Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 539–547 539 Catholic Theology in America: Quo Vadis? R EINHARD H ÜTTER Duke University Divinity School Durham, North Carolina O N * September 19, 2010, at Crofton Park in Birmingham, England, Pope Benedict XVI beatified John Henry Newman. Soon afterwards, on October 9, 2010, the Catholic Church in England for the first time commemorated Blessed John Henry Newman. For that day, the Office of Readings of the Liturgy of the Hours provided a well-chosen passage from the Apologia Pro Vita Sua, Newman’s most famous work. “I believe the whole revealed dogma as taught by the Apostles, as committed by the Apostles to the Church, and as declared by the Church to me,” wrote Newman, referring to his faith as a Catholic. “I receive it, as it is infallibly interpreted by the authority to whom it is thus committed, and (implicitly) as it shall be, in like manner, further interpreted by that same authority till the end of time.” In itself this affirmation of the magisterium of the Church is unexceptional, but Newman goes on, emphasizing his docility: “I submit, moreover, to the universally received traditions of the Church, in which lies the matter of those new dogmatic definitions which are from time to time made, and which in all times are the clothing and the illustration of the Catholic dogma as already defined. And I submit myself to those other decisions of the Holy See, theological or not, through the organs which it has itself appointed, which, waiving the question of their infallibility, on the lowest ground come to me with a claim to be accepted and obeyed.” Had I been presented with Newman’s affirmations on the feast of the Holy Innocents, 2004, when my wife and I were received into the full communion of the Catholic Church, I could have made his word my * The present article is a slightly more expansive version of “The Ruins of Discon- tinuity,” published in First Things 209 ( January 2011): 37–41. 540 Reinhard Hütter own, not only without qualification but also with a real sense of joy. For my experience has been like Newman’s, who expressed it better than I can:“It was like coming into port after a rough sea; and my happiness on that score remains to this day without interruption.” As I was to learn, however, becoming Catholic is one thing; becoming a Catholic theologian is quite another.The former entails the loving assent to the Church’s faith; the latter involves the arduous acquisition of theological wisdom. As a result, while I could see that the former requires catechetical instruction—one needs to know what the Church teaches—I came to see that the latter requires a deeper spiritual and theological formation. This formation is not easy to acquire. Catholic theologians in the making must negotiate a difficult and often treacherous landscape in America, for our late modern times are all too absorbing. Where do “young” Catholic theologians—whether still in graduate programs, or in their first teaching positions, or “late born” like myself—find the kind of intellectual and spiritual guidance and formation that allows them to pursue a vision other than that of simply being functionaries of their academic guild? The problem was not unknown to me. As a Lutheran theologian I recognized that the general pattern of modernity has pushed theological analysis and reflection to the margins of the intellectual life and the universities.To survive, theology departments have steadily adopted theologically extraneous perspectives of self-understanding and standards of self-evaluation that ever so subtly estrange theologians from their subject matter. For the up-and-coming young theologian who seeks advancement, and who wishes to be globally marketable to any institution that offers a job, it becomes nearly impossible to resist the pressure to embrace the attitudes and behaviors expected by the secular university. So where can Catholic theologians in the making be theologically and spiritually formed today so that they may aspire to the most intellectually rigorous understanding of the revealed truth? Where will they be instructed with the greatest fidelity to the Church? What will help them resist the one-sided and exaggerated contemporaneous academic emphasis on originality and productivity? The unity and coherence of theology can be accounted for only if we explicitly conceive of it as an ecclesial intellectual practice of the Church, arising from the Church’s nature and mission.This was the burden of the argument in my 1999 book, Suffering Divine Things: Theology as Church Practice. The book was intended as an implicit challenge to certain forms of liberal Protestant theology that, uprooted from any ecclesial setting and accountability, rapidly had come to endorse a historicist relativism and subjectivism and eventually ended up embracing and celebrating individual arbitration in all matters of faith and morals.To me this conclusion felt Catholic Theology in America 541 like a new discovery, but of course I had only reproduced, in an “evangelical catholic” key, what then-cardinal Joseph Ratzinger already had argued in his small but important book, The Nature and Mission of Theology: Essays to Orient Theology in Today’s Debates: that theology is essentially ecclesial, and theologians have an essentially ecclesial vocation. And so, with a firm sense that becoming a Catholic theologian required me to enter into a specifically church-oriented tradition of intellectual and spiritual formation, I gladly became, once again, a student of theology, this time Catholic instead of Lutheran. Some sobering surprises lay ahead.As I looked for well-developed and intellectually continuous Catholic modes of theological inquiry—the very conditions for the possibility of a spiritually sound and intellectually rigorous formation in Catholic theology—I found myself challenged in a rather unexpected way.The Church welcomed me as a believer, but her theological life seemed less hospitable. From the outset I sensed a troubling fragmentation, and Alasdair MacIntyre’s famous image from After Virtue of a scientific discourse in ruins came to haunt me again and again. Reading around in the current theological literature, I found that important concepts often were ripped from the original contexts only to be revised, reenvisioned, and recombined.Various theologies du jour seemed quickly to replace each other, and the imperative of immediate impact and relevance haunted all too many publications. Newman himself saw the danger in fragmentation, which ends up tempting us to build our theological vocations on a personal source synthesis. When he became a Catholic, he wanted to submit himself to the Church’s theological tradition rather than pick and choose on his own. As he wrote,“Gradually and in the course of ages, Catholic inquiry has taken certain definite shapes, and has thrown itself into the form of a science, with a method and a phraseology of its own, under the intellectual handling of great minds, such as St. Athanasius, St. Augustine, and St. Thomas; and I feel no temptation at all to break in pieces the great legacy of thought thus committed to us for these latter days.” In my efforts to allow my mind to be formed by the Catholic theological tradition, my own sensibilities moved in the same direction. I did not want to inhabit a theological world that had been broken into pieces, for that would involve an approach that required me to reassemble the fragments myself, and the danger would be that my old Lutheran sensibilities—or, worse, my secular academic sensibilities—would do the reconstructing. Although it is possible to employ the term too simplistically, I think the situation of fragmentation arises from what Pope Benedict XVI has envisaged under the rubric of a “hermeneutic of discontinuity,” an approach to 542 Reinhard Hütter theology that draws a sharp line between pre–Vatican II Catholicism and the new and different spiritual and intellectual atmosphere supposedly mandated by the council. As a Lutheran I experienced the dangers of a modern, liberal Protestant theology insufficiently rooted in ecclesial tradition, in part because of a similar hermeneutics of discontinuity—in this case, one that spoke of the vast difference between premodern and modern worldviews. By this way of thinking, older Protestant dogmatic theology was no longer viable, and Protestantism needed to be put on a new footing that would be relevant to “modern man.” In both the more recent Catholic talk of discontinuity and the older Protestant habit of doing the same, the rich and sophisticated theologies of the past are cut off from the present, depriving theological students of the pedagogy of tradition. The notion of discontinuity has been reinforced by the pervasive adoption of the parliamentary political geography of left and right, progressive and conservative. These labels create the illusion that the Church’s theological culture involves taking sides, either on behalf of the past or for the sake of the future, when the contrary is true.As Newman understood, the future of the Church is best served by a submission to her past modes of reflection—modes that educate us to meet future challenges with a faithful intelligence.As long as categories of secular politics dominate the theological imagination of the Church, an intellectually rigorous and spiritually alive Catholic inquiry in Newman’s sense and a correlative formation of future Catholic theologians hardly seem possible. In view of the poverty of a hermeneutics of discontinuity, I have found myself regularly drawn into a form of contemporary Catholic thought that has flourished in the modern era and that provides a nuanced vision of continuity: historical theology. I consistently encounter profound work being done in patristic and medieval studies and in studies of the early modern and modern periods—work that is historically rich, intellectually sophisticated, and ecclesially relevant. This remarkable work would have been inconceivable without some significant institutional initiatives undertaken in the last century: the intentional development of centers of patristic and medieval studies at leading Catholic universities in America. These institutional efforts were flanked by renewed study of the Reformation and Counter-Reformation periods, and, more recently, by the noteworthy initiatives undertaken by younger scholars investigating Catholicism’s varied responses to the Enlightenment. The same fruitful renewal of already existing dimensions of the Catholic tradition strikes me as the case for philosophy as well. Whether Catholic philosophers in America continue to draw on the philosophia perennis (as, fortunately, many still do), or on phenomenology, or on the analytic tradi- Catholic Theology in America 543 tion, or whether they work by way of meticulous interpretations of such classical figures as Plato,Aristotle,Aquinas, Scotus, Ockham, or Suarez, there is at work a consistently rigorous mode of inquiry that serves as a great inspiration and model for the intellectual formation of a late-born Catholic theologian like me. In instances when I found myself comparing the philosophy and theology departments of Catholic universities, the philosophy departments struck me most often as superior, not only in intellectual rigor but also in Catholic substance. When Catholic theology in America is again able, across the board, to match or surpass the intellectual rigor and Catholic substance of the best Catholic philosophy departments, we can call it a new day in Catholic theology in this country. What will bring about this new day? My previous Lutheran theological education, received at two German universities, taught me the importance of an intellectually demanding theological formation in a reasonably coherent curriculum. In the years of my training, Lutheran theological formation in Germany was still characterized by a tangible inner coherence among all subdisciplines and by an accountability to a shared theological inquiry that always was larger than the sum of its parts. There also still existed distinct theological schools (or remnants thereof) that facilitated and intensified theological formation—schools that had formed around such eminent theological figures as Friedrich Schleiermacher, Albrecht Ritschl, Martin Luther (of the Luther Renaissance of the early twentieth century), Karl Barth, and Rudolf Bultmann. Something similar is necessary in contemporary Catholicism, both to combat fragmentation and to provide a means for students to achieve a theological synthesis that is communal rather than merely personal. Indeed, the decades after Vatican II provide important evidence of this necessity. Most of the dogmatic theologians who at present serve as points of reference, orientation, or departure for Catholic theology in America were trained before Vatican II, at a time when dogmatic theology not only was an intellectually robust and rigorous intellectual discipline but also was dominated by theological schools, the most influential of which were schools of various forms of Thomism (broadly conceived) or of Suarezianism (an attempt at a synthesis of Thomis, Scotism, and Nominalism). This is true of Karl Rahner, Bernard Lonergan, Hans Urs von Balthasar, Henri de Lubac, and others.These theological schools provided the intellectual horizon for the important innovations and insights these figures brought to the Catholic tradition. Soon after the council, and in the wake of rather precipitous curriculum reforms, the unity of dogmatic theology rapidly disappeared; at the same time, its intellectual rigor tangibly declined. Interestingly, this decline 544 Reinhard Hütter coincided in complex ways with Karl Rahner’s unparalleled influence on the discipline. Rahner’s early work goes under the label of Transcendental Thomism. It is conceptually rigorous and had the potential for forming a theological school, the first beginnings of which could be seen in the American context in the years immediately following Vatican II. Rahner himself, however, developed in ways that led him to read Vatican II more and more through a hermeneutics of discontinuity and rupture, and this mentality came to define the work of most of his American disciples. Faithful to the hermeneutics of discontinuity, they ceased to regard as relevant the basic thrust of Transcendental Thomism—to revise and renew a continuous theological tradition. As a result, the third generation of American Rahnerians has merged with those who understand systematic theology exclusively as critical reflection on the role of religion in political and cultural contexts, usually in service of a program of liberation, selfrealization, and social justice. Today, post-post-Rahnerians—always in pursuit of the paradigmatic modern Protestant goal of relevance—treat revision of the Catholic faith and morals as the main task of contemporary Catholic theology. Where the hermeneutics of discontinuity and rupture dominates, Catholic systematic theology is shaped by revision and construction in service of social, cultural, and political ends. In addition to Karl Rahner, Bernard Lonergan has had an important influence on Catholic systematic theology in America, again with the potential of forming a theological school, of which there were indeed tangible beginnings. But Lonergan is difficult to understand and, hence, hard to teach. Today the efforts to communicate Lonergan’s important insights have born fruit in a remarkable edition of Lonergan’s works. But there is no ongoing school of Lonergan, either here or in Europe. Rahner and Lonergan do not exhaust the options today. Avery Cardinal Dulles was, for better or worse, a one-man school. Over the course of several decades, his fairness, objectivity, and aversion to polemical discourse won the respect of the whole field. But his influence was largely personal. He was the embodiment of the learned, ecclesially formed theologian. Since his death no theologian has been able to assume this position and role, perhaps because Dulles, like the other influential theologians in the decades after Vatican II, was trained before the council and thus within the reigning school theologies of the era. Because these schools were set aside by the hermeneutics of discontinuity, they have been unavailable to the generations trained after the council. Only now are they being revived. One can point, first, to the relatively small but active Communio movement, which was inspired by an important group of conciliar and postc- Catholic Theology in America 545 onciliar theologians, first and foremost among them Henri de Lubac, Hans Urs von Balthasar, and Joseph Ratzinger. This theological movement is characterized by a sweeping theological vision, a renewal of theological biblical exegesis by way of a sustained recovery of the theologians of the patristic and early medieval periods, an authentic and profound fidelity to the magisterium, and a consistent and sustained engagement with the wider culture. Without doubt, the Communio movement will remain important, but it is not conducive to forming a theological school. Unlike Rahner and Lonergan’s theological syntheses, both of which undertook to infuse modern, post-Kantian concepts into a modified, but still identifiably Thomistic frame of reference, the Communio movement is diverse. It is unified by a shared vision, a shared intuition, and a shared approach of patristic ressourcement rather than by a shared conceptual vocabulary. For a theological student already formed in proper ways, the great Communio theologians provide the occasion for a profound spiritual illumination and theological edification, in large part because they are exemplary soloists.Yet today we have a greater need, perhaps, for basic training; this requires a disciplined school of inquiry that may not soar to the heights one finds in the best of the Communio movement but nonetheless reliably provides the basis for an intelligent appreciation of its achievements. As I immersed myself in the treasures of the Communio movement, I continued to search for a Catholic inquiry that, in Newman’s words,“has taken certain definite shapes, and has thrown itself into the form of a science, with a method and a phraseology of its own.” I eventually found what few observers of the Catholic theological scene would have expected thirty years ago: a small band of theologians who might best be called Ressourcement Thomists. These are students of the doctor communis,Thomas Aquinas, who seek a coherent and rigorous Catholic theological inquiry that has the intellectually and spiritually formative power of a school. They are in conversation with biblical exegesis and intentional about receiving the documents of Vatican II in a hermeneutics of renewal and development. Moreover, this emerging Thomist Ressourcement is aware of a certain tendency in all schools to become narrow, and it seeks to avoid this danger by pursing its work in dialogue with Protestant theology and with Jewish and Muslim thought. Rooted in the synthetic vision of Thomas Aquinas, this Thomist Ressourcement is abidingly committed to a search for a coherent but expansive Catholic inquiry and uncompromisingly insistent on high intellectual standards as well as the communicability of theology. Catholic theology in America: Quo vadis? What kind of Catholic inquiry will welcome, orient, guide, and instruct young theologians in the 546 Reinhard Hütter years to come? Not a few of them will have been inspired by the works of an Augustine, a Bonaventure, an Aquinas, a Newman, a Scheeben, a de Lubac, a Maritain, a von Balthasar, a Ratzinger. Where will they find a coherent Catholic inquiry that comprehensively draws them in and equips them intellectually and spiritually in ways that will enable them to continue this grand tradition? The Communio movement and the Thomist Ressourcement are squarely rooted in the Church’s doctrinal and intellectual tradition, and both are eager to engage and resist an increasingly obvious cultural and political context of sovereign secularism. As de Lubac emphasized, we embrace the gospel not as isolated individuals ensconced in the competitions of the academy, but under the tutelage of what de Lubac called la maternité de l’église—the motherhood of the Church. Catholic theology in America stands at a crossroads. Some Catholic theologians seem already to have anticipated what Walker Percy described as the split-off “American Catholic Church.”The Church these theologians seem to have on their minds is an ideal construct, a specious amalgam of current political ideals. A more difficult labor awaits those who wish to stand on the shoulders of the doctors and councils of the Church to learn, even now, the fullness of the mysteries of Jesus Christ. This labor can begin only with the acknowledgment that, in Newman’s words, Catholic theology “has taken certain definite shapes, and has thrown itself into the form of a science, with a method and a phraseology of its own, under the intellectual handling of great minds, such as St. Athanasius, St. Augustine, and St. Thomas.” Through a patient labor in pedagogy that trains theological students within these “definite shapes,” the handing on and development of Catholic faith can be accomplished. Ultimately, what is at stake—as Augustine realized during his own lengthy struggle with the trendy theologies of his day—is our heart’s desire. We will not find what we seek in Jesus Christ unless we put ourselves under the tutelage of the “church of the living God, the pillar and bulwark of the truth” (1 Tim 3:15), for “great indeed, we confess, is the mystery of our religion” (1 Tim 3:16). As Newman reminds us again and again, “private judgment” cannot reliably interpret the Holy Spirit’s work in Christ’s Body.And so Catholic theology cannot establish itself as a de facto counter-magisterium, remaining in a splendid isolation from the Church. Nor should it seek to win a lasting standing in the secular academy that provides it a career path like that of any other academic profession. Nor, finally, will Catholic theology flourish if it is transmuted into “religious studies” to market its remnants in a post-Christian society. Whatever one thinks about the best way to give coherent and even sophisticated shape to Catholic theology, we must acknowledge that the Catholic Theology in America 547 Church herself gives us our theological task: to assist the bishops in communicating, explaining, defending, and understanding the faith that comes from the apostles—a faith that is to be shared and witnessed to, in season and out of season. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 549–560 549 Redeemable Suffering? St. Thomas Aquinas on the Meaning of Human Suffering and the Passion of Christ T HOMAS J OSEPH W HITE , O.P. Dominican House of Studies Washington, DC N EAR the end of his famous work the Summa theologiae (ST III, q. 69, a. 3), St. Thomas Aquinas asks an interesting question in his treatise on baptism:Why is it that the baptized are subject to death?1 Why is it that people who are baptized still suffer and die? The question could sound like a skeptical cajole. Do you mean to tell me that people who are Christian die? Employed this way, the question would be a rhetorical taunt, not meant to seek an answer, but to end a conversation. Christianity should not be considered as a serious possibility because the problem of evil it diagnoses, it seems itself unable to remedy. But Aquinas in fact means business in asking this question, and he is thinking on a deeper and more challenging level. He is letting the question lead him not only into a consideration of the mystery of redemption in Christ, and the character of human suffering, but also into a consideration of the very structure of things. To what does God give priority in the way he governs the world? How does suffering fit into the order of things? Aquinas is asking the question of what suffering ultimately means. For that is in fact what is at stake in speaking about “redeemable suffering”: does suffering mean anything, or could it? Can it be meaningful to suffer, or perhaps we should say, can there be ultimate meaning in life, despite suffering? 1 This essay originally was presented as a talk in the Merton Lecture Series of the Catholic Chaplaincy at Columbia University, February 16, 2011. 550 Thomas Joseph White, O.P. He gives three answers to the question, which I will briefly paraphrase, in the inverse order in which he himself presents them: First, it is suitable that the baptized die, despite baptism into the life of Christ, for were this not the case “human beings might seek to be baptized for the sake of freedom from suffering in the present life, and not for the sake of the glory of eternal life. Wherefore the Apostle Paul says in I Cor. 15:19: ‘If in this life only we have hope in Christ, we are of all men the most miserable.’ ” Aquinas here is employing an argument from Augustine in the City of God: baptism is not about the stakes of remedying our life in this world only, and if it were then the whole of the Christian religion would be misconceived and delusional. Rather, the claim that baptism is about freedom from suffering and death is precisely a claim about what is ultimate and what is not, and whether we live for this life only, or whether we do not.The claim that through baptism we can attain to eternal life, then, provides the ultimate interpretive light on our understanding of suffering and death, and not the inverse, as if we were to say:“because we do die, Christianity must not be true.” In fact, the skeptic refuses the claim that baptism saves, not because of the reality human suffering, but because he or she judges the stakes of human existence in terms that are too restricted. In short, her or his view of salvation is materialistic. It pertains to this world only, and thus is too limited. Second,Aquinas claims that the fact that we are subject even to suffering in baptism is fitting for our spiritual training. “Namely, in order that by fighting against the vices of our fallen nature and other defects to which humanity is subject, such as passibility, the human person may receive the crown of victory.” Temptation and suffering can lead the human spirit to fall into nihilism, or despair, but they are also the opportunity for growth and inner development of virtue. We have in and through the mystery of suffering the possibility to come to a deeper realization of what is more ultimately real, and to gain purchase on those virtues that last, in the face of a world where evil certainly does exist but may not yield the ultimate verdict on the meaning of life. In short, suffering invites us to choose sides in a world torn dramatically between the struggles of moral good and evil, and it can be in some cases the invitation to move toward our best selves and our highest destinations. Evidently if we were to absolutize this point of view in a simplistic manner we’d end up instrumentalizing suffering artificially: suffering is beneficial because it gives us the opportunity to become good people. Suffice it to say, Aquinas does not advocate such an un-nuanced view. Last, he claims that baptism works in us by conforming us through the course of our lives to the paschal mystery of Jesus Christ. Just as Christ Redeemable Suffering? 551 suffered and died, and rose physically from the dead, so too the grace of God conforms us to Christ, inwardly.We are given the graces of baptism to unite our minds and hearts to Christ in this life, by spiritual habits of faith, hope, and charity, so that we might live through suffering and death in union with Christ and with God, so as to attain to eternal life (which consists in the beatification of the soul) and eventually to the resurrection from the dead. “Wherefore a Christian receives grace in Baptism, as to his soul, but he retains a passible body, so that he may suffer for Christ therein: yet at length he will be raised up to a life of impassibility. . . . So the Apostle Paul says in Romans 8:17: ‘We are heirs indeed of God, and joint heirs with Christ; yet so, if we suffer with Him, that we may also be glorified with Him.’ ” In short, Aquinas has given us three themes to consider: free will and its importance in understanding the meaning of suffering; the place of the development of character and the discernment of ultimate values in the face of suffering; and the mystery of conformity to Christ—who himself suffered as God made man—so that united to him we might be delivered from the power of moral evil and death. Three points of inquiry, to which we return below. But let’s take a detour and look for a moment at the other option, the more contemporary point of view: the idea that suffering is meaningless. II Albert Camus was born in 1913 in Algeria, the son of a French workingclass couple in the Northern African colony. Educated at the University of Algiers,Albert moved to France only after he turned 27 in 1940 amidst the onset of the Second World War. Despite his colonial origins and the fact that he never held an academic university post, Camus is in some ways the archetypical modern French intellectual. In Paris, he joined the resistance movement against German National Socialism, and was an active communist, who wrote regularly in the liberal free press under Nietzscheaninspired pseudonyms (Caligula, Caesar Borgia). After the war, he and Jean-Paul Sartre would come to symbolize in different ways the advocacy of secular socialist European humanism in the 1950s (Camus, though, was always ambivalent about the theoretical aspirations of humanism or what it might genuinely represent). Camus’s first wife was a morphine addict, and he passed through a series of affairs, for decades, amidst serial marriages. Sexuality seemed to amount to a kind of psychological anesthetic to his existentialist qualms. (The exploration of sensualism in the face of the threat of nihilism is a well-known theme in his famous 1944 play Caligula.) He wrote essays of political and philosophical tonality, but also plays and 552 Thomas Joseph White, O.P. novels, from around the time he was thirty, through the course of his life; for these latter he was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1957. He is said to have claimed that the most absurd way in which one might die would be in an auto accident, and fittingly enough, he perished in a car driven by a friend, in 1960, at the age of 47. It does not seem that his death was a suicide. I am referring to Camus in this context not because of the peculiarly French melodrama that characterized his life, but rather because of a theme in his writing that characterizes well a dilemma of modern secular human beings: the theme of the absurdity of suffering. Who says “absurd” in fact designates that which lacks any true purpose, or that which is purposeless. In other words, that which has no final cause, no teleology. In his 1942 essay The Myth of Sisyphus Camus takes as his image for the absurdity of human existence the condition of a character from an ancient Greek legend. Sisyphus, a mere mortal man, tried to overcome the power of death and in doing so strove against the gods. As a punishment, they condemned him to perpetually push a heavy boulder up a hill, only to see the boulder each time returned by gravity to the place from which he had originally moved it. The cycle permits no improvement and yet it must continually be taken up anew.The struggle of Sisyphus, then, is simultaneously pointless and painful. Like life, no discernable meaning can be found in this activity, and it is accompanied by existential disincentives. The image is like Nietzsche’s eternal return, but instead of being filled with the existential triumph of the superman, or the wisdom of Zarathustra, Camus’s conundrum lacks the vigor of confidence. How should we live with the absurd, or should we? Thus the claim of this particular book is famous: Camus says that the only real philosophical question is whether one should kill oneself or not. A terrible question and perhaps quite an immature and adolescent one in some ways, but of course the deeper revolt or issue that is at stake concerns the reason to live. Not for a salvation that transcends this world, and not because there is a deeper discernable meaning inscribed in things, but only for the modest joys of being in a world marked by suffering, despite that suffering. And in view of a hope that is not salvific, but only for the modest changes that a humanistic political ethic can afford. Perhaps this seems a world away from the reflections of Aquinas we considered a few minutes ago. However, it is not entirely so, for surprising reasons. In fact, at age twenty-three, in 1936, a few years before he came to Paris, Camus wrote his master’s thesis in Algiers, “Neo-Platonism and Christian Thought,” a study of the human condition according to Plotinus and Augustine of Hippo. Camus was particularly marked by Augus- Redeemable Suffering? 553 tine’s conception of the fallen human being, and Augustine’s account of the effects of original sin, which include the tendency toward selfishness, the tenacity of lust, and the inevitability of mortality.While he could not see clear to the redemptive side of Augustine’s anthropology—his study of grace and the mysteries of salvation (which nonetheless continually haunted Camus)—the Frenchman was sensitive to the darker side of this vision of the human plight.We find undergirding some of his restless existentialist reflections a frustrated desire for salvation, for the infinite, for the heroic—a desire knowingly refused and purposely suppressed, and then intentionally re-channeled into political activism. But the vision of the human person characterized by the inevitability of finitude and weaknesses of moral compromise has been retained: the human being naturally desires liberation from suffering and a higher purpose or horizon, but none can be found. And given that we cannot attain to God, no transcendent purpose is available, and thus an absurdity results. This is not the moral optimism of Rousseau or the political optimism of Hegel. Camus wants to find purposefulness in the midst of a universe of the absurd, and to elevate the human spirit and the human community above the fray of mere interests of survival in view of a life of humane politics, arts, and philosophy: a kind of secular ecclesiality, where the primacy of the human thrives in a world that is not evidently friendly to the human, and where the human being has evolved arbitrarily and for no real reason. Meaning is sought, in other words, despite the absurd conditions in which human consciousness and freedom have arisen. It would be a short trip from this vision of man to the vision we encounter today in English-speaking secularism. We would need to add the study of the modern sciences to the equation. In a post-religious world, we are in the slightly absurd situation of having to make meaning freely out of the gratuitous evolution of a consciousness capable of selfawareness and analysis.Through the modern sciences and technology we can pursue a humanism that would seek to liberate us progressively from the conditions of pain that characterize suffering humanity. This suffering is in itself purposeless, or meaningless, but with the advent of a human drive to lessen the powers of such an evil, humankind can push forward in the humanization of the physical universe by technology, making it more successfully habitable and less painful. Liberalism seeks to expand this modest goal by political models of inclusivity. Death is inevitable, and does not entail any meaning as such. It is for this life alone that we can live, by moments of joy and human achievement, despite the fact that there is no transcendental value to ascribe to this life. Like Sisyphus, we find our meaning “merely in the present moment of being,” as 554 Thomas Joseph White, O.P. we push against the weight of a purposeless cosmos.Against the backdrop of a sometimes hostile universe, the acceptance of our unique humanity in its fragile, momentary goodness and finite glory is our highest value, an acceptance without any recourse to salvific agency, or any life of grace, that would save us in the midst of our plight of suffering. III Let us pass from Camus and our contemporaries to a different consideration: the ontology of love. Catholic Christianity affirms a different metaphysics, of course, from that of the absurdists. It holds that the core meaning of human existence stems from love: not romantic or emotional love, though not excluding these, but a deeper spiritual and personal love. Behind being, and within being, is the mystery of love. By which we mean what? Well, love is analogous, and has multiple realizations, which are like and unlike one another, in different degrees and running through all things, but in different ways. According to the first letter of John, God is love. Consequently, love is first and foremost something utterly transcendent of the world, and incomprehensible, coextensive with the being of God itself.We know this transcendent love as we know of God, that is to say: not in itself but only by its effects. There is a relative intelligibility, beauty, and goodness inscribed in the existent world that we inhabit. However, what we perceive to be good in itself—the world around us, ourselves—is also being in flux, dependent, and derivative, and so it leaves an inevitable trace of a hidden origin from a transcendent source. We are invited then to think transcendentally or metaphysically, in view of the uncreated, underived love that created the world. However emotionally or existentially trying it is to think this, yet it is a firm truth of reason:There is a hidden goodness from before the foundations of the world who is uncreated love, who has given us existence gratuitously, in the munificence of his bounty. Analogically speaking, love also characterizes creatures, even those which are inanimate or irrational. Things are characterized by intrinsic qualities, by which they tend toward purposes: from the brilliance of light to the solubility of water, to the sprouting form of plants, to the reproduction of animals, the physical world is characterized by the goodness and beauty of things as they tend toward perfections inherent in them. Analogically speaking, they “love,” so to speak, in their very beings, by way of these innate inclinations to natural perfection that characterize them from within. Modern sciences depend implicitly upon concepts of teleology for the study of the “laws” of nature.We presuppose these truths when we study the formal characteristics of material realities and their patterns Redeemable Suffering? 555 of behavior, or when we delight in them or take interest in their intelligibility and orderliness. But more properly speaking, love especially characterizes rational creatures, or persons. Persons have spiritual souls, which make them capable, unlike other animals, of rational and conceptual knowledge and spiritual, voluntary love.To love freely and intelligently is human, to be human is to love in such a way. For the human being is before all things marked by an insatiable spiritual desire for love at the core of the soul, and this desire craves satisfaction by the unique fulfillment of happiness. We desire to love and to be loved and to find happiness thus, and this appetite inevitably and necessarily works itself out in all the pathways trod by human freedom, which is this restless seeking of happiness.The desire for happiness is a tortuous desire that we cannot escape, but which we can shape from within by reason and habitual choice, seeking freely to love more or less well, more or less nobly and realistically, or in base and delusional ways, in accord with reason or with irrationality, and in accord with falsehood or the truth. Love in fact also characterizes the life of reason itself: there is a spiritual inclination in us that desires the truth, such that we can learn to love the truth.The pursuit of the truth consequently can also and perhaps especially make us happy and free us: We can be freed by the love of the truth. To become happy, then, is to love well and to be loved, but it is also to find the truth concerning that which is ultimate and affords perspective, to see all things in the light of this truth, wherein the mind alone can rest.To seek the truth, and to discover stable and noble forms of love that abide: this is the purpose-filled vocation of the human being who is bound to love. If this is our starting point, then the problem of suffering is immediately more complicated, for we are obliged from the beginning to make a crucial distinction between moral suffering—which stems from the inner conundrums of our spiritual life, in its implacable desires for love and for the truth—and physical or emotional suffering, which is rooted in the body and its material and emotional pathos.There is a hierarchy of suffering, then, not because we need to say that mental anguish or spiritual heartbreak is worse than physical suffering, or vice versa, but because there is a distinction of kinds, a duality, by which we are characterized. Suffering from a sense of meaninglessness is different from suffering from cancer. The two can overlap or interpenetrate (and often do), but they still are utterly distinguishable, and Christianity takes them both utterly seriously, because it takes seriously the suffering of the whole person. Let’s return now to Aquinas’s first reason for the suffering and mortality of baptized Christians: the argument from free will. Baptism is not 556 Thomas Joseph White, O.P. chosen freely in order to take away mere physical pains or to reach a material accommodation with the cosmos.What, after all, would unending life in this world as we know it be like spiritually? Would we want it? Why is it that most people would answer “no” to this latter question, even while they simultaneously feel a deep instinctual (truly natural) wish not to die? Analogously, then, baptism is most fundamentally motivated not by a desire for perpetual life in this world, but by a spiritual desire for a higher, eternal life, by an inclination to be united to God by love and to love the truth concerning God in a way that transcends the sorrows of this world. One of the places we suffer most is inwardly in our capacity to love, and so our happiness depends above all on our gaining perspective and wisdom and fortitude in our very capacity to love rightly. Baptism is a remedy to suffering, then, above all because it invites us to choose in grace, by virtue of the charity that is poured into our hearts by Christ, to love the triune God above all things, in and through everything, and to acknowledge ourselves loved in Christ.The deepest fortitude of the soul in the face of sufferings comes from loving and being loved—in the truth—and this is possible in a most ultimate way only by grace, a grace that alleviates our deepest spiritual suffering. But what about the physical suffering, and the psychological and mental agony it can engender, that so characterize our existence? We could give a thousand vivid and diverse examples, a hypnotizing tableau both fascinating and terrible. Recall that St. Thomas appealed in his second argument to the possibility of growth in virtue even in this life, in the midst of our suffering, by way of the moral virtues and the theological virtues, of faith, hope, and love. Is this just Pollyanna? Is Christianity motivated by the misguided pursuit of wish fulfillment in the midst of unavoidable moral tragedy? Given the witness of saints, it is not clear that it is. Suffering can and does become the occasion for human beings to grow inwardly—morally, spiritually—and to be more generous toward others, sometimes in astonishing ways. We think of the life of Teresa of Calcutta, who made a thousand acts of beauty and spiritual love blossom amidst a desert of suffering in the ghettos of Calcutta, or of Thérèse of Liseaux, the Carmelite saint, whose excruciating battle with tuberculosis was the occasion for a heroic but also utterly beautiful act of offering of her life to God in excruciating pain, an act she made in faith and wished to make on behalf of those who do not believe in God. Or of Maximillian Kolbe, the Polish Franciscan, who died in Auschwitz giving thanks to God—even at the moment of his execution by lethal injection—that he had been permitted to give witness to his faith. Maybe it is not fanaticism. Maybe it is the triumph of love. Redeemable Suffering? 557 And yet we are not all saints, you might say.Yes, but the passivity of suffering works also in the ordinary person, and even the weak person, to push him or her toward the consciousness of the absolute, and a more deliberate choice of the good, and sometimes a reluctant martyrdom.There is no one on a cancer ward who is not in some way seeking the truth.The work of living with our mortality and with the mystery of evil is also the work of discerning the deeper meaning of things. And this is something St. Augustine spells out as well. He says in the City of God that God permitted the first death, mortality, so as possibly to spare us the second death, eternal separation from God.We are brought by mercy around to the consideration of the last things, and of the journey back to God as our ultimate resting place. Even in suffering, and in a certain sense, especially in it, we can find the peace that God alone can give and that the world cannot procure. In short, suffering can lead to purification, by which we attain to our deeper selves and to a new-found hope in God alone. Suffering can purify us of the spiritual dilettante in us, and it may push us toward more ultimate forms of inward resolution and truthfulness. This is a form of wisdom procured through the crucible, but it is wisdom the world requires—and, in truth, a wisdom we require, if we are to rejoin the wisdom of God. IV Let us speak finally then about the suffering of God in the passion of Christ. This was the third of Aquinas’s “reasons” regarding baptism and mortality. In fact it is, of course, fundamental.The Catholic faith teaches that in Christ, God became human and lived an ordinary and extraordinary human life among us, to eventually bear witness to his own identity through his death, by way of crucifixion. And this same person, the Son of God made man, also rose physically from the dead in his human nature, in a transformed, or glorified, state of body and soul.This state of Christ’s resurrected humanity is itself a new creation, a new beginning or recreation of humanity, that foreshadows the end times, the life of the world to come. Thus Christian baptism is an invitation to union with Christ, not only in this world, through love and fidelity to God even through suffering, but also through death unto the beatification of the soul in glory and the eventual resurrection of the body from the dead. Is the effectuation of bodily resurrection impossible for God? Well, it is as easy or as difficult to raise the dead to eternal corporeal life as it is to create the world from nothing in the first place. That is to say, it is absolutely impossible for whoever is not God, but it is in truth mere child’s play for God. If God exists, then God can raise the dead. And God does exist and he has raised the dead, in Jesus Christ. 558 Thomas Joseph White, O.P. The claim that God suffered in Christ then is mysterious. God did not assuredly have to become incarnate and human to save us, nor did he have to suffer to do so. But, as Aquinas notes, by his incarnation and his paschal mystery God makes love the victorious inward form of our human life in this world, even after we have fallen into sin and the power of death. He does not restore us back to a state in which we are free from the power of evil (simply hitting the reset button of human creation, as it were), but rather, in the midst of the fallen state that currently characterizes humanity, in which the power of evil has some real reign over us and within us, God has come among us as a liberator, to whom we can be joined, a power of love to transform and heal, to whom we can be united by grace.The passion of Christ then does work by love, but it is a love that renders humanity righteous, from within so to speak: Christ is now our righteousness, through his own human charity and justice, his moral purity and his grace, against the backdrop of a human race that is compromised or marred by evil, or just banality and indifference.And it is his righteousness that he in turn offers to us, his members, by a participation in his grace. He takes on the form of suffering Adam in love, so that we the children of Adam who suffer might become united to the love of Christ that can conquer sin and death. On this account of things, our suffering now in this world, despite its potential absurdity or its horror or its sheer existential trial, is not meaningless, but meaningful, because we can take up the life of Christ into ourselves, his life of grace. Our intellects and wills—which innately desire to love and to find the truth—can now be strengthened from within to live by Christ in the truth about God, and to love, even in the midst of suffering, in union with God and for the good of others. The Catholic theological tradition here speaks of meriting in Christ, of suffering with him and in him, not only for our own purification of sins, but even for the redemption of others, for their good, so that God might in turn offer grace and consolation to others, as a result of our union with Christ.The mystical body of the Church in this world is seen as the Church suffering, or the community of human beings who live by the grace that draws us in by love toward God, but also toward the radical offering of our lives on behalf of the neighbor, and even the enemy. On this view, the burden we shoulder in daily life is not the absurd stone of Sisyphus, but the Cross of Jesus: if we take up our cross daily in him, we grow in life, and we are able to communicate that life to others, in a hidden but real way.That is the victory of the truth and of love that can be inscribed on our souls, even sometimes with radiant beauty, often in hidden ways known only to God. But it is a victory which can bear us through trial and pain, and even seemingly inexplicable suffering, into the life of God. Redeemable Suffering? 559 Let us conclude by asking: Is this reasonable to believe? We should respond by saying: It is a gift to believe. Only by faith is it possible to believe in the ultimate salutary purposes of suffering, by faith which is itself a grace given by God. This grace, however, is offered to all, if we wish to accept it, to seek it, and to cooperate with it. Note that we are left with this great difficulty: how to deal with the irreducible duality of man.We are body and spirit, and we suffer in both, for different reasons. A culture that absolutizes the body makes the spirit suffer from the suppression of its desire for transcendence and encases it in meaningless commercialistic and sensual banter. The greatness of the self is suppressed and the absolutization of the body is preferred.A culture that glorifies the spiritual, however, has to contend with the frailty of our corporeality and its transience.The temptation in that case is the inverse: to deny the inherent goodness of this material world, or its meaningfulness, and to absolutize spirit to the denigration of flesh. Everything around us is ashes, illusion, samsara, and the only thing that transcends all is sensibly unknown.The spiritual life is attained by the ascetic denial of the corporeal. Camus wanted to find a way out of this dilemma through a purely intraworldly humanism, which accepts that the infinite desires of our spiritual life cannot be met, but which wishes nonetheless for some kind of political and artisitic nobility that will exist in the moment, hovering over the abyss, without purchase in the very fabric of things, a fleeting if absurd meaning. Christianity, however, posits that the Word became flesh and dwelt among us. God took upon himself the form of a servant and became obedient, even unto death on the Cross, so that the human world, and even the physical world, might be illumined by a higher spiritual meaning, and by the giving of divine life.The crucifixion illuminates the world: It is the presence of the absolute Logos, or transcendent reason of God, present in the sensible, the bodily, present even in suffering and death.The Cross is the reconciliation of the spiritual and the corporeal, the victory of love in the midst of suffering, and the claim of ultimate and perennial meaning, even in a world of alteration and change.This mystery of wholistic unification, of God and man, and body and soul, and suffering and death with resurrection and eternal life—it terminates in the glory of the resurrected life of Christ, where God has delivered us definitively from the power of evil and the power of death.The resurrection of Jesus Christ, then, is the hope of all humanity, the implicit unique hope of every human person, whether recognized or not. In the resurrected Lord we can perceive the term of our personal pilgrimage and that of the collective history of suffering humanity. How can we set out in that direction? In faith. It is not an impossible 560 Thomas Joseph White, O.P. pathway to walk, for it begins in prayer, and if we ask God, He will help us to pray, and to believe in the resurrected life of Jesus. He will open the eyes of our heart to perceive this mystery. He will illuminate our minds to N&V follow after the Risen Lord. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 561–565 561 Euthanasia and the Fragility of Living a Burdensome Life N ICHOLAS TONTI -F ILIPPINI John Paul II Institute for Marriage and Family Melbourne, Australia A Personal Perspective I N several Australian jurisdictions there are proposals to permit mercy killing or assisted suicide.This article began as a letter I wrote to members of Parliament, as a person whose protected status would be likely to be affected were the law to permit euthanasia. I am dealing with my own terminal illness (combination of renal failure, advanced ischaemic heart disease and rheumatoid auto-immune disease) and am dependant on haemodialysis and palliative care. I have undergone fifteen angioplasty procedures and the placement of eight stents to attempt to recover some blood flow after the failure of coronary bypass surgery. The last such procedure was unsuccessful, as the blocked artery could not be accessed. The rheumatoid disease causes chronic pleuropericarditis. I mention these matters only to establish that I am no stranger to suffering and disability and am well aware of the limitations of palliative care. It is particularly difficult to control chronic pain because the effectiveness of most forms of pain relief is of limited duration, given the development of therapeutic tolerance. I have reached the limits of what palliative care can offer. I cannot speak for all people who suffer from illness and disability, but think I can speak more credibly about suffering, illness, and disability than those people who advocate for euthanasia and present an ideological view of suffering and disability. Facing illness and disability takes courage, and we do not need those euthanasia advocates telling us that we are so lacking dignity and have such a poor quality of life that our lives are not worth living. Professionally, I have been involved with issues to do with the care of the terminally ill for many years, having been Australia’s first hospital 562 Nicholas Tonti-Filippini ethicist, twenty-nine years ago, at St. Vincent’s Hospital, Melbourne, where I was also Director of Bioethics for a period of eight years. Since then I have been a consultant ethicist in private practice and have taught ethics in the medical faculties of the University of Melbourne and Monash University, before taking my current position at the John Paul II Institute.The Institute is associated with the Lateran University in Rome and is a registered Higher Education Provider in Australia, offering accredited specialist graduate courses in Bioethics and in Theological Studies in Marriage and Family. Also relevant is that recently I had the experience of chairing a Working Committee of the Australian National Health and Medical Research Council (NHMRC), which prepared guidelines for the care of people in an unresponsive state or a minimally responsive state, and of receiving a large number of public submissions on that topic.The topic is closely related to this issue. The strength of submissions from people who care daily for Australia’s most dependent and needy individuals was overwhelming, and I highly recommend reading the public submissions on the NHMRC’s website or at least the NHMRC’s Ethical Guidelines for the Care of People in an Unresponsive State or a Minimally Responsive State (2008). Importantly, the guidelines provide a careful analysis of the way in which care decisions may be made so as to preserve respect for the dignity and worth of people who are so profoundly disabled and to provide care for the families and others who care for people with post coma unresponsiveness (PCU) or minimally responsive state (MRS). Note that PCU is the preferred term and more accurate than “permanent vegetative state” (PVS) because the reality is, all that we can observe is unresponsiveness and we do not know what level of brain activity may occur in that state. I have also had a long-term association with a home hospice service that serves the eastern area of Melbourne. I would like to record my own view that it would not benefit seriously ill people, particularly those who are terminally ill and suffering intractably, if the current law that prohibits euthanasia were rescinded.The current legal situation, while not perfect, does provide a measure of protection against the terminally ill being regarded as a burden.As a chronically ill person, I know well what it is to feel that one is a burden to others, to both family and community, how isolating illness and disability can be, and how difficult it is to maintain hope in the circumstances of illness, disability, and severe pain, especially chronic pain. For several years, until I objected, I received from my health insurer an annual letter informing me how much it costs the fund to maintain my health care. I dreaded receiving that letter and the psychological reason- Euthanasia and Fragility 563 ing that would seem to have motivated it. Each year I was reminded how much of a burden I am to my community. The Dignity of the Chronically Ill The fear of being a burden is a major risk to the survival of those who are chronically ill. If euthanasia were lawful, that sense of burden would be greatly increased, for there would be even greater moral pressure to relinquish one’s hold on a burdensome life. Seriously ill people do not need euthanasia. We need better provision of palliative care services aimed at managing symptoms and maximizing function, especially as we approach death.The dignity of people who are chronically or terminally ill would be better protected and supported if, rather than being assisted to die, people were given more help in their attempt to live more fully with the dying process. If euthanasia or assisted suicide were to become a legitimate option with a determined structure, such as was the case in the Australian Northern Territory for a brief period and is the situation in Switzerland, Belgium, the Netherlands, and Oregon, then life for the chronically seriously ill would become contingent upon maintaining a desire to continue in the face of being classified as a burden to others. Essentially such legislation or guidelines involve isolating a category for people whose lives may be deliberately ended. Their protected status as a member of their communities depends on a contingency. Passage of such legislation would imply that our community considers that our continued survival depends on us not succumbing to the effects of pain and suffering, depends on us not losing hope. Chronically ill people need the unequivocal protection of their lives. We need protection and encouragement from our community; we do not need this form of discrimination. Far from protecting the dignity of those who are seriously ill and suffering, a law to facilitate euthanasia would undermine dignity by undermining our sense of individual worth as a person, no matter our suffering and disability. It should be noted that of the seven deaths that happened under the terms of the Rights of the Terminally Ill Act in the Northern Territory of Australia—which, before it was overridden by Commonwealth legislation, permitted euthanasia—four did not actually meet the criteria.1 The legislation was manifestly unsafe, and I would argue that legislation that permits euthanasia could never be made safe for those of us who 1 David W. Kissane,Annette Street, and Philip Nitschke,“Seven Deaths in Darwin: Case Studies under the Rights of the Terminally Ill Act, Northern Territory, Australia,” The Lancet 352 (1998): 1097–1102. 564 Nicholas Tonti-Filippini have serious chronic illnesses, because the essence of such legislation is to make respect for our lives contingent upon the strength of our will to survive. Such legislation depends on each of us, who have a serious illness and are suffering, not losing hope. If euthanasia is lawful, then the question about whether our lives are overly burdensome will be in not only our minds, but the minds of those health professionals and those family members on whose support and encouragement we depend. The mere existence of the option will affect attitudes to our care, and hence our own willingness to continue. That desire to live is often tenuous in the face of suffering and in the face of the burden our illnesses impose on others, our families and the wider community. Politicians would gain nothing worthwhile for us by supporting the legalization of deliberately ending the life of those who request death. Such requests warrant a response in solidarity from our community, a response that seeks to give us more support and better care, rather than termination of both life and care. Further, if euthanasia were lawful, then health professionals would be obliged to mention the possibility, and that would dramatically change their vocational role in which they encourage us to live as well as we can with our illnesses. Christian Care of the Dying The unqualified protection of their lives is important for people who are chronically ill. However it is also important there be an acceptance of the human condition and our mortality so that the chronically ill are not subjected to inappropriate efforts to prolong life. When a person is considered to be in the last phase of life, then more than ever, it seems, issues to do with the meaning of life and the purpose for our existence become evident. Dying is a most important phase of a person’s life, as we are led through growing disability to surrender the things of this life and to prepare for the life to come. Christians believe that it is not an end but a transition to a new beginning. In the dying process, not only the dying person but those around them become acutely aware of the human condition. Christians believe that we are made in the image and likeness of God, for the purpose of communion with him, and we have free will. We accept the biblical story of mankind which tells us that we are affected by sin and that that fallen nature is characterized by suffering, war, oppression, poverty, vain striving, disappointment, and death. Death is part of the human condition: we are born dying—“the wages of sin” (Rom 6:23; cf. Gn 2:17).At the same time, however, we believe that we are redeemed by Christ’s life, death, and resurrection and are called to communion with Him. Euthanasia and Fragility 565 That belief in resurrection humanizes the dying process by giving us hope. It humanizes the dying process by allowing us to accept that life is in transition, that we are called to be with God, and therefore death is both tragedy and gain. Before us we have Christ’s example, in which, at Gethsemane and in prospect of his own death, he expressed his complete and free submission to the will of the Father. His death transformed us through the sacrifice he made for our sins. For us, then, death is the end of our earthly pilgrimage; through death, we look forward to life in complete communion with Him. For that reason, we are not obliged to use every possible means to prolong life but can accepts death’s inevitability in prospect of the life to come. Christ’s suffering, death, and resurrection also provide insight into the mystery of suffering. We know from experience and from the biblical account of the Fall that suffering is an inescapable burden of human existence. Christ has also shown that suffering in others provides the opportunity to love as he did in response to those he encountered. Christ’s own suffering also shows us how best to respond in acceptance of the divine will for us. His suffering, especially his cry of abandonment on the Cross, also indicates the human reality of extreme suffering both in its effect on us (as it disables rational function) and in our need for the support of others. Empathy diminishes suffering. The experience of suffering is for us thus a factor of personal growth, as we find that our love of others increases our capacity to suffer and, further, that love responds effectively to suffering through empathy. We also come to realize that though suffering dehumanizes, love humanizes, N&V both the victim and those who love him. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 567–624 567 De Lubac on Natural Desire: Difficulties and Antitheses C HRISTOPHER J. M ALLOY University of Dallas Irving,Texas H ENRI Cardinal de Lubac (1896–1991), learned, profound, and noble, challenges godless readings of the world grounded proximately in modernity. De Lubac’s diagnosis is that modernity’s godless readings had roots in the “hypothesis of pure nature” developed especially from Thomas de Vio, a.k.a. Cajetan (1469–1534), to Francisco Suárez (1548–1617). According to the hypothesis, there corresponds to human nature a naturally obtainable and fulfilling natural end. Positing such an end, de Lubac maintains, renders God irrelevant in the natural order and consequently impertinent when he calls. In fact, de Lubac insists, man as he is concretely constituted has an innate and unconditional desire for supernatural union with God.1 This desire marks concrete human nature as such; it is not the result of actual or habitual graces. Consequently, concrete man can achieve no genuine rest in a purely natural end. Recently, de Lubac’s thesis, which won wide support for decades, has been challenged. This article seeks to contribute to the renewed debate, focusing chiefly on the theological issues at stake. The article will, first, expound de Lubac’s thought, his diagnosis of the problem of then contemporary theology and his proposed solution. Second, it will offer an evaluation, tracing two implications of his solution and identifying two presuppositions of his diagnosis. I assume the following: A meaningful world is one in which a rational being—that which alone can be created for its own sake—is able to obtain an end that, even if not ultimate, brings genuinely finalizing rest and joy. 1 See Joseph A. Komonchak,“Theology and Culture at Mid-Century:The Exam- ple of Henri de Lubac,” Theological Studies 51 (1990): 585. 568 Christopher J. Malloy This assumption does not forestall the debate, for one may still ask whether any world that is not meaningful is possible.As to the first implication of de Lubac’s solution, if the assumption is true, we must countenance the following dilemma. Either (a) since no world that is not meaningful is possible, should God create beings identical with us in nature, he is bound to grant the grace whereby the beatific vision may be obtained, or (b) God can create beings identical with us in nature and not offer them grace, since the divine freedom is such that there can be a world without meaning. The former horn of the dilemma destroys the gratuity of grace.The latter horn portrays a meaningless world as possible, thus presupposing the divine freedom as possibly arbitrary, all the while, of course, unwittingly omitting to countenance this meaninglessness. I say “unwittingly” because de Lubac is immersed in a (proper) consideration of God’s actual supernatural benevolence, and this immersion is to his credit. Still, if the gratuity of grace rests on possible arbitrariness, one may reasonably object to the thesis, especially since de Lubac identifies earlier roots of modernity’s problems in voluntarism.As to the second, de Lubac’s solution also implies that moral rectitude would be impossible for concrete man without entitatively supernatural grace. De Lubac’s solution is the outcome of his diagnosis, which is grounded in insufficient appreciation of the divine traces that would be present in man in a purely natural state. This deficit is displayed both through de Lubac’s conception that man in a purely natural state would be autonomous and also through his correlative denial that human nature as such could be meaningfully called if its appetite could find genuine rest in a purely natural end. I turn now to the exposition. Exposition of de Lubac’s Thought De Lubac’s Diagnosis De Lubac perceived two speculative problems in mid-century: an assumed autonomy of man vis-à-vis God and the separation of grace from nature.The more obvious problem was the widespread conception of man as being radically autonomous from God. Enlightenment thinkers and Nietzsche had seen the God depicted by tradition as a heteronymous, extrinsic tyrant condemning depraved man. Understandably, modern and post-modern thinkers threw off the shackles of religion and theism and defended godless readings of the world. The second problem, the hidden root of the first, involved trends in Catholic theology, before and after the Enlightenment. Catholic theology was marked by the urge to separate grace from nature and theology from De Lubac on Natural Desire 569 philosophy.2 Though this theology rejected the Enlightenment divorce between God and the world, it implicitly accepted a thesis that, becoming a worldview, led to the secularism it rejected.This thesis was the socalled “hypothesis of pure nature.” Sundry were the versions and sub-theses of the hypothesis. I shall suggest an articulated version of the hypothesis in the Evaluation section. It should suffice here to state the thesis in a generic way: There corresponds to human nature a naturally attainable and fulfilling natural end. De Lubac levels three charges against this hypothesis. First, portrayed as self-sufficient for the attainment of a connatural end, human nature is erroneously conceived as independent of the divine power:“In that economy, as they present it, all of man’s moral life would depend exclusively on his own innate powers, exercised in full autonomy, ‘almost as understood by Aristotle.’ ”3 Again, “If we begin by dissociating the two orders completely, in order to establish the existence of a natural order that could be fully and finally self-sufficient, we are all too likely to end up by seeing not so much a distinction as a complete divorce.”4 De Lubac drives home the point by noting that thinkers as far apart as Michael Baius (1513–89) and Augustine could agree that under any conditions, man requires divine help. De Lubac summarizes their agreement on this point: man is so made that on any hypothesis to fulfill his destiny he has need of God’s external help. For both of them, a state in which man would be left to his own wisdom and powers, in which he would have to develop and perfect himself unaided, is quite out of the question. In this sense neither of them has any room for the idea of ‘pure nature.’5 2 See Henri Cardinal de Lubac, Surnaturel: Études historiques (Paris:Aubier, 1946), 174f. [hereafter, Surnaturel]. Unless otherwise stated, translations of Surnaturel are mine. 3 Henri Cardinal de Lubac, The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 1998), 47 [hereafter, Mystery], citing Guy de Broglie,“De gratuitate ordinis supernaturalis ad quem homo elevatus est,” Gregorianum 29 (1948): 463. See also Surnaturel, 153f. See, briefly treating this claim, Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters (Ave Maria, FL: Sapientia Press, 2010), 314–15. The “closed-in” view is commonly traced to Denis the Carthusian and Cajetan, but these readings are arguably mistaken (Feingold, 78 and 102–20). Echoing de Lubac is Nicholas Healy,“Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace:A Note on Some Recent Contributions to the Debate,” Communio 35 (2008): 542ff. 4 Mystery, 35. See also Henri de Lubac, “Le mystère du surnaturel,” Recherches de science religieuse 35 (1949): 89 [hereafter, “Le mystère”]. 5 Henri Cardinal de Lubac, Augustinianism and Modern Theology, trans. Lancelot Sheppard (New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2000), 1 [hereafter, Augustinianism ]. Christopher J. Malloy 570 Even though their agreement is only superficial when contrasted with their crucial differences, neither Augustine nor Baius could brook a system in which man is conceived as not needing God’s aid. So, in spite of the sometime de facto and ad hoc utility of the hypothesis of pure nature in defense of the gratuity of grace, was not the relative autonomy which [the hypothesis] granted to nature, as it defined it, a temptation to independence? Did it not encourage in this way the ‘secularization’ let loose at the Renaissance and already anticipated in the preceding centuries by the Averroist movement? . . .Was it not too wide a concession to opponents to admit the hypothesis of a state—and as a result to acknowledge in us a whole sphere of activity—in which it was not the principles of sovereign charity and unconditional submission that reigned, but those of commutative justice?6 Of a kind with this illusion of autonomy is a deceptive mirroring of the supernatural in the natural. Proponents of the hypothetical state spoke of natural graces and of friendship with God, of “a disinterested love of God, a love that is ‘most excellent’ [excellentissimus ] and ‘above all things’ [super omnia ], directed towards ‘the author of nature,’ and existing as a fruit of ‘pure nature.’ ” Consequently, de Lubac maintains, grace (supernatural grace) is rendered an irrelevant repetition.7 Second, connected with this flip side of the illusion of autonomy is the presupposition that God would owe a purely natural man a proportionate end. De Lubac considers this presupposition patently false: God is thereby conceived as man’s debtor. Supposedly, to man in the state of integral nature there would be an end proportionate and due, just as to man in the state of grace there is, supposedly, an end proportionate and due.8 De Lubac links this erroneous conception with the errors of “Pelagianism, or Baianism.”9 The systems of both Pelagius and Baius are “naturalizing.” That is, both make union with God something proportionate to man; consequently, union with God is naturally “owed.” Pelagius contends that one can perform good works by one’s own power, without an inward grace, and thus, merit union with God. Baius affirms the necessity of grace, on account of nature’s impotence, but he conceives of union with God as being the end to which man is entitled. Since man is entitled to 6 Augustinianism, 233. 7 Mystery, 40. See also “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 88; and Surnaturel, 247–57, in the context of the entire chapter. De Lubac rejects this inclusion. 8 See Mystery, 62. 9 Mystery, 48; see also Surnaturel, 488. De Lubac on Natural Desire 571 this end, grace is owed him: “The integrity ensured by this gift of the Spirit was in no way something gratuitous for it was not a better good, but something whose absence would properly have constituted an evil, an evil against nature.”10 Such errors are echoed in various ways in the hypothesis of pure nature, which proffers a “beatitude” which the creature requires and which God owes him. In the “purely natural world” where this creature lives, all idea of God’s free gift is lost. How can one say that such a picture, in either possible form, is in harmony with any idea we could have (no matter whether from reason or revelation) of the one true God? Is there any justification for formulating as possible a hypothesis by whose terms God must in justice assure man of any beatitude, however “natural”? Is there any justification for proposing in this way a possible order in which God would, in the strict and proper sense of the word, owe man something?11 De Lubac urges this critical observation vehemently, as we shall see.The hypothesis of pure nature, as construed above, makes God man’s debtor because, de Lubac insists, it involves the claim that it would be against the divine wisdom and justice to establish an order in which it is per se impossible, in that order, for a creature to attain a proportionate end.12 Third, de Lubac charges that in the hypothesis of pure nature, the character of created spirit as such is betrayed, being said to have no aspirations beyond a limited ambit, to be self-enclosed, to be uninterested in 10 Augustinianism, 4. See also ibid., chaps. 1 and 2. On the other hand, there is Cornelius Jansen (1585–1638), who subjects fallen man to strict predestination. Despite the apparent opposition between Jansenism and Baianism, both are fundamentally agreed on this: Innocent man would be owed grace and, when offered it, would control it of his own accord (see ibid., 36–38, 64, and 67–68). According to de Lubac, even some pious persons subscribed to the possibility of an autonomous exercise of human agency. One senses in the background William of Ockham (Quod. I, q. 16 [Opera theologica, vol. 9 (St. Bonaventure, NY: 1980), 87:11–15 and 88:22–28]). In contrast to this conception of a somewhat autonomous self-actualization, see ST I, q. 105, aa. 3–5. 11 Mystery, 48. 12 I say “per se impossible” instead of saying, with the commentatorial tradition, that such an order must have at least some (rational beings) who attain the natural end. For examples of this tradition, see the commentary of Sylvester of Ferrara (1474–1528) on ScG III, chap. 51, par. 1; and Cajetan’s commentary on ST III, q. 9, a. 2, par. 1. A similar description, though not approval, of this tradition is found in S. Dockx,“Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine selon saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Archives de philosophie 27 (1964): 91f. In my opinion, saying simply “If such were per se impossible, God’s justice and wisdom would be threatened” aims at the principle involved:To such-and-such a nature, such-and-such an end ought not (sin aside) for the most part be impossible of attainment. Christopher J. Malloy 572 God. The reason for the charge is this: Man in the state of pure nature would, according to proponents, have only an “obediential potency,” that is, a non-repugnance, to grace. Now, the primary instance of “obediential potency” is, de Lubac submits, the “miracle,”13 wherein God by his absolute power can effect whatever is possible in any given thing, even though there be in that thing no inclination to such an effect.14 Constricting the natural desire to a case of obediential potency for a miracle, Suarez and others ended up describing it as a mere “velleity,” an impossible wish.15 In effect, the dualist theory denies “all natural desire to see God.”16 As de Lubac implies, a spiritual being in the purely natural state would be “called to close itself definitively within itself.”17 De Lubac challenges this limitation of spiritual aspirations:“It is a mark of that spiritual creature not to have its destiny circumscribed within the cosmos.”18 St. Thomas, he says, “could recognize in the human spirit something else than a totality closed in upon itself or upon this world.”19 Though flittingly mirroring the supernatural, the hypothesis leads, ultimately, to a morality without religion and tears20 and to the death of personal relationships,21 tempting man to independence from God.22 How little the difference between man thus conceived and the atheistic and deistic detours of Enlightenment humanism! Does [this thesis] not lead us to suppose a being similar to that so often presented by rationalist philosophies—both ancient and modern: a being sufficient to himself, and wishing to be so; a being who does not pray, who expects no graces, who relies on no Providence; a being who, depending on one’s point of view, either wants only to continue as he is, or seeks to transcend himself, but in either case stands boldly before 13 See Mystery, 140–43; Augustinianism, 127 (n. 109), 191–92, 199–205, and 212–13. See also Komonchak, “Theology and Culture at Mid-Century,” 586. 14 See De potentia, q. 6, a. 1, ad 18. 15 See Augustinianism, 162f., esp. n. 55; see also Surnaturel, 433. 16 Mystery, 10. 17 Henri de Lubac, Le mystère du surnaturel (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 2000), 55, emphasis mine (hereafter, Le mystère. Unless otherwise indicated, translations referencing Le mystère are mine). 18 Mystery, 110. 19 Augustinianism, 174. See also ibid., 158–63, 169, 174, 190–91, and 214–15; Mystery, 28–29, 31f., 60 (n. 16), 108–9, 115, 128f.;“Le mystère du surnaturel,” 87; and L. Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” Nouvelle revue théologique 75 (1953): 562 (both parts of this two-part essay are contained in the same volume). 20 See Mystery, 47. 21 See Mystery, 48, and above, note 6. 22 See Surnaturel, 153–55. De Lubac on Natural Desire 573 God—if he does not actually divinize himself—in a proud and jealous determination to be happy in himself and by his own powers?23 Given these terrific weaknesses, the hypothesis is objectionable in itself. Of course, de Lubac here and there avows, God could have created such a purely natural order.24 Moreover, de Lubac admits the hypothesis once had utility, when it was deemed necessary for the protection of the gratuity of grace and the freedom of God, for an equitable solution to the fate of deceased, unbaptized infants, and in defense against a certain excessive pessimism about human nature.25 In its chief use, however, to identify the gratuity of the supernatural, the thesis is in fact entirely irrelevant. In the concrete order, man by nature desires a supernatural end.26 So, to suggest that some “purely natural man” does not desire this end in no way establishes the actual gratuity of grace. Indeed, the hypothetical order of pure nature involves some other man, an abstract man,“a different ‘me.’ ”27 “What have I to do with him?”28 Between these two men, placed in these two orders with different finalities, there can be no identity of acting subject because no identity of nature: “The difference between the one and the other does not affect solely their individuality; it cannot but affect the nature itself.”29 As a result, the “pure nature” theorists utterly fail to accomplish their chief end. Since the thesis is incapable of identifying the gratuity of grace in the present order, one need not hold it. Given the divorce of religion and reason it occasions, it ought not to be held. For in fact, a man persuaded that this pure nature prolegomenon underpins the Gospel of Christ is confronted with a dilemma: (1) renounce himself totally, only to find an unrelated self in grace, or (2) renounce the offer of grace as superfluous to his ownmost concerns.The markings of this alternative constitute a sad Wirkungsgeschichte: A ghetto Christianity impotent to transform culture pitted against an Enlightenment ideology that at bottom rejects the faith. Paradoxically, these three agree: Catholic proponents of “pure nature,” Enlightenment deists and atheists, and Christian defenders of “total depravity.” Together they hold that 23 Mystery, 47. 24 See Augustinianism, 106, and Mystery, 14, 54, 74, 75, etc. 25 See Augustinianism, 107–16, and 231–32, and n. 66. See also Surnaturel, 103 and 180. 26 See Mystery, 31. 27 Mystery, 59. 28 Mystery, 62. 29 Henri de Lubac, Le mystère, 87. See also ibid., n. 1, and Mystery, 59 and 101–2. The position taken here is at least rhetorically firmer than that in “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 91–94. 574 Christopher J. Malloy the principles of human nature do not incline man to supernatural union with God.30 De Lubac’s Solution Against these drawbacks, de Lubac underscores the relevance of grace, defends its gratuity, and articulates the depths of human dependence upon God. Central to the accomplishment of these aims is his famous thesis: Man in the present order has an innate, unconditional, and inefficacious desire for the supernatural vision of God.31 How does this thesis achieve these aims? First, since the desire is innate and concerns the ultimate, grace answers the inmost human exigence.32 As innate, the natural desire does not first arise at the provocation of experience; it is neither accidental nor alterable.33 De Lubac hereby parts with those who insist the desire is “elicited,” brought on by experience. He grants that an “elicited” desire 30 See Henri Cardinal de Lubac, A Brief Catechesis on Nature and Grace, trans. Br. Richard Arnandez (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1984), 122 (hereafter, Brief Catechesis ). 31 Dockx (“Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine”) also holds this thesis, presenting to my mind the best exegetical argument of Thomas’s texts in its favor. Dockx’s claim is that created intelligence as intelligent nature has subsistent being (God) and thus union with him as its ultimate perfective object. Hence, created intellect naturally desires the vision of God. Note: for Dockx, the desire is not an elicited act of the will triggered in light of a judgment of convenience; it is not the intellect’s desire as moved or movable by the agent intellect; it is not an obediential potency to the universal divine causality. Rather, this desire is proper to the intellect, just as any form has a relation to its proper object. As a result, the intellect innately tends towards beatific union with God (see 55–81). This tendency, however, is not an operation but a relation (habitudo; rapport) or proportion of the perfectible to the perfection, of matter to form (see 61f. and 64f.). Dockx explains: In precision from its mode of operation and in consideration solely of its adequate object, intelligence has being as its object. Now, there is an innate appetite for the proper object of a power as form. So, created intellect has an innate appetite for being itself subsisting.Yet, no created intellect can attain subsistent being; it can attain it only indirectly, by “abstracting” from a consideration of particular beings. There arises in the intellect a “drive” ( poussée) to see God (63), and no act of intelligence short of the vision will ever appease this appetite (64). More recently developing the notion of the intellect’s distinctive appetite, but not concurring with the thesis of a natural desire for the supernatural, is Reinhard Hütter, “Aquinas on the Natural Desire for the Vision of God: A Relecture of Summa contra Gentiles III, c. 25 après Henri de Lubac,” The Thomist 73 (2009): 573–79, working from an article by Marie-Joseph Le Guillou. 32 See Mystery, 136–37. The desire must, of course, run even deeper than that weight of selfishness that so characterizes us (see Augustinianism, 69). 33 See Mystery, 54f. De Lubac on Natural Desire 575 arises, but the elicited desire signifies a more profound, ontological desire.34 One might not discover the innate desire consciously, but that does not tell against its profoundly determining effects.35 Not only innate, the desire is also unconditional; it is so absolute that its eternal non-fulfillment would cause the pain of damnation: In me, a real and personal human being, in my concrete nature—that nature I have in common with all real men, to judge by what my faith teaches me, and regardless of what is or is not revealed to me either by reflective analysis or by reasoning—the “desire to see God” cannot be permanently frustrated without an essential suffering.To deny this is to undermine my entire Credo. For is not this, in effect, the definition of the “pain of the damned”?36 The “pain of damnation” would strike anyone who, sharing our human nature, is confronted by the permanent frustration of this desire. Some wish to entertain the thought of a limbus puerorum, wherein “metaphysical” suffering does not take place, but to do so involves missing the mark of human psychology.37 Since the desire for God concretely present in man is innate and unconditional, its everlasting frustration must constitute suffering.38 34 It could be called “the ontological appetite of intellectual substance, practically identical with its finality” (Augustinianism, 125). See also ibid., 124–25 and 141–42; Mystery, 136f.; and Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 301–3, and Feingold’s evaluation in ibid., 324–29. Here, de Lubac considers that he is following Scotus. Of course, for the latter, this “innate appetite” is, actually, “nothing more than an ontological relationship towards whatever perfects a thing” (Scotus on the Will and Morality, selected and trans. by Allan B.Wolter, ed. by William A. Frank [Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 1997], 43). Dockx’s approach seems mixed: He describes the desire as a simple relation, on the one hand, and as a drive and a (divine) movement on the other hand (see “Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 80). If it were simply a relation to that which can most perfect the desirer, the desire would not be a “weight” of nature, and the portrait would resemble Scotus’s (see Feingold, 35f., n. 17). Yet, Scotus denies that the souls of unbaptized, deceased infants are afflicted (for references, see Feingold, 56, n. 30; and Serge-Thomas Bonino,“The Theory of Limbo and the Mystery of the Supernatural in St. Thomas Aquinas,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy at the Heart of TwentiethCentury Thomistic Thought, ed. Serge-Thomas Bonino, trans. Robert Williams and revised by Matthew Levering [Ave Maria, FL: Sapientia Press, 2009], 148f.).Would Dockx find this acceptable? 35 See Mystery, 54 and 136–37. 36 Mystery, 54; see also ibid., 54–57, and “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 91f. 37 De Lubac nevertheless appears sympathetic to an extent with the thought of Francis Toletus (1532–96) on the limbus peurorum (see Augustinianism, 141–42 and n. 169). 38 See de Lubac, Mystery, 203f. 576 Christopher J. Malloy At times, de Lubac indicates or implies that this desire would necessarily obtain for any created spirit as such, that no created spirit could have any other genuinely finalizing end than the vision of God; a purely natural finality is impossible.39 According to this line of thought, any created spirit that failed to obtain the vision of God would suffer the aforesaid affliction. De Lubac’s second achievement, identifying the gratuity of grace, can now be set in relief.Though innate and unconditional, the desire is inefficacious.40 It is “no kind of divine seed” of glory; it cannot achieve its 39 For direct statements to this effect, see Mystery, 55, 110, and 198–200;“Le mystère du surnaturel,” 106–8 and 116; Henri de Lubac, “Duplex Hominis Beatitudo,” Recherche de science religieuse 35 (1948): 297; and Surnaturel, passim. See also the references in note 62. In addition to these direct statements, there are indirect ones. First, de Lubac remarks,“For St.Thomas, the end of created spirit ‘in every hypothesis is God himself, in other words the supernatural’ ” (Mystery, 67, n. 41, citing Dom M. Capuyns, Review of Surnatuel, in Bulletin de théologie ancienne et médiévale 5 [1947]: 252).With this favorable citation of Capuyns, de Lubac goes well beyond those who deny merely that Thomas ever speaks of the “concrete possibility” of a purely natural end (see Mystery, 12, emphasis mine). Second, there is de Lubac’s remark on a contention by Thomas that the soul, being created immediately by God, has as its end an immediate re-union with God (see De unione Verbi incarnati, a. 1; see also De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 10):“Whatever weight we attach to his argument, whatever its exact significance, how could anyone maintain that for him, in a ‘purely natural universe,’ the human soul would not have been directly created by God?” (Mystery, 67). Third, in his early work, there is a more emphatic denial of the intelligibility of a purely natural finality (see Surnaturel, 456 and 468–71, and also Michael Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade: Über die Beziehung des Menschen zu Gott nach Henri de Lubac, no. 13, Sammlung Horizonte [Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1979], 199f. and 374). It should be noted, however, that de Lubac offers qualifications in later texts:“Even if one went on to say that any natural finality has become concretely impossible for that created spirit, that existing being, it could never be an absolute judgment, but only one from supposition [ex suppositione]” (Mystery, 101; see also “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 105). Some object that, because of de Lubac’s insistence that created spirit can have no other end than the vision, this supposition must boil down to a “supposition of creation.” To this contention, Figura answers that de Lubac is thinking “from above down”; that is, it is not that the existing world exacts what is due from God; rather, it is that God wills this end, and thus makes what is fit for it (Der Anruf der Gnade, 364f.; see also Malevez,“La gratuité du surnaturel,” 576–78; and Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 541). Healy correctly insists that de Lubac speaks of a twofold beatitude. Healy also faithfully displays de Lubac’s pronouncement on the character of natural beatitude, on that aspect of beatitude that corresponds to the capacity of nature: It is terrestrial, unstable, transitory, mixed, and immanent (see 553–55). 40 “The supernatural is the object of an absolute though inefficacious desire, without ceasing to be absolutely gratuitous” (Surnaturel, 438; see also ibid., 453f; Augustinianism, pp. 171f; and Mystery, 85f., 111, and 137). De Lubac on Natural Desire 577 end.41 Moreover, this desire in no way entitles man to its end:The desire “of itself achieves nothing, since it indicates no kind of debt or requirement.”42 De Lubac thus identifies the gratuity of grace in a radical manner and in any order. Even in Surnaturel (1946), he presents the following remarkable citation from William of Ockham (1285–1347):“God is a debtor to no one in any way.”43 It should be noted that although Thomas, following Augustine, recognizes that God is debtor to no one, Ockham has added the phrase quocumque modo.44 In turn, de Lubac augments Ockham’s addition: “In no sense and according to no title—neither natural nor moral—do we have rights over God. ‘God is debtor to no one in any way.’ These words of Ockham are the refrain throughout the tradition.”45 Since God is sovereign and free, in no sense is any creature on a par with him; the “two” are not comparable as those who confront each other within a larger context of justice. God is the measure. Seeing that some failed to take cognizance of his categorical denial of any creaturely claim or entitlement, de Lubac later stressed a “double gratuity”: creation ex nihilo and call ex gratia. Admitting the possibility of a purely natural order, he accepted Pius XII’s warning in Humani Generis (1950):“Others destroy the true ‘gratuity’ of the supernatural order when they say that God is not able to establish beings gifted with intellect without ordering and calling them to the beatific vision.”46 De Lubac sides with Augustine against Pelagius and his unwitting disciple, Baius: “All, rightly speaking, is grace (although a distinction is to be made between one grace and another).”47 With Augustine, he admits that in some sense there is a reward for works; it is but God’s crowning of his own gifts.48 In truth, however, there can be no question of any created nature having as its due the supernatural:“In my view, which is that of every Catholic, any idea of a claim of created nature in relation to the supernatural should be absolutely excluded.”49 There is neither a juridical claim nor 41 Mystery, 84. See also note 94. 42 Mystery, 137. 43 “Deus nulli est debitor quocumque modo” (William of Ockham, In I Sent., d. 41, q. 1 [Opera theologica, vol. 4 (St. Bonaventure, NY: 1979), 608:16f.]). 44 See Augustine, De libero arbitrio, III, chap. 16; and Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 309 and 380–82. 45 Surnaturel, 487–88. See also Surnaturel, 489; Augustinianism, 12; Mystery, chaps. 5 and 12; and Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 309–12. 46 Pius XII, Humani Generis, 26 (DS 3891). 47 Augustinianism, 2. 48 See Augustinianism, 16. 49 Augustinianism, 29. See also de Lubac Mystery, 207. Christopher J. Malloy 578 an ontological claim: “Every demand must be banished.”50 It is erroneous to admit any debt in either order, even if men were without sin.51 It cannot be emphasized enough how frequently de Lubac insists upon the point: God could have refused to give himself to his creatures, just as he could have, and has, given himself.The gratuitousness of the supernatural order is true individually and totally. It is gratuitous in itself. It is gratuitous as far as each one of us is concerned. It is gratuitous in regard to what we see as preceding it, whether in time or in logic. Further—and this is what some of the explanations I have contested seem to me not to make clear—its gratuitousness remains always complete. It remains gratuitous in every hypothesis. It is for ever new. It remains gratuitous at every stage of preparation for the gift, and at every stage of the giving of it. No “disposition” in the creature can ever, in any way, bind the Creator.52 Since de Lubac has identified the radical gratuity of grace in any order, he has identified it for concrete man, whose “supernatural finality is not hypothetical but a fact.”53 At this point, we can appreciate de Lubac’s third accomplishment: Innately and unconditionally drawn to the vision, unable to achieve it or to claim it, man is radically dependent upon God. He must approach God as a humble recipient. As Nicholas Healy nicely puts it, the natural desire constitutes “a kind of created infrastructure that opens nature from within to receive and participate in the new and unimagined gift of deification,”54 desired “only in the context of a friendship that is gratuitous.”55 Created spirit is, as indicated above, radically unlike anything else; non-rational things may be able to achieve their ends by the powers given them, but man depends on the free offer of grace, since he is made to be dependent. This poverty marks his grandeur: “There can be no question here of any kind of debitum naturae, anything owed to nature, no suggestion of anything resembling a demand. Man’s longing for God is in a category of its own.”56 It is a paradox: “Man cannot live except by the vision of God—and that vision of God depends totally on God’s good pleasure.”57 50 Henri Cardinal de Lubac, Augustinisme et théologie moderne, no. 63, Théologie (Aubier, 1965), 47. 51 See Mystery, 183f. 52 Mystery, 236f. See also Augustinianism, 233; and Mystery, 84–86 and 130. 53 Mystery, 62. See also “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 91–99. 54 Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 561. 55 Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 548. 56 Mystery, 88. 57 Mystery, 179; see also ibid., 58, and “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 116. De Lubac on Natural Desire 579 A spirit who understood and accepted his dignity would not grow fearful in the face of this need.58 He would not have it any other way, for union with God is not only beatitude and rest but leitourgia, love, and adoration.59 A holy soul will bear itself before God humbly, stating that its wish is “Only yourself, oh Lord.”60 Here, de Lubac places his finger on the pulse of the mystical life. He adds that such humility must be coupled with a renunciation of merit: The holy soul wishes to receive God only as a gift and not as a reward.61 In sum, theologies based on the “pure nature” hypothesis show little understanding of the dynamism and dignity of created spirit. Unlike all natural things, even animate, the intellectual being rises above itself spontaneously. It is not satisfied with that which it can grasp.The hypothesis of pure nature thus betrays created spirit, mechanically applying the axiom “every form has its proper and proportionate end” to created spirit.Yet, the axiom can apply only to non-intellectual beings.62 De Lubac identifies the relevance of grace by pointing to an innate and unconditional desire for the vision of God, yet, he maintains, despite man’s indigence owing to this exigence, grace is wholly gratuitous. 58 See “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 110. 59 See the conclusion to Surnaturel, and Mystery, chap. 12. 60 In my opinion, this point holds good for both the natural and the supernatural orders. Of course, the “ecstasis” in the natural order would be infinitely inferior to that of charity. So, in either order, God would be loved for his own sake. Since this ecstatic love would be the ruling appetite, the very character of the desire for knowledge of him would bear this mark. On this, see Servais Pinckaers, “The Natural Desire to See God,” Nova et Vetera 8 (2010): 627–46. 61 See, e.g., Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade, 319, 324, and 375–77, pointing especially to the conclusion of Surnaturel, to “Le mystère du surnaturel,” and to the concluding chapter of Mystery.This is undoubtedly the horizon within which to understand the imprecise remarks of Pope Benedict XVI on merit (see Spe Salvi, 35). Healy’s entire piece is bedewed with this precious insight. 62 De Lubac teaches that created spirit, as such, is open to something more than that which it can attain by natural powers, implying that anything short of realization of this openness would end in frustration. See Augustinianism, pp. 22, 169–79; and Mystery, pp. 31–32, 102–18, 130, and 136f; see also Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” passim. For his part, Dockx argues in effect that created spirit forms the single exception to the above-cited axiom because of the proportion, in the order of formal causality, of created intellect to the divine intellect: The intellect as intelligence, capable of the intelligible, is proportionate to the First Intelligible. Of course, its active power is entirely disproportionate, and in respect of this power, created spirit can be said to have its proportionate end. Christopher J. Malloy 580 Evaluation De Lubac rightly saw that the modern crisis was rooted, in no small part, in the expulsion of the divine from nature. For all the good associated with his work in this regard, which is not to be denied (as, much less, is the splendid quality of his works on sundry other topics), it seems a number of questions can be raised as to the accuracy of the diagnosis and the efficacy of the solution. I contend that de Lubac’s solution implies two problems and that his diagnosis is premised upon two weaknesses. But first, a statement of my own thesis and two critical notes on de Lubac. The “hypothesis of pure nature” usually involves more than one claim. My proposal involves the following four claims. (1) In accordance with the principles of his nature, man (as man) has a connatural, attainable, adequate though not perfect, end. (2) This end does not share the formality of the object of graced desire. (3) In any divinely instituted order inclusive of man, there remains a role for this natural (though not necessarily ultimate) end, precisely in virtue of which (that is, in virtue of the backdrop of this in itself meaning-sustaining end) the call to grace and glory can be seen as gratuitous. (4) In an order in which God intends the deification of rational beings, the stuff of the natural end would obtain in the realization of the ultimate end, there being a twofold, hierarchically differentiated attainment of God, one generic and the other specific, one imperfect and the other perfect, the former subsumed by the latter, neither attainable without the other by any agent that has acted freely. Next, a critical remark. De Lubac’s insistence that no created spirit can be adequately satisfied with a proportionate end63 is in tension64 with his explicit admission, several times stated, of the legitimacy of the hypothesis of a purely natural state. That is, these positions are inconsistent—unless one swallows the implication that any purely natural state would be bereft of meaningful finality, which is to say, intelligibility. Finally, a critical observation.There is “a fundamental ambiguity” in de Lubac’s corpus with respect to the relation between the natural desire and human nature.65 The relation is characterized in more than one way. At times, as indicated above, the desire is identified with the finality of this human nature or even with human nature itself.66 At other times, this 63 See note 39 above. 64 See Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 563f., 681, n. 64, and 682f. 65 Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 329. 66 “The desire to see Him is in us; it is we ourselves; yet, it is fulfilled (comblé) only by pure favor” (Le mystère, 209; see also Mystery, 62f.; Augustinianism, 142; “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 111; Surnaturel, 483 and 488; and also Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade, 272f.). De Lubac on Natural Desire 581 human nature is distinguished from the desire that God impresses upon it.67 In his later work, de Lubac draws a threefold ontological (not temporal) distinction to underscore the double (we could say triple) gratuity: the creation of human persons, the imprinting of the desire for the supernatural, and the actual offer of grace and glory.According to this conception, (a) from the existence of God, no created thing follows of necessity; (b) from the creation of rational beings, the imprinting of the desire for the supernatural does not follow as something in any way necessary or due; and (c) from the imprinting of this desire, the offer of grace does not follow as something in any way necessary or due.68 Of course, if the difference between two men with two different finalities is indeed a difference of species, then the gratuitous “movement” in stage (b) is not to the point.69 David Braine helpfully steers us away from reading de Lubac as speaking with philosophical precision here. We should read him instead as presenting us with human persons in this concrete order of divine wisdom.70 If we do this, we are left with the relevant double gratuity: the creation of a man with an innate, unconditional, and inefficacious desire for the supernatural and the divine call to grace and glory.These observations lead me to my questions regarding the implications of de Lubac’s solution. 67 See Surnaturel, 486–87. Here, the desire could not be unless God intended to meet it. 68 See Mystery, 80–81, 84–86, 102; see also Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 332–35; and David Braine,“The Debate between Henri de Lubac and His Critics,” Nova et Vetera 6 (2008): 583. 69 Curiously, de Lubac seems to have recognized this in 1949 (see “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 101–3). Further, to the “three elements” to which he refers here (ibid., 103) he adds, in Mystery, a fourth, a really existent “me” who has not been endowed with a natural desire for the supernatural. On the mature distinction, see Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade, 358–61. 70 Thoughtfully representing de Lubac’s instincts and insights, Braine contends that whereas human nature is not specifically different under different orders of providence, yet human persons are radically different under different orders of providence. In virtue of what are they different? Feingold would maintain that they could be different only in virtue of having different essential or accidental principles. Not the former; therefore, the latter. Braine points not to either but to relation: Such persons have/are relations to God that are fundamentally different in this order of providence than they would have/be in a possible, purely natural one (see “The Debate,” 547–57 and 559–72). In fact, we could not be dealing with the same persons, since it is “ontologically impossible” to jump from one order to another (see Braine, “The Debate,” 571, 583, and 588). (Healy gets at the same thing [“desire of the human heart” (“Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 546)] but maintains de Lubac’s terms [see, e.g., 542, 547, and 552].) For a response to this suggestion, see note 114 below. 582 Christopher J. Malloy Implications of de Lubac’s Solution Purely Natural Man Miserable? Given the recourse he takes to shore up the gratuity of grace—his employment of Ockham’s statement—does not Lubac imply that we by nature, even without sin, would be beings toward misery ?71 The thrust of Ockham’s passage, at least as de Lubac wields it, is that God in no way pays any debt.72 De Lubac in practice follows Ockham’s denial that any creaturely exigence is such that it would be repugnant to the divine justice for God not to meet it. For Ockham, “If the finite goodness of a created nature does not constitute a decisive reason for God to love it enough to create it, the fact that certain conditions are required for its finite flourishing does not combine with divine self-love to generate an overriding reason to situate the nature in advantageous circumstances either.”73 Ockham takes his principle to its conclusion: God could in justice refuse eternal life to one whom he has made deiform through charity. Moreover, God could damn such a one, even though he has actually kept God’s precepts: Punishment is owed [to the sinner] because God has thus ordained it. For, as God creates any creature by his mere will, so by his mere will he can do with his creature whatever pleases him. For, just as, if someone were always to love God and do all the works acceptable to God, God could annihilate that person without injury [to his justice], so after all those works God could give him, not eternal life but eternal punishment, without injury [to his justice]. And the reason is that God is no one’s debtor, but whatever he does to us, he does out of mere grace. 71 Here, there is some similarity between Baius’s position and de Lubac’s, except that Baius responds by destroying the gratuity of grace. De Lubac’s twofold response will appear in what follows. 72 For his part, Augustine scrupulously grounds pain in sin, whether original or actual, and he supposes a “middle” state between actual sin and righteousness, whereby those who die before the use of reason may be neither rewarded nor punished: “But that defect would not be worthy of condemnation unless it were voluntary” (Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will, chap. 15, trans.Thomas Williams [Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1993], 100). For the grounding of blame in sin, see ibid., chaps. 15–22. For the affirmation both of a life “intermediate between sin and right action” and also of a judgment “intermediate between punishment and reward” see ibid., chap. 22, p. 116. Though it is reasonably said that man in the state of integral nature would not be free from suffering, yet (and this is my point), his final end would not be per se impossible of attainment. 73 Marilyn McCord Adams, “Ockham on Will, Nature, and Morality” in The Cambridge Companion to Ockham, ed. Paul Vincent Spade (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 264. De Lubac on Natural Desire 583 Therefore, by the fact that God does something, he has done it justly. For it is obvious that Christ never sinned, yet he was punished most vehemently unto death.”74 It is unthinkable that de Lubac would wish to go as far as this.75 Still, he articulates no other viable way, given his positive thesis, of identifying the gratuity of grace.76 1. The Implication. So, de Lubac’s answer to the question concerning the gratuity of grace is that God owes nothing to anyone in any way. 74 William of Ockham, In IV Sent. (Reportatio ), q. 5 (Opera theologica, vol. 7 [St. Bonaventure, NY: 1984], 55:11–21). See also William of Ockham, In I Sent., d. 17, q. 1 (Opera theologica, vol. 3 [St. Bonaventure, NY: 1977], 452:1–5, 453:11–22, 454:12–17). One must hold this thesis “so that God may be necessitated by nothing to confer eternal life on anyone. Thus, this opinion greatly diverges from Pelagius’s error” (In I Sent., d. 17, q. 1 [Opera theologica, vol. 3, 454:26–455:2]). For Feingold’s criticism of de Lubac on this point, see Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 377–84. 75 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 381f. 76 Figura adverts to this solution to the difficulty presented by a natural desire for the supernatural (see Der Anruf der Gnade, 378f; see also 363 and 368). Still, he prefers to consider de Lubac as approaching the question from the top down (see note 39 above). Paradoxically, de Lubac criticizes the theory of pure nature as having its genesis in voluntarism (see Augustinianism, 109 and 111; Surnaturel, 169f.; and Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 297–99 and 339–43). Henri Rondet, to whom de Lubac refers, also ascribes the “separation” of glory from nature to the birth of voluntarism. However, significantly, Rondet locates the key to this story in the loss of the place of debitum:The connection between grace and glory was gradually attenuated, until William of Ockham sundered it (see William of Ockham, In I Sent., d. 17, q. 1 [Opera theologica, vol. 3, pp. 452–56], and In IV Sent., q. 11 [Opera theologica, vol. 7, 207:11–22]; see Henri Rondet, Gratia Christi: Essai d’historire du dogme et de théologie dogmatique [Paris: Beauchesne, 1948], 240–46; and Armand Maurer, The Philosophy of William of Ockham in the Light of Its Principles, no. 133, Studies and Texts [Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1999], 261f.). Contrary to what I am proposing here, Laurence Renault argues that it was Ockham who first introduced into theology the philosophical principle that one can have a natural desire only for that for which one has a capacity (see Laurence Renault, “William of Ockham and the Distinction between Nature and Supernature,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 191–202). Lawrence Feingold, in his review of the collection edited by Bonino (The Thomist 74 [2010]: 632–36), points out a number of deficits in Renault’s analysis, such as his failure to draw an adequate distinction between Scotus and Thomas. I would note, further, that Renault’s presentation of Thomas lacks contour. Most importantly, it is Ockham’s denial of any debitum whatsoever that really represents the innovation, and this denial is in spirit diametrically opposed to the thesis of a proportion between desire and capacity which Renault traces to Ockham as to its font. Christopher J. Malloy 584 Now, if this answer is viable, there is a possible order in which the following obtain: (1) created persons have an innate, unconditional, and inefficacious desire for the supernatural vision of God; (2) the everlasting frustration of their desire is identical to that which constitutes the suffering of the damned; (3) these persons actually do obey the natural law; yet (4) God without injustice or failure in wisdom never meets this desire.The net result of such a situation would be an innocent human being suffering the pain of the damned. It is of some solace that de Lubac avows that truly innocent suffering would not be a “penalty.”77 Still, would it not be ontological frustration of an absolute desire?78 Thomas, by contrast, teaches, “That which is according to nature can be called neither punishment nor evil, for that which is natural for each thing is in every case fitting for it.”79 Hence, for Aquinas, the lack of vision for one who died in a purely natural state would not constitute a punishment: “It is one thing not to be bound to have something [i.e., not to be bound to be in some condition, namely, the condition of not having the beatific vision], which does not have the character of punishment but of defect only; it is another thing to be bound not to have it [i.e., to be bound not to have the beatific vision], which has the character of punishment.”80 We should be precise about what Thomas means:The lack of vision for a man in a purely natural state (a) would not be “inflicted” by judicial order on account of guilt, as is absence of vision for the damned, and also (b) would not “afflict.” How, on de Lubac’s principles, could one establish the non-afflicting character of the loss of vision for any innocent human, short of taking recourse in grace, which is not owed, or in some ad hoc solution? Turning to the concrete order, one may ask how de Lubac’s thesis could, without demanding grace, establish the non-afflicting character of the loss of vision for someone in our order who died before acting freely.81 Before pursuing this question, I must acknowledge a few things. (a1) The actual fate of unbaptized, deceased infants is one thing; (a2) the longstanding doctrinal permissibility of limbus puerorum is another; and (a3) its intellectual integrity is yet another. 77 See Surnaturel, 456. 78 On the absolute desire, see Surnaturel, 484. On the ontological frustration, see Steven Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature as a Theonomic Principle: Reflections on the Nature/Grace Controversy,” Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 138. 79 ST I–II, q. 85, a. 6, sc 2. 80 De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 15. 81 Hence, the precipitous movement to forbid theories of Limbo. De Lubac on Natural Desire 585 Regarding (a1), the contemporary solution favors a hidden communication of grace, constituting a respectable and hope-filled solution provided it preserves the gratuity of grace and does not neglect the ordinary means of its communication. All should recognize the second (a2) unless some magisterial statement to the contrary settles the matter.With Thomas, I will be arguing for the third (a3). (b) The theological labor towards the theory of limbus puerorum was convoluted and controverted. One who would assess these labor pains cannot ignore the generally agreed historical observation that the distinction between the natural and supernatural realms was not conceptually established until Philip the Chancellor (†1236). The difficulty facing us is this. Some humans die before being capable of actual fault, though, as we know by faith, each is culpable of original guilt upon ensoulment. Clearly, participation in original guilt merits loss of vision, loss of that exceeding good in no way due to nature. However, would it be fitting for beings innocent as to personal fault to be tormented? And would they not be tormented if they suffered either pain of sense or anguish at the pain of loss? In his career, Thomas offered two ways of resolving the difficulty concerning the fate of infants who die without baptism. In his early work, he contended that infants in limbo are not afflicted because their desire to see God remains an imperfect will or velleitas.82 Being just and wise, such separated souls virtuously moderate their desire according to that true insight in the Stoic ethic.83 Further, they share in divine goods in a natural way, and in this sharing they even rejoice.84 Though not described as “beatitude,” the end causative of such joy would be tantamount to a post-terrestrial heightening of what Thomas elsewhere describes as the beatitude proportionate to human capacity. Here in his commentary on Lombard’s Sentences,Thomas situates this natural rest within a horizon of wonder emerging from a crowning human desire for knowledge of the essence of God. In De malo, q. 5, a. 3, Thomas presents a different solution. The souls of departed, unbaptized infants do not desire the supernatural 82 See In II Sent., d. 33, q. 2, a. 2, obj. 2 and ad 2. For some of Feingold’s remarks on the limbus puerorum, see his The Natural Desire to See God, 203, 213, 228, 247–50, 350–53, and 368. Maritain dislikes the term “velleity” but regards the desire as conditional (see Jacques Maritain, Approaches to God, trans. Peter O’Reilly [New York:The Macmillan Company, 1954], 98f.). On velleitas in this connection, see Bonino, “Theory of Limbo,” 135–37. 83 See Bonino,“The Theory of Limbo,” 132–34. Cf. Mystery, 128, 195f.; and Surnaturel, 484–91. 84 See In II Sent., d. 33, q. 2, a. 2 and ad 5. Christopher J. Malloy 586 vision of God because they have no idea of God under this formality. Although punished, they would not be afflicted.85 They “do not lack the natural knowledge that the separated soul by its nature deserves.”And what is such knowledge? “It belongs to natural cognition that the soul know that it is created for happiness, and that happiness consists in the attainment of the perfect good.” Yet, of course, that good is not identical with God unveiled in vision; of this, the deceased infants have no clue.86 Thomas makes no appeal, even in the concrete order, to preternatural gifts preserving such infants from possible awareness of such a surpassing end.87 Clearly,Thomas’s opinion has developed. How shall we understand this development? I would suggest that key features of both solutions can stand together, the former being taken up and nuanced by the latter. My contention here rests upon another claim, namely, that Aquinas’s principles lead one to distinguish the species of the natural end from the species of the supernatural end.88 (Towards the end of 85 See De malo, q. 5, a. 3. 86 De malo, q. 5, a. 3 (Thomas Aquinas, On Evil, trans. Richard Regan [New York: Oxford University Press, 2003], 241).Aquinas is indeed describing such infants (a) not only as punished and unfortunate in light of their call, but (b) as not afflicted by this punishment because of their ignorance of their de facto end, and also (c) by implication, even naturally blessed. By contrast, see Braine,“The Debate,” 561. There is a crucial distinction between actual and original sin at stake here. Bonino stresses that this natural beatitude is not a separate beatitude from supernatural beatitude. It is a generic, unspecified form of fulfillment, objectively intermediate between the pilgrim state and ultimate beatitude, the supernatural vision (Bonino, “Theory of Limbo,” 142f.). I would stress a distinction of formal objects as a way of precising the distinction Bonino rightly draws here. Bonino makes a good case for his reading in light of De malo, q. 5, a. 3, ad 3, which implicitly locates the “penal” character of the loss of vision in its contrareity to the natural desire. Whereas de Lubac reads such desire as an urgent pressure immediately directed towards the supernatural, Bonino by contrast upholds the relative sufficiency of the “stuff ” naturally attainable (the ‘certain imperfect beatitude’) and denies that we are immediately ordered to the vision (see Bonino,“Theory of Limbo,” 145). 87 Bonino describes such solutions as “extrinsicist” (Bonino, “Theory of Limbo,” 131f.). By contrast, Braine seems to teach the necessity of such gifts even in a purely natural order (see Braine, “The Debate,” 566). 88 One can also discern this in Thomas’s corpus. The formal object of the utmost yearning of the human heart—an understanding of the essence of the first cause—is different from that of the desire rooted in grace.Thomas alludes to the distinction of formal objects in various places (see, e.g., ST I–II, q. 5, a. 5, ad 3; De caritate, a. 2, ad 16, and a. 9; see also Long, “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 138, 140–41, 145–47, 154).The ground of this distinction is the principle that different species have different ends, each species having its connatural end (see In II Sent., d. 3, q. 1, a. 6, ad 5; De veritate, q. 27, a. 2; Quaestio disputata De De Lubac on Natural Desire 587 this essay, I will discuss the integral unity of both in the concrete order.) The De malo references this distinction: These souls can have no clue about God as he is disclosed through faith and vision, for these disclosures are of a different kind (formality) than that to which nature gives them access. So, the second solution stands. On the other hand, knowledge of the essence of the first cause is a desideratum, although it must be justly moderated while allowed to inspire a wonder guiding the dynamic progression of natural beatitude’s “felicity in motion.”Thus, the first solution stands.89 Aquinas has his ways out of the horrible test case posed above. De Lubac, however, is reticent to grapple with it: “If it were absolutely anima, a. 7, obj. 10 and ad 10; ScG III, chap. 150, par. 5; ST I, q. 62, a. 6, ad 3; and ST I q. 75, a. 7, obj. 1 and ad 1).The finis proximus is not called proximus because any order must have direction to the finis ultimus supernaturalis but because in the present order the two are in play in a hierarchically ordered manner that allows the asymmetrical compenetration of both without confusion (see note 216 below). Now, since human reason cannot fathom the formality of supernatural beatitude, faith is necessary, so that one may be made aware of the goods of grace and glory (see ST II–II, q. 4, a. 7). Since the supernatural good is arduous of attainment, because of sin and because of its infinitely surpassing character, hope also is required for there to be a completed, unconditioned movement of the appetite (see In III Sent., d. 23, q. 1, a. 5; ibid., d. 26, q. 2, a. 3, qla 1; ScG III, chap. 153, par. 5; and ST I–II, q. 40, a. 1, ad 3; recently treating this topic with relevance to the concrete order, and so treating not natural but divine hope, is Hütter, “Natural Desire,” 573–77). So, without hope, even faith would not beget a movement of man towards the vision (In III Sent., d. 26, q. 2, a. 5, qla 4, ad 2 [Mandonnet, p. 847, par. 163]). Of course, there can be an inchoate desire for what is possible or not possible (see De virtutibus, q. 4, a. 1, and Compendium theologiae II, chap. 7).Yet, one can choose to love only that which is possible of attainment (see In IV Sent., d. 14, q. 1, a. 2, qla 2), for choice regards a completed appetitive act. Desire for what is impossible remains incomplete or conditioned; it is a velleitas (see In II Sent., d. 22, q. 1, a. 3, ad 1) but not necessarily a “superficial” one (cf. Surnaturel, 433). Since the appetite is not inclined naturally to a good that is out of proportion with it, the supernatural end is not naturally desired (see De veritate, q. 22, a. 7). Finally, if one is to tend to the supernatural good as is befitting a citizen, just as by nature one tends to the finis ultimus cui (see note 177 below), one requires charity (see De caritate, a. 2). In certain texts, Thomas compactly treats these considerations together (see In III Sent., d. 23, q. 1, a. 4, qla 3, ad 1; De veritate, q. 14, a. 2; ibid., q. 27, a. 2; ScG III, chap. 150, par. 5; Super I Cor, chap. 13, lect. 4, par. 806; Super II Cor, chap. 5, lect. 2, par. 160; De spe, a. 8, ad 8; ST I, q. 62, aa. 1–2; ST I–II, q. 62, aa. 1–3). For a brief discussion of de Lubac’s handling of these texts, see note 95 below. 89 Maritain marvelously describes the desire (see Maritain, Approaches, 97–100). Showing the theologically scientific relevance of the theory of limbus puerorum is M.-R. Gagnebet,“L’amour naturel de Dieu chez saint Thomas et ses contemporains II,” Revue thomiste 49 (1949): 68–70. Christopher J. Malloy 588 necessary—though the attentive reader will have grasped by now that I do not think it so—to try to imagine the essential activity of a created spirit to whom God did not will to give any access to his own joy . . . ”90 Without counting the cost to his theory, de Lubac laments that the only “end” attainable by such a being would be incessant “circling” around an unknown God. Yet, since any man with our concrete natural desire could have only a supernatural finality,91 this “not attractive” circling would be vanity.92 “There must of necessity be some ultimate goal when one will finally be wholly in act. Otherwise the journey can only be one of despair. The spirit which never reaches its goal, the vision of God, has failed to achieve its destiny.”93 Despair! It must be kept squarely in mind that de Lubac is speaking not merely of sinful men but of any man that would share our nature without grace. Indeed, if he remains consistent to his teaching on created spirit as such, he is speaking of any possible created spirit, for he often insists that created spirit can have no natural and theo-centric end,94 that to it there corresponds no natural finality.95 Consequently, 90 Mystery, 203. For his earlier consideration of this terrible end, see Surnaturel, 459f. 91 See note 39 above. 92 See Mystery, 204. 93 Mystery, 204. Elsewhere, de Lubac charges that to fear the spirit’s natural and inevitable restlessness is to lack faith (“Le mystère du surnaturel,” 110). 94 See Surnaturel, 240–57 (in the context of the chapter), and 451–60. See also notes 16–19. 95 See note 39 above. Thomas’s numerous texts on the duplex hominis beatitudo seem ripe material for a rejoinder (see Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 137 and 141; and Dockx,“Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 51).Yet, has the second set of texts been neglected? It has not. (1) Dockx, approaching the matter with speculative vigor, aims to deal with the principles underlying any and all of these texts (see note 31 above). (2) Laporta also treats the “two sets” of texts:“The entire effort of this work was to show that Thomas, by using the terms ‘natural appetite’, ‘natural desire’, etc., does not usually speak of a conscious, psychological activity but of the unalterable finality of every created nature” ( Jorge Laporta,“Pour trouver le sens exact des termes appetitus naturalis, desiderium naturale, amor naturalis, etc. chez Thomas d’Aquin,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 40 [1973]: 92). Laporta specifies, with regard to humans, that Thomas speaks now of natural desire according to the one true ultimate end of any man (beatific vision) and now of the natural desire from the point of view of what is attainable by natural powers (the end proportionate to the agent intellect, ultimately intellectual activity when freed from the need for phantasms—contemplation of separate substances). (3) Finally, de Lubac also addresses these texts, as Healy rightly notes (see “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 553–57). One way in which de Lubac treats these texts is that he discerns therein three different comparisons between De Lubac on Natural Desire 589 de Lubac must choose one of the following strained readings of Pius XII’s teaching. Either (a) the Pope’s teaching affirms the possibility of some order of intellectual creatures without an innate desire for vision; thus read, the teaching would be (for de Lubac) totally irrelevant for identifying gratuity in the concrete order.96 But, to the contrary, the Pope’s teaching includes the causal reason:Those destroy the gratuity of grace when/since they thus deny this possibility. Or (b) Pius affirms that God could create intellectual creatures with such a desire yet without efficaciously ordering them to the vision. Read thus, Humani Generis implies as really possible a meaningless world. Is either of these readings conveniens? It is instructive, in relation to Pius’s teaching, to observe the difference between de Lubac and Rahner on the question of what is “due.” In Mystery, de Lubac calls Rahner to witness for him a couple of times. De Lubac refers to the desire ever evoked by the supernatural existential as similar to what he means by natural desire.97 He then cites approvingly Rahner’s conclusion regarding this existential:“The loss of a good which is possible but not the object of an ontological ordination prior to free endeavor (voluntas ut res) can only be felt as a painful evil when the loser wills it freely.”98 For both theologians, this taut passage is to be interpreted as not descriptive of our desire for God. Both claim that man as he presently exists would feel everlasting perfect and imperfect beatitude: evening knowledge—morning knowledge; that natural knowledge that one will also enjoy while glorified—vision of God; and merely terrestrial knowledge of God—vision of God. For this breakdown, see Surnaturel, 451–65, and “Duplex,” 290–99. It is to be admitted that Thomas quite often pits a pilgrim beatitude—whether natural or supernatural or both—against the heavenly beatitude. It is not valid to conclude that therefore his principles do not admit a natural, adequate but imperfect, post-terrestrial, and theo-centric end (see note 177 below). However much one points to the space de Lubac leaves for the traces of natural beatitude in the one true beatitude (see, e.g., Healy, 553ff. and 562–64), these do not amount to an intelligibility-constituting admission. Another way de Lubac resolves the difficulty imposed by these texts is having recourse to the notion of an “inefficacious” desire (which he understands to be absolute) for the supernatural (for references to de Lubac, see note 40 above; for a response, see note 153 below). 96 See, e.g., Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 551f.; and Mansini, “The Abiding Theological Significance of Henri de Lubac’s Surnaturel,” The Thomist 73 (2009): 605. 97 See Mystery, 55, n. 4. 98 Mystery, 57; citing Karl Rahner,“The Relationship Between Nature and Grace,” Theological Investigations, vol. 1, 312, n. 1. Rahner’s essay is a development of his initial response to the following anonymous article: D.“Ein Weg zur Bestimmng des Verhaltnisses von Natur und Gnade,” Orientierung 14 (1950): 138–41. Christopher J. Malloy 590 deprivation of vision as painful, even should the loss not be occasioned by a conscious, free act.99 Still, the thesis de Lubac hopes to exact from this passage in Mystery is quite other than Rahner’s meaning. Rahner roundly criticizes the description of the desire for the supernatural as being natural or constitutive, since such a characteristic would make grace due to concrete man.100 Why? Presumably, Rahner finds a meaningless universe impossible. On at least three counts do these theologians differ. (1) For Rahner, the abiding supernatural existential, being neither grace nor an essential human principle, could not touch a race of innocent people without the divine commitment actually to offer grace.These would be two aspects of a single gratuity (ontologically) additional to the gratuity of creation.101 For de Lubac, the desire belongs to nature. (2) Rahner holds that the silent waiting that man as man would live would constitute a meaningful existence, genuine fulfillment within a horizon of wonder.102 So, for Rahner, man as such (prescinding from sin) would be intelligible and not vain without grace.103 As is implied by de Lubac’s thesis, 99 The actual fate of infants dying without baptism is tangential to the point I am making. 100 See Rahner, “Relationship,” 303–15. Malevez sums up the trenchant critique well: “Without doubt, here as well, one can say that God owes it to himself to grant [grace] to us, but this does not remove the necessity of admitting that he also owes it to us to grant us this grace. Once his decree to create is supposed, he must grant to man himself a destiny without which his nature is neither intelligible, nor definable, nor possible” (“La gratuité du surnaturel,” 576). For an excellent treatment, see David Coffey,“The Whole Rahner on the Supernatural Existential,” Theological Studies 65 (2004): 98–104 and 111–14. 101 As Coffey argues, the existential is the beginning of the offer of grace. Grounded in God’s intention to give himself to man, it can be said to constitute the penultimate material disposition in man for divine indwelling, sanctifying grace being the ultimate disposition already aligned with the quasi-formal causality of indwelling (see Coffey, “The Whole Rahner,” 115). 102 “Perceiving God’s silence is also an answer that makes the listening meaningful” (Karl Rahner, Hearer of the Word, trans. Joseph Donceel [New York: Continuum, 1994], 151; see also 69–73). Coffey elaborates this underdeveloped but discernible element in Rahner’s thought (see Coffey,“The Whole Rahner,” 111–13). 103 Of course, one may ask two questions regarding Rahner’s thought about the state of pure nature. First, need we be as skeptical as he about arriving at some knowledge of what man would be like were he in that state (see Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 687–89)? Second, does what Rahner allows himself, by transcendental analysis, to describe man to be correspond to an intelligible form of existence? Rahner (see Hearer, chap. 2) to a certain extent makes man simply an embodied spirit who is waiting for a possible, historically delivered “word” from God.The indication that the human texture is (also) historical is well taken, De Lubac on Natural Desire 591 man as such (prescinding from sin) would be utterly meaningless and vain without grace. (3) Granted, for both Rahner and de Lubac, the vision is, in the concrete order, the object of an ontological ordination that marks every single spirit prior to free endeavor. For both, the permanent lack of the vision could not but be felt as the pain of the damned, unless one took refuge in ad hoc solutions, which both theologians seem to eschew. Notwithstanding this agreement, for Rahner, any person afflicted by the permanent lack of supernatural beatitude would have to be guilty of at least original sin. For de Lubac, a person so afflicted could be entirely innocent. There is thus a terrible poignancy in de Lubac’s Pascalian exclamation, “The inborn grandeur and wretchedness of the spiritual creature!”104 Although sin and grace magnify it, this exclamation stands apart from sin, for man’s condition is a “mysterious lameness, due not merely to sin, but primarily and more fundamentally to being a creature made out of nothing which, astoundingly, touches God.”105 The lameness of which he speaks is not reducible to the absolute dependence of every created being upon God, both directly and through the mediation of interactive secondary causes pertinent to that order. It is a lameness vis-à-vis an end specifically supernatural, the only end one desires by nature and the very one unattainable except by a divine condescension of a specifically different sort than that pertinent to the order “already” constituted.106 Precisely insofar as de Lubac insists on the radically special character of spiritual “nature”—that which has no proportionate end—he unwittingly conjures up this specter of a naturally miserable man, describing it as “the paradox itself of human nature (or, rather, of created spirit).”107 yet the vector of ultimate human inquiry, it seems to me, is rather vertical than horizontal.The eros towards the universal ultimately discovers (in principle, that is) angelic substances, spiritual persons. Further, this eros drives towards the discovery and contemplation of the divine being, which must most of all be personal. Hence, the movement towards the universal transcends into a movement towards non-material individuals and ultimately the infinite individual.The natural human telos is quasi-angelic. Both the inquiry and the life requisite thereto require friendship, as does the full flowering of that end. 104 Augustinianism, 174. 105 Mystery, 113–14, emphases mine. 106 The implications of de Lubac’s thought match his own description of Gregory of Valencia’s thought (see Augustinianism, 111). 107 Surnaturel, 456. Dockx, it seems, would also leave any innocent and non-predestinate persons in this pickle (see Dockx,“Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 93). De Lubac, however, finds the situation “healthy” (“Le mystère du surnaturel,” 110). Alasdair MacIntyre describes Aquinas’s reading of Aristotle in similar terms 592 Christopher J. Malloy 2. Alternative Redeeming Strategies for de Lubac. The irrationality of the above implication appears to have moved de Lubac, at times, to discover alternative solutions. First, he sometimes entertains an opposite extreme, stepping out from his voluntaristic shelter for the gratuity of grace and approaching the logic of neo-Platonic emanation and return:“As a result—at least so it seems—how could the just and good God frustrate me, if it were not I who by my own fault turned myself away from him freely?”108 Second, sometimes he finds shelter by conceiving the gratuity “from above down.”109 It is not the desire that binds God, but God who freely decides to call man, and thus creates him with this innate desire: “If there is in our nature a desire to see God, this cannot be except because God wants for us this supernatural end which consists in the vision.” Because God wills the vision for us unceasingly, he unceasingly gives us this desire so that “this desire is nothing else than his call.”110 This line of thought from Surnaturel is later made more circumspect. The desire may cautiously be read as a sign of grace: “But, one may perhaps say, it remains true none the less that once such a desire exists in the creature it becomes the sign, not merely of (see Alasdair MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990], 137f.). MacIntyre, as Aquinas, is interested in the actual order of things. His contention is thus accurate that one who discovers the inadequacy of any humanly attainable end must wash ashore in a Hobbesian dispersement of soul and quest for power. My point is that if this description is taken to be an accurate description of homo sapiens, then any divine institution of rational nature without grace must be unintelligible. 108 Le mystère, 80. See also “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 91. On the neo-Platonic association, see Mansini, “Surnaturel,” 608f. 109 See Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade, 318–19, 323–27, 364–66, and 373f.; and Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 563 and 569–71. Balthasar once exercised this strategy: see Hans Urs von Balthasar,“Who Is Man?” in Spirit and Institution, trans. Edward T. Oakes (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995), vol. 4 of Explorations in Theology, 25f. 110 Surnaturel, 486f.; see the entire Conclusion. See also “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 117. S. Dockx’s solution to the dilemma is the same: It is not that God is obliged but that he is wise in all his works (see Dockx,“Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 87). The question is begged. Utilizing De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 1, Dockx contends that even when considered as sinner, “Man cannot be made in vain” (88).Thomas does not say that sinful man cannot be made in vain. He says, “In order that he not be made frustrated and in vain,” God intended a redeemer. God could, however, have left all men in sin forever; it would be they who were in vain, not he who was unwise. Rahner’s critique of D. (“Ein Weg zur Bestimmng des Verhaltnisses”) is applicable to Dockx’s article as well (see note 100 above). De Lubac on Natural Desire 593 a possible gift from God, but of a certain gift. It is the evidence of a promise, inscribed and recognized in the being’s very self.”111 The certainty of the sign’s reference remains, even though recognition of this desire and its reference requires revelation.112 As has been abundantly noted by de Lubac’s critics, the first strategy undermines the gratuity of grace.113 Neither does the “from above down” approach constitute an answer. Effectively, the “above down” approach identifies only a single gratuity, the divine freedom to create or not to create a world in which intellectual creatures innately desire him and by grace can attain him. The approach is praiseworthy in its focus on the concrete. And in the concrete order, nature is for grace just as the end is first in the order of intention. Notwithstanding, we have here no identification of a double gratuity because we have here no discerning metaphysical gaze on the principles responsible for created effects.114 Thus, the approach begs the 111 Mystery, 207. See also Mystery, 25, and Le mystère, 81: “Ma finalité, dont ce désir est l’expression. . . .” Again, it is a certain sign but only because God determines in advance to give himself freely (see “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 117). See also Surnaturel, 467, 469, and 486–88; and Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 301f. and 305–7. When arguing thus, de Lubac avows not to say, with Edmund Brisbois,“There is naturally in the human will a desire for the divine vision, independent of man’s vocation to his supernatural destiny” (Edmund Brisbois, “Le désir de voir Dieu et la métaphysique du vouloir selon saint Thomas,” Nouvelle revue théologique 63 [1936]: 1113). Rather, for de Lubac, the desire is radically grounded in the elevation of man, as inchoately supernatural (see Mystery, 101–2). In the context of de Lubac’s argument, this passage from Brisbois affirms an innate and overwhelming desire, conscious or no, regardless of the call to deification. Brisbois in fact presents a subtle thesis:There is an ontological élan to the beatific vision, short of the call to deification, but such an élan would be compatible with a psychological rest short of the vision, for, in order that it may come to act, it must be awoken by the divine call (see Brisbois,“Le désir de voir Dieu,” 1108f.). 112 This change in de Lubac’s thought concerning the demonstrative value of the desire does not touch the issue of gratuity (see Surnaturel, 468–71; “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 117–19; and Mystery, 208). 113 Texts such as these have worried some of his critics (see, e.g., Rahner, “Relationship,” 304–13; Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 681f.; Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 369f., 383f., 389–92, and 428; and Mansini, “Surnaturel,” 605–7). I include Rahner because he recognized de Lubac’s thesis as what is at stake in the article by “D.” cited in note 98 above (see Coffey, “The Whole Rahner”). Malevez (see 673–75) criticizes Hans Urs von Balthasar for begging the question as well. These criticisms are pertinent to certain drifts in contemporary theology that seek support in some elements of de Lubac’s thesis. 114 I think Braine’s thoughtful intervention that de Lubac meant to speak of persons and not of natures (see note 70 above) also falls prey to this neglect. The intervention cannot here be given a response sufficient to do it justice. I would simply 594 Christopher J. Malloy question: Could God constitute a man with this innate and inefficacious desire and yet not call him to glory?115 Clearly, this approach cannot identify the requisite gratuity of grace.116 raise one question. On what is the relation founded? There must always be a foundation of a relation that is real. In the persons of the Trinity, this “foundation” is the opposed relations themselves, which subsist.The real relation that is the status “created” arises on account of the real subsistence of dependent being. So, does not the mere claim that relation pertains to “person” as providentially ordered by God beg the question? Why does not Braine intelligibly trace this relation to a distinct intrinsic foundation? For, if the essential and accidental principles in two persons are identically the same (specifically), but the orders of providence are supposedly distinct, of what is one speaking when one appeals to “relation”? Clearly, the category “created” would belong to each person. So, what is the foundation of the distinctive relation in the special order? (The mandate to find a foundation is not merely Thomistic; see Augustine, De Trinitate,V, chaps. 3 and 4.) So it would seem, Braine is speaking of a radical divine tempering of the existential situation. But if we follow this thought out, are we not led back either to Rahner’s tracks (see text below) or to de Lubac’s (imprecise but at least intelligibly grounded ) tracks? For his part, Mansini also brings the distinction between nature and person into play here.We are utterly different as persons, although we are the same as having the same human nature. So far, he would seem to be in agreement with Braine. I strongly suspect, however, that Mansini would not be reluctant to trace that difference metaphysically to superadded principles, for he does not hesitate to indicate as principles of the differences our own human actions. These indeed make us radically different: Two roads diverged . . . (see “Surnaturel,” 606f.). 115 This is the response necessary to accusations of “essentialism,” etc. (see Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,”567f. and 682f.). A frequent critic of essentialism, Lonergan offered a reflection on the natural desire in 1949 (Bernard Lonergan, “The Natural Desire to See God,” in Collection, vol. 4, Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan [Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1988], 81–91). Here, Lonergan contends for the priority of world order to distinct essences. Essences, he maintains, function as quiddities of parts of possible world orders; what comes first is world order; in light of some world order, certain essences would be fitting.This view of things in mind, Lonergan dismisses the premises of what he labels “essentialism” and “closed conceptualism.” Essentialists assume that possible world orders emerge only in light of possible essences, world order consisting in various possible and contingent nexuses among the selection of possible essences.Thus, essentialists determine certain limits of world orders in light of preconceived notions of essences. Accept these assumptions, Lonergan maintains, and one can argue (a) for the possibility of an order without grace and (b) that the location of the dual gratuity of grace rests against the backdrop of a possibly satisfying natural beatitude. Reject these assumptions and one can still argue for (a) but not for (b). In rejecting (b), Lonergan begs the question of how to establish the special gratuity of grace. Of course, the divine will is constituted by one act. The issue is that if grace is to be doubly gratuitous it must be possible for God not to offer grace to men such as we (even prescinding from sin). Further, we might ask Lonergan De Lubac on Natural Desire 595 Still, for both difficulties, we should consider what de Lubac more deeply wishes to affirm.117 Various lines of his thought offer the elements for three irreducibly distinct scenarios one might deduce from his principles: (1) The desire cannot be in man except as inchoately supernatural, instilled only with the view to deification; (2) The desire can be instilled without such a view; and (3) The desire is entirely natural but, because a meaningless world seems repugnant to God’s justice, God owes it to himself to deify man. If (1), the desire must be a certain sign of the call, cannot be entirely natural, and is the what is “ordered” if “order” is intelligibly first? And if we ask this question, we run into the question of finality, since essence and finality are necessarily correlative. On the other hand, Lonergan recognizes a natural beatitude that, albeit imperfect,“excludes all sorrow, all regret, all wishing that things were otherwise” (“Natural Desire,” 87). One grants Lonergan the intellect’s desire to know, but the requirements for the intelligibility of a world order and the gratuity of grace seem to make of natural beatitude something other than sheer “paradox.” Instructive is his later thought. Still holding the thesis of a natural desire to see God, Lonergan produced the following in 1955.This piece is remotely similar to Dockx’s 1964 piece, though it seems sustainable in those of its elements that leave in tact the stability of a purely natural end: Bernard Lonergan, “Excursus: The Natural Desire of the Intellect,” in The Triune God: Systematics, vol. 12, Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007), 645–59. In this piece, he calls on (b) to identify the gratuity of grace (see “Excursus,” 653).Apparently, unlike de Lubac, Lonergan saw Humani Generis as apropos. In addition, in this piece, he denies that the lack of satisfaction of the full scope of the desire to know must result in no imperfect beatitude. Indeed, he states, “We deny that naturally speaking the blessed would not have everything they want.We concede, however, that they would not have everything that the divine omnipotence could bestow upon them” (ibid., 657). For a good treatment of the difficulties of Lonergan’s several forays into this question, see Guy Mansini, “Lonergan on the Natural Desire in the Light of Feingold,” Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 185–98. 116 See Bishop André-Mutien Léonard, “The Theological Necessity of the Pure Nature Concept,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 325f. 117 In what follows, I agree with Braine and Healy that the common criticism of de Lubac (see note 113 above) involves failure to appreciate de Lubac’s meaning (see Braine, “The Debate,” 573f. and 583f.; and Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 536, 540–42, 547f., 553, and 561–64). As I see it, his critics find the possible world (enunciated in the text above) to be so unintelligible (see Healy, 544) that they suppose de Lubac could not have held it to be possible; thus, they conclude, he implicitly held that grace must be given. In truth, for de Lubac, insofar as God is covenantally beneficent, yes; insofar as he is simply just, no. De Lubac, and also Braine and Healy, thus identify the gratuity of grace, but de Lubac, and also Braine and Healy, do this at the cost (1) of failing to specify the specific gratuity of grace and (2) of losing the intelligibility of the natural order. See also note 175 below. 596 Christopher J. Malloy beginning of the end. De Lubac sometimes says as much. If (2), the desire is no infallible sign, and there is a possible order in which man is naturally miserable. De Lubac implies and sometimes states as much.118 If (3), grace must be given to one who commits no fault. De Lubac sometimes says as much. He holds distinctly each of these positions in concert with his laudable aim. In my opinion, he holds the first and the third positions for reasons he finds conveniens,119 while his default doctrinal position is the second, which implies as possible a naturally miserable order in which everything is so completely “grace” that one cannot account for the special entitative gratuity of deification.120 Required for such precision would be taking cognizance of what is due to some creature (debitum) on the presupposition of a given order.121 I now proceed to sketch this proposal. 3. Thomas on debitum naturae (what is due to nature). Concerning the debitum naturae, there is a via media between naturalism and voluntarism,122 one that avoids the Scylla of God as debtor and the Charybdis of the divine as absolutely arbitrary (howsoever actually beneficent): “Although God is not a debtor to any creature, yet there can be something due to the creature, that, namely, which is required for it to imitate the exemplar of divine wisdom.”123 It is the very character of justice that implies debt,124 and debt implies “a certain order of exigence or necessity of something to that to which it is ordered.”125 God renders 118 See Mystery, 31, 84, 179, 183, and 203f. 119 I thus disagree with the common diagnosis (see note 113 above) and agree with Braine (see note 117 above). If he sticks to his logic, de Lubac would have no difficulty describing the possible world taught by Pius XII as either totally irrelevant or, if relevant to us, lacking “intelligibility.” The early de Lubac would have no difficulty finding such a world also to be lacking “goodness” (cf. Malevez,“La gratuité du surnaturel,” 682). 120 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 381f. That the gratuity regards the utmost exigence is less significant than that it regards a specification of the natural élan (see Rahner, “Relationship,” 307–9 and 312f.; Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 576f. and 683–85; and Reinhard Hütter, “Desiderium Naturale Visionis Dei—Est autem duplex hominis beatitudo sive felicitas: Some Observations about Lawrence Feingold’s and John Milbank’s Recent Interventions in the Debate over the Natural Desire to See God,” Nova et Vetera 5 [2007]: 131). 121 Lawrence Feingold’s impressive dissertation demonstrates the importance of this topic. I am grateful to him and to Steven Long for helping me clarify the following argument. 122 See De veritate, q. 6, a. 2. 123 In IV Sent., d. 46, q. 1, a. 2, qla 1, ad 4. 124 See De veritate, q. 23, a. 6, ad 3. 125 ST I, q. 21, a. 1, ad 3. De Lubac on Natural Desire 597 what is due not according to commutative justice, which regards those who have mutual, real relations and who encounter each other within a wider context of justice. God is the distributor of all perfections: He gives or provides a thing its substantial being, all the perfections supposed by that substance, the perfections ordered to that substance, the end to which that substance is ordered, and the attainment of that end. Hence, only distributive justice pertains to his relationship with the world, for he is the measure of all. God renders what is due according to a twofold order: Everything is ordered to God as to the ultimate end, and some created things are ordered to other created things, both subsisting things and accidents. So, something is owed to God and something is owed to created beings. As regards the first, it is God who renders to himself what is due, for it is due that the order he establishes be fulfilled.The second order of debt depends on the first, for God creates according to a pattern of his wisdom.126 He renders what is due in the second way in order that the truth of some divine idea be preserved in that of which it is an exemplar.127 God necessarily creates wisely but is debtor to none, for all things are ordered to him, he to none, and any order including created exigencies hangs on his (ever wise) mercy.128 The debt that concerns us pertains to this second kind, which can be divided into what pertains to the condition of nature and what is due to meritorious activity.129 The former is distinguishable into what pertains to subsistence and what pertains to operation or wellbeing.130 According to subsistence, that is due a thing which pertains to its existence, essence, and proper principles.According to operation and well-being, that is due to a thing which befits its condition and conduces to its good operation. It befits the condition of a man in the state of integral nature to be in an upright condition, to have natural justice.131 To provide such pertains to the divine justice.132 It pertains to divine liberality vis-à-vis any terrestrial man to offer grace and supernatural justice. Moreover, this liberality is so perfect with respect 126 In addition to ST I, q. 21, a. 1, see De veritate, q. 6, a. 2, and q. 23, a. 6. 127 See De veritate, q. 23, a. 6, ad 3. 128 See ST I, q. 21, a. 1 and, esp., a. 4. See also In IV Sent., d. 46, q. 1, a. 2, qla 1. 129 See ST I–II, q. 111, a. 1, ad 2. 130 See Dockx, “Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 83f. Sundry texts in Aquinas include De veritate, q. 12, a. 3, ad 17; In Boet. De Trinitate, q. 3, a. 1, ad 2; De Divinis nominibus, chap. 8, lect. 4, pars. 775–77; and ST I, q. 25, a. 5. 131 This is political, not despotic, order; hence, a certain concupiscence is compatible with natural justice. 132 See De malo, q. 16, a. 2, ad 17. 598 Christopher J. Malloy to man that—at least during the pilgrim state—God could withdraw supernatural justice and reduce a man to a naturally good state, without threat to the divine justice.133 (Observe that this supposition depends for its intelligibility on an identity of nature and hypostasis between the man supernaturally elevated and the same person so reduced.)134 Yet, God could not, except on account of sin, withdraw natural justice without an infringement of his divine justice, which infringement would be an affront to the first sense of debitum.135 Pertinent to the good operation of something is its specific operation, that perfection which is its end, the finis quo (the end by which),136 to which there corresponds a proper object and with respect to which the intelligibility of its nature derives. Now, to each species there is a distinct, connatural end.137 Hence, men and angels, who as to their proximate 133 See De malo, q. 16, a. 2, ad 17. In this careful and differentiated response,Thomas, reflecting on what pertains to divine justice, indicates that, although God could withdraw supernatural righteousness without injustice, he could not withdraw natural righteousness from a human being.And Thomas also affirms, elsewhere (De malo, q. 5, a. 3), that to a separated soul in the state of natural righteousness natural knowledge is due. Of what could this be knowledge other than of God as first cause? On this, see also Hütter,“Desiderium,” 100f. Cf. Mystery, 71;“Le mystère du surnaturel,” 93–98; and Malevez,“La gratuité du surnaturel,” 565 and 572. 134 I would note, further, that although Thomas contends that men and angels were created in the state of grace, he describes the contrary position not as impossible but as less fitting and less probable (see ST I, q. 62, a. 3, and the surprising expressions, no doubt slips but revealing ones nonetheless, in ST I–II, q. 109, a. 2, and ST I–II, q. 114, a. 2; see also Jean-Pierre Torrell, “Nature and Grace in Thomas Aquinas,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 185). De Lubac’s contention that we would be dealing with two essentially different men, and thus two persons, is not consonant with Thomas’s thought. More importantly, “nature” of its nature is a universal, applicable to many; thus, its very character is “abstract” although the essential principle in a man is concrete. So, to disparage as “abstract” someone’s notion of nature is to disparage the very category “nature.” On this, see Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 335f. Of course, if a man in the state of pure nature is of a different essence than I, then Pius XII’s teaching is as pointless a defense of gratuity as de Lubac claims the hypothesis of pure nature to be. 135 See De potentia, q. 6, a. 1, ad 3. 136 See ST I, q. 105, a. 5. Things are for their operations. The proposition that the imperfect is ordered to the perfect obtains with respect to an identify of formal object (see note 88 above). 137 Long peppers his essay with this claim (see “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 143; 146, n. 16; 148, n. 18; 151; 152; 155f.; 159; and 174).To be precise, Thomas teaches that a species is derived from its end taken formally, not materially. That is, if we would indicate that end which specifies a species, we must take account not only of the thing but of the formality under which we attain it (see note 88 above). One may also indicate the following text: “Each thing is De Lubac on Natural Desire 599 end attain God under different formalities, are of different species, though they are gratuitously directed to an ultimate end.138 This connatural operation pertains to the debitum ex conditione naturae (what is due according to the condition of nature).139 Actual attainment of the ultimate end, however, is not in the power of any creature, even one deified by grace. Hence, a creature can be said only to merit attainment of the ultimate end, on the promise of God who predestines and calls a man to this end and infuses his grace as the assistance whereby it may be merited condignly.140 Condign merit involves a true title to eternal life and so pertains to the ratio of debitum.141 This debt respects the internal relations of the effects of the ordered to the end fitting for it according to the character of its form (secundum rationem suae formae ): for different ends belong to different species” (ScG III, chap. 150, par. 5). Thomas is not speaking here of “operation” and “beatitude” but of “form” and “end.” See also Super II Ad Corinth., chap. 5, lect. 2, pars. 160f. The point made here is, in part, a response to Dockx. 138 See Quaestio disputata De anima, a. 7, obj. 10 and ad 10. Feingold drives this crucial distinction home (see Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 254, 297–99, 319–22, 332, 336–37, and 382–85). See also Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 688. For an excellent treatment of the continuing place of nature and its proportionate end for persons endowed with or called by grace, see Hütter, “Desiderium,” 98–117. 139 See ST I–II, q. 110, a. 1, circa finem; see also Dockx, “Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 84f. Natural things achieve their proximate ends and in this achievement they attain the divine similitude to which they are proportionate (ScG, III, chaps. 17–18). Hence, God remains the ultimate end by way of the proximate end. 140 See ST I, q. 62, a. 4; ST I–II, q. 114, a. 3; and Super Epist. Ad Rom., chap. 8, lect. 4, par. 655. 141 In his commentary on Romans, Thomas raises a difficulty. Paul states, “To one who works, his wages are not reckoned as a gift but as his due” (Rom 4:4, RSV). The statement has had a twofold exposition.Thomas judges, correctly in my estimation, that the literal sense is that a to-be-justified person does not work, since justification cannot be condignly merited (for this point, see Super Epist. Ad Rom., chap. 6, lect. 4, par. 517). What is interesting is Thomas’s iteration of another, then entertained, exegesis. Some read the statement as true and applicable of one who is already graced.While Thomas will not agree that Paul has such a person in mind here, yet, what Thomas says of this person he holds to be truth. Read in this way, the statement requires a word of precision (I stress it): “not reckoned as a gift alone but as something due (secundum debitum ).” Such a claim raises a difficulty, however, apparently conflicting with Paul’s statement in Rom 8:18: “The sufferings of this time are not worthy of future glory” (Vulg.). The latter passage seems to make one conclude,“Accordingly, that recompense is not rendered according to debt but according to grace.”Thomas solves the apparent contradiction with his standard distinction of two ways of considering the works of the justified: (1) simply as products of free will, or (2) as produced by the free 600 Christopher J. Malloy supernatural order. Because of this order, to which all freely acting persons are at least called and for which all are freely bought by Christ, certain persons are blessed with the power to become sons ( Jn will insofar as it is moved by its principle, God predestining. Although considered in the first way, such works “do not have anything condign, that the reward of eternal life may be given them,” yet in the second way, “the aforesaid reward is owed them as something due,” for they have become sons (Rom 8:14). In connection with this non-literal reading, Paul’s “who does not work” is understood with regard to external works, which, because some might not have occasion to perform them, are not in all cases required (Super Epist. Ad Rom., chap. 4, lect. 1, par. 329–30). For the literal exposition, which regards the man to-bejustified, see ibid., par. 331. In earlier texts,Thomas states that, by meriting, which presupposes election and grace, we make something our due (see In III Sent., d. 18, q. 1, a. 4, qla 1, ad 1), as by sinning Adam made death our due (see In III Sent., d. 19, q. 1, a. 1, qla 1). See also In II Sent., d. 38, q. 1, a. 2.This latter text gives evidence of a proportionate proximate end being due to a thing of a given nature, for the end proper to each thing is its proper operation. The ultimate end, God, to which each thing is ordained as to its end, is not obtained except through the medium of this proximate operation. Here, we encounter the desirable precision: It is not God whom one makes due to oneself through acts of charity but rather the consummate operation (glory) by which one is united to God, himself the end to which one is referred. Now, that this text identifies the ultimate operation of man as the beatific vision should be read as follows: The perfection naturally attainable by man remains ineffably less than the perfection of the beatific vision, though sufficiently terminative to bring adequate rest to the appetite (on this, see Hütter, “Natural Desire,” 570, 573–79, and 586f.). Therefore, natural perfection is not ultimate. Further, on account of its less than perfect character, natural perfection is per se specifiable by the supernatural end (see Malevez,“La gratuité du surnaturel,” 683–85, and Hütter,“Desiderium,” 101). Clearly, the supernatural end is not “due” to human nature, though Thomas in this article speaks of the proper end as being due. Again,Thomas writes,“Mereri, sicut dictum est, est facere aliquid sibi debitum. Hoc autem contingit tribus modis. Uno modo quando aliquis facit de non debito debitum; sicut aliquis primo motu caritatis meretur vitam aeternam, faciens eam debitam sibi, quae prius ei debita non erat” (In III Sent., d. 18, q. 1, and 5; see also ibid., a. 2). Earlier, he had specified that the natural “vision” of God (“vision” here is to be understood quite analogously) is naturally due to the angels (In II Sent., d. 4, q. 1, a. 1). Again, he writes, “Dupliciter autem aliquid debitum existit: uno quidem modo secundum naturam, alio modo secundum operationem. . . . Secundum operationem autem, sicut merces operanti debetur. Illa ergo dona sunt hominibus divinitus gratis data quae et ordinem naturae excedunt, et meritis non acquiruntur, quamvis et ea quae pro meritis divinitus dantur, interdum gratiae nomen vel rationem non amittant: tum quia principium merendi fuit a gratia, tum etiam quia superabundantius dantur quam merita humana requirant” (Compendium theologiae I, chap. 214). Implied here is that what is rendered according to merits is due on the supposition of its principles, grace and the virtues, and the call according to which these are infused. Indeed, as De Lubac on Natural Desire 601 1:12), heirs of the promise (Gal 4:7 and Rom 8:17) whose good works God promises to reward. Those who die in divine grace are heirs to eternal life.142 This point is not hindered by the fact that, on account of the infinitely tender mercy of God, just as punishment will be lighter than guilt, so the reward rendered will exceed merit.143 To work something greater than justice (according to a certain equality of proportion)144 is one thing; to work something less is another.145 Borrowing Paul’s image of “clay” in the hands of the potter,Thomas mercy founds the natural order and the justice pertinent to orders of exigence established therein, so mercy founds the supernatural order and the justice of orders of exigence promised therein.The teaching continues in Thomas’s mature works. See ST I–II, q. 111, a. 1, ad 2, wherein Thomas links merit with that which is due.As is clear to anyone with a remote understanding of Thomas, dona supernaturalia are not due to man. Dona supernaturalia, as the very question indicates, regard the following: grace, infused virtues, gifts, etc. Significantly, vita aeterna does not fall under the dona supernaturalia simply as a principle of action. Grace, infused virtues, gifts, etc., are principles of action and, as such, they are not merited. Vita aeterna, though the supreme gift, also constitutes an object attained by proportionate action. Since grace and the theological virtues and infused moral virtues, etc., render human action capable of attaining it, vita aeterna is also something condignly merited.Thomas clarifies, in ST I–II, q. 112, a. 2, ad 1, that whereas grace is not merited, glory is. Similarly, he makes clear in ST I–II, q. 114, a. 3, sc, that the reward is rendered according to (covenantally established) justice. 142 See ST I–II, q. 114, a. 3, and Super Epist. Ad Rom., chap. 8, lect. 4, pars. 652–55. This title, supreme, packs compositely other gifts. On account of the dignity of deification with which God initially constituted men, they were “naturally” (i.e., supernaturally) immortal. On account of this gift of immortality, “it was due to [man] to receive an incorruptible body” (debebatur sibi incorruptiblile corpus [Super Epist. Ad Rom., chap. 5, lect. 3, par. 416]). 143 See, e.g., In Psalm 35, par. 4; ST I, q. 21, a. 4; and Compendium theologiae I, chap. 214. 144 See Super II Ad Corinth., chap. 4, lect. 5, par. 150. 145 See In IV Sent., d. 46, q. 1, a. 2, qla 2.This quaestiuncula is quite significant. It will be pointed out that Thomas twice states that he is “speaking of the ordinary [divine] power.”There are no grounds that I see for interpreting this to mean that God could by his absolute power withhold what is due. Rather, in drawing the distinction between the ordinary or ordained power and the absolute power of God,Thomas maintains that God could have created other things and could have ordered creation otherwise than he has.To us, some other order of things might appear inconveniens, but it would not in fact be unjust (see, e.g., ST I, q. 25, a. 5, ad 3).Any order would be patterned upon divine wisdom. In the quaestiuncula,Thomas says that God could not act against the just order established, speaking of his ordinary power, just as he could not make something without it imitating him, insofar as it participates being. But in no order could any created thing not imitate God! One may also urge that the common assertion that William of Ockham invented the distinction between the powers of God is erroneous; it is.Yet, Ockham’s innovation by “his association of God’s absolute power with the ontological singular” 602 Christopher J. Malloy draws an analogy between natural debt and supernatural debt:Whereas it is not due to unformed clay that it be formed this way or that, yet it is due to clay formed nobly that it be put to noble use; so, as it is not due to nature to receive grace, yet it is due to one deified to receive glory.146 Further, per impossibile (supposing the impossible), were damned persons to convert to God by grace,“it would be unjust (iniquum) for them to be punished perpetually after they had gained a good will.”147 Similarly, God would violate his own justice if he were to deprive an already beatified creature of the vision of God.148 As the debitum naturae does not make God debtor to the creature but to himself, neither does Christian merit make God a debtor to us.149 God brings to completion that which he initiates, for he is faithful to himself. The heart of the matter, therefore, is that since God (Mary Anne Pernoud, “The Theory of the Potentia Dei According to Aquinas, Scotus and Ockham,” Antonianum 47 [1972]: 92) is most significant indeed. Each “thing” is considered chiefly as a singular, and formal causality is minimized because both conceived as plural in individuals (see André Goddu, “Ockham’s Philosophy of Nature,” in The Cambridge Companion to Ockham, 148f., and Marilyn McCord Adams, William Ockham, 2 vols., no. 26, Publications in Medieval Studies, ed. Ralph McInerny [Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987], chap. 15) and considered an individual in relation to prime matter (see Maurer, Philosophy of William of Ockham, 399f.), which is said to have its own being and intelligibility (see Adams, Ockham, 646f.). For Ockham, the forma totius is an empty concept (see Maurer, 393f.).What remains to be appreciated in the causal relations among things is chiefly efficient causality. Hence, different kinds of motion are reduced to local “motions of the parts” (Goddu, 149). Ockham’s emphasis on freedom of indifference, moreover, eclipses final causality, since it is the agent’s willing X that establishes X as end. In such a framework, talk of the due order of one thing to another loses traction; accidents proper to certain ways of being are too easily dismissed as nonnecessary instrumental efficient causes. And of course God can do without these (see William of Ockham, Quodl. 6, q. 6 [Opera theologica, vol. 9, 604f.: 18–20]).Advertence to the profound difference between Aquinas’s thought and these notes of Ockham’s metaphysics should caution one from concluding that their readings of potentia absoluta were not significantly different (cf. Pernoud, 91).Whereas Ockham teaches that God can both absolve someone from sin and save him without the infusion of created grace (see William of Ockham, Quodl. 3, q. 10, a. 2 [Opera theologica, vol. 9, 241:35–43]; idem, In I Sent., d. 17, q. 1 [Opera theologica, vol. 3, 452–56]; and Maurer, 261–63), Aquinas holds grace to be the formal cause of deification, without the infusion of which “the remission of sins cannot be understood” (ST I–II, q. 113, a. 2). 146 See In IV Sent., d. 46, q. 1, a. 2, qla 1, ad 2; see also Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 225. 147 ScG IV, chap. 93, par. 2. 148 See ST I–II, q. 5, a. 4. 149 See ST I–II, q. 114, a. 1, ad 3. De Lubac on Natural Desire 603 is faithful to himself, there is a proper place for debt.This means that we are speaking, ultimately, of the intelligibility of the divinely willed motions in creation. For Thomas, no motion is intelligible without respect to its end. To deny either debitum naturae or Christian merit thus strikes either at the very intelligibility or at the “efficacity” of the divine motions in creatures. In willing some order, God wills the attainment of the intrinsic end of that order—the manifestation of his glory through creatures’ attainments of their ends. Although not each thing must needs achieve its end in every case, yet, I would argue, the very intelligibility of the order as a whole requires the non-impossibility in that order of the attainment of the end of the order, which attainment will involve, ultimately, the chief things in that order. Indeed, the very inclination each thing has for its proportionate end is instilled in it by the author of nature150 who in authoring an order promulgates a law that corresponds thereto.151 To say, then, that there is an innate natural inclination to an end surpassing both the resources within the natural order and the divine providential solicitude formally pertinent thereto is to say that God, as author of nature, creates to no end, that he instills a motion that has no aim.152 It is here that we discover a theo-logical rebuttal to de Lubac’s appeal to Ockham’s statement in defense of an absolute, innate, yet inefficacious desire: Since God is debtor to himself, the order he establishes must be possible of fruition.153 The to my mind self-evident assumption that undergirds 150 See ST I, q. 105, a. 4, and Sententia libri Ethicorum I, lect. 2, par. 21. 151 ST I–II, q. 93, a. 6. If law is ordered to an end, just what “end” could God ever have in mind by the natural law of reason if there were no relatively sufficient finality? 152 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 227–29 and 370–72. Cf. Dockx,“Du désir naturel de voir l’essence divine,” 91. 153 Two points in response to de Lubac’s anthem of an absolute and inefficacious desire are in order. First,Thomas nowhere, to my knowledge, states unequivocally that there is a real albeit insufficient order to or desire for the supernatural end. There is one apparent exception: In Boet. De Trinitate, q. 6, a. 4, ad 5. Indeed, one might take this text as a genuine exception. Or, one might take it, as one can take ibid., q. 1, a. 3, ad 4, as inconclusive. (On Sylvester of Ferrara’s interpretation of the former text and texts similar thereto, see Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 184–88 and 399, n. 6.) Even in the midst of texts stressing the natural desire to see God,Thomas can, as Long notes, express himself more precisely:“Intellectus igitur quantumcumque modicum posit de divina cognitione percipere, illud erit sibi pro ultimo fine, magis quam perfecta cognitio inferiorum intelligibilium” (ScG III, chap. 25, par. 6; see Long, “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 144). Relevant to a full analysis of the entire argument in ScG III, chaps. 25–51, is a well-rounded reading of Thomas that appreciates nuance and complexity. Aquinas himself invites this nuance in key places; see, for instance, ScG I, chap. 11, 604 Christopher J. Malloy my evaluation is thus dialectically validated:To hold as possible a meaningless world is simply absurd.154 4. A Final Lubacian Strategy. I consider that the above reflections also undercut the viability of de Lubac’s final strategy to identify the gratuity of grace, namely, his appeal to our desire to receive the gift as something gratuitous and unexpected.155 Guy Mansini has raised the objection that to desire something with a “precisive qua, [a] specifying as” is to have a consciously molded desire.156 Such a desire could not be innate; it would have to be elicited; thus, it need not be unconditional. If Mansini’s argument holds, it cuts off the effectiveness of this final appeal. However, further elaboration seems to me desirable. I find three difficulties with the Lubacian appeal. A person depicted as one who desires beatific union with God but remains not-expectant, one “holding-[himself]-in-readiness,”157 appears to me both unfittingly par. 5 (sic enim homo). For a recent and contextualized exegesis of ScG III, chap. 25, see Hütter, “Natural Desire.” Second, when Thomas claims that natural principles do not suffice, he does not mean that they really and innately but insufficiently incline. In each case, he draws an analogy between principle and finality: As natural principles order or incline to connatural ends, so supernatural principles order or incline to supernatural ends. The latter principles are therefore necessary for there to be said inclination (see note 88 above). I would point to the following text: “The end towards which the divine generosity directs or predestines man, namely, the fruition of himself, is in every way elevated above the faculty of created nature. . . .Therefore, by his natural principles alone, man does not sufficiently have an inclination to that end.” De Lubac concludes that Thomas holds he does have an insufficient inclination.Thomas intends nothing of the sort: “Therefore, it is necessary that there be superadded to man something by which he may have an inclination to that end, as by his natural principles he has an inclination to the end that is connatural to him. . . . For as that end is ordained for us by God not through our nature, so the inclination to the end is worked in us solely by God” (In III Sent., d. 23, q. 1, a. 4, qla 3).Thomas manifests the principle underlying this point elsewhere:“The act of anything is not divinely ordered to something exceeding the proportion of the power which is the principle of the act.” It is a matter of divine institution “that nothing act beyond its power” (ST I–II, q. 114, a. 2).Thomas’s diction “not sufficient” or “insufficiently” need not imply “a real but insufficient”; it certainly implies nothing of the sort when he states,“Free will is not a sufficient cause of [read ‘condign’] merit” (ST I, q 62, a. 4). Has Thomas become semi-Pelagian? In short,Thomas means that nature and natural principles incline to the supernatural end only when moved by grace, actual and/or habitual. 154 See Léonard, “The Theological Necessity,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 328. 155 Healy (“Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace”) sets this strategy in relief. 156 See Mansini, “Surnaturel,” 605f. 157 Healy, “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 547 (see also 548 and 561f.). De Lubac on Natural Desire 605 heroic and tragic. (a) Such a one seems oriented towards God as Father before God has become his Father, that is, before God has adopted him as son. His disponibility renders him already gracious towards God. But one cannot present oneself to God graciously with a graciousness that is not received (1 Cor 4:7).There can be no son who has no father ( Jn 5:19f.), just as no son can “contribute” to his own generation,158 unless we are speaking of acts of free will preparatory to justification. But since such acts do not produce justifying grace but only dispose one thereto—whether because enabled by actual graces (Dominican thesis) or because recognized graciously by God (Franciscan thesis)—even in this light no one is made a child of God even by the will of man ( Jn 1:13f.). Mansini’s remark that de Lubac here turns apologetics into mystagogical catechesis targets this difficulty.159 (b) Appearing tragic, such a person exhibits the root difficulty, for it is an absurd world that constitutes the condition for the possibility of such remarkable patience. That absurdity renders the patience nihilistic. It is tantamount to a meaningless holding oneself, as some post-modernists say,“in a mature proximity to absence.”160 (c) Granted, I cannot place particular demands upon my friend, and God is an ultimate friend, truly through charity and in some respect even in a purely natural order. Still, we must draw distinctions.Two unrelated men who encounter one another may or may not engage in actual friendship; their resources are limited. Neither has a claim of friendship on the other.Yet, if one is son to the other, if they are brothers, if they dwell in the same city, if they share a nature (!), we can begin to speak of claims of justice that are not destroyed but protected by any friendship that might develop. Further, should one approach the other in an offer of friendship, the other is not wrong to take this offer as a gesture of intended friendship and to base his decisions in accordance with that judgment.That is, friendship is also a state, not a kind of existential stringing-out of possibly continuing affection—not a tease made delightful only through surprising renewals. Now, in establishing a created order, God takes that initiative. He already gestures. Thus, there is a lack of parity in our comparison 158 Cf., Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Last Act, trans. Graham Harrison, vol. 5, Theo- Drama:Theological Dramatic Theory (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1998), 86:“This ‘passive actio’ is a condition [Mitbedingung] of the ‘active actio’ and imparts to the latter a certain quality of ‘letting go.’ ” 159 See Mansini, “Surnaturel,” 616 in the context of 612–17. 160 Louis-Marie Chauvet, Symbol and Sacrament:A Sacramental Reinterpretation of Christian Existence, trans. Patrick Madigan and Madeleine Beaumont (Collegeville, MN:The Liturgical Press, 1995), 58–81. 606 Christopher J. Malloy between two unrelated (!) men and between the human being and God.The very creative act signals a real commitment on God’s part to a dynamically coherent order.The human response of pursuing hopefully (in a natural sense) the fulfillment of natural inclinations would thus only wrongly be conceived as placing demands upon God. Such hopeful pursuits flower organically. But what meaning can Lubacians find in any world without grace?161 Finally, of course, one must grant the precious insight that de Lubac (and Healy and others) offer:The greatest saints wish to love without conditions, and so, they (more and more frequently) stress that their desire is to love, not to “merit.”Their heaven does not rest with vision but beats with ecstatic love.Who can gainsay them? Notwithstanding, it would be a mistake to interpret (and then pit) the saints’ wishes against dogmas—for instance, that we “truly merit” eternal life (Trent, Session VI, Canon 32). Saints are awakened to this love that shines upon them.The trajectory of their love is the trajectory of ever more purified intentionality, beginning with a desire for their own good and reaching the point at which only the beloved counts and therefore union with him. The saints do not transgress the teachings of Trent with their minds but transcend them with their hearts.162 In connection with this concern about a meaningless world, one can ask whether de Lubac implies the moral wretchedness of created spirit.163 Purely Natural Man Morally Wretched or Sub-personal? First, the naturally realized despair, outlined above, seems to point in the direction of natural wretchedness. Unless somehow such innocent creatures were supernaturally or preternaturally (i.e., with an ad hoc solution) preserved from awareness of their awful state, they would despair.164 Such a state, even if it could not be theological despair, would seem to hinder 161 Pinckaers importantly contends that the human person who awaits God non- expectantly would attain an “imperfect yet real ” beatitude (“The Natural Desire to See God,” 642, emphasis mine). In good Franciscan (!) fashion, he even describes the situation as involving “a very pure joy that could, in principle, constitute a real bliss, though imperfect” (644). 162 This transcendence is the hermeneutical key to oblations such as St. Thérèse’s and to total consecrations to Mary Immaculate, the sacrificial characters of which are premised upon the teachings of the Church (see Trent, Session VI, chap. 16, and canons 26 and 32). 163 It ought to go without saying that such wretchedness could be only of a completely different order than that of offense against the intimate advance of the Trinity. 164 It seems to me entirely contrary to the spirit of de Lubac to think of such odd possibilities; see only Mystery, 203f. De Lubac on Natural Desire 607 virtuous action.Would, then, preventative graces be “due”? But nothing can be due! So, natural and innocent man would be unable to live a virtuous life. But if this were the case, grace would not perfect but destroy what is natural.165 Second, natural moral wretchedness is found in the early de Lubac’s examination of a pair of disputed texts regarding angelic sin. (Though Thomas’s texts concern angels, they have implications for features of human life, and de Lubac seems willing to draw them.)166 The dispute: According to some,Thomas implies (from prima pars on) that, were angels created in the state of pure nature, they could not sin.These interpreters point to texts in which Thomas teaches that purely natural angels would enjoy all natural goods pertinent to them upon their creation. Thus, it could be only with respect to supernatural goods, to which alone they as separated substances would be in potency, that they could sin. So, they could sin only if God were to offer grace.167 They would sin only if they refused it. This reading is disputed by others who point to Thomas’s consistent teaching that no created thing can by nature be impeccable.168 165 See ST I, q. 60, a. 5. 166 Gagnebet makes a reasonable case that what de Lubac teaches regarding the angels applies, mutatis mutandis, to his views regarding man (see M.-R. Gagnebet, “L’amour naturel de Dieu chez saint Thomas et ses contemporains,” Revue thomiste 48 [1948]: 396, referring to de Lubac, Surnaturel, 432, and 247, n. 2). De Lubac’s note makes reference, approvingly, to Jean Mouroux, Sens chrétien de l’homme (Paris:Aubler, 1945), 176–81; in English translation: The Meaning of Man, trans. A. H. G. Downes (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1961), 182–86. 167 See De malo, q. 16, a. 3; ST I, q. 63, a. 1, ad 3, and ibid., a. 3. One can add whatever one wishes concerning the interrelations of these angels (the higher teaching the lower); all such interrelations would not, it seems to me, interfere with Thomas’s basic point that separated substances naturally attain their natural ends instantly.There may be another pertinent difficulty, however. Although the issue is enormously tricky, I venture a question: Might such readings be differently construed were they more grounded in advertence to a distinction between (a) love of one’s own beatitude and (b) an ordering of self to God as finis cui, not, indeed as to one who benefits from our action (see ScG III, chap. 18, n. 5) but as to one to whom we dedicate ourselves, to whom we will the good? On the other hand, Gagnebet’s analysis in favor of such readings is impressive and difficult to contest (see “L’amour II,” 1949, 72–86). 168 See De veritate, q. 24, a. 7; ScG III, chap. 109; and ST I, q. 63, a. 1. Is this implicit in ScG III, chap. 1, n. 5 (see also Hütter, “Natural Desire,” 539f.)? Of course, the first group agrees that no creature is “naturally impeccable” since by this phrase is meant only “that which has in its nature certain principles such that sin is absolutely repugnant to it” in any order (see the following fine article: C. Courtès, “La peccabilité de l’ange chez saint Thomas,” Revue thomiste 53 [1953]: 158, n. 5). After all, ST I, q. 63, a. 1 houses the ‘ad 3’ just noted. 608 Christopher J. Malloy So, this second group concludes, by “goods pertaining to the natural order”—with reference to which Thomas says no angel can sin—Thomas signifies those goods “within the reach” of an angelic nature. Such goods exclude both supernatural goods and also that good which is the angel’s natural but theo-centric end. (Goods within an angel’s reach would include self-knowledge, knowledge of some natures lower that that angel, acts of will dependent upon such knowledge, etc.) Inasmuch as he rejects the former group, de Lubac is closer to the latter group.169 Now, if the reading by the first group is accurate (and about this I am uncertain), these texts bear unmistakable witness to the intelligibility of a natural finality. At any rate, whereas the champions of the second group do not hold that such angels would of necessity sin, de Lubac’s early work implies that the angels would. There, he holds that angels can have no natural and theocentric end.170 Thus, they can have no natural, elected “turning to the Creator.”Their only possible natural love of God above all would be preelective and pre-moral. Such love is the natural love present even in the demons.171 The love necessary for a free love of God—and here, de Lubac appears to include any rational spirit—is the “amor gratuitus, alone meritorious because in it alone is morality completed.”172 “[C]ompleted” does not mean “further perfected” but “actually achieved,” and such achievement requires grace: “A spirit . . . must come to its ‘conversion,’ that is to a choice, and this makes it necessarily enter into the supernatural or exclude itself therefrom.”173 Here, de Lubac is speaking about any 169 See Augustinianism, 169; and Surnaturel, 231–60. For a treatment of the tacit dialogue between Maritain and de Lubac, see René Mougel, “The Position of Jacques Maritain Regarding Surnaturel : The Sin of the Angel, or ‘Spirit and Liberty,’ ” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 59–83. 170 See references in note 94, especially Surnaturel, 240–41. Long’s diagnosis is on the mark (see Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 134f., n. 3, and 151). 171 It is analogically present in all created things, for God is the end of all things (see ST I, q. 60, a. 5, ad 5, and note 139 above). 172 Surnaturel, 250. 173 Surnaturel, 256f. For a brief exposition of de Lubac’s explicit claims and the apparent scope thereof, see Gagnebet, “L’amour,” 1948, 394–97 and idem, “L’amour II,” 1949, 48–54 and 72f. For Thomas’s thought to the contrary, see, e.g., ST I, q. 60 and De caritate, a. 2, ad 15.The discussion in ST I, q. 60, is highly nuanced and relates “natural love” to various other loves—supernatural, rational, elected, etc. Although Thomas holds that there remains a “natural love” of God in the demons—one that could not be elected—such a love is not the only one that he calls “natural” in this question. Again, in ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3, Thomas simply cannot be asking about a natural, non-elected love (see Gagnebet, “L’amour II,” 1949, 45.The nub of the problem is stated well on ibid., 92). De Lubac on Natural Desire 609 spirit.174 Consistently, de Lubac adds that natural love reaches God only as principle of being but not as object.175 Thomas, to the contrary, describes natural rational love (dilectio) as reaching God as the principle and end in the state of integral nature.176 Further, for Thomas there is not only a non-elected natural rational love of God but also a freely elected, natural rational love of God.177 M.-R. Gagnebet has 174 Was the early de Lubac in agreement with the nominalist John Bockingham, who claimed that any soul God can create must be either in mortal sin or worthy of the beatific vision (see Augustinianism, 109)? 175 See Surnaturel, 251 and 255. Although Braine does not state the matter thus, he implies that a virtuously lived life in the state of pure nature would not be possible without certain preternatural gifts (see “The Debate,” 565). That Braine implies a natural misery is evident from the references given in note 120. Besides these references, I would indicate Braine’s clear definition of “extrinsicism”: that conception according to which “the gift of grace when given comes as something entirely unnecessary to the good life as such—necessary only to give mankind the means to a higher end, a greater beatitude” (571; see also 575). If one allows for a possibly softened sense of “entirely unnecessary”—which allowance I believe would still allow the spirit of the point Braine wishes to make—one can object to the description of this conception as “extrinsicist.” First, the objection. By simply turning the tables, I would submit that if grace is absolutely necessary to the intelligibility of created man, then grace is necessary. And grace would be so necessary should created man have no proportionate end that could meaningfully satisfy his appetite. Second, the softening. Of course, certain preternatural gifts and certain determinations of natural law could be described as highly fitting, though probably not as “absolutely necessary.”Aquinas walks a delicate tightrope on this matter, offering diverse arguments for the giving of divine law (see ST I–II, q. 91, a. 4). Only the first reason in the responsio indicates necessary grounds for divine law even for those without sin—that God ordains men to a supernatural end. For an exposition of Aquinas on this matter and for criticisms of de Lubac’s Surnaturel also relevant to Braine’s thesis, see Gagnebet, “L’amour II,” 1949, 50–72. Gagnebet maintains both that man in a natural state would be capable of a fully moral life and that his end would not be obtained terrestrially but only post-terrestrially (see 61–72). (Gagnebet’s analysis is profound and, in my opinion, accurate.) To be sure, Braine does call to mind the actual order of grace, human freedom, and sin as concretely grounding the gratuity (see, esp., 584f. and 589). Sin no doubt makes grace triply gratuitous. Human freedom—if not simply nominally conceived—does render the effects of grace (but not the divine will, as Lonergan reminds us, refusing to ascribe to any created motion any divine attributes) contingent. But to render the effects of grace contingent is not to identify the gratuity of grace. 176 See ST I–II, q. 62, a. 1, ad 3; De virtutibus, q. 4, a. 1, ad 9; Super I Ad Corinth., chap. 13, lect. 4, par. 806; and ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3, ad 1. 177 A person in a purely natural state can love God above himself naturally and freely. See In III Sent., d. 29, a. 3; De divinis nominibus, chap. 4, lect. 9 and 10; ST I, q. 60, a. 5; ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3; Quodl. I, q. 4, a. 3; and ST II–II, q. 26, a. 3. Especially 610 Christopher J. Malloy amply demonstrated this claim.178 (Of course, according to Aquinas, sin so dampens human nature’s vigor that it is not possible for postlapsarian man to elicit a free act of love for God without grace.)179 Since turning to the Source and End of being is the acme of what natural law calls for, were one unable to turn to the first cause freely even in the state of integral nature, one would be, in any order without supernatural grace, both naturally miserable and also naturally wretched (or sub-personal).180 noteworthy is Thomas’s affirmation that this natural love could be used “more or less” by a rational creature (in the state of integral nature) in preparation for grace (see Quodl. I, q. 4, a. 3, ad 2). For a good, recent presentation, see Thomas Osborne, Love of Self and Love of God in Thirteenth Century Ethics (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005), 70–86. For references concerning de Lubac’s rhetorical criticism of the possibility of a free, natural, and God-centered love, see note 7 above. 178 See M.-R. Gagnebet, “L’amour,” 1948, 424–46, and idem, “L’amour II,” 1949, 31–102. 179 See ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3. Thomas describe the human condition after sin, the condition into which we are born (antecedent to our experience of immoral neighbors), as one in which we spontaneously prefer our limited, private good to the true common good. The explanation he gives is that nature, though not altered in its principles, is wounded, so that a man cannot without grace achieve the most important things for which he is naturally constituted, things he could achieve were he in a state of integral nature. A static image of this wound could be a fractured plate that has not fallen asunder. A dynamic image might be a car whose engine, though intact, has suffered harm: It can putter at 35 MPH but it cannot do its factory-advertised maximum. Just why this is so, or how, is difficult to discern. That Adam has not only lost gifts but acquired disorder is clear, but why does the generative act produce other than a man intrinsically in a natural state, whose concupiscence is materially natural, and only extrinsically in a state of sin (in virtue of the divine judgment)? Might another explanation be the ubiquity of God’s condescension to man and the concrete determination of free man’s sole ultimate end? In short, man is confronted by God’s offer of himself. Thus, one cannot lovingly choose to love God in a purely natural way; one cannot lovingly choose to have a purely natural relationship with the God who calls, for to do so would be to offend seriously that very God, exposing the truth that one never in fact loved him (that is, freely) at all.Whoever loves a friend is ready to respond to that friend, and whereas finite friends can advance intimacy unfittingly or immoderately or in an untimely or imprudent manner, the Uncreated Friend’s every move is fitting. For a fine account of the vitiation of the natural inclination in fallen man, see Jacques Maritain,“La dialectique immanente du premier acte de liberté,” Raison et raisons (Paris: Egloff, 1947), 139–46. 180 To explain Thomas’s texts on angelic sin, one can attend to Thomas’s teachings on the radical freedom of the will with regard to specification of the object and formation of practical judgments. Also, one can heed Thomas’s teaching on love of the finis cui. For a list of texts in the commentatorial tradition defending the view that angels could not sin unless called to the beatific vision and that their De Lubac on Natural Desire 611 Because de Lubac seems driven to his positive thesis in virtue of his presuppositions concerning a purely natural order, I now turn to consider these. Presuppositions of de Lubac’s Diagnosis Purely Natural Man Autonomous? De Lubac considers that were man not to have an absolute and inefficacious desire for the supernatural, he would not be radically dependent upon God. But on the contrary, neither Thomas nor reliable defenders of the theory of “pure nature” leave space for autonomous self-actuation.181 It must be granted that there have been some deviations.182 However, even “average” theological approaches avoid such deviations.183 In any case, we may dismiss deviations as irrelevant. When Thomas entertains the powers of the integral state of human nature, he adds the cautious reminder: Man can do nothing “without the divine help.”This divine help is not the auxilium of entitatively supernatural grace; it is the natural providential help, requisite in the natural order, just as the auxilium of grace is uniquely requisite in the supernatural order.184 Were man created in a purely natural state, God, transcendently causing every reduction of potency to act,185 would sustain him in a good state of being, moving him to his fitting end interiorly and by the instrumental agency of an unspeakably vast array of interconnected secondary causes.186 The divine causality would be all encompassing efficiently, exemplarily, and with respect to finality. Further, a being’s achievement of its end, a return to the First Being according to its own “being not impeccable” is a predicate ascribed to them because there is possible a world in which they are peccable, that of the call to glory, see Surnaturel, 315ff. For a classic defense that the predicate “peccable” applies to any but the glorified angels, see Jacques Maritain, The Sin of the Angel: An Essay on a Re-Interpretation of Some Thomistic Positions, trans. William Rossner (Westminster, MD: The Newman Press, 1959). For a lucid treatment of Thomas’s appreciation of created freedom, see Tobias Hoffmann,“Aquinas and Intellectual Determinism:The Test Case of Angelic Sin,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89 (2007): 122–56. 181 See, e.g., ST I–II, q. 109, aa. 1–3; see also Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 224, n. 44, and 314, n. 69. 182 Healy points to some examples (see “Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” 545f.). 183 See, e.g., the following work of a professor of letters: Louis Mercier, American Humanism and the New Age (Milwaukee:The Bruce Publishing Company, 1943), 72–77. 184 See ST I–II, q. 109, a. 1. 185 See ST I, q. 44, a. 1 and ST I, q. 105, a. 5. 186 See, e.g., ST I–II, q. 98, a. 4, ad 3. 612 Christopher J. Malloy modality, would manifest the splendor of being-itself-subsisting.187 In fact, the Thomistic view on the ubiquity of divine causality continues to raise consternated eyebrows.188 It is thus difficult to fathom on what grounds de Lubac and others could content themselves, on this point, with a critique of a strawman. Purely Natural Man Incurious? Finally, does not de Lubac presuppose the irrelevance of grace to a man in a purely natural state when he describes such a one as not being dynamically open to God?189 Apparently, de Lubac finds the only relevance of grace in the coupling of his positive and negative theses: “It is precisely because the ultimate finality of this human nature is supernatural that it can receive sanctifying grace.There is in it not only an ‘obediential potency’ [ potentia obedientiae], but a certain ‘natural order’ [ordo naturalis] to the receiving of that grace, whereas in the case of miracle such ‘ordo naturalis’ does not exist.”190 But on the contrary, human beings qua human (that is, conceived apart from grace) are uniquely fit for a divine self-disclosure. 187 See ScG III, chap. 25, par. 1. 188 Scathing remarks have been made about a recent, rather straightforward, Thomistic defense of the ubiquity of providence. See Long, “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 167–72, and his earlier essay (Steven Long, “Providence, Freedom, and Natural Law,” Nova et Vetera 4 [2006]: 557–605). Long’s diagnosis is profound: Modern man accepts from Molina an “aseity of the will.” Also apathetic towards the supernatural, modern man thus considers himself allsufficient (see 171). Notwithstanding these remarks, I find Lonergan’s solution more attentive to the analogy of faith than either the two-lane highway Long seems to espouse or the four-lane highway Molina embraces (see Bernard Lonergan, Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St.Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1, Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan [Toronto: 2000]). Further, I sympathize with Braine’s criticisms of a certain monergism (see “The Debate,” 587–89). However, perhaps here I have fallen prey to the medicinalism I shall charge against Lubacians (see the end of this essay). 189 See note 94 above. In addition, de Lubac at times describes the natural end, as conceived in this hypothesis, as though it were thought to be equally alternative to the supernatural (see Surnaturel, 453).At other times, he admits the legitimacy of holding two ends, one subordinated to the other (see ibid, 452), yet he describes the subordinated one as not theo-centric. Incidentally, Braine helpfully asks us to follow Thomas’s expression: a twofold end, not two ends (see “The Debate,” 560). However, Braine also conceives of a purely natural order as implying “nothing beyond a mundane kind of existence,” making it true from a certain perspective that man would thus be placed “back among the brutes” (“The Debate,” 565). 190 Mystery, 141–42 (emphases mine). De Lubac on Natural Desire 613 1. Wonder within Imperfect Beatitude. Were man created in a purely natural state, he would come profoundly to wonder about and love the first cause.191 One could even trace philosophical and mystical dimensions of this human desire.192 The origin of the speculative 191 The considerations to follow in the text are not antithetical to the work of Karl Rahner, different epistemological frameworks notwithstanding. For Rahner, rational man is self-transcending: In any particular act of cognition, man gathers a glimmer of the horizon, which recedes before him the more he seeks it. But in this receding of the horizon, man actually approaches it asymptotically. It would be false to ascribe to Rahner an “asymptotic” approach that blurred the distinction between the formality of the supernatural desire and the formality of the natural desire (Braine ascribes such a blurring to von Balthasar [see “The Debate,” 565 and 585]; Coffey rightly denies it of Rahner [see “The Whole Rahner,” 104f.]). This ever-transcending character of human knowing makes man uniquely fit for a divine self-disclosure, although we must, in an effort to consider this character, not color it too much with the tints and hues of concrete life, which is imbued already with the supernatural existential and with grace (see Rahner, Hearer; and Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 579f.). God in fact seizes everyone by creating each with an abiding ordination to grace, the “supernatural existential,” by which all that is in us is polarized by a “new,” inmost determination of our being, though one not identical to us in our natural being. Again, on the supernatural existential, see Coffey, 95–118. I would take issue with Rahner’s theory insofar as it (a) appears paradoxically to make “machinelike” the personal and particular movements of grace in man and (b) seems to beg the question as to how it may be an “inmost determination” while not being either constitutive of natural being or itself the habitus gratiae. Still, might we find some parallels between aspects of the supernatural existential and the traditional notion of “actual graces”? I propose this as a furthering of Coffey’s suggestion (see note 101 above) that the supernatural existential might be seen, on the order of material causality, as the penultimate preparation for indwelling. (Sanctifying grace would be the ultimate disposition for indwelling.) Paramount for my suggestion is the insistence that God is absolutely immutable. Consequently, an “offer of selfcommunication,” if it is to constitute neither essential human principles nor habitual grace would seem to have to have some other ontological status. I suggest it may be a single term for the resultant existential complexity of the human condition due to the multifarious sets of actual graces by which God “hounds” after souls, thereby coloring the human condition (see Malevez, 678f.). Should man in a free, particular decision—and here, I would wish to part with Rahner’s sequestration of the decision to an athematic realm, however true it is that no man can with certainty judge his own heart—abandon this divine play, he would do violence to himself as concretely realized, turning God’s loving approaches into coarse whips (Mal 4:1–2). If we attend, with a metaphysical gaze, to the “principles by which” our condition is colored, we come to actual graces and not to principles of human existence. See, as an example of such effort, Brisbois,“Le désir de voir Dieu,” 1104ff. 192 Georges Cardinal Cottier, following Maritain’s reflections, has sketched the contours admirably in his essay “On Natural Mysticism,” in Surnaturel:A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 273–94. 614 Christopher J. Malloy wonder would be the natural desire to know, which, upon encounter with things, would blossom into a desire to know their quiddities, their causes, and the quiddities of their causes.193 In all his movements, moreover, a natural man would be drawn to whatever is good and true and beautiful. He would explore the heights of “natural mysticism.”194 Philosophically, as he came rightly to grasp that there must be an ultimate cause of all things—whether he were a philosopher or a lucid human being (Wis 13; Rom 1; Acts 17)—he would desire to know the essence of this cause.195 Further, he would recognize this cause—by way of affirmation, negation, and supereminence—to be personal, since “person” describes what is most perfect in being. Although this notion of “person” would be quite different from that unveiled through faith (whether to Abraham or through our Lord), it would be nonetheless genuine if plumbed.196 But this philosophical approach could not but be coupled, in an upright man of flesh and blood, with a mystical desire. Indeed, these “two” approaches went hand in hand with the great neo-Platonists. Certain features of Plotinus’s mystical experience—and that of the great Hindu and Islamic mystics—could be found here, features all of which need not be traced simply to grace.197 (While critiquing one aspect of neo193 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 38. See also, for an elaboration of the profound structural roots of the elicited desire, Hütter, “Natural Desire,” 561, 565f., and 585–91. Hütter weaves a delicate path in his contextualized exegesis of ScG, III, chap. 25. On the one hand, he holds, Aquinas affirms that man is capax visionis; man has an inclination by which he naturally reaches out to this vision. On the other hand, he stresses the difference between the simple motion of desire and the firm desire of what is possible (see “Natural Desire,” 573–77).This latter line of thought seems to pick up a theme otherwise apparently dropped, that the desire for knowledge of God is a desire “for knowledge itself of God” and not for “knowledge of God himself ” (“Natural Desire,” 561, 565f., and 585–91). I raise the same question to Hütter that I raise to Feingold: Ought we not render this more precise by advertence to a distinction of formal objects? The natural wonder, rooted structurally in the essence of intellect, arises through knowledge of effects and arrives at the question, “What is this first cause?” The question cannot be answered except by the gratuitously offered vision of God, although the formality under which knowledge of God is desired by the grace leading towards vision is different from that of this strictly natural question. 194 See Cottier, “On Natural Mysticism,” passim. 195 Among the classic texts are the following: ScG III, chaps. 25 and 50; ST I, q. 12, a. 1; and ST I–II, q. 3, a. 8. 196 See ST I, q. 29, a. 3. Lonergan maintains that one cannot show the impossibility of a natural religious worship of a personal God (“Natural Desire,” 88f.). 197 See, for instance,Augustine, Confessions,VII.Although one has reason to contend against Augustine that a personal, distinct Logos cannot be found by human De Lubac on Natural Desire 615 Platonism, one need not critique all aspects.) Consequently, the vector of this twofold pursuit, speculative and mystical, would be eminently vertical as to its telos. In an upright person, the desire to know and to be united with the first cause would be the crown of desires, but it would be contoured.198 One would desire without qualification what could be naturally attained and would find rest in this loving contemplation of him through creatures.199 Still, recognizing that one could not penetrate to the essence of the first cause either philosophically or mystically, one would be in a state of loving wonder. However, recognizing such penetration to be beyond one’s capacity, one would not pine away with an unconditional desire but virtuously direct it towards fuller development of what is attainable. Further, the formal object of this desire would be distinct from that of the believer’s desire.200 With such contours, about which more would necessarily obtain than can experience, has one any reason to deny that there can be a “para-conceptual” approach to the divine by way of human ascesis? Again, see Cottier,“On Natural Mysticism,” passim. 198 Long captures this contour (see “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 149f., and n. 20). Towards the end of Surnaturel, de Lubac describes three irreducibly distinct “thomistic” takes on the natural desire, as though it was not thought to have any contour (see Surnaturel, 478f.).The fact is that various positions are not incompatible. One can say that in some text Thomas is speaking of a natural desire, qua “modalized” by grace, to know the Holy Trinity. This does not exclude the fact that the natural desire, short of such modalization, would have the knowledge of the essence of the first cause as its object.Again, one may say that the desire remains a “velleity” in the sense that its non-realization would not cause suffering, though it would cause wonder, and yet deny that the formal species of the object of the velleity is the supernatural vision of God. 199 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 416–21. 200 This point is in partial response to both Lonergan and Dockx: Although in truth the beatific vision alone completely perfects the human mind (it is what Lonergan calls the “transcendental” or “adequate” object [“Natural Desire,” 82f.]), it does not follow that the latter has the former as its natural end or formal object.The human mind is made to know being, but being is analogical, not univocal (according to Aquinas). So, although God is Ipsum Esse Subsistens, he does not fall within the range of the human (or angelic) mind’s formal object. In fact, Aquinas maintains that the passive intellect is in natural passive potency only to those things of which it is capable in virtue of the agent intellect (see De veritate, q. 18, a. 2). See Super II Ad Corinth., chap. 5, lect. 2, par. 160. Maritain says it best: “[It] is a desire which does not know what it asks” (Approaches, 97). I would illustrate the matter thus: A rational animal without eyes that wished to know the cause of periodic heat on earth, would want to know the cause of heat, but this cause actually is the luminous sun. On this remove, see note 88 above; see also Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 149; cf. Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 42 and 423. 616 Christopher J. Malloy judiciously be said, one finds the “both/and” that de Lubac rejects: Both a proportionate end and recognition of something desirable beyond this—a genuine but not ultimate beatitude. 2. Specific Obediential Potency. Thus we encounter the tertium quid between the caricature of non-repugnance201 and the projection of an absolute but inefficacious desire—the horizon of wonder, what came to be called “specific obediential potency” for grace.202 (De Lubac employs this term but only with reference to his thesis; so, if one grasps the argument, one will see no parity of conception.) The term “specific obediential potency” indicates the “greatest dignity of an intellectual nature created in the image of God: its unique capacity to receive the grace of God in order to be elevated to a supernatural end.”203 The term can be articulated as follows. A “potency” is the capacity for some perfection or act.204 Potencies are distinguished as active and passive. An active potency is the capacity to bring about some act: A potter has the active potency to make of clay a vessel, and a healthy man has the active potency to get up and walk. A passive potency is the capacity to be brought to some perfection. Passive potencies are of two types: natural and non-natural.205 A natural passive potency for some act or perfection (T ) is the capacity something (F ) has for T, to which F can bring itself in virtue of its natural active potency.A non-natural passive potency is the capacity F has for T, to which F cannot bring itself because F lacks the natural active potency. So, Thomas holds with Averroes, if F has no natural active potency for T, neither can it have for T any natural passive potency properly so called.There is no natural passive potency where there is no natural active potency.206 (Of course, one could make 201 See Hütter,“Desiderium,” 107–17. Cf. Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade, 157. De Lubac is aware of the caricature (see “Le mystère du surnaturel,” 89). 202 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 117–20, 339–43, and 413f.; and Long, “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 150f. and 157–66. For de Lubac, the only “specific obediential potency” is the natural desire for the supernatural (see Mystery, 60 and 142f.). 203 Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 159. 204 See Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 149–54. 205 See Compendium theologiae I, chap. 104; see also Feingold,The Natural Desire to See God, 149f. 206 See In II Sent., d. 12, q. 1, a. 1; In III Sent., d. 2, q. 1, a. 1, qla 1; ibid., d. 26, q. 1, a. 2; De veritate, q. 18, aa. 2 and 5; ScG III, chap. 156, par. 7; De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 10, ad 13. For texts pertinent to the obediential potency, from which texts principles may be gathered and an argument formed—if one submits experience and medicinally minded judgments to the discipline of theological science—see De De Lubac on Natural Desire 617 further nuances with respect to ordinations differently experienced within a species: For example, the male and the female with respect to generation.207 ) For sake of precision, we can distinguish nonnatural potencies in view of the different agents that possess the relevant active potency. If the agent is created, the potency can be described generically as non-natural. If the agent can only be divine, the potency can be called obediential. We can unpack “obediential potency” as follows, beginning with its description as generic. God can do all things that can be done, anything makeable, that is, anything not per se impossible.208 Anything that he does do, however, will be ordered in accordance with some wise plan.209 Because of God’s omnipotence, even though a given order of things has no active potency for X, if X is neither impossible nor repugnant to the order, God can realize it. Let us restrict the analysis to possible things. Although in some given order wherein there is no natural active potency for Q, there is nonetheless a potency for Q, an obediential potency vis-à-vis divine power. Let Q stand for generic obediential potency vis-à-vis the divine power.210 There is a more precise obediential potency than that which is generic. Whereas Q indicates a potency common to many kinds, let Z stand for that which is possible only for a certain kind of thing (yet never with respect to any natural active cause). All Z are Q, but not all Q are Z. The limited conditions for Z being possible indicate specific obediential potency. The specification is on the part of the recipient: Only this kind can receive the perfection. Now, since only created intellect can be elevated to grace and glory, created intellect has a “specific obediential potency” to grace and glory. We veritate, q. 8, a. 12, ad 4; De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 10, ad 13; and Compendium theologiae I, chap. 104; for a thorough discussion, see Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God, 136–54. 207 I am grateful to graduate student Christopher Kellerman for challenging me toward this nuance. 208 In this respect, Ockham’s formulation (see Maurer, Philosophy of William of Ockham, 247, and Adams, Ockham, 1155) is a precision, leaving ample latitude; it is perfectly amenable to Aquinas’s thought. 209 There can be, according to Aquinas and also Ockham, no exercise of God’s power describable as absolute and not ordered. See note 145 above and Maurer, Philosophy of William of Ockham, 255–59. As Adams states, there is simply no medieval that understood the “two powers” of the divine will to signify “two distinct powers” in God; it is God’s only will that is considered in two lights (see Adams, Ockham, 1186f.). However, when we consider the details, crucial differences emerge. 210 For Thomas on this, see De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 10, ad 13. 618 Christopher J. Malloy have pegged the specificity generically. The stuff of this specificity is found in the natural wonder adumbrated above. The development of the category “specific obediential potency” and its dynamic realization in man at the crest of his desires makes it possible to identify both the unique fittingness of the call to glory and the intelligibility of a world with created intellects not called to glory.211 Upholding the goodness of a purely natural order does not put man and God on a par as contractual partners. Rather, it supports intelligibly a conception of the life of grace as entirely gratuitous, ever upheld by the gratuitous offer of grace. Earthen vessels are we, and not only because of sin.The gratuity of grace rests against the backdrop of the intelligibility of the same rational hypostasis without a divine call.212 3. Does the Appeal to Obediential Potency Imply Dualism or Extrinsicism? The standard objection to the attempt to identify the gratuity of grace in the theory of obediential potency is that it leads to a dualistic, two-tier conception of nature and grace. It must be granted that even some great theologians have invited the charge by their phraseology. Matthias Scheeben comes to mind.213 However, appreciation of Scheeben’s theology disposes of this concern. At any rate, a true grasp of the meaning of scholastic expressions should at least dispose of caricatures. An explanation that grace neatly develops nature ought to be given. One might take a certain loose conception of Hegelian sublation as a model of the way in which grace builds upon nature according to the formula gratia non destruit sed perficit naturam (grace does not destroy but perfects nature).214 What is the difference between man in the state of pure nature and a man called and divinized? One could reply: the latter has certain superadded forms: sanctifying grace, theological virtues, and gifts of the Spirit. Nevertheless, because of the way too many a reader receives formulas such as this, it is better to indicate the one overarching difference between the two men.The second man is a man whom 211 Braine’s criticism that the category is “thoroughly unspecific” seems to me off the mark (see “The Debate,” 557). Only intellectual creatures have this potency, and they have it in virtue of the wonder about God that they would have even in a purely natural order. 212 Coffey (“The Whole Rahner,” 100 and 111–13); Hütter (“Natural Desire,” 569); and Léonard (“The Theological Necessity,” 325–30) maintain this thesis as well. 213 See Matthias Scheeben, Nature and Grace, trans. Cyril Vollert (St. Louis: B. Herder, 1954). 214 I take the Hegelian image from Brugger through Coffey,“The Whole Rahner,” 112. De Lubac on Natural Desire 619 God is drawing to himself.The causal analysis (superadded forms, etc.) helps indicate the various means whereby this personal calling is executed and achieved.215 The elements of this divine drawing, featured in the Abrahamic life of those called by grace, hardly “sit upon” an at bottom natural man.To the contrary, these elements engage him in an unspeakably more radical dependence than that which a purely natural man would experience. He now subsists upon the words and graces coming down from God. As a reading of the secunda pars exhibits, the Abrahamic life discloses the tension between the pondus of human nature considered in itself and life in the Spirit. Of course, Abraham’s life also discloses our de facto alienated condition due to sin. I simply wish to highlight the former disclosure, for not everything can be said at once.Within this focus, it can be said that everything pertaining to Abraham goes with him, yet everything is put to a higher service. When God calls a man to himself in intimacy, he galvanizes all properly human dynamisms for an all-embracing end inclusive of every other licit and practicable end. However, this inclusion is not merely some external yoke; it indicates the formatio of what without that inclusion would have its sights set lower. Put in loosely Hegelian terms, the divine call affirms the goodness of what is natural in life, cancels natural life’s limitation of scope (a limitation able to be appreciated only hazily by reason—since the formal object of faith would be off the radar—but distinctly by faith), and employs the whole of that life with greater clarity and on a higher plane. An intramundane example can exemplify the sublation: Mozart introduces the two dimensional melody of Ah! vous dirai-je Maman into a three-dimensional flowering. Putting it another way, Long remarks that when grace is offered, nature become “modalized.”216 Henceforth, nothing within man can remain neutral with respect to the ultimate end.217 The Friend who discloses himself can no longer be treated with as an acquaintance. Therefore, our fall through Adam’s sin not only deprives all human persons of a just relation to God, not only merits the loss of grace, but 215 This sketch aims to point the way towards addressing legitimate concerns of de Lubac, Braine (see “The Debate,” 575), and Healy (“Henri de Lubac on Nature and Grace,” passim). One finds a very suggestive indication of the biblical spirit of this narration of the pure nature hypothesis in Mansini, “Surnaturel,” 606f. 216 Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 146; see also 147–50 and 153. 217 The entire movement of the Summa theologiae may be read along the lines of Irenaeus’s exegesis of Paul: From animal man to rational man, from rational man to justified man, from justified man to spiritual man.There is a radical tension— what de Lubac would call a “death to self ”—inscribed in this escalating, Abrahamic call. Christopher J. Malloy 620 also vitiates human nature’s order to its connatural end.218 In this light, de Lubac seems justly critical of the notion that original sin simply leaves us with a purely natural man.219 Nevertheless, is he not wrong to charge that human nature as such—bereft of both grace and sin—would be tempted to rest in a purely mundane end?220 Conclusion Effectively, de Lubac bade his readers abandon the then-regnant hypothesis of pure nature since, as he perceived, no purely natural order could be “theonomic.”221 Further, he bade them subscribe to a natural desire for the supernatural. His strategy may be framed as an anthropological question: What is created spirit like? The options de Lubac presents are these: Either it is totally uninterested in higher things or it deeply yearns for the beatific vision. Given these options, who would not choose the latter? Having chosen the latter, however, one encounters theological and anthropological difficulties.Theologically, there is the following insoluble alternative: Either (a) because any world must be meaningful, God must offer grace should he create a spirit that does not sin; or (b) because the divine freedom is such that nothing is due to any creature in any way, a meaningless world is possible. Either a conception of grace as necessary or a conception of divine liberty as absolutely arbitrary even if contingently benevolent.Anthropologically, one countenances a naturally miserable and wretched or sub-personal man, a pure “vacuole” for grace.222 Going to the root of the matter, one can ask whether de Lubac sufficiently dealt with the Enlightenment threat at its roots. Or, rather, did he presuppose as non-theonomous and autonomous what “pure human nature” with a natural finality would be? This would be to concur not with the thomistic tradition but with key problematic features of the 218 See note 179 above. 219 See Surnaturel, 375, and A Brief Catechesis, 41–53 and 81–87. Rahner and Hans urs von Balthasar are also rightly critical thereof (see Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 575 and 581). Long’s response is apropos: Grace really can order nature to a higher end (Long, “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 153, 155, n. 29). 220 See, esp., Malevez, “La gratuité du surnaturel,” 685f. 221 Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 152f. and 167–83, and Hütter, “Desiderium,” 112–13. 222 Long,“On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature,” 151; see also 152 and 175; see also Michel Bastit,“Is Thomism an Aristotelian System?” in Surnaturel:A Controversy, ed. Bonino, 87–101. Cf. Figura, Der Anruf der Gnade, 226, n. 55, and 372. De Lubac on Natural Desire 621 Enlightenment. The premise that led to the unhappy alternative need not stand. As Gagnebet lucidly states: Saint Thomas had no need to suppose in our nature a chimerical ‘innate, absolute natural desire’ for the beatific vision in order not to conceive of grace as a purely extrinsic gift. He was content to recognize the openness of our spiritual faculties to the plenitude of being and of good.223 A remedy for the illusion of conceiving the creaturely order qua natural as turned inward, self-sufficient, wretched, and miserable might be found with a change of approach to the physical and moral worlds.We could, as Long suggests, aim to rediscover—naturally anterior to the travail of sin and despair—the world as disclosive of God’s power, deity, and wisdom (Rom 1:19f.;Wis 13:3–5).224 This rediscovery could bring us, in harmony with the spirit of de Lubac, to reject a godless interpretation of natural dynamisms: Rather than judging things to be blindly moving hither and thither, rather than judging human inclination to be inertial “conatus” or chance happening or will to power, rather, also, than following the pessimism of certain reformers, we might discern within a contemplative outlook that natural dynamisms have their order to an end (and ultimately to the end), the human being naturally bearing the melody of this symphony of ends.225 Here, there is something marvelous to ponder beneath the outrages of sin—the multifarious yet harmonious dialogue of finalities in the world.226 This is not a prescription to ignore sin and its devastation or to promote the heretical notion that a merely natural end is actually attainable by any son of Adam who acts freely; it is an effort to distinguish causally so as to unite fruitfully. If we approach such a gaze, we may discover not the wretchedness of concrete man qua human but the unique dignity of the rational being qua rational.227 Of course, difficulties and oddities present themselves for my thesis. These are of two sorts. (1) There is a first set of oddities or difficulties that 223 Gagnebet, “L’amour II,” 1949, 95. 224 Although there is no unstained child of Adam, our Lord and our Lady excepting, there is yet the nature itself, its powers, and its primal dynamisms to good.Without grace, these peter out for lack of vigor and thus significantly miss their mark. 225 It carries these naturally, yet, on account of sin, it does not carry them electively unless healed by grace. 226 I say beneath in the genetic order, not in some spatial order. Sin is a deprivation of the due good in rational beings. It is not that we find a realm untouched by sin. It is that we still find the powers with their fundamental dynamisms to the good. Sin is appalling because of its contradiction to these dynamisms. 227 I find an excellent example of this approach in Cottier,“On Natural Mysticism,” 273–94. 622 Christopher J. Malloy are central, closer to matters of principle. (a) How can my thesis account for the pain of the damned? (b) How can it account for the devastation of original sin and the de facto reality that any human person is either in the state of grace or in the state of sin?228 (c) Since despotic control over one’s passions is a modally, albeit not entitatively, supernatural gift (i.e., a preternatural gift), concupiscence would naturally arise. But Aquinas argues from the existence of concupiscence to the impossibility of long obeying the moral law, even though any particular mortal sin can be avoided.229 Does this oddity not constitute a troubling scenario, the very one I find in de Lubac? (2) Ancillary perplexities arise when one examines portraits of hypothetical orders, even those that are not venturous. (a) Given the necessarily communal texture of the human enterprise, already exercised human freedom affects that which is to be exercised. Likely, in a purely natural order, some would miss the moral mark. If they did, might not external pressures on the morally upright develop to the point of making virtuous activity practically impossible?230 Would the divine providence be bound to answer with additional helps? (b) Would (non-glorious) bodily resurrection be due, or would it be completely gratuitous? To these and questions like these I think two different but not incompatible sets of responses can be given. On the one hand, they (or some of them) can be utilized by theological wisdom in conversation with rational inquirers who do not believe by way of a “protreptic” wooing towards the faith, along the lines of Aquinas’s own approach throughout the Summa contra Gentiles.231 As I would argue, this precise kind of protreptic wooing would suggest to non-believers the relatively inconveniens character of a purely natural explanation of the given order. Even though the effects of sin and grace must constitute the real point of departure for discussion with non-believers, the protreptic I suggest simply contributes to our appreciation of the concrete order God has chosen, an order absolutely more fitting than a purely natural one.232 Such wooing would be guided by a higher wisdom and indebted to what is disclosed to faith, but it might lead some unbelievers by appealing to the 228 See Braine, “The Debate,” 546–50 and 576–80. 229 On this nuance, see Lonergan, Grace and Freedom. 230 Braine, MacIntyre, and many others could raise this question. 231 See Thomas Hibbs, Dialectic and Narrative in Aquinas: An Interpretation of the Summa Contra Gentiles (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995); and Mark Jordan, “The Protreptic Structure of the Summa Contra Gentiles,” The Thomist 50 (1986):173–209. 232 See, for instance, ScG IV, chap. 52. The argument is not necessary but highly fitting, nor do the arguments conclude to the utter irrationality of any world with men without grace. De Lubac on Natural Desire 623 vector of that which comes under the formal object of natural inquiry. Still, such wooing need not premise as utterly unintelligible a purely natural order. Would not a critical thinker find such an apologetic irrational and so flee the ghetto? Consequently, another set of responses— attempted answers to these thousand difficulties—is in order. The first set of questions is the more pressing. What follow are not definitive answers but sketches offered in the hope that such difficulties need not obscure the intelligibility of the core of my thesis, which is that, whereas the hypothesis of pure nature presents difficulties, de Lubac’s thesis presents absurdities. For his part, Rahner could answer (1a) with reference to the supernatural existential:The “sun of righteousness” is received by the malicious as an affliction. But if it is unfitting that grace be found in hell, one might appeal to the modalization of the natural desire by grace and to the malice that would ensue upon the pronouncement, “I never knew you.”233 (1a) remains a difficulty calling for meditation on the ramifcations of the natural love of God with respect to its modalization by grace.234 With regard to (1b), some may rely on the fact that various positions have been taken on original sin and its effects, some of which, though to many Pelagian, the Church has not (yet) seen fit to condemn.235 The position to which I allude is that fallen man as such is in the state of nature. I on the other hand would suggest that the havoc Adam wreaked upon himself included not only the sheer loss of original justice, a compact endowment of supernatural grace and preternatural gifts, but thereby also the loss of that good state of nature (natural justice) which he could have enjoyed as debitum naturae apart from grace and sin. Accordingly, we inherit a nature identical in species to Adam’s but vitiated in state, as the difficulty in executing acts of virtue, for which nature is in principle a seed, exhibits.236 As to (1c), does it not seem, to the contrary, that it could not be impossible to obey the natural law in a purely natural order?237 If so, perhaps one should distinguish the kind of concupiscence we suffer by inheritance from the kind that would afflict 233 Cajetan provides a thoughtful reflection: The damned suffer over their punish- ment—their share in certain evils—and not over the evil of fault. But the saints delight over the good of God more than over their share in good. See his commentary on ST II–II, q. 17, a. 5 (Leonine ed., vol. 8, 131a). 234 See Gagnebet, “L’amour II,” 1949, 92. 235 I am thinking of certain opinions espoused by Gregory Biel (see Heiko Augustinus Oberman, The Harvest of Medieval Theology: Gabriel Biel and Late Medieval Nominalism [Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2000]). 236 See Torrell, “Nature and Grace,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, 172–79. 237 On this, see Gagnebet, “L’amour II,” 1949, 45–68. 624 Christopher J. Malloy a rational animal without preternatural gifts. Or, if such a distinction is not possible and if it were thus true that it would be impossible long to obey the natural law in a purely natural order, would not certain preternatural gifts seem to be due? As to the second set, I take it that similar questions could arise about contingencies possible under de Lubac’s hypothesis, for, if a natural desire for the supernatural were possible, surely there would be many possible scenarios, some quite odd to our minds. Neither less significant nor more profound difficulties ought to derail scientific projects of theology, which ought primarily to work from and towards central principles. Short of a theology based in principles and worked out scientifically, one is tempted to direct the theological compass by medicinal considerations. Such considerations and their outcome may have practical utility, yet the diagnosis may labor under a misapprehension of the real causal situation. If diagnoses are badly made, so will be the corresponding prescriptions. Difficulties are not absurdities, but are absurdities affirmable? A reductionistic theological anthropology is what one risks theoretically. Practically, one risks ill-equipped moral theologies needlessly battling ill-framed questions.238 Rhetorically, one risks alienating rational dialogue partners and retreating into the ghetto. Perhaps Fr. Gilbert Narcisse states it best: In moving forward we need a theology anchored in metaphysical wisdom yet attentive to the existential sphere in which we live and move and have our being. Advertence to a theologically differentiated consciousness—one that exercises an ontological approach on the one hand and recognizes on the other hand existential considerations (and messiness)—will thus be necessary if we are to save the truth of the phenomena while retaining a rightly ordered compass.239 Without neglecting questions and difficulties, one does not go astray—in fact, all disputants in this discussion can happily join—in pressing the ear to N&V the concrete hope intoned by the deacon’s chant: Felix culpa!240 238 See Benedict Ashley’s fine essay on these problems: “What is the End of the Human Person? The Vision of God and Integral Human Fulfillment,” in Moral Truth and Moral Tradition: Essays in Honour of Peter Geach and Elizabeth Anscombe (Dublin: Four Courts Press, 1994), 68–96. Upon reading his essay, I was happy to note that my portrait resembles Ashley’s (see 79–81). 239 I find balanced and to the point the features of a possible future path for theology sketched by Gilbert Narcisse (see the conclusion of his essay, “The Supernatural in Contemporary Theology,” in Surnaturel: A Controversy, 307–9). 240 I owe enormous thanks to Lawrence Feingold and Steven Long for their assistance on matters pertinent to this article. In addition, I am grateful to an anonymous peer reviewer for many helpful suggestions. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 625–656 625 The Surnaturel Controversy: A Survey and a Response E DWARD T. OAKES, S.J. Mundelein Seminary Mundelein, Illinois A LTHOUGH the Second Vatican Council left in its wake a host of disputes about its meaning and impact (disputes that live on to this day), no result of the council seems more secure than this conviction: that in the clash between neo-scholasticism and ressourcement theology, the latter had decisively won. In that famous preconciliar struggle over how to understand the relation of nature to grace, the battle lines were drawn between a school of neo-Thomism centered in the Roman universities (and represented most effectively by Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P.) and the so-called nouvelle théologie headquartered at the French Jesuit theologate at Fourvière (near Lyons, where Henri de Lubac, S.J. was in the vanguard). The former side posited a two-fold end for the human species, one natural and the other supernatural; while the latter held that God had aboriginally intended the human race for only one end, a specifically and exclusively supernatural one. But by the time the council had completed its last session on December 8, 1965, nearly everyone agreed: the prior reigning synthesis, as bequeathed by the manual Thomists and anti-Modernists, was over and done with.1 1 So Walter Kasper:“There is no doubt that the outstanding event in the Catholic theology of our century is the surmounting of neo-scholasticism,” which Kasper defines as “the attempt to solve the modern crisis of theology by picking up the thread of the high scholastic tradition of medieval times.The aim was to establish a timeless, unified theology that would provide a norm for the universal church. It is impossible to deny this attempt a certain grandeur. But in the long run a restoration was bound to fail.” Walter Kasper, Theology and Church, trans. Margaret Kohl (New York: Crossroad, 1989), 1.This view, it bears recalling, was 626 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. Recently, however, this same neo-scholasticism—which had been thought moribund these past four and a half decades, and whose obituary has been written so many times—has shown surprising signs of life. Not just noted experts long familiar with this debate, but also young scholars who have investigated this issue with fresh eyes, claim that de Lubac can hardly be regarded as having spoken the last word. Indeed, they go further and claim that he fundamentally misunderstood both Thomas Aquinas and the Thomist tradition generally. Finally, they even charge that many of the woes now afflicting the Church in the wake of Vatican II—declining vocations, a confused moral theology, a revitalized secular hostility to the Christian religion—can all be traced to an overhasty adoption of his thesis. In what follows, I wish first to outline the Lubacian consensus that obtained for most of the postconciliar period; then in the second section I will try to survey, as much as the space of an article permits, the recent attacks on the viability of that consensus; and finally I will conclude with some reflections of my own.Throughout these three sections, we must keep in mind two separate issues: (1) Did de Lubac misinterpret Thomas’s teaching on nature and grace? This question is fundamentally exegetical and belongs under the rubric of historical theology. (2) Even if de Lubac successfully showed that Thomas’s Renaissance and Baroque commentators diverged from the position of the Common Doctor, does that mean that they were wrong on the issue itself? That is, might not the commentary tradition represent a legitimate development of St. Thomas’s more fundamental insights? In other words, even if de Lubac was correct on the exegetical point of Thomas’s historical position, maybe Catholic theologians should adopt the (newly minted) position of the commentators anyway, as being the most logical and consistent in light of new developments.2 After also endorsed by no less an authority than Joseph Ratzinger (a cardinal at the time when he penned these lines): “It is my view that the neoscholastic rationalism that was trying to reconstruct the praeambula fidei . . . with pure rational certainty, by means of rational argument that was strictly independent of any faith, has failed; and it cannot be otherwise for any such attempts to do that kind of thing. In that sense, Karl Barth was right when he rejected philosophy as a basis for faith that is independent of faith itself.” Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1994), 136; emphasis added. 2 This distinction seems to form the basis of Garrigou-Lagrange’s concession that “one cannot follow St. Thomas by falling into a material literalism.” P. R. Garrigou-Lagrange, “La possibilité de la grâce est-elle rigoureusement démonstrable?” Revue thomiste 94 (1936): 214, note 20: “il ne faut pas, pour suivre saint Thomas, tomber dans un littéralisme matériel.” Ironically, John Henry Newman would agree, at least formally. The Surnaturel Controversy 627 all, is that not what development of doctrine means? Why should the same not hold true of the Thomist tradition? But to understand how that position of the commentators has come to the fore once more in revitalized form, one must first see how de Lubac convinced the vast majority of twentieth-century theologians of the rightness of his thesis that man has only one, supernatural end. I Perhaps the best way of getting a sense of how much the postconciliar consensus was taken for granted would be to look at the reminiscences of those trained in theology at that time and who now look back on their training from our more unsettled times. Prior to Vatican II most seminarians were taught that in order to preserve the sheer gratuity of grace (that is, the teaching that grace is not “owed” to nature, that nature cannot therefore make a claim on grace for its proper fulfillment), there must be something, at least hypothetically, called “pure nature” that could get along without grace. For if it could not, that is, if grace were truly indispensable to nature, that would mean that grace must be an “exigency” of nature, which then God would “owe” that nature, and its gratuity would thereby be undermined. But then, if nature can be fulfilled without grace, why should nature bother with grace at all, if it can get by just fine using only its own powers of self-fulfillment? Such a devastating rhetorical question then led to this “obvious” conclusion: banish all talk of that figment “pure nature” from theology! And from this axiom came all that followed, as described in this vivid memoir: Declaring “pure nature” not to belong to the subject matter of theology was also the remedy against what Maurice Blondel labeled an “extrinsicist” view of grace, or what we as students referred to as “Suárez’s cream cake.” It is the well-known picture of nature and grace as two tiers, one on top of the other, without an intrinsic connection between the two. Human nature is complete in itself, and it might well do without grace, that is, without a personal relation to God.Without the cream of grace, it would be a little dry and less tasty, but the cake of nature is not really affected by the cream topping. However, from a religious, and hence also from a theological perspective, such a view was completely unacceptable. It alienated grace and faith from our personal, concrete, everyday life and from the larger reality of society and the world by promoting a flight into a distinct spiritual realm. It domesticated and isolated theology, confining it to the little, sheltered niche of the supernatural, fully disconnected from the humanities and sciences.3 3 Harm Goris,“Steering Clear of Charybdis: Some Directions for Avoiding ‘Grace Extrinsicism’ in Aquinas,” Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 67–79; here 69. 628 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. Those who were professionally trained in theology during that time, whether as seminarians or as aspiring professors, can easily recognize the truth being described here, both as to how the issue seemed at the time and how students were struck by the perfect obviousness of de Lubac’s attacks on the hypothesis of natura pura. Karl Rahner, who received his training in theology much earlier, and thus knew well the theology against which he battled, of course did not take for granted the victory over the neo-scholastic account of pure nature.Yet he too speaks of that tradition as inherently untenable, which thus now deserves to lose its hold on the theological world: [T]he orientation of “nature” to grace is conceived of in as negative a way as possible. Grace is, it is true, an unsurpassable perfectioning of nature; God as the Lord of this nature can command man to submit to his de facto will and to be receptive to his grace, which directs man to a supernatural life and end. But of itself nature has only a “potentia oboedientialis” to such an end, and this capacity is thought of as negatively as possible. It is no more than non-repugnance to such an elevation. Of itself, nature would find its perfection just as readily and harmoniously in its own proper realm, in a purely natural end, without an immediate intuition of God in the beatific vision.When it finds itself in immediate possession of itself—as part of the essence of the spirit, reditio completa in seipsum —it meets itself as though it were “pure nature.”4 Of course what Goris and Rahner are describing here is the new attitude and position adopted in de Lubac’s wake, which rejects out of hand the utility of the concept of pure nature, but not the argument that led to the new consensus. For that argument one must go to de Lubac’s epochal Surnaturel,5 together with the later clarificatory tomes that expatiate on this thesis in more detail, Augustinianism and Modern Theology 6 and The 4 Karl Rahner, S.J.,“Nature and Grace,” in Theological Investigations IV, trans. Kevin Smyth (London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 1966), 165–88; here 165.Against this view Rahner proposes his own, one based entirely in the empirical order of salvation history as currently established by God: “Our actual nature is never ‘pure’ nature. It is a nature installed in a supernatural order which man can never leave, even as a sinner and unbeliever. It is a nature which is continually being determined (which does not mean justified) by the supernatural grace of salvation offered to it” (ibid., 183; emphasis in the original). 5 Henri de Lubac, S.J., Surnaturel: Etudes historiques, nouvelle edition preparée et préfacée par Michael Sales (Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1991); first edition published in 1946. 6 Henri de Lubac, S.J., Augustinianism and Modern Theology, trans. Lancelot Sheppard (New York: Crossroad, 2000), first published in English in 1969; abbreviated henceforth as Augustinianism. The Surnaturel Controversy 629 Mystery of the Supernatural.7 The impact of these three works, both on Vatican II itself and above all on the postconciliar consensus, can scarcely be exaggerated, as the citations above from Goris and Rahner vividly show. But what was his argument? As we noted at the outset, there is a historical component to his argument and a more directly theological one.The first tack argues that Thomas never countenanced a theory of pure nature in any of his writings, and that when his later commentators did so, they inevitably distorted the views of the Common Doctor.The second argues that, even if traces of what would later become the pure-nature tradition can be found in Aquinas, the thesis should still be rejected for a host of reasons: the concept of pure nature, so goes the claim, creates a “fortress mentality” against the wider culture, is harmful to the Church’s sacramental life, and damages the Church’s missionary commission to make converts of all nations. De Lubac’s first line of argument rests on the common medieval axiom that Thomas repeats throughout his writings: grace perfects nature.8 Obviously, if grace perfects nature (that is, brings it to completion), it must belong in some intimate way to nature. Another favorite passage from the Common Doctor says: “All knowing beings implicitly know God in everything they know,”9 an axiom repeated on other 7 Henri de Lubac, S.J.,The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Crossroad, 1998); first published in English in 1967; cited henceforth as Mystery.The latest edition translates all the Latin quotations. Surnaturel was never translated, perhaps because Augustianism and Mystery were meant to supersede it. 8 It would be tedious to cite every mention of this axiom in the Thomist corpus, but here are a few:“Since therefore grace does not destroy nature but perfects it, natural reason should minister to faith as the natural bent of the will ministers to charity” (ST I, q. 1 a. 8, ad 2);“Final and perfect happiness can consist in nothing else than the vision of the Divine Essence.To make this clear, two points must be observed: first, that man is not perfectly happy so long as something remains for him to desire and seek; second, that the perfection of any power is determined by the nature of its object” (ST I–II, q. 3, a. 8, resp.);“Grace is proportionate to nature as perfection is to the perfectible” (De veritate, q. 27, a. 5, obj. 17);“Nature is anterior to grace. . . .The gifts of graces are added to nature in such a way that they do not raise it but rather perfect it” (In Boetium de Trinitate, q. 2, a. 3). Of course Thomas is not remotely innovating here but draws on a common medieval legacy. 9 De veritate, q. 22, a. 1, ad 1.This passage was especially favored by the Transcendental Thomists like Joseph Maréchal and Karl Rahner, because they held it justified their attention to Immanuel Kant’s transcendental method of attending to the inherent dynamism of the human intellect.Thus Rahner: “For Thomas the concept of God is that which comes last in all our knowledge. But the outreach [Vorgriff ] toward the infinite being is the previous condition of our very first conceptual knowledge, so that in every such knowledge God is already implicitly known.” Karl Rahner, S.J., Hearer of the Word, trans. Joseph Donceel (New York: Continuum, 630 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. occasions.10 If all knowing beings actually know God, albeit implicitly, in every act of knowledge, then obviously this must be an endowment of their nature. But by far the most significant texts justifying de Lubac’s thesis are those passages in which Thomas speaks of the human intellect as endowed with an innate desire to attain ultimate felicity by gazing on the divine essence, the so-called “natural desire for God.”11 Most of these passages come from Thomas’s extended treatment of this very question in Part III of his Summa contra Gentiles, where he says quite explicitly: Since it is impossible for a natural desire to be incapable of fulfillment, and since it would be so frustrated if it were impossible to reach an understanding of divine substance such as all minds naturally desire, we must say that it is possible for the substance of God to be seen intellectually, both by separate intellectual substances [angels] and by our [human] souls.12 So much for de Lubac’s textual justification (citations which of course could be extended further). But he also has a more directly theological argument to make, or rather and more specifically, an eschatological one: if there 1994/1941), 52. De Lubac, however, was diffident of the project of the Transcendental Thomists, so their use of de Lubac’s Surnaturel need not be considered here. 10 “Every intellect naturally desires the vision of the divine substance” (ScG III, chap. 57). 11 This phrase, “the natural desire to see God,” will become the flashpoint in this debate. For how can God endow a creature with a natural desire for something and not fulfill it? For one side of the debate, it would be like God creating a rational animal without the ability to reason, a logical contradiction. Since Thomas clearly holds that rational creatures (both human and angelic) have that natural desire, while other passages hold that grace is necessary to achieve a supernatural end, the debate gets quite complex. For a good overview, see William R. O’Connor, The Eternal Quest: The Teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas on the Natural Desire for God (New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1947) and Reinhard Hütter, “Aquinas on the Natural Desire for the Vision of God: A Relecture of Summa contra Gentiles iii., c. 25 Après Henri de Lubac,” The Thomist 73 (October, 2009): 523–91. 12 ScG III chap. 51, 1; emphasis added. Space does not allow any more citations, but the chapter headings of the ScG give a good indication of the gist of the argument: “That the ultimate felicity of man consists in the contemplation of God” (chap. 37); “That the ultimate felicity does not consist in the knowledge of God gained through demonstration” (chap. 39); “That in this life we cannot see God through his essence” (chap. 47), etc.To be sure, this set of chapters is also paired with other chapters asserting the necessity of grace for that natural desire to be fulfilled: “That no created substance can, by its own natural power, attain the vision of God in his essence” (chap. 52). How to reconcile those two contrasting positions is of course the problem that constitutes this debate. The Surnaturel Controversy 631 were such a thing as a de facto pure nature currently now obtaining in the created world and operating inside the context of salvation history, then that same pure nature would have to be reflected in the eschaton as well, a point refuted by Scripture:“He [Christ] is the image of the invisible God, the firstborn of all creation. For by him all things were created: things in heaven and on earth, visible and invisible, whether thrones or powers or rules or authorities; all things were created through him and for him” (Col 1:15–16; emphases added). From which de Lubac draws this conclusion: It is said that a universe might have existed in which man, though without necessarily excluding any other desire, would have his rational ambitions limited to some lower, purely human, beatitude. Certainly I do not deny it. But having said that, one is obliged to admit—indeed one is automatically affirming—that in our world as it is this is not the case. . . . In me, a real and personal human being, in my concrete nature—that nature I have in common with all real men, to judge by what my faith teaches me, and regardless of what is or is not revealed to me either by reflective analysis or by reasoning—the “desire to see God” cannot be permanently frustrated without an essential suffering. To deny this is to undermine my entire Credo. For is not this, in effect, the definition of the “pain of the damned”? And consequently—at least in appearance—a good and just God could hardly frustrate me, unless I, through my own fault, turn away from him by choice. The infinite importance of the desire implanted in me by my Creator is what constitutes the infinite importance of the drama of human existence.13 Although de Lubac does not mention the issue directly, this passage obviously has a bearing on the topic of limbo, specifically the limbus infantium, where it was held that unbaptized infants go who die before reaching the age of reason. The trouble with that hypothesis (now almost universally abandoned)14 is that limbo becomes, as it were, the place where the hypothesis of pure nature takes on reality, even though it is admitted by all hands that God in fact never created anything outside of Christ, anything in a state of actual pure nature.15 From this concession, admitted by all sides, de Lubac comes to the most vivid expression of his thesis: 13 De Lubac, Mystery, 54. 14 See Edward T. Oakes, S.J., “Catholic Eschatology and the Development of Doctrine,” Nova et Vetera 6 (2008): 419–46 for details on the abandonment of this hypothesis by Pope Benedict XVI and the papally convened International Theological Commission. 15 “All theologians agree that this state of pure nature never existed. Baius and Jansenius [erred by denying] its possibility.” Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, Grace: Commentary on the Summa theologica of St. Thomas, IaIIae, q. 109–14, trans. Dominican Nuns of Corpus Christi Monastery (St. Louis: B. Herder, 1952), 23; 632 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. For this desire is not some “accident” in me. It does not result from some peculiarity, possibly alterable, of my individual being, or from some historical contingency whose effects are more or less transitory. . . . It is in me as a result of my belonging to humanity as it is, that humanity which is, as we say,“called.” For God’s call is constitutive. My finality, which is expressed by this desire, is inscribed upon my very being as it has been put into this universe by God. And, by God’s will, I now have no other genuine end, no end really assigned to my nature or presented for my free acceptance under any guise, except that of “seeing God.”16 This position, so boldly stated, of course raises again the problem of the gratuity of grace: if God has so constituted us that we desire the beatific vision by nature, yet we can attain that end only by a freely bestowed gift of grace, which we are given not because it is owed to us but because God freely (“gratuitously”) gives it to us, does that then not mean that God has created us for an end naturally and inherently desired but only to be attained by something beyond nature? What does that say about God? Why would God create a nature subject to such futility? This conundrum is indeed a knotty one, and de Lubac’s proposal for solving it came under heavy attack at the first appearance of Surnaturel, an attack recently renewed, as we shall see in the next section, where his proposed solution will be subjected to closer analysis by setting it against its perceived weaknesses. It must be conceded by all hands, however, that it was always at least de Lubac’s intent to preserve the gratuity of grace. Here, in nutshell, is his position: However, whether one adopts or rejects [pure nature], if one succeeds in making clear—as at all costs we must—that the supernatural end can in no case be the object of any requirement or debt, even by a being who here and now has no other end, then there will no longer be any need to refer to this indirect consideration of an order that is purely natural even as to its finality. We have seen that it is not an adequate emphasis added.This position is commonly held in the Dominican commentary tradition:“Dominican tradition continually opposed the notion of a pure nature created without being in a state of grace, or of a fallen nature that could be equated with a pure nature left to its own resources without grace. . . . Consequently, there never has existed a state of pure nature, and the capacities of fallen human nature are more diminished (due to the historical rejection of grace and the concrete consequences of sin) than they would be had something like a state of pure nature ever existed.” Thomas Joseph White, O.P., “The ‘Pure Nature’ of Christology: Human Nature and Gaudium et Spes 22,” Nova et Vetera 8 (2010): 283–322; here 292. We will take up the impact of the condemnation of Baius and Jansenius in the next section of this article. 16 De Lubac, Mystery, 54–55; emphasis added. The Surnaturel Controversy 633 consideration. Perhaps we may now go so far as to admit that it is not a necessary one either.17 In other words, if the gratuity of grace can be preserved without the hypothesis of pure nature, then the hypothesis has lost its viability. Now whether this passage just quoted represents a true solution to, or is just a restatement of, the problem, merely recast in different words, is precisely the issue and will largely constitute the terms of the debate set in motion by de Lubac’s work. Obviously, as he formulates the issue, the paradox remains a paradox: (1) we are made for God, and our hearts are restless until they reach final union with God in the beatific vision; yet (2) we cannot attain that vision by means of our natural powers alone. But for de Lubac, that is precisely the point! Consider an analogy: all infants and children need the love of their parents, without which they wither. And yet love is not love unless it is freely given.18 De Lubac has long been known as a theologian who insists that Christian revelation is inherently paradoxical, from the God-man Jesus Christ, to the juxtaposition of free will and predestination.19 But of course theology has never contented itself with merely conceding the paradox and going no further; otherwise Christology would never have arisen, and the debate over nature and grace would not have been so heated. So let us now get a better idea of the exact contours of de Lubac’s views by 17 De Lubac, Mystery, 73; emphasis in the original. Note also that a page later de Lubac covers his right flank by conceding that the concept of pure nature might still hold utility under other presuppositions : “And if there are those who feel that it is impossible to preserve that divine truth except by reference to the system of ‘pure nature,’ I would be the first to tell them that not merely have they every right to maintain it, but that they would be wrong to reject it” (ibid.,74). Far from being a concession granted to his critics after the promulgation of Humani Generis, de Lubac made this same point in Surnaturel : “Le nouveau système [of pure nature] ne fut donc point sans rendre d’éminents services.” De Lubac, Surnaturel, 153. 18 Victorian fiction is filled with descriptions of children raised by prosperous parents who take care of their every physical need but deprive them of love (“the poor little rich boy”). For an example in real life, the philosopher Bertrand Russell recounts in his autobiography that he was given every material comfort as a child born to the ruling classes, but the lack of love in the household withered his personality. 19 See Henri de Lubac, The Church: Paradox and Mystery, trans. James R. Dunne (Staten Island, NY: Alba House, 1969) and Paradoxes of Faith, trans. Paule Simon, Sadie Kreilkamp, and Ernest Beaumont (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987). For a lucid account of this important dimension of de Lubac’s thought, see Rudolf Voderholzer, Meet Henri de Lubac, trans. Michael J. Miller (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2008), 117–21. 634 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. seeing how they measure up to recent challenges thrown up by revisionist theologians who think that the tradition attacked by de Lubac has more viability than he realized. II The challenge to de Lubac’s theology of the supernatural comes from several quarters. In the United States, a young scholar, Lawrence Feingold, has recently published a revised version of his doctoral dissertation, The Natural Desire to See God According to St.Thomas and His Interpreters,20 which defends (most of) the classic commentators of Thomas down through the centuries; and Steven Long, building on Feingold, argues the same point from a more analytic and conceptual perspective in his recent book Natura Pura.21 In France, the Dominicans of the Toulouse Province sponsored a symposium in 2000 in which several scholars, both lay and clerical (with the clerics coming both from the secular presbyterate and from several different orders—including the Jesuits), criticized de Lubac from numerous angles.22 One thing must be said at the outset of these works (and also of the journal articles generated by these books): they all adopt a tone of reasoned criticism.There is no tone of heresy-hunting among de Lubac’s recent critics, no instance of unfair characterization or overheated rhetoric.23 Moreover, historical claims are always backed up with texts, most of which were either ignored by or not cited in de Lubac; and finally, the specifically theological arguments adduce many relevant considerations that must be taken into account if de Lubac is to be adequately defended in the future. 20 Lawrence Feingold, The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas and His Interpreters, second edition (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2010). The dissertation carries the same title (Rome: Apollinare Studi, 2001). Besides being more accessible, the second edition has translated all the texts that the dissertation had cited in the original language; and many of the arguments have been made clearer and more cohesive.The 2010 version will be the edition quoted throughout in this article. 21 Steven A. Long, Natura Pura: On the Recovery of Nature in the Doctrine of Grace (New York: Fordham University Press, 2010). 22 All contributions were published in Surnaturel:A Controversy at the Heart of Twentieth-Century Thomistic Thought, ed. Serge-Thomas Bonino, O.P., trans. Robert Williams and Matthew Levering (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2009). 23 “It must be borne in mind that my criticism of de Lubac’s positions does not mean to imply any unorthodox intention on de Lubac’s part, for it is clear that his intention was always to think with the Church. Secondly, I do not mean to imply any global criticism of de Lubac’s other theological views, which I respect. The question under dispute is limited to the concrete issue of the interpretation of the natural desire to see God.” Feingold, Natural Desire, 317, note 2. The Surnaturel Controversy 635 Before getting into the specifics of the case raised against the thesis of de Lubac’s Surnaturel and his later books, however, perhaps it would prove helpful to summarize the anti-Lubacian case in more generic terms. Although the challenge raised against de Lubac is too new to have filtered down into the classroom long enough to have generated reminiscences like the one cited above from Harm Goris, nonetheless perhaps we can anticipate what some future memoirist might say in the next generation. For the climate of opinion affecting the reception of de Lubac’s work has definitely shifted. Here is one possible formulation of how that reassessment might be written at some future date: When the Jesuit theologian Henri de Lubac published Surnaturel in 1946, he irrevocably altered the Thomist understanding of grace. Even more, he changed Thomism itself, which now gives Thomas priority of place over his later commentators by embedding him in the patristic tradition he knew so well. Finally, and most crucially, man is now seen as inherently open to the supernatural. No longer is grace seen as “topping out” nature, like icing atop a layer cake. Unfortunately, de Lubac had made his case so convincingly that problems soon followed in his overpowering wake. After Vatican II, grace came to be seen as so intrinsic to man that the supernatural gifts of revelation, the Church, and the sacraments seemed, at best, merely symbolic reminders of an already realized redemption. Clearly the time has come for a reassessment of Surnaturel.24 Just as de Lubac challenged neo-scholasticism on two main points— that it misunderstood Thomas from the ground up, and that the reigning consensus boxed the Church into a ghetto of irrelevancy—so too the challenge to him disputes him at both these points: he is the one, his critics say, who has distorted the true doctrine of the Doctor Angelicus ; and, far from giving the Church new relevance to the secular world, the acceptance of his position has caused the Church’s true supernatural identity to become obscured, especially among believers. The charges might sound extraordinarily sweeping; but so too, after all, were de Lubac’s attacks on the prior consensus that had reigned in the preconciliar decades immediately after the First World War and continued to be taught in seminaries up to the eve of Vatican II. So if de Lubac is wrong, then his error must be as sweeping as were his attacks. At all events, the case against de Lubac is both exegetical (did he get Thomas right?) and theological (is his position, whether reliant on the “real” Thomas or not, coherent?). As mentioned, Feingold’s case is primarily 24 Adapted from the publisher’s blurb to Bonino, ed., Surnaturel: A Controversy. 636 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. historical and exegetical, so to him we first turn, after which we will look at Long’s. II.1 Feingold’s thesis against de Lubac depends on a crucial distinction, which he believes de Lubac has elided: that between an innate natural desire and an elicited natural desire for God. According to Feingold, if God had planted in us an innate natural desire for celestial beatitude, then God would be “bound” to give us the means to fulfill that desire, just as God is “bound” to give us the gift of reason if he is to make us specifically rational animals. But the gratuity of grace is preserved, maintains Feingold, if that fully natural desire of which St.Thomas so often speaks is elicited : St. Thomas, when dealing with the natural desire to know God’s essence, is plainly speaking of an elicited natural desire: a desire spontaneously aroused on the basis of prior knowledge of God’s effects in the world. However, the real question is deeper and more difficult. Does this natural elicited desire correspond to an underlying innate appetite for the vision of God? . . . In fact, if one conceives the natural desire to see God as an innate appetite or inclination, then it follows that it will be absolute rather than conditional, for a conditional desire is possible only on the basis of knowledge.25 So which view does Thomas hold? Early on, Feingold concedes that Thomas never directly addressed this question,26 and this omission might, it seems to me, undermine his thesis from the outset. Later on he will show that the commentary tradition legitimately developed Thomas’s doctrine by introducing important distinctions in order to counteract Baius and 25 Feingold, Natural Desire, 15, 20; emphasis in the original. 26 “The texts of St. Thomas concerning the natural desire to see God do not directly address or explicitly determine the question of whether the natural desire in question is elicited or innate, which explains the divergence of views which have existed and which still exist in this matter.” Feingold, Natural Desire, xxxiii. Further: “St.Thomas seems to contradict what he frequently asserts elsewhere. Indeed, he has said: ‘There can be no natural desire except for things which can naturally be possessed.’ [Feingold’s footnote: III Sent., d. 27, q. 2, a. 2, ad 4; see also De veritate, d. 2, q. 27, a. 2.] How can there be a natural desire to see God’s essence if created intellects have no natural power to see it? If the created intellect has no natural passive potency, properly speaking, to see God, how can it have a natural desire for that vision? . . . A resolution of this doubt will have to show that at least in a certain respect there can be a natural desire for something which natural active forces are unable to obtain” (ibid., 168; emphases in the original). But what Feingold concedes here is precisely de Lubac’s point: man is a paradoxical animal. The Surnaturel Controversy 637 Jansenius, who denied not just the existence of pure nature but also (and most crucially) its very possibility.27 But of course it would never have occurred to the commentators that they were introducing these distinctions—either between pure nature and unmerited grace, or between innate and elicited natural desires—out of thin air. Later distinctions became necessary because of other distinctions definitely present in the texts of Thomas, such as this key one: Man by his nature is proportioned to a certain end for which he has a natural appetite, and which he can work to achieve by his natural powers.This end is a certain contemplation of the divine attributes, in the measure in which this is possible for man through his natural powers ; and in this end even the philosophers placed the final happiness of man. But God has prepared man for another end, one that exceeds the proportionality of human nature.This end is eternal life, which consists in the vision of God in his essence, an end which exceeds the proportionality of any created nature, being connatural to God alone.28 Admittedly, this passage does not explicitly assert that this latter end, one that exceeds the proportionality of human nature, is not a part of 27 It would take this analysis too far afield to discuss the differences between Michael Baius (or Michel de Bay, 1513–89), a delegate at the Council of Trent, and Cornelius Jansenius (1585–1638), bishop of Ypres, Belgium. However, what they have in common is what is crucial in this context. Baius anticipated Jansenism in that he held that in Eden innocence (original justice) was not a supernatural gift to Adam and Eve but a necessary component of human nature itself; that is, that God was tautologically unable to withhold from Adam the gifts of original justice, so that original sin reverses this order: now nature is inherently sinful.Without grace, man necessarily sins in all that he does, even in striving after virtue for its own sake; and now even involuntary concupiscence is sinful, including in infants. Building on these positions, Jansenius held that grace was due to Adam by right. For that same reason, original sin utterly vitiated human nature, such that pagan virtues are in reality vices before God. Both Baius and Jansenius were condemned by a series of popes, not least because they ran afoul of Trent’s condemnation of Luther’s assertion that concupiscence is itself a sin. In the context of these condemnations, it becomes obvious why theology had to distinguish, at least conceptually, nature from grace, a point that de Lubac is willing to concede, albeit diffidently: “But without for the moment going back any further than the time of Baius, it is possible, I believe, to show that this idea of pure nature, as it is understood by modern theology, is a systematic idea, quite legitimate no doubt and perhaps useful, but recent.” De Lubac, Augustinianism, 106; emphasis added. But why should the “recent” provenance of the doctrine tell against it necessarily? Is not de Lubac here implicitly invoking a kind of “originalism” or “primitivism” that goes against Newman’s Essay on Development ? 28 De veritate, q. 27, a. 2; emphases added. 638 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. man’s nature. However, elsewhere Thomas, almost anticipating the later condemnations of Baius and Jansenius, says: “Reason and will are naturally directed to God, inasmuch as He is the beginning and end of nature, but in proportion to nature. But reason and will, according to their nature, are not sufficiently directed to God as the object of supernatural happiness.”29 Elsewhere Thomas makes these crucial distinctions:“There can be no inclination except to that which is similar and fitting.”30 Even more telling is this axiom of his thought: “Now it is evident that whatever tends to an end has, in the first place, an aptitude or proportion to that end, for nothing tends to a disproportionate end.”31 Thus the transition from the texts of the Angelic Doctor to his commentators is, if not absolutely seamless, nonetheless smooth and unproblematic.32 The only way to reconcile the earlier-cited statements in the Thomist corpus that de Lubac favors with these just-cited ones used by Feingold is, the latter claims, to make a distinction between innate and elicited desires, which is just what the famous and nearly canonical Dominican commentator Thomas de Vio Cajetan (1469–1534), for example, does in his commentary on the Summa: “Note that natural appetite is generally used in two senses. First, with regard to an inclination implanted by nature. . . . Second, it is taken for a second act, by which one tends to something previously known.”33 29 ST I–II, q. 62, a. 1, ad 3. 30 ST I–II, q. 8, a. 1. 31 ST I–II, q. 25, a. 2. 32 James Healey makes the fascinating observation that both classical scholastics and Jansenius failed to notice the essential paradoxicality of their respective positions when set over against each other:“Despite these deficiencies, however, Jansenius’s critique of pure nature is not without value. . . . In stressing this sanating [healing] role of charity Jansenius therefore emphasizes a link between goodness and grace which had perhaps been neglected by the Scholastics in their concern to protect the supernaturality of grace and the possibility of a naturally good act. . . . Finally, there is perhaps some merit in Jansenius’s insistence that for Augustine nature too is grace. For if the assertion that ‘all is grace’ shows theological carelessness and exposes one to the risk of neglecting the extraordinary gift of God which is theologically expressed as ‘supernatural,’ it is nonetheless true that nature too is God’s gift. . . . If anything, Jansenius seems to have missed the full significance of this understanding of nature. For what is ‘natural’ rather than ‘supernatural’ is not ‘man’s’ rather than ‘God’s’ but, in its own way, a manifestation of the generosity of God which is even more extraordinarily manifested in ‘supernatural’ grace.” James G. Healey, S.J., Jansenius’ Critique of Pure Nature (Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1964), 76–77. 33 Commenting on ST I, q. 78, a. 1, notation 5, in the Leonine edition at Vol. 5, 252; full citation in Feingold, Natural Desire, 19, note 35. The Surnaturel Controversy 639 Only the second can be properly called a natural desire for God. That is, inclinations “implanted by nature” pertain to hunger for food and the like, and the failure to attain them leads to death. But the second kind of natural desire, one that follows on philosophical reflections of the world leading to a realization that there is a First Cause, that kind of desire can be adequately fulfilled by using one’s natural powers of reasoning independent of supernatural grace (Aristotle serves as the test case here). Therefore, say most of the commentators, supernatural grace gives not just the means to reach the supernatural destiny that God intends for rational creatures, it gives a new end as well; that is, it gives a quite different—an entirely unexpected—kind of fulfillment, precisely because a new end first comes into view with the bestowal of grace.34 The trouble with this distinction between innate and elicited natural desires is that the second depends, in Cajetan’s words, on “something previously known,” which means that an elicited desire can be elicited only from someone who has already reached the age of reason, a concession which brings us back to the old specter of limbo. At least one must give Feingold credit here for not flinching from the issue, even if it damages his case, since the hypothesis of limbo has almost completely disappeared—and not just from the common opinion (the sententia communis) of theologians either, but from magisterial documents as well, as even critics of de Lubac concede.35 Still, there can be no question that Feingold’s attack on de Lubac, as well as his defense of the commentary tradition, directly entails, at least for him, the existence of limbo, as he unflinchingly concedes: With regard to the text of St.Augustine [Confessions 1.1] and the great theme of man as imago Dei, analogical distinctions also need to be 34 Whenever Thomas quotes St. Paul to the effect that “Eye hath not seen, nor ear heard, neither have entered into the heart of man the things which God hath prepared for them that love him” (1 Cor 2:9), this is a reliable indicator that he is speaking of a twofold end for man, a natural one that man expects, since it is born out of his natural (albeit elicited) desire and thus set vividly before his imagination in the wake of philosophical contemplation; and a supernatural one that, if granted, comes utterly without anticipation. 35 “Ever since Jacques Maritain and his inseparable friend, Charles Journet, the doctrine of limbo has been hard put to find defenders. . . . Even more, The Catechism of the Catholic Church makes no mention of limbo in regard to infants who die unbaptized (see no. 1261).This silence is eloquent when we consider that up until the middle of the twentieth century this doctrine was commonly held as a certain theological truth and was diffused widely among the Christian people by catechesis.” Serge-Thomas Bonino, O.P.,“The Theory of Limbo and the Mystery of the Supernatural in St.Thomas Aquinas,” in Bonino, ed., Surnaturel:A Controversy, 117–54; here 117, note 1. Edward T. Oakes, S.J. 640 made. There is a restlessness of the heart that comes from nature, and another far higher restlessness that is the product of grace. Likewise, resting in God can have a natural as well as a supernatural realization for St. Thomas, for he recognizes limbo as a state of natural happiness in which the souls of the unbaptized who died before the age of reason rejoice in a natural contemplation of God and do not experience interior restlessness of dissatisfaction.36 One can readily see how Feingold got himself enticed into this culde-sac. For he rightly notes not just that de Lubac’s version of the natural desire to see God undermines the thesis of limbo, but also that any attack on him must entail the existence of limbo: The fact that the deprivation of the vision of God causes no suffering for the souls in limbo can only be either because they experience no natural desire to see God, or because their natural desire to see God is only a conditional one whose frustration causes no suffering.The first possibility must be discarded because St. Thomas had already demonstrated in ScG III ch 50–51 that all intellectual creatures naturally desire to see God, once they consider His existence. It follows, therefore, that the natural desire to see God in those without knowledge of Revelation can only be a conditional desire. . . . Furthermore, these articles of St. Thomas on the lack of spiritual suffering in limbo reveal a fundamental incompatibility with de Lubac’s interpretation of the natural desire to see God. Precisely because de Lubac holds the desire to see God to be the most absolute of all desires, he cannot admit that it could be frustrated or unfulfilled without causing an essential suffering. This certainly seems to imply a significant form of spiritual suffering, which is precisely what St.Thomas emphatically excludes from limbo.37 Feingold errs, however, when he implies that limbo was first mooted as a defense of elicited natural desire. Admittedly, he never asserts the historical connection, but the implication is there because of the way he ties the two together logically. But in fact limbo was first introduced to get around Augustine’s teaching that unbaptized infants go directly to 36 Feingold, Natural Desire, 203; emphases in the original. This entailment is mentioned frequently in Feingold’s text, as here:“Furthermore, it is precisely for this reason that St.Thomas, followed by the vast majority of Catholic theologians for seven centuries, held that limbo would be a state of natural joy without any spiritual suffering for many individuals of our concretely existing human race” (ibid., 391). Here again Feingold elides the hypothesis of pure nature with the concrete reality of limbo. Worse, he relies on a consensus that no longer obtains. The large listing of page numbers under “Limbo” in his Index is another indication of how much his argument relies on this jejune theologoumenon. 37 Feingold, Natural Desire, 352; emphasis in the original. The Surnaturel Controversy 641 hell.38 Of course, once that hypothesis began to win over the majority of theologians, the concept of natura pura gained a new purchase on the theological imagination; and from that point on, the assertion of limbo marched pari passu with continued theological reflection on the meaning of a nature not endowed with grace. Unfortunately for Feingold’s thesis, once the hypothesis of limbo is abandoned for other reasons, it only begs the question to appeal to the authority of the medieval doctors for its restitution, as Feingold clearly does here: Third, an unconditional natural desire for the vision of God would contradict St. Thomas’s well-known teaching concerning the lack of spiritual suffering in limbo, since the lack of realization of an unconditional natural desire would necessarily cause spiritual suffering and an essential frustration of the spiritual creature.39 The trouble with this argument, besides its sheer reliance on authority, is that it ignores the shift in logic that has taken place in the twentieth century. St. Augustine was driven to his version of an infantile hell because of this syllogism: 1. Our hearts are restless until they rest in God. 2. Baptism is necessary for salvation, that is, for the attainment of the beatific vision, without which our hearts remain inherently restless. 3. Therefore, unbaptized infants suffer the restless torments of hell, eternally. The medieval advocates of an infantile limbo, on the other hand, used a different syllogism: 1. Baptism is necessary if the human rational creature is to be given both the supernatural desire for the beatific vision and its actual attainment. 2. However, there are two ends in every rational creature: the contemplation of God as First Cause, which can be attained using reason’s natural powers; and the contemplation of the divine essence, a gift of supernatural grace given in baptism. 38 See Augustine’s Opus incompletum contra Julianum and Sermon 294 for especially gruesome depictions of infantile suffering in hell. 39 Feingold, Natural Desire, 428. But Thomas clearly holds that “demonstration from authority is the weakest form of proof ” (ST I, q. 1, a. 8, ad 2). 642 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. 3. Therefore, infants who die without baptism can still enjoy the felicity of natural contemplation in limbo, since the attainment of that end remains possible without grace and would be unaffected by its deprivation. The modern view, endorsed by Vatican II40 and Pope John Paul II’s encyclical Redemptor Hominis,41 says there is only one end for rational creatures, a supernatural end. Of course, no magisterial document has ever denied that baptism still remains necessary for salvation. So how can the dilemma—that baptism is necessary for salvation and yet all human beings are called to one divine end—be solved without lapsing into St. Augustine’s assertion of an infantile hell? The paradox is resolved by introducing a new premise, the notion of solidarity, the key word for interpreting Pope Benedict XVI’s encyclical Spe Salvi.42 In other words, not only is the idea of felicity in limbo rendered impossible, since every human being has been inscribed by Christ and is destined for him (Col 1:16b), so that eternal separation from him would entail eternal suffering; 40 “In reality it is only in the mystery of the Word made flesh that the mystery of man truly becomes clear. . . . For since Christ died for all, and since all men are in fact called to one and the same destiny, which is divine, we must hold that the Holy Spirit offers to all the possibility of being made partners, in a way known to God, in the paschal mystery.” Gaudium et Spes §22. 41 “Christ, the Redeemer of the world, is the one who penetrated in a unique, unrepeatable way into the mystery of man and entered his ‘heart.’ ” Redemptor Hominis §8; the rest of this same paragraph goes on to endorse Gaudium et Spes §22. 42 “[W]e should recall that no man is an island, entire of itself. Our lives are involved with one another, through innumerable interactions they are linked together. No one lives alone. No one sins alone. No one is saved alone.The lives of others continually spill over into mine: in what I think, say, do and achieve. And conversely, my life spills over into that of others: for better and for worse. So my prayer for another is not something extraneous to that person, something external, not even after death. . . . It is never too late to touch the heart of another, nor is it ever in vain. In this way we further clarify an important element of the Christian concept of hope. Our hope is always essentially also hope for others; only thus is it truly hope for me too. As Christians we should never limit ourselves to asking: how can I save myself? We should also ask: what can I do in order that others may be saved and that for them too the star of hope may rise? Then I will have done my utmost for my own personal salvation as well.” Spe Salvi §48; emphasis added. Note also this encyclical’s endorsement of de Lubac’s book Catholicism: Christ and the Common Destiny of Mankind at §§13–14, especially here: “Against this, drawing upon the vast range of patristic theology, de Lubac was able to demonstrate that salvation has always been considered a ‘social’ reality” (§14). The Surnaturel Controversy 643 but also the absence of some souls from heaven supposedly languishing in limbo would affect the felicity of souls in heaven too.43 The introduction of the notion of solidarity has obvious implications for the theology of baptism. It still remains necessary for salvation, and still remains inherently efficacious ex opere operato. But now this sacrament, pace St.Augustine and the medieval doctors, is seen—as St. Paul saw it—as a sacramental plunge into the death and resurrection of Jesus, sacramentally incorpor ating the new Christian into the Body of Christ, the Church, which is obviously and quintessentially a social reality.44 Given all of these developments (to which de Lubac of course made his own contribution),45 but considering also and above all the fact that these developments have been taught by both councils and popes, we can now conclude that any theology of nature and grace that entails the 43 “This real life, towards which we try to reach out again and again, is linked to a lived union with a ‘people,’ and for each individual it can only be attained within this ‘we’. It presupposes that we escape from the prison of our ‘I,’ because only in the openness of this universal subject does our gaze open out to the source of joy, to love itself—to God.” Spe Salvi §14. 44 It would take us too far afield to analyze in detail Paul’s theology of baptism, but this at least can be noted:“One could say without exaggeration that the concept of the body forms the keystone of Paul’s theology. In its closely interconnected meanings, the word soma knits together all his great themes. It is from the body of sin and death that we are delivered; it is through the body of Christ on the Cross that we are saved; it is into His body the Church that we are incorporated; it is by His body in the Eucharist that this Community is sustained; it is in our body that its new life has to be manifested; it is to a resurrection of this body to the likeness of His glorious body that we are destined. Here, with the exception of the doctrine of God, are represented all the main tenets of the Christian Faith—the doctrines of Man, Sin, the Incarnation and Atonement, the Church, the Sacraments, Sanctification, and Eschatology. To trace the subtle links and interaction between the different senses of this word soma is to grasp the thread that leads through the maze of Pauline thought.” J. A.T. Robinson, The Body: A Study in Pauline Theology (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1952), 9. At a minimum we can conclude from this passage that baptism entails much more than an individual’s ticket of admission to heaven. Rather, it involves a sacerdotal (1 Pt 2:9) responsibility to make the Church more and more the universal sacrament of salvation that she declares herself to be (Lumen Gentium §1). 45 It has long been recognized that Gaudium et Spes §22 is directly reliant on de Lubac:“By revealing the Father and by being revealed by him, Christ completes the revelation of man to himself. . . . It is through Christ that the person reaches maturity, that man emerges definitively from the universe and becomes conscious of his own being.” Henri de Lubac, Catholicism: Christ and the Common Destiny of Man, trans. Lancelot Sheppard (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1989), 339. See Paul McPartlan, Sacrament of Salvation:An Introduction to Eucharistic Ecclesiology (Edinburgh:T & T Clark, 1995), 74. 644 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. necessary conclusion that the limbus infantium actually exists, will have undermined its case irreparably. But perhaps the hypothesis of pure nature (as a purely hypothetical possibility, if not as an actually obtaining reality in salvation history) can still be rescued using other arguments, as Long tries to do; and so to him we now turn. II.2 Although Steven Long has nothing but praise for Feingold’s work,46 he wisely refrains from resorting to that pis aller of medieval eschatology, an infantile limbo. But he does adopt and make his own several other features of Feingold’s work, and at times sharpens them with more directly theological arguments, which means less reliance on the argument from mere authority. Like Feingold, Long readily concedes de Lubac’s orthodox intentions;47 and like Feingold, he admits that one reason the debate has remained so intractable down through the ages is because of an inherent ambiguity in Thomas’s original texts: It helps to put to rest the exegetic difficulty. It is without doubt true that there is a problem in the very texts of Aquinas, and a problem which seemingly does not allow much room for maneuver with respect to its solution: because the doctrinal points which constitute the elements of the problem—one is almost tempted to say “constitute the contradiction”—are starkly and clearly stated in St. Thomas’s text.Yet the realization that there are indeed two sets of texts, one of which was not merely an interposed corruption, itself marks a decisive advance toward correct interpretation of Thomas’s teaching. . . .The second set of texts hedges about, and delimits, the possible signification of the first set, and vice versa. That is, on the supposition that we do not wish to 46 The first chapter of Natura Pura is a republication of his article “On the Loss, and the Recovery, of Nature as a Theonomic Principle: Reflections on the Nature/Grace Controversy,” Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 133–83; all citations will be from the pagination in the book version. Chapter 2 of Natura Pura focuses its polemics against Hans Urs von Balthasar’s (alleged) endorsement of de Lubac in his influential monograph, The Theology of Karl Barth. But a treatment of this part of his argument would take this article beyond its proper focus and so will not be discussed here. The same must apply a fortiori to any critique leveled by Long against Etienne Gilson, Jacques Maritain, Jean Porter,Tracy Rowland, or Joseph Ratzinger. One does wish to salute, however, Long’s courage in taking on this “cloud of witnesses.” 47 “[D]e Lubac’s account of the natural desire for God, despite what I shall argue to be its doctrinal deficiency, is rooted in a genuinely profound theological need to overcome the loss of natural order as a theonomic principle.” Long, Natura Pura, 11. The Surnaturel Controversy 645 suppose St.Thomas’s texts to exhibit raw incoherence, then we need to read these texts in relation one to another.48 Given this duality of texts, Long (along with Feingold) accuses de Lubac of a tendentious selection of texts from the Thomist/Thomistic corpus, highlighting the first set while ignoring the second; this obviously only “solves” the problem by ignoring it. Of course, de Lubac would reply that the same might be said of St. Thomas’s commentators, only from the opposite side. But since both Feingold and Long concede that the first set of texts in Thomas shows him to be, at the least, more nuanced than the neo-scholastic tradition had noticed, we are now finally in the position to take the inadequacies of both neo-scholasticism and de Lubac into account, in order to forge a stronger synthesis.49 One of the great merits in Long’s book is the way he transposes this debate to a discussion of the moral law, both natural and divinely promulgated, a dimension long missing from this debate. As is conceded by all sides, St. Thomas recognizes both forms of law; but rarely has it been noted that his discussion of the interrelationship of these two versions of law has direct bearing on the nature-grace relationship. Consider this passage from the prima secundae : 48 Long, Natura Pura, 13, 15; emphasis in the original. He gives samples here: “On the one hand, we have St. Thomas’s argument that to know God is the end of every intelligent substance (Summa contra Gentiles III, 25), that there is indeed a natural desire for God (ScG III, c. 25; and Summa theologiae I–II, q. 3, a. 8); and that no natural desire may be in vain (ST I, q. 75, a. 6; Compendium 104). On the other hand, we have his clear affirmation that human and angelic natures are distinguished based upon their differing natural and proximate ends whereas their supernatural beatific end is the same (ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1; Quaestiones de anima a. 7, ad 10).” Long, Natura Pura, 13. 49 Guy Mansini makes the perfectly correct observation that this dilemma goes back to the New Testament and is not some tiresome piece of theological arcanum bequeathed to us by the Angelic Doctor: on the one hand, Scripture speaks of everything being made through Christ and for Christ ( Jn 1:1–3; Col 1:15–16), while on the other it speaks of our elevation to grace on the analogy of adopted sons (Rom. 8:14–17). It is of course the whole point of adoption that it is not owed to the natural child (one thinks of Charles Dickens’s novel David Copperfield here). So the paradox is rooted in revelation. See Guy Mansini, O.S.B., “The Abiding Significance of Henri de Lubac’s Surnaturel,” The Thomist 73 (2009): 593–619.Thomas Joseph White sees this same tension in Gaudium et Spes, supposedly the document where de Lubac has been most univocally vindicated: “Gaudium et Spes is, after all, replete with moral exhortations that are meant to inspire or appeal to the conscience of modern human beings of all backgrounds (including non-Christians and the areligious). . . . In other words, the document is replete with appeal to principles of natural law.”White, “ ‘Pure Nature’ of Christology,” 285. 646 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. If man were ordained to no other end than that which is proportionate to his natural faculty, there would be no need for man to have any further direction on the part of his reason besides the natural law and human [positive] law, the latter of which is derived from the former. But since man is ordained to an end of eternal happiness, which exceeds the proportion of man’s natural faculty, as stated above, therefore it was necessary that, besides the natural and the human law, man should be directed to his end by a law given by God. . . . But to his supernatural end man needs to be directed in a yet higher way. Hence, the additional law given by God, whereby man shares more perfectly in the eternal law.50 Now, since no one has ever claimed that St. Thomas considered the natural law to be a mere “hypothesis,” meant only to guarantee the gratuity of the divine law, Long is able to draw this inexorable conclusion: “The proportionate capacity of human nature is not a fiction, it is not a limit concept, it is not merely ideational; rather, it is something created by God.”51 Or, as he earlier puts it in a felicitous image, nature is not a vacuole (a biological term referring to a cavity or vesicle in the cytoplasm of a cell), by which he means: “Created nature in all its ontological density is not the theologian’s posit; it is God’s effect.”52 Of course that effect is permeated with signs of God’s involvement in salvation history. But those effects do not obliterate nature; rather they presuppose it in its integrity, however difficult it may be to sort out one from the other: Of course, the concept of pure nature can be exactly specified [through abstraction].What cannot be exactly specified are circumstantial aspects of divine providence that we could only know in relation to their actual promulgation through God creating nature apart from grace, which He has not done. But any further ordering of nature in and by grace cannot efface the primordial ordering of nature that is presupposed 50 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 4, resp. and ad 1. 51 Long, Natura Pura, 201. Further:“Human nature is a real principle in the human person, and its species is derived, not from the ultimate supernatural end of beatific vision, but from its proportionate natural end” (ibid., 200). But far from cordoning off the natural law into a separate realm independent of the drama of salvation history, Long fully admits their mutual interpenetration: “Nothing in this, however, is to suggest that the natural end in its proper integrity and completeness may be attained apart from grace in the actually existing providential order. Nor can the ultimate supernatural end be attained by one who rejects the impress of the divine wisdom in the natural law and its dominion over his actions. For both natural law and the lex nova are participations in the eternal law” (ibid., 200–201). 52 Long, Natura Pura, 64; emphasis in the original. The Surnaturel Controversy 647 by grace, and on the basis of which man is defined and placed in an intelligible species: the contrary is simply irrationalism, denying that we can know human nature in its essential teleological structures because these are further ordered in grace.To be further ordered is not not to be, nor is it to be naturally unknowable.53 Even when one concedes these trenchant arguments (as I do), problems still lurk in Long’s analysis. For example, in a lengthy footnote, he seems to concede more than he realizes when he is addressing the great conundrum in this debate, the place where Thomas says: “Since it is impossible that a natural desire be frustrated, which would happen if we could not arrive at the understanding of the divine substance that all minds naturally desire, it is therefore necessary to affirm that it is possible to see the divine substance by way of the intelligence.”54 This quotation clearly belongs in the first set of statements, the ones that support de Lubac’s thesis. Long recognizes the difficulty and handles it by claiming that Thomas is speaking as a theologian, that is, from the point of view of revelation, which alone can tell us that the desire to see the divine essence is proximately possible, whereas a philosopher can only deduce that it is abstractly possible. From which Long concludes: “only revelation seems to assure the possibility of the divine vision in the second sense of proximate possibility, such that the natural desire becomes unconditional.”55 But of course, that was precisely de Lubac’s thesis: that our natural desire for God is unconditional and that its eschatological frustration entails hell; and he always 53 Long, Natura Pura, 72–73; all emphases in the original.This passage happens to be directed against Balthasar but has obvious relevance to de Lubac, although he is willing to concede a greater debt to the pure-nature tradition in Balthasar than in de Lubac: “Balthasar will argue, correctly, that the nature confronting our intelligence does not exist in a separated or ‘pure’ fashion (‘separated’ or ‘pure’ in the sense of being unaffected by its mode of being and its relation to God’s grace): ‘God’s real world order [says Balthasar] is the de facto unity of two materially distinguishable and distinct orders that can be differentiated in analysis but are still not separate in reality.’ No Thomist could say it better.” Long, Natura Pura, 66; quoting from Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Theology of Karl Barth: Exposition and Interpretation, trans. Edward T. Oakes, S.J. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992), 280; emphases in the original. One recalls here as well Balthasar’s famous criticism of what he called Barth’s “christological bottleneck,” by which he meant that Barth’s theology was so relentlessly christocentric that it could make no room for creation (or even the Church) as self-subsistent realities. In my opinion (although the point cannot be argued here), Balthasar is more nuanced on this issue of nature’s self-subsistence vis-à-vis Chirst than de Lubac. 54 ScG III, chap. 5. 55 Long, Natura Pura, 226, note 11; emphasis added. 648 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. considered himself a theologian (a historical theologian, to be sure). So Long seems to have brought us right back to the starting point with nothing resolved. Finally, there is the pesky issue of limbo again.Although, as I said above, Long wisely avoids making his case for natura pura rely on that jejune theologoumenon, he comes close at one point to insisting on the reality of an infantile limbo, and—as with Feingold—does so merely on the authority of the Common Doctor: “[I]f the natural desire for God were formally a desire for supernatural beatific vision, it would follow that to be perpetually deprived of this end proper to nature would be a punishment.Yet St. Thomas teaches exactly the contrary.”56 What I have attempted to do in this section is to present as fairly as I can the case against de Lubac as lodged by Feingold and Long, together 56 Long, Natura Pura, 14. Again, I would like to register my bafflement at the way the question of limbo keeps getting dragged into the debate. It is supposed to be conceded on all sides that the concept of pure nature serves merely as a hypothetical possibility to preserve the gratuity of grace and to block the way to Baianism and Jansenism.Yet, obviously, if limbo did exist, that is, if infants (or Aristotle, or Averroes, or even, of all people, Suleiman the Magnificent, as Dante held) really were enjoying right now a natural bliss outside of the precincts of heaven, then there would be in the actual order a pure nature, that is, a pocket of reality untouched by Christ, a clear contradiction of the Prologue to John’s Gospel and of the christological hymns in Colossians. Plus, limbo presupposes that baptism cannot be seen as a sacrament of salvation unless the non-baptized are denied salvation. But to subscribe to that binary conclusion (a legacy of St. Augustine’s lingering Manicheeism) means the establishment of an insidious temptation in the minds of the baptized, such as to make them resent the idea of the non-baptized “sneaking into” heaven by the backdoor, so to speak. One cannot imagine an attitude more antithetical to Spe Salvi—or of Ratzingerian theology more generally: “We cannot start to set limits on God’s behalf; the very heart of the faith has been lost to anyone who supposes that it is only worthwhile, if it is, so to say, made worthwhile by the damnation of others. Such a way of thinking, which finds the punishment of other people necessary, springs from not having inwardly accepted the faith; from loving only oneself and not God the Creator, to whom his creatures belong.That way of thinking would be like the attitude of those people who could not bear the workers who came last being paid a denarius like the rest; like the attitude of people who feel properly rewarded only if others have received less.This would be the attitude of the son who stayed at home, who could not bear the reconciling kindness of his father. It would be a hardening of our hearts, in which it would become clear that we were only looking out for ourselves and not looking for God; in which it would be clear that we did not love our faith, but merely bore it like a burden. . . . It is a basic element of the biblical message that the Lord died for all—being jealous of salvation is not Christian.” Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, God Is Near Us:The Eucharist, the Heart of Life, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2003), 35–36; emphasis added. The Surnaturel Controversy 649 with possible critiques of them that arise solely from within the presuppositions of their own respective analyses. In the next and final section, I would like to step back from the debate as currently conducted to see if there might be a way of more directly unraveling this Gordian knot by the introduction of other considerations. III III.1 Although the previous analysis might make it sound like this debate has reached a standstill, there are in fact more convergences between supporters and critics of de Lubac than are at first apparent.Toward the end of his book, Feingold shares one of his great worries about the long-term effects of de Lubac’s interpretation of the natural desire for God: “[O]ne of the great pastoral problems of our time is that so many people, Catholics and non-Catholics alike, take Heaven for granted as something somehow due simply to natural goodness.This view debases Heaven by naturalizing it.”57 Actually, de Lubac agrees! Most secondary scholarship on de Lubac, both pro and con, largely ignores his criticism of liberal Catholicism in the wake of Vatican II.58 Even as early as 1969 he was attacking the liberal 57 Feingold, Natural Desire, 443. Anyone who has been to a postconciliar funeral will readily commiserate with Feingold here and join in singing his keen. Say the deceased was an avid golfer—in that case you can be sure someone at the wake or during the eulogy will speak of the late, much-lamented Uncle Wilbur as now enjoying himself in the Great Golf Course in the Sky.When the aged senator from West Virginia, ninety-two-year-old Robert Byrd (known as the King of Pork for all the federal largesse he poured into his state), died in the summer of 2010, the Catholic (!) bishop of Charleston (the capital of West Virginia) chirruped that the Senator was surely now in heaven. One wonders if the burdened taxpayers from other states agreed, whose children will be saddled for generations to come with paying off the federal debt that was used to fund all that Appalachian bacon. 58 An exception is Voderholzer:“For de Lubac, the seventies were also overshadowed by many disappointments. He had helped in so many ways to prepare for the Second Vatican Council and only a few years before had had to defend himself against the accusation that he was an innovator, yet now he was suddenly considered the proponent of an old, supposedly obsolete theology. For his eightieth birthday, on February 20, 1976, de Lubac received a handwritten letter from Pope Paul VI. He showed it to the superior of the house, but he did not even want to look at it, and his Provincial would not read it either.”Voderholzer, Meet de Lubac, 95. See also Christopher J. Walsh, “De Lubac’s Critique of the Postconciliar Church,” Communio: International Catholic Review 19 (1992): 404–32.According to Walsh, there was evidently a complete breakdown of trust at that time between de Lubac and his Jesuit superiors.At one point, an article that de Lubac had written was rejected for publication in a Jesuit organ for its criticisms of liberal Catholicism (oh, the irony!), which prompted de Lubac to call the episode “a final 650 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. partisans who were appealing to that vapid fata morgana called “the spirit of the council” to justify their deviations from both the council itself and core Christian teachings. In an address delivered at Saint Louis University on the occasion of its sesquicentennial, where he received an honorary doctorate, de Lubac addressed the perhaps surprised assembly in words that can only be described as a jeremiad: The Christian thinkers of the past are looked down upon as if they no longer had anything to say; the traditional formulations of faith are stated in such a way as to appear ridiculous, so as to hasten their replacement. And under the pretext of merely changing this or that word or phrase, it is the very essence of our faith which runs the risk of being sifted away. . . .Whatever is recriminatory, whatever excites, is declared prophetic, even if it is evident that it stems from ignorance, or from concessions made to what is currently in vogue—and this is the exact opposite of what we mean by prophetic! . . .We must not be afraid to say so: there is nothing in all of this that is promising. A faith which dissolves itself is unable to engender anything whatever. A community which breaks up is incapable of radiating or of attracting others. Agitation is not synonymous with life.That last hatched slogan is not necessarily a new thought.The noisiest critics are frequently the most sterile.59 Furthermore, he explicitly links the pathology here described with a loss of the sense of the supernatural, precisely the gravamen of the concerns about de Lubac’s theology in both Feingold and Long. In other words, just because de Lubac is most famous for his criticisms of “extrinsicism,” that does not make him an advocate of “intrinsicism,” at least if that term is defined to mean that man has any claim, by virtue of his natural desire for God, on divine grace, or still less that he can entirely dispense with the supernatural merely by, say, working to reform “unjust social structures.” On the contrary, for de Lubac, Gaudium et Spes sought for an openness to the world precisely in order to announce the salvation that comes from Christ: But [de Lubac continues] is it not just the opposite for some? Does not such an “openness” become a forgetfulness of salvation and of the gospel, a tending toward secularism, a loosening of faith and morals? Finally, this “openness” becomes for others a loss of identity, in a word, example of police methods practiced by certain intelligentsia reigning at that time in France in the Society of Jesus” (as cited in Walsh,“De Lubac’s Critique,” 411). 59 Henri de Lubac,“The Church in Crisis,” Theology Digest 17 (1969): 312–25; here 317. A revised version of this address was published in Nouvelle Revue Théologique 91 (1969): 580–96. The Surnaturel Controversy 651 the betrayal of our obligation toward the world. Because the Council, following the desire of John XXIII, did not wish either to define new dogmas or to pronounce anathemas, many conclude that the church no longer has the right to judge anything or anyone; they recommend a “pluralism” which is not the pluralism of the theological schools but that of entirely different beliefs from those of the normative faith. . . . The word “renewal” can cover a multitude of abuses!60 De Lubac continued these critiques until his last book, published in 1989, Mémoire sur l’occasion de mes écrits.61 (After the appearance of this book, he suffered a series of strokes and died on September 4, 1991, in the care of the Little Sisters of the Poor.) Perhaps nowhere was he both more poignant and more succinct than in this passage from an earlier book: “People nowadays speak about the Church more than they experience her.They discuss questions of faith more than they live its mystery. From this comes the expected result: a somnolence, a lassitude, a refusal to react—indeed a secret complacency—in the face of destructive forces.”62 Needless to say, all these citations manifesting de Lubac’s cri de coeur can be readily taken by his critics as confirming their critique, and perhaps they are right; it would have to be conceded, though, that de Lubac himself never abandoned his prior writings on nature and grace.63 But at 60 De Lubac, “Church in Crisis,” 319. 61 Translated as At the Service of the Church: Henri de Lubac Reflects on the Circum- stances that Occasioned his Writings, trans. Anne Elizabeth Englund (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993). See also Henri de Lubac, Entretien autour de Vatican II (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1985); an abridged translation of this book-length interview appeared as De Lubac: A Theologian Speaks (Los Angeles:Twin Circle, 1985). 62 Henri de Lubac, L’Église dans la crise actuelle (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1969), 18. 63 This refusal to back down can be seen most clearly in a work de Lubac wrote for the International Theological Commission, to which he had been appointed by Pope Paul VI: Henri de Lubac, A Brief Catechism on Nature and Grace, trans. Richard Arnandez, F.S.C. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1984).Also, this anecdote from Voderholzer is telling:“Whereas de Lubac was regarded by proponents of a self-styled progressive trend as a theologian who had meanwhile become hopelessly obsolete, there was, on the other hand, no lack of critics who claimed that he was primarily responsible for the onset of the crisis in the Church. In 1975 someone mailed de Lubac photocopied excerpts from the book entitled Gethsemane by the Archbishop of Genoa, [Giuseppe] Cardinal Siri. The cardinal denounced ‘the historical conscience,’ ‘hermeneutics’ and the ‘existential reference’ as hallmarks of a theology leading to destruction, for which de Lubac was chiefly to blame, along with Karl Rahner and Jacques Maritain. De Lubac resolutely defended himself against these charges in a letter dated November 15, 1975. . . .Without entering into a discussion with Siri, de Lubac referred to the approval of his work by Pope Pius XII and to the favorable judgment of Étienne Gilson.”Voderholzer, Meet de Lubac, 97. 652 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. least Feingold and Long are on the same page with de Lubac on this issue: all theologies on the nature/grace dialectic must always serve this thoroughly biblical injunction: So we do not lose heart.Though our outer nature is wasting away, our inner nature is being renewed day by day. For this slight momentary affliction is preparing for us an eternal weight of glory beyond all comparison, because we look not to the things that are seen but to the things that are unseen. For what is seen is transitory, but the things that are unseen are eternal. . . . So from now on we regard no one from a human point of view; even though we once regarded Christ in this way, we do so no longer. Therefore, if anyone is in Christ, he is a new creation. The old has gone; behold, the new has come! (2 Cor 4:16–18; 5:16–17; RSV, emphases added).64 III.2 Given the fact that both de Lubac and his critics Feingold and Long want to preserve the gratuity of grace in the face of the secularist onslaught, but also considering their different approaches to attaining that commonly held aim, might there be another way of reconciling their differences? Here I would like to pick up on one line in de Lubac’s lament against liberal Catholicism cited above: his plaint that a loss of the sense of the supernatural had led to “a loosening of faith and morals.”65 If we tie this together with Long’s remarks about the natural law cited above in section II.2 of this article, I think we can find a possible rapprochement on the horizon. In my opinion, Long scored a bull’s-eye when he showed that the existence of natural law and its continued validity ( pace Barth) even after the promulgation of divine law entails this already-cited conclusion:“Created nature in all its ontological density is not the theologian’s posit; it is God’s effect.”66 But perhaps this insight can be taken further: can we say something about the place of desire inside the framework of natural law? That is, since law implies choice, and since choice entails the possibility of disobedience (otherwise there would be no freedom), then what one desires, when set against the moral law, is of obvious relevance. What strikes me, in other words, in this debate is that the term “desire” is still spoken of too abstractly, without a due allowance being made to 64 Oddly, both Feingold/Long and de Lubac could find in this passage validation for their respective views, although to establish that would require both careful exegesis of this passage and an account of how they make different use of this passage, something that cannot be attempted here. 65 De Lubac, “Crisis in the Church,” 319. 66 Long, Natura Pura, 64; emphasis in the original. The Surnaturel Controversy 653 the phenomenology of desire in the light of original sin—with its legacy of the fomes peccati, that is, of temptation and concupiscence. But the only way to distinguish proper desires sensu stricto for innately necessary goods (the hunger for food, the instinct for self-preservation and the like) from improper desires that deflect a person from either his natural or his supernatural end (temptation properly speaking), is to view actions and desires in the light of philosophical ethics and/or moral theology.67 For that project, one may perhaps best begin with an important observation from the always brilliant pen of Blaise Pascal, who said: “If man is not made for God, why is he happy only with God? If man is made for God, why is he so hostile to God?”68 In my opinion, debate on the Surnaturel controversy has focused too much on Pascal’s first rhetorical question but not enough on the second. It is, after all, relatively uncontroversial to say that man cannot find his happiness in health, money, sex, or worldly ambition—a point on which the pagan moralists were also agreed (except maybe the Epicureans), and as Aristotle makes clear in Book X of his Nicomachean Ethics. But after the coming of Christ, a new reality entered the world, one that provokes a different kind of “desire,” best summed up in Lucifer’s non serviam. Thus enters, for the first time in history, the chance for human beings to make a definitive No to God’s definitive Yes (2 Cor 1:18–20). Moreover, according to Balthasar, this No continues to become more obstreperous, what he calls a crescendoing No, as he explains in this important passage: Human reason, in its secularizing role in world history, prevents those who reject Jesus’ provocation from returning to a “numinous” worldview in which the divine and worldly commingle, unseparated. . . .This leaves the field clear for what must be called “post-Christian atheism.” For when nature is deprived of divinity, the presence of the Creator within it fades. To the observer who sees matters only in terms of the utile, God disappears into the background.This is a natural process, and over against it is heard the claim of Jesus to be “the way, the truth, and the life” ( John 14:6)—a claim that attracts to itself and concentrates all the religious aspirations of mankind. He goes on to say that “no one comes to the Father except through me.”This is not to deny the ultimate salvation of all who do not know him and adhere to other religions; he is saying that the latter religions do not mediate salvation: he 67 I must wonder aloud here whether the sex-abuse crisis now roiling the Catholic Church is not due, at least in part, to the failure to distinguish various species of desire, very much including sexual desire. Desires are, after all, inherently enddirected. But without an analysis of the morality of a particular end in view, moral confusion and even chaos will ensue. 68 Blaise Pascal, Pensées, trans. Honor Levi (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 8. 654 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. alone does. Once this has become sufficiently well known to mankind, the other religions (those that still remain) are bound to acquire a certain anti-Christian slant.They will try to appropriate all the features of the religion of Jesus that seem to commend it to mankind. . . . The only exceptions are those religions that are directly or indirectly dependent on the biblical revelation, first of all Judaism, and then Islam. They constitute a very strange kind of exception, however, for both of them—first of all Judaism, and then Islam—reject the full claim made by Jesus and so will be particularly susceptible to militant atheism ( Judaism) or to an emphatically anti-Christian theism (Islam).69 Therefore, when theologians speak of “natural desire,” they must carefully attend to the deep, post-Incarnation ambiguity of that phrase. Under that rubric, future debate will have to revisit, among other issues, the common medieval axiom that “it is impossible for a natural desire to be incapable of fulfillment” (ScG III, chap. 51, 1). One hardly needs to be a doctrinaire Darwinian to see how often natural desires go unfulfilled. Indeed, this axiom represents insuperable hurdles for theodicy in a world where natural, innate desires often go unfulfilled, such as in the widespread episodes of starvation in modern history, caused both by nature (the Irish potato famine in the nineteenth century, although that was also abetted by the British government’s laissez-faire economic policies) and by man (the Soviet-engineered famine in the Ukraine in the 1930s).Well before the publication of Darwin’s On the Origin of Species in 1859,Alfred Lord Tennyson penned these lines, which were first published in 1850: Are God and Nature then at strife, That Nature lends us evil dreams? So careful of the type she seems, So careless of the single life. . . . “So careful of the type?” But no. From scarped cliff and quarried stone She cries, “A thousand types are gone: I care for nothing, all shall go.” (In Memoriam, stanzas 55–56) But leaving aside biology and even theodicy, surely this axiom must yield in any event to the Bible’s assertion that creation is subject to futility, and not (just) because of sin but because of something inherent in its identity as a created reality: 69 Balthasar, Theo-Drama IV, 438–39; emphases in the original. The Surnaturel Controversy 655 For creation was subjected to futility, not of its own accord but by the will of him who subjected it in hope, because creation itself will be set free from its bondage to decay and obtain the glorious liberty of the children of God.We know that the whole of creation has been groaning in travail together until now; and not only creation, but we ourselves. (Rom 8:20–23a; emphasis added). Of course all men desire by nature to be happy, an almost tautological truth on which Aristotle, St. Thomas, the signers of the Declaration of Independence, and even Nietzsche are agreed. In that sense, this innate desire cannot be frustrated, since an innate and frustrated desire is selfcontradictory.70 But other, more spiritual forces are at work for which the word “desire” (under any rubric) can hardly serve. Rather, because of the coming of Christ onto the stage of history, efforts to build the terrestrial city take on an inevitable Promethean motivation, one which the Church refutes by her very presence in history. Again Balthasar: We must not be afraid to utter the harsh truth. In making his provocative claim to have reconciled the world in God, Jesus never suggested that he was creating an earthly paradise. The kingdom of God will never be externally demonstrable (Luke 17:21); it grows, invisibly, perpendicular to world history, and the latter’s fruits are already in God’s barns. Man responds to this provocation by attempting to manufacture the kingdom of God on earth, with increasing means and methods of power; logically this power that resists the powerlessness of the Cross is bound to destroy itself, for it bears the principle of self-annihilation within it by saying No to the claim of Christ. And so we are brought to the following formulation, extravagant though it may seem: mankind’s self-destruction is the only foreseeable end to the world, left to itself, and the only end it deserves, insofar as it prefers to hoard what is its own (that is, power, Mammon) rather than gather with Christ. It has already decided its own fate.71 70 As many philosophers (above all, Arthur Schopenhauer) have pointed out, a suicide kills himself to put an end to a situation of current misery, in which of course he is motivated by the desire to be happy, not miserable. 71 Balthasar, Theo-Drama IV, 442; emphasis added. Moreover, just as de Lubac, Feingold, and Long do, Balthasar worries that this same attitude has infected Christians: “Further—and this is something that even more clearly unveils the apocalyptic situation—this fascination so weakens the Christian organism that the alien wasp is able to inject its anesthetizing sting and lay its eggs right inside it, with the result that the body, now hollowed out from inside, serves as welcome food for the enemy.” Balthasar, Theo-Drama IV, 441. He knows well the voice that animates this spirit and mocks them with their own voice here: “Why, if we are serious about God’s incarnation in Jesus, [say these secularizing Christians] should we not salute ‘atheism in Christianity’? For the latter’s norm now resides 656 Edward T. Oakes, S.J. The perspective offered here represents, of course, only a first step in bringing de Lubac’s supporters and critics to a new synthesis. But at least we can say this: based on Christ’s overthrow of the principalities and powers of this world by his entry into history as God’s definitive revelation, grace crowns and completes human efforts and human nature only N&V because it first of all turns them upside down.72 in this divine impulse in man, not in the alienating spell case by a tyrant in heaven” (ibid.). 72 “Looked at in this way, it is not the battle between the two cities of Jerusalem and Babylon that forms the theological heart of history, but a deeper, more hardfought, more crucial struggle. It is the ‘Babylon within us’ which we must throw to the ground at whatever cost.” Hans Urs von Balthasar, A Theology of History (New York: Sheed & Ward, 1963), 146. Nonetheless, Balthasar hastens to add that nature still has its own self-subsistent reality, even when grace turns our expectations upside down and even when we overthrow the “Babylon within.” Indeed, the last sentence of A Theology of History says: “If we miss out the level at which creation has a content proper to itself, then everything dissolves into pan-Christism, reducing the grace-given event of God’s becoming man to the dead level of a cosmological, gnostic process” (ibid., 148). Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 657–670 657 The Situation of Natural Law in Catholic Theology RUSSELL H ITTINGER University of Tulsa Tulsa, Oklahoma I N Catholic theology, discussion of natural law can lean in one of two different directions. When natural law is used as one of the resources for inquiry about practical matters, inquiry moves toward particular actions, cases, and classes of actions. This is moral theology in its fully practical office. When we ask how natural law stands within the economies of creation and redemption our inquiry points toward the foundations of theology.The question “Is divorce licit under the natural law?” corresponds to the first; the question “Does the sacrament of marriage include natural law requirements of marriage?” corresponds to the second. Debates about natural law can arise either way. Not infrequently debates begin in one line only to jump into the other. The sexual questions which have captivated moral theologians for the past half century alternated between issues of precepts and deeper issues of anthropology.This is exactly what we ought to expect for any tradition that takes natural law seriously. The two documents I shall consider in this essay lean more toward the sources than toward practical argument. Neither intends to solve a particular moral question. Veritatis Splendor (1993) is the first papal encyclical devoted exclusively to moral theology. As its subtitle indicates, the encyclical treats foundational issues—one of which is the natural law component of moral theology.1 The International Theological Commission’s study, The Search for a Universal Ethics:A New Look at the Natural Law, considers natural law as a common component of the great “wisdom traditions.”The exposition is heavily weighted toward perennial anthropological and metaphysical themes. Veritatis is in every respect the stronger account because it looks 1 De Quibusdam Quaestionibus Fundamentalibus Doctrinae Moralis Ecclesiae, On Certain Fundamental Questions Concerning the Church’s Moral Teachings. 658 Russell Hittinger ad intra to the coherence of moral theology. The Search aims at dialogue with extra-ecclesial parties for purposes, and under terms of dialogue, that are not always clear. But the two documents—one pontifical, the other a curial paper—give us an interesting picture of how natural law is situated in Catholic theology at the half-century mark from Vatican Council II. First, I want to put the two documents in a specific historical and political context. After the collapse of political christendom—marked in the Catholic world at 1870, when the Roman communion ceased being a de facto arrangement of national churches superintended in many ways by temporal sovereigns—the magisterium had to develop a Catholic position on a wide array of moral issues and social problems: economic justice, associational liberties, church-state relations, and of course, marriage, which from the beginning was the most intense skirmish line along which Catholic moral teachings conflicted with the laws and public policies of the secular regimes.Addressing these broad issues, encyclicals went beyond the more narrowly tailored decrees about moral conduct in canonical and confessional cases.The older division of labor in Catholic christendom that informally distinguished between authority in public policy and authority in ecclesiastical order, corresponding to the competence of royal courts on the one hand and ecclesial tribunals on the other, had become defunct. Rome now had to speak about the moral dimensions of public policy across the board. Leo XIII used natural law as an appeal (and sometimes as an argument) to resituate the problems of society and authority. His use of natural law was elegantly neo-Thomist, and it won the admiration of the Catholic world because Leo succeeded in balancing the disputed moral or political question with the deeper questions about the nature and end of man and the origin of authority. In the twentieth century, however, the list of disputed issues treated at least partially in terms of natural law multiplied, and came to include the “life” issues such as war and peace, abortion, contraception, and sexual conduct generally, as well as the ever-burgeoning sector of problems that spun out of the post-war human rights project (1948). John XXIII’s Pacem in Terris (1963) enumerated some two dozen human rights grounded in natural law.To accommodate the expanding field of social doctrine, the revised Code of Canon Law (1983) states: “The Church has the right always and everywhere to proclaim moral principles, even in respect of the social order, and to make judgments about any human matter in so far as this is required by fundamental human rights or the salvation of souls.”2 2 CIC (1983) can. 747, §2. Natural Law in Catholic Theology 659 The cumulative effect of a century of teachings in the arena of moral theology and social doctrine left the subject of natural law feeling rather cluttered at the practical end of the spectrum. It was easy to lose sight of the coherence that ought to obtain between this bevy of particular moral teachings and the principal sources of moral theology. Thus, the problem of coherence needed to be reconsidered and repaired where it was found wanting. This is the context in which we should read Veritatis Splendor, which addressed the coherence of moral theology precisely as theology. But knowledge of this history also helps us to understand the ITC paper, which keeps in view a human rights movement that has gone awry, multiplying and changing the content of rights to such extent that only an apophatic universal remains—a “negative anthropology.”3 That is to say, we can affirm what man is not, but not what he is prior to self-defining liberty. Veritatis turned to the question of what kind of component natural law is in moral theology, and how it relates to the other sources of doctrine: sacred scripture, christology, theological anthropology, ascetical theology, and ecclesiology. Because it addressed (according to the subtitle) “fundamental questions” rather than fully practical ones, the encyclical was free to make more explicit and to give a more nuanced account of the assumptions that govern the magisterium’s use of natural law theory (or pieces thereof). I shall make no effort to summarize this very rich encyclical. Instead, I call attention to one of the assumptions that Veritatis was at pains to clarify. Namely, that natural law forms an organic part of moral theology. Why shouldn’t the Church concern itself only with the habits and actions immediately ordained to salvation—for example, the theological virtues, the gifts of the Spirit, the Beatitudes, the works of mercy, and sacramental actions? Some theologians raised the question from a slightly different angle.Why shouldn’t the things belonging proximately to the natural law fall within the magisterium of scholars and experts whose expertise pertains to temporal matters? In effect, the two concerns held together rather tersely in the Code of Canon Law (“in so far as this is required by fundamental human rights or the salvation of souls”) were being pulled from either end, philosophical and pastoral.The encyclical notes: In their desire, however, to keep the moral life in a Christian context, certain moral theologians have introduced a sharp distinction, contrary to Catholic doctrine, between an “ethical order” which would be human in origin and of value for “this world” alone, and an “order of salvation” for which only certain intentions and interior attitudes 3 The term “negative anthropology” is taken from Rocco Buttiglione, Karol Wojtyla (Grand Rapids, MI:William B. Eerdmans, 1997), 53. 660 Russell Hittinger regarding God and neighbor would be significant.This has then led to an actual denial that there exists, in Divine Revelation, a specific and determined moral content, universally valid and permanent. (§37) The encyclical explains that moral truths—in principle accessible to human reason (§29)—not only constitute a “preparation for the Gospel,” but are also situated within it (§3). The moral law, thus understood, is presupposed in two ways by moral theology: first, as principles of moral order are derived from human nature; second, as those very same principles are clarified and integrated in the teachings of Christ. “[T]he Magisterium does not bring to the Christian conscience truths which are extraneous to it; rather it brings to light the truths which it ought already to possess, developing them from the starting point of the primordial act of faith” (§64). Thus, the encyclical’s lengthy exegesis of Matthew 19 on the query of the rich young man. Jesus’s exhortation to discipleship explicitly presupposes knowledge of moral law. Keeping the commandments, beginning with the negative precepts, is a “basic condition” for justice, love of neighbor, and for moral maturity and freedom.This module of morality is not unique to either Jewish law or Christian doctrine. As St. Paul contends in Romans 2:14–16, the “conflicting thoughts of the gentiles” give witness to the law as the norm of conscience, according to which “God will judge the secrets of men” (§59).This same law is also explicitly presupposed by Christ when he teaches what is necessary to live a life ordered to the kingdom. From this latter perspective, the moral law is incorporated within another starting point—the life of faith. According to the encyclical, the moral theologian cannot leave behind the natural law component for the purpose of a morality of “salvation” without subverting Scripture and “the living tradition.” To be clear, this is not a fideist position.The encyclical is not saying that there is a “universally valid and permanent” body of moral truths because, according to Matthew 19, Jesus says so or because the Church says so. Nor does it suggest that our only access to moral truth is Scripture or tradition (§3). Rather, the encyclical contends that the moral law, as something proportionate to human reason, forms an organic part of Jesus’ teaching, and therefore it is already internal to moral action in the light of faith. Alasdair MacIntyre has astutely noticed the importance of at least one prong of this position: It is not just that the natural law can be known by the exercise of the powers of reason, independently of revelation, but also that the knowledge of divine law afforded by revelation presupposes a prior knowledge of the precepts of the natural law. It is a revealed truth, that is to say, that Natural Law in Catholic Theology 661 the truths of the natural law can be known prior to and independently of any revealed truths, including this particular revealed truth.4 MacIntyre assures the reader, “that in holding this I am not being theologically eccentric.” He is not at all.5 MacIntyre, however, is more immediately interested in the purely philosophical aspects of debate over natural law, and therefore he does not draw out all of the implications for moral theology. One of these would surely be the following. Even if the institutions of a given culture—universities, courts, the media, other churches and religions—had no further use of natural law either as a supposition or as an explanatory framework, the Church nevertheless would be bound to teach and affirm the natural law. Furthermore, it would need to affirm it precisely as the natural, created measure of human acts; that is to say, as truths that conscience “ought already to possess.”When we hear the words of Matthew 19:8 “From the beginning . . . ” we can grasp both prongs of the commitment to natural law. For the natural sign of the sacrament of marriage is nothing other than marriage “from the beginning.” With respect to this sacrament at least, to erase the natural law would erase the sacrament of the New Covenant. The double commitment therefore is embedded in Catholic theology at levels deeper than what come under the concerns of moral theology or philosophy. Indeed, the theological affirmation of natural law in Veritatis makes the moral theologian more responsible to the natural law than the moral philosopher, and by extension makes the systematic (sacramental) theologian more responsible than the moral theologian. Admittedly, this does not make the work of moral theology easier. Interestingly, according to the Scripture, the rich young man hesitates but does not offer a serious objection to the proposition that moral rectitude is a necessary condition for pursuing eternal life. He declines radical discipleship. Veritatis, on the other hand, deals with the situation in which 4 Alasdair MacIntyre,“From Answers to Questions,” in Intractable Disputes about the Natural Law: Alasdair MacIntyre and Critics, ed. Lawrence S. Cunningham (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2009), 341. 5 Indeed, his brief treatment of Romans 2:14–15 is virtually the same as that of Veritatis Splendor (§59).“It is also a revealed truth that we human beings all of us stand accused before God of our violations of and rebellion against his law. But we could not be rightly held responsible for those violations and that rebellion if we were not aware of God’s law, simply qua human beings, and not only aware of the precepts that comprise God’s law, but aware of the compelling character of their authority.” Ibid., 344. Put in this way, MacIntyre is suggesting that some precepts are not only known but also known in their compelling authority.This puts the issue in the foyer of law, if not higher law. 662 Russell Hittinger the moral prerequisites are the stumbling block “for the Christian conscience.” Put in this way, the moral of the story has been transposed. What was the easy matter now appears difficult and controversial. This surprising transposition is implied but is not made explicit in the encyclical. Nevertheless, it is an important symptom that needs to be carefully discerned by moral theologians. The proposal that there exist moral norms prior to human construction, consent, and choice is a rather alarming message in our culture. In proof of which, we only need to consider the fact that questions of human nature and moral conduct are much more likely to be church-dividing issues than questions concerning justification, predestination, and the function of sacraments. From one point of view, the “natural” morality presupposed by the Gospel is the easier thing, objectively speaking; from another point of view, it is just the opposite. The double commitment also makes it necessary for moral theologians to reckon more seriously with philosophy than what they have been prepared or inclined to do over the past several decades. When it was issued, Veritatis was received in some parts of the Catholic world as a rebuke of progressive-leaning moral theologians. Not very much imagination is required to see that it also cuts the other way—moderating quasi-Barthian currents in Catholic theology that would have nature disappear into grace. If the natural law component is not sustainable without philosophy, it is a daunting responsibility for theologians. For in the institutions of late modernity (not only universities but also in the far greater domain of political, jurisprudential, and corporate life), the major schools of ethics do not explicitly share the same starting points or explanatory framework; indeed, none can be put in any useful way into the category of natural law.6 Therefore, either theologians need to leave the natural law component without philosophical articulation or they will have to do much of that work themselves. In effect, they will have to wear two hats. Thomas Aquinas investigated natural law in his dual role as philosopher and theologian, for which there is no equivalent office or craft in our secular institutions, and increasingly less so in ecclesiastical ones. As Fergus Kerr puts it: “[Thomas] is a philosopher and a theologian, and we are never going to agree on where to put the emphasis.”7 But the problem of emphasis and ongoing debates about it in interpreting Thomas are set 6 MacIntyre, “From Answers to Questions,” 51. 7 See Fergus Kerr, After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), chap. 6, “Natural Law: Incommensurable Readings.” Natural Law in Catholic Theology 663 within, and can arise only within, a tradition that is doubly articulate. Veritatis requires the natural law component to be treated in just that fashion.8 The Search for a Universal Ethics: A New Look at Natural Law (2009) differs from Veritatis not only in its curial pedigree and magisterial weight (a study paper allowed to be published by the Cardinal Prefect of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (hereafter CDF), but more relevantly, for our purposes, in the questions as well as the audience it addresses. The Search aims to orient and enrich a dialogue outside of the immediate environs of moral theology:“[I]n this document we intend to invite all who ask themselves about the ultimate foundations of ethics and of the juridical and political order, to consider the resources that a renewed presentation of the teaching of the natural law contains” (§9). However, in shifting from sources of moral theology to the resources for dialogue, ITC moves to even more difficult terrain than the one occupied by Veritatis. Of course Veritatis too worries about negative anthropology and exaggerated notions of individual autonomy which disorient the natural law that theology presupposes. But it has the signal advantage of correcting and moderating claims of autonomy, as well as the array of different understandings of natural law, within the landscape of its own tradition. The Search appears to tackle the issues on an open field with recourse only to natural law. It claims no more authority than being one wisdom tradition among others—albeit a tradition with centuries of experience in this field of inquiry.9 The subtitle indicates something “new.” But in its treatment of the anthropological and cosmological assumptions, The Search differs very little from Veritatis.10 For example, the authors do not equate natural law with 8 One cannot ignore the fact that the encyclical is shaped by a high, neoThomistic rendering of both natural law and the sources of moral theology.“The Church has often made reference to the Thomistic doctrine of natural law, including it in her own teaching on morality.” VS §44. 9 The Search treats natural law in the light of what the Catholic tradition has cumulatively discovered and formulated over the centuries, including what it has learned from shortcomings in its own experience. On the latter score, the authors note recurring problems of emphasizing too strongly biological nature at the expense of freedom; of having in other ways emphasized too strongly reason, with the inevitable pitfall of rationalism; of having made anthropological assumptions which needed to be adjusted in view of historical and cultural contexts; of suggesting that the precepts of natural law are an already-assembled system, even down to the most proximate level of precepts governing a problem or case; and not always making sufficiently clear the processes of formation needed for a mature appropriation of the natural law (§§10, 38, 52, 56, 59, 99). 10 Including what we have termed the double commitment. Christianity treats the natural law both a preparation for faith and as a teaching within it: “The new 664 Russell Hittinger purely immanent laws of nature (§10); nor do they suggest that natural rights are terms of obligation without natural law (§88).They contend that the relative autonomy of moral truth, and freedom of choice regarding finite goods, already imply a transcendent, though not necessarily a supernatural, end (§§42, 63, 77). Faithful to the Thomistic tradition, they contend that the good of knowing the truth about God is not merely a theoretical, explanatory addendum to natural law, but is contained seedlike in the foundations and experience of moral truth as one of the first precepts (§50). Apropos of Yves Simon’s suggestion that natural law can be discussed in terms of three foci—reason, nature, and god11—The Search recognizes that while reason, nature, and God each has its own salience, the price paid for hiving off one, to the exclusion of the others, will be a doctrine of natural law that is not open to reality as a whole. The vision of the world within which the doctrine of natural law developed and still finds its meaning today, involves therefore the reasoned conviction that there exists a harmony between the three substances [sic—bad translation of ces trois instances ] which are God, man, and nature. In this perspective, the world was perceived as an intelligible whole, united by the common reference of the beings that compose it to a divine founding principle, to a Logos. (§69) The authors are surely correct that a discussion of natural law that puts reason, nature, and God into competition (§§74–75), or that refuses to give to each foci the salience that experience and reason will allow, if not demand, falls short of the Catholic tradition. Interestingly, the ITC does not situate its presentation and its understanding of dialogue in the fashion of a model United Nations plenary session. Rather, it puts its discussion of moral universals in the context of “great wisdom traditions, both religious and philosophical.” Offering our contribution to the search for a universal ethics, and proposing a rationally justifiable foundation, we desire to invite experts and the spokespersons of the great religious, sapiential and philosophical traditions of humanity to proceed to an analogous work, beginning from their sources, to reach a common recognition of the universal moral norms based on a rational approach to reality. (§116) Law of the Gospel includes, takes up and brings to fulfillment the requirements of the natural law.The orientations of the natural law are not therefore external normative demands with respect to the new Law” (§112). These two are mentioned several times: §§12, 23–24, 26–27, 69–71, and 101. 11 Yves R. Simon, Tradition of Natural Law, ed.Vukan Kuic, intro. Russell Hittinger (New York: Fordham University Press, 1992 reprint; orig. 1965), 129. Natural Law in Catholic Theology 665 Wisdom traditions, on this view, recognize and make explicit (in different ways and in various degrees) (1) that there is a “common patrimony” of moral values, (2) that certain moral actions are required by human nature itself, and (3) that the human person stands in a “creative and harmonious manner in a cosmic or metaphysical order that surpasses it and gives meaning to his life.” (§11, 12). Wisdom traditions, in other words, are open to reality as a whole, even if their vision is partial in this or that aspect.Appeal to sapiential traditions is reminiscent of John Paul II’s encyclical Fides et Ratio (1998).12 As The Search recalls, Catholic theology fed upon the bread of sapiential traditions as a praeparatio evangelicae, and once assimilated to theology, the two “form a whole” in the Catholic mind (§26). ITC does not mean by dialogue either the Habermasian or Rawlsian methods for reaching norms mutually acceptable to the parties of the discussion (§8). It also eschews dialogue that is “a purely inductive search, on the parliamentary model, of a minimal already-existing consent.”This is a dialogue, in fact, without a “search.” As the authors remark, the dialogue has not proven adequate either to secure foundations for the post-1948 human rights project or to win support of religions and wisdom traditions, which need more than a “minimal ethic” (§6).Apparently, The Search envisages a dialogue rather different from what is usually meant by “public reason.” Rather than holding back one’s best considered reasons, it puts the mature line of reasons on the table, inviting others to do the same. Appropriation of the “evidences” of natural law either by the individual or by a culture is a slow process, requiring action and reflection—in a wisdom tradition, an “apprenticeship” (§53, §38). This certainly has the aura of an inter-religious rather than a legal or political dialogue. One is reminded of C. S. Lewis’s illustrations of the Tao in The Abolition of Man, albeit with Thomistic glosses.The idea is very attractive. Let those who have non-reductive anthropologies (open to reality as a whole) put their best understanding of human good and flourishing in common view, and then let us see where they “converge.”The hope will be that this kind of discussion will achieve more than the “minimal ethic” in a very narrow and completely practical grounding, such as the one stipulated in the U.N. Declaration of 1948.13 Even if we are not so naïve as to believe that a dialogue of wisdom traditions could reform, much less replace, the legal and political conventions governing human rights, it would still be of 12 Although it is not quoted or cited, see Fides et Ratio (1998), particularly §§81–82: “Philosophy lacks its sapiential function if it is addressed only to ‘particular and subordinate aspects of reality—function, formal or utilitarian.’ ” 13 The Search notes with alarm the fragmentation of the human rights project since 1948 (§§5–6, 115, and note 42). 666 Russell Hittinger value. A few strong convergences in the fashion of Lewis’s Tao would speak more effectively to human conscience than the dubiously abstract and highly politicized lists of rights that are continually multiplied and revised. There is nothing more disappointing and demoralizing than false universals in what pertains to human life. But there are two aspects of the ITC paper that I find disappointing. First, while the document affirms clearly enough, even insistently, the importance of prudence in judgments that make the natural law effective, its depiction of universal moral norms prior to prudence is not very clear. Second, it leaves out of the picture what kind of dialogue can be conducted with secular modernity. Regarding universal moral norms, The Search is understandably reluctant to put a system of precepts in front of its proposals about human nature. For one thing, on anthropological grounds alone it rejects the notion of pure practical reason that can generate a priori such a system of norms. Quite reasonably, the authors also want to acknowledge contingencies of culture and history and the effects of sin—“ideology and insidious propaganda, generalized relativism, structures of sin, etc” (§52). Furthermore, they are at pains to emphasize that a mature understanding of moral truth is an achievement dependent upon the agent’s formation in sound social institutions and acquisition of moral virtue.All of this reflects the paper’s strategic decision to discuss natural law within and among time-tested wisdom traditions. When we ask, however, what precepts of natural law are universally binding in a normative sense of the term, the document wobbles somewhat.The paper quotes St. Jerome’s remark on the Golden Rule: “Who of us does not know that homicide, adultery, theft and every kind of greed is evil, since we do not want them done to ourselves. If we did not know that these things are bad, we would not ever lament if they are inflicted on us” (§51). Accordingly, there is no prudence, just as such, about whether to commit adultery. Provided that one can pick out the relevant facts (this is my neighbor’s spouse), the negative precept suffices. Granting that negative precepts need to be completed within a larger moral project (§24), it is very important to emphasize that sound moral reasoning of the more complete kind depends upon what agents can know at this simpler level. To be sure, The Search says strongly enough that there are “precepts and values that, at least in their general formulation, can be considered as universal, since they apply to all humanity” precisely because they are derived from anthropological constants (§52). Here, it is the anthropological constant that is immutable, for it is the ground for values and Natural Law in Catholic Theology 667 precepts that “can be considered” universal in their “generality.” But this doesn’t quite capture what Jerome and others wanted to say about the negative precepts.We also read that we must safeguard “the fundamental data expressed by the precepts of the natural law that remain the same throughout cultural variation” (§54). It’s difficult to know exactly what the paper means, but on my reading the “data” are the anthropological constants, while the precepts seems to be a kind of sign or expression of a good or value. It is less clear that a precept is a sign of a command or obligation. At §59, the paper states: There is here a perspective which, within a pluralist society such as our own, has an importance that cannot be underestimated without suffering significant loss. Indeed, it stems from the fact that moral science cannot furnish an agent subject with a norm that may be applied adequately and almost automatically to concrete situations; only the conscience of the subject, the judgment of his practical reason, can formulate the immediate norm of action. But at the same time it can never abandon the conscience to mere subjectivity: the subject needs to acquire the intellectual and affective dispositions that permit it to open itself to moral truth in such a way that its judgment may be adequate. Natural law cannot, therefore, be presented as an already established set of rules that impose themselves a priori on the moral subject, but is a source of objective inspiration for his process, eminently personal, of making a decision. At least some readers will sense that a step is missing in this very condensed account. Assuming that the paper is correct that natural law should not be presented as an already assembled system of moral precepts, it does not necessarily follow that the natural law is only “a source of objective inspiration for his [the agent’s] process, eminently personal, of making a decision” [mais elle est une source d’inspiration objective ] (§59). In what precise sense are the inspirations precepts ? Are they just objective indicators en route to the discovery of adequate moral norms? These paragraphs seem to suggest the latter. “[O]nly the conscience of the subject, the judgment of his practical reason, can formulate the immediate norm of action” (§59). “Prudence” the ITC insists, “is a necessary passageway to authentic moral obligation” (§58). The quotation taken from St. Jerome however suggests an intermediate step—a small one, and rather thin, but important nevertheless. Between our grasp of the human good (anthropological constants) and fully practical judgments perfected by prudence, there are some moral norms of the natural law upon which even prudence must rely. Precisely in this zone we might expect some initial but sturdy convergence of 668 Russell Hittinger moral judgment among wisdom traditions regarding the negative precepts of the moral law.Without such convergence, the dialogue is apt to remain in the anthropological sphere of “objective inspirations” that perhaps intimate, without explicitly reaching, specific precepts. If this were true, we would be agreeing about human values, so to speak, but not about morality. Another conspicuous problem is that the secularized institutions of the West are not organized within a wisdom tradition; nor do they constitute one.Whereas a wisdom tradition is open to reality as a whole—a natural transcendence so to speak (§97)—the modern, western mind does not view nature or the “natural” as “impregnated with an immanent wisdom,” but rather, to use The Search’s own language, it is “deprived of immanent teleology or finality” (§72). This is only to acknowledge that prior to choice and prior to satisfying procedures of consent,“the natural” is merely immanent, along the lines of what Charles Taylor has called “closed world structures.”14 Purpose is assigned rather than discovered within the ordinary frame of things. By shifting the problem of authority from an internal structure of a theological tradition to the moral authority of a “common patrimony” implicit in many wisdom traditions, The Search does not relieve the problem—at least not for secular interlocuters. For example, when it proposes that there are moral “messages” in the nature of things and that natural law is not imposed on creatures from without but is inscribed in their very nature (§§11–12, 63), it summons a quite different meaning of the “immanent” than what will be obvious to most agents formed in the institutions of western secular culture. For them, nature is not obviously a semiotic (a book, or a ladder) in the sense that we have inherited from Paul, Bonaventure, or Thomas.The immanent rather is a domain of freedom just for the reason that it does not require transcendent messages, much less messages that arrive so intimately with authority.15 The immanent, for all practical purposes, is nothing other than what is bereft of, or perhaps still waiting for, authority. This is why the sciences and contemporary institutions of civic formation, education, and economic activity are deemed useful, and indeed legitimate. Precisely by not requiring a sapiential philosophy or religion to interpret transcendent “messages,” freedom is protected.When the ITC expresses the “urgent” need to reach common foundations (of a natural law sort) for the human rights proj14 Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 2007), 551. 15 Again,Taylor (544):“The immanent order can thus slough off the transcendent. But it doesn’t necessarily do so. . . . It is something that permits closure, without demanding it.” Natural Law in Catholic Theology 669 ect, it will have to anticipate a response that, on its view, is terribly inadequate if not irrational. Namely, the renewed claim of rights to liberty within this indeterminate “immanent” condition. These rights will be invoked against customs, positive laws, and the natural law insofar as they are norms antecedent to choice and consent.16 While the problem of liberty unseated from nature is more likely to be bridged in dialogue with wisdom traditions, it remains the tougher problem in the familiar world of secular modernity. In one place, The Search remarks: “In order that the notion of natural law may serve the elaboration of a universal ethics in a secularized and pluralistic society such as ours, it is therefore necessary to avoid presenting it in the rigid form that it assumed, particularly in modern rationalism” (§33). This prescription strikes me as a good way to facilitate dialogue among wisdom traditions, at least those that already regard modern rationalism as a dead end. In dialogue with Eastern Orthodox Christians, for example, keeping natural law at arm’s length from rationalism would count as a sine qua non. The same holds for dialogue with the great religious traditions, which tend to have a greater affinity for what we in the West would call the intellectualist rather than rationalist anthropology. It is much harder to see how the prescription has medicinal value for dialogue with a “secularized” society. Its denizens are not bothered by rationalism so much as by appeals in the public order to transcendent values—not only the supernatural, but also what ITC means by natural law (§97). Not surprisingly, C. S. Lewis’s illustrations of the Tao in The Abolition of Man include quotations from only two modern, western authors, Hooker and Locke, and only the latter is a modern in the relevant sense of the term. For its part, The Search makes clear enough that the Church often invokes natural law (moral truths antecedent to faith) defensively, against a belligerent secularism that dismisses a natural law foundation of moral choice and conscience as a purely confessional subversion of civic dialogue.17 The ITC authors are anything but naïve about who is their main antagonist on questions of natural law. ITC is faithful to untutored common sense and to its own tradition in affirming that “independently of the theoretical justifications of the concept of natural law, it is possible to discover the fundamental elements of the awareness of which it wants to give an account” (§37). Some rudiments of moral truth are so close to human experience that they are available to 16 The authors touch upon, but do not adequately grapple with, the problem of natural rights at §§88–90. 17 In §35, of the “four principal contexts” in which the Catholic Church invokes natural law today, three are clearly defensive. Russell Hittinger 670 anyone. One can interpret and appropriate these “evidences” even against the grain of one’s inherited explanatory frameworks and the institutions which go along with them.Yet the dialogue that an individual person can conduct in what Gaudium et Spes calls the “sanctuary” of his own conscience is not a sufficient condition for the broader and more difficult dialogue envisaged by ITC.18 By grasping the first precepts of natural law one has already crossed the threshold into a world of social and intellectual formation, and, for good or ill, into informal and formal explanatory frameworks. We return, as we must, to the question of what to do or to say to the modern antagonist.We are speaking of an antagonist who is an apostate from the Catholic wisdom tradition. This is the issue around which The Search maneuvers all too carefully, and understandably, but disappointingly. In a press conference during a recent trip to Portugal, Benedict XVI expressed hope for a dialogue between religion and modern rationality. Today we see that this very dialectic represents an opportunity and that we need to develop a synthesis and a forward-looking and profound dialogue. In the multicultural situation in which we all find ourselves, we see that if European culture were merely rationalist, it would lack a transcendent religious dimension, and not be able to enter into dialogue with the great cultures of humanity all of which have this transcendent religious dimension—which is a dimension of man himself. So to think that there exists a pure, anti-historical reason, solely self-existent, which is “reason” itself, is a mistake; we are finding more and more that it affects only part of man, it expresses a certain historical situation but it is not reason as such. Reason as such is open to transcendence and only in the encounter between transcendent reality and faith and reason does man find himself. So I think that the precise task and mission of Europe in this situation is to create this dialogue, to integrate faith and modern rationality in a single anthropological vision which approaches the human being as a whole and thus also makes human cultures communicable. (Pope to Press, papal flight to Portugal, 11 May 2010) Pope Benedict’s obiter dicta are quite good. The “single anthropological vision” entertained by the Pope requires the secular civilization either to develop a wisdom tradition or to reattach itself to the one it abandoned. The Pope surely has the latter option in mind.This hope moves the question beyond the specific problem of natural law groundings for a common morality to the prospects of what would have to be a profound intellectual, moral, and spiritual conversion. The moral precepts presupposed by the Gospel do not necessarily constitute the easiest step. The urgency of the N&V dialogue will have to be moderated by the virtue of patience. 18 Gaudium et Spes, §16. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 671–706 671 Natural Law, the Understanding of Principles, and Universal Good S TEPHEN L. B ROCK Pontifical University of the Holy Cross Rome, Italy A LA recherche d’une ethique universelle is a rich and profound reflection on the doctrine of natural law.1 As one would expect from a group of professional theologians, it is a very scholarly document. But its motive is quite practical. The aim is to find a “common ethical language,” a moral discourse that can express universally recognized goals and principles, so as to foster worldwide collaboration in the causes of peace, justice, and human flourishing. The title speaks of a recherche —a search, an investigation. Fortunately, however, the document is not a detective story, in which everything is supposed to become clear at the end. I say this because its Conclusion, especially in the first paragraph, is really rather misleading. . . .We call natural law the foundation of a universal ethic that we seek to gather from the observation of and reflection on our common human condition. It is the moral law inscribed in the heart of men and of which humanity becomes more and more aware as it advances in history. This law has nothing static in its expression. It does not consist in a list of definitive and immutable precepts. It is an ever-flowing source of inspiration in the search for an objective foundation of a universal ethic. (A la recherche, §113; my emphasis) 1 International Theological Commission, A la recherche d’une ethique universelle: nouveau regard sur la loi naturelle (2009); hereafter A la recherche. For the English I have used Joseph Bolin’s translation, with some changes (http://www.pathsoflove.com/universal-ethics-natural-law.html).Translations of St.Thomas herein are mine. I thank Kevin Flannery, S.J., Steven Jensen, and Christopher Malloy for very helpful remarks on the paper. 672 Stephen L. Brock The italicized sentences cannot, I think, be squared with the rest of the document. It is quite explicit about the fact that natural law consists in a set of definitive, immutable precepts.2 Granted, the set is not closed.3 Being very general, the precepts are apt to be supplemented by more particular norms and judgments. But they cannot be abrogated, and the primary ones admit of no exceptions. In this sense, natural law certainly is “static.” It stands still. Nevertheless it is also “dynamic,” in the sense that it is “powerful,” an origin or principle of action and change. Change and action always depend on relatively unchanging things. To walk on a treadmill is to go nowhere. Natural law functions as a principle of action and change by directing us toward the end that constitutes the fulfillment of our nature; that is, our fulfillment, the end we are “cut out for” by the very fact of being human.This does not change, because human nature, in the sense of what is strictly essential to being human, does not change.4 Whatever §113 means, the document as a whole is very clear about all this. It is true of course that natural law is “inscribed in the heart of men.” Also true is that it is not written there as a “list,” as though one could simply look inside oneself and read off its precepts.Their typical way of coming to mind is in the course of thinking about matters they concern—now one, now another—and with a view to the conditions of their fulfillment in this or that situation. That is, the normal way of considering them is a practical way. To pull them out from particular practical issues and treat them together, as a sort of list, would pertain to the theoretical reflection proper to the philosopher or the theologian. But if natural law is not written in the heart of men as an abstract list, exactly how is it written there? The document gives prominence to this question, dedicating to it the whole of Chapter 2, under the heading “The perception of common moral values.” The question is fundamental, because it is bound up with the very idea of a “natural” law. This means a law that human nature itself brings us to know, through a kind of spontaneous development of our minds—as opposed to what we may know through special training or investigation or study. This is why the knowledge of it would be so universal or common.As natural, it is apt to be known by everyone, whether wise or simple, erudite or unlettered, virtuous or even vicious. Near the beginning of Chapter 2 special importance is assigned to Thomas Aquinas’s teaching on natural law (§37). The chapter draws 2 See, for example, §9, §52. 3 See §11, §27, §59. 4 See §64. Natural Law and Universal Good 673 extensively upon him. In this essay what I mainly want to consider is Thomas’s understanding of that precept of natural law which he holds to be the very first to enter the human mind: “the good is to be done and pursued, and the bad is to be avoided.”5 Chapter 2 does discuss this precept briefly (2.2, §39–43), and I think that what it says about it agrees well with Thomas. But it seems to me that the first precept deserves a good deal more attention, both with respect to its own content and with respect to its relation to the other primary precepts of natural law.6 Regarding these others, which I shall call the “lower” precepts, the chapter’s rather lengthy treatment of them does seem to have Thomas’s teaching in view. But it begins with a passage that I find not to sit easily with his teaching, and I think that this can be traced, at least in part, to a failure to consider exactly how these precepts are related to the first precept. I shall begin with this passage and work back to the first precept. My overall aim is to underscore the genuinely intellectual character of the common knowledge of natural law and the highly universal scope of its dominant concept, that of the good. I. Natural Law, Concepts, and Knowledge of Human Nature The document’s discussion of the “lower” precepts of natural law begins as follows: Once we posit the basic affirmation that introduces us to the moral order—“One must do the good and avoid the bad”—we see how there arises in the subject the recognition of the fundamental laws that should govern human action. Such recognition does not consist in an abstract consideration of human nature, nor in the effort of conceptualization that would be proper to philosophical and theological theorization.The perception of the fundamental moral goods is immediate, vital, based on the mind’s connaturality with values and engaging affectivity as well as intellect, the heart as well as the mind. It is an often imperfect grasp, still obscure and dim, but which has the depth of immediacy. It is a matter of the simplest and most common givens of experience that are implicit in the concrete action of persons. (§44) This passage seems to reflect the position on the common knowledge of natural law proposed half a century ago by Jacques Maritain.The document does not cite Maritain, and indeed I think that in part the resemblance is only apparent. But it may still be a source of confusion. 5 Summa theologiae (hereafter ST ), I–II, q. 94, a. 2 (hereafter 94.2). 6 Thomas calls “primary” those general precepts that are naturally understood by all. He also posits “secondary” natural law precepts, which are more specific and like conclusions from the primary; see ST I–II, q. 94, aa. 4–6. 674 Stephen L. Brock Maritain develops his view with reference to 94.2. On his reading, the way in which the lower precepts of natural law are naturally and commonly known must be what Thomas elsewhere calls knowledge “by connaturality” or “through inclination.” According to 94.2, all of these precepts regard goods that are objects of natural human inclinations. According to Maritain, reason’s natural apprehension of these goods as good would be a very direct effect of the inclinations. It is not that reason consciously reflects on the inclinations and then goes on to judge their objects good. Nor does reason start from a consideration of the various dimensions of human nature to which the inclinations correspond. Rather, the very presence of the inclinations casts a kind of light upon the things that are their objects, and reason spontaneously judges the things in this light, seeing them as desirable—as good. Maritain holds that such judgments involve no rational formulation or conceptualization. The common apprehension of the precepts of natural law would be, in his metaphorical language, an apprehension “in which the intellect, in order to bear judgment, consults and listens to the inner melody that the vibrating strings of abiding tendencies make present to the subject.”7 Section 44 of A la recherche does seem to propose a similar view. It speaks of the perception of the fundamental moral goods as based on the “the mind’s connaturality with values.” It also denies that this consists in an “abstract consideration of human nature” or in the “effort of conceptualization” that is proper to philosophical and theological theorizing. Now, I do not think that A la recherche really means to present the common knowledge of natural law as an entirely non-conceptual affair, or even as involving no concept of human nature. Other places in the document show this clearly enough. In the rest of this section I shall look at some of these, and I shall also consider Thomas’s view on these points. In the next section I shall consider whether the knowledge consists in judgment by connaturality. One very strong indication that the document views the common knowledge of natural law as somehow conceptual is its repeatedly speaking of this knowledge as a matter of “formulation”—the formulation of precepts.8 It is very difficult to imagine how the mind could formulate precepts without employing concepts. The document also indicates that the concepts involved in this knowledge are universal, and so in some sense 7 Jacques Maritain, Man and the State (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), 92. See also his “On Knowledge through Connaturality,” The Review of Metaphysics 4 ( June 1951): 473–81 (esp. 477–80); and “Du savoir moral,” Revue Thomiste 82 (1982): 533–49. 8 See the very next section (§45); also §11, §52. Natural Law and Universal Good 675 abstract. It describes the precepts themselves as very “general” (§46, §47). Moreover, if it denies that the common knowledge of natural law involves “theoretical conceptualization,” it also denies this of the expressions of moral wisdom that have been passed down in the various cultural traditions (§12). And yet it is obvious that the document’s examples of such expressions involve universal concepts (§12–17). One of them even refers directly to man’s “essence”; that is, to human nature (§13). So the exclusion of theoretical conceptualization from the common knowledge of the precepts need not be taken as an exclusion of universal concepts altogether. There can be no doubt that for Thomas the common knowledge of natural law involves universal concepts. Natural law, as naturally known, is a law in the proper sense of the term (ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, ad 3). Law consists of precepts, which he describes as “universal propositions of practical reason ordered to actions.”9 A proposition is a combination of the concepts of the subject and the predicate.Thomas also characterizes the knowledge of the precepts of natural law as knowledge of truths (ST I–II, q. 93, a. 2, corp. & ad 3).The act by which the mind apprehends truth is judgment, or what he calls “composition and division.” This, he says, results from comparing some thing (the subject) with some concept (the predicate) that is proposed about it (ST I, q. 16, a. 2; I, q. 85, a. 2, ad 3). And he says quite generally that whatever the mind understands, it forms a concept of (ST I, q. 27, a. 1).To say that the knowledge of natural law involves concepts is simply to say that it is genuinely rational or intellectual knowledge. Does it involve a concept of human nature? §44 of A la recherche says that the common knowledge of natural law is not the result of an “abstract consideration of human nature.”Whatever this means, I do not think it can be that the common knowledge of natural law includes no understanding or no concept of human nature at all. The document certainly presents human nature as something “to be fulfilled,” and natural law as directing toward this fulfillment.10 And it speaks of the common knowledge of natural law in these same terms, as knowledge of what is in conformity with human nature, as such.11 That for Thomas the common knowledge of natural law involves knowledge of human nature is implicit in the very way in which he introduces the “lower” precepts of natural law in 94.2:“all those things to be done or avoided that practical reason naturally apprehends to be HUMAN goods pertain to the precepts of the law of nature.”Apprehending something to be human means apprehending it to be connected with 9 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 1, ad 2; on natural law in relation to this, see I, q. 94, a. 1. 10 See §36, §40. 11 See the immediately preceding section (§43); also §9, together with §64. 676 Stephen L. Brock man; that is, with what has human nature. Any intellectual apprehension of man involves some grasp of man’s nature. The intellect’s very object, the feature according to which anything is intelligible, is “what the thing is,” the nature of the thing understood.12 It may be grasped more or less perfectly. But to have no understanding of a thing’s nature is to have no understanding of the thing at all. In order to understand the goods that Thomas connects with the lower precepts in 94.2, clearly one must know the corresponding dimensions of human nature.13 We could not understand that it is good for man to preserve his being according to his kind if we had no grasp of what it is to be a subject of being of some kind (though it may take a philosopher to assign an expression to this, such as “hoc aliquid ” or “substance”). We could not understand the good of the generative act or of nurturing offspring if we had no concept of animal. If we had no concept of reason, we could not understand the good of knowing the truth about God, or that of life in society (fundamental for which is speech); and we certainly could not know the good of acting according to reason, which is also the basis of a primary precept (94.3). In fact, as we shall see, some grasp of reason and of its practical operation is involved in the sheer grasp of the good, which is the basis of the very first precept of natural law.14 When §44 of A la recherche excludes the “abstract consideration of human nature” from the common knowledge of natural law, I think that this is just another way of saying that the knowledge does not depend on “theoretical conceptualization” about human nature. It is not the result of what Thomas calls the “speculative mode” of considering a thing. This mode consists in “defining and dividing and considering its universal predicates,” or in other words,“resolving into universal formal principles” 12 See, e.g., ST I, q. 17, a. 3, ad 1; I, q. 85, a. 6. 13 In 94.2 Thomas says that to one who is ignorant of what man is, the proposition “man is rational” is not per se nota. However, he does not say that this proposition is not per se nota omnibus or that the concepts involved in it are not “known to all.” They could be, even if some people do not know them. For in this context, “known to all” does not mean known by absolutely everyone. If it did, then there would be nothing of this sort, since our minds begin as tabulae rasae. It means something that everyone is naturally apt to know, requiring no special training or study or reasoning. See section III below. 14 See below, at n. 38. It has been argued that the common knowledge of natural law cannot rest on knowledge of human nature, because (a) human nature includes practical reason, (b) knowing something requires seeing it operate, and (c) if one’s practical reason is operating, one already knows natural law, since it consists of practical reason’s first principles. But if some grasp of practical reason’s operation is involved in the very grasp of the good, then all the knowledge of the principles themselves actually presupposes it. Natural Law and Universal Good 677 (ST I, q. 14, a. 16).Thomas contrasts this with the “practical” mode, which consists in the “application of form to matter.”15 It is clear that both of these modes presuppose some knowledge of the thing. The speculative mode takes the thing known and analyzes it into its formal principles; the practical mode applies the thing’s form to matter. Both modes, in fact, presuppose knowledge of the thing’s form,“what it is.”And in a way, even the practical mode starts from “abstract” knowledge of the thing, in the sense of universal knowledge. For it proceeds toward the concrete, applying the form to matter. What the practical mode does not presuppose is an analysis of the thing into its “formal principles.”These would be the parts of its definition.The practical mode requires only a “confused” conception of the thing. Even the confused conception, however, involves some grasp of the parts of the definition. These are just what the “confusion,” the blend, is a blend of. They must be known first, because they are simpler and more universal than the thing defined. The more universal is known prior to the less universal (ST I, q. 85, a. 3). First the parts of the definition are known, in themselves; then the thing itself is known, confusedly; and finally the parts of the definition are distinguished, seen as parts of the definition. The defining terms, considered absolutely, are known before the thing defined; otherwise the thing defined would not be made known by them. But insofar as they are parts of the definition, they are known afterwards; for we know man by a certain confused cognition before we know how to distinguish all the things that belong to the concept of man. (ST I, q. 85, a. 3, ad 3) It is the last step that is proper to the speculative mode: formulating the definition, resolving into an orderly “list” the defining parts of what has already been grasped confusedly as an intelligible whole.We may say that knowing natural law does not require a scientific grasp of man. But it does require an “abstract” grasp, in the sense of a universal one, and one that does somehow contain the parts of man’s definition, the various dimensions of his nature. It might be objected that human nature is a purely speculative matter. It is not something devised or constructed by human reason, as practical things are. The knowledge of natural law is practical knowledge. So even if the confused grasp of human nature does not depend on the speculative 15 ST I, q. 14, a. 6. Evidently “matter” here is to be taken very broadly, for what- ever the particular subject is to which the form is applied. The thought is that whereas a form considered by itself or absolutely is something common or universal, actions and their effects are in singulars; see ST II–II, q. 47, a. 3. Stephen L. Brock 678 mode of considering the nature, how can that grasp pertain to the knowledge of natural law? Clearly Thomas’s distinction between speculative and practical modes does not strictly line up with the distinction between speculative and practical matters. Both modes can apply to the same thing, for instance house (ST I, q. 14, a. 16). Of course house is a practical matter. But he also indicates that things that one cannot effect can enter into one’s practical consideration, insofar as they have a bearing on what one can effect.16 Our reason does not produce its effects out of nothing. In its practical work it “uses” natural things. (To use a thing is “to apply it to some operation”: ST I–II, q. 16, a. 4.) It even uses human nature. Just as a man exists by nature, so do all of his per se attributes, such as being capable of laughter and capable of mental discipline. If then some cause does not make a man absolutely, but rather makes a man such, it will not belong to that cause to constitute the things that are a man’s per se attributes, but only to use them.Thus the statesman makes a man civil; but he does not make him capable of mental discipline, but rather uses this property of a man so that he become civil.17 II. Natural Inclination, Synderesis, and Knowing the Goods As Good So it seems clear that A la recherche is not adopting Maritain’s view that the common knowledge of the precepts of natural law does not involve a conception of human nature or any other conceptual knowledge.This however does not rule out the possibility that it is treating the common understanding as a case of judgment “by connaturality.” Nor does what we have seen so far about Thomas rule it out of his view. For pace Maritain,Thomas never says that judgment by connaturality is a non-conceptual mode of knowing.What he says is that it does not involve a “perfect use of reason” (ST II–II, q. 45, a. 2). By this he seems to mean that it does not require scientific consideration of the matter being judged. And it seems clear that for him the common knowledge of natural law does not require scientific consideration. 16 See ST I, q. 14, a. 16, end of the corpus, on God’s practical consideration of evils; also ST I–II, q. 14, a. 6. 17 Thomas Aquinas, In XII libros Metaphysicorum expositio, ed. M. R. Cathala and R. M. Spiazzi (Marietti: Turin, 1950), Lib.VI, lect. 3, §1219. In a way, A la recherche is aiming at this very thing, the application of people’s natural aptitude for mental discipline to a “civilizing” process—one that would be worldwide. Part of this aptitude is a natural understanding of principles, and part of this is the common knowledge of natural law. Natural Law and Universal Good 679 On this question I find it difficult to determine the document’s position. The mere use of the word ‘connaturality’ in §44 does not decide the question. As we shall see, at least in Thomas the word does not always refer to judgment by inclination. Some passages in A la recherche do suggest that it is treating the knowledge of natural law as a case of judgment by connaturality. For example, the paragraph immediately after §44 echoes Maritain’s metaphor of listening to the inner melody of abiding tendencies. In his search for the moral good, the human person sets himself to listening to what he is and becomes aware of the fundamental inclinations of his nature, which are quite different from simple blind impulses of desire. Perceiving that the goods to which he tends by nature are necessary for his moral fulfillment, he formulates to himself, under the form of practical injunctions, the moral duty of carrying them out in his own life. He expresses to himself a certain number of very general precepts that he shares with all human beings and that constitute the content of that which we call natural law. (§45)18 Here some role is certainly being assigned to the natural inclinations. However, it also says that these inclinations are not at all “mere blind impulses of desire.”This suggests that perhaps the inclinations are to be seen as rooted in the understanding of the goodness of the things that are their objects.That understanding would not itself depend on the inclinations. This, I believe, is definitely Thomas’s view. Elsewhere I have called attention to the fact that not only Maritain, but also several other recent interpreters of 94.2, simply assume that the natural inclinations to which the precepts of natural law correspond are pre-rational. That is, they would exist independently of, and prior to, the intellect’s apprehension of their objects as good, and that apprehension would somehow depend upon them.19 I have argued that 94.2 does not justify this assumption, and that it is quite incompatible with many other things that Thomas says about natural law. The natural inclinations that Thomas has in mind in 94.2 are inclinations of the will—the rational appetite. The will’s movement always follows some rational apprehension of its object as good. Even the inclinations cited in 94.2 that are toward goods which are according to natures that man shares with irrational creatures should be seen as inclinations of the will. For this community in the objects of 18 Other passages suggesting that it is knowledge by connaturality are §46, §52, and perhaps most strongly, §63. 19 See my “Natural Inclination and the Intelligibility of the Good in Thomistic Natural Law,” Vera Lex 6.1–2 (Winter 2005): 57–78 (hereafter “Natural Inclination . . .”). 680 Stephen L. Brock inclination does not exclude diversity in its modes.20 Man’s inclination toward these goods is in the rational or intellectual mode. Consider, for example, what Thomas says earlier in the Summa about the inclination common to all substances toward their conservation in being: [E]ach thing naturally desires to be in its own way. Now in things that have cognition, desire follows apprehension. But the senses do not apprehend being except under the aspect of here and now, whereas intellect apprehends being absolutely and according to all time. Hence every possessor of intellect naturally desires to be forever. (ST I, q. 75, a. 6; my emphasis) I will not repeat here all of my earlier arguments for this way of reading 94.2. But one that I did not previously take up can be drawn from the very mode of knowing that Thomas associates with the precepts of natural law.This is the mode characteristic of the type of intellectual virtue that he calls intellectus principiorum, the understanding of principles. Following Aristotle, Thomas distinguishes five groups of virtues by which the intellect attains truth in a sure and stable way (ST I–II, q. 57). Two of these are practical.They regard the truth about things that are in our power to bring about, which are always particular and contingent things. Art regards products, and prudence regards actions. The other three groups regard the truth about universal and necessary matters. Such matters are not in our power, and the virtues in these groups are called speculative virtues.This is so even though two of them, scientia and intellectus principiorum, include virtues that regard the practical domain: scientia includes moral science, and intellectus principiorum includes synderesis, which is the habit of the precepts of natural law. For even practical matters have necessary features that can be considered in a universal way and that are not, as such, in our power. Moreover, unlike prudence, neither moral science nor synderesis presupposes right appetite. The truth of prudence, like all truth, consists in conformity with the matter being judged, the “res” (ST I–II, q. 64, a. 3). But in addition to this, the truth of prudence also entails conformity with right appetite. This is because the res of prudence is a particular action, judged as to its choiceworthiness. An action’s choiceworthiness is judged in light of the end, and right appetite is needed for the right apprehension of the “particular end,” the end as existing under the conditions of the concrete situation (ST I–II, q. 57, a. 5, corp. & ad 3). But 20 See ST I, q. 60, a. 1, together with aa. 3–5. Of course I do not mean to deny that our pre-rational inclinations have “moral significance” (see A la recherche, §79–80). Natural Law and Universal Good 681 synderesis does not presuppose right appetite, because it apprehends the end universally.This apprehension is the very source of the appetite’s first rectitude, which is the rectitude of the will’s natural inclination.21 The truth of synderesis, like that which regards speculative matters, is simply its conformity with its res. So although the truths pertaining to synderesis regard the practical domain, its way of knowing them is the same as that of any other intellectus principiorum.This way, Thomas says, is by a kind of “immediate perception.”22 Its immediacy consists in the fact that truths fall under it insofar as they are apt to be considered as per se notae, known by dint of themselves.Thomas makes no distinction between what per se nota means in the case of truth about speculative things and what it means in the case of truth about practical things. One of his fullest accounts of its meaning is found precisely in 94.2. As usual, the account is in terms of propositions and their components. A proposition is per se nota insofar as its predicate belongs to its subject’s very ratio or concept. Insofar as this is so, the perception of the proposition’s truth follows immediately upon its formation. Now, this does not mean that the truth of such a proposition is perceived by everyone. For perhaps not everyone grasps the concepts involved. Some concepts are grasped only by “the wise,” those whose minds have received special cultivation. But many concepts are acquired spontaneously, through ordinary experience, without any special instruction or study. The truths that rest on these concepts are known “naturally” and “to all.”The knowledge of them is not innate, but the sufficient aptitude for knowing them is. Even the most uncultivated people are apt to know them, and if their faculties are not stunted, they will know them. The precepts of natural law are known in this way, through the natural habit of synderesis. In calling this mode of knowing truth a “perception,” as it were a sort of seeing, Thomas is not making it something entirely passive. For the light by which the mind sees these truths is primarily the mind’s own. It is the light of the “agent intellect,” which is the soul’s power to abstract the intelligible forms of things from the matter represented in their sensible images.The abstracted forms themselves also “illumine”; it is through them that the mind discerns the truth about the things that they are the forms of.23 But it is only by the agent intellect’s abstracting the forms from matter that the illuminating power of the forms is actualized. And 21 See ST I–II, q. 62, a. 3, quoted below, at n. 25. 22 ST I–II, q. 57, a. 2. Notice that §44 of A la recherche also speaks in terms of “perception” and “immediacy.” 23 See ST I, q. 84, a. 5, together with I–II, q. 3, a. 6. 682 Stephen L. Brock so Thomas says,“From the very nature of the intellectual soul, it belongs to man that, having grasped what a whole is and what a part is, he immediately grasps that every whole is greater than its part; and likewise with the others.”24 He is saying that all the truths pertaining to the natural intellectus principiorum are known in this way. Thomas insists that the agent intellect is a power of the human soul. In the article of the Summa in which he argues for this, he cites the fourth Psalm:“The light of Thy countenance, O Lord, is signed upon us” (ST I, q. 79, a. 4). It is worth recalling that later, in the place where he argues for the existence of natural law, Thomas cites this same Psalm, this time glossing it: [T]he Psalmist, after saying, “Offer up the sacrifice of justice,” adds, “Many say, Who showeth us good things?,” as though someone had asked what the works of justice are; in answer to which question he says, “The light of Thy countenance, O Lord, is signed upon us”; as though to say that the light of natural reason, whereby we discern what is good and what is bad, which pertains to natural law, is nothing else than an imprint on us of the divine light. (ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2) Thomas does say that the practical principles are in a way “more” connatural to man than the speculative ones (ST II–II, q. 47, a. 15). But he is not there talking about “judgment by connaturality.” He is talking about the fact that the practical life is more common, more typically human, than the speculative. Both sets of principles are known in the same way: by the natural light of the agent intellect, which brings out the intelligibilities of sensible things and displays their truth. Now, A la recherche does allude to the mode of knowing that characterizes intellectus principiorum, at the beginning of its discussion of the very first precept of natural law. Every human being who reaches conscience and responsibility experiences an interior call to do good. He discovers that he is fundamentally a moral being, capable of perceiving and expressing the call that, as we saw, is found within all cultures:“One must do the good and avoid the bad.” On this precept are based all the other precepts of natural law.This first precept is known naturally, immediately, by practical reason, just as the principle of non-contradiction (the intellect cannot simultaneously and in the same respect affirm and deny the same thing of a subject), which is at the basis of all speculative reasoning, is grasped intuitively, 24 ST I–II, q. 51, a. 1.The “others” are the other truths pertaining to the intellectus principiorum, whether speculative or practical. In this article he refers to the latter as “principles of common justice.” Natural Law and Universal Good 683 naturally, by theoretical reason, as soon as the subject grasps the meaning of the terms used. Traditionally this knowledge of the first principle of the moral life is attributed to an innate intellectual disposition called synderesis. (§39) I have quoted the passage in full because I shall want to return to it later. But for the moment what is of interest is the fourth sentence, where the first precept of natural law is likened to the principle of non-contradiction, just as it is in 94.2. Both are understood naturally and immediately, being per se notae truths resting on concepts that we naturally acquire. What is not so clear in A la recherche, however, is that according to 94.2, all the primary precepts of natural law are understood in this way. They are all “naturally known.” The first precept, which rests on the concept of the good, says that the good is to be done and sought, and the bad avoided. The other precepts rest on concepts of certain particular good things. As goods, these things share in the truth of the first precept. They are things to be done or sought, and their contraries are bad and to be avoided. And the precepts regarding these things are naturally known and pertain to natural law, because our mind naturally understands them and their goodness. “All those things to be done or avoided that practical reason naturally apprehends to be human goods pertain to the precepts of the law of nature” (94.2). After making this assertion, Thomas goes on to lay out the order in which these goods and the precepts regarding them fall into the human intellect. It is here that he associates the goods with man’s natural inclinations: “all the things to which man is naturally inclined, reason naturally apprehends as good.” However, he does not actually say that the natural inclinations to these things are the source of the apprehension of their goodness. In 94.2 he does not really say anything about the apprehension’s source, except that it is “natural.” But after all, 94.2 is not a stand-alone treatise. In 91.2 he had been very clear that the source is the natural light of reason. Through this, the rational creature—unlike others—shares in the eternal ratio,“by which he is naturally inclined to his due act and end.” The only inclination that 91.2 connects with natural law is that of the will, its desire of the last end (ad 2). But perhaps even clearer than 91.2 is an earlier passage in the Prima secundae.The topic is the theological virtues, which order us to a supernatural end. Thomas draws a comparison with our order toward our “connatural” end, which is through a certain “natural inclination.” But this [inclination] comes about in function of two factors. First, in function of reason or intellect, insofar as it [intellect] contains first Stephen L. Brock 684 universal principles known to us by the natural light of the intellect, from which reason proceeds both in speculable and in practical matters. Second, through the rectitude of the will naturally tending toward the good of reason.25 Here it is very definitely the understanding of principles that is the source of the inclination to the end, not the other way round. The end itself is “connatural,” but the understanding is not at all “judgment by connaturality.” It is an understanding of per se notae truths, wherein the predicate pertains to the very concept of the subject. Practical reason’s natural apprehension of certain things as human goods does not depend on the voice of inclination persuading it to combine subject and predicate. Once rendered intelligible by the mind’s light, subject and predicate combine themselves.We can really see that these things are human goods.26 Or at least, there can be little doubt that this is Thomas’s view. In the next two sections I shall raise and try to resolve two issues about it. In the course of this it should become clear why I say that A la recherche could have given more attention to the very first precept. III. The Good Is What All Desire The first issue concerns the origin of the very concept of the good. In 91.2 Thomas traces natural law to the light by which we discern what the good is and what the bad is, and in 94.2 he makes the very first precept to be founded on the concept of the good, the ratio boni. His formulation of it is that of the Nicomachean Ethics, I.1, 1094a3:“the good is what all desire.” The concept of the good, then, is inseparable from the concept of desire. But where do we get this concept? Must it not be drawn from some experience of desire? And if so, must not pre-rational desire or inclination play a role after all in the genesis of the knowledge of natural law? From very early in our development, we all do experience pre-rational desires, those of the sense-appetite. Even if the natural inclinations that Thomas has in mind in 94.2 belong to the will, and follow upon reason’s apprehension of their objects as good, must not reason’s very grasp of the concept of the good originate in the experience of sense-desire? On the other hand, although for Thomas the concept of the good is inseparable from the concept of desire, he certainly does not think that 25 ST I–II, q. 62, a. 3; cf. De veritate, q. 14, a. 2, c. (from Nihil autem potest . . . through the next sentence). 26 The “seeing” is not merely being “certain” of them. Faith too is certain.Yet “faith implies only assent to what is proposed. But understanding implies a certain perception of truth”: ST II–II, q. 8, a. 5, ad 3. Natural Law and Universal Good 685 what we primarily mean by ‘good’ is what the sense-appetite desires.To be sure, this is one meaning of ‘good’: the delectabile. But it is not the primary meaning.The primary meaning refers to what is “good in itself,” what “has in itself that whence it is desired” (ST I, q. 5, a. 6)—what is intrinsically fit to be desired.What the sense-appetite desires is not always of this sort. It does not always even seem to be of this sort. “What is desired according to concupiscence seems good because it is desired. For concupiscence perverts the judgment of reason, such that what is pleasant seems good to it. But what is desired with intellectual appetite is desired because it seems good in itself.”27 So sense-desire does not seem to be a sufficient basis for forming the concept of the good. Before seeking for the origin of a concept, we need to make sure that we are clear about its content. What does “desire” mean? My dictionary calls it a type of “feeling.” Perhaps that does not quite fit the kind of desire called “will.” Nevertheless it is probably right that by “desire” we usually mean some type of “psychological” act or disposition, something that only beings with “inner awareness” have. Descartes calls all desires “thoughts”; Hume calls even will an “impression.” But taken generally, this is not at all what Thomas means by desire—desiderium or appetitus.The very formula of the good that he uses in 94.2 is an indication of this. Bonum est quod omnia appetunt.The good is what all desire.As is clear both from the neuter omnia and from other passages, what Thomas means by “all” in this formula is not just all men. Nor is it just all animals. It is all beings.28 Not all beings have will or sense-desire, or any sort of “psychological” activity at all. But all do have desire. If for us this word inevitably conveys something psychological, then we can speak instead of “inclination.” We are supposed to see this as an inseparable feature of absolutely everything. For Thomas, desire or inclination is simply a certain sort of tendency, or effective order, toward something. Not every tendency is an inclination. Some tendencies are merely imposed upon a thing by something else and are incidental or even contrary to the thing’s inclination. An inclination is a tendency rooted in the thing itself—ultimately in its nature, in what it is. It is somehow the thing’s “own.” This is not found only in animals. Plants are inclined to grow, to reproduce, and so on. Inanimate things have inclinations toward their proper activities.Thomas ascribes inclination or desire even to prime matter (ST I, q. 5, a. 3, ad 3). Of course Thomas’s views of the constitution of these beings differ in many ways from those of modern natural science. Has modern science entirely dispensed with the notion of inclination? I doubt it. But for our 27 Thomas Aquinas, In XII libros Metaphysicorum expositio, Lib. XII, lect. vii, §2522. 28 See ST I, q. 5, a. 1. 686 Stephen L. Brock purposes, the question is incidental. We are not talking about the scientific account of things, but about the common experience from which the common concept of the good originates. Our experience is of a world made up of things that all have inclinations—toward states, activities, and movements of various sorts.We find ourselves quite surrounded by desire. And we observe it in things.We do so all the time. It would be silly to say that you see a dog chasing a rabbit, but that you cannot tell whether the dog desires the rabbit—that only the dog can tell this (and he keeps it to himself). Of course desire is not observable in the way that, say, color or sound is. It is “underneath” the sensible objects. But then, so are many kinds of action, such as “chasing.” It is the very business of intellect to get underneath the sensible objects, to under-stand them.29 If we cannot see a dog desiring a rabbit, then neither can we see a dog chasing a rabbit.We cannot even see a dog. And to call something a dog, or even a tree or a rock, is already to attribute a host of inclinations to it. It is mostly in light of their regular activities and movements that we form our conceptions of what the things around us are.What they are, and what they are inclined to be and to do, enter our minds together.This is “a nature”: an inner principle of both the existence and the activity of a thing. Even if, as with “a substance” (a subject of existence and activity), it takes a philosopher to formulate the general definition of “a nature,” some confused concept of what a nature is comes quite naturally to us.30 It is desire understood in this very broad sense, then, that for Thomas goes hand in hand with the notion of the good. Rather than with feelings, what we should associate desire with is movement and action. A desire is a tendency toward something, toward really possessing something, and so it is typically a tendency toward bringing the thing about, or conserving it, or in some other way acting to promote its real existence. This association of desire with action is just what the first precept of natural law expresses: the good, as “what all desire,” is “to be done and sought.” And its contrary, the bad, which would be “what all shun,” is “to be avoided.” Desire pertains to the very concept of the good, and action and movement pertain to the very concept of desire. This is why the first precept is a per se nota proposition. Sense-desire, we said, does not seem to be a sufficient basis for the concept of the good. Its object does not always even seem truly fit for us to desire. It might explain the concept of “the desired,” but it does not explain the concept of “the desirable.” By contrast, in Thomas’s view 29 See ST I, q. 18, a. 2; II–II, q. 8, a. 1. 30 See A la recherche, §64–65. Natural Law and Universal Good 687 there is indeed a sense in which “what all desire” can be identified with the intrinsically desirable. For even if some desires are disordered, it is common to all things to desire their proper perfection.This for Thomas is the “nature” of the good, what desirability primarily “consists” in: perfection.31 Of course, like desire itself, perfection comes in many different forms or modes. And one thing’s perfection is not another’s.32 Nevertheless Thomas sees it as a genuine nature that is common to all perfect things, just as he sees “being” as a nature that is common to all beings. In fact they are almost the same nature. For an unqualifiedly “perfect” thing is a thing that is fully “in act,” and this is a thing that has “fullness of being” (ST I, q. 5, a. 1; I–II, q. 18, a. 1). This notion of “fullness of being” is also closely associated with that of action. “Every agent effects its like,” Thomas is fond of saying. To act is somehow to “influence” things, to “pour” one’s being into them. What acts, to the extent that it acts, is “full” of being, so full as to be apt to “overflow.”The notion of “fullness of being” is thus readily conveyed to us by the actions of things.And so is the fact that they desire this fullness. For as a general rule, to the extent that a thing is fully in act and can act, can pour forth its being, it will do so. “Each thing, insofar as it is in act, acts, and tends toward what suits it according to its form” (ST I, q. 5, a. 5). Quite generally, things are disposed to promote their being and their perfection.They are inclined to it, desire its continuance and its diffusion. And everyone knows this. We also see here a close connection between the notion of the good and that of the nature or the form of a thing, “what it is.” Likeness is communication in form.What acts causes something to be like it, to have something of its own being, the being that is according to its own form. Its “fullness” of being is the completeness of the being that is proportioned to its form.33 It is measured by the form, as the fullness of a bottle is measured by its inner shape. The order toward perfection is what makes desire intelligible. Perfection is desirable per se. If we observe a desire for something—say, a desire for food, perhaps our own desire for it—but we do not see how the object desired perfects the desirer, we wonder why the desire exists. But when we see that the object enhances or favors the desirer’s own being, 31 See ST I, q. 5, a. 1; Summa contra gentiles, Lib. I, c. 37 (“Amplius. Communicatio . . .”). 32 Thomas says that “the good is what all desire” does not mean that what all desire is one single thing; it means that all objects of desire share somehow in the nature of the good: ST I, q. 6, a. 2, ad 2. And clearly, as with being, they do not all share in it equally or in the same mode. It is not said of them univocally, but analogically. 33 ST I, q. 5, a. 5. On likeness as communication in form, see ST I, q. 4, a. 3. 688 Stephen L. Brock we no longer wonder. We do not ask: why does it desire to enhance its being—what good is that? Rather, now its desire makes sense. We have traced the desire to something desirable per se. So in a way it is right to say that our concept of the good presupposes the experience of “pre-rational” desire. But this is not solely or even primarily our own sense-desire. It is the desire, the inclination to perfection, that we see commonly in the things around us.34 It should be noticed that the thought is not that the notion of the good is “implied” in that of perfection, or fullness of being, or “conformity with nature,” as though it were “derivable” from these by some kind of conceptual analysis. Rather, these notions are included in that of the good.35 The notion of the good does add something new to them. It adds the relation to desire.This is a causal relation. Desire is the effect of goodness.36 To understand the good is to understand a form of explanation; that is, a kind of cause, the final cause. The goodness of a thing explains the desire of it and the movement toward it that the desire is apt to give rise to.That perfection makes a thing intrinsically apt to be desired, and that it is actually desired because it is apt to be, are shown by the very fact that for the most part, this is what things do desire. On the whole, desire presents itself as a function of perfection. Regarding the origin of the concept of the good, however, this is not for Thomas the whole story. In understanding that perfection or fullness of being is desirable, we are not merely seeing that it makes sense for a thing to desire its perfection.We find this, the existence of a perfect thing, to be something that is fit to desire, not just for the thing itself, but absolutely, without qualification. We see perfection as something simply to be approved of, something that simply ought to be. And this consideration gives rise to a desire of its own. Thomas does after all make the 34 Really even our sense-desire is normally for things that do somehow perfect us, according to some dimension of our nature. If these things are not always (nor always even seem) unqualifiedly “good in themselves,” it is because they may be repugnant to our last end. This end pertains primarily to our rational nature. A sign of this is that our primary desire, the one that controls our action, is the desire of the will, the rational appetite. For the most part, sense-desire does not induce us to act without the consent of the will. On the need to regulate the “pre-rational” desires of our various “parts,” including that of reason itself, in view of the last end, see below, n. 60. 35 See my “Natural Inclination . . . ,” 71–73. I develop this point more fully in “The Primacy of the Common Good and the Foundations of Natural Law in St. Thomas,” in Ressourcement Thomism, ed. Reinhard Hütter and Matthew Levering (Washington:The Catholic University of America Press, 2010), 241–50. 36 “Just as the causality of the efficient cause is taken according to influence, the causality of the end is taken according to appetite”: ST I–II, q. 2, a. 5, ad 3. Natural Law and Universal Good 689 general concept of the good (still taken as “what all desire”) go hand in hand with the apprehension of a “psychological” desire—not sensual, however, but intellectual. First, he says, the intellect understands “a being” (ens ); then it apprehends itself understanding a being, which goes with the apprehension of “a true”; and then it—intellect—apprehends itself desiring a being, this apprehension being inseparable from apprehension of “a good.”37 Even if the desire “in the things themselves” is what first leads us to see the connection between desire and perfection, in seeing perfection to be intrinsically desirable we are also calling for desire of it, as it were issuing a directive that it be desired.38 And we are naturally so constituted as to respond to such a directive.That is, we have the natural capacity and aptitude to desire what the intellect judges desirable, the power of will. This is why, in explaining the good—the universal good, the good as “what all desire”—Thomas sometimes relates it to no desire other than that of the intellectual appetite.39 In a way the good as “what all desire” and the good as “what the will desires” are the same. For the intellectual soul in a way is “all things,” and it has a special affinity or “connaturality” with the whole of reality.40 In a way its desire reflects the desires of all things. But only in a way. It is not that the mind simply mimics the desires that it observes.41 The desires in non-rational things are for particular, limited modes of the good, and the desires themselves are limited, conditioned. But from the experience of particular modes of being, the mind 37 ST I, q. 16, a. 4.The corpus of the article reminds us that on the side of “reality,” the apprehension of something as “good” requires the apprehension of it not only as “a being” but also as “perfect.” 38 On this see my “Natural Inclination . . . ,” 68–70.This apprehension of the intellect’s own desire—the desire of the will—is a practical apprehension, one that directs toward and causes that desire.The intellect grasps the will’s act, not only by the act’s intelligible presence, but also and even first of all by grasping itself as the act’s principle (see ST I, q. 87, a. 4, ad 3).Thus some apprehension of practical intellect’s operation is present in the very grasp of the good, and so at the very root of the knowledge of natural law; see above, n. 14. 39 See, for example, De veritate, q. 1, a. 1. 40 See Summa contra gentiles, Lib. III, c. 112 (“Praeterea. Manifestum est . . .”). I say “special” because there is an affinity with all things that is common to every being;“a being, as a being, does not have the character of something repugnant, but rather of something agreeable, because all agree in being”: ST I–II, q. 29, a. 1, ad 1. 41 Still,Thomas stresses the idea that practical reason somehow “imitates” nature. See, e.g., In Politicorum, proem.; ST I, q. 60, a. 5; I–II, q. 87, a. 1; II–II, q. 31, a. 3; q. 50, a. 4; q. 130, a. 1. A la recherche speaks of “a universal ethical message immanent in nature . . . which men are capable of deciphering” (§11; see §69–70, §78). 690 Stephen L. Brock forms a universal conception of being, not contracted to any particular mode—the sheer “form” of being, taken absolutely. And it does the same with the perfect and the good. It conceives goodness, as a sort of nature or form, the form by which good things are good.This conception is what enables us to appreciate and to be moved by the good in all its universality, as pertaining to all things. It serves as principle of a desire that relates to the good, not merely in a determinate or particular mode, but absolutely—a desire that responds and inclines toward good things just insofar as they are good.42 In a way, the very “abstractness” of the mind’s grasp of the good makes this grasp the principle of the most perfect form of appetite, the fullest “engagement of affectivity” (§44).43 Think of the difference we saw between the way in which rational beings desire existence and the way other beings do. In all of this, we are talking about the mind’s natural understanding of the nature of the good, the understanding that is common to all. To be sure, it is a highly “confused” understanding. It belongs to the metaphysician to resolve this understanding back into the simpler “formal principles” that it presupposes and implies:“a being,”“a perfect,”“a true,” etc. And the understanding is “abstract” also in the sense in which this signifies an imperfection: it is “sketchy,” needs “filling in.” The natural understanding of the good does not express the myriad modes that pertain to the good as it is found in reality. But it is by no means so abstract as to be utterly empty. This special relation to the good that the mind’s universal apprehension generates is the root of our freedom.44 It is bound up with our very status as persons. I would say that its special character is itself something 42 See ST I, q. 59, a. 1. 43 On appetites as more or less “perfect,” see ST I, q. 80, a. 1. On intellect as “more noble” than will, absolutely speaking, because its object is “more abstract,” see ST I, q. 82, a. 3. 44 See, e.g., Thomas Aquinas, Sententia libri Ethicorum Aristotelis, Lib. III, lect. 13 (Marietti §517–518):“something can seem good to someone in two ways. In one way, taken universally, as by a certain speculative consideration. And this sort of judgment of a good does not follow any particular disposition, but the universal power of reason syllogizing in matters of action just as in the things that are by nature. But because matters of action are contingent, reason is not bound to assent to this or that, as happens in matters of demonstration; but a man has it in his power to assent to one part or the other of a contradiction; as happens in all opinionable matters, and especially about matters of action in which many aspects are considered, according to any of which something can be judged good or not good.” (The other way is “as though by a practical consideration, with a view to action”: ibid., §519. It is here that the person’s appetitive dispositions play a crucial role—though not quite a necessitating one; see ST I, q. 83, a. 1, ad 5.) Natural Law and Universal Good 691 we naturally perceive. For even if everything good can be loved in some way, it takes no special training to understand that only rational beings can be loved as friends. In a way this is just what Thomas is saying in 94.2, when he makes “life in society” a good that pertains to the nature proper to man, the nature of reason. It is a good that we naturally apprehend, and naturally apprehend as proper to reason. Thomas also offers the metaphysical analysis of this.To love someone with love of friendship, Thomas observes, involves wishing him well, wanting him to “have” the good. But we cannot, properly speaking, wish the good for an irrational creature, because it is not properly capable of having the good, this being proper to the rational creature, which, through free choice, is master of its disposal of the good that it has. Hence the Philosopher says in Book 2 of the Physics that we do not speak of good or bad befalling such things, except by a likeness.45 But however special our relation to the good is, it is still a relation to universal good. There is goodness in irrational things.46 And our own desire naturally extends to that too.According to Thomas, even charity in a way extends to irrational things.We might call this Thomas the conservationist: “irrational creatures can be loved out of charity, as good things that we wish for others; insofar, to wit, as we want them to be conserved for God’s honor and man’s use” (ST II–II, q. 25, a. 3). Irrational creatures serve the honor of God because they are His effects, and they are good— good in themselves, perfect, full of being. As for their utility to men, we saw that this is not only bodily but also spiritual. They furnish us with “intelligible light,” light that neither speculative nor practical intellect can do without. What I am stressing is the universality of the form or nature that serves as the foundation of the first precept of natural law. Goodness, as we naturally understand it, is not something that belongs only to man, let alone only to human action. It is by no means confined to the “human” good. 45 ST II–II, q. 25, a. 3. In Physics II.6, 197a36–b22, Aristotle says that things like happiness and good fortune and their opposites are properly ascribed only to beings endowed with choice, beings that deliberately adopt “practical proposals,” such that it makes sense to say that things may “turn out well” (or badly) for them.We do not say that things are going well or badly for a tree or a horse, but only for a person.The connection of the first precept of natural law with happiness will be central in the next section. 46 It is right there in Physics II (see previous note) that Aristotle argues at greatest length for the existence of final causality, the causality of the good, in nature. Stephen L. Brock 692 I shall return to this point in the final section. But first I want to address another problem, which has more to do with the specifically human good. IV. Particular Human Goods and the Whole Human Good The problem centers on the relation between the notion of the good and the “lower” precepts of natural law.These all regard things that “practical reason naturally apprehends to be human goods.” I argued that for Thomas, this apprehension does not consist in judgment “by connaturality” or “by inclination,” but rather in a knowledge of truths as per se notae.These are propositions in which the predicate pertains to the very concept of the subject. The problem is that this seems to mean that the notion of “human good” enters into the concepts of the things that the lower precepts concern: the conservation of our existence according to our kind, basic familial and social relationships, knowledge of the truth about God, etc. Each of these, it seems, would have “human good” somehow written into its concept, and that would be why its being a human good is a naturally understood per se nota truth. Yet this seems to run afoul of Hume’s argument (invoked by several recent writers on natural law) that “ought” cannot be derived from “is.” And in the previous section we suggested that for Thomas himself, the notion of the good adds something to the notions of being, nature, perfection, etc.47 They are contained in its concept, not it in theirs.The goodness of a thing cannot be gathered from the mere analysis of what the thing is. Now, this objection rests on the supposition that in the propositions in question, “human good” plays the role of the predicate. I would like to suggest that this is not the case, and that instead, what plays the role of the subject is “human good.”What is per se nota would not be, for example, “the conservation of human life is a human good.” (I am not saying that this proposition is not true, but that the predicate does not pertain to the very concept of the subject.) It would rather be “the human good includes the conservation of human life.” If we want a proposition with the copula, we can say “the human good is in part the conservation of human life.” Taken as a unit, the human good is a certain whole. The goods that the lower precepts regard are parts of it.They are parts whose belonging to it is immediately evident. They belong to its very concept or definition.48 It is like the way in which it is evident that a line is part 47 A la recherche says the precepts are not “deduced” from the definition of man; that is “rationalism” (§33). 48 Not all human goods do.There are other things that are parts of the human good but do not belong to its very concept; say, some vitamin D in one’s diet. “The human good includes vitamin D” is true, but it is not per se nota. Natural Law and Universal Good 693 of a triangle. Being part of a triangle does not belong to the definition of a line. But as Thomas says, having parts that are lines does belong to the definition of a triangle.49 This claim makes sense, of course, only if the human good, taken as a certain whole, has already been somehow apprehended—at least in some confused way—even prior to the understanding of the lower precepts of natural law.The apprehension of it must somehow enter into the understanding of the very first precept. I wish to argue that this is indeed so. We may be tempted to see the first precept as empty or vacuous, providing no genuine practical direction. What it tells us to do and to seek is just the good, without specification.This may seem too general or indefinite to guide action.The good, after all, is “convertible with being.” There is nothing that does not have some goodness in it. If a thing had no goodness at all—no perfection, no being—it would be nothing. It would not even be bad. But the answer to this is right here, in the fact that there are bad things. The first precept is founded on the concept of the good, but it does not 49 “The first way of saying per se is when that which is attributed to something pertains to its form. And since the definition signifies the form and essence of the thing, the first mode of per se is when the definition or something placed in the definition is predicated of something, . . . whether it be placed directly or obliquely. As in the definition of triangle is placed line, whence line belongs per se to triangle; and likewise in the definition of line is placed point, whence point belongs per se to line. And he goes on to give the reason why these are placed in the definition, saying that the substance, i.e., the essence, which the definition of them—i.e., of triangle and line—signifies, is made from these, i.e., from line and points. . . . And he says this so as to exclude those things that are parts of the matter and not of the species, which are not placed in the definition, as semicircle is not placed in the definition of circle, nor finger in the definition of man, as is said in Metaphysics VII”: Expositio libri Posteriorum analyticorum, ed. R. M. Spiazzi (Marietti:Turin, 1955), Lib. 1, lect. 10, §84 (on Post. an. I.4, 73a35–37; the Metaphysics reference is to VII.10–11, 1034b20 ff.).The phrase “whether it be placed directly or obliquely” is referring to the fact that some parts of a thing’s definition are said directly of the thing, because they express what the whole thing is, e.g., “man is an animal”; while other parts of the definition are said of the thing by way of an “oblique case” or a preposition or some other expression. This would be how those parts of the definition that are also parts of the thing itself would be said of the thing.Although we cannot say “a triangle is a line,” line does belong to the definition of triangle, and we can say “a triangle is made from a line.” And although we cannot say simply that the human good is the conservation of human life, we can say that the human good is in part the conservation of human life. As for the examples of semicircle and finger, they would be like the example of vitamin D in note 48; they are parts of the thing, but not parts of its definition. 694 Stephen L. Brock speak only of the good. If we reduced the first precept to “the good is to be done and sought,” cutting out what it says about the bad, then indeed it would provide no direction for action; just as if we took the principle of non-contradiction, which is founded on the concept of a being, and cut out what it says about non-being, it would provide no direction for thought. It would be no principle at all. To understand a thing is also to understand its proper opposite. The principle that is founded on the concept of a being refers not only to being but also to its intelligible opposite, non-being. And similarly the principle founded on the concept of the good also refers to the bad. Hence what the principle means by “the good” cannot be merely whatever has some goodness in it. For even the bad has some goodness in it, and yet the very same principle says that the bad is to be avoided. The principle can hardly be saying that some of what is to be done and sought is to be avoided.What “the good” refers to, in the first precept of natural law, is not whatever has some goodness in it. It is what is unqualifiedly good.Thus, each thing has as much of good as it has of being, for good and being are convertible. . . . But only God has the entire fullness of His being through something one and simple. Every other thing has the fullness of being suited to it through diverse factors. Hence in some things it happens that they have being up to a point, and yet they lack something of the fullness of being due to them. . . . So however much it has of being, it has that much of good, while insofar as it lacks something of the fullness of being, to that extent it lacks goodness, and is called bad. . . . But because fullness of being itself pertains to the concept of the good, if a thing lacks something of its due fullness of being, it will not be called good unqualifiedly, but only in some respect, insofar as it is a being.50 This is what all desire: not just some perfection or some being, but their total perfection, their fullness of being. Whatever is repugnant to that, even if it has some perfection and goodness in it, is to be shunned and avoided. So the first precept does provide genuine direction.And the very concept of what it directs toward is that of a kind of whole, something complete and “full.” It is a whole with many really distinct parts, many “diverse factors.”51 50 ST I–II, q. 18, a. 1. See ST I, q. 5, a. 1, ad 1. 51 By contrast, God’s “fullness of being” is an utterly simple reality. Nevertheless it is something that others can “take part in” to a greater or lesser degree, according to some likeness. Even His goodness has to be understood in the manner of a whole, as “wholly” in act and as “containing” all perfections. See ST I, q. 4, aa. 1 & 2; q. 6, aa. 1 & 2. Natural Law and Universal Good 695 Now, as Thomas formulates it, the first precept of natural law does not explicitly refer to the human good. It speaks of the good absolutely, as what all desire.And indeed it is not only the human good that is to be done and sought, or only the human bad that is to be avoided. For anything whatsoever, it is true that it ought to do and seek its good and to avoid its bad. In this sense, the first precept, considered simply as a certain truth, seems to apply to absolutely everything. I shall return to this point in the last section. But in 94.2 Thomas is considering the first precept as something practical, the very first principle of practical reason. It is the truth by which human reason first offers any direction to action. So considered, it can only refer to human good; that is, the good that can be done or sought by human action. For the only action that reason can direct is human action. This I think is why, after setting out the first precept, Thomas can say at once that all other precepts of natural law are founded upon it,“such that all those things to be done or avoided that practical reason naturally apprehends to be HUMAN goods pertain to the precepts of natural law.” As the first practical principle, then, the first precept is referring to and directing toward the specifically human good. But it is directing toward the human good as a whole. For it is also directing away from whatever detracts from the human good or renders it defective, whatever is a human bad. To be sure, the precept presents this whole in a quite unarticulated and confused way. But then, that is what one would expect in the merely natural knowledge of it, the knowledge that is common to all—just as the common knowledge of human nature is a confused knowledge, acquired prior to any analysis of it into its various dimensions. Yet, as we saw, even the common knowledge of human nature does somehow include knowledge of its various dimensions.These pertain to its very concept, albeit confusedly. And in the same way, there are particular goods, fulfillments of the various dimensions of human nature, that pertain to the very concept of the human good. For each, its belonging to the human good is a truth that is per se nota omnibus. Each is naturally apprehended to be a human good. This apprehension does not present the goods in an abstract list. But it is such that when any of them is considered, by practical reason, it is immediately understood as a human good and as something for man to do or pursue, and anything seen to be repugnant to it is immediately understood as bad and as something to be avoided. For practical reason always has the whole human good somehow in view and sees everything else in relation to it.This is because the first precept is its very first principle, always included in its consideration. Of course a particular, concrete instance of one of these goods can also be considered in other respects, and according to these, one might judge 696 Stephen L. Brock it not to be done or pursued. And a particular instance of something repugnant to one of the goods, and so to the human good as a whole, might be judged not to be avoided. This only means that it is after all possible to judge, and to choose and act, contrary to our better judgment and contrary to natural law.52 In effect, I am saying that what the first precept of natural law directs us toward is our last end, happiness.53 In 91.2 Thomas calls natural law “the first direction of our acts to the last end.”54 In 94.2 the main thesis is that although its precepts are many, there is one precept in which the others are rooted and to which they are referred. The others regard particular or partial goods. Surely then the first precept must regard the last end itself, man’s whole perfection and good, which excludes all defect, all that is bad. The other precepts belong to natural law because they regard things that are naturally understood to be parts of this whole. Obviously the first precept presents this whole only in a very “sketchy” way. It does not express exactly what our happiness consists in. Nor of course does it simply prescribe happiness. As Aristotle says, even if being happy depends chiefly on what we do, it also depends on good fortune, which cannot be prescribed. But if someone’s conduct complied fully with the first precept, and if his conduct succeeded fully in achieving its aim—in fully accomplishing and attaining the good, and in fully avoiding the bad—then indeed he or she would be happy. What the first precept sets before us is a goal of complete possession of the good and complete deliverance from the bad. It answers perfectly to what Thomas 52 A la recherche is surely right to speak of the first precept as a “moral” principle (§39). However, it might give the impression that what the first precept means by “good” is solely the “moral” good, the goodness inherent in morally good acts. For the document’s formulation of the precept is “one must do the good and avoid the bad” (§44); it leaves out “pursue.” It sounds as though the good is entirely something we “do” or effect, not also something we receive or share in (partly through what we do). The last end, happiness, involves both. The moral rule is the rule directing to the last end: see ST I–II, q. 21, a. 1, ad 2, together with a. 2, ad 2 (. . .“the common end of human life”).The properly moral good is only part of the whole human good, and the dictate pertaining to it—the dictate to “act according to reason”—is a “lower” precept (ST I–II, q. 94, a. 3). 53 Despite the possible confusion signaled in n. 52, A la recherche does associate the first precept with happiness (see §41). On the first precept as ordering to happiness and as moral, see Giuseppe Butera,“The Moral Status of the First Principle of Practical Reason in Thomas’s Natural-Law Theory,” The Thomist 71 (2007): 609–31. 54 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, ad 2. Pertinent is what he had said earlier about law in general: “the first principle in matters of action, which practical reason concerns, is the last end. Now the last end of human life is happiness or beatitude. Hence law must regard most of all the order that is toward beatitude”: ST I–II, q. 90, a. 2. Natural Law and Universal Good 697 calls the “common concept” of happiness:“a perfect overall good” (bonum commune perfectum ).55 A passage from the discussion of happiness in the Prima secundae offers confirmation of this reading. In this passage Thomas is trying to show that it is not possible for someone to have more than one last end at the same time. One of his arguments is this: [S]ince voluntary actions take their species from the end . . . it must be from the last end, which is common, that they take the nature of their genus; just as natural things are placed in a genus according to some common formal nature. So, since all the desirable objects of the will, as such, are of one genus, the last end must be one. And [this is clear] above all because in any genus there is one first principle, and the last end has the nature of a first principle. (ST I–II, q. 1, a. 5) When we call the things that the lower precepts concern “human goods,” we are seeing them as “desirable objects of the human will.”We are treating “human good” as a sort of genus to which they all belong.56 Things are placed in a common genus insofar as they are somehow referred to a common first principle, as natural substances are placed in the genus “body” because they have the same first intrinsic principle, bodily matter. The principle by reference to which things are placed in the genus of human goods is man’s last end. This is the chief human good—“the” human good, taken unqualifiedly.“Human good” is said of things per prius et posterius, and what it is first said of is the last end. It is said of anything else by reference to that.To be “a” human good, a member of this genus, is either to be the last end itself, or else to contribute somehow to the last end.This is what “a human good” means.57 55 “It is the common notion of beatitude that it be a perfect overall good; and this [Boethius] signified when he said that it is ‘a state that is perfect in the gathering of all goods,’ by which is signified nothing other than that the blessed person is in the state of perfect good”: ST I–II, q. 3, a. 2, ad 2. Notice that whereas Boethius’s formulation speaks of a “gathering of goods,”Thomas’s gloss presents happiness as more of a genuine unity,“perfect good.”We do not start from various specific “basic goods” and only subsequently see the need to “integrate” them. We start from the good as a whole, although we immediately see that it has various parts. 56 Here “genus” is taken in the broad sense of something predicated commonly of different kinds of things. It need not be univocal. Nor need it enter into the essential definitions of the things that belong to it. Human life, for example, is a human good, but its definition does not include its goodness. 57 It is no objection that the last end itself is a human good, whereas matter is not a body but only potency for one. This only shows that “human good” is not univocal in the way that “body” is. 698 Stephen L. Brock To be sure, as the same article indicates, “last end” can itself be said in many ways. For instance, it may mean that in which man’s last end truly consists, the vision of God. Not all are seeking this. Or it may mean the end that a given individual is seeking. This may differ from what others are seeking, and even from what he seeks at another time. But we can also speak of the last end as naturally understood, its “common notion.”This is the same for all, “because all desire to fulfill their perfection.”58 And there are some perfections that we naturally understand to be included in the last end. These are the particular goods that pertain to natural law. They are intrinsic to the last end, not just instrumental to it. But they need to be seen in subordination to it.59 And this is how practical reason naturally does see them. Returning to the theme of inclination, this way of understanding the first precept of natural law and its relation to the other precepts makes 94.2 line up closely with the account of the will’s natural inclination in ST I–II, q. 10, a. 1.The inclination reflects the precepts. . . . [T]he principles of intellectual cognition are naturally known. And likewise the principle of voluntary movements must be something naturally willed. Now this is the good in general, to which the will naturally tends, as indeed any power tends to its object; and also the last end itself, which stands to appetible things as the first principles of demonstration stand to intelligible things; and universally all the things that suit the willing subject according to his nature. For by the will we desire not only those things that pertain to the power of the will, but also those things that pertain to each of the powers and to the whole man. Hence man naturally wants not only the object of the will, but also other things suited to other powers, such as the knowledge of the true, which suits the intellect; and being and life and other such things that regard natural continuance; all of which are comprehended under the object of the will, as certain particular goods. First he cites the existence of naturally known principles of intellectual cognition, arguing that there must likewise be something naturally willed that serves as principle of voluntary movements. Then he considers what this is, distinguishing three aspects of it. I think we can see a correlation between these and what he says about the knowledge of natural law in 94.2. 58 “We can speak of the last end in two ways: in one way, according to the very notion of last end; in the other, according to that in which the notion of the last end is found. And so with respect to the notion of the last end, all agree in the desire of the last end, because all desire to fulfill their perfection, which is the notion of the last end, as has been said”: ST I–II, q. 1, a. 7 (the reference is to a. 5). 59 See A la recherche, §79. Natural Law and Universal Good 699 The first aspect is the good in general, which is the will’s proper object. This means that whatever the will wills is willed under the concept of good.To this corresponds the fact that the first precept of natural law, and hence natural law as a whole, is founded on the concept of the good. Everything in the law has to do with the good. Of course not everything that the will can will fits the law; even the bad has some good in it, and as such it may be willed. The law, after all, is supposed to direct the will. The second aspect is the last end, the complete or perfect good. Its place among appetibles is like that of the first principles of demonstration among intelligibles.The last end is the will’s primary object, the primary good. To this, I have suggested, corresponds the first precept of natural law. Finally come all the things that suit the will’s subject according to his nature, taken universally. These are particular goods falling under the will’s object, goods to which our will naturally tends, not simply because it is will, but because it is human will. These “fill in” the common concept of the last end as the perfect good.To them would correspond the lower primary precepts of natural law.60 Thomas calls all of these—the good in general, the last end, and the things that suit man’s nature—“something naturally willed.” He is seeing them as a package.Any desire for a good as good, under the universal ratio boni, implies desire of the last end, the whole or perfect good. And the desire for the whole good is a desire for whatever particular goods are immediately understood to be essential parts of it. Even though a man’s particular choice can run contrary to these goods, he cannot altogether lose the desire for them, taken universally. V. The Universal Good and Wisdom Earlier we noted that Thomas’s formulation of the first precept of natural law does not speak explicitly of the human good, but simply of the 60 He says that these goods include both what suits man’s various powers and what suits the whole man.The goods cited in the corpus of 94.2 as pertaining to the lower precepts all seem to regard the whole man, according to the various dimensions of his whole nature. It is the whole man that is a substance, an animal, and rational.The “parts” of human nature, such as the sense-appetites, are mentioned in the second objection and reply.The inclinations of these parts, he says, pertain to natural law insofar as they are ruled by reason. Actually even reason’s own innate inclination to truth in general has to be regulated and ordered to the last end (see ST II–II, q. 167, a. 1, ad 1, on the vice of curiositas )— though it would be reason itself that does the regulating. Reason is man’s dominant part, and to it belongs the work of ordering toward the good of man as a whole. This suggests again that the inclinations cited in the corpus of 94.2, pertaining to man as a whole, proceed from reason itself. 700 Stephen L. Brock good, which he had formulated as what all desire. I suggested that insofar as the first precept is apprehended by practical reason, the good that it regards is the human good. But taken simply as a truth, its scope is broader. It applies to all beings. For each thing, it is true that it ought to do and pursue the good and to avoid the bad, in the way proper to it. Natural law, we should recall, is “a certain irradiation and participation of the eternal law, which is the immutable truth” (ST I–II, q. 93, a. 2).The eternal law is the law “by which it is just that all things be perfectly ordered.”61 All true order is toward the good and away from the bad.That all things fall under the order expressed in the first precept is shown by the very fact that all things do tend to do and pursue their good and to avoid their bad, each in its own way.62 The obvious objection to this is that it blurs the distinction between speculative and practical principles. But now, we have already seen that knowledge of speculative matters, such as human nature, can play a role in practical reasoning. In 94.2, Thomas says that being is what falls first into our apprehension “absolutely,” and that it is included in everything whatsoever that one understands. So it is included in practical understanding too.63 Certainly practical thought has to respect the principle of non-contradiction. The other common principles that Thomas cites in 94.2 also play obvious roles in practical thought. That “the whole is greater than the part” is implicit in the understanding that the common good is a greater good than the private.And that “things that are equal to one same thing are equal to each other” has application in matters of justice; the equal distribution of goods is often achieved by measuring them against a single measure. If only some principles are called practical, it must be because only they are intrinsically apt to direct action.They alone are rules of action, 61 ST I–II, q. 93, a. 2, obj. 2; cf. ST I–II, q. 93, aa. 4 & 5. 62 I think a similar point holds for those “lower” precepts that regard goods pertain- ing to the natures that man has in common with other things. The orders to these goods are naturally seen as common. We see that all substances tend to preserve their being according to their kind.We see the order between male and female, parents and offspring, as something that “nature has taught all animals” (94.2). (We also see the order to the goods proper to man as just that, proper to man ; that is, common to all men.) As for the first precept, I think it can be said to regard the inclination pertaining to the nature that we share, and see that we share, with all beings : the inclination to the good. Of course, unlike natural law, the participation in the eternal law that belongs to irrational things is not properly called “law” (ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, ad 3). 63 A la recherche only sees the principle of non-contradiction “at the base of all speculative reasoning” (§39, my emphasis). Natural Law and Universal Good 701 precepts. But must their truth be confined to the sphere of human action? If so, how can Thomas see fit to correlate many of them with inclinations that man shares with non-human things? It may be that the precepts do not serve as principles, for reasoning about such things, because we do not reason about such things practically.We all see that reasoning practically about things not in our power is otiose. So perhaps the first precept of natural law serves as a principle only for practical thought. But I would still suggest that the concept upon which it is based, the universal concept of the good, is at work from the very start in the understanding of both speculative and practical matters.64 Thomas says that the good is the first thing to fall in the apprehension of practical reason. He does not say, however, that what the good first falls into is the apprehension of practical reason. Reason first becomes practical through the apprehension of the good; through this it immediately becomes practical, because as we saw, right then it begins to know and to direct the will.65 But this does not entail that the apprehension of the good is only practical, not also speculative.We saw too that the apprehension of the good involves the perception of desires and actions that do not arise from our knowledge, those of the things around us. Taken on the whole, as “what all desire,” the good is a speculative notion.Thomas says that the “rule of human reason”—natural law—is “gathered from the created things that man naturally knows” (ST I–II, q. 74, a. 7). He says this quite generally. He certainly does not except the first precept. Of course I do not mean that we naturally understand the good in the speculative “mode” that we discussed early on. The natural understanding of it does not consist in “defining and dividing and considering its universal predicates.”That would be the metaphysician’s job. Most people reason about the good only in a practical way. But such reasoning 64 Here I am correcting something I said in “Natural Inclination . . . ”: that “our original apprehension of the good is practical, not speculative” (74). In part, I was simply assuming that it could not be both. But I had no good reason for this assumption. I was also thinking that we are not originally in a position to judge whether the generation of an entire species proceeds from some inclination toward the species’ good. But this is incidental.We do, quite naturally, explain the typical activities of the members of a species as functions of the species’ good.We see the members as belonging to the species “by nature,” according to what they essentially are, and as having genuine inclination to the good of the species.We see this good as defining their inclination, as its “formal principle,” and we see their very existence as depending on this inclination.That we may subsequently call this view into question, as Empedocles did and more recent thinkers have done, is also quite incidental. 65 What moves the will is practical reason: ST I–II, q. 9, a. 1, ad 2. 702 Stephen L. Brock supposes at least a confused grasp of what the good is. And on the other hand, neither do I mean only that some of the things that we naturally understand to be good are speculative things, while others are practical things. I am talking about the good itself, this universal intelligible “form,” according to which whatever has it is “apt to be desired.”As we naturally grasp it, this form functions both in a practical way, as that by which our own understanding gives rise to certain things, and in a speculative way, as a principle for explaining certain things that we merely observe.What it gives rise to is our own desire and, through that, our own action.What it explains are the desires in the natural things around us, together with the effects of these desires—the movements and actions of these things, and even their very existence, insofar as this too is an effect of natural movement, action, and desire.A tree that is growing is doing what is good for it, doing what it ought to do. And since for the most part what trees do is what is good for them, we are naturally led to judge that they do it because it is good for them, that it constitutes a true object and cause—a formal principle —of their inclination.66 In both cases—in both the speculative and the practical function of the concept of the good—what is at work is the good as good; that is, as a form of causality, final causality. Final causality has this double function.We speak of an end as a “cause” in the sense of that on account of which something observed is done, that which it is done for; and we also speak of an end as a “cause” in the sense of that which something is to be done about—a “cause to pursue,” a “cause for rejoicing,” etc. A la recherche is aimed at promoting the “causes” of peace, justice, and so forth.The intellectual grasp of the good as what all desire is at once an explanation of what we observe and the origin of the intellect’s own desire, that of the will. I think it is far from otiose to consider that we naturally understand our own good, and the order of action regarding it, in light of the universal good.This has practical importance.We see the good generally as a nature whose sway extends to all things.We see the good of any particular thing, including our own, as a “participation” in this nature.We also see that for each thing, what its perfect good consists in depends not only on the thing’s own nature, but also on the natures of other things. What the healthy activity of a tree consists in, for example, depends not only on what the tree is, but also on what many other things are—the earth, the air, the sun, and so forth. Now, a tree is so constituted as to act spontaneously in a way that is for the most part well-coordinated with the other 66 It requires further consideration, though perhaps not a great deal, to reach the judgment that some mind is at the origin of this inclination—the sort of consideration that Thomas lays out in his Fifth Way (ST I, q. 2, a. 3). Natural Law and Universal Good 703 factors. But we are not. In order to attain our end, and even in order to know what our end is with sufficient precision to move ourselves toward it, it is not enough to have grasped the general concept of the good.67 Nor is it enough to have grasped also the essential dimensions of our own nature.We need to know about the rest of reality too—a good deal more about it than what we “naturally” know. This fact too is something we naturally grasp.We all see the need to learn the “facts of life.” To put it another way, we naturally want to share in the good as much as we can.68 But what we naturally or immediately know about the good as a whole is very sketchy.The concept of the good as “what all desire” is some sort of grasp of the nature of the good, but it is very imperfect. It does not present this nature in light of its own first principles. What our end is, and what the due order to it is, depend ultimately on our relation to these. But since the good extends to everything, the inquiry into its first principles is in effect an inquiry into the first principles of all reality. And in 94.2 itself Thomas indicates that this is something that we naturally perceive. Cited first among the goods to which man is naturally inclined according to the nature proper to him, the nature of reason, is “to know the truth about God.” Regarding this, we should also recall a famous article appearing just prior to the Treatise on Law in the Summa theologiae.69 Here we are shown the urgency with which the question of the end naturally presents itself. The article is about whether a person can have venial sin together with only original sin, without mortal sin.This is not possible, it says, because until reaching the use of reason, he can have only original sin; and upon reaching it, he is faced at once with a grave choice. It is a choice about the very use of his reason. For “the first thing that then occurs to a man to ponder is to deliberate about himself.”This means to inquire into his end. If he takes the inquiry seriously, ordering himself as best he can to his “due end,” he will “turn to God,” obtain grace and be quit of original sin. If not, he sins mortally.70 67 The question would be what the “common concept” of the end is “found in”: ST I–II, q. 1, a. 7; cf. q. 5, a. 8. 68 Only that which is a “bonum universale” can fully satisfy the will: see ST I–II, q. 2, aa. 7 & 8; q. 5, a. 1. 69 ST I–II, q. 89, a. 6. See also In II Sent., d. 42, q. 1, a. 5, ad 7; De malo, q. 5, a. 2, ad 8, and q. 7, a. 10, ad 8 and ad 9. 70 “I am going to ask you a question, my dear brethren. . . . It is this:—‘Why were you sent into the world?’ . . .There are those who recollect the first time, as it would seem, when it came home to them.They were but little children, and they were by themselves, and they spontaneously asked themselves, or rather God spake in them, ‘Why am I here? How came I here? Who brought me here? What am I to 704 Stephen L. Brock Grace of course belongs to the supernatural order. But Thomas is also talking about how reason naturally functions. In what he says I think we can see three things.The first is the absolute primacy of the last end.This is what first occurs to a person to think about when he reaches the use of reason—the full capacity for deliberation and moral action.The second is that our natural understanding of the last end is not only sketchy, but also something whose sketchiness we naturally perceive.That is why we at once see the need to deliberate about it, to bring it into better focus.The third is that we naturally understand that what our true last end consists in somehow calls into play our relation to the whole world.71 Otherwise why would serious inquiry into it necessarily lead to God? If one gives full due priority to his own perfect good, then the very nature of the situation, as he naturally perceives it, is such that his thought and his desire will be oriented toward the source of all good, which is the source of all being. A la recherche does have important things to say about the relation between God and natural law. It calls attention to traditions of wisdom that assert the existence of a divine order of goodness in things (§12ff.). Against Grotius, it insists that in the doctrine of natural law, reference to God is not an “option” (§32). It also says that “only taking into account the metaphysics of the real can give to natural law its full and entire philosophical justification” (§62). These points, however, only concern God’s place in teachings about natural law. The document does not say much about how God is involved in natural law as “naturally known.” It does speak of a natural inclination “to know God,” but only after citing the inclination to live in society, and entirely in the context of man’s general need for “personal relationships.” The person’s relational character also expresses itself in the tendency to live in communion with God or the Absolute. It shows itself in the religious sentiment and in the desire to know God. Certainly it can be denied by those who refuse to admit the existence of a personal God, but it remains no less implicitly present in the search for truth and meaning that dwells in every human being.To these tendencies specific to man corresponds the need perceived by reason to realize in the concrete this life of relations and to construct life in society on just bases that correspond to natural right. (§50–51) do here?’ Perhaps it was the first act of reason, the beginning of their real responsibility, the commencement of their trial; perhaps from that day they may date their capacity, their awful power, of choosing between good and evil, and of committing mortal sin”: John Henry Newman, “God’s Will the End of Life,” Discourses Addressed to Mixed Congregations (London: Burns & Oates, 1881), 104. 71 Very pertinent here is A la recherche, §12. Natural Law and Universal Good 705 There is no further mention of a natural inclination regarding God. Nor is there any mention of God’s being inevitably “on the horizon” at the moment of reaching the use of reason.72 In 94.2, Thomas cites the inclination to know the truth about God prior to the inclination to live in society. I do not think he is suggesting that men naturally locate their end chiefly in this very knowledge. We saw that he judges the active life “more connatural” to man than the speculative. Not many are prone to be philosophers. But he is definitely presenting the philosopher’s goal—wisdom—as something that everyone naturally sees a strong need for. Wisdom is the chief intellectual virtue, the one that “considers the highest cause, which is God” (ST I–II, q. 66, a. 5).To know about the universal good “pertains to wisdom”; the good is a feature of “universal being,” which is “a proper effect of the highest cause, namely God” (ibid., ad 4). Even simply grasping the universal concepts of good and being is already the basis for an “immediate order to the universal principle of being” (ST II–II, q. 2, a. 3). If people quite generally see the need to know the truth about God, is it not because they see that without it they are very much more in the dark about where life is headed, about what they can and cannot hope for, and about how to pursue their hope? Surely it is not just part of a generic need for personal relations (much less a “sentiment,” which sounds “pre-rational”). Its bearing on our desire for “fullness of being” is really quite global. Consider the desire for conservation in being. With respect to it, the question of God is in a way even more pressing than the need for society. Society is a powerful factor in our survival, but not even the best social order can abolish death.“Every being with intellect naturally desires to be forever” (ST I, q. 75, a. 6). We all want to know the truth about death, and we know that it is tied to the truth about God. Atheists too can see that the question of God’s existence is a grave one. And I strongly doubt whether Thomas would agree that some desire for a God—understood as a supreme good —can ever be truly denied, even by someone who denies that a God exists. I am stressing the question about God and its universal practical import. It is bound up with the question of our true end, which is the absolutely first practical question. Natural law is what first directs us toward our end, and as Thomas seems to see it, the first effect of this direction is to raise these very questions. If this is right, then it signals some rather large issues for the project that A la recherche has in view. For instance, would a “universal ethical language” not require general agreement that there is such a thing as 72 It does say that upon reaching the use of reason, one experiences “a call to accomplish the good” (§39). 706 Stephen L. Brock mankind’s common end? To what extent would it require agreement about what that end is? Might it even require a “universal language of the divine”? What we have seen does suggest that from Thomas’s perspective, it would at N&V least require a universal language of “the natural.” Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 707–735 707 Diplomacy and Theology in the Dialogue on Universal Ethics J. B UDZISZEWSKI University of Texas Austin,Texas I. How to Read the Document C ONSIDERING the International Theological Commission’s hope of encouraging broad dialogue between the Church and other parties about the natural law, there is a certain advantage in knowing how an outsider might view its authors’ work.Allow me to try.Though Catholic, I am a convert from Protestantism, and before that a convert from secularism. Though a natural law scholar, I have pursued the subject from inside the Church for a smaller fraction of my life than I pursued it from outside.Though I would hope to be considered in a small way a disciple of Thomas Aquinas, I was not introduced to his thought in any of the conventional Catholic ways. I am not “in” on the Church’s consultations; the very diction of curial documents still seems a bit strange to me; and the sheer mass of such documentation presents to me the aspect of a labyrinth. Although all these are limitations, sometimes a limitation can be of service, and perhaps this is one of those times. Having learned the hard way, let me hazard the suggestion that anyone who wishes to engage the documents of the Church—to enter into the spirit of their deliberations and even, perhaps, respond—must keep two points in mind. I apologize to insiders, to whom these points may seem obvious. But others may bring different expectations, such as those formed in Protestantism, other traditions, or secular academia. The first and most important is that the documents of the Church are not purely works of doctrine, but also works of religious diplomacy.This is most plainly true when their audience lies partly or wholly outside the Church, when they are addressed, for example, to the United Nations 708 J. Budziszewski Assembly, to “representatives from the world of culture,” or simply to “all men of good will.” But it is often just as true when they are addressed from one body of the Church to another, as for example in the present case, for the task of the International Theological Commission is to advise the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. In making the ITC statement public—hereafter I will call it simply the Statement—of course the Church knew that the world was looking over her shoulder. More than that, at least in this case she wanted the world to look. Even if this fact could not have been guessed from the Statement’s text, it would have become obvious as soon as she began to call the world’s attention to it. Within a few months, for example, Cardinal Bertone, the Vatican Secretary of State, mentioned it in an address to the Italian Senate, wherein he declared that “it addresses topics of great importance which I wish to point out and to recommend especially in this context of the Senate, that is, an institution whose main function is legislative.”1 Because the imperatives of such a document are not only theological but diplomatic as well, it may devote greater attention to some points than one would expect, while others may be so delicately understated as to seem almost not stated at all. The other thing to keep in mind is that the most conspicuous feature of the deliberations of the Church is not hierarchy, as popularly supposed, but massively parallel, massively distributed discussion. Numerous bodies and individuals in diverse places and times consider various facets of each problem. Authority is exercised, but more sparingly than one might expect. Even apart from the protective guidance of the Holy Spirit, this mode of deliberation would be unlikely to produce irreversible mistakes in doctrine. The gears turn too slowly for that. It is much more likely to produce gaffes in diplomacy, gaffes, because history unfolds faster than doctrine. Like a churning sea, the world is always tossing up new challenges to the teaching of the Church, and she reacts much better than she anticipates.When the new war is at hand, she is still rethinking her strategy for the last one— a point to which I will have occasion to return later on. From what I have already said, it will come as no surprise when I suggest that the Statement has two linked goals, one diplomatic, the other philosophical and theological. Consequently it must be read from both angles. II. Diplomatic and Theological Aims The diplomatic goal of the Statement is to encourage dialogue among the various religions and wisdom traditions about the natural moral law.“The 1 Address of Cardinal Tarcisio Bertone, Secretary of State, During His Visit to the Senate of the Italian Republic, 28 July 2009. Diplomacy and Theology 709 search for a common ethical language concerns everyone,” it declares. “Enlightened by the Gospel, engaged in a patient and respectful dialogue with all men of good will, Christians partake in the common search for human values to promote.”2 One reason to encourage dialogue is to help the various religions and wisdom traditions come to share a deeper understanding and respect for the truth about the human person.These traditions show significant convergence on many of the concrete ethical particulars of this truth. However, they show great differences in the ways that they try to explain these particulars, and this hinders further convergence. Another reason to encourage dialogue is to reassert and secure the place in public moral discourse of the Catholic Church herself, a place which is presently threatened not only by secularist ideology but by the hostility of some other religions. Yet in protecting her place in the conversation, the Church is not just acting as another interest group, but attempting to follow her vocation.The primary element in her vocation is to be the witness and guardian of the gospel. But the gospel illuminates and fulfills the natural law at the same time that it transcends it; Jesus Christ restores the true nature of man as the image of God, an image which for long was obscured by sin, and goes on to reveal that man’s destiny is not merely natural but supernatural. Consequently, the Church also understands herself as the authentic interpreter and guardian of the natural law: “Certainly the natural law is accessible to human reason, common to believers and nonbelievers, and the Church does not have it exclusively, but since revelation takes up the requirements of the natural law, the Magisterium of the Church has been established the guarantor and interpreter of it.”3 On the one hand the natural law is “a fundamental link with the new law of the Spirit of life in Christ Jesus,” while on the other it “offers a wider base for dialogue with persons of another orientation or of another formation, in view of the search for the common good.”4 The philosophical and theological goal of the Statement is to restate the doctrine of natural law in such a way as to clear up points which may obscure the hoped-for dialogue and to help it to advance. One of the aims of restatement is to enable non-Catholics to recognize natural law for what it is, as the truth about man, accessible to reason, rather than as a teaching of purely Catholic interest, accessible only by revelation.Another aim is to counsel the Church in her response to the confusions about 2 Statement, §3. 3 Statement, §34. 4 Statement, §112, quoting John Paul II, Papal Address to the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, 18 January 2002. 710 J. Budziszewski natural law which circulate outside her boundaries, especially in the secular world.These confusions are manifold. Among the most prominent are moral relativism and legal positivism. At a deeper level still, they include ideologies which divide reason from truth, divide power from goodness, divide nature from freedom, or deny transcendence, viewing man as a purely material being or a creature of the state. In order to pull up these errors at the root, the Church must see natural law clearly in the context of all three phases of salvation history: Creation, Fall, and Redemption. The philosophy and theology of the Statement do not contain any obvious errors. In view of the scrutiny that they had already received before publication, one would not expect them to. If its presentation may be said to contain weaknesses, they lie more in overemphasis, underemphasis, and omission.When a document has dual purposes, however, small faults in theoretical presentation may constitute large faults in diplomacy. III. WHAT Is In and What Is Out If the Church is serious about dialogue with other religions and wisdom traditions, then she must find ways to show the prospective dialogue partners why dialogue is important. Why must we achieve a universal ethics? It isn’t enough simply to say that today the human race confronts great ethical problems; other religions may think they have the answers to these problems already. Nor is it enough simply to assert that the global scale of these problems requires consensus; other religions may view their solution as more likely to be found in imposing their answers on the rest of us. What has to be done is to show that natural law is worth thinking about even from their point of view. This would seem to require showing adherents of other traditions that the natural law doctrine begins from the same experiences that all humans share, but provides deeper resources for understanding them, and this seems to be the Statement’s intention. Prudently, though, it first tries to foster hope that consensus about ethical norms is even possible. In order to foster that hope, the Statement surveys the great religions and wisdom traditions of the world, calling attention to how much consensus there is already. Not only do the traditions agree that there are universal rules,5 they substantially agree about their particulars. In particular, the golden rule is explicitly proposed almost everywhere, at least in its negative form, “Do not do unto others what you would not wish them to do unto you.” 5 “[T]hey generally agree in the recognition that the great ethical rules are not imposed by a determinate human group, but are universally valid for every individual and for all people.” Statement, §12. Diplomacy and Theology 711 Moreover, the ethical precepts of two traditions, Hinduism and Islam, can be brought into correspondence with the precepts of the Decalogue.6 Therein lies the first surprise. Just Hinduism and Islam? I am a little surprised by the understatement. Catholic tradition has long considered the Decalogue an unparalleled summary of the natural law written universally on the hearts of man, even though universally obscured by the evasions and subterfuges of men. Despite the prevalence of sin, don’t all peoples reprobate murder and theft? Doesn’t every great wisdom tradition approve honor to parents? Isn’t greed held universally in dishonor? Even where devotion to the One High God is obscured by the cult of lesser gods, isn’t reverence for deity commended everywhere?7 Pope Benedict XVI had far more warmly emphasized the universality of the precepts of the Decalogue in his address to the ITC three years previously:8 The contribution of the International Theological Commission, aimed above all to justify and describe the foundations of a universal ethic that is part of the great patrimony of human knowledge which in a certain way constitutes the rational creature’s participation in the eternal law of 6 “Different precepts of the Hindu tradition can be put in parallel with the requirements of the Decalogue” (Statement, Section 13).“From the prescriptions of [the] positive divine law [of Islam] many persons regain the great elements of the moral patrimony of humanity and they can be set in relation to the Decalogue” (Statement, §17). 7 As anthropologist Clyde Kluckhohn wrote during the previous generation’s debate over relativism,“Every culture has a concept of murder, distinguishing this from execution, killing in war, and other ‘justifiable homicides.’ The notions of incest and other regulations upon sexual behavior, of prohibitions upon untruth under defined circumstances, of restitution and reciprocity, of mutual obligations between parents and children—these and many other moral concepts are altogether universal.” Still earlier John M. Cooper had spoken of a “universal moral code” which “agrees rather closely with our own Decalogue taken in a strictly literal sense.” Clyde Kluckhohn,“Ethical Relativity: Sic et Non,” Journal of Philosophy, 52 (1955): 663 (article reprinted in Ethical Relativism, ed. John Ladd [Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1985], 78–95). John M. Cooper,“The Relations Between Religion and Morality in Primitive Culture,” Primitive Man [now Anthropological Quarterly] 4 (1931): 36. Interest in moral universals seems to be increasing among contemporary anthropologists, albeit largely under the influence of evolutionary psychology rather than the doctrine of natural law. 8 Benedict XVI, papal address to the members of the International Theological Commission, 5 October 2007. See also the remarks on natural law in his previous address to the ITC on 1 December 2005, and his address to the participants in the International Congress on Natural Moral Law on 12 February 2007. See also the papal addresses of John Paul II to the ITC on 7 October 2004, and to the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith on 18 January 2002. The relevant encyclical letters of John Paul II include Veritatis Splendor, 6 August 1993, Evangelium Vitae, 25 March 1995, and Fides et Ratio, 14 September 1998. 712 J. Budziszewski God, is eagerly awaited. It is not, therefore, a theme of an exclusively or mainly denominational kind, although the doctrine on natural moral law is illuminated and developed to the full in the light of Christian revelation and the fulfillment of man in the mystery of Christ. The Catechism of the Catholic Church sums up well the central content of the doctrine on natural moral law, pointing out that it “states the first and essential precepts which govern the moral life. It hinges upon the desire for God and submission to him, who is the source and judge of all that is good, as well as upon the sense that the other is one’s equal. Its principal precepts are expressed in the Decalogue.This law is called ‘natural,’ not in reference to the nature of irrational beings, but because reason which decrees it properly belongs to human nature” [CCC 1955].With this doctrine two essential goals are reached: on the one hand, it is understood that the ethical content of the Christian faith does not constitute an imposition dictated to the human conscience from the outside but a norm inherent in human nature itself; on the other hand, on the basis of natural law, in itself accessible to any rational creature, with this doctrine the foundations are laid to enter into dialogue with all people of good will and more generally, with civil and secular society. Compared with the Pope’s remarks about the Decalogue, the Statement’s sparse references give a certain impression of retreat. I hope I am not reading too much into them. If I am, my excuse must lie in the importance of the point in question. Concerning the Decalogue’s relationship with the golden rule, two common misconceptions must be discouraged. One is that its precepts are obscure—that although they may follow from the golden rule, they are at best remote rather than proximate implications. On the contrary,“there are certain things which the natural reason of every man, of its own accord and at once, judges to be done or not to be done: e.g.‘Honor thy father and thy mother,’ and ‘Thou shalt not kill, Thou shalt not steal: and these belong to the law of nature absolutely.”9 The opposite misconception is that the golden rule generates the precepts of the Decalogue all by itself, without help, as though he who said the former said the latter. But the golden rule concerns only the second tablet of the Decalogue, duties to neighbor, and it generates these 9 Thomas Aquinas, ST I–II q. 100, a. 2. The point of St. Thomas’s apparently contrary remark that “formerly, theft, although it is expressly contrary to the natural law, was not considered wrong among the Germans,” I–II, q. 94, a. 4, is not that the Germans did not know the wrong of theft in the abstract, but that when they raided other tribes they did not recognize this theft as wrong, because they did not recognize it as theft. St. Thomas knew that the Germans punished private theft. For discussion, see J. Budziszewski, The Line Through the Heart: Natural Law as Fact,Theory, and Sign of Contradiction (Wilmington, DE: ISI Books, 2009), 45–46. Diplomacy and Theology 713 duties only in the light of right desire. Imagine a man reasoning, “I wouldn’t mind if that fellow slept with my wife; fidelity is boring, and possessiveness is old-fashioned anyway.Therefore, he shouldn’t mind if I sleep with his.” In fact, the Decalogue and golden rule co-illuminate each other, and a certain perception of both is found universally. IV. WHO Is In and Who Is Out Surprises lie too in what is and is not included in the Statement’s survey of religions. Separate sections are allotted to Hinduism, Buddhism, Islam, African religions, and Taoism and Confucianism, the latter two treated together. The weight given to African religions is surprising, because although they are “traditional” in the sense of being passed on from generation to generation, they do not constitute a “tradition” in the sense of a self-conscious, developing, coherent inquiry into the truth with which one might enter into dialogue. Rather we are speaking of various animistic observances which happen to be widespread on the African continent.The treatment of animism is surprising in another way too: The human being, microcosm within the macrocosm, lives intensely the drama of the clash between life and death.The task that falls to him, of assuring the victory of life over death, orients and determines his ethical action.Thus man should identify, in a consequent ethical horizon, the allies of life, gaining them to his cause and thus assuring his own survival which is at the same time the victory of life. This is the profound meaning of the traditional African religions.10 I think this language might startle African Christians, who would instantly recognize phrases like “identifying the allies of life” as euphemisms for the placation of good and evil spirits, both human and nonhuman, by means of witchcraft and necromancy. Of course the authentically religious longings of all people should be treated with respect. Surely, though, it passes beyond respect to describe soul-enslaving practices as though they were somehow humanizing. If we are to speak so flatteringly about witchcraft in the global South, then why should we not speak that way about, say, abortion in the global North? Radical feminists do. Ginette Paris writes,“Our culture needs new rituals as well as laws to restore abortion to its sacred dimension, which is both terrible and necessary.” She considers abortion “a sacrament for the gift of life to remain pure.”11 But complicity with this sort of speech in no way contributes to real dialogue. 10 Statement, §16. 11 Ginette Paris, The Sacrament of Abortion, trans. Joanna Mott (Dallas: Spring Publi- cations, 1992), 92, 107. J. Budziszewski 714 In charity, I do not think the authors of the Statement were trying to be complicit with it. Perhaps they meant only that like other traditional cultures, African cultures contain “cultural capital” which can serve as a praeparatio evangelica 12 —such things as the cherishing of children, the honoring of parents, and the veneration (I do not say propitiation and worship) of ancestors.This is certainly true, but if that was their intention then they should have written with greater attention to necessary distinctions. In speaking of animism and paganism, a better tone was struck by then-Cardinal Ratzinger in his book Introduction to Christianity, where he wrote that in ancient times,“in an environment teeming with gods,” when Christians were asked to which god their God corresponded, “the answer ran: to none of them. To none of the gods to whom you pray but solely and alone to him to whom you do not pray, to that highest being of whom your philosophers speak.” He rightly remarks, “The choice thus made meant opting for the logos as against any kind of myth.”13 Surely this must be the answer not only of Christians but of all who adhere to natural law. Another odd thing about the survey of world wisdom traditions is that it omits Judaism. To be sure, ancient Jewish writings are respectfully discussed in a later section, in the context of Sacred Scripture. But they appear in that section because they are part of Christian Scripture, not because they make up Jewish Scripture. Certainly the Jewish and Christian religions grow from the same root. To Christianity, Judaism is an older brother. But this does not make Judaism and Christianity the same religion, and the omission of Judaism from the Statement’s survey of wisdom traditions gives the disquieting impression that Jews are not partners in the intended dialogue, that they come into the picture only as precursors to Christianity. I am sure that this impression was not intended. No doubt the authors of the dialogue were trying to emphasize the very closeness of the bond between Jews and Christians, not to shut them out. Nonetheless the impression is hard to resist, and it is a diplomatic gaffe. Judaism has a natural law tradition of its own, the rabbinical tradition of the Seven Commandments given to the “Sons” or descendants of Noah, who include all humans now living. The fact that the Statement relegates the tradition of Noahide Commandments to a footnote is a scandal. 12 A point the Statement makes, not about cultures, but about wisdom traditions, in §12. 13 Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, Introduction to Christianity, trans. J. R. Foster (New York: Herder and Herder, 1970), 94–95. Diplomacy and Theology 715 V. What Happened to Protestantism? Protestants are omitted from the survey too, probably for similar reasons. The problem is not that they are too far away, but that they are too close; in the eyes of the Church they are not exactly an independent tradition, or even a disputatious family of traditions, but another group of separated brothers.Yes, they have certain difficulties with natural law, but the diplomatic strategy seems to be to minimize these differences, as though the differences were all a misunderstanding which is clearing itself up. Not until later in the Statement, in an otherwise admirable discussion about the damage sustained by natural law tradition in modern times, are Protestants even mentioned.We meet in one section the observation that “several factors led to the secularization of the notion of natural law. Among these, one can recall the growing divorce between faith and reason which characterizes the end of the Middle Ages, or some aspects of the Reformation[.]”14 A footnote maintains that Protestant hostility to natural law arose no earlier than the nineteenth century: The position of the Reformers as regards the natural law was not monolithic. More than Martin Luther, John Calvin, basing himself on St. Paul, recognizes the existence of the natural law as ethical norm, even if it is radically incapable of justifying man.‘Nothing, indeed, is more common, than for man to be sufficiently instructed in a right course of conduct by natural law, of which the Apostle here speaks [. . .].The end of the natural law, therefore, is to render man inexcusable, and may be not improperly defined as: the judgment of conscience distinguishing sufficiently between just and unjust, and by convicting men on their own testimony, depriving them of all pretext for ignorance.’ In the three ages following the Reformation, for the Protestants the natural law served as the foundation for jurisprudence. Only with the secularization of the natural law, in the 19th century, has Protestant theology distanced itself from it. Only from this period has there been opposition between Catholic and Protestant opinion on the question of the natural law. But today the Protestant ethic seems to manifest a new interest in this notion.15 That’s all; no more is said.There is no greater scandal to Christian natural law tradition than that even some Christians reject it, and I wonder why the Statement gives it so little attention. Many Protestants do show greater interest in natural law today than formerly; the Statement is not wrong about that. However, the multiplicity of voices in Protestantism, some for the natural law and others against, makes 14 Statement, §31. 15 Statement, §36. 716 J. Budziszewski natural law diplomacy harder, not easier.The problem is not that there will be no one on the other side to talk to, but that no one on the other side speaks for the other side as such. Not only do some of the voices react against the Catholic Church, they react against each other, so that the Church may meet stumbling blocks even when she does everything right. Consider for example the agreement on the doctrine of justification achieved between the Church and the Lutheran World Federation in 1999, one of the greatest triumphs of the Church’s interreligious diplomacy in modern times.16 At the time, when I was still firmly Protestant, the Joint Declaration struck me like a thunderclap. Reading it, recalling Luther’s words that justification was the article on which the Church stands or falls, I thought to myself, “The Reformation is over.” Reaction among wellinformed Protestants whom I knew was quite different. Most were simply indifferent; intuitively if not theoretically congregationalist, they viewed all faith as local. Among those who did take an interest, some held that the agreement was merely verbal, a trick of ambiguous wording, signifying nothing. Others held that it was real but unimportant, because the article on which the Church stands or falls is really the sovereignty of God (what has Wittenburg to do with Geneva?) Still others held that it was real, but that the liberals in the Lutheran World Federation did not represent their views. A sizable group conceded that the Declaration would be important if the Catholic Church meant what she said, but this would have required renunciation of the Council of Trent, therefore the Church must have been lying. My point is not that dialogue with such a fractured, multifarious world as Protestantism is impossible—on natural law or any other topic—but that it requires much greater energy and much more explicit attention than the Statement gives to it. One must not simply assume that Protestants will come around on their own. A still deeper complication of dialogue about natural law with Protestants is that even if it were true, as the Statement suggests, that Protestant theology began to distance itself from natural law only in the nineteenth century—a claim which is at least debatable—the roots of this hostility go all the way back to the Reformers. They lie in suspicion of reason and nature as such, the former a “whore,”17 the latter depraved beyond recognition.To be sure, not even Luther denied the reality of the natural law; in 16 Joint Declaration on the Doctrine of Justification by the Lutheran World Feder- ation and the Catholic Church, 31 October 1999. 17 “As a young man must resist lust and an old man avarice, so reason is by nature a harmful whore. But she shall not harm me, if only I resist her. Ah, but she is so comely and glittering.” Martin Luther, “Last Sermon in Wittenberg” (Second Sunday in Epiphany, 17 January 1546), in Luther’s Works,Vol. 51, ed. and trans. John Diplomacy and Theology 717 fact he insisted on it strongly, a point which cannot be emphasized enough. The problem is that no such endorsement could continue to survive in the soil of such awful qualms. Calvin’s theology is quite favorable to natural law doctrine. In various works, he finds a basis in natural law for the ordinance of marriage, the condemnation of fornication, the esteem due to the capable, the honor due to the old, the prohibition of incest, the help given to the needy, the affection of fathers for their children, the duties of sons toward their fathers (more generally of children toward their parents), and the even greater duties of husbands toward their wives. More fundamentally, he understood—something Luther did not—that nature could not actually be bad.What he held was that our good nature is in a bad condition, which is exactly correct. Nor, unlike some of his followers, did he hold that no good is left in us; what he held was that each good is injured. But the extremity of some of Calvin’s language, and his denial of free will, led some of his would-be heirs to different conclusions, thinking that we have altogether lost our nature and received in its place something else, a “sin nature”—an idea Calvin himself would have viewed as Manichaean.18 Present-day hostility to natural law among Protestants comes in several varieties, some of which are losing influence, but some of which are gaining.To speak just of the North American continent, the first branch—what is left of it—is rooted in the liberal Protestantism of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. In reaction to the Reformers’ suspicion of unredeemed reason, these liberals defended a certain understanding of reason, but a diminished understanding which set itself against revelation; the Catholic understanding of reason and revelation as complementary to each other was as foreign to its thought as it was to Luther’s. Having relativized Scripture, they have now gone on to relativize nature and reason as well, so that liberal Protestantism looks more and more like secular relativism with a Christian veneer.The second branch is a reaction to the reaction. In my country, its strongest representatives are neo-Calvinist.19 They draw from a strong intellectual tradition, but this tradition is primarily exegetical.Viewing itself as B. Doberstein, gen. ed. Helmut T. Lehmann (Philadelphia: Muhlenberg Press, 1959), 371–80, quoting from 376, emphasis added. 18 As Calvin wrote against the Manichees,“it is not admitted that there is any thing naturally bad throughout the universe; the depravity and wickedness whether of man or of the devil, and the sins thence resulting, being not from nature, but from the corruption of nature; nor, at first, did anything whatever exist that did not exhibit some manifestation of the divine wisdom and justice.” John Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion, Book 1, Chapter 14, Section 3, trans. Henry Beveridge (public domain; online version at www.ccel.org). 19 Foundational to this school of thought is the work of the Dutch Reformed thinker Abraham Kuyper. See especially “Calvinism and Politics,” one of the 718 J. Budziszewski rooted in Scripture rather than in autonomous reason, which it regards as the wisdom of men in opposition to “the foolishness of God,”20 it is deeply suspicious of philosophical articulations of natural law. The third branch, I am tempted to say, is a reaction to this reaction to the reaction. Surprisingly, its sources lie largely in the Anabaptist world, small in numbers but growing in influence. Suspicious not only of philosophy but even of systematic theology, neo-Anabaptists—I will call them that—emphasize the necessity of maintaining the purity and integrity of the Church against the powers and principalities of the world, recalling St. Paul’s affirmation that “our commonwealth is in heaven.”21 In their view these powers and principalities include not only human authorities, but even the dynamisms implanted in Creation itself, so irredeemably damaged by the Fall that they are actually hostile to man.22 Although both neo-Calvinists and neo-Anabaptists are suspicious of natural law (though for different reasons), neo-Calvinism has a certain conflicted attraction to the doctrine. One might go so far as to say that while pushing it out through the front door, neo-Calvinism invites it in again through various back doors, such as the idea of “common” or “preserving” grace, which sustains the structures of Creation even in the face of sin. Both Lutheran and Reformed historians have lately rediscovered the natural law theologies of such thinkers as Vermigli, Althusius, and Turretin.23 In the meantime, interest in natural law has grown strongly among Evangelicals,24 despite their biblicist leanings, because as biblical literacy vanishes among the Stone Foundation Lectures that Kuyper delivered at Princeton University in 1898. All six lectures are available at www.kuyper.org. For discussion, see J. Budziszewski, Evangelicals in the Public Square (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2006), 55–72. 20 1 Cor 1:25. 21 Phil 3:20. All scriptural quotations are from the RSV. 22 Illustrative of this tendency is the thought of the Mennonite theologian John Howard Yoder, whose influence on American Protestants has been strong but mostly indirect. For critical discussion of his views of natural law, focusing on his book The Politics of Jesus:Vicit Agnus Noster, 2d ed. (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1994), see J. Budziszewski, Evangelicals in the Public Square, 87–119. 23 See, e.g., A Preserving Grace: Protestants, Catholics, and Natural Law, ed. Michael Cromartie (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1997) and Stephen J. Grabill, Rediscovering the Natural Law in Reformed Theological Ethics (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2006). 24 In the U.S., the expression “Evangelical” has different connotations than in Europe, having to do with the movement and culture—today the largest among American Protestants—which descends from the Great Awakenings and preserves some of its revivalistic characteristics. Evangelical historian Mark A. Noll observes that the Evangelical style of communication is “direct,”“personal,” and “popular,” Diplomacy and Theology 719 citizens, there no longer seems to be a common language in which Christians can address non-believers.25 To capitalize on these openings, I wish the Statement had said more about what it means for nature to serve as a norm in the face of the Fall. Natural law theorists do not imagine that nature is not fallen, but they seek to view the Fall in right perspective.We have not ceased to be human and become something else; we have not lost our nature and acquired a wicked nature, as though there could be such a thing as an evil substance; but our nature is disordered. Even though it preserves the same intelligibility, our vision of it is obscured and our power to follow it impaired; we are at odds with ourselves. As Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger once remarked in an interview, “[C]reation has been damaged. Human existence is no longer what was produced at the hands of the Creator. It is burdened with another element that produces, besides the innate tendency toward God, the opposite tendency away from God. In this way man is torn between the original impulse of creation and his own historical inheritance.”26 Such is the Church’s teaching. But let us be frank: Don’t some statements by officials of the Church seem to run from it? If Protestants sometimes dwell on the Fall so obsessively that natural law is obscured, don’t Catholics at times seem afraid to speak of it at all, and isn’t this a diplomatic failing too? The deposit of faith is all one piece; the schism of 1517 did not divide the Christian patrimony; yet one of its tragic consequences is that both sides sometimes speak as though it did. According to some Protestants, the doctrine of the Fall belongs to them. According to some Catholics (though not the Church herself), they can have it. I do not think the authors of the Statement are running from the doctrine of the Fall, but I wish they had said more about it. One more point about Protestants—at any rate conservative Protestants.Although they accommodate themselves to the secular world much more than they realize, they dreadfully fear a religious syncretism which would sell the Christian birthright for a mess of pottage, obscuring the Gospel merely to win agreement to glib platitudes, like the dictum of the Parliament of the World’s Religions in 1993 that “[e]very human being depending more than anything else on a speaker’s “ability to draw a crowd.” It attempts to “simplify the essentials of religion in a way that gives them the widest possible mass appeal.” The result is that Evangelicals are “intuitionist,” trusting their “sanctified common sense,” but mistrusting the work of the intellect. Noll offers these observations in the context of an internal critique in The Scandal of the Evangelical Mind (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1995). 25 For discussion, see J. Budziszewski, Evangelicals in the Public Square, 15–37, 119–21. 26 Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, God and the World: A Conversation with Peter Seewald (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2002), 51. J. Budziszewski 720 must be treated humanely.” It must be conceded that the Statement’s discussion of other religions and wisdom traditions does little to calm this fear. Its authors do recognize the danger. For example, though guardedly remarking that projects like the Parliament are “worthy of interest,” they warn,“But can the purely inductive search, on the parliamentary model, of a minimal already existing consent, satisfy the requirements to base law on what is absolute? Further, does such a minimal ethic not perhaps lead to the relativization of the strong ethical needs of every particular religion or wisdom tradition?”27 But there is a problem even here. The first of the sentences just quoted is profoundly important, because natural law is not universal in the sense of being a least common denominator.To put it another way, there are two universals, not one. Although the law is written everywhere on the heart of man, it is everywhere entangled with the evasions and subterfuges of men.Yet there is something odd about the second sentence. If the natural law doctrine is correct, then people of different religions and traditions do not have authentically different “ethical needs”; as human beings they have the same ethical needs, albeit differently interpreted by their traditions. Of course differences of interpretation must be respected. Even so, some interpretations must be more adequate than others, for if not, then why bother to have a dialogue? Strangely, then, the language of the Statement seems to make room for ethical relativism even while criticizing ethical “relativization.” I am sure this was not the intention of the authors, but many Protestants who share its concern about relativism will find such language unsettling. One must not be ungenerous, for the authors of the Statement were threading the eye of a needle.They had to be open enough to other traditions to encourage a genuine conversation in which each could hear all the others, yet not so open as to plaster over divisions and forget what they had to say. It is so hard to strike the right balance. The very attempt to avoid offense in one quarter may give offense in another. Even so, if the diplomacy of natural law is so much more difficult than the authors of the Statement seem to realize even as regards Protestants, who are “separated brethren,” then how much more difficult will it be among the adherents to other religions and wisdom traditions? Consider just the response to the Holy Father’s lecture in Regensburg,28 in which Islamic mobs in various parts of the world turned to violence to prove that their religion was 27 Statement, §6. 28 Benedict XVI, “Faith, Reason and the University: Memories and Reflections.” Papal Address to representatives of science at University of Regensburg, Regensburg, Germany, 12 September 2006. Diplomacy and Theology 721 not violent, this despite the fact that Pope Benedict had studiously avoided saying that it was. VI. Secularism and Freedom I can imagine someone wondering why modern Western secularism is not included in the survey of wisdom traditions. Certainly its intellectual program has been running for quite a while, and one would find it difficult to deny that at least in its very early phases it constituted a seriously reasoned inquiry into the truth about man. Yet the Statement is right to leave secularism off the list, for secularism is no longer is what it was.Today it is less like a wisdom tradition than an assault on the possibility of wisdom. During the course of several centuries,Western reason finally became so convinced of its doubts that it clipped its own wings, binding itself with fierce oaths not even to think about flying. It tends to deny that there is a truth about man, or at least that such a truth could be discovered.The Statement does not ignore it; far from it. But instead of including it in the survey of wisdom traditions it discusses it in other places—as a series of misadventures, such as voluntarism, which pushed the early modern doctrine of natural law in the wrong direction; as a series of confusions, such as moral relativism and legal positivism, which obscure clear thought today; and as the cause of the crisis which makes the search for a universal ethics so crucial today. Not that the Church has no interest in talking with secularists, and not that she just wants to scold. On the contrary, the Statement takes secularist confusions about natural law with the greatest seriousness, especially the mistaken view that freedom competes with the immanent law of our nature and with the transcendent God in whom this law finds its source. The true nature of freedom receives more intense and sustained attention in the Statement than any other theme in the doctrine of natural law. While admitting that the commands of God are authoritative, the Statement is careful to avoid voluntarism, the view that He is an arbitrary tyrant whose commands are right “just because He says so.”What voluntarism overlooks is that the will and power of God are united with His goodness and wisdom. But the problem of arbitrariness has another face too; showing that God’s commands are wise and good is not enough. Even wise and good commands, if they were merely imposed from outside, would seem to deprive us of our freedom. This is the problem Kant called heteronomy. Its solution is not what he called autonomy, which makes God and nature irrelevant, but participated theonomy.29 29 Statement, §63, quoting John Paul II, Encyclical Veritatis Splendor, §41. 722 J. Budziszewski God does not rule by jerking us around, but by drawing us as participants into His own Providence.The way this works is that when we follow the natural law by employing our powers of reason, we fulfill the inbuilt potentialities of our own created nature more and more.30 Rather than seeing the sovereignty of God, and the dignity and freedom of man, as enemies, this way of thinking unites them. Man cannot displace God, because he cannot reinvent his humanity.We already have a nature; we already are as He created us. But God is not a tyrant, because our freedom lies in becoming more fully what we are, and in order to humanize ourselves, we must cooperate with the divine creative act, the fiat by which God made us in His image. I don’t disagree with the teaching that I have just paraphrased; I do think the Statement could have explained it more clearly.The problem is not theological but diplomatic. It lies in the placement of the accent. Rather than giving equal emphasis to divine authority and human freedom, the Statement lays its stress on human freedom. If I were trying to make a case for this difference in emphasis, I might argue as follows. Those whom the Church would like to draw into dialogue include, among others, both secularists and members of other monotheistic traditions. All too many in both categories see the sovereignty of God as contradicting the liberty of man. Those in the former category need to be reassured about freedom, because they see divine authority as endangering it. Those in the latter category need to be taught about freedom, because they see it as a challenge to divine prerogatives. The point this hypothetical argument misses is that the former group cannot be reassured about freedom unless they are also taught about authority, and the latter cannot be taught about freedom unless they are also reassured about authority. So greatly does the discussion of freedom emphasize immanence that it comes close to obscuring transcendence; so greatly does it stress human freedom that some readers, both secularist and religious, may be left wondering what God has to do with the matter at all—in what sense His commands are really commands. To be sure, even in the discussion of freedom, the note of transcendence is not lost, and it rings more sonorously later in the Statement. But shouldn’t it be more resonant in this part too? Isn’t there something to be said just for the trembling gladness of crying to God, “Command me”? Does it make us voluntarists to obey Him, not “just because He says so,” but just because He is the good and glorious God? To put it another way, doesn’t it also belong to the law within ourselves that we are most ourselves when 30 The natural law is “nothing else than the rational creature’s participation in the eternal law.”Thomas Aquinas, ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2. Diplomacy and Theology 723 we get out of ourselves, when we forget ourselves in Him? He is greater than we are; it is not as though when He poured good into creatures, He somehow drained Himself of uncreated Good. Our freedom and glory are to look up.We were made to sing with the hosts of heaven, “Worthy art thou, our Lord and God, to receive glory and honor and power.”31 In another sense, the Statement doesn’t say enough about human freedom. I said a few paragraphs above that we cannot displace the Creator because we cannot reinvent our humanity. But the transhumanist asks: Why can’t we? With help from nanotechnology, biotechnology, and the cognitive and information sciences, why can’t we provide ourselves with an improved human nature, not this old paleolithic hand-me-down, but one we make for ourselves?32 The authors are at least partly aware of the danger, remarking that “rapid developments in biotechnology,” such as “genetic manipulation and cloning, “threaten the very identity of the human being,” requiring an “ethical and political reflection of universal breadth.” In the same vein, they warn against “accept[ing] as legitimate everything that is doable in the sphere of biotechnology,” and insist that “the legislator cannot give up the distinction between what is human and what are extrinsic and superficial criteria.”33 But the problem is greater than not knowing where to say “No” to biotechnological innovations. We face a ramifying transhumanist ideology driven by a strange combination of industrial competition, military planning, scientific hubris, and eschatological dreams. As in the days of Babylon on the plain of Shinar, men have begun to murmur among themselves, “Come, let us build ourselves a city, and a tower with its top in the heavens, and let us make a name for ourselves.”34 One version of the dream envisions adjusting people to their particular lots in life in order to “enhance” their performance and satisfaction. We could have soldiers who don’t need to sleep, file clerks who never get bored, laborers who never go on strike, miners who prefer the heat and dark, abortionists who don’t have bad dreams. Perhaps it is not difficult to see that such manipulations would not enhance but diminish us.Then again, some people do find the point difficult.Why should anyone have to be a square peg in a 31 Rv 4:11a. 32 Such dreams are no longer limited to the readers and writers of science fiction: See for example Mihail C. Roco and William Sims Bainbridge, eds., “Converging Technologies for Improving Human Performance: Nanotechnology, Biotechnology, Information Technology and Cognitive Science” (National Science Foundation and U.S. Department of Commerce, June 2002), also called the NBIC Report.This document is readily available on the internet. 33 Statement, §§1, 7. 34 Gn 11:4. J. Budziszewski 724 round hole? I wish the Statement had taken more time to explain what ought to be obvious but isn’t. Better to make the hole square. Better even to be a square peg in a round hole, than to have all our corners cut off. Another version of the dream is more difficult to answer. In this version, which is more egalitarian, everyone is re-engineered the same way (except perhaps the engineers), so that life is more to our liking. Everyone could be smarter. Everyone could be stronger. Everyone could be more musical. And why stop there? Everyone could live forever, even if this meant putting an end to children, a point Europe has almost reached anyway. No one need ever become depressed, even if he had something to be depressed about. No one need ever suffer pangs of conscience, no matter what he had done. No one need ever go mad from not knowing the meaning of his life, for our minds could be readjusted so we thought we knew already, or just didn’t need to know.War would come to an end, because nations would peacefully submit to whatever their programmers decided to have them submit to. My language may seem tendentious, and I admit that I am painting the portrait of the Next Man in the hues of the Last Man. But has the Next Man ever been more than a mask for the desires of the Last? The authors of the Statement know about transhumanist dreams but seem to view them solely from the angle of the misconception that freedom and nature are opposed.35 Surely the authors are right that this misconception has deep historical roots and has not yet run its course. Indeed hostility to nature has entered a vicious and virulent phase.36 Even so, I wonder whether the ITC, like armies everywhere, is preparing to fight the last war all over again. The next one will not be the same. Having opposed nature for all these generations, we moderns or postmoderns have at last become so confused about what a nature is that we have actually come to think that we can make one. VII. Transhumanists and Freedom I think a transhumanist challenged by the Church would carry the ball to his opponent’s territory. I imagine him arguing like this: You say freedom lies not in denying but in following our nature—in humanizing ourselves, becoming more what we are, fulfilling our inbuilt potentialities, our 35 Statement, esp. §71. 36 See for instance Warren M. Hern, M.D., “Is Pregnancy Really Normal?” Family Planning Perspectives 3:1 ( January 1971), wherein the author argues that pregnancy “may be defined as an illness” which “may be treated by evacuation of the uterine contents.” Diplomacy and Theology 725 “immanent intelligibility.” 37 Very well, I concede—so it does! But what you call a human being is just a sophisticated mechanism; what you call its nature is its operating system; what you call its subjectivity or consciousness is its executive function; what you call its immanent intelligibility is the objectives built into its program; and what you call desires are their internal representations. Fulfilling our immanent intelligibility can therefore mean nothing more than becoming more successful in attaining what our programming leads us most strongly and persistently to desire. What then is our longest and strongest desire? Preeminently, the increase of our power, or the power of our descendants, with whom we are programmed to identify. If so, then to act on this desire simply is to act freely, simply is to follow nature, simply is to humanize ourselves. Suppose the greatest step we could take to increase the power of our descendants were to make them something different than we are—to free them from human limitations. You might say that by taking such a step, we would not humanize ourselves but only abolish humanity.38 Say rather that in this case, the highest expression of our freedom is also its terminal expression—that abolishing humanity is the most humanizing act we can perform. What parent would not sacrifice himself for his children? You might also object that even if we expressed our own freedom by reinventing humanity, we would destroy the freedom of our descendants—we would be turning them into artifacts, treating them as things. Perhaps you imagine them complaining that they didn’t ask to be transhuman! But I notice that you don’t level the same accusation against the Creator, for after all, we didn’t didn’t ask to be human. Well, our descendants haven’t asked to be human either. Why should we force them to be? You say that created nature isn’t a limitation on our freedom, but the divine gift that makes it possible. So be it! Then we will be as gods to them—dying gods, burdened with our sins—and their reinvented nature will be the gift from us that makes their freedom possible. There are no two ways about it. If our freedom is following our nature, then their freedom is following theirs.To go with their new nature, they will simply have a new freedom. And wouldn’t it be a lot more fun? Dialogue with transhumanists—and make no mistake, there will have to be dialogue with transhumanists—will require considerably more equipment than the Statement provides, and will require it at several different levels. At the level of discursive reason, the metaphysics lesson must be prolonged. The differences between substances and mechanisms, between natures and programs, between the immanent intelligibility of our nature and what we strongly want, these things and others must be made more 37 Statement, §23. 38 Alluding to C. S. Lewis, The Abolition of Man: or Reflections on Education with Special Reference to the Teaching of English in the Upper Forms of Schools (New York: Macmillan, 1947). 726 J. Budziszewski clear, or the dialogue will go nowhere.The whole ontology of modernity must be called into question, a stupendously formidable task.At the level of simple insight, the power of the mind by which it sees what it understands, the matters we are discoursing about must be brought closer to the eye, made accessible to intuition. One thing that needs to be “seen” before it can be understood is the sheer horror of the transhumanist ambition. The danger is not that proponents of this ideology could achieve what they desire, but that they might do great damage by trying.An even more important thing to be “seen,” or at least glimpsed, is divine transcendence. If we think that just because secular people are afraid of God, they must have no longing to see Him, we are mistaken. Under every disguise, that desire remains real and powerful, and must be offered the hope of satisfaction. VIII. Politics The Statement devotes an entire chapter to the implications of natural law for policy and statecraft.The chapter contains much good. I am especially glad to see its insistence that the common good is real and not just an aggregate of private goods.Yet in other ways, the chapter underwhelms. At a pivotal point in its exposition, the Statement declares that the common good which society should pursue has four contours. “[T]hese are: freedom, truth, justice, and solidarity.These four values correspond to the requirements of an ethical order in conformity with the natural law.” As a political and ethical theorist I must confess that such language makes me cringe, not in the least because I disagree, for I don’t.The problem is that the expressions look suspiciously like platitudes.The Church knows quite well that no profit will be made from clichés. I mentioned earlier that the Statement is critical of the minimalist, least-common-denominator approach to dialogue which leads to ponderous platitudes like the principle of the Parliament of the World’s Religions in 1993 that “Every human being must be treated humanely.”Yet at points like this, it gives the strong appearance of following a similar approach. The problem is not just that the language of freedom, truth, justice, and solidarity is so vague, but that its vagueness makes it so perilously easy to hijack. Secular precedents are innumerable. I cannot help but think of the unholy trinity of values in contemporary secular bioethics, “autonomy, beneficence, and justice,” where all too often autonomy means that the patient may kill himself, beneficence means that his caretakers may kill him when doing so is judged to be “in the best interests of all concerned,” and justice means that John Rawls would approve. The Church’s invocations of freedom, truth, justice, and solidarity are saved from platitudiny, if I may coin a word, by the fact that an immense Diplomacy and Theology 727 depth of discussion lies behind each one, a deep, murmuring background of thought and commentary. One who expects definitions to be provided on the spot will usually be disappointed. Instead they are meant to serve as placeholders for that vaster literature which is tucked away almost out of sight.This fact excuses a great deal of writing which would otherwise seem to mean nothing. In fact it means a great deal. On the other hand, it cannot be said to make the doctrine of the Church clear to outsiders, a diplomatic essential which I think she may underrate. Considering each of these four bland expressions in turn, let us grade the risk of hijacking. “Justice”—here the risk of hijack is very great, because liberal theories of justice have almost completely obscured the classical insights to which the natural law tradition is committed, and the Statement says far too little about these errors. “Solidarity”—the intention of this term is to warn us against selfish individualism and remind us that each bears responsibility for the common good. However, the Statement provides too little armament to guard against authoritarian and collectivist distortions of the idea. Nor can it be protected merely by invoking other generalities such as “human dignity” or “subsidiarity,” because if not fully explained, these too can be hijacked. All claim to believe in human dignity; they cannot all be right. The principle of subsidiarity, one of the most profound contributions of Catholic social doctrine, declares that the purpose of larger, stronger, more extensive forms of association such as states and transnational organizations is not to destroy or absorb smaller, weaker, more local forms of association, but to help them. Yet in the administrative state, subsidiarity is commonly invoked precisely to justify shoving smaller associations aside.“We are not destroying or absorbing them, we are helping them,” say the bureaucrats, as they take over their functions and deprive them of anything to do. What about the other two expressions? “Truth”—one might think that here the risk is small, because the secular world is less concerned to capture the term “truth” than to deny that truth exists.The premise is true but the conclusion does not follow. “Freedom”—here the risk is diminished by the Statement’s vigorous effort to restate what freedom means; as I have explained, the thrust of its efforts is to rescue the term from its previous hijackers and restore it to its proper meaning. Grave danger persists, however, and not just for the reasons already discussed. Let me explain. Every view of freedom is some view of freedom—some view of what it is for, in what it consists, and what political and moral conditions it requires. To safeguard freedom one must have true answers to these questions. But this means that in order to exercise freedom, one must 728 J. Budziszewski already be confident about at least part of the truth, even if one is still in search of the rest. Freedom and truth are intimately joined. The authors of the Statement know all this. Unfortunately, they fail to develop the political implications of denying it. This is a serious flaw, because contemporary secular polities do deny it. It seems to them that the only thing reason can tell us with confidence is that nothing else can be known with confidence. If secularists reasoned coherently, then at this point they would simply abandon the ideal of freedom; surely, if the faculty of reason is too weak to find out what freedom is, then the idea of freedom is incoherent.That is not what happens. Instead, diminished reason is set to work inventing rationalizations for the indulgence of whatever passions and appetites men happen to have, and “freedom”—redefined—is one of these rationalizations. Notice, though, that in order to ground the polity on this sort of “freedom,” it is not enough to be agnostic and say “We do not know the truth.” One must be antinoetic, one must say “We cannot know the truth,” and one way or another, this must become a public creed. The details are unimportant. Perhaps we will say that public policy must be “ethically neutral”; perhaps we will say that legitimate, nonauthoritarian dialogue requires “bracketing” the claims of conscience; perhaps we will say that the state must be “political, not metaphysical.” Such notions never mean that the state has no metaphysical commitments.What they mean is that it has ardent metaphysical commitments, but they are all negative:Any conception of reality which proposes that truth can be discovered must be viewed as an enemy. In such a world, the Church itself is held in deep suspicion, just because she does make this proposal. Never mind that she believes in freedom; the freedom she proposes is a deeper freedom than secularists desire, and threatens the foundations of their polity. Nor is only the Church held in suspicion. Psychological training for secularist citizenship must begin in childhood; consequently, even the institution of the family comes to be viewed as illiberal and dangerous. Parents inevitably teach their children what they believe, but this forms children in such a way that they may not be sufficiently antinoetic when they grow up. A point in defense of the Church’s readiness to use overgeneral expressions is her view of how the human mind comes to know things. As I hinted earlier, not only in her thought, but also in her mode of expression, she relies not just on discursive, logical reasoning, on abstraction and inference, ratio, but also on purely receptive, intuitive understanding,“that simple vision to which truth offers itself like a landscape to the eye,”39 intellectus. Discursive reasoning is the way of knowing most characteristic 39 Josef Pieper, Leisure: The Basis of Culture, trans. Alexander Dru (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2009, orig. 1952), 28. Diplomacy and Theology 729 of human beings. Direct vision is more properly angelic; today the secular world does not even believe in it.Yet in reality, the two processes interpenetrate and depend on each other, for mind does not live on definitions alone. So, when the Church directs man’s attention to “human dignity” or asks him to look into his “conscience,” she views herself as pointing to realities into which anyone may see at least partly, if only he is willing to look. Indeed, the fact that human beings have some small share in pure receptive insight is the only reason we can improve a definition, for in the end, each definition refers to a real thing, seen by the mind as the eye sees the object of sight. For the same reason, even if the thing is not seen in clear focus, nevertheless we can talk about it. Each eye can compare what it seems to see with statements from all the other eyes in play. This is a lofty hope but a right one, and the diplomacy of the Church depends on it. It is also a chancy one, inasmuch as it depends on pure eyes among all those who join in the seeing, and our age is not known for purity. “When your eye is sound, your whole body is full of light; but when it is not sound, your body is full of darkness.”40 One more point needs to be made about the Church’s engagement with the world of politics. Governments must often base policy on the advice of scientific experts. In order to protect the environment, for example, one must know what is happening to it. Is the global atmosphere actually warming? If so, is such warming a cyclical event or a long-term trend? Is it influenced by human activity, and can anything be done about it? In the meantime, whatever may be happening to the climate of the earth, the climate of debate passes through swings of its own; we tend to forget that a scant two generations ago, the great concern among scientists was global cooling. Although the Church speaks with authority about morals and doctrine, she knows she has no special competence in science. In the popular view, she is antiscientific. On the contrary, all too often Church officials jump on the latest scientific bandwagon just because the scientists whom she consults have jumped onboard already. At various times she has been assured by penologists that prisons rehabilitate, by psychologists that sexual abusers who have undergone therapy can be safely returned to active ministry, by biologists that the hypothesis of natural selection explains macroevolution, by political scientists that simple transfer of wealth to the governments of poor nations will make poor nations richer, and by economists that forgiveness of debt on a huge scale would not cause moral hazard. Each of these matters is at least open to question, but the Church 40 Luke 11:34. 730 J. Budziszewski too quickly accepts the confident pledges of her expert advisors that they are beyond debate. A case in point:The Statement goes beyond calling for the protection of the environment. It takes planetary warming so much for granted as to cite it as one of the reasons for the search for a universal ethics: “The good of the species appears as one of the fundamental aspirations present in the person. We are particularly conscious of it in our time, when certain perspectives such as global warming revive our sense of responsibility for the planet as well as for the human species in particular.”41 This incautious endorsement of the global warming scenario was composed before the explosion of the “Climategate” scandal at the Climatic Research Unit of the University of East Anglia, England, in which the content of leaked email messages gave strong reason to believe that researchers at the CRU had colluded to manipulate data, interfere with the peer review process, and punish outside scientists who dissented from their conclusions.Though official investigators drew milder conclusions, even they criticized the University for a “culture of withholding information.”42 In the meantime it has become clear that the much-vaunted “consensus” of the scientific community concerning the warming of the planet is more like a powerful but contested opinion. What actually happened at the CRU may take years to sort out, but the event is a salutary reminder that communities of experts are much like little polities, with their own gatekeepers, their own ways of withholding and distributing resources, their own publicity machines, their own ways of policing consensus, and their own ways of punishing dissent.This is especially true in fields like climatology, where the data are messy, the modelling methods highly sensitive to minute changes in assumptions, emotions run high, and the distinction between scientific theory and political ideology is easily blurred. Scientists themselves—except when they hold minority opinions—are often remarkably oblivious to the possibility of bias and runaway groupthink, viewing their disciplines as immune to the foibles of the world, perfectly in harmony with the ideal of rational inquiry. 41 Statement, §49. In §1, the Statement more obscurely includes “the climate” among the “pressing concerns, which call upon all humanity and whose solution goes quite beyond national boundaries.” Insofar as this is listed in addition to “ecological equilibrium,” “protection of the environment,” and “natural resources,” it is probably another endorsement of the hypothesis of worldwide climate change, but in this case the intention is less clear. 42 James Randerson, “Climate Researchers ‘Secrecy’ Criticised—But MPs Say Science Remains Intact: Leaked Emails from UK’s Climate Research Unit Show Scientists Withheld Information—But Inquiry Blames University.” The Guardian, 31 March 2010, retrieved 29 July 2010. Diplomacy and Theology 731 The members of the Church do well to remember that just as there are fads, prejudices, and irrational convictions in the nonscientific world, so there are in science. “[I]n the course of history,” the ITS remarks, “Christian theology has too easily justified with the natural law anthropological positions which, consequently, have appeared conditioned by their historical and cultural context.”43 Just so, but the error is not confined to anthropology. IX. Praeambula amicitiae cum natura Natural law cannot be properly appreciated except in the context of salvation history. The authors get this capital point exactly right when they remark that although the pagans were already aware of natural law, from the moment it was taken up by the Fathers it was “apprehended in the environment of a history of salvation that leads one to distinguish different states of nature (original nature, fallen nature, restored nature), in which natural law is realized in different manners.”44 Thus natural law must be viewed from three perspectives: Creation, Fall, and Redemption. On Creation depends the inner coherence of the natural order, including the nature of man. It is “the act by which God structures the whole universe, giving it a law”45—not just bringing it into existence, but making it reflect His wisdom. From the Fall comes man’s difficulty in recognizing the work of Creation, for he “has removed himself from the source of wisdom.Thus acting, he has falsified the knowledge that he was able to have of the objective order of things, even on the natural level. Men, knowing that their works are bad, hate the light and elaborate false theories to justify their sins. Thus the image of God in man has been gravely obscured. Although their nature still refers them to a fulfillment in God beyond themselves (the creature cannot pervert itself to the point of not recognizing any longer the testimonies that the Creator offers of himself in the creation), in fact men are so gravely harmed by sin that they do not recognize the profound meaning of the world and interpret it in terms of pleasure, money or power.”46 By Redemption our nature is restored, and this in two ways. In the first place, “Jesus Christ manifests in his own person . . . an exemplary human life, fully conforming to the natural law. For that reason he is the ultimate criterion for correctly deciphering the authentic natural desires of man 43 Statement, §10. 44 Statement, §26. 45 Statement, §22. 46 Statement, §104. 732 J. Budziszewski when they are not concealed by distortions introduced by sin and disordered passions.”47 In the second place, the Holy Spirit becomes for us the principle of life, freeing us from the power of sin, so that we begin to have not only the desire for good, but the ability to do it.Thus the New Law “gives man the effective capability of overcoming egoism by fully actualizing the humanizing demands of the natural law.”48 In the third place, the Holy Spirit reveals that we are ordained to a supernatural end, an end that does not destroy our natural powers but exceeds them. Man is “called by God to a destiny that transcends the finality of physical nature.”49 All this the Statement explains clearly and beautifully. One might only wish that it had explained more fully how it all bears on the prospects and conduct of dialogue about natural law with nonbelievers. Isn’t a certain change required in the angle of vision? Traditionally the Church has viewed the doctrine of natural law as one of the praeambula fidei,“preambles” of faith, and certainly it is. But if it is true that the natural law can be clearly viewed only in the light of salvation history, then shouldn’t we also call faith one of the praeambula amicitiae cum natura,“preambles” of friendship with nature? Declarations about natural law address themselves to “men of good will,” but the gospel came to us “while we were yet sinners.”50 These two addresses must cooperate. I should not wish to be misunderstood, for I am far from suggesting that faith is a preamble and the natural law is not. What I am suggesting is that the relationship between the two preambles is, so to speak, dialectical.They co-illuminate each other; each becomes more clear when they are seen together. Nor am I suggesting that dialogue about natural law is futile before all of our dialogue partners have been converted; what I am suggesting is that the dialogue is unlikely to achieve its ends unless we are explicit not only about our philosophy but also about our theology. How does failure to appreciate the difference among the created, fallen, and redeemed states of nature impede dialogue? By way of analogy, suppose everyone was born with broken hands, and no one had ever seen an unhurt hand. Hands would still have the purposes given to them by the order of creation, but because the use of the hands to grasp, to gesture, to caress would cause pain, it would be difficult for anatomists to recognize these purposes. Some might even deny that hands do have purposes.Though some of our powers are more broken than others, our 47 Ibid. 48 Statement, §102. 49 Statement, §66. 50 Rom 5:8. Diplomacy and Theology 733 case is much the same. If I ask my students the purpose of the respiratory powers, they answer without hesitation, “To take in oxygen”; of the ingestive powers, “To nourish us”; of the visual powers, “To show us the physical world.” But if I ask them the purpose of the sexual powers, they become confused. By far the greatest number reply, “To give pleasure,” ignoring the fact that the exercise of every voluntary power is pleasurable, and if the production of pleasure were the criterion of function, then the purpose of breathing, eating, and seeing would be pleasure too. The immanent intelligibility of sex is so obscured by concupiscence that we imagine concupiscence to be its intelligibility. Another result of the failure to distinguish the three states of nature is despair.The Statement rightly declares:51 The search for a common ethical language is inseparable from a hope of conversion, with which individuals and the community detach themselves from the forces that seek to imprison the human being in indifference or drive him to raise walls against others or against foreigners. The heart of stone—cold, inert and indifferent to the lot of one’s neighbour or of the human race—must be transformed, under the action of the Spirit, into a heart of flesh, sensible to the calls of wisdom, to compassion, to the desire for peace and to hope for all.This conversion is the condition for a true dialogue. But conversion requires grace, which we are helpless to supply to ourselves. Our helplessness in the face of the disorders of fallen nature, our inability to cure them by powers of our own, the chasm that divides us from ourselves, all these things stun and dismay an honest mind and heart. The hope of redemption gives us the confidence to be honest, to meet the eye of conscience steadily without flinching. If we know nothing of this hope, it is excruciatingly difficult to be honest. Whether by denying the natural law, or by pretending that we fulfill it, we avert our gaze. The final result of failure to view nature in the light of salvation is that when the Godward impulse is denied, it turns elsewhere; when Christian eschatology is denied, rather than evaporating, it spills. The Church has had long experience with diverted spiritual longings and spilled eschatology. Some are mentioned in the Statement, such as the ideology by which the State “raise[s] itself as the bearer of ultimate meaning.” But newer and stranger manifestations are even now appearing on the horizon. Perhaps the most bizarre example is the argument of Tulane University physicist Frank J.Tipler that through the advance of science, intelligent species will 51 Statement, §4. 734 J. Budziszewski literally evolve into God.52 The idea that dependent being could turn into absolute Being is so muddled that one hardly knows how to argue with it, yet arguments of this sort are taken seriously by serious people. In a dialogue about natural law, the introduction of salvation history might seem to be an impudence. Shouldn’t it be left alone? As I read them, the authors of the Statement hold a different view. They insist on introducing salvation history, and I think they are right. It might be objected that in the context of natural law, such matters cannot be raised at all. After all, don’t they lie beyond the province of natural reason? Yes, but that does not get us off the hook. Perhaps a contrast will be helpful. One of the things embedded in human nature is the love of self; another is the impulse toward transcendence, like a ghostly preparation for the spiritual virtue of hope.Those who do not know what they truly are by nature cannot love themselves properly, but at least the knowledge of what they are by nature is accessible apart from revelation.Those who do not know what the object of transcendence is cannot hope properly either, but alas, that knowledge is not accessible apart from revelation.The unfulfilled longing for such knowledge drives otherwise reasonable people either to despair or to false objects of transcendence, bewitching sirens, luring them to destruction.What is to be done? The paradox is that not all of the questions that vex dialogue about natural law are contained within natural law. On the one hand the reality of natural law can be grasped by every person of good will; on the other hand, its contours will seem cloudy apart from the light of grace, and the stirrings it awakens may madden us.About problems like this, we scarcely yet know what to do. X. Conclusion As I close this response to the “The Search for Universal Ethics,” I am painfully aware that although I have tried to address not only the philoso52 In several books, beginning with The Physics of Immortality (New York: Double- day, 1994), Professor Tipler tries to prove that the laws of physics require the existence of God and the resurrection of the dead. What he means by these terms, however, is not what they mean in the Creed. He expects intelligent species to develop their scientific abilities at an exponentially increasing rate of growth, until eventually they evolve an unlimited intelligence which uses all of the resources of the universe. He identifies this intelligence with God. Because its computational speed will increase faster than the universe can collapse, in “experiential” terms its life will have infinite duration.This deathless intelligence would run simulations of every intelligent being that has ever existed. Consequently, all the dead will all live again forever in virtual reality, which will be indistinguishable from ordinary reality.Tipler considers the argument a confirmation of Christianity, a supposition about which, perhaps, nothing more need be said. Diplomacy and Theology 735 phy and theology of the document, but also its diplomacy, my own diplomacy is maladroit. If, while trying to dance, I have succeeded only in bruising toes, I hope that my clumsiness will be pardoned.The more I study the Statement, the more impressive it seems to me.Yet when I try to approach it as an outsider might, I cannot help but feel that it should have been more attractive on the first reading, perhaps even on the second. The Church has immensely long experience in her diplomacy, and the authors of the Statement are far better dancers than I will ever be.Yet in the presentation of the doctrine of natural law, it seems to me that their adroitness too could be improved. Insofar as nature and grace are the two proper foundations of the Church’s entire approach to the world, perhaps the discussion of this difficulty is important enough to risk the appearN&V ance of an ingratitude which is far from my intention. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 737–762 737 St. Thomas, Natural Law, and Universal Ethics L AWRENCE D EWAN, O.P. Dominican University College Ottawa, Canada A RE there objective moral values capable of bringing people together and securing peace and happiness for them? What are they? How are they recognized? How are they realized in the life of individuals and of the community? These questions about good and evil, questions which always return, are today more urgent than ever, in as much as people are more aware of forming a single community in the world.1 The Holy Father, Benedict XVI, in an address to the International Theological Commission in October of 2007, spoke of the project of the ITC concerning natural law as “aimed above all to justify and describe the foundations of a universal ethics that is part of the great patrimony of human knowledge which in a certain way constitutes the rational creature’s participation in the eternal law of God.” In this respect he concluded: 1 This is from the Introduction to The Search for Universal Ethics: A New Look at Natural Law, a document published by the International Theological Commission [henceforth “ITC”], in the translation published on the Web page: www.pathsoflove.com by Joseph Bolin. (The Vatican web page presents the document in French and in Italian.) A preliminary note at the beginning of the footnotes tells us that the document was approved in December of 2008, and names the members of the subcommission that produced it. Let me say at the outset that I am very grateful to Joseph Bolin for having translated for us all this important document; here and there I find reason to substitute my own translation, but let that not indicate any lack of gratitude towards him. In this paper St. Thomas’s Summa theologiae will be indicated by “ST” (and where helpful I sometimes include the pagination from the edition published by the Collège Dominicain d’Ottawa, 1941); also, the reader will find considerable use of italics; in the main, this is my own responsibility. Thanks are due to Enrique Alarcon for making available the Opera omnia of St.Thomas online. 738 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. It is not, therefore, a theme of an exclusively or mainly denominational kind, although the doctrine on natural moral law is illuminated and developed to the full in the light of Christian revelation and the fulfillment of man in the mystery of Christ.2 Again, on January 15, 2010, Pope Benedict, speaking to the members of the Congregation on the Faith on the occasion of their plenary assembly, recalled their 2008 publication of Dignitas Personae on certain bioethical questions. He said: There are in fact specific contents of Christian revelation that cast light on bioethical problems: the value of human life, the relational and social dimension of the person, the connection between the unitive and the procreative aspects of sexuality, and the centrality of the family founded on the marriage of a man and a woman.These matters engraved in the human heart are also rationally understandable as an element of natural moral law and can be accepted also by those who do not identify with the Christian faith. The natural moral law is neither exclusively nor mainly confessional, even if the Christian Revelation and the fulfillment of Man in the mystery of Christ fully illumines and develops its doctrine. As the Catechism of the Catholic Church says, it “states the first and essential precepts which govern the moral life” (n. 1955). Established in human nature itself and accessible to every rational creature, the natural moral law thus determines the basis for initiating dialogue with all who seek the truth and, more generally, with civil and secular society. This law, engraved in every human being’s heart, touches on one of the essential problems of reflection on law and likewise challenges the conscience and responsibility of legislators.3 My contribution here is intended to underline certain features of natural law as presented by St. Thomas Aquinas, features that discourage any secularizing or Pelagian tendencies that the quest for “universality” might occasion. Still by way of introduction I wish to recall the treatment 2 Address of his holiness Benedict XVI to members of the International Theolog- ical Commission, Friday, 5 October 2007; to be found on the Vatican webpage. Italics are his. 3 Address of his holiness Benedict XVI to members of the Congregation on the Faith on the occasion of the Plenary Assembly, Friday, January 15, 2010 (from the Vatican webpage). In the last sentence quoted, the English word “law” as first used is given in the French as “loi” but in its second occurrence is given as “droit;” so also, in German, the first word is “Gesetz” and the second is “Rechtsauffassung.” The meaning of the English would be clearer, I would say, if in the second place it said: “(reflection on) what is just.” Natural Law and Universal Ethics 739 by St. Thomas of the case of the gentiles, referred to by St. Paul, who obeyed the law as written in their hearts: . . . [Paul] commends in them the observance of the law, when he says: “They naturally do what pertains to the law,” that is, what the law commands, viz. as regards the moral precepts, which are prescribed by natural reason, just as concerning Job4 it was said that he was just and upright and fearing God and distancing himself from what is bad. Hence, he himself said: “My feet have followed his tracks; I have kept to his pathways.” But that [Paul] says: “naturally” raises a question, for he seems to give support to the Pelagians, who said that man through his natural wherewithal could observe all the precepts of the law. Hence, one must explain: [1] “naturally”, i.e. through nature reformed by grace. For he is speaking of the gentiles converted to the Faith, who through the grace of Christ began to observe the moral [precepts] of the law. Or one can say: [2] “naturally”, i.e. through the natural law showing them what is to be done; in accordance with Psalm 4: “The many say: who shows us what are good? Signed etc.”; which is the natural light of reason in which there is the image of God; and nevertheless it is not excluded that grace is necessary to move the affections ; just as also through the law there is knowledge of sin, and yet grace is further required to move the affections.5 4 Job is presented in the book of Job as a foreigner, indeed as a member of a people detested by the Jews after the fall of Jerusalem. Cf. Le Livre de Job, traduit par le R. P. Larcher, O.P., a separate volume of La Sainte Bible, traduite en français sous la direction de l’École Biblique de Jérusalem (Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 1950), Introduction, 7–8:“Job est précisément un étranger. On le fait vivre en dehors de la Palestine, aux confins de l’Arabie et du pays d’Édom. Houz, sa patrie, est mis en relation avec Édom dans Gen. 36.28 et dans Lam., 4.21. . . . Non seulement Job est un étranger par rapport au peuple de l’Alliance, mais il appartient encore à une race qui se rendit odieuse aux Juifs lors de la chute de Jérusalem (cf. Ez., 35; Abd., 1; Ps., 137.7). S’il est présenté comme un serviteur modèle de Yahvé, on doit en conclure qu’une tradition vénérable et indiscutable l’avait imposé en Israël.” 5 St. Thomas, In Ad Romanos, chap. 2, lect. 3, re verse 14 (my italics): “[Paulus] commendat in eis legis observantiam, cum dicit: ‘Naturaliter faciunt quae sunt legis,’ id est, quae lex mandat, scilicet quantum ad praecepta moralia, quae sunt de dictamine rationis naturalis, sicut et de Job dicitur, quod erat iustus et rectus ac timens deum et recedens a malo. Unde ipse dicit: vestigia eius secutus est pes meus, vias eius custodivi. “Sed quod dicit ‘naturaliter,’ dubitationem habet. Videtur enim patrocinari Pelagianis, qui dicebant quod homo per sua naturalia poterat omnia praecepta legis servare. Unde exponendum est: ‘naturaliter,’ id est per naturam gratia reformatam. Loquitur enim de gentilibus ad fidem conversis, qui auxilio gratiae christi coeperant moralia legis servare.Vel potest dici:‘naturaliter,’ id est per legem naturalem ostendentem eis quid sit agendum, secundum illud Ps. IV, 7 s.:‘Multi dicunt: quis ostendit nobis bona? signatum, etc.,’ quod est lumen rationis naturalis, in qua 740 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. Our topic, then, is universal ethics: how appropriate is the use of the doctrine of natural law in the quest for such a universal ethics? Would it be better to speak simply about “nature” and “reason” in ethics, leaving aside the “law” dimension? I would say that it would be inadequate from the viewpoint of reason itself. The punishment in another life is very important for morals.6 We see this well in the presentation of natural law in Cicero’s De re publica 3.7 Notice that law as such brings with it the power of coercion, the menace of punishest imago Dei. Et tamen non excluditur quin necessaria sit gratia ad movendum affectum, sicut etiam per legem est cognitio peccati, ut dicitur infra III, 20, et tamen ulterius requiritur gratia ad movendum affectum.” The references to Job are to 1:1 and 23:11. 6 On the need for fear as well as love regarding divine providence, cf. St.Thomas, Commentary on Job, prologue: “. . . nothing calls men back from wickedness and leads them toward good so much as fear of and love for God.” (Cf. Thomas Aquinas, The Literal Exposition on Job: A Scriptural Commentary Concerning Providence, trans. Anthony Damico, Interpretive Essay and Notes by Martin D.Yaffe, [Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1989)], 68.) I take it that this was the point of the line of thought presented as Ivan Karamazov’s in Fyodor Dostoyevsky, The Brothers Karamazov, trans. Constance Garnett (New York: Random House, 1950), 78–79: Another character, Miusov, speaking of Ivan Fyodorovitch Karamazov: “. . . Only five days ago, in a gathering here, principally of ladies, he solemnly declared in argument that there was nothing in the whole world to make men love their neighbors. That there was no law of nature that man should love mankind, and that, if there had been any love on earth hitherto, it was not owing to a natural law, but simply because men have believed in immortality. Ivan Fyodorovitch added in parenthesis that the whole natural law lies in that faith, and that if you were to destroy in mankind the belief in immortality, not only love but every living force maintaining the life of the world would at once be dried up. Moreover, nothing then would be immoral, everything would be lawful, even cannibalism.That’s not all. He ended by asserting that for every individual, like ourselves, who do not believe in God or immortality, the moral law of nature must immediately be changed into the exact contrary of the former religious law, and that egoism, even to crime, must become, not only lawful but even recognized as the inevitable, the most rational, even honourable outcome of his position” (italics mine). 7 Marcus Tullius Cicero, The Political Works of Marcus Tullius Cicero: Comprising his Treatise on the Commonwealth; and his Treatise on the Laws.Translated from the original, with Dissertations and Notes in Two Volumes. By Francis Barham, Esq. (London: Edmund Spettigue, 1841–42). Vol. 1. Chapter: Cicero’s Commonwealth: Book III. (http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/546/83303; accessed on 2010-07-10): “[Lœlius speaking] There is a true law, a right reason, conformable to nature, universal, unchangeable, eternal, whose commands urge us to duty, and whose prohibitions restrain us from evil.Whether it enjoins or forbids, the good respect its injunctions, and the wicked treat them with indifference.This law cannot be contradicted by any other law, and is not liable either to derogation or abrogation. Neither the senate nor the people can give us any dispensation for not obeying this universal Natural Law and Universal Ethics 741 ment.8 To ignore the need for this feature is to set aside the difficulties proper to human nature.9 Having “zeroed in” on natural law as our topic, I see three or four points that need our attention. These are (1) natural law and human knowledge law of justice. It needs no other expositor and interpreter than our own conscience. It is not one thing at Rome and another at Athens; one thing to–day and another to–morrow; but in all times and nations this universal law must for ever reign, eternal and imperishable. It is the sovereign master and emperor of all beings. God himself is its author,—its promulgator,—its enforcer. He who obeys it not, flies from himself, and does violence to the very nature of man. For his crime he must endure the severest penalties hereafter, even if he avoid the usual misfortunes of the present life” (my italics). 8 Cf. ST I–II, q. 90, q. 3, ad 2; q. 92, a. 2 corp. [1217a33–36] and ad 3; q. 95, a. 1 corp. [1231a17–27]; q. 100, a. 9; II–II, q. 64, a. 3. Cf.Thomas regarding those same gentiles spoken of by Paul, To the Romans, chap. 2, lect. 3: “he [Paul] shows their dignity, in this, that, not having such law, they themselves are law for themselves, inasmuch as they fulfill the office of law towards themselves, instructing themselves and inclining themselves towards the good; because, as the Philosopher says [EN 10.9 (1180a21–24)], ‘law is a statement having compulsive power, issuing from some prudence and understanding.’ ” [Super Ep. Ad Romanos, chap. 2, lect. 3:“Tertio ostendit eorum dignitatem, in hoc scilicet quod huiusmodi legem non habentes, ipsi sibi sunt lex, inquantum scilicet funguntur officio legis ad seipsos, instruendo se et inducendo ad bonum, quia, ut Philosophus dicit Ethic., ‘lex est sermo coactionem habens ab aliqua prudentia et intellectu procedens.’ ”] 9 As I pointed out in my book Wisdom, Law and Virtue (New York: Fordham University Press, 2008), chap. 17, p. 311, Thomas certainly uses the need to provide coercion to approach the need for the political order, seen as the source of law. The need for law is regularly argued by Thomas on the grounds of the unruliness of youth (beyond what parents can deal with). Cf. especially ST I–II, q. 95, a. 1. One might think that it is only the fallen human being who has need of law and political government. However, in Thomas’s Sentences Commentary we read: “At the beginning, when God fashioned man, he could have [poterat] formed another man from the mud of the earth whom he might have left in the condition of his own nature, as mortal and susceptible to injury and experiencing the battle of concupiscence against reason ; in that person nothing of human nature would have been missing, because this [condition] follows from the principles of the nature. Nevertheless, this weakness would not have had in him the character of sin or punishment, since this weakness would not have been caused by the will” (In II Sent., d. 31, q. 1, a. 2, ad 3 [ed. Mandonnet, p. 810]). Concerning the undesirable side of matter, cf. ST I, q. 91, a. 3; this is the reason that a natural human being would have a battle with the side of passion which is difficult to control rationally.Thus, it seems to me that the argument for the necessity of human law, as based on the presence among us of unruly youth, should not be taken as dependent on the theological premiss of fallen man, i.e., on original sin; it is an argument which considers what pertains to human nature as such. 742 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. of God; (2) Thomas’s conception of “natural inclination” as found in rational creatures; (3) primacy of human natural friendly love for God more than for ourselves; and (4) original sin and the weakening of that natural inclination. I begin with the conception of law presented by St.Thomas, a conception taken from our experience of law in human affairs. The definition he proposes is: . . . [law] is nothing other than an ordering by reason towards the common good, promulgated by one who has responsibility for the community.10 God as Origin and Promulgator of Natural Law That all law has a divine origin is a doctrine not difficult to find in the writings of Thomas Aquinas. At ST I–II, q. 93, a. 3 the explicit point is that all law derives from the eternal law, eternal law which has already been explained as “the plan of divine wisdom inasmuch as it is directive of all acts and movements.”11 Prior to this, the particular location of the discussion on law within the moral part of the ST already suggested this doctrine. The ST, and in general the work of St. Thomas, is meta-philosophical. It is a study and teaching of what has been revealed to us by God himself, and thus surpasses mere human wisdom, that is, philosophy. However, revelation presupposes the order of nature, and Thomas’s teaching envelops philosophy rather than excluding it.12 In the ST 1–2, the more summary overall picture of the moral order,13 the treatment begins with beatitude, the ultimate goal of human life, as something whose attainment depends in some measure on human action;14 it then speaks of (1) that action, (2) its principles within the human agent, viz. the virtues, and finally (3) the extrinsic principles of that 10 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 4 (ed. Ottawa, 1209a3–7).The Latin runs: “potest colligi defin- itio legis, quae nihil est aliud quam quaedam rationis ordinatio ad bonum commune ab eo qui curam communitatis habet promulgata.” 11 ST I–II, q. 93, a. 1 (ed. Ottawa, 1218a48–50): “lex aeterna nihil aliud est quam ratio divinae sapientiae, secundum quod est directiva omnium actuum et motionum [eternal law is nothing else but the plan of the divine wisdom inasmuch as it is directive of all acts and movements].” 12 Cf. ST I, q. 1, a. 1 (ed. Ottawa, 2b9–20) and I, q. 2, a. 2, ad 1. 13 Concerning the division of the moral part of the ST into two parts, first more universal and second more particular, cf. ST I–II, q. 6, prologue. 14 ST I–II, q. 5, a. 7. Natural Law and Universal Ethics 743 action, primarily God. So presented, God is seen as guide by virtue of law and support by virtue of grace.15 Law thus is presented as a divine influence. One might think that this means merely that some special sort of law, the “divine law” specially revealed to us by God, is such a help.16 As the ST 1–2 carefully develops the overall causal picture, one sees that the word “law” names a reality found according to priority and posteriority, flowing from the divine intellect and will, and remaining, wherever properly found, a rational participation in that divine reality.17 Thomas begins the ex professo treatment of law with a general presentation of the essence of law, and does so, as I said, by considering primarily law as human beings make it. His general definition, I repeat, is: “ . . . [law] is nothing other than an ordering by reason towards the common good, promulgated by one who has responsibility for the community.” Once this is done, he presents the variety of kinds of law: eternal, natural, human, and divinely revealed laws.18 Eternal law is the plan of direction of the universe, the plan present within God himself. It is thus identical with God himself.19 This obliges 15 ST I–II, q. 90, prologue; the distinction between law and grace, guidance and support, is not hard and fast: what is most truly the New Law is the grace of the Holy Spirit: I–II, q. 106, a. 1. God is “extrinsic” to created reality in the way that the efficient cause is other than its effect; he is so present to every creature as to be most deeply within it, because of the nature of his proper effect, the act of being; we may say that his immanence flows from his transcendence: cf. ST I, q. 8, a. 1 in toto. On his mastery as mover of created reality, cf. ST I, q. 105, aa. 3, 4, and 5. 16 It should be noted that, in the vocabulary of the ST, “divine law” [lex divina ] refers to the divinely revealed law: cf. ST I–II, q. 91, a. 4; it is a higher mode of participation in the eternal law than is the natural law: cf. ibid., ad 1. On the other hand, the expression “eternal law” [lex aeterna ] signifies the plan within the divine mind, thus identical with God himself: ST I–II, q. 93, a. 1. 17 Notice ST I–II, q. 100, a. 2 (ed. Ottawa 1260a47–49), speaking of the human being’s being in a community with God through “divine law,” i.e., revealed law: “Sed communitas ad quam ordinat lex divina, est hominum ad Deum, vel in praesenti vel in futura vita. Et ideo lex divina praecepta proponit de omnibus illis per quae homines bene ordinentur ad communicationem cum Deo. Homo autem Deo coniungitur ratione, sive mente, in qua est Dei imago.” [But the community towards which the divine law orders is of human beings toward God, whether in the present or the future life. And therefore the divine law proposes precepts concerning all those matters through which humans are well ordered towards community with God. But man is conjoined to God by reason or mind, in which there is the image of God.] 18 ST I–II, q. 91 in toto. For simplicity’s sake I omit the “law of sin” (cf. I–II, q. 91, prologue) presented in a. 6. 19 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 1, ad 3. Lawrence Dewan, O.P. 744 us to reflect on the sort of unified field the general term “law” names. Early in the ST, that is, in question 13 of the first part,Thomas explained the way in which human language bears upon divine things.20 This is the doctrine of “the divine names.” What do we mean when we say the words “good” or “wise” of God? We learn that it is through a sort of analogy that “good” is said of God.To say:“God is good” is not to say merely that God is the cause of the goodness of creatures, or merely that God is “not bad.” Rather, we mean that what we call “goodness” in creatures exists by priority, in a higher way, in God.21 Thus, as regards the reality named, it is found more truly in God than in creatures, whereas the name applied is applied first to that which is found in creatures, and has the mode of signifying appropriate for creatures.22 All this surely applies to “law” as well. It is a word invented to name the human reality, but it is said properly of the eternal law which is in God, and indeed that is what most of all deserves the name “law.”23 The presentation of eternal law gives the most dominating metaphysical vision of the domain of law.We then can see the way that, within the life of the rational creature which is man, there is a root of all man’s lawmaking, a root in what is called “natural law,” this being the name of our participation in the eternal law.24 Presenting eternal law, in ST I–II, q. 91, a. 1, St.Thomas immediately recalls the presentation of divine providence in ST I:We read: . . . law is nothing else than a dictate of practical reason in the leader who governs some perfect community. Now, it is evident, given that the world is ruled by divine providence, as was had in book 1, that the whole community of the universe [communitas universi] is governed by divine reason. And therefore the very plan [ratio] of the government of things present in God as in the governor [ principe] of the universe has the intelligible note [ratio] of law. And because divine reason [ratio] conceives [concipit] nothing temporally, but rather has an eternal concept 20 Cf. my paper “St. Thomas and the Divine Names,” Science et Esprit 32 (1980): 19–33. 21 ST I, q. 13, a. 2 (ed. Ottawa, 77b42–47). 22 ST I, q. 13, a. 6 (82b15–30). 23 I have spoken here of “law” along the lines that Thomas teaches concerning the positive, absolute names such as “goodness” and “wisdom.” It is true that the word “law” indicates, when said of God, a relation to creatures. However, I take it that it is the sort of relation to creatures that is involved in all divine acts of understanding and willing of creatures. They are said of God as being in him eternally (ST I, q. 13, a. 7, ad 3), and this is true of “law” also, as is clear in such texts as ST I–II, q. 91, a. 1. 24 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2; also cf. q. 93, a. 6. Natural Law and Universal Ethics 745 [habet aeternum conceptum], as is said in Proverbs 8.23,25 one ought to call such law “eternal.”26 Providence was discussed in ST I, q. 22, and the full sapiential vision of law must include that teaching. Here I wish to focus on one feature of the doctrine of natural law. Natural law is properly called “law,” something that cannot be said of the eternal law’s participation by lower, nonrational creatures. Natural law is properly law because of the human being’s participation in providence, as rationally providing for himself in some measure.27 We are not, of course, the source of the legislation; rather, it is in us as in those who are ruled and measured by it.28 Natural law is possessed by the human being primarily through the vision of what goodness is,29 a vision that attests to our immediate relation to the universal cause of being and goodness.30 What is primary in 25 The Vulgate, at Proverbs 8.22–24, has wisdom say: “[22] Dominus possedit me ab initio viarum suarum,Antequam quidquam faceret a principio. [23] Ab aeterno ordinata sum, et ex antiquis antequam terra fieret. [24] Nondum erant abyssi, et ego iam concepta eram.” [The Lord possessed me from the beginning of his ways, before he had made anything, from the beginning. From eternity I was ordered, and from of old, before the earth was made.The depths were not yet, and I had already been conceived.] 26 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 1. For Thomas’s conception of the universe as primarily a community of persons ordered towards the divine personal being, cf. “St. Thomas, the Common Good, and the Love of Persons,” chap. 16 in my book Wisdom, Law, and Virtue. 27 ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, ad 3.The participation by non-rational creatures in the eternal law “cannot be called ‘law’ save by likeness.” 28 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 3, ad 1 and I–II, q. 91, a. 2. In this respect I do not like the language of para. 115 in the ITC document. We read: “To be able to be recognized by all men and in all cultures, the norms of behavior in society should have their source in the human person himself, in his needs, in his inclinations. [Bolin trans.; italics mine.] The French is:“Pour pouvoir être reconnues par tous les hommes, dans toutes les cultures, les normes du comportement en société doivent avoir leur source dans la personne humaine elle-même, ses besoins, ses inclinations.” 29 Intellect, as knowing what goodness is, is the very principle of will: cf. ST I, q. 59, a. 1. 30 ST II–II, q. 2, a. 3 (ed. Ottawa, 1416a6–17). So true is this that in some texts Thomas identifies natural law simply with the natural light of reason whereby we know the difference between the good and the bad. We read in a sermon given in Lent of 1273, entitled Collationes de decem praeceptis, and sometimes De duabus praeceptis caritatis et decem legis praeceptis, that the natural law just is the light of the human intellect conferred by God on the human being at creation: “ . . . lex naturae; et haec nihil aliud est nisi lumen intellectus insitum nobis a Deo, per quod cognoscimus quid agendum et quid vitandum. Hoc lumen et hanc legem dedit 746 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. Thomas’s presentation of law is its being rational, an expression of reason.31 The vision of that reasonableness is the source of the obligation it presents to us.32 In so speaking I by no means wish to obscure the element of inclination which the law includes. Such inclination is, intrinsically, a sort of loyalty to the reasonable.Thus, in speaking, in ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, of the eternal law as regulating all of creation, St.Thomas speaks first of all things, inasmuch as they participate in the impression coming from God, as having natural inclinations towards their proper acts and goals; he goes right on to say that inasmuch as the rational creature has a more excellent participation in divine providence, as itself providing for itself and others, it too participates in the eternal law by having natural inclination to the due act and end. Yet in concluding this very passage, what Thomas points to as natural law in us is the light of natural reason by which we distinguish the good from the bad.The properly human inclination is rooted in the light of natural knowl- Deus homini in creatione.” [ . . . the law of nature; and this is nothing else but the light of the intellect placed within us by God, through which we know what is to be done and what is to be avoided. God gave man this light and this law in creating [him].] As described by James Weisheipl in Friar Thomas D’Aquino (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1974): “ . . . the points in the vernacular sermon were jotted down and later written out in Latin ‘after Thomas had preached’ ” (402) by one of Thomas’s secretaries, Friar Peter d’Andria (319); and so one must be prepared for a sort of “short-hand” way of speaking. That the intellectual light spoken of here is to be identified with the agent intellect we see in such a passage as the following, from the Disputed Questions on Spiritual Creatures 10 (a work dated 1267 in Rome, according to the Leonine editor, B.-C. Bazan): “ . . . we say that the light of the agent intellect about which Aristotle speaks is immediately impressed on us by God, and in function of it we distinguish the true from the false, and the good from the bad. And it is about that that the Psalm says:‘The many say: who will show us good things? The light of your countenance has been stamped upon us, O Lord,’ i.e. [the light] through which what are good are shown to us.Thus, therefore, that which produces in us actual intelligibles, in the mode of participated light, is something of the soul and is rendered multiple in keeping with the multitude of souls and of human beings.” It should be underlined that actual knowledge of the first intelligibles and first truths is a product of abstraction from sensible experience, not something inborn; the intellectual light or agent intellect must derive information from sensible things even as regards the first notions and first truths: cf. Qq. de anima, q. 5, De veritate, q. 11, a. 1, Quodlibet 10.4.1 [7]. 31 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 1. 32 Reason as ordering towards the end is the principle of obligation here: cf. ST I–II, q. 90, a. 1 and especially I–II, q. 99, a. 1. Natural Law and Universal Ethics 747 edge.33 Thus, the treatment of our human “natural inclination” used in explaining the triad of the theological virtues reads: . . . the theological virtues order the human being towards supernatural beatitude in the way that the human being is ordered to the end connatural to him by natural inclination. Now this comes about in function of two items: firstly, in function of reason or intellect, inasmuch as it contains the first universal principles known by us through the natural light of the intellect, from which reason proceeds both in things to be considered and in things to be done. Secondly, through the rightness of the will naturally tending towards the good of reason.34 However, as already touched upon, two essential features of law are (1) that it be made by the one responsible for the common good of the community for which it is law,35 and (2) that it be promulgated to those subject to the law.36 I take this to mean that law appears in its adequate reasonableness only when it is so promulgated as to reveal its having its proper origin. I was delighted to find this conception confirmed by the Catechism of the Catholic Church in its presentation of natural law.37 We read: 33 Consider ST I, q. 60, a. 1 sed contra (of which St.Thomas obviously approves): “. . . dilectio sequitur cognitionem, nihil enim amatur nisi cognitum, ut Augustinus dicit, X De Trin. Sed in Angelis est cognitio naturalis. Ergo et dilectio naturalis.” [. . . love follows upon cognition, for nothing is loved unless it is known, as Augustine says in 10 On the Trinity. But in angels there is natural knowledge. Therefore, there is also natural love.] In the case of natural law, both its cognitive features and its inclinative features are viewed as coming forth from the nature of the rational being, from the essence of the intellective soul. However, each comes forth from that essence taken precisely as apt to give rise to that sort of perfection. Hence, there does not seem to be any reason to regard inclination as prior to and a cause of our natural knowledge (and thus to speak of knowledge through inclination). Inclination is rather viewed by St. Thomas as something that accompanies knowledge naturally. For the two aspects,“per modum cognitionis” and “per modum interioris principii motivi,” cf. ST I–II, q. 93, a. 6. 34 ST I–II, q. 62, a. 3: “ . . . virtutes theologicae hoc modo ordinant hominem ad beatitudinem supernaturalem, sicut per naturalem inclinationem ordinatur homo in finem sibi connaturalem. Hoc autem contingit secundum duo. Primo quidem, secundum rationem vel intellectum, inquantum continet prima principia universalia cognita nobis per naturale lumen intellectus, ex quibus procedit ratio tam in speculandis quam in agendis. Secundo, per rectitudinem voluntatis naturaliter tendentis in bonum rationis.” Cf. “Jacques Maritain and the Philosophy of Cooperation,” chap. 13 in my book Wisdom, Law, and Virtue. 35 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 3. 36 ST I–II, q. 90, a. 4. 37 I am using the English translation given on the Vatican website. 748 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. Man participates in the wisdom and goodness of the Creator who gives him mastery over his acts and the ability to govern himself with a view to the true and the good.The natural law expresses the original moral sense which enables man to discern by reason the good and the evil, the truth and the lie: The natural law is written and engraved in the soul of each and every man, because it is human reason ordaining him to do good and forbidding him to sin . . . BUT THIS COMMAND OF HUMAN REASON WOULD NOT HAVE THE FORCE OF LAW IF IT WERE NOT THE VOICE AND INTERPRETER OF A HIGHER REASON TO WHICH OUR SPIRIT AND OUR FREEDOM MUST BE SUBMITTED.38 Here Leo XIII is presented as clearly teaching the need to recognize a higher reason as the source of an authority rightly seen as legal. The Adequacy of Natural Law’s Promulgation This raises the question of natural law’s adequate promulgation. So much is it an issue that in Thomas’s article on the necessity for promulgation of law, in the question on the definition of law, an objection is based precisely on the case of natural law. One finds what is essential to law maximally in natural law, says the objector, and yet it stands in no need of promulgation! To this Thomas replies: “. . . it is to be said that the promulgation of the law of nature is from the very fact that God places it 38 Catechism of the Catholic Church, paragraph 1954; my italics. The text quoted by the Catechism here is from Libertas praestantissimum, 597, an encyclical letter of Pope Leo XIII, published June 20, 1888. [The uppercase letters are from me.] An English translation of Libertas praestantissimum can be found in The Church Speaks to the Modern World:The Social Teachings of Leo XIII, edited, annotated, and with an Introduction by Etienne Gilson (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1954), 55–85, and entitled “On Human Liberty.” For the quoted passage, cf. para. 8 at p. 62 and the notes i and j at p. 82. Notice also the following passage from the same place in the encyclical, stressing the importance of the supernatural dimension [Para. 8]: “ . . .To this rule of action and restraint of evil God has vouchsafed to give special and most suitable aids for strengthening and ordering the human will.The first and most excellent of these is the power of His divine grace, whereby the mind can be enlightened and the will wholesomely invigorated and moved to the constant pursuit of moral good, so that the use of our inborn liberty becomes at once less difficult and less dangerous. Not that the divine assistance hinders in any way the free movement of our will; just the contrary, for grace works inwardly in man and in harmony with his natural inclinations, since it flows from the very Creator of his mind and will, by whom all things are moved in conformity with their nature. As the Angelic Doctor points out, it is because divine grace comes from the Author of nature that it is so admirably adapted to be the safeguard of all natures, and to maintain the character, efficiency, and operations of each.” Natural Law and Universal Ethics 749 within the minds of human beings so as to be naturally known.”39 Now, for this reply to be sufficient, it surely requires that our knowledge of natural law include an appreciation of divine providence as its source. This is a point on which Suarez insisted in his presentation of natural law.40 He explains that the issue is not: “does the natural law come from God as author of natural reason?” It is rather:“does it come from him precisely as a legislator?” He holds that it comes to us in such a way that we know it is from God as from a legislator.41 The ultimate objection to this in Suarez’s discussion bears upon the need for God to intimate to the human being what the law is. For law really to be law, there must be, not only the will of the legislator in the matter, but also the intimation or insinuation that that is his will. Here Suarez answers that intimation of the will follows with the same necessity (as he had earlier mentioned), viz. from the perfection of divine providence.And thus the very judgment of right reason naturally inserted in man is the sufficient sign of that divine will, nor is any other insinuation necessary. And he says: The proof is, that the judgment of reason indicates, just by virtue of itself, divine providence of a sort fitting for God, and morally necessary for his full lordship and due subjection of man to him, in which providence this legislation is contained. Furthermore, for this reason it is known through natural reason that God is offended by sins which are done against natural law, and their punishment pertains to him, and judgment [in their regard]: therefore, the natural light itself is, just by itself, the sufficient promulgation of natural law, not only because it manifests the intrinsic inappropriateness or appropriateness of acts, which the uncreated light of 39 The objection (ST I–II, q. 90, a. 4, obj. 1) reads: “Videtur quod promulgatio non sit de ratione legis. Lex enim naturalis maxime habet rationem legis. Sed lex naturalis non indiget promulgatione. Ergo non est de ratione legis quod promulgetur.” [It seems that promulgation does not belong to the essence of law; for natural law has the essence of law in the highest degree; yet natural law has no need of promulgation.Therefore, it does not belong to the essence of law that it be promulgated.] And the reply (ST I–II, q. 90, a. 4, ad 1): “Ad primum ergo dicendum quod promulgatio legis naturae est ex hoc ipso quod Deus eam mentibus hominum inseruit naturaliter cognoscendam.” 40 On this, see especially Franciscus Suarez, S.J. [1548–1617], Tractatus de legibus et legislatore Deo, in Opera Omnia, ed. Carolus Berton (Paris, 1856): apud Vivès, t.V. Book II is De lege aeterna, et naturali, ac jure gentium. Cap.VI: An lex naturalis sit lex divina praeceptiva (pp. 104–12). The following three paragraphs in my main text are reproduced from “Natural Law and the First Act of Freedom: Maritain Revisited,” chap. 14 in my book Wisdom, Law, and Virtue, at 558–59. 41 This, of course, is precisely what Thomas shows in ST I–II, q. 91, aa. 1 and 2. God as princeps of the universe is the supreme legislator, pronouncing the eternal law (a. 1), and natural law is a participation in the eternal law (a. 2). 750 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. God shows: but also because it intimates to man [hominis, sic; lege homini ] that the contrary actions displease the author of the nature, as the supreme Lord, and care-giver, and governor of that same nature: therefore, this is sufficient intimation of that law, as Thomas judges in I–II, q. 90, a. 4, ad 1 . . . 42 He is referring to Thomas’s saying that the promulgation of natural law is sufficient, by virtue of God’s inserting it into our minds so that it is naturally known. The point here seems to be that we have by natural reason43 some knowledge of a perfect providence, and thus we see our natural knowledge as the expression of a law.44 Our Knowledge of Natural Law and Our Knowledge of God Thus far, then, we must conclude that one’s knowledge of the morally right has the quality, the status, the nobility, of natural law precisely inasmuch as it is recognized as guidance provided by the author of natural reality. This suggests a very “cognitive” encounter with natural law and its author. That is, where Jacques Maritain’s conception of natural law stressed non-conceptual knowledge,“knowledge through inclination” as the meaning of natural law’s being “naturally known,”45 I believe that Thomas is conceiving of will as depending on intellect, inclination as flowing from cognition.46 42 Suarez, Tractatus de legibus, para. #24, p. 112A. 43 What I mean here by “natural reason” is a spontaneous reasoning process found in all humans (as will emerge in what follows). 44 I think that in this matter Suarez is better than Maritain. Maritain, in the posthu- mously published study La loi naturelle ou loi non écrite (Texte inédit, établi par Georges Brazzola) (Fribourg: Éditions Universitaires, 1986), 105–11, takes the position that the natural law depends on reason, “not on will”: “Loi naturelle dépend de la Raison, non du vouloir.” Thus, in his table on p. 106, he has this very explicitly.Thomas Aquinas’s position is portrayed as divine reason issuing in the natural law which enters man through the natural inclinations, thus bringing us to the precepts. This seems to me quite wrong, most of all in the expression “not on will.” Obviously, law, for Thomas, is an expression of reason. However, it is the work of the governor, and this providential role is presented by Thomas, very explicitly, as “what pertains simultaneously to intellect and will”: cf. ST I, q. 22, prologue, and a. 1, ad 1, on God as giving precepts. Cf. also ST I–II, q. 97, a. 3, ad 1: “ . . . dicendum quod lex naturalis et divina procedit a voluntate divina” (and cf. the entire article).Thus, also, Maritain’s criticism of Suarez (in the same context) on this issue as non-Thomistic is wrong. 45 According to Maritain, only the absolutely first principle of natural law: “that we must do good and avoid evil,” is known to all human beings just by virtue of the concepts involved, and this, Maritain says (Man and the State [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951], 90), is not the law but rather its preamble and principle. Quoting from “Jacques Maritain and the Philosophy of Cooperation,” which is chap. 13 in my book Wisdom, Law, and Virtue, at 213: “Regarding the second Natural Law and Universal Ethics 751 Notice that Maritain excludes the first principle of the law from “the law.” I would contrast this with Thomas who is ready to say that the very light of the human intellect is “the law.”47 (Maritain is being affected by his own view of natural law as “known through inclination.” Obviously, he does not want to say this about the first principle of the law.) Our cognitive encounter with natural law as properly promulgated raises the question of the sort of knowledge we have of God at the very outset of natural law.48 In fact, that is already an essential issue, even apart from the promulgation question, when one recalls that the Ten Commandments are presented as first principles of natural law,49 and that the Ten Commandments themselves he presents as based on the law of love! We read: element, gnoseological, Maritain asserts that natural law is ‘known to human reason not in terms of conceptual and rational knowledge’ (82–83), but ‘through inclination’ (91). ‘That kind of knowledge is not clear knowledge through concepts and conceptual judgments; it is obscure, unsystematic, vital knowledge by connaturality or congeniality . . .’ (91–92). Only the absolutely first principle of natural law:‘that we must do good and avoid evil’ (90) is known to all human beings just by virtue of the concepts involved, and this, Maritain says (90), is not the law but rather its preamble and principle.” (Numbers in the foregoing refer to pagination of Maritain’s Man and the State.) 46 Cf. above, notes 33 and 34. 47 Cf. above, note 30. 48 This is a question I have discussed before in these pages in connection with Kevin Flannery’s book Acts Amid Precepts: The Aristotelian Logical Structure of Thomas Aquinas’s Moral Theory (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2001). Cf. my review article in Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 431–44. 49 I quote from “Jean Porter on Natural Law: Thomistic Notes,” which is chap. 15 in my book Wisdom, Law, and Virtue, at 245, speaking of the question whether the multiplicity of precepts indicated in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2 are presented as per se nota propositions: “It is true that Thomas here does not give an exact list of precepts, preferring to assign fields in accordance with the three levels of natural inclination he notes.And already, by the time we get to the particular applications which are the Ten Commandments, we are said (in the prima secundae context, at any rate) to be in the domain of conclusions, not per se nota principles. It should be noted, however, that St.Thomas changed his view of the presence of the per se notum as regards the precepts of natural law. Thus, while in the Prima Secundae the Ten Commandments are presented as immediate conclusions from the first principles, by the time he writes the secunda secundae Thomas has decided that they are most manifest principles of natural law: thus, they are surely being considered as per se nota. [ST II–II, q. 122, a. 1 (2034a3–6): Respondeo dicendum quod praecepta Decalogi sunt prima praecepta [Piana: principia] legis, et quibus statim ratio naturalis assentit sicut manifestissimis principiis. [‘the precepts of the Decalogue are the first principles [other reading: precepts] of the law, and to which natural reason immediately assents as to most manifest principles’ (my italics)].” Lawrence Dewan, O.P. 752 It seems that not all the moral precepts of the Old Law are reduced to the ten precepts of the Decalogue; for the first and principal precepts are:“you shall love the Lord your God,” and “you shall love your neighbour,” as is had in Matthew 22. But these two are not contained among the precepts of the Decalogue.Therefore, not all the moral precepts are contained in the precepts of the Decalogue.50 And the reply: . . . it is to be said that those two precepts are the first and general precepts of the law of nature, which are known by virtue of themselves to human reason, either by nature or by faith. And therefore all the precepts of the Decalogue are related to those two as conclusions to general principles.51 While52 I do not agree with Maritain that the knowledge of natural law is non-conceptual, I do agree that it is natural. St.Thomas teaches that the human being has a spontaneous reasoning to the existence of God.We see what I have in mind in Thomas’s answer to the question: does it belong to natural law that the human being offer sacrifice? He says: . . . Natural reason declares to man that he is subject to some higher being, because of the deficiencies that he experiences in himself, with respect to which he needs to be helped and directed by some higher being.And whatever that is, it is that which everywhere is called “a god.”53 50 ST I–II, q. 100, a. 3, obj. 1: “Videtur quod non omnia praecepta moralia veteris legis reducantur ad decem praecepta Decalogi. Prima enim et principalia legis praecepta sunt, ‘Diliges dominum deum tuum, et, diliges proximum tuum,’ ut habetur Matth. XXII. Sed ista duo non continentur in praeceptis Decalogi. Ergo non omnia praecepta moralia continentur in praeceptis Decalogi.” 51 Ibid., ad 1:“ . . . dicendum quod illa duo praecepta sunt prima et communia praecepta legis naturae, quae sunt per se nota rationi humanae, vel per naturam vel per fidem. Et ideo omnia praecepta Decalogi ad illa duo referuntur sicut conclusiones ad principia communia.” The option, “by nature or by faith,” touches on the issue: Original Sin has weakened natural inclination as regards the love of God more than our own selves (cf. ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3 [1354b39–49]); as also on the need for revelation even of the truths of reason knowable by philosophy yet pertaining to the faith: ST I, q. 1, a. 1. 52 The following three paragraphs are from my paper “The Foundations of Human Rights,” Science et Esprit 62 (2010): 227–36, at 235–36. 53 ST II–II, q. 85, a. 1 (1861b48–54): “Respondeo dicendum quod naturalis ratio dictat homini quod alicui superiori subdatur, propter defectus quos in seipso sentit, in quibus ab aliquo superiori eget adiuvari et dirigi. Et quidquid illud sit, hoc est quod apud omnes dicitur ‘deus.’ ” Natural Law and Universal Ethics 753 Thomas is not presenting a scientific demonstration of the existence of God, but is reporting and attempting to describe what is some universal spontaneous natural inference. Man’s experience of himself is as a being which cannot stand by itself, without aid, and which cannot survive without steering, without direction, from some source of intelligent direction, moving things along for man’s protection and welfare. Here, then, we have a type of natural knowledge, that is, not the fruit of deliberate study and method, but given in the way that eyes and ears are given, and yet a knowledge which is not merely the intellectual insight into starting points, whether of simple terms like “the good” or of propositions like “the good is to be done and promoted, and the bad avoided”, but a naturally occurring, spontaneous reasoning process.54 This is to say that Maritain was right in speaking of natural law as the last refuge of intellectual agreement among men, men who cannot agree in theoretical matters at all. We are dealing with what is often a rather implicit confidence that nature is a source of divine wisdom. Since writing about such natural knowledge of God in my Flannery review in these pages, I have noticed the relevance for the topic of what St. Thomas taught concerning natural justice and “what is right among the peoples” [ius gentium ]. I wish here to cite this most important consideration for the doctrine of natural law, as taught by Thomas in ST II–II, q. 57, a. 3, the third article in Thomas’s question on the object of justice; it asks about the difference, if any, between the naturally right and what is right among the peoples [ius gentium ]. We read, in the body of the article: I answer that it must be said, as has been said, that the naturally right or just [ius aut iustum ] is that which by its own nature is adequate or commensurate for the other person. Now, this can occur in two ways. In one way, as regards the absolute consideration of it: as the male by its nature [ratione ] has commensurateness relative to the female, that from it [the female] it [the male] generates [something], and [similarly] the parent [is so related] to the child, that it nourish it. In another way, something is naturally commensurate to the other person not as regards its absolute nature [rationem ], but in accordance with something that follows from it: for example, the ownership of possessions [ proprietas possessionum ]: for, if this field is considered absolutely, it has nothing whereby it should belong more to this person than to that one; but if it is considered as regards the convenience for 54 For more on this doctrine of spontaneous reasoning to the existence of God, see my above-mentioned review article of Kevin Flannery’s book in Nova et Vetera 5 (2007): 431–44, at 433–38. 754 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. cultivating, and as regards the peaceful exploitation of the field, so taken it has some rightness towards belonging to this one person and not to this other: as is clear from Aristotle, in Politics 2 [chap. 5: 1263a21]. Now, to apprehend something absolutely belongs not merely to man, but also to the other animals, and therefore the “right” which is called “natural” in the first way is common to us and to the other animals. But from the “naturally right,” so said, “that which is right among the peoples” is separated, as the Jurisconsul says, because the former is common to all animals, while the latter is common solely to human beings among themselves. [This is because] to consider something by comparing it to what follows from it is proper to reason, and therefore this is natural for the human being, in accordance with natural reason which decrees it.Thus, Gaius, the jurisconsul, says that what natural reason establishes among all human beings, this all peoples obey, and it is called “what is right among the peoples.”55 We thus see here that Thomas makes personal ownership of property something pertaining to the object of natural law for human beings. I suggest that the same considerations apply to the general spontaneous “sizing up” of the human condition, of which Thomas spoke in ST II–II, q. 85, a. 1, on offering sacrifice to a God as pertaining to natural law. Particular Remarks on the ITC Document It hardly needs saying that it is the Church’s obligation to direct the minds of all who will listen to the foundations of morals, that is, to natu55 ST II–II, q. 57, a. 3:“Respondeo dicendum quod, sicut dictum est, ius sive iustum naturale est quod ex sui natura est adaequatum vel commensuratum alteri. Hoc autem potest contingere dupliciter. Uno modo, secundum absolutam sui considerationem, sicut masculus ex sui ratione habet commensurationem ad feminam ut ex ea generet, et parens ad filium ut eum nutriat.Alio modo aliquid est naturaliter alteri commensuratum non secundum absolutam sui rationem, sed secundum aliquid quod ex ipso consequitur, puta proprietas possessionum. Si enim consideretur iste ager absolute, non habet unde magis sit huius quam illius, sed si consideretur quantum ad opportunitatem colendi et ad pacificum usum agri, secundum hoc habet quandam commensurationem ad hoc quod sit unius et non alterius, ut patet per Philosophum, in II Polit. Absolute autem apprehendere aliquid non solum convenit homini, sed etiam aliis animalibus. Et ideo ius quod dicitur naturale secundum primum modum, commune est nobis et aliis animalibus. A iure autem naturali sic dicto recedit ius gentium, ut Iurisconsultus dicit, quia illud omnibus animalibus, hoc solum hominibus inter se commune est. Considerare autem aliquid comparando ad id quod ex ipso sequitur, est proprium rationis. Et ideo hoc quidem est naturale homini secundum rationem naturalem, quae hoc dictat. Et ideo dicit Gaius iurisconsultus, quod naturalis ratio inter omnes homines constituit, id apud omnes gentes custoditur, vocaturque ‘ius gentium.’ ” For the vocabulary of natural reason as source of a decree:“dictat,” cf. again ST II–II, q. 85, a. 1: offering sacrifices is part of “natural law [lex]” and “natural right [ius].” Natural Law and Universal Ethics 755 ral law. It is ironic that contemporary society has given rise to a considerable global movement to protect nature, the “green” movement, while at the same time abusing human nature in a way that undermines the rational foundations of human life. The document of the ITC argues soundly in pointing to the variety of cultures that manifest awareness of universal principles. It is in the approach through “experience” followed by “foundations” that I find tendencies that trouble me.The doctrine of “natural law” is a doctrine of divine help. If one does not have the view of divine instruction and the threat of punishment, one is not in a doctrine of law. This raises the question of the distinction between awareness of the “morality” of certain courses of action and “theoretical justification in terms of ‘natural law.’ ” Surely, the doctrine of natural law is a doctrine of common awareness of a God and punishment (at least as it was presented by Cicero). An approach where one acknowledges “natural inclination” but does not consider nature as the product of a providential supreme agent is not much help in morals. Thus, I question their distinction (not all distinction) between the awareness and theoretical justification. I compliment the ITC document for gathering in its notes a valuable documentation for the history of natural law. As I finish rereading the introduction of the ITC document, I ask whether the distinction between “common experience” in chapter 2 and that of “theory” in chapter 3 is such that the chapter 2 “precepts of the natural law” are so called per se or per accidens. Cf. note 37 in para. 32: quoting Hugo Grotius (b. 1583-d. 1645).This also touches on the rejection by modern rationalism of the link to divine wisdom. This is what I wish to avoid, that is, the picture without God as required source. In paragraph 36 we see the distinction between the “behavior” recommended by a variety of cultures and the “theoretical explanation” of the type of behavior. ITC acknowledges the difficulty this involves, as to dialogue on the foundation of the moral norms. At paragraph 37 we read: Still, independently of the theoretical justifications of the concept of natural law, it is possible to discover the immediate givens of consciousness56 of which it wants to give an account.The object of this chapter is precisely 56 I substitute here a more literal translation than Bolin’s “the fundamental elements of the awareness,” so as to retain what may be a Bergsonian echo. 756 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. to show how to gather together [comment sont saisies] the common moral values that constitute natural law. We will then see how the concept of natural law is based on an explanatory picture that founds and legitimizes moral values, in a manner that can be shared by many.57 My point is that we should not exclude from “the immediate givens of consciousness” in this matter the divinity of the source of the experience : otherwise, we are not speaking of the experience of being subject to natural law as law. My concern is about the way one distinguishes between moral awareness and rational foundation. I do not like the restriction of “concept” to the realm of “explanatory picture.” This smacks of the Maritainian “knowledge through inclination” explanation of natural law.58 I notice the headline of paragraph 39:“moral experience: one must do good.” I wonder about the word “experience” here; I would say that we are already at the first “concept” and the first “moral truth.” I notice that they speak of the experience of this moral “call”—“fait l’expérience d’un appel intérieur à accomplir le bien” (“experiences an interior call to do good”). I would bear down hard on this word “call”: Who is calling? In paragraph 42 we read: Thus it recognizes the eternal law, i.e., the plan of God regarding creation, and participates in God’s providence in a particularly excellent manner, guiding itself and guiding others.59 Are we in “experience” or “theoretical foundations”? Are we discovering “the immediate givens of consciousness”? Does it recognize the plan of God as the plan of God? At paragraph 43 we come to this: 57 French:“Pourtant, quoi qu’il en soit des justifications théoriques du concept de loi naturelle, il est possible de mettre au jour les données immédiates de la conscience dont il veut rendre compte. L’objet du présent chapitre est précisément de montrer comment sont saisies les valeurs morales communes qui constituent la loi naturelle. C’est seulement ensuite que nous verrons comment le concept de loi naturelle prend appui sur un cadre explicatif qui fonde et légitime les valeurs morales d’une façon susceptible d’être partagée par plusieurs.” I added the French “comment sont saisies” in citing the English, because the document is not merely speaking of “gathering together” the moral values, but of their very “way of being grasped.” The italics in certain words are mine. 58 Cf. above, at note 45. 59 French: “En cela, elle perçoit la loi éternelle, c’est-à-dire le plan de Dieu sur la création, et elle participe à la providence de Dieu d’une manière particulièrement excellente en se dirigeant soi-même et en dirigeant les autres.” Natural Law and Universal Ethics 757 The moral obligation that the subject recognizes does not come, therefore, from a law that would be exterior (as a heteronomy), but affirms itself from within the subject itself. In fact, as indicated by the maxim we have cited—“One must do good and avoid evil”—, the moral good determined by reason “imposes itself ” on the subject. It “ought” to be accomplished. It has a character of obligation and of law. But the term “law” here does not refer to scientific laws, which limit themselves to describing the factual constants of the physical or social world, nor to an imperative imposed on the moral subject arbitrarily from without. The law designates here an orientation of the practical reason which indicates to the moral subject what kind of action is conformed with its fundamental dynamism and necessary for its being, which tends to its full realization.This law is normative in virtue of an internal requirement of the spirit. [Here, pace Bolin, I would suggest the word: “mind”.] It is born in the very heart of our being as an invitation to the realization and transcending of ourselves. It is not therefore a matter of subjecting oneself to the law of another, but of accepting the law of one’s own being.60 We see here a regretable tendency to justify the legal character of the precept simply on the basis of nature in itself, rather than as coming from the wise author of nature itself. This will not do !—There is not sufficient attention to the appropriateness of the term “law” here. No one is a law unto himself.61 And what has happened to the grasp of the eternal law, mentioned above, in paragraph 42? Moreover, the French “appel” [English “invitation”] implies a someone inviting: it can hardly be merely our own self that is doing the calling or inviting.62 60 French [43]: L’obligation morale que perçoit le sujet ne vient donc pas d’une loi qui lui serait extérieure (hétéronomie pure) mais elle s’affirme à partir de luimême. En effet, comme l’indique l’axiome que nous avons évoqué: “Il faut faire le bien et éviter le mal”, le bien moral que la raison détermine “s’impose” au sujet. Il “doit” être accompli. Il revêt un caractère d’obligation et de loi. Mais le terme de “loi” ne renvoie ici ni aux lois scientifiques qui se contentent de décrire les constantes factuelles du monde physique ou social, ni à un impératif imposé arbitrairement de l’extérieur au sujet moral. La loi désigne ici une orientation de la raison pratique qui indique au sujet moral quel type d’agir est conforme au dynamisme foncier et nécessaire de son être qui tend à sa pleine réalisation. Cette loi est normative en vertu d’une exigence interne à l’esprit. Elle jaillit du cœur même de notre être comme un appel à l’accomplissement et au dépassement de soi. Il ne s’agit donc pas tant de se soumettre à la loi d’un autre que d’accueillir la loi de son propre être. In fairness to the ITC I will note that the last sentence could be translated: “Thus, it is not so much a matter of subjecting oneself to the law of another as rather a matter of accepting the law of one’s own being.” 61 Cf. ST I–II, q. 90, a. 3, ad 1, and again ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2. —One can be a “law unto oneself ” but as receiving the law from a higher power. 62 Would it be relevant here to recall that St.Thomas presents law as pertaining to the discussion of the external principles of human action? Cf. above, note 15. 758 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. Paragraphs 44–47 are placed under a general heading: 2.3. La découverte des préceptes de la loi naturelle: universalité de la loi naturelle. (Bolin: The discovery of the precepts of natural law: universality of natural law.) What we find here is a reading of ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2, but with considerations suggestive of the thinking of Jacques Maritain.We are told that the knowledge is not “conceptual” (at least as this pertains to “philosophical and theological theory”).There is much insistence on the role of affectivity (as if we could not have conceptual thinking as the source of affectivity). After reading through to the beginning of paragraph 52, I am convinced that it is worthwhile to offer my own reading of I–II, q. 94, a. 2. It is normal to understand later parts of the ST in the light of what Thomas has already taught in the earlier parts. Thus, I base myself on the nature of our “natural inclinations” as presented by St. Thomas already in I–II, q. 62, a. 3, with the natural knowledge preceding the natural movement of the appetite (not “knowledge through inclination”). Then, secondly, I would stress the point that for Thomas the first level of natural inclination, common to all substances, surely includes the natural love for God more than for one’s own self, together with the natural inclination towards preservation, not only of the individual as an individual, but of the species: that is, reproduction! (cf. ST I, q. 60, a. 5, ad 1 and ad 3).63 The second level is not proper to “all living beings” (cf. paragraph 49) but to animals, in that it speaks of the more particular mode of reproduction, viz. sexual relations and the education of the young.The third is not about “the tendency to living in communion with God or the Absolute” (cf. paragraph 50) but to know the truth about God, and to live in society. The love of God pertains to the first level of natural inclination (cf. ST I, q. 60, a. 5). I will grant that we must have “imperfect”64 knowledge in these matters, as distinct from philosophical demonstration.65 However, the human being’s knowledge of God is fundamental for the doctrine of natural law as such.66 63 Indeed, the inclination to reproduce one’s kind is found in all natural things, and is used by St. Thomas as the approach to God’s willing things other than himself, in ST I, q. 19, a. 2. 64 Cf. para. 44:“C’est une saisie souvent imparfaite, encore obscure et crépusculaire, mais qui a la profondeur de l’immédiateté.” English: “It is a grasp often imperfect, still obscure and dim, but it has the profundity of immediacy.” 65 Cf. ScG chap. 3, par. 38 in toto. 66 Again, cf. ST II–II, q. 85, a. 1: that offering sacrifice to God pertains to natural law. Let us recall also the doctrine of St. Thomas commenting on Psalm 8: the natural instinct to find God in the universe. On all this I refer the reader to my review of Flannery, cited in note 48 above. Natural Law and Universal Ethics 759 Coming now to chapter 3, with the move from “experience” to “theories,” notice in paragraph 61 the note 60: At this first level, the expression of the natural law sometimes abstracts from an explicit reference to God. Certainly the openness to transcendence makes part of the virtuous behaviors that must be expected from the fulfilled man [French: Certes, l’ouverture à la transcendance fait partie des comportements vertueux qu’on est en droit d’attendre de l’homme accompli ; I would translate: Certainly openness to transcendence constitutes part of the virtuous behavior one has a right to expect in a mature human being ], but God is not [I add the word: “yet,” French has “encore”] necessarily recognized as the foundation and the source of the natural law, nor as the last end that mobilizes and hierarchizes the different virtuous behaviors.The explicit non-acknowledgment of God [French: “Cette non reconnaissance explicite de Dieu” I would translate as: This absence of an explicit recognition of God] as the ultimate moral norm seems to prevent the “empirical” approach to the natural law from being constituted as properly moral doctrine.67 My first question here would be: have they thus far given the reader enough notice of the importance of knowledge of God in the fundamental awareness of natural law, such that he might appreciate this present judgment of theirs? Their words “sometimes abstracts” suggests that natural law can be “experienced” with or without appreciation of the role of God in its existence. I think there should have been more knowledge of God present in their account of the “experience” of natural law. As I begin rereading chapter 3, I notice their speaking of the harvest obtained from the sort of experience they had in mind in chapter 2: 60. The spontaneous acquisition of fundamental ethical values, which are expressed in the precepts of the natural law, constitutes the point of departure of the process that then leads the moral subject to the judgment of conscience, in which it enunciates the moral requirements that impose themselves on it in the concrete situation. It is the task of the The ITC is certainly right to underline [paragraph 52] the possibility of weakening or obliteration of some precepts; the problem of sin, etc. 67 French: “A ce premier niveau, l’expression de la loi naturelle fait parfois abstraction d’une référence explicite à Dieu. Certes, l’ouverture à la transcendance fait partie des comportements vertueux qu’on est en droit d’attendre de l’homme accompli, mais Dieu n’est pas encore nécessairement reconnu comme le fondement et la source de la loi naturelle ni comme la fin dernière qui mobilise et hiérarchise les différents comportements vertueux. Cette non reconnaissance explicite de Dieu comme norme morale ultime semble interdire à l’approche ‘empirique’ de la loi naturelle de se constituer en doctrine proprement morale.” 760 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. theologian and of the philosopher to return to this experience of the acquisition of the first principles of ethics, to demonstrate their validity and to ground them in reason. The recognition of these philosophical or theological foundations, however, does not in the least condition the spontaneous adherence to common values. In fact the moral subject can put into practice the orientations of natural law without being capable, by reason of particular intellectual conditions, of explicitly comprehending them and their ultimate theoretical foundations.68 It does not sound as though the “moral subject” has appreciated the rationality of what he or she thinks is right. In short, I wonder if their split between chapter 2 and chapter 3 is really good for a presentation of the importance of natural law. I do, of course, agree with paragraph 61 on the value of metaphysical vision for an appreciation of natural law. However, I think that the embryonic metaphysics in the “experience” of natural law is underestimated by the document. When they spoke earlier of the meaning of “law” they mentioned the eternal law, but they gave no sense of the good person’s appreciation of God as cause of law. Already, before that, I had said: “Even as I finish rereading the introduction of the ITC document, I ask myself whether the distinction between ‘common experience’ in chapter 2 and that of ‘theory’ in chapter 3 is such that the chapter 2 ‘precepts of the natural law’ are so called per se or per accidens.” It is still a good question, I am afraid. Or should we say that they themselves answered it in note 60? I repeat its conclusion: This absence of an explicit recognition of God as the ultimate moral norm seems to prevent the “empirical” approach to the natural law from being constituted as properly moral doctrine.69 68 French: “[60] La saisie spontanée des valeurs éthiques fondamentales, qui s’expri- ment dans les préceptes de la loi naturelle, constitue le point de départ du processus qui conduit ensuite le sujet moral jusqu’au jugement de conscience dans lequel il énonce quelles sont les exigences morales qui s’imposent à lui dans sa situation concrète. Il appartient au philosophe et au théologien d’opérer un retour sur cette expérience de la saisie des premiers principes de l’éthique pour en éprouver la valeur et la fonder en raison. La reconnaissance de ces fondements philosophiques ou théologiques ne conditionne pas toutefois l’adhésion spontanée aux valeurs communes. En effet, le sujet moral peut mettre en œuvre pratiquement les orientations de la loi naturelle sans être capable, en raison de conditionnements intellectuels particuliers, d’en discerner explicitement les fondements théoriques ultimes” [italics mine]. 69 French, note 60: “Cette non reconnaissance explicite de Dieu comme norme morale ultime semble interdire à l’approche ‘empirique’ de la loi naturelle de se constituer en doctrine proprement morale” [italics mine]. Natural Law and Universal Ethics 761 In paragraph 63, where they present natural law as a participation in the eternal law, notice the way they put it: The natural law is therefore defined as a participation in the eternal law. It is mediated, on the one hand, by the inclinations of human nature, expressions of the Creative Wisdom, and, on the other hand, by the light of human reason which interprets them and which is itself a created participation in the light of divine intelligence. Ethics presents itself as a “participated theonomy.”70 We must recall that this is an expression of their interpretation of ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2 on the natural inclinations and their role in our formation of natural law precepts. I favour a reading of “natural inclination” in the rational creature which rather sees the appetitive dimension as flowing from the intellective dimension (cf. I–II, q. 62, a. 3). Note 64, attached to the expression “participated theonomy,” requires our comment; we read: John Paul II, Encyclical Veritatis splendor, n. 41—The teaching on natural law as the foundation of ethics is accessible by right to natural reason. History attests to this. But in fact, this teaching reached its full maturity only under the influence of Christian revelation. First of all, because the comprehension of the natural law as a participation in the eternal law is strictly linked with a metaphysics of creation. Now, although this is of right accessible to philosophical reason, it was truly presented and explained only under the influence of biblical monotheism. Secondly, because revelation, e.g., through the Decalogue, explains, confirms, purifies, and completes the fundamental principles of the natural law.71 I certainly do not oppose the reference to revelation of the Decalogue. This is especially true in that, as St.Thomas teaches (ST I–II, q. 109, a. 3), 70 French, note 64:“La loi naturelle se définit alors comme une participation à la loi éternelle. Elle est médiatisée, d’une part, par les inclinations de la nature, expressions de la sagesse créatrice, et, d’autre part, par la lumière de la raison humaine qui les interprète et qui est elle-même une participation créée à la lumière de l’Intelligence divine. L’éthique se présente ainsi comme une ‘théonomie participée.’ ” 71 French:“L’enseignement sur la loi naturelle comme fondement de l’éthique est de droit accessible à la raison naturelle. L’histoire l’atteste. Mais, de fait, cet enseignement n’a atteint sa pleine maturité que sous l’influence de la révélation chrétienne. Tout d’abord, parce que la compréhension de la loi naturelle comme participation à la loi éternelle est étroitement liée à une métaphysique de la création. Or, celleci, bien qu’elle soit de droit accessible à la raison philosophique, n’a été vraiment mise au jour et explicitée que sous l’influence du monothéisme biblique. Ensuite, parce que la Révélation, par exemple à travers le Décalogue, explicite, confirme, purifie et accomplit les principes fondamentaux de la loi naturelle.” 762 Lawrence Dewan, O.P. after original sin we do not have an adequate natural love for God, and that latter love is the basis for the conception of the Ten Commandments (I–II, q. 100, a. 3, ad 1). I would follow Thomas in seeing the divine causality which is creation as appreciated by Aristotle. One should notice how much of the doctrine of inclinations of nature is taken from Aristotle as imitation of the divine.72 Still, at this point we are touching on the issue I wish to highlight, namely that natural law as law requires rational appreciation of adequate promulgation. I wonder if the approach of the document is not too slanted towards a “non-law” conception of the general “experience” of natural law. Conclusion In general, my complaint is that the use of the word “law” involves one in our awareness of divine promulgation, whereas the line taken by the ITC tends towards a “self-perfection” picture. One sees that in their paragraphs 43/44/45. So also, the downplaying of conceptualizing, and their sort of stress on connaturality depreciates the cognitive quality of natural inclination as presented by St.Thomas. Their point about the first level of inclination is, I believe, deceptive, in that it obscures the role of the creature’s love for God more than for oneself as primary in natural inclination of all substances. ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2 should be read in the light of the earlier part of the ST, especially I, q. 60, a. 5. The question that remains is: how legitimate is my criticism of the document of the ITC? Are my concerns relevant? I think so.They pertain to Thomas’s insistence on the need for revelation even as regards what is N&V naturally knowable.73 72 Cf. my paper “St. Thomas Aquinas as an Example of the Importance of the Hellenistic Legacy,” Doctor Communis (2008), fasc. 1–2 (Vatican City): 88–118. 73 ST I, q. 1, a. 1 (ed. Ottawa, 2b9–20). Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 763–773 763 Determinacy in Natural Law K EVIN L. F LANNERY, S.J. Pontifical Gregorian University Rome, Italy A DOCUMENT of the International Theological Commission is a strange animal. It is not a magisterial document, although it is approved for publication by the Prefect of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. It is not simply an academic publication (like an article in a journal or a monograph), although it does put forward the ideas of a group of academics speaking qua academics. It is also obviously the work of a commission, and so does not pretend to be putting forward a position that is internally coherent in all respects; it is rather an “agreed statement,” onto which the members of the commission (including said Prefect), after presumably lobbying for various sentences and formulations, are willing to sign.Whatever the limitations of such documents, however, they are worth producing and studying.They are a way for the Church in Rome to come to understand better what respected Catholic scholars not in Rome are thinking about important questions and to remain in contact with them. They are also a way for Catholics in general to come to understand the intellectual culture the Church’s magisterium is to some extent addressing when it issues genuinely authoritative documents. In 2009 the International Theological Commission presented to the public a document on natural law entitled A la recherche d’une ethique universelle: nouveau regard sur la loi naturelle (henceforth A la recherche).1 In this article, I consider a number of remarks in A la recherche having to do (for the most part) with the bearing of the primary precepts of the natural law upon the moral characterization of particular human acts.Around the time of the Second Vatican Council, one begins to encounter in the writings of certain 1 The document was composed in French and the French version is the basis of the present article. English translations of A la recherche are my own. 764 Kevin L. Flannery, S.J. Catholic scholars the idea that the general precepts of the natural law are all well and good, but they cannot speak in a determinate way to particular situations and to particular acts that a person might perform.The motivation behind such theories is often—and often explicitly—a desire to allow the use of contraceptives in marriage despite the Church’s exceptionless proscription. But the theories invariably make claims about natural law itself and about its principal exponents, especially Thomas Aquinas. Regarding the more theoretical aspects of ethics, Thomas—in many (but not in all) respects—follows Aristotle, who says in a number of places that we cannot expect from ethics the same type of precision we find in the sciences.What Aristotle says in this regard is perfectly true: the analysis of human acts is not like the analysis of the objects of mathematics or even of biology, where it is important to fix these objects (numbers and animals) by means of definitions so that they might play in their respective sciences predictable and determinate roles. A biologist, for instance, has a problem if an animal he has placed within a particular bird species shows up also, according to his own rules of taxonomy, in a species of dogs. This sort of thing happens, however, all the time in ethics. An act that might be described as a simple act of truth-telling (a member of that “species”) turns out on closer analysis to be also an act of merciless revenge; or an act of striking a match on an ill-lit street corner turns out to be also the launching of an assassination attempt. But none of this means that, according to Aristotle or Thomas, we cannot make judgments about the morality of particular acts. Far from it. As Francisco Suarez, with Thomas in mind, pointed out back in the seventeenth century (long before “the pill,” that is, but not before theoreticians thought to seek ways to allow acts prohibited by exceptionless precepts), ethics is about particular acts: that is where it begins and (in many ways) finishes.2 Any attempt exhaustively to classify human acts as one does species of animals will soon be recognized as futile and even ridiculous; but (for instance) the man striking the match knows perfectly well what he is doing and why, as can we know, if we are informed about the plot. One sees (perhaps vestigial) traces of this philosophical controversy in A la recherche’s translation and/or interpretation of a passage from Thomas’s Summa theologiae I–II, q. 94, a. 4, which asks whether natural law is the same everywhere. A la recherche §53 begins with the remark: It is impossible to remain at the level of generality, which is that of the first principles of the natural law. Moral reflection must in effect descend 2 Francisco Suarez, Tractatus de Legibus, ed. M. André and Carolus Berton (Paris: L. Vivès, 1856), vol. 5 of Opera Omnia 2.7.7 (and, more generally, 2.13). Determinacy in Natural Law 765 into the concreteness of action in order to shed there its light. But the more it is faced with concrete and contingent situations, the more its conclusions are affected by an element of variability and incertitude. A few lines later comes the passage from Thomas: Practical reason [writes Thomas in the Summa theologiae] is concerned with contingent realities, in which human actions are performed.This is why, even though in the general principles there is a certain necessity, the more one confronts particular matters, the more indetermination there is. A la recherche §53 then marks an ellipsis, after which it gives the reader another sentence, which is taken from the same article of the Summa theologiae and acknowledges that “there is not the same practical truth or rectitude among all peoples with respect to proper but only general matters” and that, even where “rectitude” is the same regarding proper matters, it is not known equally to all.3 In Thomas, but not in A la recherche, there then follows the example of a person who is “obliged” to return a deposit left to him in trust but is actually obliged not to return it, for to do so would be unjust.4 The section that contains this example is marked in A la recherche §53 by another ellipsis; it then concludes with a last bit from ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4:“And here, the more one descends into detail, the more the indetermination increases.”5 3 The French of A la recherche, following the CERF translation (see note 6), speaks of “applications particulières” where Thomas’s Latin has simply “propria.” Since in Thomas’s account of natural law the distinction between general precepts (“praecepta communia”) and proper precepts is so important, it is best to adhere closely to Thomas’s choice of terms here. Things proper (proper precepts, for instance) are not necessarily particulars. (See, for instance, ST I–II, q. 94, a. 6 corp.: “. . . ad legem naturalem pertinent primo quidem quaedam praecepta communissima, quae sunt omnibus nota, quaedam autem secundaria praecepta magis propria, quae sunt quasi conclusiones propinquae principiis.”) 4 A deposit is simply an object left to one in trust by its owner. See below, note 7. 5 Here is the whole of A la recherche §53:“Il est impossible de demeurer au niveau de généralité qui est celui des principes premiers de la loi naturelle. La réflexion morale, en effet, a besoin de descendre dans le concret de l’action pour y jeter sa lumière. Mais plus elle affronte des situations concrètes et contingentes, plus ses conclusions sont affectées d’une note de variabilité et d’incertitude. . . . Bien qu’il vécût à une époque de chrétienté, un théologien comme saint Thomas d’Aquin en avait une perception très nette. ‘La raison pratique, écrivait-il dans la Somme de théologie, s’occupe de réalités contingentes, dans lesquelles s’exercent les actions humaines. C’est pourquoi, bien que dans les principes généraux il y ait quelque nécessité, plus on aborde les choses particulières, plus il y a d’indétermination . . . Dans le domaine de l’action, la vérité ou la rectitude pratique n’est 766 Kevin L. Flannery, S.J. One interesting thing about these various translations from ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4 is that they repeat almost word for word the standard French translation,6 except where we read in A la recherche of “indetermination” [“indétermination”]. In fact, in the relevant places, the standard French translation renders Thomas’s “invenitur defectus” and “invenitur deficere” much more accurately as “on rencontre de défaillances” (“one encounters defects”) and “les exceptions se multiplient” (“the exceptions are more numerous”). What does it mean to encounter failure or defect in the application of a general principle? This is best understood by studying the larger passage in the Summa theologiae to which the various bits given in A la recherche §53 belong. After saying (as we have seen) that practical truth or rectitude can differ among peoples, although not with respect to general matters but only proper matters, and that, even when the rectitude is the same, it is not always known equally to all,Thomas says that there is much more regularity in speculative reason: it is true everywhere that the interior angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles—although not everyone knows this. He then continues: But, with respect to the proper conclusions of practical reason, neither [1] is truth or rectitude the same with everyone—nor [2], for those for whom [the truth or rectitude] is the same, is it known equally. For everywhere the following is right and true:‘one ought to act according pas la même chez tous dans les applications particulières, mais uniquement dans les principes généraux; et chez ceux pour lesquels la rectitude est identique dans leurs actions propres, elle n’est pas également connue de tous. . . . Et ici, plus on descend dans le détail, plus l’indétermination augmente.’ ” In the appended note, it gives the bits taken from Thomas’s ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4: “Ratio practica negotiatur circa contingentia, in quibus sunt operationes humanae, et ideo, etsi in communibus sit aliqua necessitas, quanto magis ad propria descenditur, tanto magis invenitur defectus . . . In operativis autem non est eadem veritas vel rectitudo practica apud omnes quantum ad propria, sed solum quantum ad communia, et apud illos apud quos est eadem rectitudo in propriis, non est aequaliter omnibus nota. . . . Et hoc tanto magis invenitur deficere, quanto magis ad particularia descenditur.” Reading A la recherche §53, one gets the impression that the last piece of quotation, “Et ici, plus on descend dans le détail, plus l’indétermination augmente,” refers to the penultimate piece (about rectitude, etc.). It does not; it refers rather to the general principle “deposits are to be returned” [“deposita sunt reddenda”]. But this is not clear in the CERF translation either, since it translates “Et hoc” as “Et ici.” If one follows the development of the argument of ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4 corp., one notices that Thomas twice introduces a sentence with the words “Et hoc.” In both cases, he is referring to the same thing: that (in general) deposits are to be returned. 6 Thomas d’Aquin: Somme Théologique (Paris: Les Éditions du CERF, 1984). Determinacy in Natural Law 767 to reason.’ From this principle, however, there follows, as if a proper conclusion, that deposits ought to be returned.And this indeed [1] is in general true although in some case or another it can happen that it would be injurious—and therefore irrational—for deposits to be returned: for instance [a], someone asks [for the return of a deposit] in order to attack the fatherland. And this [i.e., principle that deposits ought to be returned] is found to be more likely to fail [deficere] the more one descends into particulars, for instance [b], if it is declared that deposits are to be returned “with this proviso” [cum tali cautione]7 or “in this way”—for as the appended particular conditions increase in number, so also increase the ways in which [the principle] can fail [deficere], so that rectitude would be found neither in returning nor in not returning [deposits]. So then it needs to be said that the law of nature, with respect to the first general principles, is the same with everyone both according to rectitude and according to knowledge thereof. But with respect to certain proper principles—which are quasi-conclusions of the general principles—[the law of nature] is the same with everyone in general, both according to rectitude and according to knowledge thereof, but in a few cases it can fail [potest deficere] both [1] with respect to rectitude, because of certain particular impediments (just as also the generable and corruptible things of nature fail in particular cases on account of impediments) and also [2] with respect to knowledge thereof. And the explanation of this is that some individuals have a reason corrupted due to passion or due to a bad custom or due to a bad habit of nature: for instance [c], as Julius Caesar informs us in The Gallic Wars, at one time among the German peoples robbery was not considered iniquitous, even though it is expressly against the law of nature.8 7 The question of whether a deposit (such as a weapon) ought to be returned to a madman occurs as early as Plato’s Republic (see R. i, 331E5–332A2; see also ii, 382C7–10). In Roman law, a cautio is often a note appended to a contract, stating its terms. In Isidore of Seville’s Etymologiae 5.25.19, a depositum is described in the following way: “Depositum est pignus commendatum ad tempus, quasi ‘diu positum.’ Deponere autem quis videtur, cum aliquid metu furti, incendii, naufragii, apud alium custodiae causa deponit.”A few lines later (5.25.24), Isidore defines a ‘hypotheca’ (originally a Greek term denoting a deposit): “Hypotheca est, cum res commodatur sine depositione pignoris, pacto vel cautione sola interveniente.” Here a cautio is equivalent to a written or verbal specification of the terms of a contract pertaining to a deposit. 8 “Sed quantum ad proprias conclusiones rationis practicae, nec [1] est eadem veritas seu rectitudo apud omnes; nec [2] etiam apud quos est eadem, est aequaliter nota.Apud omnes enim hoc rectum est et verum, ut secundum rationem agatur. Ex hoc autem principio sequitur quasi conclusio propria, quod deposita sint reddenda. Et hoc quidem [1] ut in pluribus verum est, sed potest in aliquo casu contingere quod sit damnosum, et per consequens irrationabile, si deposita reddantur; puta [a] si aliquis petat ad impugnandam patriam. Et hoc tanto magis 768 Kevin L. Flannery, S.J. I have attempted to make the structure of this argument more apparent by inserting bracketed numbers and letters. This structure is announced in the first sentence: “with respect to the proper conclusions of practical reason, neither [1] is truth or rectitude the same with everyone—nor [2], for those for whom [the truth or rectitude] is the same, is it known equally.” This is basically Thomas’s response to the question asked in the title of the article: “Whether the law of nature is one [the same] with everyone.” He will first [1] explain how the rectitude [“rectitudo”] of even proper principles (which are “quasi conclusions” of the general principles)9 can differ among different people—without, however, a loss of rectitude in their application. He will then [2] show how difference of rectitude in application might not be an issue and yet, among certain people, the rectitude be unknown. He gives three examples: the first two [a] and [b] pertain to [1] (rectitude differently applied); the third [c] pertains to [2] (ignorance even where rectitude differently applied is not an issue). Most of the above passage is about [1]; failure with respect to knowledge [2] is discussed only at the very end of the quotation. “Failure” (or defect) is the subject of both sections [1] and [2]. The word itself ought not to be understood as necessarily connoting a bad situation. In section [1], it refers to the fact that the proper principle as invenitur deficere, quanto magis ad particularia descenditur, puta [b] si dicatur quod deposita sunt reddenda cum tali cautione, vel tali modo, quanto enim plures conditiones particulares apponuntur, tanto pluribus modis poterit deficere, ut non sit rectum vel in reddendo vel in non reddendo. Sic igitur dicendum est quod lex naturae, quantum ad prima principia communia, est eadem apud omnes et secundum rectitudinem, et secundum notitiam. Sed quantum ad quaedam propria, quae sunt quasi conclusiones principiorum communium, est eadem apud omnes ut in pluribus et secundum rectitudinem et secundum notitiam, sed ut in paucioribus potest deficere et [1] quantum ad rectitudinem, propter aliqua particularia impedimenta (sicut etiam naturae generabiles et corruptibiles deficiunt ut in paucioribus, propter impedimenta), et etiam [2] quantum ad notitiam; et hoc propter hoc quod aliqui habent depravatam rationem ex passione, seu ex mala consuetudine, seu ex mala habitudine naturae; sicut [c] apud Germanos olim latrocinium non reputabatur iniquum, cum tamen sit expresse contra legem naturae, ut refert Iulius Caesar, in libro De Bello Gallico.” 9 In Thomas, this concept of a “quasi-conclusion” is important. (See, for instance, In IV Sent., d. 33, a. 2c and ST I–II, q. 94, aa. 4–6.) The proper principles (or precepts) are not deduced from the general (or common) principles but are specifications of them. I discuss this more fully below. A la recherche appears to appreciate that the lower precepts of natural law are not deduced from higher precepts; see, for instance, §54, where we read: “in morals pure deduction by syllogism is not adequate” [“qu’en morale la pure déduction par syllogisme n’est pas adéquate”]. But, as will be shown below, it occasionally loses hold of this truth. Determinacy in Natural Law 769 originally formulated is simply not present—without, however, any loss of rectitude. In example [a], there is no negative aspect whatsoever: the principle is absent but (and) justice is done.The holder is not obliged to return the deposit to the owner who would use it in order to attack the fatherland; in fact, he is obliged not to return it and he does the right thing. Reading example [b], one does get the impression that Thomas is not much in favor of the accumulation of legal specifications (“as the appended particular conditions increase in number, . . . rectitude would be found neither in returning nor in not returning [deposits]”); but what he apparently regards as not especially good is not the failure of the general principle to make an appearance at the concrete level—it is left in the background in order that the law might be more precise—but rather the loss of a clear message regarding the natural law in that particular regard. Section [2] does refer to a bad situation (a certain population is regularly committing theft), but the problem is not simply the absence of the principle (for, as we have seen, absence is not per se a negative) but the fact that the absence is due to the ignorance of the people of something they ought to know. So then, with respect to [1], the proper principle “deposits are to be returned” sometimes either [a] fails to apply, as when returning a weapon to a man would be irrational if he clearly intends to use it to attack the fatherland,10 or [b] is so qualified in positive law that its original form for that reason fails to be present at the level of concrete application. In this latter case, instead of speaking of the general principle “deposits are to be returned,” judges and lawyers speak of the qualified principle “deposits are to be returned except when doing so might threaten the fatherland” (or something similar).Thomas’s main point with respect to [1] is simply that, at the level of application, a proper principle might be subject to variation (without loss of rectitude) either because of particular circumstances (impediments to its application) or because of the decisions of legislators. With respect to [2] and the example [c] of the Germans who thought that robbery was not iniquitous, it is important to note that Thomas concludes that point with the remark “even though it is expressly against the law of nature.” This connects the example to his original formulation of his response, as contained in the first sentence of our quotation: (to repeat) 10 See ST II–II, q. 57, a. 2, ad 1. Note that in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4 Thomas says that the proper principle “deposita sint reddenda” is a quasi-conclusion of the general principle “ut secundum rationem agatur.” He then says that returning the deposit (the weapon) to the other person would be “damnosum, et per consequens irrationabile”; in other words, it would contradict the general principle from which the proper principle is “derived.” 770 Kevin L. Flannery, S.J. “with respect to the proper conclusions of practical reason, neither [1] is truth or rectitude the same with everyone—nor [2], for those for whom [the truth or rectitude] is the same, is it known equally.” In example [c], he is assuming that neither of the issues identified in [1] (that is, in examples [a] and [b]) is involved.The rectitude of the law remains without variation: the Germans just lack knowledge about its application in certain circumstances.11 What can we conclude from all this regarding the supposed “indetermination” of moral precepts as applied in concrete instances? Consider the three examples that Thomas gives (which appear to exhaust the possible types of cases). In example [a], a weapon, for instance, is not to be returned to the person who owns it but who wants to use it in order to attack the fatherland.To return the weapon,Thomas maintains, would be to go against the general principle (‘one ought to act according to reason’) from which the proper principle (‘deposits are to be returned’) is derived as a quasi-conclusion.There is no indeterminateness here: what the law calls for is clear. In example [b], a deposit is to be returned with a proviso (such as,‘unless doing so would threaten the fatherland’).Again, no indeterminateness here: if anything, such a law might be faulted for being too determinate in stating things that might just as well be left implicit. In example [c], certain Germans believe that in some circumstances stealing is permitted (and, obviously, in the same circumstances, they do not believe that deposits are to be returned). Again, according to Thomas’s account, what natural law calls for is clear and determinate— even if these individuals do not fully grasp the pertinent principle. There is, therefore, no basis for A la recherche’s claim that ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4 contains an argument for the indeterminateness of general practical principles. Thomas holds no such thing. And one certainly finds no support in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4 for A la recherche’s (somewhat later) assertion that “only the conscience of the subject, the judgment of his practical reason, is capable of formulating the immediate norm of action” [A la recherche §59].12 This is not to say that Thomas would not acknowledge that there are instances when the application of a general precept is not 11 Thomas refers us explicitly to Caesar’s De bello gallico, where the Germans are not said to countenance all stealing but “stealings” that occur beyond the confines of the city: “Latrocinia nullam habent infamiam quae extra fines cuiusque civitatis fiunt, atque ea iuventutis exercendae ac desidiae minuendae causa fieri praedicant” [Alfredus Klotz, ed., Commentarii belli gallici (Leipzig:Teubner, 1957), vol. 1 of C. Iuli Caesaris commentarii 6.23.6]. 12 “[L]a science morale ne peut fournir au sujet agissant une norme qui s’appliquerait de façon adéquate et comme automatique à la situation concrète: seule la conscience du sujet, le jugement de sa raison pratique, peut formuler la norme immédiate de l’action” [A la recherche §59]. Determinacy in Natural Law 771 clear;13 but neither would he assert that there is something in principle indeterminate about the application of general principles to particular cases. When, with a particular type of situation it is not obvious where justice stands, a lawmaker must make a decision and his decision will carry the weight of law—until replaced, in legitimate fashion, by another and presumably better law. It has to be acknowledged, however, that one does find in A la recherche statements that go quite contrary to the idea that only personal conscience is capable of applying general principles in concrete instances. Just after making that statement in A la recherche §59, the document remarks that moral science “does not abandon conscience to mere subjectivity: it aims at the subject’s acquisition of intellectual and affective dispositions that allow it to open itself to moral truth such that its judgment is adequate.”14 It mentions a number of “sins against nature,” including suicide and “certain sexual practices . . . directly opposed to the reproductive finalities inscribed in man’s sexual body.”15 It speaks of “murder, theft, lying, wrath, greed, [and] avarice” as universally recognized “objects of reprobation.”16 Regarding lying, it cites in a positive way Augustine’s argument for its intrinsically evil character [A la recherche §26, n. 30]. A la recherche also puts forward another purportedly Thomistic argument, intended apparently as support for the idea that natural law can have a direct bearing upon positive law in certain regards; in fact, however, it betrays considerable confusion regarding Thomas’s moral theory and consequently presents something weaker than that theory. The first two sentences of §91 read as follows: Positive law must endeavor to put into practice the requirements of natural law. It does this either by way of conclusion (the natural law prohibits homicide, positive law prohibits abortion), or by way of determination (natural law requires that the guilty be punished, positive 13 See ST I–II, q. 96, a. 1, ad 3; ST II–II, q. 47, a. 9, ad 2 and q. 60, a. 3, ad 1. See also Aristotle’s Politics iii, 15, 1286a9–31; 16, 1287a23–25, b15–25. 14 “Mais en même temps elle n’abandonne pas la conscience à la seule subjectivité : elle vise à faire acquérir au sujet les dispositions intellectuelles et affectives qui lui permettent de s’ouvrir à la vérité morale de telle sorte que son jugement soit adéquat” [A la recherche §59]. 15 “Ainsi certaines pratiques sexuelles s’opposent-elles directement aux finalités reproductrices inscrites dans le corps sexué de l’homme” [A la recherche §80]. 16 “Par ailleurs, certains comportements sont universellement perçus comme objets de réprobation: meurtre, vol, mensonge, colère, convoitise, avarice . . .” [A la recherche §36]. 772 Kevin L. Flannery, S.J. penal law determines the punishments to be applied for each category of crime).17 In a note appended at this point (n. 82), ST I–II, q. 95, a. 2 is cited. ST I–II, q. 95, a. 2 does indeed make the important distinction between conclusions—or, actually, quasi-conclusions—and determinations.18 Thomas says, that is, that, from the general principle of natural law “one should do no evil to anyone,” one can derive, as “a sort of conclusion,” the precept “one must not kill.” He then adds that (as A la recherche §91 accurately reports) natural law requires that the guilty be punished but leaves to positive law, as “a sort of determination,” the specific punishment. One notices, first of all, that A la recherche has replaced a primary (general) precept of the natural law with a secondary precept: in fact, with the fifth commandment. But that is not so important for present purposes. It would appear that A la recherche is attempting to toughen up the bond between natural law (which “prohibits homicide”) and positive law (which “prohibits abortion”) by making it into straightforward deduction. It is willing to concede that the relationship between the precept ‘the guilty should be punished’ and the particular punishment is merely that of determination—but at least (it seems to be saying) Catholic legislators can insist that a ban on abortions is entailed logically by the natural law precept prohibiting homicide. Thomas, however, is in no need of such help; indeed, it undermines his whole approach to the relationship between natural law and its particular applications. In ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4, he calls attention to the parallel between the principle of non-contradiction and the first precept of practical reason (“good is to be done and pursued, evil avoided”). In the theoretical realm, any proposition, whether it be one of the axioms of geometry or the simple proposition that Socrates is seated, is a specification of the principle 17 “Le droit positif doit s’efforcer de mettre en oeuvre les exigences du droit naturel. Il le fait soit par manière de conclusion (le droit naturel interdit l’homicide, le droit positif prohibe l’avortement), soit par manière de détermination (le droit naturel prescrit de punir les coupables, le droit pénal positif détermine les peines à appliquer pour chaque catégorie de crimes)” [A la recherche §91]. 18 On quasi-conclusions, see above, note 9. That Thomas is speaking about quasiconclusions in ST I–II, q. 95, a. 2 is apparent in the “hedged” language he uses: “Derivantur ergo quaedam a principiis communibus legis naturae per modum conclusionum, sicut hoc quod est non esse occidendum, ut conclusio quaedam derivari potest ab eo quod est nulli esse malum faciendum.” The argument continues: “Quaedam vero per modum determinationis, sicut lex naturae habet quod ille qui peccat, puniatur; sed quod tali poena puniatur, hoc est quaedam determinatio legis naturae.” Determinacy in Natural Law 773 of non-contradiction in the sense that its truth excludes the truth of its contradictory. It is cannot be denied that an axiom of geometry is, in a sense, closer to the principle of non-contradiction on account of its necessity (and the other’s contingency); but in both propositions—the axiom and the contingent proposition—we encounter the full force of the principle of non-contradiction.To say that Socrates is seated and not seated (at the same time and in the same sense) is as much a violation of that principle as to say that the whole both is and is not greater than the part. A similar thing can be said about the practical realm. An injurious and spiteful remark is as much a turning away from the good as is a murder— although, of course, the precept against murder is closer to the first precept of practical reason than any precept against gossiping.To defraud an elderly woman of her small investment is as much a violation of the precept “deposits are to be returned” as is a billion-dollar ponzi scheme: the same principle is immediately involved. So, for A la recherche to change Thomas’s quasi-deduction into a simple deduction, with the (supposed) idea of giving more force to natural law, is to miss the whole point of Thomas’s very careful depiction—in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4 and elsewhere—of the relationship between higher and lower precepts.That relationship is always one of specification, whether as quasi-conclusion or as determination (as when a determinate punishment is specified). Specification of a higher precept (such as the first precept of practical reason) in either way does not weaken its force or render the precept’s application at a lower level indeterminate.19 I conclude, therefore, that the claim on the part of A la recherche to be representing the thought of Thomas Aquinas in its remarks about natural law’s “indetermination” is unsustainable. I would further maintain (although I have not argued explicitly for this thesis here) that Thomas’s understanding better represents the way in which law—including natural N&V law—works. 19 For helpful criticisms of this essay, my thanks to Fr. Stephen Brock and Prof. John Finnis. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 775–789 775 Teleology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good— Reflections on the ITC’s The Search for Universal Ethics: A New Look at Natural Law S TEVEN A. L ONG Ave Maria University Ave Maria, FL T HE International Theological Commission’s document on natural law—The Search for Universal Ethics:A New Look at Natural Law 1—manifests a rich awareness of the speculative and essentially teleological foundations of the natural law. It likewise displays awareness of the history of metaphysical obscuration that has marginalized and distorted proper understanding of the natural law, thus engendering a false ethos of the absolute autonomy of the human moral agent vis à vis divine Providence: an apotheosis of arbitrary will criticized in Veritatis Splendor. In what follows below, I address three distinct foci of the ITC paper. First I engage the document’s teaching inasmuch as it vindicates the primacy of the speculative in relation to the practical—a judgment focally articulated in its stress on the centrality of metaphysical wisdom for moral judgment, and its corresponding judgment of the essential moral import of natural teleology. Secondly, I will address the ITC document’s affirmation of the strategic importance of a non-competitive account of divine and human causality for the understanding of natural law as a mode of the divine providence.This is perhaps the most strategically important of the several speculative judgments that frame our understanding of the eternal law in both its natural and its graced participations. Further, disorder with respect to it engenders a distinctively 1 This essay cites the translation of Joseph Bolin, revised March 25, 2010, and available on the internet at www.pathsoflove.com/universal-ethics-naturallaw.html#2.3. Steven A. Long 776 erroneous superordination of the autonomy of the human agent in relation to natural and divine law. Thirdly, and finally, I will briefly offer comment regarding the document’s treatment of the common good in relation to just claims or “rights.” I. The Primacy of the Speculative and the Normative Role of Natural Teleology The document unequivocally affirms the priority of the speculative vis à vis the practical in moral theology and philosophy, chiefly through its unremitting stress upon the definitory importance of metaphysical truth, but also by its clear and unequivocal affirmation of the essential ethical import of natural teleology. It observes (§61) “two levels of coherence and depth” in the “philosophical justification of natural law.”Thus “[t]he idea of a natural law is justified primarily on the basis of reflective observation of the anthropological constants that characterize a successful humanization of the person and a harmonious social life.”Yet it continues to note (§62) that the defining character of the natural law is a function of metaphysical judgment: Still, only by taking into account the metaphysical dimension of reality can we give natural law its full and complete philosophical justification. In fact metaphysics allows one to comprehend that the universe does not have in itself its own ultimate reason for being, and manifests the fundamental structure of reality: the distinction between God, subsistent being itself, and other beings placed by him in existence. God is the Creator, the free and transcendent source of all other beings. Thus, it continues (§63): The Creator is not only the principle of creatures but also the transcendent end towards which they tend by their nature. Thus creatures are animated by a dynamism that carries them to realize themselves, each in its own way, in the union with God. This dynamism is transcendent, insofar as it proceeds from the eternal law, i.e., from the divine plan of providence that exists in the Spirit of the Creator. But it is also immanent, since it is not imposed on creatures from without, but is inscribed in their very nature. Purely material creatures realize spontaneously the law of their being, while spiritual creatures realize it in a personal manner. They interiorize the dynamisms that define them and freely orientate them towards their complete realization.They formulate them for themselves, as fundamental norms of their moral action—the natural law in its proper sense—and they endeavor to realize them freely.The natural law is therefore defined as a participation in the eternal law. Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 777 The definition of a thing is not accidental but rather essential to it. As St. Thomas teaches in Summa theologiae, q. 79, a. 11, the only difference between acts of speculative and practical intelligence is that in the latter, knowledge is further ordered to the good of an operation—something accidental to knowledge as such, which is essentially defined by the adequation or conformity of the mind to the real. For knowledge to be ordained to the good of an operation, one must of course will the operation; as a human act, this presupposes rational desire—the motion of the will—which presupposes knowledge that is prior to and that specifies the motion of the will toward the desired good. Thus a speculative knowledge—a speculum—is implicitly and actually present in every practical cognition. It could not be otherwise.Thus the nature of reality necessarily defines one’s moral vision—moral life cannot momentarily detach from the nature of reality later to return. It is not a function of deriving reasons for action from propositions lacking reasons for action: because good—in all its analogical modalities, ethical as well as culinary, athletic, technical, et alia—is nothing other (cf. ST I, q. 5, aa. 1–3) than being with a conceptual relation to appetite as perfective. Robert George, in measured response to criticisms of the new natural law theory advocated by Germain Grisez, John Finnis, John Boyle, and himself, has argued2 that “in the epistemological mode of inquiry, our (practical) knowledge of human good(s) is methodologically prior to our (speculative) knowledge of human nature.The latter presupposes the former: It is not, as neo-scholastics suppose, the other way around.” He argues further elsewhere3 that one may not derive a conclusion with a reason for action from premises that do not contain reasons for action. This latter point is incontrovertibly true.Yet the question is: does an adequate understanding of being and nature contain no reasons for action for human beings? Or: is knowledge of that to which man is naturally ordered not precisely a speculative knowledge of an order with practical implications (and thus, in the real order, a knowledge containing reasons for action?)? Is man’s nature teleologically ordered, or is it not? Because insofar as it is, knowledge of that order will therefore involve reasons for action and practical implications. Is there an order to the good? What sort of reality is an “ought”? 2 Robert P. George, “Recent Criticism of Natural Law Theory” University of Chicago Law Review 55 (1988): 1416. 3 Cf. Robert P. George,“Natural Law and Human Nature” in Natural Law Theory, ed. Robert P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 31–41, especially, for example, 38: “We cannot deduce or infer reasons for action from premisses that do not include reasons for action. We cannot deduce or infer basic reasons for action from anything.” 778 Steven A. Long Before we desire an end, we must know something of it, and as this knowledge precedes appetition, it precedes the practical cognition that ordains truth to the good of an operation. Thus the dependence of the practical upon the speculative is not a matter of logical derivation of “value” from “fact,” but of the necessary inception of appetite in knowledge of reality. In order for there to be right appetite of the end, there must first be knowledge of the end.4 Knowledge as such is essentially speculative—a matter of the conformity of mind and thing: it is accidental to knowledge qua knowledge that it be further ordered to the good of an operation.Whereas sciences are differentiated as speculative or practical by their objects, according as these objects essentially concern doing or making, or do not, acts of the mind are differentiated by their ends. Either the end is simple knowledge, or that knowledge is further ordered for the sake of the good of an operation.Thus, for example, there may be speculative knowledge of practical science (I may contemplate the structure of the good life not immediately to apply it to action, but simply to understand it—yet ethical science is essentially practical).Whilst often the speculative is thought of as merely tantamount to the theoretical, this is not the case (although the speculative includes the theoretical): for example, whether someone is, or is not, in the room with one, is speculative knowledge unless one is ordering that knowledge toward the good of an operation. Although in practical knowing one orders the known truth to the good of an operation, whether it is truth that is so ordered is a function of conformity or nonconformity to the real: it is a speculative function. To be clear, it is hardly the case that merely because I order some judgment to my operation that therefore that judgment is true: to the contrary, its truth is a function of adequation to the real irrespective whether I wish to apply it to action or not. No matter what I may wish to order my knowledge to practically, whether it is true is not merely a function of what I plan to do. For example, whether salt will or will not ease the pain of a wound is not merely a function of my practical intention to order the application of salt to the good of the operation of easing the pain of a wound (something that one would swiftly discover has the opposite result). This awareness of the primacy of being and of the speculative leads to the realization of the normative moral role of unified teleology. The docu4 ST I–II, q. 19, a. 3, ad 2: “In his autem quae sunt ad finem, rectitudo rationis consistit in conformitate ad appetitum finis debiti. Sed tamen et ipse appetitus finis debiti praesupponit rectam apprehensionem de fine, quae est per rationem.” Latin derived from the Corpus Thomisticum, S.Thomae de Aquino opera omnia, made available online by the University of Navarre at www.unav.es/filosofia/alarcon/ amicis/ctopera.html#OM. Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 779 ment teaches (§69):“The concept of natural law presupposes the idea that nature is for man the bearer of an ethical message and establishes an implicit moral norm which human reason actualizes.” It comments on the disastrous implications for ethics that ensue insofar as“the corporeal world was identified with extension, certainly regulated by intelligible mathematical laws, but deprived of any immanent teleology or finality.” The point could not be clearer in the document’s affirmation that (§73): In this context, in which nature no longer conceals any immanent teleological rationality and seems to have lost all affinity or kinship with the world of spirit, the passage from knowledge of the structures of being to moral duty which seems to derive from it became effectively impossible and fell under the criticism of “sophism or naturalistic fallacy,” denounced by David Hume and then by George Edward Moore in his Principia Ethica (1903). In effect the good was disconnected from being and from truth. Ethics was separated from metaphysics. This is, of course, the description of a pathology of judgment: the good cannot be separated from being, because outside of being there is nothing.The role of the speculative in practical affairs—of being, nature, and natural teleology—is essential: the capacity to abstract from natural teleology does not establish its nonexistence or practical irrelevance. Knowledge of the ends for the sake of which human nature and action are ordered cannot help but be foundational in understanding the human good, and for achieving the corresponding prudential judgments regarding circumstances.5 Further, without the order of ends specifying the order 5 One must note that the precepts of the natural law, while perfected in application to the singular, are not determined or formally promulgated by that application— otherwise one has the Kantian ethic of the agent giving the law to himself rather than the participation of the agent in a normative and ethically directive order that is perfected in act through virtuous conduct: something that the first part of the document clearly rejects. One does not prudentially judge whether it is good or bad to betray one’s spouse or murder and cannibalize one’s neighbor—that is already under precept. Reading §§52–59 as implying more than that adequate prudence virtuously applies the norm of the law but rather that it determines it, would be to view the whole ethical life as determinatio, whereas intelligible general direction is not less direction for being more intelligible.Yet prudence does determine the agent in the application of precept such that the results of that application lie within the genus of the precept: hence there is determination, but it is of the agent with respect to the application of the law, not of the law itself qua law, whose author is God, but of the law qua this further perfection of instantiation regarding particular circumstance.And on this divine authorship as essential to the natural law, the document could not be more clear. Thus formulations such as (§58) “Prudence is a necessary passageway to authentic moral obligation” could— 780 Steven A. Long of inclinations and the consequent order of precepts, individual goods in their ethical role become disjunct, atomized, and potentially infinitized, losing the ratio of the good, the distinctive normative place of each in a good life. Thus the truth of the hierarchy of ends defining the ratio boni is of foundational importance for our moral life. Of course, were it true that efficiency did not presuppose teleology, this would destroy the very possibility of all knowledge of order in the world and accordingly render human action impossible—for if action were not by its nature more ordered toward one effect than toward another, rational choice would be impossible. As St.Thomas notes, without an end no reason either for determinate action or for the cessation of action is assignable.6 Just as the universe is a cosmos, an ordered whole of efficiencies ordained toward finalities which are ordered to the ultimate end, so is the ethical life a microcosm, an ordered whole whose order is specified by the order of ends, inclinations, and precepts.This of course stands opposed to the erroneous view that treats only positive science, and chiefly the positive science most abstractively immersed in quantity, as an adequate cognition of nature—a view that cannot even make sense of the end of becoming a good hypothetico-deductive physicist. Correction of such error begins with recognition of the primacy of the speculative, and of the essential role of natural teleology in moral life.7 absent the requisite distinctions—be misleading. Virtuous determination of the agent regarding singular circumstance is essential to the application of the law and as such a passageway to it and further instantiation/actuation/determination of it; but it is not a passageway to the law as in itself the very intelligible constitution of the law. 6 Summa contra gentiles III, chap. 2. 7 On this score, one must observe that even reason is teleologically ordained to its end prior to any act of reason: teleological order is the formal precondition of efficiency.There can be a tendency to suppose that, because man moves toward his end as specified by reason, that therefore his inclinational ordering is a pure function of understanding. Whereas, reason itself is ordained to the true prior to the understanding that reason is ordained to the true; and, further and more specifically, that understanding inform, incite, and specify volition is a function of the teleological ordering of human nature as a whole (granted, under the form of reason). One understands that water is good for one, but knowledge of one’s own thirst plays a role in this understanding. This does not mean that lower inclination trumps reason, but that reason discriminates the ordering in lower inclinations and so moves us to a genuinely rational appetite with respect to their objects, placing these in relation to the whole universe of good.Yet that I am such a being as, ensuing upon knowledge of a good, to be incited to desire for it, is a function of my entire nature and its teleology, and not merely of reason: granted that there must be rational apprehension of the good in order for one’s will to be moved by it and toward it (which involves Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 781 II. At the Heart of the Eclipse of the Metaphysics of Being: The Absolutization of Human Autonomy The ITC document’s insight into the roots of moral antinomianism in the erroneous treatment of human and divine freedom as competitive—as though the divine causality were no different than a finite causality, or other also the rational grasp of one’s own subrational appetites and their objects in relation to the order of ends). For example, to say no more, such volition presupposes the general natural rational volition of the end—of the good in general, happiness—which is prior to further specification of the desire for happiness. Act is prior to potency, absolutely speaking. And to know the good precisely as object of desire —under that ratio —one must first know the good, and be moved to desire it. Hence our understanding of the objective good that ordains is distinct from our understanding of the objective good precisely as ordaining, for the first is prior to the motion of the will, while the latter is subsequent. The knowledge of the good for man precisely as such includes reference to the motion of the will, because the good for man implies the ordering of man to something as an end, and potency is known only in relation to act: this is to say that the perfection of the end is thus known as terminating a motio, as activating a potency, even though in relation to act as such potency is accidental, because potency is for the sake of act and is defined by it. Although action is essentially ordained to end, it is accidental simply to the perfection specified by “end” that it be terminus of the act: the end is an extrinsic cause, as Thomas teaches (ST I–II q. 7, a. 3, resp.; also q. 7, a. 4, ad 2), even while it is “the most important cause of the act insofar as it moves the agent to act” (ST I–II, q. 7, a. 4, ad 2:“Ad secundum dicendum quod finis, etsi non sit de substantia actus, est tamen causa actus principalissima, inquantum movet ad agendum. Unde et maxime actus moralis speciem habet ex fine”).The notion of the good for man includes the attainment of that good through the motion of the will—this is the very reason why Thomas distinguishes our attainment of happiness and the reality in which happiness consists as both pertaining to beatitude. Yet it is potency that is ordered to act and not the converse, and so our knowledge of some perfection can rationally direct the will —we judge something worthy of desire; whereas it is only following upon actual inclination that reflexive knowledge of the good as perfecting appetite occurs. In a way similar to that in which, because one knows, one knows oneself to be a knower, so likewise because one is volitionally moved by rational apprehension of the nature of the good, one knows oneself to be ordered to the good. Even if it be said that the knowledge of the good for man requires only the knowledge of something as potentially moving the will, the understanding of this potential motion can occur only on the basis of prior knowledge of act, because potency is knowable only in relation to act.To know the will as potentially moveable relative to a judgment of reason about being as perfective seems to require prior knowledge of the will as actually moveable, which is to say of the good as actually moving the will; and for that prior knowledge to occur, we must have known something about being, some objective aspect of a thing that actually incited appetite: the will must have been moved. Hence in our knowledge of the good, there is a first utterly speculative moment wherein our knowledge/judgment 782 Steven A. Long than the very cause of human free acts themselves—is strategically crucial. It is subtle, and stated as cautiously and prudently as one can imagine— because this issue was the core of the De auxiliis disputations before the Holy See, the most difficult and profound set of disputations ever to be taken up by the magisterium. Here the document’s teaching is wholly correct. If one pursues the speculative etiology of the eclipse of metaphysics, one finds there a neuralgia that derives from the arguments regarding God and human freedom, from the Church’s failure to judge the doctrine of Molina, and from a consequent skepticism about the role of causal metaphysics within theological method.After all, consequent on the failure to judge Molina’s teaching, causal metaphysics became associated with what came widely to be viewed as a paralogism of speculative reason regarding divine and human agency. But a direct implication of the Molinist account is that the agency of the human will stands without the divine efficiency, and therefore stands without the divine causal providence. Molina of course taught that the will is free only when, all requirements being retained, the will could will otherwise.8 But if among the “requirements” is the divine causality, the result is that human free acts must then be held to stand outside the divine causality.As St.Thomas puts the matter expressly regarding the divine agent causality and providence (ST I, q. 22, a. 2, resp.): For since every agent acts for an end, the ordering of effects towards that end extends as far as the causality of the first agent extends. Whence it happens that in the effects of an agent something takes place which has no reference towards the end, because the effect comes from a cause other than, and outside the intention of the agent. But the causality of God, Who is the first agent, extends to all being, not only as to constituent principles of species, but also as to the individualizing principles; not only of things incorruptible, but also of things corruptible. Hence all things that exist in whatsoever manner are necessarily directed by God towards some end; as the Apostle says: “Those things that are of God are well ordered (Romans 13:1).” of being forms, specifies, defines, and attracts the motion of the will—the known object ordains such motion, as it were.Thereupon we reflexively know the rationally apprehended reality precisely under the formality of its attraction of the will’s motion—not merely the good (that ordains), but precisely the good as ordaining. Because of the universal extension of teleology as the very condition of all efficiency, it is important not to overstate the efficiency of reason with respect to the motion of the will: the reason informs and specifies the will, but it is of the nature of man that the teleological ordering of his nature be such that certain known goods rationally attract. 8 Cf. Molina’s Concordia, q. 14, a. 13, disp. II. Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 783 The ordering of effects toward the end extends as far as the causality of the first agent extends, and it is quite clear that the causality in question is agent causality. If human freedom is subtracted from the effect of divine agency, then of course human freedom lies outside the divine providence, and accordingly wholly outside the eternal law, outside the divine providential ordering.Thus natural law would be impossible, because natural law is nothing other than the rational participation in eternal law, and eternal law and divine governance generally extend only so far as divine agency extends. As Thomas puts it in ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2, resp.: Wherefore, since all things subject to Divine providence are ruled and measured by the eternal law, as was stated above (Article 1); it is evident that all things partake somewhat of the eternal law, in so far as, namely, from its being imprinted on them, they derive their respective inclinations to their proper acts and ends. Remove human freedom from the divine providential government, and one has abolutized human freedom, rendering it a se, and rendered the very idea of natural law an impossibility.This is the proximate effect of defining human freedom in relation to God—who as cause of universal being is cause both of the necessary and the contingent—rather than defining freedom by its rational nature. Yet it is such a freedom that is articulated by the implied libertarian account of freedom that is in seedling present within Molina’s formulation. To the contrary, however, God is not merely a finite cause, but the source of all other causality, which accordingly is as such inscribed within the effect of His agency. Inasmuch as the proper object of God’s causality is being, to say that a thing possesses “liberty of indifference” to the divine causality is to speak of something as standing outside of being, to speak of it not existing. But not existing is neither freedom nor any other real attribute. The non-competitive view of divine and created agency and causality— that is, that God’s causality is inclusive, not exclusive, of human freedom, because human freedom is a providential divine gift—is essentially intellectualist as St. Thomas Aquinas develops it. The ITC document is wholly correct in cleaving to this account (cf. §75 and §77). For St.Thomas, freedom of the will with respect to any finite object, inclusive of revealed truths, follows from the very nature of intellect and will.The intellect is ordered to the universal true, and the will is natively ordered toward the universal good, good in general (universal because rationally specified). But no finite good can compel the will, because no finite good is as such universal good.9 9 Cf. ST I, q. 82, a. 2, ad 2. 784 Steven A. Long Hence even grace, construed as an object of choice, cannot compel the will. Only were man to see God would his will be wholly perfected and fulfilled in such a manner that nothing save cleaving to God would be possible. But regarding all terrestrial objects of volition, man is free. Freedom is thus defined by the will as a proximate cause in relation to its terrestrial objects, and not by its relation to God, a doctrine upon which Thomas strongly insists in De malo.10 Man’s freedom is defined, not by a spurious liberty of indifference to divine causality that nothing real possesses or could possess, but by the nature of the rational will in relation to its finite terrestrial objects. Man is not a se.As the ITC document puts it (§77),“Freedom is therefore not an absolute self-creator of itself, but an eminent property of every human subject.” As Thomas Aquinas puts it, just as one may be cause of a thing without being the first cause, so one may cause one’s own free act without being the first cause of one’s own free act.11 As nothing moves itself from potency to act save by virtue of that which is first in act, and man is not always proceeding to apply the natural motion of the will to act, God moves us from potency to act with respect to our own self-determination in freedom. Indeed, the divine simplicity is such that God has no real determined relation to the creature, whereas the creature is really determined toward and dependent upon God. The only difference between God willing X and God not willing X is the being of X, for there is no change in God. Thus, while grace as an object of choice is subject to our freedom—as we are free, say, to reject a grace calling us to prayer, or worship, et alia—grace in relation to the divine simple will is simply efficacious, because either God does or does not will the effect. 10 De malo q. 16, a. 7, ad 15:“And therefore necessity and contingency in things are distinguished not in relation to the divine will, which is a universal cause, but in relation to created causes which the divine will has ordered proportionately to the effects, namely in such a way that the causes of necessary effects are unchangeable, and of contingent effects changeable.”—“ Et ideo necessitas et contingentia in rebus distinguuntur non per habitudinem ad voluntatem divinam, quae est causa communis, sed per comparationem ad causas creatas, quas proportionaliter divina voluntas ad effectus ordinavit; ut scilicet necessariorum effectuum sint causae intransmutabiles, contingentium autem transmutabiles.” 11 ST I, q. 81, a. 1, ad 3: “Dicendum quod liberum arbitrium est causa sui motus; quia homo per liberum arbitrium seipsum movet ad agendum. Non tamen hoc est de necessitate libertatis, quod sit prima causa sui id quod liberum est; sicut nec ad hoc quod aliquid sit causa alterius, requiritur quod sit prima causa eius. Deus igitur est prima causa movens et naturales causas et voluntarias. Et sicut naturalibus causis, movendo eas, non aufert quin actus earum sint naturales; ita movendo causas voluntarias, non aufert quin actiones earum sint voluntariae, sed potius hoc in eis facit; operatur enim in unoquoque secundum eius proprietatem.” Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 785 The perfection of our freedom in free acts is thus a gift, and even a gift for which we may and should pray. Hence in the composite sense, insofar as God moves me freely to will, I am not not-freely moving to will, because I cannot freely move and not freely move at the same time and in the same respect, and freedom is not a denial of the law of noncontradiction.What makes the act free is that we are ourselves interiorly the source of the act, and no finite object of our free choice can compel our choice.Yet as an act the free choice stands within and not without the divine causal providence. Considered from the most formal and metaphysical perspective, the question is whether God is genuinely the first cause of every perfection of being. If so, then God must be the first cause of the perfection of our free acts of self-determination, and this is indeed the teaching of Aquinas. Hence he writes in De malo, q. 3, a. 2, ad 4: When anything moves itself, this does not exclude its being moved by another, from which it has even this that it moves itself. Thus it is not repugnant to liberty that God is the cause of the free act of the will.12 Thomas famously argues (ST I–II, q. 109, a. 1, resp.) that no creature, no matter how noble, can even proceed to its act unless it first be moved by God, and that the action of any created being depends upon God in two ways, “first inasmuch as it is from Him that it has the form whereby it acts; secondly, inasmuch as it is moved by Him to act.”13 12 “Similiter cum aliquid mouet se ipsum, non excluditur quin ab alio moueatur a quo habet hoc ipsum quo se ipsum mouet. Et sic non repugnat libertati quod Deus est causa actus liberi arbitrii.” The antecedent text of this response to the fourth objection is also very much to the purpose:“Ad quartum dicendum quod cum dicitur aliquid mourere se ipsum, ponitur idem esse mouens et motum; cum autem dicitur quod aliquid mouetur ab altero, ponitur aliud esse mouens et aliud motum. Manifestum est autem quod cum aliquid mouet alterum, non ex hoc ipso quod est mouens ponitur quod est primum mouens: unde non excluditur quin ab altero moueatur et ab altero habeat hoc ipsum quod mouet.”—“To the fourth it should be said that when it is said that something moves itself, that the same thing is mover and moved. But when it is said that something is moved by another, the moved is taken to be one thing and the mover another. But it is clear that when something moves another, from this it is not taken to follow that it is the first mover: wherefore it is not excluded that from another it is itself moved and from this other it has even this, that it moves.”Thence the lines follow that “when something moves itself, this does not exclude that it is moved by another from which it has even this, that it moves itself. And thus it is not repugnant to liberty that God is the cause of the free act of the will.” 13 ST I–II, q. 109, a. 1, resp.: Manifestum est autem quod sicut motus omnes corporales reducuntur in motum caelestis corporis sicut in primum movens corporale; 786 Steven A. Long If we remove the positive substance of man’s free acts from the transcendent divine causality, it will follow as a necessary corollary that the positive substance of these free acts is alike removed from divine providence. And that which lies outside divine providence is not subject to the direction of eternal law. From this point onward, that which for St. Thomas defines the natural law—namely, that it is a rational participation in the eternal law —will become something extraneous and alien.14 On this supposition, finite human creatures roam the earth creating ex nihilo the added perfection or reality of their free determinations, entirely outside of the divine causality, the divine providence, and the eternal law.15 The volitional agent is thus removed from the divine jurisdiction in being removed from the divine causality. This directly implies a way of understandita omnes motus tam corporales quam spirituales reducuntur in primum movens simpliciter, quod est Deus. Et ideo quantumcumque natura aliqua corporalis vel spiritualis ponatur perfecta, non potest in suum actum procedere nisi moveatur a Deo. Quae quidem motio est secundum suae providentiae rationem; non secundum necessitatem naturae, sicut motio corporis caelestis. Non solum autem a Deo est omnis motio sicut a primo movente, sed etiam ab ipso est omnis formalis perfectio sicut a primo actu. Sic igitur actio intellectus et cuiuscumque entis creati dependet a Deo inquantum ad duo: uno modo, inquantum ab ipso habet perfectionem sine formam per quam agit; alio modo, inquantum ab ipso movetur ad agendum.” I.e., “. . . all movements, both corporeal and spiritual, are reduced to the absolutely First Mover,Who is God. And hence no matter how perfect a corporeal or spiritual nature is supposed to be, it cannot proceed to its act unless it be moved by God. Now this motion is according to the plan of His providence, and not by a necessity of nature, as the motion of the body of the heavens. But not only is every motion from God as from the First Mover, but all formal perfection is from Him as from the First Act. Hence the action of the intellect, or of any created being whatsoever, depends upon God in two ways: first, inasmuch as it is from Him that it has the form whereby it acts; secondly, inasmuch as it is moved by Him to act” (my emphasis). 14 If the volitional act is not subject to divine causality, it is alike not subject to divine providence. This inference is absolute. St. Thomas does not, of course, envision this causality as violent or external. Rather, the divine causality of the acts of the will is precisely that whereby they are naturally constituted as volitional acts. God causes necessary things necessarily, and contingent things contingently, and the will is denominated as “free” because it is not an operative power prefixed to only one effect, but has for its formal object the universal good as specified by reason. Thomas holds that no finite good may compel the rational will, so that the will is objectively free with respect to its natural finite objects. Yet he also maintains that the rational will cannot proceed to its own act of free self-determination unless moved from potency to act with respect to this act of free self-determination by God. 15 The citations possible for this doctrine of St. Thomas are numerous. But, for instance, see ScG IIIb, chaps. 89–90.The title of chapter 89, is quite clear:“That the Movement of the Will, and Not Only the Power of the Will, is Caused by God.” Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 787 ing the natural law that Thomas’s philosophy and theology prohibit—a way which treats nature and natural law not as manifestations of divine government 16 but as demarcating a zone of independence from divine governance. Nature and reason go from being manifestations and expressions of normative divine order to being antipodes of divine order to which one may appeal in order to “safeguard” human freedom from divine authority. God moves from being the author and perfector of human liberty and virtue to being a threat to authentic human freedom and an alien distortive influence upon morality. The symmetry of these implications with Kantian autonomism is arresting, yet this aspect of the Kantian teaching is a late and secular effect of what is originatively an intraCatholic error. Practically speaking it is an error that removes both moral law and grace from any authoritatively directive role in human life. It is not difficult to see how, given the perspective of such an absolutization of human freedom, the magisterium of the Church with respect to moral life should be received with hostile skepticism as nothing other than an inherently futile and falsifying exertion of raw power over an interiority and freedom natively transcendent of such merely external exactions— or as the ITC document puts it (§77): Further, through the emergence of a metaphysical conception in which human and divine action compete with one another, inasmuch as they are understood univocally and placed, wrongly, on the same level, the legitimate affirmation of the autonomy of the human subject implies that God is excluded from the sphere of human subjectivity. Every reference to something normative coming from God or from nature as an expression of God’s wisdom, every “heteronomy,” is perceived as a threat to the subject’s autonomy.The notion of natural law then appears incompatible with the authentic dignity of the subject. The magisterium’s directions thus come to be viewed in the same way as a bowling league would be were it to issue pronouncements on correct use of the generative powers: at best ultra vires and at worst comically 16 For St.Thomas, the rational creature both passively and actively participates the eternal law. It passively participates this law because its very own nature, act, object, and end are established by the eternal law and received from God as first cause.Yet unlike the case of lower creatures who participate the divine government in a merely passive way—precisely because the rational creature is created, sustained, and actuated as such—it actively participates the eternal law and shares in its own government. Because its passive participation includes the possession of reason, the rational creature receives its ordering from God not merely passively but rationally and preceptively, as giving it reasons to do and not to do. Cf. ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2. 788 Steven A. Long pathetic. Such an error at the root of the spiritual life is manifestly not finally compatible with the Catholic ethos. Yet many, through concessions to modernity and postmodernity on this fundamental point, have exposed the Catholic life to this foundational and destructive error.17 Eventually the project of mere rhetorical and irenic accomodation of mutually exclusive propositions will require that the project of theology as wish fulfillment give way to theology as scientia and sapientia.The ITC document does well to prompt theologians toward the realization that the first—scientia —is essential and necessary, and cannot be replaced by even the most elevated rhetoric. III. The Common Good A brief concluding remark seems in order regarding the document’s treatment of the common good. It speaks (§86) of the common good as corresponding “to a requirement of the social nature of the person,” as defining “the ensemble of values that appear as humanizing for a society” and as expressing not a vague social agreement but based upon and expressing “the requirements of their common humanity.” Surely this is nothing other than the hierarchy of ends as defining the ratio boni, the ends of human nature as a common good. The document states, “The person is therefore prior to society, and society is humanized only if it responds to the expectations inscribed in the person insofar as he is a social being.” Importantly, the sense of this priority is that of the ex natura perfections defining the hierarchy of ends—“the ensemble of values that appear as humanizing for society”—and not any contractarian or autonomist superordination of the individual person to the goods perfective of human nature. The document in addition teaches that natural right is 17 Some authors seem to suppose that the reality of human freedom as lying within rather than without divine causal providence should absolutely require God to overcome every defect of each and every created liberty. But God does not in justice owe it to the defectible creature to overcome every defect even in the proportionate natural order—any more than God owes it to every pear tree that it yield perfect fruit—much less in the order of supernatural fruition whose attainment is the very reality of God Himself.Yet some are more willing implicitly and actually to relativize and reduce to created proportions the exalted perfection of the beatific vision—which is proportionate to no creature whatsoever—than to stress to the wayward wills of men the absolute priority of divine grace and the lesson of humility. It cannot be denied that this unfortunate tendency, articulated in doctrinal terms, has real implications finally inconsistent with acknowledgement of the governance of divine providence and eternal law, whether in the mode of man’s rational participation (the natural law), or man’s graced participation (the life of faith, hope, and charity, and finally of beatific vision). Theology, Divine Governance, and the Common Good 789 derivative rather than foundational, since it is derived from justice in accord with natural law (§89):“Right is not arbitrary: the requirement of justice, which derives from natural law, is prior to every formulation and emancipation of right. It is not right which decides that something is just.” Rights are derived and limited from above by the natural hierarchy of ends, while being derived and limited, from below, by prudence in relation to circumstance: Natural right is never a measure fixed once for all. It is the result of an evaluation of the changing situations in which man lives. It enunciates the judgment of practical reason assessing what is just. Natural right, the juridical expression of the natural law in the political order, thus appears as the measure of the just relations between the members of the community. One observes, however, the need to bring out as clearly as possible the metaphysical dignity of the common good. Granted that there may be certain methodological uses for conceptions of the common good as purely instrumental, in reality the common good is not a mere instrument, but rather a good that of its nature is more communicable to many, more intelligibly irradiant, more universal and rationally diffusive. Far from a mere utility, it represents a noble object of aspiration, striving, and service. Man does not live, breathe, and die for a mere utility or instrumentality. Precisely because the document offers a teleological and metaphysically realistic consideration of the common good, it would be strengthened by a clearer affirmation of N&V the non-instrumental nature of the common good. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 791–824 791 On Nature, Freedom, and Person in Aquinas and Beyond J OHN M. M C D ERMOTT, S.J. Sacred Heart Major Seminary Detroit, Michigan T HE following essay, particularly its analyis of Aquinas’s thought, was first composed in rudimentary form when the author was a member of the sub-committee of the International Theological Commission entrusted with writing a document on the natural law, A la recherche d’une ethique universelle: nouveau regard sur la loi naturelle. Although not all the members agreed entirely with its presentation, it influenced the final composition of the third section, “The Theoretical Foundations of the Natural Law.” While the author might have “tweaked” a few phrases slightly differently, he had no difficulty in approving the whole document and considers that the ITC’s final document and his own views correspond.1 This essay, however, has implications in philosophy and dogma far beyond morality. The Problem The relation between nature and person is quite complex.Various opinions about the identity of each have proliferated in the history of philosophy. In modern times the influence of Galilean-Newtonian physics has led many to imagine “nature” as an inert mass subject to universally deterministic laws. In contrast to that determinism the person is interpreted as a free 1 Besides the document’s foundations in Scripture, tradition, and magisterial docu- ments an attentive reader will also discover the influence of Servais Pinckaers, O.P., (compare his Les Sources de la Morale Chrétien, 3rd ed. [Fribourg: Editions Universitaires, 1993], 406–62 with sections 2.3–4 in the ITC’s document) and Jacques Maritain’s dynamic interpretation of the natural law (cf. Neuf leçons sur les notions premières de la philosophie morale [Paris: Téqui, 1950] and Man and the State [Chicago: U. of Chicago, 1951]).Yet these thinkers were scarcely mentioned in the sub-committee’s discussion. 792 John M. McDermott, S.J. center of activity removed from nature and capable of manipulating its laws.2 This opposition between person and nature not only results in man’s alienation from nature but also introduces irresolvable philosophical dilemmas. How can man influence his world if that world is predetermined by physical laws? Why is man, living in a body, not himself determined by the physical laws? Inversely, if man acts freely, does he not change the course of events and natures off which “natural laws” are read? Does not freedom precede and relativize laws? How is moral action to be determined if nature no longer supplies norms? The breakdown of the Newtonian synthesis in physics has opened the way to a reevaluation of the relation between nature and person. Long before Galileo, St. Thomas offers good guidance in contemplating the mysterious relation of person and nature. Since Aquinas borrows his “natural” foundation from Aristotle, with his “philosopher” our analysis should start. Aristotelian Nature The classical understanding of nature as a principle of motion and rest is expressed well by Aristotle in Physics II, 1 (192b 14–15.21–23) and repeated in Metaphysics V, 4: “Nature in the primary and proper sense is the substance (ousia ) of what have in themselves as such a principle of motion. . . . It is the principle of motion of natural objects inhering somehow, either potentially or really” (1015a 13–19).That definition, however, contains various ambiguities, which are manifest in five previous explications that the definition attempts to summarize. First, nature is understood as “the genesis of growing things,” then as “the first inherent principle from which a growing thing grows,” and, thirdly, as “the source from which the primary movement in each natural being is present in it insofar as it exists as itself ” (1014b 14–20). Already one notices a slight oscillation between the nature itself and its internal principle of motion. As the Physics says,“As many things as have such a principle [of motion], have a nature. And all these are a substance; for there is some subject (hypokeimenon ), and nature is always in a subject” (192b 32–34).Variability is accentuated in the subsequent understandings. Fourthly, “nature 2 For person as a free, self-conscious center of activity cf. Max Müller and Alois Halder, “Person,” in Sacramentum Mundi (New York: Herder & Herder, 1968–70), 4:405; Karl Rahner, S.J.,“Jesus Christ,” in ibid., 3:206; Jacques Maritain, The Person and the Common Good, trans. John Fitzgerald (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame, 1966), 39–41; Luigi Stefanini, “Persona,” in Encyclopedia Filosofica (Venice: Istituto per la Collaborazione Culturale, 1957), 3:1297–1303. This is also the emphasis of Kierkegaard, Barth, Heidegger, Jaspers, and Sartre: cf. Stefanini,“Personalismo,” in Encyclopedia Filosofica, 3:314–16. Of course this “modern” (Rahner) notion of person fits perfectly with Boethius’s naturae rationalis individua substantia. Nature, Freedom, and Person 793 means that out of which any of the beings by nature is or becomes; it is that first which is unorganized (arrythmistos : not reducible to form) and unchangeable from its own potency.” Here Aristotle is referring to the “prime matter” into which forms are introduced in change (192b 27–35).Yet, fifthly, nature is the “substance of beings by nature.” Aristotle specifies this by noting that “nature is the prime matter . . . and also the form and substance; this is the end of the becoming ( genesis : generation)” (Metaphy.V, 4, 1015a 7–11). In commenting on this passage St. Thomas notes that the substantial form gives the name of the species and the shape is the “sign of the species” insofar as the shape “follows the species.” Explaining how the form can be designated “nature,” he observes that the form can be not only the form of the part (forma partis ) but also the form of the whole (forma totius ), or the species, “as if we say that man’s nature is not only the soul but the humanity and the substance which the definition signifies.” Citing Boethius’s definition of nature as “the specific difference informing each thing,”Thomas comments: For the specific difference completes the reality’s substance and gives it a species. As the form or matter is said to be nature because it is the principle of generation, which is said to be nature according to the name’s first application, so the species and substance are said to be nature, which is generation’s goal. For generation is terminated at the species of the one generated, and the species results from the union of form and matter. (In V Metaphysicam, 820–22) Thus one sees that matter, form, and their combination can all be considered in turn “nature.” Furthermore, there is an inherent tension in the form, which both informs the matter and provides the goal of the nature’s becoming as it dynamically penetrates ever more the matter: “since nature means two things: the matter and the form, of which the latter is the end, and since all the rest is for the sake of the end, the form must be the cause in the sense of a final cause (that for the sake of which)” (Phy. II, 1, 193b 12–13; 8, 199a 30–32; Metaphy.V, 4, 1015a 17–19).Thus “the nature understood as becoming ( genesis: origin, generation) is the road toward nature” (Phy. II, 1, 193b 13–14) and “nature is the end and the ‘for the sake of which’ ” (Phy. II, 2, 194a 28–29). Hence a final cause is present in things that by nature come to be or are (Phy. II, 8, 198b 10–12; 199a 7–8); final and formal causes often coincide (Phy. II, 7, 198a 24–25). “Nature is a cause that acts for a end” (Phy. II, 8, 199b 32–33). It joins the “already,” which impresses its form on a nature, to the “not yet” of the goal to which the nature is inherently ordered.The Summa theologiae later summarizes these various tensions and oscillations within the 794 John M. McDermott, S.J. notion of nature understood as a principle of motion: “Because this type of principle is formal or material, matter as well as form is commonly said to be nature.And because the essence of any reality whatever is completed through a form, which its definition signifies, it is called nature.” Indeed, the specific difference, which completes the definition,“is taken from the reality’s proper form” (ST I, q. 29, a. 1, ad 4). Besides the oscillations between form and matter, formal and final causes,“already” and “not yet,” the identity of nature with substance introduces another polarity into the study of natures. Aristotle recognizes the distinction between first, or individual, substance and second substance, which is the qualitative, or formal, part of first substance, to which definition corresponds. For substance, like nature, can apply to the underlying matter, the form, and the combination of the two (Categories 5, 2a 11–3b 23; Metaphy.V, 8, 1017b 10–26;VII, 10, 1035a 1–2;VIII, 1, 1041a 13–b 7; 2, 1043a 26–28; XII, 3, 1070a 9–13). So Aristotle distinguishes substance from substance, “The substance is the form (eidos: shape) present in the reality; from this form and the matter the whole substance is said to be” (Metaphy.VII, 11, 1037a 29–30). Since matter is the principle of diversity among members of the same species while form assures their essential likeness (Metaphy.VII, 8, 1034a 7–8;VIII, 1, 1042a 25–29; De generatione et corruptione I, 3, 318b 15–17), the distinction between first and second substance (nature) depends upon seeing the abstracted universal as somehow identical with the composite of matter and form, yet also diverse from the same composite. This unity in diversity of matter and form means that substance and nature can be considered either universally or particularly. Indeed Aristotle’s considerations of substance and nature often slide back and forth from the universal to the particular: “sometimes it escapes notice whether the name signifies the composite substance or the act (energeia) and the form” (Metaphy.VIII, 3, 1043a 29–30). If truth is to be attained, the form known by abstraction must represent the concrete nature known, yet the abstraction in the mind is not the same as the concrete, material substance. So nature and substance can be understood in terms of a universal form or of a particular matter.Yet Aristotle realizes that all abstractions from material instances are not identical with those instances; no universal definition or demonstration can apply to individual substances, even though the universal forms actually exist in matter (Metaphy.VII, 11, 1036b 21–32; 1037a 5–10; 13, 1038b 8–16; 1039a 14–19). Aristotle sees that in universals like “man” and “horse” it is impossible to abstract fully from matter; thus there is no definition of a concrete, material whole (Metaphy. VII, 10, 1035b 27–31; 11, 1036a 2–6; 11, 1036b 2–7.21–30). For St. Thomas and later Nature, Freedom, and Person 795 Scholastics such abstracted forms as “man” are known in relation to the sensible phantasms from which they are abstracted and the matter remains implicit in universal definitions as “common matter” in distinction from individuating matter (ST I, q. 75, a. 4c; q. 85, a. 1, ad 2).3 Precisely because first substance contains matter, it can be identified also as a nature. Insofar as motion is defined as “the act of the potency” (Phy. III, 1, 201b 10–11; 2–3, 202a 6–15; Metaphy. XI, 9, 1065b 14–1066a 34), it involves both potency and act. Act is the equivalent of form as potency is of matter (Metaphy. VIII, 6, 1045a 24–25; IX, 8, 1050b 2–3; XIII, 10, 1087a 16–17). Matter is unlimited (aoriston: indefinite: Metaphy. VII, 11, 1037a 27; XIII, 10, 1087a 16–17) or infinite (Phy. III, 7, 207b 34–208a 3) and equivalently “non-being” (cf. Metaphy. IX, 10, 1051a 34–1051b 1; XII, 2, 1069b 14–34; XIII, 10, 1087a 16–17; XIV, 2, 1089a 26–30), existing not in itself but only potentially in relation to a form, which it “desires” (Phy. I, 9, 192a 20–23; II, 1, 194b 8–9; III, 6, 206b 14–16; De gen. et cor. I, 5, 320b 16–17; Metaphy.VIII, 6, 1045a 23–24; XII, 5, 1071a 10–11). “The infinite is the matter of the perfection of size, and it is a whole in potency but not in act. . . .As infinite it is does not contain but is contained.Therefore the infinite is also unknowable. For matter has no form (eidos)” (Phy. III, 6, 207a 21–26). As non-being it cannot change or be moved (Phy.V, 1, 225a 10–12.20–23; De gen. et cor. II, 1, 329a 26–27; Metaphy. XI, 1067b 30); change needs limits and matter has no limits (Phy. VI, 10, 240a 27–b 12); as a formless infinite, it can exist only within the limits of form (Phy. III, 6 206b 12–16). Since it is unlimited, it also has no directions (cf. Phy. IV, 8, 215a 7–9). As potency matter is not subject to becoming;“for if it came to be, there would have to be some existing first from which it came,” whereas matter is “for each thing the first subject from which something comes to be and which exists not accidentally” (Phy. I, 9, 192a 27–32). For its part a pure form would have nothing toward which it might move, and it cannot be affected by other things (Metaphy.VII, 8, 1033b 19–29; De gen. et cor. I, 7, 324b 15–16). “Neither form nor matter comes to be” (Metaphy. XII, 3, 1069b 35).Yet “in everything that becomes, matter is present” (Metaphy.VII, 8, 1033b19–20). Only 3 Cf. John Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: Catholic University, 2000), 330–33, where a corporeal essence includes matter as well as form; also 351–75, for Thomas’s hesitations on designating the ultimate principle of individuality. Robert O’Donnell, C.S.P.,“Individuation:An Example of the Development in the Thought of St.Thomas Aquinas,” New Scholasticism 33 (1959): 49–67, earlier noted the development but wound up rooting the individuality of material composites in the substantial form instead of matter signed by quantity. Paradoxically the form, the principle of universality, grounds individuality. 796 John M. McDermott, S.J. in the conjunction of matter and form do becoming and motion occur, and only in this composite understanding can matter be said to be that out of which natural becomings come to be (Metaphy.VII, 7, 1032a 15–17).4 A final tension should be mentioned. Since every change involves continuity and discontinuity, not annihilation and creation, nature and substance can also be contrasted to each other. As “a principle of motion and change” (Phy. III. 1, 200b 12), nature is clearly dynamic. But substance can be understood as “the ultimate subject (hypokeimenon)” underlying change (Metaphy. V, 8 1017b 23–24: VIII, 1, 1042a 32–b 5). Here it is considered a more static element. Since, however, nature and substance can be identified—Thomas notes,“As is clear from Metaphysics V, substance has a double appellation: in one way it is essence or nature, in another way it stands for supposite or hypostasis” (ST III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 3)—a paradoxical oscillation or tension between its static and dynamic moments results. Beyond these meanings Aristotle also extends the meaning of “nature” to include all substances (Metaphy.V, 4, 1015a 11–13).This would apparently include inanimate substances since for Aristotle the basic elements and the simple bodies move themselves to their natural places of rest (Phy.VIII, 4, 255b 8–21; De caelo II, 13, 295b 20–23; III, 2, 300a 20–301b 32; IV, 1, 308a 23–33; 3, 310b 23–311a 7; 4, 311b 15–312a 8; De gen. et cor. II, 2, 330b 31–34).5 Clearly “nature” is an analogous concept.This insight is important for the acknowledgment of natural law. For there is a necessary connection between a nature’s form and its end. As Thomas maintains, the form is a reality’s principle of action: “Anything whatever acts according to the exigency of its form, which is the principle of action and the norm for the work” (In III Sent., d. 27, q. 1, a. 1c). Natural things, indeed all agents, act by their form (ST I, q. 15, a. 1c; q. 42, a. 1, ad 1). Aristotle’s universe has one final goal: the Prime Mover, or God (Metaphy. XIII, 4, 1070b 34–35; 7, 1072b 3–4; 10, 1075a 13–19; b 34–1076a 4). Since in an interconnected universe “all things are ordered toward one (end),” “God and nature make nothing in vain,” and “there is a final cause in what happens 4 On the paradoxical notion of matter in Aristotle and Aquinas cf. John McDer- mott, S.J., “The Mystery of Matter,” Angelicum 87 (2010): 993–1014. 5 Aristotle’s universe is almost alive. In Phy. VIII, 1, 250b 14 he describes the universe’s eternal movement “as a sort of life” (oion zoe tis ) to all natural things and accepts the comparison of the universe to an animal in ibid., 2, 252b 17–28 and 253a 7–20; for “motion is the natural state” (ibid., 3, 253b 9) and animals are self-moving (ibid., 4, 254b 12–19).Yet Phy.VIII 4, 255a 1–19 denies to heavy and light things the internal motion proper to living realities. A similarly organic, living universe is postulated by Friedrich Schelling, System of Transcendental Idealism (1800), trans. Peter Heath (Charlottesville: U. of Virginia, 1978), 124–27. Nature, Freedom, and Person 797 by nature” (Metaphy. XII, 1075a 19–20; XI, 8, 1065a 26–27; De caelo I, 4: 271a 34), one would expect natures to attain their end.That, however, is not always the case. Aristotle acknowledges accidents (contingent events), where the purpose of nature is not attained but monstrosities occur; impediments to nature’s fulfillment can occur (Phy. II, 8, 199a 2–11.33–b 4). In accidental occurrences chance (or spontaneity) is recognized as an accidental or “indefinite” cause, not a definite cause in the strict sense; such a cause is “unclear to man” (Phy. II, 5, 197a 8–14; Metaphy. V, 30, 1025a 24–25). For chance, which is opposed to what is or becomes always or usually, proceeds from matter, which is the “cause” equally of something’s existence or non-existence (De caelo I, 12, 283a 34–b 5). Hence in contrast to chance, which is disorderly, nature produces its results “for the most part” or “without exception” (Magna Moralia II, 8, 1207a 2; b 19). The “for the most part” allows for failure in individual cases. Matter, which is always capable of being otherwise, is the cause of the accidental (Metaphy. VI, 2, 1027a 13–15; VII, 7, 1032a 20–22). Conversely, since “matter is unknowable in itself ” (Metaphy.VII, 10, 1036a 8–9) and science is of what is always or is for the most part, the contingent falls outside the realm of science (Metaphy.VI, 2, 1027a 19–28). It is “something close to non-being” (ibid. 1026b 21). A principal paradoxical element in this understanding of nature derives from the role of matter. On the one hand, unless matter were joined to form, there would be no motion and hence no nature to be studied. On the other, matter is unintelligible to man, and thus he is prevented from fully understanding existing singular substances and motion itself. As a combination of form and matter, act and potency, being neither act nor potency but both, motion’s reality is incomplete; hence “it is difficult to grasp what it is” (Metaphy. XI, 9, 1066a 17–31). St. Thomas’s World St.Thomas takes Aristotle’s basic understanding of nature and expands it to fit his Christian Weltanschauung.Thomas’s God is more than Aristotle’s pure form, or thought thinking himself: He is the infinite, omnipotent Creator of heaven and earth, whose knowledge extends to every material singular (ST I, q. 14, a. 11c et ad 1; q. 22, a. 2c).6 Hence nothing escapes His will (I, q. 19, a. 6c).To allow for God’s infinity both transcending the finite order and allowing Him to intervene freely in it,Thomas postulates an order of esse alongside the order of Aristotelian essences.This existential order allows 6 All subsequent references to Thomas’s works in our main text are continuous, i.e., unless otherwise noted, the numbers refer to the work previously cited or referred to. 798 John M. McDermott, S.J. him to distinguish angels from each other without appeal to Franciscan “spiritual matter.” Furthermore it explains how the judgment in returning to the phantasm can be man’s highest intellectual act, the act in which truth is attained (I, q. 16, a. 2c); instead of affirming beyond form its juncture with matter, which is unintelligible to man, now judgment affirms the act of existence, the deeper intelligibility undergirding the form-matter composite. In addition to these enlarged philosophical insights Thomas knows that through the Incarnation a supernatural order of redemption and grace has been grafted into a fallen natural order. Man’s way of attaining God is no longer principally by contemplation but by love, specifically by believing and loving God’s only Son (I–II, q. 5, a. 7, ad 2; II–II, q. 23, a. 6c; III, prol.; q. 1, a. 2c; q. 3, a. 9c). In an historical economy of salvation the accent falls upon love beyond knowledge (I, q. 82, a. 3c). All of these expansions and additions introduce further tensions into a basic Aristotelian understanding of nature. Let us enumerate some of them. First, nature is more than both a singular instance, understood statically or dynamically, and an abstraction. In trying to explain original sin’s propagation, the Summa theologiae considers all Adam’s children as “one man insofar as they unite (convenient) in the nature which they receive from the first parent”; since they are as many members of the one body moved freely by the first parent, original sin appears as a “sin of nature” (I–II, q. 81, a. 1c). Though the disorder in willing was due to the will of Adam, he moves by generation all who derive from his origin.The basic principle is this:“what pertain to the nature of the species are passed on by parents into children unless there is a defect of nature.” Just as original justice was to be passed on through generation, so the disorder of original sin, which corrupts nature, is passed on (q. 81, a. 2c; 4c).The infection derives from the nature’s origin (q. 83, a. 4, ad 2).This aspect may have been implicit in Aristotle insofar as his first understanding of nature recognized that “nature” (physis) derives from “to beget or engender” (phyo) or the passive “to be born from” (phyesthai) (Metaphy.V, 4, 1014b 16–18).Thomas recognizes this meaning on account of the relation between natura and nascere (ST I, q. 29, a. 1, ad 4; III, q. 2, a. 1c). Certainly it shows an awareness that “nature” involves the concrete whole of the species, not merely individuals who happen to possess a common form.7 7 Thomas is not always consistent on this point; in ST I, q. 39, a. 4, ad 3 he writes: “The unity or community of human nature corresponds not to reality, but to a way of thinking (secundum considerationem ); hence the term “man” does not stand for the common nature unless a modifier (additum ) requires it, as when one says, ‘man is a species.’ ” Nature, Freedom, and Person 799 Second, given that God is a creator who works through efficient as well as final causality (I, q. 2, a. 3), all of irrational creation is seen as an instrument directed by the principal Agent, moving it like an artist and directing it to an end (I–II, q. 6, a. 1, ad 3).This universal nature need not be considered an inert mass, but has its own innate, active power (I–II, q. 85, a. 6c). For God creates the natures with an innate tendency or appetite (I–II, q. 26, a. 1c). “Nature is nothing but the reasonable cause (ratio) of a certain art, specifically God’s art, imparted to realities by which the realities themselves are moved to a determined end” (In II Phy. 14). Yet, because the divine knowing is infinite, one with His will, and non-discursive, it cannot be used as a middle term in deducing conclusions about finite results of His knowledge (ST I, q. 14, a. 1c et ad 3; 2c; q. 3, a. 1; a. 7c; a. 8c et ad 1, 3; 14c et ad 1, 2). Thus He can seek the good of nature as a whole by allowing the corruption and defect of individual natures (I, q. 22, a. 2, ad 2). Third, even though man cannot perceive the end intended by God, Thomas does not wish to deny the intelligible finality impressed on every creature. Without that finality the “way” to affirming God’s existence in terms of final causality would be destroyed (I, q. 2, a. 3). “The natural necessity inhering in realities that are determined to one (end) is a certain impression of God who is directing them to the end” (I, q. 103, a. 1, ad 3). This necessity is traced back to the form, whereas contingency is ascribed to matter. Even the most contingent reality has something of necessity in it.Thus the human mind by abstracting particular material instances attains “universal and necessary reasons.” But Thomas realizes that even this abstract necessity is relative to the particular instances from which it is derived. “Hence if universal reasons for realities that can be known are considered, all sciences concern what are necessary. If, however, the realities themselves are considered, some sciences deal with what are necessary, others with what are contingent” (I, q. 86, a. 3c). So in all real material beings there is an oscillation between necessity and contingency, reflecting their hylomorphic composition.This supports the oscillation of analogy between God’s and man’s knowledge of impressed ends. Fourth, since human freedom is central to Christianity, the universe cannot be rigidly determined.While it is true that “nature is determined to one (end)” because of the single form informing the nature and, hence, irrational creatures possess an “operative potency determined to one end,” man on the basis of his free will is master of his own acts and thus directs himself to his own end: “The will is not determined to one (end)”; nonetheless it does not escape divine providence (I, q. 22, a. 2, ad 4; q. 41, a. 2c; q. 83, a. 1c; q. 92, a. 2, ad 2; q. 103, a. 5c et ad 2, 3; I–II, q. 1, a. 2c). (This accords with Aristotle’s position that rational beings can produce 800 John M. McDermott, S.J. contrary effects: Metaphy. IX, 2, 1046b 4–5; 5, 1048a 8–9.) This indeterminacy in choice occurs even though the nature’s basic love or inclination is not divorced from the will: “In an intellectual nature the natural inclination is found to be according to the will” (I, q. 60, a. 1c). The will is recognized as a potency, or faculty, of the soul, which in union with the body constitutes human nature and is the subject of the potencies that function as its proximate principles of operation (I, q. 75, a. 1c et ad 1; a. 4c; 77, q. 1, aa. 3–5; a. 6c et ad 2; q. 78, aa. 1c, 4c).While it might be possible to reconcile natural necessity with freedom by pointing out that nature’s end-directedness need only be “for the most part” (I, q. 103, a. 1c), thus allowing with Aristotle for the interference inherent in matter, Thomas chooses a better way. Even though the will can be distinguished from and even opposed to nature, it is ultimately rooted in nature: The will is distinguished from (dividitur contra) nature as one cause from another: for some things happen naturally, other voluntarily. However there is a different manner of causing proper to the will, which is master of its own act, beyond the manner which is appropriate to nature, which is determined to one goal. But because the will is grounded in some nature, the motion proper to nature necessarily participates in the will: just as what is due to a prior cause is participated in by a subsequent cause. For in every single reality esse itself, which is through nature, is prior to willing, which is through the will. This explains why the will naturally wills something. (I–II, q. 10, a. 1, ad 1) Thomas balances the will as nature with the will as free by distinguishing the necessary object of the will, happiness, from the objects, or goods, short of that end which are subject to free choice.The final end is given by nature, the intermediate goods are subject to the will’s free choice (I, q. 82, a. 1c et ad 1, 3; a. 2c et ad 1, 2; I–II, q. 5, a. 4, ad 2). Thomas also distinguishes the former’s act as willing from the latter’s as choosing, the former faculty as voluntas, or voluntas ut natura, from the latter as liberum arbitrium, or voluntas ut ratio, but insists that they are one faculty (I, q. 83, a. 4c et ad 1, 2; I–II, q. 6, a. 4c; III, q. 18, a. 3c).Thus he attempts to hold human freedom within the bounds of nature and preserve his arguments from finality. But underlying tensions remain. Fifth, in his famous Surnaturel H. de Lubac shows how Thomas understands angelic freedom as something transcending the necessity of nature. He has to allow the possibility of sin in a creature without matter, which in man impedes insight. The problem is already identified by his predecessors: if, according to Aristotle, the intellect, whether theoretical or practical, cannot err about its proper object, it surely does not err about Nature, Freedom, and Person 801 the good and the true, especially about its own preeminent good. How then can an angel sin? Thomas insists that a creature, created from nothing, cannot be impeccable—only God is impeccable by nature—even though the creature has a natural love for his Creator.The very potency implied in that love distinguishes him from God. Hence, according to de Lubac,Thomas distinguishes: “The angel naturally moves himself toward God insofar as God is the author of his natural being, but not insofar as God is the author of his supernatural beatitude.” But the natural love opens toward a greater, supernatural love whereby the angel has to choose freely to accept God supernaturally or not.Thus two regions are postulated, one natural, or necessary, the other free, or voluntary. There has to be a choice or a “conversion” to enter into the supernatural order to which the creature is called by nature. For the supernatural order is the order of freedom. Hence the angel is naturally peccable but can only attain his end in the supernatural vision of God.8 Sixth, even in the case of man there is a tension between his nature and his actual supernatural calling. Insofar as God is man’s and the universe’s final cause, there should be a proportion between man’s end and his nature “because the end responds to the beginning ( principium: principle)” (I–II, q. 2, a. 5, ad 3). But God’s infinity seems to destroy any proportion (cf. I, q. 12, a. 2, obj. 4; I–II, q. 2, a. 8, obj. 3): “No created intellect can know God infinitely” nullus autem intellectus creatus potest Deum infinite cognoscere (I, q. 12, a. 7c et ad 1). Thomas oscillates in his characterization of man’s final natural end, at times proposing “universal good” or “good in the universal,” which can be understood as an abstract good grasped by the intellect as parallel to the “universal true” or the “common true” (I–II, q. 1, a. 2, ad 3; q. 2, a. 7c; q. 5, a. 1c; a. 8c et ad 2; q. 10, a. 1, ad 3); at other times the same end or universal good is identified with God Himself (I, q. 105, a. 4c; q. 106, a. 2; I–II, q. 2, a. 3c; a. 8c et ad 1–3; q. 3, a. 1c; q. 5, a. 3c; q. 9, a. 6c).Yet the possession of God as supreme good in the beatific vision is purely supernatural, surpassing every natural principle and power (I–II, q. 5, a. 5c et ad 1). Seventh, the previous oscillation is linked to Thomas’s distinction between essence and existence. Since the concrete nature which knows is an existential nature and its natural intellectual operation attains the truth in a judgment, which affirms the existence of an object, the concrete man is naturally more than an essence or nature. His active intellect, which ultimately produces the judgment, must refer to the existential order, which 8 Henri de Lubac, S.J., Surnaturel (Paris: Aubier, 1946), 219–60, esp. 246, 254. For the development of this insight in his other works cf. John McDermott, S.J.,“De Lubac and Rousselot,” Gregorianum 78 (1977): 740–58. 802 John M. McDermott, S.J. God, pure esse and First Truth (I, q. 3, a. 4c; q. 16, a. 5c; II–II, q. 4, a. 2, ad 3), grounds. So the agent intellect participates in the divine intellect, from which it receives its light (I, q. 12, a. 2c). Since the divine intellect and the divine esse are identical (I, q. 14, a. 4c), the agent intellect participates already in God to whom it is referred. Insofar as the intellect’s judgment is a motion, that is, a conversion to the phantasm involving composition and division (I, q. 84, a. 7c; q. 85, a. 5c et ad 1–3), it refers to God as its ultimate termination; thus it desires God as the fulfillment of its motion. But the God so desired is not an abstract God; for a judgment goes beyond the subject of the sentence, be it an abstract concept or a concrete indexical referent, to existence.9 The judgment refers to and seeks the one God who is to be attained immediately in Himself. So there is a natural desire to see God in Himself, a natural desire for the supernatural vision (I, q. 12, a. 1c; I–II, q. 3, a. 8c; Summa contra Gentes III, cc. 50–57; Compendium theologiae I, cc. 3, 103–6; etc.). Nature at once is nature and strains beyond the bounds of nature.10 Thomas can clearly distinguish natural and supernatural orders by their end: the natural end is “proportionate to a created nature which the created 9 Karl. Rahner, S.J., Geist in Welt (Innsbruck: Rauch, 1938), 82–83, notes that there cannot be an “it” without a universal concept, i.e., a judgment must have as its subject a noun which is abstract (even if it has an internal reference to matter: cf. John McDermott, S.J., “Dialectical Analogy: The Oscillating Center of Rahner’s Thought,” Gregorianum 75 [1994]: 680–86), but the late Maritain, “Réflections sur la nature blessée,” Approches sans entraves (Paris: Fayard, 1973), 264–72, esp. 270–72, allows for an existential basic judgment without and before an abstraction. On this point Rahner seems to be correct, since an indeterminate “it” or “that” refers ultimately to the prime matter, which as infinite cannot be distinguished from existence. Maritain may have been trying to avoid the paradox that the concept of being is included implicitly as subject in the existential judgment producing the concept of being; thus the concept of being would be both a part and the totality of the judgment: cf. Existence and the Existent, trans. Lewis Galantiere and Gerald Phelan (1948; rpt. Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1975), 22–35, esp. nn. 13 and 14.There can be no perception of matter without a simultaneous perception of form.That insight seems clear from the experience of Helen Keller as quoted and elucidated by Ernst Cassirer, An Essay on Man (1944; rpt. New Haven:Yale, 196), 33–41. 10 William O’Connor, The Eternal Quest (New York: Longmans, Green, 1947), 7–23, examines all Thomas’s texts about the natural desire for the supernatural. His own interpretation that the desire is an imperfect act of tendency which arises in the intellect after it has attained knowledge of God’s existence (181–83) does not quite convince, since the intellect per se is not a desire. Moreover it seems more an elicited than a natural desire.Transcendental Thomists place the natural desire for the supernatural at the foundation of their theologies, allowing an amalgamation of intellect and will: cf. John McDermott, S.J.,“The Theology of John Paul II:A Response,” in Nature, Freedom, and Person 803 reality can attain according to the power of its own nature,” whereas the beatific vision “exceeds the proportion and capacity ( facultas) of a created nature” (ST I, q. 23, a. 1c). Likewise, alongside the natural desire to see God in Himself, he affirms that “the natural desire of a rational creature is to know all those things which pertain to the intellect’s perfection; and these are the species and genera of things and their reasons (rationes)” (I, q. 12, a. 8, ad 4). Correspondingly “the first and proper object of the [human] intellect” is identified as “the quiddity of the thing itself,” or, more precisely,“the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter” (I, q. 85, a. 5c; q. 84, a. 7c). For knowing its proper object, the essence of a thing, what it is, constitutes the intellect’s perfection (I–II, q. 3, a. 8c). Corresponding to the oscillation between God and finite natures as the intellect’s proper object is Thomas’s oscillation on the meaning of truth. On the one hand truth is seen as the con-form-ity of the intellect with the object known (I, q. 16, a. 8c et ad 3).“Our intellect is true insofar as it is conformed to its principle, viz., the realities from which it receives knowledge” (I, q. 16, a. 6).This apparently consists in the mind’s possession of the form of the reality known: Since every reality is true insofar as it has the proper form of its nature, the intellect, insofar as it knows, is necessarily true insofar as it has the likeness of the thing known, which is its form insofar as it knows. Therefore truth is defined through the conformity of intellect and reality. (I, q. 16, a. 2c) Yet, on the other hand,Thomas is well aware of Aristotle’s view that truth is in judgment (ScG I, c. 59; Metaphy. IV, 7, 1011b 25–29, 1012a 1–29;VI, 4, 1027b 18–34). He allows for that in the passage immediately following the previous quotation as he discusses how “the intellect can know its conformity to the intelligible reality”: “Nevertheless it does not apprehend this [conformity] insofar as it knows about something what something is, but when it judges that a reality is such as is the form which it apprehends about the reality; then it first knows and speaks what is true. And it does this by composing and dividing.”That will lead to the conclusion: Therefore truth can indeed be in sensation or in the intellect knowing what something is, as in some true reality, but not as the known in the knower, which bears the name of the true; for the perfection of the The Thought of Pope John Paul II (Rome: Gregorian, 1993), 63–64, n. 36, for references to the basic “paradox” in Rousselot, Maréchal, Lonergan, Alfaro, Rahner, de Lubac, von Balthasar, and Mouroux. But they never explain why the paradox is only an apparent contradiction. 804 John M. McDermott, S.J. intellect is the true as known.And therefore, properly speaking, truth is in the intellect composing and dividing, but not in sensation nor in the intellect knowing what something is. (Cf. also ST I, q. 16, a. 4, ad 2; De veritate I, 3c) The priority of judgment accords with Thomas’s emphasis on the existential order which is affirmed in judgment:“Truth is grounded more in a reality’s esse than in the quiddity” (In I Sent., d. 19, q. 5, a. 1c).Yet the “truths” of both concept and judgment are reconciled insofar as human truth is based on the realities known and their truth consists in their accord with the mind of the Creator (ST I, q. 16, a. 3, ad 2, 3; a. 5c et ad 2; q. 21, a. 2c).Thus all truth is grounded in God whose knowing is existential, yet insofar as His truth transcends judgment’s plurality it is more like man’s simple apprehension (I, q. 16, a. 5c et ad 1). “God, according to His simple intelligence, possesses that perfection of knowledge which our intellect possesses through the knowledge of complex objects and the knowledge of simple objects ( per utramque cognitionem et complexorum et incomplexorum )” (ScG I, c. 59). In God the simplicity and unity of infinite esse is reconciled with a plurality of ideas (ST I, q. 3, a. 7c; q. 11, a. 3c; a. 4c; q. 15, a. 1c et ad 3; a. 2c et ad 1, 2).11 On Freedom Given the complexity of the understanding of “nature,” it is hardly surprising that the notion of freedom should be neither straightforward nor simple.Two principal understandings can be readily identified.12 The first, liberty of indifference or free choice, called in Latin liberum arbitrium (which can refer to the faculty as well as the decision), has been mentioned above. It presupposes a distinction between will and intellect, the will’s formal object being the good (I, q. 19, a. 3c), which characterizes the end sought (I, q. 6, a. 2, ad 2; q. 19, a. 1, ad 1), and the intellect’s formal object, the true (I, q. 16, a. 3, ad 3; a. 4, ad 2; q. 59, a. 2, ad 2; I–II, q. 3, a. 7c). Since the will is guided by the intellect, which knows the universal true as a universal good (I, q. 59, a. 3c; q. 82, a. 3, ad 2; a. 4c et ad 1; q. 83, a. 3c et ad 2), the will is not restricted to any particular finite good (I–II, q. 13, a. 2c). It has power over its own acts and is thus capable of choosing opposites (I, q. 83, 11 Cf. Eileen Sweeney, “Thomas Aquinas’ Double Metaphysics of Simplicity and Infinity,” International Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1993): 287–317, for Thomas’s balance between transcendental oneness and plurality. 12 Other notions of freedom: independence, doing what one feels like doing, and following reason, can also be found in Thomas’s thought, but they are subordinate to these two principal notions: cf. John McDermott, S.J., “The Mystery of Freedom,” Lateranum 74 (2008): 493–542. Nature, Freedom, and Person 805 a. 1c), even, it is said at times, choosing between good and evil: “Liberum arbitrium maintains itself in indifference between choosing well or choosing badly” (I, q. 83, a. 2c; I–II, q. 114, a. 9c). In the actual choice the intellect acts like a form, the will like matter informed by the intellect (I–II, q. 13, a. 1c).The principal difficulty with this schema resides in its inability to offer a reason for the actual choice. Since none of the finite goods presented as possible objects of choice to the intellect can fill the whole horizon of possible goods, the final choice of the intellect seems to be arbitrary. A secondary difficulty concerns the object of the will’s natural appetite. Since the will’s object is not internal to the faculty, as the true is to the intellect, but is an external good (I, q. 19, a. 1, ad 3; q. 82, a. 3c), that is, a concrete actually existing good, it is hard to see how a “universal good” can serve as the will’s object. If it is abstract, it is not exterior to the knowerlover; if it is concrete, it must be God Himself. Then the difficulty again arises about a natural desire to possess God in Himself, a supernatural goal. A third difficulty attaches to the reconciliation of divine omnipotence with human freedom. Insofar as man is seen as master of his acts, an apparently independent center of activity, how can that independence be reconciled with God’s omnipotent providence? For the will is not sufficient to move itself unless it be moved by God (I, q. 83, aa. 2–4). The debates between Molinists and Bañezians mark the impossibility of resolving the question as it is formulated.13 Perhaps the question has been improperly formulated. A second understanding of freedom can be labeled Pauline or Augustinian. The will has been created to choose the good. The choice of evil not only contradicts God’s intention (I, q. 63, a. 1c) but also is hard to explain insofar as evil is nothing in itself ( per essentiam) but only the privation of a good, or the lack of a good which it should have (I, q. 49, a. 1c; 3c et ad 4; q. 65, a. 1, ad 2, 3). As such evil has no proper cause; it occurs only by accident (I, q. 49, a. 1c; q. 3, a. 5; I–II, q. 75, a. 1c).A privation cannot be directly chosen. It does not exist in itself but only in a good subject (I, q. 48, a. 3c).When God frees a fallen will from its subjugation to sin, then it becomes free in the choice of the good. This freedom is inherently 13 The sixteenth century’s end and the whole seventeenth century were filled with the controversy de auxiliis between Bañezian and Molinist theologians, whom successive popes had to interdict from accusing each other of heresy (DS 1997, 2008, 2170–71). In 1748 Benedict XIV again had to intervene to impose peace and silence (DS 2564). Cf. Christian Pesch, S.J., Praelectiones Dogmaticae, V (Freiburg: Herder, 1916), 346–63; Hermann Lange, S.J., De Gratia, 2nd ed. (Valkenburg: St. Ignatius, 1926), 331–37. Also cf. John McDermott, S.J., “The Neo-Scholastic Analysis of Freedom,” International Philosophical Quarterly 34 (1994): 149–65, and “Mystery of Freedom,” 517–25, for a longer explication of the inherent difficulties of this analysis of freedom. 806 John M. McDermott, S.J. dynamic.“Sin is contrary to natural reason; consequently freedom from sin is a true freedom, which is joined to the servitude to justice since through both man tends toward what is appropriate to him (quod est conveniens sibi)” (II–II, q. 183, a. 4c). For Thomas there is no opposition between freedom and the necessity of the end:“Of necessity the will inheres in the ultimate end, which is beatitude” (I, q. 82, a. 1c).This holds not only with regard to the end but also with regard to the means.To choose a disordered means is not freedom but its lack:“It belongs to the perfection of its freedom that liberum arbitrium can choose diverse things, if the order to the goal is preserved; but to choose something by turning aside from the order to the goal, which is to sin, belongs to freedom’s defect. Hence there is greater liberum arbitrium in the angels who cannot sin than in us who can sin” (I, q. 62, a. 8, ad 3).The blessed cannot not love God (I, q. 60, a. 5, ad 5), and freedom of choice is not denied to them (III, q. 18, a. 4, ad 3). Likewise, since God is free and cannot sin (I, q. 49, a. 2c; q. 63, a. 1c), the capacity to sin does not essentially belong to freedom.“Just as inability to sin does not diminish freedom, so also the necessity of a will rendered firm toward the good does not diminish freedom: as this is clear in the case of God and the blessed” (II–II, q. 88, a. 4, ad 1).That is why a vow does not limit freedom; rather, Thomas quotes Augustine praising “the happy necessity which compels to do the better.” Earlier Thomas notes how the possibility of choosing evil is not really freedom: Although liberum arbitrium can turn to good and evil, nonetheless of itself it is ordered to the good; therefore what hinders it in doing good, simply hinders and corrupts it; for that reason freedom from what hinders is said simply to be freedom, and this is freedom from sin; what hinders it from doing evil, which corrupts it, only accidentally (secundum quid ) impedes it. (In II Sent., d. 25, q. 3, a. 5, ad 2) Such a schema, whereby man chooses goods insofar as they are participations in the Supreme Good, allows for the reconciliation of human freedom and divine omnipotence: man chooses any good in the attraction of the Supreme Good, the source in which limited goods participate and of which they are likenesses (ST I, q. 6, a. 1c et ad 2; a. 2c et ad 2; a. 4c; q. 44, a. 3c; q. 60, a. 5c).The obvious difficulty with such a view is that it obviates the need for choice at all. It is impossible to explain how one can choose evil, which is nothing positive. Since evil, as a privation of good, only “exists in” a good, making it a lesser good, any choice would involve the lesser good, which as good still participates in the Supreme Good. Thus the choice of the good, though lesser, would still implicitly involve the choice of God (I, q. 44, a. 4, ad 3). Moreover, if freedom Nature, Freedom, and Person 807 consists ultimately in the choice of the good, God could have created man free and impeccable, and the whole justification for God’s permission of sin in Paradise would fall away. Furthermore, impeccable man would be like God; but it is impossible that a creature, who is not the measure of the good, should be equated with the good itself. As long as any intelligent creature is distant from God, the possibility of turning from Him is real (I, q. 63, a. 1c).14 Clearly these two understandings of freedom balance each other off. Liberty of indifference remains static, motionless and ineffective, unless the actual movement of choice is applied to it.Augustinian liberty, which starts with the will as a dynamic power oriented to its end, remains incapable of changing direction, of actually making a choice, unless it can win a certain distance from its own dynamism through the intellect’s abstractive power, a power at the basis of freedom of indifference. Furthermore, these two notions of freedom correspond to “nature” understood as dynamic and to its equivalent “substance,” the persistent static substrate of change.15 A further point of juncture between “nature” and “freedom” can be found in the underlying notion of matter. As we saw earlier, motion, which is so difficult to grasp, happens because of matter, in itself unintelligible; only insofar as matter is joined to form can motion come about. Matter also is responsible for the distinction between first and second substance and the intellect’s oscillation between those two understandings. Matter plays a similarly central role in human freedom. Its very unintelligibility prevents the world from being reduced to a determinist, rationalistic schema: the individual as such is not subject to science. Indeed, since choice is a motion, going beyond static contemplation, matter is also at the 14 Admittedly Thomas attributes sin, on the one hand, to error or ignorance and, on the other, to the choice of a good “without the order of an owed measure or rule” insofar as there is “only the absence of consideration of what should be considered” (ST I, q. 63, a. 1, ad 4). But ignorance and error excuse from sin while mere lack of due consideration concerns the intellect alone, not the will in which sin is located. Such an evasion presupposes a clear distinction of intellect and will. Cf. John McDermott, S.J.,“Metaphysical Conundrums at the Root of Moral Disagreement,” Gregorianum 71 (1990): 717–32, 736–40, and “Mystery of Freedom,” 525–31, for a criticism of the choice of evil and the transcendental Thomist understanding of freedom. 15 Romano Guardini, Der Gegensatz (Mainz: Grüünewald, 1925), 209–20, notes the need of uniting in complementarity the double notion of freedom; this insight finds its place within a universe of polar opposites. Similarly the complementarity of polar opposites is upheld by Erich Przywara, S.J., Analogia Entis, 2nd ed. (Einsiedeln: Johannes, 1962) and Hans Urs von Balthasar, Theologic: I.The Truth of the World, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2000); both thus make room for freedom. 808 John M. McDermott, S.J. root of freedom’s choice.Yet matter alone suffices to explain freedom as little as it explains motion. As for motion so also for freedom, form is required. Man needs the abstract intelligibility of form in order to guide his choice and win distance from the immediacy of his desires. Otherwise he is blind in identifying the possible objects of choice.Thus the structures of motion, substance, and freedom reflect the tension in man’s hylomorphic composition. To understand these mysteries man has to approach reality from various perspectives. He must oscillate between formal and material as well as static and dynamic aspects in order to approximate reality and leave himself open to the mystery of freedom.16 Before leaving the topic of freedom,Thomas’s treatment of God’s freedom should be mentioned. In God are found exemplified in a superlative way both types of freedom. As supreme Good immediately present to Himself, God can be said to love Himself necessarily. He is joined to His end since He is His end (I, q. 19, a. 3c). This is the perfection of Augustinian freedom.Yet vis-à-vis creation He is free to choose to create or not to create various finite entities. He possesses complete freedom of choice (I, q. 19, a. 10c). This implies distinction not only between the divine intellect and the divine will, in order to prevent the perfectly simple God from having to create everything that He contemplates, but also within His spiritual faculties. In His intellect “knowledge (scientia ) of vision,” which comprehends all actual beings past, present, and future, is distinguished from “knowledge of simple intelligence,” whereby all possible beings are known (I, q. 14, a. 9c). Analogously His antecedent will, which “in a first consideration” regards good or evil “absolutely,” that is, apart from particular circumstances, is distinguished from His consequent will, which effects what it wills (I, q. 19, a. 6c). Why He chose this creation instead of that remains a mystery, and Thomas can only assure his readers that insofar as God’s will is one with His intellect, He chooses everything in view of His own goodness, orders everything created to His goodness, and in the resultant order of the universe wills means in view of ends, His choice is “rational,” not arbitrary (I, q. 19, a. 1c; a. 2c; a. 3c; 4c; 5c et ad 1). These assurances complete the circle of Thomas’s theological presentation.The beginning of the Summa theologiae argues to the existence of God on the basis of the order in the universe: both the final causality exhibited by things in motion and the purpose exhibited by the universe’s unity point to God’s existence (I, q. 2, a. 3c). All freedom and 16 Cf. John McDermott, S.J., “Matter, Modern Science, and God,” forthcoming in Angelicum for the oscillations in modern science’s relation to reality that leaves it open to God. Matter thus fulfills the same role in modern as in ancient physics. Nature, Freedom, and Person 809 all meaning are thus referred to God, in whose simplicity not only is His intellect distinguished from His will but also knowledge of vision is distinguished from knowledge of simple intelligence (I, q. 14, a. 9c) and antecedent will is distinguished from subsequent will and will of sign (I, q. 19, a. 6, ad 1; a. 11c). The plurality, attributable to matter, of earthly creation, which nonetheless constitutes a single universe, is thus mirrored in the “pluriunity” of God. On Person “Person” is a novel concept to the ancient world. Aristotle does not pay any attention to it, and it is not until the Christological controversies of the early Church that it comes to prominence. Although Tertullian hits upon the fortunate terminology of two substances, God and man, conjoined “in one person” (in una persona: Adversus Praxean 27), he never explains what “person” means nor the relationship of the two terms “person” and “substance.”17 But the phrases become embedded in the Christian tradition of the West.Then for the Council of Chalcedon, striving, after decades of tumultuous controversy, to establish and clarify the Church’s explicit unity of faith, St. Leo the Great proposes the Western formulation involving two substances or natures in one person. Upon the reading of Leo’s Tomus ad Flavianum the Chalcedonian Fathers immediately accept it as the faith of Peter and the Church.They define that the two natures, human and divine, come together “into one person and one subsistence” (DS 302). While the formulation marks the terminological middle ground between Nestorius and Eutyches, Leo and the Fathers neglect to render precise the exact meanings and relation of the terms “nature” and “person.” Two more centuries of controversy are necessary to attain those insights which St. Maximus Confessor wrings out of the Monotheletic controversy. Unfortunately St.Thomas has no access to Maximus’s texts.When the greatest of Western doctors attempts to cast light upon the mysteries of the Trinity and the Incarnation, the insights of the greatest of Eastern doctors are denied him. Nonetheless his brilliant intellect, psychological sanity, and fidelity to Church tradition enable him to approach the Trinitarian and Christological notions of “person” in such a way that he sheds his own light upon the mysteries. His starting point is anchored in the Western tradition. Augustine understands the “three” within the one divinity as 17 Cf. Alois Grillmeier, S.J., Christ in Christian Tradition, vol. I, 2nd ed., trans. John Bowden (Atlanta: Knox, 1975), 121–31. Grillmeier is a good guide to the patristic controversies; he implicitly refutes Harnack’s thesis about Christianity’s alleged “Hellenization.” 810 John M. McDermott, S.J. relations, even though he does not explicitly identify the three relations as persons.18 Boethius offers a definition of person as “the individual substance of a rational nature.” Of themselves these understandings are contradictory. Boethius apparently defines nothing more than an individual rational nature (De persona et duabus naturis 3), a substantial in-se or per-se, an “absolute,” while Augustine stresses the opposite of substance, “relation,” which is ad aliquid (De Trinitate V, 6.12–15), and which Aristotle lists among the accidents in Categories 7 (6a 36–8b 24).Thomas borrows from Augustine the notion of relation, ad aliquid (ST I, q. 28, a. 1c; a. 2c; a. 4c), and from Boethius his definition resting on the per se of substance (I, q. 29, a. 1c; a. 4c). Can the two definitions be reconciled? In the prima pars, q. 29, Thomas commences his study of Trinitarian person with Boethius’s definition and ends with an Augustinian “subsistent relation.” After noting that “individual” limits Boethius’s “substance” to first substance, specifically to “rational [first] substances which have mastery of their act” so that “they act per se” (a. 1), Thomas adds that “individual” designates “the mode of subsisting which is proper to particular substances” (ad 3).This permits the distinction in article 2 of a reality’s essence from “the subject or supposite which subsists in the genus of substance”; this latter, insofar as “it exists of itself ( per se ) and not in another, is called subsistence.” The same subsistence, as underlying a common nature, is called res naturae (a reality of nature), and, as underlying accidents, “a hypostasis or substance.” Deftly Thomas has distinguished subsistence, or person, from a common nature.Thus subsistence is said to contain “individuating principles” beyond “common matter and form” which make the matter-form composite “this man” (ad 3). One is tempted to identify matter signed by quantity with subsistence, but Thomas assures the reader that the substrate subsisting of itself as an individual does so by virtue of its form, which supplies the “actual esse to matter.”Thus form is the “principle of subsisting” ( principium subsistendi ) whereas matter is the “principle of standing under” ( principium substandi: ad 5).Thus esse as well as matter constitute the subsistent individual, who is spiritual because he possesses a form, is rational, and exercises freedom. Thomas is ready for his next step. Since God neither supports accidents nor is individuated by matter, individuating distinctions can be attributed to existence. Loosened from substance and nature, person is redefined as “what is most perfect in all of nature, viz., a subsistent in a rational nature” (a. 3). This perfection is applied to God insofar as it designates a “subsisting reality (rem subsisten18 Luis Ladaria, S.J., “Person y Relacion en el De Trinitate de San Agustin,” Misce- lanea Comillas 30 (1972): 271–83. Nature, Freedom, and Person 811 tem )” (ad 3). Hence, “individual,” applied to God, denotes “incommunicability,” not materiality, and “subsistence” means “to exist per se” (ad 4). Clearly Thomas has shifted the accent from the essential order of Boethius’s “substance” to the existential order of “subsistence.” Hence in article 4 “person” can be more easily distinguished from the divine nature common to the three divine persons. Admitting that the word “person” must be accommodated from its original meaning so as to avoid heresy, Thomas uses “person” to indicate a “relative” reality (relativum) in God. Likewise “individual” is understood as “what is distinguished not in itself, but from others,” and “person” signifies “what is distinct in [the divine] nature.” Because his previous analysis of processions in God has led him to see that “a distinction in God only happens through relations of origin” and person signifies “what is distinct in the divine nature,” Thomas identifies divine person with “relation.” Since “relations” in God cannot be accidents but are identified with the divine essence which subsists, “divine person” means “relation as subsisting.”19 Thomistic Tensions Thomas’s analysis of “person” contains some ambiguities. If “subsistence” means “to exist per se,” one might expect every existing nature, especially the divine nature, to be qualified as a “person” (cf. III, q. 3, a. 3, ad 1; De potentia q. 8, a. 3c). For God is “self-subsisting esse” (ipsum esse per se subsistens: ST I, q. 44, a. 1c; q. 12, a. 4c; q. 7, a. 1, ad 3). Moreover, if person means the ability to “act per se,” each person of the Trinity would be able to act independently; that would dispute the understanding of God’s nature as a single principle of activity (III, q. 3, a. 2c; a. 4c et obj. 1; q. 32, a. 1, ad 1). In his sanity Thomas draws neither conclusion. But he is willing to stretch the meaning of person from individual substance to subsistent relation because he wishes to maintain the analogy between divine and human persons (I, q. 29, a. 4, ad 4).That allows him to use Boethius’s definition in his Christology, interpreting it as an individual subsisting in its nature (III, q. 2, a. 2c).Thereafter a double understanding seems to develop, depending on whether Thomas places the emphasis upon the individual subsisting or upon the subsisting individual. Initially emphasis is placed on the individuality of the supposite as opposed to the nature understood more universally:“For nature signifies the essence of the species which the definition signifies.” Since accidents and individuating principles are added to the formality of species (ratio speciei), it is possible to distinguish the nature from the “supposite of the nature.” Though really (secundum rem) different, 19 Cf. our “Is the Blessed Trinity Naturally Knowable?” to appear in Gregorianum 93 (2012). 812 John M. McDermott, S.J. they are not separated “since in the supposite the very nature of the species is included.”The supposite is the totality (totum) which “has the nature as the formal part perfecting it.” For that reason “in hylomorphic composites nature [viz., humanity] is not predicated of the supposite,” viz., “this man” (III, q. 2, a. 2c). Here supposite, or person, seems to intend both the first substance, the totality, and its material substrate. Like first substance, it can be understood as either a part, the supposite distinct from the nature, or the whole, the supposite embracing the nature.Thomas notes that this distinction between nature and person, or supposite, is clear in beings composed of form and matter, but less clear in beings, like God, in whom there is nothing beyond the “formality (ratio) of species or nature.” In Him the distinction of supposite from nature is not real (secundum rem) but merely intentional (secundum rationem intelligendi). “For it is called nature insofar as it is a certain essence, but the same thing is called a supposite insofar as it is subsisting” (III, q. 2, a. 2c).Thus beyond material individuality a subsistence is recognized as distinct from nature in God and angels. But is not God’s subsistence identical with His esse per se (I, q. 29, a. 2c) and therefore with His essence, or nature (I, q. 3, a. 4c)? What does Thomas here intend by “subsistence”? Subsistence again seems to involve “existence per se.” For “only that which exists per se . . . has the formality (ratio ) of a person.” Precisely because Christ’s human nature exists, not in itself, but in the person of the Word, it does not have its own personality (III, q. 2, a. 2c et ad 3; a. 5c; q. 16, a. 12, ad 2). How is “person” then related to “existence”? Certainly “esse belongs to the person’s very constitution” (III, q. 19, a. 1, ad 4). Further specification of that relation, however, allows a variety of formulations. Christ’s human nature “exists in the person of the Word” (III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 1), who, we just saw, exists per se. “The hypostasis is previous to and higher than the human nature” (III, q. 6, a. 1, ad 2), and the Word exists previous to and independent of the nature assumed in the Incarnation (III, q. 2, a. 5, ad 1; a. 6c; q. 3, a. 1, ad 3). For the Word has an uncreated esse according to His divine nature (III, q. 16, a. 10, ad 3).Yet Thomas apparently reverses the relation when he writes that “the Word subsists in it [the human nature]” (III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 1; a. 5, ad 1; a. 8c). For “everything that subsists in a human nature is a person” (III, q. 16, a. 12c et ad 1); it belongs to the formality (ratio ) of the person “to subsist in some nature” (III, q. 2, a. 4c). This corresponds with the earlier understanding whereby the person subsists in a rational nature and the divine Word subsists in the divine nature (I, q. 29, a. 3c; q. 30, a. 4c; q. 33, a. 2, ad 3). Why does Thomas employ such variations? Here we run into one of the greatest exegetical problems in the Thomistic tradition: what exactly Nature, Freedom, and Person 813 does “subsistence” mean? At first sight it might be possible to distinguish subsistence from existence insofar as the latter, esse, is only a part of the total subsistence, which unites existence to essence and whatever “individuating principles” are added to them. So Jesus’ humanity “exists” only with the “borrowed” existence of the Word, and the Word “subsists” in the human nature because that nature is assumed into the whole that is the incarnate Word. Although Jesus’ humanity is incomplete without its existence, the Word is always a complete person in His existence, which secondarily actuates the assumed humanity. In this sense the person mediates esse to the human nature. Person is “what has esse,” while nature is “that by which something has esse (id quo aliquid habet esse )”; thus the Word has esse by His divine nature and this esse “becomes the esse of man” (III, q. 17, a. 2c et ad 1–3). While subsistence would include existence per se, it must be more than that. It is an individual something or, better, someone that “has” a nature. This subsistence must supply individuating principles beyond matter and accidents; for the eternal Son, in whom no accident exists, “has deity under a determined personal property”; indeed the Son “has” both natures (III, q. 17, a. 1c et ad 2; q. 35, a. 1c et ad 2). In the Trinity the incommunicability of personhood consists in the subsistent relation resulting from the order of processions (cf. I, q. 29, a. 3, ad 3; a. 4, ad 3; q. 30, a. 4, ad 2; III, a. 3, q. 1, ad 2). But how does the Son as an individual personal relation have the humanity? Toward a Resolution To identify more closely in man what has esse, exists per se, is individual, and acts freely, one can have recourse to Thomas’s earlier disquisition about the “essence of the soul” in the prima pars, q. 77, aa. 4–7.There he seeks to explain the unity between the soul and its potencies. Given that man’s hylomorphic unity is due to its form, or soul, there has to be a unity in the soul and the potencies, or faculties, which perform its operations. Since knowing involves the unity in diversity of sensation, abstraction, and judgment (conversio ad phantasma ), an internal spiritual unity must underlie man’s diverse ways of knowing. Indeed man’s ways of knowing correspond to his internal composition of body, form, and existence.Thomas explains the unity in terms of the essence of the soul from which as a principle emanate in a hierarchical resultatio man’s diverse faculties, starting with intellect and will and proceeding to his sensible and nutritive faculties.The essence of the soul functions as both active and final cause. Thus, as the unity diversifies into multiplicity, the diversity also returns to unity, bringing with it the stimulations from the 814 John M. McDermott, S.J. outside world.The soul’s essence comprises an ontological unity, simultaneously diverse from the faculties and containing all of them virtually. Like the person it can easily be understood as part and whole. It must also be the ground of individuality, since not only is it one but also from it the sensible faculties flow, yet it has to be spiritual, since it is ontologically higher than the spiritual faculties of intellect and will. Finally, although this is not mentioned by St. Thomas, it must be the point joining essential and existential orders, since in judgment existence is predicated of the affirmed subject. Although existence is not perceived per se through the senses, Thomas reminds his reader that ultimately in knowing it is not so much the faculty that knows as the whole man who knows through the faculties (I, q. 77, a. 5c; q. 75, a. 2, ad 3; q. 76, a. 1c).Thus there seems to be in man a point of spiritual individuality; it can be identified with the whole person, which embraces the concrete existential nature, yet is capable of distinction from it as person from nature. Furthermore this point is at the juncture of the essential and existential orders, for the person not only exists per se but also has esse. At this point of spiritual individuality in a concrete humanity, the spiritual individuality of the Son, who exists as an individuated relation, can enter to substitute for a human person and take possession of a concrete humanity. So the spiritual individuality of the second person of the Trinity corresponds analogously with the spiritual individual person in a human nature. Indeed, Thomas remarks, as the name “person,” applied to each of the three Trinitarian persons, serves to designate a “vague individual,” so it often functions among men: “Vague individual, as some man, signifies the common nature with a determined mode of existing which coincides with individuals so that he might be one subsisting per se distinct from others” (I, q. 30, a. 4c). Leaving aside the difficulty of defining exactly what “mode” means in Thomism, one sees that Thomas intends a correspondence between what is most individual in the Trinity and what is most individual in man.That correspondence allows the substitution of a Trinitarian person for a human person at the point of greatest spiritual individuality. Many advantages flow from such an interpretation. First it reconciles various axioms about action that are otherwise contradictory. On the one hand, “nature designates a principle of action,” or motion, and a thing’s proper operation occurs “according to its form”: “operation follows nature” (I, q. 2, a. 3; III, q. 19, a. 1c; a. 2, sed contra). On the other, actions or acts are attributed to the person: actiones (actus ) suppositorum sunt (I, q. 39, a. 5, ad 1; q. 40, a. 1, ad 3; III, q. 7, a. 13c; q. 20, a. 1, ad 2) and “acting belongs properly to the person” (III, q. 3, a. 1c). Insofar as natures do not emit actions determined in their particularities but give a specific propulsion allowing leeway for further particularization (“for the most part”), Nature, Freedom, and Person 815 the person can be seen as the one who determines the choice, or election, most concretely. For persons,“who have control of their acts, are not only acted upon, as are other things, but they act through themselves ( per se ); yet actions are in individuals” (I, q. 29, a. 1c). So a man recognizes that his nature demands sleep, but the individual person can decide when, where, how long, etc. “To operate belongs to a subsistent hypostasis, but according to form and nature, from which the operation receives a species” and “the operation is a certain effect of the person according to some form or nature” (III, q. 19, a. 1, ad 3, 4). Second, by placing freedom in the person, the hesitancy inherent in freedom of indifference can be overcome; whereas the interplay of intellectual and voluntary faculties set the condition of possibility for choice, the actual choice depends upon the person. A human child does not choose to be born from his parents; he or she must react to the gift of life which comes from love. No neutrality is permitted. As Blondel often writes, Nous sommes embarqués. So much more urgent is the demand when a person is confronted with Jesus Christ who died for him. Person calls to person as depth to depth. In the person, knowing and loving come together to overcome the indifference of choice before rationally proposed alternatives.“To act is attributed not to the nature as agent, but to the person. . . . Action is, however, attributed to the nature as to that according to which the person or hypostasis acts” (III, q. 20, a. 1, ad 2).Third, such a view explains how Jesus can be impeccable while subject to temptation: though His will is being repulsed by His impending fate, death and the abolition of all that His human nature naturally seeks in life, the ultimate choice depends upon the divine person, who, being divine, cannot sin.“Father, if you wish, take this cup from me, but let your will, not my will, be done” (Lk 22:42). Fourth, because Jesus identifies Himself as the Father’s Son, His inmost identity is relational. Insofar as freedom exists for love, the free person is never closed within himself. Thus the substantial in-itself of Boethius’s definition is reconciled with Thomas’s “subsistent relation.” “Relation” is just as primordial as personal “in-se.” Indeed, alongside the modern notion of person as free, self-conscious center of activity is an equally modern notion of person as relation.20 Fifth, Christ’s direct knowledge 20 Cf. Martin Buber, I and Thou, 2nd ed., trans. Ronald Smith (New York: Scrib- ner’s, 1958), 3–4 et passim; also Marcel, Mounier, Blondel, Nédoncelle, as noted in Stefanini, “Personalismo,” 1313–14. Emmanuel Mounier, Le Personalisme (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1951), 8, starts with a substantialist view of person but strongly rejects all closed individualism; person is for communication (35–50). Similarly Karl Rahner, S.J., “Person: C. Theological,” in Sacramentum Mundi, 3:418, insists that man‘s social orientation is equally primordial to 816 John M. McDermott, S.J. of the Father would be personal, beyond the abstractions normally provided by the intellect. This allows for growth in His explicit human knowledge—that is, knowledge mediated by concepts—of Himself.Yet His utterly personal knowledge of His Father lets Him—otherwise pure audacity for a Jew—address His Father as Abba and communicate it to those whom He taught to pray “Our Father” (cf. Gal 4:6; Rom 8:15).21 Sixth, such a spiritual individuality grounds personal immortality; what survives death is no universal form but a person, and there is no need to invoke esse as a second principle of individuality alongside matter.22 Difficulties Unfortunately multiple difficulties beset this interpretation of Thomas. First, the Angelic Doctor never identifies the essence of the soul with person; indeed, it is called the soul’s essence and as such seems to belong to the essential order; for “the essence of the soul is the act of the body” (III, q, 46, a. 7, ad 1). Second, other texts do not support this interpretation. Thomas holds that man’s substantial form per se has esse, communicates it to the body, and causes esse actually in its subject; moreover, the soul subsists per se and is therefore incorruptible (I, q. 75, a. 6c; q. 77, a. 6c; a. 7c; cf. q. 29, a. 2, ad 5; q. 42, a. 1, ad 1). Despite the language of subsistence, the soul is not a person, since a person “has the complete nature of a species” (I, q. 75, a. 4, ad 2). So our attempt to limit the language of subsistence to the person is not utterly persuasive. Distinctions might possibly be constructed: for example, the soul as part of the composite does not subsist per se since its totality depends upon the possession of a body (“the form in [composite creatures] is not a complete subsistent”: I, q. 13, a. 1, ad 2), but in a separated state it may be said to “subsist in its esse” insofar as it retains the esse of the composite and thus possesses an esse totius (an esse of the whole) and a perfectum esse (I–II, q. 4, a. 5, ad 2; I, q. 76, a. 1, ad 5). Yet, even while defending the separated soul’s essential beatitude, Thomas admits that something is missing to the separated soul’s bene esse (well being), since it still desires the “administration of the body” (I–II, q. 4, a. 5c et ad 5). More tellingly, he admits that the separated soul lacks “the the free person: “Intercommunication and self-realization, self-possession, grow in principle in like and not inverse proportion.” 21 On the significance of Abba cf. John McDermott, S.J.,“Jesus and the Son of God Title,” Gregorianum 62 (1981): 227–317, esp. 278–81, 316–17. 22 Cf. John McDermott, S.J., “How Did Jesus Know He Was God? The Ontological Psychology of Mark 10:17–22,” Irish Theological Quarterly 74 (2009): 272–97. For man’s immortality cf. ibid., “Faith, Reason, and Freedom,” Irish Theological Quarterly 67 (2002): 328–31. Nature, Freedom, and Person 817 perfect nature of the species” (I–II, q. 4, a. 5, ad 2), which apparently denies its personhood. Thomas’s language may not be totally consistent on this point as he searches for an answer to one of the most difficult problems of theology. One might seek to preserve the language of “personal subsistence” by arguing for a development from the prima pars to the tertia pars: the question of the hypostatic union forces Thomas to be more precise in his use of language. But further difficulties remain. Third, because esse stands to essence, or nature, as act to potency (I, q. 9, a. 2c; q. 50, a. 2, ad 3; q. 75, a. 5, ad 4), it seems superfluous to posit an intermediate entity, the person, to join esse and essence. The form possesses esse and is the “principle of being” (principium essendi: I, q. 76, a. 2c) and the “cause of being” (causa essendi ) to the matter (I, q. 75, a. 5, ad 3). Fourth, tied to the previous problem is the question of the number of existences in Christ. The tertia pars holds that since the human nature is personally united to the Son and esse pertains secundum se to the person as the one who possesses esse, there is in Christ only one esse, the Son’s divine esse, “because it is impossible that there not be one esse for one reality” (III, q. 17, a. 2c et ad 2).With this affirmation, however, comes a plethora of new problems. Since the divine esse belongs to the whole Trinity (III, q. 17, a. 2, ad 3), would not the whole Trinity be actuating Christ’s humanity? Furthermore, since “act is proportioned to that of which it is the act” and “every reality has esse according to its form” (I, q. 12, a. 3c; q. 42, a. 1, ad 1), where is the proportion between the infinite divine esse and the human nature?23 Christ’s humanity must either become divine or be overwhelmingly crushed or splintered through the divine esse. Most probably in the face of such problems Thomas wavers in formulating his position. Earlier the tertia pars asserts that since the hypostatic union “has only one real esse in the created nature . . . consequently it has a created esse” (q. 2, a. 7, ad 2), and De Unione Verbi Incarnati, a. 1c et ad 10, written at approximately the same time as the tertia pars, affirms a subordinate, secondary esse in Christ.24 Of course the secondary esse raises equally troubling questions: How are both existences 23 ST I, q. 42, a. 1, ad 1 also states that “esse is the form’s first effect.”That may seem at first paradoxical, given the identification of esse with act and form with potency, but one allows for a mutual causality between form and esse, as between matter and form, in producing the existing individual nature. For form mediates “actual esse” to matter (I, q. 29, a. 2, ad 5). 24 Franz Pelster, S.J., “La Questio Disputata de Saint Thomas ‘De Unione Verbi Incarnati,’ ” Archives de Philosophie 3 (1925): 198–245, has proven the authenticity and date of De Unione Verbi Incarnati. 818 John M. McDermott, S.J. joined? How does Thomas avoid his own principle that “for one reality there can be only one esse”?25 A final difficulty with our exegesis is that Thomas does not draw conclusions which seem to flow naturally from it.Whereas our interpretation would locate the actuation of the free act in the person beyond the will, Thomas clearly maintains in Christ not only two wills, human and divine, the former moved interiorly by the latter as with other holy men (III, q. 18, a. 1c et ad 1–4), but also a liberum arbitrium in which the will as ratio makes the election (III, q. 18, a. 4c et ad 1–3; q. 18, a. 5c et ad 2). Freedom is not located in the person; “since the will belongs to the nature, any type of willing (ipsum quod est aliqualiter velle ) also belongs to the nature” (III, q. 18, a. 1, ad 4). Furthermore, the beatific vision is ascribed to the “superior part” of Christ’s soul, not to the person (III, q. 46, a. 8c), while the lower part suffers, strange as it may be that the principle of man’s essential unity should itself be divided. Lastly, Jesus’ miracles are caused not by His acting person but by the divine nature (III, q. 19, a. 1 et ad 1, 2, 5; q. 43, a. 2c).26 Toward a Conclusion: Thomistic Disarray Our analysis of Thomas’s doctrine on the relation of person and nature does not lead to a pellucid conclusion.27 One suspects that Thomas himself is not clairvoyant about the relation, but with his usual balanced breadth of vision he wishes to keep together as many elements as are necessary to uphold the Church’s dogmatic faith. Certainly the leading theologians of the twentieth century fail to agree among themselves on how to interpret Thomas’s 25 While following Cajetan’s position, Shawn Colson, “Accrued Eyes and Sixth Digits: Thomas Aquinas and Cardinal Cajetan on Christ’s Single Esse and the Union of Natures,” Nova et Vetera 8 (2010): 55–87, ignores the disproportion between the infinite divine esse and the human nature as well as the problem of the whole Trinity assuming Christ’s humanity. As will become clear below from the divergent views of modern Thomists, such are the main problems of Christ’s ontological constitution. 26 While Thomas does not formulate the later axiom, omnia opera Trinitatis ad extra sunt communia, he supplies a basis for it in his discussion of the Trinitarian missions:“God’s creative power is common to the whole Trinity” (ST I, q. 32, a. 1; q. 43, a. 7, ad 3; q. 45, a. 6c). 27 This section restricts itself principally to the person-nature relation in Christology, where the problems are most obvious. Omitted is relation between Trinitarian and Christological “person,” which most thinkers do not analyze. Also omitted is the problem concerning the relation of human and divine, personal knowledge in Jesus, which underlies modern Christologies on account of modern philosophy’s turn to the subject and historical-critical studies in biblical exegesis. For an answer cf. McDermott, “How Did Jesus Know?” 272–97. Nature, Freedom, and Person 819 Christology. The variety of their interpretations is astounding. Billot postulates one divine esse in Christ; since this is the esse of the Trinity, there have to be three modes of possessing it; hence this one esse is joined to Christ’s humanity “through the mode of filiation.” Moreover, on account of the lack of proportion the divine esse actuates Christ’s human nature “quasiformally.”28 Garrigou-Lagrange and the early Maritain see personality as a substantial mode terminating a nature; the mode thus renders the nature capable of becoming the immediate subject of existence. GarrigouLagrange then constitutes the divine person the source of all activity, whereas the nature becomes “that by which a thing is such as it is, in such a species.”29 De la Taille interprets Christ’s secondary human esse along the model of the beatific vision as a finite actuation created by God’s uncreated act whereby the Word terminates the human nature, exercising a terminative, not an informative, act. Since the Word’s esse is received from and relative to the Father, when it actuates Christ’s humanity, the humanity has a different relation to the Word than to the Father and the Spirit.30 Galtier affirms two existences in Christ, but the secondary esse produces only an incomplete being (ens quo), since the complete being is what is united to the divine personal esse. He interprets person as an independent, rational, free totality, adding to nature only “a total and exclusive possession”; since Christ’s human nature is possessed by the Word, it is not a human person. The divine person does not influence Christ’s humanity beyond the manner in which God exercises His influence on any other human nature.31 Diepen accepts two existences in Christ, since a nature specifies its act of existence as its formal principle.The human existence is somehow integrated into the divine, while the “person” possesses exclusively its nature, which is joined to its proportionate existence.The person mediates esse to the nature, giving it a subsistence so that the whole becomes autonomous and incommunicable. 28 Louis Billot, S.J., De Verbo Incarnato, 4th ed. (Rome: St. Joseph, 1904), 57, 132–33, 142, n. 1, 149, 157–58, 165; also Pietro Parente, L’Io di Cristo, 2nd ed. (Brescia: Marcelliana, 1955), 213–19, 229, 231–33, 246, 340. 29 Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P., De Christo Salvatore (Turin: Marietti, 1949), 87, 89, 116; Jacques Maritain, Degrees of Knowledge, 4th ed., trans. G. Phelan et alii (New York: Scribner’s, 1959), 433. 30 Maurice de la Taille, S.J., “The Schoolmen,” The Incarnation, ed. C. Lattey (Cambridge: Heffer, 1926), 183–86; idem, The Hypostatic Union and Created Actuation by Uncreated Act, trans. Cyril Vollert (West Baden Springs, IN: West Baden College, 1952), 58, 62–63, 68, 72–74. 31 Paul Galtier, S.J., L’Unité du Christ (Paris: Beauchesne, 1939), 101, 132–36, 200–234, 247, 262, 319, 334, 348; idem, De Incarnatione et Redemptione (Paris: Beauchesne, 1947), 175, 180–82, 185, 192–203, 209–12, 237. He admits a proximity to the Scotist position of Déodat de Basly, O.F.M., in L’Unité, 313–17. 820 John M. McDermott, S.J. The personal subsistence is “the crowning of individuation.” “The esse humanum realizes the human nature in and with its hypostatic union with the Word.” The person then exercises the act of existence so that Christ’s humanity is seen as the divine person’s “created prolongation” or “temporal annex” insofar as it is “a participation in the personal being of the Son of God.”32 The middle Maritain deepens Diepen’s position, seeing the person, or subsistence, as a state of active, autonomous exercise of an act of existence; thus in Christ, not His human nature but the Word exercises the human esse received in that nature.33 If there is a lack of consensus among earlier conceptualist theologians in the twentieth century, later transcendental Thomists encounter similar difficulties. Lonergan understands person as an individual subsistent in an intellectual nature. A human person is a complete nature with its proportionate esse. But that proportion is lacking in the Incarnation for both the created esse and the divine esse.The esse of Christ’s humanity is not proportionate, since it is supernatural on account of its assumption by the Word; for it is assumed into unity with the Word’s divine esse, its extrinsic condition, just as contingent created being is intended by God along with His infinite being. It follows the divine esse of the assuming Word “in the manner of a simply posterior term, as the ultimate disposition for a form is said to follow the form’s reception.” Ultimately unity is grounded in the being by which something is, and “the incarnate Word is simply one.” Christ’s immanent human operations are of the man Christ alone but the humanity has a real relation to Word alone, who assumes it and is its intrinsic cause.34 Rahner employs at least six different understandings of “person,” according to need.A Trinitarian person is a mode of subsistence or a mode of presence, depending on whether he is talking of the immanent or the economic Trinity; in Christology he defines person as a “self32 Herman Diepen, O.S.B.,“La Critique du Baslisme selon saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue Thomiste 50 (1950): 97–98, 101–2, 104, 107–11, 115–16, 297, 303–18, 321–22, 324; idem, “L’unique Seigneur Jésus-Christ,” ibid. 53 (1953): 34–35, 37–39, 45, 47–51, 53, 55–57, 59, 61. 33 Maritain, Degrees, 436–43. 34 Bernard Lonergan, S.J., De Verbo Incarnato, 2nd ed. (Rome: Gregorian, 1961), 245–52; idem, De Constitutione Christi ontologica et psychologica, 4th ed. (Rome: Gregorian, 1964), 9, 20–24, 33–34, 57–61, 69–79. For the Trinitarian person-nature relation cf. John McDermott, S.J. “Person and Nature in Lonergan’s De Deo Trino,” Angelicum 71 (1994): 153–85. Of all the theologians, Lonergan presents the most consistent doctrine of person, analogously bridging Trinity and Christology. Cf. Giovanni Rota, “Persona” e “Natura” nell’Itinerario speculativo di Bernard J.F. Longergan (1904–1984) (Milan: Glossa, 1998), 175–282, for greater detail; Rota also points out Lonergan’s double notion of “nature,” the dynamic existential subject affirming truth as well as the Aristotelian principle of motion and rest. Nature, Freedom, and Person 821 conscious, free center of activity” and, more closely applied to the hypostatic union, as the event of man’s self-transcendence into God.35 Because in the hierarchy of being, greater union corresponds to greater independence, Mahlmberg allows for two existences and analogously two persons in Christ integrated into one; the human esse and person are relatively (secundum quid) such as not to oppose the divine person and esse.Though Jesus is otherwise like other men, his human nature is entirely supernatural since it is constituted by the hypostatic union; moreover the term of his transcendence is not the Trinity but the Son, who exercises a special causality actuating the nature’s potency and brings about (setzt) all its operations.36 Wiederkehr understands the hypostatic union as a communication of relations based on the parallelism of relations between the Son and the Father in the Trinity and its reflection in Jesus’ man-God relation. In this way Jesus’ human person and esse are integrated in a gradated analogy into the Word’s person and esse.“God relates Himself to Jesus exactly as He relates Himself in Himself to His Son, and therefore Jesus is the eternal Son of God and the eternal Son is none other than Jesus.”“Man” and “Son of God” are related in their turn as condition of possibility and realization.There exist a divine filiation and a filial divinity, and the subject of both is not found outside Jesus’ human personality and subjectivity. This gives meaning to Jesus’ history, as, under the Logos, Jesus becomes the expression of who the Logos is; yet, to preserve this unity, Wiederkehr identifies the Word’s will with Jesus’ will.37 Schoonenberg allows Jesus to be a human person in whom the divine nature is “enhypostasized.”38 Indeed, many followers of Rahner allow Jesus to be a human person—his concrete nature, like Boethius’s, fulfills the definition of person: free, selfconscious center of activity—in some unique relation with God.39 In 35 Cf. John McDermott, S.J., “Karl Rahner in Tradition: The One and the Many,” Fides Quaerens Intellectum 3 (2003–7): 30–34, 36–45, 58–59, n. 112; for greater detail cf. idem “The Christologies of Karl Rahner,” Gregorianum 67 (1986): 87–123, 297–327, but this earlier article overlooks Rahner’s insight of person as event. In “Jesus Christus,” Lexikon für Theologie und Kirche, 2nd ed., ed. Josef Höfer and Karl Rahner (Freiburg: Herder, 1957–67), 5:959, Rahner introduces a different ontology into Galtier’s basic Christology. 36 Felix Malmberg, S.J., Über den Gottmenschen (Freiburg: Herder, 1960), 40–49, 60–61, 69–70, 80–86, 93–105. 37 Dietrich Wiederkehr, O.S.B., “Entwurf einer systematischen Christologie,” Mysterium Salutis, ed. Johannes Feiner and Magnus Löhrer (Einsiedeln: Benziger, 1965–76), 3/1: 566–73, 576–77, 616–21. 38 Piet Schoonenberg, S.J., Ein Gott der Menschen, trans. H. Mertens (Zurich: Benziger, 1969), 74–99. 39 E.g., John Dwyer, Son of Man and Son of God (New York: Paulist, 1983), 3, 79–80, 124, 131, 148;William Dych, S.J., Thy Kingdom Come: Jesus and the Reign of God 822 John M. McDermott, S.J. brief, modern Christologies manifest much confusion in failing to explain the normative language of the Church’s doctrine (DS 424–26, 432, 516, 555, 558). Conclusions Another series of theologians from various schools converge upon a different notion of person. Maximus Confessor, Maréchal, Rousselot, Mouroux, the late Maritain, Clarke, and Wojtyla locate person in that center of spiritual individuality, where knowing and willing are joined and from whose unity the natural faculties devolve.40 They do not handle the problems resulting from Thomas’s existential order; Maximus has no essence-existence distinction, the others ignore the question on this point. (Maritain stands at the threshold of identifying person with the essence of the soul, but it is perhaps his commitment to the existential order, distinct from the essential order, that makes him hesitate to pass over the threshold.) In fact, since the order of freedom transcends the essential order, there is no need to appeal to a separate existential order to relativize nature and indicate how God is free to intervene in the world while remaining transcendent. Substituting the order of freedom for the existential order also dissolves all the problems regarding the rela(Herder & Herder, New York, 1999), 54–55; Roger Haight, S.J., Jesus Symbol of God (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1999), 296, 439, 441–43, 461; on Jon Sobrino, S.J., cf. John McDermott, S.J., “What Went Wrong with Catholic (NT) Exegesis and Christology?” Angelicum 86 (2009): 815–19, esp. n. 66. Though from different traditions both Leonardo Boff, O.F.M., Jesus Christ Liberator, trans. Patrick Hughes (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1978), 181, 192–93, and Edward Schillebeeckx, O.P., Jesus: An Experiment in Christology, trans. Hubert Hoskins (New York: Seabury, 1979), 33, 601, 604, 655–56, 661, also consider Jesus a “human person.” On Schillebeeckx cf. McDermott, “What Went Wrong,” 821–24. 40 Guido Bausenhart,“In allen uns gleich ausser der Sünde” (Mainz: Grünewald, 1992), 147–78; Daniele Moretto, Il Dinamismo intellettuale davanti al Mistero: La Questione del Soprannaturale nel Percorso speculativo de J. Maréchal (Milan: Glossa, 2001), 325–64; John McDermott, S.J., Love and Understanding: The Relation of Will and Intellect in Pierre Rousselot’s Christological Vision (Rome: Gregorian, 1983), 266–90; idem, “The Theology of John Paul II: A Response,” in The Thought of Pope John Paul II, ed. John McDermott (Rome: Gregorian, 1993), 55–68; John McDermott, S.J., and Glenn Comandini,“The Problem of Person and Jean Mouroux,” Sapientia 52 (1997): 75–97; Benedikt Ritzler, Freiheit in der Umarmung des ewig Liebenden (Bern: Lang, 2000), esp. 409–93 (on Maritain); W. Norris Clarke, S.J., Person and Being (Milwaukee: Marquette, 1993), esp. 42–108. Joseph de Finance, S.J.,“L’Éclair de la liberté,” in S.Tommaso Teologo, ed. Antonio Piolanti (Vatican: Pont. Accademia Romana di S.Tommaso, 1995), 35–49, also locates freedom beyond the natural will in the “spiritual subject,” or “the invisible center of personal consciousness,” that stands before God. Nature, Freedom, and Person 823 tion of esse to the person. These thinkers see man primarily as created freedom called to respond to God’s omnipotent love as mediated through his fellow men and the finite structures of the world. In their view, human nature is not merely an individual principle of activity but refers to the entirety of the species, in which various polarities are held in balanced yet dynamic tension.41 For the nature does not ground itself, but in its limitations, which render it incapable of fulfilling itself, it is always referred to its ground, God. In individuals nature gives a direction, but the ultimate specification of that direction depends on freedom. Personal freedom, though transcending nature, is not arbitrary. Rather, it is called to respond to God through the structures of nature. Nature, being a concrete whole containing all members of a species, reveals itself as universal and particular, in itself and in relation, static and dynamic, developing through time yet retaining intelligible continuity and giving guidelines for action. For there can be no final opposition between personal freedom and nature. A good God created both nature and freedom, and a constant opposition of nature and freedom would result in an unhappy, destructive rendering of man, forced into perpetual opposition to himself. As men are intended to live in solidarity, helping each other to achieve a common end, so individual man is a unity of nature and personal freedom. Freedom embraces nature as a condition of possibility even while transcending it and expressing itself in it. Since human freedom is neither arbitrary nor autonomous but always dependent upon God as its ultimate condition of possibility, human freedom shows that the person, the “I” at the center of free decisions, is simultaneous inhimself and in-relation. Man is created as the image of God precisely in his freedom. Since God is love, man is simultaneously loved and challenged to respond to love in the orders of creation and redemption. As John Paul II repeated so often, man only finds himself and becomes free in giving himself; man is created to sacrifice himself for God and his fellows. In this he quotes Gaudium et Spes 24 and, of course, reaffirms the 41 This reference to a concrete nature embracing all men is explicit in Maximus (cf. Hans Urs von Balthasar, Cosmic Liturgy, trans. Brian Daley [San Francisco: Ignatius, 2003], 155–57, 159–65, 216–18); Pierre Rousselot, S.J., L’intellectualisme de saint Thomas, 2nd ed. (Paris: Beauchesne, 1924), 127, 130–31 (cf. McDermott, Love, 29–30, 276–77); and Jean Mouroux, The Meaning of Man, trans.A. Downes (1948; repr. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1961), 119–26. Clarke, Person and Being, 6–24, considers being as relational and communicative before he treats personal relationality, and Karol Wojtyl/a, The Acting Person, trans. Andrzej Potocki (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979), 275, 278, 283, 284–85, 292–96, presupposes the concrete natural unity of mankind as the basis for interpersonal solidarity. 824 John M. McDermott, S.J. truth of Sacred Scripture (Mk 8:34–37; Lk 17:33; Jn 12:24–25; 15:13).42 Such an understanding of person unites not only Thomas’s Trinitarian and Christological applications but also the main currents of modern personalism, some of which emphasize the relational aspects of the person (I-Thou), others the individual possession of freedom.43 This understanding upholds the natural law on two principal counts. First, at the beginning “nature” was employed by moral thinkers to indicate an objective, intelligible basis for morality; moral conduct was thus liberated from arbitrary subjectivity, mere custom, or civil law. The affirmation of a basic structure of freedom oriented to self-sacrificial love prevents irrational arbitrariness from ruling.The structure of love is “natural” in the sense of “objective.” Second, even with the contrast between person and nature, nature and natural operations provide norms for moral action insofar as they are meant to harmonize with the structure of love. Just as the structure of nature points beyond itself to God’s existence, so also it provides an objective orientation for the fulfillment of natural tendencies which correspond with the demands of love. There exists an intelligible finite order in the world.Though love alone is absolute, alone providing the norm for all human morality, natures enable reason to idenN&V tify the specific norms of love’s correctly ordered action.44 42 E.g., John Paul II, Redemptor Hominis 21; Veritatis Splendor 85–87; Centesimus Annus 41; Gratissimum sane 11–12.14; Ut Umum Sint 28. 43 Having three centers of free activity in the Trinity does not deny monotheism since the three persons, being love, give themselves fully to each other.There is no division of will among them. They act in complete concord. Insofar as a nature is a principle of activity and they act as one principle, “nature” can be predicated of them. Certainly the analogy of nature applied to God’s “nature” must be very tenuous, since His nature is not only pure freedom, not bound by laws of development, but also infinite mystery. 44 Cf. John McDermott, S.J., “Faith, Reason and Freedom,” 307–32, for a metaphysics of freedom; “Science, Sexual Morality, and Church Teaching: Another Look at Humanae Vitae,” Irish Theological Quarterly 70 (2005): 237–61, for an example of the correspondence between personal and natural aspects in morality; and our forthcoming “The International Theological Commission and the Natural Law,” in St. Paul, the Natural Law, and Contemporary Legal Theory, ed. Jane Adolphe and Robert Fastiggi (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books), for a personalist grounding of the natural law. Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 825–841 825 Evidence, Lost and Found: A Concluding Unscientific Postscript RUSSELL H ITTINGER University of Tulsa Tulsa, Oklahoma Introduction I N 1988, Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger traveled to England to give the annual Fischer Lecture for the Catholic Chaplaincy at Cambridge University.1 With a paper entitled “Consumer Materialism and Christian Hope,” he came prepared to speak about the “characteristic signs of the times.”The most troubling sign, he averred, is that “what is moral has lost its evidence.” Only a small number of people in modern society will believe in the existence of commandments come from God; and still fewer are convinced that these commandments—if there are such—are handed down without error through the Church, through the religious community. The idea that another’s will, the Creator’s will, has a call upon us and that our being becomes as it should be through the harmony of our will with his will is a concept foreign to a great part of mankind. In any case . . . [t]he idea of his being active in our midst or of man being under his will seems to most to be a naïvely anthropomorphic image of the divine by which man himself is over-rated. Now the concept of a personal relationship between God and Creator and each individual person is certainly not missing from the religious and moral history of humanity; but it is limited in its pure form to the realm of biblical religion. What was first of all common to all of pre-modern 1 Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger, “Consumer Materialism and Christian Hope,” Teach- ers of the Faith: Speeches and Lectures by Catholic Bishops, Foreword by Cardinal Cormac Murphy-O’Connor, ed.Tom Horwood (Catholic Bishop’s Conference of England and Wales, 2002), 78–94. Russell Hittinger 826 mankind, however, lies really along the self-same line: the conviction that in man’s being there lies an imperative, the conviction that man does not devise morality itself by calculating expediencies; rather he comes upon it in the being of things.2 The Cardinal’s speech is an important documentary antecedent to the International Theological Commission’s report, The Search for a Universal Ethics: A New Look at Natural Law (2009). He put the question of “evidence” into a context where it once received an answer—the common patrimony and primeval testimony of wisdom traditions which, in different ways and with different emphases, affirmed “the necessity for harmony between human existence and the message of nature.”3 He quoted C. S. Lewis’s discussion in The Abolition of Man (1943) of the Chinese Tao.The Tao, Lewis said, is the “way, the road” which every man “should read in imitation of that cosmic and supercosmic progression, conforming all activities to that great exemplar.”4 Cardinal Ratzinger pointed out that among wisdom traditions Christianity has the advantage both in the complexity and the intensity of the “evidence”:The incarnate word, the scriptural word, the liturgical word, and the cosmological word. Christianity is not Gnosticism, and therefore there is no Christian theological evidence “cut off ” from the primeval testimony of nature.“The impossibility of a human existence cut off from this,” he proposes, “is indirect proof for the truth of the Christian faith and its hope.”5 Just as the eternal Logos engenders signs in created nature, so too the incarnate Logos uses these evidences in order to institute signs for the mysteries of redemption. The key point is reached at the conclusion of the Cardinal’s prepared remarks. Referring to wisdom traditions in general, he proposed that “Morality is not man’s prison; it is rather the divine in him.”6 This conviction implies that the whole man is open to reality as a whole.Were this not true, the order of nature would amount to a mere aggregation of “details,” and man’s own interpretation of these details would amount to partial constructions of his own subjectivity—or, what is more likely, the constructions of social, political, and legal forces. Morality, then, would be a “prison.” Perhaps we should go even further to say that whatever is “divine” in man demands that the individual be emancipated from this prison of mere partialities which can force but only pretend to bind his 2 Ibid., 87. Emphasis added. 3 Ibid., 89. 4 Ibid., 88, quoting C. S. Lewis. 5 Ibid., 94. 6 Ibid., 92. Concluding Unscientific Postscript 827 conduct.7 Thus, for the modern person, “morality has lost its evidence.” He can “see through” all things but not “see.”8 That “seeing through” is not the same as “seeing” is a problem that Augustine raised in connection with natural law. Is not this appearance of the universe evident to all whose senses are not deranged: Then why does it not give the same answer to all? Animals, small and great, see it, but cannot ask the question. They are not gifted with reason to sit in judgment on the evidence brought in by the senses. But men can ask the question, so that the invisible things of God are clearly seen, being understood by the things that are made ; but by loving these things, they become subject to them, and subjects cannot judge.And these things will only answer the questions of those who are prepared to judge. . . .They look just the same to both, but to one man they say nothing and to the other they speak. O it would be truer to say that they speak to everyone, but are only understood by those who compare the voice which comes to them from outside with the truth that is within. (Conf. X.6)9 What could be more human than to “see through” but not “see”? It is not only a modern problem. Surely, all wisdom traditions are familiar with this phenomenon, and, each in its own way, offers counsel and discipline to correct such inattentiveness. To be at this point is already to be fairly well along the path. If we begin a dialogue or a “search,” as The Search characterizes it, we need to know where to begin. Should we begin in what is allegedly man’s prison, or in rerum naturam, or in a wisdom—or perhaps somewhere in between? Dialogical Considerations The Search begins with a dialogue with those who are at least somewhat advanced, who see some things, see through others, but who can profit from discourse. In the case of dialogue among wisdom traditions, this presupposes not merely a common pool of propositions to which dialogical partners are ready to give assent once they understand the meaning of what is proposed, but also that they enjoy some common patterns of consent within their respective social, moral, juridical, and religious institutions.The moral is not in a theory, much less in a future yet-to-be-realized. Moral evidence is 7 “[T]he moral imperative is not man’s imprisonment from which he must make his escape in order finally to be able to do as he wants.” Ibid., emphasis mine. 8 Ibid., 90. Quoting C. S. Lewis. 9 The Confessions of Saint Augustine, trans. Rex Warner (New York: Signet Classic, 2001), 208. 828 Russell Hittinger already lived.This would be a very favorable situation for the “search” for natural law components of a universal ethics. We are working today within a less favorable situation. As Cardinal Ratzinger worried, modern times evince both a fracturing and a homogenizing of perspective about moral evidence.To enter a dialogue is to find oneself “confronted all at once by a determined defense of the fundamental judgments of modernity”10—namely, that there are facts which still need to be organized by human experimentation, and that the moral will make its appearance when the disparate material of nature is fully humanized by human choice. And, as it is, everyone knows this to be true. In his homily at the pro eligendo summon Pontifice Mass (19 April 2005), he famously characterized this movement from pieces of evidence to a uniform truth: “We are moving towards a dictatorship of relativism which does not recognize anything as for certain and which has as its highest goal one’s own ego and one’s own desires.” Although his appraisal is not as bleak as the Cardinal’s, J. Budziszewski brings out both the opportunities and the perils of dialogue about natural law today, which he neatly captures with the terms “diplomacy and theology.” In the face of such a diverse public, he warns, it is a tricky thing to know what scarcely needs to be said, what can be said in terms of “placeholders,” and what can be said in expectation of serious disagreement—or worse yet, of disagreement that can hardly be articulated. I will restrict my comments to his term “placeholders.” Any project that is both diplomatic and theological, which is to say both dialogical and doctrinal, will make use of placeholders. A placeholder is a term that readily invokes assent while leaving the depth of meaning out of view. For instance, Budsziszewski tags a sentence in §87 of The Search :“Such a natural order of society in the service of the person is connoted, according to the social doctrine of the Church, by the four values that derive from the natural inclinations of the human being and which designate the contours of the common good that society should pursue; these are: freedom, truth, justice, and solidarity.” One can agree that these four values—freedom, truth, justice, and solidarity—look “suspiciously like platitudes.” Interestingly, however, The Search here quotes another document which paraphrases (out of order) the very subtitle of Pope John XXIII’s Pacem in Terris (1963). In the original, the four terms were proffered not as “values” but principles upon which peace is achieved: truth, justice, charity, and liberty. Placeholders might represent a rhetorical point of departure, as a word or phrase can 10 Id. 78. Concluding Unscientific Postscript 829 signify the conclusionary meaning of a whole line of thought. Placeholders might also signify a gap in a particular line of thought, to which the interlocutors can return later. Principles on the other hand are points of departure in a normative sense of the term. I make this observation not to criticize Budziszewski but rather to buttress his point. What was once meant to be an argument, driven at each step by four principles, had become a placeholder fifty years later. Let us consider for a moment Pacem in Terris. It is a touchstone for contemplating the dual aims of diplomacy and theology. Pacem is both dialogical and doctrinal. Most importantly, for our purposes, it is the first papal encyclical to treat natural law in general terms for a general audience—for men of good will—and even more significantly for the express purpose of mobilizing collaboration along a wide front of moral, social, and political issues. Pope John distinguished quite clearly between “error as such and the person who falls into error,” as well as between “a false philosophy of the nature, origin and purpose of men and the world, and economic, social, cultural, and political undertakings, even when such undertakings draw their origin and inspiration from that philosophy.”11 Hence, he hoped that there might emerge a legitimate sphere in which Catholics can collaborate with Protestants, with those who hold no religion, and possibly with those who hold an anti-religious ideology, in social and political endeavors12 —insofar as these undertakings express “morally lawful aspirations,”13 especially collaboration in defense of “man’s natural rights.”14 Pacem in Terris locates evidence in and for a very specific dialogue that was one notch below the dialogue between wisdom traditions—not so far below that the exercise would have been in vain. In his opening allocution to the Second Vatican Council, Pope John reminded the bishops that “history is the teacher of life.”15 A common historical experience can have 11 Pacem in Terris §§158–159. 12 Despite the fact that these sections of Pacem in Terris were framed with several qualifications of both a moral and doctrinal nature, they ignited more debate in the external forum of domestic politics than any other part of the encyclical. Qualifications, e.g.: Catholics should do nothing that compromises morality and religion (§157); that one must not forget the possibility and need for conversion (§158); that fruitful cooperation is not a foregone conclusion but must be discerned according to prudence, which is itself measured by the principles of natural law and the directives of ecclesiastical authority (§160); and that gradual growth is better than the impetuosity of political revolution (§§161–162). 13 Pacem in Terris §159. 14 Pacem in Terris §157. 15 Gaudet Mater (October 11, 1962), Sacrosanctum Oecumenicum Concilium Vatican II, Constitutiones, Decreta, Declarationes (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1993), 858. 830 Russell Hittinger a useful winnowing effect for interlocutors of good will. Some options are recognized almost immediately as dead ends, while others remain what William James called “live options.” Thus, discerning the “signs of the times” enables one to know where, in medias res, a dialogue ought to begin. For Pope John, the experience of the post-war generation created an opportune moment for setting forth natural law principles governing peace as tranquility of order.The pathologies of totalitarian states were in full evidence; western Europe was still being rebuilt from the devastation of the war; the Cuban missile crisis had made everyone aware of the need for at least some limits to use of lethal force, even in defense of a good cause; and the rapid pace of decolonization made it imperative that the new polities be founded on the four principles comprising the encyclical’s subtitle.The Pope did not need to convince his reader that morality is not “man’s prison.” Enough people had been sent to real graves and been in real prisons for the difference to be evident. It is precisely in this kind of situation that placeholders can be used temporarily in a benign way to capture important dimensions of the moral order which were already being learned by experience. This certainly was Jacques Maritain’s view. Referring to the drafts in process for a U.N. Declaration of the Rights of Man, he observed in 1947 that “the perspectives open to men, both on the planes of history and of philosophy, are wider and richer than before.”16 Put to one side Maritain’s somewhat specious argument about connatural affectivity as the way that natural law is first known. It is irrelevant to the case in point, which is that both assent and consent (truth and feasibility of agreement) sometimes are more favorable under certain conditions of shared experience. Between what is first in the order of cognition and what is final in the order of philosophical explanation stand other “evidences” that point toward both.This is no more surprising than the fact that many Catholics could make little sense of the morality of contraception until faced with the problem of abortion. For its part, Pacem in Terris provides a rather traditional picture of natural law, beginning with the encyclical’s opening sentence: “Peace on Earth—which man throughout the ages has so longed for and sought after—can never be established, never guaranteed, except by the diligent observance of the divinely established order.”The encyclical’s list of some twenty-five natural or human rights (§§8–36) stands between two discussions of divinely created order (§§2–7, 37–38) which serve as bookends. The first is a substantive prelude, while the second is a forceful reminder 16 Jacques Maritain, “Introduction” to the UNESCO document, Human Rights: Comments and Interpretations (1948). Concluding Unscientific Postscript 831 and admonition. In the prelude, the Pope speaks of the whole created universe, marked by order, intelligibility, and beauty. He distinguishes carefully between the order of nature as a whole and the excellence of human participation in eternal law. After enumerating the rights, he quotes St. Thomas: “Human reason is the standard which measures the degree of goodness of the human will, and as such it derives from the eternal law, which is divine reason. . . . Hence it is clear that the goodness of the human will depends much more on the eternal law than on human reason” (§38).17 In its own time and place, Pacem in Terris attempted a fairly high level dialogue, making use of Budziszewski’s notions of diplomacy and theology. The Pope takes note of contemporary desiderata —what men want and hope to achieve regarding justice and peace.The word “value” (valor ) is not in the encyclical.18 Instead, we find animorum appetitiones and other such phrases to indicate what people are trying to accomplish (§§79, 159). These, in turn, are judged “lawful” in light of the four principles. When the dialogical and doctrinal aims are conflated, the placeholders come to include more than the historical and social evidence. History might be the “teacher of life,” but it also teaches that opportune moments for dialogue are often short-lived. Indeed, very shortlived.Take, for example, Maurice Cardinal Roy’s remarks sent to Paul VI in 1973 on the “Occasion of the Tenth Anniversary of the Encyclical ‘Pacem in Terris’.” Cardinal Roy was a distinguished churchman of his time, to say the least.19 In a section entitled “A Method for Our Times,” the Cardinal admits to being somewhat puzzled by John XXIII’s theme of order, especially as it relates to cosmological, metaphysical, and anthropological matters. He asks, “Is this answer still valid, ten years later?” For today, this idea of nature is very much questioned, if not rejected. There is argument concerning the word itself, which could lead one to suppose that there is a strict parallel between man and his morality and biological laws and behavior.There is argument also about its content, negative (what nature forbids) or positive (what nature permits). The 17 Citing ST I–II, q. 19, a. 4. 18 The valori were superimposed, first in Italian, as headings for newspapers, and through this venue entered into other translations. 19 Having been the Archbishop of Quebec, subsequently the first President of the Pontifical Council on the Laity, then of the Pontifical Council on Justice and Peace, and finally the President of the Pontifical Council on the Family. Pope Paul VI addressed his letter, Octogesima Adveniens, on the Eightieth Anniversary of Rerum Novarum (May 14, 1971), to Cardinal Roy, who, in turn addressed his thoughts to the Pope on the subject of Pacem in Terris. 832 Russell Hittinger concept also seems too “essentialist” to people of our time, who challenge, as being a relic of Greek philosophy, the term “Natural Law,” which they consider anachronistic, conservative and defensive. They object further that the expression was defined arbitrarily and once and for all in a subjective and western manner, and is therefore one-sided and lacking in any oral authority for the universal conscience. . . . Although the term “nature” does in fact lend itself to serious misunderstandings, the reality intended has lost nothing of its forcefulness when it is replaced by modern synonyms. . . . Such synonyms are: man, human being, human person, dignity, the rights of man or the rights of peoples, conscience, humaneness (in conduct), the struggle for justice, and, more recently,“the duty of being,” the “quality of life.” Could they not all be summarized in the concept of “values,” which is very much used today? Admitting that the very first sentence of Pacem asserts that peace is “diligent observance of the divinely established order,” Cardinal Roy was unable to contain his dismay: “[T]his word [nature] jars the modern mentality, as does, even more, the idea that it summons up: a sort of complicated organic scheme or gigantic genealogical tree, in which each being and group has its predetermined place.”20 These well-intentioned suggestions for how the magisterium might improve and expand the dialogue unfortunately allow diplomacy to get the better of theology. Pope John’s Pacem in Terris proceeded quite differently. He began with what men of good will, in a certain time and place, seem prepared to affirm about morality and its institutions. He gives no argument that they ought to do so, for they are already trying to do so. Nor is there need to tamper with the evidence. Allowing the generation to speak for itself, Pope John draws what is “sound” and “lawful” into a framework of principles in which they can be better understood and stand some chance of succeeding. Rather than smuggling into the dialogue “synonyms” of the sort Cardinal Roy had in mind, Pacem draws the common experience back into a picture in which the traditional terms remain intact. In his Cambridge lecture, Cardinal Ratzinger proposed something similar with regard to Christianity and the wisdom traditions: Practical reason also needs the guarantee of an experiment, but a greater kind of experiment than can be conducted in the laboratory. It 20 “Reflections by Cardinal Maurice Roy on the Occasion of the Tenth Anniver- sary of the Encyclical ‘Pacem in Terris’ of Pope John XXIII” (April 11, 1973), in The Gospel of Peace and Justice: Catholic Social Teaching since Pope John, presented by Joseph Gremillion (New York: Orbis Books, 1976), 557–58. Concluding Unscientific Postscript 833 requires the experiment of successful human existence which can come only with subsequent history itself. For this reason, practical reason was always ordered towards the grand enterprise of experiencing and testing the collective visions of ethics and religion. Just as science, on one hand, depends upon the brilliant breakthroughs of great individuals, so, on the other hand, the construction of a systematic ethic depends upon the particular vision of individuals who were given a glimpse of the whole.The grand ethical developments of Greece and of the Near and Far East, about which we spoke a moment ago, have forfeited nothing in terms of the validity which lies at the heart of their assertions. We may look upon them now, however, as tributaries, which flow towards the grand river of Christianity and its explanation of reality.21 Cardinal Ratzinger’s picture, however, is importantly different from Pacem in Terris, at least as it regards dialogue.What he means by the “grand enterprise” presupposes wisdom traditions that outlast the occasional moral insights of a generation. Pope John hoped that such would be the case for the post-war generation, for whom “the truth of life” among the honest discussants would be sufficient to achieve a common law grounded in human dignity.22 Roy’s perplexities, however, indicated that this hope needed to be moderated. Indeed, with respect to natural law foundations, the story of that generation is better described as evidence that was found, and then frittered away.We ought to read Veritatis Splendor (1993) in this context. Philosophical and Theological Considerations When Cardinal Ratzinger spoke of men having lost evidence of what is moral he was referring to the general moral estate of society in the late twentieth century.We are reminded of Walker Percy’s book, “Lost in the Cosmos.”The perennial tradition of natural law however will not agree, without important qualifications, that what is moral has lost its evidence. Remarking on Romans 1:20,Augustine said:“O it would be truer to say that they speak to everyone, but are only understood by those who compare the voice that comes to them from the outside with the truth that is within.” Thomas famously contended that there are self-evident ( per se nota ) propositions which “can be exteriorly denied by the mouth but not interiorly denied by the heart.”23 21 Ratzinger, “Consumer Materialism and Christian Hope,” 92–93. 22 Veritas vitae, which St.Thomas says is not the truth of speech but the rectitude of one’s existence in conformity to divine law. ST II–II, q. 109, a. 2, ad 3. 23 . . . etsi exterius negentur ore, nunquam interius negari possunt corde. Super Sent., lib. 1, d. 3, q. 1, a. 2, s.c. 1. 834 Russell Hittinger Let us consider four aspects of evidence corresponding to different acts of intellect. They are arranged along a spectrum: immediate grasp of a principle, spontaneous inferences, reasoned out implications for action, and philosophically justified accounts. Although each has its own salience, the first two can prove especially difficult to describe because of their simplicity. Simple things are foundations for dialogue, but they are not easy to dialogue about. Regarding first evidences, we should rework Thomas’s dictum: things which cannot be internally denied but which are usually reported confusedly by the mouth. Stephen Brock and Lawrence Dewan develop different but overlapping lines of questions about Thomas’s understanding of the first stirrings of knowledge of the natural law.What is present to the intellect, explicitly and implicitly, prior to either a fully practical or a properly scientific appropriation of the evidence? They critically press the distinction between natural law as discovered in the immediate givens of consciousness and natural law as it is presented and affirmed in an adequately justified account or theory (§§27, 31–33, 37, 44, 59, 113). Some distinction of this sort is unobjectionable. Indeed, it is required if we are to express the difference between what is first in the order of learning and what is first in the order of being, and to mark the different deployments of the intellect—making spontaneous inferences and judgments from what it first grasps of certain principles, and attempting to achieve, and perhaps arriving at, a properly ordered account. The question, then, is whether The Search transfers—at least in some sections of the report—evidence that belongs in the experiential starting point (or very close to it) over to what can only be grasped and understood through a theoretical justification? This is a rather tricky problem. But much stands or falls on getting it right, not only for the purpose of interpreting Thomas, but for the authors’ own project of locating a common knowledge expressed by the wisdom traditions. Two passages of The Search report draw Brock’s attention: This natural law is not at all static in its expression; it does not consist in a list of definitive and immutable precepts. It is a source of inspiration that always springs up in the search for an objective foundation for a universal ethics. (§113) Once we posit the basic affirmation that introduces us to the moral order—”One must do good and avoid evil”—we see how there arises in the subject the recognition of the fundamental laws that should regulate human action. Such recognition does not consist in an abstract consideration of human nature, nor in the effort to conceptualize, which would be proper to theoretical philosophy and theology. The Concluding Unscientific Postscript 835 perception of fundamental moral goods is immediate, vital, based on the connaturality of the spirit with values and engaging both affectivity and intellect, both the heart and the spirit. It is a grasp often imperfect, still obscure and dim, but it has the profundity of immediacy. It deals with the data of the most simple and common experience, which are implicit in the concrete action of persons. (§44) The main point of these passages is clear enough.The ITC wishes to correct the caricature that natural law is an already-assembled, static, or conceptually abstract program—in the fashion, say, of pure practical reason or a completely rehearsed philosophical justification. Either way this caricature should be corrected because it collapses the spectrum of evidence into the starting point. Brock agrees that natural law is neither a “closed set” nor, at first, a “list.” First precepts of natural law engender conclusions unfolded by reason and determinations fashioned by jurisprudence, so it is true that the natural law in man is not static. Moreover, he points out, to speak of a list (of goods and precepts) is to put concepts into a proper order, and thus it is already to think of first evidence philosophically. Having insisted that one extreme must be avoided, does The Search swing in the other direction—finding too little evidence in the first stirrings of our knowledge of natural law? If there is no conceptualization, then what is first given might have the “profundity of immediacy” but it would not stand firmly in the cognitive, and therefore the veridical, order. Brock proposes that the order of precepts presented in ST I–II, q. 94, a. 2 ( can be read in tandem with Thomas’s treatment of happiness in the first three questions of I–II. It is telling, for instance, that the first precept of law in q. 94, a. 2—the good is to be done and pursued and what is contrary resisted—directs action to the human good in which the parts (its various dimensions) are aspects of an intelligible whole.This certainly seems to imply conceptualization, albeit one that is not complete in a philosophical sense.“The other precepts,” Brock writes,“rest on concepts of certain particular good things.As goods, these things share in the truth of the first precept. They are things to be done or sought, and their contraries are bad and to be avoided.”Thus, the particular goods belonging to natural law are goods that the intellect naturally understands to be included in the end, that is “our last end, happiness, in a sketchy way.” What is immediately given are not just desires, needs, inclinations, and “nudges” of nature but an intellective act that naturally grasps an intelligible whole.This interpretation preserves The Search’s interest in correcting a caricature of natural law.At the same time, it preserves a conceptual 836 Russell Hittinger purchase on what is most “common” and universal. In §37 of the document we can make good sense of the assertion that “independently of the theoretical justifications of the concept of natural law, it is possible to discover the immediate givens of consciousness of which it wants to give an account.” But we would have to correct at least the language in what follows:“We will then see how the concept of natural law is based on an explanatory picture that founds and legitimizes moral values, in a manner that can be shared by many.” Put in this way, what is conceptually shared is put much too far toward the philosophical side of the picture. Just here I want to make four points. Although in no way complete, they might be useful for gathering strands of earlier discussion and pointing toward issues to be discussed more thoroughly. First, consider the price to be paid for speaking of the first evidences of natural law as an “inspiration” or a pre-conceptual avidity (if, indeed, such is meant by The Search §§27, 37, 59, 113).What is most “common” loses its location in what is naturally known. If the first evidence of natural law is understood as an “inspiration” prior to the intellect’s grasp of the true and the good, how could there be precepts (in the strict sense of the term) which obtain at the very outset? A conceptual natural law would have to ensue upon a pre-conceptual one, and therefore precepts could emerge only in crossing that threshold. Doesn’t this picture conflict rather directly with Thomas’s teaching that the participation in Eternal Law proper to man is in the created light of the intellect (ST I–II, q. 91, a. 2)? In his detailed and philosophically challenging essay, John McDermott reminds us that nature is “an analogous concept.” In a composite creature like man, different dimensions of nature are simultaneously operative. Even so, we do not want to describe what is proper to the human grasp of natural law as a transition from a condition lacking that proprium. Second, unless great care is taken, a concept itself might not suffice for being under a precept. One could argue that first and ‘most common’ moral concepts are indeterminate with respect to particular actions.This is the problem that arises in Kevin Flannery’s careful and contained exegesis of The Search §53/59 and ST I–II, q. 94, a. 4. If indeed the most general practical principles—the most common precepts—are tokens of precepts still-to-be-constructed, then we would seem to be put once again in a strange transition from a natural law that is directive (not merely affectively nudging but in some way rationally indicating) but not obligating, to a natural law that is fully and adequately preceptive. If precepts of the latter sort are the work of conscience or prudence, then natural law properly speaking can emerge only rather late in the game. What, then, becomes of the distinction between antecedent law and the Concluding Unscientific Postscript 837 application of the law in certain circumstances? In a lengthy footnote (note 4), Steven Long also worries about the ITC language, which could suggest to some readers that the ethical life is chiefly or wholly a matter of determination or ad hoc verdicts of prudence.That position stands in at least the suburbs of the moral theology criticized by Veritatis Splendor. Third, we recall the anthropological question that Cardinal Ratzinger spoke about in his Cambridge lecture—openness to reality as a whole. This depends upon intellect and rational appetite. To sharpen the question: Does the good first manifest itself as practical, which is to say under the restriction of what we do or make? If so, then the intellect is first open and ordained to a good only under a certain aspect: that of directing the will—a very important aspect, to be sure. As Brock notes, “Thomas says that the good is the first thing to fall in the apprehension of practical reason. But he does not say . . . that what the good first falls into is the apprehension of practical reason.”Thomas preserves a praxistranscending ordination to the truth of the good.The intellect is ordered to the true, irrespective of whether it terminates in directive action. Steven Long puts it deftly. “No matter what I may wish to order my knowledge to practically, whether it is true is not merely a function of what I plan to do.” If, as Long contends, the inception of rational appetite is in knowledge of reality, then morality is not “man’s prison.” A fourth point can serve as a segue to Laurence Dewan’s essay. Suppose that Thomas is correct, that what the good first falls into is the apprehension of practical reason.This leaves standing the possibility of the operational primacy of practical reason in the order of finality, which is nothing other than the pursuit and possession of happiness. Thomas himself raises the question. Human happiness is a good for man himself. Whereas speculative acts chiefly reach things extra hominem, practical acts are concerned with things ipsius hominis, such as how he acts and is acted upon. Therefore, human happiness consists more in the excellence of practical virtue. Thomas concedes that such would be the case if man were himself [objectively] his own ultimate end (ST I–II, q. 3, a. 5, ad 3). For a battery of reasons, which we will not rehearse here,Thomas denies that the finis cuius, the very end for which one ultimately acts, is the excellence of self-directive acts.24 But if it were the case, that would have an important implication for natural law, for natural law would be a law directing man to his own good precisely as final, both as finis cuius and finis quo. One might be puzzled about what kind of a law orders a rational 24 More strongly, Thomas denies that any act of the human soul can count as the finis cuius.The speculative operation, however, is more agreeable to a final good extra animam. ST I–II, q. 2, aa. 7–8. 838 Russell Hittinger creature merely to its private good. But this is only the beginning of difficulties which will arise in the train of that premise. My point is that more than one very important issue intersects with the question of the relationship between speculative and practical reason. We are here in the domain of a philosophical problem that also stands rather close to our theme of first evidences. Can the intellective creature be under natural law without some inkling of what he is being directed to, and by whom he is being directed? Lawrence Dewan also worries that The Search’s depiction of the spectrum running from experience to philosophical explanation is not quite right. How do we align a conceptual grasp, a spontaneous inference, and a theoretical justification of natural law? And when we speak of being under the natural law, are we in the sphere of experience or justification? ITC is clear about the latter question, but in some passages it is not so clear about the former. Homing in on “the experience of being subject to natural law as law,” Dewan proposes that “we should not exclude from ‘the immediate givens of consciousness’ in this matter the divinity of the source of the experience.” We recall that this was one of Cardinal Ratzinger’s concerns in his Cambridge lecture: “Morality is not man’s prison; it is rather the divine in him.” Two passages from The Search strike a note that seems discordant with other sections. In each case, the ITC appears to be trying to correct a certain caricature of natural law by widening the gap between experience and justification. To be able to be recognized by all men and in all culture, the norms of behavior in society should have their source in the human person himself, in his needs, in his inclinations. (§115) The moral obligation that the subject recognizes does not come, therefore, from a law that would be exterior (as a heteronomy), but affirms itself from within the subject itself. In fact, as indicated by the maxim we have cited—“One must do good and avoid evil”—the moral good determined by reason “imposes itself ” on the subject. . . . This law is normative in virtue of an internal requirement of the spirit. It is born in the very heart of our being as an invitation to the realization and transcending of ourselves. It is not therefore a matter of subjecting oneself to the law of another, but of accepting the law of one’s own being. (§43) These and other such passages underscore the traditional teaching that natural law is not in us in the fashion of a positive law. It is not imposed. But it cannot be true that the human soul is the “source” of the law, at least not if one wishes to affirm, on the explanatory side of things, that Concluding Unscientific Postscript 839 natural law is “participated theonomy” (§§60, 62, 63). If a self-originating ground of natural law is false on the explanatory side, why should it seem true on the experiential side? From these words (in §43) we could draw two different conclusions. The first is that participation in the Eternal Law is not a matter of being subjected merely to the law of another creature. This conclusion is compatible with a rough and philosophically untutored insight that we are dependent upon a prior or higher law that is distinct from the conventions of the city.The second is that natural law is not in any way a law received from another, a teaching more or less along the lines of Kant. Clearly, these are quite different conclusions.25 Depending on which one we follow, the notion of “transcendence” in morals will differ considerably. If the divine is the source of the law, transcendence is implied at the very outset of “being subjected.” On the other view, the divine could be an upshot of the moral life, coming into view as we transcend ourselves. As The Search itself recognizes (§§31–32), in modern times the divine source of natural law usually is dismissed at both ends of the experienceconcept-explanation spectrum. Modern natural law theory prescinds from reason informed by faith, along with the confessional expressions and justifications of such experience. It also holds that reference to God at the experiential and at the purely philosophical level is “optional” because the concept of morality and duty is coherent in itself. Surely, the ITC does not want to paint itself into either of these corners. What are the options? One option is to move the issue of the “divinity of the source” completely to the side of philosophical explanation. The problem with this option is twofold. In the first place, the explanation will have little or no resonance in ordinary experience. I am afraid it will look like the rabbit pulled out of an empty hat. In the second place, the explanation might contradict ordinary experience, or at least one’s initial estimation of it. For ordinary experience, why not say that it is enough to understand (to use the ITC’s words) that as regards natural law one is not subject “to the law of another, but of accepting the law of one’s own 25 The translation is not always reliable. For example, the French text at §38, “Ce n’est que progressivement que la personne humaine accède à l’expérience morale et devient capable de se dire à elle-même les préceptes qui doivent guider son agir,” in the Bolin translation reads: “The human person only progressively comes to moral experience and becomes capable of giving himself the precepts that should guide his action.” Se dire and se donne, however, are not the same.To say or to formulate does not imply a legislative act. 840 Russell Hittinger being.” Perhaps this is what we earlier discussed as a “placeholder.” Surely, one’s nature is not a “law.” Eventually, a proper explanation will have to uproot the placeholder. Is this a mode of explanation, or is it rather a correction or negation? Another option is to approach the issue in the way suggested by Dewan. Usually, evidence for the theological dimension is put either in the domain of faith or in the domain of demonstration. Dewan warns that the intermediate terrain should not be passed over too quickly. Treating the natural law obligation in religion, Thomas held that “Natural reason declares to man that he is subject to some higher being, because of the deficiencies that he experiences in himself, with respect to which he needs to be helped and directed by some higher being. And whatever that is, it is that which everywhere is called ‘a god’ ” (ST II–II, q. 85, a. 1).Thomas, Dewan explains, “is not presenting a scientific demonstration of the existence of God, but is reporting and attempting to describe what is some universal spontaneous natural inference. Man’s experience of himself is as of a being which cannot stand by itself, without aid, and which cannot survive without steering, without direction, from some source of intelligent direction, moving things along for man’s protection and welfare.” Where does this dictate of reason stand in the scheme of evidence? It is the created intellect declaring to itself, in a rough way, how it stands in a scheme of things.This manner of taking stock needs to be distinguished on the one hand from God speaking about Himself (revelation) and on the other hand from a demonstration. Dewan contends that this dictate of reason, as “a type of natural knowledge,” needs to be put closer to what The Search calls “moral awareness.” . . . not the fruit of deliberate study and method, but given in the way that eyes and ears are given, and yet a knowledge which is not merely the intellectual insight into starting-points, whether of simple terms like “the good” or of propositions like “the good is to be done and promoted, and the bad avoided,” but a naturally occurring, spontaneous reasoning process. The position developed by Dewan seems especially useful for understanding an implicit consensus among wisdom traditions. For one thing, it leaves intact the other points along the spectrum: what is given by nature, the first intellective vision of the good, philosophical explanations and justifications, and the data of faith. “Natural law,” he writes, “is possessed by the human being primarily through the vision of what goodness is, a vision that attests to our immediate relation to the univer- Concluding Unscientific Postscript 841 sal cause of being and goodness.” This seems to be the experiential soil for wisdom traditions. Conclusion None of the authors in our collection of essays impeaches the ITC for ignoring the metaphysical aspects of natural law (for example, §§34, 77). Dewan notes favorably the document’s references to St.Thomas, Leo XIII, and the Catechism of the Catholic Church on natural law as participation in the Eternal Law. It is surely a strong suit of the document. For his part, Steven Long applauds its “affirmation of the strategic importance of a non-competitive account of divine and human causality for the understanding of natural law as a mode of the divine providence.” He continues:“If human freedom is subtracted from the effect of divine agency, then of course human freedom lies outside the divine providence, and accordingly wholly outside the eternal law, outside the divine providential ordering.Thus natural law would be impossible, because natural law is nothing other than the rational participation in eternal law, and eternal law and divine governance generally extend only so far as divine agency extends.” Undoubtedly, this is an issue of singular importance for systematic and philosophical theology. A non-competitive relationship between divine and human agency is also implicit in the wisdom traditions. Getting the account right, therefore, will at least partially constitute an answer to Cardinal Ratzinger’s question of whether morality is “man’s prison.” Neither the essayists nor the ITC report hold that such an account is merely “optional” at the level of theoretical justification. While this is under dispute everywhere else, it is so not here. But in these essays, the issues do not so much gravitate toward the work of a fully philosophical justification, but stand instead at the beginning, in what we can call the role of concepts in initial experience. I would not have predicted this tendency of the debate. But here it is. I have learned much from both The Search and the essayists in this volume. For whatever errors and misconceptions that have entered the debate through my postscript, I have only myself to blame. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition,Vol. 9, No. 3 (2011): 843–863 843 Book Reviews Surnaturel: A Controversy at the Heart of Twentieth-Century Thomistic Thought edited by Serge-Thomas Bonino, O.P., translated by Robert Williams, translation revised by Matthew Levering (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2009 ) 362 pp. The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters by Lawrence Feingold, second edition (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2010 ) 527 pp. I N his contribution to Surnaturel: A Controversy, Gilbert Narcisse, O.P., writes that without the supernatural, “the theologian loses his object of study and all epistemological capability of attaining it.” And again,“there is no theologian without a theology of the relationship between nature and grace” (295). Just so and after more than sixty years, Henri de Lubac’s Surnaturel (1946) has not lost its fascination for Catholic theologians.Two things, at least, have recently contributed to an even greater attention to the topics dealt with in what must strike the theological novice as a collection of excessively abstruse historical essays into some of the dustiest nooks and crannies of the archives of “scholasticism.” The first is the claim of John Milbank and his congeners to the mantle of de Lubac, the claim that Radical Orthodoxy builds on and completes the work of Surnaturel. The second is the publication of a Roman dissertation entitled The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas and His Interpreters (2001), the second edition of which has recently appeared from Sapientia Press. In this volume, Lawrence Feingold both meets the issues on the historical ground of de Lubac’s predilection, but finds his interpretation of St. Thomas untenable, and also concludes that de Lubac’s own construction of the relation of the natural and supernatural orders is incoherent. This is provocative, since for many contemporary theologians, whether heirs of Karl Rahner or of Hans Urs von Balthasar, many of the conclusions of Surnaturel both historical and theological, are as it were “settled law.”We might as well mention here too the conclusion of 844 Book Reviews Fergus Kerr’s recent study of de Lubac that “it is hard to believe that he did not plan his books in order to destroy neoscholastic theology.” So, minds are once again focused where they were more than sixty years ago. Minds need not be focused in exactly the same way, however. Is there some historically trustworthy and theologically irenic way to enter into the issues raised by the interpretation and Wirkungsgeschichte of Surnaturel? Yes. In 2001, the Revue Thomiste published the papers of a symposium, “The Supernatural: A Controversy at the Heart of Twentieth-Century Thomistic Thought,” edited by Serge-Thomas Bonino, O.P. The first book before us is the English translation of this volume. In his introduction, Bonino says that while there can be no demand of nature for the supernatural, neither can nature be thought to be in a condition of simple nonrepugnance to grace.There is a “congenital openness of the mind to the supernatural.” And this sense of things is part of the legacy of de Lubac, part of his enduring achievement, along with which Bonino counts making us pay closer attention to texts and the history of doctrines, reembedding St. Thomas in the tradition of the Fathers, and a bestowal of the primacy to theology over philosophy in the articulation of Christian wisdom. These things are “henceforth irreversible acquisitions” (viii). Moreover, about half of the contributors indicate in one way or another their satisfaction with de Lubac’s interpretation of the natural desire to see God.This is not a volume written from a single point of view. De Lubac’s Surnaturel provokes interest from several directions, and the collection before us accordingly provides an entry into the entire nest of related questions in four chief ways. Some are interested in the history of theology, contemporary or medieval or Baroque. Some are interested in locating the guidance of St. Thomas in determining the res, the matter itself. All interests are served by the book before us. Part One takes us to the year of grace 1946 and is devoted to de Lubac himself and the production and immediate reception of Surnaturel. Part Two examines “Nature and the Supernatural in Thomas Aquinas.” Part Three takes up nature and the supernatural in post-Thomist scholasticism. Part Four, finally, listens for reverberations of Surnaturel in contemporary theology. In Part One, Etienne Fouillioux, emeritus professor of history at Lyons, describes for us the place of de Lubac in French Catholic culture and theology in 1946. He was already well known as the author of Catholicisme (1938) and the Le Drame de l’humanisme athée (1944).And he was recognized as raising questions about contemporary scholastic theology in such works as Corpus Mysticum (1944). Furthermore, he had attained a certain moral authority by his personal conduct during the War as a leader of the “spiritual resistance” and by his rebuke of anti-Semitism Book Reviews 845 and Pétainism. He was editor of Recherches de science religieuse and had been elected a delegate to the General Congregation of the Society of Jesus in 1946. It is important especially for Americans to try to be aware of the variously fractured state of French Catholicism after the War and to recognize de Lubac’s place in it. Fouilloux contributes enormously in short compass to our appreciation of the flammable materials surrounding de Lubac, ready to be touched off by any stray spark. Georges Chantraine, S.J., the friend to whom de Lubac left his literary remains, editor of the oeuvres completes, and his biographer, follows Fouilloux’s setting of the scene with a précis of Surnaturel. He gives us in short form de Lubac’s reading of the Fathers, his construal of post-Thomist scholasticism’s production of the “hypothesis” and then “system” of “pure nature,” and his charge that it reduces nature’s appetite for grace to an obediential potency. It next falls to Henri Donneaud, O.P., to detail the various receptions of Surnaturel by the traditional Thomists Charles Boyer, S.J., Rosaire Gagnebet, O.P., and Marie-Joseph Le Guillou, O.P. He alerts us to the necessity to distinguish “natural desire” taken as an ontological, structural appetite built in to the nature, on the one hand, and on the other, taken as a conscious, elicited desire fully directed to the vision of God only under the guidance of grace. Part One finishes with an essay by René Mougel on de Lubac’s relation to Jacques Maritain apropos of the sin of the angels.What is missing in this part, as Bonino notes in the introduction, is a comparable article on de Lubac’s relation to Etienne Gilson. Bonino remarks in the introduction that de Lubac’s exegesis of St. Thomas has, not surprisingly, been surpassed.The essays in Part Two give evidence of this claim. Michel Bastit opens the section by asking whether Thomism is an Aristotelian system.The importance of this question stems from the fact that, granted the Platonic, and Neoplatonic, resources available to St. Thomas, it matters a great deal whether and at what points he makes Platonism to frame Aristotle or rather to be framed by him. Bastit observes that St.Thomas preserves the Aristotelian diversity of being. He supplements the Platonic formal hierarchy with Aristotelian substance. And he asserts the real distinction of esse and essence within a composition of principles that preserves the unity of beings. The upshot is that Aristotle enables St.Thomas to escape Neoplatonic pantheism, and Aristotelian “consistency of nature and specificity of each being” provide “the guarantee that Redemption has a subject,” and that grace will be gratuitous (101).The relevance for an appreciation of Surnaturel is understated but clear. If one inserts Aristotelian nature into a Plotinian emanationism, 846 Book Reviews then the natural desire for God will be structural, ontological, for therein natures lose their consistency and so distinction. If, on the contrary, participation is framed by Aristotle, there can be no such natural desire as de Lubac understands it. Furthermore, Cajetan is, as it were, rehabilitated as a reader of St.Thomas one must reckon with. Jean-Miguel Garrigues renders a similarly understated verdict on de Lubac’s strictures on characterizing nature as in obediential potency to the supernatural. He does this by asking about the “natural grace” of Christ, the grace that follows upon the origin of Christ’s humanity in its assumption, and discussing the potency of this nature for the grace of union. It is an obediential potency, according to St. Thomas. This does not, however, mean that the fitness of human nature so to be assumed is denied or ignored. Rather, the fitness for union derives from the nature itself as rational, as capable of vision.Thus the potency of human nature in general to grace and glory is obediential, and still, it is fitting that it be so endowed. Serge-Thomas Bonino, in his own contribution to the volume, investigates St.Thomas’s theory of limbo, which most approaches the idea of “pure nature” and which de Lubac mostly skips. St. Thomas entertains the position common to the thirteenth century that such souls’ knowledge of the supernatural call to the vision of God need not induce suffering under the condition of their virtuous resignation. But he prefers to argue for their complete ignorance of such an end on the ground that the knowledge of it is impossible apart from revelation. Though St. Thomas does not speak of “beatitude” for such souls, and it remains that de facto they are suffering a penalty for original sin, there is here the limning of a “natural end” of man, and any innate ordering to or proportion unto vision is denied.Vision is not connatural to human nature. In what many readers will find to be one of the more valuable contributions, J.-P.Torrell, O.P., sorts out St.Thomas’s view of the state of original justice and the state of corruption. Contrary to Peter Lombard, St. Thomas holds that man was created in grace in view of his supernatural end. Even so and precisely in order to come to a just appreciation of grace, he takes up the task of contrasting what man could do in virtue of original grace (Adam’s first state), what he could do in virtue of uncorrupted nature but without grace (the never realized state of “integrity”), and what ungraced nature can do now, after corruption by sin (our actual condition prior to justification).Within this project, the concept of “integral nature” occupies the same strategic position as that of pura naturalia. St.Thomas’s synthesis of the Areopagite and St. Augustine on the effects of original sin is very clearly and helpfully presented. Book Reviews 847 For many, Part Two will be the most important: it provides as it were by triangulation a judgment as to de Lubac’s exegesis and interpretation of Thomas. The studies clearly if in a muted voice raise questions about the adequacy of de Lubac’s handling of nature, obediential potency, and “pure nature” in St.Thomas. Part Three contains three studies, the first of which, by Lawrence Renault, addresses a part of the post-Thomist history of the theology of the supernatural omitted by de Lubac, the part played by William of Ockham, who denied there could be an innate desire for a supernatural end, and much before Cajetan taught the strict proportion between an end and access to an end. Jacob Schmutz contributes an essay on the metaphysical path of late scholasticism to the separation of the natural and supernatural orders that de Lubac alleges occurs in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century scholasticism. This metaphysical path more and more conceives of created causality as something independent of God. While St. Thomas and the thirteenth century leave us with the view according to which the causality of second causes is itself wholly created, this inheritance of Neoplatonism is progressively transmuted into a view where the creature adds something to the divine causality, and we end with the thesis espoused by Molina according to which God and the creature are partial causes of one and the same effect. “Influence,” which in the thirteenth century was another name for procession from the First Cause, ends up by naming the divine causality as the condition of the mere maintenance in being of the second cause.The last contribution to this part of the volume is a study of the natural desire to see God as treated by the Salmanticenses. It begins with a very clear delimitation of the distinction of natural appetite or natural, innate desire, and elicited conscious desire that those just entering the discussion will find helpful, although the author’s clarity unfortunately diminishes when he presents the difference between the elicited desire to see God, which is the desire to know what the First Cause is, and the elicited desire to attain to this knowledge as one’s beatitude. Part Four brings us to “the question of the supernatural today.” Georges Cottier, O.P., seeks to re-introduce the notion of a natural mysticism, a mysticism of the ego engaged in a radical experience of itself, and its being prior to any act, prior to any unfolding of the soul into its powers, and this in contrast to contemporary efforts to make of all mysticism a supernatural one, in which the Christian revelation resounds and the grace of Christ is operative.The rehabilitation of a natural mysticism, concomitant with a recognition of naturally available truths in other religions will make us less liable to confound Christianity with other religions. This same issue is 848 Book Reviews taken up also by Gilbert Narcisse, O.P., who examines the impact of de Lubac on contemporary theology. He points to four areas where contemporary positions, though they do not follow directly from the theses of the Surnaturel, nevertheless are fostered by them. One of these is the issue already visited by Cottier, the move from the unique mediation of Christ to the recognition of many non-Christian (or cryptically Christian) mediations of revelation and grace.The others are the transition from rationalist apologetics to a fundamental theology conceived to be addressed to men already touched by grace, the transition from theology sub ratione Dei to theology sub ratione Trinitatis (Balthasar), and the shift from Thomistic metaphysics to philosophical pluralism. Narcisse closes with the observation of the role of metaphysics in the ability to keep a firm hold on the gratuity of grace. In a last essay, Benoît-Dominique de La Soujeole, O.P., correlates the nature-grace extrinsicism which de Lubac laments with modern ecclesiology. St. Robert Bellarmine’s distinction between the soul and body of the Church, according to which one could belong to one and not the other, survives into the twentieth century, where the Church as visible and natural society remains in principle something that can be separable from the Church as communion in grace and charity. La Soujeole follows Cardinal Journet in seeking a more adequate conception of the unity of the Church, and finds help in identifying the visibility of the New Law not only in the means of grace, but in the effects of grace in the visible community of charity.This provides a broader basis on which to re-think not only the question of unity, but that of membership, as well. This is an altogether fine collection of essays. I mentioned that about half the contributors express sympathy with de Lubac’s interpretation of the natural desire to see God.That no essay directly addresses this issue in St. Thomas or in itself is a disappointment, but also a sign of the enormity of the question. The large volume by Lawrence Feingold is the demonstration of this enormity.This second edition is a friendlier version of the original dissertation in that the extensive Latin quotations have been translated, the exposition at some few points streamlined, and at others made more pointed. There are many reasons to read this book. First, there is the importance of the res, of a correct understanding of the natural desire to see God, for both theological anthropology and apologetics. Second, we want also to know what St.Thomas taught about this.Third, we want also to know whether the subsequent scholastic reception of St. Thomas preserved or deformed his teaching. Fourth, we want to know the adequacy of de Lubac’s reception of both St.Thomas and his scholastic heirs, the better to sort out our Book Reviews 849 own very messy theological inheritance. This last interest is connected to questions about the nature and practice of Catholic theology, about which Feingold says: “a global vilification of an entire period of over four centuries in the history of Catholic theology cannot fail to be seriously detrimental to the cause of theology and the life of the Church, because it introduces a violent rupture rather than organic growth” (440). On all four counts, Feingold’s book must, I think, be counted indispensable. Moreover, the orderliness and clarity of his exposition give us a model of how to write, and the charity of his discussion a model of how to conduct ourselves. He also alerts us to an important pastoral dimension of the proceedings:“one of the great pastoral problems of our time is that so many people . . . take heaven for granted as something somehow due simply to natural goodness” (443). What is in this book? A first chapter introduces us to ST I–II, q. 3, a. 8, where St. Thomas says that, once we know from the things that have been made that God their cause exists, we naturally desire to know the essence of that cause. It follows from this, St. Thomas concludes, that man’s perfect happiness, wherein every desire is perfectly satisfied, consists in the vision of God. Four questions structure the ensuing reception of this argument. First, does this conscious “elicited” desire to know God manifest the existence of another and more basic desire, an unconscious but “innate” desire to know God, which would amount to positing a constitutive ordination in man unto the vision of God? Second, is the natural desire to see God absolute or conditional? That is, is it like a settled intention for an end known to be attainable, or is it like a wish that things could be so, in the absence of seeing how they could be so? Third, is the argument whose grand conclusion is that our happiness consists in the vision of God demonstrative or an indication of fittingness? Fourth, does the desire to see God show the impossibility of there being a state of “pure nature” for human beings? The questions fit together as follows. If the desire is innate, then it is absolute. If the desire is absolute, and supposing it is an object of certain natural knowledge, the argument constitutes a philosophical demonstration that our ultimate end is the vision of God. Last, if the desire is absolute, its fulfillment is owed, something due to man, and it is impossible that God could have established and left man puris in naturalibus to pursue an end and a happiness other than the vision of God. In chapter 2, Feingold lays the groundwork for understanding both St. Thomas’s position and the entire subsequent history of the question by sorting out St. Thomas’s analysis of appetite and desire, so providing the systematic context in which a natural desire to see God is asserted. Every 850 Book Reviews nature, every power of every nature, has a natural appetite unto its proportionate end. This is a constitutive inclination which makes the nature or power be what it is; it is what is later called innate desire. A constitutive inclination, it is always “on,” and so is to be distinguished from elicited appetite, the appetite or desire that follows upon knowledge in those creatures with a cognoscitive capacity. Elicited desire in man follows the intellect’s cognition of some good. It is conscious, and it absolutely depends on entertaining consciously the good in question. Natural appetite, the constitutive appetite that specifies a nature or power, is evidently something always and necessarily in force; it is not facultative. It is a mistake, however, to think that elicited appetite is by contrast always free. Deliberated acts of will bearing on how to attain to some known good are certainly free; they are what we call “choices.” But prior to them there are naturally elicited acts of will for goods, natural in the sense that, once the good is presented to appetitive power, the power must incline to them in act. For men, these are such things as life, virtue, society, and knowledge. And there can be natural specifications of these general inclinations. A natural specification of the inclination to knowledge following on the natural knowledge of God’s existence is the desire to know God’s essence. When St.Thomas speaks of a natural desire for the vision of God, does he mean an innate desire or a naturally occurring elicited act of inclination toward the good of knowing the first cause or both? The canvass of texts Feingold makes in chapter 3 shows us that the most natural way to take St.Thomas is that he is asserting the existence of an elicited desire, naturally evoked upon the knowledge of God’s existence, and a desire that is conditional, for it comes with the realization that the knowledge of the essence of God is not within the compass of our cognoscitive power to attain to on its own. Even so, questions remain. Is the natural desire to see God the same as desiring supernatural happiness? But in that case, how can it not be what is otherwise described as the act of the theological virtue of hope? And then, how can grace not be required to incline us to the supernatural end of glory? St.Thomas does not leave this matter with all the clarity his readers would desire in every text. The subsequent history is the series of triangulations and calculations, as it were, by which the Thomist tradition puts text to text and finds its way to what must be the answer. The role of John Duns Scotus in this history is the first order of business after the canvass of St.Thomas’s texts. For Scotus, the potency to see God is natural, not obediential, and the desire to see God is innate. For St. Thomas, the desire seems to be something naturally knowable, naturally available to us according as we come to the knowledge of the exis- Book Reviews 851 tence of the First Cause, and then, want to know its essence. But Scotus holds that the natural desire cannot be known apart from revelation, which informs us of the de facto end of man, the vision of God.This has the consequence that the natural desire for the vision of God is emptied of any apologetic value in manifesting the truth of Catholic doctrine. The history Feingold shows us subsequent to Scotus is the history of a long argument within the parameters set by St.Thomas and Scotus, the story as Feingold tells it of a steady contemplation of the reality of the supernatural order and an increasingly happy and integrated articulation of this reality as bestowed in Christ. Denis the Carthusian begins the dialectic in the mid-fifteenth century. He sees that the first order of business is to oppose Scotus.There can be no natural desire for the vision of God if natural desire means innate desire, a pondus naturae that operates even prior to knowledge, for such innate desire cannot extend beyond the proportion of nature.The potency to supernatural happiness and vision is obediential and not natural. This draws the difference between Scotus and St.Thomas very successfully. But then, Denis does not know how to handle the texts of St.Thomas that do assert a natural desire to see God. Supposing this natural desire is what Scotus means by natural desire, Denis aptly raises two fundamental questions: First, how can such a natural desire to see God be compatible with the supernatural and gratuitous character of actually seeing God, if a natural desire cannot be in vain? And second, how can there be an argument from a datum of nature—natural desire for vision—showing something that we otherwise treat as a mystery known only by revelation? There follows a long chronicle of the efforts to sort out these issues. Cardinal Cajetan again shows that there can be no Scotist innate inclination to the vision of God. Such would make us not merely capax Dei, able to share the divine nature (2 Pt 1:4), but already and in virtue of our created being sharers in that nature. By nature, we have a natural desire for an end proper and proportionate to that nature. And knowing God as God knows himself is obviously a perfection not proportionate to man.What inclines us to God supernaturally possessed, what orders us to such possession, is not nature but grace and the theological virtues. Feingold at this point reviews the many texts of St.Thomas that establish this and so Cajetan’s faithfulness to his master.There is as well an exhaustive review of the objections to Cajetan put forward by Gilson, Jorge Laporta, and de Lubac.That the potency to vision be obediential, not natural, is required if the gratuity of the supernatural order is to be maintained. For St.Thomas, a natural potency for some perfection is always and necessarily and with no exceptions allied with a natural active potency that can produce the fulfillment in question. That 852 Book Reviews there is no human capacity to realize on our own the vision of God is of course implied in the necessity of grace to attain such an end. However, not all obediential potency is the same.There is the potency of any created thing to obey the God who can make sons of Abraham out of stones. And there is the potency of man to become a son of God. In the former case, the potency is generic; in the latter, we are dealing with a specific obediential potency, in which the subject of the potency does not pass away (as do the stones), but in which it is perfected along the lines of its own nature, precisely as one who knows and loves. Here again Feingold reviews the texts of St.Thomas one by one and in detail in order to demonstrate to the reader the accuracy of Cajetan’s reading of St.Thomas. It is this notion, that of a specific obediential potency, that entails that grace perfects nature and that renders the charge of “extrinsicism” against Cajetan and Suárez false. When it comes to making sense of ST I–II, q. 3, a. 8, and parallels, however, the great commentator stumbles. Such argument is not in the philosophical but in the theological order, Cajetan hazards. We are to understand that St. Thomas is arguing from supernatural effects to their supernatural cause. Or we must distinguish knowing God as cause and knowing him unrestrictedly in his essence. A successful march on what we must understand St. Thomas’s assertion of a natural desire to see God to entail begins with Sylvester of Ferrara, who establishes in the first place that St. Thomas is speaking of an elicited desire, once the existence of the First Cause is known, and who in the second place points out that it is a naturally and necessarily elicited desire: it cannot be that we do not desire to know what God is once we know that he is. Sylvester also brings to prominence the distinction between wanting to see God, and wanting the vision of God to be our happiness.The first is spontaneous and natural; the second is a desire moved by grace. Denis, Cajetan, and Sylvester read St. Thomas as opposed to each other; Soto and Toletus do not, and they make St.Thomas affirm a natural desire to see God as Scotus understands it. This chapter is not some function of scrupulosity in treating the record, but shows us a possibility within the dialectic of positions, a possibility that will be refused by the very next generation of de Soto’s students, a possibility that Suárez, the omnivore, will be aware of in the final construction of an adequate reading of St.Thomas, and a possibility that will be resurrected in the twentieth century by Jorge Laporta and Henri de Lubac. Collectively, Bartolomé de Medina, Domingo Báñez, and Francisco Suárez construct the position that Feingold labels the “consensus,” the consensus of some three hundred years.The desire to see God is an elicited Book Reviews 853 desire; it is a conditional, an imperfect desire; and it provides an argument for the fittingness of our call to a supernatural end, but not a demonstration of the possibility of the call and still less of its actuality.With this, the way to read all of St.Thomas’s texts together has been reached.As well, one of the major but little-emphasized implications of St.Thomas’s position is expressed in detail, and that is the necessary existence of a connatural final end for man, and the consequent realization that, with no injustice, man could have been let to exist in a state of “pure nature.” Feingold notes the extent to which the possibility of “pure nature” is defined by magisterial teaching after Jansenism. Enter de Lubac. Feingold is careful to inform us that he understands himself to be dealing very narrowly with de Lubac’s theological anthropology, and with nothing else in his theological production. He distinguishes himself explicitly from John Milbank. Milbank takes the entire production of de Lubac as a systematic whole, the key to which is Surnaturel. Feingold does not. De Lubac is one with Jansenius in denying the possibility for us of a state of pure nature. He does this not by asserting that grace and glory are due to prelapsarian Adam, but by holding that finality to vision is already a part of the natural constitution of man. Fundamental to de Lubac’s position is the thesis that a supernatural finality is “imprinted” on our nature, for only so is “extrinsicism” avoided, wherein grace when given would be imposed on a human being already and erroneously conceived as self-sufficient, with a merely obediential potency to grace. Second, this intrinsic finality, already given with the nature and defining the nature, is itself a “natural desire” for the vision of God; in the later language it is an “innate” desire for vision, something prior to any elicited and conscious desire to see God, which elicited desire is only a manifestation of what is alone ontologically and theologically interesting, the innate desire, the pondus naturae whose resting place is vision. Third, since the desire for vision is innate, and a natural desire is determined to one end alone, there can be no other end for man; his only end is vision. De Lubac embraces the position of Scotus that the potency for vision is natural, but he is more radical, for while Scotus thought a purely natural beatitude possible for us, de Lubac holds that, absent the vision of God, we are in misery. The fact that our only end is vision entails, fourth, the impossibility that man with the nature he now has could exist in a state of “pure nature.” Since it follows from the natural, innate desire that our actual end is in fact vision, and the application of the axiom that no natural desire can be in vain is to be applied simply and without qualification, it must be, fifth, that the natural desire itself cannot be known apart from revelation.Were 854 Book Reviews it otherwise, then from the natural desire naturally known, we would come to know what Catholic tradition insists can only be known by revelation, namely, that our actual end consists in the vision of God. Sixth and last, this intrinsic finality unto vision ought not be conceived as an actual “ordering” of man unto vision, and so it does not in any way imply that grace and glory are due to man, a debitum naturae. It is grace and the theological virtues, not the natural desire, that “orders” man to a strictly and completely gratuitous supernatural end. It is with this last point that things start to come unraveled.What could an intrinsic finality of nature toward an end possibly be that does not “order” the nature toward the end? The distinction de Lubac needs at this point is not given in St. Thomas, for whom our nature is connaturally ordered toward a connatural end, and for whom it is sanctifying grace and the theological virtues that give us an intrinsic finality toward a supernatural end, and actually order us toward that end. If the nature is not intrinsically ordered by nature toward vision, and if being actually so ordered is a gratuitous gift, then it follows also that a state of pure nature is perfectly possible, and in fact, it is actually entertained when St.Thomas writes of limbo, in the beginning as at the end of his career. Theologically, the problem de Lubac’s position faces is the gratuity of grace. He tries to preserve gratuity by distinguishing nature taken abstractly (not ordered to vision) and taken concretely (ordered to vision), but as Feingold shows, it is difficult to maintain this as a real distinction.This proposal, moreover, points to the underlying philosophical problem of de Lubac’s position which is indeed the integrity of nature. A created nature, precisely in its real distinction from the divine nature, must have a finality unto another end than that of the divine nature. It cannot have a supernatural finality inscribed in it except on pain of ceasing to be a created nature with a proportionate end. And a created nature with no proportionate end is no nature. De Lubac is sometimes represented as maintaining the “openness” of human spirit to grace, as we have seen above (Bonino). But on Feingold’s showing, he does far more. He makes the link between nature and grace so tight as to destroy the gratuity of grace.The problem can be expressed by asking whether the intrinsic finality de Lubac postulates is itself natural or supernatural. It is natural, contained within the nature, else how does it provide the solution to the problem of extrinsicism? But if it is a finality toward something supernatural, how can it not also itself be something supernatural? “Openness” is rather maintained, for Feingold, by asserting a specific obediential potency:“potency” asserts a possibility really verified in this subject,“obediential” says that the realization of the possibility will Book Reviews 855 be directly by God’s agency alone; and “specific” asserts that the realization of the potency does not do away with the subject or change its nature; no, the nature is preserved, and created spirit remains created spirit in realizing by the grace of God a supernatural end. It is Feingold’s exposition and defense and deployment of this notion of a specific obediential potency that is one of the greatest services of his study. It is deployed not only to maintain gratuity, but also, in tandem with the natural desire itself, to demonstrate the fittingness of our being called to vision. The desire shows, says Feingold, man’s transcendence: it projects him to a desideratum absolutely exceeding—transcending—his natural capacity for perfection, and in this way declares the excellence of human nature. And to say the potency for the realization of this desire is specifically obediential declares that its actualization will be the actualization and supernaturalization of precisely this created nature, human nature, maintaining its integrity, completing it and super-completing it in the direction of its own highest aspiration, the possession of the truth of things, and indeed, the Truth of things. The consensus view whose construction Feingold shows us does not give us a nature “closed in on itself.” The natural desire, conditional though it be, is conscious, and it connects us with what is above us precisely insofar as we are humans, and so, consciously, something that de Lubac’s interpretation evidently does not do. It is misleading to characterize this understanding as making the desire a “mere” velleity, as if so to call it were to make it something unimportant, trivial, of no great theological moment. Feingold’s exposition is especially strong where he points out that the two ends of man, connatural and supernatural, as envisaged by the Thomist tradition are not alternatives. Pure nature may be hypothetical, but our connatural end remains our really and truly existing connatural end, which is to know God from the things that have been made. That we are also assigned a supernatural end does not do away with this. Rather, the supernatural end fulfills our capacity for natural happiness, and overfills it, but in the same line already projected by our connatural end, the knowledge of God. The assertion of two ends does not render us closed to grace, and the fulfillment of the natural desire for a natural happiness does not give us parallel universes, or layers. Part of the answer to the charge of extrinsicism is precisely to insist that it is nature that comes to rest in the super natural end. Beyond the historical question, beyond the important matters of how to understand “nature” and obediential potency etc. already touched on, Feingold’s study is significant for thinking through yet again the crucial issues de Lubac himself thought to address. 856 Book Reviews First, it is important in answering the question, to whom do we think we are speaking when we take up the work of evangelization? Are we speaking to already secret Christians? Are we speaking to people already necessarily interiorly moved in some way by the supernatural order? For both de Lubac and Rahner, though on different accounts, the answer is Yes. Or are we speaking to pagans, and perhaps to people in a condition worse than paganism (as Peter Wust would have it), but in any event people “separated from Christ, . . . strangers to the covenants of promise, having no hope and without God in the world” (Eph 2:12)? On the other hand, for de Lubac and Scotus, to declare that we naturally desire God is to say something known only by revelation. It is part of the content of faith, not a preamble. But if the desire is naturally elicited upon entertaining the idea of God, it can in principle play a role in addressing the gospel to every man, and no matter what his moral condition. Second, why are we faced with the daunting task of the evangelization of peoples who have abandoned the gospel? De Lubac promoted his version of the natural desire in part because he thought it was the antidote to the view—Cajetan’s and Suárez’s—that led to the cultural triumph of the Enlightenment and the de-Christianization of Europe. But if there was in the consensus view no such a divorce between nature and grace as de Lubac alleged, and if, in fact, this view that de Lubac scorned is true, and if we do not suppose that the truth about nature and grace led to the demise of Christian Europe, and if we set aside crude secularization hypotheses about the incompatibility of electric lights and angels, then still, de Lubac’s question remains: what did lead to its demise? We can once again round up the usual suspects. Politically, there were the “wars of religion,” that is, there was the rise of the absolutist state (D. B. Hart), which robbed the Church of her public authority, and which had an interest, carried out by its ideological apologists, in suppressing the very idea of nature (Pierre Manent). Philosophically, there was, first, rationalism, and the introduction of rationalism into the analysis of the act of faith in England (William Chillingworth), and the erection of reason as the tribunal of what can count as the content of faith in Germany (Kant); second, there was skepticism, so fixing the limits of what reason can know that positivism rules our relation to the world, and relativism our relation to human ends and moral action. Was theology then blameless? No. Although there was always something odd and disproportionate in blaming the rise of atheism and secularism—the cultural suicide of Europe—on the sixteenth- and seventeenth-century elaboration of the possibility of “pure nature” by certain Jesuit and Dominican schoolmen, it is not so odd to blame the same schoolmen if Book Reviews 857 it is true that they contributed to the construction of the idols of the authority of conscience and absolute freedom of indifference that were later to be worshiped by the Enlightenment without benefit of clergy (see John Lamont in the April 2009 issue of The Thomist). Sapientia Press has rendered a quite signal service in making these two N&V volumes available to a wider audience. Guy Mansini, O.S.B. Saint Meinrad Seminary St. Meinrad, Indiana World Upside Down: Reading Acts in the Graeco-Roman Age by C. Kavin Rowe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009 ), 310 pp. R ECENT years have witnessed a resurgence of interest in the task of theological interpretation of Scripture, the results of which have been mixed. More often than not, biblical scholars struggle to break out of the strictures of our discipline, making the leap from the ancient text to the contemporary situation awkwardly and uncertainly.The contributions of theologians to the various new theological commentary series, on the other hand, often ride roughshod over the ancient text. In World Upside Down: Reading Acts in the Graeco-Roman Age, C. Kavin Rowe bridges the seemingly unbridgeable divide, showing how the book of Acts speaks to the first-century Christian situation and in so doing can address contemporary issues, as well. Rowe argues against two common interpretations of Acts. Based on the constant reminders of Paul’s innocence, one standard reading sees Acts as an apology for the early Christian movement, suggesting that Christianity posed no threat to the Roman Empire. More recently, some interpreters have argued that, on the contrary, Acts is an anti-imperial text that challenges the claims of Caesar. Against both of these readings, Rowe suggests that the key to understanding the message of Acts lies in holding together the dialectical tension between the gospel’s challenge to pagan culture and the rejection of political insurrection. After an introductory chapter laying out the basic premises of the study, the argument unfolds in three chapters, followed by a conclusion that brings together Rowe’s reading of Acts with contemporary political and theological questions. The second chapter shows how the announcement of the gospel disrupts various aspects of Roman society.The early Christian proclamation of a God who demands exclusive worship inevitably challenged not only religious convictions but also the social, political, and economic realities of the empire.This clash of cultures lies at the heart of four episodes in Acts that are representative of the character of the book as 858 Book Reviews a whole.The first story, the confusion of Paul and Barnabas for Zeus and Hermes in Acts 14, demonstrates the distinctiveness of the Christian message. In contrast to the common pagan practice of identifying gods of different names as different manifestations of the same god, Paul and Barnabas pose a sharp distinction between the God revealed in Jesus Christ and the various pagan gods, thus challenging the whole pagan sacrificial system. The scandal of this message is made evident by the reaction of the people, who drag Paul out of the city and stone him. Episodes in Philippi,Athens, and Ephesus reveal a similar pattern. The exorcism of the woman with a spirit of prophecy (Acts 16) threatens not only the religious practices of the Philippians but also a source of income. Despite superficial similarities to the pagan practice of substituting different names for the same gods, the Areopagus speech (Acts 17) calls for an abandonment of idolatry. Insofar as worship was bound up with political life, Paul poses not only a religious threat but also a political one.The conversion of a large crowd in Ephesus and the subsequent burning of magical books (Acts 19) put the city in an uproar. Again, the challenge is not simply “religious,” but rather comprehensive, affecting economics and civic life as much as religion. Based on this evidence, one might be tempted to side with the proponents of an anti-imperial reading of Acts, but this is not the whole story. Alongside these periodic disruptions of Roman society, Luke also describes a series of trials before Roman officials, each of which ends in Paul’s acquittal. Scholars have often read these trials as Luke’s defense of the Church, and they have gone on to infer that, for Luke, the Church and the Roman Empire could peacefully coexist. In his third chapter Rowe offers a more nuanced reading of the text that holds together both these passages and those that are more amenable to an anti-imperial reading. It is true, he notes, that at every one of Paul’s trials the Roman officials acquit him of the charges. Despite the efforts of Paul’s opponents to paint him as an insurrectionist, the Romans recognize that the early Christian movement was not interested in sedition—even the claim that Jesus is “Lord of all” (Acts 10:36) does not for Luke entail the establishment of a worldly empire in competition with Rome. Those who have argued that Luke offers a pro-Roman picture of the empire ignore an important element of Luke’s story, however. Though the Romans acknowledged Jesus’ innocence, he nevertheless ended up on the cross. Given Jesus’ fate, Paul’s acquittals are tinged with uncertainty. The fourth chapter seeks to account for the tension revealed by the preceding argument. Rowe attributes the complexity of the Church’s position vis-à-vis the empire to three interrelated practices of the early Christians: confession of Jesus as Lord, universal mission, and the forma- Book Reviews 859 tion of Christian communities. Though Acts consistently portrays the early Church as innocent of the charge of insurrection, this does not mean that this confession of Jesus was totally innocuous. In designating Jesus “Lord of all,” Luke implicitly undercuts imperial claims to universal sovereignty. Yet this is not a challenge to Caesar’s political power. On the contrary, Rowe argues, it is Caesar’s claim to the title “Lord of all” that challenges the universal sovereignty of the God of Israel exercised through Jesus Christ. This confession leads naturally to the Christian impulse to universal mission, because Jesus’ lordship is closely tied to salvation (cf.Acts 4:12).The desire for the salvation of all drives Jesus’ disciples to spread the message throughout the entire world, and this mission entails the formation of Christian communities. The gospel is not simply a matter of the heart, but rather something that calls forth social embodiment. When taken together and read in their proper light, these three practices account for the tension in Luke’s story.The new way of life that Luke offers operates on fundamentally different terms than Greco-Roman culture and thus accounts for the clash with Roman civilization. At the same time, because it operates on these different terms, this way of life does not entail a bid for earthly power over against Caesar. Rather, Luke’s message is a “light for revelation to the gentiles” (Luke 2:32); its purpose, to call the gentiles out of darkness into the light of the gospel. Rowe’s final chapter bears the provocative title “The Apocalypse of Acts and the Life of Truth,” and it takes steps toward applying the argument of the preceding three chapters to a contemporary setting. Acts, Rowe argues, sets forth a way of knowing that is not simply a matter of ratiocination, but rather is an embodied epistemology springing forth from the concrete practices of the early Christians.These practices inherently make universal claims that are unappealing to moderns whose purported allegiance is to tolerance above all else, and so Rowe closes the book with a discussion of the implications of Acts for political theology and the question of truth. He begins by addressing the common assertion that polytheism, because it can include a number of gods from different cultures, was inherently tolerant. Despite the surface plausibility of such a claim, a closer look at Roman history reveals numerous instances of imperial intolerance toward certain religious groups, including but not limited to the Druids and the Christians. Perhaps more importantly, tolerance does not stand alone, but rather necessarily entails distinctions between what will and will not be tolerated.Thus, polytheism “defines a particular kind of tolerance—the kind that places a missionizing Christianity outside its limits” (167, emphasis in original). Rowe goes on to criticize the bifurcation of politics and theology. Like tolerance, politics is 860 Book Reviews not practiced in a vacuum, but rather has a theological—one might say more neutrally, a metaphysical—basis. One of the fears perpetuated by the modern narrative of the so-called “Wars of Religion” is that religious certitude breeds violence and bloodshed. Bringing together the various strands of his argument, Rowe offers a dialectical assessment of the relation of Acts to tolerance and bloodshed. On the one hand, he notes, “in a crucial way, the vision of Acts is profoundly intolerant” (170). The confession of Jesus as Lord of all by necessity demands the conversion of all. On the other hand, the narrative of Acts eschews the use of force to spread the gospel. For Luke, witness rather than coercion is the manner of the gospel’s encounter with the world. Rowe has offered us a masterful reading of Acts, as well as an erudite example of how to bring together historically sensitive readings of the New Testament with contemporary theological questions. As comfortable interacting with philosophers such as Charles Taylor and Alasdair MacIntyre as he is offering close readings of the Greek text of Acts, Rowe makes a compelling case for the unity of faith and life, the central theme of his book. One of his most refreshing contributions is the correction he offers to standard anti-imperial readings of the New Testament. It has become a commonplace in certain circles to assert that in proclaiming Jesus as Lord the early Christians were challenging the claims of Caesar. Rowe suggests that this is to put things backwards, at least as far as Luke is concerned. Jesus does not challenge Caesar’s claim to lordship; on the contrary, from Luke’s perspective Caesar’s claim to lordship challenges the more fundamental lordship of the God of Israel exercised through Jesus Christ.The distinction, though subtle, is an important one. World Upside Down also raises several questions. As already noted, the designation of Acts as an “apocalypse” is a provocative one, and one that calls for more justification. Though I am sympathetic with the sense in which Rowe seems to be using the term, a more detailed engagement with those who deny the apocalyptic character of Acts would have been apropos, given the common scholarly bifurcation of salvation history (a common characterization of Luke’s thought) and apocalyptic. A more difficult question concerns how one might fruitfully apply the vision of Acts to a cultural setting in which to some extent Christians occupy the place of Caesar.The issue is no doubt thorny and complex, but it would have been helpful to see this work, which addresses questions of contemporary significance, grapple with one of the most difficult and relevant issues for Christians today. Finally, Rowe’s suggestion in the last few pages that to deny the worldview of Acts is to distort the text’s meaning, though true to Acts, raises the perennial question of whether an unbe- Book Reviews 861 liever can understand a believer’s text. Is conversion a necessary prerequisite to reading Acts rightly, such that one who contests the vision of Acts (to use Rowe’s language) will inevitably misread the text? Given his penchant for dialectic, one might expect Rowe to offer the traditional answer Sic et non, but I suspect he would find such an answer ultimately unsatisfying. At any rate, it is one of the pressing questions the work raises, and one that would have benefited from a fuller discussion. That the work raises such questions is a testament to Rowe’s learning and theological acumen. World Upside Down exemplifies a responsible and sophisticated approach to the often nebulous field of theological interpretation, and for that we are in his debt. May it turn the world of New Testament scholarship upside down and call us back to the unity of faith and life fundamental to the gospel. N&V Rodrigo J. Morales Marquette University Milwaukee,Wisconsin Commentary on the Gospel of John, by Thomas Aquinas, translated by Fabian Larcher, O.P., and James A. Weisheipl, O.P., with introduction and notes by Daniel Keating and Matthew Levering, 3 vols. (Washington, DC:The Catholic University of America Press, 2010 ). T HE present revival of interest in Aquinas’s biblical interpretation can be attributed to at least two factors. One is that scholars have placed a greater emphasis on the interrelation between the Summa theologiae and Aquinas’s scriptural interpretation. Aquinas’s interpretation of Scripture deeply informs his judgments contained in the Summa, and the Summa in turn serves our reading of Scripture by its ability to arrange the sacra doctrina found in Scripture into an ordered wisdom that helps illuminate (rather than obscure) the contents of Scripture. Another factor is that historicalcritical methods of exegesis have proven insufficient by themselves for engaging the realities taught in Scripture. This has led to an increased openness for resourcing pre-critical exegetical methods of interpreting Scripture.When scholars turn to the exegetical past, they find Aquinas a valuable and largely unexplored resource for contributing to a renewed engagement with Scripture. These factors (among others) have so profoundly contributed to a renewed focus on Aquinas’s biblical interpretation that Adian Nichols, O.P., recently observed,“St.Thomas’s reputation as an exegete has probably never stood higher than it does today.” It is in this fertile setting that a new English translation of Aquinas’s commentary on the Gospel of John is welcomed. Aquinas’s commentary 862 Book Reviews work on John is special. Scholars have recognized that within Aquinas’s commentary corpus, certain commentaries are particularly excellent, and one of these is his commentary on John. The new English edition from The Catholic University of America Press’s Thomas Aquinas in Translation series is not the first English edition of Aquinas’s Super Ioannem, but the new edition contributes significantly to the former, thanks to the efforts of Daniel Keating and Matthew Levering.The foundation for the English translation remains the same—that from Fabian Larcher, O.P., and James Weisheipl, O.P.—but the new edition corrects previous translation mistakes, adds a section of Aquinas’s commentary entirely left out of the former translation, and includes a prologue attributed to St. Jerome with a commentary by Aquinas that helps illuminate Aquinas’s “overall estimation of the Gospel of John.” One of most valuable aspects of this new edition, however, is the inclusion of footnotes throughout the commentary that reference Aquinas’s Summa theologiae, patristic sources, and various councils, heresies, and lesser-known figures alluded to by Aquinas. These notes enable the reader to get a sense of the scriptural roots of Aquinas’s Summa and helps properly situate Aquinas’s commentary within the Church’s tradition of theological reflection. Keating and Levering introduce the commentary with some helpful insights into Aquinas’s interpretive method. They address, first, the relationship between the literal and spiritual senses of Scripture. In Aquinas’s commentary on John, the literal sense takes precedent, with some chapters lacking a single spiritual interpretation. But spiritual interpretations (i.e. the “mystical sense”) do occur, and Levering and Keating offer some guidance in understanding Aquinas’s turn to the mystical sense by providing a case study of Aquinas’s mystical interpretation that occurs with Jesus’ words to Mary Magdalene, “Do not hold me, for I have not yet ascended to the Father.” Since Jesus clearly has no problems in other locations with people touching his post-resurrected body (Mt 28:9; Lk 24:39), there must be, according to Aquinas, a meaning in addition to the literal sense that the Holy Spirit is seeking to teach. It is this realization that leads Aquinas to explore the mystical sense of this passage. Keating and Levering then address another striking element of Aquinas’s commentary on John, and really of almost all of his commentaries: the number of “parallel” biblical texts cited by Aquinas from both the Old and the New Testaments. For Keating and Levering, this practice demonstrates Aquinas’s belief that “the realities of faith are present and active throughout history, preparing for and/or fulfilling the work of deification in Christ through the Holy Spirit” (xvii). Levering and Keating conclude their introduction by addressing the various sources that contribute to Book Reviews 863 Aquinas’s interpretation of John.The sources include patristic commentary, especially Origen, Augustine, and Chrysostom, with Augustine having first place among the three; heretics, especially Arius, and heterodox figures, such as Apollinarius, Nestorius, and Eutyches; Aristotle, who appears explicitly in only nine of the twenty-one chapters, although the influence of his thinking can be found throughout; and the Glossa Ordinaria, which is clearly present but scarce, with Aquinas’s Cantena aurea having much more influence than the Glossa. The contributions contained in the new English edition of Aquinas’s Commentary on the Gospel of John will surely assist in stoking interest in Aquinas’s biblical interpretation. One can only hope that commentaries from pre-modern exegetical luminaries like Aquinas continue to find their way into the modern classroom and onto the shelves of the modern preacher. N&V Charles Raith II Baylor University Waco,Texas