas seipsam movet. 27 Lewis and Short, A Latin Dictionary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1879), for “licet” start off with “it is lawful,” but soon come to “one is at liberty to do so and so.” The systematic use of “law” in the translation is deceptive. One sees that by comparing the use of the word concerning all lying as illicit, even lies which are venial sins: cf. ST II–II, q. 110, a. 3, ad 4; a venial sin, as such, is not against any law whatsoever: cf. ST I–II, q. 88, a. 1, ad 1. I might note that there is no common linguistic origin for “lex” and “licet.” Lawrence Dewan, OP 444 Flannery translates: Since, therefore, voluntas moves itself to counsel, but counsel is an enquiry that is not demonstrative [line 318] but oriented toward opposites, voluntas does not move itself of necessity. This, I submit, is wrong.The translation should be “by counsel.”The will’s self-motion has its willing the end as cause and its choosing the means as effect; its instrument, through which it so moves itself, is deliberation, a nondemonstrative act of reason; and thus the resultant choice is a non-necessitated act of the will.This most important point of doctrine is obscured. Jean Oesterle rightly has “by.”28 While I have chosen to indicate the few points where I differ with Flannery, I return in conclusion to my view that this is a very valuable study, stimulating reflection on a rather neglected sphere of Thomistic N&V methodology. 28 Cf. St.Thomas Aquinas, On Evil, trans. Jean Oesterle (Notre Dame, IN: Univer- sity of Notre Dame Press, 1995), at 241, before note 40. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 5, No. 2 (2007): 445–64 445 Analogical Concept versus Analogical Judgment: Whose Aquinas, Which Rationality? A Discussion of Speaking the Incomprehensible God: Thomas Aquinas on the Interplay of Positive and Negative Theology by Gregory P. Rocca (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2004) R EINHARD H ÜTTER Duke University Divinity School Durham, North Carolina B ERNARD Montagnes, OP, opens The Doctrine of the Analogy of Being According to Thomas Aquinas—originally published in 1963, but only very recently available in English translation—with a pertinent observation leading up to two questions: Several recent worthwhile works have come to revive interest in the Thomist doctrine of analogy—which unfortunately has become a subject of somewhat hackneyed scholarly interest and upon which, it seems, too much has already been written. Is it still necessary, after these recent works, to run the risk of adding a new title to a bibliography whose discouraging mass would rather suggest to us abandoning such an enterprise? Does the contribution made by these recent studies leave any room for a new study?1 1 Bernard Montagnes, The Doctrine of the Analogy of Being According to Thomas Aquinas, trans. E. M. Macierowski, ed. Andrew Tallon (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 2004), 7. Originally published as La doctrine de l’analogie de l’être d’après Saint Thomas d’Aquin (Louvain: Publications Universitaires/Paris: Béatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1963). 446 Reinhard Hütter Unsurprisingly, these questions did not keep Montagnes in 1963 from adding an important study to an already sizable library of Thomists treating “analogy in Aquinas.” Nor did it keep Gregory Rocca in 2004 from seeking to integrate this increasingly complex discussion into the even wider horizon of cataphatic and apophatic God-talk by reconstructing how for Aquinas precisely the exigencies of such God-talk call for the practice of theological analogy. Even the slightest familiarity with the delicate question of the proper interplay between cataphatic and apophatic theology in general, and in the thought of Thomas Aquinas in particular, commands an immediate sense of respect for Rocca’s achievement. His book offers a highly nuanced and impressively comprehensive treatment of the topic: of St.Thomas in the context of his Platonic, neo-Platonic, and Aristotelian sources; of the tradition of Thomist commentators; and of the contemporary Thomist discussion. In short, the work under discussion represents an impressive exemplar of Dominican scholarly dedication to St. Thomas’s profoundly complex as well as profoundly rewarding thought.An exhaustive bibliography together with very useful indices of names, subjects, and especially works of Thomas Aquinas round off a substantial study, making it a premier guide for in-depth research on the given topic. Offering a sustained investigation into and presentation of St.Thomas’s theological epistemology, the book is in no way just another treatment of the arguably overworked topic of “analogy in Aquinas.” Rather, Rocca’s project, quite ambitiously and in a much broader scope, aims at demonstrating that “Aquinas’ theological epistemology is a combination of negative and positive theology and that his positive theology is rooted in an analogy subsisting in judgments, including the judgments of faith” (xvi). Conceived in this way, the project entails a distinct polemical edge in that it aims at substantiating a claim, as crucial as it is controversial, that for St. Thomas the unity of theological analogy rests not in the unity of an alleged analogical concept but in the act of judgment. An all-too-clear signal for those sufficiently initiated into the intricacies of intra-Thomistic disputes, this claim amounts to a crisp line drawn between, on the one side, the venerable tradition of Cajetan’s interpretation of St. Thomas’s account of analogy upheld in the twentieth century by Thomistic luminaries Antonin Sertillanges, Gerald B. Phelan, Charles Journet, Eric Mascall, James F. Anderson, and Jacques Maritain and, on the other side, a respectable, recent line of fundamental critique of Cajetan’s “conceptualist” approach advanced by Hampus Lyttkens, Santiago Ramírez, George P. Klubertanz, Ralph McInerny, and Bernard Montagnes, recently reaffirmed by John F. Wippel, and now also embraced by Gregory Rocca. On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 447 Precisely because Rocca argues that the unity of theological analogy does not rest in an analogical concept but in the act of judgment, he is anxious to relate the question of analogy to the truths of faith instead of focusing exclusively on what neo-scholasticism considered St.Thomas’s philosophical doctrine of God. In other words, he is eager to present the theological epistemology of the doctor communis as a second-order reflection that arises organically from the first-order theological judgments that are constitutive of his doctrines about God and creation. Rocca approaches what he calls the “fragile though fruitful unity of Aquinas’ positive and negative theology” (xvi) in four consecutive steps constituting the four parts of the book: “God the Incomprehensible and Negative Theology,”“Analogy and the Web of Judgment,”“Crucial Truths about God,” and “The Divine Names.” In all four parts, Rocca displays a magisterial command of the topical threads running through the vast net of St.Thomas’s oeuvre. In addition to drawing consistently on the Summa theologiae as well as the Summa contra Gentiles, he pays commendably close attention to the early Scriptum super libros Sententiarum as well as the important disputed questions De veritate and De potentia, the biblical commentaries (especially the one on the Gospel of John), the relevant commentaries of Aristotle’s work (Physics, Metaphysics, Peri Hermeneias, Posterior Analytics) and of his commentator Averroes, and the neo-Platonic tradition as addressed in St. Thomas’s commentaries on Denys’s De divinis nominibus and the Liber de causis. Rocca treats his subject matter—Aquinas’s theorizing about the very logic of the discourse about God in light of Aquinas’s own practice of such discourse—in a genetic-historical way. Such an approach yields a richly nuanced picture of St.Thomas’s thought, which in its very development over the years, remains profoundly faithful to the central axioms operative across a vast spectrum of material and topics. However, the distinct disadvantage of a genetic-historical reconstruction of Aquinas’s thought is that this approach intrinsically inhibits the transition to a speculative mode of discourse in which the subject matter itself—in the way, after all, it concerned St. Thomas himself—could be investigated in the proper speculative mode of metaphysical as well as theological discourse. While the genetic-historical approach allows one to advance considerations about theological and metaphysical matters—due to its specific formal object, the genealogy of Aquinas’s own thought in the context of the relevant historical and textual sources—any consistent instantiation of this method must, however, refrain from theological and metaphysical discourse proper lest it lose the unity and specificity of its particular formal object by way of which the theological and metaphysical matters 448 Reinhard Hütter are addressed. Nevertheless, it becomes quite obvious to any appropriately attentive reader that beneath its genetic-historical surface there is a commendable speculative energy at work in Rocca’s discourse, an energy barely tamed by the strictly historical-reconstructive conventions as they still, quite arguably, dominate much of the recent renaissance of Thomistic scholarship. I In the first part, “God the Incomprehensible and Negative Theology,” Rocca offers a concise account of the tradition of negative theology up to Pseudo-Dionysius and John Damascene, as well as a substantive chapter on God’s dual incomprehensibility, a discussion that arises from a sophisticated interpretation of question 12 in the prima pars of the Summa theologiae. By analyzing in detail how St. Thomas subtly qualifies the unmitigated apophaticism operative in the negative theology of the Areopagite and his followers, Rocca clears the path for an appreciation of Aquinas’s own, markedly different via negativa, which includes the way of causality, the way of negation, and the way of preeminence. Rocca argues convincingly that St. Thomas employs the via negativa in a threefold way, applying it differently in various contexts, but most importantly using it “as an integral whole in those situations where a positive predicate is first affirmed of God, then denied, and finally affirmed once again in a supereminent fashion” (72–73). Most helpful is Rocca’s astute identification of three types of theological negation operative in a rather implicit way in St.Thomas’s via negativa: qualitative, objective modal, and subjective modal. Rocca summarizes the matter in a succinct way: Qualitative negations are absolute denials, while modal negations are relative denials; objective modal negations remove the finite mode of the creature from God, while subjective modal negations refuse to assert of God those imperfections arising from our human manner of understanding and signifying. (62) Already in this first part, Rocca drives home again and again a central point too-often neglected in the context of contemporary postmodern flirtations with a consummate apophaticism that happily assimilates Dionysius and Meister Eckhart with Heidegger and Derrida, and that suggests a serendipitous proximity of Thomas Aquinas: Negative theology in St. Thomas functions as an integral, corrective, and subsequent moment to an antecedent affirmative theology.As Rocca rightly emphasizes, “For the sake of his theological project, Thomas requires a specific On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 449 knowledge of God as close to essential knowledge as possible, and the strategy of successive qualitative negations serves that end” (64). These negations cannot arise from any intuitional insight into God. Rather, Thomas does base the negations upon some primary affirmations which assert that God is pure act and infinite subsistent being; in various ways he claims that God is the infinite positivity of being without knowing what that pure positivity is or how it is God.Yet, it is from these affirmations that his negative theology lives and moves and has its being. (64) With this programmatic statement Rocca anticipates the central claim of part three,“Crucial Truths about God.” However, it is precisely in light of the nature and weight of such a far-reaching anticipation that the following question imposes itself: What difference would it have made had he opened up the book with the “Crucial Truths about God,” that is—dare I say it—with the praeambula fidei? Such an order would have followed more closely the ordo disciplinae of the Summa theologiae, where these affirmations arise from the recently rather unjustly disparaged and sidetracked “five ways” of rationally demonstrating the existence of God, as Rocca expressly states later in part three: Aquinas fashions the proofs for God’s existence into formidable theological tools: they are indisputably foundational for his systematic theology because he seeds within their premises and harvests in their conclusions the monotheistically revolutionary truth that God is the pure, infinite, subsistent act of being. (224) However, instead of following St.Thomas’s ordo disciplinae by privileging the ontological premise of God as ipsum esse subsistens, Rocca frontloads the problematic of theological epistemology, being faithful thereby again to a genetic-historical entry into his particular topic instead of privileging the substantive as well as conceptual exigencies of the subject matter per se. Nevertheless, Rocca is perfectly clear that an ineluctable affirmation, being at the very root of sacra doctrina as well as the metaphysics of esse, remains primordially antecedent to all subsequent epistemic and linguistic entailments: Aquinas’ via negativa is . . . a moment within [rational theology] serving to correct the oversights and deficiencies of affirmative theology and doing the best it can to construct a negative theology of the One who cannot be known essentially. . . . Affirmation and infinite positivity are the fecund roots of all subsequent negations. (72) 450 Reinhard Hütter This, in other words, means that apophatic discourse is not superadded upon but is all the way down integral to a robustly cataphatic Christian theology. II Part two, “Analogy and the Web of Judgment,” constitutes the heart of the book. After an informative chapter on analogy in Aristotle and in neo-Platonism, Rocca ably sketches the scathing critique of analogy advanced in twentieth-century Protestant theology, most prominently by Karl Barth, Wolfhart Pannenberg, and Eberhard Jüngel. To state their respective concerns briefly: Barth is haunted by an allegedly overarching conceptual univocity of being, with the term applicable to both Creator and creature such that human beings by way of natural theology secure a comprehensive conceptual handle on the Creator and, hence, conceive an idol of their own making. Barth decries the “analogy of being” as the epitome of “natural theology,” the latter being a synonym for the kind of metaphysical presumption typical of unredeemed theological inquiry under the condition of sin. In short, for Barth, between the analogy of being and the analogy of faith there obtains an irreconcilable and, hence, interminable “hamartiological” conflict. Quite likely, however, Barth attacked in Aquinas a concept of analogy he saw advanced by his contemporary Erich Przywara, S.J., who on this matter was arguably closer to Scotus and Suarez than to Aquinas. The early Pannenberg, a more subtle medievalist and a Scotus scholar, brings greater precision to the Barthian concern. He contends that constitutive of any form of analogy is an indispensable conceptual core of univocity, a “common logos” that ultimately compromises God’s transcendence. Jüngel, quite contrary to Pannenberg, conceives the fundamental problem of analogy along the lines of Kant’s reduction of all analogy to the analogy of improper (exterior or metaphorical) proportionality and consequently of such profound apophatic entailments that in the end the God of the Gospel is utterly obscured—a concern more recently forcefully expressed by the late Colin Gunton.The strategy of these critiques is only all too obvious: to reduce analogy to and consequently to dismiss it either as the ultimately unmitigated univocity of predication and being between God and creation—and thus to impale it on the horn of idolatry—or as the consummate equivocity of predication and a consequent positioning of God beyond being and nonbeing—and thus to impale it on the horn of agnosticism. Rocca astutely uses this set of criticisms as a foil to present St.Thomas’s genuine account of analogy, an account that in its substance constitutes a devastating witness either to the lack of hermeneutical goodwill from the side of the Protestant critics or to a disconcerting lack On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 451 of familiarity with St.Thomas’s oeuvre. Building on the work of Lyttkens, Montagnes, Klubertanz, and McInerny, Rocca makes what strikes me as a conclusive case against Cajetan’s theory of analogy as four-term proportionality being the proper interpretation of St. Thomas’s own account of analogy. The analogy of proper proportionality according to Cajetan predicates inherent perfections of each analogate and is held together by one analogous concept “that transcends all the analogates, possesses a unified meaning proportionally the same, and abstracts from the proper concepts of the analogates” (114). One problem with Cajetan’s theory is that the analogous concept oscillates between a clear concept (actually many concepts and only proportionally one concept) and a common but confused concept achieved by a special abstraction. At least the historical and hermeneutical side of the question can now be regarded as settled: Cajetan seems to rest the case of his interpretation of St.Thomas exclusively on a particular stage in the latter’s development reflected in a position advanced in De veritate, question 2, article 3, ad 4; question 2, article 11; and question 3, article 1, ad 7, to which he never returned. Moreover, Rocca rightly points out that, quite conceivably, an argument can be advanced “that analogy as proportionality is ultimately grounded in the properties of analogy as referential multivocity, also known as analogy of attribution” (124). Still, it should not be forgotten that a convincing historical and hermeneutical case does not per se constitute a demonstrative argument. On the metaphysical level, however, the defenders of Cajetan’s theory deserve such an argument. While, for reasons already mentioned, Rocca does not offer such an argument, one can find a rather sustained metaphysical engagement of Cajetan’s account in Montagnes’s earlier study. The strength of Rocca’s genetic-historical approach is this: He can convincingly demonstrate that St.Thomas’s advance beyond his transitory position in De veritate, and, hence, his final mature solution, hinges on an expanded meaning of the term proportio: “This broad sense of proportio as ‘direct relation’ is the bridge that allows theological attributes to cross from us to God and, more generally, is the philosopher’s stone Aquinas utilizes to transmute analogia as four-term proportionality into analogia as referential multivocity” (123). Rocca employs the term “analogy of referential multivocity” in order to designate the linguistic practice of analogia in which multiple predications of one name to many things occur. Such multiple predications can be based on reference, attribution, or proportion to some one reality. In the latter case, proportio tends to carry the broad meaning of any relation at all: It is “ ‘proportion with a reference to one’ Reinhard Hütter 452 (proportio ad unum)” (107). Rocca makes a persuasive genetic-historical case for this thesis by way of a close textual reading of a wide range of St. Thomas’s writings, an analysis that builds carefully on the prior work of Klubertanz and especially Montagnes. While Rocca’s relationship to Montagnes is explicit and far-reaching, it is instructive to observe the difference between the two. Montagnes, whose primarily philosophical study was guided by an intrinsic metaphysical concern and discourse, offers a clearer conceptual account of the reasons why St. Thomas was able (after the short experimental stage in which he considered proportionality) to return in his mature work to the analogy of relation: It is the metaphysics of participation that enables Aquinas to shift from the problematic formal causality centrally employed in the Scriptum to the efficient causality of his later work that enables him to conceive the analogy of attribution as an intrinsic analogy.2 In short, St. Thomas was for a relatively brief time conceptually stuck with the problems that arose from the way he employed formal causality as the premier conceptual tool to understand the analogical causality between God and beings, the fundamental problematic being the serious risk of comprising both in one and the same form. Consequently, for a while he entertained the analogy of proportionality precisely to overcome the conceptual dangers of univocal, formal similarity inherent in formal causality. However, as soon as St.Thomas saw his way through to conceive the causal dependence of creatures upon God as one not of formal but rather of efficient causality by way of participation, he was able to return to the analogy of intrinsic attribution. Whereas Montagnes insists by way of metaphysical argumentation that for St. Thomas the analogy of relation arises from the metaphysics of participation—and, hence, the practice of epistemic judgment arises from the order of being3—Rocca, characteristically using the term “analogy of 2 Ibid., 75–79. 3 Ibid., 77: “According to [the] analogy unius ad alterum, must beings be defined starting from God or God starting from beings? This question calls for two complementary replies. Our knowledge follows an order per prius et posterius which goes from beings to God. It never coincides with the ontological order of creative causality: what is first for us is never first in itself.Whatever we know of God we know by means of beings, by ascending from the effects to their cause. In short, for us, the primary analogate is the creature. But since beings receive by participation what God is by essence, they depend upon Him as the primary instance from which they have what they are. Of itself, being does not include dependence upon a cause in its definition, otherwise one would have to say that God is not a being, since He is not caused. Still, if being pertains to God per prius and to creatures per posterius, one must conclude that beings cannot be defined On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 453 referential multivocity,” clearly privileges the linguistic practice of epistemic judgment (“speaking the incomprehensible God”!) in a way that keeps the precise relationship between the orders of being and knowledge in Aquinas somewhat in suspense. On the one hand he emphasizes the primarily logical nature of the practice of analogical judgments: For Aquinas the analogy of referential multivocity is primarily a logical mean between univocity and pure equivocity and as such is neutral as regards the ontological question of whether a subject possesses an analogous predicate intrinsically or not. (127) On the other hand, he wishes to affirm a certain notion of this logical order arising from the order of being: That being said, however, it is also true, as a kind of corollary to our main thesis, that Aquinas grounds the analogous predication of the divine attributes in the real similarity between creatures and the Creator-God, and also uses the notion of analogy to refer not merely to logical realities but also to metaphysical structures of causality within the real world. (127) Rocca leaves the matter with the broad affirmation of such a relation, which clearly privileges the logical nature of the practice of analogical judgments. Montagnes, in contrast, leaves no doubt about the precise metaphysical relationship obtaining between the order of being and the order of knowing: In the last analysis, the unity of being rests upon the unity of the first cause of being. The unity that one discovers is not only that of the concept of being, but also the real unity of the Principle of being. Hence, the structure of analogy and that of participation are rigorously parallel: they correspond to each other as the conceptual aspect and the real aspect of the unity of being.As long as one has not returned to the real unity of the Principle, the multiplicity of beings has not yet truly been reduced to One. In short, the analogy of being . . . suppose[s] to reproduce the unity of order which ties beings up with their Principle. Thus and thus only does the realistic and critical character of the theory of the analogy of being show up within Thomas’s philosophy.4 independently of their dependence upon God, as the effects of creative causality: esse quod rebus creatis inest non potest intelligi nisi ut deductum ab esse divino.The causal dependence on God creates the relation necessary for analogy by reference to a primary instance without risk of confounding beings and God in one and the same form or notion.” 4 Ibid., 91. 454 Reinhard Hütter Montagnes’s way of putting the matter presses the question how the metaphysical and the properly theological aspects of analogy are precisely related. If one follows Rocca, St.Thomas seems to have moved back and forth between, on the one hand, the unfolding of sacra doctrina informed by a deep theological intuition—giving rise to the interplay between cataphatic and apophatic God-talk—and, on the other hand, the best of logical tools available to conceptually support and unfold this theological intuition. If one follows Montagnes, however, St. Thomas treats analogy first and foremost in an ontological way in the sense that whenever analogy is applied, the content of what is said must be taken into account first and foremost. Unlike Montagnes, Rocca conceives analogy pertaining primarily to the domain of logic: That is, he understands it as a formal structure of predication.And indeed, such a primarily logically conceived notion of analogy is more conducive to an immediate application to the theological interplay between cataphatic and apophatic God-talk. However, at the same time it remains rather unclear in Rocca’s reconstruction whether, and if so how, for St. Thomas proper metaphysical discourse—as the intellectual reception and speculative penetration of reality and the analogy of participation in being—is at least integral to, if not constitutive of, the scientific execution of sacra doctrina. Rather, Rocca’s impressively learned and comprehensive genetic-historical reconstruction suggests in so many ways—perhaps against his own best intentions—that St. Thomas practiced a highly personal form of bricolage, albeit an overwhelmingly successful one due to his conceptual “wizardry” (124, note 75), fusing from highly disparate and historically contingent conceptual material a personal metaphysical synthesis of doubtless ingenuity, but which was in no way integral to (while formally independent of) his theological project. It is in conveying the impression of “Aquinas the metaphysician” that Rocca fails to convince. Precisely in this regard, on the contrary, Montagnes does convince by reconstructing St.Thomas’s metaphysics in the speculative act itself, that is, in the procedure proper to the formal object of metaphysics. Hence, while Montagnes and Rocca are in fundamental agreement about their shared opposition to the Cajetanian interpretation of analogy as proper proportionality, a difference as instructive as it is significant opens up between the two. Briefly, contrary to Montagnes, Rocca prioritizes— especially in matters theological—the act of judgment over the mind’s first act of simple understanding, the act of obtaining concepts. Rocca plays off Aquinas’s ex professo treatment of this matter against what he reconstrues as St.Thomas’s de facto practice. According to Rocca, St.Thomas employs a rather broad meaning of the terms apprehensio and conceptio, such that at least On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 455 some concepts turn out to be the result of epistemic judgment and other related rational procedures. Fundamentally, for Rocca,“every predication is a judgment seeking and bespeaking the truth” (154). Consequently, judgment is involved in concept-formation such that at least some concepts follow from judgment and not vice versa. Drawing upon Edward Schillebeeckx,William Hill, Etienne Gilson, Henri Bouillard, David Burrell, and Colman O’Neill, Rocca accounts for the practice of analogical judgments without any need to seek recourse in some “analogous concept”; rather, “analogy is a matter of making true predications about God, of using concepts in judgments” (157). It is quite worthwhile to attend closely to Rocca’s central thesis: Analogy as judgment . . . , which is analogy-in-the-act rather than analogy-after-the-fact, uses and abuses concepts by claiming in their very employment to refer to a Transcendent that is not open to conceptual insight. Theological analogy, paradoxically, in its truth-claim sans intuitive apprehension, asserts what cannot be fully conceived or defined, and yet makes its assertions with concepts inextricably bound to creaturely modes. Aquinas’ theological analogy subsists in the judgments he makes about God, judgments that necessarily transcend the very concepts that comprise them. The basic unit of theological analogy is the complete statement, and the meanings of discrete concepts must be referred back to the truth-claim of the whole proposition. Moreover, while analogyin-the-act arises in the judgments themselves, his formal doctrine of analogy is only established once he takes a reflexive look at his original theological judgments and analyzes what must be the case epistemologically in order for them to be true. If we tend automatically to think of judgments as built up out of concepts, so that truth is meaningdependent, in the case of theological analogy we must also reverse the direction and think of the meaning of the divine names as truthdependent. (194–95) However, what does it mean exactly to say that “the meaning of the divine names [is] truth-dependent”? In se, this surely is true, but quoad nos this claim remains problematic. Does the very practice of judgments not presuppose in all cases the initial obtaining of concepts: In other words, can there plausibly be any “original theological judgments” without antecedent “concepts inextricably bound to creaturely modes”? Of course, the very point of the supernatural virtue of faith is to actively receive a broad range of concepts and judgments by way of Scripture and tradition that inform faith’s discursive activity. However, Scripture and tradition together with the concepts and judgments they convey can only be effectively received Reinhard Hütter 456 in a context in which the analogicity of creaturely concepts in their regular creaturely modes is already fully at play, inexorably producing meaning, and open to a proper metaphysical analysis. Hence, the question arises— and Montagnes and Rocca seem to come down on different sides— whether in the speculative order there obtains an indissoluble and constitutive relation between predicamental and transcendental analogy, reflecting the analogical unity of being, or whether theological analogy explodes any relation such that the meaning of divine naming has to become inherently truth-dependent? Ultimately, Rocca seems to see unity in theological analogy arise solely from the acts of judgment that use and abuse concepts in their attempted reference to the transcendent. By contrast, Montagnes insists also in matters of theological analogy on the analogical concept and its special unity per prius et posterius: [T]he analogical concept has a totally special unity; it does not stand above its inferiors but it applies to them without any intermediary, and it does not represent them equally but applies to them per prius et posterius. . . . Accidents and substance, creatures and God are gathered in the unity of being only in virtue of the relation of causality and participation which binds the second term to the first, the accidents to the substance, the creatures to God. Being stands above neither predicamental nor transcendental diversity; it belongs per prius to God and per posterius to creatures.The concept of being immediately designates God or creatures, substance or accidents, not separated and disjoint [sic], but considered within the unity of the relation that binds them to the primary instance. For predicamental analogy, there is no primary instance other than substance, and for transcendental analogy no primary instance other than God, the ultimate term of reference of all the meanings of being, the principle of order by relation to which all else is unified. In short, the unity of being hangs upon the real unity of the First Being.5 Contrary to Montagnes, Rocca advances a reading of St. Thomas that allows the concept of being as the root of all judgments as well as the fruit of some of them. He rests his case on the fact that Aquinas understands the mind’s concept in a broad sense, that is, as “a definition, a judgment, or anything at all in which the intellect speaks its interior word” (173). The key for Rocca is the “final concept” (173) that constitutes the telos of a process of antecedent judgments. And so he concludes that Aquinas’ theological or transcendental analogy may also be seen as broadly conceptual, in the sense that the meanings of that analogy are 5 Ibid., 81–82. On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 457 themselves the fruit of a web of interwoven theological first-order judgments stretching out toward the truth. (173) To put the matter differently, Rocca’s reading of St. Thomas can arguably be understood as awkwardly poised between, on the one hand, a Thomist account that—along the lines of Montagnes—reciprocally integrates the transcendent analogy and the analogy of being, and, on the other hand, Karl Barth’s “analogy of faith” (analogia fidei).6 Because human language has no inherent capacity to refer properly to God, God in a gracious act of self-revelation contingently confirms human language— and does so again and again in the Spirit’s freely faithful and faithfully free activity—such that it can give appropriate witness to God’s self-revelation. It is the truth of God’s self-revelatory act that produces the meaning of the gratuitously confirmed language such that the meaning of all proper theological concepts in their utter contingency upon God’s self-revelation is all the way down truth-dependent.While it might go against his own best intentions, it seems clear that Rocca occupies ground rather proximate to Barth when he claims that “Aquinas’ theological or transcendent analogy may also be seen as broadly conceptual, in the sense that the meanings of that analogy are themselves the fruit of a web of interwoven theological first-order judgments stretching out toward the truth” (173). In short, the more Rocca loosens the relationship between predicamental and transcendental analogy, the more his reading of St. Thomas approximates Barth’s analogia fidei, an analogy cut loose from any substantial moorings in predicamental analogy and allegedly arising solely out of true judgments about God and creatures as normatively witnessed to in Scripture and as expanded under the guidance of the Spirit by the grammar of faith. 6 According to Bruce McCormack, one of the most able contemporary inter- preters of Karl Barth’s theology, for Barth “the ‘analogy of faith’ refers most fundamentally to a relation of correspondence between an act of God and an act of a human subject; the act of Divine self-revelation and the human act of faith in which that revelation is acknowledged. More specifically, the analogy which is established in a revelation event is an analogy between God’s knowledge of Himself and human knowledge of Him in and through human concepts and words. . . .There is nothing in the being or knowing of the human subject which helps to bring this event about—no capacity or pre-understanding which might be seen as a necessary precondition to its occurrence. . . . God’s self-knowledge does not become analogically related to a prior human knowledge of Him in revelation; rather human knowledge is conformed to His. God’s act is the analogue, ours is the analogate.” Bruce McCormack, Karl Barth’s Critically Realistic Dialectical Theology: Its Genesis and Development 1909–1936 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), 16–17, original emphasis. 458 Reinhard Hütter III The third part of Rocca’s work,“Crucial Truths about God,” is inherently linked to the first part; and, arguably, according to the ordo disciplinae, it should have preceded part one, a point made above.This part ends with a chapter carrying the same heading in which Rocca offers a brilliant and rich account of St. Thomas’s profound theological vision. He concludes the chapter with a particularly helpful discussion of the notion of participation and the complex discussion around it, concluding with Cornelio Fabro’s claim that “participation is the special ontology of analogy, and analogy the special semantics of participation” (287).And again the question arises: If, instead of functioning solely as an adage, Fabro’s claim had functioned as axiomatic and, hence, had governed Rocca’s first part all the way down, would it not have required Rocca to acknowledge the essential metaphysical relationship between predicamental and transcendental analogy—very much along the lines of Montagnes? However, the main point of this third part, an extensive commentary on the relationship between Aristotle and St. Thomas, is not only to display “the primary supportive pillar of his theological epistemology— the existence of God the Creator” (199), but also to show that in ascertaining the philosophical underpinnings of this pillar, St.Thomas operates all the way down as a theologian; that is, while he employs discursive reason to the utmost degree in the form of an ancillary metaphysical speculation, he consistently gives pride of place to faith and theology. In order to demonstrate this thesis—a thesis that, especially in its finer points, remains hotly debated among Thomists—Rocca employs the hermeneutical strategy of reading Aristotle not “through” or “by way of ” St. Thomas’s own commentatorial interpretation, but rather “over against” it, in order that the theological presuppositions operative in Aquinas’s interpretation of Aristotle become traceable. Consequently, he reads Aristotle in light of the best of recent historical scholarship and, unsurprisingly, encounters a deeply aporetic philosopher in general and, in particular, a profound tension between the account of a first mover offered in the Physics and the one offered in the Metaphysics. According to Rocca, it is not St. Thomas’s superior metaphysical insight, the work of a more profound and consequent speculation, that overcomes the aporetic moments in Aristotle. Rather, St.Thomas is able to synthesize Aristotle on the basis of his antecedently and independently held theological beliefs. Aristotle, in other words, only gains overarching consistency under St. Thomas’s able commentatorial hands, which are consistently guided by faith: “The deeper truth that Aquinas possesses is the knowledge of God as creative pure act and subsistent being, as the infinitely perfect Creator On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 459 and absolute initiator, out of nothing, of all being, motion, and time” (220). Rocca substantiates this claim in a magisterial discussion of the way St.Thomas handled Aristotle’s proof for God’s existence based on motion, creation ex nihilo, and the question of the philosophical (non)-demonstrability of the world’s eternity. Tucked away in a long footnote we find Rocca’s own position: “In my opinion, Aristotle never taught a philosophy of creation, nor did he even possess the proper principles from which he might have deduced it. Instead, Thomas has completely transformed Aristotle’s ‘principle of motion’ into the ‘bestower of being’ ” (229). Needless to say, with this claim Rocca puts himself into opposition with much of traditional Aristotelian Thomism. And on purely genetic-historical grounds, he might even have a point. But genetic-historical grounds are categorically different from proper metaphysical grounds.The former are extrinsic to the speculative act of metaphysical discourse, the latter are intrinsic.While I agree with Rocca’s point that faith in God the Creator was the decisive “context of discovery” in which Aquinas read Aristotle’s works, I would also want to maintain that his speculative interpretation and development of Aristotle occurs in a completely consistent way based on the formal object of metaphysics itself in the parameters of its proper “context of justification.” Hence, while St. Thomas’s “transformation” of Aristotle might possibly be ascertained on genetic-historical grounds, an answer to the question whether this transformation amounts to a consistent and compelling metaphysical advance beyond Aristotle’s position requires entering proper metaphysical discourse. In short, the larger question opened up by Rocca’s third part is one in large part extrinsic to his claims about the practice of judgment constituting the unity of theological analogy. Rather, this question pertains to the pressing problem after the accomplished reconstruction, as successful as it is comprehensive, of the “genuine, unadulterated, historical Aquinas”: whether Thomist theology and its entailed metaphysics can be appropriated only hermeneutically in a fundamentally interminable historical mode of ongoing efforts of reconstructive interpretation or whether it is possible, and by now mandated, to retrieve a substantive continuation of the speculative discourse ad mentem S.Thomae informed by the respective dual formal objects of sacra doctrina and metaphysics.To be sure, Rocca’s historically plausible way of construing the relationship between a historically “original” Aristotle and St. Thomas’s creative reception of him undoubtedly contributes to an unbroken contemporary trend of “liberating” St. Thomas’s crucial theological insights from their alleged Babylonian captivity in the fetters of an irretrievably outdated Aristotelianism.And, of course, these theological truths are per se in no need of any metaphysical underpinning—Aristotelian, 460 Reinhard Hütter Platonic, or otherwise. This is always important to remember, and St. Thomas would be the first to do so (ST I, q. 1, a. 6, ad 3; and a. 8, ad 2). However, St.Thomas’s unique and lasting contribution to theology (quite different in that regard from the theologians of the earlier patristic period) was to contemplate the theological truths in such a way that their deepest understanding was fostered by and ultimately coincided with a true metaphysical analysis of the world: in short, the formal object of metaphysics being an integral component in the elucidation and defense of the knowledge received by way of the formal object of theology. Rocca’s genetic-historical reconstruction, as nuanced, comprehensive, and astute as it is, however, tends to sever the one from the other. So the crucial theological truths come to hang strangely, un-Thomistically mid-air, held aloft by a somewhat Augustinian/Barthian “from aboveness,” in their retrieved core ultimately unencumbered and unsupported by a proper metaphysical argumentation operating “from below.” IV The fourth part, “The Divine Names,” is the shortest but brings home the arguments of the preceding parts. First, Rocca offers a lucid account of Aquinas’s positive theology of the Divine Names, stretching from the Scriptum super libros Sententiarum via the De potentia to the famous question 13 in the prima pars of the Summa theologiae.“The substantial, proper, and analogical divine names are predicated primarily of God as regards the absolute perfection they signify, for God is the perfection in an infinite manner and causes the participated perfection in creatures” (329). The concluding chapter on the distinction between the reality signified and the manner of signification brings to closure Rocca’s central thesis on analogy—drawing here especially upon the prior work of William Hill and the early Edward Schillebeeckx: Analogy comes to pass when the mind predicates the name and its meaning of God in an act of judgment claiming a truth about the holy darkness of God, which transcends anything the concept can intuitively grasp on its own. . . .The truth of the judgment is what makes us realize that the concept, as used but not as conceived, has been extended beyond the creaturely realm. We never really know in a clear conceptual fashion what a divine name might mean for God, and whatever we do know about such a name is always a consequence of the judgments we have already made about God. (350) Since in Aquinas the analogical nature of divine predication and the use of the res/modus distinction are matters of judgment instead of concept formation, the danger of the “common core of univocity” is On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 461 avoided. His theological analogy depends not on a more profound conceptualization but on a recognition of the truth about God. (351) I regard Rocca’s account of the analogical nature of divine predication as a correct and moreover succinct reading of Aquinas. Rocca indeed successfully avoids the danger of the “common core of univocity” by squarely placing the res/modus distinction into the realm of logic by making it a matter of predication that is ultimately based on faith, on the recognition of the truth about God that does not directly and integrally depend on the knowledge of God by way of creatures. But here the question arises whether Rocca—in order to avoid the rightly dreaded “common core of univocity”—has poured out the baby with the bathwater. While “the act of signifying goes further than the ratio nominis,” as Schillebeeckx rightly insists, both the act of signifying and the ratio nominis ultimately depend on the analogy of participation in being. Whatever is predicated of God according to this analogy must be understood as indeed a knowledge of God, even though it remains a knowledge of God by way of God’s creatures. It seems to me that the predication in the act of judgment always presupposes the analogy of being and all the concept formations entailed in it.The conceptualization inherent to the analogy of participation in being constitutes an indispensable vehicle for a recognition of the truth about God.While theological analogy as the practice of judgments is in no way limited to the scope of the analogy of being, the former always comes by way of the latter as grace always comes by way of being. V Rocca’s book is an impressive achievement of stupendous scholarship and lucid analysis. It proffers an excellent reconstruction of St. Thomas’s thought that deepens our understanding of his theology at crucial points of contention and that sets a high mark to be reached by alternative Thomist accounts in the tradition of Cajetan.A magisterial contribution to Thomistic studies, Rocca’s work will be the foremost study on St.Thomas’s theological epistemology in general and on analogy in particular for years to come. Rocca clearly presupposes and draws upon the strong tradition of historical Aquinas research in the wake of Martin Grabmann and MarieDominique Chenu, but under the surface of his genetic-historical method one can clearly sense a renewed interest in the normative “so what” question on the other side of an exhaustive and at points exhausting historical reconstruction of the “authentic” Aquinas. However, the adopted method does not allow Rocca to transition substantively into the normative and 462 Reinhard Hütter speculative mode of inquiry constitutive of the theological and metaphysical discourse proper and characteristic of St.Thomas. Nevertheless, Rocca is passionately interested in and committed to the theological substance of St.Thomas’s thought and the entailed practice of analogical judgment. Such a return to a reconstruction of St. Thomas’s theology in light of its proper formal object and with an eye to its ongoing contemporary relevance is warmly welcomed. The return to speculative theology proper, however, also brings back the notorious question of how the formal object of theology and the formal object of metaphysics relate to each other and whether it is advisable in general as well as in the particular case of St. Thomas to reconstruct theological substance and practice in light of the former, unmediated by and only contingently related to the speculative exigencies of the latter. In other words, the specter of the long-standing but lately derided commentatorial tradition of Aristotelian Thomism looms as the unaddressed “other” on the margins of Rocca’s genetic-historical discourse. While Rocca displays an impressive command of the best current historical scholarship (internationally) on the Aristotelian and neo-Platonic strands in Aquinas’s thought, his reconstructive discourse remains in large part extrinsic to the substantive metaphysical issues preoccupying St.Thomas in his encounter with Aristotelian and neo-Platonic texts. In consequence and in comparison to Montagnes, Rocca’s Aquinas displays less than his full speculative, metaphysical force, which consists largely in his compelling integration of neo-Platonic elements into an unmitigated Aristotelian framework and hence thereby properly and successfully expanding Aristotle’s metaphysics of substance on its own grounds into a metaphysics of esse. It is never a good practice to enlarge an already-large volume; however, the book ends rather abruptly.While a convincing reconstruction is one thing, reimplementation is another. How can and should St. Thomas’s theological epistemology and his practice of analogical judgment inform contemporary theology? A return in a concluding chapter to the discussion with the Protestant theologians Barth, Pannenberg, and Jüngel, as well as the Catholic theologians and philosophers Gustav Söhngen and Erich Przywara, would have helped to more forcefully make Aquinas’s ongoing relevance bear upon the dominant discussions of twentiethcentury theology. Rocca opens the door wide but remains on the threshold. Hopefully, in his next book he will offer a more expansive engagement of the twentieth-century criticisms of analogy as well as the presently widespread infatuation with an unmitigated apophaticism. However, even in its present form, Rocca’s work offers a salutary antidote to a number of important contemporary readings of St. Thomas’s On Gregory Rocca’s Speaking the Incomprehensible God 463 thought. For one, his reconstruction achieves a most desirable mean between two lines of thought: Thomists in conversation primarily with contemporary analytic philosophy of religion (and its strong Scotist/ Suarezian undercurrent of conceptual univocitism in God-talk), such as Eleonore Stump,7 whose philosophical doctrine of God—despite gestures to analogical predication—makes God all too knowable; and Thomists deeply influenced by the subtle adoption of Wittgenstein’s late philosophy (in Cornelius Ernst’s, Herbert McCabe’s, and Fergus Kerr’s versions of Thomism), such as the early David Burrell8 and Denys Turner9 promoting an apophaticism that makes God all too unknowable. Moreover, and now in agreement with Denys Turner as well as Aristotelian Thomism (to mention just Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, Jacques Maritain, and Ralph McInerny) and in marked contrast to Radical Orthodoxy as well the reading of Aquinas advanced by Henri de Lubac and other representatives of the “nouvelle théologie,” Rocca rightly emphasizes the central role the philosophical proofs for God’s existence play in Aquinas’s way of “doing theology,” a role that can be disregarded only at the grave peril of seriously distorting the overall coherence of his project. Most important, for contemporary Catholic theology Rocca’s book constitutes a salient invitation to return to a serious consideration of St. Thomas’s unique balance between positive and negative theology; the ongoing mandate for Catholic theological epistemology should be nothing short of this balance.While Cardinal Léger’s concern about an ecclesia unius doctoris10 might have been apropos in the heyday of neo-scholasticism, the present state of Catholic theology seems more likely to conjure up the specter of an ecclesia nullius doctoris (Nikolaus Lobkowicz). Moreover, while legitimate and substantive objections to his reconstruction of Aquinas’s account can be raised from other Thomists or, for that matter, Scotist or Suarezian perspectives, Rocca’s study nevertheless serves as a salutary reminder of the level of conceptual sophistication to which the Catholic theological tradition is committed in order to truly and faithfully think 7 Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003). 8 David B. Burrell, CSC, Aquinas: God and Action (London and Henley: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979). 9 Denys Turner, Faith, Reason, and the Existence of God (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004). 10 At the Second Vatican Council, Cardinal Léger exclaimed, “Vae Ecclesiae unius doctoris!” as in the course of the council discussion on section 15 of the decree Optatam totius on the theological education of priests several bishops pressed for the explicit mentioning of Thomas Aquinas instead of leaving the matter with the more general rendition of a patrimonium philosophicum perenniter validum. See Acta synodalia, pt. III, vol.VII, 709. 464 Reinhard Hütter about, speak of, and most importantly proclaim the Triune God, Creator, and Redeemer.Theology has to a large degree abandoned the commitment to search for and contemplate the truth (singular!); consequently it is progressively eroded by a secular as well as ecclesial culture that feeds on the fast-food of intellectual consumer choice and the pragmatic concerns of pastoral expediency. Only the increasing submission to the rigor and labor of speculative theological contemplation—to which Rocca untiringly gestures beyond the confines of his genetic-historical reading—will help avert the danger of the ever-increasing banalization of Christian God-talk N&V in the very discipline of theology itself.