Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 711–730 711 Humanae Vitae 17: Vaticinium ex eventu? An Illustration from the Maritains’ Moral Guidance to Maurice Sachs ROMANUS C ESSARIO, O.P. St. John’s Seminary Brighton, Massachusetts Introduction I N REMARKS prepared for a conference that commemorated the twenty-fifth anniversary of Humanae Vitae, Father Ernest Fortin, A.A., made the following observation:“In retrospect, Humanae Vitae can be said to have been truly prophetic. It foresaw that the use of contraceptives and the development of a contraceptive mentality would deal a severe blow to family life and therewith to society as a whole.”1 The text that Father Fortin probably had in mind is found at §17 of the 1968 encyclical letter of Pope Paul VI: Not much experience is needed in order to know human weakness, and to understand that men—especially the young, who are so vulnerable on this point—have need of encouragement to be faithful to the moral law, so that they must not be offered some easy means of eluding its observance. (Humanae Vitae, §17) In 1993 at Assumption College in Worcester, Massachusetts, Father Fortin included among the unhappy consequences of the widespread acceptance of contraceptives the fact that “homosexual partnerships are 1 Ernest Fortin,“Humanae Vitae’s Silver Jubilee:Twenty-Five Years Later,” in Ernest L. Fortin: Collected Essays, vol. 4, Ever Ancient, Ever New: Ruminations on the City, the Soul, and the Church, ed. Michael P. Foley (New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2007), 164. 712 Romanus Cessario, O.P. being granted both family status in law and the right to adopt children.”2 He wondered about future “nightmarish choices.” He was right to wonder out loud. In 2008, Massachusetts and Connecticut now recognize civil marriages between persons of the same sex. This paper reports on the distinctively Catholic moral guidance that Jacques and Raïssa Maritain gave to a certain young Frenchman named Maurice Sachs. We know of course that Jacques Maritain and Pope Paul VI were friends. It remains speculation whether the following story of Maurice Sachs may have contributed to that warning—the one Father Fortin calls “prophetic”—that is contained in §17 of Humanae Vitae. In other terms, whether this text does in fact constitute a vaticinium ex eventu. Some Background to Sexual Mores entre les deux guerres Taking a broad view, the English philosopher, Roger Scruton, has observed that the situation of French intellectuals during the early twentieth century was not unlike that of the English intellectuals. Writers and artists were drawn in three directions—towards a kind of iconized vision of France and her Catholic faith, towards a flamboyant bohemianism that defied bourgeois conventions, and towards the new universal faith of the communist Church.3 The Maritains became acquainted with representative figures from each class.The early decades of the twentieth century also witnessed a marked increase in the number of homosexual liaisons that occurred among les vedettes of the Paris literary and artistic salons.These ephemeral gay relationships were countenanced for the most part by the fashionable elite that inhabited le beau monde.What one may describe as a sociological phenomenon, this “world” forms some of the background for the exercise of that divine mission to evangelize that Jacques and Raïssa Maritain undertook with passion during “les Années Folles.” The Figure of Maurice Sachs (1906–1945) To explore the Maritains as spiritual guides for the perplexed, I have chosen one figure from the period, Maurice Sachs, a man whose biography is subtitled, Les travaux forcés de la frivolité.4 If we follow the standard accounts of this Frenchman’s topsy-turvy life, he comes out looking like the poster boy for French-style bohemianism. Truth to tell, however, 2 Ibid. 3 In private research that Professor Roger Scruton has contributed to a research project on natural law underway at the Institute for the Psychological Sciences in Arlington,Virginia. 4 Henri Raczymow, Maurice Sachs, ou Les travaux forcés de la frivolité (Paris: Gallimard, 1988). Sachs himself coined the expression. See p. 423. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 713 Maurice Sachs at various times and at other times perhaps simultaneously followed all three of the directions that Roger Scruton sketches out to describe the paths taken by early twentieth-century French intellectuals. It should be noted first of all, that the second path, that of flamboyant bohemianism, was not explicitly or exclusively homosexual. It was, again on Roger Scruton’s account, a path of wit, satire, bohemianism and cosmopolitanism, a thousand miles from the patriotic fervor of Charles Péguy. It owed much, however, to Péguy’s contemporary Guillaume Apollinaire, illegitimate son of a Polish mother. Apollinaire coined the term “surrealism” and revived interest in the works of the Marquis de Sade. He wrote erotic novels as well as the verses (for example, Alcools) which made him famous, and was perhaps the first apostle of Transgression.5 Among his friends were Jean Cocteau, Erik Satie, Marc Chagall, and Max Jacob, all of whom belonged after World War I (at the end of which Apollinaire died of influenza, weakened by a head wound received at the front) to the circle which frequented Le boeuf sur le toit.6 This celebrated 5 “Alcools (1913) was a selection of poems written over the previous fifteen years. It combined classical verse forms with modern imagery, involving transcriptions of street conversations overheard by chance and the absence of punctuation. It opened with the poem ‘Zone,’ in which the tormented poet wanders through streets after the loss of his mistress. Among its other famous lyrical pieces is ‘Le pont Mirabeau.’ Some of its poems were inspired by Jacqueline Kolb.Annie Playden, an English governess, inspired the Rhineland piece, ‘La chanson du malaime.’ ” For further information, see www.kirjasto.sci.fi/apollina.htm. And of course one notes the unmistakable and almost overbearing Christian symbolism of “Zone,” which intimates something of the intensely Catholic milieu of early twentieth-century France. It seems that no matter what the position (from nihilistic transgression to apostolic exhortation) an intellectual or artist adopted in those days, Catholicism was inevitably close at hand.Also noteworthy is the temptations of paganism and its connection with eroticism, which would preoccupy Georges Bataille (another failed Catholic) for the rest of his life. It is interesting to observe as well that Bataille was at first deeply involved in surrealism until his break with Andre Breton.The scene at the end of Histoire de l’oeil involving the mutilation and murder of a Catholic priest is perhaps the most ugly expression of the rage some of these men felt at being not only tied to a Catholic past, but involved in a Catholic present. No wonder so much of this work in transgression is taken up in the search for new gods, in the form of idols and concepts. 6 Le Boeuf sur le Toit, op. 58 (The Ox on the Roof, subtitle The Nothing-Doing Bar ) is a surrealist ballet. It is based on a score composed by Darius Milhaud that is strongly influenced by Brazilian popular music (the title is that of an old Brazilian tango, one of close to thirty Brazilian tunes quoted in the composition). Originally the piece was to have been the score of a silent Charlie Chaplin film (Cinéma-fantaisie for violin and piano). Its transformation into a ballet was the making of the piece, with a scenario by Jean Cocteau, stage designs by Raoul Dufy, and costumes by Guy-Pierre Fauconnet.The choreography was deliberately 714 Romanus Cessario, O.P. eighth-arrondissement cabaret was the place at which Stravinsky and Diaghilev could be seen along with the surrealists, the fauves, poets like Jacob and Paul Claudel—and just about anybody who was anybody among the bohemians of the day.7 It played a great role in the “education” of the unattached adolescents of the period—or so we are told by one such who was prominent among those who frequented Le boeuf.8 The person in question was the above-mentioned teenager Maurice Sachs, a budding novelist who seduced and betrayed in endless succession, and who finished life as a prisoner of the Gestapo, having first worked for them as an agent happy to betray even his friends. On the surface, Sachs was the epitome of the serial double-dealer whose predatory homosexuality began in adolescence, when he was educated in a Parisian English-style boys school, and later led to promiscuous affairs with everyone who mattered—including Gide, Coceatu, and Jacob—as well as with many who did not.9 Persuaded by Cocteau in 1925 to embrace Catholicism, Sachs shortly thereafter entered a seminary with a view to becoming a priest. However he shortly left on account of a relapse into promiscuous homosexuality, and seems thereafter to have drifted away from the practice of the Catholic faith, though not from his Catholic friends.10 Nor did his Catholic friends abandon him. In his acclaimed biography of Jacques and Raïssa Maritain, Jean-Luc Barré very slow, in marked contrast to the lively and joyful spirit of the music. The premiere was given in February 1920 at the Théâtre des Champs Élysées and comprised, besides the ballet, Adieu New York by Georges Auric, Cocardes by Francis Poulenc and Trois petites pièces montées by Erik Satie.The version for chamber orchestra was followed by another for piano duet, subtitled Cinema Symphony on South American Airs. Its performance lasts about a quarter of an hour.The ballet gave its name to a well-known Parisian bar-restaurant that opened in 1922. For further information, see www.boeufsurletoit.com. 7 Sergei Pavlovich Diaghilev (Russian: Cеpге́п /∑ па́влOвп / ч дя́гп / леB/Sergei Pavlovich Dyagilev), also referred to as Serge (March 31, 1872–August 19, 1929), was a Russian art critic, patron, ballet impresario and founder of the Ballets Russes from which many famous dancers and choreographers would later arise. 8 Maurice Sachs, Witches’ Sabbath, trans. Richard Howard (New York: Stein and Day, 1964), 72. 9 The school was L’École de l’Isle-de-France, which Sachs referred to in The Sabbath as le college de Luza. 10 “Il parlait beaucoup, beaucoup de Paris et en particulier de la Maison Maritain à Meudon. . . . À la fin, nous avions decidé de nous rencontrer à Meudon apres la guerre.” “Letter of Richard Hitzler to Raïssa Maritain,” in Maurice Sachs, Jacques and Raïssa Maritain, Correspondance (1925–1939), eds. Michel Bressolette and René Mougel (Paris: Gallimard, 2003), 323. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 715 reports that Jacques Maritain as late as 1949 plaintively wondered out loud, “Poor Maurice Sachs, is he dead, is he alive?”11 As will become evident in what follows, Maurice Sachs affords a good example of the second of Scruton’s directions—the bohemian.Thanks to his association with André Gide, Sachs also briefly followed the third, the communist, direction.12 And his attachment to the first or Christian direction may not be as short-lived as many commentators assume. We know, for instance, that from his prison cell at Fuhlsbüttel, a Nazi concentration camp located near Hamburg, Sachs recalled his early association with the Maritains that led to his baptism.13 Richard Hitzler, a fellow prisoner at Fuhlsbüttel who, unlike Sachs, survived his internment, reports that, during his final days, Sachs repeatedly expressed the ardent wish that he would be able to return after the war to the Maritains’ home at Meudon, which since the spring of 1923 had provided a spiritual gravitational center for the poets, painters, and musicians whom they had met in the company of their own evangelist, Léon Bloy.14 To appreciate the Maritains’ influence on Maurice Sachs, we must examine closely the evolution of their friendship with him. Abandoned by his father at the age of five, Maurice Sachs was brought up in straightened circumstances. “From the time of his teens,” writes one author, the physically unappealing yet highly seductive Sachs, whom [Jean] Cocteau has depicted in his memoirs stuffing his pockets with toilet paper he pretended was money, followed an essentially theatrical calling, an endless getting into character. Sachs has hastily been labeled ‘the 11 Jean Luc Barré, Jacques & Raïssa Maritain: Beggars for Heaven, trans. Bernard E. Doering (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005), 405. The book has been favorably reviewed by John F. X. Knasas in Catholic Historical Review 93 (2007): 435–36. 12 His biographer includes a chapter on “Maurice ‘communiste.’ ” See Raczymow, Maurice Sachs, 249–56. 13 The prison, originally built as a regular prison in 1879, was converted to a satellite concentration camp after the Nazis’ takeover of Germany in 1933, when it was placed under the control of the SS and SA. Most of the inmates were antiNazi sympathizers, Jews, Jehovah Witnesses, Roma, gays, and others whom the regime wanted to lock up. Over seven hundred people were interned in the camp following Kristallnacht in 1938.“Konzentrationslager Fuhlsbüttel” (Fuhlsbüttel concentration camp) was referred to as “KolaFu” in common parlance and became a synonym for oppression and death through hard labor. Fuhlsbüttel was often an initial point of incarceration for prisoners who were sent on to other camps such as Buchenwald, Neuengamme, Ravensbrück or Sachsenhausen.The camp was liberated in May 1945, by which time over 250 people had been murdered there. A camp memorial has been constructed nearby. 14 Sachs, Correspondance, 23. See also, Barré, Maritain, 149ff. 716 Romanus Cessario, O.P. Jean Genet of the twenties,’ but the resemblance is superficial, based on their shared combination of homosexuality, thieving, black marketeering, and later fascination with Nazi Germany.15 This sketch published in Yale French Studies represents the standard unsympathetic account of the teenager that the Maritains welcomed into their affections. At the same time, this short description helps us to appreciate Raïssa Maritain’s first reaction to Maurice Sachs: “something mysteriously dark,” she opined.16 What follows touches only the high points of the interaction between the Maritains and Maurice Sachs, whose true personal dispositions and intentions, it should become evident, are not always easy to judge. We begin in July 1924, when, at Meudon, Jacques the Evangelist first receives Jean Cocteau, and eventually welcomes his friends, including the eighteen-year-old Maurice Sachs, who in February of the same year, had become one of Cocteau’s “secretaries.”17 Twelve months later, August 2, 1925, to be precise, and urged on by Cocteau, Maurice Sachs visits Jacques Maritain in order to pursue instructions in the Catholic faith. Jacques begins with the Trinity.18 By the end of the month, Maurice receives baptism with Raïssa Maritain as godmother and Jean Cocteau godfather by proxy—Jacques standing in.The place: the private chapel of the Maritains at 10 rue du Parc, Meudon. It is on the same day, August 29, 1925, that we read in Raïssa’s Journal,“Baptism of Maurice. Still, I am not reassured. This lad has something mysteriously dark about him that makes me ill at ease.” Maurice’s First Communion and Confirmation by the Bishop of Versailles follow appropriately.19 His biographer, Henri Raczymow, describes the young Maurice Sachs as an all or nothing man.20 Soon the new convert is thinking about pursuing a priestly vocation, and in the meantime, about taking up temporary residence with the Maritains. Raïssa holds out the advantages of his living with them: The presence of the Most Blessed Sacrament and “la douce 15 David J. Jacobson, “Jews for Genius: The Unholy Disorders of Maurice Sachs,” Yale French Studies 85 (1994): 183. 16 Barré, Maritain, 216. See also, Raczymow, Maurice Sachs, 58, citing Jacques Mari- tain, Journal de Raïssa (Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1963):“Ce garçon, écrira-t-elle dans son Journal, a quelque chose de obscur qui m’inquiète.” 17 Barré, Maritain, 180–226, devotes a chapter to the meeting of Maritain and Jean Cocteau titled “God or Jean Cocteau?” See also, Sachs, Correspondance, 33 note 1. 18 Raczymow, Maurice Sachs, 101. 19 Ibid., 106. 20 “Sachs, c’est toujours tout ou rien” (ibid., 108). Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 717 influence de Jacques.”21 On January 2, 1926, Maurice enters the Séminaire des Carmes, 21 rue d’Assas, which in 1792 had been the scene of the martyrdom of 115 priests and three bishops.22 The Maritains, Jean Cocteau, Max Jacob, and his peer friend, Jean Bourgoint, support him variously and variously.23 Maurice perseveres in his vocational resolution for about six and a half months. With certain allowances, Maurice adapted to the rigorous schedule of the seminary. Jacques Maritain, it is said, helped him to obtain permission to wear the clerical soutane in advance of the usual time. Maurice argued that the cassock would help him sustain the moral requirements of his new vocation, although he later confessed a perverse fascination with the dress-style of the soutane. At the same time, for six months, he made his daily morning meditation, mostly while reading Pascal, and assisted, kneeling, at Mass, even though he later reported in his diary that he suffered from spontaneous movements of the flesh.“But still,” Sachs further recalled, “it is a futile and merely nervous erection when the imagination does not sustain it with any incongruous image; there is no harm in it, at most a certain surprise and embarrassment.”24 Sachs nonetheless goes on to admit that these occurrences caused him “to feel remorse,” and that they led him to ask for permission to serve the Mass, an activity which he imagined would ease his discomfort. All in all, Maurice’s very first days in the Seminary were not without peace, especially when at the end of the day he came before the Blessed Virgin Mary. “There was no occasion to forget her,” writes Sachs. It was here that I prayed best, it was here that I believed best. Perhaps because it is easier to believe in the Holy Virgin than in God; for she created neither heaven nor earth, but a man in our image; because everything in us believes in her, as all that we are has grown within her, nine months from the day of conception.25 Not bad for a young convert burdened with past disorders and present temptations. 21 Letter of Raïssa Maritain to Maurice Sachs, November 19, 1925, Archives Madeleine Castaing, cited in Raczymow, Maurice Sachs, 110. 22 The web site reports: “L’accueil du séminaire des Carmes: Durant la Première Guerre mondiale, des séminaristes venus du nord et de l’est de la France sont hébergés dans l’ancien couvent. En 1919, Mgr Verdier y fonde un séminaire universitaire, toujours en fonctionnement aujourd’hui.” 23 Max Jacob ( July 12, 1876–March 5, 1944) was a French poet, painter, writer, and critic. He too was a convert to Catholicism. 24 Maurice Sachs, Witches’ Sabbath, 128–29. 25 Ibid., 132, original emphasis. Romanus Cessario, O.P. 718 Seminary discipline soon taxed the immature virtuous dispositions of the young Maurice.After two months of presumably good willed endeavor, he began to think of his cell as a “chamber of horrors and demons.”26 Old deep-seated habits, including losing struggles with masturbation, recurred: “I groaned in my solitude; I ran to the chapel, the garden, returned, knelt, got up again, fell back, started up, and finally sank down, beaten, into my lacerating pleasures.”27 Neither the ascetical practices of the period, which included using the discipline and other instruments of physical penance, nor the more humane suggestion of Jacques Maritain that he take up a minimum amount of apostolic activity—which Maritain, one assumes, rightly considered would put the still teenager,“M. Le Cure Maurice Sachs,” into living contact with other persons—were sufficient to calm his unholy desires. Then came the summer vacation months of 1926 when the diocesan seminarians were allowed to return to their families. Maurice left with his maternal grandmother Alice Bizet—sometime daughter-in-law of the composer Georges—for the French Riviera. The devil was waiting for him, as Jacques Maritain, who took the time to escort grandmother and grandson to the Gare de Lyon, may have instinctually anticipated. “I had come in utter innocence of heart,” Maurice later pleaded with his reader to believe in faith.28 Still, the highly charged atmosphere of the beach side resort, Juan-les-Pins, quickly overpowered this all too recently converted habitué of le beau monde.The young American writer Glenway Wescott, who would later become a familiar figure in the New York artistic and gay community, introduced Maurice to a teenage boy named Tom Pinkerton, who was then vacationing with his high-strung mother on the Côte d’Azur.29 Infatuation developed first, followed by what may have been a mutual seduction. “We succumbed to the exhaustion of our 26 Ibid., 135. 27 Ibid. 28 Ibid., 140–41. 29 As a writer, Glenway Wescott (1901–1987) left behind a series of novels, includ- ing The Grandmothers and The Pilgrim Hawk, noted for their remarkable lyricism. As a literary figure, Wescott also became a symbol of his times. Born on a Wisconsin farm in 1901, he associated as a young writer with Hemingway, Stein, and Fitzgerald in 1920s Paris and subsequently was a central figure in New York’s artistic and gay communities.Though he couldn’t finish a novel after the age of forty-five, he was just as famous as an arts impresario, as a diarist, and for the company he kept: W. H. Auden, Christopher Isherwood, Marianne Moore, Somerset Maugham, E. M. Forster, Joseph Campbell, and scores of other luminaries. See Jerry Rosco, Glenway Wescott Personally:A Biography (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2002). Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 719 forces of resistance but took no pleasure in doing so,” Maurice later wrote, perhaps tendentiously.30 The public scandal caused by Maurice’s sudden preoccupation with the sixteen-year-old Tom was enough to make the recently repentant Cocteau react strongly, and to insist that Maurice return immediately to Paris. Once back at the seminary, the priest who had baptized him the year before counseled:“Better make a good Christian than a bad priest.”31 In November 1926, Maurice left the seminary to fulfill his military service. From his military barracks, he wrote to Jacques on November 23, 1926, recounting his religious practices: “The only thing is that there is no Mass, but I make my stations of the cross while walking up to the stables which are two kilometers away, and I make my mediation while combing my horse.”32 After finishing his military service in April 1928, Maurice took on literary projects, eventually left for the United States where he opened an art gallery, married the daughter of a New York Presbyterian minister (whom he thereafter shortly abandoned), and subsequently took up a relationship with a young man, Henry Wibbels, in California. In March 1933, he encountered Jacques Maritain in Chicago. Later that same year Maurice returned to France. In 1939, Sachs was assigned to the commander of the British troops in Caen, then in 1942, he impulsively volunteered for service in Germany, where he briefly worked in 1943 for the Gestapo, that is, before he was arrested and sent to the Fuhlsbüttel concentration camp.33 Even his work as an informer betrayed his conflicted state of soul: “Though willing,” reports one authority, “to turn in other resistance workers, he refused for example, to hand over a Jesuit priest.”34 Maurice perished toward the end of the war, perhaps on a forced march. His death certificate is dated April 14, 1945. The Maritains’ “Intemperate Zeal” The above account of Maurice Sachs’s life largely follows the account of his biographer, Henri Raczymow, complemented with excerpts from Sach’s own “illusionist” autobiographical essay, Le Sabbat, translated as 30 Sachs, Witches’ Sabbath, 142. 31 Ibid. 32 “Seulement pas de messe, mais je fais mon chemin de croix en montant à pied aux écuries qui sont à deux km. et ma méditation en étrillant mon cheval.” See Sachs, Correspondance, 183. 33 His biographer speculates that the decision to go to Hamburg may have been made for no reason more profound than the “l’impatience de changer d’air.” See Raczymow, Maurice Sachs, 410. 34 Jacobson, “Jews for Genius,” 198. Romanus Cessario, O.P. 720 Witches’ Sabbath.35 In 2003, Michel Bressolette and René Mougel published an edition of the known correspondence between Sachs and the Maritains. The letters, cards, and telegrams date from 1925 to 1939, the year that Maurice disappears into the fog of the Second World War. So we have a privileged vantage point from which to inquire about what transpired between the Maritains and this young Jewish convert whom today some would say suffered from deep-seated same-sex tendencies. Secular studies of Sachs take for granted his dominant sexual preferences; they have a more difficult time granting the authenticity of his conversion to Catholicism, still less of accepting it as something permanent.The Correspondance, on the other hand, raises questions about these assumptions. Maurice after all had fallen under the sway of the Maritains’ “intemperate zeal.”36 In his first letter to Jacques, dated July 28, 1925, the nineteen-year-old Maurice states things clearly: “Nothing concerns me more than Baptism. I regret the years empty of faith that are behind me.”37 As the days pass, the exchanges between Maurice and each of the Maritains intensify both in rhythm and spiritual density. On August 13, 1925, Raïssa quotes to him large chunks of the Liturgy for the feast of the Assumption—“les Anges se réjouissent de son Assomption et ils en louent le Fils de Dieu.”38 Maurice replies appreciatively, although it is clear that he has not yet completed his mystagogy: “I am accustoming myself,” he writes, “to fear no longer the Church in her exterior rituals.”39 Again, Maurice acknowledges the satisfaction he found in reading the copy of the Imitation of Christ that the Maritains sent him.Though at the same time, he writes revealingly: I do not have to confess the sins of the catechism, but I must fortify my heart against the human affections that suddenly surge into my heart like gushing water. They upset the calm blood that passes tranquilly through our arteries when we love only God and those who are like us in this love.40 Certain of Maurice’s human affections center on, among others, Jacques Maritain who reminds him of images of Christ and on Jean Cocteau, 35 See Barré, Maritain, 208ff. 36 Barré, Maritain, 205.The conversions for which the Maritains were instrumental did not win the admiration of all, even of the ecclesiastical authorities. 37 Sachs, Correspondance, 33. 38 Ibid., 39. 39 Ibid., 44. 40 Ibid., 49, 50, my translation. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 721 whose initials are the same as those of Christ’s—J. C.41 Then there is the figure of Jean Bourgoint, who on March 11, 1966 would die a Cistercian monk, caring for lepers in the Cameroon.42 He was Maurice’s peer and one of Cocteau’s ephebes, whom Maurice later introduced to Le Père Pressoir, the seminary priest who would soon baptize Maurice and later serve as his spiritual guide. From the day of Maurice’s baptism through the rest of 1925, the exchange of letters between Maurice and the Maritains continues steadily. Even the editor of their correspondence is constrained to remark: “Mystère des lettres et leur rapidité, 29 sept. 7 h moins 1/4.”43 All in all, these accelerated communications reflect the struggles of a young man exposed suddenly to the highest forms of Catholic spiritual doctrine, including a compendium of the entire mystical doctrine of St. John of the Cross, and at the same time trying to understand how the baptism which gave him every grace of the Christian life still leaves him uncertain of himself.“My spirit is weak, distracted, and sometimes tepid,” he writes to his “très chers et doux amis,”“and my body is sometimes shaken up by the demon.”44 Maurice also writes individually to Raïssa and Jacques. Each in turn replies. Sometimes on the same day. For instance on October 20, 1925, when Jacques briefly reminds Maurice of his prayerful sentiments, and suggests that he send a letter to Fribourg, Switzerland. After hearing High Mass at Notre Dame, Maurice exclaims: “It’s the only possible environment. One must be either a poet or a priest. Jacques is both, but he is a miracle.”45 A Catholic comprehension develops in Maurice. On November 2, 1925, he asks his Godmother to pray for his grandfather, Jacques Bizet, whose anniversary of death falls on the next day. As November draws to a close, Maurice, who has decided to move in with the Maritains, cries out,“My God, I can’t wait to live at Meudon. What better preparation than to sleep under your chapel and to pray for long times in your house which is the House of God.”46 December interrupts the rhythm of letters. Maurice is living with Jacques and Raïssa. By January 4, 1926, Maurice again takes up his correspondence with the Maritains. Now from the seminary, des Carmes. 41 Maurice to the Maritains,“Letter of 6 August 1925,” in Sachs, Correspondance, 35. 42 For further information on Jean Bourgoint, see Jean Bourgoint (Frère Pascal), Le Retour de l’enfant terrible: Lettres, 1923–1966, ed. Jean Hugo and Jean Mouton (Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1975); and Georges Lauris, Itinéraire d’un enfant terrible. De Cocteau à Cîteaux (Paris: Presses de la Renaissance, 1998). 43 Letter 23, in Sachs, Correspondance, 62. 44 Sachs, Correspondance, 66. 45 Ibid., 80. 46 Ibid., 84. 722 Romanus Cessario, O.P. During the first month, the letters from the seminary reveal the interests of Maurice’s life, his personal relationships, including Raïssa’s sister, Vera, and their mother, who of course live with the Maritains, his efforts to begin a spiritual life, especially of prayer, and his concern to settle affairs left over from his former life, such as the payment of debts. Something of the emotionally immature and of the mawkishly sentimental inform these letters—such as the hand drawn sketch that depicts his friends on a field of roses and stars.47 At the same time, Maurice reports on his careful reading of Jacques’s books as they appear, for example, on February 13, 1926, Élements de philosophie (Premier Fasicule). On March 7, the old feast of St.Thomas Aquinas, Maurice sends a poem on a homemade card decorated with religious symbols. By the end of the month however, he writes to his dear friends:“I am very weak.What now! God gave me a little of his Cross and I let it down.”48 On the Monday of Holy Week, Maurice writes in order to borrow 660 francs from Jacques. Maurice was in the habit of visiting the Maritains and his other Paris friends when his seminary schedule allowed, and he did so on the following Easter Sunday. By June 6, Raïssa is constrained to remind him: “It is not without cruel struggles that nature cedes to grace.” By the middle of July 1926, after passing some days of retreat at Solesmes,“where he cried for the first time in six years,” Maurice is moved to consider a Benedictine vocation as the only way to ensure his perseverance.49 The Maritains continue to support the young seminarian by giving sound spiritual advice, by assuring him of their personal support, and on the part of his Godmother, Raïssa, by offering a womanly expression of understanding and consolation. Even while on vacation, Maurice still writes “home.” The first letter from Juan-les-Pins is written on the feast of Saint Mary Magdalene. Three days later, on the feast of Saint James, Maurice writes to Jacques: “Thank you, thank you for all that you have done for me. My heart is full of gratitude for you, for you James the Apostle.”50 On July 31, the feast of St. Ignatius,“How beautiful will be the day of my ordination; I will be able to bless you as my heart blesses you.”51 On the Vigil of the Assumption, Maurice sends a post card from Lerins. Next on 22 August, he writes,“I prayed this morning to ask God for all the graces of conversion 47 Ibid., 103. 48 Ibid., 121. 49 Ibid., 149. 50 Ibid., 151. 51 Ibid., 153. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 723 that we hope for, by the intercession of our Mother.”52 From these external signs, Maurice’s Marian and liturgical spirituality appears in order. He expresses himself as one would expect from a seminarian of the period, even while on vacation. Then arises the storm. On August 29, 1926, Maurice writes to Jacques as to a secular father confessor, and he tells him that since four days he has lived in horrible disarray and deception: “I am taking the only remedy. I am leaving here tomorrow for Solesmes.There, I hope to gain my composure.”53 Maurice had met Tom Pinkerton. “Pray Jesus that he will humble me and that he will bend me. I belong to Him, and still all of me wants to be elsewhere. . . .Write!”54 It would be difficult to overlook the conflicted state of Maurice’s soul. The rational in Maurice reaches out for truthful counsel from the “apostle” who had guided him to Catholic faith. His emotional powers however are captivated by other, less reliable forces. Things did not improve for Maurice. After he had both finished another stay at Solesmes and spent some time at Meudon, Jacques is obliged to write on October 1, 1926, a sharp letter of admonition: “The Maurice of before, we did not know.This time, during the few days that you spent at Meudon, we met him. He and the Christian Maurice were at the same time before us, creating together an unhappy peace.”55 This exercise in fraternal correction displays a masterful expression of both spiritual paternity and spiritual direction. Jacques spared no effort to curb the waywardness that he rightly recognized as recapturing the soul of Maurice Sachs. Like a father, Jacques explained the classical teaching on repentance: “Your life from before has left profound marks in you that only a long practice of the most strict Christian life is able to erase.”56 Later the same month, Maurice writes confidentially to Jacques, informing him that he has seen “the young American,” though without committing a carnal sin. But this affaire is not finished. For two months now, my heart has been aching, admits Maurice. Maurice spends time at another French Benedictine monastery, SaintBenoît-sur-Loire, along with his old friend Max Jacobs (+1944), whose religious conversion achieved stability with his retirement to Benedictine life.57 52 Ibid., 155. 53 Ibid., 156–57. 54 Ibid., 157. 55 Ibid., 165. 56 Ibid., 167. 57 “Jacob converted to Christianity in 1909 and became a Roman Catholic in 1915, but he nevertheless continued to oscillate between extravagant penitence and 724 Romanus Cessario, O.P. “Jacques,” Maurice writes,“I am not doing well.”58 Again on November 5, Maurice tells Jacques that he vows not to have sexual relations with Tom Pinkerton, who is not homosexual, but at the same time allows that he cannot live without his friendship altogether. Maurice sends Tom the Imitation, and he encourages him to return to the practice of the faith. He also warns Tom to escape the “constant torment that homosexuality is.”59 This long letter written from Saint-Benoît-sur-Loire expresses clearly Maurice’s at least unconscious identification with what St. Paul writes in the Letter to the Romans: “For I take delight in the law of God, in my inner self, but I see in my members another principle at war with the law of my mind, taking me captive to the law of sin that dwells in my members” (Rom 7:22–23).60 Or, to cite a text of the Second Vatican Council that may apply to Maurice, “And being weak and sinful, they frequently do what they would rather not, and fail to do what they would.”61 Theological Analysis It is possible to interpret the personal and epistolary exchanges between the Maritains and Maurice Sachs within the context of the “vocational teleology” that dominates the first chapter of the 1993 encyclical letter, Veritatis Splendor. Pope John Paul II there appeals to the dialogue of Jesus with the rich young man as related in the nineteenth chapter of Saint Matthew’s Gospel. “Teacher, what good must I do to gain eternal life” (Mt 9:16)? “Because God is there,” Raïssa wrote early on to a young Maurice worried about his conversion, “you have nothing to fear. I do not say, you have nothing to do, that would be to miss what is apparent. ‘If you love me, keep my commandments.’ ”62 Maurice, it seems difficult to deny, was an earnest searcher, at least for a time. The Maritains embraced him and their other “guests” from the perspective of the overarching participation of the rational creature in the divine goodness.“L’infinie Bonté de Notre Seigneur.”63 They acted toward wild bohemianism until 1921, at which time he retired into semi-monastic seclusion at Saint Benoît-sur-Loire. He lived there most of the time, supporting himself by painting, until World War II, when he was interned in the concentration camp at Drancy, near Paris, where he died.” See the website concise.britannica.com/ ebc/article-9043189/Max-Jacob 58 Sachs, Correspondance, 172. 59 Ibid., 174. 60 Ibid., 173–77, no. 119. 61 See Vatican Council II, Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern World (Gaudium et Spes), §10. 62 Sachs, Correspondance, 45. 63 Ibid. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 725 Maurice based on their conviction that, as St.Thomas teaches,“each creature is stretched out toward the attainment of its own perfection, which is a likeness of the divine perfection and goodness.”64 In other words, the Maritains pursued their evangelizing efforts inspired by a confidence that the basic dynamisms of creation flow from the divine will from which all striving for perfection derives. Veritatis Splendor repeats this key interpretative principle of Thomist moral theology: The moral life has an essential “teleological” character, since it consists in the deliberate ordering of human acts to God, the supreme Good and ultimate end (telos) of man. This is attested to once more by the question posed by the young man to Jesus: “What good must I do to have eternal life?”65 The encyclical further reminds us, “Only God can answer the question about what is good, because he is the Good itself.”66 Or, as Raïssa wrote in 1925 to Maurice, “Only the Good God, in effect, is able to begin, continue, and accomplish the work of our sanctification.”67 Maurice received instruction in both nature and grace. Adoptive sonship is prefigured by a more limited likeness of God in the created nature, which as St.Thomas also teaches, becomes fuller as it approaches the absolute expression of the divine sonship.68 The adoptive sonship of the Christian is not a sonship that is simply and univocally natural as is that of Christ who is the eternal Word. Rather, there exists within human nature—which is specifically different from the divine nature—an analogical likeness to God that is able to undergo transfiguration. This may be expressed in an analogy of proper proportionality: Christ the natural Son is to the Father as the adoptive son is to the Trinity. Love for the full truth of man’s divine good can surmount the difficulties that human weakness and a fallen world create. Only the man whose operational capacities are conformed to Christ through the infused theological and moral virtues will love as does Christ. Maurice had come to understand that the goal of life is to become like Christ. As late as August 1927, he tells Jacques that he wants to include an image of the Shroud of Turin in a book of 64 See Summa theologiae I, q. 44, a. 4: “Et unaquaeque creatura intendit consequi suam perfectionem, quae est similitudo perfectionis et bonitatis divinae.” 65 Veritatis Splendor, §72. 66 Ibid., §9. 67 Sachs, Correspondance, 45. 68 See ST I, q. 33, a. 3. Also, my “Sonship, Sacrifice, and Satisfaction: The Divine Friendship in Aquinas and the Renewal of Christian Anthropology,” Letter & Spirit 3 (2007): 69–91. 726 Romanus Cessario, O.P. poems that he intends to publish, with the title, the “Miraculous Sketch of Jesus.”69 And of course, he found in Jacques himself a living resemblance of how Maurice envisaged the Savior. His personal embrace of Christ raises other questions. While trying to rationalize an acceptable relationship with Tom Pinkerton, Maurice wrote to Jacques: “I think about God with fear and revolt.”70 If Maurice Sachs today were to seek entrance into a Catholic seminary, he would have to confront the directives for persons with same-sex tendencies set down by the 2005 “Instruction” of the Congregation for Catholic Education.71 Grace is called to stand before the psychological tribunal. It is useless to engage in historical psychoanalysis. At the same time, it is evident from the Correspondance that the Maritains did not hesitate to regard Maurice’s baptism as the start of a new life. In doing this, they clearly drew on classical Catholic teaching about the “rich reality” that baptismal grace bestows.72 How then did they regard what in Maurice today would be called “deep-seated homosexual tendencies”? Three points emerge: 1. First, the Maritains refused to hypostasize homosexuality. Note in the 2005 “Instruction” that the use of the word “tendency” to describe homosexual leanings is meant to signal that while the Church considers “homosexual tendencies” distelic and therefore incapable of perfecting human nature, such tendencies are not as close to the appetites as natural inclinations. In Catholic moral thought, there exists only one sexual inclination, only one sexual orientation. It should be noted that the “Instruction” of 2005 speaks of tendencies that are “objectively disordered.”73 The terminology is that of the Catechism of the Catholic Church.74 On the other hand, when discussing the moral anthropology of Catholic life, Veritatis Splendor employs the word “inclination” seven times.The word “tendency” however appears only 69 Sachs, Correspondance, 215. 70 Ibid., 176. 71 Congregation for Catholic Education, “Instruction Concerning the Criteria for the Discernment of Vocations with Regard to Persons with Homosexual Tendencies in View of Their Admission to the Seminary and to Holy Orders” (2005). 72 See CCC, §1279: “that includes forgiveness of original sin and all personal sins, birth into the new life by which man becomes and adoptive son of the father, a member of Christ and a temple of the Holy Spirit.” 73 Congregation for Catholic Education, “Instruction,” §2. 74 CCC, §2358: “Virorum et mulierum numerus non exiguus tendentias homosexuales praesentat profunde radicatas,” emphases added. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 727 once, and then to describe a trend of thought not a psychological state. The Maritains read correctly Maurice’s human and religious inclinations.They were less successful, it seems, in comprehending his disordered and predominately homosexual tendencies. Veritatis Splendor employs twice the adjective “disordered” to describe sinful actions.The Catechism cites the 1976 “Persona Humana” document of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (issued during the height of the sexual revolution in North America). It defines homosexual acts as intrinsically disordered.75 Disordered tendencies to commit such acts describe psychological dispositions toward sin. The theological word would be “temptation.”76 In any case, the Church does not locate homosexual lust at the level of being. The Maritains obviously viewed Maurice’s past profligacy as something altogether remediable.They believed in the forgiveness of all personal sins that baptism brings.They knew what Aquinas teaches about the fomes peccati. In short, temptations after baptism should be overcome by manfully resisting them by the grace of Jesus Christ.77 We can infer the gist of their spiritual counsel from what Maurice plaintively says when his struggles with presumably sexual temptations had led to discouragement. In a 1927 letter, Maurice complains to Jacques: “You tell me that God wants me to play the hero. But what thanks should I give God who permitted that my heart and my body be perverted at an age when one is ignorant, and who ten years later requires heroism of me?”78 “Manfully resist.” “Play the hero.” 2. The Maritains brooked no sympathy for any chosen expression of homosexual lust. Aquinas never discusses explicitly homosexual tendencies. He alludes to what since the late nineteenth century we call homosexuality in the treatise on the old law where he notes that the sixth commandment forbids the “vices against nature” and cites Leviticus 19:16:“You shall not lie with a male as with a woman; it is an abomination.”79 He mentions the same “vice against nature” in the reply to an objection in the treatise on the natural law.80 Again, 75 CCC, §2357, citing Persona Humana, §8: “actus homosexualitatis suapte intrin- seca natura esse inordinatos.” 76 For an interesting essay that mentions classical outlooks on sexual temptations, see John Joseph Williams, “Ordered and Disordered Friendships: Some Classic Distinctions,” Faith & Reason 29 (2004): 33–47. 77 CCC, §1264. 78 Sachs, Correspondance, 228. 79 ST I–II, q. 100, a. 11. 80 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 3. Romanus Cessario, O.P. 728 “homosexuality” appears in the treatise on intemperance, where Aquinas discusses the shamefulness of homosexual coitus.81 And again, when he is discussing the sins of lust.82 All sins of lechery go against reason, but some—what Mary Ann Glendon likes to call the filthy five—also go against nature; they are not only against reason but also contra naturam: masturbation, bestiality, sodomy, contraception, and fetishes. The first mention of sodomy in the Summa theologiae comes, however, when Aquinas discusses pleasure. In this article, the Common Doctor offers what may be the closest thing to clinical psychology in the Summa, namely, that some men are sick of soul and so take pleasure in cannibalism, bestiality, homosexual congress, and other things not in accord with their nature.83 Do such persons act from an innate inclination to find pleasure in practicing the vices against nature? It would come as a surprise to discover that the Maritains thought so. There is no evidence to think that Aquinas did. There are persons who take pleasure habitually in bad sex. Maurice seems to have been one of them. He shared his bed with men up until his arrest in 1943. Does the word “tendency” adequately describe his condition? Perhaps. Then there is the testimony of Maurice himself: “My life is impossible because I love equally virtue and sin, God and the devil.”84 In other words, he explains himself in terms of a choice. 3. The Maritains believed in the power of contemplation to pacify the lower powers of the soul.What distinguishes deep-seated homosexual tendencies from, as the “Instruction” puts it, “homosexual tendencies that were only the expression of a transitory problem”?85 It is important to determine criteria to answer this question. Those who experience the latter may be admitted today into seminaries. Others may not. It seems to me that if we follow the lead of Aquinas, then we will find ourselves obliged to discover a way to evaluate the pleasure that an individual takes in the prospects or realization of 81 ST II–II, 142, a. 4. 82 ST II–II, q. 154, a. 11. 83 ST I–II, q. 31, a. 8. 84 Sachs, Correspondance, 267.This reminds one of an aphorism from The Way (#24): “You tell me that in your heart you have fire and water, cold and heat, empty passions and God: one candle lit to St. Michael and another to the devil. Calm yourself. As long as you are willing to fight there are not two candles burning in your heart.There is only one: the archangel’s.” 85 Congregation for Catholic Education, “Instruction,” §2. Humanae Vitae, the Maritains, and Maurice Sachs 729 sexual congress with a person of the same sex. The Catechism of the Catholic Church tells us that many of them find their situations a trial—“pro maiore eorum parte constituit probationem.”86 We find ourselves back to Maurice Sachs and his advice to Tom Pinkerton: at all costs, escape the “constant torment that homosexuality is.”87 For their part, the Maritains proceeded on a premise that Aquinas enunciates in Summa theologiae I–II, question 38: “The contemplation of truth is the greatest of all pleasures.We have seen that every pleasure assuages pain. The contemplation of truth therefore assuages pain; and it does so the more, the more perfectly one loves wisdom.”88 How else may one interpret the words of Raïssa? “God will make known to you interiorly and little by little what he desires of you. And little by little, and sweetly, he will teach you how to remain strong by his love.”89 Postscript Maurice continued to exchange letters with the Maritains during his period of military service. He also continued for a time to practice the Catholic faith. He reported back to the Maritains on conversations with his confessor, who advised him to marry. . . .And so one assumes that “the torment of homosexuality” remained an issue for Maurice. On November 20, 1927, he writes to Jacques, and confesses to some form of relationship with a certain Jean Mangüe that had the same effect on Maurice’s desire to marry as what had happened at Juan-les-Pins had on his desire for the priesthood. “A brutal warning,” he tells Jacques.90 Marry, we know however, Maurice did. But his struggles with homosexual impulses continued. They eventually took a toll on his religious practice.“But you know better than I,” he writes to Jacques in April 1934, “how essential is the Eucharist, which I cannot receive without a firm purpose of not living in a manner that St. Paul condemns.”91 Jacques agrees, and the next month tells him that if a firm purpose is impossible, there is nothing else to do except to wait, while still doing all that is in one’s power.92 The last letter that Maurice writes is addressed to Raïssa Maritain, shortly before Christmas 1939. Sin appears to have worked its 86 CCC, §2358. 87 Sachs, Correspondance, 174. 88 ST I–II, q. 38, a. 5. 89 Sachs, Correspondance, 45. 90 Ibid., 226. 91 Ibid., 291. 92 Ibid., 292. 730 Romanus Cessario, O.P. sad effect.“I am born, it seems to me, without the sense of the eternal. . . . I remain indifferent toward life eternal. Mille et mille affections. Maurice.”93 On November 16, 1943, Maurice Sachs was arrested by the Gestapo under the pretext of article 175, the section of criminal law that condemned the practice of acts “against nature.” Ordinarily, those who, like Maurice Sachs, served as agents for the Nazi government were exempt from this law, except when the Gestapo found reason to lose confidence in them.This they did in the case of Maurice when they discovered that he had alerted a Jesuit priest, le Père Jean Nicot, who was working undercover in Hamburg with the help of the Swiss consulate. Illusionist accounts of his death circulated after the end of World War II. On February 4, 1951, KarlLudwig Schneider published an article in the Berlin magazine, Welt am Sonntag, proving that Maurice Ettinghausen (Sachs’s real family name) had been killed by a Flemish S.S. officer while trying to escape a prison march. On April 21, 1951, his mother had a funeral Mass celebrated for him at N&V Saint-Philippe-du-Roule in Paris. 93 Ibid., 312. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 731–764 731 The “Inseparable Connection” between Procreation and Unitive Love (Humanae Vitae, §12) and Thomistic Hylemorphic Anthropology1 PAUL G ONDREAU Providence College Providence, Rhode Island Humans are amphibians—half spirit and half animal. As spirits they belong to the eternal world, but as animals they inhabit time [and are thus ordered to temporal goods].This means that while their spirit can be directed to an eternal object, their bodies, passions, and imaginations are in continual change [since they are directed to temporal objects]. —C. S. Lewis, The Screwtape Letters I F AN ENGAGED couple is asked why they are getting married, they will say, usually, because they love each other. No surprise there. They very well might add, and should add, that they are getting married because they want to have children (however many that may be and whenever they may come).And thus we have the celebrated “inseparable connection,” as Humanae Vitae (§12) calls it, between the unitive and procreative dimensions of human sexuality.2 Often, appeals are made to 1 I would like to express my gratitude to the Centre for Philosophical Psychology of the Institute for the Psychological Sciences (Arlington,VA) at Blackfriars Hall, University of Oxford, England, which made possible the writing of a substantial part of this essay. 2 The 1983 Code of Canon Law follows suit: “[marriage] is by its nature ordered to the good of the spouses (ad bonum coniugum) and the procreation and education of offspring” (canon 1055; trans. Canon Law Society of America, Code of Canon Law. Latin-English Edition [Washington, DC: Canon Law Society of America, 1984], 387). 732 Paul Gondreau the body-soul unity in the human being as the foundation for this inseparable connection. But such appeals can at times be vague or at least lacking in metaphysical depth and clarity.3 Here is where an anthropology that brings the full weight of Aristotelian hylemorphism (matter-form causality) to bear on this issue, such as we find in St.Thomas Aquinas, can offer a marked contribution. With this essay, then, I would like to invite consideration of the indivisible union of the procreative and unitive dimensions of our sexuality as a reflection of the body-soul unity, such as we can understand in light of Aquinas’s robust hylemorphic (or integrated) account of the human being. The Union of Matter and Form In a hylemorphic account of reality, all things (save God and the angels) are composed of matter and form, that is, of material “stuff ” arranged or determined (read: informed) in some specific way (hylemorphism comes from the Greek hyle ˜ for “matter,” and morphe ˜ meaning “form”). Indeed, matter exists only insofar as it is informed—one never finds matter without a form—since the form is what organizes or determines matter to be the particular kind of material thing it is.4 Matter possesses the possibility of becoming, via the form, a specific kind of thing: wood has the potentiality of becoming either a desk, or a table, or a chair, or a piece of paper, or a floor, or a statue, or a piece of kindling, and it is the form which determines the specific kind of wooden thing it becomes. Without its form, matter remains in pure potency. This makes form the actualizing principle, or that which gives “act” or actual existence to matter: “matter has actual existence by the substantial 3 Humanae Vitae, in fact, simply makes a general appeal to the natural law as the basis for this inseparable connection, but follows with little by way of exposition on this. For its part, Pope Benedict XVI’s encyclical letter Deus Caritas Est, §5, begins its attempt at arguing for the union of eros and agape on the simple fact that “it is man, the person, a unified creature composed of body and soul, who loves,” but follows with virtually no elaboration on this. 4 Richard J. Connell (Nature’s Causes [New York: Peter Lang, 1995], 73 and 104) defines matter in the sense of material cause as “that from which something comes to be and which remains within,” and as “that out of which something is made and which remains within.” When it comes to form or formal cause, which he observes stand out as “some of the more confusing [words] in the vocabulary of Aristotle,” he offers various meanings: form signifies the “principle within the substance” and which give it its nature; form means that which constitutes the species as such or signifies “what the individual things are.” Procreation and Unitive Love 733 form,” Thomas writes, “which makes it exist absolutely.”5 Because of matter’s dependence upon form, we can say matter is for the sake of form.6 There is, then, a kind of duality in all things on account of their matter-form composition. By no means, however, does this equate with dualism.There is no inherent opposition between matter and form, even if form, the actualizing principle, is superior to matter, the passive or potential principle. Instead, there is substantial inseparable unity between the two, precisely since matter’s actual existence is provided by its union with form. Form is the principle of unity of all material things.7 Modern Science and Aristotelian Hylemorphism Today it is often assumed that this older hylemorphic view of the natural world (inspired by Aristotle) does not square with, and indeed has been eclipsed by, what modern science has uncovered. However, recent scholarship has begun to show that the Aristotelian doctrine of hylemorphism (matter-form composition) can be reconciled with the modern scientific account.8 To say, as I think one can and must, that modern science has focused almost exclusively on what the Aristotelian would call material causality (in addition to efficient causality) and has largely ignored the notion of form (as well as of final causality)—or at least that 5 Aquinas, Summa theologiae I, q. 76, a. 6.Also, in III, q. 3, a. 7 ad 1,Thomas explains: “A created nature is completed in its essentials by its form.” 6 “Since the form is not for the matter, but rather the matter for the form, we must gather from the form the reason why the matter is such as it is, and not conversely.” ST I, q. 76, a. 5. 7 “[T]he form, through itself, makes a thing to be actual since it is itself essentially an act. . . . Wherefore the unity of a thing composed of matter and form is by virtue of the form itself, which by reason of its very nature is united to matter as its act.” ST I, q. 76, a. 7. 8 Scholars who argue this include: Connell, Nature’s Causes, esp. 57–122; idem, Substance and Modern Science (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988); idem, From Observables to Unobservables in Science and Philosophy (Landham, MD: University Press of America, 2000); Nicanor Austriaco, “Immediate Hominization from the Systems Perspective,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 4 (2004): 497–516; idem,“How to Navigate Species Boundaries:A Reply to The American Journal of Bioethics,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 6 (2006): 61–71; and John Goyette,“Substantial Form and the Recovery of Aristotelian Science,” The Thomist 66 (2002): 519–33. Goyette has also argued against a plurality of substantial forms being found in one substance in “St.Thomas on the Unity of Substantial Form,” in Restoring Nature: Essays in Thomistic Philosophy and Theology, ed. Michael M.Waddell (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press, 2008). Cf. Benedict M. Ashley, “The River Forest School and the Philosophy of Nature Today,” in Philosophy and the God of Abraham, ed. R. James Long (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1991), 1–16. 734 Paul Gondreau modern science dismisses form (and finality) as causes—is not to say the experimental method of modern science has disproved formal (or final) causality as such. While formal (and final) causality may have fallen on hard times, one could argue that in many ways modern science implies or even begs for the equivalent of what Aristotle calls form. To give just once piece of evidence for this, one can look at the relatively new field of systems biology that has arisen in the wake of postgenomic science.9 Whereas scientists overall used to think the measure of the complexity of a species was to be found at the genomic level, they have had to revise this view. Advances in genomic science have shown that the chromosomal differences among species are relatively insignificant. For instance, many species, such as apes, have more chromosomes than human beings, while many species of animals have fewer.And at the level of genes, whereas one would expect the most complex animal species, the human being, to own more genes than any other organism (there are 22,000 total genes in humans, compared to, say, 6,000 in yeast), one would be surprised to learn that an organism like rice (with 38,000) has significantly more genes than humans.10 As a result, systems biologists have come to recognize that an organism’s material components, looked at on their own or simply as a net sum, do not help us identify what is distinctive of a species as a structural unity; they do not tell the whole story of an organism. Instead, systems biologists have come to see that an organism, considered as a unified whole, is greater than the sum of its parts. And they prefer the term “state cycles” to signify the distinctiveness and structural unity of an organism.11 Put more technically, state cycles is the term employed by systems biologists to designate the organism as a specific type of organization, that is, “as a single, unified network of interacting molecules [namely, of DNA, RNA, lipids, metabo9 The following overview of systems biology and its relation to Aristotelian- Thomistic biology is taken from Austriaco, “Immediate Hominization from the Systems Perspective,” 500–502. In this essay Austriaco explicitly targets the suggestion of Jean Porter (“Is the Embryo a Person?: Arguing with the Catholic Traditions,” Commonweal 129 [Feb. 8, 2002], 8–10) that it is difficult to reconcile modern science, at least on the issue of embryogenesis, with Aristotelian-Thomistic hylemorphism. For an overview of and introduction to systems biology (provided by Austriaco), cf. Hiroaki Kitano, “Systems Biology: A Brief Overview,” Science 295 (March 1, 2002): 1662–64. 10 Cf. Matt Ridley, Genome:The Autobiography of a Species in 23 Chapters (New York: Harper Collins, 2000), 4.The gene count is provided by Austriaco in an oral presentation to an interdisciplinary faculty seminar on being human at Providence College, Providence, RI, on January 25, 2007. 11 For more on state cycles in systems biology, see Stuart Kauffman, At Home in the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995). Procreation and Unitive Love 735 lites, and proteins] which is organized in a species-specific manner.”12 Among other things, state cycles account for the enduring stability of organisms while they undergo dramatic changes—such as when the species-specific pattern of molecular interactions in a human being remains constant throughout one’s entire lifespan, despite the fact that, as biologists have shown, nearly ninety-eight percent of the atoms in the mature human body are replaced over a two-year period. Because the term state cycles signifies that which accounts for the structural (or organizational) and species-specific unity of a living thing in a way that the mere material (i.e., molecular) components, even as a net sum, cannot, one can say that “state cycles” stands out as a more or less equivalent term to what Aristotle and Aquinas mean by “form” (or formal cause). Form signifies nothing other than that which confers structural and species-specific unity upon a thing’s material components (upon organic matter in the case of living things), since form is present to the entire body and to all of its parts. Form completes the story of an organism and ensures the enduring stability of a thing in the midst of its numerous biological changes. Hence the lasting value for modern science of matter-form causality: “[Aristotelian hylemorphism] remains a potent explanation for biological species” is what the biologist and bioethicist Nicanor Austriaco concludes.13 The field of systems biology provides strong counter-evidence to the Scottish philosopher David Hume’s famous denial of formal causality, as he asserts nothing holds a thing together, nothing makes a thing stable over time.14 Reconciling modern science with Aristotelian hylemorphism does present its terminological hurdles, however. Étienne Gilson noted in his correspondence with Jacques Maritain that simple disagreement over the meaning of the word “nature” separates Thomist philosophers from modern scientists.15 To be sure, terms such as matter and form carry a 12 Austriaco, “Immediate Hominization from the Systems Perspective,” 504. 13 Austriaco, “How to Navigate Species Boundaries,” 68. 14 David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1888), Bk. I, Pt. III, section 14 (“Of the Idea of Necessary Connexion”), 155–72; and Bk. I, Pt. IV, section 6 (“Of Personal Identity”), 251–63; cited in Stephen L. Brock, “The Rational Primacy of the Common Good and the Natural Presuppositions of the ratio boni,” paper delivered at a conference on “Providence, Practical Reason, and the Common Good,” Providence College, Providence, Rhode Island, April 26, 2008. 15 Étienne Gilson, Jacques Maritain, Correspondance, 1923–1971, ed. Géry Prouvost (Paris: J. Vrin, 1991), 250 (letter of Gilson, Sept. 8, 1971); cited in Lawrence Dewan, O.P.,“St.Thomas and the Divinity of the Common Good,” paper delivered at the conference “Providence, Practical Reason, and the Common Good.” 736 Paul Gondreau much wider or more metaphysically precise sense in the writings of such a proponent of Aristotelian hylemorphism as Aquinas than they do in modern science. Whereas, for instance, modern science denotes matter almost exclusively to mean a quantifiable, measurable thing, for Aquinas (and Aristotle) it also and especially means a principle of potentiality, or, again, that which possesses the possibility of becoming, via the form, a specific kind of thing. The Human Being as a Matter-Form (Body-Soul) Composite Like all bodily beings, the human being, too, is composed of matter and form. The human being is unique, however, in that he is composed of organic matter (which he shares with all other animals) and a rational form. The human being is constituted by an animal body joined to an immaterial or spiritual soul.16 If the human soul, owning its various intellectual and sensate powers, is immaterial, it is because those acts unique to the human species, namely, abstract thought and free choice, cannot be reduced to the material.17 Accordingly, we can say animality represents In their correspondence, Maritain expressed optimism on the possibility of dialogue with evolutionary scientists, and of convincing them of the need for a God to supply the substantial forms of new species. But Gilson was dubious, given that Descartes’s elimination of substantial form from reality had resulted in the inability of modern science to recognize form and finality as intrinsic to nature. 16 Cf. ST I, q. 76, aa. 1 and 4, and a. 6, ad 1, where Thomas writes:“the same essential form makes man an actual being, a body, a living being, an animal, and a man.” 17 As for human thought implying its being grounded in an immaterial mind (soul), a biologist friend once employed the following useful argument to convince a materialist why this is so. If human thought is reducible entirely to the material (namely, to neurological chemicals), then every human thought or idea must be reducible to what is finite, that is, no thought can exceed the limits of the particular, since the material is of its very nature composed of the particular (“particles”), and thus of the limited or finite.The problem, however, arises from the fact that we can conceive of things that go beyond the finite or the particular; we can have thoughts that extend to the infinite or the indefinite, such as when we conceive of an infinite (indefinite) set of numbers. Here a metaphor of a box filled with marbles can be employed, where to every thought would correspond a marble, at least if human thought is reducible entirely to the material. Put in other terms, every time we have a thought a marble must be placed in the box. However, when we conceive of an infinite (indefinite) set of numbers, we could never have enough marbles in the box. A finite, limited set of marbles is not proportioned to an infinite set of numbers, that is, is not proportioned to a thought that goes beyond the finite.The mind therefore cannot be limited to the finite, the limited, the material. For more on the immateriality of the human soul, Procreation and Unitive Love 737 what is bodily in the human being, the matter, while rationality represents what is formal in man, the soul. What is more, the human being is on account of his (material) body and his (immaterial) soul.18 In the hylemorphic view, matter (material cause) cannot tell the whole story of man (or of any created thing). Such a story reduces the human being to nothing more than a mechanized aggregate of material components (molecules, genes, etc.). Form supplies what is specific as such to a being in a way the material components on their own cannot. As the form of the human being, the soul completes the story of man, just as form completes the story of any being. Put in other terms, the body is the necessary condition for the existence of the soul, even while the soul, for whose sake the body exists, is necessary for the realization of the body. Wishing to stress the profundity of the hylemorphic bond between body and soul in the human being, and aware that the soul, as form, marks the principle of unity in human nature,Aquinas does not hesitate to write: “the intellectual soul is united by its very being (per suum esse) to the body as a form.”19 Here all the powers of the soul, whether sensitive (and thus affective) or intellectual (or rational), share an intimate unity and synergy both with each other and with the body, of which the soul, with all its powers, is the form.The soul is the source, the principle, of all the body’s vital motions and actions. Far from a loose, accidental juxtaposition, then, see Brian J. Shanley, O.P., The Thomist Tradition (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2002), 153–66; for Aquinas’s argument, see ST I, q. 75, a. 5. 18 In coming to adopt this integrated anthropology, Aquinas would draw especially upon Aristotle, but also upon St. Augustine, for whom, as Joseph Torchia, O.P. (chapter entitled “St. Thomas Aquinas: A Subsistent Individual,” in his Exploring Personhood: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Human Nature [Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2007]) points out, the human being is a “harmonious union” of body and soul; cf. Augustine, De civitate Dei, Bk. XIX, ch. 3 (for Aquinas’s citation of this passage, cf. ST I, q. 75, a. 4). At the same time,Torchia notes a “certain uneasiness on Augustine’s part regarding the possibility of a true psychosomatic unity [in the human being]” in his “The Significance of the Communicatio Idiomatum in St.Augustine’s Christology, with Special Reference to His Rebuttal of Later Arianism,” in Studia Patristica, vol. 38, Papers Presented at the Thirteenth International Conference on Patristic Studies Held in Oxford 1999. St. Augustine and His Opponents. Other Latin Writers, eds. M. F. Wiles and E. J. Yarnold (Leuven: Peeters, 2001), 306–23, at 321. 19 ST I, q. 76, a. 6 ad 3; emphasis added. Previously in I, q. 29, a. 1 ad 5,Thomas maintains:“the soul ever retains its nature of unibility (unibilitatis) [with the body].” For a more profound look at the metaphysical hylemorphic conception of the human being in Aquinas, cf. Anton Pegis, St.Thomas and the Problem of the Soul in the Thirteenth Century (Toronto: Pontifical Institute for Mediaeval Studies, 1978). 738 Paul Gondreau the union of the immaterial (the rational soul) with the material (the organic body) in the human being constitutes a profound, if paradoxical, unity.The human being is one. This view of the human being as a substantial composite of matter and form, of body and soul, provides us with the metaphysical key to a truly integrated sexual anthropology. Defining the human being as a fundamental unity of body and soul marks the most crucial step, in my opinion, at rendering a proper account of the meaning and purpose of human sexuality, and more particularly of the inseparable connection between procreation and unitive love of which Humanae Vitae §12, speaks. Let us sketch this out. Sexuality Follows Primarily upon the Bodily Animal Dimension of Human Nature Aquinas explains how certain essential attributes accrue to our nature that, while not entering into the definition of the human being as a rational animal per se, nonetheless proceed immediately, and thus essentially, upon that which does enter into this definition. Put simply, there are certain essential human attributes, call them “proto-essential” properties, that follow immediately upon our animality (expressive of the body or of our matter) and upon our rationality (expressive of the soul or of our form).20 While risibility is an example of an attribute following upon human rationality, sexuality, on Aquinas’s account, is an attribute that proceeds upon our animality or upon our bodies.21 The very basis of the sexual 20 Thomas calls these attributes “proper accidents,” but this should not be taken to mean they are “accidental” (in the Aristotelian sense of the term).The following remarks on human sexuality as an attribute or proper accident of our nature are pulled from Aquinas’s De ente et essentia, chs. 5–6. I wish to express my gratitude to Stephen A. Hipp for providing me with his (unpublished) “Succinct Presentation of the De ente et essentia and the De principiis naturae of St.Thomas Aquinas.” 21 “[T]he diversity of male and female among animals derives from matter.” De ente et essentia, ch. 5; cf. Aristotle, Metaph., Bk. X, ch. 11 (1058b21–23). Aquinas goes on to note in ch. 6 of the De ente that only those proper accidents that ensue upon the human form (the rational soul) will characterize the whole human species as such, such as risibility, since “laughter results from some apprehension on the part of the [rational] human soul.” In this way, we say all human individuals are risible. However, since, as the principle of individuation, matter accounts for what differentiates (or individuates, concretizes) particular human beings, the proper accidents that derive from the matter (the human body) pertain only to individuals. Maleness and femaleness are thus to the individual what risibility is to the human species. In this way, we say only some human individuals are male and some female. But since any true human being must share in full rationality Procreation and Unitive Love 739 differentiation between male and female, obviously the distinguishing mark of sexuality as such, is animal bodiliness.This does not mean, as shall be seen immediately below, that our sexuality is wholly reducible to what is bodily in us. Nor does it deny the important social and psychological aspects of our sexual identity. Much modern scientific research has shed considerable light on the importance of an individual’s social and psychological self-identity as a man or as a woman. But that animal bodiliness provides the primary foundation for our sexuality is supported by the simple biological fact that the sex chromosomal complement (XX for females, XY for males) determines one’s sex, including all respective sexual characteristics (genitalia, bone and muscular structure, etc.).22 In a word, sex, inclusive of our affective loves and desires, belongs to us primarily as embodied beings. Without our bodiliness, without our animality, we have no truly satisfactory way of explaining the malefemale sexual complement. Human sexuality implies embodied altereity, embodied complementarity. While this point may seem obvious, especially as we consider it in light of the entire animal kingdom, it needs to be stressed. For, even respectable moral theologians have advanced misleading notions of what constitutes maleness and femaleness as such.23 and full animality, every human individual must be both risible and either male or female. Every human individual must possess the proper accidents that follow upon the rational form (e.g., risibility) and upon the animal matter (e.g., maleness or femaleness) as from its essential principles. Therefore, although maleness and femaleness fall into the category of proper accidents, they may in no case be classified as accidental, just as denoting risibility as a proper accident does not mean it is accidental to human nature. Citations from the De ente are done in consultation with the translation of A. Maurer, Aquinas on Being and Essence (2nd ed.;Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1968). 22 “The X and Y chromosomes are known as the sex chromosomes for the obvious reason that they determine, with almost perfect predestination, the sex of the body” (Matt Ridley, Genome:The Autobiography of a Species in 23 Chapters, 108). That one can find isolated cases of hermaphroditism (the possession of ambiguous genitalia) does not change this fact, since hermaphroditism results from an aberration in nature, inasmuch as it is caused by either a genetic mutation, a chromosomal aberration, a birth defect, or a hostile exterior agent, such as a virus; cf. James A. Monteleone, “A Biological Perspective: Problems Associated with the Determination of Sex of Rearing in the Presence of Ambiguous Genitalia,” in Sex and Gender: A Theological and Scientific Inquiry (St. Louis: Pope John Center, 1983), 65–80, at 66. And even in these cases, one sex over the other always predominates (though this may be difficult to ascertain). 23 Thus, for instance, John Grabowski (Sex and Virtue:An Introduction to Sexual Ethics [Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2003], 109–11), who appeals to the person/nature distinction as it is known in light of the Trinitarian mystery in order to argue that maleness and femaleness are constitutive of 740 Paul Gondreau Psychiatric Research and Human Embodiedness Important research in the field of clinical psychiatry helps show that the sexual anthropology which holds up animal bodiliness (or human biology) as the primary basis of our sexual differentiation is not out of step with current science. To quote one leading researcher, sexual identity is less a matter of the malleability of our nature and more a reality of “our constitution by the genes we inherit and the embryogenesis we undergo.”24 More personhood rather than of human nature. Mary Shivanandan (in her Notre Dame Seminary School of Theology Aquinas Lecture, “Happiness in John Paul II and Thomas Aquinas,” given on April 20, 2007) amplifies this view, as she criticizes Aquinas’s anthropology because of “his rejection of man as a substantive relation in the manner of the Trinitarian persons.” Grabowski’s argument stands on an analogy drawn between the male-female relation on the one side and the FatherSon relation in the Trinity, which is indeed constitutive of Personhood in God but not of the divine nature, on the other.While an admirable attempt, this argument by analogy fails on many counts, not least of which because, by abstracting sexuality from human nature, Grabowski abstracts maleness and femaleness from the bodily, animal dimension of the human being. This, of course, is to jettison the very basis of the male-female distinction. Grabowski and Shivanandan’s argument also fails to take into account the fundamental difference between the way relation applies to God and the way it applies to us. As Aquinas explains in ST I, q. 29, a. 4, relation in God is the divine essence itself, whereas relation in creatures is an accidental property of nature. To reduce maleness and femaleness to strict relational properties constitutive of personhood is to make maleness and femaleness pure accidental properties (not to be confused with maleness and femaleness understood as proper accidents, as previously noted). This is tantamount to suggesting that being a man or a woman is no more essential to one’s identity than any other relational property of one’s person, such as being a teacher or a student. Furthermore, Grabowski and Shivanandan imply an equivocal notion of nature. For, the universal nature that a man and a woman share in common is purely abstract relative to the individuals themselves, as no man or woman is human nature. Concretely speaking they are separate beings. But the universal nature that the divine Persons share in common is concrete, as the Father is the divine nature, the Son is the divine nature, the Holy Spirit is the divine nature. Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are one in being, they are the same being (consubstantial, or homoousios, to use the term of Nicaea). 24 Paul McHugh,“Surgical Sex,” First Things 147 (November, 2004): 34–38.As chief psychiatrist at Johns Hopkins Hospital, McHugh conducted extensive research into hermaphroditism (the possession of ambiguous genitalia) and confused sexual identity. Based on this research, he writes: “we in the Johns Hopkins Psychiatry Department eventually concluded that human sexual identity is mostly built into our constitution by the genes we inherit and the embryogenesis we undergo. Male hormones sexualize the brain and the mind.” Matt Ridley (Genome: The Autobiography of a Species in 23 Chapters, 217–18) agrees: “nature does play a role in gender. . . . The evidence from the genome, from imprinted genes and genes for sex-linked behaviours, now points to th[is] same conclusion.” In support, Procreation and Unitive Love 741 and more, researchers are challenging the nominalist view which holds that male and female sexual identity refers to nothing grounded in natural reality (human biology) but simply to cultural conditioning or social upbringing (nurture).They are coming to recognize the fixed biological grounding (nature) of our identity as males and females, as men and women (without, however, denying the role of nurture).25 Further, if some therapists suspend judgment on whether persons with confused sexual identity can be said to suffer from a psychopathology, these same therapists, in the clinical setting, often endorse traditional adolescent gender roles (such as associating “rough and tumble” play with boys and the preference of playing “with dolls” with girls) in determining whether one has a gender identity disorder.26 Sex and Procreation Looking at our sexuality in light of the biological datum of our embodiedness, it is obvious that the male-female complement (sexual dimorphism), manifested primarily in the male and female genitalia, exists for the sake of procreation. With animal bodiliness providing the basis for the male-female distinction, we can therefore say that human sexuality owns an intrinsic ordering to procreation. Indeed, procreation expresses the primary meaning of our sexuality.27 As human sexuality arises immediately, see the work of the psychiatrist Leonard Sax, Why Gender Matters: What Parents and Teachers Need to Know about the Emerging Science of Sex Differences (New York: Doubleday, 2005). Sax concludes that behavioral differences between girls and boys are not just caused by cultural factors but are innate and result in large measure from the composition and development of the brain itself. One could also cite in support the work of the professor of psychology and psychiatry at Cambridge University, Simon Baron-Cohen, The Essential Difference:The Truth about the Male and Female Brain (New York: Basic Books, 2004). 25 In his Taking Sex Differences Seriously (San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2004), Steven Rhoads takes issue with the view which holds that, on the one hand, malefemale gender roles are a social construction (thereby opening the door to their being “deconstructed”), while, on the other, the reproductive differences between male and female are few and relatively unimportant. Rhoads argues that there exist hormonal, chemical, even neurological, as well as psychological, differences between men and women that are innate, with the result that “[m]en and women have different natures, and generally speaking, different preferences, talents and interests.” 26 This is true, for instance, for the psychiatrists Kenneth J. Zucker and Susan J. Bradley and their case studies are found on 341–43, Gender Identity Disorder and Psychosexual Problems in Children and Adolescents (New York: Guilford Press, 1995). 27 This, essentially, is what the sixteenth-century Thomist Cajetan argues in the quaestiunculae he inserts (“De sacramento matrimonii triplex quaesitum,”“Quaestiones de usu matrimonii” and “De delectatione morosa triplex dubium”) in his commentary on the Supplement of the Summa theologiae, all found in the Leonine edition of the Summa (pp. 370–75). Paul Gondreau 742 and thus essentially, upon the body, upon our animality, human sexuality is ordered immediately, essentially and primarily to procreation. Hardly is it possible, then, to abstract the procreative dimension from an act—the sex act—which of its very nature is first and foremost an embodied act, an act of sexual biological union. This biological ordering to procreation leads Georges Cottier, theologian of the pontifical household under Pope John Paul II, to note that sexuality allows humans to participate in a kind of “biological infinity.”28 If to modern ears it sounds off-putting to ally human sexuality so closely with the animal or “biological” side of our natures, this is due in large measure to the disdain that Cartesian rationalism has implanted into our heads for what is inferior and animal-like in us. But we need to appreciate that by grounding our sexuality in the objective order of being, namely, in our organic embodiedness belonging to the animal kingdom (which is at the same time infused with the rational), Aquinas avoids the two extremes to which the human regard for sex can often lead. The one extreme outright deifies human sexuality, as in the case of the ancient fertility cults, popularized most recently in The Da Vinci Code’s honoring of “the sacred feminine” through orgiastic ritual worship. Also veering toward this extreme, one could say, are those current theological trends which, even if remaining faithful to the Catholic tradition, identify sexual union between husband and wife too intimately with the sacred mystery of the divine. The other extreme banalizes sex in a Jansenist-like manner, perhaps even to the point of scorning it as inherently disdainful or sinful. Lurking never far from Aquinas’s mind in this regard is the medieval version of this extreme, Albigensianism (or Catharism). Albigensianism proposes a recycled Manichaean-like condemnation of matter and all things associated with it, including marriage and sex, as inherently evil, and it was against this heresy that St. Dominic fought in the first formative years of the Order he would found and which St. Thomas himself would later join as a youth. Perhaps it is with Albigensianism explicitly in mind that Thomas quickly dismisses the view that says sexual pleasure within marriage cannot be enjoyed without sin: “this cannot be” (hoc non potest esse), he insists in uncharacteristically strong language, since sexual pleasure within marriage, arising from the “sweet bond” (suavem societatem) of sexual union, is a “good action” (operationis bonae) to be enjoyed.29 28 Georges Cottier, O.P., Défis éthiques (Saint-Maurice, Switzerland: Editions Saint- Augustin, 1996), 24. 29 ST Suppl., q. 49, a. 6 (cf.Thomas’s Commentary on Peter Lombard’s Sentences, Bk. IV [hereafter cited as IV Sent.], d. 31, q. 2, a. 3; and Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, Bk. X, chs. 3–4); and Summa contra Gentiles III, ch. 123. Procreation and Unitive Love 743 Sex and the Unitive or Personalist Dimension If we say human sexuality is ordered exclusively to procreation, we distinguish in no way the meaning and purpose of our sexuality from the rest of the animal kingdom.To be genuinely human, our sexuality must share in what is unique and noblest in us, it must be integrated into the totality of human life. Indeed, that sexual intercourse between humans is commonly referred to as “making love,” which we would never say of animals (even monogamous animals), or even that sexual intercourse between humans is performed facing each other and “at will” (whereas all other animal species mate “in heat” and never face to face in an erect manner) and lasts exceedingly longer than copulation among all other animal species indicates, even at the biological level, that there is a qualitative difference to our sexuality. It indicates that sex as owing to our animality undergoes a radical alteration in the human being.30 Obviously, it is human rationality that accounts for this qualitative difference, for this radical alteration. To repeat, rationality—by which we mean reason and free-will taken together—is expressive of the form (the soul) in the human being and distinguishes us as humans. The hylemorphic anthropology outlined above allows us to sketch, in the following terms, the way in which our sexuality is integrated into the totality of our persons as rationally ensouled embodied beings. As matter is for the sake of form, as the body is for the sake of the soul, so is human sexuality for the sake of the soul’s highest, noblest functions: intellectual knowing and loving. Sexuality implies, then, not only the offering of one’s (procreative) body, but the offering of one’s entire self in the deepest bonds of knowledge and love, in the deepest bonds of personal communion and friendship. For it is in friendship that knowledge and love unite.Thus, if sexual union between animals constitutes a mere bodily union, sexual union between humans constitutes a union of persons, who are composed of both animal bodies and rational souls. Subsequently, we can say human sexuality owns another essential dimension: the unitive or personal (or “love-making”). Human sexuality, in its primary ordering to procreation as owing to the body, is at the same time ordered essentially to personal, unitive love as following upon the (rational) soul. By means of the unitive dimension, in other words, our sexuality participates in the rational dimension of human life, that is, in the psychical (from the Greek psyche ˜ for “soul”). Georges Cottier even calls human sex the “great paradox” in that it reflects the paradoxical union of 30 Cf. Cottier, Défis éthiques, 25; and Servais Pinckaers, O.P., The Sources of Christian Ethics, trans. Mary T. Noble, O.P. (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1995), 438. 744 Paul Gondreau body and soul in human nature.31 This unitive dimension derives from the bodily (procreative) side as a result of the soul’s union with the body, since, again, animal bodiliness marks the primary foundation of our sexuality. Aquinas does not name this other dimension “unitive” or “personal,” though he has nearly the equivalent, as when he affirms that “the form of marriage” (forma matrimonii) consists in an “indivisible union of souls” (in quadam indivisibili coniunctione animorum), or when he speaks of marriage as a “society of domestic fellowship” (domesticae conversationis consortium).32 These denominations broach closely with, and to a certain extent encapsulate, what the classical tradition, beginning with St.Augustine, calls the “secondary” (read:“personalist”) goods of marriage: first, life partnership (or mutual help); second, sexual fulfillment (or remedy for concupiscence); and, third, conjugal love.33 Aquinas follows suit, holding up procreation and the rearing of children as the “primary end” (or good) of marriage, the principalem finem, and conjugal friendship its subordinate “secondary end” (or good), the secundarium finem, as again it derives from the bodily (procreative) side of our sexuality.34 Such a view of marriage finds support from Jesus’ remark that in the resurrected state there is no more giving and taking in marriage (Mt 22:30), as this locution makes little sense if procreation does not mark the primary purpose of marriage (presumably the unitive dimension will remain for those married couples who attain to the beatific vision, since all the blessed will be joined in unitive love).35 31 Cottier, Défis éthiques, 25. 32 The form of marriage as an indivisible union of souls comes in ST III, q. 29, a. 2, while domesticae conversationis consortium appears in ScG III, ch. 123. One also finds St.Thomas calling marriage a “conjugal society” (associatio matrimonium) in ST Suppl., q. 41, a. 1 (reproduced from IV Sent., d. 26, q. 1, a. 1). Cf. ST II–II, q. 26, a. 11. 33 These secondary goods are indeed called “personalist” by the moralists John C. Ford and Gerald Kelly, Contemporary Moral Theology, vol. 2, Marriage Questions (Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1963), 38–39, and 75–76. For a definitive treatment of love in Aquinas’s thought, see Michael Sherwin, By Knowledge and By Love: Charity and Knowledge in the Moral Theology of St.Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2005). Cf. Peter Kwasniewski, “The Ecstasy of Love in Aquinas’s Commentary on the Sentences,” Angelicum 83 (2006): 87–93; and Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003), esp. 277–306. 34 ST Suppl., q. 41, a. 1 (IV Sent., d. 26, q. 1, a. 1). Cf. Guy de Broglie,“La conception thomiste des deux finalités du mariage,” Doctor Communis 27 (1974): 3–41. 35 Thomas writes in his commentary on Matthew 22:30 in ST I, q. 98, a. 2 ad 1: “After the resurrection man will be like an angel, spiritualized in soul and body [i.e., where ‘the soul will, to a certain extent, communicate to the body what properly belongs to itself as a spirit’ (I, q. 97, a. 3)].” Procreation and Unitive Love 745 Much maligned for relegating conjugal friendship, that is, the unitive dimension, to secondary status,Aquinas is yet much misunderstood on this point. It would be a grave error to read “secondary end” as signifying “accidental” or “non-essential.”36 The unitive remains just as essential to our sexuality as the procreative.The consortium of marriage is not parceled out into two types of ends, essential and non-essential, but is the ground of co-essential ends. The conjugal act has a per se ordering both to procreation, its per se primary ordering, and to unitive love, its per se secondary ordering.The ordination to unitive love, while secondary, is not merely per accidens. As the moralists Ford and Kelly put it: “the secondary, personalist ends, while remaining essentially subordinate, are nevertheless truly essential ends of marriage, just as the primary ends are.”37 For an analogy of how sexual union can have a per se ordering to two types of ends, primary and secondary, consider the co-essential primary and secondary ends of a professional sports team, where the secondary end of winning a division title is no less essential than, even if subordinate to, the primary end of winning the entire league championship. Likewise, when a mother prepares a meal for her family, the secondary end of serving good tasting food is no less essential than, even if subordinate to, the primary end of providing wholesome nutrition to her family. So while it is true Aquinas gives near exclusive attention to the procreative end, it is no less true that the procreative and unitive (or personalist) dimensions of human sexuality stand side by side in Thomas’s system of thought, even if one is subordinate to the other.To be sure, in a crucial passage from the Summa contra Gentiles, Aquinas does not hesitate to elevate the “secondary” good of conjugal love to the very summit of friendship; for St. Thomas, marital love holds the rank not only of a 36 Thus the misleading observation of Marie Leblanc (“Amour et procréation dans la théologie de saint Thomas,” Revue Thomiste 92 [1992]: 433–59, at 434) when he writes: “The gift of life in view of human progeny stands out clearly and constantly in the works of St. Thomas as the primary and essential end [of marriage]; on this point he does not modify his thought” (translation my own). I read this as implying that, on Aquinas’s account, procreation marks the only essential end of marriage. It is no doubt on account of the confusion that the term “secondary” engenders that the 1983 Code of Canon Law simply drops out all language of primary and secondary ends when holding in canon 1055 that marriage “is by its nature ordered to the good of the spouses (ad bonum coniugum) and the procreation and education of offspring” (trans. Canon Law Society of America, Code of Canon Law. Latin-English Edition, 387). 37 Ford and Kelly, Contemporary Moral Theology, vol. 2, 76; emphasis theirs.While dated, Ford and Kelly’s treatment of this issue, which spans 75–126, remains excellent. 746 Paul Gondreau “friendship of equality” (aequalis amicitia), but of maxima amicitia,“the highest type of friendship.”38 The Nuptial Grammar of Human Sexuality: Marriage Marks the One End of Sex Only in marriage can the offering of oneself in loving personal communion which is at the same time profoundly bodily, that is, procreative, take place. Only marriage—heterosexual marriage—unites the procreative and unitive dimensions, as corresponding to the substantial union of body and soul. We can therefore say marriage, nuptiality, marks the intrinsic teleological meaning of human sexuality. Better yet, human sexuality has but one end, marriage, with two essential, complementary dimensions: the procreative (expressive of the body) and the unitive (expressive of the soul).39 Human sexuality, and by consequence the sexual act, have a “grammar” written into them: a nuptial procreative-unitive grammar as owing to our constitution as body-soul composites, as rationally ensouled embodied beings. Human sexuality is deeply symbolic, then of the human being as a body-soul (procreative-unitive) unity. As Pope John Paul II’s theology of the body points out, the body-soul constitution of the human being owns a “spousal” meaning. To say human sexuality is inherently nuptial in meaning does not deny the wider social or psychological dimension of our sexuality that extends far beyond marriage.The distinction between male and female impacts the whole of our lives and applies to numerous aspects of our character and to 38 ScG III, ch. 123.This qualification of marriage as maxima amicitia is all the more significant in light of the fact that, as Charles J. Reid (Power over the Body, Equality in the Family. Rights and Domestic Relations in Medieval Canon Law [Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2004], 105) observes, canonists and lawyers since the twelfth century had stressed “the sense of obligation (debitum) [rather than friendship] that bound [married] parties together.” At the same time, Reid (99) does explain how “women and men were recognized [in twelfth- and thirteenthcentury theology] as spiritual equals, who benefited equally from Christ’s salvific acts. Men and women alike and in equal measure have gained eternal life through Christ’s death and resurrection.” For more on male and female equality in Aquinas, cf. Michael Nolan,“The Aristotelian Background to Aquinas’s Denial that ‘Woman is a Defective Male,’ ” The Thomist 64 (2000): 21–69. 39 Kenneth Schmitz has often stressed to me (in personal conversation) that we should not speak of two ends, the procreative and unitive, for the unified being that is man, but of only one. Ramón García de Haro also emphasizes the same point in Marriage and the Family in the Documents of the Magisterium, trans. William E. May (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993), 244, as pointed out by Mary Shivanandan (Crossing the Threshold of Love: A New Vision of Marriage in Light of John Paul II’s Anthropology [Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1999], 110). Procreation and Unitive Love 747 distinctions in roles across the societal spectrum. Nor does it deny a higher derived or even allegorical application of the nuptial meaning of human sexuality, such as when we speak of celibacy or mystical union with God in nuptial terms.40 Nevertheless, it remains true that the primary meaning of our sexuality is nuptial—understood as union “in the flesh”—and that only a hylemorphic anthropology makes this fully intelligible. We should note that the biblical witness, deeply influential on Aquinas’s view of human sexuality, confirms what the foregoing philosophical reflection otherwise demonstrates on the nuptial meaning of human sexuality being inscribed in the hylemorphic makeup of the human being.41 (Especially paramount here is Gen 1:26–27, which attests to God’s institution of the procreative dimension of human sexuality via our embodied sexual complementarity; and Gen 2:18–25, which testifies to God’s institution of the unitive or personalist dimension of our sexuality.) This does not mean the biblical testimony serves no other purpose than to “window dress” a philosophical perspective that otherwise stands well enough on its own.The Thomist view on sex and the human good is rooted both in what Scripture reveals and in what unassisted reason can determine. Distinguishing In Order To Unite Aware that in today’s mindset distinction often equates with separation or compartmentalization—whereas the Thomist seeks to distinguish always 40 Pope John Paul II (Man and Woman He Created Them:A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein [Boston: Pauline Books, 2006], General audiences of Jan. 16, 1980, and May 5, 1982, 185–90, and 440–43) speaks of the nuptial meaning of celibacy as a union in the spirit, whereby a man or a woman makes the disinterested gift of oneself not exclusively to another human person but to all of God’s people. Thus, the Pontifical Council for the Family (The Truth and Meaning of Human Sexuality: Guidelines for Education within the Family [Boston: Pauline Books, 1996], 34) calls “virginity or celibacy the supreme form of that self-giving that constitutes the very meaning of human sexuality,” though in a derived, analogical sense, since marriage as a union “in the flesh” serves as the prime analog for its being assigned to celibacy. Cf. Grabowski, Sex and Virtue, 87–88. Aquinas, for his part, allows for this extended meaning of the term in ST II–II, q. 152, a. 2, ad 1. As for mystical union, when the mystics use such nuptial imagery as a “kiss on the mouth” (as in Bernard of Clairvaux’s Sermon 7 on the Song of Songs ) or “betrothal” (as in Teresa of Avila’s The Interior Castle) to describe the loving union of the soul with God, these images must be understood as purely allegorical, since God has no body. 41 Evidence for the influence of the biblical witness on Aquinas’s account of human sexuality is seen in the simple fact that his commentary on the Genesis creation narrative is woven into his anthropological treatise in the Prima Pars of the Summa, particularly when he treats of the distinction between man and woman (qq. 92–102). 748 Paul Gondreau in order to unite—we need at this point to stress the inseparable union between the procreative and unitive dimensions of human sexuality. Distinctions must be drawn but always with the aim of seeing how the unity of the larger whole is maintained. So we must avoid making too hard and fast a distinction between the two dimensions of human sexuality—just as we should avoid fixing too hard and fast a line of division between body and soul—as if to give the impression there is a purely “bodily” side of sex that can be set apart from a purely “psychical” or “rational” side.As the human being is a fundamental unity, as each human individual is his body and his soul, so is human sexuality a fundamental unity of the procreative (the bodily) and the unitive (the rational or psychical), even as the latter derives from the former: “it is neither the spirit alone nor the body alone that loves,” writes Pope Benedict XVI in his inaugural encyclical letter Deus Caritas Est (§5),“it is man, the person, a unified creature composed of body and soul, who loves.” Every procreative aspect of human sexuality participates, then, via the hylemorphic union, in the unitive dimension, and every unitive act participates in the procreative. The substantial union between body and soul establishes a profound come-and-go between procreative and unitive aspects of our sexuality.While we can, and must, distinguish the procreative as expressive of the body from the unitive as expressive of the intellectual soul, it would be tantamount to a kind of dualism to suggest a separation of the procreative (bodily) side of sex from the unitive (rational/ psychical) dimension. Anthropological Alternatives in a Post-Modern Culture As should seem clear by this point, the principal thrust of this essay is to suggest that one’s stance on the morality of sexual practice is ultimately grounded in the way one views the human being, whether consciously formulated as such or as merely implied in one’s actions.And the Thomistinspired hylemorphic conception of human nature, which Catholic tradition has appropriated for its own (see Catechism of the Catholic Church, §365), leads one to conclude that our sexuality comprises the two coessential and indivisible dimensions of the procreative (expressive of the body) and the unitive (expressive of the soul). Put in other terms, while our sexuality certainly orders us to sexual pleasure, the anthropology adopted here insists human sexuality targets not merely pleasure, but two higher co-essential goods (procreation and unitive love-making), into which sexual pleasure is subsumed. If, then, we live in a post-modern world that by and large rejects the Catholic vision of human sexuality, it is because the Catholic view of the Procreation and Unitive Love 749 human person vies with other, more dominant anthropologies to which most people, to varying degrees, adhere. In general, these other dominant views of the human being fall into one of two camps, yet both yield near identical fruits in the arena of sexual conduct. The first, and most widespread, is the Cartesian view of the human being (the view inspired by the seventeenth-century philosopher René Descartes, the so-called “Father of Modern Philosophy”). Having difficulty seeing the human individual as anything other than a thinking being who is embodied in a problematic, accidental sense, the Cartesian account pits the body in fundamental and perpetual contest with the soul. The soul, and thus the human person, is identified primarily with the ego or with the self-conscious thinking self—recall Descartes’s famous dictum, “I think, therefore I am”—and the body is relegated to the “less than human.”42 Citing Descartes, Pope Benedict XVI recounts in his encyclical Deus Caritas Est how Descartes was greeted humorously with “O Soul!” by a philosopher acquaintance of his.43 In the sexual sphere, the Cartesian view has certainly played a significant role in the post-modern tendency to consider the body a pure instrument without value in and of itself. Not infrequently, the body today is treated as a kind of morally neutral playground, as a kind of Never-Never Land, where, like Peter Pan, we prefer perpetually to play without a proper grown-up sense of moral responsibility.44 The body’s sole aim, at least sexually speaking, is utilitarian, namely, to provide pleasure or enjoyment for the “self ” (the soul).“Consent,” provided by the “self ” (the soul), is the only essential ingredient to morally acceptable sexual activity. The Cartesian attitude thus leads to a destructive domination of the body. It incites us to live not in deferential harmony with our bodies, but to exploit and conquer our bodies, to use or manipulate our sexual organs as a mere means to satisfying sexual desire. Generally speaking, we 42 Evidence of how deeply the Cartesian undercurrent runs in post-modern thought comes from the philosopher Owen Flanagan, whose anthropological study The Problem of the Soul:Two Visions of Mind and How to Reconcile Them (New York: Basic Books, 2002) implies a Cartesian anthropology as its presupposed starting point. In the opening lines of the preface, Flanagan (ix) takes it as a given that a “humanistic image” of the human being (as “spiritual beings endowed with free will”) and a “scientific image” of man (as “evolved according to the principles of natural selection”) are in “conflict” and are simply “incompatible.” An Aristotelian-Thomist would never grant such an anthropological mindset as a presupposed starting point. 43 “The Epicurean Gassendi used to offer Descartes the humorous greeting:‘O Soul!’ And Descartes would reply: ‘O Flesh!’ [cf. René Descartes, Oeuvres, ed.V. Cousin (Paris 1824), vol. 12, 95ff]” (Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, §5). 44 My gratitude here to Thomas Joseph White, O.P. 750 Paul Gondreau are morally justified in whatever we choose to do with our bodies, provided we respect the bounds set by “consent” and by the criterion that one often hears loosely formulated as “so long as no one gets harmed.” The other dominant anthropology which holds favor today, particularly among various philosophers and countless natural scientists, and which piggybacks, so to speak, the Cartesian view, even if quite distinct from it, is the one that advances a materialist mechanized view of the human being.This anthropology explains human life wholly in terms of molecular interaction or genomic design, and considers human thought as reducible entirely to neurological chemicals: “we are all animal,” is how one philosopher puts it,“[since t]he mind or soul is the brain . . . [with the result that] we are fully embodied creatures.”45 The evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins employs even starker language, as his renowned The Selfish Gene refers to human beings as “survival machines” and as “robot vehicles” that are “blindly programmed” to preserve selfish interests.46 In terms of sexual conduct, this view of the human being as a mere machine, like the Cartesian account, also encourages us to treat the body, or, more specifically, our sexual organs (with their concomitant pleasure), in utilitarian means, that is, as mechanized, manipulable objects without inherent value.The body can be treated purely recreationally, as a toy. For evidence of how such a Cartesian/mechanist-like attitude toward the human body manifests itself in the sexual arena, one need merely point to the current social phenomenon in America known as “hooking up.” In the culture of “hooking up,” young adults engage in non-committal sex detached not only from love and commitment but from all romantic involvement. According to a telling journalistic account of this phenomenon, in the world of “hooking up” sexual encounters act as “the primary currency of social interaction.”47 45 Flanagan, The Problem of the Soul, xii and 6. Flanagan holds this in light of “advances in evolutionary biology, genetics, and the sciences of the mind, cognitive science and cognitive neuroscience.” Speaking for many scientists, Ridley (Genome, 2) asserts that the human genome—the complete set of human genes— accounts for “the question of whether and how our actions are determined” as well as for “this curious sensation called free will.” 46 While softer in tone, Ridley (Genome) yet speaks of the human being in mechanized terms as well when he calls us “working machine[s]” (22), and “the most complicated biological machine on the planet” (25) which are capable of the “mechanism” known as learning (106), and so on. This language is common in the scientific community. 47 In her book, Unhooked: How Young Women Pursue Sex, Delay Love and Lose at Both (New York: Riverhead Books, 2007), Laura Session Stepp (4–5) notes the following in response to numerous conversations she had with “real girls and young Procreation and Unitive Love 751 Such stark examples of contemporary sexual conduct as “hooking up” sets in relief Pope Benedict XVI’s rather strong assertion in Deus Caritas Est (§5) that the body today is “exploited at will,” that human sexuality is treated as “a commodity, a mere ‘thing’ to be bought or sold.” The encyclical does not stop there, pointing to the Cartesian/mechanistinspired attitude of the human body as a contributing cause of such exploitation, and then labels this attitude for what it is: a veritable “debasement of the human body,” a “hatred of [human] bodiliness.”48 “The Radiance of the Flesh” Needless to say, evaluating our sexuality from a Thomist hylemorphic angle places us in a different universe. It is the universe of “the radiance of the flesh,” to use Dante’s phrase from The Divine Comedy (a work that draws heavily upon the thought of St.Thomas) when affirming how our humanity is “lovelier for being whole”—and by “whole” he means an organic body “robed about” a rational soul.49 If we follow the Thomist women”: “Young people have virtually abandoned dating and replaced it with group get-togethers and sexual behaviors that are detached from love and commitment—and sometimes even from liking. . . . Relationships have been replaced by the casual sexual encounters known as hookups. Love, while desired by some, is being put on hold or seen as impossible; sex is becoming the primary currency of social interaction. . . . [H]ooking up, in the minds of this generation, carries no commitment. Partners hook up with the understanding that however far they go sexually, neither should become romantically involved in any serious way. Hooking up’s defining characteristic is the ability to unhook from a partner at any time.” Later (6) she recounts how in a three-hour conversation with four young working-class women about men and sex, “[n]ever once during the conversation did they use the word ‘love.’ ” 48 “[T]he contemporary way of exalting the body is deceptive. Eros, reduced to pure ‘sex’, has become a commodity, a mere ‘thing’ to be bought and sold, or rather, man himself becomes a commodity.This is hardly man’s great ‘yes’ to the body. On the contrary, he now considers his body and his sexuality as the purely material part of himself, to be used and exploited at will. . . . Here we are actually dealing with a debasement of the human body: no longer is it integrated into our overall existential freedom; no longer is it a vital expression of our whole being, but it is more or less relegated to the purely biological sphere.The apparent exaltation of the body can quickly turn into a hatred of bodiliness” (Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, §5). 49 Dante, Paradiso, Canto XIV (trans. Anthony Esolen [New York: Modern Library, 2004], 147); according to Esolen (from personal conversation), next to the Bible, Aquinas was Dante’s most influential source. One potent manner by which St. Thomas affirms the goodness and integrity of the human body is to accord it an essential role in the beatific vision of God after the final resurrection, as when he writes: “There will be a kind of beatitude for our bodies, inasmuch as they will see God in his sensible creatures and especially in the body of Christ” (IV Sent., d. 49, 752 Paul Gondreau anthropological account to its logical conclusion, as traditional Catholic moral teaching does, we find ourselves affirming the full moral worth and integrity of the human body, that is, the intrinsic moral worth of our (procreative) bodies. Convinced that the human being is on account of his material body and his immaterial soul,Thomistic hylemorphism reminds us that we must take moral ownership of our bodies, together with our souls, since what we do to our bodies we do to our very persons. Hardly morally neutral, the human body is morally charged. Little wonder certain scholars should identify in Aquinas a pronounced anti-Manichaean defense of “the metaphysical and moral goodness of bodiliness, sexuality, marriage, and procreation.”50 Aquinas is well known for staking his claim as a tireless defender of God’s entire created order—for which reason G. K. Chesterton dubs him “St.Thomas of the Creator”—no matter how “low grade” or inferior that level of nature might be, including our animal-like procreative embodiedness.51 Indeed,Aquinas does not hesitate to affirm that the human body, because of its dignity of being fitted to a rational soul, stands apart from all other bodies as a most excellent expression “of the divine art” (ab arte divina).52 This must be borne in mind when considering the disparaging criticisms commonly leveled against Catholic moral teaching, and more particularly against Humanae Vitae. Often such criticisms amount to nothing more than ruses, either because they outright misrepresent the Catholic defense of the human body, if not of conjugal love, or because they often issue from an underlying Cartesian bias. We see an example of the latter when we are told the Catholic teaching on human sexuality amounts to nothing more than an “obsession” with the “mechanics” of procreation.53 q. 2, a. 2, ad 6; emphasis added). Also, in Quodlibet 8, q. 9, a. 2, he explains: “The blessed . . . will find their joy in the contemplation of the divinity and the humanity of Christ.” Our resurrected bodies will share in the contemplation of Christ’s humanity, inasmuch as this contemplation will include the perception our bodily senses will have of his body. 50 Peter Kwasniewski argues this in his address “Aquinas on the Grandeur and Limitations of Marriage,” offered at the conference “Sacraments in Aquinas,” held at Ave Maria University, Naples, Florida, February 1–3, 2007. 51 Chesterton, Saint Thomas Aquinas (Garden City: Image Books, 1956), 119. Among those who have highlighted this aspect of Thomas’s thought, Josef Pieper merits first mention; cf. his Guide to Thomas Aquinas (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1991), 120–33. 52 ST I, q. 91, a. 3. 53 Thus, for instance, the Catholic priest and sociologist/novelist Andrew Greeley (Sex:The Catholic Experience [Allen, TX: Thomas More, 1994], 75 and 82), who charges “conservative hierarchies” in the Catholic Church with being “obsessed with the mechanics of the pro-creative process” and with holding “romantic Procreation and Unitive Love 753 To speak of the procreative process as if it were a mere machine is deeply revealing of a disdain for the organic beauty of the human body and of a supposition that the procreative dimension is purely accidental to our sexuality. Because it embraces all that is authentically human, the Catholic vision of human sexuality draws the line in the sand when confronted with a Cartesian-like disregard for the human body (i.e., for human “biology,” procreation), and thus with a truncated approach to moral living. Avoiding a Dualist-leaning (Cartesian) Anthropology in Our Sexual Acts Human sexuality has one end, heterosexual marriage, with two essential dimensions, the procreative (expressive of the body) and unitive (expressive of the soul). Since body and soul always remain a substantial composite, we can see that separating or opposing in any fashion the procreative and unitive dimensions is, at bottom, to opt for a dualist-leaning Cartesian anthropology.Whenever one attempts to further the aims of one of the dimensions at the exclusion of the other, or to pit one dimension in fundamental and perpetual contest with the other, one implies a disintegrated view of the human being. If we consider those sex acts that Catholic moral teaching has traditionally labeled as opposed to the nuptial meaning of human sexuality, from homosexual intercourse to masturbation, to premarital sexual relations and even to artificial contraceptive use, we can see that each of these acts attempts to uphold one dimension at the expense of the other (normally the unitive at the exclusion of the procreative). There is a denial, at least in practice, of the hylemorphic union of body and soul, of the fundamental unity of the human being. There is a denial of the symbolic meaning of human sexuality as a body-soul (procreative-unitive) composite. By these acts human persons live as if they were either disembodied spirits or pure bodies. Such persons live as “fragmented selves,” to use the memorable line from Augustine when describing his earlier life of sexual dissipation in the Confessions.54 love” in ill repute. Consider as well the remarks of the psychotherapist and moral theologian Daniel A. Helminiak (Sex and the Sacred: Gay Identity and Spiritual Growth [New York: Harrington Park Press, 2006], 93), who takes a Cartesian-like swipe at human bodiliness in favor of the interpersonal dimension of sex when he writes: “Psychological studies show that the distinctive function of human sex is intimacy and relationship, not procreation” (emphasis his).The views of Greeley and Helminiak are shared in the very least implicitly by most theologians who dissent from Humanae Vitae. 54 Augustine, Confessions, Bk. II, ch. 1 (trans. Henry Chadwick [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992], 24). Indeed, in describing his “disintegrated self,”Augustine 754 Paul Gondreau Among other things, respecting the human being as a body-soul (procreative-unitive) composite means the sexual act must at all times have at least a symbolic orientation to procreation. This symbolic ordering is absent where the sexual act of its very nature suppresses it, as in the case of intentional sterilization, contraceptive intercourse, or same-sex intercourse. However, since the actual conception of a child is accidental to this ordering, the symbolic orientation to procreation is maintained in those instances where the procreative end is not per se suppressed yet where the failure to produce a child is foreseen. This is the case for those couples whose infertility results either from advanced age or from some other natural or accidental cause. It is also the case for those couples who, with the express intention of not conceiving a child for morally justifiable reasons, observe the natural method of birth regulation (natural family planning). Failure to produce a child as a result either of natural or unintended infertility or of following the natural method of birth regulation does not in itself remove the symbolic ordering to procreation. It is analogous to the way the symbolic ordering to seeing is not removed or suppressed when the failure to see results either from natural or accidental blindness (similar to infertility) or from the express intention to close one’s eyes in order to sleep (similar to the couple practicing natural family planning). But failure to see as a result of the act of purposefully blinding oneself does remove the symbolic ordering to seeing, since it is per se opposed to it. So in the case of conjugal intercourse between spouses who are infertile or who are observing the natural method of birth regulation, the fullness of embodied complementarity, and thus the symbolic orientation to procreation, remains present. Furthermore, group persons, or societies, such as marriage, whose unity of order transcends the individuals themselves who comprise it, are presumed to last unto perpetuity and do not dissolve simply because they do not achieve their ends. A baseball team survives even if it suffers a losing season; a marriage survives even if it fails to produce children. Marriage as Maxima Amicitia: Uniting the Two Dimensions Let us return to Aquinas’s qualification of marriage as maxima amicitia,“the highest type of friendship.”That St.Thomas should reserve maxima amiciwrites the following:“At one time in adolescence I was burning to find satisfaction in hellish pleasures. I ran wild in the shadowy jungle of erotic adventures.”Then in ch. 2 he quickly adds: “Clouds of muddy carnal concupiscence filled the air. The bubbling impulses of puberty befogged and obscured my heart so that it could not see the difference between love’s serenity and lust’s darkness. Confusion of the two things boiled within me. It seized hold of my youthful weakness sweeping me through the precipitous rocks of desire to submerge me in a whirlpool of vice.” Procreation and Unitive Love 755 tia for man and woman in marriage, rather than for men alone, as one might expect from a medieval author, ought to arrest us.True enough, the opening pages of Genesis, which certainly impacted Aquinas, hold up the conjugal relationship as the most fulfilling of human friendships. But in the history of western literature that stretches even into the Renaissance and modern periods, one would be at pains to find one male-female (conjugal) friendship that could rival the deeply fulfilling male friendships that abound in the best known pieces of western literature up to Thomas’s day—from the friendship enjoyed by Gilgamesh and Enkidu in the Mesopotamian Gilgamesh epic, to Achilles and Patroklus in Homer’s Iliad, to Beowulf and Wiglaf in the early medieval epic Beowulf, to Roland and Olivier in the early twelfth-century epic The Song of Roland.55 Aquinas could easily have echoed this literary tradition. Or he could have stayed within the more measured language of his former Master General of the Dominican Order, Raymond of Peñafort (†1275), who affirms in his Summa on Marriage that God created woman to be man’s “companion and friend” in marriage.56 Furthermore, presumably St.Thomas, writing in an age of arranged marriages, that is, in the age of adulterous courtly romance where affective love often occurred outside marriage, had few contemporary examples in mind on which to stake his claim of maxima amicitia.57 If 55 Perhaps there is one exception to this: the marriage of Odysseus and Penelope in Homer’s Odyssey, symbolized by their immovable marriage bed which Odysseus built around the stump of an olive tree, fashioning one of the bed posts out of that stump still rooted in the ground. But as in the marriage ceremonies of the Shakespearean comedies or of the Jane Austen novels, which occur only at the end of the work, even here we fail to see the conjugal friendship from within and the subsequent long-term playing out of the marriage: Odysseus is absent for twenty long years and we merely witness his reunion with Penelope at the end of the epic. It is my colleague in English literature Brian Barbour who has pointed out to me (in personal conversation) this absence of a sympathetic presentation of a happy, fulfilling marriage from within and of the subsequent playing out of that marriage in Western literature.Again, if one does find a happy marriage in literature, invariably it occurs only in the context of the wedding ceremony itself (à la Shakespeare or Jane Austen), that is, only at the inception of the marriage rather than in the long-term playing out of the marriage. On the other hand, presentations of bad marriages from within, including the playing out of those marriages, abound in the history of Western literature. 56 Raymond of Peñafort, Summa on Marriage,Title II, n. 3 (trans. Payer, 20):“The Lord did not form (the first woman) from the man’s head lest she seem to be the ruling lady, nor from the feet lest she be considered a servant, but from his side so as to be a companion and friend.” According to Payer (“Introduction,” 6),“the parallels [between Raymond and Aquinas] suggest a use of Raymond by Aquinas.” 57 Charles J. Reid (Power over the Body, Equality in the Family, 29–30) notes: “the canonists [and thus also the theologians] of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries 756 Paul Gondreau mutual respect was often present in such arranged marriages, friendship in the highest sense of the term most likely was not. So if marriage holds the rank of maxima amicitia in Aquinas’s estimation, it is because marriage, to quote him again, constitutes an “indivisible union of souls” (indivisibili coniunctione animorum), or a domestic society of loving personal communion (domesticae conversationis consortium), which enjoys the “sweet bond” (suavem societatem) of sexual procreative union.58 In other words, marriage rises to the level of maxima amicitia because it unites the two essential dimensions of human sexuality, procreative and unitive. No other type of friendship can rival the degree of intimacy and union, which is both physical and affective/spiritual, that marriage attains. It is not without pertinence that in his commentary on the Genesis creation narrative, woven into the anthropological section of the Prima pars of the Summa, Thomas asserts that one of God’s purposes in the creation of man and woman was “so that man might love (diligeret) woman all the more, and did not share our conception of marriage as belonging primarily to the parties themselves to arrange. . . . Most marital decisions in twelfth- and thirteenthcentury Europe continued to be influenced, above all else, by dynastic and familial considerations.”Thus courtly love, i.e., the genre of romance literature dating from the High to Late Middle Ages (e.g.,Andreas Capellanus’s Art of Courtly Love or Chretien de Troyes’s Lancelot: Knight of the Cart), celebrates adulterous love for the simple reason that romantic sentiments typically occur outside (arranged) marriages. However, the anonymous late-medieval Sir Gawain and the Green Knight, which aims at countering the dominant adulterous, unchaste themes of courtly love, marks an exception to this. For more on the relation of canon law to Thomas’s teaching on marriage, cf. Seamus P. Heaney, The Development of the Sacramentality of Marriage from Laon to Thomas Aquinas, S.T.D. dissertation (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1963). 58 ScG III, ch. 123:“The greater the friendship, the more need for it to be firm and lasting. But the friendship of man and woman is counted strongest of all, since they are united not only in the union of the sexes, which even among beasts makes a sweet bond, but also in all things related to their society of domestic fellowship, as a sign whereof a man leaves even father and mother for the sake of his wife (Gen 2:24).” In the following chapter,Thomas explains how polygamy is opposed to the friendship of marriage: “If the wife has one husband only, whereas the husband has more than one wife, there will not be a friendship of equality on both sides (non erit aequalis amicitia ex utraque parte).There will not be the friendship of a free man with a free woman, but a sort of friendship of a slave with his master.” My gratitude here to Michael Sherwin, O.P. Likewise for Raymond of Peñafort (Summa on Marriage, Title II, n. 3 [trans. Payer, 20]), the companionship and friendship that husband and wife enjoy, as implied in the Genesis creation account, entails a “conjugal society” whereby both enjoy “an undivided manner of life.” Procreation and Unitive Love 757 cleave to her more closely.”59 Humanae Vitae, for its part, holds that marriage marks a “very special form of personal friendship, in which husband and wife generously share everything, without undue reservations or selfish convictions” (§9). We can say more.The term Aquinas employs to speak of marriage as a “society” of domestic fellowship is consortium. Consortium as it applies to conjugal life means marriage is more than a simple social union. It is a society that has been institutionalized in the robust juridical sense of the term.60 Marriage is not “merely” a friendship or a communion, but a permanent aspect of the entire human social order, that is, an institution. Since the consortium of marriage is an institution with permanent value and is of interest to everyone in society, it is wrongheaded for western culture to seek to turn marriage into a “private agreement.” To be sure, Aquinas’s denomination of marriage as a consortium only underscores how deeply “personalist” and unitive his vision of sex and marriage truly is.This term consortium means marriage is to be regarded as a group person, a society with a unity of order that transcends the spouses as individual partners. Married partners hold themselves out as one; they attain a veritable “two-in-oneship”—something no society would say, for instance, of cohabitating couples. Speaking juridically, marriage is more than a mere “partnership,” since partnerships are for a determinate period of time (as when an individual and an automobile dealership agree on a lease contract) and can dissolve at any moment, and normally do dissolve when the determinate period of time expires.The consortium of marriage, on the other hand, is again presumed to last unto perpetuity, that is, it is a unity (a group person) that is regarded as permanent. Evidence for this is seen in the fact that no state reduces marriage to a pure partnership, since 59 ST I, q. 92, a. 2.The Latin verb Thomas uses for love, diligere, signifies a properly human form of love, that is, freely chosen, spiritual love. It is significant that he elects not to use amare, which signifies more general, sensual love (as it relates to sex), even if diligere includes amare, at least in reference to marriage.These words on marriage as maxima amicitia serve as an important qualification of Aquinas’s more off-putting remarks, at least as these remarks sound to modern ears.These would include Thomas’s assertion (in ST I, q. 98, a. 2, sed contra [cf. as well q. 92, a. 1], and II–II, q. 164, a. 2, ad 1) that women are of most help to men in the begetting and rearing of children, or that in this domestic fellowship the man is by nature the “head” (caput) and “governor” (gubernator) of the woman—though Aquinas does add (in ST II–II, q. 164, a. 2, ad 1) that in the post-lapsarian condition the woman suffers on account of such headship, as she is made “to obey her husband’s will even against her own.” 60 These and the following remarks take their inspiration from Russell Hittinger, both from personal conversation and from his lecture “Social Justice: Devolution or Subsidiarity?”, delivered at Providence College in Providence, RI on Oct. 23, 2007. 758 Paul Gondreau no state allows two individuals to contract a marriage for a determinate period of time (say, for eighteen months), something it does for partnerships (as in the case of the automobile lease). Every state presumes that a contracted marriage lasts unto perpetuity, and it is only when informed after the fact by those spouses seeking a divorce that it thinks otherwise. Further, we would be remiss if we did not situate this view of marriage as maxima amicitia against the backdrop of the Aristotelian teaching on friendship, which was deeply influential on St. Thomas. If we keep in mind, for instance, the Aristotelian view that friendship implies “equality” and “community,” and that the highest type of friendship is the one where friends admire the virtuous character of each, that is, where friends “are similar in virtue and wish goods [of virtue] to their friend for the friend’s own sake,” we have the foundation for a high estimation of the personalist, unitive dimension of sex: “In fact there is a virtue proper to both husband and wife,” affirms Aquinas in his commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, “that renders their friendship delightful to each other, [since] friendship of this kind can be based on virtue, utility, and pleasure” (i.e., it unites in a unique way the three types of friendship).61 And we can be sure Aristotle’s declaration that a friend “is another self ” was not lost on Aquinas’s appreciation of Scripture’s claim that in marriage man and woman “become one flesh” (Gen 2:24), in such wise that it can be “put asunder” by no human being (Mk 10:9).62 So while looking upon marriage as maxima amicitia does not mean that marriage, like the polity, provides all the goods requisite for human flourishing, the friendship of marriage is emblematic of that which the polity ultimately aims at: the cultivation of virtuous friendship. The Marriage “Debt” At seeming odds with the view of marriage as maxima amicitia is what medieval theologians, Aquinas included, often include in their treatment 61 Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (trans. C. I. Litzinger [Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1993]), Bk.VIII, lect. 12 (§1723). Aristotle’s remarks on friendship cited in the text come from Nicomachean Ethics, Bk. VIII, chs. 3 (1156b8–11), 8 (1159b3), 9 (1159b32), and Bk. IX, ch. 4 (1166a30). For St.Thomas’s succinct summary of Aristotle’s teaching on friendship, cf. ST II–II, q. 25, a. 7. 62 In addressing the distinction between love of concupiscence and love of friendship in Aquinas, Ferrucio Galeotti (“Amore e amicizia conjugali secondo S.Tommaso d’Aquinas,” Doctor Communis 25 [1972]: 39–59) argues that because marriage implies a love of friendship, which centers on the other as another self rather than on the other as a good ordered to the satisfaction of one’s immediate needs, the friendship of marriage is properly human and thus profoundly personalist. Procreation and Unitive Love 759 of marriage: the notion of the marriage “debt” (debitum).63 While this notion comes from St. Paul, when it is raised scholars not infrequently snicker at it for the archaic and inadequate way it speaks of marriage, and disregard it as an excusable “hiccup” in the Pauline corpus. Mindful that married partners have “power” or “dominion” (e’ notriáfx in the original Greek; potestas in the Latin Vulgate) not over their own bodies but over each other’s bodies, St. Paul enjoins his readers in 1 Corinthians 7:3–4:“Let the husband render the debt (o’ ueikǵ in Greek; debitum in the Vulgate) to his wife, and the wife also in like manner to her husband.” Sometimes o’ ueikǵ/debitum is translated in English as “conjugal rights,” as in the RSV: “The husband should give to his wife her conjugal rights, and likewise the wife to her husband.” Whatever one’s preferred translation, at bottom the marriage “debt” signifies that married partners have the moral obligation to grant conjugal intercourse to each other whenever it is asked, within the bounds of reason. But on this matter, too, we need not see the marriage debt as necessarily out of step with contemporary “personalist” approaches to human sexuality.When, through marriage, a man and a woman bind themselves in life-long love and fidelity to each other, they become united in body and soul. They become “another self,” to use Aristotle’s language for friendship, in the deepest and most intimate sense of the term. That is, their entire persons, including their bodies and their souls, belong to each other. In a sense, and as in fact evoked by the marriage vows of Thomas’s own day, each has a claim on the other’s body and soul as on his/her very person.64 To speak of “debt” is to speak of what is owed, due, on the basis of fundamental equality in personal dignity—and this, essentially, is what Aquinas argues when discussing the matter.65 Each spouse is due the total gift of body and soul of the other as another self in the deepest bonds of 63 An entire article is devoted to the matter in ST Suppl., q. 64 (this is pulled from IV Sent., d. 32, q. 1). As remarked earlier, Reid (Power over the Body, 105) notes how canonists and lawyers since the twelfth century had stressed “the sense of obligation (debitum) that bound [married] parties together.” Raymond of Peñafort, who was himself a thirteenth-century teacher of canon law, gives central treatment to the notion of the marriage debt in his Summa on Marriage (cf., e.g., Title II, nn. 9–11 [trans. Payer, 23–24]). For a modern treatment of it, cf. Ford and Kelly, Contemporary Moral Theology, vol. 2, 63–74. 64 According to Raymond of Peñafort (Summa on Marriage, Title II, n. 2 [trans. Payer, 20]), the “customary words” pronounced at the moment of marital consent (at least in the thirteenth century) were “I take you as mine” by the bridegroom and “I take you as mine” by the bride. 65 ST Suppl., q. 64, a. 5 (IV Sent., d. 32, q. 1, a. 3). 760 Paul Gondreau friendship (maxima amicitia). Granted, the medievals see the rendering of the marriage debt largely as a kind of legal transaction and as an antidote to concupiscence, or, as St.Thomas explains, as an assuagement of sexual desire.66 But this does not mean a more “personalist” take on the marriage debt signifying the offering of one’s body and soul in the total gift of self is absent from such a view. The Primacy of Procreation At a time when current fashion touts the primacy of the personalist dimension, sometimes at the expense of the procreative, the preeminent role of the procreative needs to be reasserted, at least if we attend to the objective metaphysical facts of the matter. To use Aquinas’s language, procreation marks the primary end (or good), the principalem finem, of marriage. Otherwise, we have no way of making proper sense of the uniqueness of marriage, that is, of distinguishing marriage from any other loving, affirming relationship. Since the unitive dimension characterizes all types of relationships that are not specifically genital or even bodily—after all, we enjoy unitive love with our friends, with our family members, and with God, the angels enjoy it with each other and with God, and God enjoys it with himself— we know the unitive or personalist dimension alone cannot be the defining mark of the nuptial meaning of our sexuality (as Aquinas’s Dominican predecessor Raymond of Peñafort already observed).67 Just as human nature cannot be defined in abstraction from the bodily (i.e., animal) dimension, so neither can we abstract the bodily, procreative dimension from the nuptial, symbolic meaning of our sexuality. Marriage is unique among all human relationships in that man and woman, while united in spiritual and affective communion, express their love specifically through their bodies. To put the matter in more technical Thomistic language, if the unitive dimension (or what Aquinas again calls the indivisible union of souls) signifies what is formal to marriage, the procreative union of bodies corresponds to what is material to marriage. Those who give 66 The argument for the marriage debt assuaging concupiscence appears in ST Suppl., q. 64, a. 1, sed contra (IV Sent., d. 32, q. 1, a. 1, sed contra). He adds in q. 64, a. 9 ad 1 (IV Sent., d. 32, q. 1, a. 5, qla. 3 ad 1): “It is ordained by God, on account of the weakness of the flesh (propter lubricum carnis), that the debt must always be paid to the one who asks lest he be afforded an occasion of sin.” 67 In his Summa on Marriage, Title II, n. 3 (trans. Payer, 20), Raymond notes that without procreation, there would be no real way of distinguishing marriage from any other cohabitating union, such as “between a brother and a sister, between a son and a mother.” Procreation and Unitive Love 761 disproportionate emphasis to the personalist dimension risk obscuring this important truth.68 The Unitive Marks the Higher, Nobler Dimension of Human Sexuality At the same time, a Thomist-inspired hylemorphic sexual anthropology does not look upon the unitive or personalist dimension as some kind of a beside-the-fact good. On the contrary, the unitive dimension expresses human sexuality’s participation in the rational, in what is highest and noblest in us.The personalist dimension raises our procreative animality, as it were, to the properly human. Signifying what is formal to marriage, the unitive dimension marks the higher, nobler meaning of human sexuality. It is in this sense that we can say the procreative is for the sake of the unitive, just as matter is for the sake of form, body is for the sake of soul. The procreative is for the sake of the building up of the love between spouses. And just as the common good is always for the sake of the individual good, so is human sexuality’s orientation to the common good of the human race (procreation) for the sake of our sexuality’s orientation to the private good of the spouses themselves (unitive love-making). Further, since form is the principle of unity between matter and form, the unitive dimension marks the principle of unity between the two dimensions.This explains why it would be odd to hear the engaged couple first say they are getting married because they want to have children and only afterward say they are getting married because they love each other. Their spousal unitive love is the “soul” of their procreative fecundity. The Procreative Reaches Beyond the Purely “Biological” The foregoing remarks expose how misleading it is to stick pejorative labels like “physicalist” or “biological” onto those moral (natural law) accounts of human sexuality which place such heavy emphasis upon the procreative dimension. Not only is the procreative for the sake of (or even internal to) the unitive love between spouses, but procreation itself signifies something much broader than a mere “biological” or “physicalist” act: “one should not 68 While perhaps inadvertent, Grabowski’s decision in Sex and Virtue: An Introduc- tion to Sexual Ethics to wait until the sixth chapter to examine the procreative dimension of human sexuality is yet quite telling. Such a delay in treating the procreative is unthinkable from a Thomist hylemorphic (or even natural law) perspective; thus, Fulvio Di Blasi (“What Nature? Whose Nature? Reflecting on Some Recent Arguments in Natural Law Ethics,” in Restoring Nature: Essays in Thomistic Philosophy and Theology, ed. Michael M. Waddell [South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press, 2008]) writes:“procreation, far from being extrinsic or secondary, is exactly the defining trait of marriage as a specific communion of persons.” 762 Paul Gondreau make the mistake of imagining that procreation and the rearing of children are not personalist values, too,” argue the moralists Ford and Kelly, “or that the so-called personalist values do not contribute to the biological or social ends.”69 To be sure, since form actualizes, informs, matter and provides the principle of unity, we can say the unitive informs the procreative and marks the principle of unity between the two. How does this translate concretely? It means we do not just “produce babies” like animals. Human biology does not function as a kind of free-floating mechanism in isolation from a social unit. Rather, we first enter into a communion of personal spousal love, from which the begetting of human children flows, followed by the welcoming of these children into this same communion of love, into a family. Procreation means the begetting of new life, the begetting of new human persons, along with the subsequent rearing or educating of those new human persons as members of a community (a family). It means attending to what Thomas calls “the training of the soul” (instructione quantum ad animam), that is, attending to the full physical, emotional and spiritual needs of these new human persons who, while lacking in knowledge and virtue, are yet made to know and love the good.70 It is in this way that the unitive love between husband and wife informs and unites to it the procreative. The procreative end cannot remain confined to the “animal” or purely “biological” dimension of human life. Aquinas drives home the personalist depth of the procreative dimension in a significantly, if subtly, worded phrase: fines autem matrimonii est proles generanda et educanda, “the end of marriage is the producing and rearing of offspring.”71 What stands out here is how this statement’s grammatical struc69 Ford and Kelly, Contemporary Moral Theology, vol. 2, 49. 70 ScG III, ch. 122: “in vain would be the generation of man unless due nurture (debita nutritio) followed, without which the offspring generated could not endure. (Sexual intercourse) then ought to be so directed as that both the proper generation may ensue and the rearing of the offspring be secured. . . . [For] in the human species the young need not only bodily nutrition, as animals do, but also the training of the soul.” Reid (Power over the Body, 87) notes that this teaching on parental responsibility by St. Thomas marks a significant theological development. Indeed, Reid explains that by appealing to 2 Corinthians 12:13–15 in expressing his view on the matter in ST Suppl., q. 49, a. 2, ad 1 (which opens with the assertion “offspring signifies not merely the begetting of children, but also their rearing”), Aquinas suggests that “sacrificial giving should characterize the parents’ relationship with the child.” 71 ST III, q. 29, a. 2. I am grateful to Mark Johnson for pointing out this phrase to me in an electronic communication on Feb. 20, 2008. One finds nearly the same wording in Vatican Council II, Gaudium et Spes, §50:“Marriage and conjugal love Procreation and Unitive Love 763 ture of one noun (proles,“offspring”) modified by two gerundives or adjectives ( generanda et educanda,“producing and rearing”) highlights the “personalist” aim of marriage relative to the procreative dimension. For, one might expect Aquinas to have said, simply, that the end of marriage is procreation, or the production of children. Instead, he inserts “rearing” (educanda) as an essential part of the procreative package. Put in other terms, we cannot speak of procreation in abstraction from the concomitant—and more “personalist”—duty of rearing children.Whenever we speak of offspring (proles), we imply therein not only their being produced ( generanda), “which is attained by conjugal intercourse,” adds St. Thomas, but also their being reared (educanda), “which is attained by the other duties of husband and wife, by which they help one another in rearing their offspring.”72 Procreation is therefore brought up and fully integrated into the higher, nobler functions of knowledge and love, into the unitive, personalist dimension of our sexuality. Indeed, procreation targets the common good proper, inasmuch as it ensures the continued (procreated) existence of the human race, and in that it often implies selfless acts of sacrificial love and service more than what the love between husband and wife implies.This allows one to attach the label of unitive love as much to the procreative dimension as to the love between husband and wife proper, if not more.73 And since the private good of persons, hardly opposed or alien to the common good, is itself enhanced by and, as St.Thomas affirms, loved “for the sake of the common good,”74 only misguided views of sex pit the individual (unitive) good of the spouses in opposition to the common good of procreation. On this score, Michael Waldstein has rightly criticized current discussions on marriage and human sexuality for largely ignoring the importance of the common good. Instead these discussions opt for a view where marriage “is seen in terms of the individual personal dignity of husband and wife and their personal love for one another as unique are by their nature ordained toward the begetting and educating of children.” Cf. Ford and Kelly, Contemporary Moral Theology, vol. 2, 84. 72 “Procreation is not just a continuation of the race or the nation. It is inherently a continuation and fulfillment of the persons of husband and wife also. Parenthood may well be, and in fact frequently is, the highest of the personalist values in a given marriage which is de facto fruitful” (Ford and Kelly, Contemporary Moral Theology, vol. 2, 49). For more of the same line of reasoning, cf. Galeotti,“Amore e amicizia conjugali secondo S.Tommaso d’Aquinas,” 39–59. 73 For passages relating procreation to the common good in St. Thomas, cf. ST II–II, q. 154, a. 2; ScG IV, ch. 78; and IV Sent. d. 33, q. 2, a. 1, ad 4. 74 ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3. 764 Paul Gondreau persons.”75 Experience might well show that those married couples who show a greater degree of generosity and self-giving love toward the common good of procreation often enjoy a deeper, stronger unitive bond in their love as spouses. It is in their procreative bodily union, as form is in the matter, as the common good subsumes the private good, whereby married couples are united in the deepest bonds of personal love. Furthermore, marriage not only targets the common good of humanity, as a society it possesses a unity of order itself, which is to say it enjoys a common good on its own, a common good to which it is ordered and by which it is perfected. Marriage in other words imitates God, so to speak, since, as St.Thomas observes, God is himself the common good of humanity—indeed, of the entire created order.76 Marriage’s imitatio of the divine in fact goes further, as married couples (pro)create in the very same way that God creates, namely, through love and through a subsequent invitation to this same communion in personal (familial) love. Married spouses participate in God’s creative handiwork in a way no other creature can, not even angels. Lastly, because God must directly create every human soul, as the union of sperm and ovum cannot “produce” an immaterial rational soul, married spouses co-create with God, inasmuch as they provide the matter while God supplies the form. Such is the dignity that the procreative dimension confers upon human sexuality. N&V 75 Michael Waldstein argues this in his address “Children as the Common Good of Marriage,” offered at the conference “Sacraments in Aquinas,” held at Ave Maria University, Naples, Florida, February 1–3, 2007.Waldstein’s purpose is to recover an element of John Paul II’s teaching (found, for instance, in Familiaris Consortio) that, as he notes, “some personalist philosophers and theologians have rejected rather sharply,” but which he shares with Aquinas. Cf.Waldstein’s “The Common Good in St.Thomas and John Paul II,” Nova et Vetera 3 (2005): 569–78. 76 “God is the common good of the entire universe and of all its parts.” Aquinas, Quodlibet I, q. 4, a. 3 (cited in Dewan, “St. Thomas and the Divinity of the Common Good,” 14). Cf. Aquinas’s commentary on Romans, In ad Roman., 1, 6 (commenting on Rm 1:20); and In Ethic., Bk. X, lect. 12. Commenting on this passage from the commentary on Romans, Dewan (“St.Thomas and the Divinity of the Common Good,” 2) writes: “Divinity signifies God’s goodness as a common good participated by all.” Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 765–778 765 Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning J OSEPH W. KOTERSKI , S.J. Fordham University Bronx, New York CAN THE USE of Natural Family Planning (NFP) to avoid pregnancy be morally justified? In discussions about the difference between NFP and contraception, one often hears the response that NFP is justifiable so long as one does not have a “contraceptive mentality.” There is something quite right about this answer, for in that case there would be something amiss with one’s basic intention.The proper method for the moral evaluation of any course of action always involves a consideration of the end of the action (finis operis), the intention of the agent (finis operantis) and the circumstances.1 Presumably what is meant by “a contraceptive mentality”2 in this context is the intention of a married couple to live out their marriage in a way that deliberately closes off their intercourse to the very 1 See Veritatis Splendor, §74; see also Catechism of the Catholic Church, §§1750, 1755–56. 2 Donald DeMarco comments on the history of the usage of this term in his article “The Contraceptive Mentality,” www.catholiculture.org/library/view.cfm?recnum =3417. Among the important sources for the term are: Stanislas de Lestapis, S.J., La limitation des naissances, 2nd ed. (Paris: Spes, 1960), 63–65, which speaks of a “contraceptive state of mind”; the “Majority Report” of the 1967 papal commission that preceded Humanae Vitae; and Elizabeth Anscombe, who noted that “the contraceptive mentality teaches that women need to be as little chaste as pagans thought men need to be,” in Contraception and Chastity (London: Catholic Truth Society, 1977). Interestingly, even the Majority Report, which argued for a change in the Church’s teaching regarding the moral permissibility of contraception in certain cases, condemned the “contraceptive mentality” as a “way of life which in its totality is egoistically and irrationally opposed to fruitfulness,” cited as “The Papal Commission Report,” in The Catholic Case for Contraception, ed. D. Callahan (Toronto: Collier-Macmillan, 1969), 159. 766 Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. possibility of procreation.What is problematic about such an intention is that it separates the inseparable meanings of intercourse within marriage, that is, its unitive and procreative dimensions.3 Regardless of the moral evaluation that we might make of the practice of NFP in general or in some specific set of the circumstances, there is reason to think that the practice of NFP with a “contraceptive mentality” is morally problematic. But presumably a couple might consider practicing NFP with an intention other than a contraceptive mentality. One might, for instance, think of morally good reasons for wanting to do so, such as spacing births a bit for the good of a mother’s health, or caring better for the sake of one’s existing children, or for the good of the marriage in a time of great pressures of some sort—these are scenarios in which a couple might remain open to any children that might come and yet might have reasons that bring them to hope that there will not be a pregnancy for a time. Is NFP in such a scenario morally justifiable? If we presume that the intention of the couple is morally acceptable here, then the issue turns to the moral evaluation of the practice—to the finis operis rather than the finis operantis. One way in which to attempt an answer to this question would be to consider whether NFP is in principle morally permissible, provided that there are morally unexceptionable motives for using it in specific circumstances. Unlike an act of contraception, where the nature of the action is morally objectionable regardless of the intentions,4 there does not seem to be anything intrinsically objectionable to the acts of intercourse themselves or to any of the actions taken in the course of deciding whether or not to have intercourse on a particular day. If spouses are using their knowledge of NFP well, their actions in preparation for and during sexual relations need be no different in those cases in which they are seeking to avoid children than in those in which they seek to have them. The difference between the two cases consists rather in the pattern of having intercourse and abstaining that the couple chooses, and this pattern exists only because of their intention. The moral quality of NFP would then need to be determined not by considering the nature of one’s acts (as in contraception) but by the ends and goals that motivate one’s free choice of a particular pattern of intermittent intercourse. The motives under discussion here seem unobjectionable. They raise no red flags about a contraceptive mentality. But what might still give one pause here is a set of background worries that one sometimes hears voiced, 3 See Humanae Vitae, §12; and Pope John Paul II, Theology of the Body: Love in the Divine Plan (Boston: Pauline Books & Media, 1997), “Reflections on Humanae Vitae,” §4. 4 See Humanae Vitae, §14. Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning 767 especially by religious people who are convinced of the goodness of raising up children for the Lord and who are convinced about the connection between the procreative and the unitive dimensions of the marital act. One might pose them thus: 1. Are we morally required to have all the children possible for us, given our current understanding of the natural rhythms of fertility? 2. Are we morally required to refrain from intercourse when we know as a couple that we are infertile? Neither of these questions is yet resolved by the answer that urges us to avoid a contraceptive mentality. It may prove helpful to think about the theological underpinnings of NFP, so as to see its justifiability beyond merely presuming this practice to be permissible so long as one does not have a contraceptive or some other morally disqualifying intention. The Writings of Father Paul Quay, S.J. Among the papers that the late Father Paul M. Quay, S.J., left at the time of his death in 1994 is an unfinished manuscript on the theology of Natural Family Planning that may help to address these questions. In cooperation with Sr. Miriam Paul (Dr. Hanna Klaus), I am presently working to bring this manuscript to completion. A year before Humanae Vitae, Quay had published an essay called “Contraception and Conjugal Love”5 that provides a splendid defense of the view that contraception contradicts not only the procreative but the unitive meaning of marriage. In many ways the relatively brief treatment given in that article to sexual intercourse as a sort of language and to contraceptive sex as a kind of lie is much like the view that Pope John Paul II would take up in his Angelus lectures on the theology of the body. Quay went on to develop his ideas at greater length in his book The Christian Meaning of Human Sexuality.6 In his posthumously published book The Mystery Hidden for Ages in God,7 one can find a thorough account of the doctrine of recapitulation in Christ that gives the larger framework. His general thesis is that Christ recapitulated in his life the whole of the life of Israel (taken together as if it were a single individual), but completing what was incomplete, perfecting what 5 Paul M. Quay, S.J., “Contraception and Conjugal Love,” Theological Studies 22 (1961): 18–40. 6 Paul M. Quay, S.J., The Christian Meaning of Human Sexuality (1985; repr., San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1988). 7 Paul M. Quay, S.J., The Mystery Hidden for Ages in God (1995; repr., New York: Peter Lang, 1998). 768 Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. was imperfect, and sanctifying what was sinful. Each Christian individual, family, and culture, in turn, needs to live in Christ and to recapitulate the life of Christ.As human beings we continue to bear the marks of the Fall, especially in the darkness of the intellect, the weakness of the will, and the distortions of our natural inclinations that are consequences of original sin, for the image of God in which we were made has been shattered. With our baptism, sanctifying grace restores the life of God within us, but coming to live and act according to His likeness requires the sacraments and other gifts of grace, so that we learn how to recapitulate the life of Christ by imitating Him at each stage of our growth. Within this general framework of recapitulation in Christ, Quay’s general approach to human sexuality and more specifically to the topic of natural family planning pays much attention to the natural and supernatural symbolism of sexuality. The mere mention of symbolism may make some people think of literature and worry that this risks reading something into biblical texts that is not there. To use such an approach successfully as a means of theological reflection depends on recognizing that not all symbols are of human invention. It would be easy to suppose that they are, given the incredible range of symbols that we human beings have devised—not only the clever symbols that poets dream up and that artists paint, but the stylized symbols of the highway department and the prosaic characters that are letters of the alphabet. Conventional signs like these involve the use of one physical object or design to represent another by means of a connection that is imposed on the sign. There is nothing, for instance, about the word “apple” (spoken or written) that resembles an apple. A picture of an apple might, I suppose, resemble the apple—unless I were the one trying to draw it! But there are natural signs as well—signs in which one physical object or event signifies something else without any human imposition of meaning: smoke is a sign of fire, certain kinds of clouds are a sign of impending rain, a baby’s cry is a sign of discomfort, and (to get closer to the point of this reflection) estrus is a sign of fertility by which the females of many animal species can alert the males that they are in heat. By contrast, human beings are the exception here.With us, sexual attraction occurs independently of the periods of fertility. Precisely because we are persons with an intellect and a will whose freedom makes us responsible for our choices, human relationships need to be mediated through spoken words and governed by properly ordering our loves. But the fact that we need to make free choices does not take away the fact there still are natural signs that operate in our lives independently of our choices.Those who have become versed in the techniques of natural family planning increas- Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning 769 ingly know how to read the cycles of temperature and of cervical fluid as signs of fertility and infertility. In addition to natural signs and conventional signs, there is also a whole world of symbolism, natural and supernatural. The distinctive connotation of “symbol” here is that the object (including events and patterns of events) that is the sign does not just point to something else on the same level.There is something in the object’s structure that makes it specially suitable to point to or mean something else on another level altogether. In fact, it is this aspect of signification that makes some physical objects particularly good symbols in literature. When the poet, for instance, say, “My love is a rose, pretty but prickly,” there is something about a rose (its loveliness, but also its thorns) that make it specially suitable for being a poetic symbol for the woman whom the poet is describing. And it is no surprise that love is frequently symbolized by fire—the inviting warmth, the fascinating flame, but also the danger of getting burnt suggests something about fire that is readily descriptive at another level altogether about human love. Human sexuality, Quay shows, manifests natural symbolisms of this sort. Sexual organs and activities not only have structures and functions at the biological level but also point to important realities in personal relationships, desires, conscious/unconscious urges, feelings, impulses, inclinations, and understandings.Without trying to make in this essay the whole case for Quay’s understanding of the symbolic structure of human sexuality, let me merely mention some examples that may help to clarify the general approach that Quay takes when reflecting on the theology of NFP. At the level of its natural symbolism, the sexual intercourse of human beings carries significance like other signs do (whether verbal, written, or iconic) as a kind of language that says various things, regardless of whether a given individual or couple is conscious of them, or prepared to say them, or even wants to deny them.The physical union of intercourse symbolizes the union of persons in a marriage.The nakedness of a couple having intercourse symbolically conveys their openness to one another and their vulnerability (not keeping anything back or hidden, but presenting oneself for the acceptance of the other, warts and all). In sexual relations bodily actions communicate various things whether we consciously affirm these meanings or not, or just do them spontaneously and without any such conscious intention, and even if we deliberately misuse them in a deceitful way, as in a seduction for some ulterior motive. The sexual activity of human beings involves so much more than the comparable activities of any other animal, precisely because there are 770 Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. persons involved, persons whose thoughts and words and choices can make their intercourse a word of love or of domination, a word of affirmation or of denigration, a word of tenderness or of indifference. In their sexual relations, do any given individuals always say by their words and their actions what they actually intend? do they really mean what their words and their actions say? do they consciously intend anything at all? When I occasionally speak on this level with the freshmen students in the dormitory where I live at Fordham, many a local Romeo and a local Juliet seem immediately to understand the distinction between what someone actually says in so many words, what one may mean (or want to say, or is thinking about possibly saying, etc.), and what one’s actions (for example, in sexual intercourse) are in fact saying. Even a Romeo who tells his Juliet of his undying affection and who truly means it may not be ready to make good on that promise, given the demands of residency, medical school, sophomore year in college, or even just final exams. At the level of supernatural symbolism, the richness of Quay’s view can be suggested by even just one passage from scripture. In Ephesians 5, husbands and wives are told to be mutually submissive to one another out of reverence for Christ.Wives are to respect and obey their husbands, like the way in which the Church should conduct herself toward Christ. Husbands are to love their wives as their own bodies and to be ready to sacrifice themselves for their wives, as Christ did for the Church. For in the relation of husband and wife we see the mystery of Christ and His Church. From the supernatural symbolism used in this passage Quay draws a number of the implications: • Just as the Lord would never seek another bride, and the Church should never seek another Lord, so too adultery is gravely wrong. • Just as the Lord will never seek another man like himself but dedicates himself to his bride, and the Church should never seek another bride but give herself entirely to this Bridegroom, so too human beings should never enter into homosexual relations. • Just as Christ the Bridegroom and his bride the Church await the marriage feast of Heaven, so too human beings should await their marriage and not engage in premarital intercourse. • Just as Christ does not strive to please himself, but should be ready to die to render His spouse pure and spotless (unlike Adam, who joined his bride in sin), so no human being should masturbate, or try to dominate one’s spouse, but should love that spouse in a way that will help that spouse to grow in holiness. Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning 771 Nor is Quay’s approach limited to showing why certain practices would necessarily be inauthentic for reflecting the relations between Christ and his bride the Church and thus for knowing what is good and right for human beings. Much of his study is devoted to showing how God has inspired the writers of Scripture to use sexuality symbolically for displaying certain things that we need to know about the mystery of God in himself and about his plans for the Church. The prophet Hosea, for instance, uses human marriage as a symbol for the covenant that God made with Israel, and Paul uses that same imagery to have us understand the relation between the Church and Christ. The Application of Quay’s Understanding to NFP What does all of this have to say about natural family planning? If we grant that human marriage symbolically points to something about the love between Christ and His Church, then the practice of NFP for the avoidance of children would, at least at first glance, appear to be gravely evil.The task of the Church on this earth is presumably (with due respect for human freedom) to bring as many souls to live in Christ as she can. How could the Church ever stand in the position of being unwilling to bear such children? It would seem that any use of NFP to avoid children would contradict the basic symbolism by which sexual activity, seen in light of the supernatural symbolism, points to a need always to stand ready for bearing new children in the Lord. Presumably, couples could only use NFP so as to have as many children as possible. Such problems require careful reflection on the structures of human fertility as well as on their natural and supernatural meanings, so as to discern the moral rightness or wrongness of specific patterns of sexual activity that makes use of the sort of knowledge that NFP brings. It would be all too easy to mistake the images being employed for the meaning to which they point. It would be all too easy to suppose that the Scriptures show us Christ and the Church as if already husband and wife, with the baptized as their children. But in fact, Christ is not our Father, and he has not begotten the children of the Church through the Seed that is the Holy Spirit. Christ is the Son of the Father, and not anyone’s Father. Revelation does not show him having entered into a generative union with his bride. Rather, the baptized are the Father’s adopted children, the sisters and brothers of Christ. This caution allows us to see that the Church should indeed have as many children as possible, but there is no need to bring the largest possible number of children into this world. The task, rather, is to bring all those who are naturally born to be reborn of water and the Holy Spirit from the womb of the Church by baptism. 772 Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. For the resolution of the problem, it is crucial to remember that the espousal of Christ and the Church is not the Bible’s only use of the symbolism of human sexuality. The espousal texts focus on the type of love found between Christ and the Church. In a way, this corresponds to the tenderness, generosity, and loveliness that is common between the engaged but that sometimes fades in human marriages. In the best ones, the idea remains as model of what the couple wants to preserve, even as they come to learn how their love needs to be deepened over time.While children are not expressly mentioned in these texts, they are prominent in other scriptural uses of sexual symbolism that are concerned with motherhood and with adoptive fatherhood. In Isaiah (1:2, 4), for instance, God speaks of the tribe of Judah as children whom he has reared despite the fact that they are the sinful sons of wicked people: “The LORD has spoken: ‘Sons have I reared and brought up. . . .’ Ah, sinful nation, offspring of evildoers, sons who deal corruptly!” While their biological generation is recognized to come from their human parents, these people are God’s children by adoption. Isaiah 29:33 (“When [Jacob] sees his children, the work of my hands, in his midst, they will sanctify my name”) treats the sons begotten by Jacob as the people that he has formed for himself and thus the work of his hands. One could recount others passages in the same vein (43:5–7, 21; 44:21; 45:11; 50:1). Correlated with God’s adoptive fatherhood is Israel’s motherhood, for it is the task of Israel, God’s people, to bear children for him. Hosea (that is, 1:10; 2: 2, 4, 5) and Ezekiel point to the link between the symbolism of fatherhood/motherhood and the symbolism of husband and wife, for example:“The LORD says,‘You took your sons and your daughters, whom you had borne to me, and these you sacrificed to them [to idols] to be devoured . . . , you slaughtered my children’ ” (Ez 16:20–21; see 23:4, 37).The individuals who were born naturally to their human parents only became God’s children by his espousal to Jerusalem, their mother. Similar sexual symbolisms are used in the New Testament, but the relationships grow more complex with the revelation that God is not just Father but Son and Holy Spirit—one God in three distinct Persons. Only one is Father, and there is only one Son whom he has begotten naturally, his eternal Word, Jesus Christ ( Jn 1:1–5, 18). All God’s other children only become his children by being reborn as children of the Church, whom Christ espoused by the sacrifice of the New Covenant on the Cross (Eph 5:25–27).We become children of the Church through reception of the word of God by faith. But Christ is not said to beget children of his Church, and the Church can only give us life supernaturally by the gift of the Holy Spirit, not by natural generation (see Gal 4:26–27, with Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning 773 echoes of Is 54:1, and Rom 8:15). A man’s love for his wife, whether she be fertile at the moment or not, should be taken to symbolize Christ’s love for his Church, which never fails, whether she is bearing new children for the Father at any particular time or not. Natural birth to Christian parents does not make anyone a Christian.We are born into a world of sin, outside of the Church and afflicted by the consequences of the Fall. But we are reborn as Christians through water and the Holy Spirit. Paradoxically, since the Church is not only his Body and his Bride but also the new Israel and the People of God, the newly (re)born Christian becomes part of the Church by becoming one of God’s People, just as a child generated from the physical union of its parents thereby comes to be a member of the family into which that child has been born. There is significance to the fact that Christ leaves his espoused Bride a virgin who brings forth the members of his body virginally, for it is by the power of the Holy Spirit who has been given to her that the Church bears us.The Holy Spirit was the agent of the Father’s begetting of the human nature of his Son in the virginal Mary, and is likewise the agent of our regeneration as children of the Church, so that we can truly be said ( Jn 3:9) to be born of the Spirit. In fact, it is only after the resurrection of Christ that he spoke of his disciples as his brothers.8 By his sacrifice and victory on the Cross, he won the Church as his bride. At Pentecost his disciples became her first-born, and we who have come later are his brothers and sisters, not because the Father has begotten any Sons other than Jesus but because he has shared with us the life of his Only-Begotten Son (Gal 3:26–27). All the children of God except for Jesus are adopted (Gal 4:5–6; Rom 8: 14–16, 23, 29–30; Heb 2:10–17). But unlike human adoption, this adoption actually bestows a share in the very life of the adoptive Father by the gift of the Holy Spirit (1 Jn; Jn 3:3–8; Eph 1:5). Quay also finds a certain support for this view at the level of natural symbolism, from the hiddenness of conception, which we now recognize to be distinct from an act of intercourse. Upon the discovery of a pregnancy, there is a need for a free and right response from those who have begotten a child to accept and nurture the child who has begun to grow within his mother. Quay reads the natural symbolism here as a kind of adoption, that is, an acceptance of the child into the family, and he speculates that there may be a certain significance to the fact that the gametes or sex cells involved in generation operate independently of the will or actions of those having sexual intercourse.The gametes are formed in the bodies of adults and depend on these bodies to be able to live, but they are actually 8 A point also made by Joseph Ratzinger in The Meaning of Christian Brotherhood (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993). 774 Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. independent organisms. Each of them lives with its own life and not with the life of the person within whose body the new organism has been formed in the way that the cells that make up our bodies do. In this respect, it is possible to grasp, far more clearly than earlier ages could, that when a child is conceived, it has not been “created,” even unconsciously, by its parents.The time of their sexual relations does determine whether it is even possible for the gametes to meet; but whether the gametes do actually unite is not even under the scrutiny, let alone the control of human volition (except, of course, for laboratory IVF). Strictly speaking, the new child’s conception has not been brought about by their will as some object that they have made, and therefore it is not something owned by them. Its actualization, even biologically, is not their doing. On this point Quay notes that the evil of in vitro fertilization (IVF) consists in its rejection (and attempted denial) of this latter fact, for IVF treats the gametes (and implicitly the child that results) as if they were parts of the parents or as if they totally belonged to the parents for their existence and for their goals. Contraception also gets this wrong by treating the gametes as some sort of foreign bodies, alien to each of the couple (or as totally dependent on the individuals), since they can be blocked and disposed of at will. IVF thus reflects symbolically a technological will to make a child, regardless of what happens to the marital union in the context of which it takes place, regardless of what happens to the zygote if “things don’t work out,” regardless of the consequent expectations laid upon the child that has been so made on the basis of the implied ownership, and, above all, regardless of the radically altered understanding of what it is to be human that is implicit in the making process. In fact, children are begotten through the creative act of God, not made as items of property desired by their parents. At the supernatural level we need to be adopted by God the Father, but at the natural level too we are begotten and conceived by parents who must, in one sense, adopt us.The child thus formed from gametic union is an independent entity, distinct from both parents, but (considered symbolically) it is utterly dependent. A child’s every trait and entire genetic endowment comes from his parents, half from his father and half from his mother.As human persons, new children are like brothers and sisters to their parents, except displaced from them in time.Yet, whenever the union of the gametes results in a healthy zygote, a new genetic type is formed, one that was hitherto non-existent. Even though a child’s physical qualities may be familiar on either or both sides of the family, they are in aggregate wholly new. But more, this person is, in a far stronger sense, wholly new. Although sharing in the personal properties of its lineage, the child remains an individual who has his own destiny. The child is not the genetic replica of any of its forebears but Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning 775 constitutes a new human type.Those of its problems that are rooted in its genes (whether the standard types of genetic disease, or some genetic predispositions to other diseases or certain traits of temperament, or various patterns and intensities of feeling and emotion) may be unique to it, or at least not shared with its family.The child that has been conceived (as zygote, as embryo, or as fetus) depends wholly on its mother’s body for its sustenance and protection.And while each parent provides a single gamete, an equality that symbolizes the gift of an equal genetic component to this new child, the size and structure of the contributions differ. Once the generation has taken place, everything else that the child needs of a material nature for its growth and development is supplied by its mother: food, elimination of waste, warmth, physical protection, suitable environment, and so on. And yet this newly conceived child is an entity that is radically distinct from the mother in whose womb it lives. In principle, the child can be separated from her completely and still survive (that is, insofar as it is possible to substitute artificially for her nurturing activities). But a bonding begins in utero, and separation from one’s mother can mean the stunting of psychological development, for the child in the womb is already in the womb responding to stimuli from her. At sixteen weeks, for instance, an unborn child already has ears that are developed far enough to hear its mother’s voice, and it can already feel its mother’s movements. Seen in this way, at both the natural and the supernatural levels there is a hiddenness to the cycles and to the actualizations of fertility. The precise manner of conception is as imperceptible to the human eye as is grace working in a soul, for the Lord is one who acts in secret and, as 1 Timothy suggests, one who “dwells in unapproachable light, whom no man has ever seen or can see” (1 Tim 6:16). What NFP relies upon, of course, is the presence of cycles of fertility, and these too, with careful discernment, bear a natural symbolism of great importance, and one that has parallels in the supernatural order.The infertile periods are not sterility, but periods in which a woman’s body rests and prepares for the next ovum to be released. She neither knows nor controls the genetic complement of that ovum. Neither does a man know or control the genetic complement of any of the sperm contained in his seed. Curiously, any number of the ancient nature religions connected the cycles of the year with human fertility and devised rituals that begged their gods for fruitfulness in their fields and in their families. Some of these rituals seem to suggest an attempt to control the outcome, and in this way are not unlike what happens when IVF (let alone the technologies under preparation to produce designer babies) tries to bring to light and to put under our control what is naturally, and quite likely by divine design, kept hidden from human eyes. 776 Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. At the natural level, we need to take note of the biological values of the biological rhythms of fertility, for the rest that it gives to a mother’s body. One of the most obvious regulative goods in this domain is this natural spacing of pregnancies, which is such that a nursing mother is highly unlikely to become pregnant again during the period when her young baby needs the strength of her body for the nourishment that she provides by her nursing. Although the love between the spouses is expressed positively by intercourse, it can also be expressed by refraining from intercourse for the good of the other spouse. It is clearly the case that many of the goods that must be sought by any couple during their fertile times will exclude simultaneously having sexual relations.There is the good of life itself, for the couple—and any children for whom they may already be responsible—need to eat and sleep.The parents clearly need to work, so as to earn what is needed for the family, to keep the home in order, to prepare meals, to take care of the sick, not only each other and their children, but their own parents and relatives and also their neighbors. Refraining from sexual relations might be needed for the sake of the common good, not only of their own family but of their community and their country. The love between the spouses can call for abstinence from intercourse for the sake of each of the characteristic “goods of marriage.”When one’s spouse is sick or absent, for instance, one must refrain from sexual relations for the sake of the basic good of mutual fidelity. Similarly, the indissolubility of their marriage could well be threatened if one forces the other to have relations (for example, a drunken husband or one who is trying to force contraceptive intercourse upon the other).And perhaps most importantly, abstinence may be needed for the sake of the third good of marriage, their children (already born or, in some circumstances, those hoped for). And there are countless occasions when a couple will rightly refrain from having relations, for example, when very tired, or when traveling and forced to spend the night without private accommodations, or when one of them is emotionally upset by a death among kin or by a quarrel, and so on. Presumably, no special consideration with regard to fertility enters into decisions of these kinds. Further, spousal love might also require intermittent abstinence for prayer (see 1 Cor 7:5–6), or in exceptional cases, even of permanent abstinence, as in the case of virginal marriages, which are, in principle, acceptable to the Church.9 9 The reasons are far from clear to most people—but most people are not called to such a life.What is involved is, in traditional language, the conceding of a right to coitus to one another, supplemented with a solemn agreement and pledge that neither party will make use of this right. Theological Reflections on Natural Family Planning 777 The Question at Hand To return, then, to the general question of this essay.What we have seen is that there are solid theological underpinnings in the natural and supernatural symbolisms of human fertility and conception for the practice of natural family planning.As noted at the beginning of the paper, the moral quality of a specific use of NFP is determined wholly by a specific couple’s motives and the relations of these motives to the natural meaning of intercourse and to the particular pattern of relations that they are choosing. The reason that we can affirm this point is that the cycle of fertility is good, and the employment of the natural activities of the body for good ends is good. Properly practiced, NFP is one manifestation of spousal love as a way to acknowledge in action the intrinsic limits to fertility. In this particular way, it can symbolize the love of Christ for his Church and hers for him. Needless to say, this judgment does not exempt a couple from their obligation to a complete openness to children in every act of intercourse, especially during the fertile times, since sexual relations at such times are, ordinarily, the necessary and sufficient condition for fertilization. What lies at the end of any causal chain is morally the initiator’s responsibility if he knows (or ought to know) of its nature N&V in advance. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 779–800 779 Original Sin and the Anthropological Principles of Humanae Vitae M ATTHEW L EVERING Ave Maria University Ave Maria, Florida I N Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body, Pope John Paul II develops Humanae Vitae’s insights regarding embodied human personhood.1 In particular, John Paul points to the difficulty of “maintaining the adequate relationship between that which is defined as ‘domination . . . of the forces of nature’ (HV, §2) and ‘self-mastery’ (HV, §21). . . . Contemporary man shows the tendency of transferring the methods proper to the first sphere to those of the second.”2 This tendency could be averted, he suggests, by means of a deeper appreciation of the body’s teleological ordering, which he calls the “language of the body.”3 Original sin has distorted this language, turning the “relationship of reciprocal gift . . . into a relationship of reciprocal appropriation.”4 This distortion has not wholly corrupted the body’s language, however. The body remains ontologically “oriented from within by the ‘sincere gift’ [Gaudium et Spes, §24] of the person.”5 Because of human body-soul unity, human bodily and spiritual teleology constitute a unity. 1 See John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books and Media, 2006). For further discussion see John M. Grondelski, “Karol Wojtyla on Humanae vitae,” Angelicum 81 (2004): 51–63. 2 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 630–31 (General Audience of August 22, 1984). For investigation of the roots of this situation as regards contemporary bioethics, see Vincent Bourguet, “Bioéthique et dualisme ontologique,” Revue Thomiste 97 (1997): 619–39. 3 Cf. John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 631. 4 Ibid., 260 (General Audience of July 30, 1980). 5 Ibid., 188 (General Audience of January 16, 1980). 780 Matthew Levering Like Humanae Vitae, John Paul’s presentation of the “language of the body” has persuaded relatively few. In the fallen world, the body seems so often to speak the language of “appropriation” rather than “gift,” the latter seeming to be the province of the spirit.The human spirit’s capacity for intelligence and freedom seems to be the source of hope for liberation from the tyrannical structures instantiated by bodiliness as we experience it in our lives. By technologically mastering the body, we hope to produce a world of physical and emotional fulfillment, rather than of physical and emotional pain. Thus theological dissenters from Humanae Vitae generally appeal to progress in “physical, economic, psychological, and social conditions” (HV, §10).As the encyclical observes,“It is also asked whether, in view of the increased sense of responsibility of modern man, the moment has not come for him to entrust to his reason and his will, rather than to the biological rhythms of his organism, the task of regulating birth” (§3).6 Because of this association of bodiliness with oppression, the role of the body has become suspect not only with respect to the moral life, but also with respect to the theology of the Cross, sacramental theology, eschatology, and so forth. The interconnectedness of doctrine thus requires that Humanae Vitae be discussed in the context of other central Christian doctrines.7 As a step in this direction, the present essay explores the links 6 Humanae Vitae goes on to note that “the Church is the first to praise and recom- mend the intervention of intelligence in a function which so closely associates the rational creature with his Creator; but she affirms that this must be done with respect to the order established by God” (§16). Quoting from Gaudium et Spes, §§52 and 51, the encyclical also offers “encouragement to men of science, who ‘can considerably advance the welfare of marriage and the family, along with peace of conscience, if by pooling their efforts they labor to explain more thoroughly the various conditions favoring a proper regulation of births.’ It is particularly desirable that, according to the wish already expressed by Pope Pius XII, medical science succeed in providing a sufficiently secure basis for a regulation of birth, founded on the observance of natural rhythms. In this way, scientists and especially Catholic scientists will contribute to demonstrate in actual fact that, as the Church teaches, ‘a true contradiction cannot exist between the divine laws pertaining to the transmission of life and those pertaining to the fostering of authentic conjugal love’ ” (§24, cf. §27). 7 David Matzo McCarthy argues that Humanae Vitae “is a statement about the very meaning of our nature and the continuity of our natural life with our supernatural fulfillment.The encyclical is not an argument from nature as much as a proposal about our nature from the givens of our true end.To speak of nature in this way is to make a claim about what binds us in human solidarity” (McCarthy,“Procreation, the Development of Peoples, and the Final Destiny of Humanity,” Communio 26 [1999]: 698).This teleological understanding of nature enables McCarthy to describe natural law not as “generated from a disinterested, general point of view Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 781 between Humanae Vitae and the doctrine of original sin. After first summarizing the principles of Humanae Vitae, I examine in detail Thomas Aquinas’s account of Adam and Eve’s sin, especially as regards soul-body unity. I suggest that the the doctrine of original sin and the teaching of Humanae Vitae rely upon the same anthropological principles. The Anthropology of Humanae Vitae Humanae Vitae argues that “one must necessarily recognize insurmountable limits to the possibility of man’s domination over his own body and its functions” (§17). Earlier the encyclical states that to make use of the gift of conjugal love while respecting the laws of the generative process means to acknowledge oneself not to be the arbiter of the sources of human life, but rather the minister of the design established by the Creator. In fact, just as man does not have unlimited dominion over his body in general, so also, with particular reason, he has no such dominion over his generative faculties as such, because of their intrinsic ordination towards raising up life, of which God is the principle. (§13) But, one might ask, what does it mean to say that human beings have only a limited dominion over their “generative faculties as such, because of their intrinsic ordination towards raising up life”? Why should human freedom be limited by an “intrinsic ordination” belonging to the body’s generative faculties? The encyclical’s answer is that although human rationality frees human beings to choose how to “use” our bodies, our bodies are not mere instruments. Just as the soul has an innate teleological ordering toward truth and goodness (a teleology that can, to varying degrees, be frustrated), so also the body has an “intrinsic ordination” toward “raising up life.” This “intrinsic ordination” is not something that the human spirit freely elicits in the body through an act of humanization. On the other hand, neither is this “intrinsic ordination” uninformed by the soul. Instead, the ordination of (in Kantian fashion)” but as “an account of human solidarity in terms of God as beginning and end” that therefore “depends (whether explicitly or not) upon an understanding of human unity in creation and our eschatological communion” (ibid., 716). By contrast, a contraceptive culture orders itself toward consumption rather than toward the communion of persons (most fully and concretely expressed in hospitality to children). McCarthy’s article shows the value of reading Humanae Vitae in the broader context of human fulfillment, to which context original sin (as the distortion of such fulfillment) belongs. For work in a similar direction, see Richard R. Roach,“More than Integration:The CTSA Report on Human Sexuality,” Communio 5 (1978): 182–201. 782 Matthew Levering the body accords with the soul’s teleological ordering thanks to the work of God in creating human body-soul unity. This approach undergirds Humanae Vitae’s insistence upon “the inseparable connection, willed by God and unable to be broken by man on his own initiative, between the two meanings of the conjugal act: the unitive meaning and the procreative meaning” (§12). Paul VI explains that “the conjugal act, while most closely uniting husband and wife, capacitates them for the generation of new lives” (§12). It “capacitates” husband and wife not in a sense that applies only to fertile couples, but “according to laws inscribed in the very being of man and of woman” (§12), whether or not they at the time have the capacity for fertility. These “laws” that capacitate human beings “for the generation of new lives” belong to the body’s teleology. The “inseparable connection” between the unitive and procreative aspects of the conjugal act results from the inseparability of the body’s teleology from that of the soul. In the conjugal act, spiritual (unitive) self-giving and bodily (procreative) self-giving are joined. It follows that as regards Paul VI’s affirmation that “each and every marriage act [quilibet matrimonii usus] must remain open to the transmission of life” (§11), this openness cannot be that of the soul over against the body. Likewise the unity of spiritual and bodily teleology enables one to understand Paul VI’s appeal to the notion of the “gift of self.” As Paul VI states, this love is total, that is to say, it is a very special form of personal friendship, in which husband and wife generously share everything, without undue reservations or selfish calculations. Whoever truly loves his marriage partner loves not only for what he receives, but for the partner’s self, rejoicing that he can enrich his partner with the gift of himself. (§9) By contrast, the rejection of Humanae Vitae flows from a view of the body as proto-human.8 Russell Hittinger points out that the pro-birth 8 Paul VI writes, “It can be foreseen that this teaching will perhaps not be easily received by all:Too numerous are those voices—amplified by the modern means of propaganda—which are contrary to the voice of the Church.To tell the truth, the Church is not surprised to be made, like her divine founder, a ‘sign of contradiction,’ yet she does not because of this cease to proclaim with humble firmness the entire moral law, both natural and evangelical. Of such laws the Church was not the author, nor consequently can she be their arbiter; she is only their depositary and their interpreter, without ever being able to declare to be licit that which is not so by reason of its intimate and unchangeable opposition to the true good of man” (HV, §18). Sensitive to the charge that the Church thereby impedes the human progress allegedly made possible by contraceptive sexual intercourse, the encyclical goes on to say, “In defending conjugal morals in their integral wholeness, the Church knows that she contributes towards the establishment of a truly Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 783 control argument of the Majority Report of Paul VI’s Commission hinges on this negative view of body, behind which stands a longstanding debate about “the scope of human dominion in the light of Genesis and natural law.”9 Quoting the Majority Report, Hittinger observes: The majority argued that “what is given in physical nature” reflects an order of dynamisms and processes that it is the duty of human agents to “humanize and bring to greater perfection.” . . .The majority averred that the inherent finalities, which Genesis says are “good,” permit us to conclude that their negation is a “physical evil.” But the humanization of nature can permit, and perhaps require, a negation of pre-moral goods for the affirmation of what is specifically human in marriage.10 As Hittinger goes on to show, this depreciation of “ ‘what is given in physical nature’ ” fits within the Enlightenment evacuation of normative content from the notion of “human nature.” For the various versions of Enlightenment “negative anthropology,” human nature can only be known in its “proto-human” material, which then “must be tamed, shaped, and humanized.”11 Unable to arrive at a normative endpoint, this humanization of the body ensures that “human nature” cannot be reified beyond history’s human civilization; she engages man not to abdicate from his own responsibility in order to rely on technical means; by that very fact she defends the dignity of man and wife” (ibid.). 9 Russell Hittinger, “Human Nature and States of Nature in John Paul II’s Theological Anthropology,” in Human Nature in Its Wholeness:A Roman Catholic Perspective, eds. Daniel N. Robinson, Gladys M. Sweeney, and Richard Gill, L.C. (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2006), 22. 10 Ibid. 11 Ibid., 18. See also Michael Waldstein’s introduction to his translation of John Paul II’s Man and Woman He Created Them, 1–128, where Waldstein remarks of the project of Francis Bacon: “Authority over nature belonged to the human race before the fall, and it is to this primeval condition that Bacon intends to return, undoing the consequences of the fall as far as possible” (ibid., 37). Drawing upon the work of Charles Taylor, Waldstein goes on to point out that late-medieval nominalism “eliminated from nature precisely those features that resist its subjection to power, namely, a strong teleology and formal causality” (ibid., 38). Regarding the majority report, Waldstein points out the same problem as does Hittinger: “The ‘Majority Report’ of Paul VI’s birth control commission (intentionally leaked to the press in 1967) is unequivocal in its support for the Baconian program, unequivocal in identifying this program with the divine will. ‘The story of God and of man, therefore, should be seen as a shared work. And it should be seen that man’s tremendous progress in control of matter by technical means and the universal and total “intercommunication” that has been achieved, correspond entirely to the divine decrees.’ It would be difficult to formulate a more unqualified allegiance with the Baconian program” (ibid., 100). 784 Matthew Levering fluid “experimental constructions of what is indeterminate in the original of nature.”12 On this view, the rational powers of the human person remain always free to construct anew what it means to be human, unimpeded by the bodily mechanisms that natural science studies. The implication is that the Creator made human bodiliness so that human rationality could re-make it in accord with the demands of rational freedom. It follows that the teleological ordering that belongs to the human body is disjoined from the human spirit’s free dynamisms. Against this disjunction, Humanae Vitae affirms the unity of spiritual and bodily teleology in the human person. The encyclical refuses to split the body’s “intrinsic ordination” from that of the spiritual powers of the human person. At the ontological level, the soul does not have to claim the body for God through “humanization.” Rather, the “intrinsic ordination” of the body forms a unity with that of the soul in the self-giving movement of love. Far from being impediments, human bodily structures are instructive in the task of understanding human fulfillment. Either the Creator made the human being as a body-soul unity, or the “human” is the realm of rational freedom that operates above and upon a proto-human substratum of bodiliness. Humanae Vitae opts for the former alternative. Adam and Eve’s Sin What is the relationship of soul and body in the doctrine of original sin? The Catechism of the Catholic Church emphasizes original sin’s character as 12 Hittinger, “Human Nature and States of Nature in John Paul II’s Theological Anthropology,” 19. Hittinger adds that “the anthropologies that assign man dominion over proto-human material are not merely a curious chapter of the Enlightenment. It is true that for thinkers such as Hobbes, Rousseau, Kant, and Feuerbach the state-of-nature scenarios were devised for a purpose of showing the basis of the civilizing mission of the state.The transition from animal to man, from laws of nature to the sovereignty of law, correlate with the movement from pre-political to citizen. Here, we can pass over the interesting question of how the ‘state of nature’ could prepare the way for such different programs of political power, from class dictatorships to republican regimes.The key point for our purposes is that after the Second World War the myth of origins was released from its earlier function of justifying the state, and turned toward the sovereignty of the individual. . . . Given the radical indeterminacy of human nature, the Enlightenment theorists tended to conclude, all the more reason for the civilizing task of the state; the contemporary mind concludes, all the more reason for individual liberty. As the French philosopher Pierre Manent puts it, human nature is a cipher, an ‘efficacious indetermination’ allowing a zone of liberty in which the individual can ‘affirm himself without knowing himself.’ ” Ibid., 20, citing Manent’s The City of Man, trans. Marc A. LePain (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998), 129. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 785 an active spiritual deformation: “man preferred himself to God and by that very act scorned him. He chose himself over and against God, against the requirements of his creaturely status and therefore against his own good” (§398).According to the Catechism, however, this spiritual frustration of the teleology of the human creature is inseparable from the frustration of the telos of human bodiliness: “the control of the soul’s spiritual faculties over the body is shattered; the union of man and woman becomes subject to tensions, their relations henceforth marked by lust and domination” (§400). Original sin causes not only spiritual death but also bodily death, which here “makes its entrance into human history” (§400). While the Catechism focuses its attention on Genesis, the inseparability of spiritual and bodily teleological frustration appears throughout Scripture, most notably perhaps in the Letter to the Romans:“Therefore God gave them up in the lusts of their hearts to impurity, to the dishonoring of their bodies among themselves, because they exchanged the truth about God for a lie and worshiped and served the creature rather than the Creator” (Rom 1:24–25). As Gary Anderson observes, 1 Corinthians and Romans develop a Christian theology of Adam and Eve’s sin.13 The Old Testament, Anderson points out, gives central place not to Adam and Eve’s sin (referred to only once more in the Old Testament, Ezekiel 28) but to the Israelites’ worship of the golden calf (Exodus 32). Genesis 2:7 states that “the Lord God formed man of dust from the ground, and breathed into his nostrils the breath of life; and man became a living being.”The word “man” here is ’adam, from the word for the ground, ’adamah.After the creation of the woman, the collective term ’adam becomes the name of the first man, Adam. St. Paul draws especially upon the collective sense of ’adam. As Anderson explains, “If the first (protos) Adam died . . . then all must die through him. Since Christ was the second or final (eschatos) Adam, his death and resurrection must also have had universal dimensions.”14 Paul 13 Gary A. Anderson, The Genesis of Perfection: Adam and Eve in Jewish and Christian Imagination (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2001), 209 (app. A). Following Joseph Blenkinsopp,Anderson comments,“Indeed it is difficult not to see the influence of a theology very similar to that of Deuteronomy. For in that book God sets life and death before the Israelites and the choice is theirs: Obey my Torah and you shall have life in the land; disobey it and you shall die in exile. Eden is Torah in miniature. . . . By placing the story of Adam and eve after the creation account of P, the editor of Torah has said something very profound about the propensity of human nature toward disobedience” (ibid., 208). As Anderson concludes, “What is revealed in microcosm through the nation Israel can be extended, in macrocosm, to all peoples” (ibid., 210). 14 Ibid., 210.Anderson remarks,“If Paul were to look solely at the central Old Testament narratives about Israel’s proclivity for sin and rebellion, he would not be able 786 Matthew Levering contrasts Jesus’ Resurrection with Adam’s sin: “For as by a man came death, by a man has come also the resurrection of the dead. For as in Adam all die, so also in Christ shall all be made alive” (1 Cor 15:21–22). In Romans 5:12 Paul likewise understands Adam in this collective sense. Given this background, let us turn to Thomas Aquinas’s theology of original sin.To understand what the created order is and how it can be healed— the goal of both the opponents and the proponents of Humanae Vitae—we need to reflect further upon what ails the human creature. Pride or Concupiscence? Aquinas considers Adam and Eve’s first sin to have been the sin of pride. Before arguing for his position, however, he sets forth four alternative construals of the first sin.15 The first alternative has its roots in Paul’s letter to the Romans: “For as by one man’s disobedience many were made sinners, so by one man’s obedience many will be made righteous” (Rom 5:19). It would seem, then, that disobedience, not pride, constituted the first sin. A second alternative is the sin of curiosity, because “the serpent” tempted Adam and Eve by promising that “you will be like God, knowing good and evil” (Gen 3:5), so that they came to think that “the tree was to be desired to make one wise” (Gen 3:6).Third is the sin of unbelief, because Adam and Eve were “deceived” (1 Tim 2:14) or “beguiled” (Gen 3:13) to think of God as selfish, and thus as a mere god rather than as the true good God. Fourth is the sin of gluttony, not merely because “the woman saw that the tree was good for food” and “took of its fruit and ate” (Gen 3:6), but also and more importantly because “the devil in tempting Christ observed the same order as in overcoming the first man. Now Christ was first tempted to gluttony, as appears from Matthew 4:3, where it was said to Him: ‘If thou be the Son of God, command that these stones be made bread.’ ”16 Of these four alternatives to pride, three have their root in human spiritual powers, whereas one—gluttony—has its root in sense appetites. In explaining his view that pride was Adam and Eve’s sin, Aquinas observes that “man was so appointed in the state of innocence, that there was no rebellion of the flesh against the spirit.”17 Recall St. Paul’s complaint,“So I find it to be a law that when I want to do right, evil lies close at hand. to say much about the state of the Gentiles. Paul’s turn to the figure of Adam as the parade example of a biblical sinner is not in accord with the basic thrust of the Old Testament” (ibid.). 15 Summa theologiae II–II, q. 163, a. 1, obj. 1–4. 16 Ibid., obj. 2. 17 ST II–II, q. 163, a. 1. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 787 For I delight in the law of God, in my inmost self, but I see in my members another law at war with the law of my mind and making me captive to the law of sin which dwells in my members” (Rom 7:21–23). Aquinas affirms that original sin brings about this “rebellion of the flesh against the spirit,” so that with Paul we experience “the law of sin which dwells in my members.” Does this mean, then, that original sin has more to do with the bodily appetites than with the spiritual powers? Indeed, in the prima secundae, Aquinas defines original sin not as pride but as “concupiscence,” which is indeed rooted in the bodily (concupiscible) powers of the soul. He explains that this definition has to do with the “material” aspect of original sin as a privation in human beings. Employing Aristotelian terminology, he notes that when original sin is considered as to its cause—which exposes its “formal” aspect, its “species” or the kind of reality that it is—then one must begin with the original justice whose opposite is “original sin.” Original justice may well seem mythological, since we cannot observe it empirically. The philosopher Daniel Dennett, for example, traces human problems to an “Original Sin” caused not by human agency but by “the first macromolecules that have enough complexity to ‘do things.’ ”18 These macromolecules unconsciously made the first “mistake,” a “copying mistake” in the code of life.The eventual product of such “copying mistakes” is the human person, who gradually comes into existence 18 Daniel C. Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995), 203 and 202. Dennett emphasizes that while there seems to be an extraordinary amount of design and natural teleology involved, in fact there is none:“There is something alien and vaguely repellent about the quasi-agency we discover at this level—all that purposive hustle and bustle, and yet there’s nobody home. The molecular machines perform their amazing stunts, obviously exquisitely designed, and just as obviously none the wiser about what they are doing” (ibid., 202). Once the “molecular machines” begin to function, then they can function badly—but even the word “function” seems to Dennett to import a false notion of teleological purpose: “Exactly the same gratuitous predicament faces anyone who, despairing of defining something as complicated as life, decides to define the apparently simpler notion of function or teleology. At exactly what point does function make its appearance? Did the very first nucleotides have functions, or did they just have causal powers? Did Cairns-Smith’s clay crystals exhibit genuine teleological properties, or just ‘as if ’ teleological properties? Do gliders in the Life world have the function of locomotion, or do they just move? It doesn’t make any difference how you legislate the answer; the interesting world of functioning mechanisms has to start with mechanisms that ‘straddle the line,’ and, however far back you place the line, there will be precursors that differ in arguably nonessential ways from the anointed ones” (ibid., 201). One might respond that this means that there will be teleology all the way down. 788 Matthew Levering filled with all sorts of encoded deficiencies.19 In Dennett’s view there is no “original justice,” but instead only a period of time in which “no opportunity for error existed” because there was no genetic copying. By contrast, Aquinas would point out that these macromolecules were not engaged in anything that could be called “sin.” Instead, as Aquinas states, the first human beings possessed a will that was already, by its very ontological constitution, drawn toward the good. So long as they did not choose created goods over the infinite good, they had not yet sinned: and in this state of “original justice,” God gave them unique gifts, so that they could not crumble spiritually or physically except by freely disordering themselves. They did so. Aquinas observes that the whole order of original justice consists in man’s will being subject to God: which subjection, first and chiefly, was in the will, whose function it is to move all the other parts to the end, as stated above (I–II, q. 9, a. 1), so that the will being turned away from God, all the other powers of the soul become inordinate.20 This sounds complicated but in fact is not, since examples of harmonious organisms breaking down are commonplace. Think of the smoothly running classroom that falls apart without the teacher, or the well-tended flock that dissipates without the shepherd.The body-soul person is made to be a harmonious organism: the rational appetite forms a unity with the sense appetites or passions, which operate on the borderline between rational and non-rational. The passions assist the rational appetite in attaining desired ends (the concupiscible passions) and avoiding undesirable ends (the irascible passions). Every movement of the rational appetite is accompanied by movement of the appropriate passions. The breakdown occurs when the rational appetite chooses against reason and thereby cannot govern the sense appetites in accord with reason. The rational appetite and the sense appetites then experience the same problem: their volition, which takes place together, is “inordinate,” misdirected. In this condition, the human person desires created goods as if they were the uncreated good, and pursues them with unruly concupis19 Dennett states, “Love it or hate it, phenomena like this exhibit the heart of the power of the Darwinian idea.An impersonal, unreflective, robotic, mindless little scrap of molecular machinery is the ultimate basis of all the agency, and hence meaning, and hence consciousness, in the universe” (ibid., 203). He intends to divorce the “little scrap of molecular machinery” which is the source of all meaning and consciousness, from any notion of a Creator. 20 ST I–II, q. 82, a. 3. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 789 cible and irascible appetites. Original sin therefore is not “concupiscence” per se, but rather it is concupiscence “so far as it trespasses beyond the bounds of reason.”21 Is original sin (“concupiscence”) therefore located primarily in the sense appetites? Aquinas seeks to hold together the rational and sense appetites, so that the body-soul unity of human action remains intact.22 As regards the cause or “formal element,” original sin is the “privation of original justice.” As experienced in the human person, however, original sin appears most clearly in the unruly sense appetites: “the law of sin which dwells in my members” (Rom 7:23). These formal and material aspects cannot be separated. Aquinas points out that “among the inward movements, the appetite is moved towards the end before being moved towards that which is desired for the sake of the end,” and so sin must corrupt the human person, as it were, from the top down.23 The sense appetites possess their rational ordering through participating in the rational appetite. In the state of original justice, therefore, “it was not possible for the first inordinateness in the human appetite to result from his coveting a sensible good, to which the concupiscence of the flesh tends against the order of reason.”24 Instead the first sin must involve the rational appetite’s ordering toward its end:“man’s first sin consisted in his coveting some spiritual good above his measure: and this pertains to pride.”25 Adam and Eve freely chose themselves above God, through an “inordinate desire for excellence.”26 This choice made by their free will, however, immediately pulled them down rather than increasing their excellence, because of the participation of the sense appetites in the rational appetite. This helps to explain the complex portrait of Adam and Eve’s sin provided by Genesis. Eve responds to the serpent’s promise that “you will be like God, knowing good and evil” (Gen 3:5) with a display of disordered rational and sense appetites:“So when the woman saw that the tree was good for food, and that it was a delight to the eyes, and that the tree was to be desired to make one wise, she took of its fruit and ate, and she also gave some to her husband, and he ate” (Gen 3:6). Aquinas observes that sins of the sense appetites followed directly upon the sin of pride: “Gluttony also had a place in the sin of our first parents,” although “the 21 ST I–II, q. 82, a. 3, a. 1. 22 ST I–II, q. 82, a. 3. 23 ST II–II, q. 163, a. 1. 24 Ibid. 25 Ibid. 26 Ibid., ad 3. 790 Matthew Levering sin of gluttony resulted from the sin of pride.”27 Given body-soul unity, once the rational appetite chooses against the order of reason, the sense appetites too lose their rational ordering. Angelism The serpent tempted Adam and Eve with two large promises: “You will not die” (Gen 3:4) and “you will be like God, knowing good and evil” (Gen 3:5). Since Adam and Eve’s intellective faculties had not been darkened by sin, Aquinas notes that they would not have thought that they would become absolutely equal to God.28 What kind of likeness to God, then, did they hope to grasp? Aquinas states that “spiritual good, insofar as the rational creature participates in the divine likeness, may be considered in reference to three things,” namely, natural being, knowledge, and power of operation.29 Genesis 3 points to the third kind of likeness, power of operation: Adam and Eve will know good and evil and thereby become wise. Adam and Eve, however, do not aim at wisdom in accord with their human measure. Rather, they aim at a likeness to God as regards knowledge that is proper to the angels. At their creation, angels receive a full participation in God’s wisdom according to their capacity, whereas human beings are created without yet receiving their full participation in God’s wisdom. In wishing to attain an angelic likeness to God,Adam and Eve wish to be free of spatio-temporal limitations. In light of the promises that they will not die and that they will know good and evil,Aquinas first observes that Adam wishes that “he should of himself foreknow what good and evil would befall him.”30 Adam and Eve seek an angelic knowledge of everything all at once, rather than having acquire wisdom through an embodied, temporal existence. Second, Adam wishes “that by his own natural power he might decide what was good, and what was evil for him to do.”31 Adam and Eve do not want to conform their behavior to moral laws inscribed by the bodily mode of existence, just as angels are not subject to norms with respect to eating, drinking, sexual intercourse, and so forth. Third, Adam “sinned by coveting God’s likeness as regards his own power of operation, namely that by his own natural power he might act so as to obtain happiness.”32 Here again Adam and Eve seek to over27 Ibid., ad 2. 28 ST II–II, q. 163, a. 2. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid. 31 Ibid. 32 Ibid. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 791 come what their bodiliness makes manifest: how could Adam “by his own natural power” attain happiness (“be like God,” Gen 3:5), when happiness requires stability in existence? Adam and Eve’s bodily mode of being underscores contingency and finitude. By contrast, Adam and Eve wish to be the source of their own operation: “You shall not die” (Gen 3:4). In short, Adam and Eve’s temptation and fall are rooted in the desire to repudiate the givens of their bodiliness.This does not mean, of course, that their pride had solely to do with the desire to rise above bodily existence toward a more “angelic” mode of being, in which they would control their bodiliness rather than submit to its givens.As Aquinas notes, Adam and Eve’s sin of pride is like the devil’s in that “both coveted somewhat to be equal to God, insofar as each wished to rely on himself in contempt of the order of the divine rule.”33 In their pride, they primarily wished to reject the submission of their wills to God’s ordo of love, an order that seemed to them a constraint. Adam and Eve also wished to reject the body-soul unity that constrained them “from below,” as it were. Rejecting God takes the form of rejecting all givens, since all givens come from God. The Punishment of Original Sin If original sin therefore displays the body-soul unity of the human person, as well as the human temptation to repudiate this unity and overthrow bodily and spiritual givens, what about the punishment of original sin? Why does a fundamentally spiritual sin receive a bodily punishment, death? Before probing the reasons for this confirmation of body-soul unity, we should ask the question that Dennett would pose: how could death be the punishment of original sin, since death was already a constitutive part of the world millions of years before the first human beings? This objection, in its basic form, is pressed also by Aquinas: “Now death is natural to man: and this is evident both from the fact that his body is composed of contraries, and because mortal is included in the definition of man.”34 Moreover, not only human beings but also animals die, and certainly they do not die as the result of an animal “original sin.” Here Aquinas quotes Ecclesiastes 3:19, a text that Dennett could approve:“For the fate of the sons of men and the fate of beasts is the same; as one dies, so dies the other.They all have the same breath, and man has no advantage over the beasts; for all is vanity.” These objections to the view that death is the punishment of original sin hinge upon the evident naturalness of death. On the other hand, 33 Ibid. 34 ST II–II, q. 164, a. 1, obj. 1. 792 Matthew Levering Aquinas also includes objections that call into question this presumed naturalness. For example, Aquinas quotes Wisdom 1:13, “God did not make death, and he does not delight in the death of the living.”35 If “God did not make death,” why did God make bodily creatures subject to the natural decomposition of matter? However one answers this question, certainly it appears that if “God did not make death,” then God also did not make death the punishment for original sin.This view gains further support from Genesis’s teaching that Adam and Eve did not immediately die, but lived on for many years.36 How then could death be the result of Adam and Eve’s heeding the serpent’s promise “You shall not die” (Gen 3:4)? Aquinas adheres to St. Paul’s remark that “sin came into the world through one man and death through sin” (Rom 5:12). Human death could only come “through sin” if God upheld the first human beings in a state of preservation from decay. Surely this supposition proves Dennett’s broader case against Christian faith:37 is this not a “God of the gaps,” who mythologically overturns the laws of nature? One can respond that God, marking the introduction of distinctively human rationality and freedom into the world, ensured that human beings would enjoy the internal harmony and physical integrity that allows for the fullest experience of human freedom.38 In this sense the inauguration of distinctively human rationality and freedom in the world truly is a sacred moment. God enables it to be a true beginning, rather than already being marked by the internal and external degeneration that crimp rational freedom. God does this because he creates human rationality and freedom with the purpose of participating in his life. 35 Ibid., obj. 5. 36 Ibid., obj. 8. 37 Dennett suggests both that religious faith will naturally fade away—“times are coming when they will no longer be viable” (Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, 514)—and that if they do not naturally fade away, then the non-religious majority will need to ensure that they do fade away:“I know, I know, the lion is beautiful but dangerous; if you let the lion roam free, it would kill me; safety demands that it be put in a cage. Safety demands that religions be put in cages, too—when absolutely necessary. We just can’t have forced female circumcision, and the second-class status of women in Roman Catholicism and Mormonism, to say nothing of their status in Islam. . . .A faith, like a species, must evolve or go extinct when the environment changes. It is not a gentle process in either case” (ibid., 515–16). 38 It is not worthwhile to probe into hypotheticals such as where Eden was located, or how Adam and Eve could have been preserved from the depredations of wild animals or storms, and so forth. Reading too literally, such questions miss the point that the first two creatures to possess distinctive human rationality and freedom were upheld, by God’s grace, in the state of internal justice and physical integrity without which full freedom is not possible. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 793 Indeed, God’s gifts to the first man and woman accord with what we otherwise know of God’s infinite creative and redemptive love. Aquinas observes that “God bestowed this favor on man, in his primitive state, that as long as his mind was subject to God, the lower powers of his soul would be subject to his rational mind, and his body to his soul.”39 Original sin brings to an end this enjoyment of body-soul harmony, but it does not bring to an end the human person’s body-soul unity. On the contrary, death is the result of this unity—although this unity is now revealed in disorder. Original sin alienates the soul’s spiritual powers from the life-giving God and alienates the soul’s bodily powers from the spiritual powers. Aquinas states that inasmuch as through sin man’s mind withdrew from subjection to God, the result was that neither were his lower powers wholly subject to his reason, whence there followed so great a rebellion of the carnal appetite against the reason; nor was the body wholly subject to the soul; whence arose death and other bodily defects.40 Neither the bodily powers nor the spiritual powers can, as it were, separate from the other and blame the other for the disorder. Because of the human person’s soul-body unity, once original sin introduces disorder, this disorder infects the whole. The presence of original sin—both as the lack of original justice and as concupiscence—means that a time will come when the material degeneration of the body causes a rupture with its life-giving form, the soul.This is why we can say that human sin, not God, causes death.After original sin, God does not need to intervene for human beings to deteriorate and die.41 Adam and Eve’s effort to take their lives into their own hands and to rule over all givens has the result that they die in accord with the givens that govern body-soul existence. In attempting to rise to the level of the angels, they instead fall to the level of animals:“death is . . . natural on account of a condition attaching to matter.”42 As Ecclesiastes says,“All go to one place; all are from the dust, and all turn to dust again” (Eccl 3:20). 39 ST II–II, q. 164, a. 1. He discusses this aspect in full in ST I, q. 95, a. 1; and I, q. 97, a. 1. 40 ST II–II, q. 164, a. 1. 41 Cf. ST II–II, q. 164, a. 1, ad 5: “Death may be considered in two ways. First, as an evil of human nature, and thus it is not of God, but is a defect befalling man through his fault. Secondly, as having an aspect of good, namely as being a just punishment, and thus it is from God.” 42 ST II–II, q. 164, a. 1, ad 1. 794 Matthew Levering A Punishment for the Soul? “Dust to dust” does not tell the full story, even if the book of Ecclesiastes sometimes seems to think so. In the context of Adam and Eve’s susceptibility to the serpent’s promise that they would “be like God, knowing good and evil” (Gen 3:5), Aquinas attends to Genesis’s teaching that God made human beings “in our image, after our likeness” (Gen 1:26).When Ecclesiastes says “all have the same breath” and “all are from the dust” (Eccl 3:19–20), this point comports only partly with Genesis. Genesis distinguishes the human being from the other animals by “the breath of life”: “then the Lord God formed man of dust from the ground, and breathed into his nostrils the breath of life; and man became a living being” (Gen 2:7). Likewise, despite Ecclesiastes’s affirmation that “man has no advantage over the beasts” (Eccl 3:19), Genesis suggests the opposite: God gives human beings, created “in his own image” (1:27),“dominion over the fish of the sea and over the birds of the air and over every living thing that moves upon the earth” (1:28). Genesis 2 confirms this portrait by exhibiting man not only as naming the animals, but also as so distinct from the other animals that no animal can truly be a companion to man. What then does it mean to be in the image of God, radically distinct from the other animals? Since God is not bodily, neither is God’s image and likeness in human beings.43 Death therefore does not entirely destroy the human being; the just punishment of original sin is not annihilation. Aquinas states,“This likeness of man to other animals regards a condition attaching to matter, namely the body being composed of contraries. But it does not regard the form, for man’s soul is immortal, whereas the souls of dumb animals are mortal.”44 If death does not destroy the soul, however, how can the punishment of death be a just punishment for original sin, which as we have seen is an act of the soul’s spiritual powers? Why is this not simply a liberation of the soul from the body? This question returns us to Aquinas’s placement of his discussion of Adam and Eve’s sin under the rubric of the virtue of temperance, whose seat is the concupiscible sense appetite. The soul, which is “the act of a 43 For further discussion of the image of God in the soul, see ST I, q. 93, as well as ch. 3 of my forthcoming Jewish-Christian Dialogue and the Life of Wisdom. See also Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 2, Spiritual Master, trans. Robert Royal (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2003), 80–100; Michael Dauphinais,“Loving the Lord Your God:The Imago Dei in Saint Thomas Aquinas,” The Thomist 63 (1999): 241–67. 44 ST II–II, q. 164, a. 1, ad 2. For further discussion of the immortality of the soul, see ST I, q. 75, a. 6. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 795 body,”45 is made for the body, and the body for the soul.The soul alone is not man: “it belongs to the notion of man to be composed of soul, flesh, and bones.”46 Furthermore, the soul is inextricably linked to the body, as its “substantial form” inhering fully in the whole body and each part of the body.47 How does this understanding of soul-body unity help us? Adam and Eve’s spiritual pride led them to seek a higher mode of existence, and their punishment is a lesser mode of existence. This punishment involves first the suffering and indignity that come with the process of dying. The punishment also includes the loss of the body in death. Ruptured from the body, the soul loses that of which it is the form. Such souls are not angels. Even when separated souls are drawn into communion with God, they are not yet what they should be in the integrity of their proper mode: an embodied form, a soul-body composite that is the whole human person. In this way, original sin as an act of pride appears yet more clearly in its contrast with humility. Humility, Aquinas says, works “to temper and restrain the mind, lest it tend to high things immoderately.”48 As a virtue, it “conveys the notion of a praiseworthy self-abasement to the lowest place.”49 Following Origen, Aquinas exhibits Jesus as the preeminent model of humility:“Take my yoke upon you, and learn from me; for I am gentle and lowly in heart, and you will find rest for your souls” (Mt 11:29).50 Mary too, as the first of the fully redeemed, models humility:“My soul magnifies the Lord, and my spirit rejoices in God my Savior, for he has regarded the low estate of his handmaiden” (Lk 1:46–48). Likewise Jesus commands humility for those who will follow him, the new Adam: “Whoever humbles himself like this child, he is the greatest in the kingdom of heaven” (Mt 18:4) and “He who is greatest among you shall be your servant; whoever exalts himself will be humbled, and whoever humbles himself will be exalted” (Mt 23:11–12). Aquinas emphasizes that humility means that the human person “must know his disproportion to that which surpasses his capacity,” so as successfully to “moderate” the rational appetite’s desire toward goods beyond one’s capacity.51 This is what 45 ST I, q. 75, a. 1. Aquinas goes on to explain that “the soul is said to be the act of a body, etc., because by the soul it is a body, and is organic, and has life potentially.” ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 1. 46 ST I, q. 75, a. 4. 47 ST I, q. 76, a. 8. 48 ST II–II, q. 161, a. 1. 49 Ibid., ad 2. 50 Ibid., s.c. 51 ST II–II, q. 161, a. 2. 796 Matthew Levering Adam and Eve, in pridefully seeking an “angelic” mode of existence in which they would have charge over life/death failed to do. Aquinas urges that humility requires above all “divine reverence, which shows that man ought not to ascribe to himself more than is competent to him according to the position in which God has placed him.”52 This means that humility first denotes “man’s subjection to God.”53 In this light Aquinas argues that human beings more easily fall into concupiscence than into pride. Concupiscence bursts upon one’s rational faculties with a powerful surge, whether of anger, lust, greed, jealousy or so forth. By contrast, one’s rational faculties should be well protected against pride. Aquinas points out that one can avoid pride by considering one’s own infirmity, according to Sirach 10:9, “Why is earth and ashes proud?” and by considering God’s greatness, according to Job 15:13, “Why doth thy spirit swell against God?” as well as by considering the imperfection of the goods on which man prides himself, according to Isaiah 40:6, “All flesh is grass, and all the glory thereof as the flower of the field.”54 One likewise recalls St. Paul’s injunction, “What have you that you did not receive? If then you received it, why do you boast as if it were not a gift?” (1 Cor 4:7). Powerful though they are, however, these rational considerations often do not sway the will that seeks a good disproportionate to its measure. Love of one’s own excellence to the point of desiring to increase it beyond all proportion leads to a prideful “aversion from God” that is the “most grievous of sins.”55 In refusing to be subject to God’s ordo, pride subjects the human creature to death and thereby turns on its head whatever excellence the sinner may have had. Despite its gravity, then, there is a ridiculous aspect to the foolishness of pride. Everything good is God’s gift, and to reject this ordo is to reject God’s gifting, the entire basis of our excellence. As Aquinas puts it, We may consider two things in man, namely that which is God’s, and that which is man’s.Whatever pertains to defect is man’s: but whatever pertains to man’s welfare and perfection is God’s, according to the 52 Ibid., ad 3.Aquinas points out in ad 2,“It is contrary to humility to aim at greater things through confiding in one’s own powers: but to aim at greater things through confidence in God’s help, is not contrary to humility; especially since the more one subjects oneself to God, the more is one exalted in God’s sight.” 53 Ibid., ad 3. 54 ST II–II, q. 162, a. 6, ad 1. 55 ST II–II, q. 162, a. 6. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 797 saying of Hosea (13:9), “Destruction is thy own, O Israel; thy help is only in Me.”56 Aquinas’s treatment of Adam and Eve’s sin under the rubric of the virtue of temperance highlights the ridiculous aspect of repudiating the basis of all one’s excellence. Aquinas observes that the virtue of temperance builds upon the natural inclination toward what is good for the human person: “Nature inclines everything to whatever is becoming to it. Wherefore man naturally desires pleasures that are becoming to man which are in accordance with reason. From such pleasures temperance does not withdraw him, but from those which are contrary to reason.”57 Temperance has to do specifically with physical pleasures, “pleasures of meat and drink and sexual pleasures.”58 It is precisely in intemperance with regard to physical pleasures that human beings appear most ridiculous, because their animal appetites overcome their rationality, as in the drunkard, the glutton, and the sexually promiscuous person. Sins against temperance are less culpable than other sins, because driven by unruly passions, but they are more “disgraceful.” Following Aristotle, Aquinas offers two reasons for this evaluation. First, sins of intemperance tend toward reducing the rational creature almost to a mere animal, and thereby are disgracefully opposed to human excellence. Second, “the pleasures which are the matter of intemperance dim the light of reason from which all the clarity and beauty of virtue arises: wherefore these pleasures are described as being most slavish.”59 Thus Adam and Eve’s first sin of pride, which is in a certain sense the “highest” kind of sin (because it seeks, albeit in a disordered way, the highest excellence), has something in common with the lowest or most “disgraceful” kind of sin. By including Adam and Eve’s sin under the rubric of temperance,Aquinas shows that the disordered rational appetite is, as far 56 ST II–II, q. 161, a. 3. Along the lines of this distinction, Aquinas interprets Phil 2:3,“Do nothing from selfishness or conceit, but in humility count others better than yourselves.” In light of the elements of “his own” that each person possesses, each person must “subject himself to every neighbor, in respect of that which the latter has of God’s.” Ibid. 57 ST II–II, q. 141, a. 1, ad 1. 58 ST II–II, q. 141, a. 4. 59 ST II–II, q. 142, a. 4. He adds,“When we say that intemperance is most disgraceful, we mean in comparison with human vices, those, namely, that are connected with human passions which to a certain extent are in conformity with human nature. But those vices which exceed the mode of human nature are still more disgraceful. Nevertheless such vices are apparently reducible to the genus of intemperance, by way of excess: for instance if a man delight in eating human flesh, or in committing the unnatural vice” (ad 3). Matthew Levering 798 as ridiculousness or foolishness goes, like the disordered sense appetite, even though the former aims too high while the latter aims too low. Again one gains an appreciation for the body-soul unity in human action, where the temperate person rejects both angelism and sheer animality.60 In sketching each cardinal virtue, Aquinas describes “three kinds of parts, namely integral, subjective, and potential.”61 The integral parts are the virtues without which one could not embody the cardinal virtue; the subjective parts distinguish, according to the object of the action, the kinds of virtues that the cardinal virtue itself includes; and the potential parts are those virtues which possess the mode of the cardinal virtue, but not its matter. Humility (and its opposed vice, pride) belongs to the potential parts of temperance, because it operates according to the mode of moderating the appetite— although in its case the rational appetite. Summary With regard to Adam and Eve’s sin, we have explored four aspects. First, we inquired into why Aquinas identifies “original sin” both as pride and as concupiscence. Original sin as Adam and Eve’s action differs in description from original sin as it is found in us, because Adam and Eve’s act of spiritual pride results most noticeably in unruly passions (“concupiscence”) in us.We emphasized the complex integration of body and soul in original sin and its effects, due to the relationship of the sense appetites to the rational appetite. Second, we noted that Adam and Eve’s pride involves, for Aquinas, a kind of angelism, because Adam and Eve wish to rule over the givens of their existence, including the bodily givens. The knowledge that they seek is the knowledge that the angels receive at creation.Third, we explored the punishment of original sin. Seeking in a disordered fashion to overcome the givens of their bodily existence,Adam and Eve came to experience these givens as punishment. Grasping at a higher mode of existence, they lost the bodily integrity in which God had sustained them in original justice, and fell to a lower mode of existence, so that human beings now live and die more like the other animals. Fourth, we asked whether the soul, separated from the body by the rupture of death, truly experiences death as a punishment. It might seem that the soul finally finds in death its liberation, the angelic life that Adam and Eve were seeking.We observed that death renders the soul less than it should be.We contrasted this with the virtue of humility, to which pride is opposed. Death exhibits the foolishness of Adam and Eve’s pride, by 60 Cf. the opening pages of Walker Percy’s Lost in the Cosmos: The Last Self-Help Book (New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1983). 61 ST II–II, q. 143, a. 1. Original Sin and the Anthropology of Humanae Vitae 799 deforming the human person in a manner analogous to the animal-like deformations caused by disordered sense appetites for pleasure. Concluding Reflections In light of our examination of soul-body unity in Adam and Eve’s sin according to Aquinas, what kind of account of soul and body serves human liberation from sin? Specifically, how should we understand human “biological rhythms” (HV, §3)? Can human beings heal their families and societies by using their spiritual powers to overrule, through technology, their bodily ordering? Recall the lengthy quotation from Humanae Vitae that we discussed in the first section of this essay: to make use of the gift of conjugal love while respecting the laws of the generative process means to acknowledge oneself not to be the arbiter of the sources of human life, but rather the minister of the design established by the Creator. In fact, just as man does not have unlimited dominion over his body in general, so also, with particular reason, he has no such dominion over his generative faculties as such, because of their intrinsic ordination towards raising up life, of which God is the principle. (§13) Human bodily powers, just like human spiritual powers, have an “intrinsic ordination.”This intrinsic ordination means that “man does not have unlimited dominion” either over his spiritual or his bodily powers. The limits on this dominion come about because God has inscribed in these powers a teleological ordering or “intrinsic ordination.”This ordering, as original sin makes clear, is a unified one. In the act of volition of the disordered soul, neither the rational appetite nor the sense appetites move in accord with reason. Instead, just as the rational appetite now tends irrationally toward finite and created goods as its ultimate end, so also “the inordinateness of the other powers of the soul consists chiefly in their turning inordinately to mutable good; which inordinateness may be called by the general name concupiscence.”62 The doctrine of original sin thus corresponds to the doctrine taught by Humanae Vitae. Humanae Vitae upholds the view that human beings cannot seek to overrule the bodily teleological ordering in body-soul actions, to reject the bodily givens, without causing a disorder whose consequences will deform human families and societies. This point, N&V indeed, is the lesson of original sin. 62 ST I-II, q. 82, a. 3. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 801–828 801 Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness A NTONIO L ÓPEZ , F.S.C.B. John Paul II Institute Washington, DC P OPE PAUL VI’ S encyclical Humanae Vitae sought to encourage man to live out “the highest vocation (munus) to fatherhood” (HV, §12) in the living memory that “the source of conjugal love is God, who is ‘Love’ (1 Jn 4:18) and who is the Father ‘from whom all parenthood in heaven and earth receives its name’ (Eph 3:15)” (HV, §8).The encyclical’s invitation to embrace the highest call to parenthood responsibly (HV, §13) is truly understood only if one sees that this responsibility of the spouses is first and foremost their response to the permanent source of their love, the Father. This response takes place in his Son, whose Spirit, the giver of life, enables the spouses to encounter each other, to establish a communion of love that is indwelt by His love, and to fulfill in ever new ways the promise contained in their love.This paper seeks to show that spousal love is fruitful because its form is filial. Spousal love is filial both because it ultimately and ongoingly comes from its source, the Triune God, and also because the Giver has given, along with the gift, the capacity to give and to be fruitful. In this sense, as we will see, the stern call to “responsible parenthood” is a tender and courageous reminder that one can become father or mother only because one is oneself always being begotten. In order to illustrate how paternity and maternity are truly “responsible” when they are an expression of the filial form of conjugal love, we will look first to an opposing view.We will see how some contemporary theological reflection in the wake of Humanae Vitae builds upon an anthropology in which the “person,” rather than being understood in terms of childhood, is seen rather as an androgynous being with a selfdetermining, self-originated will, which takes its own autonomy as the measure of love and its very fruitfulness. The term filiality, when it 802 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. appears at all, seldom moves beyond a nominalistic or voluntaristic sense. Since it would be unrealistic to attempt to respond to the many voices and views here, for the sake of clarity, the first part of the paper will be limited to a critical examination of the influential work of M. G. Lawler. In particular, we shall consider his understanding of the experience of married love, which, in his view, requires a rejection of Humanae Vitae. The second part, then, in an attempt to account for Humanae Vitae’s assertion that the “highest mission of parenthood” must be conceived and lived in the memory of one’s own childhood, retrieves an adequate conception of the experience of love that then grounds the particularly spousal experience of love and its call to fruitfulness.This second section will form the basis for the third section’s account of the meaning of fruitfulness and fecundity that is presupposed by the encyclical. The Rhetoric of Experience One of the many significant contributions of the Second Vatican Council grew out of its awareness of the modern dichotomy between life and faith, man and God. In response to this perceived dichotomy, the Council appealed to man’s own “experience” to help him discover who he really is (Gaudium et Spes, §21) and to remind him of his own familiarity with the divine revealed mysteries (Dei Verbum, §8; GS, §13).1 Experience, so the Council claims, is a means of access to a unified knowledge of oneself in relation to one’s own self, to the world, and to God. In so doing, the Council’s insight benefited from the Magisterium’s critique of the modernist understanding of experience and also retrieved a term that the Church had regarded with suspicion since the council of Trent.2 Referring to many of the contributions of Vatican Council II, Lawler ascribes great significance to the role experience plays in theological reflection. His concept of experience, however, is sociologically interpreted to mean, simply, what it is that married couples live out and do. According to Lawler, this experience lacks intrinsic meaning and its 1 See Alessandro Maggiolini, “Magisterial Teaching on Experience in the Twenti- eth Century: From the Modernist Crisis to the Second Vatican Council,” Communio: International Catholic Review 23 (1996): 225–43. See also Angelo Bertuletti, “Il concetto di esperienza,” in L’evidenza e la Fede, ed. G. Colombo (Milan: Glossa, 1988), 112–81. 2 Pius X, “Encyclical Pascendi,” in The Doctrines of the Modernists (The Encyclical Pascendi of Pope Pius X) and Modernist Errors (The Decree Lamentabili of July 4, 1907), ed. L. Watt (London: Catholic Truth Society, 1937). Behind the retrieval of the concept of experience also lies the reflection on the meaning of action. See Maurice Blondel, L’action (1893). Essai d’une critique de la vie et d’une science de la pratique (Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 1993). Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 803 cultural interpretation is thus unavoidable.3 Faithfulness to the concrete experience of married couples, which indicates the increase of divorce and use of contraception, calls in Lawler’s view for a reconsideration (or a re-reception, in his terms) of the meaning of fruitfulness and of the Church’s declaration on contraception.4 To understand the meaning of fruitfulness in a way that does justice to the data collected from the experience of married couples, says Lawler, it is necessary to examine the conceptual framework according to which fruitfulness is understood, that is, the theological reflection on the ends of marriage and the undergirding conception of marriage itself. Lawler sets out to ground his rejection of Humanae Vitae historically, but the understanding of marriage he presents is limited to a primarily anthropological, rather than theologically grounded, perspective, and the reading he offers of the history of the development of doctrine regarding the 3 Lawler follows Rahner’s appreciation of pastoral theology and Lonergan’s theo- logical method. See, for example, Michael G. Lawler, What Is and What Ought to Be (New York: Continuum, 2005), 44–67. 4 “The sociological evidence,” says Lawler,“is clear: what is in virtually the whole church is a re-reception of the doctrines of divorce and remarriage, and contraception. I further suggest that it is about past time to acknowledge theologically and to teach magisterially that re-reception as not only what is but also what ought to be the belief of the future church.” Later on he writes:“The question can be put baldly here: How can anyone say that the church believes that artificial contraception and remarriage after civil divorce and without annulment are morally wrong when some 89 percent of the communion-church does not believe the former and some 64 former percent does not believe the latter? . . . [T]his does not prove anything theologically. It does however, raise questions that converted theologians cannot ignore” (Lawler, What Is and What Ought to Be, 170). This book is Lawler’s methodological synthesis of his previous work. See also his Marriage and the Catholic Church: Disputed Questions (Collegeville, MN: The Liturgical Press, 2002); idem, Secular Marriage, Christian Sacrament:A Theology of Christian Marriage (Mystic, CT: Twenty-Third Publications, 1985); idem, Symbol and Sacrament: A Contemporary Sacramental Theology (Omaha, NE: Creighton University Press, 1995); idem, Ecumenical Marriage and Remarriage: Gifts and Challenges to the Churches (Mystic, CT: Twenty-Third Publications, 1990); Michael G. Lawler and Thomas J. Shanahan, Church:A Spirited Communion (Collegeville, MN:The Liturgical Press, 1995); Center for Marriage and Family, Marriage Preparation in the Catholic Church: Getting It Right (Omaha, NE: Creighton University Press, 1995); Christian Marriage and Family: Contemporary Theological and Pastoral Perspectives, eds. Michael G. Lawler and William P. Roberts (Collegeville, MN: The Liturgical Press, 1996); Lawler, Family: American and Christian (Chicago: Loyola Press, 1997); idem, Marriage and Sacrament: A Theology of Christian Marriage (Collegeville, MN: The Liturgical Press, 1993); Center for Marriage and Family, Time, Sex, and Money: The First Five Years of Marriage (Omaha, NE: Creighton University Press, 2000). 804 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. ends of marriage has far-reaching limitations.5 He determines that this history can be classified according to three heuristic models. The first model, extending from the second to the twentieth century, views marriage as an institution whose raison d’être is procreation. In view of Augustine’s conception of the goods of marriage and Aquinas’s reinterpretation of them as ends, Lawler contends that in this first model the faithfulness of the spouses to each other (fides) and the indissolubility and sacramentality of their union (sacramentum) are secondary to and dependent upon offspring.6 Lawler argues that this model is typified by the 1917 Code of Canon Law, which defines marriage as a contract in which “each party gives and accepts a perpetual and exclusive right over the body for acts which are of themselves suitable for the generation of children” 5 Lawler’s understanding of sacrament and of marriage relies heavily on Edward Schillebeeckx. See his Christ the Sacrament of the Encounter with God (London: Sheed and Ward, 1963); idem, Marriage: Human Reality and Saving Mystery, trans. N. D. Smith (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1965); idem, “Christian Marriage and the Reality of Complete Marital Breakdown,” in Catholic Divorce:The Deception of Annulments, ed. Pierre Hegy and Joseph Martos (New York: Continuum, 2000), 82–107. See Lawler, Symbol and Sacrament, 5–62 and 176–215. Lawler does mention Rahner’s understanding of God and pastoral theology but makes little use of his concept of marriage and symbolic ontology. A less biased historical account of marriage would have allowed him to see that the understanding of the Church moves from the consideration of marriage as a state of life in dialogue with virginity; to an elaboration of marriage as a sacrament, once the ages of the persecutions passed and the Church had to define before the world what is specific about her identity; through the controversies with the rising liberal state that understood marriage exclusively as a contract on which the state had the final say; to the contemporary understanding of marriage as sacrament and state of life. For an account of the historical development of marriage, see among others: P. Adnès, Le Mariage (Paris: Desclée, 1963); Christian Marriage: A Historical Study, ed. Glenn W. Olsen (New York: Crossroads, 2001); Juan Francisco Muñoz García, El matrimonio, misterio y signo, 5 vols. (Pamplona: EUNSA, 1971–1982). See John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books and Media, 2006); Angelo Scola, The Nuptial Mystery, trans. Michelle K. Borras (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2005); Marc Ouellet, Divine Likeness.Toward a Trinitarian Anthropology of the Family, trans. Philip Milligan and Linda Cicone (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2006). 6 Lawler, What Is, 153–64; idem, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 27–42. Augustine, De Bono Coniugali (PL 40), bk. 1. Aquinas has a more nuanced understanding of the ends of marriage than Lawler’s account might seem to grant. See his Commentary on the Sentences IV, dd. 26–42; Supplementum, qq. 41–68; and Summa contra Gentiles III, 123–26, 137; IV, 78. Bonaventure’s treatment of marriage in his Commentary on the Sentences IV, dd. 26–29, is also useful here. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 805 (canon §1081, 2).7 This is true, but Lawler does not elaborate here on the difference between canon law’s normative authority to define and distinguish, which is one thing, and its role in developing theological reflection, which cannot be reductively equated with his necessarily spare and seemingly clinical definitions. Reacting to, among other things, the Lambeth Conference’s approval of the morality of artificial contraception, and drawing on Dietrich von Hildebrand and Heribert Doms’s personalistic reflections on marriage, Lawler contends that Pius XI’s Casti Connubii (1930) “introduced for the first time in theological history a new ecclesial doctrine, namely procreation as the end of sexual intercourse rather than the end of marriage.”8 With this second stage, says Lawler, the Church moved from a procreative model of marriage to one of procreative-union. Here the conjugal union takes precedence over the offspring, which is reduced to a “part” of married life. On this reading of marriage, the discussion regarding the nature of marriage begins to veer away from the “ends” of the conjugal act toward its nature.9 The final stage took place with Gaudium et Spes, a constitution which, according to Lawler, proposes “an entirely new and previously unheard-of Catholic model of marriage, a model of interpersonal union.”10 Lawler notes that Gaudium et Spes examines the nature of marriage without using the language of ends and hierarchy, and thus abandons the prior legalistic, narrowly biological model of marriage. He defines what he means by “interpersonal union” first by reducing the discourse on marriage to the place and meaning of the conjugal union in married life, and then by 7 See, for example, Lawler, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 92–117. For the discus- sion of marriage as a contract, see Carlo Caffarra, “Marriage as a Reality in the Order of Creation and Marriage as a Sacrament,” in Contemporary Perspectives on Christian Marriage, ed. Richard Malone and John R. Connery, S.J. (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1984), 117–80. 8 D. von Hildebrand and H. Doms are the two most frequently cited sources in Lawler’s description of the “personalistic turn.” 9 Lawler, What Is, 157.Theological reflection on marriage has moved from focusing its attention on the ends of marriage to studying the meaning of the conjugal act.The discussion regarding the ends has disappeared in a world that can no longer understand the meaning of causality and participation. Consequently, the debate has been reduced to the discussion of the meaning of the conjugal union. While this reflection, enhanced by a deeper knowledge of biology and a retrieval of the concept of person, has brought crucial insights to the reflection on marriage, as we will see in section three, it is necessary to incorporate the anthropological, Christological, Trinitarian, ecclesiological, sacramental, and nuptial dimensions of marriage to offer an adequate account of the meaning of conjugal love. 10 Lawler, What Is, 158; idem, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 33–37. 806 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. seeking to enlarge this horizon by explaining that the “interpersonal covenant,” which is the married “communion of life and love” (GS, §48), consists of many other aspects.11 According to this third model, typified in the revised Canon Law (1987), what counts in marriage, then, is not so much the presence of children but rather the love that the spouses share with each other. An examination of Lawler’s conception of the human body and the meaning of love can help us understand the way he accounts for the relation between conjugal union and offspring. This third model moves away from a too narrow identification of sexuality with genitality, which by definition is unable to distinguish human from subhuman sexuality, toward a concept of sexuality specific to the human person who is “a spiritual animal, vitalized by a human soul.” Lawler argues that experience witnesses to the fact that conjugal union, more than the fusion of two bodies, is the fusion of two ensouled bodies, two persons. This, for Lawler, means that “the primary end of sexual intercourse is the marital union between the spouses,” and not procreation.12 “To get really real about sexuality and sexual activity in the modern world, the exclusive connection between sexual intercourse and procreation,” therefore,“has to be abandoned.”13 The fact that the conjugal acts of infertile couples or those acts that take place during times of nonfertility still preserve their intrinsic goodness—which is more than merely a remedy for concupiscence—makes it clear, says Lawler, that the conjugal union should be viewed under this personalistic reading. Specifying that he does not diminish the importance of offspring, Lawler argues that the persons and their mutual love are what determine the nature of marriage. Conjugal union expresses nuptial, personal intimacy, pleasure, and at times, though not necessarily always, is also a means for reproduction. In this view, fruitfulness has to do first and foremost with the well-being of the couple, their “spiritual communion.”14 This split 11 Lawler, What Is, 162; idem, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 36. 12 Lawler, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 35. 13 Ibid., 177. This separation between sex and procreation also justifies cohabita- tion, which, according to Lawler, should be open to offspring. See ibid., 162–92. Karol Wojtyla and Angelo Scola, among others, also seek to integrate a personal understanding of the conjugal act.Their studies, however, arrive at the inseparability of the three different elements forming the nuptial mystery: unity, sexual difference, procreation. See K.Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, trans. H.T.Willetts (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993), 224–44; and Scola, Nuptial Mystery, 3–52. 14 It is true, as Lawler indicates, that it is the love of the spouses that matters most for the offspring. The reciprocal love of the parents is crucial for the education of their children. See Lawler, Family, 166–75; idem, Marriage and Sacrament, 69ff. Nevertheless, emphasizing this point to the extent of breaking the intrinsic link Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 807 between the personal and the biological/genital dimensions of sexuality, however, indicates that the sexed body only partially expresses the person. The dichotomy here between the personal and the biological in spousal procreativity reaches its logical conclusion in Lawler’s affirmation that, as the experience of “monogamous, loving, committed homosexual relationships” witnesses, there is no need to contend “that personal complementarity can only be realized in and through genital complementarity.”15 The bodily union of the “one flesh” is personal before it is biological/genital, which means that the union could include both heterosexual and homosexual persons. Deprived of any ontological depth, sexuality, according to Lawler, now has a primarily cultural meaning and its right use consequently depends on the sexual orientation of the person—an orientation which he sees as innate and therefore normative.16 His between the proles and the spousal love handicaps Lawler’s conception of the relation between conjugal love and offspring. This relation is crucial because fecundity is a dimension of unity, not its outcome. In this regard, there is much talk about the meaning of fruitfulness in Lawler’s work, but reflection on the meaning of childhood is basically absent.This lack contributes to the incomplete character of the understanding of marriage’s fruitfulness underlying Lawler’s account.A very interesting account of the consequence for children of this division between conjugal love and proles, which is at the root of so many divorces, can be seen in Elizabeth Marquardt’s sociologically grounded work, Between Two Worlds:The Inner Lives of Children of Divorce (New York:Three Rivers Press, 2005). 15 Todd A. Salzman and Michael G. Lawler,“New Natural Law Theory and Foundational Sexual Ethical Principles: A Critique and a Proposal,” Heythrop Journal 47 (2006): 182–205. For a similar reflection, see also their “Quaestio Disputata. Catholic Sexual Ethics: Complementarity and the Truly Human,” Theological Studies 67 (2006): 625–52. A few years earlier Rowan Williams reached the same conclusion. See his “The Body’s Grace,” in Theology and Sexuality: Classic and Contemporary Readings, ed. Eugene Rogers (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), 309–21. 16 For Lawler, sexuality, in fact, could mean “either security through fertility or role definition or cooperation with God in a sacred created activity” (Symbol and Sacrament, 178). Another important consequence of this proposal of the body’s incapacity to adequately express the person is Lawler’s conviction that a single conjugal act does not fully communicate personal love. He claims that a marriage is “consummated” only after several years of common life together, in which the spouses have had numerous occasions to physically express a loving unity and to share life together. See, among others, Lawler, Symbol and Sacrament, 202–3; idem, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 100–101; idem, Secular Marriage, 82, 109.While it is true that history deepens love and that the human soul cannot be identified with the body, Lawler’s principle of totality, according to which married life is seen as a whole with a loose connection to its parts, evacuates the meaning of a single conjugal act and hence is unable to adequately account for incarnate human freedom. In the natural language of the body the spiritual word of love expresses itself with precision and freedom in bodily form. 808 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. personalist interpretation of genital complementarity, which sees the physical genitals as organs of the whole person, including his or her sexual orientation, allows [him] to expand the definition of the natural, reasonable, and therefore moral sexual act to include both heterosexuals and homosexuals.17 Lawler approaches love in its three aspects as eros, agape, and philia. In terms of the place within married love of eros, “that rambunctious, irrational, and selfish component of human love,” Lawler says that “when it dominates there is never mutuality and equality; there is only the selfish drive to dominate and to use.”18 Nevertheless, and without playing down the erotic dimension, Lawler writes that spousal love is, first of all, agape. Spouses love each other for their own sake.Agapic love considers the other as equal to oneself and hence married love, to be true and human, must be perfectly symmetrical. Lawler’s theological reflection is unable to come out from under the shadow of the theology of the manuals. His treatment of canon law remains legalistic, and here he reads agapic love predominantly through the virtue of justice and the lens of equality.To affirm any difference between the spouses is seen as unjustly pitting the one against the other and as leading inevitably to hierarchical subservience.19 The human person is conceived as an individual who first possesses certain inviolable rights, and then at a second moment freely decides to enter into marriage and let his “I” become a “We.”20 For Lawler, agapic love is therefore mainly 17 Salzman and Lawler, “New Natural Law Theory,” 198. It is important to note that the concept of person, as a unity of body and soul, does not inform Lawler’s conception of the conjugal act. His texts leave the reader wondering in what way the soul informs the body. The anthropology he presents identifies conception with (animal) reproduction and the personal with the unitive dimension of conjugal love. In this view, then, the body is a neutral instrument of the personal will that seeks union with another human person. 18 Lawler, Marriage and Sacrament, 100. 19 I am not lobbying, of course, for a separation of justice and love, and I recognize Lawler’s claim to ground equality in man’s image of the divine. However, it is important to consider the relation between love and justice carefully.To think of love in terms of justice, and to do so without critically sifting “justice” from, e.g., its common distributive conception, leads to an identification of love with power. The relation with another, then, always remains dialectic, equivocal, or questionable. See Lawler, Marriage and Sacrament, 98–102; idem, Christian Marriage and the Family, 22ff. For a reflection on the circularity between justice and love, see John Paul II, Dives in Misericordia; idem, Dominum et Vivificantem.The last section of this paper suggests a more adequate framework for the understanding of love. 20 While it is true that the spouses are equal since they are created in the image of God, as we shall see in the third section, the claim of radical symmetry between the spouses eliminates the notion of difference between male and female, which Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 809 a love of friendship, which alone “can mandate the reciprocal consent to love.” “Why,” asks Lawler, “would a man and a woman freely choose to yield their individual rights and become a coupled-We for life? A short answer is because they wish to be best friends for life.”21 While it is true that love seeks only to affirm the other while allowing oneself to be defined by the beloved, Lawler’s understanding of love does not only set aside any discourse on “the ends of marriage”; it results in making the goods of marriage extrinsic to love itself. Procreation, faithfulness, and sacramentality, in this view, always simply follow a free decision of the person and are subordinate to man’s initiative. Indeed, they enrich human married love but they do not constitute an integral part of it; their presence or absence does not affect the nature of love.22 In fact, Lawler contends that these heuristic models do not claim to define the “nature” of married love. A theoretical model “is an imaginative construct, postulated by analogy with a familiar reality and used to construct a theory to correlate a set of observations.” At the Second Vatican Council, Lawler tells us, the Church changed her way of accounting for the reality of marriage, because the cultural, sociological, political, and economic context of marriage had changed. Lawler’s theology therefore seeks to correlate the present experience (of marriage) with the theological tradition while maintaining their equal status.23 Theology is empirical—not deductive or upheld by a metaphysics, he says, because “experience and not ontology makes reality”24; correlational—it does not look for causes but for a relation between past and present that gives equal importance to both; and probabilistic— seeking for certainty would be form of a-historical thinking that lacked the necessary integration of sociology and theology.What these models claim to then reappears in the guise of unjust inequality. Lawler’s conception of person can also be found in Lawler, Christian Marriage and the Family, 38–58; idem, Symbol and Sacrament, 201–9; idem, Secular Marriage, 59–61; idem, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 43–65, 162–92. 21 Lawler, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 154.The long answer is his re-examination of the doctrine regarding the ends of marriage. See also idem, Marriage and Sacrament, 98–104; idem, Christian Marriage and the Family, 22–28, 32–33. 22 Granted, my comments presume the existence of this or that “nature”; on the opposing view, of there being no such thing as nature, it becomes possible to defend divorce and cohabitation, along with contraception. 23 Lawler, embracing Rahner’s theory of the supernatural existential, contends that present experience can and does illumine tradition and past theological reflection because our present is “graced.”This, according to him, means that contemporary experience has equal status with tradition; any experience is, in this sense, revelatory. This is why he rejects Tillich’s and Tracy’s understanding of correlation. See Lawler, What Is, 1–24 and 77–88. 24 Ibid., 48. 810 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. do, then, is to be faithful to the reality of marriage as it is experienced by believers and nonbelievers alike. None of the models, not even the interpersonal one, claims to account exhaustively for the empirical data collected by sociological sciences. They remain open-ended and their validity resides in their capacity “to explain all the observations that [they] seek to explain.”25 Lawler claims that the existence of different models of marriage does not presuppose a relativistic theology. Rather, multiple models must exist because God is an unfathomable mystery. Following Rahner’s interpretation of God, Lawler believes that no theological or sociological attempt to account for the reality of marriage can claim to pronounce definitively on that human and divine reality. The historical development of these models is a sign of scientific progress. Although it is not the final word on marriage, the interpersonal model is the most accurate evaluation of the sociologically retrieved data on the experience of married life produced by the Church.26 Lawler contends that Gaudium et Spes’s interpersonal model as he reads it should guide the way married couples live their intimate communion of life and love.27 What married couples within the ecclesial community do, however, is more than just the living out of Christian doctrine as designed by theologians. The ecclesial community shapes and generates doctrine. Lawler’s understanding of the Church as communio—that is, the Church is neither a “democracy” nor a “monarchy” but rather a “super-diocese”—leads him to argue that the members of the Church must freely receive a doctrine “presented to [them] as apostolic truth and ecclesial faith,” after “critical judgment of the data.”This reception has to do with the relevance or irrelevance of a teaching, not its truth. Lawler contends that only if it is considered relevant, can a teaching be taken as part of the belief of the Church, though 25 Lawler, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 28–29. 26 This quote may help in grasping his understanding of the complementarity of theology and sociology: “for the theological prescription of what ought to be to be realistic it should be preceded by the sociological description of what is. Karl Rahner puts it well.The task of practical theology is both description and evaluation of the present world and ecclesial situation. For description, theology relies on social science; for evaluation of the present situation, theology distills this description in the still of ecclesial and theological perspective” (Lawler, What Is, 42). 27 “The action required by the interpersonal union model is quite different: the procreation and nurturing of the relationship between the spouses, a relationship that is mutually loving, faithful, self-sacrificing, just, companionate, forgiving, and peaceful. In a marriage, the time to procreate children is when the spousal relationship is sound and the climate, therefore, right for the procreation of children and their positive nurture into functioning adults” (Lawler, Marriage and the Catholic Church, 38). Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 811 he offers only the sociological reading of experience as a criterion for judging “relevancy.”28 In this understanding, the interpersonal model of marriage, however, is still in the process of being-received by the Church. Echoing an early critique of Humanae Vitae, Lawler claims that Paul VI’s encyclical represents a step back because, unlike the interpersonal reading of marriage, it still proposes the biologistic, procreative reading. Humanae Vitae, then, could not be seen as in continuity with Gaudium et Spes. Contrary to what Paul VI thought, Lawler considers “the majority report” as the judgment that is truly faithful to the Conciliar doctrine on marriage. Had Paul VI allowed the Council to decide on this moral issue, the outcome would have been altogether different. Lawler contends that, as was the case with usury, slavery, and religious freedom, the current official position of the Church on contraception as expressed in Humanae Vitae has not been received.29 Since the rejection or “re-reception” of Humanae Vitae does “not make the traditional teaching necessarily false,” what matters, says Lawler, is to see that Humanae Vitae is utterly “irrelevant to the life of the whole church, a theological fact that has been abundantly documented by sociological research.”30 He claims that “what is,”—i.e., what happens—“ought to be the belief of the future Church.”31 This conclusive statement in Lawler’s recent work leaves the reader wondering whether Lawler’s heuristic models and use of experience end up, in fact, doing what he claims they do not, namely, defining the nature of married love and fruitfulness. The alternative is to reduce “belief ” to sheer opinion. An attentive comparison of the two documents, however, reveals that Humanae Vitae continues and deepens the doctrine on marriage found in Gaudium et Spes.32 Both see marriage as originating from God who is Love (GS, §48; HV, §8); describe marriage as a communion of persons constituted by the self-gift of the spouses (GS, §49; HV, §8); elucidate the 28 Lawler, What Is, 121. “The past,” writes Lawler “is always re-appropriated or re- received in the church.” See also idem, Church for his ecclesiological reflection. 29 Lawler, What Is, 127–29. 30 Ibid., 163. 31 If relevance and reception are the main criteria, one can still ask what the rejec- tion of Christ’s message and his death on the cross in utter abandonment would mean for Christ’s claim to truth. Ultimately, it seems that Lawler’s theological methodology, with its consequent understanding of marriage, despite its claim to be concrete and compassionate, is unable to shed any significant light on the problem of evil and suffering experienced in every married life. 32 The following comments follow Alain Mattheeuws, Union et procréation. Développments de la doctrine des fins du mariage (Paris: Cerf, 1989), 124–31. 812 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. meaning of the conjugal act in positive terms and determine that it is ordered to expressing and enhancing the union of the spouses (GS, §49; HV, §11); and clarify that by nature marriage is ordered to the procreation and education of children (GS, §§48, 50; HV, §10–2). It is true that Gaudium et Spes indicates that marriage “is not instituted solely for procreation” (GS, §50); yet it also clarifies that the morality of the conjugal acts “does not depend solely on sincere intentions or on an evaluation of motives, but must be determined by objective standards” (GS, §51). Humanae Vitae sees the unitive and procreative dimensions of conjugal love as those “objective standards” and calls them “two essential dimensions of the conjugal act” (HV, §12).What Humanae Vitae does that Gaudium et Spes does not, is to draw out the moral implications contained in the ontology of the person and of love presented in Gaudium et Spes.33 Where is the step backward that Lawler regrets? If we have understood Lawler correctly, his judgment that Humanae Vitae reinstates a previously overcome, inadequate model of marriage, is simply a fundamental disagreement between his own understanding of experience and love and that of the Council. Humanae Vitae therefore brings to light this fundamental misinterpretation of the Council. Lawler’s anthropology rests on a presumption that offspring, faithfulness, indissolubility, and sacramentality are ultimately extrinsic to the very experience of conjugal love. Let us now look at an elaboration of an anthropology that seeks to take into account those factors. The Discovery of the Self While the reigning confusion about the meaning of experience should warn us to be cautious, the term nevertheless remains indispensable when the meaning of person and of love is at stake.34 Man discovers through experience who he is.35 Given the purpose of this essay, we will limit 33 This is further proved by the speech of Paul VI to the Equipes of Notre-Dame in 1970 and by John Paul II’s work on theology of the body. Lawler does not provide any sustained engagement with John Paul’s theology of the body, which is an important missing element in his treatment of marriage. 34 See, e.g., Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person, trans. Andrzej Ptocki (Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1979); Giovani Paolo II, Uomo e donna lo creò. Catechesi sull’amore umano (Rome: Città Nuova, 2001), 5–24. 35 As recent moral theologians have demonstrated, every moral experience regards not only the “what” but, intrinsically connected to this, the “who am I?” See, for example, Servais Pinckaers, O.P., The Sources of Christian Ethics, trans. Sr. Mary Thomas Noble (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 1995); 48–50; Livio Melina, José Noriega, and Juan José Pérez-Soba, Una luz para el obrar. Experiencia moral, caridad y acción cristiana (Madrid: Palabra, 2006), 29–67, 84–98. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 813 ourselves to a few considerations on the meaning of human experience, following J. Mouroux’s work, in order to offer an alternative reading to Lawler’s and to ground an adequate understanding of fecundity.36 Mouroux seeks to show that “experience” is the person’s incarnate, affective awareness of his historical and dramatic relation with the antecedent, symbolic, and non-intrusive self-manifestation of being’s truth through reality. “Experience” refers then to man’s totalizing and lived encounter and relation with the one who alone is, the one who is the divine mystery. This encounter has its beginning with God and not with man—who finds himself always already in relation with the mystery—and is always a mediated one: either through the symbolic richness of reality, or the presence of a witness—the other seen as a sacrament of God.37 The sense of immediacy frequently ascribed to experience refers to the person’s being freely engaged in this encounter, not to a gnostic “direct presence.”38 Despite its indispensable relevance, it is crucial to acknowledge that experience is not the final, all-encompassing horizon. Experience presupposes but does not encompass either the person’s life or the divine mystery—and the latter in a twofold sense: experience is unable to exhaust God and incapable of grasping God in 36 Jean Mouroux (1901–1973) reflected deeply on Aquinas and was also in dialogue with other significant French theologians, including de Lubac, Danielou, Blondel, and Rousselot. On the topic of experience, his was a lone positive voice between the Modernist Crisis and the Second Vatican Council. It did, however, open up a path for reflection that many have followed. See, among others, Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 1, Seeing the Form, trans. Erasmo Leiva-Merikakis (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1983); Joseph Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology: Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology, trans. Sr. Mary Francis McCarthy (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987), 343–55; Luigi Giussani, The Risk of Education: Discovering Our Ultimate Destiny, trans. Rosanna Giammanco Frongia (New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2001), 98–102. For the present purpose I would like to mention these works by Mouroux: Sens chrétien de l’homme (Paris:Aubier, 1945); idem, Je crois en Toi. Structure personelle de la foi (1949; Paris: Du Cerf, 1966) (English translation: Jean Mouroux, I Believe: The Personal Structure of Faith [New York: Sheed and Ward, 1959]); idem, L’expérience chrétienne. Introduction à une théologie (Paris:Aubier, 1952) (English translation: Jean Mouroux,The Christian Experience: An Introduction to Theology, trans. George Lamb [New York: Sheed and Ward, 1954]); and idem, Le mystère du Temps (Paris: Aubier, 1962). 37 For faith as knowledge by way of a witness see, e.g.,Augustine, De fide rerum quae non videntur (PL, 40); Le témoignage, ed. Enrico Castelli (Paris: Aubier, 1972). 38 Even the immediacy proper to mystical experience is not lacking in a sense of mediation. Since God is Triune, one “sees” the Father in the Son through the Holy Spirit. To advocate an absolute lack of mediation would entail a rejection of Trinitarian theology and of metaphysics. 814 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. himself.39 Since it is inexplicable without its relation to God, human experience is always religious experience. Experience exists so that man, who is a communal being, might grow as a person by living his constitutive relation with God. Experience, then, is essentially dynamic and historical.The encounter with God by way of a historical witness that happens gratuitously, and which in a sense is always already taking place, bespeaks a relation whose fulfillment is prophetically present in the historical circumstances but whose final form cannot be deduced from those circumstances or from man’s own desires. This dynamic movement that characterizes human experience, however, does not mean that historical development determines human nature. Rather, on the one hand, man is born, is given to himself, is a self from the beginning, and has the task to be and become himself.40 On the other hand, as his own sexed bodiliness witnesses, this task is undertaken always within his being-given and cannot be completed by his own means. Human experience, then, refers to the growing awareness of a path originated by the encounter with Another through a witness, a path whose goal is the personalization of the human being.41 Given that Christian experience is the unexpected fulfillment of human and religious experience in the divine mystery made present in Christ—that sacrament of the Father in whose light one is able to read and understand every other experience—in theological terms we could say that growth into humanity is both the indwelling of the Trinity in the believer and the participation in the communion of saints, a participation which makes of the human person a truly anima ecclesiastica. The depersonalization of experience, that is, the contraction of experience to its objective or subjective pole, rather than seeing it as the lived encounter in which two subjects know each other, is its most drastic reduction.42 According to Moroux, the empiricist and idealist interpretations are the two common forms this reduction takes.Whereas the idealist reading considers experience a sheer construct of the subject, the empiricist sees experience as what is simply lived out by a passive subject who does not critically assess what happens to him. On this reading, simple, direct contact guarantees knowledge, as though the living out of 39 Mouroux, L’expérience chrétienne, 369.This second incapability also secures man’s impossibility of knowing that he is in a state of grace. 40 Mouroux, L’expérience chrétienne, 19–24; Giussani, The Risk of Education, 98–99. 41 See Mouroux, Je crois en Toi. 42 In this regard the subjectivistic, emotivistic, and idealistic reductions of experi- ence are ultimately a rejection of the dialogical nature of the person that is itself in relation with another. See Mouroux, L’expérience chrétienne, 19. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 815 something were identical with awareness of its meaning.43 Emotions, feelings, and whatever else one undergoes become the essential content of human experience. In a manner consistent with this reading, Lawler and other contemporary theologians characterize the Magisterium’s theological method as an artificial deduction and imposition of ethical norms from a priori ethical principles or abstract metaphysical reflections, without taking into serious account the real and lived experience of actual men and women.The Church, it is claimed, tends to offer a limited and self-referential theology that is unwilling to listen to the voices of concrete individuals because it fears having to change its position on, for example, contraception, divorce, or homosexuality. Lawler says that by not paying attention to human experience, the Church ends up either blocking doctrinal development or elaborating ethical norms that are unreal and incoherent.The Church, he claims, has always defended marriage’s indissolubility but, de facto, has rarely followed her own understanding.44 43 In this light, many contemporary theologians believe that lived married experience grants their theoretical reflection an a priori authority over that of consecrated people.This claim, however, misunderstands the nature of love and the structure of experience. Experience of conjugal love does not coincide with lived conjugal love. The former is the historical, growing, affective awareness of the origin, meaning, depth, and telos of the latter (in this regard experience cannot be identified with a knowledge by connaturality either).To identify conjugal love with the experience of it amounts to imposing on love a logos that is extrinsic to it and hence unable to give itself through the experience of love. It is not a coincidence that, e.g., Lawler’s critique of Humanae Vitae disregards the encyclical’s numerous references to the “concrete” experience of love. Furthermore, the dichotomy that these authors baldly presume between married and consecrated life is rooted in a reductive understanding of virginity as lack of sexual activity and in an identification of virginity with life of singlehood. If virginity is the eschatological anticipation of the way eros and agape come together in God’s love, an anticipation offered to man by the Crucified Risen Christ, then conjugal love finds its truth and not its negating opposite in it.These theological reflections on marriage tend to conceive the conjugal and virginal states of life apart from the logos of agape brought by Christ, whose contribution to man’s experience of love is therefore reduced to a moral enhancement.The incapacity to see the integral relation between virginity and married life and the existence of both in Christ’s form of love leads ultimately to marriage’s loss of any horizon able to transcend and hence embrace and enlarge the married experience of love. See Lawler, Symbol and Sacrament, 201–15; Lisa S. Cahill,“Marriage: Developments in Catholic Theology and Ethics,” Theological Studies 64 (2003): 78–105; Kenneth R. Himes and James A. Coriden, “The Indissolubility of Marriage: Reasons to Reconsider,” Theological Studies 65 (2004): 453–99; Stephen Pope, “The Magisterium’s Arguments Against ‘Same-Sex-Marriage’: An Ethical Analysis and Critique,” Theological Studies 65 (2004): 530–65. 44 Lawler, What Is, 144–53; Himes and Coriden,“The Indissolubility of Marriage,” 498–99. 816 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. Although it is true that one “learns from experience,” it is important to realize that Lawler’s claim—that the experience of many married couples and how they live out their marriages should bring about a reconsideration of doctrine—is the conclusion of a deductive methodology based on an anthropology and a metaphysics that themselves contradict experience.45 Conceiving God more as an a-personal, unfathomable mystery rather than a Trinitarian communion of persons, and hence consciously self-limiting the nature of experience, Lawler’s system postulates a notion of person as an androgynous singlehood that determines himself and his own bodiliness out of his free choices.To claim that the experience of conjugal love (as revealed by sociological research) is sufficient grounds for a reconception of doctrine is to introduce into the experience of married couples a concept of the person and his relation to God that does not respect what experience makes evident about either of them.46 Looking now at the experience of love—which is not merely one of many experiences that the human being may have, but rather the privileged place given to man to discover himself and the meaning of the whole—will help us to see that the logos of agape gives itself to be known from within the experience of love, and cannot be imposed on it from the outside as one of many possible models. The experience of love is always an experience of creatureliness and hence it is called to enter into the logos that offers itself as agape. Participation in the logos of agape, as we will see in the next section, offers man the possibility of experiencing true fruitfulness. In this regard, the experience of evil—for instance, 45 It is therefore insufficient to state, as Lawler does, that experience offers data and that meaning is mediated culturally. Meaning, which always has a cultural dimension, is offered to the human person from within experience itself and, although it is greater than one’s experience, it is not extrinsic to it. 46 Mouroux cogently shows that experience has three meanings: empirical, experimental, and existential. The first refers to what happens to man, what he perceives through sense knowledge.The second refers instead to the measurable data upon which science is built. In his summary of Mouroux’s concept of experience, J. Ratzinger comments that whereas empirical experience refers to the Aristotelian and Thomistic “nihil in intellectu nisi in sensu,” the experiential refers to the Platonic “nihil in sensu nisi per intellectum.” Ratzinger follows W. Beinert in explaining “experiential” as “existential” experience. See Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 346–50.Yet if life is greater than experience, and life shows that the human being is a person inasmuch as he lives his relation with God through concrete historical circumstances, then the previous two levels are subsumed in and ordered to the “experiential” or existential level. Experience, Mouroux claims, must be taken in all its personal totality; and this totality includes having being created by a Triune God who is Love. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 817 the case of abusive parents—and its consequent theological and anthropological distortions of the meaning and experience of love, can indeed impede an adequate interpretation of one’s own experience.Yet these are distortions of what things are.Things as such can be understood only in light of a proper ontology and anthropology.The reduction of the experience of love to the empiricist-experimental level, and the relegation of the “experiential” level to culturally determined extrinsic models, do not do justice to experience because they prevent the logos borne by experience itself from speaking. My claim, however, is that to understand the experience of married love, one must see it within the form of love experienced by the child with his or her parents.The natural relation between childhood and marriage will help us to see the relation between natural and sacramental love and the relation between baptism and the sacrament of marriage. The initial experience of human love, first of all, indicates that love itself precedes and enables one’s encounter with it. A child is conceived in love: within that love he begins to be aware of his own difference with respect to those to whom it has been given to exist, as it has been given to himself to exist.The wonderful recognition of one’s own having been invited to exist, as John Paul II beautifully explains, is awakened through man’s own nuptial body, the sacrament of his very person, in his encounter with the other.47 Love not only awakens the self through the nuptial body, but also entrusts this wonderful recognition to the parents’ and the child’s freedom. It is only, as Ferdinand Ulrich says, if the father and mother enter a priori into the modesty of the finite, that the child may experience them positively as parents in the first place. The child can receive himself from his parents as a “gift to himself,” his existence can be something that is thanked for, only through their Yes to the difference, which can never be closed, between the finite origin that they are and the infinite origin.48 If the parents accept that difference, then the child’s encounter with love through the maternal embrace will reveal not only that love (and life) is beautiful (it gives itself to be seen), good (it gives itself) and true (it does not deceive). It also makes the child aware that his gratitude is finally to 47 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 13:1. See also Adrian J. Walker, “On ‘Rephilosophizing’ Theology,” Communio: International Catholic Review 31 (2004): 143–67. 48 Ferdinand Ulrich, Der Mensch als Anfang. Zur philosophischen Anthropologie der Kindheit (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1970), 77–78. 818 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. be offered to the ultimate paternal Source from which he comes.49 This encounter with love allows the child to discover that his very self exists always already only within love, and that all his creativity will be an expression of his having been handed into existence. Experience witnesses that the human person is a gift whose free participation in the gratuitous and paternal source makes the person be. The encounter with Love that precedes and offers itself to the freedom of the child, but without determining its answer, contains within itself the promise that what is given will remain and grow.What is given, however, is not some-thing but a communion with someone. The encounter with love reveals not only that a person comes from someone, and is this dialogue with the Source in and through the witness, but that love is a communion of persons. As experienced in childhood, the presence of the other—in this case the parents—is not a threat to an abstract independence but the promise of communion.50 The encounter with the beloved contains the same prophecy. Experience is not only the continuous introduction into a love that is always greater. The promise of communion also brings to light another element that is crucial for understanding the awareness proper to experience: a true experience of love, and hence every experience, is always an experience of conversion. Such conversion is not a breakthrough to power, as E. Johnson would contend, but rather a renunciation of one’s own self-will for the sake of the other.51 Experience teaches that the true form of love is one in which the affirmation of oneself is given in terms of an affirmation of the other as the meaning of one’s own existence.The surrender, therefore, is a true death to the egotistic self that seeks to impose its own little measure on love—even if the beloved agrees with this measure. Ultimately this surrender is to Love itself, a conversion to the Origin with and through the witness. If the ultimate horizon of experience were not Love itself, the surrender to another would alienate the self. At the same time, if it were not through and with a witness, history and the cosmos would be meaningless. 49 Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 5, The Realm of Metaphysics in the Modern Age, trans. Oliver Davies et al. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1991), 613–27. 50 Livio Melina, José Noriega, and Juan José Pérez-Soba, La plenitud del obrar cristiano: dinámica de la acción y perspectiva teológica de la moral (Madrid: Palabra, 2001), 345–77. 51 Elizabeth Johnson, She Who Is:The Mystery of God in Feminist Theological Discourse (New York: Crossroad, 2005), 61–67. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 819 The experience of love bears within itself both the mark of childhood and that of the Cross.The former indicates that the person has received everything as a gift, himself first and foremost. This having received himself releases the child into a spontaneous self transcendence. In this way he imitates the love that has generated him and gradually discovers that the mark of the Cross is integral to the gift of self. As revealed in Christ, and as human experience intuits, this giving of oneself for the other’s sake has Love itself as its adequate measure.The experience of the filial form of love—that is, human love as authentically existing within the preceding divine love, in the movement of conversion toward its permanent source, through the acceptance and abandoning of oneself to the promise of communion and fruitfulness that the encounter with the other person conveys—remains at the core of married love (Gn 2:24). Bearing in mind this filial nature of the experience of love, we can now ponder the meaning of marriage’s fruitfulness. The Child’s Fatherhood Lawler seems to perceive spousal friendship as the end of marriage itself. In so doing, he overlooks the reality that, as Alain Mattheeuws acutely lifts out of Gaudium et Spes, conjugal love—which is sacramentally and ecclesially immersed in God’s love for the Church in Christ—constitutes the essence of marriage.The love of the spouses is not its own end.52 The experience of conjugal love witnesses that it comes from Another and has this Other as its telos.To conceive marriage in terms of conjugal love allows us to approach the question of its fruitfulness from the point of view of the vocation to and mission of love that finds its telos, and hence its truth, in sacramental married love.53 Thus, as we shall see, fruitfulness regards both the growth of the persons of the spouses in their entrusting one another to the complete form of their married love, and the exuberant fruit of the conjugal bond, the child. This is true, however, inasmuch as these two elements are rooted in the Paternal source through Christ in the Spirit, and are at the service of Triune Love.This framework is able to preserve and deepen the content of the Thomistic and Augustinian accounts of the ends and goods of marriage. For the sake of clarity I would like to approach the concept of married fruitfulness in four points.These reflections attempt to draw on the Christological,Trinitarian, sacramental, and 52 Mattheeuws, Union et procréation, 239. 53 The sacrament of marriage is married love in its truth, not a spiritual enhance- ment.What is intuited in the human experience of love (which is always in relation to God, as we saw in the preceding section) reaches its truth here. 820 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. ecclesial illumination of marriage proposed by Gaudium et Spes, which Lawler’s theology of marriage, I believe, would benefit from engaging.54 1. Sacramental married love is fruitful and lives out its vocation to parenthood responsibly if it acknowledges that its form is filial; that is to say, if the spouses recognize that the source and end of conjugal love is not simply the will of the spouses but, in them and through them, the God who has revealed himself in Christ as Love (HV, §8).55 The first meaning of fruitfulness is then the recognition that married love is itself the fruit of the interaction between God’s love and the spouses’ love. Fruitfulness in sensu stricto occurs within this encompassing event.The vows that the spouses make at the ceremony grow out of a generative past that is not limited only to the directly preceding time of courtship and engagement. The sacrament of marriage, as has frequently been discussed, has its roots in baptism.The spouses were created in Christ’s image so that at a certain moment in history, they could find their place in existence in Christ’s “place,” that is, in his relation of love with the Father in the Holy Spirit. Baptism then is not simply the conditio sine qua non for a valid sacramental wedding. It is the defining moment of the person who receives it because it incorporates him into Christ and his body, and it is precisely that to which every man is called.56 Baptism is the incorporation into Christ and his body, the Church, which opens the person up to communion while also making him disposed toward it; he is no longer under the sway of the claim of autosoterism. Man, who has brought division and segregation upon himself (as de Lubac has shown), is retrieved by Christ from the hellish solitude that is marked by fear that the Father is the deceiver, and is re-grafted into that communion for which he was made.57 54 As mentioned earlier, Lawler’s sacramental theology does not include these dimensions of marriage, which are made explicit by GS.This framework suggests reading conjugal love in terms of gift, and thus is able to retrieve causality and teleology within sacramental married love.Alain Mattheeuws, among others, has pursued this road in his Les ‘dons’ du mariage. Recherche de théologie morale et sacramentale (Paris: Culture et vérité, 1996). 55 “Authentic married love,” says GS §48, “is caught up into divine love and is governed and enriched by Christ’s redeeming power and the saving activity of the Church, so that this love may lead the spouses to God with powerful effect and may aid and strengthen them in sublime office of being a father or a mother.” 56 In this sense, it is not coincidental that Paul VI in his Ecclesiam Suam placed a tremendous insistence on the Church’s need to help Christians acknowledge and deepen the truth of their baptism. 57 Henri de Lubac, Catholicism: Christ and the Common Destiny of Man, trans. Lancelot C. Sheppard and Sr. Elizabeth Englund (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1988). Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 821 This insertion into and opening up to communion reveals its form within man’s specific vocation. Marriage is the form that the call to communion of some baptized Christians takes; it is, in this sense, the flourishing of the form of love given in baptism.As created in Christ, man is in a certain sense also created for friendship, thanks to the Spirit, the Person-Communion, as John Paul II suggests.58 The Holy Spirit, the Spirit of Christ, guides the spouses from within that they might know one other, fall in love, and grow in that love until they are given the freedom to say a total yes to each other in Christ.59 The fact that marriage takes place in the Church before a witness is the lovers’ discrete and clear acknowledgment that the ultimate origin of their love is Christ, the sacrament of the Father, and not themselves. Being married in Christ is the offering to him of the gift received, a deeper participation in his love for them through their mutual love. It is a free and gratuitous act of expropriation that follows the nature of love, which, as we saw, has within it the form of childhood and of the Cross. This expropriation is, at the same time, the beginning of the fulfillment of the promise of communion. Christ receives the offering of their love and makes it part of his love for the Church and the Father. The Father, in response to his Son’s love, sends the Spirit to the spouses so that they can both be and live an indissoluble communion whose form, like the Son’s love for the Church, is Eucharistic: thankfulness and the gift of oneself to the end. The Spirit of Christ, the person-communion, is the one who makes the bond, the communion of love of the spouses, sacramentally indissoluble.60 Marriage becomes and remains a sacrament, which means that “Christ abides with them thereafter so that just as He loved the Church and handed Himself over on her behalf, the spouses may love each other with perpetual fidelity through mutual self bestowal” (GS, §48). This act of faith, which the Father rewards with the Spirit of Christ, allows the spouses to experience their sacramental bond itself as a God-given fruitfulness.61 This fruitfulness is the fertile ground in which children, when they are given, are 58 John Paul II, Dominum et Vivificantem, §34. 59 The numerous forms of this are determined by the Spirit himself. For a reflec- tion on the role of the Holy Spirit in marriage, see Il matrimonio in Cristo è matrimonio nello Spirito, ed. Renzo Bonetti (Rome: Città Nuova, 1998). 60 See Ouellet, Divine Likeness, 79–101. 61 For a deeper reflection on faith as the encounter with a presence, see, among others, Mouroux, Je crois en Toi; Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est; Luigi Giussani, The Journey to Truth Is an Experience, trans. John Zucchi (Montreal: McGillQueens, 2006). 822 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. received.This mutual self-gift, the self-transcendence that characterizes the spouses’ love, is not, however, an end in itself. Human love, through Christ in the Spirit, is caught up in divine love so that “this love may lead the spouses to God” (GS, §48).The filiality of spousal love does not mean only that it has its source in the Father’s love, it also means that conjugal love is part of the movement of return to the Father. Conjugal love is transcendent both in its origin and its telos. Earlier we indicated that every true experience of love is an experience of conversion. Now we can see that the total reception of the human beloved for life is authentically human only if it lets go of the voluntaristic hubris that looks to do only what is “humanly feasible,” and lets itself be embraced instead by the reckless, divine measure of love.Without this eschatological perspective, spousal love and its fruitfulness remain incoherent.We will return to this again at the end. 2. The fruitfulness of filial conjugal love consists also in representing the Father. We saw that conjugal love is a communion of life and love because it participates in God’s love. Divine love, in fact, cannot but generate a form of love that is similar to its own: communion. In this regard, conjugal love represents the Father in that it makes evident to human experience the fact that it does not come from itself; that is, it is always being begotten (sacramentally).62 Its being itself gift is, at the same time, an icon of its source. Furthermore, conjugal love represents the Father because, analogically to God’s, conjugal love has an inextricable order. Without affirming any sort of subordinationism, it is possible to affirm the irreplaceable position the Father— who gives all of himself in begetting the Son, without ceasing to be himself—holds for the divine communion of persons. The wellknown misinterpretations of the term “communion” have at their root the fear that the establishment of a beginning, a hierarchical principle, would entail the enslavement of the other members. This would indeed be the case, if hierarchy were taken to mean power in a worldly sense.Yet the Father as revealed in Christ is the one who gives all of himself: to the Son (and to the Spirit with the Son) the Father gives life in itself; to man, the Father gives participation in his life.The Father is the one whose gift of himself is that of making the 62 The meaning of evidence here presupposes an understanding of truth as self- disclosure that gives itself through a sign without pre-determining it, and that calls for man’s free and rational response. See Angelo Bertuletti, “Sapere e libertà,” in L’evidenza e la fede, ed. Giuseppe Colombo (Milan: Glossa, 1988), 444–65. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 823 other be.63 If authority, as its Latin root indicates, is to make someone grow, a father fulfills his task not only by begetting a child, but by exalting the one whom he begets. It is thanks to the father’s authority that the child can truly experience freedom.64 That authority is indeed self-surrender, as Christ reveals of God the Father, does not mean that a father’s position of authority within the family is lost in his self-sacrifice. If this were the case, his gift of self would not be a true surrender but rather a rejection of the logos of love. The absence of fatherhood always entails the disintegration of communion and hence the loss of identity. Furthermore, the absence of the father who surrenders himself (while remaining father) that the other might be also prevents the development of freedom and makes it almost impossible to avoid the decline of conjugal friendship into an egotistic affirmation of self. While both spouses are creatures, and as such, both take their form of existence from the Son—thankfulness, acceptance, and gratuitous response—within conjugal love it is the husband who also represents the Father.65 This mission is utterly disproportionate to man’s efforts. “In love and in fidelity,” Balthasar says, “the woman has 63 While for obvious reasons we cannot develop this point here, it is important to say that this understanding of the divine processions in terms of gift does not eliminate the absolute equality of the divine persons. The Father possesses the divine essence only as given and the Son as received and reciprocated in gratuitous response. See Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theo-Logic:Theological Logical Theory, vol. 2, Truth of God, trans. Adrian J.Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), 123–70. I dealt with this issue in my “Eternal Happening: God as an Event of Love,” Communio: International Catholic Review 32 (2005): 214–45. 64 Irenaeus’s famous statement, “Gloria Dei vivens homo,” as Orbe explains, indicates that “contrary to other ideologies, God seeks to glorify the human being divinely in everything. God wants to throw himself in the human being; that he be clarified with God’s own clarity.” Antonio Orbe, “Glora Dei vivens homo (Análisis de Ireneo, adv. haer. IV, 20, 1–7),” Gregorianum 73 (1993): 263. 65 An adequate understanding of this requires viewing conjugal love and the family as one reality. In addition, it must also attend to the asymmetry of the dual unity of male and female. Interpreting Genesis 2:23, Balthasar explains that “the word that calls out only attains fulfillment when it is understood, accepted and given back as a word.This clearly shows us the way in which man can be primary and woman secondary, where the primary remains unfulfilled without the secondary. The primary needs a partner of equal rank and dignity for its own fulfillment. . . . The woman, who is both ‘answer’ and ‘face,’ is not only man’s delight: she is the help, the security, the home man needs; she is the vessel of fulfillment specially designed for him. Nor is she simply the vessel of his fruitfulness: she is equipped with her own explicit fruitfulness.Yet her fruitfulness is not a primary fruitfulness: it is an answering fruitfulness” (Balthasar, Theo-Drama:Theological Dramatic Theory, 824 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. an easier time of it. . . . The woman is not called upon to represent anything that she herself is not, while the man has to represent the very source of life, which he can never be.”66 The fact that the human father cannot be the very source of life is precisely what calls him to be most transparent to the Paternal source that gratuitously allows him to communicate life. This representation of the Father has little to do with the human father’s precarious good intentions or his moral coherence.The capacity of the human father to represent the origin is mediated to him by Christ. In Christ, the husband’s gift of himself acquires its truth; the memory of the origin, the Father, is both ontological-sacramental and existential. For human love to be caught up in divine love means too that the husband’s love for his spouse, in being like Christ’s for the Church (Eph 5:25–27), becomes more transparent to what it is called to be. In this regard, human fatherhood is not simply a “role” that can be exchanged. The wife cannot be herself, that is, the icon of divine gratitude and creaturely, fruitful reception of divine love (Gen 4:1), if the husband does not represent the paternal origin. At the same time, the husband’s generativity and authority are themselves elicited by the wife’s response to love’s presence.This circularity, which does not obviate the hierarchical order of conjugal love, shows that the husband’s gift of self is always already a response to an antecedent love.67 Only asymmetry between husband and wife, as the experience of conjugal love witnesses, respects equality—that is, being created in the Son’s perfect human response to the Father on the Cross who gives all of himself for man’s salvation. 3. As filial, conjugal love is fruitful because it has been given the possibility of a further giving and the generation of a person. Created in the image of God the giver, the communion of life and love is offered the capacity to give superabundantly, i.e, to conceive another. Fruitfulness, a crucial term in Scripture, is always a superabundant fulfillment.68 The vol. 3, The Dramatis Personae: The Person in Christ, trans. Graham Harrison [San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992], 284–85). 66 Hans Urs von Balthasar, New Elucidations, trans. Sr. Mary Theresilde Skerry (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1986), 221. It is important not to draw a direct and unilateral relation between the persons of the Trinity and each member of the family. 67 Karol Wojtyla, “Radiation of Fatherhood,” in idem, The Collected Plays and Writings on Theater, trans. Boleslaw Taborski (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987), 333–64. 68 It suffices here to recall that Christ transforms 180 gallons of water into wine ( Jn 2:9), that twelve baskets of bread remain after having fed thousands (Mt 14:20), and that Christ washes the disciples’ feet ( Jn 13:5–10). Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 825 fruitfulness that man desires, and which he often confuses with the fulfillment of expectations, is not simply the successful accomplishment of great deeds, but more importantly, the begetting of someone—whether a child or a people. Human love arrives at its truth when it is allowed to enter sacramentally into the absolute measurelessness of divine love. In their gift to each other—a gift that, as experience witnesses, is constitutive of their very being and of their marriage—the parents thus participate in a fruitfulness that, like their bond, is greater than they are.The fruit of marriage is “excessive,” first of all, because it comes from the spouses’ communion of life and love. The child is conceived only with and through another—who is truly other only if sexually different. Fruitfulness is not a gift that the spouses have in storage to exchange when they deem it appropriate. It is a dimension of the communion they have been allowed to form and is therefore not simply the outcome of an act of two individuals.This is also why the child always incarnates their unity in a new way.69 When calculation is introduced, when the parents seek to determine the form and the content of the fruitfulness of their God-given communion, they claim the Father’s place for themselves. In so doing, they limit their love and thus break its fruitful unity asunder.The child, when he comes to be within this fragmentation, is introduced into his own identity and into the family only as a replica of a poverty that has little to do with divine exuberance. Fruitfulness, therefore, is fulfillment, not as “meeting the need” or the desire of the spouses, but as over-fulfillment. The mutual indwelling proper to spousal love contains within itself the fruitfulness proper to God, that is, the capacity to generate, with God’s help, another person. After several decades of IVF and various other recent biotechnological achievements, contemporary man has come to think of procreation technologically. Within this mindset, the child is seen as something the parents have the right to receive, and, when advisable and feasible, also the right to modify in order to offer the child a life of as little suffering as possible.70 The child, however, is not just 69 Today this is no longer obvious. Androgynous anthropology conceives fruitful- ness solipsistically by denying the meaning of sexual difference or interpreting it in terms of symmetrical complementarity. See David C. Crawford, “Liberal Androgyny:‘Gay Marriage’ and the Meaning of Sexuality in Our Time,” Communio: International Catholic Review 33 (2006): 239–65. 70 In this sense, Gregory Stock comments: “IVF still accounts for fewer than 1 percent of live births in the United States. Improvements, however, may transform the procedure enough to integrate it into routine procreation.With a little marketing by IVF clinics, traditional reproduction may begin to seem antiquated, 826 Antonio López, F.S.C.B. another subject of the human species, the obvious outcome of a fecund bodily union. It is a gift, a completely new being, given to itself with its own singular destiny to meet and mission to live. The fruit of marriage, in this second sense, is excessive because the child is a third, another person.The child’s first smile and his communication through language are just two moments that reveal that the child is not something but someone, a spiritual human being.71 Like the Logos, the child is never a repetition of the parents, no matter how much the child may take after them.As the only-begotten Son of the Father shows us, the closer to the source, the more perfectly new is one’s re-living of the origin.What this means is that the more closely the spouses live out the relation to the source of their love, the more truly personal and fruitful their love will become. It is only distance from the origin that results in dreary monotony and “elderliness.”72 Married fruitfulness, as it is given to the eyes of faith to see, is a participation in Christ’s fruitfulness on the cross.73 Christ’s Eucharistic self-surrender on the cross is absolutely unreserved, and so is able to introduce a new fruitfulness into history. Christ’s virginal fecundity introduces a new meaning of bodily human generation, while, at the same time, it is the way in which God the Father blesses the couple. This blessing could be one of offspring, but it could also be one of the sacrifice of not being able to have children. Conjugal love participates in the form of the cross and sometimes this means if not downright irresponsible. One day, people may view sex as essentially recreational, and conception as something best done in the laboratory” (Gregory Stock, Redesigning Humans: Our Inevitable Genetic Future [New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2002], 55). See Joseph Ratzinger, “Man between Reproduction and Creation: Theological Questions on the Origin of Human Life,” Communio: International Catholic Review 16 (1989): 197–211. 71 I dealt with this in my Spirit’s Gift: The Metaphysical Insight of Claude Bruaire (Washington, DC:The Catholic University Press, 2006), 83–113. 72 Meister Eckhart wrote that “Novitas est propria principio, vetustas autem omnis est separatio et distantia ab eodem; veterascit ergo omne recedens et elongatum a principio, renovatur autem et innovatur accedendo et redeundo ad principium” (Meister Eckhart, Exp in Sap., in Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Âge, IV, 264; cited in Vladimir Lossky, Théologie négative et connaissance de Dieu chez Maître Echkhart [Paris: J. Vrin, 1960], 366). If, as we mentioned, the parents accept their own difference from the divine source in their acknowledgment that they have been sacramentally introduced into divine love, they will allow their children to be themselves in their relation to their (paternal and divine) origin.The implications of the loss (or distortion) of fatherhood for the formation of the child are enormous. 73 See Aquinas, Super Sent. IV, d. 26, q. 2, a. 1, ad 3. Toward an Understanding of Fruitfulness 827 embracing not only the sacrifice of an ongoing surrender—to one another, to one’s own family, and to the Father—but also that of being unable to beget. If the spouses, then, embrace this sacrifice as a participation in the sufferings of Christ, the fecundity proper to marriage, which we discussed above, is transfigured. Christ’s Eucharistic offer of himself for his bride, the Church, makes the sacrifice offered by the spouses spiritually fecund and, in a way that is frequently not given to them to perceive, it also makes the community grow. In this case, the fecundity of conjugal love, by means of the sacrifice, comes closer to Christ’s supernatural fecundity.This brings us to our concluding point. 4. Conjugal love lives its own given fecundity responsibly if it accepts being placed at the service of another. Christ’s claim that there is no greater love than to give up one’s life for one’s friends ( Jn 15:13) does not only reveal the measure of love. It also reveals that this gift of his life is not his own initiative. He, the one sent by the Father, accomplishes his work within the modality and time determined by the Father. He does what he sees the Father doing, and awaits patiently from him the fulfillment of his hour. In a similar way, the spouses, having been incorporated into Christ’s love for the Church, are invited to put their married love at the service of Christ’s mission through the Church. In this regard, responsible fruitfulness is either obedience to the form of love to the end as determined by Christ, or it is simply reproduction, a technical calculus. In Christ, however, God has brought love’s ever-greater and truer measure to man.This obedience to love, as we mentioned earlier, is what secures the personal creativity of the spouses.The parents introduce the children to the truth of love only if they themselves accept their own sonship; that is, if they recognize and teach their children that reality is positive because the Father is good and all-giving, and that the Father’s design for Christ “to be all in all” is the fulfillment of human existence.Taking responsibility for spousal fruitfulness is, first and foremost, a matter of allowing the Father’s love to take effect within conjugal love. Humanae Vitae’s clarification that every conjugal union is both unitive and procreative, then, is not a prohibition or a distortion of the experience of conjugal love, but rather a reminder that married love, as a true, sacramental participation in Christ’s love for the Church, is an education N&V toward the truth of love and love’s fruitfulness. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 829–836 829 “I Am Awaited by this Love, and So My Life Is Good”: Children and Hope G. J. M C A LEER Loyola College Baltimore, Maryland T HE FINAL fantasy of the Marquis de Sade was to take hold of the sun and hurl it into the earth. In this paroxysm of annihilation God’s law would finally be lifted from human flesh utterly. It is a curiosity in the history of ideas to see a similar image in a 2007 book by David Benatar. Published by Oxford University Press, Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence,1 is a work of Analytic philosophy aiming to justify a pro-death ethics. Discussing the norms that ought to guide human extinction, Benatar observes that science gives hope that a meteor may strike the earth and finally kill off the entire human population (164–65). Indeed, science, he says, gives us sure hope that human extinction is coming sooner rather than later. His pro-death platform includes the following theses and items: • “Bringing people into existence always inflicts serious harm on those people” (184). (Emphasis on the always.) • Abortion is a moral obligation (127) • Non-procreative sex is the norm of sexuality (127) • There is no human right to procreation2 1 D. Benatar, Better Never to Have Been:The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006). 2 Benatar is aware that the European Convention on Human Rights and the United Nations Universal Declaration on Human Rights says otherwise (ibid., 102, fn 8). 830 G. J. McAleer • A positive legal right to procreate must be acknowledged. However, this is only a concession to contingent privacy issues. Should government secretly administer a contraceptive through drinking water akin to florid today the practical problems of privacy would be overcome (107; 110–11). • On John Stuart Mill’s authority that government ought legally prohibit “paupers from breeding hereditary paupers,” sterilization and abortion for “the most harmful reproduction” must be compelled by law. Of course, one would have “to control for possible biases”3 in the selection process of the coerced. Christians should not dismiss Benatar’s book as nonsense worthy only of the National Enquirer. The book has pedigree: it is published by Oxford; the readers of the manuscript mentioned in the Preface who proposed the book for publication hold prominent positions in the academy; and the book itself is full of recondite discussions of the best philosophers in the Analytic tradition—the dominant form of philosophy in the Anglo-Saxon world. In one sense, Catholic Christians should also be especially pleased with the book: mainstream philosophy now acknowledges that procreation is a serious philosophical issue. To put it mildly, this was hardly true when Humanae Vitae appeared. Analytic philosophy has come a long way since Peter Singer’s complete dismissal of sexual ethics in 1979.4 Indeed, as Benatar’s discussions make clear, there has been a quiet and growing interest in the topic for some time now in Analytic circles. My essay is built around two questions:Are Benatar’s arguments valid? What does this book tells us about the history of ideas in the West? Benatar does not address any Catholic arguments about procreation but, given his claim that coming to exist is a harm, his pointed question, “Why have children?” is clearly an interesting one to Catholics. The question might seem easy for Catholics to answer, and in a sense this is true, but I wonder about its persuasiveness. The right answer is not a surprise: Catholics hope for children because, as Boethius says, Love rules 3 Ibid., 113. This seems fantastical and ludicrous though the stature of Mill in liberal circles should give us pause. Sir Keith Joseph, one of the intellectual pillars of Thatcherism, lost national credibility in England by suggesting the same (see his Birmingham Speech 1974). Even the conservative Catholic press St. Augustine’s Press has published a collection of essays by Vittorio Hösle who advocates enforced sterilization (though not abortion) for environmental reasons.V. Hösle, Objective Idealism, Ethics, and Politics (South Bend, IN: St.Augustine’s Press, 1998). 4 P. Singer, Practical Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), preface. Children and Hope 831 the sky. But Benatar’s pro-death platform stems from his humanitarianism and it is, I think, undeniable that Catholic ideas about love have lost serious ground to humanitarian ideas about love.There is greater sympathy for Bono than Benedict. And what about the history of ideas: How did Western thought ever arrive at a closely argued rational demonstration for the morality of extinguishing all human life? Boethius speaks about “the rich and fruitful harvest of Reason” assaulted by “the barren thorns of Passion,”5 and Nietzsche uses his literary greatness to praise the fecundity of the will to power,6 and yet now an absolute sterility is celebrated by philosophy. There is no doubt that Humanae Vitae was keenly attuned to the times. Love, sex, birth, and marriage all suffered radical change in the West in the 1970s.7 Attending to these questions, the most consequential documents of Catholic social thought, Evangelium Vitae and Donum Vitae, for example, show Pope Paul VI’s depth of insight. But Humanae Vitae is forty years old. Benatar’s themes are more radical, it seems to me, than those discussed in the encyclical. The encyclical is about marriage; it is written from the perspective of married love and about the responsibilities of marriage.There is a host of debates the encyclical still speaks to, especially when one considers the voluminous literature on the family and marriage from within psychology and the industry of fertility medicine. But the philosophical debate is now running far ahead of these sorts of concerns. Benatar does not mention marriage and he might best be said to be most interested in the phenomenon of vulnerability. He does address sexual ethics but not until the fifth chapter and what he has to say is derivative of his earlier argument about human suffering. Benatar has two basic arguments. One, the less foundational, is a rehash of Schopenhauer: ours is a “world of suffering” (14). Unlike Schopenhauer, Benatar is optimistic. Schopenhauer’s famous pessimism is that although one is morally obliged to annihilate oneself the will at the core of reality is eternal, and slips away from you in the moment that you try to annihilate it.You might nought yourself but you cannot nought the will. Its structural alienation renders it eternally fecund, eternally suffering. Benatar is an optimist, however, because he is assured by science that extinction is inevitable: and so, sure in his hope that all human procreation, all suffering, will cease. This Schopenhauer-like argument relies on a more basic argument deriving from humanitarian sentiment. “I have argued,” writes Benatar, 5 Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy (London: Penguin, 1999), 4. 6 F. Nietzsche, The Genealogy of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). 7 D. Frum, How We Got Here:The 70’s (New York: Basic Books, 2000). 832 G. J. McAleer “that so long as a life contains even the smallest quantity of bad, coming into existence is a harm” (60). It is a curiosity of Benatar’s book that whilst de Sade longed for the annihilation of the world on account of twisted love Benatar longs for the elimination of worldly sentient life on account of rationality (163). He does not mention love. The topic of procreation certainly does not naturally suggest the theme of love to Benatar.The reason: parents are never loving because given the vulnerability to suffering of every child parents should be aghast at playing “procreational Russian roulette” (92); indeed, as he puts it, playing with a fully load gun pointed at the head of one’s child.To give birth is no act of love. On account of vulnerability, no human life is “worth starting” therefore there is no moral duty to procreate (94). Rather is there a duty not to procreate (101). To support these claims, the central argument is: a) suffering is bad and b) stopping all procreation eliminates suffering (ultimately) and c) the undoubted pleasures found amidst the suffering that is human life cannot justify birth. “Only existers suffer harm,” (29) says Benatar, but surely, the optimist will argue: only existers have pleasure and these pleasures of life must be put in the balance against harm experienced (29–30). His subsidiary, Schopenhauerian argument shows the pleasure-harm balance test does not favor procreation. Yet even if it did somehow, the balance test idea ignores a crucial asymmetry, observes Benatar.The non-existence of pain is a good thing but the absence of pleasure is not a bad thing. Loss of pleasure is only a bad thing if it is a diminishment of human aspiration and comfort but in the absence of people the loss of pleasure is not a diminishment and not a bad thing, therefore (30). It still makes perfect sense, however, to say that a universe without pain is a good thing even if there are no people to enjoy life without pain. Analytic philosophy is rightly praised for its caution in building arguments. No implications of an argument are warranted until they follow with a cast-iron logic from the premise of the argument. Benatar is oddly lacking here. Christians, for example, do not think that all suffering is bad; indeed, most people do not. All cultures recognize that self-discipline implies unpleasantness of some sort and they do not regard this unpleasantness as a harm. Benatar, unaccountably, from what I can tell, assumes that pain and suffering are harms. By having a child, I harm the child, for the child will suffer. This is not right, though. It is certainly true that I put the child in harm’s way, but do I harm the child? A general puts his troops in harm’s way but it is the enemy that harms them. Benatar runs together the physical reality of pain with the moral phenomenon of harm and seems to think wherever the first is found so is the second. His natu- Children and Hope 833 ralism is unargued for, he smuggles in the idea of harm, and it is surely false anyway.What Benatar says, seems to me false:“Bringing people into existence always inflicts serious harm on these people” (184). False: because putting someone in harm’s way is not the same as inflicting harm upon him or her. There seems to be some odd confusion in Benatar’s ideas of agency and causation.8 There are at least two other reasons the argument fails, one moral, the other ontological. Is Benatar right about the asymmetry? He thinks a balance test of suffering and pleasure is irrelevant because a loss of suffering is a good and a loss of pleasure is morally indifferent. But what if one is not a scorched-earth utilitarian like Benatar? One might think, as do Smith, Hume, and Scheler, that the realization of high values is a basic moral desideratum. Creating actors able to realize high civilization values, despite suffering, is a conceivable ethics, obviously, and recognizably, animated by the idea of noble life, I would have thought. Benatar thinks the asymmetry idea a knock-down insight, the entire book is built upon it, and yet anyone interested in civilization values is going to argue that the loss of pain is good and the loss of civilization values bad, not morally indifferent. That is, those values themselves matter; and yes, people have suffered for their art! Admittedly, Hume might crack under pressure: he might concede Benatar’s point that loss of refinement is a negative only if humans suffer diminishment. Hume’s ethics puts a strong emphasis on utility or happiness, but Smith explicitly rejects Hume on this point:9 Smith, like Nietzsche, and perhaps Peirce, thinks that beauty is the foundational value and pain filled human effort serves beauty.10 Catholics will insist that persons can only serve persons. Smith’s position is unsatisfactory. But Catholics will join with Smith in resisting Benatar’s asymmetry and make the point that the realization of love is worth being born and suffering for.There is nothing odd at all in saying that a universe without love is a diminished universe. To live for love is to live for persons. Generosity is inseparable from the nobility of birth. This is why Pope Benedict XVI, in Spe Salvi (§3), cites St. Josephine Bakhita: “I am awaited by this Love. And so my life is good.” It is hope that is Benatar’s undoing; it is an unexamined premise assumed in his argument. Benatar hopes for extinction because he is an essentialist about suffering. This hope is based on a misunderstanding about the ontology of children. Benatar thinks that for as long as humans 8 “Since all existers suffer harm, procreation always causes harm.” Benatar, Better Never to Have Been, 50. 9 A. Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1974), 179 and 183. 10 Ibid., 181–82. G. J. McAleer 834 live there will be suffering. Christians do not believe this, obviously.The world may perish but eternal life is our hope. But Christians believe more. St. Paul speaks of the form of this world passing away. Benatar thinks every child is essentially suffering.To his mind, every birth repeats the past. Here, he has drunk deeply of Schopenhauer’s essentialism. But is a child the past? Human nature is, essentially, vulnerable, but not suffering. For every child is novitas mundi. Ontologically, it is undeniable, it seems to me, that the world begins anew with every child. Every child is unique. As the medieval Dominican theologian Robert Kilwardby puts it: a person is res in actu sui generis.This uniqueness is not a repetition of the past; it is a beginning, a radically new beginning. Every child is the hope of the world made new. Christians have children because they grasp that ontologically a child is what the Incarnation revealed: a refreshing of the world. More, birthing, a wound of love, to use Thomas Aquinas’s phrase, is suffering evacuated by love, an act expressive of the ontology of hope that is a child. Every child is an ontological hope, a fresh beginning for the world: the child’s vulnerability rightly acted out makes the child, each person, a vessel of mercy (Augustine), refreshment for others.A child is not essentially suffering. A child is true history, novitas mundi. Each child is the form of the world passing away, vulnerability begun as hope, acted rightly upon, love.11 Perhaps one will simply shrug and say “Benatar’s are the views of a lonely radical.” This may be true in some sense, but a question persists. Nietzsche was a lonely radical but The Genealogy of Morals starts with a celebration of fecundity.What is it about the history of ideas that today a radical might question what even a thinker of audacious originality like Nietzsche took for granted? Unlike Nietzsche, Benatar is a humanitarian; his moral complaint is that we suffer. Nietzsche thrilled to the idea that what does not kill you only makes you stronger. By contrast, Benatar wants to avoid every “unpleasantness.” Indeed, his moral complaint is against sentience as such since it means experiencing “unpleasantness” (p. 2). Is his theory logically the end point of humanitarianism? Certainly, since de Lubac’s wonderful book The Drama of Atheist Humanism, a core Catholic thesis is: eliminate God and you eliminate man.The problem humanitarian love poses to Christianity cannot be underestimated. Humanitarian sentiment is so similar to Christianity: both the Christian and the humanitarian long for the end of suffering; action that re-makes the world; that alleviates poverty; that cures; that overcomes prejudice with sympathy. So similar are the aspirations of Christians and humanitarians that many 11 This paragraph owes much to the influence of the American Catholic pragma- tist, D. G. Leahy. Children and Hope 835 Christians are sincerely puzzled if told there is not a straight line from Bono to Benedict. Isn’t it true that humanitarians respect human life as much as Catholics? Don’t the wealthiest humanitarians spend their fortunes on respecting human life, trying to cure malaria, to ensure fresh water for all? Why were some of the best modern Catholic thinkers, people like de Lubac, Scheler, Kolnai, so suspicious of humanitarianism? This is an enormous topic, actually, but a part of the answer, and it might seem an odd answer, is: Catholics are suspicious of humanitarianism’s hyper-moralism.12 As Aurel Kolnai pointed out in the ’40s, humanitarianism is hostile to moral hierarchy. Egalitarianism is a preponderant emphasis of humanitarianism and thus moral distinctions must be elided. Certainly, the idea of intrinsic evil, the idea that a certain kind of act can never be moral, is deeply offensive to the social justice sensibility of the humanitarian. It encourages the idea that there might be “intrinsic discrimination between human ‘needs,’ ” as Kolnai puts it. In turn, this suggests judgment and complexity, and so a break on broad policy solutions. Extremely anxious to resolve social problems, social suffering, social justice activists find deference to a variegated moral order intolerable for this reason. Rejecting the idea of intrinsic moral evil might seem an excuse for immoralism, and it is, but its motivation is avidity for the reign of goodness. Benatar’s book is a perfect example of this: he is sincere about wanting to end suffering. Noughting the human accomplishes this.Vulnerability (74) is replaced by monism.This explains his obscuring the distinction between the natural and moral orders. What does monism secure? It delivers the resolution of moral tension. It delivers purity. Strange to say, but an upshot of Benatar’s ethics is impeccability.War, hunger, exploitation are all done away with by monism but so also greed, vanity, sloth, egoism, and sexual impurity. Benatar’s strange recourse to angelic impeccability is signaled by the alienation of the body that courses through the book. Schopenhauer’s brilliant writing skills might furnish Benatar with snappy starts to a few chapters but Schopenhauer is not worthy of bring argued with seriously. No arguments are offered as to why Schopenhauer’s pessimism is misplaced, or why we are normatively rational, as Benatar thinks, and not willful, as Nietzsche thinks. There is something “obscene” about our planet (89), we are told, and we must be “suspicious” of “human drives” to procreate (96). To observe man’s “curious, manifold, and contradictory attributes” is impossible for the humanitarian. For our complex nature suggests something 12 Paragraphs following owe much to Kolnai’s essay,“The Humanitarian versus the Religious Attitude,” The Thomist 7 (1944): 429–57. 836 G. J. McAleer religious: that man is torn between fallness and nobility; that civilization betokens God because human aspiration seeks to recuperate what is sensed as amiss. Indeed, this militancy for angelic impeccability is, as Kolnai pointed out, the core contradiction of humanitarianism: it concludes in “a N&V decisive moral abandonment of man.”13 13 Ibid., 452. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 837–856 837 St. Thomas’s Moral Psychology and the Rejection of Humanae Vitae K EVIN E. O’R EILLY Milltown Institute Dublin, Ireland W E LIVE in a day and age when not only do many Catholics question the Church’s teaching on birth control, they accept as self-evident the notion that the Church has got it wrong on this matter.1 This state of affairs has led to a situation in which couples, when they contracept, no longer seemingly experience pangs of conscience; rather, this mistaken self-evidence functions as a major premiss in their moral reasoning. Contraception has of course led to a whole range of other aberrations in the area of sexual morality—some of which, incidentally, were foreseen by the encyclical2 —and the moral blindness that is widespread with regard to these aberrations arguably has one of its roots in contraceptive mentality that has emerged over the course of the last few decades. This essay aims to engage with those psychological dynamics that have contributed to widespread confident rejection of Humanae Vitae 3 by 1 For a discussion of this issue, see Desmond Connell,Archbishop of Dublin, Christ Our Life (Dublin: Four Courts Press, 1995), 149–54. 2 See Humanae Vitae, §17. All translations are from Janet E. Smith, Humanae Vitae: A Generation Later (Washington DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 1991). 3 There are of course other factors that have contributed to the inability of many to appreciate the riches of this encyclical. Thus, to name but one, there is the abiding deleterious legacy of Descartes’s anthropological dualism, issuing in a notion of freedom that is well-described by John Paul II: “A freedom which claims to be absolute ends up treating the human body as a raw datum, devoid of any meaning and moral values until freedom has shaped it in accordance with its design. Consequently, human nature and the body appear as presuppositions or preambles, materially necessary for freedom to make its choice, yet extrinsic to the person, the subject and the human act” (Veritatis Splendor, §48).The focus of this 838 Kevin E. O’Reilly drawing upon the work of St.Thomas on the emotions, for the emotions play a role both in our perception of moral reality and in our reasoning about the same. I will argue, on the basis of St.Thomas’s texts, that affectivity is integral to the perception of what constitutes the human good, which perception provides the starting point for the practical reason as it deliberates about the means to attain this good. It will thus become apparent that knowledge of the natural law can never be divorced from the agent’s affective constitution.This knowledge is also a function of the life of grace, which perfects nature.4 Given the sanitary effect of grace on the life of reason, it is not difficult to appreciate how ultimately the most exalted grasp of the natural law is reserved for those who are immersed in the living faith of the Church. On the other hand, as we shall see, the sanitary effects of grace can be undermined by moral vice, the most harmful of these being that of lust. It is precisely this vice, let loose by the uncoupling of the unitive and procreative aspects of the marital act, occasioned by the practice of contracepting, that lies at the root of the failure even of many Catholics to perceive the truth of the beautiful and wholesome teaching of Humanae Vitae. The Truth of the Practical Intellect For St.Thomas “the truth of the practical intellect depends on conformity with right appetite,”5 a conformity that pertains rather to contingent matters than to necessary ones, for we have influence only over contingent affairs, whether these concern interior actions or external works. Hence, concludes Thomas, “it is only about contingent matters that an intellectual virtue is assigned to the practical intellect, namely, art, as regards things to be made, and prudence, as regards things to be done.”6 Here we are dealing with human action, namely things to be done. Prudence—“the right reason of things to be done”7—the subject of which is the practical intellect in its relation to the right will, constitutes the pertinent virtue in this domain. Just as we are rightly disposed to the principles of speculative truth (such as the principle of contradiction) by the natural light of the active intellect, so too we are rightly disposed to the principles of the reason of things to be done—which principles are provided by the essay is however on the psychological dynamics that have undermined the moral vision necessary to see the correctness of Humanae Vitae’s teaching and to live it out in conjugal life. 4 See ST I, q. 62, a. 5; De malo q. 2, a. 11. 5 ST I–II, q. 57, a. 6. 6 Ibid. 7 ST I–II, q. 56, a. 3. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 839 ends to which man is rightly disposed—by the rectitude of the will.8 Thus, the constitution of a person’s will fundamentally determines the principles of the reason of things to be done, namely prudence. A person’s affective condition either facilitates or impedes his prudential reasoning, influencing the degree to which the latter is in conformity with truth. Affectivity and the Perception of Moral Truth At the beginning of the secunda secundae pars,Thomas famously observes that “General remarks about moral matters are of little use because human actions are about particular things.”9 Particular concrete moral cases confront us with the fact that human beings are moved by passions. As Gilson points out, “the study of the passions, therefore, must precede any discussion of moral problems.”10 In adopting this approach,Thomas displays his moral realism; as Paul Gondreau tells us,“the moral quality of human life begins for him in the most concrete of human experiences: the movements of sensitive affectivity, the passions.”11 In Thomas’s view, choices and intentions do not belong to the realm of abstraction; rather, we desire particular objects, we fear particular outcomes, and so on. One main reason for Thomas’s positive attitude towards human affectivity is his espousal of Aristotelian hylomorphism, that is to say, the theory of form and matter which he inherited from Aristotle, albeit adapting it according to his own purposes. On the basis of this hylomorphism, Thomas views the human person as a unitary composite being, comprising both body and soul. One consequence of this view is that one cannot separate the sensible and psychic dimensions of human life, a point expressed well by Judith A. Barad: “[T]he psychic and corporeal elements of emotional experience are not characteristic of two entities; together they make up one affective experience.”12 Again, a hylomorphic conception of human nature demands that any affective movement be informed by and integrated into the life of reason. In this view, it becomes apparent that the moral life engages the whole person.13 Of particular interest to us is the effect of affectivity on our 8 Ibid. 9 ST II–II, prol. (my translation). 10 E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St.Thomas, trans. L. K. Shook (New York: Random House, 1956), 271. 11 Paul Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul in the Theology of St.Thomas Aquinas (Münster: Aschendorff, 2002), 108. 12 Judith A. Barad,“Aquinas on the Role of Emotion in Moral Judgment and Activ- ity,” The Thomist 55 (1991): 399. 13 See Servais Pinckaers, O.P.,“Les passions et la morale,” Revue de sciences philosophiques et théologiques 74 (1990): 381–86. 840 Kevin E. O’Reilly perception of the good. In this regard it ought to be noted that whether the object of the will be a true good or merely an apparent good, there is always an affective influence on reason. The question on any particular occasion is: given the appetitive condition of the practical reason, to what extent does affectivity facilitate or impede an objective perception of reality on the part of the person? To what extent is the affective response in accord with the very constitution of the reality at hand, thereby facilitating reason in accomplishing its work in fidelity to the demands of truth? Aquinas himself notes that “the fact that something appears good in particular to reason, whereas it is not good, is due to a passion.”14 Passion can even obstruct a man’s reason from considering in particular what he knows in general; passion in effect fetters the reason, thereby preventing it from arguing from the appropriate premiss. An incontinent man, for example, may well be aware that to fornicate is wrong, but on account of passion be blind to the fact that this particular act is one of fornication and therefore immoral. This happens because, instead of reasoning from the universal premiss “No fornication is lawful,” the incontinent man employs the premise “Pleasure is to be pursued.” We in effect reason about the universal proposition which is “suggested by the inclination of the passion,”15 and reason to a conclusion accordingly.Thomas explicitly refers to this argument, which occurs in his treatise on the passions, in his treatment of the natural law.Although the general principles of the natural law, in the abstract, cannot be blotted out from human hearts, they can be eradicated in the case of a particular action,“insofar as reason is hindered from applying the general principle to a particular point of practice, on account of concupiscence or some other passion.”16 In order that the conclusion of practical reason may in fact be in accord with the particular objective reality at hand, “a right appetite of the end” is required so that reason “may hold itself aright in respect of principles, i.e., the ends, on which it builds its argument.”17 We ought to bear in mind, with regard to all that we have said thus far, that reason always remains the first principle of human acts; all other principles of human acts are subordinate to reason, but in various ways. Some, 14 ST I–II, q. 77, a. 2, ad 2. Elsewhere he states that “a man is changed as to his disposition according to the passions of the sense appetite. Hence something seems fitting to man when experiencing a certain passion which would not seem so with the passion absent; for example, something seems good to a man when angry which does not seem so when he is calm. In this way, on the part of the object, the sense appetite moves the will” (ST I–II, q. 9, a. 2). 15 ST I–II, q. 77, a. 2, ad 4. 16 ST I–II, q. 94, a. 6. 17 ST I–II, q. 58, a. 3, ad 2. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 841 such as healthy bodily members, obey reason without resistance, “for as soon as reason commands, the hand or the foot proceeds to action.”18 In contrast to healthy limbs, “the appetitive faculty obeys the reason, not blindly, but with a certain power of opposition.”19 Thomas cites Aristotle’s analogy of the exercise of political power, whereby a man rules over free subjects who enjoy a certain right of opposition, in order to elucidate the relationship obtaining between reason and the passions. Reason, for example, might dictate that a special diet is necessary if one is to regain or to maintain one’s health; this demand, however, cannot take effect until the sensitive appetite approves of it and translates it into actual practice. Insofar as the passions do not follow the lead of reason, therefore, they impede its judgement. When however they do follow the judgement of reason, they facilitate the execution of its command since they are inclined to the good which is in accord with reason. Moreover, as Mark D. Jordan tells us,“so far as the passions are brought under right reason, they increase the exercise of reason and so nearness to the good.”20 It is precisely this inclination of the appetitive faculty to the good which is in accord with reason that constitutes moral virtue. Moral virtue is not simply that appetitive condition which inclines a man to what is in accord with right reason; in order to count as moral virtue it must be joined with right reason. Moral habits are “to be considered as virtues insofar as they are in conformity with reason.”21 The movements of passion furnish the matter of moral virtue, while moral virtue itself is constituted by the habitus of choosing informed by the rule of right reason. As Gondreau puts it, “reason’s penetration into sensibility helps the concupiscible and irascible powers engage actively in the work of virtue, whereby they desire themselves the good of reason and where they exercise their proper activity within the arena of virtuous duty.”22 Grace, Affectivity, and Our Knowledge of the Good At the beginning of his treatment of grace in the Summa theologiae, Thomas deals with the question of the relationship obtaining between grace and knowledge. He tell us that the act of the intellect is like that of any created being in that it depends upon God in two ways:“[F]irst, inasmuch as it is from Him that it has the form whereby it acts; secondly, 18 ST I–II, q. 58, a. 2. 19 Ibid. 20 Mark D. Jordan, “Aquinas’s Construction of a Moral Account of the Passions,” Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie 33 (1986): 92. 21 ST I–II, q. 58, a. 2. See I–II, q. 61, a. 2; also II–II, q. 141, a. 6. 22 Gondreau, The Passions of Christ’s Soul, 281. Kevin E. O’Reilly 842 inasmuch as it is moved by Him to act.”23 God of course enlightens the soul with natural light in the case of natural knowledge, but we ought not to confuse this light with that of grace. A new light added to the natural light of reason is not required in order to know the truth in all things, but only in the case of those that surpass the bounds of natural knowledge. In the latter case, “the light of grace or prophecy which is called the light of grace, inasmuch as it is added to nature,”24 is needed. By grace the nature of the soul is transformed so as to participate in the divine nature, “after a manner of likeness, through a certain regeneration or re-creation.”25 The recipient of grace is thus enabled in his intellective power to participate in the divine knowledge through the virtue of faith and in his power of will to participate in the divine love through the virtue of charity. Grace, however, is to some extent imperfect, for it does not heal man completely: although the mind is healed by grace, human nature “remains corrupted and poisoned in the flesh, whereby it serves the law of sin (Rom 7:25).”26 Even when transformed by grace, the intellect is beset by the darkness of ignorance since it cannot know the various possible outcomes of events or know fully what is for our good. Grace, however, by uniting man to God, affords him the care and guidance of “God,Who knows and can do all things.”27 This care and guidance of course pertains to divine providence, whereby God watches over and cares for men in all things—in this case with regard to all that lies beyond their knowledge and capability. Moreover, it is clear that the healing effects of grace in the mind can be vitiated on account of the corruption of the flesh which is a constitutive feature of human existence.Thomas’s hylomorphic conception of human nature can be adduced in order to support this claim: the human person is a unitary composite being, comprising both body and soul; he is a psychosomatic unity. We cannot therefore divorce the sensible dimension of human life from the psychic when we enter the dispensation of grace.28 Grace perfects human nature, it does not destroy it. In the supernatural order, as in the natural, it is necessary to acknowledge the move23 ST I–II, q. 109, a. 1. 24 Ibid. 25 ST I–II, q. 110, a. 4. 26 ST I–II, q. 109, a. 9. 27 See ST I–II, q. 109, a. 9. 28 For a contemporary phenomenological discussion of this point, a discussion which is hugely indebted to Aristotle and Aquinas, see Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person, trans. Andrzej Potocki (London: D. Reidel, 1979), 187–258. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 843 ments of sensitive affectivity in the moral life. In both of these orders disordered sensitive affectivity serves to undermine the life of reason. Recta ratio and the Theological Virtue of Faith In order for reason to attain the status of recta ratio it is not enough that it unfold in the context of the natural virtues, for these are unable to confer upon it union with its proper Final End, namely God as Father, Son and Holy Spirit. If ratio denotes man’s power to grasp reality then, as Pieper points out as he comments on Thomas, it cannot be “that reason which arbitrarily restricts itself to the province of purely natural cognition.”29 Ratio, in its broadest sense, refers to man’s power to grasp reality in its fullness.Thus, Pieper continues: [M]an grasps reality not only in natural cognition but also—and this reality is a higher object of knowledge and the process of grasping it a higher process—by faith in the revelation of God. If therefore the Summa Theologica states that Christ is the chief Lord (principalis Dominus), the first owner of our bodies, and that one who uses his body in a manner contrary to order, injures Christ the Lord Himself,Thomas is not of the opinion that this proposition exceeds the pattern of “mere” rational order, but rather that for Christian thought to be guided by divine revelation is the very highest form of “accord with reason”—this in spite of the fact that elsewhere Thomas knows how to distinguish sharply between natural and supernatural cognition. “The order of reason,” accordingly, is the order which corresponds to the reality made evident to man through faith and knowledge.30 Time and space do not permit an extensive treatment of the theological virtue of faith. Its ecclesial context, however, ought to be signalled very clearly. Although Thomas does not develop an explicit ecclesiology, it is clear that the Church is for him “the background to sacrament, grace, and life where the Incarnation continues in history after the Ascension of the risen Christ.”31 The Holy Spirit governs the universal Church:“If we say: ‘In’ the Holy Catholic Church, this must be taken as verified insofar as our faith is directed to the Holy Ghost,Who sanctifies the Church; so that the sense is: I believe in the Holy Ghost sanctifying the Church.”32 Since the 29 Joseph Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1966), 156. 30 Ibid. 31 Thomas F. O’Meara, O.P., “Theology of the Church,” in The Theology of Thomas Aquinas, ed. Rik van Nieuwenhove and Joseph Wawrykow (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005). 32 ST II–II, q. 1, a. 9 ad 5. Kevin E. O’Reilly 844 Holy Spirit is the Spirit of truth, the Church therefore cannot err.Accordingly, since the creed or symbol has been published by the authority of the universal church it can contain nothing defective.33 Those who think that the symbol offers a seeming alternative to the truth of faith found in Sacred Scripture have misunderstood the relationship between the various symbols and Holy Scripture. The truth of faith is indeed contained in Scripture, but “diffusely, under various modes of expression, and sometimes obscurely.” Since many simply would be unable to afford the time necessary in order to understand the truth of faith as it is presented there, “it was necessary to gather together a clear summary from the sayings of Holy Writ, to be proposed to the belief of all. This indeed was no addition to Holy Writ, but something taken from it.”34 With regard to this point, we ought to bear in mind that the term “Scripture” is understood differently by Thomas than it is by theologians of our own time. For Thomas Holy Scripture encompasses God’s revelation in the Old and New Testaments and its transmission in the Church. Consequently, he does not perceive any clear-cut separation between Scripture, on the one hand, and the authoritative documents formulated by the Church throughout the course of her history.This intertwining of Scripture and Tradition may well appear strange to a postmodern sensibility, but we ought to bear in mind that for Aquinas the tradition of the Church is to a large extent “the tradition of explaining Scripture.”35 Indeed, as Valkenberg tells us, In this vein, the Church and its tradition can be seen as vehicles for receiving and transmitting the Scriptures in a liturgical and doctrinal setting. The Fathers and Teachers of the Church, the Synods and the Magisterial documents, they are all involved in this sacra doctrina: it is a continuing process of handing down the words of God.36 In our own times, Humanae Vitae, as a magisterial document of the highest authority, forms part of this process. Since faith, which perfects the intellect, is essentially ecclesial in its character, it follows that immersion within the life of the Church is necessary for right judgment concerning reality in its totality. Connaturality with the mind of the Church, the explicator of Scripture and the receptor and transmitter of Tradition, furnishes the necessary condition for opti33 ST I–II, q. 1, a. 9, sed contra. 34 ST II–II, q. 1, a. 9, ad 1. 35 Wilhelmus G. B. M.Valkenberg, Words of the Living God: Place and Function of Holy Scripture in the Theology of St.Thomas Aquinas (Leuven: Peeters, 2000), 11. 36 Ibid. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 845 mum functioning of the life of the intellect.37 This condition extends to every member of the Church, including—nay, especially—to theologians. The following comment from Thomas is highly instructive in this regard: [I]t must be said that the custom of the Church has the greatest authority which must be followed in all things, because even the very teaching of the catholic theologians has authority from the Church. Hence we should stand more on the Church’s custom than on the authority of Augustine or Jerome or some other teacher.38 In this regard,Valkenberg’s words, already quoted, are of note: [T]he Church and its tradition can be seen as vehicles for receiving and transmitting the Scriptures in a liturgical and doctrinal setting. The Fathers and Teachers of the Church, the Synods and the Magisterial documents, they are all involved in this sacra doctrina : it is a continuing process of handing down the words of God.39 Grace, nevertheless, never leaves behind the order of nature. Human freedom remains in tact, while those forces that influence man in his natural constitution can never be annulled. In this regard we have in mind specifically the role of virtue in coming to knowledge of the demands of the natural law. The dynamic interplay between nature and grace is indeed highly complex and cannot form a part of our investigation here. It suffices to note that religious conversion has as its natural concomitant a moral transformation—any conversion to the faith which lacks this transformation must be deemed to be suspect. On the other hand, those forces that bear upon man in his natural constitution can either cooperate with the life of grace or undermine it. Our own times have given rise to various forces that unfortunately serve the latter purpose. Over a period of time they have altered the configuration of the affective structure of many individuals including, unfortunately, a significant proportion of the faithful.They have consequently undermined perception of what constitutes the true good in various domains of human existence, particularly the sexual. Arguably, the confusion engendered by theological dissent from the teaching of Humanae Vitae has been one important source for the practical 37 See Kevin E. O’Reilly, “Objective Prejudice: St. Thomas on the Elevation by Grace of the Life of Reason,” Angelicum 84 (2007): 59–95, for an extended argument supporting this contention. 38 Aquinas, Quodl., 2, 4, 2. 39 Valkenburg, Words of the Living God, 11. Kevin E. O’Reilly 846 rejection of the Church’s teaching on contraception by all too many Catholics.40 Whatever may the merits of that assertion, the consequences in the order of moral psychology of the separation of the unitive and procreative aspects of the conjugal act cannot be underestimated. John Paul II has of course outlined these consequences in detail in his Love and Responsibility. As a prelude to my own treatment of the effect of lust—as expounded in the texts of St. Thomas—on the failure to appreciate the teaching of Humanae Vitae, which lust has its roots in the uncoupling of the unitive and procreative aspect of the marital act, let me quote briefly from this important text: If the possibility of parenthood is deliberately excluded from marital relations, the character of the relationship between the partners automatically changes. The change is away from unification in love and in the direction of mutual, or rather, bilateral,‘enjoyment’. . . .When a man and a woman entirely reject the idea that he may become a father and she a mother, when they deliberately exclude the possibility of parenthood from their relationship, the danger arises that objectively speaking there will be nothing left except ‘utilisation for pleasure’, of which the object will be a person.41 Chastity, Lust, and the Life of Reason Thomas tells us that the vice which most undermines the life of reason and will is lust, for “the effect of the vice of lust is that the lower appetite, namely the concupiscible, is most vehemently intent on its object, to wit, the object of pleasure, on account of the vehemence of the pleasure.”42 When the attention of the soul is strongly directed to the activity of a lower power, its higher powers are correspondingly weakened in their operation. Consequently, Thomas tells us, “when the whole attention of the soul is drawn to lower powers (i.e., the concupiscible power and the 40 But see also note 3 above. 41 Karol Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, trans. H.T.Willetts (London: Collins, 1981), 228. This dynamic of “utilization for pleasure” has its roots in original sin. As John Paul II tells us: “It is as if the personal profile of masculinity and femininity, which before [the Fall] had highlighted the meaning of the body for a full communion of persons, had made the way only for the sensation of sexuality with regard to the other human being. It is as if sexuality became an obstacle in the personal relationship of man and woman” (The Theology of the Body: Human Love in the Divine Plan [Boston: Pauline Books and Media, 1997], 119. General audience of June 4, 1980). Desire for personal communion is directed by lust to the satisfaction of bodily desire, “often at the cost of a real and full communion of persons” (ibid., 123). 42 ST II–II, q. 153, a. 5. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 847 sense of touch) in acts of sexual lust because of the strong pleasure therein, the higher powers, namely, reason and the will, necessarily suffer deficiency.”43 Lust contracts dullness of judgement by plunging man’s sense into earthly things, “whereby his sense is rendered incapable of perceiving divine things, according to 1 Corinthians 2:14: The sensual man perceiveth not these things that are of the Spirit of God.”44 This dullness of sense in judging, that is to say, folly, is analogous to the sense of taste which is infected by an evil humour and which renders things sweet in themselves to be without savour for the one afflicted by this infected sense.Thomas’s description of the negative impact of lust on reason and will is marked by profound psychological insight. On the part of reason, the four acts in matters of action are adversely affected: the simple understanding which apprehends some end as good, counsel about what is to be done for the sake of the end, judgement about things to be done, and reason’s command about the thing to be done are all undermined by lust.45 In other words, rectitude of will, which provides those ends to which man ought rightly to be disposed, is undermined, as are the three steps which constitute prudence’s “transformation of truth into decisions corresponding to reality.”46 The disordering of the will occurs as a result of a twofold inordinate act occasioned by lust. On the one hand, there is the pleasure which a man desires inordinately and the concomitant hatred of God on account of his having forbidden the desired pleasure. 43 De malo, 15, 4.Thomas, quoting Gregory the Great’s Moralia, lists the eight daugh- ters of lust: “blindness of mind, lack of consideration, inconstancy, temerity, selflove, hatred of God, love of this world, and despair of the next” (ibid.). 44 ST II–II, q. 46, a. 2. 45 ST II–II, q. 153, a. 5: “Now the reason has four acts in matters of action. First there is simple understanding, which apprehends some end as good, and this act is hindered by lust, according to Daniel 13:56, ‘Beauty hath deceived thee, and lust hath perverted thy heart.’ In this respect we have blindness of mind.The second act is counsel about what is to be done for the sake of the end: and this is also hindered by the concupiscence of lust. Hence Terence says (Eunuch., act 1, sc. 1), speaking of lecherous love:‘The thing admits of neither counsel nor moderation, thou canst not control it by counselling.’ In this respect there is rashness, which denotes absence of counsel. . . .The third act is judgment about the things to be done, and this again is hindered by lust. For it is said of the lustful old men (Dan 13:9):‘They perverted their own mind . . . that they might not . . . remember just judgments.’ In this respect there is thoughtlessness. The fourth act is the reason’s command about the thing to be done, and this also is impeded by lust, insofar as being carried away by concupiscence, a man is hindered from doing what his reason ordered to be done.” See also De malo 15, 4. 46 Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues, 162. 848 Kevin E. O’Reilly On the other hand there is the desire for those things that are directed to the end.47 The net result is well summarized by Joseph Pieper: Unchaste abandon and the self-surrender of the soul to the world of sensuality paralyzes the primordial powers of the moral person: the ability to perceive, in silence, the call of reality, and to make, in the retreat of this silence, the decision appropriate to the concrete situation of concrete action.48 One cannot overstate the blinding effects of unchastity: “This blindness is of the essence of unchastity itself, which is by its very nature destructive. It is not its outward effect and consequence, but its immanent and essential property.”49 Nevertheless, one ought to distinguish between chastity as temperentia or unchastity as intemperentia, on the one hand, and chastity as continentia or unchastity as incontinentia, on the other. The former is the fruit of a deep-seated attitude in man, an attitude which is as it were second nature to him.The latter results from an inclination which has as yet not become integrated into the existential core of man. Continent chastity entails a form of strenuous control, while incontinent unchastity exhibits a mere lack of control. Just as the former does not constitute the perfected virtue of temperance and moderation, neither does the latter instantiate consummate intemperance. The sensitive appetite of the continently chaste man resists reason by its evil desires: it is merely by force of will that he restrains his concupiscence; in contrast, the sensitive appetite is obedient to the reason of the temperately chaste man.50 The good of reason that penetrates down into the sensitive appetite is greater than that which reaches the will alone.51 Continence is less perfect than temperance because, as Pieper puts it, “by the former, the directing power of 47 ST II–II, q. 153, a. 5.We should note that Thomas conceives the human being as ontologically unitary in nature. He therefore views the cognitive and volitional activities of the soul as inseparable in their principle, even though they constitute distinct operations.There is therefore no such thing as pure reason or pure will; rather, they mutually inform one another. For Thomas, the spiritual activity of man is a synthesis of the acts of intellect and will. If either functions in a defective manner, the other will necessarily be distorted in its operation. 48 Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues, 160. 49 Ibid. One ought to be clear, along with Pieper, that “it is not reference to the province of sexuality that produces the blindness and deafness brought about by unchastity”; the destructiveness, rather, “lies in the fact that unchastity constricts man and thus renders him incapable of seeing objective reality” (ibid., 160–61). 50 See ST II–II, q. 155, a. 4. 51 See ST II–II, q. 155, a. 4, ad 3. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 849 reason has been able to mold only the conscious will, but not yet the sensual urge, whereas by the latter will and urge are both stamped with ‘rational order.’ ”52 The source of ignorance of the incontinent and the intemperate man differs: in the case of the former it arises from the appetite being inclined to something by passion while, in the case of the latter, it issues from habit. The intemperate man is characterized by the greater degree of ignorance. Thomas adduces two reasons in support of this contention. Firstly, the ignorance of the incontinent man lasts only as long as the passion endures, “just as an attack of intermittent fever lasts as long as the humor is disturbed,” whereas the ignorance of the intemperate man never ceases on account of its being rooted in habit,“wherefore it is likened to phthisis or any chronic disease.”53 Secondly, while “the ignorance of the incontinent man regards some particular detail of choice, that of the intemperate man regards the end itself.”54 In other words, the incontinent man is better than the intemperate man because, as Aristotle states, “he retains the best principle, to wit, the right estimate of the end.”55 It might seem that the sin of incontinence is more incurable than the sin of intemperance and that the incontinent man sins more gravely than the intemperate man: For a person’s sin is cured by admonishment and correction, which are seemingly no good to the incontinent man, since he knows he is doing wrong, and does wrong notwithstanding: whereas it seems to the intemperate man that he is doing well, so that it were good for him to be admonished.56 It must be borne in mind, however, that mere knowledge does not suffice to cure the incontinent man; the inward assistance of grace, “which quenches concupiscence,” is also required in addition to “the external remedy of admonishment and correction, which induce him to begin to resist his desires, so that concupiscence is weakened.”57 The intemperate man can be cured by these same means, but with greater difficulty.There are two reasons for this greater difficulty. Firstly, his reason is corrupt as regards its estimation of the last end, which in the practical domain functions as a first principle. And just as “it is more difficult to bring back to 52 Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues, 163. 53 ST II–II, q. 156, a. 3, ad 1. 54 Ibid. 55 Ibid. See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, bk. 7, ch. 8. 56 ST II–II, q. 156, a. 3, obj. 2. 57 ST II–II, q. 156, a. 3, ad 2. 850 Kevin E. O’Reilly the truth one who errs as to the principle,” so too “in practical matters with one who errs in regard to the end”58 Secondly, the inclination of the habit of the intemperate man issues from a habit, which is difficult to eradicate, while that of the incontinent man arises from passion, which is more easily controlled and suppressed. Chastity and a Proper Vision of Family Life At this juncture, I would like to examine briefly how Thomas’s moral psychology in relation to chastity and lust can afford us a deeper appreciation of Humanae Vitae’s reflections on self-mastery and chastity. Paul VI is clearly aware that the weakness of incontinence afflicts most human beings. When prophetically pointing out how easy it would be “[for many] to justify behavior leading to marital infidelity or to a gradual weakening in the discipline of morals,” he calls attention to “human weakness” and to the “temptation” to which human beings, particularly the young, are prone.59 As already indicated in our brief quotation from John Paul II, the uncoupling of the unitive and procreative aspects of the marital act gives rise to a utilitarian attitude toward one’s spouse: bilateral pleasure in the body and sex become the order of the day. Expressed in more traditional categories the vice of lust, along with that blinding of reason which is its essential property, is unleashed. Moral realism reigns supreme in the encyclical when it states that “Not much experience is needed to understand human weakness and to comprehend that human beings, especially the young, are so susceptible to temptation that they need to be encouraged to keep the moral law. It is wrong to make it easy for them to violate the law.”60 It would be foolish to presume that most people, particularly the young, have reached the stage where the virtue of chastity engages not simply the intellect but also the sensitive appetite and that they never experience sensitive inclinations that are incompatible with their state of life. In other words, continence and not temperance is most likely to be the most one can expect from them. Most people, moreover, are not Kantian self-legislating agents and moral wisdom is not distributed in a democratic fashion. It therefore falls to the lot of those who have the greatest purchase on that wisdom to provide suitable guidance for their fellow human beings. In this way one can hope to limit the cause of moral failure in the realm of sexual relations to the realm of incontinence. Since the incontinent man sins 58 Ibid. 59 Humanae Vitae, §17. 60 Ibid. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 851 through passion, once this passion passes he repents;61 the incontinently unchaste man does not lose sight of the end with respect to sexual relations and can therefore continue to struggle with the disordered inclinations of his sensitive appetite. It is to be hoped, moreover, that through habituation to the discipline of the chaste life, facilitated by the cultivation of conditions that promote chastity and discriminate against unchastity, the seal of reason will eventually extend not simply to the will but also to the sensitive appetite. In other words, it is to be hoped that situations that once provoked a struggle within his fragmented being will at length evoke pleasure in espousing the true good of human being. In that case, the incontinently unchaste man will have become temperately chaste. Failure to make it difficult to violate the moral law on the part of those who have authority in society is wrong since it creates the conditions in which citizens can easily become habituated to immoral practices. This fact applies in particular to matters which touch upon the virtue of chastity, for when the incontinently unchaste man becomes habituated to being unchaste on account of his frequent encounters with temptation, he naturally becomes intemperately unchaste.The strength of resistance on the part of the continently chaste man can likewise be undermined and, over a period of time, it is not impossible that he too can become intemperately chaste; such a possibility is open even to the temperately chaste man. And we have outlined the deleterious psychological impact of such intemperance: the true good of man, which furnishes the first principle of prudential reason, is no longer recognized as such; indeed, that which is objectively harmful to his well-being appears to him as self-evidently good. Little wonder, therefore, that Paul VI advises “educators and all others whose right and duty it is to be concerned about the common good.”62 In continuity with the moral wisdom of the tradition which we have seen St. Thomas expound, he recognizes the need “to work to create conditions favourable to the cultivation of chastity, so that the norms of the moral order might be kept and true freedom might prevail over licence.”63 By no stretch of the imagination could it be maintained that conditions favourable to the cultivation of chastity have been fostered in the developed world since the promulgation of Humanae Vitae.While Paul VI could condemn the forms of entertainment at that time that “arouse man’s [base] passions and that foster dissolute morals, such as obscene 61 ST II–II, q. 156, a. 3. 62 Humanae Vitae, §22. 63 Ibid. Kevin E. O’Reilly 852 literature and corrupt theatrical and film productions,”64 the situation has worsened considerably since then. Thus, for example, various television series which have a grip on the popular imagination present a vision of reality in which sexual dissoluteness reigns supreme. It is difficult to encounter a film in which there are not sexually graphic scenes. Pornographic publications abound. In the name of child protection, an increasing number of primary school pupils are given sexual instruction. Information campaigns aimed at countering the transmission of sexually transmitted diseases accept and communicate as self-evident that there is nothing wrong with casual sex and that it is a constitutive component of the lifestyle of most “normal” people. We witness public authorities, in some cases, leading the way in legislating for a more “enlightened” attitude to the gay lifestyle, thereby introducing into the family “practices opposed to the natural and divine law.”65 One could continue the litany. Little wonder therefore that there is a diminished appreciation, even on the part of many Catholics, of the sublime truth of the Church’s teaching on human sexuality. In recent times there has grown an appreciation of the fact that there is no such thing as pure reason, pace Kant, thanks especially to the work of Hans-Georg Gadamer.This notion is however not a novel one in the history of western thought and is clearly to be found in Aristotle and Thomas, albeit implicitly.66 This point ought to be clear from our exposition of Thomas’s understanding of the influence of faith and of the passions on the life of reason. There is arguably however also a recognition that reason cannot escape the influence of the social practices which furnish the context in which it necessarily operates.67 Growing up in a society which in large part rejects Church teaching on issues of marriage and sexuality, young people are more liable to come to regard this teaching as selfevidently wrong, insofar as they have any familiarity with it at all. Expressed in terms of the syllogistic structure of human action, the major premise is often informed by a vision of the place of sexuality in human life that is heavily coloured by the vice of lust.This vision is formulated concisely by John Paul II: “When carnal desire is not kept within the bounds of the appetitus concupiscibilis but communicates itself to the will, on which it tries to impose its characteristic attitude to the object, it orients the subject first towards ‘the body and sex’ and secondly toward ‘enjoyment.’ ”68 The major 64 Ibid. 65 Humanae Vitae, §23. 66 See O’Reilly, “Objective Prejudice,” 59–95. 67 See O’Reilly, “The Vision of Virtue and Knowledge of the Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas,” Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 41–66. 68 John Paul II, Love and Responsibility, 149. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 853 premise of the practical syllogism might therefore receive the following formulation: Any attractive body is a legitimate object of pursuit for the purpose of sexual gratification.69 Pleasure is the order of the day and, as John Paul II tells us, “all else—the ‘person,’ that person’s ‘body,’ ‘femininity’ or ‘masculinity’—is only a means to it.”70 Notions of personal communion are jettisoned and men and women “remain only an object of attraction, in a certain sense as happens in the world of living beings, which, like man, have received the blessing of fertility.”71 Conclusion The thrust of my argument in this essay has been to show how human reason is undermined by the vice of lust.While the teaching of the encyclical can clearly be seen to be in accord with right reason by those endowed with the same on account of that colouring of the life of reason which is the fruit of a rightly ordered affective structure, which in turn is the fruit of a life of moral virtue and in particular of a life lived in accordance with the virtue of chastity, those whose reason is infected by lust are rendered blind to the truth of this teaching.The following words from Archbishop Desmond Connell offer a concise portrayal of the further consequences of the moral blindness engendered by a contraceptive mentality and bear negative testimony to the fact that continence “always appears and acts in connection with the other virtues (nexus virtutum), and therefore in connection with prudence, justice, fortitude, and above all with charity”:72 Approval of contraception logically extends the blessing of moral approval to the sexual revolution, which has resulted in the chaos of 69 The following passage from John Paul II on the deforming effects of carnal concupiscence helps to elucidate the point just made: “For sensuality furnishes love with ‘material,’ but material which can only be shaped by the appropriate creative activity on the part of the will.Without this there can be no love, there is only the raw material which is used up by carnal concupiscence as it seeks an ‘outlet.’ This results in actions, interior and exterior, which have as their sole object the sexual values connected with a person, and which take the direction of mere sensuality—‘the body as a possible object of enjoyment.’ Their relation to the person is therefore a utilitarian, a ‘consumer’ approach. They make the person an object of enjoyment. Whether the acts are purely internal or partly external depends in large measure on the sensual make-up of the person concerned” (Love and Responsibility, 151). 70 Ibid., 155. See also 159: “Concupiscence is a consistent tendency to see persons of the other sex through the prism of sexuality alone, as ‘objects of potential enjoyment.’ ” 71 John Paul II, Theology of the Body, 125 (General audience of July 23, 1980). 72 Ibid., 409 (General audience of October 24, 1984). Kevin E. O’Reilly 854 broken families, co-habitation, promiscuity, uncertainty about the limits that define the nature of the family. It has helped to shape a society of widespread divorce, and encouraged such resentment against new life in the womb as to create blindness to the injustice of abortion. Addiction to sex as an absolute good in itself prompts the kind of fascination that flirts with pornography and, at times, even takes the plunge that defiles the minds of the reading and viewing public through the communications and entertainment media. Clouded in a turbulent fog of invasive emotion, they become blind to spiritual reality, and, accepting a degraded dignity as normal, they lose their affinity with the things of God.The currency of the language of love is devalued and placed on a par with the language of lust.73 The foregoing phenomena certainly negate the assumption that “underlying human sexuality is a Christoform natural law which orders persons to an ecstatic generosity that moderates domination and promotes life,”74 an assumption clearly operative in Humanae Vitae as evidenced by the claim that “if both essential meanings [ratio] are preserved, that of union and procreation, the conjugal act fully maintains its capacity for [fostering] true mutual love and its ordination to the highest mission [munus] of parenthood, to which man is called.”75 The blinding of reason by lust to the Christoform splendour of the natural law has profound ramifications for the life of society, a point made in Humanae Vitae 76 and borne out by the litany quoted above. Likewise, as we have also argued, the ethos of society in our own times—marked by that Cartesian dualism that seeks to dominate and manipulate the material conditions of being—undermines the ability of many to perceive moral truth in the area of sexuality.77 The following truth, delineated in Veritatis Splendor, becomes obscured to their moral vision: Only in reference to the human person in his “unified totality,” that is, as “a soul which expresses itself in a body and a body informed by an immortal spirit,” can the specifically human meaning of the body be grasped. Indeed, natural inclinations take on moral relevance only insofar as they refer to the human person and his authentic fulfilment, a fulfilment which for that matter can take place always and only in 73 Archbishop Desmond Connell, “Reflections on Humanae Vitae,” Irish Theological Quarterly 64 (1999): 304. 74 G. J. McAleer, Ecstatic Morality and Sexual Politics: A Catholic and Antitotalitarian Theory of the Body (New York: Fordham University Press, 2005), 116. 75 Humanae Vitae, §12. 76 Humanae Vitae, §17. 77 For a masterful treatment of the political ramifications of dualistic anthropology, see McAleer, Ecstatic Morality, 156–87. Moral Psychology and Rejection of Humanae Vitae 855 human nature. By rejecting all manipulations of corporeity which alter its human meaning, the Church serves man and shows him the path of true love, the only path on which he can find the true God.78 The powers of concupiscence, when given free reign, since they are identical to the practical dynamics that issue from an anthropological dualism, necessarily give existential support to the erroneous belief that such dualism is in keeping with the truth of human nature.They thereby “detach the language of the body from the truth, that is, they try to falsify it.” In contrast, the power of love “strengthens it ever anew in that truth, so that the mystery of the redemption of the body can bear fruit in it.”79 This essay has attempted simply to understand how men of our time have failed to appreciate a teaching which is in accord with reason, a teaching which prophetically foresaw the effects of its own rejection. Such an approach might be deemed somewhat negative in its tenor, a criticism that the author accepts. Such negativity is however grounded in the anthropology and the moral realism that inform Humanae Vitae, both of which in turn are grounded in a metaphysical realism. Such realism dictates that there are limits to the extent to which humans can violate the dictates of the natural law without undermining their own well-being, both physical and psychological. History offers examples of how the collapse of civilizations on account of moral dissoluteness contained within it the seeds of a renewed appreciation of the moral law.There comes a point when continued transgression of the moral law becomes impossible on account of its destructive consequences and, even in the absence of an appreciation of the natural law, decadent civilizations are compelled to obey it in spite of themselves. This process entails a habituation to virtuous practice that serves once again to awaken the moral vision of civilizations. There are indications that the same dynamic is about to unfold once again, although not 78 Veritatis Splendor, §50. 79 John Paul II, Theology of the Body, 406. General audience of October 10, 1984. Further on, John Paul II tells us that continence, the expression of a rightly ordered affectivity animated by true love, is “the fundamental condition for the reciprocal language of the body to remain in the truth and for the couple to ‘defer to one another out of reverence for Christ,’ according to the words of Scripture (Eph 5:21). This ‘deferring to one another’ means the common concern for the truth of the language of the body” ( John Paul II, Theology of the Body, 408). The fact that continence is accompanied by “the gift of the fear of God (a gift of the Holy Spirit)” perhaps gives weight to the idea that the practical rejection of the teaching of Humanae Vitae, with its attendant unleashing of the psychological dynamics of lust, has been responsible for the diminished levels of immersion of the faithful in the life of the Church in the last few decades. See also ST II–II, q. 45, aa. 2 and 3. 856 Kevin E. O’Reilly yet in the developed world: perhaps I can simply instance the abstinence campaign that has yielded such great success in the fight against AIDS in Uganda. One can only hope that the penetrating moral vision that is the fruit of chastity and that illumines Humanae Vitae from beginning to end may have once again been ignited on the African continent and that it may N&V spread to the so-called developed world. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 857–878 857 Integration and Transcendence of the Person in the (Marital) Act A DRIAN J. R EIMERS University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana T HE QUESTION that lay at the basis of John Paul II’s ethics and anthropology is that of love, and following the Second Vatican Council’s teaching, John Paul II taught that love is realized in sincere, disinterested gift of self.1 This gift of self is realized in acts, by which the person accomplishes his will and realizes his intentions. In his earlier philosophical treatise Person and Act 2 our author proposes a thoroughgoing account of the essence of this experience, “a human being acts,” in order to account for the integration and transcendence of the person in act. Through such an analysis he intends to provide, as the basis of his personalistic ethics, an adequate account of the person as given in experience. In his ethical analysis of marital love, Love and Responsibility, and then later in his theology of the body audiences, John Paul II argues that the most complete and thoroughgoing gift of self between human persons in this life is that gift made by husband and wife in their marriage vows, a gift that is realized and represented most perfectly in the physical act by 1 Vatican II, Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern World Gaudium et Spes, §24. See Karol Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, trans. H. T. Willetts, (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993) (in Polish: Mil ość i odpowiedzialność [Krakow: Wydawnicto, 1960]), 95–100, 125–26; John Paul II, Redemptor Hominis, §21; idem, Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books & Media, 1006), 15:1–3, 17:5–6, 32:4, etc. 2 Karol Wojtyla, Osoba i czyn (Lublin:Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL, 2000). Unless otherwise noted, citations for this article are from “Persona e atto,” in Karol Wojtyla, Metafisica della persona:tutte le opera filosofiche e saggi integrativi, ed. G. Reale and T. Styczeń (Milan: R. C. S. Libri S.p.A., 2003), 831–1216, cited in the text as Person and Act. / 858 Adrian J. Reimers which the marriage is consummated. In this paper we will look at that specific act by which is expressed the complete and mutual gift of self in marriage, with particular attention to the concepts of integration and transcendence, as developed in Person and Act. In doing so, I hope to show the essential continuity between that dense and difficult philosophical work on the human person and his more accessible studies on love and sexual expression The Human Act A word on Wojtyla’s phenomenological method is in order here. In the tradition of Husserl’s original inspiration—“Back to the things themselves”—Karol Wojtyla intends to examine this particular datum of experience, “a human being acts,” an experience that each of us has from the subjective perspective, as we undertake our own acts, as well as from the objective, observing the acts of others. He intends to investigate, therefore, what must pertain to this experience—its phenomenological essence—in order to extract from the analysis an account of the person as moral subject. Although his works indicate the necessity of a metaphysical account of the person and his acts,3 for the purposes of Person and Act he confines himself largely, but not uncritically, to the phenomenological perspective. The Essence of “a Human Being Acts” By the expression “a human being acts”Wojtyla means the kind of experience each of us has innumerable times every day.4 By its essence, this experience,“a human being acts,” is both a subjective event in consciousness and an objectively efficacious cause. The act is a conscious event, something reflected in or given to consciousness, and this is essential to the experience of “a human being acts.” Indeed, the consciousness of the act arises precisely because of the role of the will in commanding the act, or (to use Wojtyla’s terms) “dynamizing” the person, as the common expression “he did it consciously” suggests.5 In consciousness, the interiority of the person comes to the fore in two ways. 3 Karol Wojtyla, “The Degrees of Being from the Point of View of the Phenome- nology of Action,” in Analecta Husserliana:The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research, vol. 11, ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1981), 125, 129; idem,“The Separation of Experience from the Act in Ethics,” in idem, Person and Community: Selected Essays, trans. Theresa Sandock, O.S.M. (New York: Peter Lang, 1993), 42–43; idem, “Persona e atto,” 888, 1064, 1162–63. 4 Wojtyla, “Persona e atto,” 839. 5 Ibid., 864. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 859 Consciousness both mirrors the subject’s experience and also reflects the personhood of the agent. First, one is conscious when he becomes aware of what his senses receive and his organism (his body) feels. Second, and more important for our present considerations, is the reflexive function of consciousness, as consciousness refers its objects back to the acting subject himself, so that he can identify his experiences as his own and as experiences of a self or ego. However, consciousness itself, even as it performs this reflexive function, is not sufficient to form that experience of self, because consciousness remains out of the direct control of the human subject. Rather this task of forming and unifying the self as center of experience must be the work of reason in its application as self-knowledge. Further, consciousness is not itself sufficient to account for the essence of the human act, because consciousness as such is of what “happens in” the person. Without the specific note of agency the experience of “a human being acts” is lost. Wojtyla identifies this note with the moment of efficacy. To distinguish between “what happens in a human being” and “a human being acts,”Wojtyla observes that the human person can be dynamized (set into motion) in two different ways. I lay my hand on a hot burner and jerk it back before I can even think. Having glimpsed an alluring young woman, the young man’s eyes are drawn to her, and he begins to feel hormonally induced stirrings in his body. Such dynamizations of the person are “happenings” that respond to some value (or disvalue); they are not willed or necessarily desired.The psychosomatic organism responds to external stimuli and internal conditions. These happenings are important to us, however, because they present values to which one can respond. On the other hand, the person can also dynamize himself in response to the values presented to him, and by this self-dynamism he acts.We experience this every day.To mount an attack in chess I move my rook to the open file. The woman is attractive, but I am married. I turn away. This acting manifests the faculty of will. It is by the will that the human person dynamizes himself. Although what happens in a human being flows from his nature as an organism in this world, that a human being acts by his own will’s choice means that he transcends the order about him. The person is self-determining, and hence by his will he makes himself to be the person he is, be this for good or evil. By his efficacy, the human person realizes values in the world and for himself. The person, whose objective existence in the world is manifest in his efficacy and whose own will determines his acts, is responsible. He is responsible for what he does in the world and for what he makes of himself. 860 Adrian J. Reimers The Shoals of Materialism and Phenomenalism By his account, Karol Wojtyla seeks to avoid the modern dangers of materialist reductionism and sensationalist phenomenalism. Materialism acknowledges the reality of the act but only as an objective event. The materialist perspective reduces the act to a causal event, itself caused by earlier events. The literature of scientific materialism is quite clear in its insistence that the sense we have of consciously controlling our acts is illusory, that our actions are the results of causal influences over which the mind has no real control.6 Wojtyla’s response to this is to observe that this account denies the very experience of acting. It ignores the awareness of our subjectivity in acting, which is intrinsic to the experience of acting. Karol Wojtyla rejects the determinist thesis as a confusion of the proper reason with its condition.7 Regardless what some third person might say—such as a scientific observer—I am inextricably aware that it is I who want something, think about it, and decide on the act. Someone else may attempt to predict my act, but I cannot. I must choose and perform the act. Without this self-dynamization, I will not perform the act. This perspective of the person in act is critical if we are to understand the essence of “the human being acts.” Phenomenalism commits the opposite error, reducing the person entirely to his consciousness, where what is important is not the interaction with the world but rather inner experience. This perspective is usually accompanied by a phenomenalist view of the world, which regards objective reality as a value-free realm of neutral events and interactions, which are in themselves neither good nor evil.Thus according to Kant’s moral theory, the will is good only by its conformity with universal law and not by what it accomplishes or even attempts.8 But we also find it in phenomenologist Max Scheler, who located morality in the intuition of and response to values. Rather than coldly acknowledging moral duty, Scheler would have the moral agent respond with warm emotion to deep and important values, from which actions spontaneously flow. The good person is he who interiorizes the richest values and lets them guide him. For Scheler as well as Kant, morality is only secondarily related to the effect one’s actions have in the world. Indeed, for Scheler 6 See, for example, Daniel Dennett, Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown, and Company, 1991), 171–76; Francis Crick, The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for the Soul (New York: Charles Scribner and Sons, 1994), 3–5. 7 Wojtyla, “Persona e atto,” 1002. 8 Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, 393–94. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 861 it is a sign of immorality if one is too concerned about “doing good.”9 Wojtyla finds such theories too subjective adequately to describe the essence of the human act, because they ignore the moment of efficacy or efficient causality.10 To put it more simply, we are bodily beings whose acts have consequences. This efficacy is not something extrinsic, but rather it is central to the act.The human act is for some purpose, to realize some value—be this a tasty omelet, a pretty picture, or a convincing lecture. This efficacy manifests what Wojtyla calls “horizontal transcendence,” which is the capacity of the subject to go outside himself toward the objects that represent heterogeneous values.11 The acting person is an agent of change in the world. The Will and Vertical Transcendence A person’s conscious experience is filled with values that attract him, as it were calling on the acting subject to respond. However, these experienced values (what “happens in” the person) are neither self-validating nor integrated with each other. Indeed, values as experienced may work at crosspurposes. I want to lose weight, but the cheesecake is tasty. As a rational being, the person is capable of inquiring about the truth of things,12 and this truth can serve to guide actions and choices. Therefore, the human person needs to seek out the truth about the good. He must transcend the realm of his own subjectivity, of his desires and the influences of other persons and things on him to find the objective truth about the values to which he is inclined to respond.Wojtyla calls this “vertical transcendence,” “which is intrinsic to self-dominion and self-possession as specific structural properties of the person.”13 As such, the person is necessarily free in the sense that he is self-determining.14 Moral choices therefore must be more than simply responses to values. The rational being, a person, is responsible to respond to values presented to him according to the criterion of truth.The truth about the good therefore becomes the foundation for the moral qualification of acts as good or evil.15 9 Max Scheler, Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik: Neuer Versuch der Grundlegung eines ethischen Personalismus (Bern und München: Franke Verlag, 1966), 48. 10 Karol Wojtyla,“The Will in the Analysis of the Ethical Act,” in Person and Community, 3–22; and in the same volume,“The Separation of Experience from the Act in Ethics,” 23–44. 11 Wojtyla, “Persona e atto,” 998. 12 Ibid., 1003. 13 Ibid., 998. 14 Ibid., 1007. 15 Ibid., 1008. 862 Adrian J. Reimers In this context it is important to note that this transcendence does not at all imply a rejection or dismissal of the values presented in human experience, presenting themselves through what happens in the person. Indeed, these values often give life its richness.16 Karol Wojtyla does not anywhere imply that the moral act must spring from an impassive consideration of the truth known by cool reason. To be sure, he warns against the “emotionalization of consciousness,” by which one’s emotional response to the world as experienced overwhelms rational considerations, particularly self-knowledge.17 The task of reason is, however, not to reject the emotional and affective experience of values, but rather to consider them in the light of truth, to determine the truth about the good in the face of experiences that propose, as it were, various values as good. On the basis of this knowledge, the person can then choose freely to shape his own acts and in doing so to form himself.And in forming himself—his own ego or self—he indirectly forms his own consciousness. Because his life is to be centered around truth and goodness, the human being is also a spiritual being that transcends the physical order, directing himself to the good known in truth.This good serves to integrate the person in his act, because his true good is the fitting good, the bonum honestum,18 according to which the values of pleasure (bonum delectibile) and use (bonum utile) can be properly ordered.This does not mean simply that the person must wisely choose the good he wants most and leave the others behind, although this dynamic may sometimes occur. Rather, the good for which the person is called in truth to live for is the bonum honestum, which is the good appropriate to him as a human being, a good that John Paul II identifies with God himself.19 As Creator, God is the origin of all created goods. Indeed, the order of created goods is the order of existence.20 It follows, therefore, that the values presented in experience (by what happens in a person) can be mutually integrated, and with them 16 See Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 109. 17 Wojtyla, “Persona e atto,” 896–903. 18 Karol Wojtyla uses the term “fitting good” or bonum honestum.The German text of the Lublin Lectures (Lubliner Vorlesungen, trans. Annaliese Danka Spranger and Edda Wiener [Stuttgart-Degerloch: Seewald Verlag, 1986]) uses “rechtschaffen.” In “Osoba: Podmiot i wspólotna” (in Karol Wojtyla, Osoba i czyn: oraz inne studia antropologiczne [Lublin:Towarzystwo KUL, 2000], 385),Wojtyla characterizes bonum honestum by the phrase “dobrem w znaceniu bezwzgledç nym i bezinteresownym,” which the English translation renders “the good in an unconditional and disinterested sense.” See Wojtyla, “Person: Subject and Community,” in idem, Person and Community, 230. 19 Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 137–38, 173; John Paul II,Veritatis Splendor, §9. 20 See Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 57. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 863 the person as a self, only in terms of the fitting good. Therefore the integration of the person in his act must ultimately rest on a metaphysical basis, on God as the source of all being. With this very brief summary some of Karol Wojtyla’s key philosophical themes, we may turn to that distinctive act by which the “two become one flesh.” The Marital Act In analyzing the human act, we tend to think in terms of transitive acts, that is, of acts that pass into external matter.21 “Making” is a resultdirected interaction with things: “Break two eggs into a bowl and beat them well, etc.” Similarly, we see acting-together in terms of mutual cooperation:“I’ll hold the beam in place while you hammer in the nails.” The purpose of such acts is to attain some result, and the performance of the act is normally subject to the will’s cool decision. Even if baker’s hands get tired, he must knead the dough a full ten minutes. For several significant reasons, this model of action does not apply well to the marital act. On the other hand, unlike the intransitive acts of which Aristotle and Aquinas speak (sensing, understanding, and the like), the marriage act can indeed have the characteristic of a making, for by it a couple can conceive a child. Let us consider this more closely. First, although conception may result from the marital union, couples seldom engage in relations with the express intention to conceive by this act. Indeed, given the biological conditions, the processes by which the sperm fertilizes the egg, such an intention is beyond their capability intentionally to realize. Second, the incentive to make love ordinarily arises not from some deliberately productive strategy to respond to environmental conditions or states of affairs, but from within as man and wife experience the desire for each other. Attracted by a spouse’s masculinity or femininity, the married person experiences a sexual urge toward the spouse, an urge that frequently manifests itself by incipient physical response. Let us note that this is not (ordinarily) a simple desire for pleasure. More than simple relief of sexual tension, the loving married couple wants to be joined to each other.As a kind of corollary to this, we may note that sexual relations have a note of spontaneity, seldom resulting from a kind of cool decision of will. Indeed, couples who closely watch the symptoms of fertility, hoping to find the right moment to be sure of conceiving, often find that too much planning cramps their love-life. It becomes a chore. In short, the act of physical lovemaking is ordinarily motivated and incited 21 Aristotle, Metaphysics, IX, 8, 1050a 30;Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I–II, q. 3, a. 2, ad 3. 864 Adrian J. Reimers by what happens in the married partners. Because of these differences from many other kinds of act, we need different criteria for understanding the act of marital union.To clarify the issue, we may also pose the question in this way: When is marital intercourse done well and when not? Spousal Significance and the Act In his theology of the body, John Paul the Great speaks of the spousal meaning of the body,22 by which the marital act acquires a twofold significance as unitive and procreative. The human body as male and female bears within itself the “sign of the gift.”23 By this John Paul means to say that the body, in its differentiation as male and female, expresses and can realize the spousal gift of self. This refers in part to the fact that the male and female bodies are designed to unite physically in sexual union, but it does not stop there. The man is drawn to the beauty of a woman’s femininity and the woman to a man’s masculine strength and beauty. The woman, whose physical constitution—including her endocrinal and nervous systems—is oriented to motherhood, has a characteristic openness to the person.24 Her brain is more globally integrated than a man’s, which for its part is more hierarchically and less integrally structured. He is a “doer” who has to prove his value in work and competition.25 And so John Paul II points to the man’s readiness to accept responsibility, to work, to protect and provide as characteristic of the husband and father.26 The spousal meaning of the body is written not simply into our reproductive systems, but into the entire psychosomatic structures of our bodies as male and female.This is one source of the delicious tension of falling in love and the delight of its realization. The person can be a gift only if he or she gives himself freely. As spousal it is a gift of the entire self.This notion is central to Karol Wojtyla’s analyses of marriage: “Its [betrothed love’s] decisive character is the giving of one’s own person (to another). The essence of betrothed love is self22 In John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, Michael Waldstein translates the Italian “sponsale” as “spousal.” See also Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 95–96, where the English translator renders “milość oblubieńcza” as “betrothed love,” and the Italian translator in Amore e responsabilità (in Karol Wojtyla, Metafisica della persona, 552) as “amore sponsale.” 23 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 14:4; and in general 14:2–16:2. 24 John Paul II, apostolic letter Mulieris Dignitatem, §18. See also John Tierney, “What Women Want,” New York Times, May 24, 2005. 25 See “Male Brains,” Reuters New Service, October 1, 2003. 26 See John Paul II, apostolic exhortation Redemptoris Custos, for a portrayal of the ideal characteristics of the good man as husband and father. / Integration and Transcendence of the Person 865 giving, the surrender of one’s own ‘I.’ ”27 Wojtyla is careful to stress that this gift is not to be regarded only in the context of sex, but precisely in its most radical and paradoxical form as the gift of one’s self to another. “The concept of betrothed [spousal] love implies the giving of the individual person to another chosen person.”28 This means that not only one’s body but also his intellect and will, his freedom and self-determination are given over to the beloved. The spouse no longer lives for himself but in union with and, in a way, as part of another. John Paul the Great develops this notion further in his theology of the body. Analyzing the creation narrative in Genesis 2, John Paul II interprets the original nakedness of the first man and woman in terms of the spousal gift that they are to be for each other: seeing and knowing each other in all the peace and tranquility of the interior gaze, they “communicate” in the fullness of humanity, which shows itself in them as reciprocal complementarity precisely because they are “male” and “female.” At the same time, they “communicate” based on the communion of persons in which they become a mutual gift for each other, through femininity and masculinity. . . . The original meaning of nakedness corresponds to the simplicity and fullness of vision in which their understanding of the meaning of the body is born from the very heart, as it were, of their community-communion. We call this meaning “spousal.”29 This union is, in fact, a communion of persons, a sharing that results in a common life, so that the two act “as one.” The “original nakedness” is therefore not only sexually significant. The body in its nakedness expresses the transparency of each to the other in the gift of self, so that their actions are in harmony. A sign of this is the rupture between them that occurred after the Fall. Their first act was to cover their physical nakedness out of shame (Genesis 3:8–9), but their second was to turn against each other when God called them to account.“It was the woman you put with me” (Gen 3:12). No longer did they act as one, but instead the man looked out for himself, and the communion was ruptured. Before the Fall it was not so, as the two lived as “one flesh.” This theme of communion of persons is an important one for John Paul II, one which he explored in a variety of ways and contexts in his writings.30 27 John Paul II, Love and Responsibility, 96. 28 Ibid., 98. 29 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 13:1. 30 See Wojtyla,“Persona e atto,” cap. 7, especially 1175–81, 1205–13; idem,“Person: Subject and Community,” 240–52. Adrian J. Reimers 866 How can two individual persons, distinct centers of consciousness and action, become one? In his theology of the body teachings, John Paul II uses the term “bi-subjectivity” to describe this unity. Commenting on Ephesians 5:22–33, he writes:“This supplementary analogy of ‘head and body’ shows that . . . we are dealing with two distinct subjects who, in virtue of a particular reciprocal relation, become in some sense a single subject.”31 And further: Still, this analogy does not blur the individuality of the subjects, that of the husband and that of the wife, that is, the essential bi-subjectivity that stands at the basis of the image of “one body,” more precisely the essential bi-subjectivity of the husband and the wife in marriage which makes them in a certain sense “one body,” passes in the whole text we are examining (Eph 5:22–33) into the image of the Church as body united with Christ as head.32 This text complements that cited above on “original nakedness” in that it emphasizes not the so much the sexual encounter as the relationship as a whole. It is a serious mistake to regard the spousal gift of self in sexual terms alone; the gift is of the person and not just of the body.33 It is uniquely that act, however, which expresses this gift. Because of specific circumstances in the life of a particular couple, another act may at a certain time express the gift of self more perfectly to the spouse (as when, for instance, a husband turns down a personally attractive professional appointment for the good of his wife). Nevertheless, it is this act which of its own nature represents that self-gift. In this act, husband and wife, putting aside the normal shame that nakedness brings with it, expose themselves to each other and unite physically so as to become one flesh. Their union takes place by means of their genital—that is, reproductive—organs, in an act whose natural finality is reproduction, the conception of not just “a child” but a “little you and a little me,” someone who comes from the two and shares something of them. No other act of itself fully represents this: “I give myself to you completely and receive your gift of self to me.” Unitive Meaning Here is the first key to understanding the marital act and its criteria.The marital embrace, to be done well, needs to express love as the free and total gift of oneself to the beloved. (They must, of course, be married for the act to express the total gift of self, for only marriage is a full commit31 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 91:3. 32 Ibid., 91:4. 33 Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 99. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 867 ment of oneself to another person such that the two become one.)34 In their physical lovemaking husband and wife intend to unite themselves fully, to express physically the unity of their life together.The point is not so much to do something but to share each other with each other, to be a married couple together. By the same token, the act is done badly to the extent one or the other withholds himself from giving fully of himself, perhaps by greedily milking his own pleasure from the act to the neglect of his wife, by her quietly submitting with her mind on tomorrow’s concerns, or by some more serious failure. Sexual intercourse is done well insofar as it expresses and serves to realize the union of the two persons who have given themselves to each other in marriage. Depending on circumstances, both interior to the persons and exterior, it may be more or less thrilling, delicious, or pleasurable, but it can always be good. Therefore, the marital act is an act of leisure, comparable to play, to making music, or even to contemplative prayer.35 The Efficacy of Sex In Person and Act Karol Wojtyla argues that an act is not constituted by subjectivity alone, that the moment of efficacy is essential to the human act.36 As a human act, therefore, the marital act is efficacious. More to the point, whether conception results or not, every marital act is efficacious and not merely an event in the respective consciousnesses of the couple. In other words, the reality of the act necessarily extends beyond any feelings, pleasurable or not, that one or both partners may experience. That the act is efficacious means that it is—and must therefore be evaluated as—more than an event in their respective consciousnesses.That organ by which the husband’s masculinity is most clearly manifest becomes hard and strong to penetrate that in his wife which manifests most clearly— and vulnerably—her femininity, that organ which is also the channel by which a new life enters the world. In this act, the man ejaculates his semen into his wife’s body, which is where that semen can sometimes have a procreative effect.The sexual act is a drama of power and vulnerability, an elemental event that can change lives. Even when this act does not attain its most dramatic effect, when it does not result in conception, the marital act is efficacious, because it causes physiological, hormonal, 34 Ibid., 211–16. 35 Here I am reminded of the opening sentence of my first book on chess, Reuben Fine’s Chess the Easy Way (New York: D. McKay Co., 1942), which my father gave me when I was a boy: “Chess, like music, like love, has the power to make men happy.” 36 Wojtyla, “Persona e atto,” 917–22. 868 Adrian J. Reimers and emotional reactions in the psychophysical organisms of both spouses. The act dramatically affects heart rate, blood pressure, the flow of hormones, as well as large and small muscle groups. The natural trajectory of lovemaking then issues in a state of physical calm, leading to tenderness of expression and, most likely, peaceful sleep.The body has its own “subjectivity” in its somatic, sensory, and emotional responses.37 These are aspects of the efficacy of the marital act. This moment of efficacy must be interpreted by the significance of the act, which is to express the union of the spouses who give themselves to each other. For weak and sinful human beings, the marital act is a powerful and—especially for the woman—dangerous event, not merely a pleasurable stimulation of the senses.As rational beings capable of understanding the efficacy of the act, both partners are responsible for the act and its consequences. The import of this becomes clearer if we consider the common attitudes surrounding the various forms of “recreational sex,” both within marriage and without, attitudes which reduce the act simply to the enjoyment of pleasures to which women and men are equally entitled.What is happening is more than parallel conscious experiences.The act itself expresses something. It is certainly possible, for example, to read this act as masculine conquest (the act is often described as “taking” the woman) and feminine submission. One might also read it as a man’s return to the womb, and by his entering the woman she “swallows him up,” as it were.The man can be the conqueror, but in his conquest he is absorbed into her scheme to domesticate him. These are not the only possible readings, but they are common enough. And we note that these readings posit either an indifference to the well-being of the other or even a positive conflict between man and woman. If, however, the act is one of union, then according to the logic of the gift the man’s penetration of his wife and her reception of his semen is not a conquest but a pledge. His strength is redeemed by her loving acceptance of his emission into her body. She will tame and care for him, because she has given herself, not just her body but her heart. In the marital union governed by the logic of gift, he does this not as her master but as loving husband and protector. Such a lived interpretation of the act is possible only if the act is truly a joint action, an act of the two in union. By the bodily expression of the marital act, the wife unites her soul to the husband in such a way that she becomes the guardian and caretaker of his masculinity. Having accepted her gift of herself, of her submission to his strength, he in turn pledges by his actions to care for her, for this 37 Ibid., 1095–111, especially 1095, where Wojtyla says that the body “possesses its own purely somatic interiority,” an interiority expressed in its reactivity. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 869 woman who has received and will nurture the evidence of his virility. In this way, the existential efficacy of their bodily interaction is responsibly grasped and understood.The couple in their embrace integrate not only their intentions but their behavior into one coherent act. Procreative Efficacy The most significant efficient causality of the marital act, of course, is procreation. Even though not every such act will result in conception and although couples incapable of conceiving can perform the act, the biological structure of the act is such that in the normal course events, the healthy young couple regularly engaging in this act without interfering with its finality will conceive a new life. The advent of reliable and relatively safe pharmaceutical and other contraceptives has led many to call this finality into question, arguing that since the same act is performed by those past childbearing age or simply using contraceptives, its procreative finality is optional. Even when rendered infertile by age, physical incapacity (such as hysterectomy), or pharmaceutical contraceptives, the act still brings pleasure and the sense of union between spouses with its attendant physical and emotional benefits. These natural and man-made factors notwithstanding, it is clear that the fundamental structure of the marital act is procreative. The only purpose that the male’s sperm serves is to fertilize a female’s egg. It has no other finality. Furthermore, this sperm is relatively vulnerable and, once emitted by the man, dies fairly quickly unless in an appropriate environment, and the vagina of the woman is particularly well suited for the protection and movement of the sperm. Similarly, the woman’s egg has but one finality, which it can achieve only upon encountering the sperm.The marital act is the means by which these are brought together.38 Every act of sexual intercourse, even if naturally or artificially sterile in a particular instance, is an instance of the kind of act by which procreation is effected. Procreative Significance As we noted above, the person in act transcends himself not only horizontally toward the surrounding world, but also vertically toward truth39 in order to realize the true and fitting good (bonum honestum). It follows that in the marital act human beings are to transcend themselves in truth 38 Of course, this encounter may now be effected by artificial means, a point which we will address shortly. However, this technological capability does not change the finality of the marital act as such. 39 On this see Edward Kaczyński, O.P., “Verità sul Bene”nella Morale: Alcuni temi di morale fondamentale (Roma: Millennium Romae, 1998), 205–27, 220. Adrian J. Reimers 870 to the fitting good, to the good as such.This good is identical with God himself, as we have already noted. Besides the physical and emotional effects of sexual relations on the spouses themselves, the finality of the act is such that by it the married couple can conceive a new human person, characterized by his own interior or spiritual life, centered on truth and good.40 Because, no merely physical interaction can result in a spiritual being, it is necessary that the Creator himself be directly and efficaciously involved in the conception of a new human being.41 This creativity is linked in such a way to the act that, even if the act is seriously flawed by sin, God respects the laws he has written into his human creatures and endows the being so conceived with a human soul. The implications of this are of immense importance. The biological relationship between sexual intercourse and procreation means that God the Creator has placed into human hands the direct responsibility for the management of this aspect and continuation of his creative activity.This is, therefore, not only a gift but also a grave responsibility. Pope Paul VI and Vatican II use the word munus, which means “office,”“duty,” or “function.”42 Husband and wife united in their sexual union not only enjoy their mutual gift of love, but simultaneously act as ministers of God’s creative love. In their union they affirm each other in their love, but this wonderful and—John Paul the Great’s term—beatifying 43 mutual gift occurs in a still more remarkable context, as a participation in the Creator’s activity. It is important here to recall the implications of these two facts: (1) that conception cannot reliably be taken as the purpose of a single act of intercourse, and (2) that married persons do not ordinarily unite for the express purpose of conceiving a child. If sexual relations, to be done well, must be an expression of loving union, then the procreative efficacy must pertain, in a way, to the union as a whole.The procreation of offspring can therefore be more appropriately regarded as the fruit of the union of man and wife rather than as the effect produced by a technique or procedure.To make something is to take charge of material and transform it according to some plan or design that the maker has in mind.This is not the situation of the man and wife in their sexual union. By their union they express what John Paul the Great calls the “primordial sacrament,” a sign of and participation in the Creator’s love by which that love is realized in the world.44 Partici40 John Paul II, Love and Responsibility, 22–23. 41 Ibid., 55. 42 Paul VI, Humanae Vitae, §1; Vatican Council II, Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern World Gaudium et Spes, §§48, 50–52. 43 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 14:1–4. 44 Ibid., 100:1–2. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 871 pating in God’s love by their free and full love for each other, the spouses become ministers of his love, opening themselves to his creative work in bringing the new person into being. This direct participation in the work of the Creator renders the vertical transcendence of the act particularly manifest. Vertical transcendence is constituted by the reference to the truth about the good, and in this case we are dealing with the good of the Creator’s love in creation. Because God is truly the First Cause and source of all being, we can appeal to no prior cause to account for his work of creation. His work as Creator satisfied no lack or deficiency on his part, nor was it a response to some impulse external to himself. Because no cause, neither final, formal, efficient, nor material, can account for the work of the First Cause,45 the work of creation can have been motivated only by the divine love.46 Therefore creation itself has the character of gift. “Through these words (Gen 1:31) we are led to glimpse in love the divine motive for creation, the source, as it were from which it springs: only love, in fact, gives rise to the good and is well pleased with the good.” 47 It follows therefore that this participation of the spouses in the Creator’s work must represent also a sharing in his love.The truth about their expression of love in marital intimacy is that it does indeed “give rise to the good,” the good represented by a new person in creation.48 It is this procreative significance and potency of the marital act that gives the act its peculiar dignity as a sharing in the divine love. Human beings can, as Karol Wojtyla notes, regard this procreative significance as an inconvenience, a secondary aspect of an act whose principal purpose is the satisfaction of libido.49 So to regard it and to restructure it so as to render the act deliberately infertile is to deny the act of what specifically constitutes its love-character. To be sure, spouses may perform the contraceptive act to express their love and affection, to experience through the closeness of their bodies their emotional and existential closeness. In doing so, however, they effectively deny to their own mutual love its intended participation of their act in the divine love. It is in this way that the contraception not only thwarts the procreative efficacy of the act but also denies its procreative significance.That significance is rejected along with the efficacy.50 Contraception denies the true greatness of marital love. 45 ST I, q. 2, a. 3; q. 44, aa. 1–4. 46 ST I, q. 45, a. 6. 47 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 13:2–4. 48 Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 51–55. 49 Ibid., 62–63. 50 We may note that natural methods of fertility control deny neither the efficacy nor the significance of the act as procreative. Indeed by their very nature they do both. 872 Adrian J. Reimers It is also in precisely this context that we can understand the Church’s rejection of in vitro fertilization techniques. In its 1987 Instruction Donum Vitae the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (CDF) condemned artificial techniques for conceiving life outside the womb, arguing: For human procreation has specific characteristics by virtue of the personal dignity of the parents and of the children: the procreation of a new person, whereby the man and the woman collaborate with the power of the Creator, must be the fruit and the sign of the mutual selfgiving of the spouses, of their love and of their fidelity.51 In-vitro fertilization pioneer Robert Edwards, who assisted in the conception of the world’s first successful “test tube baby,” finds the CDF position “pernicious”52 and bigoted, because it denies to infertile couples the joy that they seek. Infertility, he argues is “a great and lasting cause of human sadness,”53 and science can now remedy it.The remedy, however, is actually a technique to harness the biological substrate of human procreation in order to produce a result.The CDF position, which John Paul II endorsed, is that procreation is not simply another event in the biological order, but rather a work in which the Creator himself is involved. It is worth noting that Edwards’s appeal to the deeply felt desire of childless couples, a desire whose frustration may often represent genuine pain, parallels the common appeal to the sexual desires of the spouses who practice contraception. In both cases, we see the application of technology according to the “greatest happiness principle,”54 to relieve subjective feelings of frustration, sorrow, or pain. Here the issue of the fitting good comes clearly to the fore.The conception of a child or the enjoyment of marital intimacy is good in itself, but both must be achieved within the context of the truth about the good of a person as such. Edwards focuses on the bonum delectabile, trying to minimize the suffering of childlessness. To evaluate the “useful good” of the IVF or contraceptive technologies, however, we must refer this utility first and above all to the “fitting good” (bonum honestum), lest in serving only the delectable good we undermine that primary good. 51 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, instruction Donum Vitae (1987), www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_ doc_19870222_respect-for-human-life_en.html. 52 Robert Edwards, Life before Birth: Reflections on the Embryo Debate (New York: Basic Books, 1989), 29–30. 53 Ibid, 31. 54 See John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 2001), 7. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 873 Here we directly engage a theme John Paul the Great developed at length in his first encyclical, Redemptor Hominis, where he asks “What is modern man afraid of?”55 His answer is that man is afraid of what he himself produces, of the work of his intellect and the tendencies of his will. But does this apply to the techniques for producing a child for an infertile couple? Later in that same encyclical, he indicates the answer. Affirming the primacy of persons over things, of ethics over technology, John Paul writes:“What is in question is the advancement of persons, not just the multiplying of things that people can use. It is a matter—as a contemporary philosopher has said and as the Council has stated—not so much of ‘having more’ as of ‘being more.’ ”56 The couple can indeed “have” a child, but in the economy of creation, within which they minister, they become “mother” and “father” precisely through who they are as “wife” and “husband,” through the realization of their spousal union. Transcendence: The Fantastic and the Authentic Our great temptation, as beings with powerful sexual urges, is to regard sex and sexual activity only on the horizontal plane.Viewed only in terms of this “horizontal transcendence” it is hard to see why this very malleable act might not be formed according to the desires of individual persons. With pharmaceutical technology we can render the act infertile. Utilizing dress, drugs (including alcohol), and setting, we can enhance the pleasure attendant upon the act. Indeed we can seek the pleasures of genital sex with the body that most stimulates our senses or fulfills our fantasies, whether this body be one of the same sex as oneself or one tailored by diet, exercise, and even surgery to fit an erotic ideal. If we are able to do these things and the attendant risks can be reduced to an acceptable level, then by the utilitarian standard, which measures acts according to their effects on the “horizontal” plane, these acts ought to be acceptable. To deny the legitimacy of this approach frequently evokes anger, as though by this denial we deprive people of some great good.This anger points to something very important. It is not that, in fact, the requirements of chastity actually deprive people of sexual pleasure. Rather the Catholic Church’s teaching, even when so winsomely explained as in John Paul the Great’s theology of the body, is offensive because it refutes the very dream of a kind of fantastic erotic transcendence. Underlying our sexual utilitarianism is a powerful myth of glorious, Dionysian sexual release—the absolute all-consuming ecstasy of the beautiful joining of 55 John Paul II, Redemptor Hominis, §15. 56 Ibid., §16. 874 Adrian J. Reimers perfect bodies swept up by irresistible passion, a joining governed only by passion and the thoroughgoing enjoyment of the other’s body without shame, restraint, or regard for anything but the moment.57 Although the call to chastity actually interferes with no one’s pleasure, it denies that alluring myth which the utilitarian culture secretly nourishes and expects its technology to deliver. In fact, that dream is an illusion. The myth of erotic ecstasy rests on a desire for transcendence, but a transcendence that is misconceived. The authentic transcendence of the marital act is situated not only within the context of a personal relationship of mutual self-gift, but within the order of God’s own love as it works in creation.The husband and wife joined in their manhood and womanhood are in truth participating in the great act of love by which the entire universe was created. In this they find not only individual personal integration, but a mutual integration in their communion. And in place of the fantastic sensual explorations of mythical “Great Sex,” they place themselves under the thrilling (and very erotic) possibility of conceiving a new life.The flaw of the myth of Great Sex is not that it expects too much but that it settles for too little. Even though it is the fullest expression of spousal love, the gift of self in marital lovemaking is not itself the fullness of marital love.The free and unrestrained gift of each others’ bodies in marital lovemaking expresses the further gift of the entire self, a gift realized in the homely domesticity of married life. The very real values of the body and sex are situated within a broader nexus of domestic and even civic values and most importantly are realized in relation to the highest and most perfect Good. This holistic—or personalistic—conception of self-gift entails an additional truth. Marital sex has a future and is therefore laden with responsibility.The mythical Great Sex is, in a way, timeless. It has no future, only the hoped for repetition of the one experience over and over, whether with one or with many partners. Hence it is necessary to repair the damage of pregnancy and childbirth to the woman’s body (for it is primarily her body that must be perfect). She must return to the perfect form of the 23-year-old virgin, to delight the senses of her partner.Then as time takes its inevitable toll, the man must resort to Viagra or Cialis to mimic the virility of his youth. Marital sex, precisely because of its transcendent character, is costly. Mother loses the firmness and perfect form of her youthful body as she bears and delivers her children. Her husband, who has pledged himself to her and gratefully accepted her love, continues to rejoice in the beauty of this person and in the manifest femininity 57 On this see Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, §§3–5. Integration and Transcendence of the Person 875 of her now maternal body. And as he ages, inevitably losing not only his hair but also that youthful sexual stamina, she continues to rejoice in his body, by the strength of which she became a mother and has had her love protected and cared for. Husband and wife love each other in the face of decline and eventual death in the realization that an authentic love between persons will never die,58 because it is ultimately rooted in and directed toward the One who is eternal love. When all is lost, then it is fulfilled. In the face of disintegration and death, it is this spousal love— the complete gift of self—that is the key to full integration of the person. Mutual Integration in the Act We may and must draw a final implication of this transcendence in the marital act.The fundamental principal underlying Wojtyla’s Person and Act is that the person is revealed through his acts, that the person is manifest most clearly and precisely in act.59 Analogously, the union of the spouses is manifest in the marital act. As we noted above, bi-subjectivity is essential to the act; it is one act performed by both together, such that neither could perform it without the other’s complementary participation. Just as the person integrates himself by his transcendence in act toward the good, so too does the couple in their act. Disintegration is the grave danger that threatens the married couple. By his organic integrity the individual enjoys safeguards against personal disintegration, for his organic constitution serves to remind him of his need for personal integration.The married couple, however, exists ontologically as two distinct beings, two relatively autonomous persons. We can readily see how the demands of social and economic life, as well as the inducements of concupiscence, can lead to strains and eventual rupture of the spousal union. If we consider this act from the perspective of its two agents, we find profound and significant forces that tend toward disintegration, even as the man and woman unite their bodies. It is well known, for example, that men and women have different patterns of sexual response. Men are quickly aroused and quickly satisfied, and their arousal is triggered most frequently by specific kinds of sensory stimulation, especially visual images and touch. Women, by contrast, are much more slowly aroused sexually, responding not so much to the immediate prospect of sexual encounter as to the context of manifest concern and affection on the part of the man.The factors are well known to those who counsel married couples. What is important to our present discussion is that, taken in themselves, 58 Karol Wojtyla,“Thomistic Personalism,” in idem, Person and Community, 174–75. 59 Wojtyla,“Persona e atto,” 863; idem,“Person: Subject and Community,” 223, and see especially note 6 to that text. Adrian J. Reimers 876 these differences can have a disintegrating effect. The sexual encounter may well look quite different from his side than from hers. Furthermore, the accomplishment of the act will have markedly different effects in the man’s psychosomatic constitution than in the woman’s.The completion of the act “reverberates” differently through the woman’s being than through the man’s. The great danger to the married couple, therefore, is that this act become in fact two, a kind of compromise encounter through which each attempts to attain his or her personal satisfaction.To succumb to this danger is to undermine the unity of the act precisely as one of union. This act by which the two become one flesh (Gen 2:24) is intended to express and realize the ongoing unity of the two persons in the marriage bond.To do so, however, the act must be performed according to its true nature. Just as the integration of the individual person in the act occurs through his transcendence toward the fitting good,60 so too the mutual integration of married spouses is realized through their marital intercourse—provided that this act is accomplished virtuously, that is, according to their willed choice of the fitting good.The applicable virtue in this case is chastity, by which one moderates and governs his sexual appetites.61 The more physical vigor and impatience of the male impulse is to be moderated and integrated with the more emotional female response and its inherent desire for a more total fulfillment. Indeed, the dynamic of the violent masculine ejaculation’s reception into the nurturing feminine body serves as an apt metaphor and symbol of the total personal integration in the act. This personal integration, however, is achieved not by focus on the biological factors of the act itself, but rather on the good toward which this one act, jointly performed, is directed. The pleasure, the physical or emotional satisfaction of one or both spouses is insufficient to serve as the principle of integration, for pleasure and satisfaction are subjective experiences of the objective reality, and as subjective are not shared goods.62 The marital act is one in which both strong feelings and experiences—“what happens in a human being”—and chosen actions—“what a human being does”—are inextricably combined, as two persons who love each other give their bodies to each other in a peculiarly intense act. The purpose of integration is to unify what happens in the person with his own self-dynamization into unity. “And the specific function of integra60 Wojtyla, Persona e atto,” 1112–13, 1154. 61 Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 168–69; John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 131:1–2, 132:2. 62 “I” may, of course, rejoice that “you” are pleased, but that does not mean that “I” share the pleasure in the sense of experiencing it with “you.” Integration and Transcendence of the Person 877 tion consists precisely in the overcoming of the boundary between ‘happening’ and ‘acting,’ ” writes Wojtyla.63 Should this integration be lost or missing—so continues Wojtyla’s analysis—then with it is lost the personal structure of self-dominion and self-determination.To protect the integrity of their mutual act of sexual intercourse, the couple need therefore to integrate the act according to the fitting good. This cannot be accomplished by a simple abandonment to whim, passion, concupiscence, or lust. In the final analysis, therefore, the marital act is to be fully rational and freely chosen, an act of the will, understood as that faculty by which the good is loved and chosen. Through the willed choice of a common transcendent good, the two can become one.64 A couple may indeed allow themselves to abandon themselves to the delights of their physical union, spontaneously responding to the beauty and sensual desirability each finds in the other. Nevertheless, such playfulness in sexual activity cannot imply a simple abandonment to exploitation of the other for selfish satisfaction, much less a denial of the transcendent good in relation to which the marital union is constituted. In Conclusion The interpretation of Karol Wojtyla’s principal philosophical work, Person and Act, has been a matter for dispute from the very time of its publication, as even his closest colleagues debated the nature of the philosophical task he had undertaken.65 By his own testimony, he sought to supply a more contemporary presentation of Aquinas’s thought, taking advantage of the resources of phenomenology.66 His concern was not only theoretical, however. Referring to the English translation of Osoba i czyn, Michael Waldstein comments: The main agenda of The Acting Person, however, is not dictated by Scheler, but by Wojtyla’s roots in the spousal theology of St. John of the Cross, specifically by the key notion:“gift of self.” . . . The Acting Person supplies the account of the person that is presupposed by St. John of the Cross’s spousal theology of self-gift.67 63 Wojtyla, “Persona e atto,” 1084. 64 Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 28–30; John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 92:5–7. 65 See especially Karol Wojtyla,“The Personal Structure of Self-Determination,” in idem, Person and Community, 187–95; and idem, “Person: Subject and Community,” 258–59 note 3. 66 Wojtyla, “The Personal Structure of Self-Determination,” 187–88. 67 Michael Waldstein, Introduction to John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 79. 878 Adrian J. Reimers Person and Act provides us with the philosophical roots undergirding the theology of the body and of the personalism we find in Redemptor Hominis, Laborem Exercens and the other social encyclicals, Salvifici Doloris, Mulieris Dignitatem, and his many addresses. In this dense and difficult philosophical work he asks himself, “What sort of being is this that is able so to possess itself that it can give itself in love?” In this paper I have looked at the act which, in a way, is fundamental to the theology of the body audiences, the act by which husband and wife become one flesh, through the lens of categories expressly provided by Person and Act. Although our contemporary culture focuses much attention on sexual activity and enjoyment, very little attention is paid to the overall structure of sexual intercourse as a personal act, as a willed and chosen response to experienced values. As a result, our contemporary conceptions of sex and sexual activities tend to be rather crudely and often unrealistically formed in terms that are more mythical than realistic. Educated men and women routinely discuss sex in terms of pleasure, a vague sensory fulfillment, and expression of deeply felt love, but without serious consideration of the nature of the act which they actually engage in, its efficacy and significance.To be sure, a study of Person and Act is hardly necessary for one who would love well.The husband and wife who would love each other well must live and act for the love of God, realizing in that mutually shared love their own union. And this is what the transcendence and integration of the person N&V in act is ultimately about. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 879–900 879 Feminism, Nature and Humanae Vitae: What’s Love Got to Do with It? M ICHELE M. S CHUMACHER University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland “M UTUAL self-donation in a communio personarum, a community of persons, was the moral framework—the humanistic framework—in which to ponder the question of birth control,” writes Michael Waldstein of the personalist vision of Pope John Paul II, even in his pre-papal writing.1 Similarly, the venerable servant of God insisted as no less “indispensible”2 to a satisfactory consideration of woman’s dignity and vocation than to that of Humanae Vitae, what he esteems an “adequate anthropology” as summarized in Gaudium et Spes, §24.3 “Man,” we read in that passage— so we are already off to a bad start, from a feminist point of view!—“who is the only creature on earth which God willed for its own sake, cannot fully find himself except through a sincere gift of self.”4 It is precisely in 1 Michael Waldstein, introduction to John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them:A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books and Media, 2006), 143. 2 John Paul II, apostolic exhortation on the Dignity and Vocation of Women, Mulieris Dignitatem (1988), §7. 3 See John Paul II, encyclical letter “On the Holy Spirit in the Life of the Church and the World,” Dominum et Vivificantem (1986), §59; idem, Mulieris Dignitatem, §7: “With these words, the council text presents a summary of the whole truth about man and woman.”The significance that he awards to this passage explains the importance that it assumed in his magisterial writings. See Pascale Ide,“Une théologie du don. Les occurrences de Gaudium et spes, nr. 24, §3 chez Jean-Paul II,” Anthropotes 17 (2001): 149–78; 17 (2001): 313–44. 4 Vatican Council II, Pastoral Document on the Church in the Modern World, Gaudium et Spes, §24. That creature, John Paul II specifies in his commentary in Mulieris Dignitatem,“is thus a person. Being a person means striving towards selfrealization (the Council text speaks of self-discovery), which can only be achieved 880 Michele M. Schumacher this, moreover, that John Paul II recognized the meaning of being in the image and likeness of God: that “man”—and honestly, we all know that the Council meant “man and woman”—“is called to exist ‘for’ others, to become a gift.”5 Four years before the Council promulgated these words,Valerie Saiving—in a very influential publication providing the “initial stirrings” of feminist theology6—objected to any such presentation of self-giving love ‘through a sincere gift of self ” (§7). In this sense, self-realization is never really selfrealization but rather communal human fulfillment. By this I mean—as will become increasingly evident—not only that we realize ourselves in the very acts whereby we contribute to the common good, but also that we are able to do so precisely because others are always and constantly contributing to our own good. Hence, personal realization—within which also consists the entire drama of salvation, as we shall see—is a properly communal fulfillment. 5 John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §7. 6 See Francis Martin, The Feminist Question: Feminist Theology in the Light of Christian Tradition (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1994), 160–61. Sally Purvis explains: “Both the content and the analytical method of Saiving’s article have become classics in Christian feminist work and are richly suggestive for developments by others” (Purvis,“Christian Feminist Ethics and the Family,” in Religion, Feminism, and the Family, eds. Anne Carr and Mary Stewart Van Leeuwen [Louisville, KY: Westminister John Knox Press, 1996], 113). As a case in point, Saiving’s analysis is taken up and developed by Judith Plaskow who critiques the theologies of Reinhold Niebuhr and Paul Tillich for highlighting and developing “certain aspects of human experience” in their theologies while others, i.e., those of women, “are regarded as secondary or ignored.” “The effect of this tendency, which is not incidental but springs from the very definitions of sin and grace, is to identify human with male experience.This identification,” Plaskow concludes, “not only impoverishes theology but leads it to support prevailing definitions of femininity” (Plaskow, Sex, Sin and Grace: Women’s Experience in the Theologies of Reinhold Niebuhr and Paul Tillich [Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1980], 4). In the meantime,American feminist theologians of such influence and stature as Mary Daly, Rosemary Radford Ruether, and Elisabeth Schüssler Fiorenza began critiquing not merely theologies purporting to speak from the universal human situation while reflecting a uniquely male perspective, but also the very Tradition and core symbolism of Christianity—indeed, even Scripture itself—as reflecting and reinforcing an oppressive patriarchal social structure. For more detail, see Michele M. Schumacher, “Feminine Experience and Religious Experience,” in Women in Christ:Towards a New Feminism, ed. Michele M. Schumacher (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2004), 169–200. It is also worth mentioning that arguments similar to that of Saiving (without direct reference) are developed by Elizabeth Johnson and Daphne Hampson, to name just two influential feminist theologians. The former argues that for women who have been oppressed the “language of conversion as loss of self, turning from amour sui, functions in an ideological way to rob them of power, maintaining them in a subordinate position to the benefit of those who rule” ( Johnson, She Who Is: Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 881 as bespeaking a masculine idea of redemption with regard to the particularly masculine sin of “pride, will-to-power, exploitation, self-assertiveness, and the treatment of others as objects rather than persons.”7 Women, on the other hand, Saiving notes, tend to very different forms of sin which read more like “triviality, distractibility, and diffuseness; lack of an organizing center or focus; dependence on others for one’s own selfdefinition; tolerance at the expense of standards of excellence; inability to respect the boundaries of privacy; sentimentality, gossipy sociability, and mistrust of reason—in short, underdevelopment or negation of the self.”8 These, Saiving maintains, are “outgrowths of the basic feminine character structure,”9 whose content remains ambiguous, although her analysis addresses both that which is natural and acquired in woman.10 Both boys and girls must learn to differentiate themselves from their mothers who, in every society, bear children and are closest to them in their infancy and early childhood. Precisely this process of differentiation is, however, different for boys and girls.Whereas a girl attains to sexual maturity, including The Mystery of God in Feminist Theological Discourse [New York: Crossroad, 1995], 77). As for the second, she writes: “That it [kenosis] should have featured prominently in Christian thought is perhaps an indication of the fact that men have understood what the male problem, in thinking in terms of hierarchy and domination, has been. It may well be a model which men need to appropriate and which may helpfully be built into the male understanding of God. But . . . for women, the theme of self-emptying and self-abnegation is far from helpful as a paradigm” (Hampson, Theology and Feminism [Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990], 155). For a development of this theme from a pastoral perspective, see B. L. Gill-Austern, “Love Understood as Self-Denial: What Does it do to Women?” in Through the Eyes of Women: Insights for Pastoral Care, ed. J. S. Moessner (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1996), esp. 304. 7 Hence, the male conception of redemption “as restoring to man what he fundamentally lacks (namely, sacrificial love, the I-Thou relationship, the primacy of the personal, and, ultimately, peace)” (Valerie Saiving, “The Human Situation: A Feminine View,” in Womanspirit Rising:A Feminist Reader in Religion, eds. Carol P. Christ and Judith Plaskow [San Francisco: Harder & Row, 1979], 35, first printed in The Journal of Religion 40 [1960]: 100–12). 8 Ibid., 37. Similar is the list of specifically female weaknesses as addressed by Edith Stein. See her Essays on Woman (Washington, DC: ICS Publications, 1996); and Mary Shivanandan,“Sentiment and Sentimentality:Woman’s Choice?” in Fellowship of Catholic Scholars Quarterly 20.2 (Spring 1997): 7–17. 9 Saiving, “The Human Situation,” 37. 10 Saiving follows Margaret Mead’s approach: “Instead of asking the question most of us ask: ‘Are character differences between the sexes the result of heredity or environment, of biology or culture?’ she asks, rather, whether there may not be certain basic similarities in the ways in which men and women in every culture have experienced what it means to be a man or to be a woman” (ibid., 29). 882 Michele M. Schumacher motherhood, quite naturally,11 a boy experiences his manhood as an achievement, as something that he must acquire.A girl simply is a woman— at least potentially—but a boy must prove himself a man.12 This phenomenon, which Saiving presents as cross-cultural, is further accented—as other feminists have noted13—in a contemporary western culture which not only encourages boys to be detached from their mothers, but also educates them according to the cultural ideal of isolated individualism.14 Girls, by contrast, are encouraged, even within this same cultural context, to develop a self-identity based on connection with and similarity to their mothers. While Saiving’s analysis was intended to demonstrate the male bias in a theology purporting to address the universal human situation without addressing the particular experiences of women,15 her critique is one that 11 “The processes of impregnation, pregnancy, childbirth, and lactation have a certain passivity about them; they are things which happen to a woman more than things that she does” (ibid., 31). 12 “The case is quite otherwise for the male, whose active desire and active performance in the sexual act is absolutely required for its completion. And here again the demand for performance is coupled with an inevitable anxiety; in order to prove his maleness, he must succeed in what he has undertaken—and it is possible for him to fail” (ibid., 32). Similar is the analysis of Michelle Zimbalist Rosaldo: “A woman becomes a woman by following in her mother’s footsteps, whereas there must be a break in a man’s experience. For a boy to become an adult, he must prove himself—his masculinity—among his peers. And although all boys may succeed in reaching manhood, cultures treat this development as something that each individual has achieved.” In contrast to womanhood as a natural category or criteria—woman being regarded as ‘naturally’ what she is— manhood is “a cultural product” achieved within a complex social structure including “elaborate systems of norms, ideals, and standards of evaluation” whereby men compete and order relationships among themselves (Rosaldo, “Woman, Culture, and Society: A Theoretical Overview,” in Woman, Culture, and Society, eds. Michele Zimbalist Rosaldo and Louise Lamphere [Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1974], 28, emphasis added). 13 See, for example, Nancy Chodorow’s classic work The Reproduction of Mothering: Pyschoanalysis and the Sociology of Gender (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1978); and Luise Eichenbaum and Susie Orback, “The Construction of Femininity,” in Women’s Spirituality: Resources for Christian Development, ed. Joann Wolski Conn (New York: Paulist Press, 1986), 128–49. 14 For an excellent analysis of this cultural ideal of individualism, beyond the feminist critique, see Robert Bellah et al., Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985). 15 Similar to Saiving’s critique of Reinhold Niebuhr’s theology on this ground, is Carol Gilligan’s faulting of Lawrence Kohlberg for his failure to account for the experiences of women and girls in his moral development theory. See Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development (Cambridge, Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 883 cuts to the very heart of John Paul II’s so-called “adequate anthropology” and even to the very heart of the Christian faith, as is evident in her argument as follows:“If human nature and the human situation are not as described [by male theologians], then the assertion that self-giving love is the law of man’s being is irrelevant and may even be untrue.”16 It must be granted that Saiving specifically addresses with these words neither the theological vision of the Council nor that of John Paul.17 Her argument nonetheless raises very significant questions, foundational to the teaching of Humanae Vitae: Firstly, that of whether it is at all possible to address human love and the ends of marriage in objective terms: in terms—to borrow from Saiving—addressing a “universal human situation” as opposed to a cultural situation marked by individualism, for example; secondly, whether it is possible to speak of self-realization in those same terms; whether, in other words, one might actually find oneself in the very act that appears as its contrary: that act expressed in the important Gospel formulation,“Whoever seeks to gain his life will lose it, but however loses his life will preserve it.”18 These two essential questions presuppose, in turn, third, requiring that we address it before the others: that of whether we might admit a metaphysical human nature, a nature, more specifically, implying an orientation to the properly human good of communion; from whence, finally, the question of the “place” (if any) of sexuality within that nature (if any). I. Of no little significance to this inquiry into the nature of love and human realization—not only for Saiving’s argument, but also for my own—is the question inspiring John Paul II’s apostolic letter on the dignity and vocation of women: that, more specifically,“of understanding the reason for and the consequences of the Creator’s decision that the human being should always and only exist as a woman or a man.”19 This very formulation, which grounds sexual difference in the mystery of creation, lies in contrast to the highly influential slogan of Simone de Beauvoir: “One is not born a woman; one becomes a woman.”20 In Beauvoir’s vision—and in the wide MA: Harvard University Press, 1982); Mapping the Moral Domain, eds. Carol Gilligan, Janie Ward, Jill McLean Taylor, and Betty Bardige (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1988). 16 Saiving, “The Human Situation,” 27. 17 Rather, she provides a specific critique of the theology of Reinhold Niebuhr. 18 Luke 17: 33. This scriptural reference is actually cited in a footnote in the very passage of Gaudium et Spes that we are considering: §24. 19 John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §1. 20 See Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, translated by H. M. Parshley (New York:Vintage Books, 1989). 884 Michele M. Schumacher approval that it has received among feminists21—is evident not only the sex-gender separation characteristic of modern feminism, but also the feminist denial of the whole metaphysical content of human nature, which has—like women herself under patriarchal control, that is to say, as she is perceived by feminism—been reduced to a sub-rational reality. Because it is woman’s “misfortune” to be “biologically destined” to transmit life, Simone de Beauvoir challenges her—that is to say, each woman—to rise above the “animal” act of giving life and to share instead in the masculine act of risking life. In so doing, she is said by Beauvoir to transcend the natural realm and enter into the properly human sphere, wherein man resides. It is in woman’s possibilities—which Beauvoir contrasts to her actual state—that she is comparable to man who, the French philosopher maintains, is a historical idea rather than a natural species.22 The feminist objection to a preconceived nature—one that is dynamically programmed by the Creator—is, therefore, based not so much upon a presentation of human nature, as upon the notion of a properly feminine nature which is aligned with the animal, or sub-rational, realm at odds with, or otherwise opposed to, the normative male, or rational, nature.23 Refusing—with good reason—to be reduced to their biological structure and/or to be “measured” by the male standard according to which they are judged not only different, but truly “Other,”24 many feminists simply refuse to grant any metaphysical content to sexual differences.25 Hence the body-spirit dual21 This insight, Donna Haraway claims, originated all modern feminist accounts of gender. See “ ‘Gender’ for a Marxist Dictionary: the Sexual Politics of a Word,” in Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1992), 131. 22 This insight she attributes more directly to Merleau-Ponty. See Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, 33, 64, 255, 34.To assimilate woman to Nature is, Beauvoir argues, “simply to act from prejudice” (ibid., 255). 23 As summarized by Virginia A Held: “The philosophical tradition that has purported to present the view of the essentially and universally human has, masked by this claim, presented instead a view that is masculine, white, and Western.” (Feminist Morality: Transforming Culture, Society and Politics [Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1993], 19). See Michele M. Schumacher,“The Nature of Nature in Feminism: Old and New” in Women in Christ:Toward a New Feminism, ed. Michele M. Schumacher (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2004), 17–51. 24 Perhaps the most classic argument among feminists in this regard is likewise that of Simone de Beauvoir: “She [woman] is defined and differentiated with reference to man and not he with reference to her; she is the incidental, the inessential as opposed to the essential. He is the Subject, he is the Absolute—she is the Other” (The Second Sex, xxii). 25 See Beatriz Vollmer de Marcellus, The Ontological Differentiation of Human Gender:A Critique of the Philosophical Literature between 1965 and 1995 (Philadelphia: Xlibris, 2004); and idem (published under her married name of Coles),“New Feminism:A Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 885 ism that they so often attribute to “androcentric” logic26 is transformed—as feminists have not only observed but also advanced—into a male-female dualism which, in turn, has given birth to a sort of androgynous hybrid that is both ideological and reactionary. Denied or otherwise refused are thus the essential differences within human nature itself—namely sexual differences affecting the whole body-spirit union of the human person—in virtue of which this nature might be understood as relational per se.27 It is precisely this refuted optic that lies at the heart of the catechism’s presentation of sexuality as affecting “all aspects of the human person in the unity of his [or her] body and soul” and thus also, more specifically, of “affectivity, the capacity to love and to procreate, and in a more general way the aptitude for forming bonds of communion with others.”28 Hence, in the feminist refutation of the metaphysical value of sexual difference, we are once again confronted with the question which more directly concerns us: that of human love and that, more precisely, of its metaphysical grounding. II. Such a metaphysical nature of love—one, more specifically, which is rooted within the human subject, and not only within his body29— might be explained in terms of the scholastic maxim: the good is what all things seek30; or “love denotes a certain adapting of the appetitive power Sex-Gender Reunion,” in Women in Christ, 52–104. 26 See Ina Praetorius,“In Search of the Feminine Condition: A Plea for a Women’s Ecumene,” Concilium (1991/6), 3. 27 In question is, in the words of Margaret McCarthy, not simply “an ‘abstract’ belonging to human nature, standing outside of or alongside difference, but a likeness carried within difference” (“ ‘Husbands, Love your Wives as Your Own Bodies’: Is Nuptial Love a Case of Love or Its Paradigm?” Communio 32 [2005], 288). Similar is the insight of Balthasar, also noted by McCarthy: “God did not simply create mankind male and female as he had created the animals male and female.” To be sure, he created them “to be one in the duality of sex,” but he also, Balthasar insists, “created their duality out of their own oneness” (Balthasar, The Christian State of Life, trans. Mary Frances McCarthy [San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1983], 227). 28 Catechism of the Catholic Church, §2332. 29 In the words of Pope Benedict XVI, “it is neither the spirit alone nor the body alone that loves: it is man, the person, a unified creature composed of body and soul, who loves. Only when both dimensions are truly united, does man attain his full stature. Only thus is love—eros—able to mature and attain its authentic grandeur” (Deus Caritas Est, §5). 30 See, for example,Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I–II, q. 27, a. 1, ad 3; I–II, q. 28, a. 6; I–II, q. 94, a. 2. Michele M. Schumacher 886 to some good.”31 It follows, then—at least for the scholastic mind—that love aims at a commingling of the subject and the object towards which he or she is naturally and willfully bent,32 an idea sadly lacking in most feminist claims.33 Love proper to the will is, in other words, by its very nature, transitive and personal. “To love,” Josef Pieper explains, “always implies to love someone or something. And if this element is missing in a definition, it has failed to hit its target.”34 This, in turn, means that there is a double dynamic involved in the movements motivated by love. I am, firstly, drawn inwardly (or subjectively) toward that which (or toward one whom) I passionately or instinctively desire or, more nobly,35 toward that which (or toward one whom) I willfully—that is rationally—esteem as good and thus desirable. Secondly, I am at the same time—hence the priority is not temporal but ontological—drawn outwardly (or objectively) as it were, by an actual attraction whose force lies less in me than in the objective goodness of the person or thing whom I love.36 These two aspects of attraction—the subjective and objective—are so interwoven in an actual act of love that it is, as Cornelius Murphy argues, “practically impossible to distinguish what is receptive from what is out-going.”37 We might thus speak of a sort of magnetic force at work in the movements that we call “love”:38 a force supposing a potential, or passive, force of attraction rooted within me—that is to say, in my nature—in the form of 31 ST I–II, q. 28, a. 5. English translation throughout from the Benzinger Brothers edition, 1947. 32 “The rational creature,”Thomas argues, “naturally desires to be happy; hence, it cannot wish not to be happy” (Summa contra Gentiles, trans. Charles J. O’Neil [Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1957], IV, 92, 4 [p. 339]). 33 The subtitle of Christina Traina’s notable exception is revelatory of the situation: Feminist Ethics and Natural Law:The End of the Anathemas (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1999). 34 About Love, trans. Richard and Clara Winston (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1972), 77. Such, more specifically, is the love of friendship. See ST I, q. 20, a. 2, ad 3. 35 The specification bespeaks the degrees of the various appetites of human beings: the natural appetites which we also share with non-animated beings, the sensitive appetite that we share with irrational animals, and the rational appetite, which is proper to us, qua human. See ST I–II, q. 26, a. 1. 36 St. Thomas Aquinas teaches, for example, that unlike the divine will, which creates the good in things and persons, our own human will is moved by the good pre-existing in things. See ST I–II, q. 110, a. 1. 37 Cornelius Murphy, Beyond Feminism:Toward a Dialogue on Difference (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 1995), 140. 38 In question is whether in fact love might properly be considered a movement, as shall be made increasingly evident. Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 887 my natural, sensitive, and rational appetites39; and a force of attracting rooted in the objective nature of the object or person whom I love. Hence, as Aquinas explains, it is the object of love that is the cause of love,40 from whence the twofold distinction regarding the union of loved and beloved: the real union,“consisting in the conjunction of the one with the other,” which is proper to joy or pleasure, and the affective union— preceding both this real union and even the movement of desire toward this end—consisting in “an aptitude or proportion” in virtue of which one might be said to already partake of that toward which (or the one toward whom) he or she is thus inclined.41 This means, as Michael Sherwin has masterfully argued, that before love is a principle of action, it is “a response to goodness,”42 particularly in the form of “a pleasant affective affinity” that St.Thomas calls complacentia.43 These two interwoven aspects of love—the subjective and objective dimensions which meet in complacentia—might also be interpreted in terms of ecstasy: that love whereby the lover is moved out of himself,44 as is the case in a properly erotic love. The so-called lover, who remains concentrated upon his own interest, does not really love in the proper sense, C. S. Lewis tells us. It is not union with the Beloved that he seeks, but merely the pleasure that she might afford him. His desire is simply for a woman, in contrast to the one beloved woman whom the truly erotic lover contemplates day and night.45 From this perspective, love cannot be 39 See ST I–II, q. 26, a. 1; and I–II, q. 94, a. 2. 40 ST I–II, q. 27, a. 1; cf. I–II, q. 25, a. 2. 41 ST I–II, q. 25, a. 2. 42 More specifically: “It is a response to God’s goodness, to rational creatures’ fellowship in this goodness, and to the goodness proper to non-rational creatures in their ordered relationship to God and our fellowship with Him” (Michael S. Sherwin, “Aquinas, Augustine, and the Medieval Scholastic Crisis concerning Charity,” in Aquinas the Augustinian, eds. Michael Dauphinais, Barry David, and Matthew Levering [Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2007], 199). See also his By Knowledge and by Love: Charity and Knowledge in the Moral Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2005), esp. 63–118. 43 “This affinity,” Sherwin specifies, is “the aptitude, inclination, or proportion existing in the appetite for the loved object” (By Knowledge and by Love, 70). 44 ST I–II, q. 28, a. 3: “To suffer ecstasy means to be placed outside oneself.” 45 “We use a most unfortunate idiom [therefore] when we say, of a lustful man prowling the streets,” Lewis explains,“that he ‘wants a woman.’ Strictly speaking, a woman is just what he does not want. He wants a pleasure for which a woman happens to be the necessary piece of apparatus. How much he cares about the woman as such may be gauged by his attitude to her five minutes after fruition (one does not keep the carton after one has smoked the cigarettes)” (Lewis, The 888 Michele M. Schumacher adequately addressed in terms of the popular maxim as “blind,” for it is necessarily endowed with an objective nature: objective with regard to its object—the other,46 who is considered objectively attractive, and thus good, not only for me but in se 47—and objective as to its subject, that is to say, with regard to the lover, who possesses the real capacity of being attracted to the other and thus also to being placed “outside himself,” so as to dwell upon the beloved or to be otherwise moved toward communion with her. This attraction, in other words, all in really being rooted in the subject, is nonetheless that whereby the lover is orientated to the beloved qua other, and not simply as an object of his own interest.When such is the situation—when the lover is not really placed outside himself, as is the case in the love of concupiscence—the object of his love remains, in fact, himself.48 Four Loves [1960; New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1988], 94). Similar is the insight of Pope Benedict XVI: “Eros, reduced to pure ‘sex,’ has become a commodity, a mere ‘thing’ to be bought and sold, or rather, man himself becomes a commodity” (Deus Caritas Est, §5). 46 The “other” is here understood not in the Sartrian sense as one who necessarily limits my freedom by setting constraints upon me, by objectifying me—that is to say, by directing me according to his own interests—but in the sense of Levinas: as one who remains mystery, and as such awakens my capacity for exchange and thus also, in a certain sense, my freedom. 47 On the other hand, to address the objective nature of love is to acknowledge not only the objective goodness of the object or of the person loved, but also and especially the fittingness of that object or person to or for me. Hence, it is possible to speak of one’s loves as either perfecting or degrading with regard to one’s very self. “Nothing is hurt by being adapted to that which is suitable to it,” St. Thomas argues; “rather, if possible, it is perfected and bettered. But if a thing be adapted to that which is not suitable to it, it is hurt and made worse thereby. Consequently love of a suitable good perfects and betters the lover; but love of a good which is unsuitable to the lover, wounds and worsens him” (ST I–II, q. 28, a. 6). Even the so-called subjective value of our loves have objective weight from this perspective, which is to say that they might be judged, according to objective criteria, as appropriate to, or befitting, one’s (human) nature. 48 “In love of concupiscence, the lover is carried out of himself, in a certain sense; insofar, namely, as not being satisfied with enjoying the good that he has, he seeks to enjoy something outside himself. But since he seeks to have this extrinsic good for himself, he does not go out from himself simply, and this movement remains finally within him. On the other hand, in the love of friendship, a man’s affection goes out from itself simply; because he wishes and does good to his friend, by caring and providing for him, for his sake” (ST I–II, q. 28, a. 3). See also Peter A. Kwasniewski, “St. Thomas, Extasis, and the Union with the Beloved,” The Thomist 61 (1997): 587–603. Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 889 When, therefore, we address love in terms of self-giving—as does Paul VI in Humanae Vitae 49 and John Paul II in his defense of the same50—this need not be understood in the negative sense as self-abnegation or selfdenial, but rather in the positive sense of a particular valorizing of the other, such that one is, as it were, forgetful of oneself: one’s thoughts and energies are concentrated more upon the other than upon oneself. This is not to deny the fulfillment of one’s own deepest desires; for these are simultaneously inclined, in a natural manner, to the being that is loved and to one’s own good.51 Eros, as Murphy explains, draws us out of ourselves,“arousing yearnings of happiness that we are powerless to resist. However, it opens up possibilities that it cannot of itself fulfill”52; hence the distinction between the transient and the transcendent nature of love.53 We are truly orientated to the other by every one of our appetitive powers—natural, sensual and rational—but our happiness does not lie in the other. Rather, that which we long for is the communion realized by a mutual gift of self: a communion which, far from negating the 49 Human love is presented, more specifically, as “a compound of sense and spirit”— bespeaking man’s corporal-spiritual unity—and thus not merely a matter “of natural instinct or emotional drive. It is also, and above all,” Paul VI insists,“an act of the free will.”This (free will) is not, in turn, to be understood—in the spirit of this same document—as an autonomous power, but rather as a God-given faculty in virtue of which one acts, in accord with objective criteria, to achieve one’s human potential—to fulfill oneself as a person—and at the same time to contribute to the good of the other. “Whoever really loves his partner” does so, Humanae Vitae teaches us, “not only for what he receives, but loves that partner for her own sake, content to be able to enrich the other with the gift of himself ” (Humanae Vitae, §9). 50 See, most especially, his famous theology of the body: Man and Woman He Created Them. 51 “Every agent acts for an end. . . . Now the end is the good desired and loved by each one. Wherefore it is evident that every agent, whatever it be, does every action from love of some kind” (ST I–II, q. 28, a. 6). 52 Murphy, Beyond Feminism, 141. 53 Every love is transient: it is ordered by necessity to an object other than the lover himself.This act of being drawn out of oneself need not, however, be understood as elevating, for I might be degraded by a love whose object is unsuitable to my own nature, as St.Thomas argues (see note 47 above), or in the positive sense of a love that entails a kenotic movement of sacrifice: an authentic giving of oneself. Especially in this second sense, the transient character might take on the specific form of immanence, that is to say, the giving of oneself in such a way as to receive the other.This, in other words is a giving which makes “room” for the reception of the other’s self gift, and this reception requires—given the nature of the gift as personal—a personalist response: the gift of one’s very self. See John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §29. 890 Michele M. Schumacher personality of its members, actually serves their development. In the words of Pope John Paul II: When God-Yahweh says,“It is not good that the man should be alone” (Gen 2:18), he affirms that,“alone,” the man does not completely realize this essence. He realizes it only by existing “with someone”—and, put even more deeply and completely, by existing “for someone.”. . . Communion of persons means living in a reciprocal “for,” in a relationship of reciprocal gift.54 III. We are now, perhaps, better positioned to respond to Saiving’s challenge of any notion of self-giving love which might foster the particular womanly tendency of seeking one’s identity in another, a tendency which Saiving qualifies as sinful. “[I]f [as male theologians insist] this refusal to become selfless is wholly sinful,” she reasons, “then it would seem that we are obliged to try to overcome it; and, when it is overcome, to whatever extent this may be possible, we are left with a chameleonlike creature who responds to others but has no personal identity of his own.”55 Obviously, Saiving is not objecting to the traditional anthropological notion of transcendence—a dynamic tending of the person towards what is greater than him- or herself—but to its very contrary: the abasement or even denial of one’s own self. On the other hand, the paradox of realizing oneself and even transcending oneself precisely in the act of being “emptied” after the pattern of Christ, as in the famous hymn of Philippians 2:3–11,56 is hardly avoidable in Christian thought and spir54 Man and Woman He Created Them, §14:2 ( January 2, 1980), p. 182. Similarly: “Human life is by its nature ‘co-educational’ and its dignity as well as its balance depend at every moment of history and in every place of geographic longitude and latitude on ‘who’ she shall be for him and he for her.” (Man and Woman He Created Them, §43:7 [October 8, 1980], p. 301); “In the [original] ‘unity of the two,’ man and woman are called from the beginning not only to exist ‘side by side’ or ‘together,’ but they are also called to exist mutually ‘one for the other’ ” ( John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §7). 55 Saiving, “The Human Situation,” 41. 56 “Do nothing from selfishness or conceit, but in humility count others better than yourselves. Let each of you look not only to his own interests, but also to the interests of others. Have this mind among yourselves, which you have in Christ Jesus, who, though he was in the form of God, did not count equality with God a thing to be grasped, but emptied himself, taking the form of a servant, being born in the likeness of men. And being found in human form he humbled himself and became obedient unto death, even death on a cross.Therefore God has highly exalted him and bestowed on him the name which is above every name, that at the name of Jesus every knee should bow, in heaven and on earth Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 891 ituality.To reject this kenotic attitude is, it would seem as some Christian feminists have argued,57 to reject the distinctively Christian manner of redemption. It is, in other words, not simply human self-realization that is in question, but salvation itself.58 Precisely this distinction which illuminates the seriousness of the stakes— the distinction between self-realization and salvation—might, it seems to me, serve our response to this important feminist challenge.As in the example of so valorizing another that one forgets or loses focus of oneself,59 the denying of oneself for love of Christ is only secondarily negative. In the primary sense, it should be understood as the positive act of preparing oneself for the divine Visitor, of making room, or clearing space, within oneself for his divinizing visit, and thus also of ridding oneself of all that hinders communion with him.60 It is precisely within this communion, moreover, that salvation is realized and not within a Buddhist ideal of emptiness. It is in this communion that the human person is fulfilled to the very and under the earth, and every tongue confess that Jesus Christ is Lord, to the glory of God the Father” (Phil 2: 3–11). 57 See, for example, Kerry Ramsay, “Losing One’s Life for Others: Self-Sacrifice Revisited,” in Challenging Women’s Orthodoxies in the Context of Faith, ed. Susan Frank Parsons (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2000), 121–33; and Sarah Coakley, “Kenosis and Subversion: On the Repression of ‘Vulnerability’ in Christian Feminist Writing,” in idem, Powers and Submissions: Spirituality, Philosophy and Gender (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), 3–39. Coakley also makes reference to the very influential Rosemary Radford Ruether (Sexism and God-Talk [London: SCM Press, 1983], 137–38) as likewise defending this notion. Tina Beattie, combining the insights of Saiving and Coakley, argues:“The problem that feminists of faith must negotiate is that, without some form of the giving of self in prayer and in human relationships, the modern, autonomous subject remains the foundation upon which the postmodernist self constructs its ostensibly deconstructive parodies and performances. . . .The challenge is to discover a way of being that preserves the fragile sense of self that women are beginning to acquire in modern culture, while allowing that self to willingly abandon herself to God in the confidence that this God is an Other who participates in our personal becoming and makes us more rather than less the selves we seek to be” (Beattie, New Catholic Feminism:Theology and Theory [London: Routledge, 2006], 72, 73). 58 This in turn requires that we admit the important, typically Catholic, distinction between objective and subjective redemption: between, that is to say, Christ’s salvific act “for us all” (cf. 1 Tim 2:6) and each one’s personal appropriation of his merits on our behalf. 59 As Georgio Buccellati puts it with regard to the Christian’s relation to Christ:“I yield to affirm.” (“Religious Vows and the Structure of Love,” Communio 23 [1996]: 562). 60 On this see, Michele M. Schumacher,“Toward a Spirituality of Poverty,” Nova et Vetera 3 (2005): 217–30, esp. 221–26. 892 Michele M. Schumacher depths of his soul. “You made us for yourself, O Lord,” St. Augustine fittingly recognizes,“and our hearts are restless until we rest in you.”61 This analogy between the gift of self, whereby we are salvifically united with Christ, and the gift of self to the human other, whereby we might be said to realize ourselves as persons, or to realize our human potential, is also expressed in what Hans Urs von Balthasar calls, with reference to Genesis 2:23,62 the “basic law” of the human person: “it is in the Thou . . . that we find our I.”63 “God became man,” Balthasar explains, “so that this law, which is understandable to us—perhaps the most understandable of all the laws of life—should turn for us into the definitive law of being, explaining and satisfying everything.”64 Obviously, he does not mean to thereby encourage the neglect or degradation of one’s own self and the subsequent assuming of another’s identity: that sinful refusal of one’s own “I” or of the dignity that is rightfully accorded to oneself as a being willed by God for his or her own sake.65 Rather, this insight might be described by what Karol Wojtyla presents as “the law of the gift”66: In the normal course of events, the thou assists me in more fully discovering and even confirming my own I: the thou contributes to my selfaffirmation. In its basic form, the I-thou relationship, far from leading me away from my subjectivity, in some sense more firmly grounds me in it.67 Like Balthasar,Wojtyla explains this law in terms of human self-discovery within the specific context of the Genesis story of Eve’s creation. In the gift of the human other, the person is revealed to himself in the whole objective truth of his own ontological and ethical goodness: he understands himself not only as loved—and thus loveable—but also as capable of love and called to love. Loved into being by the Creator who—in virtue of the 61 Augustine of Hippo, Confessions I, 1. 62 “This at last is bone of my bones and flesh of my flesh.” 63 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Convergences:To the Source of Christian Mystery (San Fran- cisco: Ignatius Press, 1983), 128. 64 “In Christian faith alone, then—to say it once more—lies the single sufficient explanation for human existence” (ibid., 130–31). See also his A Theological Anthropology (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1967), 312–13. 65 Cf. Gaudium et Spes, §24; and John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §7. 66 Karol Wojtyla, “The Personal Structure of Self-Determination” in idem, Person and Community: Selected Essays, trans. Theresa Sandok, O.S.M. (New York: Peter Lang, 1993), 194. 67 Karol Wojtyla,“The Person: Subject and Community” in idem, Person and Community, 242–43. Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 893 primary gift of human freedom—has entrusted the rational creature to himself, this creature comes to know himself as an object of love.With the gift of the woman—the gift of another human “I”—he is given, or revealed, to himself also and more specifically as a subject of love: his ontological orientation to interpersonal communion68 is inwardly appropriated, as it were, and his loving powers are awakened within him. He thus knows himself as possessing a certain value not only “before God,” but also as for himself:“first,” John Paul II explains,“because he is ‘man’; second, because the ‘woman’ is for the man and, vice versa, the ‘man’ for the woman.”69 The gift of the human other—whose reception is prepared by the gift of human freedom—is thus the origin of a call to interpersonal communion: to “the shared life that makes up the pure and simple guiding thread of human existence,”70 wherein John Paul II recognizes the unfolding of the whole drama of human history, including the history of salvation.71 It is a history marked by the determining question of who she will be for him and he for her, the question of whether a utilitarian or a personalist value will be ethically awarded to the ontological orientation expressed as “being for” another.72 IV. Let us opt for the second of those meanings: the personalist meaning of “being for.”Would it not be possible from within this personalist optic to regard those so-called masculine and feminine tendencies to sin within 68 “The man’s solitude in the Yahwist account presents itself to us not only as the first discovery of the characteristic transcendence proper to the person, but also as the discovery of an adequate relation ‘to’ the person, and thus as opening toward and waiting for a ‘communion of persons’ ” (Man and Woman He Created Them, §9:2 [November 14, 1979], 162). 69 Ibid., §9:1, pp. 161–62. “While Genesis 1,” he continues, “expresses this value in a purely theological (and indirectly metaphysical) form, Genesis 2, by contrast, reveals, so to speak, the first circle of experience lived by man as a value” (ibid., 162). 70 Ibid., §43:7 (October 8, 1980), 301. 71 See John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §7. 72 See John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §43:7 (October 8, 1980), 301; cf. John Paul II, Mulieris Dignitatem, §14. “Only a person can love and only a person can be loved.This statement is primarily ontological in nature, and it gives rise to an ethical affirmation. Love is an ontological and ethical requirement of the person.The person must be loved, since love alone corresponds to what the person is” (ibid., §29) It is not surprising, then, that Michael Waldstein recognizes already in the pre-papal writings of John Paul II (Karol Wojtyla) “the truth about the human person” and “the heart of the individual drama of our lives” presented as “the history of love or its negation” (Waldstein, introduction to Man and Woman He Created Them, 143). For a very thorough philosophical analysis of this ethical and ontological concept, see Kenneth Schmitz, “Selves or Persons: A Difference in Loves?” Communio 18 (1991): 183–206. 894 Michele M. Schumacher more positive terms, namely, as tendencies in love and more specifically still as differing and complementary manners of self-giving: love in the form of self-bestowal and love in the form of receptive availability?73 Woman’s admittedly negative tendency to “dissipate herself in activities which are merely trivial,” make it possible, Saiving observes, “to perform cheerfully the thousand-and-one routine tasks—the woman’s work that is never done—which someone must do if life is to go on.”74 Likewise, her sinful tendency—as noted by Edith Stein—to hover “anxiously over her children as if they were her own possessions,” binding them to herself at any cost, even that of their own freedom and that of her husband’s paternal authority and rights,75 are more positively regarded, she notes, in terms of a particular capacity to sympathize with and serve other human beings,76 a value which is addressed by John Paul II in terms of the specific “genius” of women.77 Similarly, man’s sinful avoidance of his paternal responsibility, noticed by Stein, is countered by what she and Saiving both acknowledge as a certain pursuit of excellence and a highly creative spirit. He is also more likely, due to his more sensual nature, as Paul Quay notes, to initiate a romantic relationship than is woman, thereby assuming the risk of unreciprocated love.78 73 “To receive someone, a guest for example, is popularly understood as offering him or her hospitality, welcoming him into one’s home, sharing what one has; but there is also a deeper, more intimate meaning which aims at an authentic communion of persons. In this second sense, one may be said to communicate who one is, to give one’s very self, but in such a way as to simultaneously welcome the other’s self-gift, as when a woman is said to ‘receive’ in the sexual embrace the man who loves her in giving himself.When this ‘other’ is the Lord, the receptive act implies both surrender and devotion as are simultaneously evoked by the German term Hingabe. In Scripture, the two forms of receptivity are perhaps best modeled by Martha, the busy hostess, and Mary, the quiet contemplative who has chosen ‘the one thing needful,’‘the better part’ (Lk 10:42). Like that other Mary, most ‘blessed among women,’ she receives Christ, not merely as visitor but as Lord; not just in her home, but in her heart” (Schumacher,“Toward a Spirituality of Poverty,” 225). 74 Saiving, “The Human Situation,” 38. 75 Stein, Essays on Woman, 75. 76 This explains, she adds, why women are “naturally” assigned the principal share of educating children. See ibid., 72. 77 See Mulieris Dignitatem, §§30, 31; idem, Letter to Women on the occasion of the Beijing Conference, Origins 25 (1995): §9; idem, Christifideles Laici, §51; idem, encyclical letter on the Gospel of Life, Evangelium Vitae (1995), §99; and Michele M. Schumacher, “The Prophetic Vocation of Women and the Order of Love,” Logos 2 (1999): 147–92. 78 See Paul Quay, The Christian Meaning of Human Sexuality (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1985), ch. 3. This typically masculine character trait stands in contrast to women’s typically sentimental disposition. On the risk of non-reciprocated love, Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 895 The countering of what might be considered sinful tendencies with positive human values—both within each individual human person and within culture as a whole—is not, however, realized in isolation but precisely within a community of persons, and more specifically still, although not exclusively, within that community of persons formed of the marriage bond: persons vowed to one another in an exclusive and permanent union, which is also open to life. My reasoning here is simple: this union so tightly binds its partners—not in what Edith Stein’s translator has rendered “the separate vocations of man and woman according to nature and grace”79—but rather in a common, shared vocation according to nature and grace: the universal human vocation to love.80 It is, moreover, within the specific vocation of marriage and the experience of spousal love—the experience of being entrusted with the gift of the other person and his specific difference by the Creator himself—that might be awakened, John Paul II argues, a personal sense of responsibility for the other and his welfare: a responsibility that should be lived as “a sincere gift of self.”81 Beyond this, it is precisely because men and women really are different and really do give themselves differently, I maintain, that they are particularly suited to provide mutual help (cf. Gen 2:18), especially, but not exclusively, in their parenting responsibilities. In so doing, moreover, we come to a deeper knowledge of ourselves and we develop as persons, both individually and communally.82 By this I do not mean that we simply rub up against see Kenneth Schmitz’s analysis of a gift that is not received, The Gift: Creation (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1982), 48–49. 79 This is the English title that is given to the second essay in the English collection of her works on women (Essays on Woman), emphasis added. The original German is more accurately translated as simply: “The vocation of man and woman according to the order of nature and grace” (Beruf des Mannes und der Frau nach Natur- und Gnadenordung). See Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, vol. 13, Die Frau. Fragestellungen und Reflexionen, ed. Hanna-Barbara Gerl-Falkovitz (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder, 2000), 56–78. 80 “God inscribed in the humanity of man and woman the vocation, and thus the capacity and responsibility, of love and communion. Love is therefore the fundamental and innate vocation of every human being” ( John Paul II, apostolic exhortation on “The Role of the Christian Family in the Modern World,” Familiaris Consortio [1981], §11). It is perhaps worth noting that Hans Urs von Balthasar recognizes in the reciprocity of man and woman “a paradigm of that community dimension which characterizes man’s entire nature” (Theo-Drama: Theological Dramatic Theory, vol. 2, Dramatic Personae: Man in God, trans. Graham Harrison [San Francisco: Ignatius Press, l992], 365). See also Margaret McCarthy, “ ‘Husbands, Love your Wives as Your Own Bodies.’ ” 81 See Mulieris Dignitatem, §14. 82 “Ours are,” as John Paul II teaches, “two complementary dimensions of selfknowledge and self-determination, and at the same time, two complementary ways 896 Michele M. Schumacher one another, purifying ourselves and the other in the process, like two diamonds in the rough. Nor is this a matter of seeking—precisely in our contrasts—the Aristotelian “mean” wherein virtue is said to reside,83 or of becoming an accomplice to the other’s shortcomings, as is the case of the silent, perfectly submissive wife, who might be thought of, in the words of Jean Bethke Elshtain, as the “perfect companion to the ‘self-made man’ of being conscious of the meaning of the body. Thus, as Genesis 2:3 already shows, femininity in some way finds itself before masculinity, while masculinity confirms itself through femininity. . . . The presence of the feminine element, next to the masculine and together with it, signifies an enrichment for man in the whole perspective of his history, including the history of salvation” (Man and Woman He Created Them, §10:1 [November 21, 1979], 166). Similarly, but from a more objective perspective than that of self-knowledge, he notes: “The Bible convinces us of the fact that one can have no adequate hermeneutic of man, or of what is ‘human,’ without appropriate reference to what is ‘feminine’ ” (Mulieris Dignitatem, §22).This insight is complementary to that of Paul Evdokimov:“The more man and woman each deepen their own type, and do so not in isolation but in archetypal reciprocity, the closer they come to fully assimilating their counterpart’s positive core, and thus arrive at their own truth” (Woman and the Salvation of the World: A Christian Anthropology on the Charisms of Women, trans. Anthony P. Gythiel [Crestwood, NY: St.Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1994], 250). Even more insightful is the argument of Margaret McCarthy who maintains that sexual difference is what accounts for the placing of nuptial love at “front and center” of the Christian tradition: “as the first and paradigmatic expression of love among other loves” (and in this regard we need only mention Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, §11): “[T]he movement towards the opposite sex,” McCarthy continues, “is never the movement of a mere aspect of oneself nor a movement towards a mere aspect of the other; it is, rather, a movement of and towards a particularity in which the whole of his or her humanity is expressed.” For this reason, she explains that “the movement towards the opposite sex is not per se a love of the other per accidens, whereby the other person is reduced to an object for the one loving (even if this is abundantly possible when sexual difference is taken to be a mere aspect of one’s humanity and not the vehicle of its manifestation). It is rather the possibility of an affirmation of the good of the other as other, that is, of his or her (similar) humanity which always exists bodily in a different manner. This possibility is moreover the possibility of one’s own fulfillment, for here one encounters ‘another self ’ not only because by seeing in the other a common humanity (or some other similarity) one identifies with the other, and so extends his love for himself thereby expanding his own good (now a larger common good), but also because by associating with this other in his or her difference and leaving one’s former place, so to speak, to be resituated, one now has oneself—one now has one’s ‘body’—all the more and is more at home” (McCarthy, “Husbands, Love your Wives as Your Own Bodies,” 267, 294). 83 Hence, for example, a woman would try to imitate the masculine qualities of her husband and he of his wife, so that both might arrive somewhere in between the typically male and the typically female. Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 897 whose tough, pragmatic, no-nonsense code is ‘free choice,’ ‘no constraints,’ and ‘my life is my own.’ ”84 Rather, that mysterious “law” of finding one’s “I” in the “thou” is operative here in a special way: not in the so-called feminine tendency to lose oneself or one’s identity in the other, the concentrating of one’s energies so much upon another’s life that we prevent him from authentically living his own.85 Nor, in that more “masculine” tactic of conforming the other to my vision of things, of aggressively seeking her good or even preparing her whole future for her and then requiring of her—for her “own good,” of course—to assume her place therein. Nor, still, is this the somewhat androgynous ridding oneself of any such tendency whatsoever or the striving to adopt, for oneself, the other’s particular character structure. No, this finding of oneself in the other means that the “thou” reveals my feminine specificity to me in contrast—or better, in its complementarity—to his own masculinity. More significantly still, my femininity is revealed in the value that he accords to it as an essential, innate aspect of my person as sexed. As such, it is specifically entrusted to him, with my entire person, for his safekeeping, a safekeeping requiring that he encourage my human, feminine and personal growth, from whence we might recognize a certain harmony between the cultural, or acquired, aspects of femininity and the innate ones.86 And indeed, it is his sincere love for me—his delight in the fact that I exist as me, and thus also as feminine—that both encourages and incites my own particularly feminine manner of loving him in return.87 84 Jean Bethke Elshtain,“ ‘Thank Heaven for Little Girls’:The Dialectics of Devel- opment,” in The Family in Political Thought, ed. Jean Bethke Elshtain (Brighton, England:The Harvest Press, 1982), 299. 85 Such is the case of C. S. Lewis’s “Mrs. Fidget”: “For Mrs. Fidget, as she so often said, would ‘work her fingers to the bone’ for her family.They couldn’t stop her. Nor could they—being decent people—quite sit still and watch her do it.They had to help. Indeed they were always having to help.That is, they did things for her to help her to do things for them which they didn’t want done.” Such, Lewis explains, is a form of gift-love,“but one that needs to be needed. But the proper aim of giving is to put the recipient in a state where he no longer needs our gift” (The Four Loves, 50). 86 For a treatment of these three aspects of every woman’s character structure (human, feminine, and personal) as it is presented in the thought of Edith Stein, see Sibylle von Streng, “Woman’s Threefold Vocation according to Edith Stein,” in Women in Christ, 105–38. In that which concerns the dynamic between the innate and the acquired aspects of femininity, see Schumacher, “The Nature of Nature in Feminism, Old and New.” 87 “The Bridegroom,” explains John Paul II, with reference to Ephesians 5,“is the one who loves. The Bride is loved: it is she who receives love, in order to love in return” (Mulieris Dignitatem, §29). It is extremely important that these words by John Paul II be read for what they are: not a “further” effort of the Church to submit women 898 Michele M. Schumacher Precisely in receiving him as a man—as gratefully encouraging and promoting his masculinity and accepting his self-gift in the form of my own selfgift—I, in turn, encourage, foster and promote his specifically masculine manner of loving.88 In so doing, I say in my own particularly feminine manner, what Bobby Vinton made popular in his 1968 hit because it was true:“Darling, most of all, I love how you love me.” V. Assuredly, to conclude, we are not without an alternative to this vision of things. In fact, many individualistic and self-centered men, as well as a growing number of independently minded and willfully “unhampered” women, prefer the tune of Tina Turner’s “What’s Love Got to Do with It?” There are, however, consequences to the words we live by. Loving one another as our humanity requires—as befits the personalist definition of the person89—entails allowing the other to give him- or herself to me and to others.To the extent that the so-called masculine tendency toward individualism has hindered authentic self-giving among men, it has likewise hindered self-giving among women. It should not come as a surprise, then, that many women have experienced self-giving as self-abnegation. On the other hand, when we refuse to give ourselves as women—in our body-spirit whole, including our female fertility—we simultaneously refuse to receive our husbands as men: to receive them, in other words, in that “reciprocally completing” manner, as John Paul II puts it, of “being a body and at the same time as being human.”90 We consequently frusto male dominance, but a personalist insistence that “the dignity of women” be “measured by the order of love, which is essentially the order of justice and charity” (ibid.). Indeed, far from arguing for the subjection of women to their husbands (cf. Pius XI, Casti Connubi, §15), John Paul II insists upon the “mutual subjection” of the spouses “out of reverence for Christ” (cf. Eph 5:21) “and not just that of the wife to the husband.”This, he teaches, is a specific “Gospel innovation” that “must gradually establish itself in hearts, consciences, behaviour and customs” (Mulieris Dignitatem, §24). For a thorough treatment of this notion of “the order of love” in Mulieris Dignitatem, see Michele M. Schumacher, “The Prophetic Vocation of Women and the Order of Love,” 147–92. 88 Helpful for this analysis might be Kenneth Schmitz’s treatment of receptivity as conditioning giving: “What is a gift? It is a free endowment upon another who receives it freely” (The Gift, 44). “Despite the absolute gratuity inherent in the gift as endowment, reciprocity is appropriate to the gift. A gift is meant to be reciprocated. The fundamental reciprocity called for, however, is not the return of another gift. It is rather the completion of the gift being given.” It must, in other words, be received (ibid., 47). 89 Cf. Mulieris Dignitatem, §29 (cited in note 71 above); and Redemptoris Hominis, §10. 90 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §10:1 (November 21, 1979), 166. Feminism, Nature, and Humanae Vitae 899 trate our husbands’ masculine manner of giving themselves and thus also that revelation of our own specific beauty and truth as feminine. We furthermore deny that prophetic display of “genius,” that particularly feminine sensitivity for persons, that Pope John Paul II challenges us to provide in the promotion of a culture of life.91 That genius is most especially at work when a woman witnesses to her husband that of which she is keenly aware: that in receiving his love, she is receiving his very person, and not only his person, but also his seed. In accepting that seed as proof of her love for him, she not only realizes her own vocation as wife and potential mother,92 she also reveals the man to himself as husband and potential father. Human love—especially marital love—is not, therefore, a finding of oneself in the other by way of either identification or aggressive dominance; nor is it a simple vis-à-vis without transcendence, a self-serving communion which like feminism and the culture as a whole, “vacillates between,” what Balthasar describes as, “the emancipation of the microego in anarchic sovereignty and the emancipation of a ‘we,’ a macro-ego, in a collective tyranny that absorbs the freedom of the individual.”93 No, true love is rather “ecstasy,” as Pope Benedict XVI, describes it: not in the sense of a moment of intoxication, but rather as a journey, an ongoing exodus out of the closed inward-looking self towards its liberation through self-giving, and thus towards authentic self-discovery and indeed the discovery of God: “Whoever seeks to gain his life will lose it, but whoever loses his life will preserve it” (Lk 17:33), as Jesus says throughout the Gospels (cf. Mt 10:39; 16:25; Mk 8:35; Lk 9:24; Jn 12:25).94 N&V 91 See Evangelium Vitae, §99. 92 She is not, in other words, simply his mistress, but truly his partner in the sense described by the second chapter of Genesis, especially verse 23. 93 “[B]oth claim universality,” he continues, “but what they portray is only a personal apartheid or a collective party” (Hans Urs von Balthasar, In the Fullness of Faith: On the Centrality of the Distinctively Catholic, trans. Graham Harrison [San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1988], 44). For a critique of the individualism that has deeply infected feminist thought itself, see Elizabeth Fox-Genovese, Feminism without Illusions: A Critique of Individualism (Chapel Hill & London:The University of North Carolina Press, 1991). 94 Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, §6. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 901–926 901 Reflections on Humanae Vitae in the Light of Fides et Ratio M ARY S HIVANANDAN John Paul II Institute Washington, DC I N A MOVIE called Castaway, Tom Hanks is marooned on a remote island in the South Pacific after a plane crash. With the help of the contents of a few FEDEX packages washed ashore with him, he builds a shelter and starts planning his escape.A reef against which the surf crashes prevents him from getting beyond the enclosed lagoon to the ocean. All the ingenuity he can muster will not allow him to surmount the wall of foam. His makeshift raft is continuously tossed back to the island. After four years, during which he comes to the point of suicidal despair, the sea gives up a large metal sheet from beyond the reef.At last he is able to build a raft using the metal sheet as a sail, which carries him over the reef. For four years the castaway had studied the seasons, the wind, and the waves. Armed with this knowledge, and a boundless faith in life itself, he sails out into the ocean and the whole wide world is once again open to him. In the encyclical Fides et Ratio, John Paul II calls the preaching of Christ crucified and risen “the reef upon which the link between the faith and philosophy can break up, but it is also the reef beyond which the two can set forth upon the boundless ocean of truth. Here we see not only the border between reason and faith, but also the space where the two may meet.”1 Man cannot escape the horizon of his own limited existence through reason alone. He needs the revelation that comes from beyond if he is to know “the boundless ocean of truth.”The key, as John Paul II says, is the preaching of Christ crucified. 1 Pope John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, §23. 902 Mary Shivanandan Although Fides et Ratio was promulgated in 1998, thirty years after Humanae Vitae 2 and fourteen after John Paul II’s own Reflections on Humanae Vitae in what is called the Catechesis on the Theology of the Body, it bears, it seems to me, a direct relation to both.3 Besides the task imposed on bishops to give witness to the truth, John Paul II gives the following reasons for promulgating Fides et Ratio: In my encyclical letter Veritatis Splendor, I drew attention to “certain fundamental truths of Catholic doctrine which, in the present circumstances, risk being distorted or denied.” In the present letter I wish to pursue that reflection on the theme of truth itself and on its foundation in relation to faith. (FR, §6) Later in the same paragraph of Veritatis Splendor the pope states: “It is no longer a matter of limited and occasional dissent, but of an overall and systematic calling into question of traditional moral doctrine on the basis of certain anthropological and ethical presuppositions.”4 The section goes on to say that the Church’s magisterial teaching on moral matters and the natural law is simply rejected in favor of a private morality. At the heart of this dissent has been opposition to the encyclical Humanae Vitae. It is well known that proportionalism and consequentialism were devised as 2 Pope Paul VI, Humanae Vitae (1968). 3 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books & Media, 2006). It is interesting to note the close relationship in time of Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical letter recommending the study of the metaphysics of Aquinas, Aeterni Patris (1879), and the encyclical on marriage, Arcanum (1880) without any intervening encyclical. Both occurred at the beginning of his pontificate at a time when contraception in the form of the condom first became widespread in industrial society thanks to the vulcanization of rubber in 1843, although John Noonan notes that Rome responded mostly to requests from French clergy for clarification on increasing use of “onanism” for birth control ( John Noonan, Contraception: A History of Its Treatment by the Catholic Theologians and Canonists [Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986], 397). A secular author, Rudolph Binion, in an extensive review of European novelists of the period, reveals the antagonistic attitude toward the family, which both fueled contraception and was fueled by it. He concludes:“In Europe at large, contraception was felt to be a first decisive step away from the family” (Rudolph Binion, Past Impersonal: Group Process in Human History [Dekalb, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2005], 30). The First Vatican Council issued only two documents, Dei Filius (1870) on revelation, faith, and the relation of faith and reason and the First Dogmatic Constitution on the Church of Christ (1870), concerned exclusively with the apostolic primacy of Peter and papal infallibility, which proved of inestimable importance in the promulgation of Humanae Vitae by Pope Paul VI in 1968. 4 John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor (1993), §4. Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 903 moral arguments in order to undermine the reaffirmation by Paul VI of the Church’s unbroken teaching on the proper regulation of births.5 In Veritatis Splendor, John Paul II takes up the question of the good and its relation to truth and freedom. Its primary focus is morality as it is related to the natural law and to Christian precepts. Its final chapter proposes the crucified Christ as revealing “the authentic meaning of freedom; he lives it fully in the total gift of himself and calls his disciples to share in his freedom” (VS, §85). Christ reveals that the open acceptance of truth is “the condition for authentic freedom” (VS, §87), and freedom which is rooted in the truth about man “is ultimately directed toward communion” (VS, §86). The encyclical then moves from a consideration of the nature of the good and its separation from truth to “the more serious and destructive dichotomy” which separates faith from morality (VS, §88). It is in order to address this dichotomy of the separation of faith not only from morality but from truth itself that John Paul II pens the encyclical, Fides et Ratio.6 So I propose that there is a direct link between this encyclical and the challenge of responsible parenthood addressed in Paul VI’s Humanae Vitae. Dissent from that encyclical has struck at the foundations not only of Christian morality and the authority of the Magisterium but of truth itself, both philosophical and theological.This is not to mention an assault on Christian anthropology and the family, which John Paul II addressed in the encyclical Evangelium Vitae (1995) and in the apostolic exhortations, Familiaris Consortio (1981) and Mulieris Dignitatem (1987). In this essay I wish to focus on the methodology that John Paul II employs in his Catechesis on Human Love, a work that was particularly 5 William E. May traces the roots of the rejection of moral absolutes and the rise of a revisionist moral theology to arguments presented to justify contraception in the Majority Report of Pope Paul VI’s Birth Control Commission set up during Vatican Council II to study the licitness of the hormonal pill for spacing births.Among the revisionist theologians, May includes Franz Bockle, Charles E. Curran, Josef Fuchs, Bernard Haring, Louis Janssens, Richard McCormick, Timothy E. O’Connell, Richard Gula, Franz Scholz, and Bruno Schuller.Among important arguments they used are the “preference” principle or principle of proportionate good, and the historicity of human existence principle. See William E. May, An Introduction to Moral Theology (Huntington, IN: Our Sunday Visitor, 1994), 107–27. Veritatis Splendor critiques erroneous views of the relationship between law and freedom, natural law and freedom, conscience and the Magisterium, which have subverted the Church’s teaching as found in Humanae Vitae (VS, §§54–83). 6 Livio Melina proposes that “Fides et Ratio can therefore be read inter alia as a particular development of the teaching of Veritatis Splendor” (Melina,“The ‘Truth about the Good’: Practical Reason, Philosophical Ethics, and Moral Theology,” Communio 26 [1999]: 641). Mary Shivanandan 904 designed to respond to the questions raised by Humanae Vitae, as he himself states in the last homily: If I draw particular attention precisely to these final catecheses, I do so not only because the topic discussed by them is more closely connected with our present age, but first of all because it is from this topic that the questions spring that run in some way through the whole of our reflections. . . . In some sense, that part, which in the overall disposition is located at the end, is at the same time found at the beginning of that whole.This is important from the point of view of structure and method.7 After a consideration of the methodology the pope employs in the catechesis, I shall show how it is a demonstration, as it were, of the principles he recommends in Fides et Ratio for the correct relationship between faith and reason.8 In the conclusion I shall propose that the Church’s teaching on sexual morality as expressed in Humanae Vitae, far from being a peripheral moral issue as the proponents of contraception maintain, is central to faith, life, and worship. The Question of Method Carl Anderson has said that Humanae Vitae is the last encyclical addressed to the modern engagement with reasoned argument.9 Paul VI, in referring to the inseparability of the unitive and procreative meanings of human sexuality, wrote:“We believe that the men of our day are particularly capa7 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §133:4 (November 28, 1984), original emphasis. 8 Charles Curran, a major dissenter from Humanae Vitae, fully understands the crit- ical role played by methodology. In The Moral Theology of John Paul II (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2005), he attacks John Paul II’s theological suppositions to discredit his teaching especially on marriage, sexuality, gender, and family. He singles out the methodology of the catechesis on the theology of the body as a major source of his critique: 4, 5. For a critique of Curran’s book on John Paul II’s moral theology, see E. Christian Brugger and William E. May,“John Paul II’s Moral Theology on Trial:A Reply to Charles E. Curran,” The Thomist 69 (2005): 279–312. For a wide-ranging critique of Curran’s moral theology see John McDermott, S.J., “Charles Curran’s Moral Theology: Foundational Sexual Ethics,” Anthropotes: Rivista di Studi sulla Persona e la Famiglia 23 (2007): 167–225. 9 Carl Anderson, “Political Reflections on Humanae Vitae,” paper given at the Theological and Pastoral Congress on the 25th Anniversary of Humanae Vitae, Pontifical Council on the Family, Rome, Italy, November 24–26, 1993. Anderson states: “The discourse of Humanae Vitae presupposes a certain social consensus which no longer exists. That former consensus included a confidence in human reason to find moral truths, an appreciation of procreation as a good of marriage and of marriage itself as a unique and stable institution” (15). Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 905 ble of seizing the deeply reasonable and human character of this fundamental principle.”10 The uproar of dissent both within the Church and secular society showed clearly that reason was no longer sufficient to convince contemporary man, who has lost faith in the very power of reason to arrive at truth. Clearly a different approach was needed. In his Catechesis on Human Love, John Paul II gives primacy to revelation in discerning the truth and meaning of human sexuality.The first part of the catechesis is devoted to the words of Christ. Guided by the text of Genesis 1:1 to 4:1, John Paul II traces the way Adam comes to the truth about God, the world, and himself and demonstrates the critical relationship between objective and subjective truth, faith and reason. There are two key Scripture passages through which John Paul II addresses the question of methodology in the Wednesday catechesis. The first is Jesus’ response to the Pharisees on the question of divorce, which Moses allowed:“Because of the hardness of your heart Moses allowed you to divorce your wives, but from the beginning it was not so” (Mt 19:3–8).11 John Paul II comments that Christ wants to change the level of discussion from questions of casuistry to the meaning and purpose of the creation of man and woman, that is to say to marriage in the “beginning.” The second passage, also quoting the words of Christ, occurs in the discussion of the resurrection. This time he is addressing the Sadducees, who deny the resurrection by proposing a fictitious scenario. Christ responds: “You are wrong, because you know neither the Scriptures nor the power of God” (Mt 22:9).12 John Paul II comments: Without any doubt, the Sadducees treat the question of the resurrection as a type of theory or hypothesis that can be refuted. Jesus first shows them a mistake in their method: they do not know the Scriptures; and then an error of substance: they do not accept what is revealed by the Scriptures—since they do not know the power of God—they do not believe in the one who revealed himself to Moses in the burning bush.13 In both cases Christ himself has pointed out the error in method, in the first place of giving a primacy to abstract reason over faith in the Word of God and in the second place of not believing in the Source itself of Scripture. John Paul II will follow Christ’s own methodology in both the Catechesis on Human Love and in Fides et Ratio. In the former he is seeking 10 Paul VI, Humanae Vitae, §12. 11 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §2:2 (September 5, 1979). 12 Ibid., §65:1 (November 18, 1981). 13 Ibid., §65:3 (November 18, 1981), original emphasis. Mary Shivanandan 906 to discover the truth of God’s plan for human sexuality, and in the latter he is setting forth the correct method for coming to truth both by faith and reason. In the catechesis he demonstrates the correct method for coming to truth; in Fides et Ratio he articulates its principles. It is precisely the error in method that John Paul II addresses in Fides et Ratio, the relation between faith and reason. And it is precisely by addressing the questions raised by Humanae Vitae from the perspective of faith as well as reason in the Catechesis on Human Love that John Paul II shows how, far from being a restriction on human freedom, the Church’s teaching opens up vistas beyond human reason to reveal man’s exalted destiny to participate in divine Trinitarian life. At the beginning of Fides et Ratio John Paul II posits the link between faith, reason, and life by commenting that the answer to the questions on the meaning of life “decides the direction which people seek to give to their lives” (FR, §1). The encyclical answers the pressing need for “a foundation for personal and communal life” (FR, §6) of which marriage and family are the most common path. In other words the pope is saying that what a person believes has a profound effect on the way life is lived. The Methodology of the Wednesday Catechesis on the Theology of the Body Michael Waldstein, translator of the new English edition of the Wednesday catechesis, has given a comprehensive and helpful account of its structure and method.14 But here we are concerned with the nature of the relationship between reason and faith in addressing the questions raised by Humanae Vitae. By choosing to begin with the words of Christ, John Paul II gives primacy to knowledge through faith. At the same time he finds in the Genesis text the ultimate justification of the path to truth of both faith and reason. Both meet in the human person, and this is a critical concept that he will develop in Fides et Ratio, especially §32, which follows a general discussion on the way men come to truth, by abstract reason and also by trust in knowledge previously acquired since it is not possible to verify every truth personally. So the one who seeks truth is also the one who believes. And this truth comes by way of a personal relationship. It involves not simply the person’s capacity to know but his capacity to entrust himself to another person. From the beginning of his catechesis on Genesis, John Paul II makes use of philosophy to illuminate the text. This is immediately noticeable in the second catechesis which recounts the priestly account of the 14 See the introduction by Michael Waldstein, John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 105–28. Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 907 creation of man, made in the image of God. First of all he emphasizes that while the priestly account is “theological in character,” since it defines man as made in the image of God, it also has a “powerful metaphysical content.”15 Man is defined in a more metaphysical than physical way. John Paul II states that “this text of Genesis has become the source of the deepest inspirations for the thinkers who have sought to understand ‘being’ and ‘existing.’ ”16 We see here the emphasis on a metaphysics of being as fundamental to any philosophical account of the nature of man and the cosmos.17 The Genesis text also shows the convertibility of being and the good (ens et bonum convertuntur). Such convertibility is, he says,“an incontrovertible point of reference and solid basis of a metaphysics and also for an anthropology and an ethics.”18 Without understanding the grounding of the Wednesday catechesis on the primacy of objective reality, “free from any trace of subjectivism,”19 it is not possible to interpret correctly the pope’s emphasis on the subjective aspect of man’s experience in the Yahwist account of creation. Later in Fides et Ratio John Paul II makes it abundantly clear that any development in philosophical method must always build on the foundation of a metaphysics of being.20 15 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §§2:4, 5 (September 12, 1979). 16 Ibid. §2:4. 17 In criticizing the English translation from the Polish of The Acting Person for obscuring the extent to which Karol Wojtyla’s ethics is steeped in the metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas, Kenneth Schmitz states that it is the view of Wojtyla himself that “the metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas, however accommodated to the present situation, is an indispensable ingredient in ethical analysis” (Kenneth Schmitz, At the Center of the Human Drama [Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1993], 61). 18 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §2:5 (September 12, 1979). Kenneth Schmitz has shown how the philosopher Karol Wojtyla considered the relationship of being, truth, and goodness as the “most original teaching of Thomas.” The good is inextricably bound up with existence (Schmitz, At the Center of the Human Drama, 52; see also 51). 19 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §2:4 (September 12, 1979). In Fides et Ratio John Paul II emphasizes that “metaphysics . . . plays an essential role of mediation in theological research. . . . If I insist so strongly on the metaphysical element, it is because I am convinced that it is the path to be taken in order to move beyond the crisis pervading large sectors of philosophy at the moment, and thus to correct certain mistaken modes of behavior now widespread in society” (FR, §83). 20 The inadequate subjectivism of the phenomenology of Max Scheler is attributed by Karol Wojtyla to the absence of a metaphysics of being: see Wojtyla, “The Problem of the Separation of Experience from the Act in Ethics in the Philosophy of Immanuel Kant and Max Scheler,” in Wojtyla, Person and Community, trans.Theresa Sandok (New York: Peter Lang, 1993), 23–44. For a superb account 908 Mary Shivanandan John Paul II describes the Yahwist account as above all presenting man in the aspect of his subjectivity, a person who knows, wills, and acts. For John Paul II, being a subject includes the traditional philosophical definition of man as a rational animal.21 It also includes the dimension of consciousness.The text, he says, is “the first witness of human consciousness.”22 From the point of view of John Paul II’s methodology in uniting faith and reason, as well as knitting modern insights of interiority onto the traditional definition of man as a rational substance, the Yahwist text is extremely important. Without going into great detail on his methodology—that has been dealt with elsewhere23—in his philosophy he points out that the Boethian definition of man is the “metaphysical terrain”24 in which human subjectivity is realized. Human action is conscious action.The human person is not only the one who acts but the one who knows and experiences himself as acting. Scholastics did not develop the unique significance of consciousness for subjectivity.The human being is not just a member of the genus “rational animal,” a human suppositum, but a unique individual. The dynamism of action helps us to understand human subjectivity since consciousness accompanies action. The individual’s whole development . . . tends toward the emergence of the person and personal subjectivity in the human suppositum. In this way, somehow on the basis of this suppositum, the human self gradually both discloses itself and in disclosing itself constitutes itself—and it discloses itself also by constituting itself.25 Consciousness is essential, says Wojtyla, for understanding the human self. The person not only knows that he knows and acts but experiences himself as knowing and acting. The suppositum must manifest itself as personal of a contemporary account of the metaphysics of being, drawing primarily on Thomas Aquinas, see Kenneth Schmitz, “Human Nature and Human Culture,” unpublished paper given at Catholic University of America, March 2008. 21 See John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §5:5, note 10 (October 10, 1979). 22 Ibid., §3:1 (September 19, 1979). 23 See Mary Shivanandan, “Subjectivity and the Order of Love,” Fides Quaerens Intellectum 1 (2001): 251–71, esp. 253–59 and 262–64. Specific articles by Karol Wojtyla on subjectivity can be found in his Person and Community, namely “The Personal Structure of Self Determination,” 187–95; “Subjectivity and the Irreducibility in the Human Being,” 209–17; and “The Person: Subject and Community,” 219–61. 24 Wojtyla, “Subjectivity and the Irreducible in the Human Being,” 212. 25 Wojtyla, “The Person: Subject and Community,” 225. Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 909 subjectivity. Not only is the human being a person by nature, but subjectivity also belongs to him by nature.26 It is in his interpretation of the Yahwist text that the full significance of John Paul II’s philosophical investigations for theology, using phenomenology as a method but without in any way reducing the metaphysical content, becomes apparent. Knowledge as Encounter It is significant that he begins with the Yahwist phrase, “ ‘It is not good that man’ (male) ‘should be alone; I want to make him a help similar to himself ’ (Gen 2:18).”27 The starting point is one directly concerned with relationship or the lack thereof. It is within the context of relationship that man comes to knowledge of himself and the world.When the pope talks of man’s consciousness, he rejects categorically the disembodied consciousness of an autonomous self. Knowledge comes through an encounter with objective reality, whether the cosmos, himself, or another human being.28 It comes by way of experience, our ordinary human experiences. The appeal to experience is fundamental because man is a body. He goes so far as to say that “our experience is in some way a legitimate means for theological interpretation.”29 In a footnote he elaborates on the “surprising convergence” between “experience and revelation.” Although faith and science are two distinct disciplines, they meet in the human person and his experience. 26 The roots of consciousness are always in the suppositum not simply in “acts of consciousness” (ibid., 226).This assures the unity and integrity of body and soul. 27 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §5:2 (October 10, 1979). In both the original Italian and the English translation, Pope John Paul II inserts the word “maschio” or “male” in reference to Gen 2:18 as well as in 2:7. This is a good example of the distinction he makes between humanity and subjectivity. Adam was created as a concrete male person but only became aware of his masculinity in the encounter with Eve.The separate creation of man and woman refers back, he says to their creation as male and female in the priestly text. See John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §3:2 (September 19, 1979). 28 Angelo Scola has developed most fully the nature of knowledge as encounter in The Nuptial Mystery, trans. Michelle K. Borras (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 2005), 224–27. He has coined the term “symbolic ontology” to capture the fact that being cannot be grasped directly by man. It does not mean that man cannot touch the real itself through intuition but the real communicates itself in a sign to form concepts. This encounter constitutes an event. Man must choose it in freedom, but the thing always remains other. This otherness or difference allows for relationship and encounter. Sexual difference is a primary form of otherness. See ibid., 225. 29 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §§4:4, 5, and §4:5, note 8 (September 26, 1979). Mary Shivanandan 910 In the Genesis text the pope discerns three succeeding levels by which man comes to know and experience himself and his place in the world. First he discovers who he is as a person with intellect and will, different from the animals with the power to determine his own destiny.This is an existential solitude, prior to man’s (male’s) solitude vis-à-vis the woman (female) and common to man, male and female. It is specifically in an encounter with the physical world and his own body that he discovers his subjectivity and his contingency before God. The text, he says, “sketches man as a person with the subjectivity characterizing the person.”30 Secondly through an encounter with Eve he discovers himself as a male person ordered to a relationship of self-gift as spouse and thirdly he discovers the generative nature of his body when Eve conceives and bears a son. Indeed through the “knowledge” involved in the bodily union of the spouses the woman discovers a new dimension of her being, that of mother, while the man discovers the dimension of fatherhood. The catecheses on knowledge and procreation are especially significant for our argument.The use of the verb “knew” for conjugal relations means that the biblical text raises the level of the act from the merely biological to the personal.There are then in the biblical understanding of “know” two aspects, intentionality and the reality of the union in one flesh. Both the husband and the wife know each other reciprocally and by doing so discover the depths of their own specific “I.” Each is known as an “unrepeatable feminine or masculine ‘I.’ ”31 This reciprocal knowledge, he says, “establishes a kind of personal archetype of human bodiliness and sexuality.” He goes on to say that, the “man” who for the first time “knows” the woman, his wife, in the act of conjugal union is in fact the same one who—in giving names, that is, also, by “knowing”—differentiated himself from the whole world of living beings or animalia, thus affirming himself as a person and a subject.32 30 Ibid., §6:1 (October 24, 1979), original emphasis. See ibid., §4:4 (September 26, 1979). 31 Ibid., §20:5 (March 5, 1980). 32 Ibid., §21:1 (March 12, 1980). Kenneth Schmitz has brought out well the rela- tional dimension of knowledge, not just of one human being to another, but of things in themselves in a metaphysics of being.“Knowledge,” he says,“is precisely the relation in and through which we come to know things as they are in their own being.” By being intelligible to man, things are rendered explicit in themselves.This makes them available for a relationship in which they retain their own integrity. In giving themselves they also affirm their identity. See Schmitz, “Human Nature and Human Culture.” According to David Schindler, “Knowing at root is but the distinctly cognitive manner of participating in the relations of love and beauty implicit in an ontology of creation” (David L. Schindler,“God Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 911 The Principles in Fides et Ratio Whereas in the Wednesday catechesis John Paul II demonstrates the primacy of revelation in coming to know truth and the role of philosophy in illuminating faith on the one hand and reflecting on the cosmos on the other, in Fides et Ratio John Paul II articulates firstly the absolute primacy of faith, putting reason in its place as the handmaid of faith; secondly he brings out the nature of the person as the one who seeks truth; and thirdly he traces the path to truth by personal encounter, thus uniting objective and subjective truth. Just as John Paul II begins the catechesis with the words of Christ, in Fides et Ratio he begins chapter one with Jesus as the revealer of the Father, an utterly gratuitous initiative on the part of God (FR, §7).With Christ eternity enters time. By his death and resurrection he bestows on man the divine life that Adam lost. “Through this revelation,” says John Paul II,“men and women are offered the ultimate truth about their own life and about the goal of history” (FR, §12).The source of its credibility lies in the authority of the Revealer. It is through faith that we can penetrate the mystery. In the act of faith the person gives consummate expression to his freedom and through it “reaches the certainty of truth and chooses to live in that truth” (FR, §13). In order to help reason understand, revelation presents signs, which urge reason to look beyond to deeper truths (FR, §13). Here John Paul II categorically states that revelation sets a point of reference not to be ignored if human life is to be understood.The reference point continually points back to God, fuller knowledge of whom can only be received by faith. Reason has the domain between these two reference points (FR, §14).33 and the End of Intelligence: Knowledge as Relationship,” Communio 26 [1999]: 527). He proposes that “knowledge is first and foremost a matter of relation, the order of which is disclosed in the creation of all things by and in the triune God revealed in Jesus Christ” (ibid., 528). In love the subject discovers the self in relation first to the Other who gives himself together with the gift of the world.The relationship with God is primary.Therefore there is a priority of the ‘objective’ as already given as a gift of God and the world.“What this means,” says Schindler, “is that knowledge takes its first and most basic order from within relation or relationship defined by love and beauty, which originates in submission of the self to the other (God and all others in God)” (ibid., 536–37). 33 Here John Paul II inserts a section on the relationship between life, reason, and faith.The truth of Christian revelation “enables all men and women to embrace the ‘mystery’ of their own life.” It offers those who want to know the truth the possibility of “taking full and harmonious possession of their lives precisely by following the path of truth.”This is the ultimate goal also of philosophy (FR, §15). 912 Mary Shivanandan Sections 31 to 33 of Fides et Ratio are pivotal for John Paul II’s close linking of reason and faith. Human beings, he argues, are not meant to live alone. More truths, even empirical truths, are believed not because they have been acquired by personal verification but on the credibility of others (FR, §31). Man entrusts himself to this knowledge and, he adds, it is often a richer truth since it is acquired in an interpersonal relationship. This is because it involves not just the capacity to know but a “deeper” capacity to entrust oneself to others and to enter an enduring relationship. One can think here of the relationship between student and a revered teacher. Such truth is not primarily empirical or philosophical. What is sought is the “truth of the person.”“Human perfection, then,” he sums up,“consists not simply in acquiring an abstract knowledge of truth, but in a dynamic relationship with others. It is in this faithful self-giving that a person finds a fullness of certainty and security” (FR, §32). In section 33, John Paul II summarizes his argument. It is the nature of the human person to seek truth, not just partial truths from empirical or scientific evidence or the true good in individual acts of decisionmaking.They look for an ultimate truth which would explain the meaning of life. The search can only end in “reaching the absolute,” as the ancient philosophers concluded. But the search for truth also needs trust and friendship, which was well accepted by these philosophers.Therefore, there is both “a search for truth and a search for a person to whom they might entrust themselves.” Christian faith offers Jesus Christ, both true God and true man. Through the order of grace Christ offers participation in divine mysteries and coherent knowledge of the Triune God. Through his humanity, the goodness of the order of creation is confirmed. There can be no contradiction between the order of faith and the order of reason, both of which are united in the person of Christ.34 In entrusting themselves to the Person of Jesus, believers find a fullness of truth not available to reason alone (FR, §33). The Relationship between the Language of the Body and Truth Since entrustment to another is such an integral part of arriving at truth, whatever might hinder self-giving to another will also inhibit the path to truth. Here we find the close link between life, reason, and faith. Reason reflects on experience to form concepts. It also uses those concepts to shed light on the truths of revelation. As we have seen, John Paul II con34 The principle of non-contradiction is cited as the first of five principles form- ing the core of philosophic thought in FR, §4. Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 913 siders experience a valid path to understanding revelation.35 The experience itself must be an objectively true experience. As John Paul II recognizes the biblical use of the verb “know” both for conjugal intercourse and knowledge as “intentionality,” reflects a deep truth about the human person, for the spousal union is the deepest selfgiving union of human persons in creation, a paradigm for all others. Angelo Scola, drawing on the insights of John Paul II, identifies the concrete experience of the man-woman relationship as the base of what he terms the “nuptial mystery,” in his view the analogatum princeps for all reality. On the one hand, the expression “nuptial mystery,” he states, “refers to the organic unity of sexual difference, love (objective relationship to the other) and fruitfulness. On the other hand, it refers objectively, through the principle of analogy to the various forms of love that characterize both the man-woman relationship and all it derivatives (fatherhood, motherhood, brotherhood, and sisterhood, etc.) and God’s relationship with man in the sacrament, the Church and Jesus Christ, all the way to the Trinity itself.”36 If the nuptial mystery is disturbed in any way, the unity of the human person dictates that the integrity of the act of knowledge will also be disturbed. And indeed as a result of original sin, the human mind was darkened.37 Here we can see a connection with the truths expressed in Humanae Vitae. John Paul II affirms that the dignity of the communio personarum demands that the language of the body in the conjugal act be expressed in the truth of total mutual self-giving. If it is artificially deprived of this truth,“such a violation of the inner order of conjugal communion, a communion that plunges its roots into the very order of the person, 35 In a footnote to his reflections on the first chapters of Genesis, John Paul II speaks of the relationship between “experience” and “revelation.” Although many would draw a line between the two, he cites Rom 8:23 “We therefore have a right to speak about the relationship between experience and revelation; in fact we have the right to raise the issue of their relationship to each other” (Man and Woman He Created Them, §4:5 note 8, [September 26, 1979]). 36 Angelo Scola, The Nuptial Mystery, trans. Michelle K. Borras (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 2005) 213–14. 37 John Paul II notes that before sin man was designed to have ready access to God through metaphysical enquiry. Original sin wounded all men’s path to God through reason. Reason became a “prisoner of itself.” The Incarnation freed reason from its weakness (FR, §22). For an insightful discussion of the relationship of language to “ontology” or “the translation of encountered existence in the language of being, giving primacy not to being but to the modality of logos,” see Kenneth L. Schmitz, “The Language of Conversion and the Conversion of Language,” Communio 21 (1994): 745. 914 Mary Shivanandan constitutes the essential evil of the contraceptive act.”38 When a couple makes use of contraception in marriage, they alter the objective truth of the language of the body. Its objective meaning of total self-gift, which includes the gift of procreation, is changed. Any reflection on the experience will also necessarily be flawed. A dualism has been introduced, separating the conjugal act from its true meaning, expressed in the body. It is significant that John Paul II speaks of “rereading the language of the body in truth” (emphasis added), which is related to a cognitive act. Is it surprising, then, that in order to justify falsifying the language of the body through contraception, theologians and ethicists have altered the very foundations of truth acquired both by reason and faith? These theologians do not understand that, as John Paul II says, If the human being—male and female—in marriage (and indirectly in all spheres of life together) gives to his behavior a meaning in conformity with the fundamental truth of the language of the body, then he too “is in truth.” In the opposite case, he commits lies and falsifies the language of the body.39 This falsification reaches to the very person of Jesus, since he is “the way, the life and the truth” ( Jn 14:6).40 The unity of truth and love is the core of revelation. Where one is not lived the other is also warped and even destroyed. 38 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §123:7 (August 22, 1984).William E. May and others, including Paul VI in Humanae Vitae, point out that the traditional view of the contraceptive act as anti-life still pertains. It seems to me that John Paul II has in mind the wider implications of falsifying the language of the body. 39 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §106:3 ( January 26, 1983), original emphasis. By using the phrase “is in truth,” John Paul II calls to mind the first letter of John on the link between truth and behavior. Ignace de la Potterie gives a detailed commentary on the use of the two different words for “knowing truth” in 1 John: “The word ginowskein is used in a more external sense and eidenai in a more internal. (The word eidenai means to know with certainty as a result of firm faith).The two words complement one another. For example the Christian knows by faith (invisible—idein—the word is linked to the ideas in Plato); he acts morally (visible) which is how we know (ginoskein) if someone is in the truth; and finally we conclude from this external behavior that the Christian has communion with God (invisible).” See Mary Shivanandan, “The Anthropological Background of Fides et Ratio,” Anthropotes 17 (2001): 139. 40 In commenting on this Scripture passage, Ignace de la Potterie states that Jesus identifies himself with the truth and is the revelation of the Father. It is because Jesus “is the truth that he is for us the life and then also the way; the mediation of truth is ordered to the mediation of communion; Jesus is the truth in order to give us life” (Ignace de la Potterie, “Je suis la Voie, la Vérité et la Vie” [Jn 14:6], Nouvelle Revue Theologique 88 [1966]: 930–37). Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 915 Erroneous Methodologies There are many contemporary examples of erroneous philosophical and theological methodologies. Mention has already been made of proportionalism and consequentialism, faulty ethical systems that were initiated in order to justify contraception. Before discussing other erroneous methodologies, it is appropriate to review Charles Curran’s critique of John Paul II’s methodology in his 2005 book The Moral Theology of John Paul II.41 Curran attacks John Paul II’s theological methodology because of its implications for reaffirming and extending the Church’s magisterial teaching on marriage, family, gender, and sexuality. Curran admits as much in the introduction: “In the past, I have on occasion disagreed with some aspects of his moral theology and continue to do so. I have tried to be fair in my analysis, but obviously my own position colors my approach.”42 It is noteworthy that in the chapter on marriage and sexuality his most significance source is the Wednesday catechesis on the theology of the body. Curran ascribes to them “little or no importance from the viewpoint of authoritative teaching,”43 effectively dismissing both their theological method and import.Yet in the process he undermines the authority of other papal documents, such as Mulieris Dignitatem, and Letter to Families, which rely heavily on the theology of the body. For Curran they are just one theologian’s approach to these fundamental issues.44 In this brief essay it is only possible to touch on a few salient points of Curran’s critique. Curran’s approach approximates the very approach that Jesus challenges in the Gospel of Matthew on divorce and the resurrection. Curran wants less emphasis on universal moral norms and instead a return to casuistry.45 The nub of his argument is that John Paul II maintains a 41 Charles E. Curran, The Moral Theology of John Paul II (Washington, DC: George- town University Press, 2005). 42 Ibid., 6. See also p. 160 where he directly links the two. Curran clarifies the posi- tion of the revisionist theologians by saying that “for the good of the person or the good of the marital relation, one can interfere with the physical structure of the sexual act in order to prevent procreation” (ibid., 111). He asserts that John Paul II’s theology of the body does not refer to all bodies. Since it does not do so, “he also would have to prove that heterosexual morality is the only meaning for sexuality for all human beings” (ibid., 168). 43 Ibid., 4. 44 Ibid., 160, 164, 165. See also Waldstein, introduction, in John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, 16, 17. 45 Curran, The Moral Theology of John Paul II, 33. “The Catholic tradition has often used casuistry as a way of trying to deal with specific moral issues, thus showing how important it is to consider all the details of the situation” (ibid.). Curran commends casuistry over “the unchangeable and universal moral norm on abortion found in Evangelium vitae.” He also links the condemnation of direct abortion 916 Mary Shivanandan dichotomy between faith and reason, between the social encyclicals and those on faith.46 It would seem that the opposite is the case. Curran asks a key question: “Do we find moral theology and Christian moral teaching only in Scripture, in Jesus Christ, and in Christian tradition? Or do we share some moral wisdom and knowledge with all humankind?”47 His very formulation of the question would seem to make the two sources of wisdom equal, where John Paul II sees a hierarchy. Curran in fact introduces a dichotomy in a way that Vatican Council II, which John Paul II follows, does not.48 Curran seeks to find sufficient human wisdom and the meaning of life in a totally human way through natural law outside the Church, as in the condemnation of slavery (even though such condemnation is intrinsic to man made in the image of God).49 His error is acceptance of the view of an “autonomous” ethic and rejection of what John Paul II called a “participated theonomy” (VS, §41) or true understanding of natural law as the participation in the eternal law by the rational creature. On Curran’s view the Church must therefore be open to such “wisdom” even on the fundamental issues of life, marriage, and gender in such a way as to give more credibility to human hypotheses than to the wisdom of faith.50 Curran consistently gives greater weight to contemporary findings rooted exclusively in historical exegetical studies, the social sciences, and other “human wisdom,” than he does to Scripture itself as understood theologically in the Church, making appropriate use of the historicalcritical method and its interpretation according to the mind of the Church or to the Magisterium of the Church. He is critical of John Paul II’s neglect of the modern historical method, charging that he uses Scripto “a particular philosophic view . . . far removed from the core of faith and from more general ethical norms, such as respect due to all life including nascent life” (ibid., 31). 46 Ibid., 19. 47 Ibid., 23. 48 See Gaudium et Spes, §22:“The truth is that only in the mystery of the Incarnation does the mystery of man take on light. . . . Christ, the final Adam by the revelation of the Father and his love fully reveals man to himself and makes his supreme calling clear.” 49 Curran’s understanding of natural law itself is dualistic, criticizing John Paul II for accepting the Thomistic view of the inclinations shared with animals as intrinsic to human nature as a union of body and soul (ibid., 114). 50 It is as if he is saying that it is possible to escape the island through human ingenuity alone instead of making use of human reason both to understand through experience the resources of the island and to interpret the assistance that comes from beyond, the view that John Paul II takes in Fides et Ratio.The pope specifically condemns Fideism (FR, §55). Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 917 ture as a proof text. John Paul II generally follows Dei Verbum’s principles which give a clearly defined but subordinate role to the historical-critical method.51 His discrimen or interpretive key is “wholeness” or unity between the Old Testament and the New, between the Bible, theology, spirituality, and life.52 This allows new theological insights to emerge from the texts themselves.53 The paucity of Curran’s approach and the richness of John Paul II’s can be seen in their respective treatment of Ephesians 5:21–33. Curran applauds the pope’s new emphasis on the equal dignity of the sexes which he, himself, regards as in opposition to “official Catholic teaching less than fifty years ago.”54 He goes on to say, however, that drawing the equality of husband and wife from Ephesians 5:21–33 is an egregious example of John Paul II’s “lack of historicity and historical consciousness,” by expanding the meaning of the text beyond a first-century understanding of the household code.55 By contrast, John Paul II sees in the text “the wisdom and the power of God.” In his Letter to Families he calls it a summa of the Church’s 51 This essay is too brief to mount a response to Curran on this point. Dei Verbum gives two main criteria for scriptural interpretation: (1) it must be in agreement with tradition, and (2) it must be mindful of biblical scholarship, that is, the meaning the authors intended, what God wanted to manifest given the literary form and cultural context in which it was composed. The footnote to the September 29, 1979 catechesis is a good example of John Paul II’s fidelity to Dei Verbum principles on the proto evangelium of Genesis 3:15. First of all he cites the Septuagint interpretation, then Irenaeus and other Church Fathers followed by modern conflicting interpretations. He then interprets the Old Testament in light of the New. 52 Two articles provide useful commentaries on John Paul II’s use of Scripture: J. Michael Miller,“Interior Intelligibility:The Use of Scripture in Papal and Conciliar Documents,” The Canadian Catholic Review (September 1993): 9–18; and S. J. Prendergast, “ ‘A Vision of Wholeness’: A Reflection on the Use of Scripture in a Cross-Section of Papal Writings,” in The Thought of John Paul II: A Collection of Essays and Studies, ed. John M. McDermott, S.J. (Roma: Editrice Pontificia Universita Gregoriana, 1993), 69–91. 53 See David S.Yeago,“The New Testament and The Nicene Dogma: A Contribution to the Recovery of Theological Exegesis,” Pro Ecclesia 3 (1994): 152–64, for a useful discussion of the emergence of the dogma of the Incarnation from scriptural texts. 54 Curran, Moral Theology of John Paul II, 188. Curran himself relies “heavily on feminist thought” (ibid., 190). 55 Ibid., 199. John Paul II avers that analyses of the passage “must begin with the preliminary understanding of the text in itself ; they must then lead us, so to speak, beyond the limits of the text, in order that we may understand if possible ‘to the very depths’ what wealth of truth revealed by God is contained within the scope of that stupendous page.” See John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §87:6 ( July 28, 1982). 918 Mary Shivanandan teaching on man and woman, marriage and creation: “St. Paul’s magnificent synthesis concerning the great mystery appears as the compendium or summa, in some sense, of the teaching about God and man, which was brought to fulfillment in Christ.”56 Through Christ’s reference to “the beginning” in Genesis, the historical state of sin, redemption, and the fulfillment of the “mystery” of Ephesians 1:3–10, John Paul II sees the whole of salvation history encompassed in the text and the definitive understanding of masculinity, femininity, and the sacramentality of marriage in creation and grace.57 At the center is Christ and his self-gift on the Cross. Demonstration of Erroneous Methodologies A comprehensive undermining of the theological foundations of the Church’s teaching on sexuality pervades a study commissioned in 1972 by the Catholic Theological Society of America (CTSA), and published in 1977 as Human Sexuality: New Directions in American Catholic Thought.58 This study, which circulated widely in and outside of seminaries for nearly twenty years, clearly illustrates the impact of an incorrect relation between faith and reason and the resulting effect of erroneous views on sexuality. One might say that as a demonstration of an incorrect method applied to marriage and sexuality, it stands in relation to Curran’s articulation of erroneous theological principles in the same way as John Paul II’s Catechesis on Human Love stands in relation to Fides et Ratio. In other words, it shows the interrelationship between a distorted philosophy and theology and the subversion of the truths on sexuality and procreation proclaimed in Humanae Vitae. Let us begin with the pastoral guidelines recommended by the CTSA theologians. With regard to marital sexuality, they argue that no physical sexual expression can be judged intrinsically wrong or perverse.The justification for such an assertion is empirical studies (that is, reason in a limited sense) which show that the diversity of sexual expression depends on culture, temperament, and education.The objective truth of the act itself is immaterial as long as it fosters the values of “self-liberation, other-enrichment, honesty, fidelity, life service, social responsibility and joyousness.”59 There can be no blanket “no” to premarital sex60 and extreme caution 56 John Paul II, Letter to Families, §19. 57 John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them, §93:1 (September 8, 1982). 58 Anthony Kosnik et al., Human Sexuality: New Directions in American Catholic Thought: A Study Commissioned by the Catholic Theological Society of America (New York: Paulist Press, 1977). 59 Ibid., 110. 60 Ibid., 167. Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 919 should be exercised in condemning variant marriage patterns, such as cohabitation, communal living and extramarital sex or adultery. They should not be ruled out, since “the empirical data does not as yet warrant any solid conclusions on the effects of such behavior, particularly from the long-range view.”61 All methods of contraception are recommended—they equate natural family planning (NFP) with contraception—with the main criteria for acceptability being medical, psychological, or personal considerations. Religious considerations are treated last. Reasons given to reject the teaching of Humanae Vitae are listed as “the person-centered approach to moral judgment”62 (prescinding from the objective nature of the act itself), a renewed (or revisionist) understanding of natural law, scientific and medical advances, insights from the psychological and behavioral sciences—all on the side of reason. A brief reference to biblical exegesis and teaching on moral matters points out that Humanae Vitae did not cite any scriptural evidence, a lack amply remedied by John Paul II in his Catechesis on Human Love.63 Confessors are advised to present both the Church teaching on Humanae Vitae as well as information on contraception and leave the choice up to the conscience of the penitent.64 These guidelines follow the methodological part of the study, beginning with the “Bible and Human Sexuality” and “Christian Tradition and Human Sexuality.” There is heavy reliance on the historical-critical method.The conclusions of the CTSA study: No single text or collection of texts constitutes anything like a coherent biblical theology of human sexuality. Scripture is not even concerned with sexuality as such, regarding it as one aspect of life, properly viewed only within the context of the whole person and the whole of human life with all its relationships and responsibilities.65 61 Ibid., 145–49. The negative effects of divorce on children were documented as early as 1989 by Judith S. Wallerstein and Sandra Blakeslee in their Second Chances: Men,Women, and Children a Decade after Divorce (New York: Cicknor & Fields, 1989). 62 Kosnik et al., Human Sexuality, 123. 63 Ibid., 114–25. 64 Ibid., 127.They argue that use or nonuse of contraception cannot provide a basis of judgment on the morality or immorality of a person’s conjugal life. 65 Ibid., 29, 30. See also their remark,“Critical biblical scholarship finds it impossible on the basis of empirical data to approve or reject categorically any particular sexual act outside of its contextual circumstances and intention” (31). Contrast this with a Jewish view: “The Halakhah ( Jewish Law) has a great deal to say about the sexual conduct of married couples. . . . Over one-sixth of the Talmud itself, one whole ‘Order’ is devoted to such matters as marriage, divorce, 920 Mary Shivanandan Some recognition is given to a greater pastoral sensitivity on the part of the Church to sexual matters but the study finds its approach to “specific issues (premarital sex, homosexuality and masturbation) . . . exaggeratedly absolute and legalistic.”66 A chapter on empirical sciences and human sexuality relies heavily on Alfred Kinsey’s flawed data on masturbation, premarital sex, and the prevalence of homosexuality.While not claiming such data is conclusive, the study warns against assuming that human experience confirms any particular moral position but then argues in favor of its own position. It is in the development of a new “theology of sexuality,” that the influence of social science theory, particularly that of sociologist Ira Reiss, is most evident. Instead of procreative and unitive, these theologians propose as a criterion that “wholesome human sexuality . . . fosters a creative growth toward integration.”67 The morality of any particular sex act is judged on whether it is self-liberating, other-enriching, honest, faithful, socially responsible, life-serving, and joyous.68 It adds that “these values are not expressed in terms of concrete, physical actions.”69 This constitutes in practice a revised moral evaluation of sexual conduct, dependent more on social science theory and data than on Christian revelation and the reflection of the Church on revelation. The Language of Deception A major argument of the revisionist theologians is that the Church’s traditional teaching on gender, sexuality, and marriage does not accord with contemporary experience. For example, the common thread running through feminist theology is that the feminist experience should determine the relevance of particular doctrines for feminists.70 The same position is and women’s rights” (Norman Lamm, A Hedge of Roses: Jewish Insights into Marriage and Married Life [New York: Philipp Feldham, Inc., 1966], 32, 33). A good critique of their Scripture interpretation is also given by Manuel Miguens, “Biblical Thoughts on Human Sexuality,” a chapter from Human Sexuality in Our Time, ed. George A. Kelly (Boston: St. Paul Editions, 1979). 66 Kosnik et al., Human Sexuality, 52. 67 Ibid., 86. 68 Ibid., 92–95. 69 Ibid., 96. 70 Sallie McFague considers the appropriate question not which doctrine is true or false but “which is a better portrait of Christian faith for our day” (Models of God, Theology for an Ecological Nuclear Age [Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1987], xiii). Rosemary Radford Ruether posits “human experience as the starting point and the ending point of the hermeneutical circle” (Sexism and God-Talk: Toward a Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 921 taken with regard to various sexual practices including contraception.The experience of couples is cited as the most convincing arguments for endorsing divergent theological views.71 Statistics are given on how many Catholics are not obeying the Church’s teaching, with the implication that it does not accord either with their experience or understanding.72 Lutheran theologian George Lindbeck challenges the widespread theological assumption that experiences are the leading partner in the exchange between doctrines and experience. He proposes a rule theory of doctrines as a more satisfactory method of explaining the link between experience and belief. In the experiential-expressive model, “The experience is the source and norm of objectifications.”73 Lindbeck holds on the contrary that “a religion can be viewed as a kind of cultural and/or linguistic framework or medium that shapes the entirety of life and thought.”74 It functions a priori like an idiom. Although it is influenced by the inner experience of the believer, the idiom is the leading partner in the exchange. “Religions,” according to Lindbeck’s approach, “are seen as comprehensive interpretive schemes, usually embodied in myths or narratives and heavily ritualized, which structure human experience and understanding of self and world.”75 Feminist Theology [Boston: Beacon Press, 1983], 12). See also Kosnik et al., Human Sexuality, 174. 71 Kosnik et al. Human Sexuality, 122. 72 Thomas Martin states that “contrary to the norms of most mainstream Christian positions, many experience genital sexuality outside of marriage.” See Thomas M. Martin, The Challenge of Christian Marriage: Marriage in Scripture, History and Contemporary Life (New York: Paulist Press, 1990), 135, 146, 147.The experiences of couples in a survey conducted by Pat and Patty Crowley, members of the 1966 Birth Control Commission summoned by Paul VI to consider the licitness of the anovulant pill as a method of birth, are cited as a prime reason in the majority report for changing the Church’s teaching on contraception. See Robert McClory, Turning Point: The Inside Story of the Papal Birth Control Commission, and How Humanae vitae Changed the Life of Patty Crowley and the Future of the Church (New York:The Crossroad Publishing Co., 1995), 86–95, 107. A reinterpretation of the data of this survey does not support all its conclusions on the negative effect of the so-called Rhythm Method on the couple’s relation.As much as 64 percent of those interviewed stated that in some way “rhythm” was helpful to their marriage. See Richard J. Fehring and Elizabeth McGraw, “Spiritual Responses to the Regulation of Births (A Historical Comparison),” in Life and Learning, vol. 12, Proceedings of the Twelfth University Faculty for Life Conference, ed. Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. (Washington, DC: University Faculty for Life, 2003), 265–83. 73 George A. Lindbeck, The Nature of Doctrine, Religion and Theology in a Postliberal Age (Philadelphia:Westminster Press, 1984), 31. 74 Ibid., 33. 75 Ibid., 32. In classical terms it is perhaps best expressed as lex orandi, lex credendi. 922 Mary Shivanandan This differs from the cognitivist or propositional approach, which is also external, by allowing for the importance of the interiorization of beliefs.76 Lindbeck holds, however, that this rule theory of doctrines does not choose between propositionally formulated truths and inner experiences. Instead “it is the framework or medium in which Christians experience rather than what they experience or think they know that retains continuity and unity through change.”77 While the experience of love, for example, of one individual changes as a result of cultural factors, it can only be called Christian love if it is shaped by the Christian story. And this Christian experience is significant only when it arises within the context of a Christian worldview or cultural-linguistic framework. Another cultural-linguistic framework will produce very different experiences, even among those who call themselves Christian.78 Lindbeck gives great importance to language. “Language . . . shapes domains of human existence and action that are preexperiential.”79 This sets in perspective the change in language for discussing sexuality, which was devised in specific contrast to the Judeo-Christian worldview.80 Although the sociologist Ira Reiss is not the architect of the “secular humanist” view of sexuality, he has played a major role in redefining the language used both to advance it and to oppose the Judeo-Christian approach.81 The terms 76 Ibid. The cultural-linguistic approach emphasizes that practice and training are essential for learning “how to feel, act, and think in conformity with a religious tradition. . . .The primary knowledge is not about the religion, not that the religion teaches such and such, but rather how to be religious in such and such ways” (ibid., 35).The stress is on the code rather than on encoded propositions. Religion is not so much a set of beliefs to choose but a set of skills to practice. Ritual, prayer, and example are more important, in his view, than explicitly formulated statements. The experiential-expressive is oriented towards private experience, while “all symbol systems have their origins in interpersonal relations and social interactions” (ibid., 38). See also ibid., 33–38, 83. 77 Ibid., 84. 78 Ibid., 83. 79 Ibid., 37. A feminist has pointed out the unconsciously negative way of speaking about fertility and conception in medical journals within a contraceptive framework. A comparison with natural family planning instruction manuals reveals the opposite. All the terms for fertility and conception speak of union and gift. See Mary Shivanandan,“Body Narratives: Language of Truth?” Logos 3 (2000): 166–93. 80 Anthropologist Margaret Mead is quoted as saying that since Kinsey,“the language of tables and variables . . . has replaced Latin as the acceptable language for the discussion of sex.” Cited in Letitia Anne Peplau, Zick Rubin, and Charles T. Hill, “Sexual Intimacy in Dating Relationships,” Journal of Social Issues 33 (1977): 86. 81 Paul Kurtz, editor of The Humanist, in his preface to a collection of essays originally published in The Humanist and titled “The New Sexual Revolution,” sums up this view: “A revolution is occurring and a new morality is emerging. This Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 923 “premarital” and “extramarital” have a sociological not a biblical source. Reiss has stated that social scientists have developed these terms explicitly to avoid the moral bias of “fornication” and “adultery.”82 Reiss’s views are evident throughout the CTSA Report, including the term “personcentered” sexuality that he coined.83 Reiss has defined ideologies as “firmly held doctrines of particular philosophical groups,”84 and concludes that “our ideology determines what we see as the ‘crucial’ issues in any social situation involving sexuality.”85 He identifies a “traditional-romantic” ideology that he describes as supporting gender-role distinction with male dominance, female fear of the body and sexual emotions, emphasis on coitus in sexual expression, and love as a redeemer of sexual guilt. In the “modern-naturalistic” view, that he chooses, gender roles are similar and egalitarian; personcentered sexuality is valued more than body-centered; sexual emotions are manageable; physical pleasure and psychological intimacy in a variety of sexual acts are the major goals of sexuality for both genders; and, finally, “a wide range of sexuality should be accepted without guilt by both genders providing it does not involve force or fraud.”86 Reiss’s main work was in the area of what he terms “premarital sexuality.” He conducted, in his own words, “the first systematic sociological study of a national probability sample in the area of premarital sexual attitudes.”87 One of the first major theorists in the field, he was influential in promoting his preferred standard of “permissiveness with affection” morality demands liberation and freedom for the individual to realize his own potentialities and satisfy his own needs, desires, and tastes as he sees fit, with a minimum of intolerant social rules and regulations. This is basically a humanist revolution. . . . Sexual liberation insists that we be emancipated from the puritanCatholic theology of repression.” Cited in The New Sexual Revolution, ed. Lester A. Kirkendall and Robert N. Whitehurst (New York: Donald W. Brown Inc., 1971), ix, x. See also Leonard V. Ramer, Your Sexual Bill of Rights: An Analysis of the Harmful Effects of Sexual Prohibitions (New York: Exposition Press, 1973). 82 Ira L. Reiss, Journey into Sexuality:An Exploratory Voyage (New York: Prentice Hall, 1986), 239. 83 Ira L. Reiss, Premarital Standards in America: A Sociological Investigation of the Relative Social and Cultural Integration of American Sexual Standards (New York:The Free Press, 1960), 83–85. 84 Ira L. Reiss,“Some Observations on Ideology and Sexuality in America,” Journal of Marriage and Family 43 (1981): 271. 85 Ibid., 281. 86 Ira L. Reiss,“Some Observations on Ideology and Sexuality in America,” 279–80. 87 Ira L. Reiss,The Social Context of Premarital Sexual Permissiveness (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1967), vii. Reiss,“Some Observations on Ideology,” 280. See also Reiss, Premarital Sexual Standards in America, 133, 144. 924 Mary Shivanandan and calling it “person-centered” behavior.88 It is not hard to see the influence of Reiss’s work on the authors of the CTSA Report. In discussing sex outside of marriage they use the term “non-marital sexuality” and discuss fornication within a context of changing the Tradition of the Church.They distinguish five approaches to “premarital” sexuality which correspond closely to Reiss’s categories. They favor the approach that “premarital intercourse is wrong but pre-ceremonial intercourse may be moral.” Empirical studies of current sexual activity are cited to support this position.89 Conclusion While the authors of the CTSA report continually nod towards the traditional teaching of the Church in giving pastoral advice, there can be no doubt that such teaching takes second place to contemporary theories of sexuality and empirical studies.These are precisely the errors of method that Christ pointed out in the Gospel, placing human reason above the word of God and not believing in its power.They are also the errors that John Paul II enumerated in Fides et Ratio. Particularly noticeable in the study commissioned by the Catholic Theological Society of America is the place of Jesus and his teaching in the text.After a brief section on the Old Testament in the first chapter, a few pages are given to the New Testament and Jesus, distinguishing between the Jesus of history and the Jesus of post-Easter faith.This is in telling contrast to John Paul II’s teaching from the first words of the first encyclical of his pontificate, Redemptor Hominis: “The Redeemer of man, Jesus Christ, is the center of the universe and of history.” In Fides et Ratio Jesus Christ crucified is the stumbling block but also the path to the restoration of man’s dignity and communion with the Triune God. Through him, life and faith are reunited. Reason, which passes between the two, can now correctly interpret the visible world in 88 Ibid., 192.The standard states that two people who have built up a stable affec- tionate relationship may engage in full sexual relations. 89 Kosnik et al., Human Sexuality, 152, 153, 158–65. Social science methods that observe human behavior can and do reveal useful but partial insights. Indeed contemporary studies on human sexuality and marriage are vindicating the truth of Catholic teaching. See W. Bradford Wilcox,“Social Science and the Vindication of Catholic Moral Teaching,” in The Church, Marriage & Family: Proceedings from the 27th Annual Convention of the Fellowship of Catholic Scholars, September 24–26, 2004, Pittsburgh, PA, ed. Kenneth D.Whitehead (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press, 2007), 330–40. See also W. Bradford Wilcox et al., Why Marriage Matters Second Edition: Twenty-Six Conclusions from the Social Sciences (New York: Institute for American Values, 2007). Humanae Vitae and Fides et Ratio 925 the light of faith and illumine faith itself to guide man on his path to his eternal destiny. Jesus Christ’s total self-gift even unto death becomes the key to interpreting man and the cosmos.Whatever distorts the meaning of this total self-gift, of which conjugal union is the prime earthly analogy, obscures the truth about God, man, and the cosmos. The acceptance or rejection of the teaching of Humanae Vitae, which reaffirms and extends the true meaning of conjugal love as total self-gift, has far wider implications than simply its impact on the sphere of conjugal relations.All these false or partial methodologies obscure the full truth of the humanum. In an article published the year of his election to the See of Peter, Karol Wojtyla/John Paul II himself writes:“It might even appear strange that the response to a concrete question in the field of conjugal morality can have such strong anthropological implications, that it can become the field of this struggle for the value and meaning of humanity itself.”90 One can go further. Since man is made in the image of God, it ultimately affects what we believe about the Trinity and Jesus Christ, how we worship as well as the integrity of reason as a path to truth. References have been given in the footnotes to show how those who redefine sexuality also redefine such dogmas as the Virgin Birth and the Trinity and vice versa.91 90 Karol Wojtyla, “The Anthropological Vision of Humanae Vitae,” trans.William E. May, Lateranum 44 (1978): 6. 91 See Donald Goergen, The Sexual Celibate (New York:The Seabury Press, 1974). Goergen does not come down in any definitive way against genital activity on the part of celibates (ibid., 103, 183). He asserts that Mary’s physical virginity is not a defined doctrine of the Magisterium and it is not necessary to maintain her virginal conception to hold that Jesus was born of the Holy Spirit.“She was not celibate; she may not have been a virgin” as Goergen defines it but “the significance of her chastity still remains.” See ibid., 126, 128, 129.With regard to homosexuality, he states that “the so-called Christian attitude towards homosexuality is beginning to change” (here he footnotes a long list of articles in support). He claims that the traditional condemnation of homosexuality stems from a misinterpretation of the sin of Sodom and Gomorrah. “We no longer,” he concludes,“have sufficient theological grounds for perpetuating a destructive attitude” (ibid., 195).The feminists have undertaken a more radical realignment of thinking on the Trinity and the Incarnation, linked to both contraception and abortion. Sally McFague, in Models of God, seeks to view the world as God’s body and to replace Father, Son, and Holy Spirit with God as lover, mother, and friend.The metaphor of God as mother, giver of life, does not mean being antiabortion, since she says God is on the side of all species not simply the human species. Population control is one way to assure the survival of all species (see ibid., 103, 104). Her theology makes no room for the Trinity, finding God as immanent and transcendent sufficient. Jesus Christ is not the Incarnate Son of 926 Mary Shivanandan Through his study of the person and human sexuality, especially as a result of the dissent on Humanae Vitae, John Paul II came to a profound understanding of the fundamental importance of foundations, both theological and philosophical. What he articulated in Fides et Ratio, he had already put into practice in his catechesis on the theology of the body. In the process he has both restored and extended the Church’s understanding of human sexuality as well as the indissoluble link between faith N&V and reason. God himself in the world; rather Jesus of Nazareth is one of the paradigmatic manifestations of the divine in the world (ibid., 183). Another feminist, Mary Elizabeth Hunt, co-founder and co-director of the Women’s Alliance for Theology, Ethics, and Ritual and Board member of Catholics for a Free Choice, argues for friendship, not conjugal union, as the criterion for marriage so that lesbian/gay relationships become “in fact, the relational equivalent of marriage.” “Problems heat up,” she says, “when the divine or God is likened not to Father, Mother, or even Parent, but to Friend.” See Mary E. Hunt, “Friends and Family Values: An Old Song,” in The Changing Face of Friendship, ed. Leroy S. Romer (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), 173, 175. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 927–950 927 Conscious Parenthood J ANET E. S MITH Sacred Heart Major Seminary Detroit, MI I N BOTH his prepapal writings and throughout his pontificate, Pope John Paul II expended an enormous amount of intellectual energy defending the Church’s teaching on contraception.1 His particular interest was to defend this teaching from the point of view of the nature of the person rather than exclusively from the nature of the sexual act as directed towards the procreative good.Yet he did not try to sidestep or supplant the importance of respect for the procreative good as a keystone in sexual ethics; indeed, he continued to recognize the procreative good as the primary good of marriage and greatly expanded our understanding of the value of the procreative good in the direction of personalism.Wojtyla progressively became clearer on the fact that he understood the procreative good to be not simply the child that results from sexual intercourse, but the conscious and even eager acceptance of the connection between the sexual act and becoming a parent with another person. Stated simply,Wojtyla maintained that the fact that sexual intercourse leads not just to children but to parenthood is a truth that those who would engage in sexual relations must acknowledge and accept for their sexual relations to be moral; they must be committed to what Wojtyla called “conscious parenthood.” In making such an acknowledgement and letting it guide their decisions about sexual matters, spouses will experience many personal goods, among them growth in self-mastery, the ability to select a spouse well, and the ability to be loving spouses and parents. 1 Let me commend readers to the unpublished dissertation of John Grondelski, Fruitfulness as an Essential Dimension of Acts of Conjugal Love:An Interpretative Study of the Pre-pontifical Thought of John Paul II (New York: Fordham University, Dept. of Theology, 1985). 928 Janet E. Smith In this essay, using Love and Responsibility as my primary source, I will show how Wojtyla used the concept of “conscious parenthood” in his attempt to meld natural law ethics with his personalistic ethics in his explanations of the Church’s teachings on sexuality.We shall also see how these themes are present and central to the argument of Humanae Vitae. Indeed, Wojtyla identified “responsible parenthood”—the usual translation of “conscious parenthood”—as the central theme of Humanae Vitae.2 Living by the Truth A fundamental principle that underlies all John Paul II’s anthropology is that human dignity is rooted in man’s ability to know the truth and to choose freely to live in accord with the truth. It is a principle he enunciates throughout his work. Veritatis Splendor provides a succinct formulation: “Although each individual has a right to be respected in his own journey in search of the truth, there exists a prior moral obligation, and a grave one at that, to seek the truth and to adhere to it once it is known.” (§34)3 Man’s dignity resides not only in his ability to know the truth and to live by it, but also in his ability to recognize the goodness of the truth. He in his subjectivity must make objective truth his own. In an article celebrating the tenth anniversary of Humanae Vitae Wojtyla claims: Man becomes capable of seeing in a more mature way the authenticity, the reasonableness, and the beauty of the objective moral order when he conceives it with his own conscience as subject. Perhaps then is accomplished precisely what St. Thomas Aquinas wanted to express by speaking of the “participation of the eternal law in the rational creature.”4 The encyclical Humanae vitae follows the same direction, postulating that man “observes with intelligence and love” the laws “written by God in his nature” (no. 31).5 In Love and Responsibility Wojtyla speaks of the objective truths that man must know in order to conduct his sexual life morally, as truths of justice: Man is endowed with reason not primarily to ‘calculate’ the maximum pleasure obtainable in this life, but above all to seek knowledge of 2 Karol Cardinal Wojtyla,“The Truth of the Encyclical Humanae Vitae,” L’Osservatore Romano,Weekly Edition in English, 16 January 1969, p. 6, www.ewtn.com/library/ Theology/WOJTLAHV.HTM 3 John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor (Boston: Pauline Books and Media, 1993): AAS 85 (1993). 4 See Summa theologiae I–II, q. 93, a. 2. 5 Karol Cardinal Wojtyla,“La Visione Antropologica della Humanae Vitae,” Lateranum 44 (1978): 125–45, trans. William E. May, www.christendom-awake.org/ pages/may/anthrop-visionjpII.htm. Conscious Parenthood 929 objective truth, as a basis for absolute principles (norms) to live by.This he must do if he is to live in a manner worthy of what he is, to live justly. Human morality cannot be grounded in ‘utility’ alone, it must sink its roots in ‘justice.’ Justice demands recognition of the supra-utilitarian value of the person; and in this the contrast between ‘justice’ and mere ‘utility’ is most clearly evident. In sexual matters in particular it is not enough to affirm that a particular mode of behaviour is expedient. We must be able to say that it is ‘just.’6 Wojtyla characterizes sexual relations that are directed primarily to pleasure as “utilitarian”: they involve using the other (and/or allowing one’s self) to be used as a sexual object.7 To engage in sexual relationships morally is to be “just” to the various relationships involved in sexual relations: it is to know the various goods that are objectively at play in the sexual realm and to be true to them. Wojtyla identifies three relationships that demand “justice” in the realm of morality, a justice that must be true to the objective truth of the human person and the nature of the sexual act.8 (1) He speaks of the need to be just to the “order of existence,” that is, to the ordination of the sexual act to the procreation of a new human being, an inestimable good. (2) He speaks of the need to be just to the Creator who made the order of nature. (3) He speaks of the need to be just to one’s beloved, who deserves to be treated with love rather than sexually exploited.These are all objective reasons why the procreative good is important; these are the truths of which people should be conscious to ensure that their sexual acts are moral. The Order of Nature In his essay, “The Problem of Catholic Sexual Ethics,” written in 1965, Wojtyla speaks of two interdependent ways of determining sexual morality.9 One way is the naturalistic or teleological way which looks to procreation, the objective natural end of the sexual act as the norm that should govern moral decisions. He notes that this way has fallen somewhat from popularity but has lost nothing of its “metaphysical value.”10 The other way is the personalistic way which involves an appeal to the experience of 6 Karol Cardinal Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility (San Franscisco: Ignatius Press, 1993), 239. 7 Ibid., 25–28. 8 Ibid., 245–49. 9 Karol Cardinal Wojtyla,“The Problem of Catholic Sexual Ethics: Reflections and Postulates,” in Person and Community: Selected Essays, trans.Theresa Sandok (New York: Peter Lang, 1993), 279–99. 10 Ibid., 280. It is important to note that Wojtyla maintains that the naturalistic approach seems “implicitly to contain elements of the personalistic view” (284). Janet E. Smith 930 the human person, to experience which realizes the need to convert the sexual urge from an instinct directed to selfish pleasure, to a motive for building a loving relationship with another.These two ways could also be distinguished as the “objective” way of assessing goods and the “subjective,” or personalist, way of assessing goods. Let me note that “subjective” here does not have the connotation of something private and perhaps idiosyncratic and opposed to the objective and measurably true.“Subjective” refers to the interior experience of the person; subjective goods are immanent goods; many of them redound to the benefit of the character of the subject. These goods can have a universal status; for example, courage is good for all human beings, but it is a good that is experienced as an interior good, as a good of the subject. Objective goods are goods outside of the acting person. Perhaps a rather pedestrian example might serve to illustrate the difference between objective goods and subjective goods. Some might own a dog for protection; protection, then, would be the objective good. Others own dogs in order to train them and sell them for profit; in this instance the objective good of dog ownership would be the financial profit. Dog ownership, of course, can also be the source of significant subjective goods such as feeling loved.We can even expect that the owner will develop certain virtues. Parents who make the brave decision to allow their children to own a dog hope that feeding, disciplining, exercising, and cleaning up after the dog will help their children become more responsible and diligent and even that their hearts will become more loving, tender, and committed. These are the personalistic, or subjective, values of dog ownership. No one should undertake owning a dog unless he or she is conscious of all the responsibilities that come with owning a dog and are prepared to accept those responsibilities; those who responsibly care for dogs will experience many subjective as well as objective goods. These two ways of assessing goods are abundantly displayed in Wojtyla’s approach to sexual morality. In Love and Responsibility, Wojtyla refers to two “orders”: the order of nature—equivalent to objective goods—and the order of the person—equivalent to subjective goods: In the sexual relationship between man and woman two orders meet: the order of nature, which has as its object reproduction,11 and the personal order, which finds its expression in the love of persons and aims at the fullest realization of that love. We cannot separate the two orders, for each depends upon the other. In particular, the correct attitude to procreation is a condition of the realization of love.12 11 Although Wojtyla uses “reproduction” here, more regularly he uses “procreation.” 12 Love and Responsibility, 226. Conscious Parenthood 931 So far from being at odds with each other, the order of nature, with its end of procreation, and the personal order, with its end of reciprocal love, should be realized together. Again, in Love and Responsibility, we read, In the world of persons . . . instinct alone decides nothing, and the sexual urge passes, so to speak, through the gates of consciousness and the will, thus furnishing not merely the conditions of fertility but also the raw material of love. At a truly human, truly personal level the problems of procreation and love cannot be resolved separately. Both procreation and love are based on the conscious choice of persons. When a man and a woman consciously and of their own free will choose to marry and have sexual relations they choose at the same time the possibility of procreation, choose to participate in creation (for that is the proper meaning of the word procreation).And it is only when they do so that they put their sexual relationship within the framework of marriage on a truly personal level.13 Clearly Wojtyla considers consciousness not simply to be awareness that X is linked to Y: those engaging in X should accept the possibility of Y and be prepared for it. And as noted above, Wojtyla is not speaking of a begrudging acknowledgment that sexual intercourse leads to children; he is speaking of a joyful acceptance of the connection between sexual intercourse and all the responsibilities entailed. Those who have a fuller understanding of the procreative good—the good of the life of the child and the good of parenthood for the parents—are more likely to achieve that joyful acceptance.Wojtyla sketches out what would be the elements of that fuller understanding. Procreative Good as an Objective Good In Love and Responsibility Wojtyla uses a classic argument to establish that the proper end of the sexual urge or act is procreation, an argument that some people might characterize as being right out of the “manuals.” Some dissenters have rejected the Church’s teaching on contraception because they believe it is physicalistic or biologistic in placing an emphasis on the biological consequence of sexual intercourse, the perpetuation of the species.14 They object that this view puts human sexual intercourse on the same level as animal sexual intercourse and that it does not recognize that human sexual intercourse has a spiritual as well as a physical dimension. 13 Ibid., 226–27 (italicized portions are Wojtyla’s emphasis; bolded are my emphasis). 14 Fr. Charles Curran regularly makes this objection; for an early instance, see Contemporary Problems in Moral Theology (Notre Dame, IN: Fides Publishers, Inc., 1970), 142–48. Janet E. Smith 932 Certainly Wojtyla is not guilty of identifying human sexual intercourse with animal intercourse, though he does not shy from noting that in a global scheme there are similarities in the purposes of both. In portions of Love and Responsibility,Wojtyla speaks of the defining feature of sexual intercourse, both ontologically and ethically, as the child that may result from an act of sexual intercourse. He speaks of the sexual urge as having a “necessity” for the whole human species: The [human] species could not exist if it were not for the sexual urge and its natural results. So that a sort of necessity is clearly discernable. Human kind can be maintained in being only so long as individual people, individual men and women, human couples, obey the sexual urge. . . . Obviously then it is not the love of man and woman that determines the proper purpose of the sexual urge. The proper end of the urge, the end per se, is something supra-personal, the existence of the species Homo, the constant prolongation of its existence.15 But Wojtyla does not understand the act of maintaining the existence of the species to be merely a biological good. In observing that sometimes the procreative purpose is seen as a nuisance, Wojtyla notes that man “often accords the sexual urge a merely biological significance” and does not realize that the “link with the very existence of man and of the species Homo . . . gives the sexual urge its objective importance and meaning.”16 Note that Wojtyla does not link the biological purpose simply to reproducing a species, but links it also to bringing into existence a human being and continuing the species of man, a species that is on an entirely different level from animals. The act of bringing into existence another member of the human species is an entirely different kind of act. In days prior to the arguments of such philosophers as Peter Singer who argue that human life does not per se have greater value than animal life, such a claim did not need further justification.17 The claim that continuing the species is a service to mankind meets with resistance in a world that has for decades been terrified that we are killing ourselves by overpopulating. Nonetheless, in spite of the hostility to human beings expressed by some environmentalists, most people would acknowledge that the continuation of the human species is a good thing and that thus at least some reproductive acts of human beings are good. The growing awareness that many portions of the globe are not repro15 Love and Responsibility, 51. 16 Ibid., 53;Wojtyla revisits this point later in Love and Responsibility, 230. 17 Cf. Peter Singer, Practical Ethics, 2nd edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). Conscious Parenthood 933 ducing themselves and thus facing severe economic challenges may restore our awareness of the goodness of reproducing the human species.18 In Love and Responsibility, Wojtyla distinguishes the order of nature from the biological order, the order occupied by plants and animals that are directed by laws of which they are not conscious. Wojtyla maintains that although the human sexual act is also directed to the general biological purpose of reproducing the species, it does not have a “purely biological significance.”The human sexual urge belongs not just to the biological order but also to the order of nature or the “order of existence.” He describes this order: The order of nature is above all that of existence and procreation. We intend the word to be taken in its fullest sense when we say that the order of nature aims at ‘procreation’ by means of the sexual act. Sexual intercourse, on all occasions, is in the nature of things affected in one way or another by its primary purpose, procreation. Looked at objectively the marital relationship is therefore not just a union of persons, a reciprocal relationship between a man and a woman, but is essentially a union of persons affected by the possibility of procreation.19 Wojtyla goes on to explain that “procreation” is the proper term for human sexual intercourse rather than “reproduction.” “Reproduction” refers to the purely biological process of bringing forth a new being, a new member of any species, whereas “procreation” refers to the bringing forth of a new person, which is of infinite value in itself. This point cannot be stressed enough. All other entities that come to be through the biological process are instrumental goods; they are here to contribute to the good of the whole, which itself is ordered to the good of human beings. Only human beings have an intrinsic, infinite value.Thus the human act of sexual intercourse has an infinitely greater value than acts of animal sexual intercourse.The respect due to a human sexual act derives not from the simply natural biological fact that it is by nature ordained to reproduction, but that it is by nature ordained to the procreation of something of infinite value.Thus, we can see that the high valuation the Church sees in human sexual relations is not at all biologistic or physicalistic; it is not based solely or primarily on the physical nature of the sexual act as a means of reproducing a species; it is based on the physical nature of the sexual act that is a means of procreating a new 18 Cf. Steven Mosher, Population Control: Real Costs, Illusory Benefits (Piscataway, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2008). 19 Love and Responsibility, 226. Janet E. Smith 934 human being. That new human being is the procreative good that is of inestimable value. Furthermore,Wojtyla maintains that well raised children are a benefit to the nation, state, and Church.20 While Wojtyla does not elaborate on what kind of goods a child supplies to the nation, state, and Church, surely among them would be included the fact that for the most part, a child brings talents and energy to a culture, not to mention economic benefits.21 Not only is having a baby beneficial to the species and to society; having a baby is also a service to God. In Love and Responsibility, when explaining why “human existence” is not just of biological significance, Wojtyla speaks of man and woman as being “rational co-creators of a new human being,” which is not just an “organism” but a spiritual entity.22 A spiritual entity cannot come to be without the help of God: For something more than the love of parents was present at the origin of the new person—they were only co-creators; the love of the Creator decided that a new person would come into existence in the mother’s womb. Grace is, so to speak, the continuation of this work. God Himself takes the supreme part in the creation of a human person in the spiritual, moral, strictly supernatural sphere.23 Through an act of physical love, lovers help transmit existence to a new person, a new immortal being. Spouses are co-creators with God in bring20 Ibid., 217. 21 Cf. Julian Simon, The Ultimate Resource 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998). 22 Love and Responsibility, 55. It is interesting to note that Church documents that speak of the relationship of the work of the spouses to the work of God in creating new human beings do not speak of them as “co-creators.” Rather, Church documents speak of spouses as “cooperators” with God, “collaborators” or “coworkers” with God. I suspect the choice of words in Church documents is made to avoid the metaphysical problems with attributing “creation” to man; to “create” technically is to bring something into existence from nothing. Only God can do so; spouses can only provide preexisting material, the ovum and the sperm, whereas God creates a new human soul out of “nothing.” Yet, I think there are merits to the term “co-create.” “Cooperate” in English more or less suggests that one is not resisting and to some extent is helping in the work of the other. To “collaborate” means to participate in work with another. Father Louis Madey, a native Polish philosopher, informed me that the Polish words translated as “create” and “co-create” in Love and Responsibility have more the sense of “artist” and “coartist”; create was likely chosen as a translation because both “artistry” and “creation” have a sense of creativity and newness about them, connotations lacking from “cooperation” and “collaboration.” 23 Ibid., 56. Conscious Parenthood 935 ing forth a new human soul. It is difficult to think what work of spouses could be more important than this task.24 Wojtyla observes that the truth about the sexual urge is “not a fundamentally obscure and incomprehensible matter.” He says it is “in principle accessible to, penetrable by the light of human thought,” and one that revelation makes even clearer.25 Man by the light of his own reason can realize that human life and thus human sexual acts are not just of biological importance. Man can realize that the good of human life is incomparably greater than any biological purpose; indeed he can recognize God’s work in creating new human life. Revelation gives us an even fuller picture of the value of the human soul. If spouses were to understand their acts of sexual intercourse as acts of “co-creation” with God, they would not likely see that procreative power of the sexual act as a nuisance that they must “fix” by technological means. In the chapter of Love and Responsibility entitled “Justice to the Creator,” Wojtyla gives attention to the need for couples to “justify” their relationship to others and also to God. And by “justify” he means “make just.” How can sexual relations be “just”? Wojtyla notes that each person is truly the property of the Creator and owes the Creator something for his existence.Wojtyla asserts: “The value of the institution of marriage is that it justifies the existence of sexual relations between a man and a woman.”26 And while he notes that marriage is a conglomerate of many acts and many different kinds of act, all of which should be performed in a loving fashion and which should serve love, he speaks of the sexual act as presenting a “particular moral problem, the internal problem of every marriage.”27 As he did earlier, he makes it clear that the sexual act presents a particular challenge to the personalistic norm, since it is so easy in the sexual realm for people to use each other “to degrade the act of mutual love between persons to the ‘utilitarian’ level.”28 Wojtyla speaks of justice to one’s spouse, one’s children, and society as “horizontal justice” and justice to God as “vertical justice.” He reminds us 24 Cf. §43 of Evangelium Vitae: “A certain sharing by man in God’s lordship is also evident in the specific responsibility which he is given for human life as such. It is a responsibility which reaches its highest point in the giving of life through procreation by man and woman in marriage. . . . [W]e wish to emphasize that God himself is present in human fatherhood and motherhood quite differently than he is present in all other instances of begetting ‘on earth.’ ” (AAS 87 (1995), 401–522). 25 Love and Responsibility, 56. 26 Ibid., 224. 27 Ibid., 225. 28 Ibid., 225. 936 Janet E. Smith that God “too is a Personal Being, with whom man must have some sort of relationship.”29 He speaks of the “rights” of God, the Creator, and the “duties” of man, the creature. Man must recognize that God made the whole of creation, the essences or natures of all things, and the whole order of nature.Wojtyla instructs, “Man is just towards the Creator when he recognizes the order of nature and conforms to it in his action.”30 But since the order of nature is a product of the thought of God, when man abides by the order of nature, he participates in the thought of God and becomes a “particeps Creatoris” a partner of the Creator, a sharer of the Creator).Wojtyla observes,“This participation is an end in itself.The value of man, a reasonable being, is nowhere more obvious than in the fact that he is particeps Creatoris, that he shares in God’s thoughts, and His laws.”31 Wojtyla tells us, “Justice towards the Creator, on the part of man, comprises as we see two elements: obedience to the order of nature and emphasis on the value of the person.”32 He insists that those who love God will love their fellow man.When he applies this to conjugal love, he says that justice to the Creator requires men and women to conduct their relationships in accord with the personalistic norm, the norm that dictates that all human beings must be treated with love.33 Wojtyla clearly means that spouses should think of the act of having a baby as an act of service to the species and as an act of justice towards God, for God designed sexual intercourse to be the source of new human life.Wojtyla understands these to be truths based on a metaphysical understanding of the value of the human person and on a religious understanding of the relationship of God to his world. Both ideas may seem strange to today’s culture because we largely think of sexual intercourse as an act that is purely physical and simply “for” the pleasure of the spouses— not one that involves the species or God or even a future child. Indeed, the modern world is ambivalent about the value of children: on the one hand, children are often treated as huge economic burdens; on the other hand, most people truly do love their children as the best thing that has ever happened to them. The notion that in addition to being a great source of love, pleasure, and meaning for the parents, children have an ecological worth and an intrinsic worth, and also are of extreme value to God are notions largely foreign to the modern mind.Yet these are the very truths that Wojtyla believes to be essential to the moral use of sexuality. 29 Ibid., 245. 30 Ibid., 246. 31 Ibid., 247. 32 Ibid., 247. 33 Ibid., 40–44. Conscious Parenthood 937 As we have seen, in Love and Responsibility Wojtyla gives four naturalistic, objective reasons that procreation is a good: (1) it results in a new human being, which is an inestimable good to the new human being and foundational for all other goods; (2) it contributes to the survival of the species; (3) it contributes to the good of the state and the Church; and (4) it is an act of justice towards God who desires more souls. The Order of the Person Wojtyla also gives four personalistic reasons why consciousness of the multifold goodness of the procreative good is good for spouses: (1) the realization of the responsibilities that come with procreation assists an individual in gaining control over the sexual urge; (2) conjugal love is not possible without acceptance of the importance of the procreative good; (3) raising a child is the occasion for becoming more self-giving and loving; and (4) the realization that one is chosen to be a co-creator with God enables people to realize their intrinsic greatness. Overcoming the Sexual Urge As we have noted, Wojtyla repeatedly makes reference to the necessity that spouses be “conscious” of the natural purpose of the sexual act—the fact that it leads to a child who benefits the species and the culture—and of the spouses’ obligations to God in reference to the sexual act. Those claims remain central to his personalistic evaluation of sexuality. For it is in respecting the order of nature that the values of the order of the person can be realized: The proper way for a person to deal with the sexual urge is, on the one hand, consciously to make use of it for its natural purposes, and on the other to resist it, when it threatens to degrade the relationship between two persons to a level lower than that of love, lower than the level on which the value of the person is affirmed in a union with a truly personal character. Sexual (marital) relations have the character of a true union of persons as long as a general disposition towards parenthood is not excluded from them. This implies a conscious attitude to the sexual instinct: to master the sexual urge means just this, to accept its purpose in marital relations.34 Indeed, the goal of Love and Responsibility is to discover and explain how it is possible to relate to another person sexually without using that person. Love and Responsibility identifies respect for the procreative end of the sexual urge as a key to ensuring that sexual attraction does not lead 34 Ibid., 229 (emphasis added). Janet E. Smith 938 to exploitation of another, but leads rather to loving treatment of another. Wojtyla states the problem in this way: Does not a woman constitute for a man, in the sexual relationship, something like a means to the various ends which he seeks to attain within that relationship? Equally, does not a man constitute for a woman the means towards the attainment of her own aims?35 He quite immediately provides an answer to that question; he speaks of the need for the two to share a common good and to be conscious that they do.36 He states, Love between two people is quite unthinkable without some common good to bind them together. This good is the end which both these persons choose. When two different people consciously choose a common aim this puts them on a footing of equality, and precludes the possibility that one of them might be subordinated to the other.37 Man’s capacity for love depends on his willingness consciously to seek a good together with others, and to subordinate himself to that good for the sake of others, or to others for the sake of that good.38 Wojtyla then goes on to specify what this common good39 must be between a man and woman who seek a sexual relationship with each other: The end, where marriage is concerned, is procreation, the future generation, a family, and at the same time, the continual ripening of the relationship between two people, in all the areas of activity conjugal life includes. The objective purposes of marriage create in principle the possibility of love and exclude the possibility of treating a person as a means to an end and as an object for use.40 Wojtyla clearly states here that the project of having and raising children together is a project that enables the spouses to redirect their sexual urge from simply being a matter of seeking selfish pleasure to seeking the good of others, to seeking the good of giving another person—one’s child—a new life, and to giving one’s spouse the opportunity to be a parent. 35 Ibid., 26. 36 Michael Waldstein,“The Common Good in St.Thomas and John Paul II,” Nova et Vetera 3:3 (2005): 569–78 37 Love and Responsibility, 28–29 (italics are Wojtyla’s emphasis; bold is my empha- sis). 38 Ibid., 29 (bold is my emphasis). 39 Ibid., n. 9, 291–92. 40 Ibid., 30. Conscious Parenthood 939 We have already spoken of the good of life for a child, and will soon speak of the good of parenthood for the spouses, but first we need to look at Wojtyla’s understanding that consciousness of prospective parenthood enables those sexually attracted to each other to emerge from the sensual and sentimental fog that characterizes sexual attraction to a consideration of the true values of the object of one’s sexual interest.To put it simply, the project of selecting a person who will be the parent of one’s children is very different from the project of seeking a sexual partner. Wojtyla never loses sight of the importance of sexual attraction—which he calls the “raw material” of love,41 but he insists that for true love to happen, the lovers must have a true understanding of their beloved, and that is best gained by having a realistic assessment of their suitability as a partner in the shared project of raising children. Wojtyla holds that the sexual urge is something that “happens to” human beings—it happens without conscious thought.42 Our very dignity, on the other hand, lies in our ability to use our consciousness to lead us to govern that urge; we only act freely if we are able to choose the means by which we allow that urge to achieve its natural end.Wojtyla discusses a “libidinistic interpretation” of the sexual urge which holds that the ultimate purpose of the sexual urge is pleasure.Against this interpretation,Wojtyla argues that recognition of the procreative end is essential to correcting this hedonistic understanding of human sexuality. He notes that the natural purpose of the sexual act, the ordination of that act to the procreation of another human person, transforms the sexual urge into something directed towards others rather than to one’s own selfish pleasure: If it follows its natural course the sexual urge always transcends the limits of the ‘I,’ and has as its immediate object some being of the other sex within the same species and for its final end the existence of the whole species. Such is the objective purpose of the sexual urge, in the nature of which there is—and this is where it differs from the instinct of self-preservation—something that might be called ‘altero-centrism.’ This it is that creates the basis for love.43 Importantly, Wojtyla does not think it sufficient simply to master the sexual urge; rather the sexual urge should be put to work for the positive values of sexuality, for the creation of new life and new love: 41 Ibid., e.g., 108. 42 Ibid., 46. 43 Ibid., 65. Janet E. Smith 940 For the will does not merely combat the urge: it simultaneously assumes within the framework of betrothed love responsibility for the natural purpose of the instinct.This is of course the continuation of the human race, which concretely requires that a new person, a child, shall be the fruit of conjugal love between man and woman. The will makes this purpose its own, and in consciously working towards it seeks greater scope for its creative tendency. In this way true love, profiting from the natural dynamic of the will, attempts to give the relationship a thoroughly unselfish character, to free their love from utilitarian attitudes. . . . [T]his is the significance of what we have called here the struggle between love and the sexual instinct.The sexual instinct wants above all to take over, to make use of another person, whereas love wants to give, to create a good, to bring happiness.44 Those who have mastered their sexual urges, and this is done by considering the importance of the procreative good, are free to give fuller attention to the values of the person; indeed, should one’s sexual passion diminish or change, the love will remain: The sexual values which a man finds in a woman, or a woman finds in a man, must certainly help to determine the choice, but the person making it must in doing so be fully aware that what he or she is choosing is a person. So that although the sexual values in the object of choice may disappear, and however they may change, the fundamental value—that of the person—will remain. The choice is truly choice of a person when it treats that value as the most important and decisive one. So that if we consider the whole process by which a man chooses a woman or a woman a man, we can say that it is set in motion by recognition of and reaction to sexual values, but that in the last analysis each chooses the sexual values because they belong to a person, and not the person because of his or her sexual values.45 It is very clear from the writings of Wojtyla that the choice of a spouse should very much include the suitability of this spouse to be a parent. He repeatedly states that those who would be married must be conscious of the fact that they may become parents with each other: When a man and woman capable of procreation have intercourse their union must be accompanied by awareness and willing acceptance of the possibility that ‘I may become a father’ or ‘I may become a mother.’ . . . [Sexual union] is raised to the level of the person only when it is accompanied in the mind and the will by acceptance of the possibility of 44 Ibid., 137. 45 Ibid., 133. Conscious Parenthood 941 parenthood.This acceptance is so important, so decisive that without it marital intercourse cannot be said to be a realization of a personal relationship . . . . Neither in the man nor in the woman can affirmation of the value of the person be divorced from awareness and willing acceptance that he may become a father and she may become a mother. . . . If the possibility of parenthood is deliberately excluded from marital relations, the character of the relationship automatically changes. The change is away from unification in love and in the direction of mutual or, rather, bilateral,‘enjoyment’.46 Wojtyla states that love, the respect for the person, requires respect for nature. Wojtyla states this repeatedly: “Acceptance of the possibility of procreation in the marital relationship safeguards love and is an indispensable condition of a truly personal union.”47 He speaks of the “creative power of love” expressing itself in procreation.48 He speaks of the acceptance of parenthood serving to “break down the reciprocal egoism—(or the egoism of one party at which the other connives).”49 Throughout Love and ResponsibilityWojtyla states his view that by rejecting the procreative good, one is also rejecting the good of the person: The intentions, and attention, of each party to the act should be directed towards the other person, as a person, the will should be wholly concerned with that person’s good, the heart filled with affirmation of that person’s specific value. By definitively precluding the possibility of procreation in the marital act a man and a woman inevitably shift the whole focus of the experience in the direction of sexual pleasure as such.50 Wojtyla states that if a couple “rule out even the possibility of parenthood their relationship is transformed to the point at which it becomes incompatible with the personalistic norm.”51 He notes that the danger arises that nothing will be left of their relationship except “utilisation for pleasure.”52 Indeed, Wojtyla finds support for his views in Gaudium et Spes. In “Parenthood as a Community of Persons” (1975) Wojtyla states, “[Gaudium et Spes 48] makes it perfectly clear that parenthood constitutes the central meaning of the marital community. In the birth and 46 Ibid., 228; see “Parenthood as a Community of Persons,” Person and Community, 331. 47 Ibid., 230. 48 Ibid., 230. 49 Ibid., 230. 50 Ibid., 234–45. 51 Ibid., 228. 52 Ibid., 228. Janet E. Smith 942 education of offspring, the spouses ‘experience the meaning of their oneness, which increases day by day.’The meaning of marital communio personarum and all it involves, particularly conjugal intercourse, is the child. In other words, the meaning of marriage is the family. One of the reasons children come into the marital community of husband and wife is to confirm, strengthen, and deepen this community. In this way, the spouses’ own interpersonal life, their communio personarum, is enriched.”53 The language of Gaudium et Spes is very strong: the meaning of marriage is the child, but it is precisely in committing themselves to having children and then in performing the tasks of parenting that the parents become a communion of persons with each other. Wojtyla responds to the objection that his claim that spouses must have a “conscious and willing acceptance” of the possibility of parenthood54 entails that they must “positively desire to procreate on every occasion when they have intercourse.”55 He speaks of this as being “an exaggeratedly strict ethical position” and maintains it would be “at odds with the order of nature,” since nature does not necessitate that each sexual act result in procreation, nor does man need to intend that each sexual act result in procreation.56 Furthermore, while he approves of timing intercourse in order to enhance the possibility of conceiving, he notes that the view that spouses should have intercourse only when intending offspring is possibly to reduce the sexual act—and one’s spouse—to a utilitarian purpose and thus to violate the personalist norm.57 Not only does Wojtyla speak against using sexual intercourse in a utilitarian way to produce offspring; he insists that the sexual act is also necessary for expressing love within marriage: “Intercourse is necessary to love, not just to procreation.”58 The conjugal act uniquely allows spouses to make a mutual gift of self to each other. In having sexual intercourse spouses should be intent on expressing love and should not concentrate on the baby-making power of the act to the extent that this would mean “a diversion of attention from the partner.”59 Wojtyla says it is sufficient “to say that ‘in performing this act we know that we may become parents and we are willing for that to happen.’ ”60 53 Ibid., 332–33. 54 Ibid., 232. 55 Ibid., 233. 56 Ibid., 233. 57 Ibid., 233. 58 Ibid., 233. 59 Ibid., 234. 60 Ibid., 234. Conscious Parenthood 943 Conjugal Love and Conscious Parenthood We have spoken earlier about how having children helps the parents grow in self-giving love.The strongest statement that Wojtyla made about the connection between parenthood and the growth in love of the spouses is perhaps in “Fruitfulness and Responsible Love,” a speech he gave commemorating the 10th year anniversary of Humanae Vitae, given only a few months before he was elected Holy Father: Parenthood belongs to the nature of this specific love which is conjugal love: it constitutes its essential feature, it forms this love in the sphere of purpose and intention and signs it finally with the seal of particular fulfillment. Conjugal love is fulfilled by parenthood. Responsibility for this love from the beginning to the end is at the same time responsibility also for parenthood. The one participates in the other and they both constitute each other. Parenthood is a gift that comes to people, to man and woman, together with love, that creates a perspective of love in the dimension of a reciprocal life-long self-giving, and that is the condition of gradual realization of that perspective through love and action. Parenthood, the gift, is therefore at the same time a rich task whose receiving and successive fulfilling is synonymous with receiving a gift: a gift moreover, which the persons themselves become for each other in marriage: the woman for the man, the man for the woman. Their reciprocal offering to each other of what they are as man and woman reaches its full sense through parenthood, through the fact that as husband and wife they become father and mother.And this is precisely the dimension and sense of the responsibility that essentially corresponds to this gift.61 Here we see that counterpoised to conjugal love and intricately wrapped up with conjugal love is the procreative good, understood not as the child, but as parenthood. And a great personalist good that comes from marriage is the love that the spouses have for each other as parents, as those who have given each other the great gift of parenthood. Natural Greatness In the closing pages of Love and Responsibility, Wojtyla returns to the importance of the procreative good, to the importance that man be conscious of the importance of this good to make his acts truly loving: The true greatness of the human person is manifested in the fact that sexual activity is felt to require such a profound justification [that it can 61 Karol Cardinal Wojtyla, Fruitful and Responsible Love (New York: Seabury Press, 1979), 23–24. Janet E. Smith 944 lead to a new human being]. It cannot be otherwise. Man must reconcile himself to his natural greatness. It is especially when he enters so deeply into the natural order, immerses himself so to speak in its elemental processes, that he must not forget that he is a person. Instinct alone can resolve none of his problems, everything demands decisions from his ‘interior self ’, his reason and his sense of responsibility. And this is particularly true of the love to which human kind owes its continual renewal. Responsibility for love, to which we are giving particular attention in this discussion, is very closely bound up with responsibility for procreation. Love and parenthood must not therefore be separated from the other. Willingness for parenthood is an indispensable condition of love.62 Wojtyla throughout his writings speaks of the need for man to “reconcile himself to his natural greatness”; in respect to sexuality this means both that man must use his reason and sense of responsibility to control his instincts and also that he should realize what an enormous honor and privilege it is to be able to resemble his Creator in his ability to love and to be able to bring forth new human life. The themes of the centrality of the procreative good and the necessity of conscious acceptance of the procreative good to sexual ethics are not confined to Love and Responsibility. They reappear in Wojtyla’s prepapal writings, such as the Lublin lectures.They appear as well in Humanae Vitae, likely as a result of various paths of influence Wojtyla had on the composition of Humanae Vitae.They also appear in many of the speeches Wojtyla gave about Humanae Vitae after its promulgation. We will not have time here to look into these many appearances.What we will do is take a quick look at some of the more important appearances of these themes in Humanae Vitae, with particular attention to conscious parenthood. Humanae Vitae Both themes appear in the very first line of Humanae Vitae, which speaks of spouses “fulfilling a mission of transmitting human life and thereby rendering a conscious and free service to God the Creator.”63 Here we have an echo of Wojtyla’s argument that honoring the procreative good is a part of a just relationship between man and God. Humanae Vitae does not speak of spouses as “co-creators” with God of new human life but it 62 Love and Responsibility, 236. 63 I will be using my own translation of Humanae Vitae. It has been published as appendix 1 to my Humanae Vitae: A Generation Later (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1991) and as a pamphlet by Catholics United for Life; it is available online at: www.aodonline.org/aodonline-sqlimages/ shms/faculty/SmithJanet/Publications/HumanaeVitae/Translated.pdf Conscious Parenthood 945 does speak of marriage as being established by God for the purpose of bringing forth new life, of all “parenthood” being rooted in the fatherhood of God the Creator, and also of spouses “sharing with God the task [operam socient] of procreating and educating new living beings.” (§8) And while the words “order of nature” do not appear in Humanae Vitae, the encyclical makes many references to “natural law” and the laws of God written into nature (cf. §§3; 10, 11, 12, 13 (twice); 18, 24, 31). Humanae Vitae also speaks of the procreative good as a value to the parents in their loving relationship; section 9 cites a key passage from Gaudium et Spes (§48):“Marriage and conjugal love are ordained [ordinantur] by their very nature [indole sua] to the procreating and educating of children. Offspring are clearly the supreme gift [donum] of marriage, a gift which contributes immensely to the good of the parents themselves.”64 Talk of laws of nature, of God as creator, and of spouses as those who cooperate with God come together in a single passage from Humanae Vitae, section 13: [Spouses] should acknowledge that it is necessarily true that an act of mutual love which impairs the capacity of bringing forth life contradicts both the divine plan which established the nature [normam] of the conjugal bond and also the will of the first Author of human life. For this capacity of bringing forth life was designed by God, the Creator of All according to [His] specific laws. Thus, anyone who uses God’s gift [of conjugal love] and cancels, if only in part, the significance and the purpose of this gift, is rebelling against either the male or female nature and against their most intimate relationship and for this reason, then, he is defying the plan and holy will of God. On the other hand, the one who uses the gift of conjugal love in accord with the laws of generation, acknowledges that he is not the lord of the sources of life, but rather the minister of a plan initiated by the Creator. Thus the naturalistic, teleological argument against contraception is well represented in Humanae Vitae. Although there is no reference to the goodness of procreation as a means of continuing the species, the other three reasons for which Wojtyla extols the procreative good—the inestimable goodness of the life that results, the mutual good of the spouses, and the service to God—are all clearly present in Humanae Vitae. “Conscious parenthood,” often translated as “responsible parenthood,” is a very prominent theme in Humanae Vitae.65 Indeed Wojtyla, in the piece 64 Gaudium et Spes, §50, in AAS 58 (1966), 1070–72. 65 Let me also note that the term “conscious parenthood” is prominent in the report that was written by a commission set up in Krakow to respond to the reports that were produced by the special commission set up by Pope Paul VI to 946 Janet E. Smith published in L’Osservatore Romano in 1969, stated:“The analysis of responsible parenthood constitutes the principal theme of the encyclical.”66 Let me clarify the meaning of “conscious/responsible parenthood.” Section 10 of Humanae Vitae focuses on responsible parenthood; the words translated as “responsible parenthood” are “conscia paternitas.” The word “responsible” is not a perfect translation of “conscia” and misses some of its important connotations. The word “conscia” appears in the very first line of Humanae Vitae, which speaks of the “free and conscious service of transmitting life” that spouses render to God.This line is reminiscent of a key passage in Gaudium et Spes that speaks of the dignity of the human person requiring that he make “conscious and free choices”—and not act under the influence of blind impulse (§17).67 We have seen above that the term plays an important role in Love and Responsibility. Fr. Louis Madey68 informed me that in Polish the word świadomość, which is translated as “conscious” throughout Love and Responsibility, connotes a deeply personalistic meaning; it means being vividly aware of some reality; it conveys experiencing something with one’s emotions as well as one’s intellect. Other words translated as “conscious” convey different notions: in one instance the word odczuwa translated means something like “gut feeling,” something deeply experienced or of which one has a deep awareness; in another instance the word refleksji means “conscious thought.” Wojtyla uses the word “conscious” frequently, much more frequently than he uses the word “rational,” a word that also can be used to indicate that one knows the reality and is accepting of reality. I suspect that Wojtyla speaks of conscious behavior more frequently than rational behavior because to speak of consciousness seems to emphasize the act of a particular person more than rationality does.To think and act rationally for the most part links the action with some objective universal order; to speak of being conscious reflects the individual’s personal appropriating of some truth. The subjective and objective come together more. I believe any work advise him on “birth regulation.”That report, commissioned by Karol Wojtyla, is “Le Fondements de la Doctrine de L’eglise concernant Les Principes de La Vie Conjugale,” Analacta Cracoviensia, 1969, 194–230.The phrase is also prominent in section 12 of Gratissimam sane,The Letter to Families, AAS 86 (1994) 868–925. 66 “Wojtyla, “The Truth of the Encyclical Humanae Vitae,” 6.” 67 “Dignitas igitur hominis requirit ut secundum consciam et liberam electionem agat, personaliter scilicet ab intra motus et inductus, et non sub caeco impulsu interno vel sub mera externa coactione.” Gaudium et Spes, §50, in AAS 58 (1966), 1070–72. 68 Father Maday is a native of Poland; currently he is vice-rector at St. Cyril and Methodius Seminary in Michigan. Conscious Parenthood 947 influenced by the thought of John Paul II that includes the word “conscious” carries many of the connotations of the discussion of “conscious parenthood” in Love and Responsibility. Again, the word “responsible” does not truly convey what the word “conscia” connotes. English speakers when they hear of “responsible parenthood” generally think of parents who perform their duties as parents well. In the context of Humanae Vitae, it is reasonable for readers to understand that “responsible parents” are those who realize that they are to raise children to be good citizens in God’s kingdom or those who manage their family size well. But a close reading of section 10 suggests that Wojtyla’s notion of the consciousness of the connection betwen sexuality and procreative good is very much operative there. It includes the senses of “responsible” just identified but means something much more. The English word “conscious” is a cognate of “conscia” and is a better translation of “conscia” than “responsible,” but it too is not quite a match for what the concept seems to convey for Wojtyla. Certainly the word “conscious” means that someone is aware of the reality that he holds in his consciousness.To speak of an agent acting “consciously” indicates that the agent knows what he or she is doing; it also suggests that he or she is aware of the consequences of an action and accepts responsibility for those consequences.The additional element for Wojtyla seems to include that the agent accepts that reality and the consequences as good; that is, a person “conscious” that sex leads to parenthood is aware of that reality and accepts it as a good. These various meanings of “conscious” appear in Humanae Vitae 10. I am going to translate the phrase “conscia parternitas” as “conscious parenthood.” Admittedly it sounds awkward at several points, but it helps to focus our attention on what is being said.We shall look at each instance where it appears in Humanae Vitae 10. Humanae Vitae 10 begins with the statement: “Conjugal love requires that spouses be fully aware of their mission [munus] of conscious parenthood. Today’s society justly calls for conscious parenthood; thus it is important that it be rightly understood. Consequently, we must consider the various legitimate and interconnected dimensions [rationibus] of parenthood.”The first dimension of which spouses should be conscious is that of the nature of man’s biological processes: “conscious parenthood means that one knows and honors the responsibilities [munerum] involved in these processes. Human reason has discovered that there are biological laws in the power of procreating life that pertain to the human person. If then we look to the innate impulses and inclinations of the soul, conscious parenthood asserts that it is necessary that reason and will exercise mastery 948 Janet E. Smith over these impulses and inclinations of the soul.”69 This passage is very reminiscent of Wojtyla’s discussions in Love and Responsibility, both of the necessity of respecting the natural order wherein sexual intercourse leads to offspring and of the necessity of man taking control of his sexual urges. The next passage speaks of parents consciously planning their family size. It states: If we look further to physical, economic, psychological and social conditions, conscious parenthood is exercised by those who, guided by prudent consideration and generosity, elect to accept many children. Those are also to be considered conscious parents, who, for serious reasons and with due respect for moral precepts, decide not to have another child either for a definite or an indefinite amount of time. Some Catholics believe that “just letting the babies come” is the default position of the Church, but this passage—and other passages in works of Wojtyla—suggest that parents are to diligently assess their ability to care for more children. Some may determine that they have the resources to “just let the babies come” and thus for them doing so would be prudent. Deliberation about the goodness of having a child should be a regular practice for most couples. Indeed, this process may lead them to have more rather than fewer children.What Humanae Vitae is advancing is that spouses should be intentional about having children.70 The next paragraph reinforces the sense of the earlier one that spouses should consciously plan their family: The conscious parenthood of which we speak here has another intrinsic foundation [intimam rationem] of utmost importance: it is rooted in the objective moral order established by God—and only an upright conscience can be a true interpreter of this order. For which reason, the mission [munus] of conscious parenthood requires that spouses recognize their duties [officia] towards God, towards themselves, towards the family, and towards human society, as they maintain a correct set of priorities. Those who are deliberating on whether to have a child or most likely another child should be considering those who are impacted by that 69 I have retranslated my own translation of Humanae Vitae to highlight the pres- ence of the word “conscious,” previously translated by myself and others as “responsible.” 70 For a discussion of what kind of reasons are acceptable for limiting family size, see Janet E. Smith “The Moral Use of Natural Family Planning” in Why Humanae Vitae was Right: A Reader, ed. By Janet E. Smith (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993) 305–26. Conscious Parenthood 949 decision: God, themselves, their family, their society. Mention here of duties that one has to God, the spouses themselves, their family, and society indicates, I believe, that a pronatalist bias may be the default position: God, the spouses, the family, and society generally benefit from new life. Nonetheless there may certainly be times when a new life would make it difficult for spouses to fulfill their duties to God, their marriage, their family, and society. The principles here are very reminiscent of a passage from Love and Responsibility: Man is a rational being, and to aspire to the fullest possible participation of his consciousness in all that he does is consonant with his nature.This applies equally to the aspiration to become a mother or a father (no distinctions must be made here) with conscious intent. A man and a woman who have marital relations must know when and how they may become parents and regulate their sexual life accordingly. They have a responsibility for every conception, not only to themselves but also to the family which they are founding or increasing by that conception.”71 Man’s ability to think and choose is the source of his dignity; Wojtyla is simply saying that man’s power of thinking and choosing are rightly employed in considering what size family to have. Humanae Vitae also sounds the theme of the benefit that comes to the spouses from their consciousness of the procreative good and the efficacy in that consciousness of helping them overcome any tendencies to use each other.Wojtyla argues that conscious parenthood is a key to achieving self-mastery and that self-mastery is a key to conjugal love. Humanae Vitae 21 states: Right and worthy family planning requires that spouses recognize and value the true goods of life and the family, and also that they acquire the habit of complete mastery of themselves and their desires. It goes on to list benefits of attaining self-mastery: Truly, discipline of this sort—from which conjugal chastity shines forth—cannot be an obstacle to love. Rather, discipline imbues love with a deeper human meaning. Although [such control] requires continuous effort, it also helps the spouses become strong in virtue and makes them rich with spiritual goods.And this [virtue] fosters the fruits of tranquility and peace in the home and helps in the solving of difficulties of other 71 Love and Responsibility, 279. 950 Janet E. Smith kinds. It aids spouses in becoming more tender with each other and more attentive to each other. It assists them in dispelling that inordinate selflove that is opposed to true charity. It strengthens in them a consciousness of their responsibilities. And finally it provides parents with a sure and efficacious authority for educating their children. As [their] children advance through life they will come to a correct appreciation of the true goods of Man and employ peacefully and properly the powers of their mind and senses. In fact, it is easy to think that Wojtyla must have been the author of the above passage, it is so reminiscent of his thoughts about sexual morality. Veritatis Splendor provides a succinct formulation of a principle John Paul II enunciates throughout his work:“Although each individual has a right to be respected in his own journey in search of the truth, there exists a prior moral obligation, and a grave one at that, to seek the truth and to adhere to it once it is known.”72 In an essay written a few months after the promulgation of Humanae Vitae,Wojtyla wrote: Conjugal love must be fruitful love, that is, “directed toward parenthood”. Parenthood which comes from love between persons is “responsible parenthood”. One could say that in the Encyclical “Humanae vitae” responsible parenthood becomes the proper name for human procreation.73 In sum, the truth in respect to sexuality that is key for Wojtyla’s sexual morality is the truth that sex leads to parenthood.Those who are conscious of that fact can make moral choices in respect to their sexual behavior, for that consciousness leads them to achieve self-mastery, and those who have self-mastery choose better in respect to spouses—they are able to choose out of love rather than out of a troublesome sexual urge.Those who marry out of love will desire out of love to have babies, whom they love and whom God surely loves. And those who are conscious that they are cocreators with God will, as Wojtyla notes, become more conscious of their natural greatness. N&V 72 Veritatis Splendor, §34; cf., for instance, Evangelium Vitae, §19. 73 Wojtyla, “The Truth of the Encyclical Humanae Vitae,” 6. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 6, No. 4 (2008): 951–984 951 Book Reviews Light in Darkness: Hans Urs von Balthasar and the Catholic Doctrine of Christ’s Descent into Hell by Alyssa Lyra Pitstick (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans, 2007), xvi + 458 pp. A LYSSA LYRA P ITSTICK ’ S revised Angelicum dissertation on Balthasar’s theology of Christ’s descent into hell hardly needs introduction after her debate with the Jesuit Edward Oakes in First Things. Few newly minted doctors have garnered such attention in the theological community.Yet the international debate can easily move in one of two directions: either a polemical war focusing on claims of heresy or orthodoxy, or a much more serious dialogue that centers on how Balthasar’s key philosophical principles, biblical and patristic exegesis, and theological tools come together in his doctrine of the descent. The nature of Pitstick’s argumentation places us at this crossroads, whence Balthasar’s critics and defenders must choose a path. Perhaps the most disappointing part of the book is the author’s treatment of Scripture and the Fathers. She does not engage contemporary exegetical studies on the key biblical passages. Rather, she focuses on select patristic, medieval and magisterial commentators. She does not adequately acknowledge the immense exegetical difficulties surrounding 1 Peter 3:19 and 4:6. Her treatment of numerous Old Testament texts tends to focus on the allegorical meaning, with little attention given to the literal sense (for example, Hosea 13:14). Such a methodology would be hard to justify even in Thomistic exegesis, where the allegorical sense depends on the literal sense. Pitstick also hesitates to acknowledge a real diversity of interpretation among the Fathers. For St. Justin Martyr and St. Irenaeus, Christ’s descent into hell was an act of liberation for the deceased righteous persons of the Old Testament.1 For St. Clement of Alexandria and Origen, 1 Peter 1 Justin Martyr, Dialogue With Trypho 72; Irenaeus of Lyon, Against Heresies, 3.20.4, 4.22.1, 4.33.1, 4.33.12, 5.31.1. 952 Book Reviews 3:19 refers to Christ preaching to the deceased of Noah’s generation in order to convert them, preparing the way for universal salvation.2 For St. Augustine, it refers to the pre-existent Christ preaching to Noah’s contemporaries within their lifetimes, whereas the descent of Christ’s soul into hell was only for the liberation of the just.3 Pitstick hardly mentions this patristic debate. Rather, she concludes that “the traditional Catholic doctrine” presents Christ only descending to the limbo of the righteous. But it could be that Christ’s victory procession through the realm of the damned (without a final offer of conversion) is the very teaching of 1 Peter 3:19. None of the magisterial documents that Pitstick cites seem to exclude the latter interpretation proposed by some of the Fathers. Ironically, despite all of their differences, the Fathers agree that Christ’s descent was triumphant. By acknowledging this diversity, the author actually would have strengthened her case that Balthasar’s doctrine clashes with the Fathers on central points. For while they diverge significantly on the nature of Christ’s descent, none of them comes close to Balthasar’s vision. The book’s stronger arguments are found in part two, which presents her synthesis and analysis of Balthasar’s proposal. She consistently points to the absence of an adequate doctrine of analogy in Balthasar.This absence can be discerned in multiple theological themes, such as (1) Balthasar’s original vision of intra-Trinitarian life that remains inexplicable without three divine intellects and wills (115–24); (2) his tendency to collapse the immanent and economic Trinity (chapters 7–8); or (3) his perplexing exegesis of the Letter to the Philippians on the kenosis of the Son and the Father (148–51). Balthasar’s Barthian vision of kenosis seems to go handin-hand with voluntarist notions of obedience and freedom (150–52, 157–64, 212–13, 227–29, 238). She clearly shows Balthasar’s programmatic connection between the portrayal of Christ’s experience in hell and the portrayal of the inner life of the Trinity (chapters 6–8). She demonstrates the consequences of an event ontology replacing a substance ontology (chapter 7, esp. 154–55, 198–202, 214–15). For example, Balthasar appears to transform sin into a positive metaphysical reality, instead of the classical deficiency of being (122–23). She suggests that for Balthasar, Christ’s charity becomes virtually insignificant for the work of redemption, having been replaced by an ultra-juridical approach (109, 113). She points to Balthasar’s apparent willingness to dismiss key elements of the patristic and artistic traditions on the descent, not to mention the subtle yet immense 2 Clement of Alexandria, The Stromata, 6.6; Origen, On First Principles, 2.5.3; Cf. W. J. Dalton, Christ’s Proclamation to the Spirits:A Study of 1 Peter 3:18–4:6 (Rome: Pontifical Biblical Institute, 1965), 29–32. 3 Augustine of Hippo, Epistle to Evodius (Epistle 164), 21. Book Reviews 953 changes Balthasar introduces into various patristic doctrines (96–97, 113). Pitstick’s meticulous research also highlights many possible tensions within Balthasar’s own thought, such as inconsistencies in his theology of Redemption, where Christ’s suffering goes well beyond solidarity with sinners and can no longer be imitated by the saints (99–112, 253, 271). The author’s explicit intention is to deal with the doctrinal issues in Balthasar’s thought, not its sources.Yet one does wonder to what extent an archeological approach to the Swiss theologian might advance a doctrinal analysis. Pitstick hardly mentions two of Balthasar’s crucial sources: Adrienne von Speyr’s private revelations and Martin Luther’s doctrine of substitution. Granted, the key text on this topic from von Speyr remains virtually inaccessible. At the heart of his Holy Saturday teaching in Mysterium Paschale, Balthasar simply mentions in a teaser of a footnote: “On all this, A. von Speyr, Kreuz und Hölle (privately printed, Einsiedeln, 1966).“4 As Peter Casarella recently pointed out, von Speyr’s influence on Balthasar’s doctrine of the descent only increased in his later years.5 While the two colleagues undoubtedly influenced one another, von Speyr’s proper contribution to their collaboration also greatly influenced Balthasar’s portrayal of Christ’s experience on the Cross and the dramatic life of the Trinity, two doctrines that are closely connected to that of the descent. It would seem that the answer to the question, “where do these doctrines come from?” could be a tremendous help in pondering the question,“how tenable are these doctrines?” For example, Pitstick identifies the doctrine of quantitative atonement as a problematic premise in Balthasar. But is quantitative atonement simply the justification Balthasar uses for his excessive reliance on one aspect of von Speyr’s private revelations? Does the theology follow the visions, or at least seek its justification in their concreteness? Or does the theology shape the interpretation of the visions, which surely cannot be direct windows into Christ’s consciousness in hell that are easily translatable into human language? What is the determining factor behind Balthasar’s conclusions? The author concludes part two with a synthetic interpretation of Balthasar, showing the close connection between his theology of the descent and still other key doctrines, including creation, ecclesiology, eschatology, Mariology and especially soteriology.The difficulties she manifests in Balthasar’s Christology have ripple effects throughout his thought. Still, 4 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Mysterium Paschale, trans. by Aidan Nichols, O.P. (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2000), 185, fn 87. 5 In his paper “The Descent, Divine Self-Enrichment, and the Universality of Salvation,” presented at the conference “Love Alone Is Credible: Hans Urs Von Balthasar As Interpreter Of The Catholic Tradition,” April 14–17, 2005. 954 Book Reviews the greatest problems continue to be found in his Christology and Trinitarian theology. But the author’s evaluation of the Swiss theologian is more analytic than synthetic.Throughout the work, she interrupts her own skillful synthesis of Balthasar’s thought with very pointed critiques. At times, she seems to leave him little room to speak. In the end, her polemics set up an obstacle to a just evaluation of Balthasar’s thought. She does not show how some of his insights might at least highlight the ways in which Christology still needs to develop, even if Balthasar’s original proposal for such a development is not altogether successful. Does Balthasar really have nothing to teach us about Christ’s suffering and death? For example, while Balthasar’s vision of the Father’s radical abandonment of the Son on Good Friday and Holy Saturday seems to go too far, is it not too hasty of a judgment to propose Christ’s constant beatific vision in via as a settled teaching of “the tradition” (171), when in fact it was a scholastic consensus that followed a real diversity of patristic positions? Despite Aquinas’s insistence, it is not clear that Christ’s constant beatific vision is the necessary consequence of the Johannine Prologue, Ephesus, and Chalcedon, as no less an authority on medieval Christology as Jean-Pierre Torrell has pointed out.6 Could it be that a lower Christology which refuses some of Balthasar’s more adventurous speculations might present a more adequate account of the biblical witness as read through the great Christological dogmas? Was the communion that Christ’s human soul enjoyed with the Father during the Transfiguration essentially the same as during the Passion?7 Despite her disappointing treatment of Scripture and homogenous reading of the patristic tradition, Pitstick’s relentless critique demonstrates that Balthasar’s doctrine of Christ’s descent into hell is hard to reconcile with important elements of the liturgical, artistic, theological, and magisterial traditions, both eastern and western. Strangely, a more objective synthesis of Scripture and the Fathers would lend greater support to some of her critiques. 6 See his Le Christ en ses mystères: La vie et l’oeuvre de Jésus selon saint Thomas d’Aquin, vol. 1 (Paris: Desclée, 1999), 135–42; idem.,“Saint Thomas d’Aquin et la science du Christ : Une relecture des question 9–12 de la ‘Tertia Pars’ de la ‘Somme Théologie’,” in his Recherches Thomasiennes (Paris:Vrin, 2000), 198–213. 7 See the recent debate between Thomas Joseph White, O.P. and Thomas G. Weinandy, O.F.M. Cap.: White, “The Voluntary Action of the Earthly Christ and the Necessity of the Beatific Vision,” The Thomist 69 (2005): 497–534; Weinandy, “The Beatific Vision and the Incarnate Son: Furthering the Discussion,” The Thomist 70 (2006): 605–15. The best synthesis of Aquinas’s doctrine of Christ’s beatific vision during the Passion is found in Matthew Levering’s Christ’s Fulfillment of Temple and Torah: Salvation according to Thomas Aquinas (Notre Dame, 2002), 58–79. Book Reviews 955 One hopes that the Balthasarians will look past the author’s extreme polemics and recognize a serious, scholarly challenge to various aspects of their master’s overall theological method, not to mention his Trinitarian theology and Christology. A balanced, critical engagement with Balthasar by disciples and critics would move the discussion towards an increasingly fruitful and genuine theology of the Paschal Mystery. N&V Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland Resilience and the Virtue of Fortitude: Aquinas in Dialogue with the Psychosocial Sciences by Craig Steven Titus (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2006), xii + 411 pp. A BOOK of four hundred and seventy pages, with a plenitude of footnotes, synthesizing several disciplines, psychosocial science, philosophy, and theology is rather daunting and an excellent challenge for the reader (and this reviewer), Thomist or not. Fr. Benedict Ashley writes on the back cover that “I know of no other reading of Aquinas’s treatment of fortitude that is more thorough and nuanced.” He is certainly correct. Resilience is composed of three parts (ten chapters) all combining Aquinas’s virtue theory and resilience research. Part one looks to the issues of resilience as such in tandem with Thomas’s philosophy of the emotions and moral development. Part two examines more thoroughly the Thomistic vision of the virtue of fortitude and resilience from a more philosophical perspective. Finally, part three examines fortitude and resilience from a theological perspective, not excluding reason but seeing it from the point of view of revelation. The beginning of the book, Titus sets up the thematic he will be covering. Why is it that suffering, difficulties, failures, negative experiences become the stuff of growth or regress in the life of a person? What is constructive to one person becomes demoralizing to another. Chapter one takes up the question: what are the causes of either success at integration or disintegration of the human personality? Resilience as a word comes from steel’s ability to resist destruction. Psychosocial thinkers use the metaphor to study why and how certain people do not implode when faced with moral or physical challenges. After summarizing authors of the field too numerous to mention in this review,Titus gives a definition of resilience from their point of view: First, resilience is the ability to cope in adverse conditions; it either minimizes or overcomes hardships. Second, it consists in resisting 956 Book Reviews destructive pressures on the human person’s physiological, psychosocial and spiritual life; that is, it maintains capacities in the face of challenges, threats and loss. Third, resilience creatively constructs and adapts after adversity; it implies recovering with maturity, confidence, and wisdom to lead a meaningful and productive life. (29) In chapter two, again summarizing psychosocial thinkers,Titus shows that temperament, emotion, intelligence, family ties, religion, and the environmental factors surrounding a child all have a part to play in aiding or hindering resilience whether in extreme or ordinary cases of trials and difficulties of life. Chapter three is a summary review of the fundamental moral theology of St.Thomas: the ultimate end of human beings, human acts, the role of the emotions and virtue, human inclinations to good ends, grace and the presence of the Holy Spirit. Of course, this presupposes faith, but human experience is also involved in knowing about virtue and character formation. The psychological scientist’s studies and findings become a supplement to moral theology’s conclusions. Aquinas’s virtue theory especially enables one to understand the moral life far more deeply than a normdriven moral theology, which can lead people into moral minimalism. In part two,Titus attempts to integrate resilience studies with Aquinas’s treatment of the virtue of fortitude, which is both a general and a specific virtue. Resilience can resemble this virtue in many ways. As a general virtue, it looks to dealing with lesser difficulties of life and is a condition for all virtues; as a specific virtue, it is courage in the face of death and its attendant fears. He then gives a schematic calling magnanimity and magnificence the virtues of initiative taking, while calling the virtues of resisting the traditional patience, longanimity, perseverance, and constancy. In both cases, he goes on to show that the virtuous person needs strength of mind, affection and action in pursuing a just cause. From the field of psychosocial science the words used to describe fortitude are hardiness, dauntlessness, intrepidity, pluck, spirit, heroism, daring gallantry, bravery, valor, bravado, security, self-confidence, self-efficiency. The emotions opposed would be panic, phobia, rashness, recklessness, and indifference. Mastering future fears is the stuff of fortitude. Living by unreasonable fear produces laziness, shamefacedness, shame, amazement, stupor, and anxiety, all of which are explained by Titus. To overcome fear one needs to act with reasoned daring or patient endurance, the latter being the primary act of fortitude. However, experience and calm reflection, friendships and selfconfidence have very important roles to play in overcoming obstacles by the virtue of fortitude as well. Book Reviews 957 Chapter five analyzes Aquinas’s notions of magnanimity and magnificence in face of achieving great goods in all matters for self and great goods for others. Truly humble people need doses of these virtues lest they tumble into doing nothing but self-abasement (which Titus speaks about at length in chapter eight). It requires confident risk-taking, special concentration because the objectives are not easy. Later in the chapter,Titus brings out how the desire for great deeds revolves around the notion of honor and the desire to pursue excellence according to one’s capacities. In an interesting side-bar from psychosocial science, Titus summarizes some findings about optimists and pessimists in this section that aid in understanding success and failure at certain projects.Taking up Aquinas again,Titus shows how false hopes, presumption, despair, insecurity, and faintheartedness derail certain projects as well as the life of virtue itself. Likewise, vainglory, ambition, and false humility bring about over self-confidence, self-complacency, and ultimate failure in many ventures. In conclusion, resilience or true fortitude is needed to “build life in the face of difficulty, but also [to] face the difficulty of building.” One small criticism of this almost perfect book may be in order now. On page 190, he mistakenly puts the passion of hope in the concupiscible function of the sensible appetite whereas Thomas puts it as part of the irascible function. Chapter six leads the reader to consider the challenge of “staying power” when pain, suffering, loss, loneliness, and the many injustices of life come upon someone.The solution is learning how to cope with the onset of anxiety, torpor, apathy, and depression by means of the virtues of endurance: patience, perseverance, constancy, and longanimity.While these virtues are distinct, they come down to “holding fast” and not letting sorrow lead one to give up the challenge of virtue and more immediate tasks requiring long-term effort. Persisting firmly is not possible for persons given disproportionately to play, relaxation, and rest, because they cannot “endure toil.” While resilience researchers rarely use these terms from Aquinas, their solutions come close to his virtue theory and his solutions to dealing with sadness are also similar to resilience thinkers: reasonable pleasures, emotional venting, receiving sympathy from friends, contemplation of truth, and refreshment through sleep and baths. In part three, Titus looks at resilience and fortitude from a faith perspective, that is, seeing how grace and the theological virtues influence fortitude and resilience. In other word, what happens when God becomes involved in living out these virtues? Hence, the title for this last section is “Fortitude and Resilience Transcended.” Chapter seven makes clear that Titus accepts the Thomistic notion of infused cardinal virtues that come with grace.As he puts it:“Infused fortitude 958 Book Reviews does not make acquired fortitude redundant; nor does acquired fortitude make infused fortitude superfluous” (280). Rather infused fortitude brings a supernatural dimension to the natural virtue by giving it a motive, namely, the love of God, martyrdom being its most profound expression. The martyr does not commit suicide but rather chooses willingly to die for the truth of faith, that is, he loves Christ more than the good things of this life. Chapter eight returns to fortitude as endurance only this time, under grace that is, the human person imitates God and by grace collaborates with God in the face of fear or sorrow. That means that a person has to hope in self and yet “under God withal.” Magnanimity, a virtue of “greatness of spirit” in doing great works, looks to the greatness of grace to achieve a great work. As Titus knows, Christianity is not all pardon, love of enemies, and soft love, but also has a corrective here. This is not an egocentric virtue because it looks outward to others including God. And it mobilizes one to face risk and the challenges of possible failure by hope in divine assistance and not mere glory and honor from human beings. Chapter nine analyzes the Christian response to pain, suffering, and sorrow, which for Aquinas is patience and perseverance.Titus provides a Christological explanation of these virtues, as Jesus showed humans how to endure what is impossible to accomplish by human efforts alone. Suffering becomes the occasion of patience which endures, though at times one must also strike out against certain evils.This of course requires prudence to know when to turn the other cheek and when to attack. Titus calls it “intelligent” patience. Chapter ten summarizes his findings and offers a neat and tidy synthesis of his work. My only quibble with his masterpiece is that from chapter six until the end of the book, he at times seems to conflate the infused cardinal virtue of fortitude with the gift of the Holy Spirit called fortitude.The two gifts are distinguishable. He says as much on pages 291–92.The infused virtue enables the person to organize his or her actions for the glory of God under reason and faith’s tutelage, which spiritual theologians will call the human mode. The gift of the fortitude, on the other hand, is an impulse/inspiration directly under the Holy Spirit which goes beyond reason and enables one to do a heroic act of virtue in the divine mode. This was the reason why Thomas insists that these seven gifts of the Holy Spirit are necessary for salvation, because we sometimes face impossible situations requiring more than reason and human effort can understand and accomplish (cf. ST I–II, q. 68, aa. 1–8). The excellence of the scholarship and the brilliance of exposition will make this book a certain read for many years to come. He is to be Book Reviews 959 congratulated for his own work of resilience and magnanimity in writN&V ing such a tome. Basil Cole, O.P. The Pontifical Faculty at the Dominican House of Studies Washington, DC The Soul of the Person: A Contemporary Philosophical Psychology by Adrian J. Reimers (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2006), 301 pp. A DRIAN R EIMERS begins with a familiar story: materialists argue that matter and the laws of its interaction are all there is; most especially, what tradition has called the “soul” is nothing more than the visible effects of the brain,“a physical system different from other physical systems only in its degree of complexity” (9). Reimers, drawing on Aristotle and Aquinas, John Paul II, Charles Sanders Peirce, and sympathetic Anglo-American philosophers like David Braine, responds in The Soul of the Person with a contemporary reformulation of human nature as both material and spiritual. He hopes thereby to defeat rival materialist accounts (as well as, though they are not the main target, dualist accounts) and reveal the essential spiritual characteristics of the human person. According to Reimers, our distorted contemporary pictures of the physical and the spiritual hinder our abilities both to understand and to accept a classical hylomorphic account of the human person. Therefore, after an introductory chapter, chapters two and three work to give us a clearer picture of what we ought to mean by the material and the spiritual, preparing the way for understanding human nature as involving both. Chapters four and five focus on the two most important powers of the human person, our powers to know and to strive for the good, arguing that their exercise both requires matter and transcends it. Finally, chapter six focuses on the metaphysical grounds of what has gone before, and a short epilogue offers a few thoughts on the afterlife. For Reimers, the material is most properly characterized in terms of pure reactivity (61): “In virtue simply of a thing’s being material, all we can say is that it has, at some place and time, interacted with something else” (47). But a material thing is also one sort of existing thing, and “the existence of things,” wrote Peirce, “consists in their regular behavior” (46).Again drawing on Peirce, a habit is “any regular behavior of a thing” (49). Therefore we can say that the existence of material things consists in their habits, their regular behavior. This regular behavior is what we mean by “essence,” and is reflected in scientific laws and classifications 960 Book Reviews that bring under the same name material things that manifest the same behavior. In understanding material things as law-governed (and therefore having essences), we have already gone beyond the crudely material, but not in a way particularly helpful for belief in the human soul. Indeed, materialism claims that the existence (regular behavior) of all things is explicable by the sorts of laws that explain material things; such laws, reflecting the pure reactivity of material things, govern objects deterministically and, at least in principle, predictably. It will be Reimers’s argument that human beings transcend the reactivity of materiality through the free and creative development of their habits, leaving at least a part of human nature ungoverned by the deterministic laws that govern purely material beings. To be spiritual, on the other hand, “is to be governed by ideal, rather than material (or physical) factors.” And ideal means “some sort of desirable future state, condition, or value that guides [i.e. governs] the actions of those who adopt it” (64). As opposed to the pure reactivity of the material, the spiritual sees and pursues what is not itself present (what is in the future and thus itself purely mental, that is, spiritual), whose identification and pursuit therefore transcend mere physical reactivity. Such activity depends on “two further, fundamental concepts: goodness (or the good) and truth (or the true)” (66).What is spiritual pursues a particular future goal (and therefore sees it as good) and must consider this goal as realizable (as possibly true).The spiritual consists in being related to truth and goodness, and this relatedness in turn reveals spiritual aspects of reality that transcend pure reactivity and physical laws. Reimers now turns to human nature as embodied spirituality, focusing first on our power to know. Knowledge requires belief, and for Reimers “a belief is a disposition of mind toward action. . . . One holds a belief to the degree that one is prepared to act in a certain way, according to the belief ” (96).As such, beliefs are necessarily ordered to truth, for only if the belief corresponds with reality will the knower succeed in acting upon it. Although Reimers then outlines a variety of embodied spiritual activities found in perception, practical work, and reasoning, the central spiritual activity of human beings is our ability to hypothesize (131). In hypothetical reasoning, we transcend mere reactivity (represented here by deductive reasoning) by leaping to a new creative hypothesis not entailed by any previous experience. Most importantly, the act of asserting the truth of any proposition is itself a form of hypothetical reasoning and goes beyond material reactivity, for “the ability to assert the truth requires more than the bare mechanisms of material interaction. By asserting truth one joins to his naturally conditioned experience the general conception of the Book Reviews 961 intellect and unifies these in an existential affirmation, one not compelled by strict deductive [or, we might say, reactive] necessity” (135). In human pursuit of the good we notice first that human actions are not determined by our appetites but instead are a result of free choices among appetites.This is possible because we not only pursue goods, but pursue them as good and therefore as tending towards the ultimate or highest good. Further, among the basic human goods towards which we are attracted and among which we choose is the good of truth, and, as we saw above, truth is a spiritual good. But if there is at least one nonmaterial good, there might be others. Further, the criteria we use to choose between material and spiritual goods in our lives cannot themselves be material: “Human beings value truth, and that means that some spiritual condition or relationship is a value. If this is so, then the criteria in virtue of which values may be judged to be authentic goods must refer to the spiritual as well as the material, for truth is a condition of the human intellect, not of the body” (197). Finally, Reimers argues that the ontological foundations of the spiritual pursuit of truth and goodness consist in the freedom of human choice and the ideal (and so immaterial) character of human knowing. Reimers argues that human beings are free, and therefore transcend reactive materiality, since they universally experience themselves as freely able to act in this way or that, no law-like (and therefore repeatable) prediction of a meaningful human choice has ever successfully been made, and history has revealed as (often violent) failures all previous attempts to control human behavior as mechanically predictable (228–41). When we consider human knowing, we see that hypothetical reasoning, assertions of truth (or falsehood), and the mental ideals that make knowing and willing possible all go beyond pure reactivity and therefore beyond the material. Reimers now concludes that, since human beings are rational and rationality (consisting in the recognition and pursuit of truth and goodness) cannot be reduced to a mechanical operation, human nature must possess an immaterial principle of some sort, and this we call the soul.With respect to the afterlife, Reimer’s notes only that “the human being . . . has a soul that enjoys a certain superiority to or transcendence with regard to the material. It is not unreasonable to grant that this soul can survive the dissolution of the body” (277). What the “experience” of such a disembodied soul might be, we can only guess.We go beyond this only with Revelation. The Soul of the Person is both a rereading of traditional hylomorphism and an argument against modern materialists. As a rereading, it is often insightful and inspiring, offering a number of interesting ways to think about traditional concepts. The defense and explanation of hypothetical 962 Book Reviews reasoning is Reimers’s account of abstraction, and the language of “ideas” and “ideal” rework “form” and “concept.” His use of contemporary examples and arguments (Gödel and Turing, for instance) make it clear that Thomistic hylomorphism can be a powerful contemporary position. On the other hand, it occasionally isn’t clear that Reimers is rereading rather than rejecting. For example, he insists that every human action is bodily and physical (91, 111). But Thomistic Aristotelianism has traditionally considered some operations of the human intellect as dependant upon, but not themselves consisting in, physical activity. If the human soul can be active after death, as Reimers thinks is possible, wouldn’t he also require the possibility of such operations? As an argument against modern materialists, The Soul of the Person is less successful. The foundations of Reimers’s arguments are human freedom and the immaterial character of human knowing, and the materialist will attack both. Here is one possible line against Reimers’s defense of human freedom: Reimers argues that we must be free because freedom coincides with our phenomenological experience and has not been demonstrated false by science or political manipulation (I am leaving out a bit of the argument. While discussing our experience, he also suggests as a “very important” argument against determinism that it is theoretically impossible for me to predict what I shall do in the future; but he refers here to Alasdair MacIntyre’s similar argument in After Virtue, either forgetting or ignoring that MacIntyre ends his discussion of the unpredictability of human behavior by asserting that it is perfectly compatible with a strong version of determinism). The determinist, of course, grants Reimers’s points, but will respond that they do not decide the issue since they neither entail nor exclude either side of the debate.We must consider a wider range of information (perhaps our Modern Scientific Understanding of the World) that, they will say, turns out to favor determinism.The same strategy will be used to respond to the spiritual character of human knowing: it depends on immaterial essences discovered by the human intellect, and while it might seem in experience that there are such things, in truth there aren’t. In short, Reimers’s arguments state clearly and forcefully how reality appears to us, but the materialist rejects such appearances as illusory. But if Reimers’s arguments are less conclusive than he often seems to think, they suggest that the burden of proof lies with the materialist. It is up to the materialist to offer convincing arguments that our experience and common sense are wrong, and in the absence of such arguments, we ought to accept the sorts of considerations Reimers brings forward.The proof that the Thomistic position is, in the end, correct, will consist not only in the forceful presentation of its interpretation of reality (what Reimers has Book Reviews 963 done), but also in the sustained engagement and refutation from the Thomistic perspective of the particular rival arguments. And although Reimers has not done the latter, The Soul of the Person, as a contemporary N&V restatement of the Thomistic position, helps make it possible. Raymond Hain University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana Trinity, Church and the Human Person: Thomistic Essays by Gilles Emery, O.P. (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2007), xxii + 303 pp. T RINITY, Church and the Human Person offers an excellent opportunity for English-speaking readers to be exposed to one of the finest students of the theology of Thomas Aquinas—Gilles Emery, O.P. This book contains ten essays (previously written in French) that are grouped around three themes: (1) the trinitarian theology of Aquinas, (2) the sacraments, Church and human person and (3) reception of Thomas’s teaching on the mystery of God. The resurgence of interest in the Trinity, with its emphasis upon the “practicality” of this doctrine, raises a host of questions regarding the purpose(s) of trinitarian reflection. In chapter one, Emery explores the purpose of “speculative” trinitarian reflection in Thomas’s theology.That Thomas’s trinitarian theology is “speculative” does not mean that it is divorced from the economy of salvation.Thomas is clear that knowledge of the divine persons is necessary to understand the gospel. Moreover, the trinitarian treatise in the Summa reaches its climax in a discussion of the economic missions.To understand rightly the purpose of his “speculative” reflection, one must grasp Thomas’s intent. Unlike some medieval theologians, his goal was not to establish the necessity of the Trinity apart from Scripture. By reflecting on “processions,”“relations,” and “persons,”Thomas wants to show that Christian teaching on the Trinity is reasonable and that attacks against trinitarian faith can be refuted. In addition, he wants to invite the faithful into a “spiritual exercise” by which they may contemplate the triune God as a foretaste of the beatific vision. Several scholars have suggested that significant differences exist between Augustine and Thomas regarding the goal of their trinitarian reflection.Whereas Augustine presents his trinitarian theology as a spiritual exercise, Thomas engages in a speculative intellectual project. In chapter two, Emery contests this claim by arguing that important continuities exist between Augustine and Thomas regarding the purpose(s) of their trinitarian reflection. Augustine’s approach in De Trinitate may be 964 Book Reviews characterized as an “exercise of the mind” designed to reveal to the soul, albeit in a limited way, something of the mystery of the triune God. Although important differences exist in their manner of presentation, Emery argues that “[t]he speculative objective of Thomas Aquinas in Trinitarian theology must not be opposed to the spiritual objective of Augustine” (71). Like Augustine, Thomas is quite circumspect about human knowledge of the Trinity: although humans can grasp that God is, they cannot grasp what God is. Moreover, for Thomas,“Speculative Trinitarian theology constitutes an exercise, an elevation of the believing mind, a training in order to see the simple and incomprehensible Triune God, which procures a foretaste of the beatific vision and makes it possible to give an account of the Trinitarian faith” (72). In chapter three, Emery argues that a direct (and complex) relationship exists between Thomas’s teaching on truth and his doctrine of the Trinity—both on the intra-trinitarian and economic levels.This chapter is structured around an analysis of the Son as “Truth” and the Holy Spirit as “Spirit of Truth.” Because truth involves a relationship to the intellect, it “bears an affinity with the intellectual process that characterizes the generation of the Son as Word conceived by the Father” (76, italics original). Thus, the Word is “Truth begotten.” Moreover, as the “Light” and “Truth” of the Father, the Word reveals the Father internally to himself and externally to the world (especially through the incarnation). Finally, the Word is the source of truth “through whom all things are true and by whom truth is communicated to the minds of creatures” (89).There are at least three reasons Thomas associates the Holy Spirit with truth. First, the Spirit is “Truth” inasmuch as the Spirit is God. Second, the Scriptures present the Spirit as the “Spirit of Truth” because he proceeds from the Word, who is Truth. Third, the Spirit is rightly called “Spirit of Truth” based on his economic work of revealing truth to human beings. Scholars sometimes fail to recognize the “profound Trinitarian dimensions” of Thomas’s teaching on truth because they do not to engage his commentaries alongside his philosophical discussions of truth (114). “Western” trinitarian theology, with Thomas Aquinas as a key representative, is sometimes criticized for failing to affirm the “personal” dimension of the actions of the divine persons. In chapter four, Emery explores the “personal mode of trinitarian action” in Thomas’s theology. Emery argues that alongside his insistence that the divine persons act with one will,Thomas “clearly maintains a relational mode of acting of each person, a proper and distinct mode that consists in the personal intraTrinitarian relationship qualifying intrinsically the act of the Father, Son and Holy Spirit” (152–53, italics original). A clear example can be seen Book Reviews 965 in Thomas’s claim that the trinitarian processions are the “cause and reason” for the production of creatures. The processions shape divine action:“the Father acts through the Son whom he begets and in the Holy Spirit whom he spirates with the Son” (126).The Father acts “through” the Son because the Son is begotten by the Father. While the effects of Father and Son are one, the actors are “personally distinct and their mode of action is also distinct” (132). In addition, because salvation for Thomas involves receiving the divine persons, human beings are, through grace, able “to enter into relation with each person in particular, that is to say, each person apprehended in a proper and distinct way” (153). In chapter five, Emery argues that a “profound connection” exists for Thomas between Church and Eucharist. An ecclesial dimension can be found in all three levels of the sacrament (the sign, the intermediate reality which is a sign and first effect, and the grace effected and signified in the sacrament).The bread and wine signify not only the unity of Christ and the Church but they also bring about this unity “by intensifying man’s union with Christ and the mutual union of members” (161). Another link between Eucharist and Church can be seen in Thomas’s theology of forgiveness. The Eucharist not only offers spiritual food for growth but it also “contains within itself a reconciling power” by virtue of the death of Christ (167). Although penance is required for full participation, the Eucharist can bring about the forgiveness of “light” sins (168). Finally, an ecclesial dimension of the Eucharist can be seen in its eschatological character: like all sacraments, it looks to the past (Christ’s passion and resurrection), present (procuring grace) and future (anticipating the ultimate fulfillment of that which they signify). Whereas medieval theologians treat “inner penance” as the res et sacramentum of the sacrament of penance, contemporary theologians tend to treat reconciliation with the church as the res et sacramentum. In chapter six, Emery suggests that Thomas’s discussion of “inner penance” provides a helpful structure for considering the relationship between “reconciliation with God” and “reconciliation with the church.” For Thomas the res et sacramentum is the “inner penance” of the sinner while the res tantum is the remission of sins.Thus, the sacrament is constituted both by the actions of the priest (sacramental absolution) as well as the penitent (contrition) such that no forgiveness is possible apart from a heart-conversion on the part of the penitent. Emery insists that Thomas’s account of penance in no way marginalizes the Church. Penance reconciles people both to God and to the Church. Moreover, it is required for inclusion in the Eucharist. Thomas, therefore, invites theologians to recognize the res et sacramentum of penance “as a personal engagement (‘inner penance’) grasped in the 966 Book Reviews ecclesial action and recognized and ratified by the Church, so that it implies readmission to the public worship of the Church” (192). While some view Thomas’s theology as a foundation for conversation with the East, others view his theology as an impediment to dialogue. Chapter seven contains a brief discussion of Thomas’s engagement with Greek-speaking theologians of the East:“In a conscious and explicit way, St.Thomas does not intend to compose only a Latin theology, but a Christian ‘ecumenical’ theology . . . which would fully integrate the contribution of the Eastern Fathers into the heart of the Catholic patrimony” (195).The four Greek authors Thomas cities most frequently (in descending order) are St. John Chrysostom (who appears frequently in his exegetical works), Pseudo-Dionysus (a Platonic influence upon Thomas), Origen (whom Thomas receives in a critical way) and St. John Damascene. Emery identifies three areas in which the influence of Greek Fathers upon Thomas can be clearly seen: (1) Thomas’s concept of “instrument” in his Christology (in which the humanity of Christ constitutes the “instrumental efficient cause” of grace, forgiveness of sins and divinization of human beings); (2) his description of the hypostatic union in the Summa theologiae, and (3) his account of the “literal senses” (plural) of Scripture. The idea that human beings possess an incorruptible “soul” has come under criticism because of the assumption that this view is inextricably linked to a “dualistic” anthropology and Cartesian rationalism.Wanting to affirm the fundamental unity of the human person, a number of theologians have become reluctant to discuss the soul. Is there a way to affirm that humans are a composite of body and soul while still maintaining the indissoluble unity of the person? In chapter eight, Emery suggests that Thomas’s theology provides the basis for a “deeply unified understanding of man that sacrifices neither the essential link between soul and body nor the primacy of the spiritual soul in man” (210). Thomas articulates a “hylomorphic” account of the unity of the human person that is incompatible with every form of dualism. For Thomas, a person is neither the soul (contra Plato) nor the body but a composite of the two. Thus, the soul is not a separate substance but a “subsistent form” or “subsistent principle.” By identifying the soul as “substantial form” of the body,Thomas secures the unity of the body (216). In the eschaton, human beings will exist in a composite of soul and body (which is required for the attainment of happiness). In chapter nine, Emery explores the interrelationship of evil and the mystery of God in the writings of Charles Journet. Although he builds upon the “classic”Thomistic explanation, Journet departs from the latter at three crucial points: his explanation of God’s knowledge of sin, his account of the divine decree by which sin is permitted, and his notion of divine suffering. Book Reviews 967 Journet does not view God’s permissive decree as the means through which God knows about sin in his creatures. For Journet, God knows sin “only in the culpable will that has refused the divine motion to the good and not in the intervention of divine decree” (245, italics original). Moreover, although Journet believes that evil must be explained in terms of divine “permission,” he rejects the Thomistic notion of God’s “antecedent permissive decree” because it does not allow for adequate dissymmetry between God’s relationship to good and God’s relationship to evil. The permissive decree, therefore, should not be viewed as “antecedent” but should rather be seen as following upon “the evil will’s nihilation of the shatterable motion” (247). Finally, Journet moves beyond traditional Thomistic approaches to evil in his discussion of “suffering” in God by affirming a kind of “quasi-suffering” in God (255). At the end of the chapter, Emery raises a number of questions regarding the viability of Journet’s proposal. In chapter ten, Emery engages George Lindbeck’s “postliberal” reading of Thomas Aquinas. Lindbeck developed his “cultural-linguistic” approach to doctrine in conversation Thomas (who is one of the most frequently citied theologians in The Nature of Doctrine). After providing an overview of the Lindbeck’s writings on Thomas, Emery examines Lindbeck’s appeal to Thomas in The Nature of Doctrine. Appeals to Thomas can be grouped into three categories: (1) Religion and experience (Lindbeck draws both upon Thomas’s account of knowledge by “connaturality” as well the Scholastic distinction between “first intentions” and “second intentions”); (2) Thomas as “Non-Foundationalist” (Lindbeck appeals extensively to Thomas in order to criticize post-Cartesian and post-Kantian “foundational” projects); and (3) “Agnosticism” of Thomas and Truth (Lindbeck draws upon Thomas’s distinction between the “mode of signification” and the “thing signified” in order to prioritize the “regulative” function of doctrines over the “cognitive” function).Although the primary purpose of the chapter was to highlight the originality of Lindbeck’s reading of Thomas, Emery briefly identifies a number of problems with Lindbeck’s reading. For example, little support can be found in Thomas’s writings for the notion that creedal statements should be viewed merely as secondorder “rules.” For Thomas, doctrines have “regulative” force precisely because they convey “cognitive propositional content” (288). This collection of essays offers an indirect (yet compelling!) apologetic for the continuing value of engagement with Thomas’s theology. Emery helps readers see how the “premodern” theology of Thomas Aquinas addresses a number of contemporary theological issues in fruitful ways. A clear example of this can be seen in his discussion of the nature of the human person (chapter eight). Emery adroitly shows how Thomas’s hylomorphic account 968 Book Reviews of human unity avoids the pitfalls of dualism and materialism. Another example can be seen in chapter seven in which Emery presents Thomas as the source of an “ecumenical” theology that integrates contributions of the West and the East. Perhaps the most compelling case for the enduring value of Thomas’s theology can be seen in Emery’s discussion of Thomas’s trinitarian doctrine (which build upon an earlier collection of essays published in Trinity in Aquinas). Critics such as Catherine LaCugna assert that Thomas’s “speculative” reflection on the Trinity exemplifies everything that went wrong in “Latin”Trinitarian theology inasmuch as he severs the life of the triune God from the economy of salvation. Emery not only shows why this reading is wrong but he also helps readers see that Thomas has an important message for theologians eager to highlight the practical relevance of trinitarian doctrine—namely, that the “practicality” of this doctrine is not ultimately to be found in its ability to provide patterns for societal structures but rather in its ability to draw us into the life of the triune God. In the first volume of his Church Dogmatics, Karl Barth insists that the doctrine of the Trinity should be “decisive and controlling for the whole of dogmatics.” Barth was not the first to recognize that trinitarian doctrine should shape theological reflection in other areas.Through his discussion of Trinity and truth, Emery provides a concrete example of the integrative nature of Thomas’s trinitarian theology by examining Thomas’s trinitarian approach to the truth. Emery’s discussion of trinitarian agency in chapter four is particularly important for contemporary discussion of divine agency. Eager to highlight the “personal” character of trinitarian action, a number of contemporary theologians have expressed dissatisfaction with the traditional Augustinian account of the unity of the divine persons ad extra. Emery helps us see that one need not abandon this axiom in order to affirm the “personal” character of trinitarian agency. Readers will discover little criticism of Thomas in this book. Perhaps some will view this as a limiting feature; however, it is Emery’s sympathy with Thomas’s thought that provides the basis for his rich exposition.While this collection of essays encourages engagement with Thomas, it also underscores the challenge contemporary readers have in properly understanding Thomas.To understand Thomas, readers must synchronically engage all his writings (not an easy task!). In particular, Emery suggests that scholars need to pay more attention to Thomas’s biblical commentaries as they engage his speculative theological/philosophical writings. N&V Keith E. Johnson Duke University Durham, North Carolina Book Reviews 969 God’s Universe by Owen Gingerich (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006), 139 pp. and Chance or Purpose? Creation, Evolution, and a Rational Faith by Christoph Cardinal Schönborn, O.P. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2007), 181 pp. O N N OVEMBER 7, 1492, just before noon, a meteorite fell on farmland near the Alsatian village of Ensisheim.Three weeks later, the Holy Roman Emperor Maximilian happened to be passing through Alsace, then a part of his empire, and so came to hear of this strange visitor from the heavens.After consulting with the experts of his day, he was told by his imperial counselors and court astrologers that it was a miracle, a sign from God indicating divine favor resting on the imperial crown. On February 8, 1969, another meteorite fell, this time on the Mexican village of Pueblito de Allende. No emperor, Mexican or otherwise, happened to be passing through at the time. But experts galore (now called scientists, not astrologers) descended on the place soon enough; and what they discovered was remarkable: the ratio of lead and argon isotopes, when matched with the known rate of decay of radioactive potassium, allows the meteorite to be dated to an age of 4.6 billion years, which means that the Allende meteorite is the oldest known macroscopic object on earth, indeed by most estimates is slightly older than the earth itself. Both meteorites are raw facts: the exact dates of their respective falls are known to history, and both objects are still being exhibited to this day. But both are also what Aristotle called reasoned facts, and therein hangs our tale. As a “reasoned” fact, the first rock was taken to be an omen favorable to the Holy Roman Emperor, the other as evidence for the genesis and composition of our solar system (and, going back further, of the universe itself). Two meteorites, then: leaving us with two raw facts, and two reasoned facts. The universe, too, is a raw fact, at least in the obvious sense that it cannot very well be ignored. But is it also a reasoned fact? After all, if we try to reason back from the universe to God, the validity of the procedure will depend on how genuinely reasonable the “fact” of the universe is. But why work backwards? Why not just start with the reality of God and then deduce the universe from God, as René Descartes tried to do? But if one agrees with Thomas Aquinas that we must work backwards from the world to God, then we have no choice but to proceed from the raw reality we know (the world) to the reasoned reality behind it, which we hope (and maybe can “prove”?) is God. But what kind of reasoned fact is the universe? Is the world actually rational, or do we impose rationality on it? Two recent books, one from 970 Book Reviews a noted historian of astronomy at Harvard University, Owen Gingerich, and the other from the Cardinal Archbishop of Vienna (and chairman of the drafting committee of the Catechism of the Catholic Church ), Christoph Schönborn, tell us a great deal about how we go from Aristotle’s “reasoned facts” to the reality of God, without whom the universe would never have come to be in the first place. Both books are quite short and can be read in an evening apiece.Yet both come out of a lifetime of reflections on this issue, albeit from two different perspectives: while both authors are committed Christians, one is a scientist and historian of science by training and profession, and the other is a teacher of the Catholic faith, speaking out of, and on the basis of, the oracles of Christian revelation, especially here the book of Genesis. For several reasons, I think it best to begin with Gingerich’s book, which began as the William Belden Noble Lectures at Harvard’s University Chapel in 2005. I recommend starting with his book because, by taking them in this order, one can follow the approach recommended by the great twentieth-century apologist Msgr. Ronald Knox, who held that if we begin with certain universally recognized enigmas, we will see the meaning of Christian dogma. Knox pointed out that before we hear of the mystery of the Trinity and Incarnation we first meet up with the mystery of personality; before we learn about the mystery of the Real Presence of Jesus in the Eucharist we come up against the distinction between reality and appearance in Plato; and before the mystery of the Holy Spirit there is the mystery of mind: “You may picture human thought as a place of solid rock,” he says, “but with a crevice here and there—the places, I mean, where we think and think and it just does not add up. And the Christian mysteries are like tufts of blossom which seem to grow in those particular crevices, there and nowhere else.” In that sense, Gingerich gives us the crevice, Schönborn the blossom. For Gingerich there is above all this ineluctable crevice—teleology : is there a point to the universe or not? Is the universe just a brute fact to be accepted without further ado? Or is it a reasoned fact that can lead, via its correct interpretation, back to God’s intentions? Gingerich’s Harvard colleague Ernst Mayr, probably the premier philosopher of Darwinism in the twentieth century, provides the debate’s opening thesis: “Cosmic teleology must be rejected by science. . . . I do not think there is a modern scientist left who still believes in it.” Maybe, but there are many scientists who think there might be intelligent life on other planets and have great hopes that the search for extraterrestrial intelligence (SETI) will someday prove successful. But these SETI enthusiasts then hit a snag: the very viability of that search rests on Book Reviews 971 the plausibility of the same cosmic teleology decried by Mayr. As Gingerich points out,“astronomers and physicists who assume that extraterrestrial intelligence is inevitable and ubiquitous are essentially saying that the set is rigged, that in some way it is designed not just to allow for intelligent life, but to make it likely.” According to physicist Paul Davies, SETI “implies that mind is written into the laws of nature in a fundamental way.” But if that is true, what has happened to the randomness touted so loudly by the resolute Darwinians? If intelligence is “written into” the laws of nature so deeply, are we not approaching Plato’s most characteristic teaching that form and mind precede matter? To that worrisome flirtation with crypto-Platonism Darwinians of the strict observance like Mayr respond that SETI proponents “are almost exclusively astronomers, physicists, and engineers. They are simply unaware of the fact that the success of the SETI project is not a matter of physical laws and engineering capabilities but a matter of biological and sociological factors.” So who’s right, Davies or Mayr? Absent the unlikely event of alien visitors to the UN General Assembly, the issue cannot be resolved. Physicists (as a rule) might set much store by SETI, but their methods are reductive. Always fond of the Copernican “principle of mediocrity” (which states that because of the uniformity of the laws of nature, man and earth cannot be that special), they seek the most parsimonious result: “Physicists love the principles of uniformity and mediocrity, for they reduce complexity and tend toward simplicity, a process that helps them get on with their business,” says Gingerich. “If friction renders the study of motion too difficult, then consider an idealized world without friction. . . . Isaac Newton made brilliant progress by assuming that celestial motions are frictionless counterparts of terrestrial motion.” Biologists, however, are schooled to see contingency everywhere.Take, for example, man’s bipedalism, which the anthropologist Richard Leakey holds is essential for the evolution from primate to Homo sapiens. In The Origin of Mankind he claims that the “origin of bipedal locomotion is so significant an adaptation that we are justified in calling all species of bipedal ape ‘human.’ . . .These humans were not like us, but without the bipedal adaptation they couldn’t have become like us.” But how did bipedalism become so advantageous to one group of primates? Here at any rate is Leakey’s answer: About 12 million years ago, a continuation of tectonic forces further changed the environment, with the formation of a long, sinuous valley [in central Africa], running from north to south, known as the Great 972 Book Reviews Rift Valley.The existence of the Great Rift Valley has had two biological effects: it poses a formidable east-west barrier to animal populations, and it further promotes the development of a rich mosaic of ecological conditions. The French anthropologist Yves Coppens believes the east-west barrier was crucial to the separate evolution of human and apes . . . [and] dubs this the “East Side Story.” Well, maybe yes, maybe no. But if Leakey is right, then as Daniel Dennett points out in Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, searching for alien intelligence makes about as much sense as searching for extraterrestrial kangaroos. Again, none of these purely speculative arguments can settle this issue. But their continuing presence in the debate over evolution (touted by people who have no religious agenda whatever and often are extremely hostile to religion in any guise) only shows, at least for Gingerich, that we are up against a real enigma, one of Knox’s crevices. On that basis he has some surprisingly friendly (though critical) remarks to make about the Intelligent Design (ID) movement. First, he rightly defends them against the charge of their being “creationists,” if by that is meant young-earth creationists who hold that the entire world is scarcely more than ten thousand years old. “ID theorists are much more sophisticated than that,” he says. “At issue for them is whether random mutations can generate the incredible amount of information content required to produce even the simplest of cells; and whether even the great antiquity of the universe could make this possible. Here science, dealing with extremely low probabilities balanced against vast numbers of opportunities, is frankly on very shaky turf.” That paragraph alone will probably lead most strict-observance Darwinians to dismiss this book in horror, but Gingerich is merely pointing to a problem that will not go away, despite the angry harumphing and empty rhetorical excommunications from atheist citadels. That said, Gingerich must also point to the central flaw in ID theory, its scientific sterility: Many leading theorists of ID argue that the evidence for intelligent input into the evolutionary process is overwhelming. With regard to final causes, those theorists make a good case for a coherent understanding of the nature of cosmos. But they fall short in supplying any mechanisms to serve as the efficient causes that primarily engage scientists in our age. Intelligent Design does not explain the temporal or geological distribution of species. Intelligent Design does not help us understand why Hawaii, in comparison with the older continental areas, has so few species, and why there would be flightless birds on the islands. It does not shed any light on why the DNA in yeast is so closely related to the DNA in human chromosomes. As a philosophical idea, Book Reviews 973 ID is interesting, but it does not replace the scientific explanations that evolution offers. So how does Gingerich, himself a committed Christian, respond to this dilemma? I think this passage summarizes his own personal creed as a Christian scientist best of all (emphases are his): Whether the mutations are anything other than mathematically random is a question without answer in a physical or scientific sense. But my subjective, metaphysical view, that the universe would make more sense if a divine will operated at this level to design the universe in a purposeful way, can be neither denied nor proved by scientific means. . . . One can believe that some of the evolutionary pathways are so intricate and so complex as to be hopelessly improbable by the rules of random chance; but if you do not believe in divine action, then you will simply have to say that random chance was extremely lucky, because the outcome is there to see. Either way, the scientist with theistic metaphysics will approach laboratory problems in much the same way as will his atheistic colleague across the hall. And probably both will approach some of the astonishing adaptations seen in nature with a sense of surprise, wonder, and mystery. Gingerich readily admits that only faith can make this transition (or “leap” if you will), a faith that has guided his own life from childhood on. The fact that few of his colleagues at Harvard are willing to follow him here does not intimidate him in the least, for this he knows above all: “The God having the creative force to make the entire observable universe in a dense dot of pure energy is incomprehensible, beyond human imagining (apart from the comparatively feeble efforts of theorists exploring the inner workings of the Big Bang). And yet we can see the consequences of this unimaginably powerful creative act: a universe congenial to the ultimate formation of life, life giving rise to intelligence that can ask questions science cannot answer. It is God’s universe.” It is God’s universe for Cardinal Schönborn too, I presume it goes without saying; but with his latest book Chance or Purpose? Creation, Evolution, and a Rational Faith, readers enter a quite different universe of argument. First of all, as might be expected, Schönborn writes as a teacher of the Catholic faith.True, he is not addressing the public in the strictly magisterial sense, telling Catholics what they must hold by solemn hierarchical decree. But surely what he asserts, that the universe is God’s creation, must belong to the essence of the Christian faith, as the opening line of the Apostles’ and Nicene Creeds profess. Second, Schönborn is entirely biblical throughout this book. In effect, he is giving an extended meditation on the meaning of several verses of 974 Book Reviews the Bible that bear on evolutionary controversies:“In the beginning, God created . . .” (Genesis 1:1); “He created everything according to its kind” (Genesis 1:11); “He upholds the universe by his word of power” (Hebrews 1:3); “You have made him [man] little less than God” (Psalm 8:6); “All things were created for him [Christ]” (Colossians 1:16); and “Subdue the earth” (Genesis 1:28). This selection is significant, for all his chosen verses express the crucial non-negotiables that the Church will always maintain and that scientific developments can never undermine. True, especially in regard to Genesis, these theological insights were expressed in the language of ancient Hebrew cosmology and therefore require interpretation.As Pope Pius XII taught in Divino Afflante Spiritu: What is the literal sense of a passage is not always as obvious in the speeches and writings of the ancient authors of the East, as it is in the works of our own time. For what they wished to express is not to be determined by the rules of grammar and philology alone, nor solely by the context; the interpreter must, as it were, go back wholly in spirit to those remote centuries of the East. . . . For the ancient peoples of the East, in order to express their ideas, did not always employ those forms or kinds of speech which we use today; but rather those used by the men of their times and countries. But by the same token the interpreter must recognize in those ancient idioms a revealed message directly relevant today, especially that the intelligibility of the universe comes from God. Almost as if he is speaking of Gingerich, Schönborn says this of Christian scientists: “Belief in God as Creator is not an obstacle but rather the opposite.Why should belief that the universe has a Creator stand in the way of science? . . . There are in fact an enormous number of scientists who . . . not only make no secret of their faith, but positively affirm it and see no conflict between science and their faith.” That point, of course, makes only a sociological observation. The teacher of the Catholic faith, however, can go much further; and at a crucial juncture in his argument, the Cardinal quotes Vatican II’s Gaudium et Spes (its Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern World), which directly asserts a positive connection between faith and science: Methodical research in all branches of knowledge, provided it is carried out in a truly scientific manner and does not overrule the moral law, can never conflict with the faith, for the things of this world and the things of faith derive from the same God. Indeed, the humble and Book Reviews 975 persevering investigator of the secrets of nature is being led, however unawares, by the hand of God, who holds all things in existence and made them what they are. This assertion, of course, cuts both ways. On the one hand, as Gaudium et Spes says in the next line (but unquoted by the Cardinal), “Consequently, we cannot but deplore certain habits of mind, sometimes found too among Christians, which do not sufficiently attend to the rightful independence of science.” On the other hand, when the results of science seem to conflict with the faith, the believer can be quite sure that the conflict is only apparent: either because the evidence is ambiguous; or because this evidence, even when entirely reliable, does not carry the philosophical and religious import claimed for it by atheists; or because Christians have misunderstood their faith by confusing a mode of expression with the truth that mode intends to express. The first difficulty requires patience, and Church teaching can handle the last one, as Pius XII did when he clarified that the “literal” meaning of the Bible refers to the meaning intended by the author of the original text in its original setting and does not depend on some superimposed literalism defined by a one-dimensional fundamentalism. But the second difficulty can only be dispatched through the hard work of spotting the inevitable contradictions that are bound to crop up whenever scientists or their atheist popularizers stray beyond their competence. In that regard, Schönborn can be quite witty. He recounts the story of one of his brother Dominicans harping at table every day about a book he planned to write that was going to prove that man is not essentially different from the other animals. Finally another Dominican got tired of these obsessive proclamations and asked, “Father, will this be an autobiography?” The rest of the brethren all laughed—except for the putative author, who kept silent. But my favorite example comes from an interview Richard Dawkins, England’s most pious atheist and loudest Darwinian, gave to an Austrian newspaper, Die Presse ( July 30, 2005), where he made this whopper of a concession: “No decent person wants to live in a society that works according to Darwinian laws. . . . A Darwinian society would be a fascist state.” With that move Dawkins has undercut his whole project, which requires that Darwinism be made applicable in all areas of life. His ethical critique of Darwinian dystopias itself testifies to man’s uniqueness, specifically his possession of a conscience independent of evolutionary forces. But at this point I must wonder if the Cardinal himself does not go a bit too far in disengaging Darwinian insights from political economy. 976 Book Reviews Although hardly the main point of his book, the author concludes with a swipe against the neo-liberal economist Friedrich von Hayek and even seems to endorse the economic philosophy of New York Times op-ed panjandrum Paul Krugman. Admittedly, this view is tucked inside a quotation from an Austrian economist, but as Schönborn cites him with approval, I think it bears notice: The United States economist Paul Krugman is right when he writes that a textbook on neo-classical micro-economics reads like an introduction to microbiology. In economics, the close relation to biology is seen especially in the writings of Hayek, . . . [who came from] a family of biologists, [and who] talks explicitly about a “sifting” by the market. Hayek holds that a high rate of unemployment—like excess population in the animal world—is economically desirable, so that natural selection can have something to work on. . . . Decoded, this amounts to saying that we have to get rid of the European social model. I dispute this reading of Hayek at several points. After all, there are perfectly harmless applications of the term “natural selection” that do not entail anything nefarious, as when we say that bloated corporations become “less fit” and thus inevitably lose out in the “struggle” to win investors. No literal slaughter of corporate managers takes place, nor did Hayek recommend killing off the unemployed. I do not deny that classical neo-liberal economics stands in tension with Catholic social doctrine, but that hardly renders the “European social model” unproblematic either. I am reminded of a remark Arnold Schwarzenegger made when he was running for governor of California: he emigrated from Austria to the United States in his youth, he said, because as soon as Austrians turn eighteen they start talking about their pensions. (The fact that he is now recommending universal health care in California is irrelevant to the observation and only shows he is being a true politician, pandering to an electorate that is perfectly willing to make use of “free” services as long as they don’t notice they have to pay for them.) Plus, I think a good argument can be made that the cradle-to-grave social services provided to most European citizens have contributed to the demographic lethargy and cultural ennui that worries so many Christian commentators, on both sides of the ocean. As I say, the Cardinal’s criticism of neo-liberal economics is but an aside to an otherwise fine book; but it does show yet again how difficult it will be to follow the mandate of Vatican II when it calls on Catholics to attend sufficiently to the rightful independence of science. But truth has a habit of catching up with us all, despite what the postmoderns say. So there is no need for believers to worry about the false claims of the Book Reviews 977 science-hijackers: “Everything that is, is created,” says Schönborn, this great teacher of the Catholic faith. “That is the first, fundamental statement the Bible makes about reality.” Which means that everything we encounter, rightly interpreted, is a gift.“What do you have that you have not received?” Paul asks rhetorically (1 Corinthians 4:7).This, for Paul— and for all Christians—is the most significant “reasoned fact” of all: everything that comes to us is pure gift. N&V Edward T. Oakes, S.J. University of St. Mary of the Lake Mundelein, Illinois Answering the Enlightenment: The Catholic Recovery of Historical Revelation by Grant Kaplan (NewYork: Crossroad, 2006), viii +240 pp. G RANT K APLAN ’ S Answering the Enlightenment presents a movement within eighteenth- and nineteenth-century German thought that sought to understand revelation in light of idealist philosophy. The first half of Kaplan’s book deals with the internal development of this tradition within the context set by Descartes and Hume. Thinkers of the “High German Enlightenment” sought to provide a clear and distinct basis for religion, one that would not be susceptible to an empirical critique. Kaplan then shows how this Enlightenment tradition was taken up and appropriated by Catholic theologians at the University of Tübingen. Kaplan begins his treatment with Gotthold Lessing, whose famous ditch emphasizes “the gap between historical and dogmatic truth” due to “doubts about the reliability of historical witness” (12, 11). Lessing puts forward the claim that Christianity’s historically based teaching served a purpose, but now should retreat so that humanity may freely progress to a higher level without outside interference from God (16). In a significant move for the Idealist tradition, he reduces religion to the ethical realm. Kaplan argues that “by adopting an Enlightenment conception of history and anthropology, however, Lessing edges closer to a position that would necessarily conflict with traditional Christian claims about revelation” (14). Lessing introduces a conflict between Christianity and humanity’s progress by arguing that a revelation from God necessarily hinders humanity’s own ability to arrive at the content of revelation on its own. Kaplan’s treatment of Lessing leads directly into Kant’s thought, which provides a fuller articulation of human autonomy and religious self-sufficiency. If Lessing points to the need to leave Christianity behind, Kant actually provides the ground to do so through an a priori system that 978 Book Reviews imposed “the same standard of truth” on religion “that holds for ethics and metaphysics” (27). Just as Kant reduces ethics to an “internal, necessary communication” accessible to everyone through pure reason, so “he equates God’s revelation with the moral law in us” (28).The consequences for religion are drastic: there can be no religious power or revelation outside of the limits of reason. Kaplan argues that Kant’s thought “shows how the elimination of historical revelation completely erodes any real relationship between God and God’s creatures” (34). God simply serves as a postulate, necessary to connect man’s moral life with happiness (44). Kaplan presents Johann Gottlieb Fichte as the culmination of the vision set forth by Lessing and Kant on religion. Fichte argues even more robustly for the absolute equation of religion and morality. Though Kant clearly intimates it, Fichte boldly states that God’s existence arises from “the transferring of something subjective into an essence external to us . . . used for the determination of the will” (47). Fichte must maintain that God is only a projection of something internal to us, because any external principle influencing the will would deprive human beings of autonomy. Thus, he equates natural and revealed religion, dissolving the latter into the former, since what is known a priori cannot be made known in history (49). Revelation has a place only as an outward proclamation of what is inward. It cannot exist in its own right since there can be no possible proof for something contingent and historical. Summarizing the thrust of these three thinkers, Kaplan describes their shortcoming as “the search for an autonomy independent from all influences . . . reason that is ‘pure’ of any divine assistance” (52). For Kaplan, Friedrich Schelling provides a noticeable departure from these three thinkers. It is clear that Schelling still stands within the same idealist tradition, maintaining similar concerns such as freedom and intuition, but he seeks to recover a real notion of God and a positive role for history. Accordingly, he sees no necessary conflict between the finite and infinite and subjective knowledge and its object. He argues that history must no longer stand apart from truth, because it is only as something occurs within history that one can have real knowledge of it (76).While thus trying to avoid a priorism, Schelling also seeks to avoid empiricism. Though there is a unity of the subject and object, this union manifests the knower’s conscious freedom, which is founded upon God’s own selfmanifestation. Humanity, through “intellectual intuition,” has the luminous presence of the Absolute within, which serves as the means by which to see reality as a whole (62). Schelling stresses history to the point that it becomes the very vehicle for the “unfolding of the Absolute itself ” (80). History plays a crucial role Book Reviews 979 in the knowledge of God, finding its place alongside the interior recognition of God and the witness of nature. Intuition provides the foundation necessary to recognize God, and does so initially through the formation of myths. These myths provide the context through which God more explicitly reveals Himself by taking an active role in history, first through Israel and then most fully in Christ. Thus, “for Schelling, Christianity is primarily a historical religion . . . one cannot remove the historical from Christianity without also ridding Christianity of its very essence” (82). Based upon his expanded epistemology and his appreciation of history, Schelling attempts to initiate a philosophy of revelation that observes how God and humanity mutually seek union, mediated by the events of history and interior acts within the person. The newly created Catholic theology faculty in Tübingen cautiously found Schelling to be a useful partner in its attempt both to critique and to interact with the prevalent intellectual atmosphere of the day. Kaplan notes that the key features of Tübingen’s method entail a focus on history and an engagement of modern thought. Tübingen theologians also emphasize the Church’s tradition as a living organism in time (99). Engaging modern philosophy brings its own pitfalls, of course. For instance, Kaplan notes that Johann Drey fails to distance himself enough from the Enlightenment in seeing revelation as too closely associated with religion throughout history (102–10).The crucial figure of Kaplan’s study, Johannes Kuhn, follows Drey in accepting Schleiermacher’s definition of religion.This definition influences the way that Kuhn characterizes revelation, which he presents as any activity of God in the world (129). In particular, Kuhn builds upon Schelling’s theory of intuition, in order to articulate the existence of a primary experience of God which occurs through an immediate perception that grounds all human knowledge (136). Though it is necessary to see creation and the human mind as a necessary basis for revelation (141, 147), Kuhn describes them as revelatory in themselves (138, 146). Thus, even while Kuhn regards himself as a critic of Schelling, he follows him in accepting a somewhat generic understanding of revelation. Kaplan argues that the use of the term “revelation” came about as a response to the Enlightenment: although the concept belongs to traditional Christian teaching, the use of the technical term arises at this later point (3). Yet, the way that the Tübingen school describes revelation could lead one to ask whether revelation has become too generalized and therefore deprived of important aspects of its traditional meaning. It is crucial in evaluating Kaplan’s treatment to ask whether the philosophical tradition of German idealism truly serves as an impetus for a fuller 980 Book Reviews account of revelation. Kaplan praises both Schelling and Kuhn, the former primarily for the retrieval of history and the latter for bringing this insight into the Catholic tradition. Schelling would certainly be an essential ally if it were one’s goal to respond to the pitfalls within the earlier idealist tradition. While one can gladly affirm Schelling’s contributions toward formulating a philosophy of history and the human study of revelation, nonetheless the risk lies in reducing religion to intuition and experience, so that Christianity comes to be seen as part of one large movement of religion. Kuhn’s appropriation of Aquinas points to the need to remain rooted primarily in the Catholic tradition. On the issue of nature and grace, Kuhn stayed rooted in the tradition by a careful, if not completely uncontroversial, reading of Thomas (154). On the issue of religion and revelation, however, he often seems to follow in the anthropocentric footsteps of Schleiermacher. In sum, Kaplan’s study provides a helpful window into the efforts of Catholic thinkers to maintain, not always successfully, the priority of God’s revelatory action while at the same time valuing the human dimensions N&V of revelation. R. Jared Staudt Ave Maria University Ave Maria, Florida