Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 1-17 1 The Rights of the Family Anselm Ramelow, O.P. Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology Berkeley, CA IN WHAT FOLLOWSI am going to claim that the family is at the “heart of society.” By “heart” we usually mean the core and center of a thing. It is to be argued that the family stands at the heart of society in the sense that it is in the middle between the state and the individual, mediating both. This mediation is important to the functioning of human society. In its absence, society is in danger of drifting into either individualism or collectivism.1 Worse yet, it may be more likely to end up a dysfunctional cooperation of both, a cooperation of Narcissus and Leviathan.2 My stronger and more fundamental claim is that families are not only useful for the proper functioning of society, but that they are bearers of fundamental rights that any state has to respect.3 We ought to 1 One thinks of the socialist attack on the family and the hope that it might eventually “wither away”; in the Soviet Union, apartments were often intentionally designed with a space insufficient for family meals. Many children that grew up under these conditions live on the streets today; cf. Tobias Jersak, “Ein Schlupfwinkel für die Kinder der Straße,” Kath.net/Katholische Nachrichten, January 17, 2009, http:// www.kath.net/news/21859. 2 Cf. a suggestive piece published in a more popular venue by Anthony Esolen, “The Alliance of Narcissus and Leviathan,” Catholic Answers Magazine, http://www.catholic.com/magazine/articles/the-alliance-of-narcissus-and-leviathan. While Hobbes and Rousseau have different visions of the state, they fundamentally agree that the human person is asocial. And both attempt to eliminate intermediate societies such as the family. At the end, individuals relate only insofar as each submits to Leviathan, i.e., the state, which alone is constitutive of all human relationships. 3 While Aristotle saw the family as basic to society (Ethics VIII, ch. 12), and the Uni- 2 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. think not only of the rights of the individual or of the common good at large, but of the rights of families. These rights are sui generis and can be derived from neither the individual nor the state. Rather, family rights are based in a fundamental relationality4 of the human person, which cannot be understood apart from the biological relationships in which these rights are rooted. I am going to establish this claim by arguing three successive points: (1) family rights are not reducible to individual rights, (2) family rights are not derivative from the common good, and (3) family rights are rooted in biological relationships. 1. Family Rights Are Not Reducible to Individual Rights A notion of family rights would be superfluous, if these rights could be reduced to the rights of individuals or constructed out of their contractual relationships. Rights and duties would then be based on what two or more individuals have agreed upon, that is, they could be derived from the wills and rights of the individuals. If there are family rights at all, they would have to be understood on the model of the social contract—ultimately a form of individualism. With regard to families, the suggestion might then be that family rights are rooted in the decision of two individuals to contract marriage. Marriage itself as a contract would appear to fit into social contract theories of human society. However, neither is the relationship of the couple exhaustively explained by a contract, nor do the implied children enter this family by a contractual choice. versal Declaration of Human Rights (art. 16/3) acknowledged its rights in principle, a formulation of family rights seems to be a recent development, emerging for the first time in Catholic thought, particularly a Synod of Bishops in 1980, John Paul II’s Familiaris Consortio (1981), and a Charter of the Rights of the Family by the Holy See (1983), addressed to all nations Christian and non-Christian; and one might add Benedict XVI, The Human Family: A Community of Peace (Message for the Celebration of the World Day of Peace, January 1, 2008). What is lacking is a philosophical conceptualization of this notion. I have explored some aspects in more detail in “Are There Family Rights?” Angelicum 88 (2011): 201–29. I will continue to refer to Catholic documents as the most consistent available source in these matters. The argument itself, however, does not depend on the faith of the Catholic Church. 4 African and feminist thought has in other ways also emphasized relationality as contrasted with individual rights. The Rights of the Family 3 The Couple For the couple itself, the decision to get married has implications that go beyond a mere contract. If it were a mere exchange of goods and services, then the notion of a contract might be sufficient. And indeed, this kind of exchange is certainly a part of the reality of marriage: shared bank accounts and merging of households and other goods, exchange of services (cooking, providing income, doing laundry and other chores, caring for and defending the other person)—all of these are part of what marriage is. But these elements are not the essence of marriage, for they might be found in other living arrangements among friends and caregivers as well. The essential exchange here is not one of goods and services, but of persons.5 Such an exchange affects the very identity of the persons involved. Personal identity is typically articulated in personal names. Now on the one hand, our names tend to locate us in a family tree, in a genealogy. In Western custom, the surname or family name identifies this place within the greater whole of a family and its relationships. If the point of reference were instead the larger collective—for example, the human species—then we probably would not name individuals, but number them; we would treat them as specimens. On the other hand, a mere first name alone might fall into the same problem: a personal name like “John” or “Susie” is a first name that might single out an individual. Individualism therefore might put the emphasis on this first name (and certainly contemporary individualistic culture has shifted to a first name basis). Yet, if this name were all that we have, then our pure individuality would coincide with pure anonymity: Which John? Which Susie? How many Johns and Susies are there in the 5 This includes a decision over the rest, i.e., the whole of one’s life: “This conjugal communion sinks its roots in the natural complementarity that exists between man and woman, and is nurtured through the personal willingness of the spouses to share their entire life-project, what they have and what they are: for this reason such communion is the fruit and the sign of a profoundly human need” (Familiaris Consortio, no. 19). The entire person is given in marriage. For Kant, in the Metaphysics of Morals, only the right to dispose over the whole person can give one the right to dispose over a part (which is of course to be thought of as mutual)—not to take a person in its entirety is tantamount to an objectification of the person; C. Langewellpott, W. Mackenthum, W. Dreier, H. P. Schweizer, and J. Frese, “Familie/Ehe,” in Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, vol. 2 (Basel: Schwabe, 1972), 899. This might also be one of the problems of cohabitation. 4 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. whole collective of society or humanity? Paradoxically, the part of our name which is not purely individual (our surname, shared with other family members) is precisely the name that allows us to identify John or Susie as more determinate individuals (albeit not infallibly) – as, say, John Kowalski or Susie Morales.6 In marriage, this surname typically changes, indicating a change of identity for the persons involved. For what happens in marriage is, again, not an exchange of goods and services, but of persons. If this exchange were one-sided, the result would be slavery; but if the exchange is mutual, then the result is to make the two persons one. Now this unity implies a change of identity for each of them. Their unity as well as the new identity is expressed in a common family name. The fact that today this frequently does not happen anymore might be more indicative of a problem than an argument to the contrary. This change of identity is therefore also a change of location within a system of families. The change consequently affects not only two individuals, but the extended families as well, even beyond the nuclear family. Marriage extends family relationships beyond blood relationships: All the members of each family are now related to all the other members of the other family. They are “in-laws”—with, for example, responsibilities of care, and certain demands for exogamy that now extend to the other family as well. While one might try to think of all these elements as merely agreed upon in a marriage contract, most of these family members were in fact not asked for their agreement. Nor do the two contracting individuals retain their previous identity purely and simply. They are no longer the ones that entered the contract; their new reality has transcended a mere contract into a different dimension of relationality that affects others as well. The new reality that emerges from their covenant, the new family, transcends mere contractual arrangements. 6 It is from these families that they receive even their first name, which is indeed their “given name”—given by their families even before they were conscious of their own existence. We know who we are only in identity and difference within genealogical family relationships. Characteristically, orphaned children and those begotten in (heterologous) artificial ways, have trouble answering this fundamental question. Cf. Paul W. McNellis, “The Family and the Analogy of Gratitude,” PhD diss., Boston College, 1993, 68. The Rights of the Family 5 Children Do Not Enter a Family by Contract What has just been said can be further explicated by noting that this essential “exchange of persons” has an end beyond itself; marriage by its very own nature is not an end in itself. Human beings enter many kinds of relationships and contractual unions, based on love or other interests. What distinguishes marriage from all these specifically is not the presence of love, but the fact that it is the place where the next generation originates by an act of procreation. What this means is that marriage cannot be understood apart from children and therefore apart from family. Marriage is not for its own sake— just as little as the acorn is there for its own sake, but has its end or telos in the oak tree. Marriage can no more be understood without the family than the acorn without the oak tree. This is so not by the choice of the marrying individuals, but because of the biological facts pertaining to the origin of human life.7 The act by which marriage is consummated and that the couple desires is by its biological nature designed to produce offspring.8 While this might not be most immediately on the mind of those consummating their marriage, their experience will often be one that transcends their “twosomeness.” It might be articulated as being submerged in the larger forces of nature, which strives to propagate the species. Or it might be, as in the Catholic understanding, God’s presence as creative of a new human soul. In either case, the act of begetting is not an act of conscious fabrication, but rather a self-forgetful act, in which greater forces are at work. The child is the objective correlate of this subjective experience. Both objectively and subjectively, marriage is about more than just two persons. Marriage aims at the origin of other 7 This biological fact, insofar as it is normative (which will be discussed below), might put limits on the choices of both the parents (children not as a right, but as a gift emerging from this biological fact) and the government (a right of parents at noninterference against a government’s attempt at restricting their number of children, e.g., China’s one-child policy). 8 It is noteworthy that in this regard sexual acts of two persons of the same sex will necessarily be frustrated. This frustration is real, considering that proponents of “same-sex marriage” also claim a right to have children and family. They do understand that children are part of what a family is, yet their acts cannot achieve that telos, which aims at children resulting from their own desired union (two becoming one flesh in a child, merging their genomes). It is reasonable to suppose that no legalization of same-sex marriage will eliminate this frustration. 6 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. persons—persons that are the very image of the one-flesh union of the spouses. Children, in their own flesh, merge the genome of their parents, and parents will delight in this image of their union. At the same time, as persons, children are also more than a delight for their parents, or an appendix of their relationship. Their existence is not a matter of their parents’ wish fulfillment or satisfaction.9 Persons are, as Immanuel Kant emphasized, ends in themselves, not means to other ends. These persons, then, will have their own individual rights that put the parents under obligations. Does this mean that we are now combining three individual rights? Are we now confronted with a contract of three persons, such that family rights are derivative from a contractual union of three persons? This does not seem to be the case, for children do not enter their families by contract. We no more choose our parents than they choose us.10 Contrary to an individualistic worldview—perhaps most radically expressed by Jean-Paul Sartre, for whom everything becomes a choice—most of our life is constituted by circumstances that we do not choose. Such circumstances are part of our finitude and will depend on our location in space and time. This location, however, is in turn determined by the family that we are born into. A short list of those things that we do not choose but that depend on our families of origin might illustrate this. We do not choose: our name, our religion, our race and skin color, our sex, our mother(!)-tongue or father(!)-land, our IQ, our health, our genetic code, our parents, our siblings or the absence thereof, our country and culture, our date of birth and the age we are born into, and our social location. Our family of origin even determines our very belonging to the human species with all its implications, that is, our fundamental biological constitution: our need for sleep or food and hydration, our mortality, even our inability to be everywhere at once, our temporality. As a result, children are radically “dependent rational animals.” They are not contractual partners of their parents. Just as the identity of their 9 That is, there is no right to have children at any price or by any method—but this is a moral limitation, not a limitation by government—although the government might have the duty to make this moral limitation respected. 10 This, of course, does not exclude the necessity of consciously deciding for and affirming our childhood and vocation in the family; cf. Benedict XVI, The Human Family, no. 6. The Rights of the Family 7 parents has become dependent on the marriage they have entered, so the very identity of children depends on the parents from whom they are born. All of this does not mean that the family trumps individual rights. In fact, with this radical dependence on the family come dangers of being profoundly damaged by family relationships. That is why in extreme cases the state can interfere with Child Protective Services. Child abuse does, of course, remain a violation of individual rights and so the larger collective is obligated to come to the aid of the individual. The institutions of the common good provide the necessary solidarity where subsidiarity fails. The rights of individuals within families have not always been constant. The observation of historical and cultural changes need not imply relativism; some changes can be seen as progress, and any variation is at least subject to evaluation. We ourselves, after all, are not always consistent and as such subject to evaluation. Unlike the people of the ancient Roman society, we do not grant family fathers the right over life and death (the ius necis, considered a right of the pater familias)11—yet in cases of abortion we today again seem willing to grant this right to mothers. While in archaic societies family members are often collectively punished for the misdeeds of their relatives, we would consider this an abuse of individual rights; yet, even today incarcerating a family father will often deprive the other individuals of a family of income and protection. Such variations and inconsistencies do not mean that the rights themselves cannot be made consistent, but precisely that we need to evaluate the various claims in the larger context of families. This includes correlating family rights with individual rights. Rights of individuals can be violated if one thinks of families too much in collective terms. Still, the fact that in many cases individual rights (and obligations) do trump family rights does not mean that family rights are derivative from individual rights. It only means that individual rights constitute a negative boundary for family rights, which in turn are presupposed. 11 The Christian religio seems to have trumped the Roman family pietas for the sake of the individual; cf. Lk 14:26. (NAB: “If any one comes to me without hating his father and mother, wife and children, brothers and sisters, and even his own life, he cannot be my disciple.”) This is emphasized by Rosemary Ruether, Christianity and the Making of the Modern Family (Boston: Beacon Press, 2000), 25ff. But obviously that does not make Christianity inimical to the family; rather, the Church’s own well-being “passes by way of the family” (Charter, L), which is an image of the Trinity (Familiaris Consortio, no. 11). 8 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. 2. Family Rights Are Not Derived from the Common Good If family rights are not derivative from individual rights, but in many ways presupposed, are they perhaps derivative from the larger common good? If so, then the state would be more fundamental than the family. The state would precede the family logically, even if not historically. Accordingly, the state would have the right to define what a family is. The state might then further have the right to assign family members to their families and regulate their relationship according to considerations of the common good.12 In some cases the state appears to do so legitimately: by enforcing, for example, the incest taboo and the duty of exogamy, the state might require the family to remain open for the good of the larger community. However, this does not mean that the incest taboo is itself an invention of the state. Other laws might even produce a genuine conflict with family rights, which could not be the case, if family rights were the product of the state to begin with. The historical record seems to show that the state finds itself in conflict with independently existing families and their rights rather than being the ground for their existence. For example, Sophocles’s Antigone dramatizes how the universal law of the state violated the right of the family to bury its members. The latter right is not a matter of mere selfishness or unrightful particularism of the human family. In Sophocles’s view it is a genuine right, and in fact even a duty of family members. While the state has its legitimate rights and claims, they are often difficult to harmonize with family rights. This would not be the case, if these were derived from the former. At times it can even be difficult to determine which of the two—state or family—is embodying a form of illegitimate particularism: The laws of the Greek polis tried to undermine the “international” family ties of its aristocratic members. Here we find the family being a threat to the state precisely because it had a wider reach, and was more universal than the state. 12 This seems to be happening currently in a California bill (SB 1476) allowing children to have three legal parents to accommodate the biological impossibility of samesex marriage (itself a redefinition of marriage and the family by courts as public institutions). Jennifer Roback Morse, “Why California’s Three-Parent Law Was Inevitable,” Public Discourse, September 10, 2012, http://www.thepublicdiscourse. com/2012/09/6197/. The Rights of the Family 9 Either way, the relationship has been one of conflict in the past, and remains so today.13 Might adoption indicate that the state is in charge of arranging family relationships? After all, here the state seems to arrange for family membership beyond blood relationships. It is a contract, into which at least the parents enter by choice, and it is a contract not with the child, but with the community at large. Parenthood appears to be delegated by and therefore derived from the state. On the other hand, adoption is the exception that proves the norm, rather than being itself the norm. Why is it the exception? Because adoption itself cannot be understood without the background of biological families. The very existence of the child presupposes the biological background; it is not provided by adoptive procedures, but presupposed by them. Adoption is precisely the exception that is trying to remedy the situation in which the biological family is missing. If such a family is present and functioning, the state cannot take away the children for the sake of adoption. It seems evident that this would be a crime and a violation of family rights14—which would not be the case, if the family were derivative from the state. Indeed, the institution of adoption tries to restore orphans to families; that is, the assumption is that the family is a more natural place for children to be than a collective state-run orphanage.15 What about the right of the state to impose burdens, such as taxation, on families for the sake of the common good? Does not the common good trump the family in this case? It does not, for such burdens require justification (just as the taxation or expropriation of individuals does). Indeed, the common good itself, which requires such burdens, arguably cannot be defined without 13 Another instance of family relationships reaching beyond state boundaries are families of emigrant workers. Cf. the Charter, art. 12: “b) Emigrant workers have the right to see their family united as soon as possible. c) Refugees have the right to the assistance of public authorities and International Organizations in facilitating the reunion of their families.” On the other hand, families have obligations beyond themselves, for the larger common good, e.g., for the poor (similarly, Familiaris Consortio, no. 47). 14 The Soviet Union considered children as belonging to the state or party; McNellis, “The Family and the Analogy of Gratitude,” 55. 15 The same would of course be true for orphanages run by religious sisters or other private institutions. Cf. also ibid., 82ff. 10 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. reference to the families. Families largely constitute this common good; they spell out its meaning.16 The common good defined apart from family structures remains exceedingly abstract. It will be based only on basic needs, not on a form of life.17 It will refer to asocial individuals and their satisfaction, while ignoring the fact that the human person is essentially relational. Relationality implies needs that cannot be provided for by either the individual itself (which would not be relational) or by the state (which is impersonal). We all have a need for some deeper relationships with other particular persons—some by choice (friendship), others by familial affinity. It seems likely that the kind of intimacy and affectivity that is needed and normal in families would be experienced as disgusting and intrusive, if it were to be provided by the larger society. The family, on the other hand, provides in its relationality an irreplaceable training ground for selfless18 and responsible behavior.19 It is important to notice that this does not exclude a kind of favoritism that 16 E.g., schools are to support families and the economy is for the family, not vice versa. The Charter of the Rights of the Family emphasizes that the family is not only a unique place for transmission of life, but also that it is uniquely suited to teach and transmit cultural, ethical, social, spiritual, and religious values; Charter, letters D and E; cf. Familiaris Consortio, no. 28. All of these are crucial elements of the common good, which becomes concrete in the life of the family. MacIntyre would see the family as too small; cf. Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals (Chicago: Open Court, 2001), 133–34. Still, local communities could very well be conceived as networks of families, or “family associations” (Charter, art. 8). 17 This would leave us with the bare juxtaposition of hedonism and administration: “It is as if the heart of man had fallen out, leaving only brains and belly.” Esolen, “The Alliance of Narcissus and Leviathan.” In application to our topic, the government is the brain, the bare physiological needs and wants are the belly—while the family is the heart of society. 18 “The mark of any society is concern for the common good, and where better than in the family do I learn that I have goods that are not simply mine but ours? Parents and children, each with their private goods, must give precedence to the shared or common good of the family if it, and they, are to flourish.” Ralph McInerny, “The Marrying Animal,” Catholic Thing, June 2, 2009, http://www.thecatholicthing.org/ content/view/1673/2. This can require struggle and bargaining; Charter, letter F. Cf. Amarthya Sen, “Gender Inequality and Theories of Justice,” in Women, Culture and Development: A Study of Human Capabilities, ed. Martha Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 259–73, esp. 260ff. 19 In Europe, Otto von Habsburg suggested giving voting rights to families, because individuals without families cannot be expected to vote from a concern for the future common good (including the ecology), whereas concern for one’s children educates in such responsibility. The Rights of the Family 11 makes it legitimate to prefer family members in situations of triage.20 Under normal circumstances and all things being equal, our obligation to family members is prior to our obligation to other people and to the state. In this relationality, the family can fulfill functions that the state cannot, which illustrates the family’s important subsidiary role in society itself.21 And, indeed, family rights are important for spelling out the importance of the principle of subsidiarity, by virtue of which the larger society should not assume responsibilities that can be fulfilled on the local level, including the family. At the same time one must not make the mistake of thinking that family rights are derived from the family’s functionality, that is, from the family’s practical and economic usefulness. All subsidiarity is based on who we are as human beings, not on considerations of utility.22 As embodied rational beings we are relational yet finite in whom we can relate to in an embodied and personal way. Our biological family is a first point of reference for such finite relations. Asking us to relate to all of humanity on the same level would be profoundly dehumanizing. Governments themselves take a similar stance when they (legitimately) ask us to consider national interests before those of other nations. This means, conversely, that the state does not have the primary responsibility and duty to provide for children (education, clothing, and feeding). This is the responsibility of the family. It is important to notice the danger that, if family structures were to be destroyed or missing, the state would have to assume this role by default. This can be illustrated in matters of education, particularly religious education. To educate children in a faith or to raise them as atheists or agnostics (itself a form of religious education) is the responsibility of parents, which they fulfill according to their conscience and best knowledge.23 In the absence 20 I.e., against the suggestion that we need a utilitarian calculus to decide whether we can save our own children before we save those of others. While Hume is sometimes quoted to the contrary—“Thus the relation of blood produces the strongest tie the mind is capable of in the love of parents to their children, and a lesser degree of the same affection, as the relation lessens”; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book II, Part II, Sect. IV, Of the Love of Relations—it is not clear that this has normative implications for Hume; for him it is a fact, not a value. 21 Including economic and other support by extended families. 22 Cf. also Esolen, “The Alliance of Narcissus and Leviathan.” 23 The Charter, art. 5, sees the conferral of education in continuity with the conferral of 12 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. of family structures, the state would have to decide in which religion children are to be raised, or whether they should be deprived of any religious upbringing, as the “new atheists” demand. Neither choice is a neutral option, nor can a choice be avoided.24 In other words, the state would be required to establish a state religion—such as Christian, Muslim, Mormon, or atheist.25 Obviously, no one would want to give the state this kind of responsibility. But since children themselves are not in a position to decide for themselves, the only other option is to support families in their choice.26 These considerations are all the more reason to hold that families do not derive their rights and existence from the state. life itself by the parents. The right of parents to educate their children also includes a right for governmental protection of children “from the negative effects and misuse of the mass media.” Ibid. 24 To wait until children are old enough to decide for themselves is already a decision to deprive them of something possibly important to their childhood. Considering the nature of the case, it might be similar to not teaching children a language until they are old enough to choose their mother language. The consequence would be that they would never learn any language. 25 The awkwardness can be shown by an example, curiously mixed with that of adoption: the governments of Spain and Morocco agreed that Moroccan children adopted by Spanish families must be raised as Muslims; this obliges the Spanish government to establish a “control mechanism” that would enable Moroccan religious authorities to monitor the children until they reach the age of eighteen to ensure they have not converted to Christianity; cf. Soeren Kern, “The Islamization of Spanish Jurisprudence,” Gatestone Institute, February 20, 2013, http://www.gatestoneinstitute.org/3595/spain-adoption-islam. 26 This might be generally true for the transmission of culture, language, and traditions. These, too, are not consciously and purposely created by the state (or any individual). For religious education, cf. Dignitatis Humanae, no. 5: “The family, since it is a society in its own original right, has the right freely to live its own domestic religious life under the guidance of parents. Parents, moreover, have the right to determine, in accordance with their own religious beliefs, the kind of religious education that their children are to receive. Government, in consequence, must acknowledge the right of parents to make a genuinely free choice of schools and of other means of education, and the use of this freedom of choice is not to be made a reason for imposing unjust burdens on parents, whether directly or indirectly. Besides, the rights of parents are violated, if their children are forced to attend lessons or instructions which are not in agreement with their religious beliefs, or if a single system of education, from which all religious formation is excluded, is imposed upon all.” The Rights of the Family 13 3. Family Rights Are Rooted in Biological Relationships From what principle are family rights derived, then? As an alternative to the derivation of matters of justice from either the individual or the state, thinkers like Michael Sandel suggest the readmission of Aristotelian considerations of virtue and related teleological notions as an important contribution, even in matters of marriage and the family.27 Taking an even stronger position on the underlying biology, Alisdair MacIntyre now accepts the “metaphysical biology” of “dependent rational animals.” Indeed, if we are dependent animals by virtue of our biological nature, then we are also for biological reasons relational. Our biology produces a reciprocal indebtedness with normative implications.28 I would like to suggest that families are the locus in which these normative implications generate rights that are sui generis. If membership in a family can be traced neither to the choice of parents and children nor to a decree of the state, then it can only be of biological origin. The question is whether biological facts can have normative implications. I claim that they do. Contrary to the modern assumption of a radical distinction between “fact” and “value,” “ought” and “is,” the facts of nature do have normative implications. For Hans Jonas, parental love is the paradigmatic moral response for an ethics based on responsibility—a responsibility that emerges from a fact; it is an obligation that one contracts, not by contract, but by biology.29 We all assume the normative implications of biological facts when we say that someone “ought” to go to the doctor, or that we have a “right” to health care in order to restore the biological functioning of our human organism. The biological functions of our human organism do indeed imply moral claims and even human rights. Basic biological needs such as food or sleep are the basis for claims of social justice, health care, and other rights. This is not different for family rights. As we have seen, a family starts with a conscious decision by a couple for marriage, that is, by two per27 Michael J. Sandel, Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do? (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2009), 253ff. 28 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals. 29 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), 130. 14 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. sons who are not biologically related. But this is merely a starting point with consequences that transcend contractual decisions. From this starting point there is constituted a whole new reality with obligations that seem to have no other foundation than the biology of procreation.30 Consider the fact that women become vulnerable physically and emotionally by the fact of childbearing, and that this seems to imply certain claims to protection and support, primarily from the husband. While this might be considered the right of an individual (the wife), the primary respondent is a family member. With these procreational relationships comes a biologically rooted distribution of family roles. Much as this is called in doubt today, some biological and hormonal facts are so basic that they can be ignored only at the peril of committing an injustice against the vulnerability of women.31 Furthermore, the need of children for their mother is different from their need for their father. Children might therefore claim an intrafamiliar right to the presence of both parents—a right that is rooted in the biological differentiation of the sexes. Even more basic are the rights of children for food and clothing. The primary respondents of these rights are again the parents (who in turn have a right to wages that can sustain a family32). The parents are responsible for the feeding and clothing of their children, not the nextdoor neighbors or anyone else. Only the parents are held accountable for neglect. There is no other reason for this than that these children are their biological offspring. Again, biology has normative consequences. Parents also have the duty to educate their own children—but not 30 This is true even for the emerging relationships to in-laws; for these respective families are themselves families only by virtue of procreational relationships. 31 Such claims are acknowledged by Sen, “Gender Inequality,” 264ff. The lack of the same thing might turn out to be more crippling to one sex than to the other (e.g., different types of nutritional needs, especially for pregnant women; there might be also different psychological needs). Susan Wolf, “Commentary on Nussbaum,” in Women, Culture and Development: A Study of Human Capabilities, ed. Martha Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 105–15, esp. 114. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (25/2) entitles motherhood and childhood to special care and assistance. Generally speaking, both the making of differences where there are none and treating people identically where there is no identity lead to injustice. 32 For the Catholic understanding, cf. Pacem in Terris, no. 19–22; the Charter, art. 10, acknowledges that a “family wage” should make it possible for the mother to stay home. The Rights of the Family 15 those of other parents.33 Accordingly, they are held accountable for the mischief of their children. This implies in turn a duty of children to obey their parents (but not a duty to obey the parents of other children, except by expressed delegation from their own parents). Parents have a right to punish their children,34 but they would surely protest, if their neighbors would try to do the same to their children. Even abortion advocates, while claiming the right to end the life of their children in the womb, would typically protest if other people would attempt to do the same in their place. Rights and duties based on biological descent are not limited to the care of children. Indeed, caring for elderly parents is the primary responsibility of their own offspring, who thereby reciprocate the care given them as children. Children are also the default persons to make end-of-life decisions for their parents. While the elderly might transfer this duty to others, in the absence of a spouse the children are the default respondents—and this not through designation by the state, but simply by biological relatedness. Likewise, children are the default recipients of the inheritance of their parents. The state might tax this inheritance, but to take it away entirely would be a confiscation of family property that would constitute a violation of family rights. Inheritance rules are not an unjustified favoritism, but are meant to help guarantee the stability and survival of the family and its persistence over time.35 Inheritance is therefore a right of the family as such, and is independent from the persistence of the individuals (whose death is, after all, precisely the cause of the inheritance case). The family has an identity that outlasts that of its constitutive individuals; it is a subject of rights that include the right of being sustained by the property that is passed on through the generations. Finally, the emotional bonds and the mutual trust that are generated by biological relatedness also constitute rights and obligations. A 33 Teachers have this right to educate by delegation from the parents only. According to the Charter, art. 5, parents have the right to freely choose a school and remove their children from classes conflicting with their moral and religious conviction. 34 This punishment is not retributive, but educational and therefore limited; as mentioned above, it does not include the death penalty. Teachers have a right to punishment by delegation from the parents only. 35 Charter, art. 9. 16 Anselm Ramelow, O.P. first indication of this fact is that family members do not have to testify against each other in court, because this would violate the fundamental and important bonds of trust in the family.36 Also, detainees have a right to remain in contact with their families (and care has to be taken that the family is adequately sustained during the time of detention).37 Also, while emotional bonds cannot be generated on demand, they are important for the healthy development of children. The family is the irreplaceable source for such bonding and in this the most fundamental school and “language of peace.”38 In this sense, too, “man does not live by bread alone,” and merely feeding children in large anonymous communities (as perhaps Plato envisioned) is not enough. Again, this constitutes a right of children to the presence of both parents, without which they might never develop the necessary and basic human dispositions.39 For example, without the love of their parents and the trust developing from it they will typically become incapable of any other learning required from them in later life. For any learning requires a minimum of trust in those from whom one is to learn. Not having had the opportunity to learn this trust as a child will lead to a lack in this basic human disposition. Children cannot become “independent reasoners” (MacIntyre) unless they have been dependent reasoners first. But such emotional bonds are not only important for children. Children in turn are themselves a source of human development for their parents, such as requiring responsible action from their side. Forgiveness and gratitude in both directions are arguably learned primarily in family relationships. At one stage or another, the generations will be dependent on each other, parents on their children, and children on their parents. Family membership constitutes asymmetrical, chronolog- 36 A Chinese policy demanding public denunciation of family members is a clear violation of such a right. McNellis, “The Family and the Analogy of Gratitude,” 56. 37 Charter, art. 9d; likewise, neither immigration nor deportation must be allowed to separate families permanently. 38 Benedict XVI, The Human Family, no. 3. 39 If this implies a right to know one’s parents, then Plato’s suggestion that children should not know their father is a clear violation thereof. Children conceived by heterologous IVF are typically in search of their father—often with good reason, because unintentional incest has become possible. Further thought might be given to the duty of the state in these matters. The Rights of the Family 17 ically structured relationships of indebtedness that are fundamental to human existence. Apart from other considerations, this should also play a role in divorce laws. Here the rights of children might too often be neglected. According to Allan Bloom, divorce is worse for children than the death of their parents, because unlike death, divorce is voluntary. Children’s experience is that, if human relations can be dissolved in this voluntary manner, then why could they not be dissolved similarly between parents and children? The threat of abandonment and the impossibility of trust seem implied, even where divorce does not actually take place. This threat affects children not merely emotionally, but on the level of their very self-understanding. The philosopher Robert Spaemann points out that children have to think of their father and mother as a unit in order to understand their very own identity. They literally are the one flesh union of their parents by combining their genetic material. And this confirms once more that family relationships are irreducible; they even constitute the basic identity of their individual members. In conclusion, family rights are not derivative, but sui generis. The family is a “society in its own original right.”40 Families are constituted not by contractual but by biological relationships of their members. Children do not choose their parents any more than parents choose their children. Families are not founded for the pursuit of a common interest. They are a communion of persons who do not share a common goal, but one another. Families mediate between the state and the individual, and cannot be deduced from either of these opposites. While the state and the individual cannot be deduced from the family either, the family can in turn make both state and individual more intelligible than they would be in themselves. Families display the fundamental human nature in its biological and relational roots—roots without which humanity would be crippled. The family might be the prime analogate for what human community is, mediating individual and state, yet irreducible even to this mediating function. One cannot derive the family from any other principle. One has to have seen and lived family life before one can know it. N&V 40 Familiaris Consortio, no. 45, quoting Dignitatis Humanae, no. 5. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 19-27 19 Without Gloss: Francis of Assisi and Western Catholicism Charles J. Chaput, O.F.M., Cap. Archbishop of Philadelphia Philadelphia, PA I WANT TO START WITH A SIMPLE STATEMENTof fact. All Christian life is a paradox. What I mean is this. In Isaiah 55, God says, “For my thoughts are not your thoughts, neither are your ways my ways, says the Lord. For as the heavens are higher than the earth, so are my ways higher than your ways and my thoughts [higher] than your thoughts” (8–9). Then in the Gospel of Matthew, Jesus tells his disciples, “You therefore must be perfect, [even] as your heavenly Father is perfect” (5:48). Scripture tells us that God is utterly different from us, vastly higher than us. Then it tells us to become like him. Therein lies the paradox. The task seems impossible. And yet we know it to be possible. We know it through the witness of the saints. In Hebrew, God is called hakadosh, “the Holy One,” with the word kadosh meaning holy. Our English word “saint” derives from the Latin word sanctus, which means the same thing: holy. Holy does not mean “good,” though holy people are always good and often—though not always—nice. St. Jerome was certainly holy and good, but “nice” might not be the first word that springs to mind in remembering him. Holy means “other than.” It means different from the world; set apart from the profane; sacred. The saints are ordinary men and women—persons with every kind of talent, weakness and personality—who took a different path, one step at a time, away from the routine hab- 20 Archbishop Charles J. Chaput, O.F.M., Cap. its of the world. They fell in love with God. They followed him. They conformed their lives to him in simple ways that became extraordinary ways. And now their example and their intercession give us hope that we can do the same. I mention all this because my job here is to consider “St. Francis and Western Catholicism.” And I want to do it by posing three questions: Who is Francis, this pope? Who was Francis, the man of Assisi? And after eight hundred years, what, if anything, can a man from the Middle Ages teach us about being alive and free and human? So first: Who is Francis, this pope? The short answer is, I do not know. I am not sure anyone really knows yet, outside the Holy Father’s friends and close coworkers. A number of Latin American bishops have told me how different the pope now seems from his years as a bishop in Argentina—much more outgoing and ebullient than they remember. But these are their thoughts, not mine. I did have the privilege of working with him for a month in November and December 1997 when we were both delegates to the Special Assembly for America in Rome. He was an impressive man. He had a keen intelligence, a healthy realism about the problems facing the Church in our hemisphere and a strong emphasis on evangelization. But these are just anecdotes from a long time ago. I do think we can draw some conclusions from the example he already gives us. He has a deep sense of the continuity of the Church. The respect he shows to Benedict, the Pope Emeritus, literally has no precedent. And his affection for Benedict clearly comes from the heart. On April 27, 2014, he canonized two of his predecessors; the two greatest men of the Second Vatican Council—Pope John XXIII, who had the vision and courage to convene it; and Pope John Paul II, who helped draft some of its key documents and who embedded the meaning of Vatican II in the life of the postconciliar Church. John XXIII and John Paul II are perfectly paired in sainthood. In canonizing them together, Pope Francis places them as bookends to one of the central events in Catholic life since the Reformation. They were untiring in their discipleship. Zealous in their love of God and God’s people. And also thoroughly human in their complexity. John XXIII saved Jews from the Holocaust as a Vatican diplomat. He radiated warmth, humor and a concern for peace. He worked a rev- Without Gloss: Francis of Assisi and Western Catholicism 21 olution in Catholic thought and life. And he also frowned on the worker-priest movement in France and forbade Catholics from voting for the Communist Party. John Paul II helped bring down the Soviet bloc. He worked vigorously for the purity of Catholic teaching. He defended the rights of workers, the suffering and the unborn. And he was also a profound shepherd of mercy—a message that runs through his whole pontificate, from his encyclical “Rich in Mercy” to his placing Divine Mercy Sunday on the universal Church calendar. Pope Francis stands in this line of great recent popes. But in choosing the name “Francis,” he also makes himself distinct from it. Until now, every pope of the last two hundred years—no matter how gifted or how saintly—has been, in a sense, a prisoner of war. The Church has centered herself in Europe. Every pope in recent history has been a European. And the civil war for Europe’s soul that began before the Enlightenment and ran through the bloodiest century in history— the twentieth century—continues today in Europe’s denial of its Christian roots and its self-destroying battles over marriage, family, sexual identity, and euthanasia. Europe has exhausted itself. Europe has exhausted the world. And so, when John Paul II called for a “new evangelization,” maybe he spoke more prophetically than he could know. Maybe a genuinely new evangelization can never be achieved except by a new voice with a new spirit from a new world. Pope Francis is no stranger to poverty or violence, the plague of corrupt politics or the cruelty of human trafficking. But neither is he a child of the Old World, with its cynicism and despair, its wars and its hatreds. Francis seems to be something different. He embodies a Christian spirit older than Europe’s civil war and younger than its fatigue and loss of hope. He is a surprise; disarming, improbable, the kind of man no one could have predicted—a surprise that keeps unfolding into more surprises. There is something stunning about a pope who—for the first time in history—takes the icon of Christian simplicity and poverty as his namesake, and then tries to live like he means it. There is something exhilarating about a pope who worries about “Christians whose lives seem like 22 Archbishop Charles J. Chaput, O.F.M., Cap. Lent without Easter.”1 Who warns that “an evangelizer must never look like someone who has just come back from a funeral.”2 Or who takes a detour in a teaching document to talk in plain language about the mechanics of a good homily.3 I asked above, Who is Francis, this pope? The answer is an anomaly. He is a Jesuit with a Franciscan heart. What does that mean? The early Jesuits played an immense role in the Counter-Reformation and the intellectual renewal of Catholic life. Their legacy goes well beyond the Society of Jesus. It still helps to shape the life of the Church. Our two previous popes—Karol Wojtyla and Joseph Ratzinger—were world-class, formidable minds by any secular standard. But we live at a time when science, in the name of reason, seems to undermine the credibility of reason itself. We live in a time that is not just anti-ideological, but in many ways anti-intellectual. It is not that people have forgotten how to think. Rather, too many of us think badly, or just do not like thinking at all. We have no common body of beliefs to inform our public logic and discourse. As Alasdair MacIntyre might say, we are all emotivists now. And religion, when it is not portrayed as a dangerous source of hatred, is cast instead as a kind of organized sentimentality; an outlet for pious good will. Pope Francis is so intensely popular because he embodies what the world imagines St. Francis was like: a mendicant and troubadour, not a judge and not a scholar. The Holy Father clearly has a sophisticated mind formed in the spirit of Ignatius. But what appeals to the world about Pope Francis are his serenity and informality; his passionate embrace of the poor and the outcast; and his studied avoidance of condemning anyone. Whether that popularity can last in the face of the pastoral challenges facing the Church is an issue for the future. How the Pope speaks and acts over the next twenty months on matters like marriage, family and sexuality—issues of burning interest to the media of the developed world—will have a big impact on the way he is treated by the press. In the end, popes lead. It is the nature of their ministry. And leaders inev1 2 3 Pope Francis, Evangelii Gaudium, §6. Ibid., §10. Ibid., §§137–59. Without Gloss: Francis of Assisi and Western Catholicism 23 itably displease somebody; sometimes a great many somebodies. But of course the real St. Francis never turned away from a task simply because it was hard. That brings me to the second of the three questions I posed for this essay: Who was Francis, the man of Assisi? Francis Bernadone—born in 1181 or 1182, died 1226—has been a magnet for pious stories almost since the day of his death. The wolf of Gubbio is a legend—lovely, but not true. And there is no evidence that the saint ever said, “preach the Gospel always; when necessary use words.” And the famous Prayer of St. Francis—“Lord, make me an instrument of your peace”—dates only to 1912, when it appeared in La Clochette, a small French spiritual magazine. We do rightly remember Francis for his joy and freedom of spirit. These qualities deeply marked the man. And through the man, they have left a lasting mark on Western Christianity. But there was a great deal more to Francis than a gentle love of nature. A Capuchin friend of mine once said that if the real Francis were alive today, quite a few moderns would see him as a religious crank. He was demanding on himself and demanding on his brothers. Poverty, chastity, and obedience are wonderful ideals when we read about them in the foggy past. Living them is another matter. And Francis took his vows and the Rule of his community utterly seriously. He expected his brothers to do the same. Actually, Francis battled with his brothers quite often, especially when they wanted to water down the inspiration that God had given him. In the year 1221, just a few years after the Franciscan community began, some three thousand friars gathered with Francis for a general chapter. And the ministers—the brothers who led the community— wanted to change the Rule. They wanted to modify it to the times, and make it less demanding. Francis fought that vigorously. He chose the following verse from Scripture as the theme for his preaching that day: “Blessed be the Lord my God, who trains my hands for war.” He spoke those words to his brothers as he began his sermon. And he won the day. The Rule was later modified anyway, but not that day, because Francis knew how to fight zealously for what he believed was right. Like Mother Teresa and so many other saints all through Church history, Francis was holy and 24 Archbishop Charles J. Chaput, O.F.M., Cap. good and kind—but when it came to matters of faith and principle, he was never soft. The key to Francis was a kind of holy radicalism. He liked to say that “the saints lived lives of heroic virtue, [but] we are satisfied to talk about them.” Francis himself never felt satisfied with pious words. He wanted to act on the things he believed. He called his brothers to live the Gospel with simplicity and honesty. And that is why he used the words sine glossa—“without gloss”—in his Testament. He saw that the Gospel was not complicated, but it was demanding and difficult. The theologians and Church lawyers of his day had written commentaries called glosses. And these glosses were very good at either explaining away the hard parts of the Gospel, or diminishing our need to follow Christ’s demands. Francis wanted none of that. He wanted to experience discipleship at its root. Francis lived in an age of political confusion in Europe; a time of the great, inhuman heresy of Catharism in France and Italy, and constant warfare between Christians and Muslims around the Mediterranean. It was also a time of deep corruption and clerical infidelity within the Church. But the medicine Francis used against that corruption was a witness of obedience, encouragement, reverence, and service—not rebellion. He knew instinctively that people are converted by love, not by rejection or fear or anger. In his biography of Francis, Augustine Thompson—the Dominican author—notes that Francis had a passionate devotion to the Blessed Sacrament. It was the heart of his life. The Mass was the grounding for all his work. There is no way of reinterpreting Francis in generically do-gooder or humanitarian terms. He had hard words for those who oppressed the poor, but even harsher words for those who ignored the Eucharistic presence. Francis had a special horror of the cheap and tarnished chalices and filthy linens that [many priests of his time] considered good enough for use in worship. Francis’ sense of beauty and decency, which he had mortified by choosing to live amid poverty and outcasts, had not been deadened. Its object was no longer fine garments and meals for himself, but items dedicated to the Lord who died for him.4 4 Augustine Thompson, O.P., Francis of Assisi: A New Biography (Ithaca, NY: Cornell Without Gloss: Francis of Assisi and Western Catholicism 25 He goes on to say that Francis demonstrated his devotion [to the Church] by kissing the hands of any priest he met . . . He begged the brothers who met a priest on horseback, especially one carrying the Blessed Sacrament, to kiss the horse’s hooves rather than wait for the priest to dismount. Francis wanted that ‘subjection to all’ which was so much a part of his conversion, to be a lived reality among the brothers. Again: Who was Francis, the man of Assisi? G. K. Chesterton, his other great biographer, put it in these words: St. Francis [was] a Lover. He was a Lover of God and he was really and truly a Lover of men . . . [And] as St. Francis did not love humanity but men, so he did not love Christianity but Christ . . . [To Francis] his religion was not a thing like a theory, but a thing like a love affair . . . What gave him his extraordinary personal power was this: that from the Pope to the beggar, from the Sultan of Syria in his pavilion to the ragged robbers crawling out of the wood, there was never a man who looked into those brown burning eyes without being certain that Francis Bernadone was really interested in him; in his own individual inner life from the cradle to the grave; that he himself was being valued and taken seriously and not being added to the spoils of some social policy or the names in some clerical document.5 This is the love that the apostles must have seen when they looked into the eyes of Jesus. It is the love, I suspect, that Pope Francis wants people to see in the eyes of every Christian and in every element of Catholic life. That brings us to the third and final question I posed here: After eight hundred years, what, if anything, can a man from the Middle Ages teach us about being alive and free and human? That term “Middle Ages” is a curious one. It is implicitly negative. It consigns an entire civilization to a kind of trough between waves. And it fits perfectly with the 5 University Press, 2012), 61. G. K. Chesterton, St. Francis of Assisi, in St. Thomas Aquinas/St. Francis of Assisi (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2002), 196–97, 266–67. 26 Archbishop Charles J. Chaput, O.F.M., Cap. vanity, the ignorance, and the amnesia of the modern era—an era that clings to its delusion that reason precludes religious faith, in the same way drowning sailors grab for a life raft. The philosopher Rémi Brague once wrote that “Christianity was founded by people who could not have cared less about ‘Christian civilization.’ What mattered to them was Christ, and the reverberations of his coming on the whole of human existence. Christians believed in Christ, not in Christianity itself; they were Christians, not ‘Christianists.’”6 We need to remember that simple lesson. The Catholic faith is not an ideology. It is a romance. It is a love affair with God. We are a people who believe in Jesus Christ—not the ideas, but the person of Jesus Christ, crucified and risen for our sake purely out of his love for us. And living the Catholic faith should be an experience of gratitude and joy that flows from a daily personal encounter with God’s son and a communal relationship with God’s people. There is a reason the Church calls St. Francis the vir Catholicus, the exemplary Catholic man. Francis understood that gratitude is the beginning of joy, and that joy in this world is the aroma of heaven in the next. He reveled in the debt he owed to God for the beauty of creation, for his friends and brothers, and for every gift and suffering that came his way. He treasured his dependence on the love of others, and returned their love with his own. He gave away all that he had in order to gain the deepest kind of freedom—the freedom to pursue God, to share God with others, and to experience life without encumbrance or fear. Maybe the best thing we can do is to compare what we know about Francis with the terrain of American life all around us—terrain we adults, including we adults in the Church, helped to create. We worship autonomy. We are jealous of our time and our privacy. Our economy runs on a steady catechesis of entitlement and dissatisfaction. And billions are spent every year on a nonstop creation of one new appetite after another. That is not living. That is not even really human. A young married friend once quipped that having fun is to joy, as having sex is to love—they ought to go together in a rightly ordered way. And when they do, life is beautiful. But too often they just do not, 6 Rémi Brague, The Legend of the Middle Ages: Philosophical Explorations of Medieval Christianity, Judaism and Islam (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009), 21–22. Without Gloss: Francis of Assisi and Western Catholicism 27 because fun and sex become things to take, things to consume. And joy and love can only grow in a heart that gives. Acquisitiveness makes us poorer and hungrier in the only things that matter. In turning away from that kind of life, Francis became fully alive; a man free to think and act without excuses, without compromise, without glosses to make the Gospel of Jesus Christ more comfortable and less liberating. Here is the point: We can make the same choices Francis did, one person, one family, one Christian community at a time. And if we do, that begins a revolution, the only kind that achieves anything that endures. Our continued interest in St. Francis is the proof. Eight centuries after he died, here were are, still moved and still drawn to the life of an Italian poor man in rags. So are millions of others. Scripture says, “Seek first his kingdom and his righteousness and all these things shall be yours as well” (Mt 6:33). We need to consider two simple questions: First, do we believe the Word of God or not? And second, if we do believe, then what are we going to do about it? We renew the witness of the Church, not with techniques or programs or resources, but with the zeal and purity and obedience of our own lives. That path leads to the kind of freedom and joy that no one could ever take from Francis, and no one can ever take from us. From the cross at San Damiano, Jesus said to Francis: “Repair my house, which is falling into ruin.” Those same words are meant for every Christian life and home and parish. How we respond is up to us. N&V Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 29-37 29 St. Francis and Pope Francis1* R. R. Reno First Things New York, NY OUR WORLD IS TAKENby Pope Francis. I would guess that if we were to stop one hundred random people on the street and ask them about the Catholic Church, we would get a few thumbs up, but mostly ambivalence bordering on dislike or at least distrust. Indeed, some are likely to express an articulate hostility. And yet, ask them about the current pope, and, if my secular friends and relatives are any indication, I would venture the responses will be significantly more positive. Whether the ugly body rust of the sex-abuse scandals or bitterness over the Church’s intransigent refusal to conform the new consensus on sex, marriage, and the family—or simply the general impulse in our society to hit the mute button on religion—Catholicism generally rankles. By contrast, the pope pleases and brings a smile. This is so because our Jesuit pope has many Franciscan qualities that arouse something deep within us. The original celebrity, Francis, was and remains a central archetype in the Western spiritual imagination. When we see his form embodied, however imperfectly, however partially, we tend to swoon, which is exactly what has happened. Here, for example, are a few Franciscan parallels between St. Francis and Pope Francis that may explain, at least in part, his general popularity. As we marinate in irony, the direct bluntness and simplicity of St. * This essay was originally delivered as a talk at the Catholic Center at New York University at a conference on St. Francis sponsored by First Things and the Thomistic Institute. 30 R. R. Reno Francis bring us up short, and at the same time his compassion reassures us that if we have the courage to show ourselves in our spiritual nakedness we will not be shamed, ridiculed or mocked. The current pope represents to us something of this powerful combination of immediate, unmediated demand and warm consolation. His famous “who I am to judge” response to a question about homosexuality can be interpreted as Franciscan in this way, especially when paired with his earlier remarks as cardinal that gay marriage is “of the devil.” I would submit that it is the Franciscan sense of his statement—the consolation of solidarity in an atmosphere of heightened spiritual demands—that encourages many liberal Catholics who, interestingly, do not believe he will change the Church’s teaching. (This stands in contrast to the secular media, which cannot see anything other than affirmation in any pastoral expression of the enduring welcome of God’s forgiving love.) Moreover and more importantly, St. Francis embodies the tremendous power of humility and renunciation—an alluring, bewitching possibility in our age of grasping accumulation. From the moment of his presentation to the world as newly elected, this pope’s many public gestures have evoked the way of lowliness. His decision to wash the feet of prisoners on his first Holy Thursday as pope provides an obvious example. But more powerful, I think, has been his renunciation of papal isolation. Unique among major leaders, he moves through the world without the thick security buffer that separates the Davos worthies from everybody else. And then there is a third Franciscan charism—unpredictability and a general disregard for the mundane requirements of institutional continuity. Pope Francis manifests these qualities as well. It gives many secularists and liberals hope that he will toss over centuries of magisterial teaching about the hot-button issues secularists and liberal care about, which pretty much boil down to sex and erasing the male-female difference. It also gives people like me heartburn, just as St. Francis did many centuries ago. But I am becoming ad hoc, and perhaps a little ad hominem. Therefore I want to step back and probe more deeply the Franciscan archetype. It is about more than simplicity and compassion, much more than foregoing a fancy Mercedes for a plain Jane Ford or being kind to animals. If we have a clearer picture of what makes St. Francis so import- St. Francis and Pope Francis 31 ant in the Western spiritual imagination, we can return to Pope Francis and ask two questions. First, what does Jorge Bergoglio’s unprecedented choice of Francis as the name for his pontificate foretell about what he discerns as the Church’s greatest need today? And, second, what does it say about twenty-first-century America that we find a pope named Francis so attractive? Fr. Augustine Thompson has worked to distinguish the historical Francis from the image of the saint that animates the popular imagination. In this essay, however, I want to stick with the Francis of faith rather than the Francis of history. It is this figure that St. Bonaventure presents in his Life of Saint Francis. There his identity has little to do with the emerging mercantile culture of medieval Italy or the particulars of life in Umbria. Instead, Bonaventure presents him as a “herald of gospel perfection.” This is so because St. Francis embodies two important theological truths: poverty and literalism. Poverty is a biblical motif we could say (rightly) that St. Francis “owns” in the West. Bonaventure returns to this theme again and again. The great saint is a lover of “holy poverty”; he embraces “sublime poverty,” queen of the virtues and root of perfection. “None was ever so greedy of gold as he of poverty,” writes Bonaventure, “nor did any man ever guard treasure more anxiously than he this Gospel pearl.” As Dante describes, Francis weds himself to Lady Poverty, an image meant to draw upon and transform Boethius’s description of Lady Wisdom. In Francis we learn that matrimony to poverty is the surest path to God. Bonaventure gives an extensive catalogue of St. Francis’s ever-renewed commitment to poverty. He declares it the foundation of his order, insisting that his followers accept the most stringent conditions rather than allow themselves to be seduced by the illusion that any degree of wealth is consistent with gospel purity. Bonaventure recounts an incident on the road where St. Francis refused to pick up a purse full of coins that his brethren wished to use to give to the poor, correctly seeing it as a snare of the devil. When invited to dine with bishops, he begs crusts of bread in advance of the meal. One Easter at an isolated hermitage there were no neighbors to beg from, so St. Francis resorted to asking his fellow friars for alms. In all things St. Francis took the way of renunciation, always seeking self-emptying and dispossession rather than possession. 32 R. R. Reno Poverty is closely connected to the second Franciscan motif, which is literalism. The great saint’s spiritual imagination is no more richly adorned than were his humble hermitages. Just as he stripped off life’s softening luxuries, he removed anything that might soften God’s word. His call first came in a dream. He saw himself among gathered soldiers emblazoned with the sign of the Cross—and so he immediately presented himself to a local count to serve as a soldier. At this point, a divine voice intervenes, telling him, in effect, that he should not be an idiot. The dream was meant to be interpreted spiritually, not literally! And St. Francis does exactly that. He sees that we cannot serve Christ unless we achieve a victory over ourselves—and then redoubles his literalism by immediately applying the teachings of Jesus to his life: “Take no gold, nor silver, nor copper in your belts, no bag for your journey, nor two tunics, nor sandals, nor a staff.” (It was only after receiving the stigmata that St. Francis could be convinced to wear sandals, in this instance as a humble hiding of the richness of divine grace.) A similar literalism characterizes his response to a voice speaking to him from the cross of Christ in the dilapidated Church of St. Damian. It said, “Go and repair my House.” So he sets about to raise funds, triggering thereby the confrontation with his father that leads to his disinheritance, thus providing the divine inheritance of poverty and securing the literal fulfillment of Jesus’s teaching that you will be hated by your mother and father for his sake. The bull-headed literalism of his response to the divine voice brings him to an almost absurd state. Stripped of all financial resources, he is reduced to carrying uncut stones to the church to contribute to its rebuilding. Just so does Francis take on the form of Christ most fully. The spiritual meaning of the Gospel is the literal meaning of Christ’s way of the Cross. The literalism of St. Francis and his poverty go together, as St. Bonaventure makes clear in his carefully stylized account of how St. Francis was called to follow Christ, received the charism of holy poverty, and founded his order. This linkage is not simply a narrative one—the fact that by trying to rebuild the churches near Assisi, St. Francis set in motion the sequence of events that led to the confrontation with his father, dispossession, and recapitulation of Christ’s burden carrying love. There is also an important conceptual link: both testify to the immedi- St. Francis and Pope Francis 33 ate availability of obedience to God’s command. Put differently, both demonstrate the real possibility of holiness. It is easy for us to mock literalism as a plank in the fundamentalist platform. This is a mistake, for literalism encourages a disposition toward the Word of God that prevents us from hiding in a self-generated fog. Some years ago I was with an academic friend. He is a game theorist with a skeptical mind. He is also a conservative Protestant. As he explained his work with a prison ministry in Texas, I found myself somewhat surprised and asked him why he was involved. He looked at me and said, “Well, more than a decade ago I realized that when Jesus tells us to feed the hungry, cloth the naked, and visit the prisoner, he actually means it. And there are prisoners in Texas. So I signed up to visit them.” The literalism of St. Francis is like my friend’s—and it makes God’s commands immediate. The same goes for his spiritual imagination more broadly. St. Francis did not have a conceptual mind and did not think in terms of kenosis or the “metaphysics of gift” or the notion of “cruciform existence.” Instead, St. Francis interpreted what it means to be Christlike in a literal way. Again, Dante sees with clarity. In the Paradiso, Francis loses all the particularity of his life and become a pure allegory of Christ. The theological insight is powerful: to be spiritualized, to be supernaturalized, is to become a perfect mirror of Christ, which means to imitate and conform to him in a literal way. Put somewhat differently: in St. Francis we see that the most spiritual reading of the passion narrative is a literal one. Thus St. Francis is most fully “supernaturalized” when he received the stigmata, the grace of the most literal possible conformity to Christ on the cross. The immediacy of poverty is easier to explain and in many ways much more powerful. It is a spiritual ideal we can achieve in an instant—if we will but do so. Poverty requires no resources, no talents, no achievements, no status, no family connections. Anyone can wed himself to Lady Poverty. Nothing stands in the way—except, of course, for our unwillingness to take the way of renunciation. And because poverty is the form Christ takes, to say that poverty is immediately accessible is to say that a deep conformity to Christ is immediately accessible, which is to say that a supernatural life in God is immediately accessible. As St. Paul puts it in his letter to the Romans (paraphrasing somewhat), we do 34 R. R. Reno not need to wait around for just the right set of dogmas to be defined or spiritual disciplines to be fine-tuned. No, as Moses teaches, “The word is near you, on your lips and in your heart.” When Jesus tells the rich young man that he must sell all his possession and give the money to the poor, the immediacy of literalism and poverty come together. There is no ambiguity about the command—and there is no impediment whatsoever to its being obeyed, no impediment, that is, except for the greatest one, which is our ongoing acquiescence to, even positive affirmation of, our bondage to sin and death. Moreover, it is important to remember why Jesus commands the way of poverty to the rich young man. It is for the sake of perfection, which is to say for supernatural life in God. The Franciscan interpretation of this parable sees the perfection obedience promises as conformity with Christ’s self-sacrificial love. We are deified insofar as we are made Christ-like, insofar as we drink the cup he drinks. By my reading of our tradition in the West, this interpretation has become canonical, at least tacitly so. The most fundamental influence of St. Francis has been to make poverty—a profoundly Cross-centered mode of life—the paradigmatic Western mode of theosis. Instead of the icon of the Pantocrator, in the West we fix upon what St. Bonaventure describes as the superluminous darkness of the cross. For this reason, it is the begging friar in his rude habit who becomes an indispensible aide to contemplation. We are bewitched by St. Francis, because in him we see the face of Christ. Pope Francis is a Jesuit, not a Franciscan. Nevertheless, the name he has chosen indicates that he wishes his pontificate to draw upon the charism of St. Francis. (This is by no means at odds with the Jesuit tradition. St. Ignatius himself wished to imitate the heroic sanctity of St. Francis.) This charism involves much more than making the poor the focal point of concern, which is after all a perennial commitment of the Church. Pope Francis consistently offers himself as a servant, not a prince. This has been the trajectory of the papacy over the last generation or two. (One thinks of John XXIII’s refusal to be carried in St. Peter’s on the papal throne, and John Paul I’s refusal of the papal crown.) But with Pope Francis the renunciations of supereminence are more emphatic. It was much reported that as the Cardinal Archbishop of Buenos Aires he rode to work on the bus. Since his election he has refused St. Francis and Pope Francis 35 the papal apartment and Prada shoes. These are symbolic, of course, but symbols matter. Recently, a Protestant friend spoke to me about a recent meeting he attended in Rome. A papal audience was arranged. He was moved by the fact that Francis asked the group of academics to pray for him. My friend intuitively grasped the mendicant spirit of the request. Pope Francis engages in a spiritual mode of begging. Pope Francis also echoes St. Francis’s literalism. He is given to blunt, spontaneous statements. His homiletical style is unadorned, and Evangelii Gaudium, the recent apostolic exhortation, is straightforward. I cannot imagine him embarking on a series of sermons of the sort that were as intellectually ambitious as John Paul II’s on the theology of the body. Nor can I see him writing theologically rich and evocative encyclicals, as did Benedict. Pope Francis seems the vicar of simple Gospel truths simply stated. And he often bears witness to them more eloquently in deed than in speech—a good Franciscan tradition. The unadorned style and rhetorical directness of Pope Francis is itself a mode of poverty. The Church has a rich intellectual tradition— artistic, philosophical, and theological. But the current pope seems to largely renounce its use, not for the sake of launching some sort of new tradition, as many did after Vatican II—Rahner, Lonergan— but for the sake of a kind of rhetorical poverty, a stripping-down of the Church’s witness to straightforward Gospel truths. Blessed are the poor. Blessed are the meek. Blessed are those who hunger and thirst after righteousness. I speculate, therefore, that Jorge Bergoglio’s choice of Francis reflects his reading of the signs of the times. Put simply: the age of Christianity’s reign over culture and society in the West has come to an end. Perhaps we have a few small and pleasant fiefs. We can gather in places like the Catholic Center at New York University: little Lichtensteins in the great empire of the modern secular university. But for the most part we have neither place nor voice. Whether we like it or not, we are impoverished. In this context, the message of Pope Francis seems to speak against the idea that we should form a robust counterculture. Instead, he seems to envision the Church in a mendicant mode. Rather than building a neo-scholastic redoubt, we are to bear witness in our poverty. Instead of St. Benedict, we are to imitate St. Francis. This is of course a false dichotomy. We need be able to give an account of the hope that is within us—and do so in articulate, intellec- 36 R. R. Reno tually sophisticated ways. But, as I have tried to show, the Franciscan charism of poverty is one of immediacy. While we must surely renew and rebuild the intellectual life of the Church, we can conform ourselves to Christ right now. We can bear witness right now. There is nothing about the poverty of our cultural dispossession and our intellectual marginality that prevents us from saying, “The Lord is risen.” In fact, it is perhaps easier. What does it say about our age that the Franciscan gestures of Pope Francis so enrapture people? Poverty has a perennial spiritual power. In his account of the life of St. Francis, Bonaventure frequently draws attention to this. It seduces cardinals and tames wild beasts. It softens the hearts of Saracens. That is true today as well. Pope Francis’s simplicity romances the editors of the New York Times. That said, perhaps our age has a special need for the Franciscan witness. We live in a paradoxical time of expansive possibilities combined with a feeling that life is a long trudge toward a distant, inaccessible goal. This contrasts with the leitmotif of Bonaventure’s life of St. Francis, which is the nearness and immediacy. St. Francis needed only the will to answer the divine call Let me give two examples. Although we are coddled to an unprecedented degree—warm, well fed, entertained, ministered to by modern medicine—we are anxious and fearful. Perhaps because we are aware of how much we have to lose, our first impulses are toward self-protection, which we do through accumulation. When we are young, we build our resumes, accumulating as many credentials as possible. Then we set out to accumulate wealth. In all this, it is striking how much we think we need—and it is even more striking how deeply we are motivated by fear. Getting a college degree has become a “necessity.” We scramble for credentials that are not so much stepping stones to a goal we aspire to as so many layers of armor that will protect us from economic peril. The habit of irony in our time is powerful cultural expression of this impulse toward self-protection. Irony creates a safe distance between us and our social contexts. It is a way of being with others without revealing oneself, a way of clothing one’s existential nakedness. “Whatever” has become a dismissive gesture that insulates us from the emotional dangers of disappointment. St. Francis and Pope Francis 37 In any event, we feel trapped. In some sense, that has always been true. Modern capitalism did not invent greed, and if our age is uniquely preoccupied with accumulating wealth, it is because we have relaxed our attitude toward honor and status, a fixation that enflamed men in earlier centuries. Moreover, we are all pinioned by death. But our age intuits something perverse about our current entrapment. Surrounded by unprecedented wealth, we fear deprivation. In an age of hypercommunication, we fear revealing ourselves to others. In this context of fear—and I want to emphasize that we are motivated by fear today much more than a grasping ambition—the pope’s Franciscan qualities have a special resonance. The Holy Father’s gestures of poverty and his blunt style remind us that what we desire—the joy of genuine freedom and fullness of life—are right there for the taking. They are immediately available. We need only say “yes” to Christ’s clear N&V words: “Take up your cross and follow me.” Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 39-55 39 Saint Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam Carol and Philip Zaleski Smith College Northampton, MA Part I: Francis and the Sultan OF ALL SAINTS,Francis of Assisi is the most transparent and the most opaque. His goodness, his generosity, his humility, his courage, his troubadour heart and mind, invite us to rush toward him, trust him, thank him, pray joyfully for his intercession. He is a man without guile, and we respond to him with a newfound innocence of our own. This is the transparency of which we speak. Yet at the core of Francis lies a mystery. Every historian, theologian, novelist, playwright, and poet who attempts to understand Il Poverello grinds to a halt before this terra incognita. This is not, as with Francis’s near-contemporary Dante, the enigma of transcendent art, its sources or genius; nor is it, as with our own near-contemporary Einstein, the parallel enigma of the origin of profound insight into the natural order. It is a deeper, more vexing mystery, one that Francis exhibits to the highest degree, and one that each of us must address, embrace, make his or her own: the mystery of holiness. What allowed this man, what could possibly allow anyone born of man and woman, to be known—inaccurately, but we see what is meant—as the Second Christ? How did it come to pass that this man rebuilt the Church, rekindled the faith of millions, received the stigmata upon his maculate flesh? These mysteries will never be and can never be fully resolved, for they are intimately linked to the Mysteries of Christ and his Cross. Thus Pius XI, in his 1926 encyclical, Rite Expiatis, quotes 40 Carol and Philip Zaleski approvingly the remark of one of Francis’s earliest biographers, Thomas of Celano, that in “all [Francis’s] efforts, public as well as private, he turned to the Cross of Our Lord, and from the moment he began to live as a soldier of Christ, the divers mysteries of the Cross shone round about him.”1 This nimbus of mystery shines around many chapters in Francis’s life. One such is the saint’s celebrated encounter with Sultan Al-Kamil in 1219 AD, in the midst of the Fifth Crusade. About this encounter little can be said with certainty, reminding us that one of the delightful ironies of historical research is that events about which we possess few or no details sometimes possess the greatest gravitas. This meeting of Christian saint and Muslim head of state has been described and misdescribed, analyzed and misanalyzed in a torrent of books, essays, articles, and speeches that shows no sign of abating. Our intention is to look at this and other encounters between Christians and Muslims in order to see what the Church and the ummah (the Islamic community) can learn from them; for the future of these encounters, we believe, is of vital importance for the happiness of humankind. In 1219, the year that saint met sultan, Francis was thirty-eight years old. It was five years before he would receive the stigmata, seven years before his death. Approved by Pope Innocent III in 1209, his Order was flourishing, although he suffered mishaps galore while attempting to spread his teaching abroad. He had been shipwrecked on the Dalmatian Coast in 1211 en route to Jerusalem and two years later had fallen sick while sailing to Morocco; in both cases he had been forced to return to Italy. His 1219 trip to Egypt would prove, therefore, to be a watershed. The other key figure in the celebrated encounter, Sultan al-Malik al-Kamil Naser al-Din Abu al-Ma’ali Muhammed, may be unfamiliar to many readers. A nephew of the great Saladin, Al-Kamil became sultan of Egypt in 1218, while the Fifth Crusade was in full flower. This Crusade, initiated by Innocent III and his successor, Honorius III, harbored a high ambition: to recapture Jerusalem and the Holy Land, a goal that required toppling the Ayyubid Dynasty in Egypt. The key to this, in turn, was the seizure of the port city of Damietta, about 120 miles north 1 See http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/pius_xi/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_ enc_30041926_rite-expiatis_en.html. St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 41 of Cairo. When al-Kamil became sultan, Damietta was already under siege by armies from several European nations. Al-Kamil was a skilled military strategist, but another side of his character emerged as soon as he took the throne—that of a seeker of peace. He extended several truce proposals to the Crusaders, most notably an offer to surrender Jerusalem in exchange for a European withdrawal from Damietta. These proposals were swiftly rebuffed by the considerably less irenic Cardinal Pelagius, leader of the crusading army; nevertheless, in 1229, ten years after Francis’s visit, al-Kamil would achieve his greatest triumph for peace, a ten-year truce with Frederick II that remains a model of judicious balance, in which the Muslims returned Jerusalem to the Crusaders while retaining possession of the Temple Mount and its holy places, the Dome of the Rock and the Al-Aqsa Mosque. Al-Kamil was also, and surely not incidentally, deeply interested in religion, as described by al-Maqrizi, a Muslim historian who flourished two centuries later: Al-Kamil much loved men of learning, preferring their society. He was passionately addicted to listening to the traditions of the Prophet. . . . He loved discussions with Muslim divines, and had a number of curious problems on jurisprudence and grammar with which he would examine scholars, and those who answered rightly he advanced and gave them his favor.2 During the intense heat of August 1219, Francis arrived at Damietta, along with Brother Illuminato and other companions, having set sail from the heel of Italy’s boot with a likely stopover in Rhodes. St. Bonaventure, in a passage from his Major Legend of Francis, provides a clue to Francis’s thoughts en route to Egypt. Francis, Bonaventure tells us, saw two lambs and declared to Illuminato, “Trust in the Lord, brother, for the Gospel text is being fulfilled in us: Behold, I am sending you forth like sheep in the midst of wolves.” What was his aim, in this extraordinary adventure? Almost certainly just what it appeared to be to his contemporaries: the conversion of the “wolves,” as most Christians 2 Al-Maqrizi, A History of the Ayyubid Sultans of Egypt, trans. R. J. C. Broadhurst (Boston: Twayne, 1980), 229. 42 Carol and Philip Zaleski saw them—that is, the sultan and his court—perhaps mingled with desire for his own martyrdom. As Dante puts it in Paradiso XI: “In thirst for martyrdom, he had preached Christ and them that followed Him in the proud presence of the Sultan.” Franciscan sources emphasize the desire for martyrdom, non-Franciscan sources the wish to convert. Upon his arrival in Damietta, Francis was appalled by the cruelties of the siege. Dominican scholar Augustine Thompson, author of a recent, richly informative biography of Francis, believes that the sight awoke in the friar “memories of his own traumatic military experiences.”3 Francis began to rush about, first warning the Crusaders of impending doom and then turning his attention to the Muslim enemy across the Nile, petitioning Cardinal Pelagius to allow him to approach the sultan in order to teach the ways of Christ. At first Pelagius refused the request, either worried about Francis’s safety or concerned that al-Kamil would mistake this private initiative as a state-authorized mission to negotiate the siege. But Francis was a master at badgering others (in a most holy way), and the Cardinal capitulated. Soon after, Francis and Illuminato sailed, without armed escort, across the Nile and into the enemy camp. Muslim soldiers surrounded them, believing them to be deserters ready to convert to Islam. When they realized their error, threats and manhandling ensued. Francis responded by shouting Soldan! Soldan!—“Sultan! Sultan!”—and the two friars found themselves in the presence of al-Kamil. We know little of what transpired during the meeting (or meetings, as the encounter extended over several days); what we do know is based upon second- or third- hand evidence presented by Bonaventure, by Jacques de Vitry, a French historian and bishop, later a cardinal, who was present at Damietta, and by more remotely placed medieval chroniclers. Sifting the sources, it is difficult to discern whether al-Kamil initially saw Francis as a potential convert or as a political agent in disguise. Francis, however, made it clear from the start that he was in Egypt to preach the Lord and thereby convert the sultan. Al-Kamil predictably summoned his theologians; Francis helpfully offered to be decapitated if he failed to convert them as well as the sultan. Needless to say, he 3 Augustine Thompson, O.P., Francis of Assisi: A New Biography (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2012), 67. St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 43 failed; al-Kamil and his mutakallimun (scholars of kalaam, the science of theological discussion), seasoned and devout Muslims one and all, were no more likely to be persuaded of the truth of Christianity under these conditions than Francis was likely to be converted to Islam. The mutakallimun considered the friar an advocate of shirk (polytheism) and recommended immediate execution. Thankfully, the sultan stayed his hand. Instead, he and Francis engaged in a discussion that lasted a few more days and that, at least at first glance, led nowhere. At one stage in the proceedings, according to Bonaventure—a careful researcher who sought out eyewitnesses and who may have heard this particular tale first hand from Illuminato—Francis offered to undergo a trial by fire, during which he and the Muslim religious authorities would walk through a conflagration, “so that you will recognize,” as Francis put it, “which faith deserves to be held as the holier and more certain.”4 When the sultan declined this proposal, explaining that the mutakallimun would prefer other approaches, Francis offered to try the flames alone, declaring that if he suffered burns, it would be suitable punishment for his sins, but if he came through unscathed, the sultan must acknowledge Christ as God and Savior. Al-Kamil rejected this as well, pleading fear of an unruly response by his subjects; he may also have been unwilling to see the little friar killed in what he surely perceived as a futile gesture. Augustine Thompson rejects the authenticity of this episode, both because he believes it does not match Francis’s character and because he rejects all such events not found in contemporary records. We must bear in mind, however, that Bonaventure, while not a contemporary of Francis, interviewed for his biography many who knew Francis well, that ordeals by fire were well attested in twelfth-century Italy, and that, as French medievalist André Vauchez points out, Francis would have been aware of the Old Testament Canticle of the three children in the furnace protected from the flames by divine intervention. In any event, the sultan closed the conversation, pressing upon Francis and Illuminato gold and silver gifts. Francis, ever in love with Lady Poverty, explained that he 4 St. Bonaventure, “The Life of St. Francis,” in Bonaventure: The Soul’s Journey into God, The Tree of Life, The Life of St. Francis, trans. and ed. Ewert Cousins (New York: Paulist Press, 1978), 270. 44 Carol and Philip Zaleski would accept only food. He and Illuminato then returned to the Christian side of the Nile, Damietta fell to the crusaders, a ghastly sack of the city ensued, and appalled by the violence, Francis quit Egypt for Syria. This remarkable encounter has given rise to an array of strange, sometimes comical, interpretations. Thus we have Jacques de Vitry in 1226, just seven years after the encounter, painting a portrait of a vicious sultan charmed into submission by an angelic friar; the portrait of Francis rings true, but that of al-Kamil is clumsy propaganda. Leaping forward to the twentieth century, we find that historical accuracy is still in arrears, as witnessed by the following nonsense from Idries Shah, renowned Sufi, bestselling author, and spiritual mentor of Nobel Prize– winning novelist Doris Lessing: Shah informs us that from his youth, Francis “was connected with the Sufis,” that he visited Egypt not to convert the sultan but to explore his Sufi roots, that in the Muslim court “he found what he was looking for,” that as a result “the atmosphere and setting of the Franciscan Order is closer to a dervish organization than anything else,” and that Francis’s vision of the six-winged seraph is, in reality, a Sufi allegory!5 In a more sober analysis, some modern historians have argued that Francis was indeed, as al-Kamil suspected, on a secret mission to negotiate peace with the Egyptian forces. There may be a grain of truth in this admittedly speculative assessment, for Francis, as we know, always preached peace. In the prologue to his Mind’s Journey to God, Bonaventure reminds us that “at the beginning and end of every sermon [Francis] announced peace; in every greeting he wished for peace; in every contemplation he sighed for ecstatic peace.”6 Nonetheless, there is no evidence that Francis opposed the Crusaders’ aims; indeed, as Thompson points out, Francis never discusses war in his writings. For the holy friar, the way to peace ran not through political manipulations but through Christ, the Prince of Peace; we may conclude, therefore, that the best evidence continues to support the belief of most historians that Francis visited the sultan in order to usher him and his court, through conversion, into the realm of the Prince of Peace. This understanding receives additional support from an important 5 6 Idries Shah, The Sufis (New York: Anchor Books, 1971), 257–65. St. Bonaventure, Bonaventure: The Soul’s Journey Into God, The Tree of Life, The Life of St. Francis, trans. and ed. Ewert Cousins (New York: Paulist Press, 1978), 53. St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 45 passage in Francis’s Earlier Rule, completed by 1221, shortly after his visit to Egypt. In chapter 16, Francis describes his recommendations for missionaries to the Muslims (whom he calls “Saracens”) and other non-Christians (whom he calls “nonbelievers”). He begins with the same words of Jesus from Matthew 10:16 that he voiced while sailing to Damietta, “Behold I am sending you forth like sheep in the midst of wolves. Be therefore wise as serpents and harmless as doves.” Francis then delineates two—and only two—ways for Christians to live “spiritually” among those of other faiths. The first is to dwell among them as professed Christians, bearing witness to the Faith, yet without “arguments or disputes.” The missionary must be, as St. Peter wrote in his first letter, “subject to every human creature for God’s sake.”7 We may recognize this as the method adopted many centuries later by Blessed Charles de Foucauld. The second method described by Francis is for Christians to go among nonbelievers as proselytizers, declaring the word of God and the necessity of baptism. This is the method that Francis employed with the sultan. In one sense it failed, for no conversion resulted. What lesson should we draw from this? That Christians should no longer preach the Gospel or make disciples of all nations or baptize in the name of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit? That all efforts at active conversion are off the table? As the most famous Christian convert of all (St. Paul) declares with rhythmic regularity in his greatest and most famous letter, “God forbid!” Preaching Christ is incumbent upon all Christians—just as the invitation (da’wah) to Islam is incumbent upon all Muslims. We may uncover the true lesson of Francis’s mission by examining the ways in which it succeeded. Above all, we should note Francis’s adherence to the divine admonition to be wise as a serpent, harmless as a dove. Such was his behavior from start to finish, even if we wish that he had been less extravagant in a few of his tactical gambits. As a result of his caution—an expression of his love—there was no bloodshed, no bitterness during the encounter. He never attacked Muhammad, the sultan, or the mutakallimun; it has been often observed that throughout his life, Francis never spoke ill of any man. While in Egypt he exhibited 7 Francis of Assisi, “The Earlier Rule,” in Francis of Assisi: Early Documents, vol. 1: The Saint, ed. Regis J. Armstrong, O.F.M. Cap., et al. (New York: New City Press, 1999), 74–75. 46 Carol and Philip Zaleski genuine tact and palpable purity of heart, qualities that induced the sultan to recognize his strange visitor as a holy man. Francis made a lasting impression, too, on the sultan’s advisors, so much so that one of them, the jurist Fakhr ad-Din al-Farisi, has the famous encounter memorialized upon his tombstone. In describing Francis’s excellences, it is important to note that the sultan, too, was wise as a serpent, harmless as a dove. Al-Kamil surely knew and treasured the great hadiths on kindness and generosity of spirit, of which the following are characteristic: Allah is kind and loves kindness and gives for gentleness what he does not give for harshness nor for anything else. Do you know what is better than charity and fasting and prayer? It is keeping peace and good relations between people, as quarrels and bad feelings destroy mankind. These principles of mutual respect and courtesy—grounded, as we shall see, in a shared understanding of the human being as a creature dependent upon God for his very being—had played, in fact, an important role in earlier Christian-Islamic encounters. A long tradition of majalis—sessions of the caliph’s court, devoted, among other matters, to religious dialogue between Muslims and representatives of other religions, can be traced back to the second Islamic century (the eighth century AD). We possess numerous accounts of these interfaith gatherings; most are literary fictions, but two appear to be authentic. The first recounts the meeting of Catholicos Timothy I, patriarch of the East Syrian Church, and al-Mahdi, the third Abbasid caliph, in Baghdad in 781 or 782 AD, just a century and a half after the death of Muhammad; the second describes the encounter of Bishop Elias bar Shinaya of Nisibis with Vizier Abu l-Qasim in southeastern Turkey in AD 1026–27. These two majalis encompassed discussion of most Christian-Muslim flash points, including prophetology, the nature of the Qur’an, the divinity of Christ, the Trinity, and so on. What strikes one immediately is the unfailing courtesy, sincerity, and goodwill of the participants. When Timothy meets al-Mahdi, the caliph tells him that “if you accepted Muhammad as a prophet, your St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 47 words would be beautiful and their meaning fine,” to which Timothy declares that Muhammad “deserves the praise of all reasonable men because his walk was on the way of the prophets and of the lovers of God,” and that the Prophet led “his community away from evil and [drew] them to what is right and virtuous.” The encounter between Bishop Elias and the vizier is even more heartening, for during this meeting—two centuries before Francis met the sultan—the two men adumbrate some tentative ground rules for successful Muslim-Christian dialogue. Elias tells the vizier that “if [your] purpose in this talk is the knowledge of our doctrine and acquitting us of the ugliness that is attributed to us, I will set forth what I have. But if the purpose is disputation and debate, I ask [you] to excuse me from it.” To this the vizier responds, “I believe that every Christian is a successful praise-worthy monotheist, even if he does not acknowledge the prophethood of Muhammad. And the only condition of inquiry is a thorough examination of the question and of the counter position. So attribute what comes from me in reply to sincerity and to no other motive.”8 Sincerity here is used in the sense detailed a century later by al-Ghazali in his magisterial Revival of the Religious Sciences: Action without intention is drudgery, whereas intention without sincerity is ostentation. . . . Sincerity without truthfulness and exactitude is but a scatter of dust. This teaching, in turn, is beautifully condensed in the following hadith: “God says ‘Sincerity is one of My secrets, which I consign to the heart of the servant I love.’” It is this sincerity of heart that Francis perceived in the sultan and the sultan in Francis, and that has come, thank God, to inform and inspire the best of Christian-Muslim dialogue today. The chief representative of this approach during the past hundred years was the great French scholar of Islam Louis Massignon (1883–1962), a friend of Blessed Charles de Foucauld, a brilliant authority on early Islam and Sufism, in particular al-Hallaj, and a devotee of the Blessed Virgin, who 8 For a superb account of these and other majalis, see Sidney H. Griffith, “The Monk in the Emir’s Majlis: Reflections on a Popular Genre of Christian Literary Apologetics in Arabic in the Early Islamic Period,” in The Majalis: Interreligious Encounters in Medieval Islam, ed. Hava Lazarus-Yafeh (Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz, 1999), 13–65. 48 Carol and Philip Zaleski in 1931 became a Franciscan tertiary, taking the name Ibrahim. This name is a key to Massignon’s perspective on Christian-Muslim dialogue, for he was convinced that recognition by Christians and Muslims of a common spiritual descent from Abraham would lay the foundation for peaceful solutions to conflicts that plagued North Africa and the Middle East in his time and continue to do so today. Reasons abound, as we discuss below, to question his presentation of Abrahamic consanguinity; nonetheless, the ardor, beauty, and scholarly integrity of his Christian love for Islam remain exemplary. During February 1934, along with Mary Kahil, a Melkite Christian, Massignon visited Damietta. The two pilgrims knelt in prayer before the altar of the abandoned Franciscan Church, on or near the site where Francis and the sultan had talked seven centuries before. There Massignon and Kahil vowed to form an intercessory fellowship, which they called by the Arabic name of badaliya (substitution), pledging to enter as far as possible into the inner life of Islam. In addition to offering aid to those in need, they prayed, in a most audacious request, to be allowed to take on the suffering of their Muslim neighbors. This was an extraordinary sacrificial act, based upon the principle of witnessing without proselytizing. A few months later, the fellowship received the blessing of Pius XI. In time, Massignon’s views on Islam spread through much of the Catholic hierarchy, deeply affecting the thought of Cardinal Montini, the future Paul VI, and profoundly influencing the generous approach to Islam as an Abrahamic religion in major documents of Vatican II, in particular Lumen Gentium and Nostra Aetate. Part II: The Church and Islam: Recent Developments Let us now look at these two critical documents, in order to determine what they say—and what they do not say—about the Church and Islam. Lumen Gentium, the Dogmatic Constitution on the Church, promulgated on November 21, 1964, by Pope Paul VI, begins, as the title suggests, with Christ the “Light of the Nations”; and in exploring the mystery of the Church that Christ founded, it seeks to relate those outside the Church to those within her fold, describing them in a series of concentric circles. Closest to the center is the Jewish people, a people “most dear to God”—“for God does not repent of the gifts He makes nor of the St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 49 calls He issues.”9 The next circle belongs to those who acknowledge the Creator, foremost among them “the Muslims, who, professing to hold the faith of Abraham, along with us adore the one and merciful God, who on the last day will judge mankind.”10 In a yet more remote circle stand all “those who in shadows and images seek the unknown God, for it is He who gives to all men life and breath and all things, and as Saviour wills that all men be saved” and those who through no fault of their own are not aware that they seek God.11 A year later, Paul VI promulgated Nostra Aetate (“In Our Age”), the Declaration on the Relation of the Church with Non-Christian Religions, affirming that “the Catholic Church rejects nothing that is true and holy” in all the world’s religions and expressing esteem for Muslims for the special reason that “they adore the one God, living and subsisting in Himself; merciful and all-powerful, the Creator of heaven and earth, who has spoken to men; they take pains to submit wholeheartedly to even His inscrutable decrees, just as Abraham, with whom the faith of Islam takes pleasure in linking itself, submitted to God.”12 Monotheism and Abraham are the two main points of connection mentioned by Nostra Aetate. But there is more: Muslims revere Jesus as a prophet, honor his virgin Mother, await the Resurrection and judgment of the dead, strive to live morally, and serve God with prayer and disciplined self-sacrifice. Above all, Nostra Aetate tells us, “this sacred synod urges all to forget the past and to work sincerely for mutual understanding and to preserve as well as to promote together for the benefit of all mankind social justice and moral welfare, as well as peace and freedom.”13 These words, as Benedict XVI put it in an address to Muslims in Cologne, amount to a Magna Carta for the Church’s dialogue with Islam. Like the Magna Carta, Nostra Aetate charts a new direction. We are to begin anew, forgetting the past—one hears an echo of St. Paul “forgetting what lies behind and straining forward to what lies ahead” (Phil 3)—and working together for the common good. Like the Magna Carta, 9 Lumen Gentium §16. Ibid. 11 Ibid. 12 Nostra Aetate §§2, 3. 13 Ibid., §3. 10 50 Carol and Philip Zaleski Nostra Aetate does not legislate, it only reorients. It does not minimize the differences between Christianity and Islam. It does not even mention, let alone interpret, the Qur’an or the Prophet Muhammad. Instead, Nostra Aetate shifts our focus to the exemplary lives of the millions of Muslims with whom we share our planet.14 In this respect, Nostra Aetate reflects the open-endedness of a council convened to regain the Church’s voice and vision for the modern world rather than to answer a particular disputed question. Pope Benedict, who had been one of the periti during the heady days of the council, came to think, as he said in a candid reflection on Nostra Aetate two years ago, that “in the process of active reception, a weakness of this otherwise extraordinary text has gradually emerged: it speaks of religion solely in a positive way and it disregards the sick and distorted forms of religion which, from the historical and theological viewpoints, are of far-reaching importance.”15 In other words, Benedict cautions, it is possible to read Nostra Aetate as if it were a charter to abandon judgments where religion is concerned. For example, some Christians, perhaps under the inspiration of Massignon, have become rather giddy about the idea of Abrahamic religions. If we share the faith of Abraham, the thinking goes, why bother about the details? Abraham is the model of hospitality toward the stranger, the other, the angel in disguise; we can emulate this hospitality by tracing our family tree back to Abraham and fostering a common Abrahamic creed: the creed of the hanif, or natural monotheist. As children of Abraham, conscious of the inadequacy of all humanly constructed images of God, we should wear our theological commitments lightly. Hans Küng and his former pupil and younger colleague at Tübingen Karl-Josef Kuschel have called this program “Abrahamic ecumenism.”16 The problem with the notion of Abrahamic ecumenism is that we are not one household of faith (as the word ecumenism would imply). 14 See the discussion by Daniel Madigan, “Nostra Aetate and the Questions It Chose to Leave Open,” Gregorianum 87, no. 4 (2006): 781–96. 15 “It Was a Splendid Day, Pope Benedict Recalls,” L’Osservatore Romano, October 11, 2012, http://www.osservatoreromano.va/en/news/it-was-a-splendid-day-benedictxvi-recalls#.U4k6DfldV8E. 16 See the discussion by Reformed theologian Cornelis (Kees) van der Kooi, “Towards an Abrahamic Ecumenism?” Acta Theologica 32, no. 2 (2012): 240–53. St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 51 And though we share Abraham, we do not agree on his significance, as Jon D. Levenson has convincingly shown in in his masterful study Inheriting Abraham: the Legacy of the Patriarch in Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. Summing up his argument informally in an essay for The Jewish Review of Books, Levenson borrowed a line from George Bernard Shaw: “if ‘England and America are two countries separated by a common language,’ then Judaism and Christianity are two religions separated by a common Abraham.”17 Far more then, are Jews and Christians separated from Islam by our vision of Abraham. Why separated by Abraham? Because for Islam, Abraham is essentially a Muslim prophet, a destroyer of idols who with his beloved son Ishmael rebuilt the Ka’aba as God’s house on earth. The points of connection to the Abraham of Genesis are fascinating, but Islamic tradition holds that Abraham’s true history and identity are as much obscured as they are revealed by the Genesis account. We are also separated by a common Jesus: Jesus seen through Muslim eyes is the son of the Virgin Mary, not the Son of God; the bringer of the Gospel, not its one great Subject; he was persecuted for his prophesy but not crucified;18 he is expected at the end of time but is not the true End for which creation longs. Honest dialogue with Muslims must necessarily bring out these differences, and they are far from trivial. By the same token, honest dialogue means, for Christians, a fuller appreciation of who Muhammad is for Islam. There have been Christians, as far back as the Enlightenment, who professed admiration for Muhammad as a preacher of natural theology; they read the early suras of the Qur’an as a lyrical restatement of the design argument, a pure monotheism of the desert, free from the Church’s suffocating thicket of doctrines and rites. But the Muhammad of Islamic tradition is far more interesting. Tradition characterizes him as the perfect man: a devoted husband and father, exemplary in his conduct of business, defender of widows and orphans, ideal statesman and judge. More exalted still, Muhammad is the man of light, created in the beginning from the 17 Jon D. Levenson, “The Idea of Abrahamic Religions: A Qualified Dissent,” Jewish Review of Books, Spring 2010, http://jewishreviewofbooks.com/articles/244/ the-idea-of-abrahamic-religions-a-qualified-dissent/. 18 Gabriel Said Reynolds, “The Muslim Jesus: Dead or Alive?” Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 72, no. 2 (2009): 237–58. 52 Carol and Philip Zaleski primordial light, so full of that light that he cast no shadow.19 The light that shone through the previous prophets from Adam to Moses to Jesus was but a partial reflection of Muhammad’s own radiance. The miracles associated with the Prophet’s career were subordinate only to the miracle of the Qur’an itself; Muhammad commanded the trees to bend in prayer, he ascended to heaven to receive his divine commission, he will intercede for his community on the last day, he is the final prophet, the seal of the prophets, and the only messenger to transmit God’s words without distortion. In every way he is the “beautiful model,” whose words and deeds, habits and customs (sunna), transmitted by the authorized hadith literature, form the foundation of Islamic ethics and etiquette, jurisprudence and spiritual life. One can no more understand Islam without the traditional biographies and saying sources than one can understand Judaism without the Talmud or Christianity without the Fathers and the Councils. We are also divided by a common monotheism. The beauty and power of the monotheism of the Qur’an is its confession of God’s majestic transcendence—and the response of communal adoration this confession elicits. The beauty and power of the monotheism of the Gospel is its message of divine humility, of the Son who emptied himself and took on the form of a slave; of the “hands that had made the sun and stars” yet “were too small to reach the huge heads of the cattle”; of Christ crucified and risen; of humanity ruined and redeemed. As St. John Paul II observed in Crossing the Threshold of Hope, not all monotheisms are alike: Some of the most beautiful names in the human language are given to the God of the Koran, but He is ultimately a God outside of the world, a God who is only Majesty, never Emmanuel, God with us. Islam is not a religion of redemption. There is no room for the Cross and the Resurrection. Jesus is mentioned, but only as a prophet who prepares for the last prophet, Muhammad. There is also mention of Mary, His Virgin Mother, but the tragedy of redemption is completely absent. For this reason 19 See Annemarie Schimmel, And Muhammad Is His Messenger: The Veneration of the Prophet in Islamic Piety (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1985), for a rich survey of traditional literary and devotional expressions of esteem for the Prophet. St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 53 not only the theology but also the anthropology of Islam is very distant from Christianity.20 To Muslims we are hardly recognizable as monotheists when we confess our faith in the Communion of Persons in the Blessed Trinity. When we speak of the “wonderful exchange” by which we gave Christ the power to die, our words must seem strange, if not shocking. Similarly, it is a challenge for our Muslim friends to convey the depth of their veneration of the Prophet to us, or to open to us what would otherwise be the sealed letter of Divine love received by so many Muslim saints and mystics—in the light of which the claim that the God of Islam is “never Emmanuel, God with us” needs to be rethought. But if we are truly friends, we can meet this challenge. This is the point of Nostra Aetate. There is all the difference in the world between learning abstract facts about another person’s religion and looking at the world as seen through another person’s eyes. When we look at the world through another’s eyes, we find a new point of departure: neither polemics about what divides us nor platitudes about what unites us. What does the world look like as seen through the eyes of Muslims? It looks like a gift. And we are in no doubt as to the giver, for his signature is everywhere. Wherever we look there are signs, ayat, of God’s power and sovereignty. Thus Sura 56 (Al-Waqi’a, “That Which Is Coming”): Consider the seeds you sow in the ground—is it you who make them grow or We? . . . . Consider the water you drink—was it you who brought it down from the rain-cloud or We? . . . . Consider the fire you kindle—is it you who make the wood for it grow or We? We made it a reminder, and useful to those who kindle it, so glorify the name of your Lord.21 What does my own life look like? That, too, a sheer gift. Christians and Muslims differ in many crucial points of theological anthropology, but 20 John Paul II, Crossing the Threshold of Hope (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1994): 92–93. 21 M. A. S. Abdel Haleem, trans., The Qur’an (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), 357. Carol and Philip Zaleski 54 we have at least this much in common: we know that we are creatures. We know this, perhaps, even before we truly know that there is a God. We are made out of dust, or similar lowly stuff—a blood clot, a drop of semen, a clinging form, a clump of cells, a bit of clay; and the dust itself is made, theologians tell us, out of nothing. To be a creature is to be marked by contingency, by fragility, by near-nonentity. Though we possess an immaterial soul, we are not the source or support of our own existence. Compared to God, all creatures—humans, angels, animals, jinn—are almost unreal. God alone is real, al-Haqq. “What is man that thou are mindful of him?” (Ps 8:4). Yet that is not the whole story. We are dust with dignity. The Scriptures, both Bible and Qur’an, after reducing human beings to dust, turn around and attribute to humankind a dignity surpassing even angels: “Yet thou hast made him little less than God, and dost crown him with glory and honor” (Ps 8:5). Hence, in the Quranic account of the creation of Adam, God commands the angels to prostrate themselves before a creature that by all indications occupies a lower rung on the scale of being; and the refusal of Iblis (the Devil) to submit to this command is the moment of his arch-rebellion and fall: We said to the angels, “Bow down before Adam,” and they did. But not Iblis: he was not one of those who bowed down. God said, “What prevented you from bowing down as I commanded you?” and he said, “I am better than him: You created me from fire and him from clay.” God said, “Get down from here! This is no place for your arrogance” Sura 7 (Sura Al-A‘raf, “The Heights”).22 We are dust, or clay, made for a purpose; we possess a dignity beyond our wildest dreams, not because of some irreducible excellence, but because we have an Author who gives us a share, apportioned to our nature, of existence, rationality, and love. To be a creature is to live in hope that the God who made us will remake us; that when the story of our life is over, we will see him as He is and become who we are. Gaudium et Spes tells us that “When God is forgotten . . . the creature 22 Ibid., 94–95. St. Francis, the Catholic Church, and Islam 55 itself grows unintelligible.”23 By the same token, when creaturehood is remembered, God and humanity draw near. We believe that this shared vision of our creaturehood (more than a vision, really, for all of us feel it in our bones) has practical implications. It is a fundamental common ground, not one that requires theological concessions; and it places Christians and Muslims, in the context of secular societies, on the same side of a host of moral and social issues. From our creature consciousness comes a certain ethic and aesthetic of adoration, embodied in the beautiful act of prostration, which takes the breath away whether one witnesses it in the daily prayer of Muslims, or in the solemn rites of Christian ordination and consecration to religious life. From our creature consciousness comes a sense of modesty. From our creature consciousness comes an instinct for repentance, and a repertoire of penitential disciplines to direct that impulse and correct morbid exaggerations. From our creature consciousness comes an awareness of death and a concomitant commitment to cherish the life of the unborn, the elderly, and the disabled. Our common ground is imperfect and often fraught, but our opportunities to make common cause, in a world that has lost its sense of creaturehood, are inexhaustible. Creaturehood is, of course, the great theme of St. Francis; his hymn, the Laudes Creaturarum, popularly known as the “Canticle of the Sun,” has its roots in the Laudate Psalms—especially Psalm 148—and the Benedicite Canticle (the Song of the Three Children in Dn 3: 52-88). Far from being a sentimental paean to our animal friends, the Canticle of the Sun calls upon creatures to praise their Creator; far from treating all creatures as equivalent, they suggest that each creature is designed to praise the Creator according to its own gifts. It is the exultant humility of il Poverello, his penitent joy in honoring God—rather than his quixotic mission to convert the Sultan—that makes Francis the paradigmatic N&V figure for dialogue between Christians and Muslims. 23 Gaudium et Spes §36. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 57-86 57 In the Name of Jesus Christ: A Few Historical Perspectives on the Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation Timothy Bellamah, O.P. Dominican House of Studies Washington, DC IN HIS RECENT STUDY“Ecclesial Exegesis and Ecclesial Authority,” Matthew Levering explores the fascinating relationship between biblical interpretation and ecclesiology, that is, how perspectives on the Church and ecclesial authority affect biblical interpretation and vice versa. By comparing the exegetical models of two notable contemporary biblical scholars, Brevard Childs and Stephen Fowl, with that of a medieval one, Thomas Aquinas, he argues persuasively that the work of the last may serve in our time to show what it means to participate in ecclesially mediated “divine doctrina.” Levering observes that while both Childs and Fowl find much to admire in Aquinas’s approach to Scripture, both find him insufficiently critical, the former faulting his seemingly eisegetical employment of theological and philosophical authorities, and the latter criticizing his apparent oversight of alleged shortcomings in the institutional Church’s interpretation. Levering, by contrast, finds Aquinas exemplary both for his actual exegetical practice and his interpretation of ecclesial authority.1 The causes of this disagreement are surely too complex for an adequate accounting here, but one matter is conspicuous, namely, the lack of a common understanding of the concept of author1 Matthew Levering, “Ecclesial Exegesis and Ecclesial Authority: Childs, Fowl, and Aquinas,” The Thomist 69 (2005): 407–67. 58 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. ity, particularly ecclesial authority. Whereas Childs and Fowl tend to be suspicious of its compatibility with divine revelation, Levering does not hesitate to declare its mediation of Christ’s authority in the world.2 In a recent essay on ecclesial authority, Nicholas Lash draws attention to the interesting ambiguity of the concept of instruction, and describes the difference between instruction as education and instruction as command. Noting the importance of avoiding confusion of the two senses, he goes on to say that it is more important to avoid subordinating the former to the latter.3 This is well and good, but Lash’s article seems to take for granted a narrow understanding of ecclesial authority, suggesting that it is merely an instrument of governance, separate from, if not opposed to, the Church’s teaching activity.4 What follows is intended to complement Levering’s inquiry by surveying the complex provenance and development of the concept of authority in the Church’s exegetical tradition. This will be for the sake of showing that Aquinas’s understanding of ecclesial mediation of sacred teaching is more easily clarified if explained by way of the Roman concept of auctoritas, as appropriated by the Church’s exegetical tradition, than by the modern English term “authority.” Further, this will allow us better to appreciate the Church’s own understanding of her mediation of divine revelation, as expressed in Dei Verbum. To see that the Latin and English terms are not always interchangeable we need look no further than the Vatican’s official English translation of the aforesaid document. Dei Verbum § 10 describes the Church’s authority in the interpretation of Scripture as follows: 2 “A richer metaphysical account of the reality depicted in Scripture would avoid this clash of competing agents and do justice to how the Church both is and is not the kingdom, and thus how the visible Church does, and does not, embody and mediate Christ’s authority in the world.” Ibid., 428. 3 Nicholas Lash, “Teaching or Commanding: When Bishops Instruct the Faithful,” America, December 13, 2010, 17–20. 4 “Nowhere in ‘The Splendor of Truth’ does John Paul II discuss disagreement in the church or the duty of episcopal authority to monitor and guide it . . . ‘It is for ecclesiology,’ said Robert Murray, S.J., an English Jesuit, ‘that [the term] magisterium till about the mid-nineteenth century referred to the activity of authorized teaching in the Church. The use with a capital ‘M’ to denote episcopal and especially papal authority was developed mainly in the anti-Modernist documents.’” Ibid, 18–19. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 59 But the task (munus) of authentically interpreting the word of God, whether written or handed on, (8) has been entrusted exclusively to the living teaching office of the Church, (9) whose authority (auctoritas) is exercised in the name of Jesus Christ. This teaching office is not above the word of God, but serves it, teaching only what has been handed on, listening to it devoutly, guarding it scrupulously and explaining it faithfully in accord with a divine commission and with the help of the Holy Spirit, it draws from this one deposit of faith everything which it presents for belief as divinely revealed.5 In this case the English translation’s “authority” corresponds to the Latin auctoritas. But the two are not always equivalent. Elsewhere in the document’s English version, “authority” appears four times, only once supplying for auctoritas.6 In two of the other three instances, it stands in for the Latin magisterium,7 and once it is gratuitous, that is, lacking any basis in the editio typica.8 It is no part of the present study’s purpose to quarrel with these translations, which strike this author as fair enough. But their variability 5 “Munus autem authentice interpretandi verbum Dei scriptum vel traditum (15) soli vivo Ecclesiae Magisterio concreditum est (16), cuius auctoritas in nomine Iesu Christi exercetur. Quod quidem Magisterium non supra verbum Dei est, sed eidem ministrat, docens nonnisi quod traditum est, quatenus illud, ex divino mandato et Spiritu Sancto assistente, pie audit, sancte custodit et fideliter exponit, ac ea omnia ex hoc uno fidei deposito haurit quae tamquam divinitus revelata credenda proponit.” Dei Verbum 10. 6 “Cum autem verbum Dei omnibus temporibus praesto esse debeat, Ecclesia materna sollicitudine curat, ut aptae ac rectae exarentur in varias linguas versiones, praesertim ex primigenis Sacrorum Librorum textibus. Quae si, data opportunitate et annuente Ecclesiae auctoritate, conficiantur communi etiam cum fratribus seiunctis nisu, ab omnibus christianis adhiberi poterunt.” Dei Verbum 22. 7 “Ut autem Evangelium integrum et vivum iugiter in Ecclesia servaretur, Apostoli successores reliquerunt Episcopos, ipsis ‘suum ipsorum locum magisterii tradentes’”; “But in order to keep the Gospel forever whole and alive within the Church, the Apostles left bishops as their successors, ‘handing over’ to them ‘the authority to teach in their own place.’” Dei Verbum 7; cf. Irenaeus, Adv. Haer. III, 3, 1 (PG 7, 848). “Patet igitur Sacram Traditionem, Sacram Scripturam et Ecclesiae Magisterium.” “It is clear, therefore, that sacred tradition, Sacred Scripture and the teaching authority of the Church.” Dei Verbum 10. 8 “Ecclesia materna sollicitudine curat”; “the Church by her authority and with maternal concern.” Dei Verbum 22. 60 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. on the matter at hand suggests that the equivalence of auctoritas and “authority” may be presumed only at the risk of misreading the above passage of Dei Verbum as well as other similar magisterial declarations. Often enough such equivalence is indeed taken for granted even by theologians taking a specific interest in the matter. Richard McBrien has observed that “authority and power are not the same thing,”9 only to conflate the two concepts in a subsequent discussion.10 And after noting the English term’s origin in the Latin auctor (author), he dedicates several pages to describing its basis in the Old and New Testaments, and in the writings of the early Church.11 And yet, the notion that the auctoritas mentioned by Dei Verbum has a clear biblical basis runs up against the term’s near absence from the Vulgate and its striking rarity in the earliest Christian literature. Roman and Early Christian Origins of the Term Here something must be said about the concept’s background, not only for the Fathers of Vatican II, but also for early Christian Latin ones such as Tertullian, Ambrose, and Augustine. To begin with the Bible, while the term “authority” is commonplace in modern English translations of the New Testament, auctoritas appears in none of the Vulgate’s corresponding passages.12 On one occasion where the NAB employs the term “authority,” the Latin equivalent is sublimitas (1 Tm 2:2), on another it is imperium (Ti 2:15), and on another, to have authority corresponds to the Vulgate’s dominari, to dominate (1 Tm 2:12). In all the other cases, the Vulgate counterpart is not auctoritas, but postestas, and this usually to translate the Greek ἐξουσία. However well the English “authority” may 9 Richard McBrien, Catholicism (Minneapolis: Winston Press, 1980), 817, 818–22. A similar discussion also appears in his “The Nature and Use of Power in the Church,” Proceedings of the Catholic Theological Society of America (1982): 38–49 (40–42). 10 Ibid., 818. 11 Ibid., 818–22. 12 The NAB New Testament employs “authority” fifty-seven times, usually as an equivalent for the Greek ἐξουσία, generally defined as ability/capability/power. A typical example is the NAB’s translation of Mk 11:27–28: “They returned once more to Jerusalem. As he was walking in the temple area, the chief priests, the scribes, and the elders approached him and said to him, ‘By what authority are you doing these things? Or who gave you this authority to do them?’” Where the NAB uses “authority” to render ἐξουσία/ἐξουσίαν, the Vulgate employs potestate/potestatem, not auctoritas. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 61 render various terms of the Hebrew and Greek originals of the biblical texts, neither Jerome nor any other Latin translator of the same texts saw fit to use the term auctoritas to render any of them.13 As for nonbiblical literature, though commonplace in Church documents since the late Middle Ages, auctoritas is virtually absent from the Latin texts of the Church’s earliest councils and entered into the Church’s lexicon only gradually, first mainly in reference to Christ or the Scriptures, later in reference also to the Church.14 13 The term’s sole appearance in the Vulgate is in 1 Kgs 21:7, where Jezebel mocks her husband Ahab for failing to take hold of Naboth’s vineyard: “A ruler over Israel of great authority (grandis auctoritatis) you are indeed!” His wife Jezebel said to him, “Get up. Eat and be cheerful. I will obtain the vineyard of Naboth the Jezreelite for you.” For a concise account of the production of the Vulgate, see Biblia Sacra Vulgata, ed. R. Weber (Stuttgart: Deutsche Bibelgesellschaft, 2007), xxxiii–xxxvii. 14 From the Latin texts of the Council of Nicaea (325), it is virtually absent in any of its forms (making only one passing appearance, with no bearing on the Church’s teaching authority): “Hoc autem omnibus aliis concessum est, nam in Meletii persona non placuit propter insitam eius insaniam et morum procacitatem atque temeritatem, quo nulla potestas auctoritatis concedatur homini praevalenti ad easdem insolentias reppedare.” “Concilium Nicaenum I,” a. 325, Conciliorum Oecumenicorum Decreta, curantibus J. Alberigo, J. A. Dossetti, P. P. Joannou, C. Leonardi, P. Prodi, consultante H. Jedin (1973), 5–18 (18). About one generation later (345–48), at the western end of the Mediterranean, in the decrees of a council at Carthage, it appeared once in connection with the prohibition of re-baptism (against the Donatists): “Discussus est titulus necessarius rebaptizationis in quo plus schismatis rabies delitescebat et adhibita moderatione legis uigor et auctoritas custodita est,” Concilia Africae 345–525, Concilium Carthaginense a. 345–348 (ed. Munier, 1974, CCSL 149, 4). The term appears nowhere in the Latin texts of the First Council of Constantinople (381), Conciliorum Oecumenicorum Decreta, 24–35. In the Latin version of the decrees of the Council of Ephesus (431) the term appears four times, once in reference to the traditions of the Holy Fathers, the other three in connection with Christ: “Haec sunt sanctorum patrum traditiones, haec divinarum scripturarum praecepta; sic aliquis et quae sunt misericordiae divinae et quae sunt auctoritatis, deifice loquitur; haec meditare, in his esto, ut tuus profectus manifestus sit omnibus, Paulus ad omnes dicit.” Ibid., 49. “Unitum ergo carni Verbum Dei secundum subsistentiam confitentes, unum adoramus Filium et dominum Iesum Christum, non seorsum ponentes et determinantes hominem et Deum velut invicem sibi dignitatis et auctoritatis unitate coniunctos (hoc enim novitas vocis est et aliud nihil) nec item Christum specialiter nominantes Deum Verbum quod ex Deo est, nec alterum similiter Christum specialiter qui de muliere natus est, sed unum solummodo Christum Dei Patris Verbum cum propria carne cognoscimus” 51; “Unus igitur est Christus Filius et dominus, non velut coniunctionem quamlibet, ut in unitate dignitatis et auctoritatis, hominis habentis ad Deum; non enim potest unire naturas sola dignitatis aequalitas” 52; “Si quis in uno Christo dividit substantias post unitionem, 62 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. For the provenance of the notion in the West, we must look elsewhere. Political philosophers of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries—notably Theodore Mommsen,15 Max Weber,16 Carl Schmitt,17 Hannah Arendt,18 and more recently Giorgio Agamben19—have noticed that the concept is specifically Roman, and that in antiquity it had no precise counterpart in Greek, as it has none in modern Western languages. This is not to say that it is untranslatable, but that translating it in any given context requires choosing from among several possibilities. No one sola eas societate coniungens ea quae secundum dignitatem est vel etiam auctoritatem aut potestatem, et non magis conventu ad unitatem naturalem, a(nathema) s(it)” 59. In the decrees of Chalcedon (451), the term makes three appearances, once in reference to the Gospels (evangelicas auctoritates) and the other two times in reference to the bishops: “Sed in hanc insipientiam cadunt qui cum ad cognoscendam veritatem aliquo inpediuntur obscuro, non ad propheticas voces, non ad apostolicas litteras nec ad evangelicas auctoritates, sed ad semet ipsos recurrunt et ideo magistri erroris existunt, quia veritatis discipuli non fuerunt” ibid., 77; “De quo si fideliter atque utiliter dolet et quam recte mota sit episcopalis auctoritas, vel sero cognoscit vel si ad satisfactionis plenitudinem omnia quae ab eo male sunt sensa, viva voce et praesenti subscriptione damnaverit, non erit reprehensibilis erga correctum quantacumque miseratio, quia dominus noster verus et bonus pastor qui animam suam posuit pro ovibus suis et qui venit animas hominum salvare, non perdere, imitatores nos suae vult esse pietatis, ut peccantes quidem iustitia coerceat, conversos autem misericordia non repellat” 82; “Confitentibus autem decrevimus, ut habeat auctoritatem eiusdem loci episcopus misericordiam humanitatem que largiri” 94. In the decrees of the Fourth Lateran Council (1215), the term appears 13 times, in reference to the Old and New Testaments, the Church, the apostolic see, bishops and prelates generally, and the Council and its decrees ibid., 230–71; cf. 234 (2x), 237, 238, 241, 249, 250, 253, 254, 262, 263, 270 (2x). In the decrees of the Council of Trent, auctoritas appears forty times, usually in conjunction with the term “apostolic,” and then often in connection with the Holy See’s apostolic authority (e.g., “interveniente etiam auctoritate sanctae sedis apostolicae, apostolica auctoritate confirmatis, auctoritate apostolica”). In the documents of Vatican II, the term is ubiquitous (it appears twenty-one times in Lumen Gentium, thirty-one times in Gaudium et Spes, etc.). 15 T. Mommsen, Römisches Staatsrecht, 3 vols. (1871; reprint, Graz: Akademischer Druck, 1969). 16 Max Weber, Politics as a Vocation (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1965). 17 Carl Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, translated as Political Theology by George Schwab (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985). 18 Hannah Arendt, “What Is Authority,” in Between Past and Future: Six Exercises in Political Thought (New York: Meridian Books, 1961). 19 Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005). The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 63 English term can render it accurately in every situation.20 Considerable attention has been given to the influence and posterity of its titular form, as it was conferred upon the Roman emperor Caesar Augustus. In addition to the title princeps (first citizen of Rome), he held that of auctoritas principis to designate his supreme moral authority, and this in addition to the powers designated by the terms potestas and imperium. Agamben has noticed that in its first instance the title belonged to the fathers (patres) of the Senate,21 and has drawn attention to its distinctness from juridical or political power, potestas, and military power, imperium. In times of crisis, such as the fall of the Republic,22 civil war, or the threat of invasion, the normal functioning of juridical institutions is suspended and replaced by a state of exception. Whereas potestas belongs to a function circumscribed by law, auctoritas attaches to a person and is not bound by law. Further, whereas the public office conferring potestas is of limited duration (in the Roman republic normally one year), auctoritas is enduring. As Richard Heinze has put it: Every magistracy is a pre-established form, which the individual enters into and which constitutes the source of his power; auctoritas, on the other hand, springs from the person, as something that is constituted through him, lives only in him, and disappears with him.23 In short, whereas potestas is legally conferred by an office, auctoritas is embodied by a person, and makes its presence felt precisely when the normal functioning of offices and legal institutions is suspended, as in times of crisis. In its various forms the term auctoritas is commonplace in the literature of the Medieval Latin West. On the face of it, one could suppose that these writers, living in a pre-Reformation, precritical, medi20 Ibid., 75. Ibid., 77. 22 Historians have variously proposed the appointment of Julius Caesar as perpetual dictator in 44 BC, the defeat of Mark Antony at the Battle of Actium in 31 BC, and the Roman Senate’s grant of extraordinary powers to Octavian under the first settlement and his adopting the title Augustus in 27 BC, as the defining events ending the Republic. 23 Richard Heinze, Auctoritas, 1925, 356, cited by Agamben, State of Exception, 82. 21 64 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. eval Catholic world were more fond of authority than we are, living as we do in a society that has made it a dictum to “question authority.” But medieval writers themselves leave little doubt that the auctoritas of their vocabulary is quite different from the “authority” of ours. Thomas Aquinas’s reflections on the conditions for waging just war on tyrants, both those who have usurped power and those who have become tyrannical after acquiring it legitimately, serve as a warning against taking for granted that he would have disagreed with the modern concern to “question authority.”24 As appropriated by early Christian writers, auctoritas soon had theological senses and was used particularly to designate God’s authorship of creation. So for example, Tertullian asks Marcion rhetorically, “Tell me, Marcion, does your god base the authority (auctoritatem) of his law on the work of the Creator?”25 Christian writers eventually extended the scope of the term to include prophets and other biblical authors, normally in connection with revelation. So, for example, Gregory the Great describes the prophet Ezekiel: Since those to whom the prophet was sent were of such depravity and obstinacy, who would not see that the person of the prophet should be despised by men so perverse. But behold authority (auctoritas) is attributed to the person, as it continues: And you will say to them, Thus says the Lord (Ezek 2:4).26 Gregory is concerned to point out that Ezekiel’s auctoritas derives from his status as a prophet. Shortly afterward in the same homily, he notes that anyone who lives in God has dwelling within the auctoritas of the divine Word: 24 See Thomas Aquinas, ST II-II, q. 40 (quaestio “De bello”), and De regimine principum. “Dic mihi, Marcion, de opere creatoris deus tuus legi suae adstruit auctoritatem?” Tertullian, Adversus Marcionem, V, ed. E. Kroymann (Turnhout: Brepols, 1954), CCSL 1, 718. 26 “Cum uero tantae prauitatis tantae que obstinationis sint hi ad quos propheta mittitur, quis iam non uideat, quia persona prophetae a tam peruersis hominibus despici ualeat? Sed ecce auctoritas personae tribuitur, cum subditur: Et dices ad eos: Haec dicit Dominus Deus.” Gregory the Great, Homilae in Hiezechihelem I, hom. 9, ed. M. Adriaen (Turnhout: Brepols, 1971), CCSL 142, 127. 25 The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 65 And because all of us who live in God are instruments (organa) of truth, often it speaks through others to me, and often through me to others, so the authority (auctoritas) of the good Word should be in us, so that a superior may freely speak rightly, and a subordinate may humbly not refuse to bring forth good things.27 So understood, auctoritas is divine in origin, but participatible by the recipients of divine revelation, by believers. But it was Augustine more than anyone else who provided a theoretical framework to explain the functioning of auctoritas in matters of faith. As he put it, “What we understand we owe to reason, what we believe to authority; what we opine, to error.”28 Medieval biblical commentators made this a stock expression. Augustine was less interested in the status auctoritas confers on an auctor than he was in its epistemological function, its bearing on what we know and how we know it. In his perspective, it belongs to the sphere beyond reason. Whereas the Romans viewed auctoritas as most clearly manifest in those states of exception wherein the functioning of legal institutions was suspended, Augustine understood it to allow us to know and think where reason is suspended, in those matters accessible by faith alone. Medieval Studies of Auctoritas and Authorship Alistair Minnis has noticed that medieval literature is a world governed by a continuous, if not homogeneous, theory of authorship, which he defines as a literary theory based on the two distinct but inextricably linked concepts of auctor and auctoritas.29 During the second half of 27 “Et quia omnes qui in Deo uiuimus organa ueritatis sumus, ut saepe per alium mihi, saepe uero aliis loquatur per me, sic nobis boni Verbi inesse auctoritas debet, ut et is qui praeest dicat recta libere, et is qui subest inferre bona humiliter non recuset” (CCSL 142, 129). 28 “Quod intellegimus igitur, debemus rationi, quod credimus, auctoritati, quod opinamur, errori. Sed intellegens omnis etiam credit, credit omnis et qui opinatur; non omnis qui credit intellegit; nullus qui opinatur intellegit.” Augustine of Hippo, De utilitate credendi 11, ed. J. Zycha (1891), CSEL 25.1, 32. 29 A. J. Minnis has observed that the concept of auctor was inseparable from that of auctoritas: “The writings of an auctor contained, or possessed, auctoritas in the abstract sense of the term, with its strong connotations of veracity and sagacity.” Medieval Theory of Authorship (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1988), 10. 66 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. the thirteenth century, biblical commentators paid unprecedented attention to the problem of explaining the relation between divine and human authorial roles. The interest they took in the human authors of the books on which they commented was keen—the prologues to their commentaries are preoccupied with them. These prologues also contain the commentators’ most explicit and elaborate methodological considerations, as well as the introduction of the various analytical techniques to be applied elsewhere in the commentaries.30 Originating in the study of profane literature, these introductions to the author and his work, or accessus, became a standard feature of biblical commentaries in the latter part of the eleventh century. Eventually they were simplified according to an established pattern including the examination of the author’s intention and mode of exposition, as well as the biblical book’s title (intentio, modus agendi, and titulus). Subsequently, twelfth-century masters, notably Peter the Chanter and Stephen Langton, structured the accessus around an introductory biblical verse, generally taken from some book other than the one at hand. With the development of university exegesis during the first half of the thirteenth century, commentators adopted another framework for the prologue, explaining a given book in terms of Aristotle’s four causes. Discussion of the author’s intention, or of the book’s purpose, was considered under the heading of its final cause, its mode of exposition under that of its formal cause, and its title or subject matter under that of its material cause. Not surprisingly, the matter of auctoritas normally appears in connection with the efficient cause, the auctores, as authorship was understood to be twofold—the primary efficient cause was the divine author, and the secondary efficient cause the human one. In the prologue to his commentary on Isaiah, Albert the Great connects the prophet’s auctoritas directly to divine revelation: For such a prophecy Isaiah is therefore to be commended. And 30 See my The Biblical Interpretation of William of Alton (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), 26–40; Gilbert Dahan, “Les Prologues des Commentaires Bibliques,” in Les prologues médiévaux (Turnhout: Brepols, 2000), 427–28; A. Sulavik, “Principia and Introitus in Thirteenth Century Christian Biblical Exegesis with Related Texts,” La Bibbia del XIII Secolo, Millennio Medievale (Firenze: Galuzzo, 2004), 269–87. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 67 indeed the revelation of this dignity is understood, because not by a fallible human spirit, nor by a mendacious demonic spirit, nor by vain mathematical conjectures has it been accepted, but inspired by the Spirit of truth itself, 2 Pt 1:21: “Not by human will has prophecy ever come, but the holy men of God spoke inspired by the Holy Spirit.” And so appears the authority of revelation (auctoritas revelationis), and as Augustine says in his Literal Commentary on Genesis, “The authority of Scripture is greater than all perceptiveness of human wits” (De Gen. ad lit. I, 37).31 Albert continues: So therefore in the aforesaid theme, the author (auctor) is commended by his name, by the congruity of his name and the (book’s) matter, by the authority (auctoritatis) of revelation, by the quality of his vision, by the piety of his intention, by the usefulness of his work, and by the fidelity and firmness of these. 32 But the matter could also come up in connection with a given book’s formal cause, that is, its mode of proceeding, or modus agendi (sometimes modus procedendi, very much like what modern scholars call its literary form), as we see in the prologue to the commentary on John’s Gospel by William of Alton, a contemporary of Thomas Aquinas. The text is worth presenting at some length: An understanding servant is acceptable to the king. These words are written in Proverbs xiv (35), in which principally the scribe 31 “A tali igitur prophetia Isaias commendatur. Et idcirco revelationis istius dignitas intelligitur, quia non spiritu humano deceptibili nec spiritu mendacii daemoniaca nec coniecturis vanis mathematicis est accepta, sed ab ipsa spiritu veritatis inspirata (2 Pt 1:21): ‘Non uoluntate humana allata est aliquando prophetia, sed spiritu sancto inspirati locuti sunt sancti dei homines.’ Sic ergo patet auctoritas revelationis et, sicut dicit Augustinus, Super Genesim ad litteram, ‘maior est huius scripturae auctoritas quam omnis humani ingenii perspicacitas’ (De Gen. ad lit., I, 37).” Albert the Great, Postilla super Isaiam., prol. (ed. Ascendorff, Opera, t. xix, 3a). 32 “Sic ergo in preinducto themate commendatur auctor a nomine, a nominis cum materia congruitate, a revelationis auctoritate, a visionis qualitate, ab intentionis pietate simul et operis utilitate et a dictorum fidelitate sive firmitate.” Ibid., 4b. 68 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. of this Gospel is commended, and consequently the Gospel itself, since the commendation of an author redounds upon his work . . . What is noted secondarily in these words is the fourfold cause of this work. The material, by the saying to the king, because this book is about Christ, who is the king of kings with respect to either of nature that is in him . . . It is objected, Ecclesiasticus 3 (22): Do not inquire about lofty things33; because in Proverbs (25, 27): The searcher of majesty will be overthrown from glory. Response: Majesty is not to be searched in a spirit of elation or curiosity or ill will, as with the heretics, but such searching is good when done in a spirit of piety for the declaration of the faith, 1 Corinthians 2 (10): The Spirit searches even the depths of God34. The formal: understanding, incomparably understanding the divine nature, to extol the human nature and the existence of both in Christ. First it is about the divine nature; afterwards it is about the human. It deals with both sublimely, indeed with certitude, not however with the certitude of demonstration, which evacuates faith, since it compels assent whether one like it or not, but with the certitude of authority (certitudine auctoritatis). Augustine: “What we believe we owe to authority . . .” Therefore this scripture proceeds by the mode of narrative, not reasoning. This certainty, though modest in other sciences, whose discoverers are men capable of lying, is greatest in this one, which the Holy Spirit inspired. Augustine, On Genesis: “The authority of this scripture is greater than the perspicacity of all human genius.”35 33 Sir 3:22: “altiora te ne scrutaveris et fortiora te ne exquisieris sed quae praecepit tibi Deus” (ed. R. Weber, Stuttgart, 2007 = W) 34 1 Cor 2:10: “Spiritus enim omnia scrutatur etiam profunda Dei” (W). 35 “Acceptus est regi minister intelligens. Hec uerba scripta sunt Prou. xv, in quibus principaliter huius euangelii scriba commendatur, et per consequens ipsum euangelium, cum auctoris commendatio redundet in opus . . . Secundario notatur in hiis uerbis quadruplex causa huius operis. Materialis, per hoc quod dicit: Regi, quia de Christo qui est rex regum agitur in hoc libro quantum ad utrumque naturam que est in eo . . . Obiicitur, Eccli. iii: Altiora te ne quesieris; quia Prouer.: Perscrutator maiestatis opprimetur a gloria. Responsio: Non est maiestas perscrutanda spiritu elationis uel spiritu curiositatis uel spiritu malignitatis ut heretici, set spiritu pietatis ad assertionem fidei bonum est, i Cor. ii: Spiritus scrutatur etiam profunda Dei. Formalis: Intelligens, intelligendo enim diuinam naturam sine comparatione, extollere humanam et utramque esse in Christo. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 69 For William, the Gospel’s formal cause, or mode of proceeding, is John’s incomparable understanding and extolling of Christ’s divine and human natures. About these natures John teaches with certitude, not of demonstration, but of authority (certitudine auctoritatis). If the framework of this scrutiny is Aristotle’s efficient cause, its broader methodological implications appear in William’s analysis of the author’s form or modus agendi. In the background here is the larger thirteenth-century consideration of the question of whether theology is a science. Alisdair Minnis has drawn attention to the stimulus this controversy provided to exegetes’ analyses of the stylistic complexities of biblical texts.36 While a complete account of this history lies beyond our purposes, we will note that Alexander of Hales (d. 1245), one of the earliest and most important thinkers to take up the question, described a variety of biblical modes of exposition and set them in marked contrast to the scientific mode. He effectively separated biblical exegesis from science by distinguishing quite sharply between human science and divine science. Whereas the former, on his view, appeals to the intellectus, or faculty of intellection, the latter appeals to the affectus, that is, the mind’s faculty of desire. And whereas the intellectus operates by division, definition and ratiocination, the affectus functions by precept, example, exhortation, revelation and oration. The Bible, as he would have it, is not a scientific work because it operates by stimulating pious affections and by treating of realities having to do with salvation: Prius agit de diuina, postea de humana, de utrumque autem agit sublimiter, ut patet certitudinaliter; non tamen certitudine demonstrationis, que fidem euacuat, cum hominem uelit nolit ad assencientum agat, set certitudine auctoritatis, Augustinus: ‘Quod credimus debemus auctoritati.’ Et ideo hec scriptura procedit per modum narrationis, non ratiocinationis. Hec autem certitudo, licet in aliis scientiis sit modica, quarum inuentores sunt homines qui mentiri possunt, in hac autem est maxima quam Spiritus sanctus inspirauit, Augustinus, Super Gen.: ‘Maior est huius scripture auctoritas quam omnis humani ingenii perspicacitas.’” William of Alton, Postilla super Iohannem, Prologus (MS Saint-Omer 260, f. 110ra–va); cf. Augustine, De Gen. ad lit., ii (ed. J. Zycha, 1894, CSEL 28.1, 39). Worth noting here is that William parts with the Latin commentatorial tradition—including Albert, Bonaventure, and Thomas—which had followed Augustine in holding that, whereas the first three Gospels were primarily concerned with Christ’s humanity, this one is mainly concerned with his divinity. 36 Minnis, Medieval Theory of Authorship, 119–33. The present discussion is largely indebted to this work. On the emergence of explicit reflections on the scientific character of theology during the thirteenth century, see the capital study of Marie-Dominique Chenu, La Théologie comme science au xiiie siècle, 3rd ed. (Paris: Vrin, 1957). 70 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. It is to be said that the mode of science that is by way of the comprehension of truth by human reason differs from the mode of science that is by the affect (affectum) of piety by divine tradition. The first mode must be definitive: divisive, collective; and this must be the mode of human sciences, because the apprehension of truth by human reason is explained by division, definitions and reasonings. The second mode must be by precepts, examples, exhortations, revelation and oration, because these modes belong to the affect of piety (affectui pietatis), and this mode is in sacred scripture.37 The following won by this view was considerable. Among others, the Dominicans Richard Fichacre and Robert Kilwardby, and the Franciscans Robert Grosseteste and William of Middleton largely adopted it, though generally substituting the term aspectus for intellectus. Despite the significant differences between their conclusions, all emphasized the primacy of the affectus.38 And yet, some of the writers who used the terminology of aspectus and affectus were capable of viewing theology as a science. Bonaventure employed this language throughout his works, but in his Breviloquium affirmed the scientific character of theology: The foregoing shows that theology, though admittedly broad and varied in matter, is nevertheless a single science. Its subject, as the One by whom all things have been made, is God; as the One through whom all things receive their being, is Christ; as that for the sake of which all things are done, is the work of restoration; 37 “Dicendum quod alius est modus scientiae, qui est secundum comprehensionem veritatis per humanam rationem; alius est modus scientiae secundum affectum pietatis per divinam traditionem. Primus modus definitivus debet esse: divisivus, et talis modus debet esse in humanis scientiis, quia apprehensio veritatis secundum humanam rationem explicatur per divisiones, definitiones et ratiocinationes. Secundus modus debet esse praeceptivus, exemplicativus, exhortativus, revelativus, orativus, quia ii modi competunt affectui pietatis; et hic modus est in sacra scriptura.” Alexander of Hales, Summa Theologica, Tractatus introductorius, q. 1, cap. iv, a. 3 (ed. Quaracchi, Opera omnia, t. iv, 1948, i, 10). This text has been presented and discussed by Chenu, La Théologie comme science, 40–41. For a discussion of its date and authenticity, see ibid., 38. 38 Minnis, Medieval Theory of Authorship, 120–27; Chenu, La Théologie comme science, 37–57. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 71 as that around which all things revolve, is the unique bond of love linking heaven and earth; as that with which the whole content of the canonical books is concerned, is the body of faith as such; as that with which the whole content of the commentaries is concerned, is the body of faith as intelligible, for according to Augustine’s work De utilitate credendi: “What we believe we owe to authority, what we understand, to reason.”39 Though less frequently, Aquinas also appealed to the affectus/aspectus distinction, and famously argued for the scientific character of theology, effectively submitting the realm of auctoritas to rational inquiry.40 William of Alton, too, made abundant use of the distinction, even if his own view of the scientific character of theology must on the presently available evidence remain a matter of speculation. Worth noting here is that the commentators of the period generally engaged in a rigorous reflection on biblical modes of exposition, substantially the same endeavor as that enjoined upon interpreters in Dei Verbum 12: The interpreter must investigate what meaning the sacred writer intended to express and actually expressed in particular circumstances by using contemporary literary forms in accordance with the situation of his own time and culture. Medieval writers described authorial modes even in their commentaries on nonbiblical writings. In his proemium to his commentary on Boethius’s De Trinitate, Thomas Aquinas follows Augustine in naming two modes of discussing the Trinity, by authorities and by rational arguments (rationes), and points out that whereas Ambrose and Hillary 39 “Ex his patet quod licet theologia sit de tot et tam variis est tamen scientia una cuius subiectum ut a quo omnia est Deus ut per quod omnia Christus ut ad quod omnia opus reparationis ut circa quod omnia unicum caritatis vinculum quo caelestia et terrestria connectuntur ut de quo omnia in libris canonicis comprehensa credibile ut credibile ut de quo omnia in libris expositorum credibile ut intelligibile secundum Augustinum, De utilitate credendi, quia ‘quod credimus debemus auctoritati quod intelligimus rationi.’” Bonaventure, Breviloquium I, 1 (Opera, Quaracchi, t. v, 20a). 40 For a few examples, see Thomas’s In I Sent., prol. a. 3, qa 2; De Ver., q. 14, ad 3; ST I, q. 1, a. 2. 72 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. proceeded by way of the former, Boethius employed the latter.41 Subsequently, he cites the aforementioned remark of Augustine to point out that Boethius’s argumentative mode of proceeding leads to the certitude of truth, whereas the same cannot be said of mere appeal to authority: Third, he treats of the formal cause when he says: “arranged according to a reasoned plan,” and he indicates the mode of treatment under three headings. First, since he proceeds by argumentation, he therefore says, “arranged according to a reasoned plan.” For a question discussed even over a long period according to probable reasons but still with doubt is, as it were, without form, not yet laying claim to the certitude of truth; and hence it is said to possess form when reasonable proof is added, through which certitude regarding the truth may be attained. In this it provides for understanding, because “what we believe, we owe to authority, but what we understand, to reason,” as Augustine says.42 On view in the excerpt above is the analogical character of auctoritas. The merely human authority Thomas has in mind here arises from probable arguments. Unlike reasonable proofs, such reasons are incapable of leading to certitude. We shall see that neither Thomas nor his contemporaries doubted that statements supported by auctoritas of another sort could indeed engender certitude. 41 “Modus autem de Trinitate tractandi duplex est, ut dicit Augustinus in I de Trinitate, scilicet per auctoritates et per rationes, quem utrumque modum Augustinus complexus est, ut ipsemet dicit. Quidam vero sanctorum patrum, ut Ambrosius et Hilarius, alterum tantum modum prosecuti sunt, scilicet per auctoritates. Boethius vero elegit prosequi per alium modum, scilicet per rationes, praesupponens hoc quod ab aliis per auctoritates fuerat prosecutum.” Thomas Aquinas, In Boethii De Trinitate proem., 9; cf. Augustine, De trin. I. 42 “Tertio (proemium) tangit causam formalem in hoc quod dicit: formatam rationibus, et tangit modum agendi quantum ad tria. Primo quantum ad hoc quod argumentando processit; unde dicit: formatam rationibus. Quaestio namque quamdiu probabilibus rationibus sub dubio exagitatur, quasi informis est, nondum ad certitudinem veritatis pertingens, et ideo formata dicitur esse, quando ad eam ratio additur, per quam certitudo de veritate habetur. Et in hoc providit intelligentiae, quia quod credimus, debemus auctoritati, quod intelligimus, rationi, ut Augustinus dicit.” Thomas Aquinas, In Boethii De Trinitate I, 5. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 73 A Few Kinds of Authoritative Sources On the rare occasions when late medieval biblical commentators refer to authoritative Christian figures collectively, they generally call them sancti, rather than patres.43 The collective reference to auctoritates is considerably broader, often including even profane writers, especially on matters of philosophy.44 Profane Writers Commonplace in medieval biblical commentaries, references to non-Christian authors are normally appeals to figures whose authority is delimited to a specific field, such as Josephus on the history of the Old Testament,45 or Aristotle on philosophy.46 Even if one may wonder about their real weight in such cases, it is clear that their qualification as auctoritates had dramatic implications for the manner in which they were cited.47 What follows is an example from William of Alton’s commentary on Ecclesiastes: Therefore it says 7,8Calumny, which is, of course, the imposi43 A case in point: “Vnde Augustinus, Ieronimus et alii sancti.” William of Alton, Super Ecl. 12, 12, mss. Basel, Univ. Bibl. B III 20, f. 112vb; Madrid, Bibl. Nac. 493, f. 165r. 44 On the meanings of sancti, magister, and auctoritas and the principle of concordia auctoritatum for the interpretation of authoritative texts in theology and law, see Marie-Dominique Chenu, Toward Understanding St. Thomas (Chicago: Regnery, 1964), 126-155 . 45 E.g., “Beth: edificavit in giro meo, id est obsessio Caldeorum uel Romanorum uallauit me ne pateret fuga; et cirvmdedit me felle, quasi dicat: in ista obsidione potatus sum aqua putrida que per fel intelligitur, Iere. ix: Cibabo populum hunc abscinthio; et labore, corporis, Caldeis resistendo et etiam Romanis, ut narrat Iosephus.” William of Alton, Super Threnos 3, 5 (ed. cit., 261); cf. Flavius Josephus, The Jewish War (trans. H. St. J. Thackeray, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997, Loeb Classical Library 203, 210, 487). 46 E.g., “Dicit ei Ihesvs: Mvlier crede michi, quia discentem oportet credere, secundum Philosophum.” William of Alton, Super Io. 4, 21, ms. Saint-Omer, Bibl. mun. 260, f. 121b; cf. Aristotle, De sophisticis elenchis ii (165a37; trans. Boethius, Aristoteles Latinus, vi.1, ed. B. Dod, Bruxelles-Leiden, 1975, 7; rev. William of Moerbeke, Aristoteles Latinus, vi.3, ed. cit., 78). 47 Ceslas Spicq has observed that it became common in the schools of the twelfth century for profane authors to be considered auctoritates, albeit inferior ones; Esquisse d’une histoire de l’exégèse latine au Moyen Âge (Paris: Vrin, 1944), 77. 74 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. tion of a false accusation, disturbs the wise, specifically, the reformed. To the contrary, Seneca says: “No disturbance falls upon the wise.” And Proverbs 12 (21) says: Whatsoever shall befall the just man shall not make him sad. Response: These authorities (auctoritates) speak of the perfect wise man, whereas this passage speaks of the imperfect one.48 Even if William provides no definition of auctoritas, his mention of it here is telling. A problem has been created by Seneca’s remark that the wise man cannot be perturbed, an assertion apparently at odds with the biblical text. Though a pagan, Seneca is an auctoritas on the matter at hand, wisdom, with the consequence that his sayings on the matter must be interpreted according to the principle of concordia auctoritatum. Put simply, his remarks must be in basic agreement with those of all other authorities on the same matter. In university interpretation, questions of this sort were normally approached with the aid of the tools of dialectics, and this for the sake of grasping the various authors’ intentions. The previous solution rests upon a distinction between two different senses of sapientem—whereas Seneca was talking about the perfect wise man, Solomon had in mind the imperfect one. Sancti It has been said that when referring to authorities, medieval theologians submitted them to a “reverential exposition” (expositio reverentialis), leading them around by a “wax nose.”49 Examination of their methods 48 “Dicit ergo Calvmpnia, que scilicet est falsi criminis impositio, contvrbat sapientem, scilicet correctum. Contra, Seneca: ‘Perturbatio non cadit in sapientem,’ Prouer. xii: Non contristabit iustum quicquid ei acciderit (Pr 12, 21). Responsio: Ille auctoritates loquuntur de sapiente perfecto. Hic autem loquitur de imperfecto.” William of Alton, Super Ecl. 7, 8 (MSS Basel, Univ. Bibl. B III 20, f. 104va; Madrid, Bibl. Nac. 493, f. 150r). Cf. Bonaventure, In Ecl. 7, 8; Seneca, Ad Lucilium xi, 85. 49 On the exegetical principle of exponere reverenter, with particular reference to Thomas Aquinas, see Chenu, Toward, 144-149. For a lucid criticism of his account, see Giles Berceville, “L’autorité des Pères selon Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques 91 (2007): 129–43, esp. 138–41. In connection with an authority’s “wax nose,” Chenu refers to Alan of Lille, “Auctoritas cereum habet nasum, id est, diversum potest deflecti sensum,” De fide catholica, i, 30 (PL 210, 333). See also Joseph de Ghellinck, Le mouvement théologique du xiie siècle, 2nd ed. (Brug- The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 75 for citing authoritative texts tells a different story. It was not typical of them to get around discrepancies between authorities by veiling them in anonymity.50 Nor did they presume to substitute their own words for those of a given author in attempting to express what the author “wished to say.” If the reverential exposition is understood as a method by which the meanings of authoritative sources are subordinated to the systematic requirements of homogenous thought constructions, then we may say that these commentators avoided the practice. More typical is William of Alton’s exposition of Jesus’s encounter with Nichodemus, where we find him interested in the term spiritus. According to Chrysostom, Jesus’s statement “The wind blows where it wills” (Spiritus ubi uult spirat in the Vulgate of Jn 3:8) refers to the motion of the wind directly and to God’s action metaphorically. For Augustine, it is a direct reference to the action of the Holy Spirit. The disagreement is lost on none of William’s contemporaries. Hugh of St. Cher,51 Albert the Great,52 and Thomas Aquinas53 mention both views and present them as alternatives. Hugh and Thomas discreetly refrain from connecting the latter interpretation with Augustine. Bonaventure explicitly opposes the two54 and William follows suit, saying without hesitation that Augustine contradicts Chrysostom: The wind (spiritus) blows (spirat) where it wills and 3,8 es: Éditions De Tempel, 1948), 233–35; Jacques-Guy Bougerol, Introduction à l’étude de Saint Bonaventure (Tournai: Desclée, 1961), 58–59. In his consideration of a few of the vexed questions concerning Thomas Aquinas’s interpretation of Aristotle, Jean-Pierre Torrell proposes that Thomas submitted the philosopher to an expositio reverentialis, which he explains as follows: “A ce point précis Thomas se sent autorisé à se substituer à lui pour le prolonger et lui faire dire des choses à quoi il n’avait même pu penser. La reconstitution historiquement exacte de la pensée d’Aristote ne l’intéresse pas pour elle-même.” Initiation à saint Thomas d’Aquin (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 2002), 348–49. Without passing judgment on the accuracy of this remark, I note that nothing of the sort can be said of William’s treatment of authoritative texts. 50 For an overview of the usage of the Fathers in medieval exegesis, see Gilbert Dahan, “Les Pères dans l’exégèse médiévale,” Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques 91 (2007): 109–26. 51 Hugh of St. Cher, Postille, in Io. 3:8 (ed. Venetiis, t. vi, 296va). 52 Albert the Great, In Io. 3:8 (ed. Borgnet, t. xxiv, 122a–b). 53 Thomas Aquinas, In Io. 3:8 (ed. Parma, t. x, 346a–b). 54 Bonaventure, In Io. com. 3:8 (Opera, t. vi, 281b). Timothy Bellamah, O.P. 76 you hear its voice. Chrysostom relates this to the wind, which is said to “blow where it wills because its gusts are naturally unhindered. Its sound is called its voice (vox).” Nevertheless, Augustine contradicts this exposition, saying “The wind (spiritus) blows (spirat) where it wills because it has in its power the heart of anyone it illuminates”.55 When he deems it necessary, William shows no hesitation in setting aside the position of an auctoritas. In his comments on Jesus’s encounter with the Samaritan woman at the well (Jn 4:20), he mentions Chrysostom’s contention that the mountain to which she referred—“Our fathers adored on this mountain”—was the same as the one on which Abraham was to sacrifice Isaac. Here, too, Hugh of St. Cher,56 Albert the Great,57 and Aquinas58 also mention the interpretation. Presenting it as one of several alternatives, they leave it unchallenged. Bonaventure leaves it unmentioned. William calls it false, despite the support of no less an auctoritas than Chrysostom: Our fathers, namely, Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, worshipped on this mountain. According to some, with whom Chrysostom would appear to agree, the woman pointed to the mountain on which Abraham intended to sacrifice his son. But this is false, because that was Mount Moria, as Genesis 22 (2) makes clear. 59 4,20 55 “Spiritus ubi uult spirat, Crisostomus exponit de uento qui dicitur spirare ubi uult, quia habet a natura alationem non prohibitam; uox eius dicitur sonus. Augustinus tamen huic expositioni contradicit: Spiritus ubi uult spirat, quia habet in potestate cuius cor illustret.” William of Alton, Super Io. 3, 8 (MS Saint-Omer, Bibl. mun. 260, f. 117va). Cf. Chrysostom, In Io. hom. xxvi (PG 59, 155); Augustine, In Io. evang. tract. xii (ed. R. Willems, 1954, Turnhout: Brepols, CCSL 36, 124). 56 Hugh of St. Cher, Postille, in Io. 4, 20 (ed. Venetiis, t. vi, 306va). 57 Albert the Great, In Io. 4, 20 (ed. Borgnet, t. xxiv, 168b). 58 Thomas Aquinas, In Io. 4, 35 (ed. Parma, t. x, 366a). 59 “Patres nostri, scilicet Habraham, Ysaac et Iacob, in monte hoc adora, secundum aliquos, quibus uidetur consentire Crisostomus, mulier ostendit montem in quo Habraham uoluit immolare filium. Set hoc falsum est, quia iste fuit mons Moria, ut patet Gen. xxii (Gn 22:14).” William of Alton, Super Io. 4, 20 (MS Saint Omer 260, f. 121rb); cf. Chrysostom, In Io. hom. xxxii (PG 59, 186). The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 77 Chrysostom’s authority affords him no pious exposition. To the contrary, he is flatly contradicted. Obviously, there can be no question here, either for William or any of his contemporaries, of auctoritas understood as a law in itself that had to be accepted.60 All the same, authoritative texts constituted a body of knowledge the recourse to which was integral to thirteenth-century pedagogy. It remains for us, then, to further consider their methods for citing them. Medieval commentators were not unprincipled in this respect. When commenting on John the Evangelist’s remark (Jn 11:2) that Lazarus’s sister Mary was the one who anointed Jesus’s feet (Jn 12:3), William of Alton lays down a clear rule and demonstrates its application. In question here is whether this Mary is to be identified with the unnamed woman who wiped Jesus’s head with perfume in Matthew’s Gospel (26:7), and further, with the unnamed sinful woman who washed Jesus’s feet with her tears, dried them with her hair, and then anointed them with oil in Luke’s Gospel (7:37–38).61 William presents the views of four authorities, no two of whom agree. Then he sorts through all of this by appealing to still another authority, the Church: It was Mary who anointed the Lord with ointment and wiped his feet with her hair, below chapter 12 (3) and Matthew 26 (7), whose brother Lazarus was sick. It is asked 11,2 60 Such is the understanding of auctoritas, which Chenu contrasts with the sayings of masters (dicta magistrali), which could be set aside without scruple. Toward, 136. 61 The conflation of the three figures stands as another example of liturgical influence upon biblical exegesis. Before William’s time and during it, Mary Magdalene was identified with the “sinner” of Lk 7:36–50 and with the sister of Martha and Lazarus of Lk 10:38–42 and Jn 11 in preaching and the liturgy of her feast day. See Nicole Bériou, “La Madeleine dans les sermons parisiens du xiiie siècle,” in La Madeleine (viiie au xiiie siècle) (Rome: École française de Rome [1992], 269–84. Translated as Modern Questions about Medieval Sermons: Essays on Marriage, Death, History and Sanctity, ed. N. Bériou and D. d’Avray (Spoleto: Centro italiano di Studi sull ’Alto medioevo, 1994), 323–99. There is an abundant literature on the development of medieval devotion to Mary Magdalene. In addition to the other collected essays in La Madeleine, see Victor Saxer, Le culte de Marie Madeleine en occident des origines à la fin du moyen-âge, 2 vols., Cahiers d’archéologie et d’histoire, 3 (Paris: Librairie Clavreuil, 1959; Katherine Jansen, The Making of the Magdalene: Preaching and Popular Devotion in the Later Middle Ages (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000). For a brief overview with extensive bibliography, see P.-M. Guillaume, “Marie-Madeleine,” Dictionnaire de spiritualité 10 (Paris: Beauchesne,1980): 559–75. 78 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. whether this would be she who figures in Matthew 26 (7) and Luke 7 (37). Chrysostom, “First it is necessary to say that this was neither the prostitute of Matthew 26 nor the one of Luke 7. They were full of wickedness, but this one is honorable and devoted.” Therefore, according to him, there were three women. Commenting on Matthew, Jerome says, “Let no one think them to be the same who poured oil on his head and on his feet. The former washed with her tears and wiped with her tresses and is manifestly called a prostitute. Of the latter, nothing of the sort has been written. And so, according to Jerome, there were two women. Also, the one who appears in Luke 7 is called Magdalene, from the village of Magdalo. This one is from Bethany. To the contrary, the Glossa: “This sinner anointed . . .” etc., and nearly the same is said in the Glossa on Matthew 26 and the Glossa on Luke 7, “Mary the sister” etc. Augustine seems to hesitate, saying “Behold, the sister of Lazarus (if, indeed, it was she who anointed the Lord’s feet with ointment, and wiped with her hair what she had washed with her tears).” Response: It is to be said that the saints are quite capable of disagreeing on matters pertaining to fact, but not on those pertaining to faith. Nevertheless, the Church holds that they were the same, and that what Jerome and Chrysostom say to the effect that they are not the same is to be understood with respect to the identity of status, because she was changed from one status to another.62 62 “Maria avtem erat qve vnxit Dominvm vngvent exter pedes eivs cap , infra xii (12, 3) et Mt. xxvi, cvivs frater Lazarvs infirmabatvr. Queritur utrum ista sit illa de qua Mt. xxvi (26, 7) et Luc. vii (7, 37). Crisostomus, ‘Primum quidem illud necessarium est dicere quoniam non hec fuit meretrix que in Mt. xxvi, neque in Luc. vii. Ille enim plene mali Hec studiosa et honesta.’ Ergo secundum istum fuerunt tres. Ieronimus supra Mt. dicit: ‘Nemo putes easdem esse que super capud effundit unguentum et que super pedes. Illa enim et lacrimis lauit et crine tersit et manifeste meretrix appellatur. De hac autem nichil tale scriptum est.’ Et ita secundum Ieronimum sunt due. Item, ista de qua Luc. vii dicitur Magdalena a Magdala castro. Hec de Bethania. Contra, Glossa: ‘Hec peccatrix iunxit’ etc. Et fere idem, Mt. xxvi in Glossa et in Glossa super Luc. vii: Maria soror etc. Augustinus uidetur dubitare dicens: ‘Ecce ipsa soror Lazari, si tamen ipsa est que pedes Domini et tersit capillis.’ Responsio, Dicendum quod sancti in talibus que pertinent ad factum bene possunt dissentire, set in hiis que pertinent ad fidem non. Ecclesia tamen tenet quod eadem fuit et The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 79 In a stroke, William gainsays Chrysostom and Jerome, and settles a question left open by no less an authority than Augustine.63 Hardly reckless, he has limited their authority according to a principle: the inerrancy of the sancti encompasses matters of faith, not questions of fact. Over and against them, he invokes the authority of the Church (Ecclesia tamen tenet). The interpretation he calls the Church’s appears in the Glossa ordinaria, the main source of which, in the event, is Bede.64 To be sure, Bonaventure, Albert the Great, and Thomas Aquinas arrive at the same conclusion, though with greater discretion.65 Thomas leaves the impression of preferring Augustine’s interpretation, though he refrains from resolving the matter explicitly and provides no general rule here for interpreting the sancti.66 In none of the above cases do we find any of these quod dicunt Ieronimus et Crisostomus non esse illam, intelligendum est quantum ad ydemptitatem status, quia mutata fuit in alterum statum.” William of Alton, Super Io. 11, 2 (MS Saint-Omer, Bibl. mun. 260, f. 143ra). 63 First he quotes Chrysostom as asserting that each of the three narratives concerns a different event and a different woman. Next, he cites Jerome to the effect that the events described by John and Luke are the same, yet different from the one described by Matthew. Then he mentions the further complication that the woman mentioned by Luke is commonly said to be (dicitur) Mary Magdalene. Despite the difficulty this presents for identifying her with the Mary whom John says is from Bethany, William finds three glosses from the Glossa ordinaria asserting that all three Gospel accounts concern the same woman, though not necessarily the same event. Finally, he quotes Augustine as tentatively identifying the Mary of John’s narrative with the sinful woman of Luke’s and suggesting that there were two anointings. Augustine says nothing here of Matthew’s account. 64 Homiliarum euangelii libri ii, ii, 4 (ed. D. Hurst, 1955, Turnhout: Brepols, CCSL 122, 209–10). 65 “Et hanc sententiam tota tenet occidentalis Ecclesia.” Albert the Great, In Io. 11, 2 (ed. Borgnet, t. xxiv, 436a). For once less discursive than William, Bonaventure leaves unmentioned the interpretations of Jerome and Augustine and contradicts only Chrysostom; in discussing the possibility of disagreements, he refers to the authors in question as expositores (Bonaventure, In Io. com. 2, 2; Opera, t. vi, 272a). As well as the figures William names, Albert and Thomas include Origen, Ambrose, and Gregory; yet passing over their other differences, both classify these authors according to a single criterion—whether they identify Mary of Bethany with the sinner of Luke’s Gospel. Bonaventure, Albert, and Thomas all leave unmentioned the question of identifying Mary of Bethany with the woman of Matthew’s version, and only Albert brings up the question of her identification with Mary Magdalene. As does William, Albert invokes the Church’s authority to settle the question. Cf. Beryl Smalley, The Gospels in the Schools c. 1100–c. 1280 (London: Hambledon, 1985), 210. 66 “Secundum ergo opinionem Augustini manifestum est quod peccatrix illa de qua dicitur in Luca, est Maria ista.” Thomas Aquinas, Super Io. 11, 2 (ed. Parma, t. x, 80 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. masters attempting to homogenize the thought of his predecessors. In the closing comment of the preceding excerpt we find a fine example of a reverential exposition. William brings two of the sancti around to his own determination without trying to “bend” the thought of either—immediately preceding his conclusion is an unambiguous acknowledgment that neither Jerome nor Chrysostom agrees with it. His reconciliation rests on the retrieval of an element of each one’s interpretation that can be squared with his own. He allows that they are correct in holding that the two biblical narratives concerned two different women, insofar as they concerned one woman in two different states, as a sinner and as a penitent. His attempt to synthesize the two interpretations rests on a distinction, not a forcing of the texts. Whatever one may make of his solution, it cannot be dismissed as a retouching or redressing of sources. Betraying little interest in cosmetics, it is a perfectly transparent exercise in dialectic. For one of Thomas’s most extensive theoretical reflections on ecclesial authority and the related matter of disagreement with the visible Church, we turn to his treatment of heresy in the Summa theologiae (ST) II-II. Here, he limits the authority of the saints by referring to that of the Church, unambiguously identifying the pope as its principal holder: 489a). Elsewhere, it is not at all uncommon to find Thomas invoking the Church’s opinion as authoritative. What follows are a few examples drawn only from his biblical commentaries: “Manifestum est autem ex praemissis quod apud Iob et amicos eius eadem erat opinio de Daemonibus quam nunc ecclesia catholica tenet, ut scilicet ex angelica dignitate per peccatum corruerint.” Super Iob 40, 10 (ed. Leonina, t. xxvi, 215b); “Item error quorumdam dicentium, Ioseph ex alia coniuge filios genuisse, et hos vocari fratres Domini, quod ecclesia non tenet.” Super Io. 2, 12 (ed. Parma, t. x, 336a). The following two examples concern the dating of Jesus’s baptism: “Sed ista opinio non videtur vera pro tanto, quia non concordat opinioni ecclesiae: tenet enim ecclesia, quod tria miracula sint facta in die epiphaniae, scilicet de adoratione magorum, de baptismo et de conversione aquae in vinum.” Super Mt. 4, 12 (ed. Parma, t. x, 42a–b); “Sed Ecclesia tenet contrarium. Credimus enim quod eodem die quo Dominus baptizatus est, revoluto anno, factum fuerit miraculum de vino; et postea revoluto anno, prope Pascha, Joannes fuerit decollatus; et quod ab isto Paschate circa quod Joannes fuit decollatus” Super Io. 2, 2 (ed. Parma, t. x, 336a). For the last reference I am indebted to G. Berceville, “Les commentaires évangéliques de Thomas d’Aquin et Hugues de Saint-Cher,” in Hugues de Saint-Cher, bibliste et théologien, ed. L.-J. Bataillon, Gilbert Dahan, P.-M. Gy (Turnhout: Brepols, 2004), 173–96, 189, n. 23. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 81 “By no means should we accuse of heresy those who, however false and perverse their opinion may be, defend it without obstinate fervor, and seek the truth with careful anxiety, ready to mend their opinion, when they have found the truth,” because, to wit, they do not make a choice in contradiction to the doctrine of the Church. Accordingly, certain doctors seem to have differed either in matters the holding of which in this or that way is of no consequence, so far as faith is concerned, or even in matters of faith, which were not as yet defined by the Church; although if anyone were obstinately to deny them after they had been defined by the authority of the universal Church (auctoritate universalis Ecclesiae), he would be deemed a heretic. This authority (auctoritas) resides chiefly in the Sovereign Pontiff. For we read [Decret. xxiv, qu. 1]: “Whenever a question of faith is in dispute, I think, that all our brethren and fellow bishops ought to refer the matter to none other than Peter, that is, to the authority of his name (sui nominis auctoritatem), against whose authority (auctoritatem) neither Jerome nor Augustine nor any of the holy doctors defended their opinion.”67 67 “Ad tertium dicendum quod, sicut Augustinus dicit, et habetur in decretis, XXIV, qu. III, si qui sententiam suam, quamvis falsam atque perversam, nulla pertinaci animositate defendunt, quaerunt autem cauta sollicitudine veritatem, corrigi parati cum invenerint, nequaquam sunt inter haereticos deputandi, quia scilicet non habent electionem contradicentem Ecclesiae doctrinae. Sic ergo aliqui doctores dissensisse videntur vel circa ea quorum nihil interest ad fidem utrum sic vel aliter teneatur; vel etiam in quibusdam ad fidem pertinentibus quae nondum erant per Ecclesiam determinata. Postquam autem essent auctoritate universalis Ecclesiae determinata, si quis tali ordinationi pertinaciter repugnaret, haereticus censeretur. Quae quidem auctoritas principaliter residet in summo pontifice. Dicitur enim XXIV, qu. I, quoties fidei ratio ventilatur, arbitror omnes fratres nostros et coepiscopos non nisi ad Petrum, idest sui nominis auctoritatem, referre debere. Contra cuius auctoritatem nec Hieronymus nec Augustinus nec aliquis sacrorum doctorum suam sententiam defendit. Unde dicit Hieronymus, haec est fides, Papa beatissime, quam in Catholica didicimus Ecclesia. In qua si minus perite aut parum caute forte aliquid positum est, emendari cupimus a te, qui Petri fidem et sedem tenes. Si autem haec nostra confessio apostolatus tui iudicio comprobatur, quicumque me culpare voluerit, se imperitum vel malevolum, vel etiam non Catholicum sed haereticum, comprobabit.” ST II-II, q. 11, a. 2, ad 3 (cf. Augustine, De trin. I, 10; Gratian, Decretum, P. II, causa xxiv, q. 1, can. 12). 82 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. Late medieval commentators’ reception of auctoritates was uncritical neither with respect to the authenticity of the various works travelling under a given authority’s name, nor with respect to their content. After repeatedly citing the De spiritu et anima as Augustine’s in his Scriptum on Peter Lombard’s Sentences and up to the thirteenth disputed question De veritate, Thomas Aquinas rejected its authenticity—and so its authority—in the fifteenth (De ver. q. 15, a. 1, ad 1). More telling is his blunt contradiction of Augustine’s assertion, important enough, that the humanity of Christ is more closely united to the Son than the Son to the Father: Because what is urged in the argument “to the contrary” rests upon what is false—namely, that the union of the Incarnation is greater than the unity of the divine persons in essence—it must be said to the authority of Augustine (dicendum est ad auctoritatem Augustini) that the human nature is not more in the Son of God than the Son of God in the Father, but much less. But the man in some respects is more in the Son than the Son in the Father, namely, inasmuch as the same supposit is signified when I say “man,” meaning Christ, and when I say “Son of God”; whereas it is not the same supposit of Father and Son.68 Thomas follows his reproof with an attempt to save something of Augustine’s remark, noting that there is, in fact, a greater verbal unity between the humanity of Christ and the Son than between the Son and the Father, insofar as the terms “man” and “Son of God” refer to the same supposit, whereas the same cannot be said of the terms “Father” and “Son.” However reverent, Thomas’s show of dialectic is by no means dishonest, as it involves no attempt to misrepresent or obscure Augustine’s intention.69 68 “Quia vero id quod in contrarium obiicitur falsum supponit, scilicet quod maior sit unio incarnationis quam unitas personarum divinarum in essentia, dicendum est ad auctoritatem Augustini quod humana natura non est magis in filio Dei quam filius Dei in patre sed multo minus, sed ipse homo, quantum ad aliquid, est magis in filio quam filius in patre; inquantum scilicet idem supponitur in hoc quod dico homo, prout sumitur pro Christo, et in hoc quod dico, filius Dei; non autem idem est suppositum patris et filii.” (ST III, q. 2, a. 9, ad 4; cf. Augustine, De trin. I, 10). 69 Albert the Great put forward a similar qualification of John Damascene’s authority: The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 83 However pedantic such usage of authoritative citations may appear to the modern reader, it was considered an indication of mastery in the medieval university. Requiring arduous labor and considerable editorial ability, compilatio of the sort these exegetes engaged in was an enterprise highly regarded in its own right. Presupposing a thorough command of the biblical text and its entire commentorial tradition, it was intended to result in compositions surpassing the originals in complexity as well as organization, and this for the sake of classroom instruction of future preachers. In his exposition of John 7:15, William of Alton attributes mastery of just this sort to the greatest auctoritas of them all, Jesus Christ: And the Jews were amazed, Mt. 13: All were amazed at his teaching; Saying: How has he become learned without having studied? They knew that he knew letters because in his teaching he adduced authorities (auctoritates).70 7,15 From his knowledge of authorities, Jesus shows himself learned, but neither William nor any of his contemporaries imagined that the Lord’s auctoritas derived from learning. They understood it as nothing less than God’s own knowledge. In the prologue to his commentary on John’s Gospel, Thomas Aquinas presents John the Evangelist as the perfect contemplative, whose authority derives from his participation in God’s self-knowledge. I saw the Lord seated on a lofty and elevated throne, and all the land was filled with his majesty, and the train of his garment filled “To the authority of Damascene, it is to be said that it is not only by reason or thought that the (divine) Persons are distinguished, because this would be Sabellianism. Hence, this auctoritas is to be understood cautiously.” “Ad auctoritatem autem Damasceni dicendum, quod non sola ratione vel cogitatione personae distinguuntur: quia hoc esset Sabellianum. Unde caute intelligenda est auctoritas, scilicet, ut rationem vocet relationem personalem quae realiter persona est, et cogitationem intellectum distinguentem personas per hujusmodi relationes personales.” Albert the Great, In I Sent. d. 1, a. 14, ad 1 (ed. Borgnet, t. xxv, 33b). 70 “Et mirabantvr Ivdei, Mt. xiii: Mirabantur omnes in doctrina eius; dicentes: Qvomodo hic litteras scit, cvm non didicerit? Sciuerunt quod sciuit litteras, quia auctoritates docendo adduxit.” William of Alton, Super Io. 7, 15 (MS SaintOmer 260, f. 131vb). 84 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. the temple (Is 6:1). These are the words of a contemplative, and if taken as if put forward from the mouth of John, they pertain well enough to the declaration of this Gospel . . . However, in John’s contemplation of the Incarnate Word, a fourfold height is designated, namely, of authority (auctoritatis), hence he says: I saw the Lord; of eternity, hence he says: seated; of dignity or nobility of nature, hence he says: on a lofty throne; and of incomprehensible truth, as he says: elevated. By these four ways the ancient philosophers attained to the knowledge of God. Some attained to the knowledge of God through authority (auctoritatem), and this way is the most efficacious . . . And so, since the whole course of nature proceeds and is directed to an end in an orderly way, we must posit something higher which directs and governs them as Lord, and this is God. This authority (auctoritas) in governing is shown to be in the Word of God, when he says: Lord . . . So therefore the contemplation of John was high with respect to authority (auctoritatem), eternity, dignity, and the incomprehensibility of the Word, which he hands on to us in his Gospel.71 71 “Vidi Dominum sedentem super solium excelsum et eleuatum et plena erat domus a maiestate eius et ea que sub ipso erant replebant templum. Ys. vi (1). Verba proposita uerba sunt contemplantis, et si accipiantur quasi ex ore Iohannis euangeliste, prolata satis pertinent ad declarationem huius Euangelii . . . In hac autem contemplatione Iohannis circa Verbum incarnatum quadruplex altitudo designatur, scilicet auctoritatis, unde dicit: Dominum; eternitatis, cum dicit sedentem; dignitatis seu nobilitatis nature, cum dicit: super solium excelsum; et incomprehensibilis ueritatis, cum dicit: et eleuatum. Istis enim quatuor modis philosophi antiqui ad Dei contemplationem peruenerunt. Quidam enim per auctoritatem Dei in ipsius cognitionem deuenerunt, et hec est efficacissima uia . . . Et ideo cum totus cursus nature ordinate in finem procedat et dirigatur, de necessitate oportet nos ponere aliquid altius quod dirigat ista et sicut dominus gubernet: et hic est Deus. Et hec gubernandi auctoritas in Verbo Dei ostenditur cum dicit: Dominum . . . Sic ergo contemplatio Iohannis alta fuit et quantum ad auctoritatem et quantum ad eternitatem et quantum ad dignitatem et quantum ad incomprehensibilitatem Verbi, quam nobis in suo Euangelio tradit.” Thomas Aquinas, Lectura super Ioannem, proemium (cf. ed. Marietti, 1952, no. 1–6.) With slight modifications, the English translation is that of James Weisheipl and Fabian Larcher, Commentary on the Gospel of St. John, part 1 (Albany, NY: Magi Books, 1980). The Latin text is from a provisional recension drawn from the known manuscript witnesses to an exemplar at Paris. The Functioning of Authority in Biblical Interpretation 85 Contemplating the Word of God, the source of all authority, the Evangelist partakes of it, and thus hands it on to us by his own words. In this perspective, authority enables communication and it itself communicated, drawing its beneficiaries into the life of God. Conclusion In the opening question of the Summa theologiae, Thomas takes up the question of whether theology is argumentative, and entertains an objection to the effect that arguments must proceed either by reason or by authority. The objector has pointed out that reason is inadequate to the science’s end, God, and that arguments from authority are unfitting because they are weak and therefore incapable of leading to certitude. At the outset of a lengthy reply, Thomas defends the use of theological argumentation from authority by grounding the said authority in revelation, and by making a remarkable declaration about revelation’s recipients—they have an authority (auctoritas) that must (oportet) be believed. He goes on to say that whereas arguments proceeding from human authority (super ratione humana) are the weakest of all (infirmissimus), those proceeding from divine authority are the strongest (efficassimus), while those proceeding from the doctors of the Church are employed as probable (probabiliter). He adds that even the philosophers may be cited as auctoritates, insofar as they were able to know the truth by natural reason.72 72 “Ad secundum dicendum quod argumentari ex auctoritate est maxime proprium huius doctrinae, eo quod principia huius doctrinae per revelationem habentur, et sic oportet quod credatur auctoritati eorum quibus revelatio facta est. Nec hoc derogat dignitati huius doctrinae, nam licet locus ab auctoritate quae fundatur super ratione humana, sit infirmissimus; locus tamen ab auctoritate quae fundatur super revelatione divina, est efficacissimus. Utitur tamen sacra doctrina etiam ratione humana, non quidem ad probandum fidem, quia per hoc tolleretur meritum fidei; sed ad manifestandum aliqua alia quae traduntur in hac doctrina. Cum enim gratia non tollat naturam, sed perficiat, oportet quod naturalis ratio subserviat fidei; sicut et naturalis inclinatio voluntatis obsequitur caritati. Unde et apostolus dicit, II ad Cor. X, in captivitatem redigentes omnem intellectum in obsequium Christi. Et inde est quod etiam auctoritatibus philosophorum sacra doctrina utitur, ubi per rationem naturalem veritatem cognoscere potuerunt; sicut Paulus, actuum XVII, inducit verbum Arati, dicens, sicut et quidam poetarum vestrorum dixerunt, genus Dei sumus. Sed tamen sacra doctrina huiusmodi auctoritatibus utitur quasi extraneis argumentis, et probabilibus. Auctoritatibus autem canonicae Scripturae utitur proprie, 86 Timothy Bellamah, O.P. At work here and in the preceding excerpts is an unambiguously theological notion of ecclesial authority that emerged from a purely human, non-Christian concept. It is an idea incomparably broader and richer than the notions Childs, Fowl, Lash, or most contemporary Christians, Catholic or Protestant, seem to have in mind in their discussions of the matter. Explicitly connected to revelation, authority of this kind is divine in origin. It is also communicable to and participatible by those living in faith, the members of the Church. To be sure, neither Thomas nor any of his contemporaries doubted the universal Church to be its primary participant, whose hierarchical structure they took as given, and left unquestioned. They understood ecclesial auctoritas to mediate divine revelation, not to obscure it. Apart from the Cathars and a few other marginal groups, few Christians at the time thought otherwise. It hardly needs to be said that this has not been the case among Christians for a long time. It has been the purpose of this brief historical sketch neither to oppose the general Western tendency to “question authority,” nor to provide a concise definition of auctoritas. By these selections, however, we have endeavored to shed light on a concept crucial to understanding what the Church says about her task of authentically interpreting the Word of God, confided to her own living teaching office, “whose authority (auctoritas) is exercised in the name of Jesus Christ” N&V (Dei Verbum 10). ex necessitate argumentando. Auctoritatibus autem aliorum doctorum Ecclesiae, quasi arguendo ex propriis, sed probabiliter. Innititur enim fides nostra revelationi apostolis et prophetis factae, qui canonicos libros scripserunt, non autem revelationi, si qua fuit aliis doctoribus facta. Unde dicit Augustinus, in epistola ad Hieronymum, solis eis Scripturarum libris qui canonici appellantur, didici hunc honorem deferre, ut nullum auctorem eorum in scribendo errasse aliquid firmissime credam. Alios autem ita lego, ut, quantalibet sanctitate doctrinaque praepolleant, non ideo verum putem, quod ipsi ita senserunt vel scripserunt.” ST I, q. 1, a. 8, ad 2. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 87-123 87 The Quest for the Vera et Sincera de Jesu: Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels Anthony Giambrone, O.P. University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, IN Introduction THE TWENTY-FIFTH ANNIVERSARYof the opening of Vatican II saw René Latourelle produce a major conciliar Festschrift: Vatican II: Assessment and Perspectives. For the first volume of this project, José Caba contributed an essay treating the “Genesis and Fruits” of Dei Verbum §19.1 In Caba’s view the council’s teaching on the Gospels essentially offered “a new way of formulating the historicity problem,” no longer moored to “the knowledge and truthfulness of those who were eyewitnesses.” Instead, in the document’s “New Framework,” criteriology and redaction criticism point the way forward. Twenty-five years later, we stand in a different historiographical place, from which both our assessments and perspectives are likely changed. If there is little to dispute in Caba’s straightforward account of the succession of drafts in the article’s genesis, one may be less satisfied with his interpretation of its fruits. What promptly followed the council is not necessarily what the council envisioned. In any event, Gospel scholarship today looks considerably different than it did just twen1 José Caba, “Historicity of the Gospels (Dei Verbum 19): Genesis and Fruits of the Conciliar Text,” in Vatican II: Assessments and Perspectives, vol. 1, ed. René Latourelle (New York: Paulist, 1988), 299–320. 88 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. ty-five years ago; while resistance is growing to overstated notions of the council’s newness.2 It is opportune, therefore, now a full half century later, to evaluate again Dei Verbum’s important teaching on the Gospels’ historicity. In this essay, I will offer a revised estimate and propose that the doctrine of Dei Verbum §19 is a classic instance of conciliar ressourcement. Rather than elaborating a wholly “New Framework,” configured by Formgeschichte (and its offspring, redaction criticism) and specially calibrated to a critical quest for the historical Jesus, Vatican II recovers a fresh view of the definitive paradigm of sacred Scripture. The Church’s teaching on the Gospels is thus best understood as adumbrating a Lukan Framework, and Dei Verbum §19 represents an exegesis of the preface of Luke’s Gospel. It is no accident (though not noted by Caba) that the council frames its doctrine in article 19 with two programmatic scriptural texts: Acts 1:1–2 and Luke 1:2–4. While this appeal to inspired Scripture remains open (and even invites) professional historical inquiry, the asphaleia of the Gospels is part of the preached message itself. The study will be structured around several interlocking themes. First, I will contextualize the teaching of Dei Verbum §19 historically and hermeneutically, supplying a broad background indicating the unlikelihood of any substantially “New Framework.” I will also provide a description of two major responses to the issue of historicity. Finally, I will consider some trends in Gospel scholarship, positioning them in relation to the council doctrine. Opiniones Novae or the Renouveau? On June 26, 1961, while the preconciliar committees were already busily meeting, Jean Steinmann’s La Vie de Jésus became the last title ever placed on the Index.3 Although the Pontifical Biblical Commission (PBC) was known as a vigilant watchdog and had aggressively censured several books in the past, this solemn condemnation through the Holy 2 For a comprehensive statement of opposition to the entrenched perspective represented by the Bologna School of council scholarship and reception, see Agostino Marchetto, Il Concilio Ecumenico Vaticano II: Contrappunto per la sua storia (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2005). 3 In generali consessu, AAS 53 (1961): 507–8. See Jean Steinmann, La Vie de Jésus (Paris: Editions de Noël, 1959). Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 89 Office was the only such action ever initiated by the PBC.4 The unexplained decree came just days after a monitum had been promulgated, the circumstances of which help explain the severe decision.5 Steinmann was incidental to a larger controversy ignited the summer before, later nicknamed “The Battle of the Biblicum.” At its heart lay a suggestive exchange: a trial run, in some regards, of those perspectives we now recognize as the two great competing conciliar hermeneutics: rupture and continuity.6 Louis Alonso Schökel, a young professor 4 In 1912, the PBC forbade several commentaries from being used in seminaries, including “several works by P. Lagrange.” At different points the PBC also aggressively censured several other publications. See AAS 26 (1934): 130 and AAS 45 (1953): 432. These condemnations were more restricted in scope, however, and were not executed through the Holy Office and its Sacred Congregation of the Index. 5 See AAS 53 (1961): 507. Contrast Steinmann’s unexplained condemnation with Cardinal Merry del Val’s ample explanation of the condemnation of Vigouroux and Brassac’s Manuel biblique (AAS 15 [1923]: 616–19) and the reasoning provided for the PBC censure of Schmidtke’s Die Einwanderung Israels in Kanaan (AAS 26 [1934]: 130). A letter from Cardinal Ruffini, a member of the PBC, informed Ottaviani about the problematic nature of Steinmann’s book. See F. Michele Stabile, “Il cardinal Ruffini e il Vaticano II: Le lettere di un intransigente,” Cristianismo nella Storia 11 (1990): 115. Ruffini later published a headlining article in L’Osservatore Romano (August 24, 1961) in which he found fault with Steinmann for omitting the infancy narratives, reducing the public ministry to a minimum and treating the resurrection lightly, declaring in sum: “A rationalist Protestant could not have been more rash or radical.” 6 Benedict XVI’s famous December 22, 2005, address to the Roman Curia technically speaks of “the hermeneutic of discontinuity and rupture” and “‘the hermeneutic of reform,’ of renewal in the continuity of the one subject-Church.” For an important study of the issue, see Agostino Marchetto, Il Concilio Ecumenico Vaticano II: Per la sua corretta ermeneutica (Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2012). These two hermeneutical perspectives had long been competing for control of Catholic exegesis; as elsewhere, the Biblical Movement is here profoundly representative of the ferment that gave rise to conciliar theology. See Karim Schelkens, “From Providentissimus Deus to Dei Verbum: The Catholic Biblical Movement and the Council Reconsidered,” in La Théologie catholique entre intransigeance et renouveau: La réception des mouvements préconciliaires à Vatican II, ed. G. Routhier, P. J. Roy, and K. Schelkens (Leuven: Leuven Universiteitsbibliotheek, 2011), 49–68. The undisguised value judgment implied in Schelkens’s dichotomy of “intransigence” and “renewal” (not equally kind descriptions) indicates the basic prejudice of his study. Still, the continuous interaction of two differently oriented forces is well documented in the history of the council—even if one has trouble seeing how Schelkens’s proposal of a “hermeneutic of shifting balances” does more than rephrase and dialectically attenuate the “paradigm shift” model he critiques. If Schelkens’s reading prefers simply to chart the ebb and flow of opposing parties (like shifting seats in Congress), 90 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. at the Biblicum, had written a progressive piece for a popular magazine arguing that Pius XII had endorsed a broadminded shift in the direction of biblical studies, a cambiamento nell’esegesi.7 Antonino Romeo, a wellplaced curial official and Scripture scholar at the Lateranum, let loose in response an intemperate seventy-page rebuttal, insisting on the continuity of Pacelli’s program with the earlier culture of Catholic exegesis and ironically accusing Alonso Schökel (and others at the PIB and elsewhere) of the very opiniones novae and “new exegesis” (nova exegesis) Pope Pius condemned directly in Humani Generis (§22–24).8 As the debate rapidly escalated, drawing in additional voices, attention focused especially on historicity, and soon the last spasm of anti-modernist panic was engulfing Rome. The pope himself expressed great impatience with this “nonsense,” and an intervention quickly became inevitable.9 In this connection, the terse monitum had been engineered around the obstructions of those whom the architects called the “modernists” (though John XXIII remained confident about the Biblicum).10 The text itself, however, was open to diverse interpretations, with forward looking young exegetes like Joseph Fitzmyer insisting that the warning “should not be regarded as a condemnation of the so-called ‘new direction.’”11 The document did briefly commend the fervent study of sacred theologically, the proper hermeneutic must be derived from Newman’s notion of development. Historians of the council would thus do well to attend again to the seven notes of a “true development”: (1) preservation of type, (2) continuity of principles, (3) power of assimilation, (4) logical sequence, (5) anticipation of its future, (6) conservation of action upon its past, and (7) chronic vigor. 7 Louis Alonso Schökel, “Dove va l’esegesi cattolica?” La Civiltà Cattolica 111, no. 2645 (1960): 449–60. The title ironically evokes the famous essay of Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange on the nouvelle théologie, “La nouvelle théologie, où va-t-elle?” Angelicum 23 (1946): 126–45. Garrigou-Lagrange had warned that the new trend was a repackaged revival of modernism. 8 Antonino Romeo, “L’Enciclica Divino afflante Spiritu e le opiniones novae,” Divinitas 4 (1960): 387–456. 9 See Peter Hebblethwaite, John XXIII: Pope of the Century (New York: Continuum, 2000), 211. 10 See Karim Schelkens, Catholic Theology of Revelation on the Eve of Vatican II: A Redaction History of the Schema De fontibus revelationis (1960–62) (Leiden: Brill, 2011), 157n2. 11 Joseph Fitzmyer, “A Recent Roman Scriptural Controversy,” Theological Studies 22 (1961): 443–44. See also the contrasting views on the monitum expressed by Peter Duncker, “Biblical Criticism, Instructions of the Church and Excesses of Form Crit- Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 91 Scripture (an obvious nod to scientific methods), but expressed concern over certain circulating opinions that questioned the “genuine historical and objective truth” (germanam veritatem historicam et obiectivam) not only of the Old Testament—an issue, it noted, already decried in Humani Generis—but also of the New Testament, even doubting the words and deeds (dicta et facta) of Jesus. It is hard to mistake the commission’s concern (shared with Romeo) that the solemn corrections Pius offered in 1950 were failing to stem a mounting tide of biblical skepticism. If Steinmann’s book was made an example in this context, it neatly sidestepped the whole business with the Biblicum, Steinmann being far away in Paris. The choice likewise—and more importantly—deftly averted speculation over the use of historical-critical methods per se, for the book deployed no scientific criticism. It postured, instead, as a kind of updated Renan: a peculiarly French biographical romance, popular yet pensive—and watery at best on basic articles of the faith.12 Of course, if the legacy of the “liberal lives of Jesus” thus lived on in Steinmann’s work, the real beachhead of critical skepticism lay elsewhere—as it also had in the time of Renan’s popularized Vie de Jésus. The more aggressive curial reaction accordingly targeted certain exegetical technicians, and two established Biblicum professors (but not Alonso Schökel) were soon deposed. These suspensions, leveled against Stanislaus Lyonnet and Maximilian Zerwick, were the climax of the brief intrigue. No formal explanation was ever given—it was accomplished with silent efficiency—but the suspicion was mercilessly clear. Lyonnet had treaded into the sensitive waters of Adam and original sin; while Zerwick misstepped on Gospel historicity.13 icism,” Catholic Biblical Quarterly 25 (1963): 22–23, and Francesco Spadafora, “Un document notevole per l’esegesi cattolica,” Palestra del clero 40 (1961): 969–81. 12 Steinmann evokes Renan with the title and structure of the work and directly engages him in the conclusion: “Renan n’a pas vu que cette mort [de Jésus] était un signe . . . Cette vie est-elle absurdité ou mystère? Quel est le sens de la mort? Quel est l’ultime destin de l’homme: Dieu ou le néant? Suivant leur réponse, les homes sur terre sont à jamais divisés sous le signe de la croix.” The popular audience of the book, along with this less than robust conclusion, likely contributed to the condemnation. The final section of Sancta Mater Ecclesia strongly insists upon the need for writers to avoid “spreading makeshift solutions” that “upset the faith of many.” 13 Lucien Cerfaux (a member of the Theological Commission) noted in a letter to Cardinal Van Roey: “le P. Zerwick avait une phrase malheureuse: Il nostro scopo è di investigare, condotti dal testo sacro stesso, fin dove giunga la libertà che la tradizione 92 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. If the “modernists” were thus soundly chastened, once the conciliar winds began to blow, the imposing front of hierarchical resistance collapsed in disarray, and any clear doctrinal lesson was soon subverted. Indeed, the confusing epilogue to this whole debacle was a sudden volte-face that saw the new pontiff, Paul VI, on the counsel of Cardinal Bea, reinstating both disciplined Jesuits in the spring of 1964.14 Although this reversal has been regarded as a full vindication, such an interpretation cannot be sustained. The decision instead appears to have been a change in ecclesiastical policy—the fall from favor of a hawkish curial party—in no way implying a nihil obstat on the scholars’ deviant exegesis. Indeed, the issuance at the same time (April 1964) of Sancta Mater Ecclesia, the landmark Instruction on Historical Truth of the Gospels, a document approved by Paul VI but commissioned two years earlier by Pope John, expressly bolstered the Church’s firm commitment to historicity—albeit with nuance and considerable good will toward modern methods. This coordinated double maneuver, loosening the reins on free debate while rearticulating the Church’s perennial teaching, is critical to appreciate, for the strategy of both Roncalli and Montini, even as cardinals, was always “to speak loudly and carry a small stick,” ever confident in the supremacy of dialogue. John XXIII had, in line with this, never ordered the hit on Lyonnet and Zerwick (which, in fact, he resented); while Paul VI’s doggedly traditional stance on historicity was repeatedly proven both during and after the council.15 Regardless, the Church was not accustomed to this indulgent mode of governance; and at every level the conflicting signals were too disorienting. It is small wonder that a culture of exegetical impunity came to e gli Evangelisti si prendono con la realità storica dei fatti e dei dotti di Gesu.” See Schelkens, Theology of Revelation, 130, cf. 115, 125. Zerwick evidently undermined the historicity of Mt 16. See the gossipy account of a former Time magazine correspondent at the council, Robert Blair Kaiser, Clerical Error: A True Story (New York: Continuum, 2002), 130. 14 Roderick MacKenzie, S.J., rector of the PIB, requested a reexamination of the case during his audience with Paul VI in March 1964. The pope agreed and charged Cardinal Bea with the investigation. The personal displeasure of Paul VI with the Lateran was evident, as he scolded the institution for “vexatious polemics” on his first visit there (October 31, 1961), shortly after removing the rector, Msgr. Piolanti. See Brian Harrison, The Teaching of Pope Paul VI on Sacred Scripture (Rome: Pontificium Athenaeum Sanctae Crucis, 1997), 60–61. 15 Ibid. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 93 reign—so much that the disgraced Steinmann would soon be rehabilitated as Yves Congar’s symbol of the Renouveau.16 Such provocation should not be taken at face value, of course. The Church had not so utterly abandoned the seriousness of her past commitments. Thus, if for many the instruction on historicity quickly came to represent much more than a charitable change of tone, the document’s positive teaching cannot be read in isolation from the monitum—itself a call to attend again to Humani Generis. At root, the events of 1961 and the redress of 1964 were two distinct magisterial efforts addressing the same exegetical disruption. The pontificate of Paul VI signaled that a long era of iron-fisted discipline was at an end—not that the advance of modernist skepticism posed no further danger. Historica Veritas It was, fatefully, within this turbulent and uncertain air that the great Dogmatic Constitution Dei Verbum was drafted. Among the many sensitive points debated during the work of composition—a laborious gestation that lasted the full duration of the council—the controversy just recounted confirms the peculiarly high stakes attached to the question of historicity. While the precursor text, De fontibus revelationis, was sufficiently unpopular that a complete redrafting was ultimately undertaken,17 chapter IV of that schema, De Novo Testamento, reveals the absolute preoccupation on the eve of the council with affirming the Gospels’ historical truth.18 Despite wide concern over the adversarial tone of the draft (which cited and even sharpened the wording of the monitum), the main points and structure, and in several places even the wording of this chapter survived intact—a significant point, considering the wider fate 16 No sooner had Paul VI finally abolished the Index in 1966 than the catechetical conferences of Jean Steinmann, Une foi chretienne pour aujourd’hui (Paris: B. Grasset, 1967)—a dubious exercise in aggiornimento—were promptly posthumously published. Endorsed in a preface by Yves Congar, flush with his triumph at the council, the work was (brazenly) celebrated as the exact “renouveau” required in the Church. 17 See the nuanced reappraisal of De fontibus in Schelkens, Theology of Revelation, 265–80. 18 For the text of Schema I, Chapter IV, see Francisco Gil Hellín, Concilii Vaticani II Synopsis in Ordinem Redigens Schemata cum Relationibus necnon Patrum Orationes atque Animadversiones Constitutio Dogmatica De Divina Revelatione Dei Verbum (Rome: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1993), 186–87. 94 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. of the infamous schema. The decisive development in reformulating the material in a more positive fashion was, of course, the well-timed appearance of Sancta Mater Ecclesia. Indeed, nowhere else in the long textual history of Dei Verbum is there such a major moment of magisterial intervention. Whole sentences, in fact, are lifted from the Instruction, and this document supplies the essential substance of Dei Verbum §19. The PBC Instruction was, as just related, drafted as the Church’s cautious answer to a crisis of historical skepticism, brewing at least since Humani Generis in 1950. As an event of direct conciliar import, however, the document also served another role. More than a few churchmen at the council, bewildered by the rumored German monster, Formgeschichte, required real guidance in addressing the questions on the floor.19 To this end the PBC offered the council fathers a kind of “voter’s guide” on the latest trends in exegesis, refining a private manuscript prepared by Cardinal Bea and already circulating for this purpose. While the magisterial text can hardly be read as delivering marching orders from theological hardliners, the weighty criticisms leveled against Form Criticism made clear the Church’s profound reservations.20 Still, a tone of ready engagement is unmistakable. Overall, the PBC’s succinct critique incisively sifted out the errant principles of Bultmannian exegesis (with a prescience quite remarkable in retrospect), yet it left a door open for a legitimate (if selective) Catholic appropriation (sana elementa). Unsurprisingly, the gesture of openness became the takeaway teaching of the document. Many specialists in biblical studies, whose theological culture was not yet so divorced from the heritage of dogmatic theology, eagerly embraced the forward looking methodology, confi19 See the account offered in the foreword to Augustine Bea, The Study of the Synoptic Gospels: New Approaches and Outlooks (New York: Harper & Row, 1965), 9–12. 20 The six principles (as enumerated by Fitzmyer) are: (1) denial of a supernatural order, (2) denial of God’s intervention in the world in strict revelation, (3) denial of the existence and possibility of miracles, (4) incompatibility of faith with historical truth, (5) an almost a priori rejection of the historical nature and value of scriptural texts, and (6) diminishment of apostolic authority as witnesses to Christ and exaggeration of the creative power of the community. Through such theses the Church understood the Form Critics to be profoundly misled by the errors of rationalism (praeiudicatis opinionibus rationalismi abducti). A famous article by Pierre Benoit, “Refléxions sur la ‘formgeschichtliche Methode,” Revue Biblique (1946): 481–512, which remains one of the best treatments of Form Criticism and well worth reading, helped shaped the magisterial view—in both openness and critique. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 95 dent that the extremes of German Protestantism lacked viability in the Catholic context.21 Thus in influential quarters all attention was turned to the differentiation of Gospel strata, and the Instruction’s fundamental concern to secure historicity was quickly obscured in its reception. The move in this direction was immediate. Fitzmyer, for instance, an eager Rome watcher in those days, in an early review of the document just months before the promulgation of Dei Verbum (with an eye no doubt to helping nudge the council fathers’ thinking), managed to spin the text as strangely uninterested in historical truth—an idea one might be forgiven for gathering from the official title, De historica evangeliorum veritate. His insistence on the point is quite remarkable. The most important word in the title is not the word historica— which might have been one’s initial impression . . . in none of the positive directives does the phrase historica veritas reappear. It is evident, therefore, that the Biblical Commission is far more interested in sketching with broad lines, the character of the Gospel truth, than in just reasserting that the Gospels are historical.22 The Commission speaks [in §9] of “truth” only, and does not specify it as “historical truth.” One might wonder what it would mean if the word “historical” were understood here, after such an admission of the redactional work of the evangelists. But if one were to ask, “Well, then, if it is not a question of historical truth, of what kind is it?” the answer would have to be, “of the Gospel truth.”23 21 Fitzmyer, “Recent Roman Scriptural Controversy,” 390, expresses the untroubled conviction that the six errant philosophical and theological premises “are rejected by Catholic exegetes.” Whether the same confidence is possible today, it is evident that a notional rejection of the problematic principles is insufficient to recalibrate a method that inherently presumes such things as “scientific naturalism.” On the treatment of miracles in historical method, see Brad Gregory, “No Room for God? History, Science, Metaphysics, and the Study of Religion,” History and Theory 47 (2008): 495–519. 22 Joseph Fitzmyer, “The Biblical Commission’s Instruction on the Historical Truth of the Gospels,” Theological Studies (1964): 387. 23 Ibid., 395. 96 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. Neither the Church in her official pronouncements on the nature of inspiration, nor the theologians in their speculative treatments of it, have taught that the necessary formal effect of inspiration is historicity. The consequence of inspiration is inerrancy, i.e., immunity from formal error in what is affirmed. The opposite of inerrancy is not simply historicity, but truth. But there is poetical truth as well as historical truth, rhetorical truth as well as legal truth, mythical truth as well as the Gospel truth.24 And “Gospel truth,” Fitzmyer finally assures, “is not something which is tied up with any fundamentalistic literalness.”25 Fitzmyer raises some genuine issues, and the animating fear of fundamentalist literalism—the guild’s familiar tic doloureaux—must be addressed. It is astonishing, nonetheless, to witness this total subversion of the text’s express concern. The very notion of “historical truth” is summarily displaced by a tautology entirely of Fitzmyer’s making: “Gospel truth”—a nebulous notion he finds for various reasons more commodious. Whatever valid concerns merit attention in articulating the precise modality of Gospel inerrancy, when confronted with the massive solemnity of the opening sentence of Dei Verbum §19—unique of its kind in the whole Dogmatic Constitution—an evasion of historica veritas cannot be maintained: “Holy Mother Church has held and still holds (tenuit ac tenet) firmly and with absolute constancy (firmiter et constantissime) that the four Gospels, whose historicity (historicitatem) she unhesitatingly affirms (incunctanter affirmat), faithfully hand on (fideliter tradere) those things that Jesus the Son of God, while he lived among men, truly (reapse) did and taught for their eternal salvation, until the day on which he was taken up (Acts 1:1–2).”26 24 Ibid., 401. Ibid., 396. 26 The phrase quorum historicitatem incunctanter affirmat was added between the last draft (III) and the final text (IV) with the following remark: “Necessario inducendum est vocabulum historicum, quod a Magistro saepius adhibitum est, ut refrenetur audacia exegetica.” The proposal of 174 fathers was: “iuxta veritatem fidemque historicam tradere omnia facta et dicta quae in ipsis continentur.” The editorial note on this proposal observes that “historia” is an equivocal term, ranging in meaning from rebus supramundanis apprehended by faith, to Geschichte and Historie. Preference was thus given to the sense “realitatem factorem seu eventum modo concreto affirmare,” and 25 Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 97 The council’s language here actually strengthens the earlier wording of De fontibus, preferring tenuit ac tenet for credidit ac credit. The official relatio on this change makes clear the desire to propose a mode of truth open to rational affirmation: fide et ratione, non tantum fide.27 If this transposes the speculative vision of Vatican I’s Dei Filius into a distinctively historical and scriptural idiom and deftly decouples the council’s doctrine from the fideism of a Bultmannian-Barthian dialectical dogmatics, it naturally also faces the ultimate question posed by Fitzmyer: What precisely do I assent to when I affirm the historicity of the Gospels?28 If “fundamentalistic literalness” poses a real problem, Form Criticism was not the Church’s introduction to literary genre, nor was the Church as critically naïve as some would pretend. The Biblical Commission, in fact, had long before officially acknowledged the possibility of merely “apparent history” (species historiae) in Scripture. Indeed, even in the worst days of the Modernist crisis, Rome allowed that in well-demonstrated cases (non facile nec temere admittendo!) one might hold that “the sacred author did not intend to recount true history properly so called (veram et proprie dictam historiam), but with the outward appearance and form of history (sub specie et forma historiae), intended to propose a parable or allegory or some other meaning from the properly literal or historical meaning of the words.”29 Texts like Jonah and Job are obviously in view, but the measured principle has impressive scope. All in all, when viewed against this magisterial precursor, the most pertinent doctrinal antecedent, the simplest and most ready interpretation of Dei Verbum’s teaching (following Sancta Mater Ecclesia) is that the Gospels are not to be reckoned as “specious” but vera historia. In other words, the “properly literal or historical meaning of the words” is indeed the less ambiguous language of historicitas was employed. See Relatio Ad num. 19 c in Gil Hellín, Synopsis, 133. 27 Ibid., 132. 28 The Time correspondent reporting on this debate at the council put his finger on the issue at the end of his article: “The problem: what precisely is meant by historicity?” Time (November 5, 1965): 5. 29 ASS 38 (1905–6): 124–25. 98 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. the meaning intended by the sacred author. This seems to capture the intent of the council’s phrase, vera et sincera de Iesu.30 Fundamentum Intelligentiae Spiritalis Exegetes will alternately trivialize or balk at the jejune affirmation that the Gospels must be taken literally. The “literal or historical meaning” is more profound and complex than reigning exegetical methods comprehend, however, and it invites more patient consideration.31 Indeed, once one appreciates that the literal sense holds foundational significance for any theology of revelation and grounds the possibility of all disciplined theological argument, the importance of getting it right will be urgently clear.32 While this applies to all the Scriptures, the status of the Gospels must be singled out, even within the New Testament, “because they are the principal testimony for the life and teaching of the Incarnate Word.”33 As a question of the first principles of theology and revelation, then, it is a matter of peculiar interest in understanding the literal and historical level of the Gospels that the robust Protestant theology of revelation at the time of the council was divided into two opposing camps, with the schools of Bultmann and Cullmann fiercely split over the fundamental relation of word and deed.34 From Cullmann’s salvation history perspec30 On the contested history of this formula, see Béda Rigaux’s commentary on Chapter V of Dei Verbum in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, edited by Herbert Vorgrimler (New York: Herder and Herder, 1969), 258–60. Considered too weak by many council fathers, Paul VI intervened and proposed vera seu historica fide digna, which, despite the advocacy of Cardinal Bea, was considered open to a new (Bultmannian) ambiguity and rejected. The Theological Commission then clarified its intention with the original formula. It means to encompass and coordinate both the objective facts (vera) and the subjective activity/intentionality of the Evangelists (sincera). 31 For a fuller treatment of magisterial perspectives on the literal sense, see Mark Reasoner’s helpful contribution in this volume. 32 “Nulla confusio sequitur in sacra Scriptura: cum omnes sensus fundentur super unum, scilicet litteralem: ex quo solo potest trahi argumentum,” Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 10, ad 1. See Augustine, Epist. 93.8.24. 33 “Neminem fugit inter omnes, etiam Novi Testamenti Scripturas, Evangelia merito excellere, quippe quae praecipuum testimonium sint de Verbi Incarnati, Salvatoris nostri, vita atque doctrina” (Dei Verbum §18). 34 For the significance of these debates on the council’s doctrine, see the commentary of Joseph Ratzinger on chapters 1 and 2 of Dei Verbum in Vorgrimler, Commentary, 170–98. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 99 tive, which generally (but not in every way) had the greater affinity with and influence on the council’s ultimate doctrine, the critical danger is clear: “The Bultmannites neglect events.”35 The divine Word (dabar), however, is indivisibly “speech” and “history.”36 In harmony with this, the classic doctrine of Catholic hermeneutics sees words and deeds to be interpretatively inseparable: littera gesta docet. In this paradigm, “history” is thus at once the prima significatio, the scriptural “letter” having its own grammatico-literary ratio,37 and the locus of the mystery of our redemption: profundissima vallis historiae38—man’s deep valley into which Christ has kenotically descended.39 The historical sense is thus the rhetorical synkatabasis of the divine Word.40 In the splendid formulation of Dei Verbum, the two dimensions of this living speech of God are inextricably intertwined, mutually manifesting and confirming 35 See the essay “Foundations: The Theology of Salvation History and the Ecumenical Dialogue,” delivered during the Third Session of Vatican II, in Oscar Cullmann, Vatican II: The New Direction (New York: Harper and Row, 1968), 25. Cullmann’s active participation in the ecumenical aspects of the council both presupposed a certain theological propinquity with Catholic doctrine (“as soon as we began to use salvation history in our discussions . . . we were speaking the same language”) and made his greater influence on the council’s outcome inevitable. 36 Precisely because “the author of sacred scripture is God, in whose power it is to signify not only by words (as man can also do), but also by the things themselves (res ipsas)” (ST I, q. 1, a. 10), the coordinated disclosure of these two registers of revealed encounter—saving deeds and scriptural text—refracts the unified action of the one divine auctor. This entails a firm congruence between littera and gesta and calls forth a single act of assent in faith. 37 Hugh: “Historia est rerum gestarum narratio, quae in prima significatio litterare continetur” (PL 176, 185 A). Origen: “historia proprim rationem habet—tou echein tên historian ton idion logon” (Sel. In Ez. c. xxviii; PG 821–22 C). Aquinas: “Cum in omnibus scientiis voces significant, hoc habet proprium ista scientia, quod ipsae res significatae per voces, etiam significant aliquid. Illa ergo prima significatio, qua voces significant res, pertinent ad primum sensum, qui est sensus historicus vel litteralis” (ST I, q. 1, a. 10). 38 John Scotus, H. in Prol. Jo. (PL 123, 291 B). Theodramatically, one might speak here with Balthasar of history as the space of the “Action.” 39 The admirabile condescensio of Dei Verbum §12–13 belongs here. On this theme, see the excellent and suggestive study by John Betz, “Glory(ing) in the Humility of the Word: The Kenotic Form of Revelation in J. G. Hamann,” Letter and Spirit 6 (2010): 141–80. 40 The rhetorical background of the Christological category of synkatabasis is not often recognized; cf. Philodemus, Rhetoric 2.25. See K. Duchatelez, “La ‘condescendance’ divine et l’histoire du salut,” Nouvelle Revue Théologique 95 (1973): 594–98. 100 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. one another: gestis verbisque intrinsece inter se connexis.41 From such a perspective, the Gospels’ bivalent “literal or historical meaning” is the privileged fundamentum, the deepest stuff of divine revelation.42 Jesus is the Gospel’s literal sense. Plainly something of great moment is at stake here for the full doctrine of Dei Verbum. To this extent, Dei Verbum §19 is not a stray plank of anti-Modernism in a sea of nouvelle théologie. Rather, operating within the relational model of revelation propounded by the council,43 the fathers were burdened to preserve the ephapax character of God’s climatic action in Christ, while yet affirming a living colloquium inter Deum et hominum (Dei Verbum §25). The Gospels exercise a unique mediation; they somehow communicate Jesus of Nazareth.44 But as a medium of encounter, scriptural metaxy is stretched toward the past. Hence the happy recovery of the God who reveals from a shrunken focus on what he reveals only bears the subjective stamp of Bultmann unless some objective, referential (here historical, Christological) meaning is upheld.45 41 On this important phrase, see Francis Martin, “Some Aspects of Biblical Studies since Vatican II: The Contribution and Challenge of Dei Verbum,” in Sacred Scripture: Disclosure of the Word (Ave Maria, FL: Sapientia, 2006), 227–48. 42 Everywhere in the tradition, “history” is recognized as the fundamentum: “Historiae veritas, fundamentum intelligentiae spiritalis” (Jerome, Ep. 129, no. 6); “Omnes sensus fundentur super unum, scilicet litteralem” (ST I, q. 1, a. 10, ad. 1). See Henri De Lubac, Medieval Exegesis: The Four Senses of Scripture, vol. 2 (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2000), 47–50. 43 On the advent of this model, see René Latourelle, Theology of Revelation (New York: Alba House, 1987), 207–48. 44 The fullness of this mediation vitally depends on upholding the proper hermeneutic. Albert Schweitzer memorably captured the experience of theological loss suffered by those who resurrected the historical Jesus and “loosed the bands by which for centuries he had been riveted to the stony rocks of ecclesiastic doctrine.” They rejoiced to see him “advancing, as it seemed, to meet them. But he did not stay; he passed by our time and returned to his own. What surprised and dismayed the theology of the last forty years was that, despite all forced and arbitrary interpretations, it could not keep him in our time, but had to let him go.” The Quest of the Historical Jesus (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2000), 478. 45 A plea must be made for the balanced retention of some “propositional” aspect of revelation. For Bultmann, objective content is incompatible with the idea of genuine revelation: “It turns out in the end that Jesus as the Revealer of God reveals nothing but that he is the Revealer” (emphasis original). Rudolph Bultmann, Theology of the New Testament II (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1955), 66. See the insightful analysis of Michael Waldstein, “The Foundations of Bultmann’s Work,” Communio 14 (1987): 115–45. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 101 A genuine grasp of the scriptural letter, therefore, cannot methodologically neglect the text’s “centrifugal” perspective, but must, as a matter of theological principle, perceive some irremediable textual resonance with the extratextual events of the Incarnation.46 Just as Christ the Word made flesh is the vision of the Father (cf. John 14:9), so the enscriptured Word presents a verbal image of the Image. The Gospels preserve an adequatio ad rem: a proper analogy to Christ by the congruence, the revelatory isomorphism of littera and gesta. The Gospels’ profound identification with the mystery of the Incarnation means that Origen’s language of the literal as “body” must not be laid aside.47 Indeed, it secures a double hermeneutical point, for it invites the key Pauline distinction between soma and sarx. There is, in other words, an inadequate sense of Scripture understood kata sarka. This “literalist” mishearing of the Word is always naïve, but simple mindedness can be cloaked in the high sophistication of science—like an endocrinologist digging for the soul in the pineal gland. To the pitied and feared fundamentalist must then be added the (more subtle) “literalist” who wields his critical scalpel on the Gospel text as though he were studying a cadaver. Both types are sarkic dullards. If the “flesh” of Scripture thus supplies a public corpus that doctors of philological science may inspect with simple-minded intelligence, the deepest fundamentum remains imperceptible apart from faith. For, in the end, it is in the Gospels that the literal and spiritual senses meet.48 In this re46 On the “centrifugal” and “centripetal” dimensions of a text, see Northrup Frye, The Great Code: The Bible and Literature (New York: Harcourt, 1982), 61. “The primary or literal meaning of the Bible, then, is its centripetal or poetic meaning . . . this primary meaning, which arises simply from the interconnection of the words, is the metaphorical meaning. There are various secondary meanings, derived from the centrifugal perspective, that may take the form of concepts, predications, propositions, or a sequence of historical or biographical events, and that are always subordinate to the metaphorical meaning.” One need not doubt Frye’s intelligence (or rare insight into allegorical meaning) to suspect that he has not succeeded as neatly as he imagines in marginalizing the Bible’s historical claims. A basic problem is his decision to make the entire Bible into poetry. This vast conflation ensures his failure to distinguish between Old Testament and New Testament modes of kerygma (his term). 47 De Principiis IV, 2.4–5. See the collection of citations in Hans Urs von Balthasar, Origen: Spirit and Fire: A Thematic Anthology of His Writings (Washington, DC: Catholic University Press of America, 1984), 86–88, 100–107. 48 De Lubac propounded the patristic idea that the spiritual sense of the Old Testament is the literal sense of the New. This notion has come under criticism from the per- 102 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. gard (and in distinction to other canonical corpora), the Gospel’s prima significatio comprehends the whole incarnate Christ—body, soul, and divinity—for here we understand “body” (soma) in its Hebrew sense of living totality (basar). From this perspective, a composite body-soul (letter-spirit) dynamic also structures the Gospels’ privileged first level revelation. The work of the evangelists gives worded shape to the literal body, while the res tantum of Christ infuses their words with life-giving spirit. The Gospels are in this way a sacrament of the sacrament of God.49 “Big Picture” and Plenary Perspectives If the Reformation deeply compromised the strength of a sacramental vision, a univocal “plain sense” of Scripture was the hermeneutical fallout. The mystery of the body was reduced to the superficial species, while the juncture of letter and spirit (hence the possibility of a grounded spiritual sense) was lost to view. In the increasingly secularized exegesis that followed, the surface itself soon disintegrated—the inevitable fate of a soulless body—so that naïveté today means thinking, “Jesus said and did everything that the Gospels have him say and do.”50 The task of anchoring a revelation worthy of faith and recovering a viable literal sense is thus the trick of somehow putting Humpty Dumpty together again— finding some theological soul for the Gospels’ dissected body. Form Criticism, let it be said, supplied the real impetus toward the Gospels’ analytic breakdown.51 Already with Conzelmann, though, the need to reassemble a coherent textual whole had become clear.52 Redaktionsgeschichte, however, and the narrative criticism that it has spawned, struggle to treat literary unity in a nonfiction framework. To spective of Jewish-Christian dialogue. See Donald McKim, ed., Dictionary of Major Biblical Interpreters (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity, 2007), 685. 49 See Denis Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2010), 219–21. 50 Dale Allison, The Historical Christ and the Theological Jesus (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2009), 1. 51 This notion may be most evident in the least famous of the three cofounders of Form Criticism. K. L. Schmidt, Der Rahmen der Geschichte Jesu (Berlin: Trowitzsch, 1919). Schmidt argued that Mark is a collection of preexisting units held together imperfectly by a secondary structure. 52 See the introductory remarks of Hans Conzelmann, The Theology of St. Luke (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1961), 9–17. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 103 this extent, the history question has remained in the custody of Form Criticism—bound, that is, to “the wrong tool.”53 It is tempting to make an end run around the issue. We might ask: How does the judgment that the Gospels are vera historia apply to individual units of tradition? Might not the Church’s doctrine have only the complete genre in view—concerned at root to fend off the extreme challenge of “mythicism”?54 Vera historia, after all, cannot be pushed too far. If errors of fact (e.g., the Lukan census) are alleged, but elusively unverifiable,55 some “apparent history” is surely hosted in the Gospels. The unhistorical “letter” of the parables, for instance, is perfectly uncontroversial.56 Such an admission offers little traction, though, since the concern 53 See the landmark essay of Morna Hooker, “On Using the Wrong Tool,” Theology 75 (1972): 570–81. N. T. Wright correctly observes, “Form-criticism, despite often being treated simply as a tool for discovering about Jesus, is designed primarily to shed light on the early church.” The New Testament and the People of God (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1992), 418. 54 Both the extremity and persistence of the position that the Gospels are absolute fiction can be seen in its opposition by as strong a skeptic as Bart Ehrman, Did Jesus Exist? The Historical Argument for Jesus of Nazareth (New York: HarperCollins, 2012). Conventionally, beginning with the work of D. F. Strauss, a more euhemeristic position is taken, and the mythic texture out of which the Jesus of the Gospels has supposedly been woven is found in the Old Testament (OT). Michael Goulder’s high estimate of the creative haggadic content of the Gospels (conceived of as midrash on the Jewish lectionary) represents a contemporary variation on the theme. See, e.g., Midrash and Lection in Matthew (London: SPCK, 1974). Some (self-published) authors search for Gospel motifs well beyond the OT, e.g., D. M. Murdock, Christ in Egypt: The Jesus-Horus Connection (Seattle: Stellar House, 2008). The recent studies linking the Gospels to Homer represent a less eccentric (but still unlikely) literary thesis, e.g., Dennis MacDonald, The Homeric Epics and the Gospel of Mark (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2000). The likeness of the Gospels to Greco-Roman romance has also been promoted. See G. W. Bowersock, Fiction as History: Nero to Julian (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). The Religionsgeschichtliche School, of course, located the fictive setting in the Hellenistic cult. The PBC Instruction certainly leaves this view no space: “Nec propter cultum quo discipuli exinde Iesum ut Dominum et Filium Dei venerabantur, hic in «mythicam» personam mutatus est Eiusque doctrina deformata.” Perhaps Fitzmyer has all this in view when he poses “mythic truth” as the specific opposite of his “Gospel truth.” 55 The long-running dispute over Lk 2:1–4 typifies a common problem in assessing much of biblical history: lack of independent evidence—either contradictory or confirmatory. This, naturally, is not unique to events recorded in scripture. Reason must here be content with converging probabilities. 56 “Sub sensu litterali includitur parabolicus seu metaphoricus,” Aquinas, Super Galatians, ch. 4, lectio 7. 104 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. is obviously with the things predicated of Jesus (not the characters of his preaching). In this regard, an important narrative claim clearly separates the Synoptic presentation of Jesus’s parables (ἐλάλησεν αὐτοῖς πολλὰ ἐν παραβολαῖς) from the purely ahistorical peje Iesous found in Thomas.57 Jesus is said to have really said things. Deeds always envelop words in the Church’s Gospels. But this only makes a judgment on the literary pattern of chriae (and other like forms) inescapable. The interest to know whether such and such a deed really happened (or whether Jesus really spoke such and such a thing) leads to a variety of possibilities. The formidable approach to this question derived from Form Criticism is to address it at the atomic level. Each concrete pericope comes under its own unique historical judgment. The patient labor of John Meier must stand as the definitive monument to this method (which Caba finds most consonant with Dei Verbum §19).58 Meier’s conceit of finding consensus in an “unpapal conclave” is (for those uncharmed by postmodern agnosticism) a refreshing blast of old-fashioned Enlightenment optimism—and, in truth, not so distant from the council’s intention in choosing tenere rather than credere.59 Of course, confidence in reason nowhere implies an equal trust in criteriology. Indeed, for many today such mechanistic ratiocination is the dangerous shadow side of the “Enlightenment.”60 Moreover, when the exegetical machine starts to spit out returns of non liquet and “not historical,” not everyone is always ready to swallow the tonic of Bernanos’s Doctor Delbende: “Face up to it!” The objections here go deep, and it is no longer enough to deflect the protest as “uncritical.”61 57 For a discussion of the present tense translation of peje Iesous (“Jesus says”), see Uwe-Karsten Plisch, The Gospel of Thomas: Original Text with Commentary (Stuttgart: Deutsche Bibelgesellschaft, 2008), 24–25. “Even in dialogues, the Gospel of Thomas is not interested in the historical background of a reported issue; the focus is exclusively on the Lord’s sayings.” 58 See John Meier, A Marginal Jew: Rethinking the Historical Jesus, Anchor Bible Reference Library, 4 vols. (New York: Doubleday, 1991, 1994, 2001, 2009). 59 Meier, Marginal Jew, vol. 1, 1. 60 See the diversified challenge of Chris Keith and Anthony Le Donne, eds., Jesus and the Demise of Authenticity (New York: T&T Clark, 2012). The provocative collection of essays in this volume comes from another conference hosted (in part) by the University of Dayton in October 2012. 61 If strong nominalist strains of thought lurk here, “participatory exegesis” will have a contribution to make. See Matthew Levering, Participatory Biblical Exegesis: A The- Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 105 Plenty might be said about this manner of panning for historical gold, but one result is of special interest. In spite of negative judgments in individual cases, larger patterns of “historicity” have emerged. Meier, for instance, can accept the global assertion of Jesus’s identity as a miracle worker—though five hundred pages of minute case studies leave one less sure.62 If such dissonance undermines the atomistic effort, Dale Allison’s decision to abandon the “criteria of authenticity” for big, broad “gist” arguments has clear appeal.63 The result for Allison is a curious construal of the literal sense as a kind of agnostic allegory of historical abstractions. The accounts of the Temptation, for instance, present “a narrative about events that probably never happened . . . [but] nonetheless rightly catches Jesus in several respects.”64 Doctrinally, the “big picture” position taken here might be put like this. The Gospels reliably “hand on” (fideliter tradere) the whole living mystery of the Christ event in the same way that Tradition communicates the full substance of the faith—but little “t” traditions, or Gospel pericopes, can come or go. Somehow the discernment of what is majuscule is made, and this or that can be pared away, but the essential integrity of revelation remains unimpaired. Is one, then, merely accepting that the Gospels are reliable grosso modo: affirming a creedal skeleton or historian’s précis (Testimonium Flavianum)?65 This flexible commitment would offer insulation against a whole series of tangled textual details. A few nonnegotiable facts can ology of Biblical Interpretation (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame, 2008). Meier, Marginal Jew, vol. 2, 617–1138. For a critique of Meier’s global criterion, see Eric Eve, “Meier, Miracle, and Multiple Attestation,” Journal for the Study of the Historical Jesus 3 (2005): 23–45. 63 See Allison’s (typically) autobiographical essay, “It Don’t Come Easy: A History of Disillusionment,” in Jesus and the Demise of Authenticity, 186–99. See also his fourth and (he says he hopes) final book on Jesus, Constructing Jesus: Memory, Imagination, and History (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker, 2010): “We should trust first, if we are to trust at all, what is most likely to be trustworthy. This requires that we begin, although we need not end, by asking, ‘What are our general impressions?’” (16). The “fact-based” approach of E. P. Sanders can also be mentioned here. 64 “The story . . . preserves a series of likely truths about Jesus—that he was a miracle worker, that he refused to give self-authenticating signs, that he thought himself victorious over demonic forces, that he could quote the Bible, and that he had great faith in God.” Allison, “It Don’t Come Easy,” 191. 65 See, e.g., Gregory Tatum, “The Limits of Reliability,” Nova et Vetera 6 (2008): 523–28. 62 106 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. be historically affirmed, while the risk of rude fundamentalism is held at bay. Pope Benedict himself (albeit as a private theologian) seems to point in this minimalist direction, even while underscoring historicity in the second volume of Jesus of Nazareth: “Many details may remain open. Yet the ‘factum est’ of John’s Prologue (1:14) is a basic Christian category, and it applies not only to the Incarnation: it must also be invoked for the Last Supper, the Cross, and the Resurrection.”66 Caution is necessary, though, on the “open details” Benedict has in mind.67 His comment is made in preface to a discussion of the difficult dating of the Lord’s Last Supper; and, as the PBC Instruction makes plain, chronology does not compromise the truth at hand. It is hardly clear, in fact—as more than a few troubled exegetes have complained—that Benedict concedes the evangelists’ fabrication of any concrete “deeds and words” reported in the Gospels.68 Indeed, volume three on the Infancy Narratives now offers the strongest conceivable demonstration of the pope’s critically informed, yet calmly courageous “fundamentalism.”69 66 Joseph Ratzinger, Jesus of Nazareth. Holy Week: From the Entrance into Jerusalem to the Resurrection (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2011), 105. 67 See Benedict’s programmatic remarks on faith and historicity at the beginning of Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfiguration (New York: Doubleday, 2007), xv–xvi. 68 Maurice Casey, e.g., maintains that Benedict is trapped in circular reasoning, defending the historicity of Jn 19:35 on the presumption that John’s Gospel is “literally true from beginning to end,” being eyewitness testimony. Jesus of Nazareth: An Independent Historian’s Account of His Life and Teaching (New York: Clark, 2010), 28–29. 69 The best expression of the pope’s overall position is articulated in connection with Mt 1–2: “At the end of this lengthy chapter, the question arises: how are we to understand all this? Are we dealing with history that took place, or is it merely a theological meditation, presented under the guise of stories? In this regard, Jean Daniélou rightly observes: ‘The adoration of the Magi, unlike the story of the annunciation [to Mary], does not touch upon any essential aspect of our faith. No foundations would be shaken if it were simply an invention of Matthew’s based on a theological idea’ (Infancy Narratives, p. 95). Daniélou himself, though, comes to the conclusion that we are dealing here with historical events, whose theological significance was worked out by the Jewish Christian community and by Matthew. To put it simply, I share this view. In any case, it should be noted that over the last fifty years there has been an about-turn in thinking on this question of historicity, based not on new historical knowledge, but rather on a changed attitude to sacred Scripture and to the Christian message in general. While Gerhard Delling in the fourth volume of the Theological Dictionary of the New Testament (1942) was still convinced of the historicity of the Magi story on the basis of historical research (cf. p. 358, n. 11), since that time, even exegetes as ecclesially minded as Ernst Nellessen and Rudolf Pesch Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 107 Truly, had the religion reporter for Time any real nose for theological scandal, the Holy Father’s recalcitrant belief in fairy tales like the magi and the star would have certainly made the better headline—not a pseudo-story about the imprecision of the Julian calendar (“Pope Benedict Disputes Date of Jesus’ Birth”).70 Benedict, then, conjures a different vision from the “big picture” theory, a vision (unsurprisingly) of patristic pedigree. The dispensable “details” touch the placement and expression, while the factum est and the meaning are affirmed.71 In this line, one could speak of a plenary view of historicity, in which problems are admitted on the level of textual arrangement, with full freedom allotted for whatever ingenious solutions one might find. But no separation into piles of “authentic” and “inauthentic” is involved. In distinction from Allison, then, this is not a surrender of concrete deeds for dynamic abstractions (e.g., “apocalyptic Judaism”). Meier is right to care about more than vague global assertions. But, dared by the legacy of D. F. Strauss to demonstrate, point by point, that real events lie behind the Gospels, Benedict appears humbly content to dare right back the impossible task of proving have rejected historicity, or at least they have let the question open. An interesting comment, in the light of this situation, is the carefully argued position presented by Klaus Berger . . . ‘Even when there is only a single attestation . . . one must suppose, until the contrary is proven, that the evangelists did not intend to deceive their readers, but rather to inform them concerning historical events . . . to contest the historicity of this account on mere suspicion exceeds every imaginable competence of historians’ (Kommentar zum Neuen Testament, p. 20). With this view I can only agree. The two chapters of Matthew’s Gospel devoted to the infancy narratives are not a meditation presented under the guise of stories, but the converse: Matthew is recounting real history, theologically thought through and interpreted, and thus he helps us to understand the mystery of Jesus more deeply.” Jesus of Nazareth: The Infancy Narratives (New York: Image, 2012), 118. 70 Sorcha Pollack, “Pope Benedict Disputes Date of Jesus’ Birth,” Time, November 22, 2012, http://newsfeed.time.com/2012/11/22/pope-benedict-disputes-jesus-date-ofbirth/. 71 This is the position of the PBC Instruction, which simply follows the patristic doctrine (citing Chrysostom, and Augustine) in allowing differences in placement and wording. See Origen, Commentary on John, 10.2–4: The Evangelists “sometimes altered things which, from the eye of history, occurred otherwise . . . [they] speak of something that happened in one place as if it happened in another, or of what happened at a certain time as if it happened at another time . . . [they introduced] into what was spoken in a certain way some changes of their own.” 108 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. a negative (non factum est)—reminding proud history of its limits.72 If the pope rests here and stops short of offering an ambitious apologia, perhaps the doctrine of vera historia means retying Schweitzer’s first of the Gordian knots.73 In highlighting only the cardinal points of Christian confession, then, Benedict chastens history.74 But this must be carefully understood. He never suggests that faith has been penned up in some creedal Alamo, ready to die in one last stand against the destructive reach of reason. Quite the contrary! The core witness of the Gospels is in a real sense the most verifiable material (if not thereby the most likely to sway all historians)—not only the matter dearest to faith.75 Even so, Benedict warns, the probative power of human science must not be exaggerated: “We may not expect . . . to find absolutely certain proof of every detail.”76 If metaphysical knowledge of necessary truth is vexed by the wounds of original sin, historical reason by its own contingent formal object deals 72 Benedict is at ease with the inconclusive nature of much historical controversy, but he is not thereby afraid to make a final judgment. On the Lukan census, e.g., he says: “The discussion could continue indefinitely . . . yet the essential content of Luke’s narrative remains historically credible all the same” (Ratzinger, Infancy Narratives, 63). 73 Albert Schweitzer related the history of Jesus research as the negotiation of three distinct scholarly dilemmas: supernaturalist or rationalist, Synoptic or Johannine, eschatological or noneschatological. While the latter two forks were resolved in favor of Synoptic (via Markan priority) and konsequente Eschatologie, respectively, Strauss exploded the first as a false dichotomy. Naturalist (rationalist) explanations of “miracles” were as dubious as supernatural claims; both falsely assumed the occurrence of a real event. See Dennis Nineham’s foreword to the complete edition of Quest of the Historical Jesus, xiii–xxxii. 74 See Ratzinger, Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfiguration, xv–xvi. 75 The Last Supper and Crucifixion are naturally less controversial as historical events than is the Resurrection, which poses a unique set of problems. If Catholic thinkers like Schillebeeckx and Gerald O’Collins (and John Meier) have ruled the Resurrection to be an eschatological event and consequently out of bounds in the study of history, Benedict, at least, concludes otherwise (with nuance). “The Resurrection does not simply stand outside or above history. As something that breaks out of history and transcends it, the Resurrection nevertheless has its origin within history and up to a certain point still belongs there. Perhaps we could put it this way: Jesus’ Resurrection points beyond history but has left a footprint within history” (Holy Week, 275). For a powerful attempt at verifying this “footprint,” see N. T. Wright, The Resurrection of the Son of God (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2003); and Michael Licona, The Resurrection of Jesus: A New Historiographical Approach (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2010). 76 Ratzinger, Holy Week, 105. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 109 always and only in probabilities. Much of history simply lies forever beyond our science’s grasp. The pope is not, then, promoting a theory of obiter dicta. It is, instead, a matter of faith and reason mutually tempering one another. Historical criticism, to begin, cannot insist on always playing judge, haughtily eschewing the servant’s role of illumining the background.77 In this sense, the reach of faith is in no way limited in its positive assent to the modest “proofs” of science. The ample use of the non liquet card is an open invitation to faith.78 At the same time, the serene confidence essential to faith never tempts it to act as a superhuman surrogate for plodding, mental labor, which retains its proper scope of judgment entirely unimpaired. Human ratio deepens (rather than “purifies”) faith’s delicate conviction, gives it new dimension, by drawing it ever more into the light of understanding from the dark seat of memoria where God touches the mind. Properly ordered theological faith, therefore, informed as it is by the analogia fidei and composed by the hierarchy of truths, never swells with ill-proportioned insight or dissipates itself through undue interest in things not revelata a Deo. It understands that the Incarnation weighs more than the visit of the magi. Yet, thus balanced in judgment, it also knows that no “jot or tittle” is incidental. God’s revelation is the ultimate measure of what man must believe. If mystical gifts would disclose the sorts of details historians might long to know—say, that the flight into Egypt “took place in February, six days after the purification”79—it is enough to remark that one does not find here veritatem, quam Deus nostrae salutis causa Litteris Sacris consignari voluit. 77 One might consider here the works of Martin Hengel, whose erudite and dignified humanism represents a different model of history in New Testament (NT) scholarship than the narrow “authenticity” arbitrations of so many historical Jesus scholars: an estimable model at once more and less subservient to the interests of faith. 78 The objection is inevitably raised that this is a feeble-minded “God of the gaps” posture; but the charge here is a rhetorical show of force. The identification of historiographical “gaps” generously recognizes the expanding conquests of historical science. The issue is more fundamental, addressing both the methodological atheism presumed by modern historians and the inherent limits of the discipline. See the suggestive (but not unproblematic) essay by Ross McCullough, “God and the Gaps,” First Things 232 (April 2013): 19–20. 79 Mary of Agreda, Mystical City of God, bk 4, ch. 8. 110 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. Memory, Faith, and Genre If the guild can detect in Benedict anything other than a fundamentalist, he will appear unsatisfying, inscrutable, or like the curious sighting of some “pre-modern” animal presumed extinct.80 In any case, where the issue has any interest, the respectable “big picture” view controls the day. A trend to note in connection with this theory is the recent rise of interest in “memory.”81 Generally accurate in the main points, but fuzzy on the details, memory has emerged in Gospel studies as a great theological hope for many, an overdue correction of Form Criticism, and a way to pull together the evangelists’ scrambled witness. In view of this, it is of interest what attention Sancta Mater Ecclesia gives to the notion. The key idea has unfortunately been distorted: “The life and teaching of Jesus were not simply related so as to be remembered (eo solo fine ut memoria tenerentur): they were ‘preached’ to provide the basis of faith and morals for the Church.”82 As translated here (wrongly), the statement would warn against overly rigid models of mnemonic transmission and put too disjunctive a stress on kerygmatic creativity.83 80 See, e.g., the critiques and complaints of Luke Timothy Johnson, Modern Theology (2008): 318–20, and Richard Hays, First Things 175 (2007): 49–53. N. T. Wright allows that “many . . . will inevitably see [Benedict’s work] as a step backwards, to a pre-modern, pre-critical reading.” Times Literary Supplement, December 14, 2011. 81 See Allison, Constructing Jesus, 1–30, 387–462. See also, e.g., James Dunn, Jesus Remembered (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2003), 881–94; Richard Bauckham, Jesus and the Eyewitnesses: The Gospels as Eyewitness Testimony (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2006), 319–57; Anthony Le Donne, The Historiographical Jesus: Memory, Typology, and the Son of David (Waco, TX: Baylor University, 2009); Chris Keith, “Memory and Authenticity: Jesus Tradition and What Really Happened,” Zeitschrift für die neutestamentliche Wissenschaft und die Kunder der älteren Kirche 102 (2011): 155–77; and especially the significant work of Robert McIver, Memory, Jesus, and the Synoptic Gospels, Society of Biblical Literature Resources for Biblical Studies 59 (Atlanta: SBL, 2011). 82 This is the misleading translation found in Murphy’s compendium, The Church and the Bible: Official Documents of the Catholic Church (New Delhi: St. Pauls/Alba House, 2007). The document actually stresses that the purpose was not only for the sole purpose of being remembered. “Cum ex eis quae novae inquisitiones contulerunt appareat doctrinam et vitam Iesu non simpliciter relatas fuisse, eo solo fine ut memoria tenerentur, sed «praedicatas» fuisse ita ut Ecclesiae fundamentum fidei et morum praeberent.” 83 The work of Birger Gerhardsson should be mentioned. See Memory and Manuscript: Oral Tradition and Written Transmission in Rabbinic Judaism and Early Christianity (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998); The Origins of the Gospel Traditions (Philadel- Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 111 It is clear from the document, however, that “faith by no means obliterated the memory of the events which had taken place. On the contrary, it reinforced these memories, because it rested on the things which Jesus had taught and done.”84 If this is true, and if kerygma and recollection are not operative in inverse proportion, the move to memory must be welcomed as a real advance—or, rather, recovery. The great merit of this paradigm is that it personalizes the process of transmission.85 If Fitzmyer hesitates about historicity with his murky proposal of “Gospel truth,” like many he hesitates precisely at this point, hardening the disjunction between memory and kerygma. As a hedge against the difficulties of positive (asseverative) inerrancy, of course, this systematic deference to the preaching of “faith and morals” cannot entail a limiting of the formal object of inerrant revelation.86 If by “Gospel truth,” then, Fitzmyer means that the four Gospels comprise a unique literary form, possessing its own hermeneutical canons, the premise is in principle perfectly sound. Attention to literary conventions has been the Church’s preferred response in this sensitive apologetic area in every relevant document since Providentissimus Deus. The difficulty is in practice, not in theory.87 Bultmann had pushed phia: Fortress, 1979); and The Reliability of the Gospel Tradition (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 2001). See also McIver (Memory, 167, 187), who speaks of mnemotechniques and “near verbatim accuracy.” The PBC leaves the disciples’ memory very much intact and even suggests a pedagogy reminiscent of Gerhardsson’s rabbinic model (i.e., “firmly impressed . . . and easily remembered”): “Dominus, cum doctrinam ore exponebat, modos ratiocinandi et exponendi tunc temporis vulgatos sequebatur, ita ad mentem auditorum Se accommodans et efficiens ut ea quae doceret firmiter menti imprimerentur et commode a discipulis memoria tenerentur.” 84 Dei Verbum §19 also endorsed such language, speaking plainly of Evangelists working ex sua propria memoria et recordatio. 85 Martin Hengel has vigorously critiqued the anonymous tradition model, an issue singled out by the PBC, rightly insisting on “the personal link of the Jesus tradition with particular tradents.” The Four Gospels and the One Gospel of Jesus Christ (London: SCM, 2000), 146. 86 On the systematic question, see Peter Paul Zarafa, “The Limits of Biblical Inerrancy,” Angelicum 39 (1962): 92–119. One may legitimately wonder whether Fitzmyer’s reading simply anticipates the widely received distortion of Dei Verbum §11. On the correct interpretation of this important text, see Marchetto, Contrappunto, 453–58 (chap. 30); and Brant Pitre, “The Mystery of God’s Word: Inspiration, Inerrancy, and the Interpretation of Scripture,” Letter and Spirit 6 (2010): 47–66. 87 See Judith Diehl, “What Is a Gospel? Recent Studies in the Gospel Genre,” Currents in Biblical Research 9 (2011): 171–99. Diehl distinguishes between an analogical and 112 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. the claim that the Gospels were not biographies but sui generis faith productions.88 His folkloric contention, however, assumed an anachronistic concept of biography (among other faulty assumptions); and since the work of Richard Burridge on ancient bioi, Bultmann’s credibility on this point has unraveled.89 A growing edge of Gospel research now sees the Gospels as far less determined by the needs of local communities than once assumed; while the evangelists’ interest in recounting real events has become increasingly hard to deny.90 A range of mimetic modes is indeed discernible in the Gospels, yet their literary originality is bound to historical seriousness.91 The Lukan preface merits a central place in this discussion, for it has become quite clear that his formal style and appeal to autopsy have their cultural and literary context in Greco-Roman historiography.92 Though derivational approach to the question of genre, allowing analogical affinities to the canonical Gospels but upholding their derivational originality. 88 The original influence of this thesis owes much to K. L. Schmidt, “Die Stellung der Evangelien in der allgemeinen Literaturgeschichte,” in Eucharisterion: Studien zur Religion und Literatur des Altes und Neues Testaments: Hermann Gunkel 60. Geburtstag, Teil 2 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1923), 50–134. 89 Richard Burridge, What Are the Gospels? A Comparison with Graeco-Roman Biography, 2nd ed. (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2004). In the foreword to the second edition, Graham Stanton remarks, “Over the last decade or so, very few books on the Gospels have been discussed more widely or have influenced scholarly opinion more strongly.” 90 See Richard Bauckham, ed., The Gospels for All Christians: Rethinking the Gospel Audiences (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998); and now also Edward Klink III, ed., The Audience of the Gospels: The Origin and Function of the Gospels in Earliest Christianity, Library of New Testament Studies 353 (London: T&T Clark, 2010). See also Martin Hengel, “The Sources of Earliest Christianity,” in Acts and the History of Early Christianity (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1979), 3–34—an essay on some first principles of NT historiography that should be mandatory reading. 91 See the innovative study of Justin Taylor exploring Auerbach’s claim that the Gospels transgress the ancient “separation of styles.” The Treatment of Reality in the Gospels: Five Studies, Cahiers de la Revue Biblique 78 (Paris: Gabalda, 2011). 92 For a summary of research, see Clarke Rothschild, Luke-Acts and the Rhetoric of History, Wissenschaftliche Untersuchungen zum Neuen Testament 175 (Tübingen: Mohr Sieback, 2004), 32–59. See also David Aune, “Luke 1:1–4: Historical or Scientific Prooimion?” in Paul, Luke, and the Greco-Roman World: Essays in Honour of Alexander J. M. Wedderburn, ed. A Christopherson et al., Journal for the Study of the New Testament Supplement Series 217 (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic, 2002), 142. Aune wishes to indicate that Luke’s preface likely resembles “the hundreds of lost mediocre histories,” and that it is misleading to gauge it only against the stan- Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 113 Luke alone of the Evangelists postures as an historian, it is enough that he does.93 The formal congruence of the synoptic Gospels implies a kind of transitive asphaleia. As a dutiful historian, Luke’s assurance assures his readers of the material they might find in Matthew and Mark.94 Luke himself plainly recognizes his special role among the “many” who have undertaken the task of telling this story, and he sees his particular purpose in drawing up a “careful ordering” (ἀκριβῶς καθεξῆς γράψαι) of the events. The irony of this purpose is that, at ground level, Luke’s order is considered primitive and unclear.95 While grand geographic and temporal patterns do give an intelligible, architectonic shape to the Lukan message, the way smaller units are collated can seem almost haphazard. Here Bultmann’s hand becomes much stronger. Plainly, the micro-units of tradition were not hammered out in the same school as the learned Lukan prologue. The most helpful thing to be said here concerns the “Eucharistic provenance” of the Gospels.96 Specifically, “The consistent portrayal of Jesus as the one coming and being encountered [in Gospel pericopes] originates in the way memories about him were recalled, told, and retold dard of the best Hellenistic exemplars. That the preface may be a work of “mediocre” quality, though, should not obscure its classification as haute litérature (at least in pretension). For the classical mind, it was the theme that determined stylistic elevation, and of Luke’s theme there can be little doubt. The Evangelist consciously presents his work as a thing serious and significant in the manner of a history, for history alone could bear the magnitude of “the events fulfilled among us” (Lk 1:1). On the Greco-Roman background, see Giuseppe Nenci, “Il motivo dell’autopsia nella storagraphia greca,” Studi Classici e Orientali 3 (1955): 14–29; and especially Guido Schepens, L’‘autopsie’ dans la méthod des historiens grec du Ve siècle avant J.-C. (Brussels: Paleis der Academiën, 1980). 93 This is not to deny the important historical concerns (and methods) of the other Evangelists. See, e.g., Richard Bauckham, “Historiographical Aspects of the Gospel of John,” New Testament Studies 53 (2007): 17–36. 94 Commentators have at times detected a note of criticism in Luke’s mention of his predecessors, and such judgments were a trope in Greco-Roman historiography. In other authors’ work, however, the polemic is much more open and unmistakable, e.g., Josephus, B.J. 1.1. See John Marincola, Authority and Tradition in Ancient Historiography (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 218–25. 95 Lukan order is commonly accepted as more nearly approximating the order of Q than is Matthean order. 96 See Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation, 65–79; also Benoit, “Réflexions,” 487. 114 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. in the presence of cultic (Eucharistic) congregations, gatherings held for the purpose of reliving the past encounters.”97 Accordingly, though one does not find in Luke (or any of the Gospels) a disciplined effort to grasp the inner connections of discrete events, such chronological inattention preserves the elemental structure of the Jesus tradition as sacramental anamnesis.98 To this degree, the cultivated memory undergirding the Gospels responds directly to the Lord’s command (hoc facite in meum commemorationem). It is not free fabrication.99 If the cultic molding of the primitive tradition indeed preserved the “hypomnemata of the apostles,”100 other portions of the Gospels do not betray the same origin. The infancy narratives, in particular, stand apart. While the expressions of Christology are pronounced in these cherished episodes, actors other than the sacramental Lord (ho erchomenos) enjoy prominence, and the stories are widely seen as mere “vehicles for the evangelist’s theology.”101 Yet, notice has long been made that “Luke indicates from time to time that Mary, the Mother of Jesus, is herself one of his sources.”102 This “uncritical” position has, of course, (less) long been ridiculed as a pious (Catholic) fantasy. The model of Mary’s deepening memory (Lk 2:51) is viable, however—as credible, at least, as any “Baptist source”—and more than piety is at stake.103 Ultimately, a decision 97 Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation, 74 (cf. 72n21). Discrete anecdotal ordering is characteristic of much ancient biography and represents the literary crystallization of the basic impact of the documented personality. See Hengel, “Sources of Earliest Christianity,” 15–18. 99 For a wide-ranging rebuttal of the Form Critical canard that nameless Christian prophets were a factory of dominical logia, see David Aune, Prophecy in Early Christianity and the Ancient Mediterranean World (Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 2003). 100 Justin, First Apology 66.3; also 33.5; cf. Dialogue with Trypho 100.4, 101.3, 102.5, etc. See also Papias’s description of Mark’s Gospel (H.E. 3.39.15) and the language employed by Clement of Alexandria (H.E. 2.15.1). 101 Raymond Brown, The Birth of the Messiah: A Commentary on the Infancy Narratives in Matthew and Luke (New York: Doubleday, 1977), 37. 102 Ratzinger, Infancy Narratives, 16. 103 See most recently Richard Dillon, who speaks of “members of the Baptist diaspora” as the source of the Baptist nativity material, but never considers pre-Lukan sources that might inform the Jesus strand. The Hymns of Saint Luke: Lyricism and Narrative Strategy in Luke 1–2, Catholic Biblical Quarterly Monograph Series 50 (Washington, DC: CBA, 2013), 5–14, 50. 98 Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 115 between the “big picture” and plenary views is closely bound to one’s decision about personal Gospel sources. The Third Gospel sets the parameters in which historica veritas must be conceived, but it is the Fourth Gospel where the issue is decided. In John, the unmistakable claim to eyewitness knowledge is melded with the most robust expression of introspective memory: the Marian model rigorously extended.104 Such a conjunction of witness and interpretation has proven too hard to swallow. As its first step in the classic “Quest for the Historical Jesus,” scholarship accordingly decided not to go down the Johannine road.105 A new generation of scholars, however, has begun to question this fundamental axiom.106 In any case, the council’s perspective is clear from the final sentence of Dei Verbum §19. There a distinction is drawn between those Evangelists “who relied on their own memory and recollection” (making room here beside John for the traditional identity of Matthew as an apostle) and those who depended on “the eyewitnesses from the beginning” (meaning Mark and Luke).107 Evangelists without some access to direct witness are not envisioned. 104 See the remarks of Ratzinger (Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfiguration, 233–34): “What John says in his Gospel about how remembering becomes understanding and the path ‘into all truth’ comes very close to what Luke recounts about remembering on the part of Jesus’ mother.” 105 The decisive impetus again came from D. F. Strauss, who managed to overmaster the influence of Schleiermacher’s predilection for John. See Schweitzer, Quest of the Historical Jesus, 80–83. 106 See, e.g., Craig L. Blomberg, The Historical Reliability of John’s Gospel: Issues and Commentary (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2001). A variety of factors have turned scholars in this direction, not least of which is the growing fund of hardboiled, archaeological evidence. See James Charlesworth, “The Historical Jesus in the Fourth Gospel: A Paradigm Shift?” Journal of the Study of the Historical Jesus 8 (2010): 3–46. 107 A distinction in status was implicit in this distinction of credentials: “Cur quatuor evangelistae non per quator apostolos scribuntur, nisi per duos discipulos et duos apostolos? Quia filii Jacob de duabus liberis et duabus ancillis nati sunt” (Ps. Jerome, Expositio quattuor evangeliorum PL 30, 567–77). The particular popularity of the Gospels of Matthew and John in the early Church no doubt owes much to their apostolic credentials. See Édouard Massaux, Influence de l’Évangile de Saint Matthieu sur la littérature chrétienne avant saint Irénée (Louvain: Louvain, 1950). 116 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. “Eyewitnesses from the Beginning” The PBC Instruction posited three stages of Gospel tradition: the preaching of Jesus, the preaching of his apostles, and the literary activity of the four evangelists. If the innovation of this arrangement was the careful (some would say “arbitrary”) distinction between periods two and three,108 this schema is not, contrary to common opinion, ever attributed to the insights of the Form Critical method. All three are found explicitly in the Lukan framework: (1) all that Jesus did and taught (Acts 1:1); (2) the things handed down (paradosis) by the autoptoi and ministers of the word (Lk 1:2); and (3) the undertaking to draw up a diegesis (Lk 1:1, 3). If all three tempora reappear (without special flagging) in Dei Verbum, in the full doctrine of the council Stage Two (paradosis) attains an unmistakable prominence. This is a key point that Caba and others miss at a great cost. The clear affirmation in §18 of the Gospel’s “apostolic origin” (origine apostolica) is only part of the council’s interest in this theme, which has its more important exposition in Chapter II on the Transmission of Divine Revelation. Apostolic preaching thus represents the crucial point of intersection linking the two poorly integrated blocks of Dei Verbum §1–2 and §3–5.109 The affirmation itself, along with the direct identification of the sacred authors as apostles and apostolici viri (meaning Mark and Luke as the respective associates of the apostles Peter and Paul) represents, of course, an obvious element in the claim to historical truth.110 It is no surprise, then, that the doctrinal precursors to this article were originally forged during the heat of the (first) Modernist crisis, in the notorious PBC responsa. Much might be said about this embarrassing magisterial corpus, but only one point is necessary here. The Biblical Commission—followed implicitly by the council’s preparatory Theological Commission 108 See the analysis of Bernard Orchard, “Dei Verbum and the Synoptic Gospels,” This Rock 7 (May 1996). The conflating of these stages took hold before 1964. See the revealing piece of David Michael Stanley, “New Understanding of the Gospels,” in The Bible in Current Catholic Thought (New York: Herder and Herder, 1962), 169–83. 109 On this tension in the document, see Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation, 168–202. 110 The wording of Dei Verbum §18 resumes the precise formulation of the discarded schema but significantly alters the final portion. Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 117 and then the full body of council fathers—reckoned the writing of the Gospels by “the authors whose names they bear,” as a revealed truth to be firmly accepted de fide.111 If de facto the question of authorship has long since fallen into the scientific jurisdiction of the Einleitungen, in the mind of the PBC, “the universal and unwavering agreement,” indeed “the continual, universal and solemn tradition of the Church” authoritatively settles the point. It is noteworthy in judging the rare force of this language that, by way of contrast, the PBC never made such a confident, or rather “obliging, certain affirmation” (certo affirmare cogat) of the “clear judgment of tradition” (luculentum traditionis suffragium) when addressing, for instance, the issue of Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch. (We must note here the ignorant but persistent habit of lampooning the responsum genre as an instrument lacking all nuance.) In 1962, in fact, the debate of the drafting committee made explicit that Mosaic authorship had status as sententia communis, but was not to be regarded (like Gospel authorship) as traditio.112 Accordingly and significantly, the PBC’s much more cautiously circumscribed 1906 pronouncements on the Pentateuch never surfaced in the preconciliar schema’s chapter De Vetere Testamento—quite in contrast to 111 De fontibus revelationis §19 Dei Verbum §18 Quattor Evangelia apostolicam originem habere Ecclesia Dei semper et ubique sine dubitatione credidit et credit, constanterque tenuit ac tenet auctores humanos habere illos quorum nomina in Sacrorum Librorum canone gerunt: Mattheaum nempe, Marcum, Lucam et Ioannem, quem diligebat Iesus. Quattuor Evangelia originem apostolicam habere Ecclesia semper et ubique tenuit ac tenet. Quae enim Apostoli ex mandato Christi praedicaverunt, postea divino afflante Spiritu, in scriptis, ipsi et apostolici viri nobis tradiderunt, fidei fundamentum, quadriforme nempe Evangelium, secundum Matthaeum, Marcum, Lucam et Ioannem. Augustine Bea’s commentary on Dei Verbum provides privileged insight into the council fathers’ thinking. He distinguishes between the “authenticity” of the Gospels (“that is, that they were written by the authors whose names they bear”) and their “apostolic origin,” and, without suggesting any doubt about the former (which is clearly articulated as doctrine in De fontibus 19), allows that Dei Verbum deals only with the “essential points”: apostolic origin and historical truth. The Word of God and Mankind (London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1967), 240. 112 See Schelkens, Theology of Revelation, 152–53. 118 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. the responsa on the Gospels.113 Moreover, the claim about the Gospels’ origin was never probatur ex traditione in the errant sense undermined by the council, that is, by an incidental catena of proof texts or appeal to some “secret” stream of knowledge. It is presented, rather, as a robust expression of the Church’s full living commitment, integrally and implicitly transmitted by liturgy, councils, popes, canons, the fathers, ecclesiastics, and so on. Vincent of Lérins and Congar might equally agree. The Biblical Commission’s vigorous avowal of the Gospels’ origin, then, was not the mere bluster of reactionary intransigence, but a forceful, self-conscious, and mature doctrinal proposition. So it was both proffered and received.114 This, I think, helps us evaluate the variegated magisterial weight of the PBC responsa.115 The question then becomes what to make of this. Plainly, it is a teaching the academy has not received. Indeed, after 1965, in the blink of an eye, the Two Source Hypothesis—which has no place for Matthean eyewitness—came to prevail in Catholic scholarship.116 Regardless 113 A growing recognition of the limited relevance of the responsa began to emerge in the years prior to the council. In 1955 a quiet policy announced by the secretary of the PBC encouraged exegetes to proceed in aller Freiheit, treating earlier pronouncements as the quaint relics of a difficult crisis now passed. See Athanasius Miller, “Das neue biblische Handbuch,” Benediktinische Monatschrift 31 (1955): 49–50. Although this perspective was never openly authorized (preserving curial bella figura), the Theological Commission, which drafted the preparatory chapter in 1962 (and certainly knew the mind of the Magisterium), studiously mined the PBC documents in preparing chapter IV on the NT, yet conspicuously neglected the same corpus in preparing chapter III on the OT. Such an embrace of the full discretionary liberty to disregard the responsa makes the free endorsement in the case of the Gospels enormously suggestive. On the status of Miller’s “clarification,” see the personal account of J. E. Steinmueller, who reports that Miller’s action was condemned by the voting Cardinals of the PBC who sought to bring him before the Holy Office. Sword of the Spirit (Waco, TX: Stella Maris, 1982), 7. 114 The language of universal Tradition in Dei Verbum §18 is emphatic and overt: semper et ubique tenuit ac tenet. 115 The responsa represent a provisional magisterial act of “pastoral prudence,” but they are not set aside tout court. See then-Cardinal Ratzinger’s authoritative explanation of The Ecclesial Vocation of the Theologian: “Their core remains valid, but the individual details influenced by the circumstances at the time may need further rectification.” 116 The movement in this direction began before the council, of course, and the last significant Catholic defense of Matthean apostolic authorship was Bishop Butler’s book in 1951—now, interestingly, just reissued: The Originality of St. Matthew: A Critique of the Two Document Hypothesis (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2011). Less than five years after the council (1968), Frederick Gast’s article in the original Je- Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 119 of whether this hasty development was precipitous or overdue, it simply borrowed the results of Protestant scholarship. No distinct Catholic debate ever transpired. The remarkable legacy of figures like Lagrange and Vaganay was casually laid aside like some obtuse Ptolemaic astronomy, an embarrassing and overburdened exegesis contorted by extraneous ecclesial commitments.117 The irony, of course, is that 1964 (the year of the PBC Instruction) saw William Farmer, the great (Protestant) champion of the Neo-Griesbach Hypothesis, first question Holtzmann’s long-held dogma of Markan priority.118 If today the Q hypothesis is thus facing a growing wave of scrutiny and skepticism, this has not been a Catholic crusade.119 It is difficult to say what is emerging here. There are zealots on both sides; yet even dogmatic adherents of Q are quietly softening their positions.120 Pierre Benoit predicted early on that Form Criticism would ultirome Biblical Commentary calmly pronounced Markan priority the uncontroversial majority view. Lagrange had already described the Two Document Hypothesis as généralement admise in 1903, but this estimate clearly indicates a continental—i.e., German Protestant—consensus. La méthode historique (Paris: Lecoffre, 1903, 249), Streeter’s important monograph, would not convince the Anglophone world until 1924. On Catholic interest in Markan priority, see John Kloppenborg Verbin, Excavating Q (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2000), 321–25. 117 For diagrams of the complex solutions proposed by Lagrange and Vaganay, see Lagrange, 45, 318. 118 See William Farmer, The Synoptic Problem, 2nd ed. (Dilsboro: Western North Carolina, 1974). Farmer suggests that the triumph of Holtzmann’s thesis of Markan priority had much to do with the Catholic-Protestant polemics of the Kulturkampf. See Kloppenborg Verbin, Excavating Q, 312–21. 119 See, e.g., Mark Goodacre, The Case against Q: Studies in Markan Priority and the Synoptic Problem (Harrisburg, PA: Trinity, 2002); David Peabody, Lamar Colpe, and Allan McNicol, eds., One Gospel from Two: Mark’s Use of Matthew and Luke (Harrisburg, PA: Trinity, 2002); and James Dunn, Jesus Remembered, 147–60; and Dunn, “Q1 as Oral Tradition,” in The Written Gospel, ed. Marcus Bockmuehl and Donald Hagner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 45–69. 120 Even Helmut Koester is ready to concede that “the name Matthew may have been connected” with the Synoptic Sayings Source. Ancient Christian Gospels: Their History and Development (Philadelphia: Trinity, 1990), 318. In this line Benedict Viviano has now proposed regarding Q as the notebook (pinax) of the apostle Matthew—a conservative theory startlingly close to Robert Gundry’s defense of the traditional authorship of the First Gospel, a conservative tour de force that (predictably) fell stillborn from the press. “Who Wrote Q? The Sayings Document (Q) as the Apostle Matthew’s Private Notebook as a Bilingual Village Scribe (Mk 2:13–17; Mt 9:9–13),” in Mark and Matthew II, Wissenschaftliche Untersuchungen zum Neuen Testament 120 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. mately undo the Two Source Theory.121 The key challenge, in any event, is articulating a firm doctrine of apostolic origin that manages to avoid meddling too much in the mechanics of the Synoptic Problem—and, at the same time, addressing the Synoptic Problem with honest attention to the Gospels’ apostolic origin.122 Standing in the dock, of course, are many highly attenuated interpretations of “apostolicity.” Sancta Mater Ecclesia had warned of minimizing the munus of the apostles, and it is pure illusion to pretend this has not happened—at great cost. The stakes are high, and it is no coincidence that Matthean scholarship specifically has gone the way of the Fourth Gospel, with the tax collector dissolving into the reconstructed fog of a community in contest with the synagogue.123 As an individual, Luke, of course, is easier than Matthew to spot. Luke speaks directly in the first person. An older Fitzmyer, in his two-volume commentary, thus mounts a substantial case that the author of the Third Gospel is indeed none other than “the traditional Luke, a sometime companion of Paul.”124 Then, in the next breath, the exegete volunteers that this “makes little difference to the interpretation of the Lucan Gospel.” The simple question is: Why not? Why do an Introduction’s theses on audience have such profound interpretative value, while the veri auctores themselves are of so little concern? It is true the evangelists hide themselves to a considerable degree—though this posture may be deceptively unassuming.125 Their sheer proximity to “the things fulfilled among us” (Lk 1:1), however, demands more thoughtful attention. 271, ed. A. Runnesson and E.-M. Becker (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2013). Benoit, “Réflexions,” 483. 122 The PBC’s 1912 pronouncement on the Synoptic Problem (AAS 4 [1912]: 465) articulates the range of issues to be considered before exegetes “discuss freely” various possible solutions. 123 The “Johannine Question” is, therefore, as critical here as the Synoptic Problem. See Raymond Brown, The Community of the Beloved Disciple: The Life, Loves, and Hates of an Individual Church in New Testament Times (New York: Paulist, 1979); and especially Martin Hengel, Die johanneische Frage, Wissenschaftliche Untersuchungen zum Neuen Testament 67 (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 1993). See also Ratzinger, Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfiguration, 218–37. 124 Joseph Fitzmyer, The Gospel According to Luke I-XII, Anchor Bible 28 (Garden City, NJ: Doubleday, 1979), 35–52. 125 The demographics of the “audience” are not announced either, but that has not deterred ingenious exegetes. On “hidden” authors, see Armin Baum, “The Anonymity of the New Testament History Books: A Stylistic Device in the Context of Greco-Ro121 Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 121 Richard Bauckham has amply shown how provocative serious consideration of the claim to eyewitness sources might be.126 If Bauckham’s work has met a mixed reception, with Catholics not always eager to embrace his vision, I would argue that, though there are plenty of places for legitimate disagreement, he represents quite well the occluded teaching of Vatican II. Most importantly, perhaps, his attempt to find in testimony the place where history and theology meet recognizes the space defined by facticity (factum est) and meaning as the substantial locus of Gospel asphaleia. Of course, he only pursues what the PBC claimed belonged to be “the sound principles of the historical method.” It is incidental that it conforms also to Catholic doctrine. It is no surprise for those guided by Catholic sensibilities, though, when Bauckham both rehabilitates in the testimony of Papias, a once-prized resource in Catholic exegesis, and erects with his body of eyewitnesses what one scholar dubs “a Protestant form of apostolic succession”—a quasi magisterial agency faithfully guarding and transmitting the deposit.127 The special interest this idea holds is in surmounting the paradigm of the duplex fons and exposing the point where the divine impulse behind tradition and Scripture coheres. If this structure approximates the basic Catholic view and ably cuts the legs from under rationalistic Formgeschichte, one could lament that it took fifty years and an Anglican to materialize the Church’s vision. As with the ongoing liturgical reform, man and Ancient Near Eastern Literature,” Novum Testamentum 50 (2008): 120–42. Richard Bauckham, Jesus and the Eyewitnesses: The Gospels as Eyewitnesses Testimony (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2006). Reaction to Bauckham’s controversial thesis has been predictably lively and sharp. See, e.g., Peter Rodgers, “Jesus and the Eyewitnesses: The Gospels as Eyewitnesses Testimony,” Novum Testamentum 52 (2010): 88–100; Judith Redman, “How Accurate Are Eyewitnesses? Bauckham and the Eyewitnesses in the Light of Psychological Research,” Journal of Biblical Literature 129 (2010): 177–97; Dean Philip Bechard, “Jesus and the Eyewitnesses: The Gospels as Eyewitness Testimony,” Biblica 90 (2009): 126–29; Jens Schröder, “The Gospels as Eyewitness Testimony? A Critical Examination of Bauckham’s Jesus and the Eyewitnesses,” Journal for the Study of the New Testament 31 (2008): 195–209; Craig Evans, “The Implications of Eyewitness Tradition,” Journal for the Study of the New Testament 31 (2008): 211–19. See especially the entire volume Journal for the Study of the Historical Jesus 6 (2008), including Bauckham, “In Response to My Respondents: Jesus and the Eyewitnesses in Review,” 225–53. Also Bauckham, “Eyewitnesses and Critical History: A Response to Jens Schröder and Craig Evans,” Journal for the Study of the New Testament 31 (2008): 221–35. 127 Tatum, “Limits of Reliability,” 524. 126 122 Anthony Giambrone, O.P. however, or the still broadly untested norms of exegesis urged in Dei Verbum §12, implementation of the council’s vision requires patience. Conclusion The doctrine of Dei Verbum §19 reaffirms traditional teaching. (People at times forget that this is what ecumenical councils do.) This implies substantial continuity with the magisterial pronouncements of the PBC, a point that has not been acknowledged—understandably, perhaps, given the uneven value of this highly contextualized material. The council’s vision, nonetheless, offers more than repetition without reform, for it also goes ad fontes, offering the Church the (re)sources of divine revelation to renew itself root and stock. In this way, specifically Lukan parameters are found for addressing the issue of historical truth. The three tempora are an important component of this, but of greatest significance is the matter of apostolic eyewitness. In this regard, it is critical not to overstate the Church’s investment in Form Criticism (and its methodological descendants), simply because this school helped the Church recognize the special importance of the threefold layering of tradition. The magisterium made a gesture of goodwill toward German exegesis, but never irrevocably linked arms. In the postconciliar experiment, however, there has been little diversity in the matter of exegetical method, and some less acceptable assumptions of the Form Critics have become deeply entrenched. As part of this, the issue of apostolicity was allowed to vanish from practical consideration: a circumstance that has strongly promoted a soupy view of the Gospels’ historicity. The present direction of Gospel scholarship suggests the wisdom of more clearly disentangling the Church’s exegesis from the rationalistic principles still inherent in redaction criticism and criteriology. Historica veritas, in the end, cannot be so easily siphoned off as a scientifically controllable problem. The temptation in this direction is multifaceted, and it was a fateful rendering of the vulgate to intellectualize asphaleia (not aleitheia!) as veritas. For Luke, though, this “reliability” is first of all confirmatory and fiducial. Faith and reason must, then, collaborate here more than they have done. The council fathers envisioned a both/and approach to the problem (fide et ratione), despite the particular need to accent reason (non tantum fide). This means recovering a nonrational- Dei Verbum §19 and the Historicity of the Gospels 123 ist (pre-Enlightenment? postmodern?) historical sensibility, above all, I suggest, by more closely studying and understanding the patristic tolerance (and limits) of Gospel disharmony: reverse engineering in some way projects like Augustine’s De Consensu. Moderating the illusory claims of positivistic history (wie es eigentlich gewesenist) is, of course, indispensable too. If the “Quest for the Historical Jesus” has advanced by always “taking one or other of two alternatives,”128 the Church sees this as a record of dangerous neglect. To reverse the course is hard, surely, but on one front there are promising signs. Perhaps the way forward will rejoin a road not taken, for some in the academy are now turning again toward John. This must challenge our whole manner of imagining history and seeking the vera et sincera de Iesu.129 The teaching of Vatican II on the historical truth of the Gospels belongs to the significant portion of Dei Verbum that “still awaits completion.”130 Sancta Mater Ecclesia spoke truly: “There will never be an end to [biblical] problems,” but “the Catholic exegete should never lose heart.” With this in mind, we may express a glad hope that, even after fifty years, the council’s sacred work still requires periti. For, in the abundance of the Holy Spirit’s gift to the Church, a special joy belongs also to those who never knew the first thrill of aggiornamento. The call to renewal also touches our hearts, a generation grateful to be the living N&V first fruits of the Second Vatican Council. 128 Schweitzer, Quest of the Historical Jesus, xvii. I would like to mention here the exegetical work of Marie-Joseph Lagrange, whose prescience, piety, and erudition can still shine as a guiding star as we continue to navigate the long wake of the storm he courageously weathered. (Another anniversary was quietly marked in 2012: the centenary of what Lagrange simply called L’ année terrible.) It is unfortunate, perhaps, that Pope Benedict missed the chance to commend Lagrange’s example in his Jesus of Nazareth series; the evocation of figures like Guardini and Daniel-Rops indicates that his ultimate inspiration lay outside professional exegesis. On the other hand, Ratzinger disavows any attempt to write a “Life of Christ” and points us instead to Thomas’s Tertia Pars (Holy Week, xvi). In thus offering a kind of “theological treatise on the mysteries of the life of Christ,” the emeritus pontiff approaches in some ways the rare vision of Lagrange, who had the profound wisdom to understand why “the Gospels themselves are the only lives of Jesus that can be written.” L’Évangile de Jesus Christ (Paris: Gabalda, 1928). 130 Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation, 168. 129 Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 125-153 125 The Humanism of the Incarnation: Catholic, Barthian, and Dutch Reformed1* Tracey Rowland John Paul II Institute for Marriage and the Family Melbourne, Australia THIS ARTICLE TAKES THE FORMof a reflection on the idea of the “humanism of the Incarnation” in which the “participant” voices will principally be those of Martin D’Arcy, Charles Journet, Karol Wojtyła, Joseph Ratzinger, and Marc Ouellet representing the Catholic academy; Karl Barth representing himself; and Abraham Kuyper representing the Dutch Reformed tradition. Martin D’Arcy (1888–1978) was a twentieth-century English Jesuit renowned for converting a rather large number of Oxford undergraduates, including Evelyn Waugh. D’Arcy is said to have been the inspiration for the character of Fr. Rothschild in Waugh’s novel Vile Bodies. Several chapters of his book The Sense of History: Secular and Sacred offer a mid-twentieth-century engagement with Karl Barth’s ideas on what is now called “the theology of culture.” D’Arcy in turn was influenced by an essay of Christopher Butler who was the Abbot of Downside Abbey. Butler’s article “On the Value of History” was published in the Downside Review in 1950, and Butler himself was following leads in the work of the Belgian Jesuit Léopold Malevez (1900–1973) whose work is known for its identification of a division between incarnational and eschatological approaches to history. For those who favor the eschatological * This essay was delivered as the keynote address to the 2013 Wilken Colloquium at Baylor University, sponsored by the Center for Catholic-Evangelical Dialogue. 126 Tracey Rowland approach, the emphasis is on the discontinuity between profane history and the final reign of God after the renewal of the cosmos, while for those who favor the incarnational approach, the general idea is that all good human actions prepare for the coming age beyond the consummation of the world.1 The eschatological approach is usually identified with an emphasis on the theology of the Cross, while the incarnational approach is identified, obviously, with the theology of the Incarnation. Malevez had been influenced by a fellow Belgian theologian, Gustave Thils (1909–2000), who was a peritus at the Second Vatican Council and a member of the Secretariat for Christian Unity. Thils is generally remembered for his doctrinal history of the ecumenical movement, published in 1955, and for his criticism of the theology of Jean Daniélou for being too far down the eschatological end of the spectrum.2 The other Catholic voices to be mentioned are Charles Journet (1891–1975), a Swiss Cardinal associated with the journal Nova et Vetera; Jean Borella, a contemporary French theologian; Joseph Ratzinger, who needs no introduction; and Marc Ouellet, the Canadian who was given the shortest odds of any Cardinal entering the 2013 conclave by Paddy Power’s Irish betting agency. Abraham Kuyper (1837–1920), representing the Dutch Reformed tradition was the prime minister of the Netherlands from 1901 to 1905, the founder of a newspaper, a university, a political party, and a religious denomination. His most famous academic works were his Lectures on Calvinism delivered at Princeton Seminary in 1898. The Princeton Seminary now hosts the Abraham Kuyper Centre for Public Theology and sponsors the annual Kuyper Prize Lecture as well as publishes the Kuyper Centre Review. My judgment of Kuyper is that he was a kind of Calvinist Alasdair MacIntyre, that is to say, he was someone keenly interested in the relationship between theological ideas and culture and he was decidedly anti-liberal. Just as MacIntyre encourages the formation of small institutions governed by persons who all share the same 1 This is Abbott Butler’s summary of the distinction in “The Value of History,” Downside Review 68, no. 213 (1950): 290–305, at 290–91. For the original analysis by Malevez, see Léopold Malevez, “Deux théologies catholiques de l’histoire,” Bijdragen 10 (1949): 225–40. 2 Gustave Thils, Histoire Doctrinale du Mouvement Oecuménique (Louvain: E. Warny, 1955). The Humanism of the Incarnation 127 theological framework, Kuyper is remembered as a champion of pillarization, the sociological term given to the denominational segregation of pre–World War II Dutch society. A fellow Calvinist, though in a tradition all his own, Karl Barth (1886–1968) was, to quote Pope Pius XII, “the most important theologian since Thomas Aquinas.” Barth was invited to be an observer at the Second Vatican Council and later published a work of reflections on the documents of the Council entitled Ad Limina Apostolorum: A Reappraisal of Vatican II. In 1966 when he met Pope Paul VI he asked the pontiff what one might colloquially call the billion-dollar question: what does aggiornamento mean, accommodation to what?3 Aggiornamento was the 1960s buzzword for theological renewal, also translated as updating and mutated as accommodating. It was closely related to the postconciliar pastoral strategy known as “correlationism,” the idea that the faith needed to be correlated to the culture of the times. As the French Dominican Marie-Dominique Chenu (1895– 1990) described the idea, one needed to look to the contemporary culture for pierres d’attente, or toothing stones, to which the faith could attach itself. This pastoral strategy was strongly associated with the postconciliar theology of the Flemish Dominican Edward Schillebeeckx (1914–2009), and it had a major impact on the direction of Catholic ecclesial life throughout the pontificate of Paul VI (1963–78). For many clergy educated in Catholic seminaries in the 1960s the correlationist project remains synonymous with the “spirit of the Council.” When applied in the 1960s, 70s, and 80s, correlationism came to mean accommodating the faith to the culture of modernity. Today proponents of this project (found mostly in the Netherlands and Belgium), argue that instead of correlating the faith to the culture of modernity, ecclesial leaders need to recontextualize the faith to the culture of postmodernity. This is because the culture of modernity and its “modern man” are now regarded as the undesirable refuse of the eighteenth century. The modern man has been variously described as a “one-dimensional man” by the Frankfurt School’s Herbert Marcuse; an animal producens et consumens by the Czech Jesuit Joseph Zverina S.J.; a “mass man” who has “no desire for independence or originality,” the description of 3 Karl Barth, Ad Limina Apostolorum (Edinburgh: St. Andrews Press, 1969), 20. 128 Tracey Rowland Germany’s Romano Guardini; a “deprived and isolated emotivist,” the assessment of Alasdair MacIntyre; a “micro-cosmic tragedy,” the term used by the Slovakian Charter 77 anti-Communist activist Rudolf Battek; a person with a weak or fractured sense of self-identity who “doesn’t know which team he is playing on,” the assessment of the Czech writer and politician Vaclav Havel; a Hobbesian egoist, the label of the English philosopher John Gray; and a new type of barbarian, the conclusion of the Czech philosopher Erazim Kohak, to mention just a few of the descriptions.4 When one adds the Nietzschean definitions as someone with a “small soul” and “herd-like morality” and communitarian criticisms of the “rootless cosmopolitan”—a being without any historical memory, and without loyalties to any traditions—one rapidly reaches the conclusion that the depiction of anyone as a “modern” and the endorsement of the culture of modernity as the natural habitat of these neobarbaric microcosmic tragedies carries strong negative connotations. This is not only so for Catholic scholars, but for Heideggerians like Havel and members of the Frankfurt school like Marcuse. To use the language of marketing managers, modernity is toxic. Whether one is correlating or recontextualizing, either way, it is something else that is positioning the faith, in effect, something else that is positioning Christ.5 One might say that if ontotheology is bad (allowing philosophy to position revelation), then zeitgeist theology is even worse. There is a huge difference between using contemporary cultural trends as a standard for the analysis of revelation and using revelation as 4 Herbert Marcuse, One Dimensional Man (Boston: Beacon Press, 1964); Jozef Zverina as quoted by Rudolf Battek, “Spiritual values, independent initiatives and politics,” in The Power of the Powerless, ed. John Keane (London: Hutchinson, 1985), 97–99; Romano Guardini, The End of the Modern World (London: Sheed & Ward, 1957); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (London: Duckworth, 1981); Vaclav Havel, “Politics and Conscience,” Salisbury Review (January 1985); John Gray, Liberalism (London: Open University Press, 1986); Erazim Kohak, The Embers and the Stars: A Philosophical Inquiry into the Moral Sense of Nature (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984). 5 “I have argued in The Priority of Christ that Jesus and the doctrines and narratives surrounding him must have epistemic primacy, that is, to say, they cannot be interpreted or positioned by anything outside of themselves.” Robert Barron, The Priority of Christ: Toward a Post-Liberal Catholicism (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos Press, 2007), 341. The Humanism of the Incarnation 129 a lens through which to read and judge contemporary cultural trends. Arguably, it is these alternative ways of engaging with the spirit of the times that determine whether one is a liberal or nonliberal theologian. All of the authors addressed in this essay share the quality of being nonliberal theologians. They are also all strongly Christocentric. The question to be posed is: what is their vision of a Christian humanism, or, to use Ratzinger’s expression, the “humanism of the Incarnation”? My macrolevel observation is that there seems to be broad agreement on two fundamental principles: first, that any humanism of the Incarnation presupposes a theology of creation and a theology of the Cross and is set within these two poles. The second principle is that, in relation to the Incarnation itself, Christology becomes the all-important point of reference. These two principles appear to apply across the various faith traditions. This means in turn that to do justice to this topic, one needs to be across the Christology of the authors surveyed, and this in turn means being across their Trinitarian theology and then applying both to their understanding of the relationship between Christ and humanity and human culture. The topic is therefore sufficiently deep to justify a doctoral-level analysis and thus what follows in this essay is merely a typical first chapter of a doctorate literature review. It is nonetheless important because if there is to be an ecumenical united front against the forces of atheism and its culture of death, then it helps to understand not only what we are all against but also, positively, what we all want to foster. In an article on the interventions of Cardinal Josef Frings in the debates of the Second Vatican Council, Joseph Ratzinger observed that Frings was keen to emphasize one general principle: For the Christian life in the world three revealed truths are always to be kept before us: creation, which teaches us to love the things of the world as God’s work; the Incarnation, which spurs us on to dedicate to God all the things of the world; the cross and resurrection, which leads us in the imitation of Christ to sacrifice and continence with regard to the things of the world.6 6 Joseph Ratzinger, “Frings’s Speeches during the Second Vatican Council: Apropos of A. Muggeridge’s The Desolate City,” Communio: International Catholic Review, 15, 130 Tracey Rowland An almost identical point was made in a summary of the position of Dietrich Bonhoffer by Jens Zimmermann, who wrote: In Jesus Christ we believe in the God who becomes human; was crucified, and is risen. In the becoming human we recognise God’s love towards God’s creation, in the crucifixion God’s judgement of all flesh, and in the resurrection God’s purpose for a new world. Nothing could be more perverse than to tear these three apart because the whole is contained in each of them.7 Consistent with Frings, Ratzinger, Bonhoffer, and Zimmermann, Abbot Christopher Butler made the point that Christian eschatology and Christian incarnationalism are not mutually exclusive and that the division identified by Léopold Malevez between the two—that is, between the incarnational and eschatological approach to history—should not be a real division but rather two poles held in tension. Butler wrote: Eschatology without Incarnation is not Christian at all, but Jewish. Incarnation without eschatology is—I know not what; Buddhism, perhaps, or Platonism. Born within the Jewish tradition and of Jewish spiritual stock, Christianity has been eschatological from the beginning . . . But its novelty was not that it simply lodged the idea of incarnation within an eschatological framework, but that it proclaimed a real, “mystical,” “sacramental” anticipation of the Last Things as the unique gift that God was bestowing on man in the Gospel—and of this real anticipation the Incarnation is the epitome and the fountainhead . . . Incarnation, for us, is eschatological, and eschatology is incarnated.8 The confessional difficulty here of course is found in the phrase “sacramental anticipation of the Last Things.” Not all Christian faith traditions will agree that the humanism of the Incarnation is something rooted in a sacramental ontology. This seems to be the neuralgic point no. 1 (1988): 131–47. Jens Zimmermann, Incarnational Humanism: A Philosophy of Culture for the Church in the World (Downers Grove, IL: Intervarsity Press, 2012), 273. 8 Butler, “Value of History,” 294. 7 The Humanism of the Incarnation 131 of dispute between the Catholic and Protestant visions, and this has been the subject of some acute comments by Charles Journet. In his work The Primacy of Peter, Journet distinguished between two different concepts of Christianity: one typical of Protestant theology and one typical of Catholic theology. The first he described as the mnemic concept, the second the ontological concept. The difference between the two is presented as a difference over the way in which the presence of Christ constitutes Christianity: On the one hand there is the spirituality of the Incarnation, or in a broader sense the spirituality of the transfiguration of matter by the spirit. This is the Catholic form of spirituality with its doctrine of the Incarnation, the instrumental causality of the sacraments, of the New Law, the visibility of the Church, the resurrection of the flesh, the immediate creation of visible things by God himself, etc. On the other hand, we have a sort of spirituality of disincarnation, or in a broader sense a spirituality of the separation of matter and spirit. On a more metaphysical plane we may see the opposition as one between a dogmatic view of the analogy of being, in accordance with which the divine privileges, especially divine sanctity, can be communicated analogically to creatures—as existence once was—without affecting adversely the divine transcendence, but rather manifesting it. On the other hand we have a dogmatic view of the uniqueness of being, which can only safeguard the divine transcendence by denying any possibility for the divine privileges to be communicated, especially divine sanctity: either a) to the humanity of Christ because of the fear of Monophysitism, or b) to creatures because of the fear of idolatry.9 According to Journet, in the Protestant account, Christ is only present in time by way of signs, tokens, and promises—which from a Catholic point of view is a kind of nostalgic return to the Old Testa9 Charles Journet, The Primacy of Peter (Westminster MD: Newman Press: 1954), 36–37. 132 Tracey Rowland ment—whereas, according to the Catholic account, Christ is really and truly present in time under the guise of signs, tokens, and promises. Journet suggests that Protestantism makes the error of considering the two natures of Christ side by side such that the human nature of Christ becomes “simply an occasion of our salvation, a mere phenomenal shell, in which the invisible God made his appearance.”10 While Journet does not distinguish between different Protestant traditions but lumps them all together and comes rather close to describing Protestant Christology as Nestorian, in another work, The Sense of the Supernatural, Jean Borella specifically indicted the Lutheran tradition on the charge of monothelitism in the sense that human nature becomes a pure instrument of divine nature, without autonomy. Borella wrote: Basically, and whatever may have been his [Luther’s] good intentions, [his] thesis rests on the radical incompatibility of nature and grace, or rather on the irreducible opposition and the mutual exclusion of the natural and supernatural orders, which grace comes to reconcile specifically, since this grace always flows from the unique hypostasis of Christ in which divinity has been united to humanity. Here, to the contrary, [that is, in the Lutheran tradition] supernature can only work by destroying nature . . . Into the heart of every Christian it introduces an insurmountable separation between what stems from the creature and what stems from the redemptive act … What disappears in this way is the “immanence of grace” of Christ the Redeemer in his creation; that is, the sacramental and ritual order, the ecclesial order, the Mystical Body, all of this sacralising of the earthly and the human cosmos which is the Incarnation prolonged, spread abroad and communicated, as the image of the first fruits of the “new heaven and the new earth.”11 Although Borella was directing his comments to the Lutheran tradition, they would seem to apply equally to the theological vision of Barth. For Barth it is Christ, not the Church, who mediates the presence of God 10 11 Ibid., 33. Jean Borella, The Sense of the Supernatural (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1998), 154. The Humanism of the Incarnation 133 to the world. As Rodney Howsare expresses the point, “missing [from Barth] is the more Eastern understanding that God unites himself, in the Incarnation, to all human nature, thereby transforming the capacities of that nature. This comes out most clearly in Barth’s understanding of the Church, the liturgy and the sacraments.”12 By reducing everything to God’s activity in Christ on behalf of the world, Barth does not give the same attention and emphasis to the role of the Church in carrying this love into the world as Catholic theologians typically do. Missing from Barth’s picture is a notion of the Church as itself a sacrament.13 Barth is generally believed to have held a neo-Zwinglian position on the sacraments, or at least, that is the strong impression he gives in his Church Dogmatics IV/4. For Barth, both baptism and the Lord’s Supper are human actions, not sacraments. Louis-Marie Chauvet argues that Barth’s Christology already bears within itself its nonsacramental theology. Chauvet remarks that there are few theologies that speak so much of events and history, and yet there are few theologies where so little takes place on the properly historical plane.14 It was perhaps for these reasons that Hans Urs von Balthasar accused Barth of reducing the order of creation to the order of grace.15 In Balthasar’s words: If revelation is centered in Jesus Christ, there must be by definition a periphery to this center. Thus, as we say, the order of the Incarnation presupposes the order of creation, which is not identical with it. And, because the order of creation is oriented to the order of the Incarnation, it is structured in view of the Incarnation: it contains images, as it were, dispositions, which in a true sense are the presuppositions for the Incarnation.16 12 Rodney A. Howsare, Hans Urs von Balthasar: The Ecumenical Implications of His Theological Style (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 2005), 97. 13 Ibid., 92. 14 Louis-Marie Chauvet, Symbol and Sacrament: A Sacramental Reinterpretation of Christian Existence (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1995), 540. 15 Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Theology of Karl Barth (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1992), 136. 16 Ibid., 163. 134 Tracey Rowland In other words, the idea is that the grace available through Jesus Christ does not stand in contradiction to, but in line with, the grace found in nature by virtue of God’s act of creation. Michael Schmaus, a professor of the theology faculty in Munich during Ratzinger’s student years, expressed the general Catholic idea like this: Man exists, not in himself, but for God. By directing himself in free decision and responsibility to God, he acts according to his ontic constitution, he acts in the way appropriate to his essence and thus comes to fulfil and perfect his being. Only when God draws him into his own triune life does man find his own deepest being; his ontic determination is a copy of God’s tri-personal life. Thus man comes to discover himself in the divine Thou when God imparts himself to him supernaturally. This communication of God’s happens in and through Christ. The relationship to Christ is therefore contained in the relationship of the creature to God . . . The whole of the rest of creation is meant to exist for the sake of the Incarnation of Christ. Thus the whole of creation comes to its essential fulfilment only through him.17 Ratzinger’s own most extensive and unbuttoned treatment of this topic can be found in an article published in 1969 in Herbert Vorgrimler’s Commentaries on the Documents of the Second Vatican Council. The article analyzed the treatment of human dignity in Gaudium et spes—the Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern World. Ratzinger’s assessment of this document was largely negative. He, along with fellow German Cardinal Walter Kasper, have both suggested that the first section of the document was never properly integrated with the second. The first section offers an account of the human person as made in God’s image, but it is only when one gets to paragraph 22 that the picture is complicated by the introduction of the Trinity. Ratzinger argued that the first section fostered the fiction that it is possible to construct a rational philosophical picture of man intelligible to all and on which all men of goodwill can agree, the actual Christian doctrines being added to this as a sort of crowning conclusion. This approach prompted the question of 17 Michael Schmaus, Katholische Dogmatik II (Munich: Max Hueber, 1949), 70–72. The Humanism of the Incarnation 135 “why exactly the reasonable and perfectly free human being described in the first articles was suddenly burdened with the story of Christ.”18 Notwithstanding this criticism and Ratzinger’s description of the language used in the paragraph about human freedom as being downright Pelagian, Ratzinger nonetheless strongly praised paragraph 22, which was to become the most often quoted paragraph of all the documents of the Second Vatican Council by John Paul II. He said that in paragraph 22 the idea of Christ’s assumption of human nature is touched upon in its full ontological depth: The human nature of all men is one; Christ’s taking to himself the one human nature of man is an event which affects every human being; consequently human nature in every human being is henceforward Christologically characterised. Ratzinger went on to say that this outlook is important because it opens a bridge between the theology of the Incarnation and that of the Cross: A theology of the incarnation situated too much on the level of essence, may be tempted to be satisfied with the ontological phenomenon: God’s being and man’s have been conjoined . . . But since it is made clear that man’s being is not that of a pure essence, and that he only attains his reality by his activity, it is at once evident that we cannot rest content with a purely essentialist outlook. Man’s being must therefore be examined precisely in its activities.19 Here Ratzinger is opening up what in other places he has referred to as the mediation of history in the realm of ontology. Both he and Karol Wojtyła converge in their interest in the uniqueness of human persons caused by their particular location within history. For this reason they share a mutual interest in what is called relationality, or that dimension of the human person who is determined by his or her relations with oth18 19 Ibid., 120. Joseph Ratzinger, “The Dignity of the Human Person,” in Commentary on the Documents of the Second Vatican Council, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler (London: Burns and Oates, 1969), 160. 136 Tracey Rowland er persons, including the Persons of the Holy Trinity. In another essay on the notion of the human person published during the pontificate of John Paul II, Ratzinger was critical of the Boethian definition of the person as the individual substance of a rational nature because it neglected the whole dimension of relationality, which makes human persons not merely members of the human race but unique individual members of the human race.20 Both Wojtyła and Ratzinger were driven to develop this dimension of Catholic anthropology as a response to issues thrown up by existentialist philosophy. A theology that has nothing to say about individuality is impotent against the power of nineteenth-century German Romanticism and its twentieth-century developments. Ratzinger believes that the uniqueness of Christian culture is rooted in the Incarnation and that all of its specific characteristics disintegrate when this belief is eclipsed.21 The Incarnation means that the invisible God enters into the visible world so that those who are bound to matter can know him. The International Theological Commission under Ratzinger’s leadership expressed the position this way: In the last times inaugurated at Pentecost, the risen Christ, Alpha and Omega, enters into the history of peoples: from that moment, the sense of history and thus of culture is unsealed and the Holy Spirit reveals it by actualizing and communicating it to all. The Church is the sacrament of this revelation and its communication. It recenters every culture into which Christ is received, placing it in the axis of the world which is coming, and restores the union broken by the Prince of this world. Culture is thus eschatologically situated; it tends towards its completion in Christ, but it cannot be saved except by associating itself with the repudiation of evil.22 In this paragraph one finds all the key elements of a Catholic Incarnational humanism and its associate culture: the Incarnation restores 20 Joseph Ratzinger, “Concerning the Notion of Person in Theology,” Communio: International Catholic Review 17, no. 3 (1990): 439–54. 21 Joseph Ratzinger, Co-Workers of the Truth (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1992), 18–19. 22 International Theological Commission, “Faith and Inculturation,” Origins 18 (1989): 800–807. The Humanism of the Incarnation 137 the union broken by Satan at the time of the Fall, it recenters culture eschatologically—that is, with a view to the return of Christ in glory and consummation of the world—but this does not happen automatically. There needs to be a repudiation of evil and thus the potentiality of the Incarnation stands always under the shadow of the Cross. The Holy Spirit and the Church are responsible for the communication of the possibilities thrown open by the Incarnation to the world. For the development of a more detailed Catholic Christocentric Trinitarian anthropology, one can have recourse to John Paul II”s encyclicals Redemptor Hominis (1979), Dives in Misericordia (1980), and Dominum et Vivificantem (1986). Known as his Trinitarian triptych, each of these encyclicals addressed the issue of the human person’s relationship with one of the Persons of the Holy Trinity. Included in this Trinitarian anthropology is the notion that the Incarnation opened up the possibility of participation in the very life of God. John Paul II stated this explicitly in Dives in Misericordia 7:4. Often this idea is expressed by the idea of the nuptial mystery. Paragraph 27 of Pope Benedict’s Apostolic Exhortation Sacramentum Caritatis offers an extensive presentation of the links between Eucharistic theology and the nuptial mystery in the following terms: The Eucharist, as the sacrament of charity, has a particular relationship with the love of man and woman united in marriage . . . “the entire Christian life bears the mark of the spousal love of Christ and the Church. Already Baptism, the entry into the People of God, is a nuptial mystery; it is so to speak the nuptial bath which precedes the wedding feast, the Eucharist” . . . By the power of the sacrament, the marriage bond is intrinsically linked to the eucharistic unity of Christ the Bridegroom and his Bride, the Church (cf. Eph 5:31–32). The mutual consent that husband and wife exchange in Christ, which establishes them as a community of life and love, also has a eucharistic dimension. Indeed, in the theology of Saint Paul, conjugal love is a sacramental sign of Christ’s love for his Church, a love culminating in the Cross, the expression of his “marriage” with humanity and at the same time the origin and heart of the Eucharist. 138 Tracey Rowland These themes have been amplified in the theology of Cardinal Marc Ouellet, who understands the sacrament of marriage, including the exchange of love between husband and wife, as the couple’s participation in the exchange of “gifts” between the divine Persons: God’s covenant with Israel and humanity is the story of a wedding. The symbol par excellence of the biblical revelation is conjugal love. A couple stands at the beginning of salvation history and another at its conclusion: Adam and Eve set the history of humanity in motion, while the Lamb and his Bride, who descends from God in heaven, concludes the adventure of historical time. In the span of time between the initial couple and the eschatological couple, the Holy Spirit implores and summons; he prays for the final fulfillment together with the Bride whom he has called.23 Salvation history is [thus] a spousal drama of Trinitarian revelation . . . The Father sends his Son as the Bridegroom, accompanied by the Holy Spirit, who prepares the bride for the encounter with the Bridegroom and the fulfilment of the eschatological wedding.24 Prepared by the Holy Spirit since the beginning of creation, the messianic wedding is celebrated on the altar of the Cross. It is precisely there that the nuptial chamber receives the sacrum commercium et conubium.25 Ouellet concludes that the Paschal event contains at once a Trinitarian and spousal meaning: A Trinitarian meaning, since the resurrection seals in the economy the unity of love which was sealed by the Holy Spirit’s procession in the immanent Trinity: a spousal meaning, because 23 Marc Ouellet, Divine Likeness: Towards a Trinitarian Anthropology of the Family (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2006), 80. 24 Ibid., 80–81. 25 Ibid., 85. The Humanism of the Incarnation 139 this anointing confirmation seals the fecund gift of the risen one as the eschatological Bridegroom who generates his bride.26 These notions of a spousal relation between Christ and the Church and of divine filiation via sacramental participation in the life and love of the Trinity are elements found in most Catholic accounts of the humanism of the Incarnation but are usually missing from Protestant accounts, and in particular are missing in Barth. In his book Karl Barth’s Theology of Culture, Robert J. Palma speaks of Barth’s “parabolic relationship between the worldly and the heavenly, the human the divine, the transitory and the eternal.”27 Thus, we might say, in shorthand terms, there is a tendency for Catholic theologians to describe the union between the human person and the Persons of the Holy Trinity using the idioms of nuptial mysticism, while there is a tendency for Protestants to shy away from this and adopt a more modest notion of a parabolic relationship. For Barth the eschatological Word to which Christianity looks forward relativizes all historical possibilities and achievements. Though his later theology expressed the point more gently, Barth never retracted his early claim that only a thoroughly eschatological Christianity bears any relationship to Christ.28 The difference in the area of sacramental theology also means that Protestants and Catholics tend to have a different attitude to matter itself, including the human body. The Catholic cult of the saints and practice of collecting and venerating the relics of the saints is the most obvious example of this difference. Theologically, the issue is one of understanding precisely how it is that Christ unites himself to humanity. That Christ was not some kind of ontological exception, but that his Incarnation affected all postlapsarian human nature in some way, comes across strongly in John Paul II’s encyclical Dominum et Vivificantem. At paragraph 50 he wrote: 26 Ibid., 87. Robert J. Palma, Karl Barth’s Theology of Culture (Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 1983), 2. 28 Gary Dorrien, “The ‘Postmodern’ Barth? The Word of God as True Myth,” Christian Century (April 2, 1997): 338–42. 27 140 Tracey Rowland The Incarnation of God the Son signifies the taking up into the unity with God not only of human nature, but in this human nature, in a sense, of everything that is “flesh”: the whole of humanity, the entire visible and material world. The Incarnation then, also has a cosmic significance, a cosmic dimension. The “first-born of all creation,” becoming incarnate in the individual humanity of Christ, unites himself in some way with the entire reality of man, which is “flesh”—and in this reality with all “flesh,” with the whole of creation. This Catholic take on the Incarnation would seem to affect not only issues like how we treat the dead bodies of the saints but also attitudes to art and culture more generally. In a reflection on the earliest disputes within the Church about art and beauty, Ratzinger observed that “iconoclasm rests on a one-sided apophatic theology, which recognizes only the Wholly Other-ness of the God beyond all images and words, a theology that in the final analysis regards revelation as the inadequate human reflection of what is eternally imperceptible.”29 He concluded that “what seems like the highest humility toward God turns into pride, allowing God no word and permitting him no real entry into history . . . matter is absolutized and thought of as completely impervious to God, as mere matter, and thus deprived of its dignity.”30 This notion of the receptivity of matter to some form of divinization reaches its most dramatic expression in paragraph 11 of Pope Benedict’s Apostolic Exhortation Sacramentum Caritatis, wherein he stated that: The substantial conversion of bread and wine into [Christ’s] body and blood introduces within creation the principle of a radical change, a sort of “nuclear fission,” which penetrates to the heart of all being, a change meant to set off a process which transforms reality, a process leading ultimately to the transfiguration of the entire world, to the point where God will be all in all (cf. 1 Cor 15:28). 29 30 Joseph Ratzinger, The Spirit of the Liturgy (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2000), 124. Ibid. The Humanism of the Incarnation 141 The theology of Teilhard de Chardin—in particular the idea that as we move through history matter itself becomes more and more conformed to Christ until we reach the Noosphere, as he called it—has never received magisterial endorsement, but the fact that a significant Catholic theologian could speculate in this way is evidence of the depth of Catholic interest in the topic of what it means exactly for the world to be transfigured to a point where God will be all in all. In addition to the different stances toward sacramental theology and the theological meaning of the first chapter of St. Paul’s Letter to the Corinthians, Ratzinger’s humanism of the Incarnation also differs from Barth’s in that he believes that Mariology has something to contribute to this topic. In this context he has written: Mariology is an essential component of a hermeneutics of salvation history. Recognition of this fact brings out the true dimensions of Christology over against a falsely understood solus Christus (Christ alone). Christology must speak of a Christ who is both “head and body,” that is, who comprises the redeemed creation in its relative subsistence (Selbständigkeit). But this move simultaneously enlarges our perspective beyond the history of salvation, because it counters a false understanding of God’s sole agency, highlighting the reality of the creature that God calls and enables to respond to him freely. Mariology demonstrates that the doctrine of grace does not revoke creation, but is the definitive Yes to creation. In this way, Mariology guarantees the ontological independence (Eigenständigkeit) of creation, undergirds faith in creation, and crowns the doctrine of creation, rightly understood.31 The nexus between Christology and versions of Christian humanism is acknowledged in almost all the authorities who write about this topic in the work of Karl Barth, and it is the central theme of Paul Louis Metzger’s work The Word of Christ and the World of Culture: Sacred and Secular through the Theology of Karl Barth. However, there appears to be no consensus among Barth scholars about how to read Barth’s 31 Joseph Ratzinger, Mary: The Church at the Source (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2005), 31. 142 Tracey Rowland Christology. There has been a debate within the school about whether Barth was primarily an Alexandrian or an Antiochene. According to George Hunsinger of Princeton Theological Seminary, who wrote the chapter on Barth’s Christology for the Cambridge Companion to Barth, Barth does have a Chalcedonian Christology, but he arrives at it by moving back and forth dialectically between the Alexandrian and Antiochene approaches.32 According to Charles T. Waldrop, however, in Barth, “Christ’s human nature is so integrally taken up and assumed into God’s being that its purely human existence is denied. In the final analysis, the degree of independence which the human nature has is extremely slight. It serves and attests God because God determines it to be that which serves and attests him.”33 Whatever the differences between Hunsinger and Waldrop, Metzger strongly argues that for Barth there is no capacity for the divine capacity inherent in the human constitution.34 Nor if we are good Barthians should we expect to find vestiges of the Trinity within creation.35 Instead Barth invented the formula vestigia creaturae in trinitate, which emphasizes that while creatures are unable to reflect the Trinity, the Trinity has the power to reveal itself in creatures.36 The central thesis of Metzger’s work is that Barth is neither a sacramentalist nor a secularist, that he is neither a Catholic nor a liberal.37 As he expresses the idea: In Barth’s work the dedivinization of culture gives rise to the humanization of culture. This reality of dedivinisation enables culture to be the human, creaturely reality as it is intended by 32 George Hunsinger, “Karl Barth’s Christology: Its Basic Chacedonian Character,” in Disruptive Grace: Studies in the Theology of Karl Barth (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2000), 136–37. 33 Charles T. Waldrop, Karl Barth’s Christology: Its Basic Alexandrian Character (New York: Mouton, 1984), 174. 34 Paul Louis Metzger, The Word of Christ and the World of Culture: Sacred and Secular through the Theology of Karl Barth (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2003), 124n9. 35 Ibid., 200. 36 Thomas G. Dalzell, The Dramatic Encounter of Divine and Human Freedom in the Theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar (Bern: Peter Lang, 1997), 91n2. Dalzell also cited Philip Rosato, The Spirit as Lord: The Pneumatology of Karl Barth (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1981), 53–56, on this point. 37 Metzger, Word of Christ, 116. The Humanism of the Incarnation 143 God to be. And although Barth guards against the secularization of human culture by emphasising the significance of the Word for the whole of creaturely reality, not simply the sacred sphere, he is still able to give space to culture to be truly secular in light of the Word. Dedevinisation and desecularization spell humanization, which in turn spells the celebration of authentic secularity . . . his dual emphasis on the de-devinization and de-secularization of culture enables him to mediate between Christ and culture in such a way that broader culture is given the space to be truly secular in distinct though inseparable relation to the sacred, in and through the eternal Word who became flesh.38 The problem for a Catholic reading this paragraph is that it sounds precisely like it leaves the order of creation unaffected by the Incarnation, at least until the renewal of the cosmos at the end of time. For Catholics, the idea is not merely that we are saved by Christ, but that one of the fruits of redemption is the possibility of theosis or deification. The idea of a de-divinised culture sounds to Catholic ears a little like a de-alcoholized cocktail—something potentially intoxicating that has had the active ingredient removed. Although Martin D’Arcy did not have the benefit of Metzger’s research, he read Barth in a way that seems close to the judgment of Metzger—although he drew a different value judgment about it. D’Arcy wrote: Barth’s meaning is that the Redemption has restored the world and that there are reflections of this new glory to be found in the works of man and of civilisation. But the restoration belongs to another plane and will not be revealed until the last day. Till then it is hidden in God with Jesus Christ. The best that can be seen in the world is a reflection like the light reflected on a pool or mountain-side. Culture, he says, has its own worth and dignity, but it is “an exclusively earthly reflection of the Creation, which itself remains . . . lost and hidden from us.” There is “no continuity between the analogies and the divine reality, no 38 Ibid., 81 144 Tracey Rowland objective relation between what is signified and what really is; no transition, therefore, definable in terms of any progress, can be made between one and the other.” Such an inflexible verdict rules out any hope of relating heaven and earth, grace and nature. History can never be more than a pastime. When the last trumpet sounds, all the works of man will fade out; they have no bearing on what then is to be revealed.39 Jessica de Cou reads Barth in this way when she says that far too much has been made of the theological significance of Barth’s Mozart essays. She argues that when Barth wrote about Mozart he was being playful and ironic.40 He thoroughly enjoyed Mozart but thought that what human beings received from Mozart was something related to the good of play. It was something absolutely human, not divine. Hence Barth’s playful comment that the angels play Bach for God but when they are home having fun by themselves they play Mozart. Evidence for something like Martin D’Arcy’s reading of Barth can be found in Barth’s Church Dogmatics, vols. 1 and 2 (§§13–24). In these paragraphs we find the great Barthian indictment of Catholic theology on the grounds that it is obsessed with the word “and”: In all its shoots the theology which says “and” derives from one root. If you say “faith and works,” “nature and grace,” “reason and revelation,” at the appropriate place you logically and necessarily have to say “Scripture and tradition.” The “and” by which the authority of Holy Scripture is relativised in both Roman Catholicism and Neo-Protestantism is only the expression, one expression, of the fact that already the majesty of God has been relativised in His fellowship with man. And in this primary relativising both are equally remote from the Reformation decision. 39 Martin D’Arcy, The Sense of History: Secular and Sacred (London: Faber and Faber, 1959), 172–73. 40 Jessica de Cou, “Relocating Barth’s Theology of Culture: Beyond the ‘True Words’ Approach of Church Dogmatics IV/3,” International Journal of Systematic Theology 15, no. 2 (2012): 154–72. The Humanism of the Incarnation 145 Contrary to Barth, D’Arcy argued that from the Catholic point of view “nature and the supernatural action of God have been wedded together, and to divorce them is, however salutary the purpose, a desecration. The task of the Christian thinker is, therefore, to do justice to the marriage, while accepting the very different roles and even temperaments of each member.”41 Specifically, D’Arcy endorses the idea of Abbot Butler that “the period between the two comings—the Incarnation and the Last Day—has a special mark like that on the doorpost of the Israelites on the night the Egyptians were smitten.” The change effected by the Incarnation is a “prevenient grace, which prepares nature and dresses it for the time when all things shall be made new.” Moreover, “the harvest to be reaped at the end of time is homogeneous with the historical seed, and in its growth that seed exercises its mysterious, biological alchemy on the inanimate matter wherein it has been placed.”42 According to Butler, whom D’Arcy admired, for a Christian, the purpose of life should not be to “pass through it, get it over, and arrive, without baggage but personally safe,” rather the Christian should arrive “at the final customs house” “with all that he acquires along the road” and it is precisely what he has to declare that will “determine forever his enjoyment of the fatherland.”43 In D’Arcy’s words, “toys in themselves are of no account, but to children they are so dear that they take them to bed with them; and when we go to sleep and awake to everlasting joy the toys of this life may well be part of our transfigured humanity . . . What we do now prefigures what we shall do with complete happiness, even as the doll cherished by the child is the first love of the future mother.”44 Abbot Butler acknowledged that cultural achievements can be the products of sinful desires or as he expressed the idea, “embellishments not of the City of God but of Babylon.” Nonetheless, he argued that the “potentialities which they thus not only actualise but deform are potentialities of ontological man and, as such, may participate in the ‘resurrection’ of grace. They and their products are therefore susceptible of supernaturalisation and can be made to subserve the reign of God.” 41 D’Arcy, Sense of History, 173. Ibid., 182–83. 43 Butler, “Value of History,” 299. 44 D’Arcy, Sense of History, 211. 42 146 Tracey Rowland To emphasize the point he suggested that we “do not enjoy a few stray ‘advances’ upon our eventual inheritance. It is the whole of that future inheritance that is mysteriously anticipated in grace.”45 With reference to the scriptural roots of these distinctions, D’Arcy suggests that Catholics and Barthians have different interpretations of St. Paul’s Letter to the Colossians 1:20, the Father is through him [Christ] to reconcile all things in himself, and St. Paul’s Letter to Romans 8:20, the creature was made subject to vanity etc. D’Arcy also suggests that a certain ambiguity in the use of the word “world” and in the description of the city of man obscured the questions whether nature and the good works of man were condemned to vanity or could be brought into relation with the supernatural order. Not only are these differences significant at the level of what we make of our cultural achievements, but much more fundamentally they are also significant for what we make of the potentialities of a Christian humanism. Several authors argue that it is Barth’s position that one cannot deduce anthropology from Christology. This however was precisely the central project of the pontificate of John Paul II, that is, the development of a Christocentric Trinitarian theological anthropology. In contrast, Philip Rosato argued that in Barth anthropology is totally conceived of as the work of the Holy Spirit: “pneumatology replaces the concept of nature, reducing the human person to a passive bystander.”46 Rosato went so far as to assert that Barth was first and foremost a pneumatologist.47 George Hunsinger implicitly concurs with Philip J. Rosato, S.J. Hunsinger writes: The work of the Holy Spirit, as Barth saw it, is miraculous in operation. The Holy Spirit is seen as the sole effective agent (solus actor efficiens) by which communion with God is made humanly possible. In their fallen condition (status corruptionis), human beings cannot recover a vital connection with God. Their minds are darkened, their wills are enslaved, and the desires of their hearts are debased. Through the proclamation of the gos45 Butler, “Value of History,” 298–99. Rosato, Spirit as Lord, 131. 47 Ibid., 134. 46 The Humanism of the Incarnation 147 pel, however, the impossible is made possible, but only in the form of an ongoing miracle. This miracle is the operation of the Holy Spirit, not only to initiate conversion (operatio initialis), but also to continue it throughout the believer’s life (operatio perpetuo). The only condition (necessary and sufficient) for new life in communion with God is the Spirit’s miraculous operation in the human heart (operatio mirabilis). Faith in Christ, hope for the world, and consequent works of love have no other basis in nobis than this unceasing miracle of grace. Faith, hope and love, in other words, do not depend on regenerated capacities, infused virtues, acquired habits, or strengthened dispositions of the soul. Those who are awakened to lifelong conversion by the Spirit never cease to be sinners in themselves.48 Barth thereby objects to all theories that imply a “systematic co-ordination of nature and grace.”49 This rules out the Thomistic idea of a material cause cooperating with a human instrumental cause, and, as stated earlier in this essay, it rules out a sacramental ontology. In the final analysis, the distance between the Barthian and the Catholic positions is quite wide because of the fundamental differences in the areas of sacramental theology and ecclesiology and even perhaps in Trinitarian theology, where there are different understandings of the role of the Holy Spirit in the economy of salvation. Barth seems to give the Holy Spirit rather a lot more work than is normally allotted by Catholic theologians. One can only amuse oneself with the thought of what Barth would make of the nuptial mystery theology of Cardinals Marc Ouellet and Angelo Scola. Nonetheless, it is the case that the Catholic theology of the Incarnation has to be held together with a theology of the Cross at one side and a theology of creation at the other and in this sense there is a strong affinity with Barth about the importance of the theology of the Cross. An example of what goes wrong when this end of the triptych is some48 George Hunsinger, “Karl Barth’s Doctrine of the Holy Spirit,” in The Cambridge Companion to Karl Barth, ed. John Webster (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 183. 49 See for example, the treatment of these issues in Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, vol. 1 (New York: Scribner, 1955). 148 Tracey Rowland how occluded may be found in some of the loopy appropriations of John Paul II’s Wednesday audience addresses on human love. These are now popularly marketed as his theology of the body. Some commentators so emphasize the effects of the Incarnation on the redemption of human sexuality that the problem of concupiscence is completely muted. I have been told, for example, that there is a colony of hippies living somewhere in Montana and that during the summer months they have given up wearing clothes on the grounds that they are implementing John Paul II’s theology of the body principles. They have allegedly been so redeemed that lust is no longer a problem. Barth and even Teilhard de Chardin would find that problematic. Moving now from Barth, to the Dutch Reformed tradition as expressed in the thought of Abraham Kuyper, we can begin with Kuyper’s most famous line that “there is not a square inch in the whole domain of our human existence over which Christ, who is sovereign over all, does not cry ‘Mine!’”50 This statement resonates well with Catholics. Catholics have never had a problem with the idea of Christ’s sovereignty and even reserve a feast day to celebrate Christ’s kingship. In 1903 Pope Pius X wrote a whole encyclical (E supremi) on the subject of “restoring all things in Christ.” The issue between Catholics and Kuyperians is one of how this sovereignty is exercised. Kuyper believed that Catholics were right not to buy into the Lutheran “two kingdoms” concept, but he thought that the Catholic error was one of believing that Christ’s sovereignty is exercised through the Church. Instead he favored the idea that the world, so to speak, can be carved up into different social spheres such as family life and professional life, and that in each of these spheres there are particular ways of respecting the sovereignty of Christ, particular precepts to be followed, and it is individual Christians who do the following, who either honor the precepts or violate them. The basic idea of sphere sovereignty is that each sphere has its own character and each is directly under the divine rule. According to Richard Mouw, Kuyper reads Genesis 1:28—that is, the be fruitful and multiply edict—as a call to cultural activity or a “cultural mandate.” Human beings are called to flourish in the kind of par50 Abraham Kuyper, “Sphere Sovereignty,” in Abraham Kuyper: A Centennial Reader, ed. James D. Bratt (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998). The Humanism of the Incarnation 149 ticipation in created life that God intends for us. The effect of the Fall is that the modes of participation become either obedient participation or disobedient participation. Kuyper’s concept of sphere sovereignty is not synonymous with the Catholic idea of subsidiarity. Subsidiarity is a principle about decentralizing authority within spheres, it is not about the sovereignty of the spheres themselves. Nonetheless, subsidiarity is perfectly consistent with how Kuyper sees the work of individual Christians within the various spheres. Where Catholics are keen to emphasize that governments have no right to interfere with the authority of parents over the education of their children, Kuyper would agree wholeheartedly but add that the Catholic Church itself has from time to time in its history been guilty of similar incursions into spheres beyond its competence. Anyone who has ever worked for the Catholic Church would know that one of its problems is that people in ecclesial positions have a tendency to exercise authority in areas that are completely outside their competence. We need many more “dykes and dams,” to use Mouw’s metaphor, to make sure that people who have expertise in one field do not try to exercise it in another. There are numerous examples, but the most common are canon lawyers who try to handle public relations, and business managers who think they are bishops. In the past there were bishops who tried to use their theological authority to make judgments about scientific matters. Kuyper died before the Second Vatican Council began, but it may be argued that his idea of sphere sovereignty, or something like it, was what the Council Fathers were driving at in paragraph 36 of Gaudium et spes, which states: If by the autonomy of earthly affairs we mean that created things and societies themselves enjoy their own laws and values which must gradually be deciphered, put to use, and regulated by men, then it is entirely right to demand that autonomy. Such is not merely required by modern men, but harmonises also with the will of the Creator. For by the very circumstances of their having been created, all things are endowed with their own stability, truth, goodness, proper laws and order. 150 Tracey Rowland This paragraph, or at least the bit about all things being endowed with their own “stability, truth, goodness, proper laws and order” is a paraphrase of statements made by both Aquinas and Augustine. It is perfectly capable of a non-self-secularizing interpretation. However, the use of the word “autonomy” has given rise to a variety of interpretations, most broadly the idea that God and the supernatural realm is one thing and the world and so called secular realm is another and that the latter exists in a state of total independence from the former. In theological parlance, a relationship of total independence is said to be an “extrinsic” relationship. There have been many popularist interpretations of this paragraph that view the relationship as extrinsic. Cardinal Angelo Scola has recently complained of precisely this problem. He has lamented that there is a latent ambiguity around the interpretation of the principle of the autonomy of earthly affairs mentioned in paragraph 36 of Gaudium et spes. With reference to some of the interpretations of this paragraph, Scola suggested that it might be “right to ask if the Catholic world, called to address the great contemporary anthropological and ethical challenges, has not been co-responsible, whether by naivety, delay or lack of attention, for the current [secularist] state of things.”51 According to Scola, paragraph 36 is an acknowledgment that there is a realm of life that is the responsibility of the laity (cf. Apostolicam actuositatem 7). This seems to be close to Kuyper’s position. The most significant distinction would be that the Church reserves to herself the competence to make judgments about matters of faith and morals that may have an impact in some particular sphere. Here the ruling against the use of contraception would be the most obvious example. The communio ecclesiology of the Second Vatican Council represents a move away from a strictly juridical account of the Church, to a view that imagines the Church as a symphonic interplay of different spiritual missions, only one of which is the Petrine, the mission of ecclesial governance. In the work of von Balthasar, which represents the most extensive articulation of communio ecclesiology, the Petrine mission or the offices of pope, bishop, and priest work in communion with other missions, in 51 Angelo Scola, “El Peligro de una Falsa ‘Autonomia,’” Humanitas: Revista de Antropologia y Cultura Cristianas 66 (2012): 296–301, esp. 299. The Humanism of the Incarnation 151 particular, the Johannine mission, which stands for the contemplative vocation; the Pauline mission, which is one of prophetic utterance and evangelization; and the mission of St. James, which is one of defending the tradition and seeing that it is transmitted uncorrupted from one generation to the next. Kuyper was writing before the Second Vatican Council, and so the only Catholic Church he knew was one steeped in the ecclesiology of the post-Tridentine theologians and thus he cannot be criticized for not appreciating the complexity and nuances of the communio ecclesiology. There seems to be a strong affinity between the communio understanding of how laypeople mediate the grace of the Incarnation to the world and Kuyper’s ideas about the activity of Christians in various social spheres. Thus Mouw makes the point that Kuyper distinguishes between the Church and the Kingdom: The Kingdom . . . encompasses the believing community in all of its complex life of participation in a variety of spheres. Whenever followers of Christ are attempting to glorify God in one or another sphere of cultural interaction, they are engaged in Kingdom activity: a Christian art guild fathered for obedience in the sphere of the arts; a Christian farmer’s group gathered for obedience in the sphere of agriculture; a Christian college or university gathered for obedience in the world of teaching and research.52 Nonetheless, Kuyper was an avowed Calvinist. In his Stone Lectures on Calvinism he wrote: Calvinism is rooted in a form of religion which was peculiarly its own, and from this specific religious consciousness there was developed first a peculiar theology, then a special church-order and then a given form of political and social life, for the interpretation of the moral world-order, for the relation between nature and grace, between Christianity and the world, between church and state, and finally, for art and science.53 52 Richard J. Mouw, Abraham Kuyper: A Short and Personal Introduction (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2011), 58. 53 Abraham Kuyper, The Stone Lectures on Calvinism (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 2007), 9. 152 Tracey Rowland For Kuyper a hallmark of Calvinism is the immediate relationship between God and man. Like Barth, there is no sacramental ontology. Kuyper specifically rejected the idea of a church as a Heilsanstalt (institute of grace) and he thought that one advance of Calvinism was that it is much more pluralistic about matters of ecclesial governance structures than the Catholic tradition. Whereas Catholics have a tendency to look at the thousands of different Protestant church structures and shake their heads with paternal tenderness, Kuyper regarded this plurality as something to be affirmed and celebrated. If Kuyper is right about Calvinism being a peculiar life form, or a culture in itself, then this raises the question of how it differs from Catholicism and its life form and culture. A paradox that first comes to mind when considering this question is that whereas the Protestant emphasis is on faith alone and the Catholic tradition’s emphasis is on “faith and works,” it is the Catholic tradition that ends up with a culture that is much more contemplative, much less work oriented. Everyone agrees that there is a Protestant work ethic, but notwithstanding the efforts of George Weigel and the late Richard John Neuhaus and the whole First Things journal, a Catholic work ethic is yet to socially arrive. Transposing this into Balthasar’s communio terminology, we can say that from the Catholic point of view Calvinism represents a lopsided emphasis on the Pauline mission. There is prophetic utterance and evangelization, but there is only a very weak Petrine mission (no pope or bishops), there is no Johannine mission at all—that is, monasteries and convents for contemplatives—and only a weak Jacobite mission that is exercised through the leading scholars of the tradition. There is also no strong sense of sacramentality, no nuclear fission, no relics of saints. Sociologists have said that Calvinist cultures are bourgeois and that Catholic cultures are erotic. Their point is that Calvinists tend to be practical and efficient people, while there is an out-of-control erotic element in Catholicism. This is what produces both the Catholic saints and the Catholic nutters. It is perhaps the difference between a view of an incarnational humanism as merely parabolic contrasted with one that is nuptial. Jeremy Begbie argues that Kuyper tended to ground culture in the created order rather than in the order of redemption.54 In this sense he 54 Jeremy S. Begbie, “Creation, Christ and Culture in Dutch Neo-Calvinism,” in Christ The Humanism of the Incarnation 153 is much like Barth and thus a classical Calvinist. Other authors such as David van Drunen argue that, for Kuyper, Christ exercises sovereignty over the world as redeemer rather than as Creator.55 But even if this is so, then this means that the emphasis is tipped to the theology of the Cross, not the theology of the Incarnation. If we agree with Begbie, then we may say in summary that Kuyper puts weight on creation (which is perhaps where his openness to natural law ideas come from, though that’s another essay); that Barth puts weight on the eschaton (although the weight may have become lighter as he moved from the young Barth to the mature Barth); and that Ratzinger and other Catholic theologians put weight on the Incarnation, though of course the Incarnation remains suspended between the theology of creation and the theology of the Cross.56 Fundamentally, there are different interpretations of what St. Paul meant about restoring all things in Christ so that he may be all in all, and different interpretations of what St. Peter meant about growing in the grace and knowledge of Christ. Friedrich Nietzsche said that if Christians wanted him to believe in their redeemer, then they would have to start looking a lot more redeemed. If when people hear of Calvinism they think of the Simpsons character Ned Flanders, or if when they hear of Catholicism they think of Fr. Ted from the Irish comedy series, then there is no wonder that the world is full of Nietzscheans. The burden, from the Catholic side, is to show that a life spent participating in sacraments makes a N&V significant difference to one’s humanity. in Our Place: The Humanity of God in Christ for the Reconciliation of the World: Essays Presented to Professor James Torrance, ed. Daniel P. Thimell and Trevor A. Hart (Allison Park, PA: Pickwick, 1991), 126. 55 David van Drunen, Natural Law and the Two Kingdoms: A Study in the Development of Reformed Social Thought (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2010), esp. chap. 7. 56 Peter McGregor argues that what is sometimes called Ratzinger’s “preferential option for the Gospel of St. John” is because, at least in part, St. John emphasizes the identity of Logos and Agape and thereby draws together the theology of the Incarnation with the theology of the Cross. See Peter McGregor, “The Spiritual Theology of Joseph Ratzinger,” PhD manuscript, Australian Catholic University, 2013. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 155-180 155 Inspired Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence in the Gospel of John and Dei Verbum William M. Wright IV Duquesne University Pittsburgh, PA COMMENTING ON ORIGEN’S THEOLOGYof biblical interpretation, Henri de Lubac states that, for the great Alexandrian exegete, the spiritual understanding of Scripture “communicates the very reality of the One whose riches are unfathomable.”1 “It is,” de Lubac writes, quoting from Origen’s Homily 6 on Isaiah, “a ‘visit from Jesus.’”2 These remarks are indicative of an understanding of Scripture as a means by which the reality, the res, of Jesus himself becomes present to the faithfilled reader. This doctrinal vision wherein Christ himself becomes present to properly disposed readers of Scripture involves an understanding of Sacred Scripture as generically sacramental. Such an understanding of Scripture has deep roots in the Christian tradition. Yves Congar describes the traditional understanding in this way: “The divine Scriptures are regarded as a kind of sacrament: a grace-bearing sign that effectively realizes communion with God, and salvation, when it is used in the right conditions. These conditions are obviously spiritual: humility, pu- 1 Henri de Lubac, History and Spirit: The Understanding of Scripture according to Origen, trans. Anne Englund Nash and Juvenal Merriell (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2007 [1950]), 382. 2 Ibid., 382, quoting Origen, Homilies on Isaiah 6.3. 156 William M. Wright IV rity of heart, a true desire to seek God and a strong love of the Gospel.”3 The Second Vatican Council incorporates this traditional belief into its teaching about the nature of Sacred Scripture in Dei Verbum. The most explicit place where Dei Verbum discusses Scripture in sacramental terms is §21, which begins, “The Church has always venerated the divine Scriptures just as she venerates the body of the Lord.”4 This comparison with the Eucharist informs the paragraph’s subsequent teaching about Scripture’s normative and spiritually nourishing role in the Church’s life. Another, more subtle, instance appears in Dei Verbum §2, which discusses the “deeds and words” (gestis verbisque) in the divine economy of revelation. Within this economy, both biblical signs (verba) and signified (res) are intrinsically related to each other (intrinsece inter se connexis). In this essay, I will argue that a sacramental understanding of Scripture as a vehicle of divine presence, present in the Church Fathers and appropriated by Dei Verbum, can be found in Scripture itself, especially (though not exclusively) in the Gospel according to John. Focusing on the Resurrection narrative in John 20, I will argue that the Fourth Gospel understands itself as a vehicle of divine presence through which later generations of believers can truly encounter the risen Jesus and grow in their relationship with him in faith and love. Not only does the Fourth Gospel provide biblical warrant for thinking of Scripture in sacramental terms, but it also illumines the traditional teaching in Dei Verbum and provides substance for further theological thinking about God’s Word in the life of the Church. The Fourth Gospel as a Vehicle of Divine Presence Encountering the Risen Lord in John 20 Chapter 20 of John’s Gospel is a sequence of four scenes, which depicts the movement of several disciples to faith in the reality of Jesus as the 3 Yves Congar, O.P., The Meaning of Tradition, trans. A. N. Woodrow (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004 [1964]), 90–91. My thanks to Francis Martin for bringing this text to my attention as well as for many conversations related to this topic. 4 All citations (English and Latin) of Church documents will be taken from the texts archived at the website of the Holy See (www.vatican.va). Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 157 risen Lord.5 It does so by first narrating the discovery of the empty tomb (20:1–10) and then Resurrection appearances to Mary Magdalene (20:11–18), to the disciples on Easter Sunday night without Thomas (20:19–25), and a second appearance to the disciples, a week later, with Thomas present (20:26–29). After this Resurrection appearance to the disciples with Thomas, John provides valuable (and famous) commentary about his purposes in writing: “Now Jesus did many other signs in the presence of his disciples, which have not been written in this book. But these have been written so that you may believe that Jesus is the Christ, the Son of God, and that by believing, you may have life in his name” (20:30–31).6 The majority of Johannine scholars regard 20:30–31 as the original ending to the Gospel narrative with chapter 21 subsequently added in the Gospel’s composition history as an epilogue. However, this exegetical position deemphasizes the many connections that vv. 30–31 have with the preceding narrative material in 20:1–29. Accordingly, as Paul Minear and others have argued, these verses should be regarded primarily as the conclusion to the narrative sequence in John 20 and not to the Gospel as a whole.7 One such connection between vv. 30–31 and the preceding narrative sequence concerns the cause of faith in Jesus as the risen Lord. The narrator claims in vv. 30–31 that the written Gospel has a causal function vis-à-vis people’s faith in Jesus as the Son of God. If we take vv. 30–31 as the conclusion to the narrative sequence in John 20, then we can more readily view its claim in light of what the preceding narrative presents as the only thing that brings about the disciples’ faith in the Resurrection: a personal encounter with Jesus as the risen Lord. In short, my exegetical argument is the following: the narrative 5 I follow the four-scene division of John 20 proposed by Ignace de la Potterie, S.J., The Hour of Jesus: The Passion and Resurrection of Jesus According to John, trans. Dom G. Murray, O.S.B. (Staten Island: Alba House, 1989), 159–90. Compare with the twoscene division of John 20 in Raymond E. Brown, S.S., The Gospel According to John, 2 vols., Anchor Bible 29–29A (New York: Doubleday, 1966–70), 2.965. 6 Unless otherwise noted, all translations of the biblical text are my own. 7 For argumentation on this point, see Paul S. Minear, “The Original Functions of John 21,” Journal of Biblical Literature 102 (1983): 85–98; Edwyn Clement Hoskyns, The Fourth Gospel, ed. Francis Noel Davey (London: Faber and Faber, 1947), 550; Gail R. O’Day, The Gospel of John, The New Interpreter’s Bible 9 (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1995), 851–52, 854–55. 158 William M. Wright IV sequence in John 20 presents a personal encounter with the risen Jesus as necessary for arriving at full, Resurrection faith in him as the Lord. John himself claims in 20:30–31 that the Gospel has been written to bring about faith in Jesus as the Son of God in its audience. This narrative logic indicates that the Gospel presents itself as mediating for its audience a genuine encounter with Jesus as the risen Lord—an encounter as genuine as that of those first disciples who saw the risen Jesus in his glorified humanity. We can appreciate John’s claim that faith in Jesus as the risen Lord requires a personal encounter with him when we examine each of the four scenes in John 20 and consider all those things that do not cause, or are insufficient to cause, people to believe in the reality of the risen Jesus.8 The first of the four scenes in John 20 centers on the discovery of the empty tomb (20:1–10). The scene opens with Mary Magdalene arriving at Jesus’s tomb in the predawn darkness, which, in view of John’s use of light and dark symbolism, is indicative of her being bereft of Jesus, who is the Light of the World (8:12; 9:5). John reports that Mary “saw the stone having been taken away from the tomb” (20:1). Mary sees the opened tomb and presumably does so at a distance because there is no indication of her looking into or entering the tomb (cf. 20:11–12). Simply seeing Jesus’s open tomb from the outside is insufficient to cause faith in him, for, as the narrative itself indicates, the open tomb can be variously interpreted. Hence Mary’s conclusion that Jesus’s tomb has been the object of grave robbery: “They took the master out of the tomb, and we don’t know where they put him” (20:2). Through Mary Magdalene, John provides his audience with an external view of the empty tomb from a distance. Then, through Peter and the Beloved Disciple, he takes his audience right up to and inside Jesus’s tomb. After hearing Mary’s claim about grave robbery, Peter and the Beloved Disciple run out toward Jesus’s tomb (20:3–4). The Beloved Disciple arrives at the tomb first, but he remains outside at the tomb’s entrance. From his position at the entrance, the Beloved Disciple bends down to look inside, and he sees Jesus’s grave clothes lying within (20:5). When Peter arrives, he actually goes into the tomb, and the Gospel’s 8 Many of these points are likewise discussed in Minear, “Original Functions of John 21,” 88–89. Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 159 audience is given to see the empty tomb from the inside. As the Beloved Disciple did from the entrance, Peter sees Jesus’s grave clothes. John adds that Peter also saw the face covering, which had been on Jesus’s corpse, now folded up and in a separate place (20:6–7). Throughout this scene, John repeatedly uses verbs in the passive voice for actions performed with respect to Jesus’s tomb: the stone “having been taken away (ērmenon)” (20:2); the grave clothes “having been laid down (keimena)” (20:5); the face covering “folded up (entetuligmenon)” (20:6). This use of the divine passive is a syntactical indication that God has acted in connection with Jesus’s empty tomb.9 This general notion of divine activity probably underlies John’s claim that the Beloved Disciple, upon entering the tomb, “saw and started to believe (kai eiden kai episteusen)” (20:8). Many commentators interpret this remark to indicate that the Beloved Disciple was the first to arrive at full faith in the Risen Jesus.10 These commentators take the Greek kai eiden kai episteusen to mean simply “he saw and believed.” This interpretation is certainly in keeping with the privilege and priority accorded to the Beloved Disciple in the Fourth Gospel. For instance, the Beloved Disciple rests upon Jesus’s chest, or heart, (en tō kolpō) at the Last Supper (13:23), in a manner analogous to the Prologue’s statement that the Son is “in the Father’s heart (eis ton kolpon tou patrōs)” (1:18); the identity of Jesus’s betrayer is revealed only to the Beloved Disciple (13:25–26); he is the disciple, who witnesses the blood and water flowing from Jesus’s pierced side (19:34– 36); he outruns Peter and arrives first at Jesus’s tomb (20:4); in John 21, 9 Donatien Mollat, “La découverte du tombeau vide,” in Études johanniques (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1979), 518; referenced by Francis J. Moloney, S.D.B., The Gospel of John, Sacra Pagina 4 (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1998), 518–20. 10 E.g., C. K. Barrett, The Gospel According to St. John: An Introduction with Commentary and Notes on the Greek Text, 2nd ed. (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1978), 561, 564, 573; Richard Bauckham, The Testimony of the Beloved Disciple: Narrative, History, and Theology in the Gospel of John (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2007), 86; Brown, Gospel According to John, 987, 1001; Hoskyns, Fourth Gospel, 540; Craig S. Keener, The Gospel of John: A Commentary, 2 vols. (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 2003), 2.1184; Moloney, Gospel of John, 520–21, 523; Rudolf Schnackenburg, The Gospel According to St. John, trans. K. Smyth et al., 3 vols. (New York: Crossroad, 1968–82), 3.312. 160 William M. Wright IV he is the first to realize that the risen Jesus speaks from the seashore to the embarked disciples (21:7). However, there are two factors, which I think work against this interpretation of the Beloved Disciple as the first person in the Gospel to arrive at full Easter faith. First, when John uses the verb pisteuein in the aorist, it is often an ingressive aorist with the sense of “began to believe.”11 For example, Jesus’s disciples “began to believe in him (episteusan eis auton)” (2:11) after the miracle at the Wedding at Cana. But as especially evidenced in the Farewell Discourses, Jesus’s disciples, although positively disposed to him, have little grasp of the significance of Jesus’s words and deeds during his ministry (e.g., 13:16–14:9, 22–24; 16:16–33). Even more stark is John’s claim that a group of Jews “began to believe in him (episteusan eis auton)” (8:30) during Jesus’s teaching in Jerusalem at the Festival of Tabernacles. It is this same group of incipient believers that Jesus engages in an increasingly sharp debate in which each says the other is associated with the demonic (8:44, 48) and which culminates in the former’s attempt to kill Jesus (8:59). In these cases, the kind of faith that is spoken of has some legitimacy, but it is very imperfect. The second major factor is the narrator’s commentary in 20:9, which interprets the activity of Peter and the Beloved Disciple at the tomb: “they had not yet known the Scripture that it was necessary for him to rise from the dead.” The evangelist explicitly claims that at that time, when they saw the empty tomb and grave clothes, both Peter and the Beloved Disciple did not have a grasp of the Scriptural (and thus providential) necessity of Jesus’s Resurrection. It is because “they did yet not know” (20:9) about the Scriptural necessity of the Resurrection that these two disciples left the tomb and went back home (20:10). The Beloved Disciple may have been the first to arrive at some general notion that God was involved in Jesus’s tomb being empty. But this incipient belief should not be confused with a full, robust faith in the reality of Jesus as the risen Lord. As Gail O’Day puts it, “What the beloved disciple 11 Jn 2:11, 22–23; 4:39, 41, 53; 7:31; 8:30; 10:42; 11:45. So too Schnackenburg, Gospel According to St. John, 3.312; see F. Blass and A. Debrunner, A Greek Grammar of the New Testament, ed. Robert W. Funk (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1961), §331 (p. 171). Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 161 believes . . . is the evidence of the empty tomb . . . [His] faith is as complete as faith in the evidence of the empty tomb can be.”12 In the first scene in John 20, therefore, the evangelist presents three things, which, although related to Jesus’s Resurrection, do not of their own accord cause faith in him as the risen Lord: the open and empty tomb (whether seen from afar, up close, or inside); Jesus’s grave clothes; the face covering, which had been on Jesus’s corpse, now lying separately. The second of the four scenes, 20:11–18, centers on Mary Magdalene, who remains at the empty tomb after Peter and the Beloved Disciple have left. In this scene, John presents Mary’s movement from hopelessness and unbelief to full faith in Jesus as the risen Lord. The scene opens with Mary “crying” (klaiousa; 20:11) outside the empty tomb, a detail that recalls Jesus’s prediction at the Farewell Discourse that his disciples will “cry” (klausete) when they no longer see him (16:20). Like the Beloved Disciple, Mary looks inside the tomb from its threshold. Unlike the Beloved Disciple and even more dramatically, Mary sees two angels seated on the slab where Jesus’s corpse had been (20:13). Astonishingly, Mary is completely unmoved by this angelophany. When the angels ask about her weeping, Mary gives basically the same response, which she had previously given to Peter and the Beloved Disciple: “they took my master away, and I do not know where they put him” (20:13; cf. 20:2).13 Mary remains fixed in her belief that Jesus’s corpse has been stolen, and not even the appearance of two angels in the empty tomb can shake this belief. After speaking to the angels, Mary turns around to see the risen Jesus, whom she does not recognize, mistaking him for the gardener (20:14–15). Jesus puts the same question to Mary as the angels did, “Woman, why are you weeping?” and his address to her as “woman” (gunai) is significant. The three other occasions in John where Jesus uses 12 O’Day, Gospel of John, 841. Similarly, Minear interprets the various things in Jn 20 that are insufficient to cause faith in the Risen Jesus (e.g., the empty tomb, the grave clothes, the angels in the tomb) as the “many other signs [which Jesus did] in the presence of his disciples” spoken of in 20:30. “Original Functions,” 88–89. 13 There is a shift in Mary’s use from the first-person plural pronouns in 20:2 (we don’t know where they put him) to the first person in 20:13 (I don’t know where they put him). This shift to the first person in 20:13 reinforces that 20:11–18 concerns Mary Magdalene’s personal relationship with Jesus. So noted in de la Potterie, Hour of Jesus, 171. 162 William M. Wright IV “woman” in the vocative (2:4; 4:21; 19:26) all appear in situations wherein Jesus is establishing a new relationship between a specific female (e.g., his mother, the Samaritan woman) and another individual, either himself or the Beloved Disciple.14 Jesus adds, “Whom are you looking for?” a question that both recalls his first words to his disciples in 1:38 and picks up on Mary’s present search for Jesus. Mary responds by reiterating her belief that Jesus’s corpse has been stolen and offers to take custody of it (20:15). The key point here is that Mary’s attention remains fixed in the past: she believes that Jesus is still dead and his corpse is missing. It is only when Jesus calls her name “Mary” (20:16), as the Good Shepherd calls his own sheep by name (10:3), that she becomes alerted to his presence. But even this new awareness that Jesus is now alive, does not constitute full faith in his Resurrection. Mary responds to Jesus by calling him “Rabbouni” (20:16), a title that is appropriate to his earthly ministry when he was her teacher and master (cf. 13:13–14), and the text implies that Mary also embraces Jesus as such (cf. Mt 28:9). Mary now believes that Jesus is alive, but she continues to relate to him as she did previously, that is, as her teacher and master. This way of relating to Jesus, however, is no longer possible after the Resurrection. Hence Jesus tells Mary to stop touching him, and he then provides the reason: “I have not yet ascended to the Father” (20:17). Throughout the Gospel, Jesus teaches that he has been sent by the Father and offers the gift of eternal life to those who believe in him (3:15–16, 36; 6:40, 47). The Prologue articulates this anthropological aspect to salvation in the language of family relations: he gave them “the power to become children of God” (1:13). For John, eternal life 14 Jesus’s first address to his mother as “woman” (2:4) occurs within a narrative dynamic wherein, as Francis Martin puts it, “the relation between Jesus and his mother is founded, not on the ties of human birth, but on the nature of Jesus’ mission as determined by the Father”; citation from Francis Martin, “Mary in Sacred Scripture: An Ecumenical Reflection,” The Thomist 72 (2008): 538. For further argumentation, see B. F. Westcott, The Gospel According to St. John (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1954), 36–37; Albert Vanhoye, “Interrogation johannique et exégèse de Cana (Jn 2, 4),” Biblica 55 (1974): 163–67. In 4:21, Jesus moves the relationship between himself and the Samaritan woman from within the horizon of extant Jewish-Samaritan relations (4:7–10) to the community of the messianic age, which he establishes (4:21–26). In 19:26–27, Jesus reveals the bonds of spiritual maternity and childhood between his mother and the Beloved Disciple by referring to the former as “mother” of the latter, her “son.” Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 163 consists in becoming a child of God. This is a participatory share in Jesus’s own relationship to the Father as the Son. Through his death, Resurrection, and entrance into the Father’s glory, Jesus establishes this new relationship between the disciples and the Father. This point is articulated in 20:17 through the use of family language in the words of the risen Jesus to Mary Magdalene. For the first time in the Gospel, Jesus refers to his disciples as his “brothers,” implying that Jesus and his disciples now relate to the same Father as sons. This point is even clearer in the message, which the risen Jesus entrusts to Mary to deliver to his brothers: “I am ascending to My Father and your Father, My God and your God” (20:17). The risen Jesus thus teaches that he opens up the divine communion to his disciples, who can now relate to the Father in a new way by participating in Jesus’s own life and identity as the Son. As de la Potterie observes, with the recognition of this new relationship with the Father and the Son, Mary Magdalene makes the characteristic declaration of having arrived at full faith in the reality of the risen Jesus: “I have seen the Lord” (20:18).15 Mary no longer relates to Jesus simply as teacher or master, but now as “Lord,” as sharing the identity of YHWH himself.16 Over the course of this second scene, we see Mary’s movement in faith from being fixated on the past—either her belief that Jesus is dead or her relating to him as she previously did—to a present encounter with Him as the risen Lord. A knowledge and relationship with Jesus during his mortal life is insufficient to cause faith in him as the Son of God. It is only when Mary personally encounters the risen Jesus as the one who has opened up the divine communion to believers, that she can confess him as “the Lord.” The last two scenes in the sequence of John 20 concern the appearances of the risen Jesus to his disciples on Easter Sunday evening without Thomas (20:19–25) and then to the disciples on the following Sunday evening with Thomas present (20:26–29). The numerous points of contact between these two scenes (not least of which is the presence or 15 16 De la Potterie, Hour of Jesus, 162–65, 174–75. I draw here on the divine identity Christology set forth in Richard Bauckham, Jesus and the God of Israel: God Crucified and Other Studies on the New Testament’s Christology of Divine Identity (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008). 164 William M. Wright IV absence of Thomas) suggest that John invites his audience to read these scenes in light of each other. Two points, which emerge from these scenes, are especially germane to this study. First, these two scenes reinforce the claim that only a personal encounter with the risen Jesus brings about faith in him as the Lord. Second, a personal encounter with Jesus as the risen Lord is not limited to seeing him in his glorified humanity. Several narrative indicators provide further support to the theological claim already articulated in the previous scene with Mary Magdalene—only a personal encounter with the risen Jesus causes faith in him as Lord. These can be appreciated by comparing the states of the disciples before and after their encountering the risen Jesus. The third scene opens with the narrator stating, “the doors were locked where the disciples were out of fear of ‘the Jews’” (20:19). John uses the same language to open the fourth scene, but with a significant omission. The narrator says, “the doors were locked” (20:26), but there is no mention of the disciples being afraid. The disciples’ encounter with the risen Jesus on Easter Sunday evening has caused a definite change in them: it has removed their fear. This change in the disciples’ status comes to light in other ways. When the risen Jesus appears to the disciples and shows them his pierced hands and side, the narrator reports that the disciples “rejoiced when they saw the Lord” (20:20). The mention of “rejoicing” (chairein) recalls the words of Jesus in the Farewell Discourse: “Now you are full of grief. But I will see you again, and your hearts will rejoice (charēsetai) and no one will take your joy away from you” (16:22). As Jesus predicted in 16:20, the disciples’ “grief [has] become joy.” After their encounter with the risen Jesus, the disciples declare their Resurrection faith to the now-present Thomas with the same language that Mary Magdalene had used in 20:18: “We have seen the Lord” (20:25)—with the verb hōran in the perfect tense. In the fourth scene, when Thomas encounters the Risen Jesus, he confesses Him as “My Lord and my God” (20:28), perhaps echoing the Scriptural name YHWH ‘elohim. Once again, this confession of Easter faith is articulated with the verb hōran in the perfect tense, although in Thomas’s case appears in the words of Jesus to Thomas: “You have believed because you have seen me (heōrakas).” In both cases, the disciples’ personal encounter with the risen Jesus has led them to confess Jesus as the Lord, as kyrios. Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 165 However, John is also quick to affirm that such a personal encounter with Jesus as the risen Lord is not limited to a direct, tangible encounter with his glorified humanity as in a Resurrection appearance. This point especially comes to light in the fourth scene where the risen Jesus appears to Thomas, a scene that segues into the narrator’s remarks about his purposes in writing the Gospel in 20:30–31. When Thomas protests the disciples’ confession “We have seen the Lord” (20:25), he sets up a direct, tangible encounter with the risen Jesus a necessary condition for his belief. John underscores this point through the extensive use of both somatic and sensory language in the condition of Thomas’s protest: “Unless I see the mark of the nails in his hands and put my finger into the mark of the nails and my hand into his side” (20:25). For Thomas, the necessity of a direct, tangible encounter with the glorified humanity of the risen Jesus as a prerequisite for faith is reinforced with the emphatic negative in the apodosis: ou mē pisteusō “I will never believe” (20:25).17 When the risen Jesus appears to the disciples with Thomas present, Jesus grants Thomas what he has requested: a direct, tangible encounter. Jesus’s invitation to Thomas repeats much of the same somatic and sensory language from Thomas’s initial protest (20:25): “Bring your finger here and see my hands. Bring your hand and put it into my side. Stop being an unbeliever, but (become) a believer.” However, there is no indication (either stated or implied) that Thomas ever touches Jesus’s glorified body. The personal encounter with the risen Jesus and his direct address to Thomas prove sufficient for Thomas to confess, “My Lord and my God” (20:28). Thomas has come to believe in Jesus as the risen Lord on account of his personal encounter with him, but a tangible experience of Jesus’s glorified humanity has also shown itself to be unnecessary for this faith. Jesus makes this point clear in his concluding beatitude: “Blessed are those who have not seen and believe” (20:29). This beatitude opens up the narrative’s scope beyond itself and looks toward future generations of believers who will believe in Jesus as the risen Lord without literally seeing him in his glorified humanity. By pronouncing them to be “blessed,” the risen Jesus indicates that the faith of 17 Thomas’s protest in 20:25 is articulated as a future-more-vivid condition, which provides additional, syntactical emphasis. 166 William M. Wright IV these future believers is no less genuine than that of those first disciples who literally “have seen the Lord” (20:25). With the scope having been so opened and the genuineness of future believers’ faith affirmed, the narrative sequence comes to rest by specifying the means by which later generations of believers will encounter the reality of the risen Jesus and come to believe in him as the Lord: through “these things [that] have been written” (20:31). This notice in 20:31 has been prepared for by previous statements, which look beyond the Gospel’s own narrative horizon to future generations of believers. During the Good Shepherd discourse, Jesus declares that he has sheep, which are “not from this fold” (likely an allusion to future, Gentile believers), and these sheep “will hear my voice” (10:16). Similarly, in his prayer of intercession in John 17, Jesus prays for all his disciples both present and future. Jesus specifically designates the latter as those “who will believe in me through their [i.e., his disciples’] word” (17:20). When taken together with the preceding analysis of John 20, these statements suggest that the principal means by which future generations of believers will encounter the reality of the risen Lord and “hear his voice” is through the disciples’ word, or to use John’s preferred term, their “testimony.” The Fourth Gospel itself claims to preserve the testimony of the Beloved Disciple, whom it identifies as “the one who testifies about these things and has written them” (21:24). The disciples’ testimony, either in oral or written form, is, therefore, a key component in the Fourth Gospel’s understanding of itself as a vehicle of the risen Jesus’s presence to later generations of believers. In the next section, I will argue that the disciples’ testimony (which includes the written Gospel) has this capacity to mediate Jesus’s presence to later generations of believers in a genuine manner because of the action of the Holy Spirit, the Paraclete. In other words, divine inspiration gives the written Gospel this unique capacity to mediate the reality of Jesus to later generations of believers. Inspired Testimony Ignace de la Potterie rightly observes that the Johannine writings often Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 167 use the language of testimony as a term for divine revelation.18 This applies to Jesus’s revelation of the Father and divine truth (3:32–33; 7:7; 8:14, 18; 18:37). Jesus “testifies to what he has seen and heard” (3:32) for he, the only one who has “seen” the Father (1:18; 6:46), speaks “what [he] has heard in the Father’s presence” (8:38). As the Father’s perfect emissary, who is himself “the Truth” (14:6), Jesus alone is able to give valid testimony about himself (8:13–14).19 More frequently, the Gospel speaks of other persons giving testimony to Jesus, such as John the Baptist (1:7–8, 15, 19; 3:28; 5:36), Jesus’s works (5:36; 10:25), the Scriptures (5:39), and through all of these is the testimony of the Father (5:32; cf. 8:18). All these witnesses testify, de la Potterie writes, “directly to the secret of [Jesus’s] being, to the mystery of his person.”20 There are only three instances where the Gospel speaks of Jesus’s disciples giving testimony about him.21 Two of the three pertain specifically to the testimony given by the Beloved Disciple. The first instance is the Beloved Disciple’s eyewitness testimony about the flow of blood and water from the side of Jesus’s corpse (19:35). The second occurs in 21:24, where the narrator states that the Beloved Disciple’s testimony has been written in the Gospel. Between these two cases (19:35; 21:24), the narrator describes the Beloved Disciple’s testimony as “true” three times. At the crucifixion, the narrator says of the Beloved Disciple, “his testimony is true (alēthinē), and he knows that he is speaking the truth (alēthē)” (19:35). Likewise, at the very conclusion of the Gospel, the narrator says of the Beloved Disciple, “we know that his testimony is true 18 For a survey discussion, see Ignace de la Potterie, S.J., La Vérité dans saint Jean, 2 vols., Analecta Biblica 73–74 (Rome: Editrice Pontificio Istituto Biblico, 1999 [1975]), 1.80–88; George Johnston, The Spirit-Paraclete in the Gospel of John (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), 135–37. 19 See Schnackenburg, Gospel According to St. John, 2.120–21, 192–93. On Jesus as the Father’s emissary, see Peder Borgen, “God’s Agent in the Fourth Gospel,” in Religions in Antiquity: Essays in Memory of Erwin Ramsdell Goodenough, ed. Jacob Neusner (Leiden: Brill, 1968), 137–48; reprinted in The Interpretation of John, 2nd ed., ed. John Ashton (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1997), 83–95. 20 de la Potterie, La Vérité, 1.82. 21 A minor exception is the Samaritan woman “who testified” to her fellow townspeople about what Jesus told her (4:39). This case reinforces the basic point that “testimony” is effectively a synonym for “evangelization” in John (so de la Potterie, La Vérité, 1.80), for on the basis of her testimony the Samaritans came to Jesus directly and believed in him. 168 William M. Wright IV (alēthēs)” (21:24). These statements in 19:35 and 21:24 combine three elements: a disciple, giving testimony, which is the truth. This three-part combination appears only one other time in the Gospel, and it is the third instance where the disciples are said to give testimony: the Paraclete promise in 15:26–27. Three things in this Paraclete text (15:26–27) stand out for present purposes. First, Jesus says that the Paraclete himself “will testify” (15:26). Insight into where, how, and to whom the Paraclete testifies can be obtained from the first Paraclete promise (14:16–17). When Jesus first announces that the Paraclete will come to the disciples, he declares that the Paraclete will dwell within his disciples: “he remains with you and will be in you” (en hymin estai; 14:17). The activity of the Paraclete is an interior activity, which he works only in Jesus’s disciples. The latter point is underscored by the sharp contrast, which Jesus draws between his disciples and the world. Jesus explicitly states, “the world cannot receive [the Paraclete] because it neither sees nor knows him” (14:16).22 Because the world does not “receive” (lambanein) Jesus (1:11; 5:43), it is incapable of receiving the Paraclete, whom Jesus will send. As Lyonnet writes, “Since the world has showed it was incapable of ‘perceiving’ the Spirit at work during Jesus’ life, it is also unable to ‘know’ him.”23 What fundamentally distinguishes the disciples from the world is their own “receiving” of Jesus in faith and discipleship (1:12; 3:3; 17:8). The Spirit has been present with Jesus throughout his ministry (1:32–34), and the disciples, “despite their intellectual simplicity, had attached themselves to Jesus, and believed and knew that he was the Holy One of God.”24 The 22 As de la Potterie observes, the Fourth Gospel often uses lambanein to designate the human reception of heavenly realities. For instance, people can receive (or not receive) Jesus himself (1:11–12; 5:34, 43; 13:20), his words (12:48; 17:8), testimony about Jesus (3:11; 3:32–33), the Holy Spirit (7:39; 14:17; 20:22), and heavenly gifts (3:27; 16:24). Hour of Jesus, 117–20. 23 Stanislas Lyonnet, S.J., “The Paraclete,” in The Christian Lives by the Spirit, ed. Ignace de la Potterie, S.J., and Stanislas Lyonnet, S.J., trans. John Morriss (Staten Island: Alba House, 1971), 60. 24 Ibid.. This connection between the Paraclete’s indwelling and the disciples’ faith receives further support from other texts that speak of the Spirit as “living water,” which “will become a spring of water in him” (4:14) and “will flow out from him” (7:37–38). The narrator’s commentary in 7:39 similarly identifies faith as the prerequisite disposition for receiving the Spirit: “he said this about the Spirit, which those who believed (hoi pisteusantes) in him were going to receive (lambanein)” (7:39). Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 169 disciples’ relationship with Jesus opens them up to receive the Paraclete and disposes them to his action upon their hearts. When Jesus says that the Paraclete “will testify” (15:26), it is understood that the Paraclete gives testimony only to the disciples and does so within them. Second, 15:26 specifies Jesus as the content of the Paraclete’s testimony: “he will testify about me.” Significant in this regard is the title “the Spirit of Truth” by which Jesus refers to the Paraclete in 15:26. This title, given to the Paraclete three times in the Farewell Discourses (14:16; 15:26; 16:13), emphasizes the “christological dependence” of the Paraclete, his essential relationship with Jesus and thus with the Father.25 The Gospel consistently identifies the divine revelation of Jesus as “the Truth.”26 As the divine Word, who reveals the Father and himself as the Son, Jesus is himself “the Truth” (14:6; 17:17), and he “has spoken the truth, which [he] heard in the Father’s presence” (8:40; cf. 18:37). As the Spirit of Truth, the Paraclete is the Spirit of Jesus, and his activity within the disciples—he speaks and announces (16:13–14), teaches and reminds (14:26), and testifies—pertains to Jesus’s divine revelation, that is, the truth. The richest expression of this activity appears in the fourth Paraclete promise: “the Spirit of Truth will lead you to all truth” (16:11). De la Potterie thus describes this activity of the Spirit: the Paraclete “will cause [the disciples] to understand the true significance and bearing of the words of Jesus . . . his task will be to interpret, through the Church, the revelation of Jesus, still not fully understood.”27 He later adds, “the task of the Spirit will be to cause the message of Jesus to penetrate into the hearts of the faithful, to give them the understanding of faith.”28 The testimony, which the Spirit of Truth gives about Jesus, is not a generic expression of his pedagogy. Rather, it has a distinctly forensic dimension, related to the context in which the third Paraclete saying (15:26–27) occurs.29 This promise appears within a unit of discourse, 25 Johnston, Spirit-Paraclete, 37. As de la Potterie summarizes, “the truth is the revelation which comes to us from the Father and is passed on to us in the actual word of Jesus” in Ignace de la Potterie, “The Truth in Saint John,” Rivista biblica italiana 11 (1963): 3–24; reprinted in Ashton, Interpretation of John, 71. 27 Ibid., 77. 28 Ibid., 78. 29 I follow, in this paragraph, de la Potterie, La Vérité, 1.391–96. 26 170 William M. Wright IV where Jesus announces to his disciples that they will receive the same hatred and persecution from the world as he did (15:18–16:4a). The occurrence of a prophetic saying about the Spirit assisting Jesus’s disciples in a future time of persecution resembles similar units of discourse in the Synoptics (Mt 10:16–25; Mk 13:9–13; Lk 12:2, 10–12). These Synoptic counterparts envision a forensic setting in which the Spirit serves as a legal advocate (or Paraclete) for the disciples, providing them with what to say or speaking on their behalf (Mt 10:19–20; Mk 13:11; Lk 12:11–12). Within the Johannine articulation, the Paraclete’s testimony similarly provides consolation and assistance to the disciples in their confrontation with the world. As Jesus indicates in the words that follow the third Paraclete promise, the primary threat to the disciples will be apostasy: “I have told you these things so that you may not fall away” (16:1; cf. 6:61–66). This inner activity of the Paraclete, therefore, “is not only a teaching . . . it is called ‘testimony’; it will consist in making the disciples’ faith unshakable, which the opposition of the world could imperil.”30 The Paraclete will convince the disciples of the reality of Jesus that they will be able to stand firm against the assaults of the world. Third, 15:26–27 establishes a connection between the Paraclete’s inner testimony and the disciples’ own testimony: “he will testify about me, and you also testify” (15:26–27). The inner testimony of Paraclete about Jesus enables the disciples to give testimony about Jesus outwardly to the unbelieving world.31 As Augustine puts it, “he will bear witness and you will also bear witness: he in your hearts, you in your voices; he by inspiring, you by speaking out loud.”32 The disciples’ testimony is thus part of their mission to the world. In his intercessory prayer to the Father, Jesus thus prays for his disciples, “As you sent me into the world, so I also send them into the world” (17:18). Later, when the risen Jesus appears to the disciples on Easter Sunday evening, he commissions them: “as the Father sent me, so I also send you” (20:21). The risen Jesus then equips the disciples for their mission by breathing the Holy Spirit into them (20:22). The Father sent Jesus into the world to reveal him 30 Ibid., 1.398. So Brown, Gospel According to John, 2.700; de la Potterie, “Truth in Saint John,” 75; Schnackenburg, Gospel According to St. John, 3.119. 32 Augustine, Tract. Ev. Jo. 93.1 (PL 35:1864). 31 Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 171 and do his work (4:34; 5:23; 8:29; 12:44–50; 18:37), and Jesus extends his mission through his disciples. Jesus was sent to make the Father known to the world for its salvation, and accordingly, the disciples’ mission and testimony has an evangelizing and missionary character. Through their word and example of visible unity (17:21, 23) and faithful, loving practice (13:35), the disciples give testimony to the truth of Jesus’s revelation (17:23). The purpose of the disciples’ testimony is “so that the world may believe that you sent me” (17:21) and by believing in Jesus, receive the gift of participating in the divine communion of life between the Father and Son (17:23). The disciples give testimony about Jesus to the world because the Paraclete has first given testimony about Jesus within the disciples. The indwelling Paraclete guides the disciples into the spiritual depths of Jesus’s revelation, causing its truth to penetrate into their hearts. This inner activity of the Paraclete enables the disciples to give testimony to the world about Jesus through evangelization and to stand firm in the confrontation that it will necessarily provoke. Similarly, the narrator’s claim that the Beloved Disciple’s “testimony is true” (21:24) connects his testimony to the activity of the Spirit of Truth, who guides the disciples “to all truth” (16:13). The Beloved Disciple’s testimony is “true” because it flows from the testimony of the “Spirit of Truth” (15:26) within him about Jesus who is himself “the Truth” (14:6). It is appropriate to say that the Beloved Disciple’s testimony—and the written Gospel containing it—claims to be inspired by the Paraclete.33 Summary We are now in position to draw together the various findings of the exegetical part of this essay. The Resurrection narrative in John 20 indicates that the only thing sufficient to cause genuine faith in Jesus as 33 The Gospel also gives evidence of having been composed in alignment with the activity of the Paraclete as described in its narrative. See William M. Wright IV, “The Theology of Disclosure and Biblical Exegesis,” The Thomist 70 (2006): 405–11; Marinus de Jonge, Jesus: Stranger from Heaven and Son of God—Jesus Christ and the Christians in Johannine Perspective, trans. John E. Steely (Missoula, MT: Scholars Press, 1977), 7–12. 172 William M. Wright IV the risen Lord is a personal encounter with him. Such an encounter with the risen Jesus is not limited to those who literally saw him in his glorified humanity, but it can be had through the Gospel itself, which contains the testimony of the Beloved Disciple. When considered in light of the Paraclete promises in the Farewell Discourse, the Beloved Disciple’s testimony comes to light as proceeding from the Spirit’s inner activity. The Paraclete comes to dwell within Jesus’s disciples after his glorification and teaches them the spiritual depths of Jesus’s revelation. The Paraclete’s inner testimony enables the disciples to give testimony about Jesus externally to the world and, by doing so, bring people to believe in him. If the inspired testimony of the disciples enables later generations to believe in Jesus as Lord, and true faith in Jesus requires a genuine encounter with him as the risen Lord, then the disciples’ inspired testimony, including its written form in the Gospel, mediates the reality of the risen Jesus to later generations, who can personally encounter him and thus believe in him. The Paraclete, who makes the risen Jesus present to the disciples (14:18, 23–26), has inspired the Beloved Disciple’s testimony and so enabled his Gospel to serve as a vehicle by which later generations can encounter the reality of the risen Jesus. Scripture as a Vehicle of Divine Presence in Dei Verbum The preceding analysis of John’s Gospel provides a helpful vantage point for viewing two key passages in Dei Verbum (§21 and §2), which articulate a generically sacramental understanding of Scripture as a vehicle of divine presence. The sacramentality of Scripture appears most clearly in Dei Verbum §21, which compares Scripture and the Eucharist.34 The paragraph begins, “The Church has always venerated the divine Scriptures just as she venerates the body of the Lord.” The reason why Scripture and the Eucharist are similarly venerated is that Christ, whom the text calls “the bread of life,” is received “from the table both of God’s word and of Christ’s 34 On this traditional comparison between Scripture and Eucharist, see Tarcisio Stramare, O.S.J., “‘Mensae duae’ studio biblico-patristico su s. Scrittura ed Eucarestia,” Seminarium 18 (1966): 1020–34. Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 173 body.”35 The Church, especially in the liturgy, receives Christ himself (albeit in different forms) in both the Eucharist and in the Scripture.36 By calling Christ “the bread of life,” the conciliar text openly alludes to the Bread of Life discourse in John 6:31–58. In this discourse, Jesus draws on biblical images that liken God’s Word (Torah) and Wisdom to food in order to reveal himself as God’s Word and Wisdom in the flesh, which he also gives “for the life of the world” on the cross and in the Eucharist (6:51).37 As the divine Wisdom says in Sirach 24:19, “Come to me, you who desire me, and eat your fill of my produce,” so does Jesus similarly declare, “I am the Bread of Life. The one who comes to me will never be hungry, and the one who believes in my will never ever thirst” (Jn 6:35). Among the many teachings of this discourse, which are essential to a sacramental understanding of Scripture, is that Christ is “the Bread of Life” in his being the Word of God as well as in the gift of himself in the Eucharist. Accordingly, Dei Verbum §21 teaches that Christ, the Word of God and “the bread of life,” comes to the Church in the Scripture and the Eucharist, and the Church “unceasingly receives and offers [him] to the faithful.” Scripture is a means by which Christ comes to the Church. Dei Verbum §21 places this mediating role of Scripture within a Trinitarian framework. The conciliar text speaks of all three Trinitarian persons in relation to the biblical books. For instance, the third sentence of §21 speaks of the heavenly Father, who “in the sacred books . . . meets His children with great love and speaks with them.” In the Scriptures, the Church receives Christ, “the bread of life,” and as they are fixed in writing, the Scriptures “impart the word of God Himself without change.” Moreover, the Scriptures “make the voice of the Holy Spirit resound in 35 Stanislaus Lyonnet observes that Dei Verbum §21 speaks of a single table, whereas Sacrosanctum Concilium (§48, 51) speaks of separate tables of the “body” and the “word.” “A Word on Chapters IV and VI of Dei verbum,” Vatican II: Assessment and Perspectives: Twenty-Five Years After (1962–1987), vol. 1, ed. René Latourelle (New York: Paulist, 1988), 178. See also Presbyterorum Ordinis §18; Perfectae Caritatis §6. 36 Lyonnet writes: “This [parallelism between Eucharist and Scripture] was certainly not done, as certain Fathers feared, in order to reduce the eucharistic presence to pure symbolism, nor with any intention of saying that the two presences are the same (for it is an analogy), but more in order to emphasize the reality of Christ’s presence in Scripture as inspired word.” “Chapters IV and VI of Dei Verbum,” 177. 37 E.g., Ps 119:103; Pr 9:1–5; Sir 15:1–3; 24:18–21. For discussion, see Brown, Gospel According to John, 1.266–69, 272–74; Schnackenburg, Gospel According to St. John, 2.43–45. 174 William M. Wright IV the words of the prophets and Apostles.” Significantly, the conciliar text articulates all these actions performed by or pertaining to the Trinitarian persons with verbs in the present tense: the Father “meets” (occurrit) and “speaks with” (eis sermonem confert) his children; the Scriptures “impart” (impertiant) the Word; they “make the voice of the Holy Spirit resound” (vocem Spiritus Sancti personare faciant). The present tense verbs indicate that this encounter between the Triune God and the faithful takes place in the present activity of reading Scripture, “especially in the sacred liturgy.” Through the reading of Scripture, the faithful can experience the Father’s affection, receive his instruction and Word, and hear the Spirit’s voice speaking to them in their present moment. Consistent with the preceding analysis of John’s Gospel, the conciliar text teaches that Scripture’s capacity to mediate a present encounter with the Triune God results from divine inspiration. The second sentence of §21 opens with an affirmation of Scripture and sacred Tradition as constituting “the supreme rule of faith.” The reason for this normativity lies in that the Scriptures “impart the Word of God Himself . . . and make the voice of the Holy Spirit resound in the words of the prophets and Apostles.” The conciliar text prefaces these claims about the Word and the Spirit’s speaking with a descriptive clause about the biblical books “as inspired by God (a Deo inspiratae) and committed once and for all to writing.” Divine inspiration encompasses both the subjective inspiration of the human authors (which Dei Verbum mentions most frequently) and the objective inspiration of biblical books.38 So understood, the inspired Scripture does not only communicate truths from the inspired authors of the past, but they also mediate an encounter with God in the present, who speaks and acts through the inspired texts. Such an understanding squares with a traditional understanding of inspiration described by Henri de Lubac: “It is not only the sacred writers who were inspired one fine day. The sacred books themselves are and remain inspired . . . The Spirit immured himself in it, as it were. He lives in it. His breath has always 38 Dei Verbum mentions inspiration on thirteen occasions, seven times for the subjective inspiration of human authors (§7, 9, 11 (x3), 14, 18), four times for the objective inspiration of biblical books (§8, 11b, 21, 24), and two times for God as the one who inspires (§16, 20). Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 175 animated it . . . It is full of the Spirit.”39 Or as Denis Farkasfalvy likewise has written, “the chief effect of [such an understanding of inspiration consists] in the presence of a spiritual fullness in the biblical text, a capability to reveal not only truths but ultimately the One who said ‘I am the Truth’.”40 Furthermore, Dei Verbum §21 teaches that this present encounter with the Triune God mediated by Scripture communicates causal power. The text speaks of “the force and power in the word of God (verbo Dei vis ac virtus inest),” a formulation that recalls both “the one table . . . of God’s word and Christ’s body” and Scripture’s ability to “impart the word of God Himself.” Consistent with its opening identification of Christ as “the bread of life,” Dei Verbum §21 expresses the power of God’s Word in language and imagery of food. The Word of God is “the food of the soul” and from it “the preaching of the Church must be nourished.” This spiritual nourishment gives “the strength of faith” and is “the support and energy of the Church.” The power of God’s word is life giving and life sustaining. It acts primarily on the faithful reader’s soul and through the soul to bodily activities (like preaching). The faithful are loved, instructed, energized, and nourished by the Triune God in the reading of Scripture because Scripture itself is a medium of divine presence and thus divine power. A key statement in Dei Verbum §2 sheds further light on Scripture’s capacity to mediate God’s presence to its readers. The overarching concern of this article is divine revelation, which, as commentators have argued, is described in historical and sacramental terms.41 The section opens by speaking of revelation as God’s action “to reveal Himself and to make known to us the hidden purpose (sacramentum) of His will” so as to draw human beings to participate in the divine communion. The third sentence in this article expounds on where and how “this economy 39 Henri de Lubac, Medieval Exegesis, 3 vols., trans. Mark Sebanc and E. M. Macierowski (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998–2009 [1959–61]), 1.81–82. 40 Denis Farkasfalvy, O.Cist., “How to Renew the Theology of Biblical Inspiration?,” Nova et Vetera (English) 4 (2006): 249. 41 René Latourelle, S.J., Theology of Revelation (Staten Island: Alba House, 1966), 460– 62; Joseph Ratzinger, “Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation: Chapter I,” in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler, trans. William Glen-Doepel et al. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1969 [1967]), 171. 176 William M. Wright IV of revelation” (Haec revelationis oeconomia) occurs: “This plan of revelation is realized by deeds and words having an inner unity: the deeds wrought by God in the history of salvation manifest and confirm the teaching and realities signified by the words, while the words proclaim the deeds and clarify the mystery contained in them.”42 The conciliar text teaches that the economy of divine revelation occurs in both “deeds and words” (gestis verbisque). This distinction between words and deeds—or “works” (opera) and “realities” (res)—which are both means of divine revelation, along with the language of signification (res verbis significatas), evoke the traditional doctrine of the senses of Scripture. Thomas Aquinas thus defines the two basic biblical senses: “that first signification whereby words signify things belongs to the first sense, the historical or literal. That signification whereby things signified by words have themselves also a signification is called the spiritual sense, which is based on the literal and presupposes it.”43 It is therefore appropriate to take this statement as bearing on Scripture both in its language (verba) and that which the biblical language presents (doctrine and res). Dei Verbum §2 suggests two ways in which Scripture can be seen as a quasi-sacramental vehicle of divine presence. The first pertains primarily to that which the biblical words present, that is, the biblical res. Within the divine economy, one of the key functions performed by the biblical text, its verba, is to “proclaim the deeds and clarify the mystery contained in them.” This claim that the deeds and realities in salvation history bear within themselves the divine mystery is highly redolent of Henri de Lubac’s exposition of the spiritual sense. For de Lubac, the spiritual sense, or mystery, does not lie primarily in the words of the text or the human authors’ ideas, but in the realities that the words present: “to discover this allegory [i.e., spiritual meaning], one will not find it properly speaking in the text, but in the realities of which the text speaks; not 42 The full Latin text reads: “Haec revelationis oeconomia fit gestis verbisque intrinsece inter se connexis, ita ut opera, in historia salutis a Deo patrata, doctrinam et res verbis significatas manifestent ac corroborent, verba autem opera proclament et mysterium in eis contentum elucident.” 43 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I, q. 1, a. 10; cited from St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 3 vols., trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1947–48). Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 177 in history as recitation, but in history as event.”44 He later adds, “the text acts only as spokesman to lead to the historical realities; the latter are themselves the figures, they themselves contain the mysteries that the exercise of allegory is supposed to extract from them.”45 By speaking of “the mystery contained in [the deeds],” the conciliar text points to a sacramental dimension of the biblical res, the realities of salvation history proper. Commenting on Dei Verbum §2, Joseph Ratzinger states that this article gives “a sacramental view [of revelation], which sees law and grace, word and deed, message and sign, the person and his utterance within the one comprehensive unity of the mystery.”46 Consistent with the theological vision inherent in the doctrine of the spiritual sense of Scripture, the realities (e.g., persons, things, events, states of affairs) presented by the biblical texts contain, veil, and reveal the divine mystery.47 More specifically, this mystery is God’s plan of salvation in Christ in which all biblical realities in some respect participate. The account of the divine economy given in Dei Verbum §2 thus involves a notion of “economic participation” of all biblical res in the mystery of Christ.48 A second way in which Scripture can be seen as a sacramental vehicle of divine presence in light of Dei Verbum §2 concerns the intrinsic relationship (intrinsece inter se connexis; translation mine) between the deeds and words, the signified and sign, in salvation history. Both the deeds and words in salvation history are revelatory and shed interpretive light upon each other. The words of the biblical text are revelatory in that through them, God delivers divine teaching and interprets the meaning of the realities in salvation history that the words present: “the words proclaim the deeds and clarify the mystery contained in them.” These mystery-bearing realities of salvation history also “manifest and confirm” what the biblical words signify. René Latourelle argues that 44 De Lubac, Medieval Exegesis, 2.86. Ibid., 2.86. 46 Ratzinger, “Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation,” 171. 47 See Hans Boersma, Nouvelle Théologie and Sacramental Ontology: A Return to Mystery (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), 154–60; William M. Wright IV, “The Literal Sense of Scripture According to Henri de Lubac: Insights from Patristic Exegesis of the Transfiguration,” Modern Theology 28 (2012): 252–77. 48 Francis Martin, “Election, Covenant, and Law,” Nova et Vetera (English) 4 (2006): 865. 45 178 William M. Wright IV this revelatory reciprocity between words and deeds is explicitly sacramental: “The sacramental character of revelation appears in the interpenetration and mutual support that exists between word and work. God performs the act of salvation and at the same time develops its meaning; He intervenes in history and tells us of the import of His intervention; He acts and comments on His action.”49 As a fruit of divine inspiration, the Bible’s linguistic articulations, its verba, possess a privileged congruence with the divine actions and realities in salvation history, which they present and whose spiritual meaning they correctly interpret.50 The biblical verba constitute that linguistic articulation and interpretation most befitting the disclosure of these sacred realities, having as it does an inspired, “intrinsic” relation with them. As Francis Martin has written of this passage in Dei Verbum §2, “The word that gives language expression to the action ensures that God’s act be rendered more intelligible and be continually present to God’s people.”51 He continues, “the biblical expression in ‘words’ has a unique capacity to transpose, express, and mediate the action, the res, or the mysterion.”52 The mystery-bearing res in salvation history are made present and their significance made known through the biblical verba (to which they are intrinsically connected) to receptive, faith-filled readers of Scripture. This same passage from Dei Verbum §2 is also cited by Pope Benedict XVI in Verbum Domini §56, where he discusses Scripture in sacramental terms. Benedict writes, “The proclamation of God’s word at the celebration entails an acknowledgement that Christ himself is present, that he speaks to us, and that he wishes to be heard.”53 According to Benedict, 49 Latourelle, Theology of Revelation, 462. As Henri de Lubac puts it (referencing several authors), “It is the same Word of God, who on the one hand, ‘realizes the plans of God in history’ and on the other, ‘translates in human words, on the lips of God’s messengers, to make the meaning of this revelation through the realities understood.’” La Révélation divine in Cardinal Henri de Lubac, Œuvres completes IV, ed. Éric de Moulins-Beaufort and Georges Chantraine (Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 2006), 68–69. 51 Francis Martin, “Revelation and Its Transmission,” in Vatican II: Renewal within Tradition, ed. Matthew L. Lamb and Matthew Levering (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 57. 52 Ibid. 53 Pope Benedict XVI, Verbum Domini §56. 50 Scripture as a Sacramental Vehicle of Divine Presence 179 the liturgical proclamation of inspired Scripture is a kind of divine presence, analogous to Christ’s Eucharistic presence: “Christ, truly present under the species of bread and wine, is analogously present in the word proclaimed in the liturgy.”54 He continues, referencing Dei Verbum §2, “A deeper understanding of the sacramentality of God’s word can thus lead us to a more unified understanding of the mystery of revelation, which takes place through ‘deeds and words intimately connected.’”55 Conclusion The analysis of John 20 has provided a Scriptural basis for conceiving of the Gospel in broadly sacramental terms as a vehicle of divine presence. John offers the written text of his Gospel as a linguistic means by which the reality of the risen Jesus can be encountered by later generations of the faithful. The Gospel has this unique capacity because the Beloved Disciple’s testimony, which it contains, results from the activity of the Paraclete in the disciple. The inspired verba of the Gospel serve as a means by which the res that is the risen Lord is made truly present to its readers and whose spiritual significance, revealed to believers by the Paraclete, is communicated. In addition to and in concert with the Scriptural teaching, Dei Verbum and Verbum Domini have provided a magisterial basis for thinking about Scripture as a vehicle of divine presence and power, which faithful readers can experience in their present. Both the biblical res, which bear the divine mystery, and the verba, which present and interpret those res in a most privileged and inspired way, have sacramental dimensions by which Jesus, the Word and Wisdom of God, feeds and sustains his disciples. Further theological thinking about the sacramentality of Scripture requires consideration of how Scripture is both similar and dissimilar to the Church’s seven sacraments. For instance, while Scripture does constitute a vehicle of God’s presence and power, it cannot, in light of the teachings of Trent, be considered as an eighth sacrament of the Church.56 As many Catholic theologians who advocate an understand54 Ibid. Ibid. 56 Cf. “Decree Concerning the Sacraments, Canon 1,” in The Canons and Decrees of the 55 180 William M. Wright IV ing of Scripture in quasi-sacramental terms have rightly noted, Scripture’s mode of making Christ present is not identical with his substantial presence in the Eucharist.57 Instead, one might employ a broader notion of sacramentality with respect to Scripture, such as that employed by the Second Vatican Council when it applies the term “sacrament” to the Church herself.58 In this way, a great deal of insight can be gained into the Church’s traditional belief and acquire a renewed appreciation for the life-giving and life-sustaining power of God’s Word given in the Scripture. For it is through the reading and hearing of inspired Scripture, especially within the context of liturgy, that its receptive readers can encounter the reality of the risen Lord and “by believing may have N&V life in his name” (John 20:31). Council of Trent, trans. H. J. Schroeder, O.P. (Rockford: Tan Books, 1978 [1941]), 51. E.g., Luis Alonso-Schökel, S.J., The Inspired Word: Scripture in the Light of Language and Literature, trans. Francis Martin, O.C.S.O. (Montreal: Palm, 1965), 374; Hans Urs von Balthasar. Explorations in Theology I: The Word Made Flesh, trans. A. V. Littledale with Alexander Dru (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1989 [1960]), 17. 58 Lumen Gentium §1, 9. 57 Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 181-218 181 Word and Event: A Reappraisal Gregory Vall Ave Maria University Ave Maria, FL IN JANUARY 1982,six years before Cardinal Ratzinger delivered his Erasmus Lecture, I took a seat in Francis Martin’s classroom for the first time. Francis’s courses introduced me to a fascinating and inspiring world of biblical scholarship, serious exegesis in a genuinely theological mode. The Old and New Testaments were shown to be mutually illuminating. Origen and Aquinas were quoted alongside Gerhard von Rad and Emile Boismard. And a painstaking analysis of the biblical text beautifully disclosed the mystery of redemption in a way that directly nourished my prayer life. Years before I became aware of a crisis in biblical interpretation, I was exposed to the remedy. The following essay is dedicated to Francis Martin as a token of gratitude and affection. For those who recognize much of real worth in modern biblical scholarship but at the same time find deeply problematic presuppositions at work within it, Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger’s Erasmus Lecture of 1988 has been a guiding light for the last quarter century. At the heart of the Erasmus Lecture is the call for a new hermeneutical synthesis. The future pontiff describes this as a project in two stages. First there must be a self-critique of the historical-critical method and its philosophical foundations, and then there is “the positive task” of joining the tools of the historical-critical method to “a better philosophy,” one that “contains fewer a prioris foreign to the [biblical] text” and “offers more resources 182 Gregory Vall for a real listening to the text.”1 Ratzinger, moreover, closely correlates the “exegetical problem” to modernity’s broader “dispute over foundations.” The search for a new synthesis, as Ratzinger conceives it, must take modernity and modern questions as its starting point but must not confine itself to the philosophically “restricted horizon” of modern thought. Patristic exegesis and medieval philosophy in particular will play important roles in broadening our horizon beyond that of the positivistic worldview of modernity.2 That is why Ratzinger also envisions the new synthesis as a sort of rapprochement between the patristic-medieval approach to Scripture and modern approaches.3 The last portion of the Erasmus Lecture is devoted to “Basic Elements of a New Synthesis.” Ratzinger offers nothing systematic or comprehensive here but attempts “merely to cut a few initial openings in the thicket.”4 Among these basic elements he gives considerable attention to the need for a fresh appraisal of “the relationship between event and word.” Ratzinger maintains that “the mainstream of modern exegesis” operates with a badly truncated notion of event, according to which the event represents irrationality; it belongs to the domain of pure facticity, which is composed of chance and necessity. For this reason, fact as such cannot be the bearer of meaning. The meaning lies only in the word.5 This “dualism between word and event” not only “banishes the event into the realm of the word-less” and the meaningless, it “actually robs the word itself of its capacity to mediate sense, because the word then 1 Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict: On the Foundations and the Itinerary of Exegesis Today,” in Opening Up the Scriptures: Joseph Ratzinger and the Foundations of Biblical Interpretation, ed. José Granados, Carlos Granados, and Luis Sanchez-Navarro, Ressourcement (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008), 20. 2 Ibid., 19. 3 See Paul T. Stallsworth, “The Story of an Encounter,” in Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: The Ratzinger Conference on Bible and Church, ed. Richard John Neuhaus (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1989), 107–8. For a concrete example of how such a rapprochement might work, see Gregory Vall, “Psalm 22: Vox Christi or Israelite Temple Liturgy?” The Thomist 66 (2002): 175–200. 4 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 20. 5 Ibid., 23. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 183 stands in a world from which all sense has been stripped.” Ultimately this dualism “cuts the biblical Word off from creation and undoes the coherence of sense between the Old and New Testaments in favor of a principle of discontinuity.”6 According to Ratzinger, this problem is at root philosophical, and its solution must be both philosophical and theological. Modern exegesis regards events as bruta facta because it holds as an unquestioned presupposition “the methodological principle used in natural science, that everything that occurs can be explained causally, on the basis of purely immanent functional connections.”7 Over against this view, which reduces intelligibility to the realm of efficient causality, Ratzinger recommends the teleological philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, according to which all things in creation “follow a certain course, that is, a movement toward a goal.” Only teleology can safeguard the biblical notion of the unity of creation and history under the aegis of a divine economy. In Scripture “God’s action thus appears as the principle of the intelligibility of history,” and all history, past, present, and future, finds its unity in the person and event of Jesus Christ. In Christ, the Word Incarnate, we see the most profound and perfect unity of word and event, and we come to recognize that “the event itself can be a ‘word.’”8 Ratzinger’s observations on word and event are profound and of great importance, but they need to be spelled out in a more systematic and thorough manner. Anyone who has made a serious attempt to bring modern biblical scholarship to the service of theological work carried out under the authority of the rule of faith will already have some awareness of the problem to which Ratzinger refers here and will appreciate what is at stake. For the sake of clarity, however, I begin with an example of how the dualism of word and event manifests itself in modern biblical scholarship. In the remainder of the essay I then attempt to sketch out, rather more fully than the Erasmus Lecture does, Scripture’s own theological vision of the unity of word and event. I consider creation and 6 Ibid., 25. Joseph Ratzinger (Pope Benedict XVI), God’s Word: Scripture—Tradition—Office, ed. Peter Hünermann and Thomas Söding, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2008), 119. 8 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 24. 7 184 Gregory Vall the Imago Dei; language and truth; God’s word in human events; time, narrative, and history; and the Christ event and the Gospels. The Dualism of Word and Event: An Example After a brief preface, Vatican II’s 1965 Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation, Dei Verbum, turns almost immediately to the unity of word and event in the divine economy. This economy of revelation is realized in deeds and words intrinsically interconnected (gestis verbisque intrinsece inter se connexis), such that the works accomplished by God in the history of salvation manifest and corroborate the teaching and realities signified by the words, while, conversely, the words proclaim the deeds and illuminate the mystery contained in them.9 The complementarity between deeds and words of which this text speaks is evident throughout Scripture. For example, the wonders by which Yahweh wrought Israel’s deliverance from bondage in Egypt lead directly to and are completed by the revelation of the law at Sinai. Again, the great chastisement of the exile both fulfills and is explained by the words of the prophets. Employing poetic parallelism, the psalmist confesses: “Yahweh is faithful in all his words, and loyal in all his deeds” (Ps 145:13).10 Similarly, in the New Testament, Jesus’s public ministry is comprised of mutually illuminating works of power and words of instruction, and each of the evangelists draws attention to this fact in his own way. Matthew, for example, dovetails narrative units with large blocks of the Lord’s teaching in an architectonic fashion.11 John, for his part, presents Jesus’s miracles as “signs”—that is, inherently significant deeds—and typically couples a sign narrative with a discourse or dia9 Dei Verbum §2. “Haec revelationis oeconomia fit gestis verbisque intrinsece inter se connexis, ita ut opera, in historia salutis a Deo patrata, doctrinam et res verbis significatas manifestent ac corroborent, verba autem opera proclament et mysterium in eis contentum elucident.” (My translation.) 10 The translations of Scripture throughout this essay are my own. 11 See John P. Meier, Anchor Bible Dictionary, s.v. “Matthew, Gospel of,” 4:628–29; and the chart in Raymond E. Brown, An Introduction to the New Testament, Anchor Bible Reference Library (New York: Doubleday, 1997), 172. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 185 logue that draws out the given sign’s significance.12 In his 1967 commentary on Dei Verbum, Ratzinger suggests that in drafting the passage quoted above the fathers of Vatican II “were merely concerned with overcoming neo-scholastic intellectualism, for which revelation chiefly meant a store of mysterious supernatural teaching . . . in order to express again the character of revelation as a totality, in which word and event make up one whole.”13 Whether it was intentional or not, however, the conciliar statement also guards against the opposite error, namely, that which would privilege events over words in the economy of redemption in order to play down the propositional content of revelation and the intellectual dimension of the act of faith, perhaps also in order to pit the intuitive, imagistic, and poetic elements in Hebraic thought against Greek rationality to the detriment of the latter. In February of 1964, while the antepenultimate draft (“Form E”) of what was to be called Dei Verbum was being prepared in Rome for consideration at the third session of the Council later that year, the Scottish biblical scholar James Barr was delivering his Currie Lectures at Austin Presbyterian Theological Seminary in Texas. With characteristic “prosecutorial zeal,” Barr undertook to dismantle the allegedly biblical concept of “revelation through God’s acts in history,” complaining that it had gained a status of unquestioned normativity in the “biblical theology” movement, which was then at the zenith of its popularity.14 Barr rightly points out that any attempt to locate revelation in God’s historical 12 As Robert Kysar notes, John combines narrative and discourse in a variety of ways, and he sometimes allows a sign to stand on its own and speak for itself. Anchor Bible Dictionary, s.v. “John, The Gospel of,” 3:916. For an in-depth discussion of “the concept of ‘sign’ in Johannine theology,” see Rudolf Schnackenburg, The Gospel According to John, vol. 1, Introduction and Commentary on Chapters 1–4, trans. Kevin Smyth (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968), 515–28. 13 Herbert Vorgrimler, ed., Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, vol. 3 (New York: Herder and Herder, 1969), 172. (Original German edition published 1967.) Ratzinger coauthored the commentary on Dei Verbum with Alois Grillmeier and Béda Rigaux, but he is solely responsible for the passage in question. 14 James Barr, Old and New in Interpretation: A Study of the Two Testaments (New York: Harper & Row, 1966), esp. 65–102, “The Concepts of History and Revelation.” Cf. David Penchansky, Historical Handbook of Major Biblical Interpreters, s.v. “Barr, James,” 423–27 (Penchansky’s admiring reference to Barr’s “prosecutorial zeal” is on p. 423). Barr had already presented a devastating critique of the exaggerated contrast between “Hebrew thought” and “Greek thought” in his first major work, The Semantics of Biblical Language (London: SCM Press, 1983 [1961]). 186 Gregory Vall acts while dissociating it from verbal communication flies in the face of the biblical evidence. Referencing the many Old Testament passages in which Yahweh is said to have spoken to Moses and the prophets, as well as the words by which Israelite tradition itself was transmitted, Barr observes that “it is entirely as true to say that in the Old Testament revelation is by verbal communication as to say that it is by acts in history.”15 Thus on a certain level, the level of the content of Scripture itself, Barr too seems to affirm the inseparability of word and event. To this point we have dealt with the relationship between word and event as these are found within Scripture. In specifying the locus and content of revelation, the neo-scholastics, whom Ratzinger identifies as the primary targets of Dei Verbum’s formulation about “deeds and words intrinsically interconnected,” give the words of the prophets and the teaching of Jesus and the apostles a certain priority over the events of the historical economy as such.16 But this is, at least in principle, a matter of privileging one part of the biblical record over another. Even if neo-scholasticism expresses the content of revelation in the postbiblical language of dogmatic propositions, these propositions are assumed to be accurate “translations” of what Scripture itself teaches. Conversely, the proponents of “biblical theology,” against whom Barr polemicizes, privilege the narrated events of redemptive history over biblical words of law, prophecy, and instruction. In either case, then, the alleged dualism of word and event is largely reducible to what we might call the intrabiblical level. The discursive teaching of the prophets, the Lord, and the apostles is given priority over Scripture’s narrative of events, or vice versa. Indeed, whether this prioritization amounts to a real dualism, or merely an exegetical and theological imbalance, depends to a significant degree on how a given version of neo-scholasticism or of biblical theology views the nature of events in general and of the biblical events in particular. Provided that the neo-scholastic theologian and the “biblical theologian” could agree that events are not merely “brute facts,” and provided they could also come to a basic agreement about the sort of reference Scripture makes to the events of redemptive history, they 15 16 Barr, Old and New, 77. René Latourelle, Theology of Revelation: Including a Commentary on the Constitution “Dei Verbum” of Vatican II (Staten Island, NY: Alba House, 1966), 210–12. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 187 might be able to work toward a resolution of their differences by way of careful exegesis of the biblical text. But this strictly exegetical and intrabiblical level, however important it may be, is not where the major difficulty lies. All parties should be able to agree that Scripture accords vital significance to words and events alike, that it presents these as inextricably bound together within the economy of revelation and redemption, and that any attempt to pit one against the other must therefore be misguided. As long as we remain on the merely exegetical level, therefore, the council fathers and James Barr both appear to be doing little more than stating the obvious. The real difficulties emerge when we press the philosophical question about the nature of words and events and their interrelation and the theological question about the nature of revelation and redemption and their interrelation. Furthermore, we have yet to consider a second and potentially much more problematic dimension of the whole matter, namely, the relationship between Scripture itself as “word” (comprising both narrative and discourse) and redemptive history as “event” (an event that, of course, involves many words). The strong tendency of modern biblical scholarship, as we shall see presently, is to view the history of Israel, the life of the historical Jesus, and the first two generations of Church history as lying somewhere “behind” the texts of the Old and New Testaments, faintly discernible in the mists of the ancient world. While this problematizing of the relationship between Scripture (word) and history (event) was to some extent inevitable, given the archeological discoveries and philological progress of recent centuries, one would not be mistaken to detect the modern dichotomy between fact and value at work here as well. To gain a concrete sense of how these tendencies manifest themselves in the deliberations of modern biblical scholars, we may return to the Currie Lectures. Here it is interesting to note that while Barr, ever the master debunker, is able to identify a host of “contradictions and antinomies” involved in the way his contemporaries bandy about the idea of “revelational history,” he offers precious little in the way of a positive counterproposal.17 He chides the leaders of the biblical theology move17 Barr, Old and New, 66–67. 188 Gregory Vall ment for “treating so grossly uncertain a concept as Heilsgeschichte [salvation history] as if it was some kind of firm ground,” but the very real theological insight that this term crystalizes seems to escape him almost entirely.18 While not explicitly embracing the dichotomy between fact and value, he opines that “the acts of God [recounted in the Old Testament] are not really and strictly ‘revelatory,’ except in the trivial sense in which any act done, or any thing said, may be considered to ‘reveal’ something of the doer.”19 With unintended irony Barr here puts his finger on a phenomenon that many twentieth-century Catholic philosophers, from Blondel to Wojtyla to Sokolowski, have considered anything but trivial: the self-disclosure of the human person through action.20 It is even less trivial to consider the possibility that the eternal and transcendent God might indeed act within space and time in a manner that is analogous to human action and that can thus be narrated as something like a matter of historical record. The cumulative claim of Israel’s Scriptures—namely, that the only true God, creator of heaven and earth, not only can act within human history but has in fact acted in very particular ways on behalf of a particular people, thus revealing himself to be a personal God, a knowable Who rather than an unknowable What—is of the greatest theological import. It is quite impossible to imagine Judaism or Christianity apart from this claim. Barr’s attempt to relegate the notion of God’s self-revelatory action within history to the margins of the biblical view of reality must in the last analysis be judged unconvincing. Still, Barr’s broader project, to discredit the biblical theology movement, has been largely successful, at least among biblical scholars. The “contradictions and antinomies” to which he draws attention appear insoluble indeed, particularly to those who, like Barr, rule out of court any appeal to metaphysics or “mysticism” where the interpretation of the 18 Ibid., 86. Ibid., 82 (punctuation added for clarity). 20 Maurice Blondel, Action (1893): Essay on a Critique of Life and a Science of Practice, trans. Oliva Blanchette (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2004); Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person: A Contribution to Phenomenological Anthropology, Analecta Husserliana 10, trans. Andrzej Potocki (Boston: D. Reidel, 1979); Robert Sokolowski, Phenomenology of the Human Person (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008). 19 Word and Event: A Reappraisal 189 Bible is concerned. One problem, which is the direct result of what Hans Frei famously tagged “the eclipse of biblical narrative,” seems especially intractable. Modern biblical scholars have become acutely conscious of two distinct and often quite divergent accounts of Israel’s history: the Old Testament’s own account, and the account that has emerged from historical-critical investigation.21 According to Barr, the proponents of Heilsgeschichte disagree among themselves, if they do not simply equivocate, when it comes to specifying which of these two accounts gives us access to God’s alleged self-revelation in history.22 Barr apparently views the very attempt to resolve this problem as misguided. Responding to those who argue that the solution lies in approaching the whole question with an authentically “biblical view of history,” that is, one obtained from Scripture itself, Barr notes that they have reached no consensus regarding what this “biblical view of history” in fact is. He is confident in any case that the Old Testament’s narrative of events is quite incommensurable with what we moderns mean by “history.” This does not trouble Barr, however, since he contends that history is “not a biblical category” to begin with.23 The biblical theology movement’s tragic flaw, in his estimation, has been to read the modern understanding and valuation of history back into the Bible. Barr is much more sanguine when it comes to the capacity of archeology and historical-critical research to give us a certain kind of reliable access to the “real history” of the ancient Near East. But this sort of investigation yields only “plain history,” which “cannot honestly be called ‘revelatory’ in any sense relatable to the actual intentions of the Old Testament texts.” Further, Barr scoffs at those who, unable to bridge the gap between Scripture and “real history,” take it upon themselves to invest the latter “with a kind of religious mysticism” and thus provide themselves with “a kind of theology-substitute.”24 At this point in Barr’s discussion the dualism of word and event has unmistakably reared its head—not at the exegetical or intrabiblical level, but precisely at the level of the relationship between biblical 21 Hans W. Frei, The Eclipse of Biblical Narrative: A Study in Eighteenth and Nineteenth Century Hermeneutics (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1974). 22 Barr, Old and New, 66–67. 23 Ibid., 69. 24 Ibid., 68. Gregory Vall 190 word and historical event. It is tolerably clear that Barr has no expectation of finding any profound theological significance, much less God’s self-disclosure, in “real” or “plain” history. Aside from the “trivial” case of persons revealing something of themselves in their deeds, the human actions and other events of ancient Israel’s actual history appear to be essentially mute. It should perhaps come as no surprise that the chasm that opens here between the Old Testament text and Israel’s “real” history is accompanied by other similar dichotomies and leads to a significantly diminished sense of the Bible’s divine origin and authority. “Scripture,” Barr matter-of-factly informs us, “does not come into existence by direct action of God, but by a human action which is a reflex of contact with God.” The logical corollary to this position is that the human action that produced the Bible “shares in the distortion and inadequacy which applies to other human acts, and especially to those human acts which claim to relate themselves to the will of God.”25 Ever the uncompromising opponent of “fundamentalism,” Barr does not evince so much as a hint of nostalgia for the traditional doctrines of inspiration and inerrancy, which in any case can only be sustained “by recourse to the sheer supernaturalism of miraculous divine intervention.” As Barr views the matter, one must choose between an utterly infallible Bible that is the product of “sheer supernaturalism” and a radically human Bible that “meets the needs of sinful men just because it is itself not free from its sinful element.”26 The irony in all this is that, having excoriated the biblical theology movement for locating God’s self-revelation in the nonverbal realm, Barr now reduces Scripture to a merely human “reflex,” a partly sinful subjective response to something he vaguely terms the human authors’ “contact with God.” Barr’s assault on “biblical theology,” in several major works throughout his career, has contributed not a little to the movement’s long, slow decline. Writing a generation after the Currie Lectures, Thomas L. Thompson treats the dichotomy between Old Testament narrative and ancient Israel’s actual history as self-evident and Barr’s diagnosis of the biblical theology movement as beyond dispute. According to Thomp25 26 Ibid., 163. Ibid. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 191 son, the proponents of biblical theology have introduced “considerable confusion” by using the word Heilsgeschichte to refer both to the biblical narrative’s presentation of Israel’s past, which is no more and no less than “a form of theologically motivated Tendenz,” and to Israel’s actual history as (supposedly) revelatory and salvific. In Thompson’s opinion the latter use has been “largely discredited,” for it locates revelation in a realm that is “open in every way to historical-critical research,” and such a realm almost by definition cannot be viewed as “an object of faith alone.”27 History and faith must be kept neatly separate. Still, Thomson holds that the Tendenz of Old Testament narrative can be viewed positively as a locus of theology and faith—paradoxically, it can even be called “salvation history”—provided we ascribe no significant historicity or historiographical intentionality to it.28 Elsewhere Thompson explains that Israel’s faith “is not an historical faith.” It “has its justification, not in the evidence of past events, for the traditions of the past serve only as the occasion of the expression of faith, but in the assertion of a future promise.”29 Salvation history is not an historical account of saving events open to the study of the historian. Salvation history did not happen; it is a literary form which has its own historical context.30 Following the trajectory of Barr’s thought well beyond Barr’s own conclusions, Thompson affirms a “biblical faith” that is invulnerable to historical-critical investigation because it is not really concerned with past events but only with present experience and future hope. It is Israel’s “experience” that is (to some extent) “communicated” and Israel’s “faith” that is “revealed” in the Old Testament, and this nonhistorical faith experience can become “our faith” too through an existential reading of the Old Testament.31 The Christian is thus able to maintain a “theology 27 Thomas L. Thompson, Anchor Bible Dictionary, s.v. “Historiography (Israelite),” 3:209. 28 Ibid., 210. 29 Thomas L. Thompson, The Historicity of the Patriarchal Narratives: The Quest for the Historical Abraham (Harrisburg, PA: Trinity Press International, 2002), 329. 30 Ibid., 328. 31 Ibid., 330. 192 Gregory Vall of the word” and of “existential experience” while he or she is freed from the burdensome and ultimately untenable notion that revelation and salvation consist in a series of divine interventions in history culminating in Jesus’s Resurrection.32 Thompson’s radical transformation of biblical theology, building on Barr’s critique, thus furnishes a consummate example of the dualism of word and event. Creation and the Imago Dei If the modern dualism of word and event “cuts the biblical Word off from creation,”33 the place to begin our attempt to recover the true unity of word and event is with the biblical doctrine of creation. Scripture’s opening sentence shows us that the unity of word and event is rooted in God’s primordial act of creation (Gn 1:1–3).34 The inspired narrative displays a perfect correspondence between God’s creative word—yĕhî ʾôr (“let there be light”)—and its immediate result—wayĕhî ʾôr (“and there was light”). What God says happens, with no remainder and no surprises. We do not read, “God said, ‘Let there be light,’ and there was a chicken,” but “God said, ‘Let there be light,’ and there was light.” His word of creation is perfectly efficacious.35 Moreover, God is neither compelled to create nor hindered from creating. The world is not the result of some combination of chance and necessity, nor is it the product of a battle among the gods. Genesis presents God’s act of creation as a speaking-into-being and thus traces the unity of word and event back to a primordial act of divine performative speech. The phrase yĕhî ʾôr is a volitive speech act. As such, it is an expression of both knowledge and will. As rational discourse, yĕhî ʾôr has intelligible content. And because the verbal form yĕhî is grammatically a jussive, or third-person volitive, it is also a sort of command.36 One speaks what one knows, and one commands what one 32 Ibid., 329. Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 25. 34 The first three verses of Genesis constitute a single sentence in Hebrew, though English translations usually break it into two or three sentences for the sake of readability. 35 “The exact echoing of the command here emphasizes the total fulfillment of the divine word.” Gordon J. Wenham, Genesis 1–15, Word Biblical Commentary 1 (Waco, TX: Word Books, 1987), 18. 36 Biblical Hebrew employs three classes of volitive verb forms: the cohortative 33 Word and Event: A Reappraisal 193 wills.37 Furthermore, when one wills what is good, the volitional word is an expression of love. And the Priestly narrative of creation is emphatic in saying that everything God created is “very good” (1:31). Creation flows forth from an eternal act of knowledge and love, or what Augustine calls God’s “eternal counsel and will.”38 If the intrinsic unity of word and event that pervades the economy of revelation and redemption is rooted in God’s act of creation, this act, the word of love by which God speaks the world into being, is rooted in his inner life. The oikonomia flows forth from the realm of theologia. The unity of word and event, then, ultimately traces back to the eternal processions of knowledge and love within the Holy Trinity. Perhaps we should not too hastily dismiss the patristic tendency to find all three persons of the Trinity in the opening lines of Genesis.39 In this context the Church Fathers also like to quote Psalms 33:6: “By the word (dābār) of Yahweh the heavens were made, by the breath (rûaḥ) of his mouth all their (first-person volitive), the imperative (second-person volitive), and the jussive (third-person volitive). See Paul Joüon, A Grammar of Biblical Hebrew, trans. and rev. T. Muraoka (Rome: Pontifical Biblical Institute, 1993), 125 (§40b). 37 In commenting on “the idea of creation by the word” in Gn 1:3, Gerhard von Rad places all the emphasis on God’s “personal will” at the expense of any notion of the word as possessing intelligible content and as divine self-communication. He is right to insist that the Priestly author affirms a “radical essential distinction between Creator and creature” and that creation “cannot be even remotely considered an emanation from God,” but he goes much too far in concluding that the created world is therefore in no sense a “reflection of his being.” Genesis: A Commentary, 2nd ed., trans. John H. Marks (London: SCM Press, 1972), 51–52. In order to uphold a biblical view of reality, one must certainly distinguish between emanation and reflection in this regard. 38 De civitate Dei 11:4: aeternum consilium voluntatemque. Translations of patristic texts are my own unless otherwise indicated. Latin citations are from the Library of Latin Texts accessed through the Brepols Publishers website (www.brepolis.net). 39 E.g., Ephrem of Syria, commenting on Gn 1:2, writes: “It was appropriate to reveal here that the Spirit hovered in order for us to learn that the work of creation was held in common by the Spirit with the Father and the Son. The Father spoke. The Son created. And so it was also right that the Spirit offer its work, clearly shown through its hovering, in order to demonstrate its unity with the other persons. Thus we learn that all was brought to perfection and accomplished by the Trinity.” Andrew Louth, ed., Genesis 1-11, Ancient Christian Commentary on Scripture, Old Testament 1 (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2001), 6. 194 Gregory Vall host.”40 Both texts present creation as a perfectly unified action of God, his dābār, and his rûaḥ.41 The biblical doctrine of God’s creation by his word is developed in the Old Testament wisdom literature. In Proverbs 3:19, for example, we read: “By his wisdom (ḥokmâ) Yahweh founded the earth; he established the heavens by his understanding.” The category of ḥokmâ further discloses the unity of knowledge and love in God’s act of creation. Human “wisdom” includes both the theoretical and the practical among its essential aspects. It is the virtue by which one does the truth for the sake of the good. To say, analogously, that God created the world by his wisdom is to say that he has acted in intelligence and love. He orders everything toward an end that is good. This is what sets the authentically biblical notion of divine power apart from every defective notion of omnipotence. As Augustine puts it, “God is omnipotent, not by reckless power, but by the strength of wisdom.”42 The world created by “the only wise God” (Rom 16:27) is itself intelligible and good, an expression of divine truth and love. Each creature, and creation as a whole, is ordered toward an end that is good. The physical universe is an event and a thing, but it is not irrational or mute. It is a word of truth and love rather than a brute fact. But for creation to speak its word of truth and love there needs to be a creature who possesses the capacity to hear and understand this word, a creature who is able to “interpret” the world. Man, created in the image of God, is endowed with precisely this capacity, and the created universe is “a gift addressed to man.”43 According to the theological tradition that comes to us through Augustine and Aquinas, “all things which occur in time are certain similitudes of those things which have been from eternity.”44 In this sense, ev40 E.g. Ambrose, In Hexaemeron 1:8. We need not suppose that the Hebrew authors possessed anything like an explicit conceptual knowledge of the doctrine of the Trinity, but only that, since the God whom they knew by revelation was in fact the true God, who is and always was three divine persons, it should not surprise us if the Old Testament contains here and there intimations of God’s inner life, intimations that come into a new light when read from the perspective of the fullness of revelation in Jesus Christ. 42 De Genesi ad litteram 9:17: “neque enim potentia temeraria, sed sapientiae virtute omnipotens est.” 43 Catechism of the Catholic Church §299. 44 Summa theologiae III, q. 23, a. 2, ad 3. 41 Word and Event: A Reappraisal 195 ery creature is made to the likeness of God. But man alone is made to the image and likeness of God. This same theological tradition locates the imago Dei in man’s rational soul with its faculties of intellect and will. For present purposes it may be helpful to restate this interpretation of Genesis 1:26–27 in terms of the analogia verbi. God, creation, and man are all λογικός (“rational”), but each in its own way. God is supremely and properly speaking λογικός. In eternally generating his Logos and breathing forth his Spirit, he eternally knows and loves all things. Creatures too are, analogously speaking, λογικός—in a finite and somewhat passive sense, as the products and expressions of God’s knowledge and love. They are intelligible and good, knowable and lovable. As a creature, man too is λογικός in this sense. At the same time, however, he possesses a participation in God’s rationality that is more active and more perfect than that enjoyed by other creatures in the physical realm. He is not only intelligible and good but intelligent and capable of choosing and doing the good. He is not only knowable and lovable, but capable of knowing and loving. Early in the history of Christian theology there emerged a strong and enduring tendency to identify the imago Dei in man with the faculty of reason (λόγος) and with the mind (νοῦς), but this did not always involve dissociating it completely from man’s bodily form. The second-century Epistle to Diognetus, in presenting the biblical teaching on the imago Dei, emphasizes man’s intellectual endowment but immediately complements this emphasis with the idea that man’s upright posture also distinguishes him from other bodily creatures and reflects his special orientation to God and heaven (Diog. 10:2). In his De hominis opificio Gregory of Nyssa develops the notion that it is the whole human person in the unity of body and soul that is made to the image of God, and not the mind alone. According to Gregory, we see in man’s rational soul a kind of participation in God’s incorporeal nature that we do not find in the body. Nevertheless, man is a single “compound nature” (σύγκριμα) and must be viewed as such.45 The mind “would have been incommunicable and isolated if its motion were not 45 De hominis opificio 16:9 (PG 44:181); trans. Henry Austin Wilson. Philip Schaff and Henry Wace, eds., A Select Library of the Christian Church: Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, Second Series, vol. 5, Gregory of Nyssa: Dogmatic Treatises, etc. (1893; Reprint, Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 1995), 405. 196 Gregory Vall manifested by some contrivance,” and so the Creator prepared the human body as the appropriate “instrument” (ὄργανον) for the exercise of reason. For example, the mouths of beasts are designed primarily for feeding and so produce only inarticulate sounds such as a bleat or bark, but the human mouth is configured to produce the much more varied sounds that are necessary for intelligible speech.46 Similarly, the suppleness and dexterity of human hands make them apt for every art of human ingenuity and to do the bidding of reason.47 In a word, the Creator endowed human nature with superior intelligence and a refined body “fit for the exercise of royalty,” so that human beings might be the “living image” of his kingship over all creatures.48 The retrieval of an authentically biblical anthropology and somatology is of the utmost importance for our fresh appraisal of the relationship between word and event. Genesis places before our eyes God’s creation of a world that is ordered toward human life and human action. The body gives man a place within this world of space and time. Man exercises his intelligence and realizes his freedom in and through the body. Actions performed in the body, and thus in the world of time and space, have real consequences. In fact, strictly speaking, they are irreversible. If I become intoxicated, get behind the wheel of a car, and kill someone, many lives, including my own, have been altered forever. I cannot press CTRL + Z and reverse the course of events. Real life has no “undo” function. This is true, of course, not only in the case of vicious or irresponsible acts. It applies equally to acts of wisdom and virtue. Because the physical universe has been created by a wise and loving God and thus bears the imprint of divine wisdom and love, there is no such thing as a brute fact, an event utterly devoid of rationality. Even events in which human beings are completely uninvolved, such as a volcanic eruption on a distant planet, must have some inherent significance. But our special concern, and certainly that of the biblical authors, is with events in which human beings are involved, events that engage human intellect and freedom, events with ramifications for human beings. In such events, human souls, acting through bodies that have been 46 De hominis opificio 8:8–9:1 (PG 44:148–149); trans. 394–95. De hominis opificio 8:2; 8:8 (PG 44:144, 148). 48 De hominis opificio 4:1 (PG 44:136); trans. 390–91. 47 Word and Event: A Reappraisal 197 created for the exercise of reason and the disclosure of personhood, leave as it were an indelible mark on the physical universe. Though we cannot devote space to the topic here, it would be helpful in this regard to reflect on the myriad ways we take up the subhuman world into the fabric of human life and culture, and in so doing humanize and spiritualize the world.49 In any case, this must not be viewed as an imposition of the sheer will to dominate. Even where the impulse to make the subhuman world serve anthropic ends is deeply tainted by sin, there takes place some authentic disclosure of the truth of things and a discovery of their true ends. Here, in the consideration of the relationship between spirit and matter, we approach the very heart of the problem, and here our modern minds stand most in need of the healing light of Scripture’s own sacramental view of reality. Language and Truth Our reappraisal of the relationship between word and event also requires careful and extensive consideration of language itself and its place in human life. We tend to dive into questions about the nature of revelation and of Scripture under the assumption that we already pretty much know what language is and how it functions. It is premature, however, to attempt to describe the nature of divinely inspired words when we have not yet devoted serious thought to the mystery of language as such. As Cardinal Ratzinger notes in the Erasmus Lecture, the modern dualism of word and event is the result not simply of a deficient understanding of event but also of a truncated notion of word.50 Biblical scholars and theologians tend to operate with an instrumentalist or merely functional view of language. Language for them is essentially a tool of the isolated, autonomous thinker who asserts his will over external reality and then utilizes knowledge as a means of power over against his environment (including other autonomous individuals). This view of things can never appreciate the true genius of language, which is fundamentally a 49 For some initial thoughts, see Gregory Vall, “‘Man is the Land’: The Sacramentality of the Land of Israel,” in John Paul II and the Jewish People: A Jewish-Christian Dialogue, ed. David G. Dalin and Matthew Levering (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2008), 131–67, esp. 140–41. 50 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 25. 198 Gregory Vall mystery of truth and love, not of “knowledge as power.” As noted above, among material beings man is uniquely endowed to “hear” the voice of creation and to “translate” it into rational discourse. Creation’s relation to the divine Logos is reflected in its intelligibility and goodness, while man’s unique relation to the same Logos is reflected in his intelligence and will, including his linguistic endowment. Jacques Maritain refers to this complementarity as the “nuptial relationship between mind and being.”51 Man’s vocation is to speak on behalf of the rest of creation, and in so doing to ascribe glory to the Creator. As Norris Clarke puts it, the human person is called to listen to the voice of being “with reverence” and to speak out “its meaning in a recreative human logos.”52 Human language is closely bound up with man’s bodily nature and embeddedness in the physical universe. The brain and the organs of speech and hearing are physical. Spoken communication depends on sound waves moving through the air. Written communication depends on physical implements such as ink and paper, or computers. Yet language mediates intellectual and spiritual realities. Human language is thus an externalization of interior life, while at the same time it involves a spiritualization of material things. A book is at once a materialized idea and a spiritualized tree, as it were. Speaking, listening, writing, and reading are activities proper to man as a unity of physical body and spiritual soul. Human language can even be called “sacramental,” in the sense that it gives invisible realities a presence in the world of space and time.53 Language is a function of man’s freedom and of his vocation to “subdue the earth” (Gn 1:28). According to the Genesis narrative, God brought the animals to man “to see what he would name them,” and “whatever the man called” each animal, “that was its name” (2:19). The seeming quaintness of this story should not lead us to overlook its pro51 As quoted (without exact citation of the source) in W. Norris Clarke, The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press), 18. 52 Ibid., 29. 53 Pope John Paul II describes the human body as “a primordial sacrament . . . a sign that efficaciously transmits in the visible world the invisible mystery hidden in God from eternity.” Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body, trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books & Media, 2006), 203 (emphasis removed). Word and Event: A Reappraisal 199 fundity. Assigning names to the beings that surround him gives man real leverage to explore, organize, and master his environment. At the same time, Genesis does not suggest that human acts of linguistic denomination and predication constitute an imposition upon external reality. At the narrative’s culmination, the man’s naming of “woman” is presented rather as a response of wonderment upon his joyful discovery of her true identity and relation to himself (2:23). Language can be a way of receiving creation from the hand of God in gratitude and praise. All man’s subsequent words, however, will be spoken under the shadow of temptation and sin. They will be liable to duplicity and to various distortions of the truth of being. An adequate reappraisal of the relationship between word and event must therefore also consider the effect of sin on language as well as the manner in which human speech, marred by sin, is progressively purified and “redeemed” precisely by being taken up into the economy of revelation. Beginning with Genesis, the Bible presents human language as deeply involved in the drama of man’s alienation from God and in the divine pedagogy by which God reconciles human beings to himself. This important topic has been given surprisingly little attention in fundamental theology and biblical hermeneutics. If we wish to appreciate how biblical words communicate the truth of events (which really is the heart of the matter), we would do well to attend to what Scripture itself teaches us about the act of narration. This is a vast topic, and here we shall have to content ourselves with an observation or two. The truth of an event, the truth that really matters, runs much deeper than the mere facts of a case, for what we take to be “fact” is often only the most superficial dimension of an event or action. And so to judge the truth or falsehood of a speech or narration on the basis of how accurately it represents this superficial level of the event will yield a deficient notion of truth and falsehood. Let us take an example. Under interrogation by Yahweh, Adam says, “The woman whom you gave to be with me gave me from the tree, and I ate” (3:12). In terms of its accuracy of representation of the facts (of the narrated story), this statement is absolutely inerrant. It is true that God gave the woman to the man to be with him, and it is true that the woman gave the fruit of the tree to the man. And yet, Adam’s speech act is profoundly sinful. Rather than accept responsibility for his actions, he manages to point blame at both God and his wife in the same breath. He 200 Gregory Vall speaks with ingratitude and attempts to deflect attention away from his own culpability.54 A speech act may then accurately narrate the facts of the case and still fail to lead us closer to the truth of the event. Conversely, a fictional narrative can communicate real truth, not only a general moral truth, but even the truth of a specific event. For example, Nathan’s parable enables David to face the sinfulness of his own actions on a specific occasion (2 Sm 12:1–15). Language pertains to man’s personhood and his call to interpersonal communion. It enables a person to reach outside his own solitude, to share something of his interiority with others, and to receive what they choose to share of themselves in return. Language enables us to make promises, ask favors, give commands, share knowledge, articulate feelings, or construct an argument. It permits human beings to share a common life and common projects. It makes possible both a personal and a communal sense of past, present, and future—a shared history. It enables “I” subjects to belong to “we” subjects and to participate in various human institutions. Language comes to each of us as the heritage of the human community and it keeps us connected to that community throughout our lives. The individual realizes his or her freedom through language and action, but only within the realm of community, tradition, custom, and law. Indeed, it is by virtue of its communal dimension that language serves man in his ongoing discovery of the truth of things. Understanding comes via conversation. Hans-Georg Gadamer describes how an authentic dialogue is more than the sum of its parts and can take on a life of its own, leading its participants together toward a deeper understanding of the topic under discussion. Thus “the sphere of the ‘We’”—where language lives—mediates between the “I” subject and the objective reality that would disclose its truth.55 As Augustine says, “Reasoning does not make things but discovers them. Before they are discovered, therefore, they abide in themselves; and when they are discovered, they renew us.”56 54 Von Rad, Genesis, 91. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics, trans. and ed. David E. Linge (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), 65–66. 56 De Vera Religione xxxix, 73: “Non enim ratiocinatio talia facit, sed invenit. Ergo antequam inveniantur, in se manent, et cum inveniuntur, nos innovant.” 55 Word and Event: A Reappraisal 201 This principle applies not only to the reasoning of the individual but also to that of a community of persons in dialogue. Ultimately, language is able to mediate between man and the truth of the created universe (including the reflexive truth of man himself) because each of these realities—man, language, and the universe—participates in its own way in the divine Logos and thus in the mystery of Trinitarian knowledge and love. This analogia verbi forms the basis for the very possibility of divine revelation and thus of our capacity for saying anything true about God in human language. God’s Word in Human Events As we ponder the mystery of human language and action in general terms, we must also begin to consider the specific ways God has revealed himself “in deeds and words intrinsically interconnected” within the divine economy. The Epistle to the Hebrews tells us that during the Old Testament period God spoke to Israel “in many partial and varied ways” (1:1). Broadly speaking, these are reducible to law, prophecy, psalmody, and wisdom, but under each of these headings one might identify numerous more specific modes by which God’s word came to Israel. For present purposes it may prove helpful to focus our attention on the way Israel sometimes discerned God’s will in the unfolding of an event per se, without any of the usual intermediaries, and then gave this revelatory event a new verbal mode of existence through narrative artistry, so that a word-event became an event-word. As an example of this let us briefly consider the betrothal of Rebekah in Genesis 24, aided by Meir Sternberg’s masterful analysis of this Hebrew narrative.57 At the outset of the story Abraham commissions a trusted servant to return to his homeland in northern Mesopotamia in order to fetch a suitable bride for his son Isaac. He promises the servant that Yahweh “will send his angel before” him (v 7), but as things turn out no angel appears in the story. Nor does the servant have a revelatory dream at a holy place en route. No prophet approaches him with an oracle. He meets no seer along the way. In order to discern God’s will in the 57 Meir Sternberg, The Poetics of Biblical Narrative: Ideological Literature and the Drama of Reading (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985), 131–52. 202 Gregory Vall affair, the servant is “thrown on his own devices” and “takes a twofold initiative that weds good sense to piety.”58 In other words, he employs faith and reason together. Rather than contrive a designedly arbitrary test of God’s will, such as Gideon does with the fleece (Jgs 6:36–40), Abraham’s servant devises a rational test for finding a friendly, strong, and hospitable woman. A maiden who would grant his request for a drink of water and then go the extra mile by drawing water for his ten thirsty camels would be just the sort of woman he is looking for. Parking his camels near the well in the late afternoon, when he knows women will be coming forth to draw water, he prays, “Yahweh, God of my master Abraham, make things come together before me today, and keep steadfast love with my master Abraham” (Gn 24:12).59 At this point, the narrator duly notes that before the servant even finishes this prayer, Rebekah makes her appearance at the well, suggesting that things are in fact already “coming together” (v 15). Rebekah’s great physical beauty makes her an especially attractive candidate for the test, which she passes with flying colors (vv 16–20). But for the servant the clincher comes when he learns that Rebekah is Isaac’s second cousin. Surely, he reasons, it was Yahweh who “guided” him directly to Abraham’s family (vv 24–27). This could be no mere coincidence. As Sternberg puts it, Rebekah “is, literally, God’s answer (in the medium of plot) to the servant’s prayer.”60 Her timely arrival is a word from Yahweh. Now the servant’s job is to convince Rebekah’s family, specifically her older brother Laban, that this is indeed a match made in heaven. He makes his pitch by way of a lengthy renarration of the sequence of events that led him to this juncture, in the course of which he takes quite a few liberties with the details (vv 34–49). He tactfully omits anything that may have given offense to the Mesopotamian family, rearranges the order of events slightly, and even modifies Abraham’s instructions in such a way as to give the impression that it was the patriarch’s intention 58 Ibid., 137. The Hiphil of Q-R-H means “to cause to converge,” with connotations of divine providence working through apparent coincidence (cf. Gn 27:20 and other forms of the same root in Ru 2:3 and 2 Sm 1:6). 60 Sternberg, Poetics of Biblical Narrative, 137. 59 Word and Event: A Reappraisal 203 all along for Isaac to marry a close relative. Sternberg illuminates the way each of these changes serves a precise rhetorical end.61 His point, however, is emphatically not that the servant is a spin doctor who sacrifices truth on the altar of persuasion. Rather, taking into consideration the lower theological proficiency of his polytheistic audience, the servant tempers his narrative to meet them at their level of understanding and leads them to recognize that Yahweh, the god of Abraham, has manifested his will for Isaac and Rebekah in a remarkable confluence of events. As Sternberg phrases it, “the servant, like many novelists after him, resorts to invention in order to give the truth a more truthlike appearance,” for “the unvarnished truth would not [have carried] enough weight to induce [the family] to part with Rebekah.”62 The servant has employed mythos, or “emplotment,” which always includes a fictive dimension, in order give the providential and revelatory event a new verbal mode of existence. The word-event has become an event-word. When narrative artistry is used in this way by someone whose mind has been illumined by the Spirit of Truth to judge concerning the action of God in history, narration is a prophetic act. Of particular interest for present purposes is Laban’s response (v 50), which indicates that he has been led by the servant’s narrative to draw precisely the correct conclusion about the event that has transpired. “The thing (dabar) has come forth from Yahweh,” he declares. “We cannot speak to you bad or good. Behold, Rebekah is before you. Take her and go, that she may become the wife of your master’s son, just as Yahweh has spoken (dibber).” The Hebrew noun dabar means “thing, event, or word.” The verb dibber, “to speak,” is its cognate. No angel, prophet, seer, diviner, or dream interpreter appears anywhere in the story, and yet, Yahweh has spoken! He has revealed his will in the course of events. He has dibber-ed through a dabar. The event-dabar is in itself already a word-dabar inasmuch as Yahweh has truly guided the course of events, but it takes on a new verbal mode of existence when the servant narrates it for Rebekah’s family and again, of course, when the inspired author of Genesis 24 narrates it for us. 61 62 Ibid., 145–51. Ibid., 149–50. 204 Gregory Vall Time, Narrative, and History A serious reappraisal of word and event within the economy of redemption must also take stock of the biblical view of time and human temporality as well as the biblical narrative’s relation to history. In the present context we can merely touch on these complex matters. The Priestly Heptaemeron, or first creation account (Gn 1:1–2:3), shows us that as soon as God speaks light into being and separates it from darkness, “the march and rhythm of time” is set in motion.63 The “days” of Genesis 1, each with its evening and morning, represent real time, a temporality regulated by cosmic cycles and thus rooted in the created order. This temporality is comprised of the days and months and years with which Israelite readers were familiar and within which they lived their lives. It is not, however, a mere succession of moments. The unique character of the seventh day (2:2–3) gives creation’s divinely instituted temporality a teleological dimension and indicates that it is ordered to man’s vocation to work and rest in imitation of the Creator. The seven-day sequence of Genesis 1:1–2:3 is the anchor for an elaborate Priestly chronology that includes the genealogies of Genesis 5 and 11 and extends throughout the Pentateuch. This chronological framework removes the primeval stories of fall, fratricide, and flood from the mythical realm of a time before time and places every event, from creation to the death of Moses and beyond, within a single historical sequence. This Priestly chronology does not, of course, supply us with anything like accurate historical information regarding the age of the cosmos, the lifespans of the patriarchs, or even the date of the exodus. It accomplishes something much more important. It teaches us that there is one seamless economy comprising creation and redemptive history. Israelite readers of Genesis, living during the crisis of the exile or the early postexilic period, would recognize that the events of their own lives fall within a single divine master plan. The story that Genesis narrates from its opening chapter is the story within which they live. In a homily given many years ago, Ratzinger aptly sums up the teaching of 63 Claus Westermann, Genesis 1–11: A Commentary, trans. John J. Scullion (Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1984), 112. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 205 the first creation narrative this way: “God created the universe in order to enter into a history of love with humankind.”64 As noted in the previous section, the act of emplotment or narration—the act by which an event is given a new verbal mode of existence—necessarily contains a fictive dimension. At a minimum, the author’s selection, arrangement, and choice of words embody an interpretive judgment. But this fictive dimension does not necessarily compromise the truth of a real event. Even if it involves a significant element of literary license, the art of emplotment, with its fictive dimension, can serve the truth of an historical event. In a moment of “invention,” the author draws forth and displays the inherent λόγος dimension of the event. As the term’s etymology suggests, to “invent” is simultaneously to discover and to contrive. What we have just said about the Priestly chronology, however, requires us to push the envelope a bit in this regard. Can a narrative that is not historical in anything like the usual sense of the term give us authentic revelation concerning a fundamentally historical economy? The short answer to this question is yes, at least when that narrative is part of a larger historical tradition and a unified, incipiently canonical testimony to history. The Old Testament contains a remarkable variety of narrative genres and subgenres, each bearing its own sort of witness to historical events and to the historical economy. The book of Jeremiah, for example, contains a great deal of reliable historical information about the final years of the kingdom of Judah, information drawn from contemporary sources and verified in many cases by extrabiblical accounts. By contrast, the book of Daniel, which was written centuries after the events it purports to recount, intentionally flouts the historical record (beginning with its opening verse) and weaves a variety of legends into a highly artificial schema of political events.65 Still, it would be quite mistaken to conclude that the authors of Daniel are unconcerned with history. Properly understood, this unusual book of Scripture bears a profound prophetic 64 Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger, “In the Beginning . . .” : A Catholic Understanding of Creation and the Fall, trans. Boniface Ramsey, Ressourcement (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1995), 30. 65 See John J. Collins, Anchor Bible Dictionary, s.v. “Daniel, Book of,” 6:2:29–37. 206 Gregory Vall witness to the establishment of the kingdom of God within the real history of the ancient Near East. The basic theological impulse behind the composition, compilation, and canonical shaping of the Hebrew Scriptures is historiographical. From the late preexilic period to the early postexilic period, the Holy Spirit prompted Israelite authors and redactors to gather the traditions of their people into a single coherent macronarrative. The result was the so-called Primary Narrative, which stretches from Genesis to 2 Kings, that is, from the creation of the world to Israel’s great political and spiritual crisis, the exile. The redactors of the Primary Narrative joined the Priestly Tetrateuch (Genesis, Exodus, Leviticus, and Numbers) to the Deuteronomistic History (Joshua, Judges, Samuel, and Kings), with the book of Deuteronomy as the keystone of the arch.66 Each of the remaining books in the biblical canon bears its witness to the divine economy by an explicit or implicit orientation to this macronarrative. For example, First and Second Chronicles, together with the books of Ezra and Nehemiah, constitute a kind of Secondary Narrative, a highly interpretive relecture of the Primary Narrative that carries the story forward into the postexilic period. Neither the Holy Spirit nor the human authors and redactors seem to have been greatly troubled by the fact that the Primary Narrative is a hybrid with respect to the historiographical character of its sources. In composing their account of Israel’s political history of the monarchic period, the inspired authors drew heavily upon the royal archives of Israel and Judah, but they also wove into their framework stories about Elijah and Elisha that must have originated in the circle of those prophets’ disciples. For earlier periods, such as that of the judges, they had recourse to at least some legendary material, as is patently the case in the narratives about Samson, for example (Jgs 13–16). For still earlier periods, such as that of the patriarchs, the sacred authors seem to have worked with material that has a certain affinity to folklore or, in a few instances, mythology. Throughout the age of the monarchy, the exile, and the postexilic 66 In other words, the Primary Narrative comprises those books that in the Jewish canon belong to the Torah and the Former Prophets. The Book of Ruth, which was composed somewhat later, belongs to the Writings. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 207 period, Israel continued to look back to the exodus and wilderness wandering as their historical point of reference and theological touchstone. Nothing that had happened in their history either prior to or subsequent to the Mosaic age made much sense if viewed apart from those founding events. But the exile did make sense as chastisement for sins against the Mosaic covenant, and the return from exile made sense as a new exodus and the promise of a new covenant. Remarkably, however, at least to our way of looking at things, the Israelites never seem to have asked themselves questions such as: “Did the exodus really happen? How do we know whether or not it happened? Which of the many versions of the exodus story preserved in our tradition is the most factual?” They did not view past events as irretrievably past and as leaving behind only traces in the archeological strata and literary record. Nor did they suppose that the only valid access to the past is by way of historical-critical research. The redemptive and revelatory events of the past were present to them in and through sacred tradition, by which we mean the whole authentic life of the people of Yahweh as it was handed down from generation to generation and constantly enriched and deepened by new encounters with the word of God. For faithful Israelites there was no need to question the reality of the exodus. Their very existence and communal life as the people of Yahweh was the vital unfolding and trajectory of the founding events. No exodus, no Israel. In exploring further the way the truth of Israel’s past was carried over into their present and future by a living tradition, Gadamer’s notion of Wirkungsgeschichte, or “history of effects,” may prove helpful. As Francis Watson points out, Wirkungsgeschichte is not merely a matter of texts generating more texts. The “historic” event—that is, “the event that marks an enduring turning point in a historical process”—“generates its own Wirkungsgeschichte out of which it is constantly interpreted and reinterpreted.”67 Textual traditions and other elements of tradition play their role within this larger historical process, which in the case of biblical Israel is the very life of the people, lived in the presence of God. 67 Francis Watson, Text and Truth: Redefining Biblical Theology (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1997), 51. On this point, see also Brice Wachterhauser, “Getting it Right: Relativism, Realism, and Truth,” in The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer, ed. Robert J. Dostal (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 65. 208 Gregory Vall As Andrew Hayes has expressed it, the Wirkungsgeschichte of an historic event is “the temporally distended impression,” which that event leaves on the flow of history.68 Maintaining a teleological view of salvation-historical events is crucial here. Israel’s many interpretations and reinterpretations of the exodus must not be viewed as so many layers of ideology superimposed upon the brute facts. The exodus event is from the beginning dense with inherent significance, but this significance only gradually unfolds and discloses itself within the subsequent history of Israel. The exodus, like every other event within Israel’s history, manifests its inner truth more and more fully as that history approaches its telos, or goal. The Christ event is as it were the final cause of the exodus, for “Christ is the end (τέλος) of the law” (Rom 10:4). The Christ Event and the Gospels In the life, death, and Resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth we see the most perfect unity of word and event. Here the eternal Logos makes his definitive entrance into the realm of space and time, making the moment of his entrance “the fullness of time” (Gal 4:4). It is important to note that all the lower levels of the unity of word and event discussed above are taken up into this fullest manifestation of unity. Through the incarnation the eternal Logos takes to himself a created humanity of physical body and rational soul, made to the image of God, and makes it the instrument and sacrament of his divine personhood. In the words of the Catechism of the Catholic Church (§470), the Son of God “communicates to his humanity his own personal mode of existence in the Trinity.” The eternal Word has spoken in human language and revealed the Father in historical deeds. Though the incarnation is a truly marvelous condescension, it is nevertheless true that the λογικός humanity of Christ was an apt instrument for the divine Logos to employ in this manner. (The Logos could not have been hypostatically united to some lower, irrational nature.) Furthermore, the “many partial and varied ways” by which God spoke to Israel in the Old Testament (Heb 1:1) have been taken up into this definitive personal entrance of the Logos into creation and history and, having reached their telos, have been transformed. 68 Private communication to the author, 2004. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 209 Through the glorification of his humanity in the Resurrection, all that Jesus Christ accomplished for our salvation in the days of his flesh has been given a suprahistorical presence and, through the mission of the Holy Spirit, has been made available to believers in all times and places through the Church’s sacramental life and in a special way through the Holy Gospels. We do not access the saving words and deeds of our Lord’s life by stripping away the layers of interpretation in order to get down to some supposed historical bedrock. Any attempt to do so gives a priori assent to the dualism of word and event. Rather, we must allow the four Gospels to lead us into the mystery of Christ on their own terms. In recent years small but important steps have been taken, both by theologians and by the magisterium of the Catholic Church, to retrieve the biblical and patristic notion of the mysteria vitae Iesu.69 It is vital that this work be carried forward, for in the last analysis only a robust and well-articulated understanding of mysterium can strike at the heart of the dualism of word and event. A mysterium is an event in which God has acted manifestly in order to reveal himself and to redeem humanity. It is a moment of divine disclosure, but it always retains an unfathomable plenitude. It is a moment of knowledge, but it is accessible only to one who loves. The term mysterium is best understood in correlation with the term oikonomia, for a mystery is essentially an “economic” event. Because each mystery participates in the economy, it must be viewed in light of the economy as a whole, even as it also illuminates the economy as a whole.70 The ultimate mystery is the “theological” mystery of God’s inner life and his eternal counsel and will, and the divine economy may be defined as his master plan for “dispensing” a certain participation in this mystery to us in time and space. It is, in the Pauline phrase, “the economy of the mystery hidden from eternity in God, who created all things” (Eph 3:9). The centerpiece of this master plan, the definitive economic 69 See, e.g., CCC §512–667; John Paul II, Apostolic Letter Rosarium Virginis Mariae (2002), nos. 18–25; Christoph Schütz, “The Mysteries of the Life of Jesus as a Prism of Faith,” Communio 29 (2002): 28–38; and Martin Bieler, “The Mysteries of Jesus’ Public Life: Stages on the Way to the Cross,” Communio 29 (2002): 47–61. 70 The Lord’s baptism in the Jordan is a good example of this. See Gregory Vall, “Lucis Mysterium: Ignatius of Antioch on the Lord’s Baptism,” Nova et Vetera 8 (2010): 143–60. 210 Gregory Vall mystery, is the person and event of Jesus Christ. He contains the whole economy within himself, for he recapitulates creation, humanity, and Israel, while he “precapitulates,” so to speak, the life of the Church and the eschaton. The oikonomia is therefore “the economy of the fullness of times, to sum up all things in Christ” (1:10). “Gospel” is a literary genre developed to present the mystery of Christ, and the mysteries of the life of Christ, precisely as economic realities. It is axiomatic in New Testament scholarship to note that the evangelists relate the story of Jesus to the Old Testament story by way of allusion and quotation while they simultaneously have the Church in mind as they narrate the events of Christ’s life. But their real reasons for doing this can only be grasped from within a theology of mystery and economy. In each discrete mystery of the life of Jesus the whole person and saving reality of Christ is truly present, and so the evangelists first of all narrate the individual events of Christ’s life in light of the Christ event as a whole. At the same time, because creation, man, and Israel are summed up in the person of Christ, the evangelists present the Christ event and the discrete moments within that event as the telos and fullness of the Old Testament economy. Finally, because the Church’s whole life of grace and glory is already present in Jesus of Nazareth—he who is our life (Col 3:4)—the evangelists narrate the past words and deeds of Jesus in light of his glorious presence at the Father’s right hand and his future coming. As a convenient example of this manner of narrating, let us consider John 6:1–71. Structurally, this passage consists of four panels. First, there is the miracle of the loaves and fishes, which John narrates with considerable detail and characteristically presents as a “sign” performed for the benefit of “the people” (6:1–15). Second, there is the much shorter narrative of Christ’s walking on the sea, which John presents as a private theophany to the disciples rather than a public sign (6:16–21). In composing these first two panels, John seems to have relied heavily on a synoptic-like (perhaps presynoptic) source, since his account agrees with Mark’s in many particulars but does not appear to be directly dependent on the latter (cf. Mk 6:30–52).71 Third, there is a 71 See Craig S. Keener, The Gospel of John: A Commentary (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 2003), 663–64, 671–72. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 211 long dialogue between Jesus and “the people” (also called “the Jews,” especially when they begin to demonstrate doubt and hostility), which John presents as a synagogue instruction given at Capernaum (Jn 6:22– 59). Fourth, there is a shorter dialogue between Jesus and his own disciples concerning their response to his teaching (6:60–71). While these last two panels do contain a few echoes of synoptic tradition, they appear more heavily dependent on distinctively Johannine tradition than do the first two panels. John has put all this together with consummate skill. On the one hand, the chapter moves back and forth between Jesus’s interaction with the people and his interaction with his disciples, while, on the other hand, it moves from action to dialogue, in other words, from event to word. vv 1–15 vv 16–21 vv 22–59 vv 60–71 Jesus’s action on behalf of the people Jesus’s action on behalf of the disciples Jesus’s dialogue with the people Jesus’s dialogue with the disciples Because the first and third panels are by far the longest, and both dialogues serve to unfold the significance of the miracle of the loaves and fishes, the chapter is reducible to a synoptic-like sign followed by a characteristically Johannine discourse, much as the previous chapter is (cf. 5:1–47). In fact, chapter 5 has prepared us for chapter 6 by thematizing the importance of Jesus’s “works” and “words” (5:36, 47). What, then, is the significance of the multiplication of loaves and fishes? In the first place, the miraculous gift of superabundant food, specifically “bread,” signifies Jesus’s teaching itself. A close association between Jesus’s teaching ministry and the miracle of the loaves is already hinted at in the Marcan account (Mk 6:34), and John develops this link in dependence on the way bread sometimes symbolizes divine revelation in the Old Testament.72 On one level, then, John 6 is a teaching about Jesus the teacher. The people call him “Rabbi” (v 25) and even acclaim him the long anticipated Moses-like “Prophet” (v 14), but neither 72 In the Old Testament, bread signifies divine revelation in three modalities: law (Dt 8:3; Neh 9:13–15), prophecy (Am 8:11–12; Is 55:1–3, 10–11), and wisdom (Prv 9:5; Sir 15:3). 212 Gregory Vall of these titles rises to a true understanding of the qualitative difference between the Mosaic law and Jesus’s doctrine.73 During the synagogue discourse the Lord hints at the true nature of what is taking place in his teaching ministry by quoting a line from the prophets—“And they will all be taught by God” (v 45; cf. Is 54:13)—and later he tells his disciples, “The words that I have spoken to you are spirit and life” (Jn 6:63). Finally, Simon Peter confesses that Jesus is “the Holy One of God,” who alone offers “words of eternal life” (vv 68–69). Of course, John has already informed his readers that Jesus not only speaks the word of God but is himself the eternal Word made flesh (1:1– 2, 14). That is why Jesus is less concerned to refer the sign of the loaves to his teaching as such than he is to identify himself as “the bread of God, who comes down from heaven and gives life to the world” (6:33). The sign of the loaves quite naturally reminds Jesus’s Jewish interlocutors of the miracle of the manna in the wilderness, but when they mention this Old Testament event in an effort to get another free meal from Jesus, they unwittingly provide him with an opportunity to compare and contrast himself to the Mosaic law. John has them quote a line from Scripture that actually combines elements of several Old Testament passages without reproducing any one of them verbatim: “Bread from heaven he gave them to eat” (v 31).74 At least some of these texts associate the miracle of the manna with the law of Moses, which was “heavenly bread,” that is, divine revelation, given to Israel in the wilderness. This Old Testament symbolism is presupposed when Jesus responds to their quotation by identifying himself as “the true bread from heaven,” that is, the definitive self-revelation of God, far superior to the Mosaic law (v 32).75 Starting with this exchange, the bulk of the bread of life dialogue develops the idea that the sign of the loaves points to the incarnation of the Logos, with the Old Testament manna/law symbolism as back73 The Torah portrays Moses as enjoying “face to face” intimacy with Yahweh (Ex 33:11; Dt 34:10; cf. Nm 12:8) but also qualifies this claim by noting that, strictly speaking, neither Moses nor any human being can see God’s face and live (Ex 33:20). The bread of life discourse locates Jesus’s superiority to Moses and his uniqueness as God’s definitive self-revelation precisely in the fact that he alone “has seen the Father” (Jn 6:46; cf. 1:17–18). 74 Cf. Ex 16:4, 15; Ps 78:24, 105:40; Neh 9:15; Ws 16:20. 75 See Keener, Gospel of John, 679–81. Word and Event: A Reappraisal 213 ground (vv 31–51). Jesus himself is “the bread which has come down from heaven” (v 41). The manna/law connection is, however, only one element in a rich texture of Old Testament echoes in John 6. The basic plot of the miracle of the loaves and fishes, as found in all four Gospels, recalls a similar miracle worked by the prophet Elisha (2 Kgs 4:42–44), and John strengthens this reminiscence by specifying that the loaves multiplied by Jesus were made of barley, as was also the case in the Elisha story (Jn 6:9, 13). John’s concise narrative of the walking on the sea, like its synoptic parallels, echoes theophanic imagery from the Old Testament (v 19; cf. Job 9:8; Ps 77:19), and Jesus’s exclamation to the disciples in the boat—literally, “I am! Fear not!” (Jn 6:20)—recalls similar expressions of divine reassurance in the oracles of Deutero-Isaiah (Is 41:10; 43:5, 10). In the book of Sirach, Lady Sophia promises her devotees that the acquisition of wisdom engenders a desire for still more wisdom: “Those who eat of me will hunger for more, and those who drink of me will thirst for more” (Sir 24:21). In the bread of life dialogue, however, the Johannine Jesus turns this statement on its head in order to indicate that he is the definitive Wisdom, who gives perfect satisfaction: “The one who comes to me will hunger no more, and the one who believes in me will never again thirst” (Jn 6:35). Though all the action in John 6 takes place in Galilee, the evangelist makes a special point of noting that these things occurred when “Passover, the feast of the Jews, was near” (v 4).76 This statement hearkens back to the cleansing of the Jerusalem temple, which according to John’s chronology took place at a previous Passover at the beginning of Jesus’s ministry (2:13), while it simultaneously anticipates the later Passover in Jerusalem that is the setting of Jesus’s passion (11:55; 12:1; 13:1; 18:28, 39; 19:14). This two-way linkage contributes to the sense that the miracle of the loaves is a pivotal event in Jesus’s ministry—the fourth of seven “signs”—while it relates the events and words of chapter 6 to John’s overarching presentation of Jesus as the “Lamb of God” (1:29, 36; 19:36). The “flesh” that the Word takes to himself in the incarnation is the very flesh that he gives as “bread for the life of the world” on the Cross (1:14; 6:51). 76 The availability of barley loaves and the abundance of green grass may also suggest a setting in early spring (6:9–10; cf. Mk 6:39). 214 Gregory Vall As Christological sign, therefore, the miracle of the loaves simultaneously points back to the incarnation and ahead to the paschal mystery. John, then, relates the sign of the loaves to the entire career of the Son of Man, who “came down from heaven, not to do [his] own will but the will of the one who sent [him]” (v 38), and who is “ascending to where he was previously” in order to make available the “life-giving” Spirit (vv 62–63; cf. 7:39). John 6 relates the sign of the loaves and fishes, not only to the story of Israel and to the Christ event as a whole but also to the life of the Church. “The twelve,” including four named members of the group, play an unusually prominent role in this chapter, which can be read almost as a kind of treatise on faith and discipleship. Jesus involves Philip and Andrew in the miracle itself, not because he needs their help but in order to “test” them (vv 5–13). Then, in the synagogue discourse he explains at some length that only those who are drawn by the Father can come to the Son, and only those who believe in the Son have eternal life (vv 37–40, 44–47). When “many of his disciples” are scandalized by his teaching and fall away, Jesus directly challenges the twelve concerning their commitment to him (vv 60–67). Speaking on behalf of the group, Peter makes his great confession of faith, but Jesus ominously points out that even within his specially chosen group of twelve there is “a devil” who will betray him (vv 68–71). Moreover, by placing some emphasis on the Lord’s having “given thanks” (εὐχαριστήσας), John drops an initial hint that the multiplication of loaves and fishes is a type of the Eucharist (vv 11, 23) and thus prepares us for the explicit teaching on the Eucharist with which the synagogue discourse culminates (vv 52–58). The connection between miracle and sacrament lies not so much in the simple fact that both involve bread as it does in the fact that the former signifies the revelation and “life” that come into the world in the person and event of Jesus Christ, while the latter is the mode by which that life is available to the Church in all places and times. The crucial link between the two is the paschal mystery: Jesus gives his “flesh” as “bread for the life of the world” upon the Cross, so that his disciples may receive this same flesh in the Eucharist (vv 51–53). In the last analysis, “life” is the unifying theme of John 6. In its mundane dimension the meal of loaves and fishes is merely “the food Word and Event: A Reappraisal 215 that perishes,” but for those with faith it signifies “the food that remains for eternal life” (v 27). In the Fourth Gospel “life” designates the true and definitive revelation of the Father, which is uniquely present in and through the person and event of the incarnate Son. Revelation is “life” because it brings one into knowledge of “the only true God and Jesus Christ, whom [he has] sent,” and this knowledge is the very essence of eternal life (17:3). As Word made flesh, Jesus is “the bread of God which comes down from heaven and gives life to the world” (6:33). This life or revelation is present in his teaching, which, because it consists in “words of eternal life” (v 68), is qualitatively superior to the Mosaic law. The latter had its own sign in the gift of the manna, which the ancestors “ate in the wilderness and yet died” (v 49). The life or revelation that is present in Jesus’s words is present also in the deeds, or “signs,” by which he does “the will” of the one who sent him (vv 38–40), above all in the great sign of the Son of Man’s being “lifted up” on the Cross (3:14–15; 8:28; 12:32, 34). Finally, it is sacramentally available to those who “eat the flesh of the Son of Man and drink his blood” in the Eucharist (6:53). The gift of life or revelation that is definitive within the historical economy is by definition also eschatological, and so it should come as no surprise that eschatology is woven throughout John 6. The particular accent that John places on the superabundance of loaves and fishes may harken back to those prophetic oracles that present the eschatological blessing as a meal of great abundance (vv 11–13; cf. Is 25:6; 55:1–3).77 Jesus himself is this meal, “the bread of life” (6:35, 48). As is well known, Johannine eschatology combines a realized dimension with a future dimension. The one who believes in Jesus already “has eternal life” (v 47), and Jesus himself “will raise him up on the last day” (v 40). These two complementary dimensions are frequently mentioned throughout the main part of the synagogue discourse, which presents Jesus himself as the bread of life and faith as the mode of access to that life (vv 32–51), but the same two dimensions of eschatology are, if anything, even more emphatically present in the Eucharistic portion of the discourse, and in the very same terms (vv 53–58).78 “The one who chews my flesh and 77 78 Keener, Gospel of John, 668. This suggests that faith in the historical Jesus and reception of the Eucharist are two equally essential, fully integral, and entirely compatible aspects of the disciple’s 216 Gregory Vall drinks my blood has eternal life, and I shall raise him up on the last day” (v 54). The Eucharist is, then, a foretaste of the heavenly banquet (v 58). In sum, the narrative of John 6 presents the multiplication of the loaves as a “sign” (vv 14, 26), a term that is for all intents and purposes the Johannine equivalent of mysterium. John illuminates this event’s place within a complex web of economically interrelated events and in the process spreads before our eyes almost the whole economy of redemption: from Mosaic law, to prophecy and wisdom, to Christ event, to the life of the Church, to “the last day.” The foregoing analysis is meant to provide an example of how the evangelists bring literary artistry to the service of the mysteria vitae Iesu, viewed precisely as “economic” realities. According to Dei Verbum, “the Church unhesitatingly asserts” the “historical character” (historicitatem) of the four Gospels. At the same time, she recognizes quite clearly their literary character, noting that the evangelists “select[ed] some things from the many which had been handed on by word of mouth or in writing, reduc[ed] some of them to a synthesis, explain[ed] some things in view of the situation of their churches, and preserv[ed] the form of proclamation” (§19). A careful comparison of the four Gospels leads to the unavoidable conclusion that the evangelists exercised a considerable degree of literary license. For example, they could insert a saying of Jesus into an entirely new context, conflate two or more events into a single account, or even change one demoniac into two demoniacs!79 To be sure, the evangelists “faithfully hand on what Jesus Christ . . . really did and taught” (Dei Verbum §19), adherence to Christ. The particularly solemn negative formulation of v 53—“Amen, amen, I say to you, unless you eat the flesh of the Son of Man and drink his blood, you have no life within you”—may well warn against treating the Eucharist as somehow secondary or unessential. 79 E.g., Matthew reworks the logion about sitting with Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob in the kingdom of God and inserts it into his account of the healing of the centurion’s servant in order to sharpen the contrast between gentile faith and Jewish unbelief (Mt 8:11–12; cf. Lk 7:1–10, 13:28–29). John’s account of the anointing at Bethany (Jn 12:1–8) combines elements from two rather different anointing stories from the Synoptic tradition (cf. Mk 14:3–9; Lk 7:36–50). Matthew changes Mark’s one demoniac to two (Mt 8:28–34; cf. Mk 5:1–20), just as he also turns blind Bartimaeus into two blind men (Mt 20:29–34; cf. Mk 10:46–52) and has Jesus enter Jerusalem on two donkeys rather than one (Mt 21:1–11; cf. Mk 11:1–11)! Word and Event: A Reappraisal 217 but the Gospels are for all that very far from supplying us with raw video of Jesus’s ministry. It is quite understandable that faithful Christians would be put on the defensive by the shenanigans of the Jesus Seminar, but any attempt to “defend” the Gospels by means of the implausible harmonization of surface details is entirely wrongheaded, for such a procedure buys into the truncated notion of event that is the root of our problem.80 The evangelists employ literary artistry, with its fictive dimension, in order to draw out and display something of the event’s economic significance. In order to draw these reflections to a conclusion, I shall attempt to sum up what is going on in John 6 in terms of the unity of word and event. In the incarnation the eternal Logos entered the world of space and time, the inherently λογικός world that he himself had created. In order to act personally within this world, he assumed a λογικός humanity, which was created ad imaginem Dei, and he made it the apt instrument of his divine personhood. In this concrete humanity, Israelite “flesh” drawn from a daughter of Israel, he entered the current of Israelite history and human history at a particular point in space and time. That current carried within it all that made Israel Israel: the cultural influences of Mesopotamia, Egypt, Canaan, and Greece; the virtues and vices of patriarchs, prophets, and kings; exodus, statehood, and exile; the exultant canticle of Hannah and the wordless martyrdom of Naboth; “many partial and varied” words of Yahweh, intrinsically interconnected with his marvelous deeds; a liturgical calendar replete with ancient rites and inspired psalms; and so forth. He walked among a people who were the product of this powerful current of history and culture, and he took upon himself their sins. Meanwhile every authentic trajectory of prophecy and piety from Israel’s past found its telos in his ministry. On the mountain in Galilee Jesus served this people a miraculously abundant meal, and in the synagogue at Capernaum he taught them the 80 For a brief account of the work of the Jesus Seminar, see H. K. McArthur and R. F. Berkey, “Jesus, Quest of the Historical,” in Dictionary of Biblical Interpretation, 2 vols., ed. John H. Hayes (Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press, 1999), 1:583–84. For a well-intentioned but wrongheaded attempt to defend the inerrancy of the Gospels by means of an implausible harmonization of surface details, see Karl Keating, What Catholics Really Believe—Setting the Record Straight: 52 Answers to Common Misconceptions about the Catholic Faith (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992), 34–36. 218 Gregory Vall significance of the sign—words and deeds intrinsically interconnected. In fact, the barley loaves signify his teaching itself, “words of everlasting life” that are more truly manna from heaven than was the Mosaic law. The loaves signify the Logos himself, come down from heaven in the incarnation. They signify his flesh, which he gives as bread for the life of the world—historically in his passion, sacramentally in the Eucharist, eschatologically in the Resurrection on the last day. Decades after the event, which by that time had already found its way into three Gospels, John the evangelist, under the inspiration of the Holy Spirit, composed his own unique account, combining pre-Marcan, synoptic-like tradition with the unique perspective of the beloved disciple. John’s concern was not to represent the event wie es eigentlich geschehen war but to disclose and make available its vertical dimension and its economic character, and to this end he exercised literary license. But John’s narrative itself also has an economic character, for inspired Scripture plays its own proper role within the economy of redemption. In it the word-event of the multiplication of loaves and fishes is present in a new modality. It has become an event-word. The Holy Gospels are themselves living bread, the Church’s daily bread, because they put us in touch with the person and event of Jesus Christ. N&V Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 219-240 219 Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism in the Church Mary Healy Sacred Heart Major Seminary Detroit, MI “THE CRISIS OF FAITH IN CHRISTin modern times began with a modified way of reading sacred Scripture—seemingly the sole scientific way.”1 This statement, penned by Joseph Ratzinger two years before he became pope, explains the decisive importance he attributed to a reform of biblical interpretation within the task of renewing the Church at large. A concern for the proper interpretation of Scripture had long been at the heart of his theological work. When he was elected to the See of Peter in 2005, Ratzinger had already spent more than half a century as a theologian whose work was articulated in distinctively biblical terms and who often reflected on questions of exegesis, faith and theology.2 His 1988 Erasmus Lecture on “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis” built on his earlier work diagnosing the problems in modern critical exegesis and pointing the way toward a more adequate hermeneutic.3 As prefect of the Con1 Benedict XVI, On the Way to Jesus Christ, trans. Michael Miller (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2005), 9. 2 For a good overview of Benedict’s biblical approach to theology, see Scott Hahn, Covenant and Communion: The Biblical Theology of Pope Benedict XVI (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos, 2009). 3 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: On the Question of the Foundations and Approaches of Exegesis Today,” in Richard J. Neuhaus, ed., Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: The Ratzinger Conference on the Bible and the Church, Encounter Series (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1989), 1–23. A new translation of the German original, which includes some sections missing from the earlier published edition, 220 Mary Healy gregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, he continued to follow closely developments in biblical scholarship. As pope, he summoned the world Synod of Bishops to address the theme “The Word of God in the Life and Mission of the Church,” following it two years later with his post-synodal apostolic exhortation Verbum Domini. He declared a year of St. Paul in 2008–9, urging all Catholics to familiarize themselves with the writings of the apostle. Finally, one of his highest priorities as pope was to complete his three-volume work of biblical Christology, Jesus of Nazareth, a book that applies the principles articulated in the 1988 address and other works, modeling a biblical theology that integrates the tools of modern scholarship with faith in Scripture as a living word from God. At the heart of Ratzinger’s work on biblical interpretation is his critique of the modern bifurcation of exegesis and faith, and his call for the recovery of a hermeneutic of faith that does justice to both the divine and human dimensions of Scripture. Such a hermeneutic, as Pope Benedict pointed out in Verbum Domini, presupposes a reliance on the Holy Spirit, for “without the efficacious working of the ‘Spirit of Truth’ (Jn 14:16), the words of the Lord cannot be understood.”4 He went on to support this principle by quoting no less than five authorities from Christian tradition: Irenaeus, Chrysostom, Jerome, Gregory the Great, and Richard of St. Victor. The liturgy too witnesses to the necessity of the Spirit for biblical interpretation, especially in the ancient prayers invoking the Spirit before the proclamation of the readings: “Send your Paraclete Spirit into our hearts and make us understand the Scriptures which he has inspired; and grant that I may interpret them worthily, so that the faithful assembled here may profit thereby.”5 This article takes Ratzinger’s proposal for a hermeneutic of faith as a starting point for exploring the thesis that biblical interpretation in the Church is an inherently prophetic activity, that is, an activity that entails a Spirit-conferred understanding of divine revelation. I will begin by is given in José Granados et al., eds., Opening Up the Scriptures: Joseph Ratzinger and the Foundations of Biblical Interpretation, Ressourcement (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008), 1–29. In this essay I use the earlier translation, the one actually delivered by Cardinal Ratzinger in New York, except where noted. 4 Benedict XVI, Verbum Domini (2012), 16. 5 Ibid., quoting Sacramentarium Serapionis II (XX): Didascalia et Constitutiones Apostolorum, ed. F. X. Funk, II (Paderborn, 1906), 161. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 221 offering a brief resume of Ratzinger’s diagnosis and his prescription for placing biblical exegesis on a more sound footing. I will then consider his proposal in light of what the New Testament itself teaches regarding an adequate hermeneutic for the interpretation of Scripture. In the third part I will turn to Kevin Vanhoozer’s theory of speech acts as a helpful lens for reflecting on what it is we do when we interpret Scripture. As we will see, Scripture presents itself as a divine act of communication, the completion of which requires the illumination of the reader’s mind by divine grace. In biblical terms, this grace is a participation in the charism of prophecy. Finally I will conclude by suggesting some theological and pastoral implications of this prophetic understanding of the work of biblical interpretation. Ratzinger’s Diagnosis and Prescription Ratzinger begins his critique by observing that modern biblical criticism began with a euphoric confidence that, freed from the constraints of tradition and dogma, it could finally deliver a strictly objective knowledge of Jesus, ancient Israel, and the early Church. In this new approach, underpinned by Enlightenment rationalism, faith was considered an impediment to an objective reading of the text, a bias that had to be methodologically excluded. “Faith itself is not a component of this method, nor is God a factor to be dealt with in historical events.”6 If God is not an actor on the stage of history, then the biblical text is a purely human reality that has to be analyzed within a strictly human horizon. The exegetical task, then, came to be envisioned as that of dissecting texts in order to excise their “mythological” elements—their claims regarding divine intervention in human events—and explain these in terms of purely worldly causality. But this approach, Ratzinger maintains, did not deliver on its promises. Instead of producing scientifically assured and agreed-upon results, it led to “the sprouting of ever more numerous hypotheses which finally turn into a jungle of contradictions.”7 Moreover, Scripture was now viewed as a collection of disparate texts written by a variety of human authors, which no longer had an overarching unity. It came to be re6 7 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 2. Ibid. 222 Mary Healy garded as “a cacophony of voices and sources, patched poorly together, and edited to further political and religious agendas.”8 Not surprisingly, in response to these developments, systematic theologians distanced themselves from biblical scholarship and sought for “a theology which was as independent as possible from exegesis.”9 For preachers and pastors, it became more difficult to explain in what sense Scripture has normative authority for Christian faith and life. Ironically, Ratzinger argues, the zeal of the critical methods to expose the biases and ideologies of biblical authors has been accompanied by a striking blindness to their own prejudices. Underlying these supposedly neutral methods are often unexamined and faulty philosophical premises. The laser beam of criticism thus needs to be focused on the critical methods themselves—not to invalidate them but precisely to free them from their own distortions and retrieve what is genuinely valuable in them. Foremost among the presuppositions that need to be reexamined is the notion that faith must be excluded for the sake of objectivity. In fact, as philosophical hermeneutics has long recognized, the ideal of approaching a text with absolute objectivity is an illusion. Every interpreter brings a perspective, a set of fundamental presuppositions that guide interpretation. If one systematically excludes Judeo-Christian faith—that faith within which the Scriptures were written—one substitutes not neutrality but rather an alien set of presuppositions. As Pope Benedict states with limpid clarity in Verbum Domini, “The lack of a hermeneutic of faith with regard to Scripture entails more than a simple absence; in its place there inevitably enters another hermeneutic, a positivistic and secularized hermeneutic ultimately based on the conviction that the Divine does not intervene in human history.”10 Thus the exclusion of faith is itself a bias that precludes understanding the biblical text on its own terms. Ratzinger’s proposal for a truly adequate hermeneutic, one that moves beyond the limitations and distortions of historical criticism, is a new synthesis of rigorous historical research with an openness to “the 8 Joseph Atkinson, “Scripture and the Exegete: Reflections on Ratzinger’s Erasmus Lecture Twenty Years Later,” Incarnate Word 2 (2009): 609–41; here 614–15. 9 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 3. 10 Verbum Domini, 35b. Emphasis in the original. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 223 inner dynamism of the word.”11 The exegete must not “approach the text with a ready-made philosophy” or “exclude a priori that (almighty) God could speak in human words in the world.”12 Rather he must be “ready to accept that the truly original may occur in history, something which cannot be derived from precedents but which opens up out of itself.”13 Only such a hermeneutic of faith is adequate to the claim of biblical religion that God has entered time and space. Historical events are not mere ciphers for theological ideas; rather, they are themselves a “word” from God, as the Hebrew word dabar with its dual meaning of “word” and “event” suggests.14 From this principle Ratzinger derives two “rules” of biblical interpretation. First, “both word and event have to be considered equally original.”15 That is, one cannot posit a dichotomy such that the meaning of Scripture lies solely in hypothetically reconstructed raw historical events, stripped of the theological clothing given them by the biblical authors—or conversely, that it lies solely in spiritual truths abstracted from the narration of supposedly unhistorical events. Rather, God’s revelation takes place through words and deeds having an intrinsic unity. As Dei Verbum expressed it, “The deeds wrought by God in the history of salvation manifest and confirm the teaching and realities signified by the words, while the words proclaim the deeds and clarify the mystery contained in them.”16 Second, exegesis must allow for the “organic continuity of meaning which exists between the Old and New Testaments.”17 All Scripture is a unity, the unifying principle of which is Christ, the Word made flesh, and the historical subject to whom this word is addressed, the one people of God. “To read Scripture as a unity therefore means to read it from 11 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 18. Ibid., 19. 13 Ibid. 14 Ibid., 20. Ratzinger expresses the point with equal clarity in his introduction to Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfiguration, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2008), xv. 15 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 20. 16 Vatican Council II, Dei Verbum (1965), 2. 17 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 20. Emphasis in the original. 12 224 Mary Healy the Church as its existential locus and to regard the faith of the Church as its true hermeneutical key.”18 On one point Ratzinger concedes perhaps too much to the modern view of the exegete’s task. He states that “texts must first of all be traced back to their historical origins and interpreted in their proper historical context. But then, in a second exegetical operation, one must look at them also in light of the total movement of history and in light of history’s central event, Jesus Christ.”19 This two-step procedure implies, if unintentionally, that faith becomes hermeneutically relevant only after the crucial exegetical judgments have been made. That is, before one moves to a theological interpretation, questions regarding the background and meaning of the text are first asked and answered within a purely historical framework. But as Ratzinger himself already noted, in the interpretation of history there can be no “pure objectivity.”20 A purely secular investigation of historical origins will lead to purely secular results. It is as though a psychologist were to evaluate Jesus’s claims and actions from a purely secular clinical perspective, which by definition considers human causality alone, and only afterward to consider the question of his divinity. In this case one risks having already arrived at the conclusion of some of Jesus’s contemporaries: “Is this not Jesus, the son of Joseph? Do we not know his father and mother? Then how can he say, ‘I have come down from heaven’?” (Jn 6:42); or even, “He is out of his mind” (Mk 3:21; cf. Jn 10:20). As Al Wolters has compellingly demonstrated, the interpreter’s stance of faith, or lack thereof, inevitably influences every step of exegesis, even such apparently neutral and technical operations as textual criticism and lexicography.21 A hermeneutic of faith, then, is one that rigorously investigates the historical origins of the text, but as open from the beginning to the transcendent mystery contained in the word. In Verbum Domini, written twenty-two years after the Erasmus Lecture, the pope expressed this more nuanced view: “To distinguish 18 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” in Opening Up the Scriptures, 6. This is in one of the sections missing from the original English edition of his lecture. 19 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis,” 20. 20 Ibid., 7. 21 Wolters, “Confessional Criticism and the Night Visions of Zechariah,” in Renewing Biblical Interpretation, ed. Craig Bartholomew et al. (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 2000), 90–117. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 225 two levels of approach to the Bible does not in any way mean to separate or oppose them, nor simply to juxtapose them. They exist only in reciprocity. Unfortunately, a sterile separation sometimes creates a barrier between exegesis and theology, and this ‘occurs even at the highest academic levels.’”22 The Biblical Hermeneutic of the New Testament Ratzinger’s thesis concerning the unity of word and deed, old covenant and new, is of course rooted in Scripture itself. The effort to develop an authentically Christian hermeneutic must therefore include a study of what the New Testament teaches and models concerning biblical interpretation—part of theology’s perpetual task of ressourcement. What implicit hermeneutical principles underlie the New Testament’s assertions regarding the interpretation of Scripture? How can they be properly transposed into today’s postmodern critical context and integrated into an adequate hermeneutic? A prominent theme in the New Testament, particularly in the Gospels, is precisely that of the misunderstanding of Scripture. In the Synoptics, Jesus repeatedly reproaches the scribes and Pharisees—the experts in biblical interpretation—with the rhetorical question, “Have you not read . . . ?” “Have you not read what David did, when he was hungry, and those who were with him . . . ?” (Mt 12:3) “Have you not read that he who made them from the beginning made them male and female . . . ?” (Mt 19:4) “Have you never read, ‘Out of the mouth of babes and nurslings you have brought perfect praise’?” (Mt 21:16) 22 Benedict XVI, Verbum Domini 35. 226 Mary Healy “Have you never read in the scriptures: ‘The very stone which the builders rejected has become the head of the corner; this was the Lord’s doing, and it is marvelous in our eyes’?” (Mt 21:42)23 Of course the scribes and Pharisees have read and quite likely memorized all these texts, yet are apparently blind to their true meaning as it comes to light through Jesus’s own words and deeds. Likewise, Jesus sharply admonishes the Sadducees, “Is not this why you are wrong, that you know neither the scriptures nor the power of God?” (Mk 12:24) Their rejection of the doctrine of the resurrection demonstrates their failure to penetrate the meaning of God’s self-identification in Scripture as the God of Abraham, of Isaac, and of Jacob: “he is not the God of the dead, but of the living” (Mk 12:27). In each of these instances, Jesus’s reprimand suggests that the problem is not merely methodological. It is not that they have failed to apply the proper exegetical techniques to the biblical text, but that their hearts are closed to a revelation of its true meaning. The very people entrusted with authority to interpret Israel’s Scriptures have, despite their erudition, completely missed the true significance of the holy texts (cf. Acts 13:27). Jesus’s admonitions serve as a perennial warning to biblical exegetes. Having analyzed the text from every methodological angle, could we merit the reproof, “Have you never read . . . ?” Pope Benedict alluded to this danger in his opening address for the 2008 Synod: St Augustine recalls the scribes and Pharisees who were consulted by Herod when the Magi arrived. Herod wants to know where the Savior of the world would be born. They know it, they give the correct answer: in Bethlehem. They are great specialists who know everything. However they do not see reality, they do not know the Savior. St Augustine says: they are signs on the road for others, but they themselves do not move. This is a great danger as well in our reading of Scripture: we stop at the human 23 Cf. Mt 9:13; 12:5, 7; 22:31; Mk 2:25; 12:10, 26; Lk 6:3. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 227 words . . . and we do not discover the present in the past, the Holy Spirit who speaks to us today in the words from the past.24 A similar motif runs through the Gospel of John. Jesus admonishes the Jewish authorities: “You search the scriptures, because you think that in them you have eternal life; but it is they that bear witness to me . . . If you believed Moses, you would believe me, for he wrote of me. But if you do not believe his writings, how will you believe my words?” (Jn 5:39, 46–47). He thereby indicts his opponents on their own grounds: They appeal to the writings of Moses to justify their rejection of Jesus (cf. Jn 6:30–31; 9:29), failing to recognize that those very writings bear witness to him (cf. Jn 7:42; 20:9). But it is not only Jesus’s adversaries who are biblically inept. His disciples too are continually confronted with their own inability to grasp the meaning of the Scriptures. Jesus repeatedly affirms that his death and Resurrection will take place in fulfillment of biblical prophecy (Mt 26:31, 54, 56; Mk 14:49). Yet each time he predicts his passion, his words meet with incomprehension (Mk 8:31–32; 9:10, 32). Luke reports that the disciples “did not understand this saying, and it was concealed from them, that they should not perceive it” (Lk 9:45; cf. 18:34). Like the scroll sealed with seven seals in the book of Revelation, the Scriptures are locked, and no one possesses the hermeneutical key that opens up their meaning. The hermeneutical key is, of course, the passion and Resurrection of the Lamb. The incomprehension of the disciples is a pre-Paschal failing that the evangelists portray retrospectively in the light of Easter faith. The Fourth Gospel often alludes to this post-Paschal enlightenment. In the episode of the cleansing of the temple, the disciples are puzzled by Jesus’s claim that he will raise up “this temple” in three days. But after his Resurrection, they “remembered that he had said this; and they believed the scripture and the word which Jesus had spoken” (Jn 2:22). The meaning of his entry into Jerusalem seated on a young donkey is likewise opaque: “His disciples did not understand this at first; but when Jesus was glorified, then they remembered that this had been written of him and had been done to him” (Jn 12:16). Until they encounter the 24 Benedict XVI, opening address at the 2008 World Synod of Bishops. 228 Mary Healy risen Lord, even the empty tomb and folded burial cloths are an enigma: Peter and John are perplexed because “as yet they did not know the scripture, that he must rise from the dead” (Jn 20:9). It is Luke who depicts in most detail the passage from ignorance to enlightenment. In the story of the journey to Emmaus, the risen Jesus rebukes the two disconsolate disciples, “O foolish men, and slow of heart to believe all that the prophets have spoken! Was it not necessary that the Christ should suffer these things and enter into his glory?” Then “beginning with Moses and all the prophets, he interpreted to them in all the scriptures the things concerning himself ” (Lk 24:25–27). Whereas previously the Scriptures were an insoluble enigma, now they appear as a luminous, unified whole bearing witness to a single plan of salvation culminating in Christ’s Paschal mystery. The enlightenment of the two is repeated for the eleven when the risen Lord “opened their minds to understand the scriptures, and said to them, ‘Thus it is written, that the Christ should suffer and on the third day rise from the dead’” (Lk 24:45– 46). Only such a divine work of interior illumination enables them to grasp the inner unity of salvation history, centered on Christ. Jesus’s Resurrection enables his followers to perceive that Scripture has been fulfilled in him. However, it is only at Pentecost that the apostles themselves become competent and authoritative interpreters of the Scriptures. Pentecost, as Luke portrays it, is the Spirit’s decisive empowerment of the Church to understand and proclaim the Word that God has spoken in Christ. Immediately after the descent of the Spirit in Acts 2, Peter delivers his Pentecost speech, an authoritative interpretation of both the Pentecost event itself and Jesus’s Paschal mystery. His entire speech is an act of biblical interpretation, centered first on a passage from the prophet Joel and then on Psalm 16. It is worth examining Peter’s speech in some detail to uncover his hermeneutic. Peter begins by quoting Joel, making minor alterations to the text to bring out his own particular emphases: This is what was spoken by the prophet Joel: “And in the last days it shall be, God declares, that I will pour out my Spirit upon all flesh, and your sons and your daughters shall prophesy, and your young men shall see visions, and your old men shall dream dreams; yea, and on my menservants and my maidservants in Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 229 those days I will pour out my Spirit; and they shall prophesy.” (Acts 2:16–18) Whereas Joel used the expression “afterwards” (Jl 2:28), Peter amends it to “in the last days,” indicating that the outpouring of the Spirit signals the arrival of the end times, God’s decisive intervention in history to bring his plan to its culmination. What just occurred, Peter claims, is the fulfillment of God’s promises to pour out his Spirit, no longer selectively on a few individuals with special tasks such as kings, prophets, and liturgical artisans, but indiscriminately on all God’s people: men and women, young and old, slave and free. The gift of the Spirit is closely linked with prophecy, the ability to speak God’s word under the inspiration of the Spirit. The first effect of the universal outpouring of the Spirit is a universal dissemination of the prophetic charism. In the background of the Joel passage is an earlier Old Testament episode, the appointment of seventy elders in Numbers 11. In that narrative, God “took some of the spirit that was upon [Moses]” and placed it on the seventy who would share his burden of leadership. Numbers tells us that immediate effect of this impartation was that the elders “prophesied, but they did so no more” (Nm 11:25), suggesting some kind of charismatic phenomena that were clearly observable but short-lived.25 When two men who remained in the camp also exhibited the same prophetic behavior, Joshua objected to Moses that they had not been with the registered group. The punch line of the story is Moses’s exclamation in reply: “Are you jealous for my sake? Would that all the Lord’s people were prophets, that the Lord would put his spirit upon them!” (Nm 11:29). Later in Israel’s history, the prophet Joel alludes to this implicit prayer to affirm that in the messianic age God will indeed bestow on the whole people his Spirit, with the consequent gift of prophecy. Peter in turn quotes the Joel text in Acts 2 to declare that Moses’s yearning and God’s promise through Joel have now been superabundantly fulfilled. The eschatological gift of the Spirit, far from rendering prophecy obsolete, has made the Church a community of prophets. Peter further highlights this point by appending to the quotation a phrase not pres25 For the association of prophecy with observable charismatic phenomena, see also 1 Sm 10:1–16; 19:20–24. 230 Mary Healy ent in Joel, “and they shall prophesy” (2:18). Through the rest of the Acts narrative, Luke depicts this declaration being fulfilled to the letter as members of the Church, men and women alike, receive prophetic words, visions and dreams, and perform prophetic signs and wonders in Jesus’s name.26 After interpreting the Pentecost event as a fulfillment of passages in Joel and Numbers, Peter proceeds to a biblical explanation of the mission of Jesus. That it is Peter who does so—Peter who had previously so misconstrued biblical prophecy that he vigorously opposed Jesus’s intent to go through with his passion (cf. Mt 16:22; Mk 8:32)—highlights the hermeneutical change wrought by the Spirit. Peter is now able to explain with boldness (parrēsia; cf. Acts 2:29) and conviction that the scandal of a crucified Messiah is precisely the plan of God as foretold in the Scriptures. He does so by interpreting Psalm 16, a psalm of David, typologically in reference to Christ. The psalmist, Peter observes, expresses confident trust that God will save him from death: “For you will not abandon my soul to Hades, nor let your Holy One see corruption” (Acts 2:27). But as Peter points out to his listeners, the fact that David’s tomb “is with us to this day”—in sharp contrast to Jesus’s empty tomb (Lk 24:1–8)—means that this prophetic hope could not have referred to David himself. Rather, the psalm looks forward prophetically to Jesus the messianic descendant of David, speaking of his Resurrection from the dead and exaltation at God’s right hand. Peter concludes his speech by coming full circle, declaring that it is Christ’s glorification that has made the eschatological gift of the Spirit available to all: “Being therefore exalted at the right hand of God, and having received from the Father the promise of the Holy Spirit, he has poured out this which you see and hear” (Acts 2:33). It is precisely the gift of the Holy Spirit that has enabled Peter to understand the deeper meaning of Psalm 16, hidden under the letter until Christ’s Resurrection from the dead. Peter’s speech, as Luke portrays it, is the inauguration of the church’s mission to authoritatively interpret and proclaim the word of God. As 26 Cf. “wonders” and “signs” in Acts 2:19. These two terms are used in the Pentateuch to describe the miraculous deeds of Moses (Dt 34:11) and were traditionally associated with the charism of prophecy. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 231 apostolic teaching, Peter’s speech, like the New Testament as a whole, has an original and definitive quality that does not belong to subsequent teaching. Because God has spoken his final word in Christ, no new revelation is to be expected after the apostolic age. But it does not follow that the prophetic charism is no longer needed for the interpretation of revelation. Indeed, such a claim would be contrary to the whole thrust of Acts 2, which emphasizes that the prophetic gift of the Spirit—limited and temporary in the seventy elders of Israel, universal and permanent in the Christian community—alone gives access to the mystery of God’s plan, foretold in Scripture and definitively fulfilled in Christ. The letters of Paul assert in a different way but with equal insistence the necessity of the Spirit for biblical interpretation. Two texts are particularly noteworthy in this regard. In 1 Corinthians 2 Paul alludes to a text of Isaiah in describing the role of the Spirit, not only in regard to biblical interpretation but in regard to any understanding of the mystery of Christ. “None of the rulers of this age understood this [God’s hidden wisdom]; for if they had, they would not have crucified the Lord of glory. But, as it is written, ‘What no eye has seen, nor ear heard, nor the heart of man conceived, what God has prepared for those who love him,’ God has revealed to us through the Spirit” (1 Cor 2:8–10, paraphrasing Is 64:4). The realities never before seen, heard or conceived refer not in the first instance to future heavenly glory, but to the Paschal mystery itself: the crucifixion of the Lord of glory (2:8). This mystery exceeds the natural capacities of the human mind and is therefore accessible only through the Spirit, “For the Spirit searches everything, even the depths of God” (2:10; cf. Eph 3:18–19). The Spirit is the light that enables a believer to comprehend the inmost divine mystery, the unfathomable love revealed and given in the kenosis of God’s Son. Only by the Spirit of God are we able to “understand the gifts freely given us by God” (1 Cor 2:12). Paul goes on to declare that not only the understanding but also the transmission of divine revelation is a Spirit-inspired activity: “we impart this in words not taught by human wisdom but taught by the Spirit” (1 Cor 2:13).27 27 The same principle is expressed in 2 Peter, applied specifically to biblical interpretation: “no prophecy of scripture is a matter of one’s own interpretation, because no prophecy ever came by the impulse of man, but men moved by the Holy Spirit spoke from God” (2 Pt 1:20–21). 232 Mary Healy In 2 Corinthians 3 Paul takes up the problem of the failure of many Jews to recognize any reference to Christ in the old covenant. Citing the passage in Exodus where Moses’s face became radiant from being in the presence of the Lord (Ex 34:27–35), Paul writes that the Israelites’ “minds were hardened; for to this day, when they read the old covenant, that same veil remains unlifted, because only through Christ is it taken away. Yes, to this day whenever Moses is read a veil lies over their minds; but when a man turns to the Lord the veil is removed” (2 Cor 3:14–16). With the image of a veil Paul suggests a spiritual blindness, resulting from hardness of heart, that blocks access to the dazzling light of divine revelation.28 The remedy for such blindness is to “turn to the Lord,” as Moses removed his veil whenever he entered the presence of the Lord (Ex 34:34). The notion of “turning” implies a conversion of heart. Paul continues: “Now the Lord [i.e., the Lord to whom we turn] is the Spirit, and where the Spirit of the Lord is, there is freedom. And we all, gazing with unveiled face on the glory of the Lord, are being transformed into the same image from glory to glory, as from the Lord who is the Spirit” (2 Cor 3:17–18). Turning to the Lord is, in effect, to receive the Holy Spirit, who opens up the Scriptures that were previously veiled. The Spirit does so, paradoxically, not by “unveiling” the Scriptures but by “unveiling” the face of the believer, bringing about an inner transformation that allows one to gaze on the Lord’s glory. Thus there is an inseparable connection between the Spirit’s work in the interpretation of Scripture and in the personal transformation of the interpreter. As Henri de Lubac put it, an adequate hermeneutic must “take into account the connection between spiritual understanding and the personal conversion and life of the Christian . . . the relationship between ‘New Testament’ and ‘New Man,’ between newness of understanding and newness of spirit.”29 The New Testament’s insistence on the role of the Spirit in biblical interpretation became a recognized principle in Christian tradition. This work of the Spirit was often described, either explicitly or implicitly, as a prophetic grace in continuity with the prophetic grace of bib28 The “hardened minds” of 2 Cor 3:14 is an allusion to the “hearts of stone” oracle in Ez 26:26. See Thomas Stegman, Second Corinthians, Catholic Commentary on Sacred Scripture (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2009), 90. 29 De Lubac, Scripture in the Tradition, trans. Luke O’Neill (New York: Crossroad, 2000), 144. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 233 lical inspiration. Commenting on Ezekiel’s warning to false prophets, “Woe to those foolish prophets who follow their own spirit, and have seen nothing” (Ez 13:3), Origen writes, “Just as the person who received the order to say these things needed the Holy Spirit, so the person who wants to explain what is secretly signified therein needs the same Spirit.”30 He goes on to assert that what was true of the words of the Israelite prophets is equally true of the words of Christ and the apostles. Gregory the Great likewise comments, “Just as the Spirit of life touches the mind of the prophet, he also touches the mind of the reader.”31 Thomas Aquinas explicitly described the interpretation of Scripture as a grace belonging to the order of prophecy: “In the New Testament those who explain the prophetic sayings are also called prophets, because Sacred Scripture is interpreted in the same Spirit in which it is composed. And so we read in Sirach 24:33, ‘I will pour out teaching like prophecy.’”32 Dei Verbum quotes Jerome in reaffirming this ancient principle, which had also been taken up by William of St. Thierry and many others: “holy Scripture must be read and interpreted in the light of the same Spirit by whom it was written.”33 Scripture as an Illocutionary Act Even where biblical scholarship formally acknowledges the principle of interpretation “in the Spirit,” it does not always succeed in carrying it out in practice or in articulating a hermeneutic that adequately accounts for it. Recent developments in the philosophy of language, however, can 30 Origen, Homilies on the Book of Ezekiel 2.2; translation adapted from Ignace de la Potterie, “Interpretation of Holy Scripture in the Spirit in Which It Was Written,” in Vatican II: Assessment and Perspectives, vol. 1, ed. René Latourelle (New York: Paulist, 1988), 220–66. 31 Gregory, Homilies on the Book of Ezekiel VII.11–12, quoted in Mariano Magrassi, Praying the Bible: An Introduction to Lectio Divina, trans. Edward Hagman (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1998), 28. 32 Aquinas, Commentary on Romans 12.8 (Marietti edition § 978), my translation. See Francis Martin, Sacred Scripture: The Disclosure of the Word (Naples, FL: Sapientia, 2006), 7–8. 33 Dei Verbum 12, quoting Jerome, Commentary on Galatians 5.19–20. Cf. William of St. Thierry, Epistola ad fratres de Monte Dei I.10.31, quoted in Magrassi, Praying the Bible, 29. For details on the patristic background of this principle, see de la Potterie, “Interpretation of Holy Scripture.” 234 Mary Healy help provide a theological grounding for this principle. In particular, Kevin Vanhoozer’s theory of communicative action can help us appreciate the full implications of the Christian understanding of Scripture as God’s word.34 Vanhoozer, a systematic theologian in the Reform tradition, has developed a hermeneutical proposal that draws from J. L. Austin’s speech-act theory and applies it to biblical texts. As Vanhoozer notes, speech act theory emphasizes that language does more than simply refer to states of affairs. All discourse is, in fact, intentional action; that is, it is action that aims at accomplishing something.35 Every statement is in some sense a “mission statement,” in which a speaker intends to communicate something to someone. Intentionality is an irreducible aspect not only of speech but of human action in general. It is what makes a human act one thing rather than another.36 A slap on the back, for example, may be a greeting, a congratulatory gesture, an attempt to save someone from choking, or an aggressive act, depending on the intent with which it was performed.37 It follows that understanding an action requires recognizing the agent’s intention. So too in speech acts, the speaker’s intention is what constitutes the act as what it is.38 Vanhoozer gives the example of a speaker who says, “Coffee would keep me awake.” The language and syntax of this sentence are perfectly clear; there is no problem decoding the meaning of the words. But what the sentence communicates depends entirely on the speaker’s intention in the circumstances in which it is spoken. In one possible scenario, the speaker who has been offered coffee is struggling to stay awake while studying for an exam late at night. In this case, the meaning of “Coffee would keep me awake” is “yes.” In another scenario, the speaker has finished studying and would like to retire soon in order to be fresh for the exam 34 Here I am drawing from Kevin J. Vanhoozer, “From Speech Acts to Scripture Acts: The Covenant of Discourse and the Discourse of Covenant,” in After Pentecost: Language and Biblical Interpretation, ed. Craig Bartholomew et al. (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 2001), 1–49. This article is a resume of Vanhoozer’s full-scale work Is There a Meaning in This Text? The Bible, the Reader, and the Morality of Literary Knowledge (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1998; rev. ed. 2009). 35 Vanhoozer, “From Speech Acts to Scripture Acts,” 11. 36 Ibid., 12. 37 Ibid. 38 Ibid., 13. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 235 the following morning; in that case, the meaning is “no.”39 Just as the concept of intention enables us to view human actions as more than mere bodily movements, so it enables us to view words and texts as more than mere sound waves and marks on paper. Understanding a text requires consideration of the author’s intention, that factor that accounts for the meaning of the communicative act. Conversely, where an author’s intention is ignored, we lose the act itself. A communicative act such as a wink, for example, is reduced to the blink, a meaningless bodily action. The result is what speech-act theorists call a “thin description.” A thin description is one that relies on lower-level concepts like “rapid contraction of the eyelid” rather than higher-level intentional categories like “flirting.”40 Applied to biblical interpretation, a thin description is one that may include philological, grammatical, textual, historical, sociocultural, and political explanations of the text, but fails to account fully for the text as a communicative act. A description is sufficiently thick, on the other hand, when it allows us to appreciate everything an author intends to communicate. It is important to clarify a possible misunderstanding, however. Intention is not to be identified with an author’s hidden psychological agenda; rather, it is what the author is actually doing in the text itself. The search for authorial intention is not a futile exercise in amateur psychology but precisely the means of allowing the author’s communicative act to be completed, resulting in understanding. Vanhoozer, again relying on Austin, offers a further helpful distinction. Speech acts have three distinct dimensions. First, there is simply the content of an utterance, the locution. The second and most important dimension is the speaker’s intention in speaking, the illocution. Third is what we might call the byproduct of the speech act or the effect it produces, the perlocution.41 Grasping the distinction between these latter two is crucial to properly interpreting communicative acts. Vanhoozer offers the example of the utterance “Jesus is Lord.”42 There are numerous ways to report on what a speaker did in uttering this statement. For example, one might say the speaker (1) emitted sound waves; 39 Ibid., 9. Ibid., 13. 41 Ibid., 15. 42 This example and its categorization are adapted from that of Vanhoozer in ibid., 15. 40 236 Mary Healy (2) spoke with a Boston accent; (3) said “Jesus is Lord.” All three of these descriptions remain at the locutionary level; they fail to describe the communicative intent of the speaker. Further, one might say the speaker (4) confessed that Jesus is Lord; (5) told her neighbor that Jesus is Lord; (6) explained how her cancer had suddenly gone into remission. These descriptions, in contrast to the first three, are illocutionary and truly arrive at the communicative intent of the utterance. Finally, one might say the speaker (7) made me feel unspiritual by comparison; (8) provoked a Roman persecution; or (9) led to the conversion of her listener. These last three describe the perlocution or byproducts of the communicative act. A speech act may produce perlocutionary effects, but it does not consist in such effects. Even if the speaker intends an effect such as the conversion of his hearer, such an effect is still a perlocution. It is what the speaker does by the speech not what he does in the speech. How does this analysis of speech acts impinge on biblical interpretation? As Vanhoozer observes, to take the divine authorship of Scripture seriously is to recognize the canon of Scripture as a single complex communicative act on the part of God.43 Interpretation is sufficiently thick when it allows us to appreciate an author’s illocutions, that is, what the author is doing in the text. But some of these illocutions only come to light on the level of the literary whole—the whole book or, in this case, the whole canon. For example, on one level the detailed account of the construction and furnishing of the wilderness tabernacle in Exodus 35–40 is meant to describe for the reader the physical arrangements for Israel’s sacrificial liturgy. But unless we read these chapters in light of the whole Pentateuch, and particularly the creation account in Genesis 1, we will fail to recognize the full communicative intent of the author or final redactor: namely, to portray the tabernacle as a microcosm of the created universe and a partial restoration of the original communion between God and man in Eden that had been ruptured by sin.44 But this in turn is 43 44 Ibid., 3. For recent studies of this symbolism, see G. K. Beale, The Temple and the Church’s Mission: A Biblical Theology of the Dwelling Place of God, New Studies in Biblical Theology (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2004), 29–80; Jonathan Klawans, Purity, Sacrifice, and the Temple (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 111–44; and Jon D. Levenson, Sinai and Zion (San Francisco: HarperOne, 1987), 111–84. Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 237 not a sufficiently thick description unless we also read the text in light of the entire canon and arrive at the communicative intent of not only the human author/redactor but also the divine author. In this case the intention, as revealed in the New Testament and especially the letter to the Hebrews, is to portray the earthly tabernacle as a “type” or figure pointing to the true, heavenly sanctuary into which Christ entered as high priest on our behalf (Heb 8:5; 9:11–14), and thus to reveal the entire sacrificial system of Israel as a foreshadowing of the infinitely more efficacious sacrifice of Christ. This is a meaning that goes beyond the intention of the human author(s) of Exodus, but it is not simply a perlocution, an effect the text produces on us when we read it as Christians. Rather, it is a part of the overarching communicative intent—the illocution—of God himself as author. Returning to the theme of the prophetic gift of the Spirit: what role does the Spirit play in God’s communicative act? As Vanhoozer notes, human authors do their best to ensure that readers correctly perceive their illocutionary intentions, but they cannot guarantee it. Authors are often misunderstood. But God “has no such limits: the Spirit is the ‘lord of the hearing’ . . . the energy that enables the Word to complete its mission.”45 Jesus says in the Gospel of John, “When the Spirit of truth comes, he will guide you into all the truth; for he will not speak on his own authority, but whatever he hears he will speak . . . He will take what is mine and declare it to you” (Jn 16:13). The Spirit completes the communicative act that is all divine revelation by enabling it to be received and understood according to the intent of the Author. Moreover the Spirit “renders the word effective by achieving its perlocutionary effects,”46 that is, its transformative effects in the life of believers. But he does so precisely in and through Scripture’s illocutions, its revelation of God and his plan. The Spirit speaks not an additional word but “what belongs to Jesus.” Perlocutions proceed from locutions and illocutions, not vice versa, as the Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son.47 This understanding of divine revelation as a communicative act, rendered efficacious by the Spirit, also has a negative corollary. As Van45 Ibid., 38. Ibid., 43. 47 Ibid. 46 238 Mary Healy hoozer points out, the rules of human discourse presuppose a kind of covenant—a bond between speaker and hearer such that we agree to be truthful communicators on the one hand and active listeners on the other.48 Interpreters violate this covenant whenever we ascribe intentions to authors where there is no evidence of that intention, or when we purvey a reductionist interpretation—a thin description—that fails to adequately attend to what an author was in fact doing. To do so is to “bear false witness”—to do a kind of interpretive violence to the text. To put it differently, the very existence of prophecy entails the possibility of false prophecy, a distortion of the word of God that is a perennial danger both in Israel and the Church. Defective biblical interpretation is, in fact, a form of false prophecy that can be profoundly damaging to the life of the Church. It is significant that Ratzinger began his 1988 lecture with a humorous yet provocative anecdote, told by the Russian philosopher Vladimir Solovyov, about the Antichrist as a biblical scholar, a famous exegete who received his doctorate at Tübingen. Ratzinger thereby alluded to the spiritual struggle and the weighty spiritual consequences involved in biblical interpretation.49 Interestingly, Pope Benedict returned to the image of the Antichrist twenty years later in his book Jesus of Nazareth, where he bluntly stated, “The fact is that Scriptural exegesis can become a tool of the Anti-Christ.”50 He notes that the Gospel accounts of Jesus’s temptations portray Satan as a theologian and Bible expert who can quote Scripture accurately. Biblical erudition and mastery of exegetical technique are no guarantee of truth. As the pope affirmed, to acknowledge this “is not a rejection of scholarly biblical interpretation as such, but an eminently salutary and necessary warning against its possible aberrations.”51 Conclusion Joseph Ratzinger’s critique of modern biblical interpretation is at the same time a signpost for the way forward. The rediscovery of God’s 48 Ibid., 45. I owe this observation to Atkinson, “Scripture and the Exegete,” 612. 50 Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth, 35. 51 Ibid. 49 Biblical Interpretation as a Prophetic Charism 239 word as “a wellspring of constant renewal” in the life of the Church,52 which he so ardently promoted as theologian and pope, will come about not by rejecting the methods and findings of modern scholarship but by integrating them into a hermeneutic of faith. Only such a hermeneutic allows Scripture to be read as it was written, as a living, divine act of communication whose center and hermeneutical key is the mystery of Christ. As the New Testament itself teaches, reading Scripture in this way is possible only through the prophetic gift of the Holy Spirit, the divine breath that animates the word and makes it ever “living and effective” (Heb 4:12). As St. Ambrose explains, Scripture is theopneustos (2 Tim 3:16) not only because it is “inspired by God” but because it “respires God,” it breathes God.53 It is the Spirit who opens up the depths hidden in the word. The work of biblical interpretation is, then, the exercise of a prophetic charism in the Church. This understanding of the exegete’s task has two implications for the life of the Church that, among the many that could be mentioned, are worth highlighting. First, interpreting Scripture prophetically—in conscious and prayerful dependence on the Spirit’s inspiration—will restore a sense of the unity of the canon. As mentioned above, contemporary biblical scholarship tends to regard the books of the Bible as a cacophony of diverse voices. Exegetes are generally content to let apparent discrepancies and even contradictions stand as simply indicating different theologies among the various biblical authors, or even among layers of redaction within a single work. This fragmented approach in turn undermines people’s confidence that Scripture reliably communicates truth about God and his will for our lives. Instead, taking seriously the divine authorship entails recognizing all Scripture as a single communicative act on God’s part, the unity of which is revealed by the Spirit within the living tradition of the Church. A deeper reliance on the Spirit’s prophetic guidance could lead to a renewed effort of scholars to show how the different perspectives among the biblical authors are complementary rather than contradictory. It could also contribute to the recovery of what tradition calls the “spiritual sense,” enabling us 52 53 Benedict XVI, Verbum Domini 1. Ambrose, De Spiritu Sancto 3.112, quoted in Raniero Cantalamessa, The Mystery of God’s Word, trans. Alan Neame (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1994), 80. 240 Mary Healy to recognize God’s gifts in the old covenant as wonderful in their own right and yet also having a yet-more-marvelous hidden significance that points to Christ. Second, the state of biblical scholarship in the Church has a direct bearing on the quality of preaching, another area of great concern for both Pope Benedict and Pope Francis.54 It is observed with increasing frequency that Catholic preaching today is too often stale, banal, and biblically impoverished. Such deficiencies are directly attributable, at least in part, to a reductive understanding of the exegetical task. For at least two generations Catholic ministers of the word have been trained in methods of interpretation that fail to rely on the Spirit’s illumination and thus often fail to arrive at Scripture’s illocutionary intent. Biblical interpretation, and thus preaching, must once again be recognized as a prophetic task dependent on the anointing of the Spirit. Where preaching is prophetic, there is divine power at work to awaken faith in the hearers, as Paul often asserts,55 and to cause their hearts to burn within them, as happened to the disciples on the road to Emmaus. If God’s people sometimes appear spiritually moribund, those who interpret Scripture prophetically will put skin and flesh on those dry bones and make them come alive with N&V the life-giving breath of Spirit (Ez 37:4–13). 54 55 See Benedict XVI, Verbum Domini 59–60; Francis, Evangelii Gaudium 135–59. Cf. Rom 1:16; 10:17; 1 Cor 1:18; 2:4; Col 1:6; 1 Thes 1:5; 2:13. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 241-251 241 Tradition and the Individual Exegete Jeremy Holmes Wyoming Catholic College Lander, WY IN HIS FAMOUS ERASMUS LECTURE,Joseph Ratzinger oppos- es an understanding of biblical studies that he attributes largely to the influence of Immanuel Kant.1 This view sees tradition as antithetical to reason, which must proceed on objective lines without the influence of faith or any other personal commitment. Kant lays out his position with unusual force in his essay “What Is Enlightenment?”: “Enlightenment is man’s emergence from his self-imposed immaturity. Immaturity is the inability to use one’s understanding without guidance from another.”2 The individual must think on his own, because tradition and the individual’s reason are absolutely opposed; any submission to tradition or authority is contrary to reason and to the dignity of the human person. But in the conclusion of his lecture, Ratzinger urges that reason and faith are not contrary to one another: the exegete must recognize that he does not stand on neutral ground above or outside history and the Church. Such a sup1 See Joseph Ratzinger (Pope Benedict XVI), God’s Word: Scripture—Tradition—Office, ed. Peter Hünermann and Thomas Söding, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2008), 112: “The real philosophical presupposition of the whole system seems to me to lie in the change in philosophy brought about by Kant.” 2 This famous essay is well worth reading to grasp how Kant’s “enlightenment” requires a kind of individualism. There are many translations on the Internet; the version I have cited is available at http://theliterarylink.com/kant.html. 242 Jeremy Holmes posed direct apprehension of the purely historical can only lead to mistaken conclusions. . . . [Exegesis] must recognize . . . faith as a hermeneutic key, as a locus of understanding that does not do dogmatic violence to the Bible, but offers the only chance we have of allowing it to be itself.3 At the same time, Ratzinger concedes the need for objectivity in exegesis. For example, because the Fathers and the medievals did not habitually refer texts to their historical setting, he argues, their interpretation “easily fell into arbitrariness.”4 So on the one hand, the exegete must avoid false claims to objectivity; on the other hand, he must not give way to arbitrariness; between these extremes stands the individual exegete in the stream of Tradition. In what follows, I want to explore this problem of how the individual exegete relates to tradition in dialogue with Ratzinger’s writings. There would not be enough space even to repeat all the marvelous things Ratzinger says toward a solution of the difficulty, much less to solve the problem definitively, so I will focus on offering two basic intuitions or mental orientations, one regarding Tradition and the other regarding Scripture. Tradition The first basic mental orientation I would like to offer is what Ratzinger argues in his essay, “The Anthropological Foundation of the Concept of Tradition,” namely, that “tradition . . . is constitutive of a humanity that is truly human, of the humanitas hominis.”5 That is to say, tradition is not opposed to human dignity, but is called for by it. The reason man is by nature tradition dependent is that “it is not good that man should be alone” (Gn 2:18): God made the human race to live in families, and families to live in societies. For man and woman to be together is good; for parents and children to be together is good; for man to live in society 3 Ratzinger, God’s Word, 125–26. Ibid., 121. 5 Joseph Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology: Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology, trans. Sr. Mary Frances McCarthy, S.N.D. (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1987), 85–100, at 87. 4 Tradition and the Individual Exegete 243 is good. Just as God created hunger and thirst so we would pursue the goods of food and drink, so he has made man and woman each lacking, and parents and children each needy in their own way, and the different members of society dependent on one another, precisely to drive them to pursue their good. And just as man’s bodily needs for food, clothing, and shelter cannot be conveniently met without the good of life together, so man’s more important needs—the needs of the mind—cannot be met without intellectual society. It is good for man as man to have tradition, that collective intellectual wealth of a society that holds it together and gives it identity and continuity. The faculty of speech encapsulates this close relation between reason and tradition. Human beings who never learn to speak are never capable of reasoning, either; speech brings with it the inner life of the mind. And yet speech is learned for the sake of communication and has as its proper goal the creation of society. So the inner life of the individual emerges on the way, so to speak, to society; the two are inherently related. Moreover, the language one learns is a patrimony of the ages, shaped by great authors of ages past and by countless unknown men and women who left their way of perceiving the world—their inner mental life—embodied in the speech they passed on to their children. The Kantian view sees reason and tradition as inherently opposed, so that complete intellectual independence is man’s true good while dependence on tradition is a necessary evil forced on him by the brevity of life. But the biblical view of man says just the opposite: to be in a tradition is good for man, and to break with tradition is sometimes a necessary result of evil. Of course, no society is perfect and many societies are evil—fathers are abusive, mothers manipulative, families dysfunctional—and as society goes, so goes tradition. As Ratzinger puts it, “Tradition, which is by nature the foundation of man’s humanness, is everywhere mingled with those things that deprive him of his humanity.”6 Sometimes it is even necessary to break family ties completely and abandon the old traditions; but the point is that to break with tradition, however necessary, is not a good in itself but an unfortunate result of evil. There is something to be said for Kant’s position: It would in fact be better to know independently of tradition, inasmuch as God’s way 6 Ibid., 89. 244 Jeremy Holmes of knowing is better than man’s way of knowing. The problem with the Enlightenment view is that it understands independent rationality as a simple negation, namely rationality without tradition. To take a parallel case, to be immobile rather than mobile is better, in the way that God is immobile, but one must think of immobility positively, as a description of pure act; simply to be immobile, as a pure negation—to be frozen— would be an evil. It is better to be pure act than to be mobile, but it is better to be mobile than to be simply immobile. The force of this comparison lies in the fact that truth is a common good. As such, the nature of truth is most clearly seen when it is possessed by many in common, that is, when a society forms around it. When Kant declares that we must discover things by our own reason, he means that we must grasp truth as an individual rather than as a member of a society: truth must be my private good. His traditionlessness is a simple negation rather than a positive essence. While it is true that to be God is better than to be man, and so to be the common good is better than to participate in the common good, it is equally true that to participate in the common good is better than not to participate in it. It is better to be Truth than to participate in a tradition, but it is better to participate in a tradition than to be a human intellectual island cut off from the mainland. It is not good for man to be alone; it is not good for man to think alone.7 This is the first basic mental orientation I would like to offer: Tradition is good for man as man. A corollary follows from it: Since every society by nature has its tradition, by which it hands on its innermost life to the next generation, and since grace does not destroy nature but elevates it, the Church must also have a tradition. But she must have a tradition commensurate with what she is: Since she is a supernatural society, the mystical body of Christ, she must have a supernatural Tradition by which she hands on to the next generation the very mind of Christ (1 Cor 2:16); since she is an eternal society, she must have an incorruptible Tradition; since her members are bound to one another by the Holy Spirit as though by a single soul, her Tradition must be guided 7 Even the angels, St. Thomas argues, are taught by and teach one another. To be entirely self-sufficient in knowledge is proper to God alone, because he alone is himself Truth. Tradition and the Individual Exegete 245 and developed by the Spirit. Here at last, in the Tradition founded by Truth itself, mankind finds a tradition one need never abandon, a society one need never leave. Outgrowths may need trimming, and human elements purged, but the necessity of a break with Tradition, inevitable in merely human contexts, will never arise here. Canon The second basic intuition I would like to offer has to do with the canon of Scripture: Because tradition is natural to man, a literary canon is also in a way natural to man. If every human society is held together by a common intellectual patrimony, and if this tradition is naturally expressed in language, it follows that when a society begins to write down its language, then it creates a set of texts that embody and transmit the tradition; and this is what I mean by a canon. This second basic intuition is borne out in the most ancient literate cultures, which used a set of normative texts not as ends in themselves, as though the production of texts were good in itself, but as instruments for inscribing their traditions word for word on the minds of the next generation.8 The Enlightenment view of humanity has obscured how natural and inevitable such a canon is. Because this view urges each individual to cut himself off from tradition and to reason everything out for himself, it disparages memorization as a slavish task. On this view, true freedom lies not in memory but in imagination, in the ability to create our own world free from every other man and even from nature; since the text is another man’s creation, to memorize it is to submit oneself to another man’s private good, which is servile.9 But in antiquity, to memorize the text was to participate in the common good, in the tradition, and so to become a full member of society. The ancestors are, literally, our antecessores, the ones who have gone before us, and by following them we enter into our inheritance and make it our own with them.10 8 David M. Carr, Writing on the Tablet of the Heart: Origins of Scripture and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 8. 9 See the fascinating analysis by Mary J. Carruthers in The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), esp. 1–13. 10 Cf. Carr, Writing on the Tablet, 11: “Indeed, that past is never ‘past’ in the way we 246 Jeremy Holmes In this traditional mindset, reading the text might be compared to living in the old family mansion: It is not a museum, with everything cordoned off, immovable and untouchable, but one’s own family house, so one has to move in and live in it, which might require moving the couch; on the other hand, it is a family possession, not simply one’s private thing, so one would not bulldoze it and build a new structure. Similarly, the ancient scribes felt free even to modify a text for new circumstances, but did not see themselves as fundamentally altering the thing.11 When the scribe composed his own work and quoted the normative texts, he did so from memory and rather inexactly; this was not at all from lack of respect for the text, but because the text had moved beyond being an external object of thought to become an interior medium in which he thought, communicated, and expressed himself.12 But even while he expressed his own thoughts through the medium of the canon, he knew that his writing did not have its meaning alone, but only in relation to the antecessores, the scribes and sages before him: Just as their work was not theirs individually but common and therefore his, so his work was not his individually but a common possession. T. S. Eliot described the poet and his work within a literary tradition this way: “What happens is a continual surrender of himself as he is at the moment to something which is more valuable. The progress of an artist is a continual self-sacrifice, a continual extinction of personality.”13 At this point it may be helpful to review what has been said. So far, I have followed a single thread across two basic mental orientations: Because man as a rational creature shares in a common good, he is by nature social; as a result, human reason is by nature dependent on society’s communal intellectual wealth, which is tradition. This was my first conclusion, and from it I drew the corollary that the Church, a supernatural society, will necessarily have a supernatural Tradition. Because human might conceive it but stands in the ancient world as a potentially realizable ‘present’ to which each generation seeks to return.” 11 See ibid., 41. 12 Ibid., 36: “He was not ‘exegeting’ or ‘citing’ older works in the way a later biblical interpreter might do. Rather the scribe was trained from the outset to think by means of blocks of tradition and express himself through those tools.” 13 T. S. Eliot, “Tradition and the Individual Talent,” The Egoist 6, no. 4 (September 1919): 54–55, at 55. The second part of the essay appeared in The Egoist 6, no. 5 (December 1919): 72–73. Tradition and the Individual Exegete 247 reason is by nature dependent on tradition, a literate society naturally creates a canon, namely a set of writings that embody and transmit the tradition; and because a canon is the means of passing on a society’s innermost life, the life of the mind, it also serves as a medium for that life as members of the society think via the canon, speak via the canon, and interpret the world via the canon. This was my second conclusion. A corollary also follows from this second conclusion: Just as the Church needs a Tradition commensurate with what she is, so she needs a Canon commensurate with herself and her Tradition. Scripture is the supernatural Canon of the supernatural society, by which the mystical body of Christ passes on her inner life to the next generation, and a medium in which she lives that inner life of thought and speech. Ratzinger captures the point when he says that Scripture is not a meteorite fallen from the sky, so that it would, with the strict otherness of a stone that comes from the sky and not from the earth, stand in contrast to all human words. Certainly, Scripture carries God’s thoughts within it: that makes it unique and constitutes it an “authority.” Yet it is transmitted by a human history. It carries within it the life and thought of a historical society that we call the “People of God,” because they are brought together, and held together, by the coming of the divine Word. There is a reciprocal relationship: This society is the essential condition for the origin and growth of the biblical Word; and, conversely, this Word gives the society its identity and its continuity. Thus, the analysis of the structure of the biblical Word has brought to light an interwoven relationship between Church and Bible, between the People of God and the Word of God, which we had actually always known, somehow, in a theoretical way but had never before had so vividly set before us.14 It would be misleading to suggest that Scripture is the extent of the Church’s literary canon. Just as she has both traditions with a small “t” and Tradition with a big “T,” so she has both a literary canon with a small 14 Joseph Ratzinger, “What in Fact Is Theology?” in Pilgrim Fellowship of Faith: The Church as Communion, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2005), 33. 248 Jeremy Holmes “c” and a literary Canon with a big “C,” so to speak, and this distinction between “big letter” and “small letter” is true of Tradition and Canon for the same reason. The same dynamic that led to Tradition and to the embodiment of tradition in the Canon leads to new traditions and writings; the newer, lesser traditions are inspired by and, so to speak, ensouled by the Tradition itself, and in the same way the newer, lesser writings draw life from Scripture, interpreting it and receiving their meaning from it simultaneously. One thinks not only of the Church’s magisterium and the writings of the Fathers and Doctors, but of Dante and Shakespeare and the whole constellation of authors whose works have formed the culture of the Church. Scripture, as the Canon at the heart of the canon, not only has the power to inspire and sustain these new works but even draws into its ambit the writings of Homer, Plato, and Aristotle, just as the Catholic faith took over the insights of pagan antiquity. The process of tradition, writing, and re-reading that gave birth to Scripture itself continues with Scripture and Tradition as its life principle. Exegesis The basic intuitions I have shared concerning Tradition and Scripture orient exegesis in a fundamental way. To begin with, it makes no sense to set Scripture and Tradition in opposition, or Scripture and Church, because Scripture contains Tradition in its very notion, and Tradition is defined in terms of the Church. Moreover, it makes no sense to pit faith against biblical exegesis, because Scripture’s very essence is to be an instrument by which the Church passes on her inner life, which is a life of faith, and so any reading of Scripture that does not build up this faith is a bad one. Faith offers the only chance the exegete has of allowing Scripture to be itself.15 To complete this thought, we have to see that, as Ratzinger says, “for the New Testament faith means the same as the indwelling of Christ” (Eph 3:17).16 As the mystical body of Christ, the Church’s inner life of faith is nothing other than to have Christ dwelling in her, to be Christ’s presence in the world. If Scripture is the mirror in which the Church 15 16 This point looks back again to Ratzinger, God’s Word, 125–26. Ratzinger, “The Question of the Concept of Tradition: A Provisional Response,” in God’s Word, 56–57. Tradition and the Individual Exegete 249 sees herself and learns to be herself, a guide rail for the process of handing on her inner life, then Scripture also must in some sense be Christ, the very Word of God. It is a more remote sense, of course. Like every book, Scripture sits lifeless on the printed page, an assembly of inkblots, until the reader “reconstitutes” those blots into living words in a human heart. But there, in that hidden place where Scripture truly exists, not as lifeless blots but as actual words, Christ is formed; this formation of Christ in the heart is Tradition; and this Tradition constitutes the Church. In this way we avoid a false objectivity, but how do we simultaneously steer away from the other extreme of arbitrariness? This is a difficult question, because Scripture’s role as Canon leads not only to “exegesis,” a reception from the text, but also to “eisegesis,” a reading into the text. While the Fathers and medievals often scandalize modern readers by their seemingly whimsical interpretation of even the smallest details of the biblical text, we have to recall that the monk’s practice of “chewing” the text by lectio divina, “ruminating” by meditation, and “digesting” it by theologizing is the Christian’s divinely graced experience of what was natural to ancient scribes. The modern reader, with his complete printed Bible and a concordance or perhaps good Bible software, has Scripture more than ever at his fingertips as a tool and an object of reflection, but our medieval monk had Scripture itself for fingers, no longer merely an object of thought but a medium for it. He thought his thoughts and communicated his thoughts by way of Scripture. So for example, when the celibate male monk desired to work out and express his most personal interior experiences in writing, he often chose to do so by commenting word by word on the Song of Songs— and it is worth observing that, as subjective as these commentaries seem to us today, the fact remains that a centuries-long tradition of celibate male reflection resulted in an understanding of the spiritual life in terms of passionate marital love!17 The medium became a message. Moreover, grace perfects nature in this situation. As Augustine argues, since God is the primary author of Scripture, and since he knew from all eternity all the thoughts of all the readers of Scripture, any truth that Scripture 17 See Denys Turner, Eros and Allegory: Medieval Exegesis of the Song of Songs (Kalamazoo: Cistercian Publications, 1995), esp. 17–23. 250 Jeremy Holmes prompts a reader to see could arguably be what the primary author intended him to get from the text.18 A sign of this is the Church’s use of patristic interpretations, even the eisegetical ones about the Song of Songs, in the liturgy, which is the privileged setting for hearing the word of God: If the Church has read and proclaimed a particular biblical passage in her liturgies as meaning a particular thing for over a thousand years, then the people of God have heard God say this through that Scripture consistently. Is this not an argument that God intended this text to be understood this way? What in a merely human context with a merely natural canon would be a creative departure from the original meaning can become in Scripture a discovery of something actually intended by the primary author. Eisegesis meets exegesis. One can see therefore how difficult it is to separate authentic Catholic practices from arbitrary interpretation. However, even at its most “eisegetical,” Catholic interpretation is not arbitrary. “Arbitrary” means that one does whatever one pleases: “Arbitrary” interpretation means that one says whatever one wants the text to mean, imposing one’s will on the text, using its authoritative aura to the benefit of propaganda. This would be an exaltation of the individual’s power over the text, which is not at all the spirit of the Fathers. In fact, as Ratzinger notes, such a spirit is actually characteristic of interpretations that abandon tradition in the name of scientific objectivity: “the daring constructions of many modern exegetes, right up to the materialistic interpretation of the Bible, show that the Word, if left alone as a book, is a helpless prey to manipulation through preexisting desires and opinions.”19 In contrast, the Fathers saw their work as entering into the great edifice of the whole text of Scripture and all the interpretations that have come before them, so that their interpretations were not their own only but a common good. Above, I quoted T. S. Eliot as describing how the poet gives over what is merely his individually in order to gain what is even more his in the common good of a tradition: “What happens is a continual surrender of himself as he is at the moment to something which is more valuable. The progress . . . is a continual self-sacrifice, 18 Augustine, Confessions, trans. Frank Sheed, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2006), book XII, chaps. 31–32, p. 285. 19 Ratzinger, Pilgrim Fellowship of Faith, 34. Tradition and the Individual Exegete 251 a continual extinction of personality.”20 This is more radically true of a Christian, who has joined not just a society but the mystical body of Christ. To quote Ratzinger: It is a death event. In other words, it is an exchange of the old subject for another. The “I” ceases to be an autonomous subject standing in itself. It is snatched away from itself and fitted into a new subject. The “I” is not simply submerged, but it must really release its grip on itself in order then to receive itself anew in and together with a greater “I.”21 Because this new subject is, as Ratzinger puts it, “the precondition and foundation of all theology,”22 when the Fathers read their own thoughts into the text of Scripture they read into it nothing other than Scripture, having taken on the mind of Christ.23 Each of them could adapt for himself the words of St. Paul: I read, no longer I only, but Christ who reads N&V within me (cf. Gal 2:20). 20 Eliot, “Tradition and the Individual Talent,” 55. Joseph Ratzinger, The Nature and Mission of Theology: Approaches to Understanding Its Role in the Light of Present Controversy, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1993), 51. 22 Ibid., 50. 23 Michael Cahill, “Reader-Response Criticism and the Allegorizing Reader,” Theological Studies 57 (1996): 94. 21 Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 253-272 253 Revelation and Understanding Scripture: Reflections on the Teaching of Joseph Ratzinger, Pope Benedict XVI* Francis Martin Dominican House of Studies Washington, DC IN BIBLICAL INTERPRETATION IN CRISIS,Joseph Ratzinger offers the following reflection on the relationship between the biblical text and revelation: In today’s theological lingo, it is common to term the Bible “Revelation” without qualification. This usage would never have occurred to the ancients. Revelation is a dynamic event between God and man, which again and again becomes reality only in their encounter. The biblical Word attests to Revelation, but it does not contain it in the sense of absorbing it and turning it into a sort of thing that one could stick in one’s pocket. The Bible attests to Revelation, but the concept of Revelation is much broader.1 In making this statement, Joseph Ratzinger refers his readers to his habilitation thesis: * I would like to thank Crystal Wirth, whose invaluable editing has improved this 1 contribution. Joseph Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretations in Conflict: On the Foundations and the Itinerary of Exegesis Today,” in Opening Up the Scriptures, ed. Jose Granados, Carlos Granados, and Luis Sánchez-Navarro (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008), 26. 254 Francis Martin where there is only the letter, there we find only the Old Testament and Judaism, regardless of whether we call this letter, “New” or “Old” Testament. The mere letter is not “New” Testament; the New Testament is truly present precisely where the letter has been surpassed by the Spirit . . . Here therefore, “revelation” is synonymous with the spiritual understanding of Scripture; it consists in the God-given act of understanding, and not in the objective letter alone.2 This statement echoes a similar one made by St. Jerome: “Let us not think that the Gospel lies in the words of the Scriptures: it is in their meaning; not in the surface but in the marrow; not in the leaves of words, but in the root of understanding.”3 Based on these and other statements to which I will refer later, I first will reflect on Joseph Ratzinger’s teaching concerning the spiritual “understanding” that makes of the Scriptures a life-giving word. For the purposes of corroboration, I will rely on the teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas on Sacred Scripture, prophecy, and sacra doctrina. In particular, his distinction between intellectus and ratio accents the fact that understanding Scripture is principally concerned with an insight into the realities revealed rather than the application of method to propositions.4 I then will turn to the phenomenological work of Robert Sokolowski, which offers a fruitful way of overcoming the impasse in biblical interpretation created by nominalism and the Kantian predicament. The key insight in this part of the study is that words are bearers of reality: They are the reality in another form of existence. This position opens the door to the ancient concept of the “spiritual sense” as an understanding not of the deeper meaning of the words as such but of the realities they mediate. I will conclude by considering the power of the Scriptural Word, 2 Joseph Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, trans. Zachary Hayes (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1971, 1989), 63. 3 On Galatians 1,11, PL 26, 347A. 4 In the Middle Ages, “The content of Scripture was not conceived of as some abstract theoretical system of truth, but as a spiritual reality reproduced in the minds and souls of the faithful under the actual influence of the Holy Spirit.” Denis Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation: A Theological Introduction to Sacred Scripture (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2010), 140. Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 255 particularly as it is proclaimed in the Liturgy. Here I will examine Pope Benedict’s statement in Verbum Domini that Christ’s presence in the proclaimed Word is analogous to his presence in the Eucharist (§56). The Intellectus Spiritualis of Scripture Joseph Ratzinger’s statement regarding the synonymity of revelation and the spiritual understanding of Scripture is illumined by Thomas Aquinas’s teaching on the intellectus spiritualis. First, intellectus is a gift of the Holy Spirit. Different than ratio, “its relation to the things made known to us supernaturally is like that of the natural light of understanding to the things we instinctively recognize (primordialiter cognoscimus)” (Summa theologiae [ST] II-II, q. 8, a. 1, ad 2).5 The light of faith illumines the principles of faith even as the light of reason illumines the principles of reason. In both cases, the light makes the principles per se nota. This idea is a commonplace in Aquinas. For instance, he defines an article of faith as “a perception of divine truth that leads us to that truth itself ” (ST II-II, q. 1, a. 6sc).6 The following text is particularly apposite: It is clear, then, that faith comes from God in two ways: by way of an interior light that leads to assent, and by way of the realities that are proposed from without and that had as their source divine revelation. These are related to the knowledge of faith as the things perceived by the senses are related to the knowledge of principles, for both make our knowledge certain. So just as the knowledge of principles is taken from the senses, and yet the light by which principles are known is inborn, so “faith 5 Translation is that of T. C. O’Brien in Summa Theologiae, Blackfriars edition, vol. 32, p. 7. 6 Perceptio divinae veritatis tendens in ipsam. Aquinas attributes the definition to St. Isidore, but T. C. O’Brien Summa theolgiae, Blackfriars edition, vol. 31, p. 28) assures us that it is not found in Isidore’s works. That Aquinas himself agrees with this definition is witnessed by the fact that he earlier used it without any attribution (Sent. III d. 25, q. 1, a. 1, qc. 1, ad 4). For another description of an article of faith, see ST II-II, q. 1, a. 6c: “the object of faith is something unseen about the divine. Consequently there is a particular article of faith wherever there is something being unseen for some distinct reason.” We may note that Aquinas gives as examples various mysteries of the life of Christ. For other examples of descriptions of an article, see Sent. III d. 25, q. 1, a. 1, sol 1; in 1 Cor 15, lect.1 (Marietti §896). 256 Francis Martin comes from hearing” (Rom 10:17), and nevertheless the habit of faith is infused.7 The proximate criterion, therefore, of judging the authenticity of a doctrinal position or pastoral practice is whether it is virtually contained in the articles of faith, which are drawn from Scripture and articulated whenever there is a particular aspect of divine truth that is being revealed. In this sense, the birth, death, and Resurrection of Christ are separate articles (ST II-II, q. 1, a. 6c). There are two ways in which this quality of being contained in an article of faith can be discerned. The first method of proceeding is to compare what is held as tradition with the articles by a process that follows the laws of human thinking (studium). This process does not merely or even principally involve applying logic to propositions, but rather involves perceiving how the two juxtaposed realities are connected to each other: “God wills that something be because of something else, but it is not for the sake of the second reality that he wills the first” (I, q. 19, a. 5c).8 It is quite permissible to employ the results of sound philosophy in this endeavor, not as a ruling principle, but as providing human insight that can be taken up into revelation: “Those who use the work of the philosophers in sacred doctrine by bringing that work of the human mind into the service of faith, do not mix water with wine, but rather change water into wine.”9 The second method of discerning the authenticity of a teaching is to rest in the reality mediated by the articles and see in them, by means of 7 St. Thomas Aquinas, “In Boet. De Trin.,” q. 3, a. 1, ad 4, in Faith, Reason and Theology: Questions I–IV of His Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius, Medieval Sources in Translation 32, trans. Armand Maurer (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1987), 69. 8 “Vult ergo [Deus] hoc esse propter hoc, sed non propter hoc vult hoc.” For a discussion of this text and its possible relation to the teaching of Vatican I on how reason, enlightened by faith, can arrive at an understanding of divine mysteries, see Jean-Pierre Torrell, “Le savoir theologique chez saint Thomas,” in Recherches thomasiennes, 37–38. “Yet it must always be remembered that the assent to these other truths, the various material objects of faith, presupposes the formal object as providing the authenticating force for the assent.” Brian J. Shanley, “Sacra doctrina and Disclosure,” The Thomist 61, no. 2 (1997): 163–88, at 174–75, with a citation from ST II-II, q. 1, a. 1c. 9 St. Thomas Aquinas, “In Boet. de Trin,” q. 2, a. 3, ad 5 (Maurer 50). Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 257 contemplative understanding, all that they contain. The penetration of faith and the intellectus spiritualis provide insight into the realities that are revealed. They enable these realities themselves to be the cause of knowledge. Although the articles of faith are enunciated in words, it is not the propositions themselves but the realities mediated by the propositions that, as an imprint of the divine knowledge, have the energy to lead the mind to judge of those things that are presented to it (cf. ST I, q. 1, a. 3, ad 2). This divine action gives understanding of not just the letter of the Scriptures but the realities behind them. The Greek Fathers spoke, in this regard, of gnosis. St. Paul prayed that his faithful hearers be filled with gnosis and professed to have received this gift himself. By gnosis, he meant a rich and living knowledge of God’s plan, the “mystery” of Christ that has been hidden for eternity in God (Eph 3:9).10 This form of knowledge pertains more to what Aquinas calls intellectus than to what he calls ratio: “That which is supreme in our knowledge is not reason, but understanding, which is the source of reason” (Summa contra Gentiles 1, c. 57, 8).11 Insofar as theology involves an act of reason vivified by faith understanding, we can extend Aquinas’s statement as follows: intellectus est theologiae et principium et terminus.12 Such a faith vision is the basis for the position that Thomas expresses in various ways. For example, “The formal objective of faith is the First Truth as this is made known (manifestatur) in Sacred Scripture and in the teaching of the Church which proceeds from the First Truth.” Later in the same question, he states: “Faith adheres to all the articles of faith because of one reason (medium), namely, because of the First Truth proposed to us in the Scriptures understood rightly according to the teaching of the Church (secundum doctrinam Ecclesiae)” (ST II-II, q. 5, a. 3c and ad 2). To cite one last text: “The formal notion (ratio) in the 10 Tradition and Traditions: An Historical Essay and a Theological Essay, trans. Michael Naseby and Thomas Rainborough (New York: Macmillan, 1967), 387–88. 11 Translation in Marie-Dominique Chenu, Toward Understanding Saint Thomas, 197, n. 60. As is well known, Pierre Rouselot developed this distinction in St. Thomas; see John M. McDermott, Love and Understanding: The Relation of Will and Intellect in Pierre Rousselot’s Christological Vision, Analecta Gregoriana 229 (Rome: Università Gregoriana, 1983). 12 Cf. In III Sent. d. 35, q. 1, a. 3, qc. 2c: “Intellectus est rationis et principium et terminus.” 258 Francis Martin object of faith is the first truth manifested through the teaching of the Church” (De caritate, a. 13, ad 6).13 Sacra doctrina, as it exists in the Church, consists of two things: the hearing and reading of the symbolic transmission of revelation; and the infused habit of faith, which is “more capable of causing assent than any demonstration.”14 In other words, doctrina involves not only the pure light which is a share in God’s knowledge of himself, but also the human activity or studium of assimilating and articulating the divine truths according to our mode of knowing. In this joint work of God and man, the greatness and the fragility of sacra doctrina and its Scripture is revealed: It is the word of God clothed in the flesh of human thought processes and words. If we ask how the prophetic word from God, that word he spoke once and for all in his Son at this, the end of the ages (cf. Heb 1:1–4), is to be preserved in the Church, the answer is twofold: First, it is given a written and normative expression; second, the epiklèsis of the Spirit allows this articulation to be impressed upon the minds and souls of its hearers. In light of these considerations, we now will return to other statements in which Joseph Ratzinger insists on the need for the gift of intellectus. In his habilitation thesis, he wrote: “Revelatio refers not to the letter of Scripture, but to the understanding of the letter; and this understanding can be increased.”15 This “increase” takes place when, through the gift of understanding, more of the reality is perceived and appreciated in its relation to the rest of revealed reality. The need for purity of heart in order to allow this increase is well expressed by the Pontifical Biblical Commission: Access to a proper understanding of biblical texts is granted only to the person who has an experienced affinity (une affinité 13 Translation in Saint Thomas Aquinas, On Charity, trans. Lottie Kendzierski (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1960), 109. An aspect of faith not treated in this study is that Christ himself is auctor doctrinae both as God, the First Truth, and as man, the privileged manifestation of that truth. See Yves Congar, The Meaning of Tradition, trans. A. N. Woodrow (New York: Hawthorne Books, 1964; reprint, San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), 173–74. 14 St. Thomas Aquinas, In III Physicorum, cap. 3, lect. 5 (Leonine ed. 11, 113). 15 Ratzinger, Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, 68. Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 259 vecue) with that of which the text is speaking . . . As the reader matures in the life of the Spirit, so there grows also his or her capacity to understand the realities of which the Bible speaks.16 The concluding lines of Ratzinger’s document on Biblical Interpretation especially concern us in this article: “The dead ends of the critical method have once again made it clear that understanding requires the understander—the key without which the text has nothing to say to the present.”17 Phenomenological Reflections on the Act of Understanding The basic principle I wish to develop in this section was summarized by Martin Luther: “He who does not understand the realities, cannot draw the meaning out of the words.”18 St. Augustine expresses the same thought: “It is in the event itself and not only in the text that we must seek the mystery.”19 A strong philosophical foundation for articulating “an understanding of understanding” is provided by Robert Sokolowski, whose thought helps detach us from an excessive attention to words and restores us to a consideration of the res or “the event itself.”20 The key insight of Sokolowski’s phenomenological approach as it is applied to the reading of Scripture can be summed up in a few quotes gathered from his writings. The first principle is: “when the words stand out, we no longer intend [i.e., are conscious of] just what is before us. A new kind of intending comes into play, one that makes these perceived marks into words and at the same time makes us intend not just the marks that are present, but the [thing], which is absent.”21 Words are a 16 Pontifical Biblical Commission, The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church (April 15, 1993) 76–77. 17 Ratzinger, “Biblical Interpretations in Conflict,” 29. 18 “Qui non intelligit res non potest sensum ex verbis elicere.” Tischreden, Weimarer Ausgabe 5, 26, no. 5246. 19 “In ipso facto, non solum in dicto, mysterium requirere debemus.” On Psalm 68 (PL 36, 858). 20 In addition to several studies of my own in which I have applied Sokolowski’s approach, I am indebted to an article, as yet unpublished, by William M. Wright IV, “The Light of the World and the Festival of Tabernacles (John 8:12): Insights from Sokolowski’s Theology of Disclosure.” I wish to express my gratitude here to Professor Wright for his generosity. 21 Robert Sokolowski, Introduction to Phenomenology (New York: Cambridge Univer- 260 Francis Martin means by which things are presented to a subject as a dative of manifestation. Sokolowski applies this principle to biblical revelation as follows: Once we recognize the fact that the written word is a prerequisite for biblical revelation . . . we must be careful to avoid the danger of making the text the primary focus, of making the text and not the things it discloses the center of our attention. Words, whether spoken or written, present things. We never have “just” words: words are vehicles to articulate and disclose things . . .Writing therefore intensifies the temptation to make the text stand on its own and become an object in its own right . . . Indeed, “textualism” can be considered a deviation analogous to the rationalism, historicism, and psychologism we discussed . . . In each case a form of manifestation—a text, a thought, a situated appearance, a perception—is taken to replace the thing manifested . . . the saving acts of God are disclosed in the Church through the reading of the biblical text.22 These words are consistent with Joseph Ratzinger’s dictum: “‘revelation’ is synonymous with the spiritual understanding of Scripture; it consists in the God-given act of understanding, and not in the objective letter alone.”23 An increase of understanding, especially with respect to the spiritual sense of the Old Testament, comes through a deeper appreciation not of the words as such but rather that “the one thing intended by the human author had dimensions that had not yet come into view, dimensions that could not appear until more had happened.”24 In earlier studies, I have spoken of the actions of God recorded in the Old Testament as being an anticipatory or “economic” participation in the mystery of Christ. The events, as well as the persons of Israel, sity Press, 1999), 78. In keeping with this orientation, I add here a remark of Aquinas concerning faith: “Such an act [of faith] does not have a proposition as its term, but a reality, since just as with scientific knowledge, so also with faith, the only reason for formulating a proposition is that we may have knowledge about the real” (ST II-II, q. 1, a. 2, ad 2). 22 Robert Sokolowski, Eucharistic Presence: A Study in the Theology of Disclosure (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1993), 143–44. 23 Ratzinger, Theology of History in St. Bonaventure, 63. 24 Sokolowski, Eucharistic Presence, 149 (italics Sokolowski’s). Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 261 share proleptically but metaphysically in the reality of Christ.25 The notion of “participation” eliminates a nominalistic understanding of the biblical text and opens the way to a deeper understanding of the whole mystery of the economy of salvation.26 The Eternal Existence of the Word as Premise for the Intellectus Spiritualis27 Just as every person after death is marked by his or her life, so Jesus Christ even now is marked by his earthly life. There are two differences in the life and death of Jesus and these form, implicitly or explicitly, the foundation for how the Gospels are written and read. The first difference arises from the fact that Jesus is risen from the dead. All that he said and did has risen with him and continues to be part of his glorious humanity: “And I saw in the midst of the throne and the four living beings, and in the midst of the elders, a lamb standing as having been slain having seven horns and seven eyes which are the seven spirits of God sent into all the earth” (Rv 5:6). Jesus, the lamb who still bears the marks of his slaughter, now is endowed with divine power and knowledge. What tradition calls the “mysteries of the life of Christ” are, each in their own way, a source of particular blessing and grace for those who touch them.28 This theological view is present already in the Letter to the Hebrews: “We do not have a high priest unable to share by experience our weaknesses, (but one) having been tested in all ways, because he is like us, (however) without sin.” The verb “having been tested” is, in Greek, a 25 Francis Martin, Sacred Scripture: The Disclosure of the Word (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2006), 274. 26 An excellent study, awaiting publication, is one by Jeremy Holmes, who, surveying several studies on the notion of participation, commends this line of thought as it has been followed up by several others. See also Matthew Levering, Participatory Biblical Exegesis: A Theology of Biblical Interpretation (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2008). 27 This section is made up of original material as well as some unpublished and published material. Much of the latter is found in Martin, Sacred Scripture, and is used here with permission. For an excellent study of the traditional understanding of the typological sense of the Old Testament, see Paolo Prosperi, “Novum in vetere latet. Vetus in novo patet: Toward a Renewal of Typological Exegesis,” Communio 37 (2010): 389–424. 28 The reader interested in following up on this theme might turn to A. Solignac, “Mystère,” in Dictionnaire de Spiritualitè X (Paris: Beauchesne, 1980), 1861–74. 262 Francis Martin perfect passive participle whose meaning in context is expressed by Zerwick-Grosvenor as “having triumphantly passed the test Jesus is forever tried and tested.”29 It is precisely because he is fixed in that act of love in which he died and “is forever tried and tested” that we are exhorted: “Let us, then, with confidence approach the throne of grace, that we might receive mercy and grace at the proper time” (Heb 4:16). The second difference lies in the fact that the Logos was present to Israel even before the Incarnation. For instance, in a series of warnings against imitating the infidelity of Israel, Paul writes, “All ate the same spiritual food, and all drank the same spiritual drink, for they drank from the spiritual rock that followed them, and the rock was Christ” (1 Cor 10:3–4).30 In some mysterious manner, the rock that was the source of water in the desert was Christ. In fact, it is possible to read John 1:10–13 as referring to the presence of the Logos to Israel before the Incarnation: He came to what was his own, but his own people did not accept him. But to those who did accept him he gave power to become children of God, to those who believe in his name, who were born not by natural generation nor by human choice nor by a man’s decision but of God. (NAB)31 Patristic texts commonly consider the theme of the Logos as mysteriously present before the Incarnation in the events by which God made himself known and which are transmitted in the Scriptures. Some salient examples occur in the writings of Irenaeus and Origen: The Son of God has been sown everywhere throughout the Scriptures [of Moses]. Sometimes He speaks with Abraham, sometimes with Noah, giving him the measurements of the ark; 29 Max Zerwick and Mary Grosvenor, A Grammatical Analysis of the Greek New Testament (Rome: Biblical Institute Press, 1979), 662. 30 This summary of the manner in which God cared for Israel in the desert is close to that of the themes in the liturgy of Sukkot as well as those in Nehemiah 9:20: “You gave them your good spirit to instruct them, you did not withhold your manna from their mouths, you gave them water for their thirst.” 31 See references in Craig S. Keener, The Gospel of John: A Commentary (Peabody: Hendrickson, 2003), 1, 401n360–62. Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 263 He looks for Adam, brings judgment on the Sodomites. There are times when He is actually seen, guiding Jacob on his way, speaking with Moses from the bush. (Irenaeus, “Against the Heresies,” IV, 10, 1)32 Thus the Word of God always showed to men, so to speak, the outlines of the things he was to accomplish in the future, the contours of the Father’s saving plan, thereby teaching us the things of God. (Ibid., IV, 20, 11) At the end of the ages the Word has indeed become human, Jesus Christ; but before this visible coming in the flesh he was already, although not yet human, the mediator of human beings (Origen, Fragment on the Letter to the Colossians [PG 14, 1297–98]). Now that I have shown how the preexistence of the Word and the Resurrection of Christ are the foundation for the spiritual reading of Scripture, I will consider the spiritual sense more in depth. Henri Crouzel suggests the complementary relation between spiritual exegesis and prophecy: Spiritual exegesis is in a kind of way the reverse process of prophecy: the latter looks to the future, but the former looks back from the future to the past. Prophecy follows the course of time forwards and in a historical or contemporary event sees darkly the messianic or eschatological fact that is prefigured. Spiritual exegesis follows the course of time backwards and, starting from the Messiah already given to the People of God, recognizes in the old Scriptures the preparations and seeds of what is now accomplished. But this accomplishment is in part prophetic in relation to what will take place in the end time.33 In Verbum Domini (§37), Pope Benedict quotes a definition of the spiritual sense given by the Pontifical Biblical Commission. This definition 32 Hans Urs von Balthasar, ed., The Scandal of the Incarnation: Irenaeus against the Heresies (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1990), 90. 33 Henri Crouzel, Origen: The Life and Thought of the First Great Theologian, trans. A. S. Worall (San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1989), 71. 264 Francis Martin continues in the same vein as Crouzel but binds the spiritual sense more intimately with the life of Christ and especially the Resurrection: As a general rule we can define the spiritual sense, as understood by Christian faith, as the meaning expressed by the biblical texts when read under the influence of the Holy Spirit, in the context of the paschal mystery of Christ and of the new life which flows from it. This context truly exists. In it the New Testament recognizes the fulfillment of the Scriptures. It is therefore quite acceptable to reread the Scriptures in the light of this new context, which is that of life in the Spirit.34 The paschal mystery, in which the Scriptures find their fulfillment, legitimizes and even calls for a spiritual reading of the whole of Scripture. The light of the Resurrection illumines all that precedes and follows it. The mention of the paschal mystery contains an allusion to the text in Luke 24:44–46, which narrates Jesus’s post-Resurrection meeting with the apostles: He said to them, “These are my words that I spoke to you while I was still with you, that everything written about me in the law of Moses and in the prophets and psalms must be fulfilled.” Then he opened their minds to understand the scriptures. And he said to them, “Thus it is written that the Messiah would suffer and rise from the dead on the third day.” (NAB) On this text, Aquinas comments thus: An intelligible light is sometimes divinely impressed on the human mind to judge something seen by others as is said of Joseph, and is obvious in the case of the Apostles for whom the Lord “opened their minds to understand the Scriptures” (Lk 24:45). (ST II-II, q. 173, a. 2c) The “intelligible light” whereby we understand the spiritual sense of 34 Pontifical Biblical Commission, Interpretation of the Bible in the Church, II, B, 2. Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 265 Scripture comes from the Risen Lord. Tradition at times associates Christ even more intimately with the words of the Scripture, particularly those of the Gospels. Beginning with Origen, the Church Fathers refer to the Scriptures as the “body of Christ.” De Lubac sums up the views of Origen, writing: In the literal meaning of Scripture, the Logos is thus not, properly speaking, incarnated as he is in the humanity of Jesus, and this is what allows us still to speak of comparison: he is, nevertheless, already truly incorporated there; he himself dwells there, not just some idea of him, and this is what authorizes us to speak already of his coming, of his hidden presence . . . near to the saints of the Old Testament: “How could they have announced the Word of God if the Word of God had not been present to them?” (Origen, Homily on Jeremiah 9,1)35 This sacramental mode of speaking is not far from Pope Benedict’s analogy between the word of God and the Eucharist: “Christ, truly present under the species of bread and wine, is analogously present in the word proclaimed in the liturgy” (Verbum Domini §56). The Power of the Word Having established from phenomenology and Scripture that the “word” is the reality itself in a different mode of existence, I wish to reflect briefly on the principle, often enunciated in both Scripture and Tradition, that the word is power. Already in the Old Testament, this underlying presupposition is given explicit expression in a great number of texts, of which the following are samples:36 35 Henri De Lubac, History and Spirit: The Understanding of Scripture According to Origen, trans. Ann Englund Nash (San Francisco: Ignatius Press), 389. The same notion is developed by Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 1, Seeing the Form, trans. Erasmo Leiva-Merikakis (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1982), 32, 529, 541. 36 For a good treatment of this theme, one could consult “Word,” in Dictionary of Biblical Theology, ed. Xavier Léon-Dufour (Gaithersburg, MD: Word Among Us Press, 1988). 266 Francis Martin By the Lord’s word the heavens were made; by the breath of his mouth all their host. (Ps 33:6; NAB) Yet just as from the heavens the rain and snow come down and do not return there till they have watered the earth, making it fertile and fruitful, giving seed to the one who sows and bread to the one who eats, so shall my word be that goes forth from my mouth. It shall not return to me empty, but shall do what pleases me, achieving the end for which I sent it. (Is 55:10–11; NAB) Not a single word of the blessing that the Lord had promised to the house of Israel failed; it all came true. (Jos 21:45; NAB) The following texts from the New Testament are a sampling of those that link the word of God, the Gospel, with power: You are already clean by the word I have spoken to you. (Jn 15:3) For I am not ashamed of the gospel. It is the power of God for the salvation of everyone who believes: for Jew first, and then Greek. (Rom 1:16–17; NAB) The word of the cross is foolishness to those who are perishing, but to us who are being saved it is the power of God. (1 Cor 1:18; NAB) For you may have thousands of tutors (paidagogous) in Christ but not many fathers; in Christ Jesus I begot you by the Gospel. (1 Cor 4:15) Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 267 And for this reason we too give thanks to God unceasingly, that, in receiving the word of God from hearing us, you received not a human word but, as it truly is, the word of God, which is now at work in you who believe. (1 Thes 2:13 NAB). The understanding of the sacramental dimension of Scripture—that is, its reality as more than a human word—is found in the ancient and medieval commentators. I will cite a few examples from St. Thomas Aquinas. Commenting on 2 Timothy 3:16, Aquinas asks why only the Scriptures should be considered divinely inspired since, according to Ambrose, “anything true, by no matter whom said, is from the Holy Spirit.” His response is that God works in two ways, one that is immediate and that pertains to him alone, as is the case with miracles; the other manner is mediate, that is, through the mediation of lesser causes, as is the case with natural operations. He then concludes, “And thus in man God instructs the intellect both immediately through the sacred letters and mediately through other writings.”37 The auctoritas of sacra scriptura is wholly singular: Scripture can cause knowledge immediately and, possessed of a unique power, it can have a referential function that brings us into contact with the divine realities themselves in a way that exceeds other faith formulations.38 In a similar vein, St. Gregory the Great affirms: “Sacred Scripture, in its very manner of speaking, is above all other sciences because in one and the same word, while it narrates an event, it sets forth a mystery.”39 St. Thomas expounds upon this idea in his commentary on Hebrews 5:12–14, in which the Christians are told they need someone to teach them again the “oracles” (logiòn/sermonum) of God, and that they need milk, not solid food: 37 “Et sic in homine instruit intellectum et immediate per sacras litteras, et mediate per alias scripturas.” In 2 Tim 3:16, lect. 3 (Marietti ed. §126). 38 In using the word “referential” in this context, I am alluding to a statement of the Pontifical Biblical Commission in its Bible et Christologie (Paris: Cerf, 1984), 1.2.2.1: “The “auxiliary” languages used in the course of the Church’s history do not have for faith the same authority (auctoritas/valeur) as the “referential language used by the sacred authors.” 39 “Sacra Scriptura omnes scientias ipso locutionis suae more transcendit, quia uno eodemque sermone dum narrat gestum, prodit mysterium.” Moralia 20,1 (PL 76,135). 268 Francis Martin For sacra doctrina is food and drink because it nourishes (potat) and satisfies the soul. The other sciences only enlighten the mind; this one, however enlightens the soul . . . This is a characteristic of the teaching of Sacred Scripture (doctrina sacrae Scripturae), that in it not only speculative things are handed on, but also those that are to be practiced through activity (approbanda per affectum).40 The Scriptures are unique in their completeness. They are food and drink; they enlighten the mind and soul; and they govern both speculative and practical activity. In his commentary on Pseudo-Dionysius’s treatise On the Divine Names, Aquinas articulates how the authority and power of Scripture arises ultimately from the Holy Spirit, who spoke through the Apostles and Prophets: Dionysius, in his teaching (doctrina) depends upon (innititur) the authority of Sacred Scripture which has strength and power (roborem habet et virtutem) because the Apostles and Prophets were moved to speak by the Holy Spirit who was revealing to them and speaking in them.41 In a commentary on Ephesians 6:13–17, Aquinas further elucidates how the power of the preached word comes from the Holy Spirit: Just as in bodily warfare this [attack on the enemy] is accomplished by a sword so also is this accomplished by the word of God which is, spiritually, the sword of the Spirit which you must take up. As it says in Hebrews 4:12, “For the word of God is living and active, sharper than any two-edged sword, and piercing through to the division between soul and spirit, joints and marrow; discerning the purposes and thoughts of the heart.” Thus preaching is called the sword of the Spirit because it cannot reach the human spirit unless it be wielded by the Holy Spirit: “It will not be you speaking but the Spirit of your Father who 40 41 Aquinas, On Hebrews, c. 5, lect. 2. Aquinas, In De divinis nominibus c. 1, lect. 1. Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 269 is speaking in you” (Matt 10:20) . . . Thus, we have weapons for fighting the demons themselves, namely, the sword of the Spirit which is the word of God. Frequently in sermons, the word of God, penetrating the hearts of sinners, drives out the tangled mass of sins and demons.42 Continuing this same line of reasoning about the Holy Spirit and Scripture, Henri de Lubac writes: Thus Scripture is not merely divinely guaranteed. It is divinely true. The Spirit did not merely dictate it. The Spirit immured himself in it, as it were. He lives in it. His breath has always animated it. The Scripture is “fertilized by a miracle of the Holy Spirit.” It is “full of the Spirit.”43 I now will consider a key action by which one becomes an “understander” of revelation, namely, the Eucharistic Liturgy, the original home of lectio divina. “The Liturgy: Privileged Setting for the Word of God” Most will recognize this title as designating the first major section of Part Two of Verbum Domini, namely, Verbum in Ecclesia. I now wish to place in prominence the active role that the biblical word plays in its own understanding. This notion is well articulated by Joseph Ratzinger in his book, Revelation and Tradition: “it becomes clear that we must go behind the positive sources, scripture and tradition, to their inner source, revelation, the living word of God from which scripture and tradition spring and without which their significance for faith cannot be understood.”44 In Verbum Domini, in the aforementioned section, Benedict builds upon this theme: 42 Aquinas, On Ephesians, c. 6, lect. 4. Henri de Lubac, Medieval Exegesis: The Four Senses of Scripture, vol. 1, trans. Mark Sebanc (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998), 82. The citations in the text are from Anselm, De concord. 3,6 (PL 157,528B) and Origen, De Princ. 4,1,7, respectively. 44 Joseph Ratzinger, “Revelation and Tradition,” in Revelation and Tradition (Montreal: Palm, 1966), 34. 43 Francis Martin 270 it must be said that Christ himself “is present in his word, since it is he who speaks when Scripture is read in Church.”45 Indeed, “the liturgical celebration becomes the continuing, complete and effective presentation of God’s word. The word of God, constantly proclaimed in the liturgy, is always a living and effective word through the power of the Holy Spirit. It expresses the Father’s love that never fails in its effectiveness towards us.”46 The Church has always realized that in the liturgical action the word of God is accompanied by the interior working of the Holy Spirit who makes it effective in the hearts of the faithful. Thanks to the Paraclete, “the word of God becomes the foundation of the liturgical celebration, and the rule and support of all our life. The working of the same Holy Spirit . . . brings home to each person individually everything that in the proclamation of the word of God is spoken for the good of the whole gathering” . . . A faithfilled understanding of Sacred Scripture must always refer back to the liturgy in which the word of God is celebrated as a timely and living word. (§52)47 In the liturgy, Christ is actually present in the proclaimed scriptures, and the Holy Spirit makes this Word efficacious in the hearts of believers. The section of Verbum Domini dedicated to “The word of God and the Eucharist” brings us to a central insight of Joseph Ratzinger, which is intimately related to our previous discussion of the power of the Word. He writes: Unless we acknowledge the Lord’s real presence in the Eucharist, our understanding of Scripture remains imperfect. For this reason “the Church has honoured the word of God and the Eucharistic mystery with the same reverence, although not with the same worship, and has always and everywhere insisted upon and sanctioned such honour.” (§55) 45 Sacrosanctum Concilium §7. Ordo Lectionum Missae 4. 47 Ibid., 3. 46 Revelation and Understanding Scripture in Ratzinger 271 The power of the Word of God, then, is grounded in an analogy with the Eucharist. In the next section, Pope Benedict proceeds to analyze the sacramentality of the word. He refers to the following remark of Pope John Paul II from Fides et Ratio: To assist reason in its effort to understand the mystery there are the signs which Revelation itself presents . . . In a sense, then, we return to the sacramental character of Revelation and especially to the sign of the Eucharist, in which the indissoluble unity between the signifier and signified makes it possible to grasp the depths of the mystery. (§13) The Pontiff returns to this earlier theme in order to understand the proclamation of the word in the light of sacramentality. Such an approach integrates the aspects of the mystery of the Word/word and points the way toward understanding: The sacramentality of the word can thus be understood by analogy with the real presence of Christ under the appearances of the consecrated bread and wine. By approaching the altar and partaking in the Eucharistic banquet we truly share in the body and blood of Christ. The proclamation of God’s word at the celebration entails an acknowledgment that Christ himself is present, that he speaks to us, and that he wishes to be heard. (§56)48 By making this analogy, Joseph Ratzinger points to the active part the Word of God plays in its being understood. The realities borne to us by the inspired Word cause their understanding. More than any other word, the inspired Word plays a sacramental role in regard to the recipient, thus the analogy with the Eucharist and the precising of what is meant by understanding this Word. I will now sum up what I have attempted to elaborate and point to the work that still lies ahead in understanding the inspired Word. 48 This passage refers to the Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1373–74, on the real presence of Christ in the Eucharist and Sacrosanctum Concilium §7, on the reality of the Church as the Body of Christ. 272 Francis Martin Conclusion In this article, I first attempted to clarify, through the teaching of Ratzinger and Thomas, that the transmission of revelation requires Sacred Scripture to be understood in its spiritual sense. The words reach beyond themselves to the divine reality. Robert Sokolowski contributes to this line of reasoning by teaching that words are bearers of reality, that is, they are the reality in another form of existence. In this light, I considered the presence of the Logos to Israel as an anticipated participation in the mystery of the Incarnation. Because the word is the reality in another form of existence, the question finally shifted to a consideration of the power of the reality. There is still much work to be done here. The direction is partially set, I think, by the understanding of what I considered last, namely, the analogous sacramental presence of Christ in the word, especially at the Eucharistic liturgy. Herein lies the urgency of restoring preaching as an essential part of the liturgy. By means of Sacred Tradition, the word of God entrusted by Christ the Lord and the Holy Spirit to the Apostles is handed on to their successors in its full purity, so that led by the light of the Spirit of truth, they may preserve this word of God faithfully, explain it, and make it more widely known. Again, though the direction has been set, there is much work to be done here as well. This is an invitation to much serious effort, while bearing in mind the Arab saying that we should save a little N&V work for our children. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 273-295 273 Violence Is Incompatible with the Nature of God: Benedict, Aquinas, and Method C Exegesis of the “Dark” Passages of the Bible Matthew J. Ramage Benedictine College Atchison, KS FOLLOWING THE LEADof then-Cardinal Ratzinger’s 1988 Erasmus lecture, this article offers principles needed to illumine some of the Bible’s “dark” texts, particularly those in which God apparently contradicts his own nature by approving, rewarding, or even commanding violence. This problem is crucial as Christians who hold divergent opinions vis-à-vis what the Bible intends to teach in matters of science and history typically agree in their expectation that the Bible gets it right when it comes to matters directly concerning faith and morals. The texts in question here, however, present believers with apparent errors precisely in this domain.1 To this end, this article attempts to instantiate Benedict’s “Method C” hermeneutical proposal in which he called upon exegetes to develop a new, fuller hermeneutical method (Method C) that makes the truth of Scripture more evident by synthesizing the best of patristic-medie- 1 There certainly exist other formidable problems concerning faith and morals in Scripture. I have treated those dealing with apparent contradictions in the Bible’s treatment of God’s nature and the afterlife in the volume Dark Passages of the Bible: Engaging Scripture with Benedict XVI and Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2013). Much of the material condensed in this essay can be found at various points within this larger text. 274 Matthew J. Ramage val exegesis (Method A) and historical-critical exegesis (Method B).2 In particular, I will tease out four points of contact between Aquinas and Benedict implied by the latter’s suggestion that Thomas’s exegesis offers a “counter-model” to deconstructive forms of modern exegesis: (1) the importance of having an “open philosophy” concerning the interplay of the divine and human in the world; (2) interpreting problematic texts in light of the divine pedagogy intelligible in the whole of Scripture; (3) ascertaining the essential message the sacred authors intend to convey in passages that ostensibly seem to contradict God’s nature by directly implicating him in evil; and (4) attending to the spiritual sense of such passages to see their relevance for the lives of believers of all ages.3 2 “You can call the patristic-medieval exegetical approach Method A. The historical-critical approach, the modern approach . . . is Method B. What I am calling for is not a return to Method A, but a development of a Method C, taking advantage of the strengths of both Method A and Method B, but cognizant of the shortcomings of both.” Benedict’s words are taken from a summary and transcript of the discussion following his 1988 Erasmus Lecture. See Paul T. Stallsworth, “The Story of an Encounter,” in Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: The Ratzinger Conference on Bible and Church, ed. Richard John Neuhaus (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1989), 107–8. Benedict’s lecture, “Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: On the Question of the Foundations and Approaches of Exegesis Today” was originally printed in ibid., 1–23. As Gregory Vall observes, “Strictly speaking, we are dealing not with two specific ‘methods’ but two general approaches. A series of basic principles unites the work of exegetes as diverse as Origen and Chrysostom, Bernard of Clairvaux, and Thomas Aquinas, so that we may speak of a single dominant patristic-medieval approach to exegesis, which Cardinal Ratzinger has labeled ‘Method A.’ When we turn to consider those biblical commentators whose work falls under the umbrella of ‘historical-critical’ exegesis, the diversity of specific methodologies is perhaps even greater. But in this case, too, fundamental principles of exegesis shared by these scholars may be identified, justifying the label ‘Method B.’” Gregory Vall, “Psalm 22: Vox Christi or Israelite Temple Liturgy?” The Thomist 66 (2002): 175–200. 3 Note that I have opted for the convention of referring to the one man Ratzinger/Benedict as “Benedict” throughout this article even in writings antedating his pontificate. Likewise, note that I will be referring to the version of the Erasmus Lecture entitled “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict: On the Foundations and the Itinerary for Exegesis Today,” in Opening Up the Scriptures: Joseph Ratzinger and the Foundations of Biblical Interpretation, ed. José Granados, Carlos Granados, and Luis Sánchez-Navarro (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008). This version of Benedict’s text (there are three different published editions of the lecture in the English language alone) reveals more explicit connections with Aquinas than the original English version published in the volume Biblical Interpretation in Crisis: The Ratzinger Conference on Bible and Church. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 275 The Problem First it is necessary to elucidate the particular problem this article will address with the help of Benedict and Aquinas. “Violence is incompatible with the nature of God and the nature of the soul . . . Not acting reasonably is contrary to God’s nature.” Benedict famously took this claim as the starting point for his reflections at Regensburg in 2006. The words he cited came from the mouth of a Byzantine Christian emperor challenging his Muslim interlocutor to justify Islam’s violent self-propagation, but Muslims do not stand alone in their need to render an account for having spread religion by the sword. One month after Regensburg, some one hundred influential Muslim leaders countered the pope with an open letter that included this argument: Moreover, it is noteworthy that Manuel II Paleologus says that “violence” goes against God’s nature, since Christ himself used violence against the money-changers in the temple, and said “Do not think that I came to bring peace on the earth; I did not come to bring peace, but a sword” (Matthew 10:34–36). When God drowned Pharaoh, was He going against His own Nature?4 At Regensburg the pontiff observed that Christianity made itself vulnerable to such criticisms when Duns Scotus broke from Augustine and Aquinas by maintaining a position that “might even lead to the image of a capricious God, who is not even bound to truth and goodness.”5 But did the danger of fashioning for ourselves a capricious God really arise with late medieval voluntarism? Are the Muslims not correct in their assertion that the Bible itself often depicts a bloodthirsty God who not only allows evil but even commands and rewards it?6 In a brief 4 See http://ww http://www.theislamicmonthly.com/open-letter-to-pope-benedict-xvi/ See http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2006/september/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20060912_university-regensburg_en.html. 6 The gravity of this claim cannot be seen if we limit ourselves to addressing individual “dark” texts as they come to our attention from time to time. It is fully recognizable by following the inspiration of Newman in his Grammar of Assent and taking account of the “cumulation of probabilities” that points to a real problem in this area. It is for this reason that scholars ultimately need to continue the present work by dwelling at length on problems like the ones treated here. 5 276 Matthew J. Ramage article such as this, I can only give a few indications to this effect, but the evidence is overwhelming. Just seven chapters into the Bible, God “blotted out every living thing that was upon the face of the ground” (Gn 7:23).7 In the next book, he seeks to kill the man whom he had called to lead his people out of slavery to the Egyptians (Ex 4:24) and slays all the first born in Egypt, including children (Ex 12:29). Later he proceeds to slay 185,000 Assyrians in one night (2 Kgs 19:35). This same God commands his people to act violently, to “utterly destroy” their enemies, showing “no mercy” and saving alive “nothing that breathes” when conquering them (Dt 7:1–2; 20:16–17). And the word of God reports that the people did just this: “[We] utterly destroyed every city, men, women, and children; we left none remaining” (Dt 2:33–34; cf. 3:6; Jo 6:21).” In fact, when King Saul does not “utterly destroy” the Amalekites, God dethrones him (1 Sm 15:8–9). Perhaps the violence of some of these texts can be accounted for by the fact that the “victims” in question were actually guilty and therefore not victims at all. For example, even by today’s standards the people of Israel may have been well within the bounds of law when employing lethal means of self-defense against the Assyrians, assuming such violence was per se ordered to that end. As for those times when the Bible indicates that God himself directly kills men, Aquinas argues that God operates perfectly in accord with his nature by directly punishing sinners with death: All men alike, both guilty and innocent, die the death of nature: which death of nature is inflicted by the power of God on account of original sin, according to 1 Samuel 2:6: “The Lord killeth and maketh alive. Consequently, by the command of God, death can be inflicted on any man, guilty or innocent, without any injustice whatever.8 This logic would seem to exculpate God when he takes people’s lives for various reasons and through various means, whether that be a flood, a plague, or his people Israel. However, many moderns find it unthinkable 7 8 All biblical citations in this essay will be taken from the RSV. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae (ST) I-II, q. 94, a. 5, ad 2. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 277 one could apply this principle so as to justify the slaughter of infant children on account of original sin and the collective sins of their people. Nor can they tolerate the fact that God, by remaining silent, apparently approves of the Psalmist when he revels in the thought of bashing Babylonian children against rocks (Ps 137:8–9; cf. Hos 13:16). It is likewise difficult to see how this accounts for times when God not only kills apparently innocent people but kills them after having set them up to fail, giving his people “statutes that were not good” and “defil[ing] them through their very gifts in making them offer by fire all their first-born” (Ez 20:23–26). He hardens hearts only in order to destroy the hardened (Ex 4:21; cf. 9:12; 10:1, 20, 27; 11:10; 14:8; Jos 11:20; Rom 9:18; 11:7–8). What is more, he goes so far as to send “evil” and “lying” spirits into individuals in order that they might fail (1 Sm 16:14; cf. 18:10; 19:9; 1 Kgs 22:19–22; cf. 2 Chr 18:21ff; Jgs 9:23). Perhaps a somewhat satisfactory answer could be made to each of these texts on a case-by-case basis, but to my mind the cumulative force of biblical evidence implicating God in evil clearly demands a more profound explanation.9 Benedict and Aquinas’s “Open Philosophy” In response to our problem, I would like to begin by recalling a relatively recent example demonstrating Benedict’s conviction concerning the significance of Aquinas for implementing his exegetical proposal. After explaining that his Jesus of Nazareth is not a “Life of Jesus” or a “Christology,” he explicitly states that Aquinas’s treatise on the life of Christ in the Summa is “closer to my intention” and that with this work “my book 9 Given the presence of these texts, history’s long pedigree of polemics against the authority of Scripture comes as no surprise. In the nineteenth century, Nietzsche famously reviled the Bible in his Genealogy of Morals, boasting that the priestly people who authored Sacred Scripture were the most vengeful “haters” in history. Today’s New Atheists carry on Nietzsche’s legacy: “we ought to be glad that none of the religious myths has any truth to it, or in it. The Bible may, indeed does, contain a warrant for trafficking in humans, for ethnic cleansing, for slavery, for bride-price, and for indiscriminate massacre, but we are not bound by any of it because it was put together by crude, uncultured human mammals.” Christopher Hitchens, God Is Not Great (New York: Twelve, 2007), 106. “One could go through the Old Testament book by book, here pausing to notice a lapidary phrase . . .and there a fine verse, but always encountering the same difficulties.” Ibid., 107. 278 Matthew J. Ramage has many points of contact.”10 Though privy to modern scholarly tools in a way Aquinas was not, Benedict identifies with the latter in his patient attentiveness to God’s word and his desire to put believers in touch with the mystery of Jesus, his “figure and message.”11 In the section of his Erasmus Lecture entitled “Basic Elements of a New Synthesis,” Benedict expounds at greater length on the importance of Thomas’s thought for helping believers encounter Christ through his word. In contrast with a Kantian “ready-made philosophy,” Aquinas’s “open philosophy” is “capable of accepting the biblical phenomenon in all its radicalism” by admitting that a real encounter of God and man is witnessed in history—and made possible today—by the Scriptures.12 For Benedict, a “critique of the critique” requires a rejection of the false presuppositions of those who would exclude a priori God’s ability to speak through human words. Aquinas’s exegesis, deeply rooted in the Catholic Tradition with its conviction that the boundary of time and eternity is permeable, allows for the Bible to be what the Church has always claimed it to be: the word of God in human words. Divine Pedagogy Following these remarks Benedict reveals a second point of contact with Aquinas: the recognition of how essential it is to grasp the Christological teleology of salvation history. Thomas serves as a salutary counter-model in the field of exegesis today, for he presupposes the action of divine providence guiding salvation history to its destination in Christ. Christ is thus for Benedict “the unifying principle” of history “which alone confers sense on it,” and God’s action gradually leading his people toward Christ is “the principle of the intelligibility of history.”13 The centrality of this principle comes into full relief if one steps back 10 Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth, vol. 2, Holy Week: From the Entrance into Jerusalem to the Resurrection, trans. Philip J. Whitmore (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2011), xvi. 11 Ibid. 12 Benedict XVI, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 23. 13 Ibid., 24, no. 37. Benedict is citing here Maximino Arias Reyero, Thomas von Aquin als Exeget: Die Prinzipien seiner Schriftdeutung und seine Lehre von den Schriftsinnen (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1971), 106; cf. “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 23, no. 35. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 279 to observe how Benedict has articulated his Method C proposal over the past two decades. His Verbum Domini is particularly significant because it has a section entitled “The ‘Dark’ Passages of the Bible,” in which the pontiff does this, though without precisely the same vocabulary. Benedict states that instances of violence and immorality in the Bible can be adequately addressed only if Catholics take seriously the fact that “God’s plan is manifested progressively and it is accomplished slowly, in successive stages and despite human resistance.” He explains that God patiently and gradually revealed himself in order to “guide and educate . . . training his people in preparation for the Gospel.” Because “revelation is suited to the cultural and moral level of distant times,” it narrates certain things “without explicitly denouncing the immorality of such things,” a fact that “can cause the modern reader to be taken aback.” What is needed for correct interpretation, therefore, is “a training that interprets the texts in their historical-literary context [another way of saying Method B] and within the Christian perspective [Method A] which has as its ultimate hermeneutical key ‘the Gospel and the new commandment of Jesus Christ brought about in the paschal mystery.’”14 The above text echoes the words of Dei Verbum and the later Catechism of the Catholic Church, which eloquently states: “The divine plan of revelation . . . involves a specific divine pedagogy: God communicates himself to man gradually. He prepares him to welcome by stages the supernatural revelation that is to culminate in the person and mission of the incarnate Word, Jesus Christ.”15 This patristically based hermeneutic of divine pedagogy articulated by Benedict and the Catechism is precisely the bridge that enables one to reconcile the unity of Scripture traditionally emphasized by Christian exegetes with the development, diversity, and apparent contradictions observed by modern scholars. For the hermeneutic of divine pedagogy affirms that Scripture has a unity in light of the fact that it proceeds from God’s one wise educational 14 Benedict XVI, Verbum Domini, §42 (emphasis Benedict’s); cf. nos. 11 and 20 for Benedict’s use of the term “divine pedagogy.” 15 Catechism of the Catholic Church, §53. I have cited the Catechism here because of its clarity and conciseness, but the Catechism itself is summarizing the Second Vatican Council constitution Dei Verbum §15. For other magisterial statements of the divine pedagogy, see Pius XI, Mit Brennender Sorge §15 and Lumen Gentium §9, which explains Israel’s relationship with God in terms of gradual instruction.” 280 Matthew J. Ramage plan for mankind and communicates God himself to man. At the same time, this hermeneutic is comfortable with diversity and apparent contradictions in Scripture since it sees these within the greater context of its progression toward Christ.16 To draw out the implications of this suggestion, I would like to sample some more texts that illustrate the importance Benedict places on a hermeneutic that takes seriously the divine pedagogy. In his In the Beginning, he describes the Bible as the story of a twofold struggle: God’s struggle to “make himself understandable to them over the course of time,” and the people of God’s struggle to “seize hold of God over the course of time.” This familiarization between God and man was a journey of faith, and “only in the process of this journeying was the Bible’s real way of declaring itself formed, step by step.” The message of the Bible becomes clearer as salvation history progresses and man acquires an increasing ability to penetrate the divine mysteries. Ultimately, however, the whole Old Testament is “an advance toward Christ,” and as such its real meaning becomes clear only in light of him who is its end. Benedict therefore argues that exegetes interpret individual texts correctly only when they “see in the text where this way is tending and what its inner direction is.”17 Benedict’s revealing interview God and the World is also illuminating, especially given our question concerning how the Christian Scriptures apparently implicate God in evil in a way that seems comparable with the Koran’s portrait of God. It is noteworthy that in this work Benedict treats precisely on the issue of whether the Scriptures exhibit development. Contrasting Islam’s belief that the Koran was dictated directly to Muhammad by God, he observes that the books of the Bible 16 “The Bible is the condensation of a process of revelation which is much greater and inexhaustible . . . It is then part of a living organism which, through the vicissitudes of history, nonetheless conserves its identity.” Benedict XVI, “Sources and Transmission of the Faith,” Communio 10 (1983): 28. 17 Benedict XVI, In the Beginning: A Catholic Understanding of the Story of Creation and the Fall, trans. Boniface Ramsey (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1995), 10–11. See also Benedict’s Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfiguration (New York: Doubleday, 2007), where he explains that the process of the Bible’s formation was “not linear . . . but when you watch it unfold in light of Jesus Christ, you can see it moving in a single overall direction.” According to Benedict and his “Christological hermeneutic,” Christ is “the key to the whole” of Scripture. Ibid., xix. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 281 “bear the impression of a history that [God] has been guiding,” since they were composed and developed over a thousand years, mediated by “quite different stages of history and of civilization.”18 As in the two texts just discussed, so here he explains, “The Bible is not a textbook about God and divine matters but contains images with perceptions and insights in the course of development, and through these images, slowly and step by step, a historical reality is coming into existence.”19 If the Christian cannot turn to a given page of the Bible for the fullness of revealed truth, then where can he find it? “The level on which I perceive the Bible as God’s Word is that of the unity of God’s history . . . In our Christian reading of it, we are more than ever convinced, as we said, that the New Testament offers us the key to understanding the Old.”20 The idea I wish to convey by sampling these works of Benedict on the importance of a divine pedagogy hermeneutic is summarized well in a fourth work, Introduction to Christianity, in which he states quite simply, “Anyone who wishes to understand the biblical belief in God must follow its historical development from its origins with the patriarchs of Israel right up to the last books of the New Testament.”21 18 Benedict XVI, God and the World (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2002), 151–52 (emphasis added). 19 “Let us compare Holy Scripture with the Koran, for example. Moslems believe that the Koran was directly dictated by God. It is not mediated by any history; no human intermediary was needed; it is a message direct from God. The Bible, on the other hand, is quite different. It is mediated to us by a history, and even as a book it extends over a period of more than a thousand years. The question of whether or not Moses may have been a writer is one we can happily leave to one side. It is still true that the biblical literature grew up over a thousand-year history and thus moves through quite different stages of history and of civilization, which are all reflected in it. In the first three chapters of Genesis, for instance, we meet with a quite different form of culture from what came later, in the exilic literature, or in the wisdom literature, and then finally in the literature of the New Testament. It becomes clear that God did not just dictate these words but rather that they bear the impression of a history that he has been guiding; they have come into being as a witness to that history.” Ibid. (emphasis added). 20 Ibid., 153 (emphasis added). Benedict again goes on to speak of the “process of collective development” and the “many stages of mediation” by which the biblical books gradually were able to “bring the history of God’s people and of God’s guidance to verbal expression.” 21 Benedict XVI, Introduction to Christianity (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), 116. It is illuminating to read the entire chapter from which this citation is taken, as in it Benedict traces the roots of Israel’s monotheism such as it developed 282 Matthew J. Ramage I now would like to illustrate briefly how one may implement this first principle concerning the necessity of a divine pedagogy hermeneutic for tackling “dark” texts. The step-by-step process by which God led his people to the fullness of truth is evident in the well-known changes made by the postexilic Chronicler to the Books of Samuel. In 2 Samuel 24:1, God incites David to sin by numbering the people, whereas in 1 Chronicles 21:1 the blame shifts away from God and on to Satan: “Satan stood up against Israel, and incited David to number Israel.” A Method B approach without the light of faith may view this solely as a piece of political propaganda to make David look better.22 For a Method C approach, however, it is not propaganda but providence that is the main force at work here. Following Benedict’s principle that Catholics need to look at the Scriptures as a whole, the Method C exegete might even admit that the Chronicler himself was at least partly motivated by political reasons here. Still, the fact that he attributed the instigation of an evil deed to Satan—a figure whose name appears as a proper noun in this text alone among all the books of the Old Testament—shows that he and his audience were beginning to suspect that Yahweh was not the direct cause of man’s evil actions. The picture painted in 1 Chronicles much more resembles that which Christians typically have in mind when considering God’s role in evil. It is not God but Satan who “incites” humans to evil and is, along with our own free will, the cause of evil actions. If this explanation is correct, it helps demonstrate the presence of a substantial unity in the Bible’s developing grasp of God’s relationship with evil; for, earlier and later texts shared in common a clear understanding that Yahweh was in charge of the entire cosmic order. Earlier authors were aware that Yahweh’s omnipotence meant that he was ultimately, in some mysterious way, the “cause” of man’s evil deeds. However, these authors explained reality in such a manner because they were operating on the premise that God is the direct cause of both good and evil. They were not fully privy to the distinction between God’s active and permissive will that was made later in the tradition. This distinction is at the heart of what is required to reconcile God’s omnipotence with 22 throughout the Old Testament period. For a helpful discussion of this problem, see Kenton Sparks, God’s Word in Human Words: An Evangelical Appropriation of Critical Biblical Scholarship (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2008). Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 283 his omnibenevolence in texts that appear to have God causing evil.23 This is where Satan, later in the tradition, eventually comes into play. In Chronicles as in the New Testament, God allows Satan to exercise his free will in tempting humans, and he allows individuals to consent to or reject Satan. Asserting “the Essential Point” A third point of contact between Aquinas and Benedict is not explicated by the emeritus pontiff himself but is nonetheless observable in the way he instantiates his own principles by attempting to determine the “essential point” asserted in concrete biblical texts. Benedict demonstrates keen awareness that certain texts seem plainly to contradict what is stated in other texts: It is because faith is not set before us as a complete and finished system that the Bible contains contradictory texts, or at least ones that stand in tension to each other.24 It follows straightaway that neither the criterion of inspiration nor that of infallibility can be applied mechanically. It is quite impossible to pick out one single sentence and say, right, you find this sentence in God’s great book, so it must simply be true in itself.25 23 Cf. ST I, q. 19, a. 9, ad 3; a. 12. Benedict XVI, God and the World, 152; cf. “The problem of dating Jesus’s Last Supper arises from the contradiction on this point between the Synoptic Gospels, on the one hand, and Saint John’s Gospel, on the other.” Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: Holy Week, 106. 25 Benedict XVI, God and the World, 153; cf. Benedict XVI, Address to Participants in the Plenary Meeting of the Pontifical Biblical Commission (May 2, 2011): “Lastly, I would only like to mention the fact that in a good hermeneutic it is not possible to apply mechanically the criterion of inspiration, or indeed of absolute truth by extrapolating a single sentence or expression. The plan in which it is possible to perceive Sacred Scripture as a Word of God is that of the unity of God, in a totality in which the individual elements are illuminated reciprocally and are opened to understanding.” See also this thought-provoking text from James Tunstead Burtchaell, Catholic Theories of Biblical Inspiration since 1810: A Review and Critique (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 299, 303–4: “Both by those who accept these claims [of inerrancy and infallibility] and by those who reject them, they have been imagined as some sort of flawless, eternal ownership of the truth, expressed in formulas that might from time to time need a little translating, but never need re24 284 Matthew J. Ramage The problem of admitting the presence of contradictory biblical texts, of course, lies in squaring it with the doctrine of inerrancy such as it is articulated in Dei Verbum: “everything asserted by the inspired authors or sacred writers must be held to be asserted by the Holy Spirit.”26 As Germain Grisez has noted in a helpful essay, it is a great mistake to read the above sentence as saying that everything in Scripture is asserted by the Holy Spirit: “Scripture contains not only many sentences expressing no proposition, but many sentences that express propositions not asserted by their human authors.”27 In a helpful footnote in which he offers illustrations from Aquinas to support his claim, Grisez adds that the council fathers would have been well aware of the difference between a mere statement on the one hand and an assertion or teaching on the other.28 Brian Harrison, O.S., in an essay that critiques a view similar to that advanced by Grisez, offers a further helpful specification. According to the Council relator of Dei Verbum 11, Harrison notes, the word teach (docere) refers to those things that are truly affirmed (asseruntur) in placing. In this sense, there has probably never been an inerrant declaration uttered or book written, nor need we look forward to one. But if inerrancy involve wild, and sometimes even frightening movement, if it mean being pulled to the right and to the left, being tempted constantly to deviate, yet always managing somehow to regain the road, then it begins to sound rather like what the Church has been about . . . In sum, the Church does find inerrancy in the Bible, if we can agree to take that term in its dynamic sense, and not a static one. Inerrancy must be the ability, not to avoid all mistakes, but to cope with them, remedy them, survive them, and eventually even profit from them. In a distinct selection of faith-leavings from a distinct epoch of faith-history, we have the archives of the process by which our ancestral faith began from nothing, involved itself in countless frustrating errors, but made its way, lurching and swerving, ‘reeling but erect,’ somehow though never losing the way, to climax in Christ.” 26 Dei Verbum §11. The text continues: “it follows that the books of Scripture must be acknowledged as teaching solidly, faithfully and without error that truth which God wanted put into sacred writings for the sake of salvation.” 27 Germain Grisez, “The Inspiration and Inerrancy of Scripture,” in For the Sake of Our Salvation: The Truth and Humility of God’s Word (Steubenville, OH: Emmaus Road, 2010), 186. 28 Ibid., 186n15. Grisez states that “the distinction between what is asserted and what is said without being asserted is one that Thomas uses regularly.” Examples he provides from the ST include II-II, q. 110, a. 3, ad 1; I, q. 77, a. 5, ad 3; q. 100, a.2, ad 2. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 285 Scripture.29 Harrison cites an important text from Raúl Cardinal Silva Herínquez to clarify: the doctrine of biblical inerrancy is better expressed by the formal criterion of teaching, since it is according to that criterion that no error can be found. For in another sense, that is, the material sense, it is possible for expressions to be used by the sacred writer which are erroneous in themselves, but which, however, he does not wish to teach.30 As Harrison proceeds to observe, the relator informed the council fathers that Herínquez’s above proposal had been accepted “substantially” by the doctrinal commission. Thus Harrison affirms Herínquez’s clarification as “a guide to what the Council means.”31 In contrast with Grisez, Harrison argues that the key distinction in the cardinal’s text is not between “affirmations” and “teachings” on the 29 Acta synodalia Sacrosancti Concilii Oecumenici Vaticani II (Rome: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1970–), vol. 4, pt. 5, 709; Brian Harrison, “Restricted Inerrancy and the ‘Hermeneutic of Discontinuity,’” in For the Sake of Our Salvation, 244. In another piece, Harrison pointedly criticizes certain “recent Catholic authors” who “have tried to reconcile [the teaching of Dei Verbum 11] with the supposed occurrence of errors in Scripture by charging that the errors they have in mind are never in fact affirmed by either the divine or human authors.” Harrison describes such a maneuver as a “contorted hermeneutic” that “unreasonably attempts to determine what is being affirmed in a given text in Scripture by appealing to content rather than form—subject matter rather than syntax . . . but this procedure—trying to identify an author’s assertions by looking at what he is talking instead of how he talks about it—violates basic, common-sense principles of verbal communication. Brian Harrison, “Does Vatican Council II Allow for Errors in Sacred Scripture?” Divinitas 52, no. 3 (2009): 279–304. The text cited here is from an updated version of the article available at http://www.rtforum.org/lt/lt145-6.html. This is a helpful critique, but it does not negate the importance of distinguishing statements from assertions as Grisez does. This fundamental endeavor to distinguish nonaffirmed statements from core assertions in the biblical text can be seen in the exegesis of Joseph Ratzinger throughout his career. But unlike the unnamed authors whom Harrison critiques, Ratzinger’s exegesis by no means neglects the syntax or how a biblical author wishes to assert his point. On the contrary, his patient attentiveness to this reality is what makes his hermeneutic so powerful. 30 Acta Vaticani II, vol. 3, pt. 3, 799. 31 Harrison, “Restricted Inerrancy,” 245. 286 Matthew J. Ramage one hand and “statements” on the other.32 Rather, for him the dichotomy is to be found in contrasting what is formally taught from what is merely “used” (adhiberi) by the sacred writers in view of making their assertions. The category of what is merely used, Harrison concludes, may include expressions (locutiones) that are “materially” erroneous.33 It is worth noting that here we have a Thomistically inspired distinction between material and formal error leveraged in order to make sense of the Scriptures. Paul Synave and Pierre Benoit make a similar distinction following the contours of Aquinas’s discussion of prophecy in the Summa: Truth is the adequatio rei et intellectus. It exists only in the judgment. And by “judgment” we obviously do not mean every proposition made up of subject, verb, and predicate, but the formal act by which the intellect affirms its conformity (adequatio) to the object of knowledge . . . An [inspired] author does not speak of everything in an absolute way . . . He tells the truth or he is mistaken only within the limits of the field of vision which he has established for himself and in which he forms his judgment . . . We must therefore respect the varying degrees of his assent, rather than take all his sentences as categorical affirmations.34 32 It is helpful to compare what Harrison writes in the above piece to another work in which he provides a helpful clarification of his view: “some biblical affirmations— above all, those that are per se less directly concerned with salvation—may be only approximations, or it may be that they express certain truths only in simple, popular language rather than in precise or technical terminology. For since the formal object of Sacred Scripture is to teach us God’s plan of salvation for the human race, and not profane history, natural science, or other forms of merely worldly knowledge for their own sakes, one should not expect or demand, as a condition of the Bible’s freedom from error, when it touches upon these subjects, the same standards of accuracy and clarity in description and terminology as we would expect and demand in works (especially modern academic works) whose formal object is these ‘secular’ branches of knowledge . . . we should not set the bar unreasonably high in deciding what is to count as truth, as opposed to error, when the sacred writers make statements about secondary matters that are only indirectly linked to the Bible’s principal and overall purpose.” “Does Vatican Council II Allow for Errors in Sacred Scripture?” http:// www.rtforum.org/lt/lt145-6.html 33 Harrison, “Restricted Inerrancy,” 245. On the distinction between the existence of material error or imperfection in contrast with formal errors in Scripture, see Matthew Ramage, Dark Passages of the Bible, 131–46. 34 Paul Synave and Pierre Benoit, Prophecy and Inspiration (New York: Desclee, 1961), 134–35. Cf. ibid., 142: “[God] certainly cannot prevent [the sacred author] from using Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 287 Abbot Denis Farkasfalvy speaks in similar terms: Divine inspiration does not imply that each passage and sentence of the biblical text must be found free of error from every conceivable point of view . . . But such a realization does not prove that God’s word asserts error. Rather, it only means that God’s message is expressed, at one or another point of salvation history, with the imperfections characteristic of human existence. 35 One might expand upon Farkasfalvy’s point by explaining that any apparent errors in Scripture are in reality material imperfections rather than formal errors since the biblical text still conveys “the human author’s concretely defined purpose and its divine author’s salvific purpose,” in such a way that “every passage expresses the truth which it is supposed to express according to God’s salvific will.” 36 Matthew Lamb, in his translation and notes on Aquinas’s Commentary on Ephesians, makes a similar point from an angle that also accounts for the divine pedagogy discussed above: We tend to regard a truth as either clearly and explicitly revealed or not revealed at all. But for St. Thomas man’s knowledge of the faith grows; truths are revealed slowly over a period of time. The Bible communicates this organic development in one way or another these erroneous views and, consequently, from letting them show through in his text. For example, no one will deny that the biblical authors had now outmoded cosmological ideas in which they believed, and that they employed them in their writings because they were unable to think apart from contemporary categories. But they do not claim to be teaching them for their own sakes; they speak of them for a different purpose, e.g. to illustrate creation and divine providence.” 35 Denis Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation: A Theological Introduction to Sacred Scripture (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2010), 232. Farkasfalvy’s explanation has many resonances with the following of C. S. Lewis. Writing on the subject of the Psalms, C. S. Lewis observes: “The human qualities of the raw materials show through. Naiveté, error, contradiction, even (as in the cursing psalms) wickedness are not removed. The total result is not ‘the word of God’ in the sense that every passage, in itself, gives impeccable science or history. It carries the word of God; and we . . . receive that word from it not by using it as an encyclopedia or an encyclical but by steeping ourselves in its tone or temper and so learning its overall message.” Reflections on the Psalms (London: Harvest Books, 1964), 111–12. 36 Farkasfalvy, Inspiration and Interpretation, 232. 288 Matthew J. Ramage of salvation-history to men up to its definitive apex in the revelation of the Word Incarnate himself. The whole of the Bible must be approached with faith; this does not mean that every sentence is a definable dogma.37 As Lamb relates, it is not as if one can find a definable dogma in every sentence of Scripture; indeed, Scripture never claims this about itself. The reason for this is that the authors of Scripture understood and taught revealed truth with varying degrees of clarity depending on their place within the course of salvation history. To discern dogmatic content within Scripture thus requires careful attention to the intentions of its authors and to the broader role of a particular text within the development of the canon as a whole. This also requires overcoming the assumption that something is “revealed” only if it is perfectly reflective of God’s own knowledge, or else it is not revealed at all. For his part, Benedict assesses concrete problems in a way that is compatible with and builds on the above understanding of inspiration and revelation. Throughout his corpus the emeritus pontiff often seeks to reconcile apparently erroneous biblical texts by inquiring into their “substance” or “essential point,” that is to say by asking what message the human and divine authors intend to teach or assert in a given text. He extends this principle even to the New Testament and Jesus’s own thought. For instance, in his treatment of the parable of Lazarus in Luke 16 he suggests that Jesus often employed images of the afterlife current in his day without “formally incorporating them into his teaching about the next life,” that is to say without intending to assert their conformity to reality. While Jesus did “unequivocally affirm the substance of the images,” the images themselves do not constitute “the principal message the Lord wants to convey in this parable.” Agreeing with Joachim Jeremias, the pope proposes that the “main point” of this parable concerns the rich man’s request for a sign rather than the nature of the afterlife, which may or may not be accurately conveyed through the imagery employed by Jesus.38 Benedict’s work here thus provides the exegete with 37 38 Ibid., 256n17. See also Ramage, Dark Passages of the Bible, 133–34. Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth, 215–16; cf. God and the World, 45, where he describes “what is actually meant” by Jesus’s promise that the man of faith can move mountains. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 289 an example of how he is to go about his work of reconciling apparently contradictory texts with Catholic teaching on biblical inspiration and inerrancy. He certainly does not go so far as to allow that Jesus himself held imperfect ideas about the afterlife, but his exegesis at least implies that an inspired author need not formally assert every last problematic statement that issues from his pen. God and the World contains a number of other examples of this type of move that are germane to our present question concerning violence and the nature of God. For example, interviewer Peter Seewald challenges him with the Levites’ slaughter of three thousand men at the command of God uttered through Moses’s mouth: “So, basically, the story of the Ten Commandments began with an enormous violation of commandment number five: Thou shalt not kill. Moses really ought to have known better.”39 Benedict’s first move in response is a characteristically honest acceptance of his interlocutor’s observation, namely that this account “does sound terribly bloodthirsty.” His next is an instantiation of one of the principles he professed to hold in common with Aquinas, namely to observe that if the episode is to make sense, “we have to look forward, toward Christ,” that is to see Scripture as a whole. Third, rather than simply saying what the passage cannot mean, he offers a suggestion for what God in his pedagogy intended it to mean: “What happens expresses the truth that anyone who turns from God not only departs from the Covenant but from the sphere of life; they ruin their own life and, in doing so, enter into the realm of death.”40 Moreover, perhaps to the discomfort of the Christian, Benedict notes that “whether there really were any stone tablets is another question.”41 Even if it were the case that one could disprove the existence of these physical artifacts, it would not change “the essential point” of the Sinai narrative, namely “that God, through the agency of his friend, really makes himself known in an authoritative way.” This is the substance of the narrative, the author’s principle concern. For Benedict, there is no need for the Christian to worry about whether the account perfectly 39 Benedict XVI, God and the World, 167. Ibid., 168 (emphasis added). 41 Ibid., 166 (emphasis added). See also his attempt to ascertain the essential point in the passages concerning creation in ibid., 75ff. 40 290 Matthew J. Ramage conforms to contemporary Western standards of historiography. Many details Christians consider essential today are in truth accidental features of the text. They were a part of the author’s presentation but not his principal concern, and in light of the above principles are not to be deemed formal “errors.” Indeed, it is doubtful that the redactors and compilers of the canon would have been unaware of the problems people raise today: they deliberately left ambiguities in Scripture perhaps in part so that later generations could “struggle with God” as they had done and perhaps build on the tradition they were blessed to receive from their ancestors.42 One finds the same modus operandi in Benedict’s discussion of whether the events that unfolded on Sinai were myth or history. Here he concretely applies the principle he praised in Aquinas concerning his “open philosophy” that is capable of accounting for a God who enters history and speaks through human words. He does not deny that the episode is imbued with a certain mythological flare (thunder, lightning, clouds, trumpets, flames, quaking, God’s hand writing on stone, etc.), but affirms that it “refers to a real event, a real entering into history by God, to a real meeting between God and his people,” and through them to a meeting with mankind. This, according to Benedict, is the “essence of the event.”43 As a last example, it is instructive to observe how our author responds when faced with passages that describe God as jealous, wrathful, and violent in his punishments: 42 While beyond the scope of this article, it is worth calling attention to the fact that Benedict’s understanding of corporate biblical authorship is capable of accounting for the phenomenon of redaction in light of the doctrine of biblical inspiration. Throughout his corpus, Benedict is able to achieve this by considering biblical authorship not merely in the individual human authors and God as divine author, but in light of “the collective subject” of Scripture, the People of God. For a discussion of the “interlocking subjects” of Scripture, see his Jesus of Nazareth, xx–xxi. As Aaron Pidel, S.J., rightly observes, Benedict “transfers the locus of intention and affirmation from the human authors of Scripture to Scripture itself.” “Joseph Ratzinger and Biblical Inerrancy,” Nova et Vetera 12, no. 1 (2014): 314. He considers all individual biblical texts in light of their place within the entire plan of salvation revealed in Scripture and culminating in Christ. Thus for Benedict the canonical books are inerrant, “but only to the extent that they bear upon the intention of the whole—the mystery of Christ.” Ibid., 330. 43 Benedict XVI, God and the World, 165 (emphasis added). Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 291 The wrath of God is a way of saying that I have been living in a way that is contrary to the love that is God. Anyone who begins to live and grow away from God, who lives away from what is good, is turning his life toward wrath . . . When God inflicts punishment, this is not punishment in the sense that God has, as it were, drawn up a system of fines and penalties and is wanting to pin one on you. “The punishment of God” is in fact an expression for having missed the right road and then experiencing the consequences that follow from taking the wrong track and wandering away from the right way of living.44 Without employing the same vocabulary as he did above, Benedict does not shy away from raising the tough question here: Is God actually wrathful, as the text evidently states? This need not be admitted if one understands that, while Old Testament authors may have held or stated that the “wrath” of the all-powerful God was the direct cause of all evil, the main point they affirmed or taught when speaking this way was that turning away from God’s love brings about disastrous consequences for man. In other words, in the sacred author’s mind the mechanism by which man gets punished for turning against God was subordinate to his teaching about the reality of the punishment itself.45 One could apply this same line of reasoning to all of the problematic texts mentioned at the beginning of the article, but here I will give only a couple examples. With respect to times when God apparently sets people up to fail, I observed above that the later tradition associated such causality not with God but Satan. If I may hazard my own application of Benedict’s principle here, the “essential point” of such passages perhaps lies in an assertion of God’s omnipotence and of man’s sinfulness in the concrete cases in question. In other words, the text’s narration that God was directly responsible for Pharaoh’s hard heart may be accidental to the more central assertions that Pharaoh closed his heart and that the whole affair falls within the scope of divine providence. When it comes to examples of God commanding the death of seemingly innocent children, might the “essential point” of God’s command not have been to 44 45 Ibid., 104 (emphasis added). Synave and Benoit, Prophecy and Inspiration, 142. 292 Matthew J. Ramage kill the children but rather to defend the people against idolatrous aggressors who habitually made God’s people fall into the same idolatry? The Spiritual Sense This leads to a fourth and final connection between Benedict and Aquinas: their agreement concerning the need for a rich doctrine of the senses of Scripture. While I believe that the principles already articulated are sufficient to account for certain troublesome biblical texts from an apologetics perspective, Benedict also identifies spiritual exegesis as an essential component of his program. Indeed, it is here that the word of God achieves its end of taking flesh in our human lives and becoming truly a “living” word. In Verbum Domini, Benedict draws on Aquinas, himself citing Augustine, to emphasize the importance of the spiritual sense. In reality “it is impossible for anyone to attain to knowledge of that truth unless he first have infused faith in Christ” since “the letter, even that of the Gospel, would kill, were there not the inward grace of healing faith.”46 In the Erasmus Lecture Benedict speaks to this at greater length: To discover how each given historical word intrinsically transcends itself, and thus to recognize the intrinsic rightness of the rereadings by which the Bible progressively interweaves event and sense, is one of the tasks of objective interpretation. It is a task for which suitable methods can and must be found. In this sense, the exegetical maxim of Thomas Aquinas is much to the point: “The task of the good interpreter is not to consider words, but sense.”47 In contrast with those whose methodologies focus solely on the “words” of Scripture, Benedict shares with Aquinas the conviction that the words of Scripture were meant to be “reread” over time, to point beyond themselves to a reality revealed through them but that transcends them.48 46 Verbum Domini, §29; cf. ST I-II, q. 106, a. 2. Benedict XVI, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 26 (emphasis added), citing Thomas Aquinas, In Matthaeum, XXVII, no. 2321, ed. R. Cai (Turin: Marietti, 1951), 358. Cf. Verbum Domini, §37. He cites Aquinas three times in this work. 48 For the reality of revelation being broader than the Bible, see Benedict XVI, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 26, and Verbum Domini, §16. 47 Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 293 In this way, their rich teaching on the senses of Scripture, while giving due attention to its words, also points beyond the words so as to show that even Scripture’s “darkest” and most problematic passages may put believers in touch with Christ. The text in its wholeness, Benedict says, must become Rabbenu, “our teacher.”49 Method A exegesis indicates that the texts of Scripture signify something in addition to their human authors’ original intended meaning: realities in the lives of believers of all ages who meditate on these texts in order to gain the knowledge and strength they need to live a life in Christ. As Benedict indicates, Christians may be privy to the fullness of revelation in a way our Old Testament forefathers were not, but the ancient truths taught therein “are of course valid for the whole of history, for all places and times” and “always need to be relearned.”50 The logic of the divine pedagogy is thus revealed when Christians discover that their encounter with Christ through a spiritual reading of Scripture’s “dark” passages is not merely one among many possible readings but rather the purpose for which the literal sense was composed in the first place. The following is an apt summary of Benedict’s twofold approach to the divine pedagogy and his attitude toward how the believer ought to approach Scripture’s “dark” passages: If I only read the Bible in order to see what horrible bits I can find in it, or to count up the bloodthirsty bits, then of course it won’t heal me. For one thing, the Bible reflects a certain history, but it is also a kind of path that leads us in a quite personal way and sets us in the right light. If, therefore, I read the Bible in the spirit 49 Benedict XVI, “Biblical Interpretation in Conflict,” 27. The Pontifical Council for Inter-Religious Dialogue eloquently describes this dimension of the divine pedagogy: “[The Church] takes her lead from divine pedagogy. This means learning from Jesus himself, and observing the times and seasons as prompted by the Spirit. Jesus only progressively revealed to his hearers the meaning of the Kingdom, God’s plan of salvation realized in his own mystery. Only gradually, and with infinite care, did he unveil for them the implications of his message, his identity as the Son of God, the scandal of the Cross. Even his closest disciples, as the Gospels testify, reached full faith in their Master only through their Easter experience and the gift of the Spirit. Those who wish to become disciples of Jesus today will pass through the same process of discovery and commitment.” Dialogue and Proclamation, §69 (emphasis added). 50 Benedict XVI, God and the World, 154. Matthew J. Ramage 294 in which it was written, from Christ . . . in faith, then indeed it has the power to transform me. It leads me into the attitude of Christ; it interprets my life to me and changes me personally.51 Method C exegesis therefore does not deny the importance of the literal sense, but in light of the divine pedagogy it shows how the literal sense opens up into spiritual senses that touch the lives of believers in every age. For example, what reflective Christian would not find wisdom for life in Origen’s spiritual exegesis of Psalm 137, where he exhorts Christians to “dash” our nascent sins before they spawn and grow into unbreakable vices?52 Or, to take up an example already mentioned, who would not be inspired with holy fear when seriously pondering the punishments associated with God’s “wrath”? While it may not be possible to find such a fitting spiritual interpretation of every problematic biblical text, our emeritus pontiff believes that this is precisely the sort of exegesis that makes a difference in our lives and represents the Bible’s ultimate raison d’être. Conclusion This article has touched on four points of contact between Benedict and Aquinas that offer fruitful avenues for reconciling Benedict’s conviction that violence is incompatible with the nature of God with some of Scripture’s darkest texts. I first observed the necessity of an “open philosophy” that welcomes the entry of the divine into man’s life. Then I illustrated how such a position opens our eyes to see in the Scriptures the divine pedagogy by which God worked to progressively lead his people to the fullness of revelation in Christ. I then surveyed a number of occasions in which we witness Benedict endeavoring to ascertain “the essential point” of biblical texts that when taken at face value appear to contradict God’s nature or otherwise contain errors. Finally, I indicated that, while the aforementioned principles may provide a rational basis on which to account for the problem at hand, the most important part of Scripture is that God teaches believers today through its darkest texts when Christians read them according to their spiritual sense. In sum, I believe 51 52 Ibid., 155. Origen, Against Celsus, 7.22. Benedict, Aquinas, and Exegesis of “Dark” Passages 295 that these avenues, while obviously not exhaustive, go a long way both toward reconciling problematic biblical texts and toward facilitating a spiritual encounter between the faithful and Christ in the “dark” texts N&V of Scripture. Nova et Vetera, E  nglish Edition, Vol. 13, No. 1 (2015): 297-320 297 Book Reviews Cosmology by Édouard Hugon, O.P., trans. Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo (Neunkirchen-Seelscheid, Germany: Editiones Scholasticæ, 2013), 376 pp. ÉDOUARD HUGON, O.P.,taught at the Angelicum from 1909 to 1929, being a confrère of Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P., Pope John Paul II’s thesis advisor. Hugon produced, with Garrigou-Lagrange’s approbation, a six-volume scholastic manual entitled Cursus Philosophiæ Thomisticæ,1 which Popes St. Pius X, Benedict XV, and Pius XI all heartily recommended. Pope St. Pius X said it contains “the unadulterated teaching of Saint Thomas.” (2). He praised the “wealth and coherence of [Hugon’s] arguments and the clarity of [his] style, . . . particularly for applying ancient scholastic principles to shed light on new advances in philosophy and to the judicious refutation of errors” (ibid.). Garrigou-Lagrange called Hugon the “theologus communis,” the “faithful echo of the Common Doctor of the Church.”2 Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo of Opus Dei’s Universidad Panamericana in Guadalajara, Mexico, has translated, in collaboration with the German publisher Editiones Scholasticæ, the Cosmology volume of Hugon’s opus. Why translate the Cosmology volume first and not, say, the Logic or Metaphysics volumes? Carrasquillo has two aims: (1) to show that natural philosophy—not metaphysics, as Christian Wolff et al. thought—must be taught before ethics, metaphysics, and theology, 1 Édouard Hugon, O.P., Cursus Philosophiæ Thomisticæ, 6 vols. (Paris: Sumptibus P. Lethielleux, 1927), http://liberius.net/auteur.php?id_auth=25. 2 Thomas Poinçoc, O.P., “Presentazione,” in Fuori della Chiesa non c’è salvezza, ed. Édouard Hugon, O.P., trans. Claudio Fauci (Chieti: Edizioni Amicizia Cristiana, 2007), http://www.edizioniamiciziacristiana.it/presfuoridellachiesa.htm. 298 Book Reviews being their basis; and (2) to disprove those who think manuals neglected modern developments in the natural sciences. The most important part of Cosmology is its prolegomena because this is where Hugon shows the necessity of studying natural philosophy, not just for further philosophical and theological studies, but also for modern science: In modern times, however, the natural sciences having been wondrously developed, Philosophy was banished from Physics; hence it happens that scientists, in exploring facts or at least aiming at proximate causes, have neglected ultimate causes and first principles. For this reason, a philosophical regard in the study of nature is more than ever desired today. (34) However, Hugon advocates a strict distinction between philosophy and modern science, saying that “many topics that today are taught in the physical sciences” are “outside of Philosophy.” Because of the importance of the prolegomena, Carrasquillo has added many of his own footnotes to help explain Hugon’s scholastic terminology for the beginning student. Thus it becomes clear why St. Thomas said boys must learn, in this order: logic, mathematics, the natural sciences, the moral sciences, and, lastly, the sapiential and divine sciences (theology).3 Hugon splits up the bulk of Cosmology into three treatises, according to Aristotle’s four causes: 1. On the World with Respect to Its Efficient Cause 2. On the World with Respect to Its Material and Formal Causes 3. On the World Insofar as It is Ordered to an End The first treatise covers such questions as monism, the contingency of the world, pantheism, the author of the world, whether the world emanates from God, creation, and the eternity of the world. The third treatise covers such questions as nature, motion, art and violence, the laws of nature, miracles, the end of nature, and evolution. In all the questions Hugon treats, he employs clear, syllogistic proofs of every principle, the objections to which he distinguishes, concedes, denies, contradistinguishes, etc., in solid scholastic form. 3 Sententia Ethic., lib. 6 l. 7 no. 17 [1211.] Book Reviews 299 The second treatise is where scholastic natural philosophy meets modern science. It is where Hugon shows his more-than-superficial familiarity with the philosophy of physics of Pierre Duhem,4 especially where Hugon argues that modern science does not disprove hylemorphism, which avoids the pitfalls of both atomism and dynamism. Hylemorphism is a “stable notion” the Council of Trent “consecrated” in its teaching on justification.5 Hugon defends it against attacks from some scientists: X. - Difficulties Resolved; Whether there is a Contradiction Between the Scholastics and the Scientists. . . . 3rd Objection. Apart from the Scholastics who are ignorant of natural things, no one else professes hylemorphism. Therefore, it is prudent to mistrust this system. Reply. In this question we must believe the philosophers more so than the physicists and the chemists, as is evident from the previous reply [“the adversaries . . . think that the question of principles is a physical and experimental one, whereas it is really a properly philosophical one”]. Further, the greatest philosophers, Aristotle, St. Augustine, and St. Thomas, adhered to this system. Even today many outside of the Scholastics support it. Barthélemy Saint-Hilaire presents this testimony of the Aristotelian doctrine: “For me, I find it to be simple and true, and it does not have the fault of being obscure; at most, I will grant that it has a certain subtlety, without being in any way sophistical. Matter and form are the logical and real elements of being.” (Préface de la Physique, p. 28.) (173, 175-76) One can only imagine what Hugon would have written had this book been published after the rise of quantum mechanics. It would further 4 Roger Ariew, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [online], s.v. “Pierre Duhem,” http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/duhem/. Hugon cites, e.g., Duhem’s Mixture and Chemical Combination: And Related Essays, trans. Paul Needham (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 2002), and The Evolution of Mechanics, trans. Michael Cole (Germantown, MD: Sijthoff & Noordhoff, 1980). 5 Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P., “Les Notions Consacrées par les Conciles,” Angelicum 24 (1947): 217–30, http://bit.ly/YPlBff. 300 Book Reviews confirm what Hugon cited of Duhem: Meanwhile, let it be clear that scientists that are true to their name do not contradict hylemorphism: “Current physics tends to recover a certain form of peripateticism” [i.e., Aristotelianism] (P. Duhem, Le mixte,6 p. 200). (177) Hugon shows that modern spectral analysis does not disprove hylemorphism: Explanation of many things that are necessary for the complete understanding hylemorphism . . . III. - On the Permanence of Elements in the Mixture . . . 3rd Objection. From spectral analysis it has been established that in the composite there appear the colors of the simple elements. But this fact shows that the powers of elements remain in act in the composite. Therefore. Reply. I distinguish the major. That the colors of the elements appear in the composite while the composite remains at rest in the compound state, I deny; that these colors appear while the mixed body begins to be resolved through the action of light or heat, I concede. I contradistinguish the minor: that this fact shows that there are powers in act in the mixed body, if this happens in the compound state itself, I concede; but that this shows there are powers in act in the mixed body if this happens only when the mixed body begins to be resolved and destroyed, I deny. And I deny the conclusion. That only implies that the powers persist in similar entities. (209-10, 214) Following this (215-16), Hugon admiringly cites Duhem,7 proving again his up-to-date knowledge of modern science. Praising Duhem, Hugon writes: IV. - The Scholastic System is Substantially Retained Today . . . It is also appropriate to write the following testimony of the most learned P. Duhem: “Little by little, however, by the 6 7 Duhem, Mixture and Chemical Combination. Duhem, Mixture and Chemical Combination, 115–16. Book Reviews 301 very effect of this development, mechanical hypotheses came up against obstacles on all sides which were more and more numerous and difficult to surmount. The atomic, Cartesian, and Newtonian systems gradually lost favour with physicists and made way for methods analogous to those advocated by Aristotle. Present-day physics is tending to return to a peripatetic form” (P. Duhem, Le mixte,8 p. 200). (225, 227) This edition of Hugon’s Cosmology is a scholastic, logically sound work that will help philosophers and modern scientists better understand the relationship between philosophy and modern science, especially modern physics. Hugon upholds the Second Vatican Council’s call that “philosophical disciplines are to be taught in such a way that the students are first of all led to acquire a solid and coherent knowledge of man, the world, and of God, relying on a philosophical patrimony which is perennially valid” and that “account should also be taken of the more recent progress of the sciences.”9 Carrasquillo’s translation is the best English-language manual in print enabling beginning and adN&V vanced students alike to have “St. Thomas as a teacher.”10 Alan Aversa Fisher More College Fort Worth, Texas Thomas Aquinas and the Philosophy of Punishment by Peter Karl Koritansky (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2012), ix + 209 pp. PETER KORITANSKY’S “CENTRAL GOAL”is “a presentation of Aquinas’s theory of punishment as superior to that of utilitarianism and modern retributivism” (8). He makes real progress toward this, and even though Thomas Aquinas and the Philosophy of Punishment will appeal most to those already sympathetic to the Thomistic tradition, it provides 8 Ibid., 119. Optatam Totius §15. 10 1983 Code of Canon Law can. 252 §3. 9 302 Book Reviews an excellent foundation for dialogue with rival theories of punishment. According to utilitarianism, punishment is a purely instrumental good justified by its promotion of the greatest good for the greatest number. It is therefore possible that an innocent person must be punished in order to promote this greater good. For most of us, argues Koritansky, the absence of a concept of desert renders this account of justice untenable. For this reason, “purely utilitarian theories of punishment are rare” (33). Koritansky then considers the popular compromise theory of H. L. A. Hart, who introduces the concept of desert as a limiting principle: you cannot be punished for more than you deserve. Nevertheless, if in fact you are punished, it can only be for utilitarian reasons, and therefore “desert” does not justify punishment, but instead prevents its unjust distribution, thereby protecting the innocent as well as those who might otherwise suffer more for their crimes than they deserve. But Koritansky argues that Hart cannot have it both ways; once we admit that desert must play a role, we can no longer eliminate it from our account of the justification of punishment more generally: “Hart’s position is that because retribution is not part of punishment’s general justifying aim, we should only consider desert insofar as it protects criminals (or noncriminals) from the excessively harsh punishments that utility might require. What Hart fails to consider is the inseparability between saying that criminals should not receive more punishment than what they deserve and saying that they deserve some amount of punishment” (37). Those who reject the utilitarian justification of punishment typically accept some form of retributivism, a position Koritansky traces to Kant, according to whom we can (and must) punish others only if (and to the extent that) they deserve it. But we need an explanation of the foundation and content of this desert (Kant offered little more than the ius talionis), and the modern formulation Koritansky discusses is the “unfair advantage” theory. According to this theory, society is, at least in part, an agreement among citizens regarding the distribution of benefits and burdens to its members. Criminals violate this agreement by avoiding their fair share of the burdens and acquiring an unfair share of the benefits. Punishment eliminates this imbalance introduced by the criminal. Nevertheless, none of the proponents of this theory, argues Koritansky, “are able to explain in any compelling way how criminal actions constitute a ‘benefit’ to the criminal himself ” (64). Neither material nor psychological benefits will work; because the casual murderer Book Reviews 303 gets little material or psychological benefit from his crime, he would be punished less severely than the enthusiastic bank robber. “The pivotal question seems, then, to be this: Can the mere performance of an action prohibited by law, considered independently from that action’s material benefits or any pleasure derived from it, constitute a meaningful benefit?” (66). John Finnis and others have suggested that the criminal possesses greater freedom of choice, which is itself a great human good, but this is a peculiar sort of freedom; all of us are free to commit murder, so the murderer does not have that freedom in a way we do not. And if it is the freedom enjoyed in the act of murder, it is much harder to see that this “freedom” is any sort of extra benefit or advantage to the murderer. This form of retributivism remains unable to explain the ground of our insights regarding desert: precisely why does one person deserve to be punished simply because he or she violated the law? Koritansky now turns to Aquinas’s position, and argues that the primary theoretical foundation of the Thomistic theory of punishment is the political common good. This common good, for which we have a natural inclination, is itself an intrinsic part of our overall good (here Koritansky’s defense of this disputed claim draws in part on Lawrence Dewan’s work). This has significant consequences: “Only by living in political society is man capable of achieving his full natural potential. Thus understood, politics is no mere instrumental good (as in the teachings of Kant, Bentham, and the unfair advantage theory of punishment [whose adherents include John Finnis]), but is part of the very fabric of the human person, and thus the individual’s participation in political society is a great intrinsic good for the individual as well as for society” (101). Given this context, punishment is a kind of evil or suffering that must be contrary to the will of the one being punished and imposed because of and in accordance with that person’s wrongdoing. The Thomistic account of punishment therefore has a retributive core dependent on desert. Further, since the political common good is an intrinsic part of human flourishing (rather than a merely instrumental good), a citizen who commits a crime harms his own good by harming the common good. “To become a criminal who prefers his own immediate interests to those of others is actually to frustrate one’s own happiness as a ‘naturally civic and social animal’” (149). Contrary to Finnis, therefore, “it is quite wrong to suggest that, for Aquinas, actions that deliberately harm 304 Book Reviews the common good constitute, in themselves, an advantage or a benefit to the criminal. Criminals are, on the contrary, supremely disadvantaged by their criminal actions which, precisely because they fly in the face of one’s natural inclination to serve and promote the political common good, make those who perform them into a worse person” (150). Punishment, consequently, does two things. It is first of all retributive in that it “restores the equality of justice by inflicting a punitive evil upon a criminal against his will” (164). And it is medicinal, for it is “designed to restore criminals back to willfully law-abiding citizens . . . , protect society, and deter other potential criminals” (167). The criminal through punishment realizes the equality of justice and is restored to his place within the political order and its pursuit of the common good. But it would be a mistake to conclude that Aquinas has a straightforwardly retributive account of punishment, as the central case of the death penalty demonstrates. Koritansky shows that Aquinas does not use the language of retribution in his defense of capital punishment, an absence about which we can only “speculate” (164). Koritansky’s conclusion is that the retributive features of punishment are foundational (you can only punish the guilty), but the medicinal consequences of punishment (in this case the protection of society) are more clearly apparent, and so in the temporal order retribution has a secondary place. The striking result is that “Aquinas can only recommend a retributive theory of punishment that considerably understates the necessity of retribution” (169). This has implications for the recent debate over the Catholic Church’s view of the death penalty. While some have argued that John Paul II’s Evangelium Vitae conflicts with Aquinas’s justification of the death penalty, Koritansky argues that according to a Thomistic account of punishment, “public officials do have the right to inflict death but . . . such a right is better not exercised when retribution is the only foreseeable good from such a penalty” (185). Because retribution requires knowledge of the internal dispositions of criminals, knowledge that is for us never absolutely certain, in the extreme case of the death penalty the guilt of the criminal is not itself enough to justify his execution. This interpretation of Aquinas is compatible with a straightforward reading of the Catechism of the Catholic Church as well as John Paul II’s Evangelium Vitae, and it allows for retribution to remain the Book Reviews 305 justificatory core of punishment while nevertheless accepting that today the death penalty is almost never justifiable. Other than a strange and frequent typographical error (random words in almost all the quotations from the Summa Theologiae are italicized for no apparent reason), this is a clear and compelling study, and Koritansky does an excellent job explaining why utilitarian and Kantian theories of punishment (including the unfair advantage theory) are problematic. Let me conclude, however, with two different challenges Koritansky’s account faces: first, many contemporary non-Thomistic accounts of punishment will remain untouched by Koritansky’s criticisms. Utilitarians, for example, have long faced the objection that utilitarianism allows for the sacrifice of the innocent. Many responses have been developed, including denying that practically speaking any such cases will come about (R. M. Hare), admitting the objection and suggesting that our moral intuitions should be revised (Peter Singer), and transforming utilitarianism into a rule-based moral theory (Brad Hooker). Koritansky cannot of course be faulted for not following up on the many branches of utilitarian and Kantian moral theory, but this is a reminder that his readers will most likely be less diverse than he would like, a fact expressed in another way in his final paragraph: “To accept Aquinas’s theory of punishment without removing it from its proper philosophical context requires a reconsideration of moral and political theories, such as natural law and the political dimension of human nature, that by many have long since been considered discredited” (198). Koritansky’s study is a necessary first step, but if the enemy is to be engaged the fight will need to be brought to his own territory. The second challenge arises in response to his arguments against Finnis and the unfair advantage theory. Let us assume, as Koritansky argues, that the political common good is indeed an intrinsic good, and therefore a criminal harms himself in harming the common good. Punishment is retributive (it reestablishes the “equality of justice”) and medicinal (it promotes the good of the criminal and of society more generally). But whereas Finnis explains the “equality of justice” in terms of advantage, Koritansky leaves obscure the precise nature of this equality. Punishment is inflicted within the context of the political order and because that order has been violated in some way. We punish, says Koritansky, because we have a natural desire to protect that order, a desire that makes 306 Book Reviews punishment part of natural law. But once we set aside the medicinal action of punishment, how can we explain the need for retribution? Saying merely that we have a natural desire to protect the common good is not enough, since “protection” refers to the medicinal aspect of punishment and not its retributive aspect. Bentham’s criticism of retributivism is that it is merely revenge, and if the Thomistic account is to avoid this charge it must be clear precisely why retributive punishment is morally good and even morally required aside from its medicinal properties. This is what Finnis’s account accomplishes, though only at the cost of other problems. Koritansky’s account needs to fill out the “equality of justice” such that achieving that equality is an obvious good that would justify punishment without appealing to its medicinal effects. But these challenges are less criticisms of Koritansky than they are indications of where we must go from here. It is a real virtue of Thomas Aquinas and the Philosophy of Punishment that it makes these problems evident and compelling, and future discussion of Aquinas and punishment will need to take Koritansky’s work as an important N&V starting point. Raymond Hain Providence College Providence, RI A Defense of Dignity: Creating Life, Destroying Life, and Protecting the Rights of Conscience by Christopher Kaczor (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2013), x + 220 pp. IN A DEFENSE OF DIGNITY,Christopher Kaczor provides a good introduction to several pressing issues in biomedical ethics, some of which are alluded to in the subtitle: Creating Life, Destroying Life, and Protecting the Rights of Conscience. The book is a collection of articles previously published by Kaczor, now conveniently collected under the rubric of human dignity, a principle that indeed has bearing upon any issue in biomedical ethics. Kaczor begins with a brief discussion of dignity, which he then applies to the question of animal rights. For the remainder of the book he treats topics under the three headings of creating life, destroying life, and conscience. Creating life concerns “fertility treatment,” that is, issues surrounding in vitro fertilization. Destroying Book Reviews 307 life concerns abortion, euthanasia, and organ transplantation. Finally, conscience concerns the right of a doctor to refuse to provide an abortion (or other procedures to which he has a moral objection). Kaczor consistently provides readily accessible arguments in clear concise prose. He tends to use the Napoleonic strategy of giving a little grapeshot, that is, he fires at his opponents with argument piled upon argument, with the surety that something will hit its mark. Some arguments prove stronger than others, but for any particular issue, Kaczor is likely to have at least a number of conclusive points in his favor. In his brief treatment of dignity Kaczor takes on Steven Pinker, the Harvard psychology professor notorious for claiming that man is now kinder and gentler, despite the Holocaust, the Russian genocide of Ukrainians, the Chinese one child policy, and modern organized crime. Pinker entered what might be called the “dignity wars” with the brazen claim that dignity is stupid. He thinks that those who use dignity as a principle in bioethics (especially Catholics) have overlooked obvious features of dignity that undermine their case. Kaczor reveals that Pinker is the one with myopic vision. Pinker’s attack against dignity can equally be turned upon his own favored moral principle of autonomy. Furthermore, Pinker overlooks distinct uses of the word dignity, some of which have little or no bearing upon questions of bioethics. Pinker props up his case by focusing upon these irrelevant meanings, and ignoring the morally significant meaning. Kaczor argues that dignity is rooted in human nature, such that each human being has dignity simply by being human, apart from any accomplishments he might achieve. The most brilliant scientist is equal in human dignity to the Down syndrome individual, or even to someone who is persistently unconscious. These latter individuals retain an orientation toward freedom and reason, even if they are unable to exercise these capacities. In chapter 2, Kaczor argues that human beings are distinctive in their dignity. However clever other animals might prove to be, they are not equal to human beings. He shows that Peter Singer, in arguing against so-called “speciesism,” often relies upon bare assertion, beginning with his definition of speciesism, which is— by stipulation—“prejudice” and “bias”; Singer implies that because racism and sexism are wrong, so “species” becomes wrong by adding the suffix “-ism”; he asserts, without 308 Book Reviews justification, that religious arguments in defense of human dignity are irrelevant; and he falsely attributes to Kant the view that human beings have dignity only insofar as they are actually conscious. In chapters 3, 4, and 5, under the rubric of “creating life,” Kaczor addresses several issues surrounding IVF. He takes on Savulescu, who argues in favor of “procreative beneficence,” which is nearly the contrary of what it sounds: when using IVF, parents have an obligation—so says Savulescu—to select the child who will be best off, which means, in the concrete, that they should choose to have the more intelligent, healthier, and stronger child (as well as, one suspects, the child most disposed to accept the views of Savulescu), and to eliminate—or kill—those children less endowed. It does not bother Savulescu that the idea of killing off the unfit and selecting the fit sounds more than vaguely familiar. Kaczor shows that if Savulescu really believed that parents should always seek a child who is expected to have the most advantageous life, then he would oppose IVF, which leads to higher risks of birth defects; he would also oppose having children outside of wedlock, which leads to a host of complications for children. If Savulescu were really concerned about people being better off, he would devote his efforts toward the relief of poverty, which has a much better chance of improving conditions than the exorbitantly expensive and ineffective IVF. Chapter 5 presents one of the few issues over which this reviewer must part ways with Kaczor. He defends so-called embryo adoption, in which a woman has an embryo (conceived by IVF) implanted in her womb, in the hope of bringing the child to term. The woman has not herself conceived the child; that was done (unethically) by someone else, and the child is a “spare,” left over after a couple has had all the children they want. Embryo adoption is an attempt to save the lives of these children from the limbo of deep freeze. A noble goal, no doubt. The question is whether implanting a child in one’s womb is a morally reprehensible act, despite the great good one hopes to achieve by it. Kaczor adeptly addresses many of the objections raised against this adoptive implantation, but I fear he may have begged the question by defining “procreation” as simply creating new human life and not as “impregnating.” This is the very question that must be resolved. Chapters 6, 7, and 8 concern various issues surrounding abortion. Kaczor takes on the infamous violinist argument of Judith Jarvis Thom- Book Reviews 309 son, in which pregnancy is compared to the state of being hooked up, involuntarily, to a violinist, who needs your kidneys to stay alive for nine months. In such a situation, argues Thompson, you surely have a right to disconnect the violinist rather than undergo the inconvenience of being continually hooked up to him. In this argument, abortion is treated not so much as killing the baby as it is disconnecting the baby, with the consequence that he dies. Kaczor picks apart the various attempts to justify this right to disconnect the baby. If this right is based upon bodily integrity (such that one should never be forced to donate a kidney), then we must also consider the bodily integrity of the baby. Furthermore, the argument is based upon an unrealistically dim view of what a mother must undergo during pregnancy. Most essentially, the idea that an abortion involves removing a baby with the side effect of death ignores the reality of what happens in the act of abortion in the world today. Quite simply, the baby is cut up or otherwise physically attacked; there are no shades of merely permitting death. Chapters 9 and 10 address euthanasia. Kaczor tackles Tristam Engelhardt, the former Catholic become Antiochian Orthodox, who maintains an extreme form of fideism. He upholds the correct conclusion concerning euthanasia—we are not allowed to put people to death even if they wish it—but he denies that human reason alone can reach this conclusion; we know it by faith alone. Kaczor shows that faith itself, as revealed in the Scriptures, teaches that reason can attain moral truths. Furthermore, theology does not answer all questions, leaving room for philosophy in our moral understanding. Indeed, theology—including the theology of Engelhardt—inevitably presupposes some philosophy. Finally, an honest appraisal of philosophical arguments concerning euthanasia reveals that they can conclude to the moral truth that euthanasia is unacceptable. Chapter 11 concerns the practice of organ donation after cardiac death. In this case, cardiac death is contrasted to brain death. Because of a shortage of organs, the transplant community has searched for new sources, and they have turned to the practice of disconnecting an individual from life support, waiting for his heart to stop beating, waiting another two minutes (or so), and then cutting him open to retrieve his organs. Kaczor calls into question (correctly, it seems) the widespread 310 Book Reviews acceptance of brain death as the true death of the individual. Medical evidence indicates that an individual can maintain his integrity long after his brain has died. Kaczor is also skeptical about donation after cardiac death, as currently practiced. He thinks there might be some room for it, however, if the practice is modified. It seems unlikely that the individual is dead only two minutes after his heart stops beating; something like twenty to thirty minutes seems more realistic. The trouble is that after such an extended time the organs are often unusable. Consequently, Kaczor recommends injecting the individual with certain organ preserving drugs prior to his death (a recommendation that raises ethical issues of its own). Then the organs might be still viable after twenty minutes. Chapters 12 and 13 focus upon conscientious objection, primarily to the practice of abortion. There seems to be a concerted effort to force doctors to perform abortions, or short of that, at least to refer patients to doctors who will perform an abortion. The American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, for instance, maintains that patients have a right to demand a treatment, so that doctors should be obliged to comply with this demand. Kaczor points out that patients do not have the right to demand all and any treatments. The wishes of those with bodily integrity identity disorder, for instance, who wish to have some healthy limb removed, should not be complied with. Too often arguments against conscientious objection presume the very conclusion they wish to reach, namely, that abortion is a central part of what it means to be a physician. Those physicians who conscientiously object are claiming precisely the reverse: it is essential to a physician to refuse to perform an abortion. I have presented only a brief sample of the many topics that Kaczor covers. He also addresses the following topics: the idea that everyone should have equal access to fertility treatment; the thorny question of treatments of ectopic pregnancy; the ethics of fetal surgery; and artificial nutrition for patients in so-called persistent vegetative state. For a wide variety of topics in bioethics, then, Kaczor’s collection (which would be very useful in a college bioethics course) provides a good introduction, relying upon sound ethical principles, grounded in human dignity. The book does not probe to the underlying source of these principles (Kaczor has done that elsewhere), which would be out of Book Reviews 311 place at an introductory level, but it does provide sound argumentation in defense of the dignity of human individuals, which dignity is, sadly, too often attacked in our world today. Kaczor has done a service for all of us confronted with the perplexities of modern bioethics. N&V Steven J. Jensen University of St. Thomas Houston, Texas Sacrifice as Gift: Eucharist, Grace, and Contemplative Prayer in Maurice de la Taille by Michon M. Matthiesen (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2013), xiii + 320 pp. UNTIL THE LATE 1960sor so, when they went to church on Sun- days, Catholics offered the sacrifice of the Mass. Then, some time in the 70s or 80s, when they went to church they “offered the sacrifice” of the Mass. They stopped doing something real, and started doing something symbolic. They stopped doing something real by way of signifying the reality, and started enacting an elaborate metaphor. If Michon Matthiesen has her way, we will drop the quotation marks, hear the Eucharistic teaching of Paul VI and his successors with unarched eyebrows, speak concordantly with the fathers, and once again start doing something on Sundays. We will offer the Sacrifice. That is, I think, the most important consequence her recent monograph on the Eucharistic theology of Maurice de la Taille could have. Maurice de la Taille (1872–1933) entered the Jesuits in 1890. After the First World War, he taught at the Gregorian University until 1930. His great work, Mysterium Fidei, runs to 773 double columned imperial octavo pages in its last edition (1934; 1st ed., 1921). Henri de Lubac describes it as “an essay in the liquidation of the over-complicated systems worked out in modern times, indeed ever since the Council of Trent, about the sacrifice of the Mass.” Understood in this way, its aim was remarkably similar to Anscar Vonier’s A Key to the Doctrine of the Eucharist (1925) or Charles Journet’s La Messe: Présence du Sacrifice de la Croix (1957), an English edition of which appeared in 2008. English translations of the first two of the three “books” or parts of Mysterium Fidei were published in 1940 and 1950, but it seems to have had little impact in the last fifty years in English language theology. Matthiesen aims 312 Book Reviews to change that, to recover a way of speaking about the Eucharist that was consigned after the council to the rubbish bin or at any rate abandoned. She begins with de la Taille’s understanding of sacrifice in a Thomist framework, an understanding that integrates Scripture and the Fathers, as well as observations from modern sociology and the history of religions. In this respect, it provides a sort of model of theological method, where authorities are appreciated according to their relation, proper or extraneous, to theology. Sacrifice is the premier exterior exercise of religion, visibly signifying both the worship exclusively due to God (latreia) and propitiation for sin. The visible signification includes both an offering of a gift and its immolation or destruction, though these can be separated in time: the offering is either coincident with immolation, or offers an already immolated or a to-be-immolated gift. The gift is not a victim without immolation. Immolation connotes the painful, mortifying aspect of sacrifice, and so its second motivation, propitiation. Here, de la Taille is strong, for such self-denial is necessarily signified when worship is given by self-centered, sinful men. Such creatures cannot justly worship God without acknowledging their culpable unworthiness even to address him. Together with worship, there are also petitionary and thankful motivations for sacrifice, and these come to further visible expression in the acceptance of the sacrifice by and the return sharing of benefits from God. Sacrifice is not accomplished unless accepted, and it is not accepted unless the good God both forgives and blesses. The blessing in its visibility consists most typically in the communion banquet, and in this way, de la Taille acknowledges the “meal theory” of sacrifice. All of this is a welcome reintroduction of the older discourse on sacrifice known to Western theology, at least since the time of St. Augustine. The next two chapters take up the more controversial aspects of de la Taille’s Eucharistic theology, as his analysis of sacrifice is deployed for understanding the sacrifice of Christ and the sacrifice of the Church. First, there is his thesis that the Supper and Cross form one sacrificial act, wherein the Supper enacts Christ’s offering of himself, and the Cross compasses his willing immolation. The unity of the Supper and the Cross is supported by patristic and liturgical witness, and de la Taille does not think that Session 22 of Trent requires a numerical distinction between the sacrifice of the Supper and the sacrifice of the Cross. He Book Reviews 313 wants to include the oblation of the Supper in a single action of sacrifice extending to the Cross, since the Supper is necessary to declare fully and exactly the interior intention of the Lord’s submission to death. Further, since priest and victim are the very same at the Supper and the Cross, differing only in the actuality but not the promise of the immolation, the question of multiplying sacrifices does not even arise. The second thesis, that of the eternality of the Lord’s sacrifice, acts similarly to explain how the Church’s sacrifice is empowered by the sacrifice of the Cross; it makes the sacrifice of the Mass strictly dependent on the sacrifice of the Cross. The Father’s acceptance of the victim of Calvary in the resurrection and ascension of the Lord means that he is present eternally as victim in the heavenly sanctuary. This does not imply for de la Taille any new celestial action by the Head of the Body, but it does make the victim of Calvary available to be offered in the many Masses of his members. The first and third parts of Matthiesen’s book work well together, since, as she claims, de la Taille’s understanding of contemplative prayer and baptism shows how he situates the Eucharist within Christian life as a whole. Worthy offering of the sacrifice of the Mass depends on our own willingness to die to self and live to God, and the spiritual good of our reception of communion depends also on our interior attitudes, on the devotion with which we welcome the benefits of the sacrifice. But the same pattern of interior acts is also at work in Christian prayer and contemplation. In passive contemplation, especially, there is a marked ascetical parallel to the self-denial involved in the propitiatory aspect of the Mass, and the union of the mystic with God replays in another key sacramental union with God in communion. Prayer and the sacramental life do not only delimit parallel trajectories, but also (in a non-Euclidian geometry!) converge on each other. De la Taille also insists that baptism includes a promise of our self-denial and education of desire after the pattern of Christ, a promise that we cannot fulfil without living from and toward the Eucharistic celebration. I wish Matthiesen had confined herself to these two and truly complementary parts of de la Taille’s thought. In the second part of her book, however, she undertakes to explain his theology of the Hypostatic Union, of sanctifying grace, and of the beatific vision by way of expounding his account of how uncreated Act gives itself to created reality (the humanity 314 Book Reviews of Christ, the soul of the Christian, or the justified mind in heaven) in a created actuation of the same. She claims that this contested metaphysical speculation is in fact systematically connected with his theology of Eucharistic sacrifice and sacrament, but she does not show that it is. Moreover, it leads her into territory in which she soon becomes lost. She begins by explaining de la Taille’s remarks on the habitual grace of Christ—the grace that the Eucharist gives us to share in—in Book Three of Mysterium Fidei, and so is led to explicate his distinction between pure and mixed perfections. Pure perfections are things like being and intellection. Mixed perfections include some potency in their definition, like rationality. They perforce have their highest instance beneath God (infra Deum—not “in God,” as Matthiesen has it). Sanctifying grace, since it bespeaks inherence in a subject to which it is not owed, and therefore a nature that is composed with potency, is a mixed perfection. She finds a text in de la Taille at this point that proves, she supposes, that he would have stood with Henri de Lubac on the relation of nature and grace. Here is her rendering: “Now [the pure natural perfection] is so from the nobility of grace, by which such goodness is brought in, so that every natural perfection whatsoever is always supernatural and gratuitous, marking therefore the unworthiness of the subject.” The identification of the subject in brackets is Matthiesen’s. She finds here “a robust statement against the notion of ‘pure nature’” (168). The statement is robust, if contradictions can be so, but it is not de la Taille’s. What she is translating is in italics in the following and fuller citation from Mysterium Fidei. Ne quis autem stomachetur, quod (1) intellectio naturalis potest progredi in infinitum, gratia autem non ita; aut quod (2) in perfectionibus mixtis recensetur gratia, cum inter puras [perfectiones] multae numerentur naturales. Hoc alterum enim ex nobilitate est gratiae, qua tantum importatur bonum, ut omni perfectioni cuilibet naturali semper sit supernaturale seu indebitum, connotans igitur subjecti indignitatem. Primum autem in laudem gratiae pariter redundat (520b) Book Reviews 315 Let no one be disturbed (1) that natural intellection can make progress unlimitedly but that grace cannot do so; or (2) that grace is counted among mixed perfections, although there are many natural perfections that are counted among pure perfections. For this second thing is from the from the nobility of grace, by which so great a good is introduced such that it is always supernatural or unowed relative to every natural perfection whatsoever, so connoting the unworthiness of the subject. But the first thing likewise redounds to the praise of grace Matthiesen wants de la Taille (who died in 1933, remember) to have the cachet of belonging to the “new theologians,” who came to prominence as such in the late 1940s. This leads her to make him say something that neither he, nor de Lubac, nor any Catholic theologian whatsoever could possibly have said in the first half of the last century. Such a lapse raises questions. Matthiesen’s book began as a dissertation. Did the director of her dissertation and her readers at Boston College see this translation? What of CUA Press, the editorial board, and those engaged to review her manuscript? To be sure, an author takes responsibility for his own work, but it looks like Matthiesen has been very ill served by her mentors and publisher. In the 1950s and 60s, Prudentius de Letter, S.J., explained and defended de la Taille’s theory of created actuation by uncreated Act. In Matthiesen’s bibliography and text, he has unaccountably become “Prudence de Letter.” There are also many other errors and solecisms a copy editor should have caught. But let us end on a happier note, in gratitude that Matthiesen has made audible once again an important voice in twentieth-century sacramental theology. Here is how she gives us to understand with de la Taille how the great Sacrifice takes up our smaller sacrifices: when the smallest acts and efforts to direct one’s life and love to God are lifted up and exhibited to God in the ecclesial sacrifice, when they are conjoined with devotio to the external ritual offering of Christ’s sacrifice, then not only do they invest this ecclesial oblation with truth and sincerity, but they also are themselves transformed into “wine” and share in the liberating efficacy of the cross. 316 Book Reviews This is the theology of sacrifice, realist, sober, both heavenly and down to earth, that will serve us for the next, and every, century. N&V Guy Mansini, O.S.B. Saint Meinrad Seminary St. Meinrad, IN Jesus and the Demise of Death: Resurrection, Afterlife, and the Fate of the Christian by Matthew Levering (Waco, TX: Baylor University Press, 2012), x + 228 pp. WITH JESUS AND THE DEMISE OF DEATH, Matthew Lever- ing offers another excellent and thought-provoking contribution. This time, his topic is Christian eschatology. As outlined in the Introduction, Levering sets out to provide a contemporary statement of classic Christian eschatology, “a theology of resurrection and eternal life” (1), which simultaneously highlights its biblical foundations and (to a lesser extent) defends the tradition’s subordinate use of Greek philosophical concepts to explicate the substance of biblical teaching. Similar to his other works, Levering makes his case dialogically by putting various theological thinkers (past and present) into conversation with Thomas Aquinas. The book is divided into two major sections concerning respectively “Jesus’ passage” from death to glorified life and “the Church’s passage” (2). This structural division itself reflects a key concern of the book: the passage of Jesus from death to glorified life with the Father is the cause of the Church’s own passage into eternity. The first section—“The Passage of Jesus Christ” (13)—comprises three chapters. Chapter 1 takes up Jesus’s descent among the dead and the so-called intermediate state between death and resurrection. Levering uses Aquinas’s account of Holy Saturday, wherein Jesus’s soul enters the intermediate state and vindicates the deceased righteous of Israel by his Passion, to strike a middle ground between N. T. Wright’s “otherworldly portrait of inactive sameness” (26) in the intermediate state and “the fully historicized accounts of Christ’s damnation [i.e., Balthasar] or Christ’s preaching in the intermediate state [i.e., Clement, Athanasius, et al.]” (22). Book Reviews 317 The eschatological nature of Jesus’s Resurrection is the subject of chapter 2. Here Levering brings Aquinas into conversation with Jon Levenson and N. T. Wright. He tracks out lines of convergence between these three thinkers, who all treat the topic of resurrection (albeit in different ways and contexts) under the heading of eschatology and in connection with the ultimate vindication of the people of God. Chapter 3 concerns Jesus’s “ascending in his glorified flesh to the right hand of the Father” (43). This chapter treats a variety of issues related to Jesus’s being at the Father’s right hand, including the bodiliness of the God of Israel (in light of the work of Mark Smith and Benjamin Sommer), the exegetical use of philosophy to identify when Scripture speaks metaphorically, and the theological significance of Jesus as being “at the Father’s right hand.” Levering argues that this expression signifies Jesus’s sharing fully in God’s power and glory in his glorified humanity and his continuing action on behalf of his Church to bring her to eschatological fulfillment with him. The major section of the book—“The Passage of Christ’s People” (61)—comprises four chapters. In chapter 4, Levering discusses the eschatological nature of the Church’s life in the world on the basis of New Testament testimony. Drawing largely (although not exclusively) on the summary statements in Acts 2:42–47 and 4:32–35, Levering identifies three markers of the Church as an eschatological community: devotion to the apostolic teaching and fellowship (i.e., faith), the Eucharist, and the sharing of possessions (i.e., charity and almsgiving). Levering then explores the eschatological dimensions of these three markers in Aquinas’s theology. On the basis of this analysis, Levering concludes, “The central eschatological reality is that we live already in union with Jesus and we allow our passage to be configured to his” (83). Before turning to the passage of the blessed into heavenly glory (chapter 7), Levering takes up two attendant issues: whether and in what sense Christians can “merit” eternal life (chapter 5) and the existence of a human spiritual soul on both philosophical and biblical grounds (chapter 6). With regard to merit, Levering summarizes the work of Gary Anderson to show that merit is a thoroughly biblical category, and he then develops Anderson’s work theologically with Aquinas. Following Aquinas, Levering argues that any consideration of Christians’ merit must presuppose God’s prior, unmerited action to justify sinners and in- 318 Book Reviews corporate them into Jesus’s own life and merits of his Passion. Regarding merit, Levering concludes, “the action of the Holy Spirit in us enables us to merit this reward [of eternal life] in justice, not because we have become self-sufficient, but because God rewards his work in us” (94). With regard to the topic of the human spiritual soul, Levering defends the existence of the soul against Nancey Murphy’s denial by employing the Thomistic account of the soul as the form of the body and (following W. Norris Clarke) “a formal cause” (101) for the brain’s neurological activity. On biblical grounds, Levering responds to Joel Green’s denial that the New Testament teaches the existence of a spiritual soul, which survives bodily death. While New Testament authors do not provide a well-developed account of a spiritual soul, Levering argues, many authors and texts (e.g., Mt 10:28; Lk 23:43; 2 Cor 5:1–8; Phil 1:21–24) do “include certain anthropological assumptions and claims” (107) that imply the existence of a human soul that passes through death into the intermediate state. The implications of such New Testament texts invite further theological and philosophical thinking on the topic, which is exactly what early and medieval Christians did by means of appropriating Greek philosophical reasoning. Chapter 7 takes up the general resurrection of the dead, the purification and renewal of creation, the beatific vision, and the state of glorified humanity. Levering returns the tripartite typology of the Church as an eschatological community (faith in the apostolic teaching, the Eucharist, and almsgiving) to show how these markers reach fulfillment respectively in the beatific vision, the renewal of material creation into a cosmic liturgy, and the state of glorified human nature as being for others and shining “with glory in accordance with the person’s degree of self-giving love” (123). The book ends with a brief conclusion about the importance of Christian eschatology and hope for life in the present world. Levering makes an illuminating and persuasive case for the biblical character and abiding value of traditional Christian eschatology. Although the body of the text is less than 130 pages, Jesus and the Demise of Death interweaves biblical, theological, and philosophical elements into an intricate, theologically sophisticated synthesis. In doing so, Levering once again showcases marvelously the enduring vitality and biblical shape of Thomas Aquinas’s theology. He creatively uses Aquinas, showing how his thought can encompass, correct, and integrate many Book Reviews 319 modern insights into a fruitful theological account. It is a showcase example of “Ressourcement Thomism.” Two things, which are not included in this book, come to mind as ways to enhance Levering’s accomplishment. First, Levering’s treatment of Jesus’s Resurrection and Ascension delves a good bit into their biblical dimensions. But he does not consider the complex array of New Testament evidence concerning Jesus’s exaltation to heaven. As Pierre Benoit has shown, while the New Testament gives consistent witness that the risen Jesus has been exalted to heaven, there are differences (though not contradictions) over how that exaltation is parsed vis-à-vis what is traditionally called the Ascension: the event narrated in Acts 1:6–12.1 The complexity of the situation is highlighted by considering when different New Testament authors locate the risen Jesus’s entrance into glory. For instance, the conclusion of the Gospel of Luke (similar to the Gospel of John) locates Jesus’s entrance into heavenly glory as following right upon his Resurrection on Easter Sunday (Lk 24:50–51; cf. Jn 20:17). By contrast, in Acts 1, Luke narrates the Ascension of Jesus as an event (1:6–12), which he locates forty days after Easter (1:3). Admittedly, Levering’s interests in Jesus’s sitting at the Father’s right hand lie elsewhere than a parsing of New Testament evidence or “when” the risen Jesus took his place at the Father’s right hand. Nevertheless, the New Testament provides a complicated body of evidence for thinking about this mystery, some further consideration of which could help fill out the theological picture.11 A second area concerns the cumulative character of Levering’s theological exposition. Structurally, the book holds together well, first charting out Jesus’s passage into the Father’s glory and then that of the Church by virtue of her sharing in Jesus’s own passage. The book comes to its thematically appropriate conclusion with a discussion of the beatific vision and the heavenly glory of the blessed. But given Levering’s dialogical approach and very unassuming prose, one can overlook (or underappreciate) the intricacies of the account that he works out cumulatively over the course of the whole book. A concluding chapter that 1 Pierre Benoit, O.P., “The Ascension,” in Jesus and the Gospel, 2 vols., trans. Benet Weatherhead (New York: Herder and Herder, 1973 [1961]), 1.209–253; reprinted from Revue Biblique (1949): 161–203. 320 Book Reviews brings together the different components of Levering’s account into a single, synthetic statement would be a welcome addition in this regard. These concerns notwithstanding, Levering has accomplished much in making a strong case for traditional, biblically founded Christian N&V eschatology. William M. Wright IV Duquesne University Pittsburgh, PA