et Vetera Nova Fall 2016 • Volume 14, Number 4 The English Edition of the International Theological Journal Senior Editor Georges Cardinal Cottier, O.P.† Co-Editors Matthew Levering, Mundelein Seminary Thomas Joseph White, O.P., Dominican House of Studies Associate Editors Holly Taylor Coolman, Providence College Gilles Emery, O.P., University of Fribourg Paul Gondreau, Providence College Scott W. Hahn, Franciscan University of Steubenville Thomas S. Hibbs, Baylor University Reinhard Hütter, Duke University Divinity School Christopher Malloy, University of Dallas Bruce D. Marshall, Southern Methodist University Charles Morerod, O.P., Bishop of Lausanne, Geneva, and Fribourg John O’Callaghan, University of Notre Dame Chad C. Pecknold, Catholic University of America Michael S. Sherwin, O.P., University of Fribourg Board of Advisors Anthony Akinwale, O.P., Dominican Institute, Ibadan, Nigeria Khaled Anatolios, University of Notre Dame Robert Barron, Auxiliary Bishop of Los Angeles, CA John Betz, University of Notre Dame Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P., Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas Christopher O. Blum, Augustine Institute Stephen Brock, Pontifical University of the Holy Cross Peter Casarella, University of Notre Dame Romanus Cessario, O.P., St. John’s Seminary Boyd Taylor Coolman, Boston College Archbishop J. Augustine Di Noia, O.P., Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith Douglas Farrow, McGill University Anthony Fisher, O.P., Archbishop of Sydney, Australia Simon Francis Gaine, O.P., Blackfriars, University of Oxford Timothy Gray, Augustine Institute Nicholas J. Healy, Jr., Pontifical John Paul II Institute (Washington, DC) Russell Hittinger, University of Tulsa Paige Hochschild, Mount St. Mary’s University Andrew Hofer, O.P., Dominican House of Studies Joseph Lienhard, S.J., Fordham University Steven A. Long, Ave Maria University Guy Mansini, O.S.B., Saint Meinrad School of Theology Francesca Aran Murphy, University of Notre Dame Thomas Osborne, University of St. Thomas (Houston) Michał Paluch, O.P., Dominican House of Studies Trent Pomplun, Loyola University Maryland Christopher J. Ruddy, Catholic University of America Richard Schenk, O.P., University of Eichstätt Michele Schumacher, University of Fribourg Janet Smith, Sacred Heart Major Seminary Christopher Thompson, St. Paul Seminary Thomas Weinandy, O.F.M. Cap., Dominican House of Studies William Wright, Duquesne University Instructions for Contributors 1. Address all contributions, books for review, and related correspondence to Matthew Levering, mjlevering@yahoo.com. 2. Contributions should be prepared to accord as closely as possible with the typographical conventions of Nova et Vetera. The University of Chicago Manual of Style (16th edition) is our authority on matters of style. 3. Nova et Vetera practices blind review. Submissions are evaluated anonymously by members of the editorial board and other scholars with appropriate expertise. Name, affiliation, and contact information should be included on a separate page apart from the submission. 4. Galley-proofs of articles are sent to contributors to be read and corrected and should be returned to the Editors within ten days of receipt. Corrections should be confined to typographical and factual errors. 5. Submission of a manuscript entails the author’s agreement (in the event his or her contribution is accepted for publication) to assign the copyright to Nova et Vetera. Nova et Vetera The English Edition of the International Theological Journal ISSN 1542-7315 Fall 2016 Vol. 14, No. 4 In Memoriam of Cardinal Cottier. . . . . . Most Rev. Charles Morerod, O.P. 1049 Commentary Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. 1051 A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology in the New Evangelization. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Khaled Anatolios 1067 Liturgy and Vocation. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Michael Heintz 1083 The Seminary and Western Culture: Relationships that Promote Recovery and Holiness. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . James Keating 1099 Articles Aquinas on the Spirit’s Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. 1113 Freedom and Heteronomy: Maximus the Confessor and the Question of Moral Creativity. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Adam G. Cooper 1133 Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy: Revisiting a Continuator of Thomas Aquinas. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Domenic D’Ettore 1153 Creation ad imaginem Dei: The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory.. . . . . . . . . . . . . . Steven A. Long 1175 Alimentum Pacis: The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas.. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . John Meinert 1193 God, the University, and Human Flourishing. . . . . . . Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. 1213 Brain Death and Organ Removal: Revisiting a High-Stakes Question. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Bernard N. Schumacher 1239 Review Essays Christology in Context: Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White, O.P., The Incarnate Lord: A Thomistic Study in Christology. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Guy Mansini, O.S.B. 1271 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization: Hahn and Wiker’s Unmasking of Historical Criticism’s Political Agenda by Laying Bare its Philosophical Roots. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Jeffrey L. Morrow 1293 Book Reviews The Philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas: A Sketch by Stephen L. Brock.. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Christopher O. Blum 1341 Healing for Freedom: A Christian Perspective on Personhood and Psychotherapy by †Benedict M. Ashley, O.P... . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Ryan Connors 1345 The Gospel of the Family: Going Beyond Cardinal Kasper’s Proposal in the Debate on Marriage, Civil Re-Marriage, and Communion in the Church by Juan José Pérez-Soba and Stephan Kampowski. . . . . . . Marek J. Duran 1349 Memory in Augustine’s Theological Anthropology by Paige E. Hochschild. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Jared Ortiz 1353 Nature and Grace: A New Approach to Thomistic Ressourcement by Andrew Dean Swafford. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Matthew J. Ramage 1357 Irenaeus of Lyons: Identifying Christianity by John Behr.. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . W. Brian Shelton 1364 The English edition of Nova et Vetera is published quarterly and provides an international forum for theological and philosophical studies from a Thomistic perspective. Founded in 1926 by future Cardinal Charles Journet in association with Jacques Maritain, Nova et Vetera is published in related, distinct French and English editions. The English edition of Nova et Vetera welcomes articles and book reviews in theology, philosophy, and biblical studies that address central contemporary debates and discussions. We seek to be “at the heart of the Church,” faithful to the Magisterium and the teachings of the Second Vatican Council, and devoted to the work of true dialogue, both ecumenically and across intellectual disciplines. Nova et Vetera (ISSN 1542-7315; ISBN 978-1-945125-05-8) is published quarterly by St. Paul Center for Biblical Theology, 1468 Parkview Circle, Steubenville, OH 43952. Nova et Vetera is distributed to institutional subscribers for the St. Paul Center by the Catholic University of America Press. All materials published in Nova et Vetera are copyrighted by St. Paul Center for Biblical Theology. © Copyright 2016 by St. Paul Center for Biblical Theology. All rights reserved. POSTMASTER: Please send address change to Nova et Vetera, 1468 Parkview Circle, Steubenville, OH 43952. Periodical Postage Paid at Steubenville, OH. This periodical is indexed in the ATLA Catholic Periodical and Literature Index® (CPLI®), a product of the American Theological Library Association, 300 S. Wacker Dr., Suite 2100, Chicago, IL 60606, USA. Email: atla@atla.com, www.atla.com. Nova et Vetera Subscription Rates: • Individuals: one-year $40.00, two-year $75.00 International: one-year $60.00, two-year $115.00 • Students: one-year $30.00, two-year $50.00 International: one-year $40.00, two-year $70.00 • Colleges, Universities, Seminaries, and Institutions: one-year $110.00, two-year $205.00 International: one-year $130.00, two-year $245.00 To subscribe online, please visit http://www.nvjournal.net. For subscription inquiries, email us at novaetvetera@stpaulcenter.com or phone 740-264-9535. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1049–1050 In Memoriam of Cardinal Cottier Most Rev. Charles Morerod, O.P. Bishop of Lausanne, Genève et Fribourg On March 31, 2016 , Cardinal Georges Cottier (whom every- one continued to call “Father Cottier”), the director of Nova et Vetera since the death of Cardinal Journet in 1975, died unexpectedly from a pulmonary embolism less than a month before his ninety-fourth birthday. For his friends, he was an always available source of light, absolutely sharp until his dying day, so that one never truly imagined that he could pass away. The readers of Nova et Vetera are in profound mourning, illumined by hope. This mourning touches not only our readers but also the innumerable and widely varied persons who have always been able to benefit from his listening and from his wisdom. In Nova et Vetera’s April–June 1975 issue, Father Cottier said with regard to Cardinal Journet: “Until the last moment . . . he worked for Nova et Vetera.” What Father Cottier said about the founder and first director (1926–1975) of our journal is true also of its second director (1975–2016). Both of them showed, in this beautiful work, their passion for truth and their love of human beings, in whom it is necessary to stir up a thirst for truth that is desire for God. Both of them enjoyed the grace of retaining their whole power of mind— their great mind—until their final day, and this grace of theirs was given also for us: we give thanks to the Lord! In the brief announcement of the death of Cardinal Journet, Father Cottier also said: Moreover, Cardinal Journet never retired from Nova et Vetera. . . . A forthcoming issue of Nova et Vetera will try to give an idea of the richness and fecundity of an oeuvre that is considerable both in quantity and in quality. If our sorrow is great, 1050 Most Rev. Charles Morerod, O.P. we remain at peace, because of the light that our beloved father and teacher has left us. And without doubt it is not rash to think that from his “eternal Country,” to which he so greatly aspired, he continues to assist us. I am certain that I am not alone in thinking that this text applies henceforth also to its author (even to a practical point: the next issue of the Swiss edition of Nova et Vetera will be devoted to him). As I have said and will say again, I wish for the beatification of our two successive directors. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1051–1065 Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P.* In the years that bring us to the second millennium, the Church is called to the great task of the new evangelization. The impulse of the Holy Spirit leads it by a road plagued with challenges: the Gospel must be announced not just to those who ignore it but also to those who try to forget it or have already done so. It has to be proclaimed without ceasing to bring us to deepen our commitment to Christ. For the new evangelization, the evangelizers themselves have to be evangelized. The encounter with Christ and full adherence to His Person are based on faith, initium salutis. If faith is a gift from God, it is important to prepare for it and resolve the doubts that are an obstacle to receiving it, and once adhering to this faith, we must not cease, with the help of God, to believe in it. So, in our preparation for the tasks that are offered to us, the living examples of a lived faith and holiness are an essential aid. And one such example is a saint of our day, St. Josemaría Escrivá. Reflecting on certain aspects of his spirituality, we will try to draw some applicable conclusions to the apostolate of faith in the context of the new evangelization. Steps: to be resigned to the will of God; to conform to the will of God; to want the will of God; to love the will of God.1 * Trans. John Martin Ruiz, O.P., from “La oración y la estructura fundamental de la fe,” in Santidad y Mundo: Actas del Simposio Teológico de estudio en torno a las enseñanzas del beato Josemaría Escrivá, Roma, 12–14 de octubre de 1993, ed. Manuel Belda (Pamplona, ES: EUNSA, 1996), 91–108. 1 Josemaría Escrivá, The Way (New York: Scepter, 2002), no.774. 1052 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. And before: Resignation? . . . Conformity? Love the will of God! 2 Meditating on faith in the spirituality of St. Escrivá, we can start with this thought that, with few lapidary formulas, describes the path of holiness lived by the saint himself and taught to his sons and daughters. Indeed, his own life is an example of a constant availability to the will of God, sought with all his soul. When this will takes the form of the Cross and draws from him wailings that might seem reproaches to God, immediately, with a sort of spontaneous reflex, he responds with total acceptance so that the deep peace that dwells in him is never destroyed. According to the spiritual tradition rooted in the heart of the Gospel and illustrated particularly by the Way of Perfection of Teresa of Avila, the love of the Father finds its concrete and everyday realization in the search of God’s will, the object of the third petition of the Our Father: thy will be done on earth as it is in heaven. And, indeed, the will of God is communicated to us through the moral conscience enlightened by faith and the promptings of the Holy Spirit. The judgments of conscience later remit the specific actions that we must carry through or, otherwise, avoid. However, if you attach to the word “action” such a broad meaning that it also includes internal attitudes, conscience asks us often for a reaction, an acceptance of the events that make up the fabric of our existence and that we have chosen or, on the contrary, we would have preferred to reject. To each individual are presented events or outside demands that repel or cost him much. This set of circumstances that do not depend on us and are integrated into our lives should be forewarned with the eyes of faith. Which leads us to a triple certainty: God’s Providence is omnipotent, embraces all things; all things work for good for those who love God (see Rom 8:28); and the Father’s will is a will that loves us. “For this is the will of God, your sanctification” (see 1 Thess 4:3). Sanctification, in turn, passes by way of participation in the Cross of Jesus. Union with God is a filial relationship in the Only Son; and Christian prayer, which expresses this relationship with the Father, has as its source the depths of the same Holy Spirit, according to the Ibid., no. 757. 2 Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1053 puzzling words of Paul to the Romans and Galatians: “For those who are led by the Spirit of God are children of God. In fact, you did not receive a spirit of slavery to fall back into fear, but you received a spirit of adoption, through which we cry: ‘Abba, Father!’ For the Spirit itself bears witness with our spirit that we are children of God. And if children then heirs; heirs of God, and joint heirs with Christ; if only we suffer with him so that we may also be glorified with him” (see Rom 8:14–17; cf. Rom 8:26–30; see Gal 4:4–7). The thought that we have transcribed obtains its entire dimension in light of this great Pauline text. The mystery of filial adoption by grace, which shapes our identity as baptized, is at the core of the spirituality of Josemaría Escrivá. Such filiation, which above all has an ontological meaning, must become transformed into life, must be lived through the exercise of the Christian virtues, among which stand out the theological virtues. And it comes to be fully life when there is a perfect union of one’s will with the will of the Father. The union, the fusion of the will, defines love and, in our case, the supernatural love of charity. But this same love presupposes that each direct his life in the light of faith. There are times when life brings setbacks, illnesses, disappointments, sufferings, trials, or also demands of sacrifices that seem to be beyond our strength. How to recognize in all this the sign of the goodness of our Father in heaven? It can then be understood why loving God’s will is an expression of holiness but also how, to reach such identification, you have to go a long way. To resign oneself to the will of God: more than once this expression has been used to indicate acceptance of the divine will. But resignation is only a first step, a procedure still very imperfect. It means that one has conquered a first movement of rebellion; but the one who resigns himself adopts an external attitude as regards the will of God. His will does not surrender to God; rather he suffers, he gives way as does the weak relative to the strong. His attitude is more servile than filial. If it depended on him, things would have been arranged differently. However, he has conquered rebellion in himself. And this can be a first step forward. To conform oneself to the divine will: This is a new development. There is submission to the will of God because the soul adopts a religious attitude, informed by the virtue of religion about God. His Lordship is recognized; one stands as the servant in relation to the Master. This compliance may already be a great and noble attitude. 1054 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. But the human will and the divine will still do not come together perfectly. The human will does not entirely allow itself to be caught; there is still a remnant of exteriority. The divine will presents itself in the form of fate, of necessity; it is not yet the Father’s will. We could bring up the great school of the Stoics; and there has even been talk of a Christian stoicism. However, one has taken a step further, because the attitude is essentially religious. To want the will of God: this step is superior in perfection, as it implies, on the part of the human will, an active, positive moment of going out to meet God’s will. However, it is possible that, as did the previous one, this attitude derives from the virtue of religion, configuring itself as the ending of this natural virtue. The virtue of religion is the most perfect of the moral virtues, but it is not a theological virtue. To love the will of God. Certainly, to love is to want. But not just any desire for the will of God is set to love in the sense used here, which is the supernatural love of charity. To love the will of God is typical of he who lives the grace of divine filiation and moves with his whole being, with the burning flame of his love, to meet what God wants, for such a will is the will of the Father and, thus, is a supremely lovable will. In such love of the Father’s will is fully carried out to term the sequela Christi, conformity with the offering of Jesus in the Garden of Gethsemane: “Yet, not as I will, but as you will” (Matt 26:39). Such love, as shown by Jesus’s offering, can be heroic; it can even lead to immolation and the sacrifice of the self. Therefore, if the love of God’s will represents the expression of theological charity, it is clear that the life of charity presupposes and simultaneously activates the life of faith. It leads, then, to faith working through love (Gal 5:6). How to know, if not, that the Providence of God, the One who is our Father, embraces all of history, whether the history of mankind or that of single individuals? He is attentive to any of our actions, to everything that happens, to every one of our encounters. He is present in the everyday things, in the most common, that make the place of our sanctification and the encounter with Christ. Josemaría Escrivá used to say to his sons and daughters, “Ordinary life is the true place of your Christian life.”3 As a result, in the education for holiness we will have to insist on what refers to the faith and strength of that faith. We will also insist on what pertains to its operational strength. I have selected some 3 Josemaría Escrivá, Conversations with Josemaría Escrivá (New York: Scepter, 2008), no.113 (translation revised). Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1055 significant texts. “Some call imprudence and rashness what is in fact faith and trust in God.”4 Confidence in God belongs to faith and hope. It is, at its root, the attitude of faith in the loving Providence of the Father and his saving action. Such confidence in the presence and action of the Father is at the basis of apostolic action. “A keen and living faith. A faith like Peter’s. When you have it—our Lord has said so—you will move mountains, humanly insuperable obstacles that rise up against your apostolic undertakings.”5 Throughout all his life, Josemaría Escrivá gave witness to a love of this kind for the will of God. I remember a few episodes concerning this. At the beginning of the Work in Madrid, he had found a precious help in Mr. José María Somoano, who died after a sudden illness on July 17, 1932. The blow was very hard to Escrivá: “Lord, why have you taken him? Why deprive yourself of a faithful servant, who could have been so effective in service to your Work? But you know more and do what is best for him and for us.”6 He strongly felt the blow he suffered, but his reaction of faith arose immediately. In the spring of 1941, his mother, from whom he had asked so much associating her with the apostolate of the Work, fell ill. He had promised to preach a course of exercises to the clergy of Lérida, in Catalonia. Having heard the doctor’s optimistic diagnosis, he leaves Madrid, entrusting his mother to the Lord. Two days later, during the exercises, they inform him that his mother is dead. Lacerated by pain, he cannot but complain to God in a filial way; but his complaint immediately follows the acceptance of God’s will: “Lord, you do this to me? While I was taking care of your priests, you do this to me?” But a little later he adds, “Let it be done, let it be fulfilled, let it be praised and eternally exalted the most just and most lovable Will of God above all things.—Amen.—Amen.” Upon arrival in Madrid, he goes to the chapel where the body rests. Just as when he received the news, he bursts into tears. When he rises again, he asks for a stole and recites the Te Deum. However, he cannot contain a lament: “My God, my God, what have you done? You have taken everything from me: everything you take from me. I thought that these my daughters really needed my mother, and you leave me with nothing . . . without anything!” But then you hear 4 5 6 Josemaría Escrivá, Furrow (New York: Scepter, 1992), no. 43. The Way, no. 489. Registro Histórico del Fundador (RHF), 20165 (pp. 1635–36). This is the catalogued collection of material pertaining to the work of Josemaría Escrivá that is held in the archives of the Opus Dei prelature in Rome. 1056 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. this prayer: “Lord, I am happy because I know you love her and that you had a detail of trust with me. . . . It has to be ensured that all my children are with their parents when they die, but sometimes it will not be possible. And you, Lord, have disposed that, in this, I had gone first.” 7 I now evoke his reaction to the death of three of his sons in a road accident in 1960. The anguished question directed to God “why?” is also followed by an act of abandonment to Divine Providence.8 And the same attitude is found again and again throughout a lifetime in which trials were not lacking, particularly when serious threats hovered over the Work.9 If we treat of this, it is because there is a reason: St. Escrivá lived deeply the mystery of the Cross, leading him to write, “The wholehearted acceptance rendered to the Will of God necessarily brings joy and peace: happiness in the Cross. Then one sees that Christ’s yoke is gentle and that his burden is not heavy.”10 It is necessary to know how to recognize the Cross of Christ in trials. To encounter the Cross “is to find happiness, joy . . . it is to identify oneself with Christ, and therefore, to be a child of God.” He adds: “The foundation of the spiritual life of the member of Opus Dei is the sense of his divine filiation.”11 St. Escrivá asks his sons and daughters to be apostles in everyday ordinary life, in which the Work completed with all its demands, with honesty, constitute the place of sanctification. Then the aspects of the life of faith particularly exalted can be understood: a “more humble, lively, and operative faith,”12 because faith shows itself in humility,13 a “sacrificed”14 faith, proper of someone who is struggling to be a saint.15 The faith of the apostle must banish doubt, and when the assault of temptation arrives, the one who wishes the salvation of souls must shout, following in the footsteps of the father of the sick child of whom the Gospel speaks: “Lord, help my unbelief.”16 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 RHF, 4417. Cf. F. Gondrand, Al paso de Dios, 3rd ed. (Madrid. ES: Rialp, 1985), 224. Cf. ibid., 206ff. The Way, no.758 (translation revised). RHF, 20119 (p. 13). Cf. Josemaría Escrivá, The Forge (New York: Scepter, 2002), no. 257. Cf. ibid., no. 324. Cf. ibid., no. 155 (translation revised). Cf. Furrow, no. 111. Cf. The Forge, no. 257. Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1057 In the writings of this blessed, we often find a term: the word supernatural. Faith gives us a “supernatural vision of events.”17 Speaking of his Work, Monsignor Escrivá repeated to his children that they are not here to realize a “human endeavor but a great supernatural work, which began fulfilling in it, to the letter, all that is needed so that it can be called, without boasting, God’s Work.”18 The Founder makes clear here what the principle, the soul of his Work is: it is a supernatural work. By saying what that Work is, he simultaneously establishes a very high standard. If fidelity to this standard were to falter, the Work would cease to exist. Indeed, the vocation is aimed primarily at the laity. They are the ones called to tend, with the help of grace, to the sanctification and apostolate in ordinary life, in which work, carried out with competence and professionalism, plays a key role. It is inevitable now to raise a vital question. What relationship exists between this vocation and the temporal commitment that, as the Second Vatican Council will recall strongly, is part of the vocation of the laity? We know that, despite the specific guidelines emanating from the Council, there are many uncertainties in this respect: it tilts between the confusion of the fields and radical separation, positions both disastrous. The guidelines of Josemaría Escrivá on this point have clarity all the more remarkable because they came to his mind in a particularly restless period, in which the passions of party affiliation seem to prevail over everything. Young people gather around him—we are in Madrid, at the beginning of 1936—they are impressed by the fact that he is never mixed in political discussions. He simply reminds them of the doctrine of the Church and the obligation of every Christian to assume their proper responsibilities in society. Above all, he never ceases to repeat the new commandment of fraternal love.19 Later, in 1939, addressing a group of students, he will put them on guard against a too human conception of acting, even if it obeys noble patriotic motives: “But do not forget that there is a higher reality: the Kingdom of Christ, which has no end. And for Christ to reign in the world, it first has to reign in your heart. Does he truly reign? Is your heart for Jesus Christ?”20 Monsignor Escrivá would never tire of asserting the autonomy 17 18 19 20 Ibid., no. 657 (translation revised). RHF, 21500, no.1. Cf. ibid. (pp. 108–09). Ibid., (p. 144). 1058 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. of the laity in the temporal sphere21: “I love liberty because without liberty we could not serve God; we would be wretched. We have to teach Catholics to live, not to be called Catholics, but to be citizens who assume personal responsibility for their personal and free actions.” He would go so far as to say, with a formula that requires a correct understanding because it contains something of a paradox: “the sons of God in the Opus Dei live despite being Catholics.”22 For this reason, such freedom is again found on the plane of elections and political commitments. What attitude will have to be adopted by the members of Opus Dei in the public life of their country? “The one they please! freely. I do not care about the position of each, I defend their freedom. Otherwise, I could not defend mine. And I’m from a land where we do not tolerate imposition.”23 Leaving aside the humor of the last words, the position of the founder of Opus Dei responds to two essential reasons. The first lies precisely in the proper supernatural character of the vocation to the Work, which must be protected from any inclination toward a purpose other than the Kingdom of God. With this, St. Josemaría does not intend to deny the necessary evangelical inspiration of the temporal commitment. However, he underlines that it is up to each individual to personally discover and make effective the concrete realization of that impulse. The second motive is the supernatural horizon where his Work is situated: “Do not forget that the world is our thing, that the world is our home, that the world is a work of God and that we are to love it as we ought to love those who are in the world. It is our job to consecrate the world to God, through this dedication to the service of the Lord, each in the exercise of their ordinary work, to be a testimony to Jesus Christ and also to serve the Church, the Roman Pontiff, and all souls. Therefore, we must understand the world, we must raise it, we must divinize it, we must purify it, and we must redeem it with Christ, because you are co-redeemers with Him.”24 Still let us cite these clear statements of 1967: “The purpose at which Opus Dei aims is to encourage the pursuit of holiness and the exercise of the apostolate by Christians living in the midst of the world, whatever their status or condition. . . . . Christ is present in 21 22 23 24 Cf. Ibid. (pp. 162–234). RHF, 20565 (pp. 36–39). Ibid. (p. 40). Ibid. (p. 45). Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1059 any honest human task. . . . Opus Dei has as its unique and exclusive mission to spread this message. . . . And to those who grasp this ideal of holiness, the Work offers the spiritual means and doctrinal, ascetical and apostolic formation needed to do it in their own lives.”25 For this reason, the members of the Work “do not act as a group, but individually, with personal freedom and responsibility.”26 Monsignor Escrivá stands against any pretension of “using the laity for ends which exceed the proper limits of the hierarchical ministry.”27 He warns against a certain way of defining the vocation of lay Catholics; it is not that these penetrate in social settings! “The members of the Work have no need to penetrate the temporal sector for the simple fact that they are ordinary citizens, equal to others, and therefore they were already there.”28 Which, taken together, is to draw a vocation of the laity, specifically a supernatural vocation to sanctification and the apostolate. *** The sense of freedom by which the person responds to the love of God and the supernatural nature of the vocation guide the concept of the spiritual life itself of Josemaría Escrivá. The insistence on ordinary life should not be understood as an invitation to uniformity. The truth is just the opposite. His experience as spiritual director has taught him that God’s ways fit each person uniquely. In a homily on the life of prayer (April 4, 1955), we read: “There are countless ways of praying, I say again. God’s children do not need a method, graphed and artificial, to go to their Father. Love is inventive, industrious; if we love, we will discover personal, intimate paths that lead us to this ongoing dialogue with the Lord.”29 And shortly before, in a beautiful passage about mental prayer, we find: “Let there not be missing in our day a few moments especially dedicated to attend to God, raising our thoughts toward Him, words have no need to come to our lips, because they sing in the heart. . . . Each of you, if he wants, can find his own channel for this conversation with God. I don’t like to talk about methods or formulas, 25 26 27 28 29 Conversations, no. 255 (translation revised). Ibid. Ibid., no. 12. Ibid., no. 66. Josemaría Escrivá, Friends of God (New York: Scepter, 1997), no. 255 (translation revised). 1060 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. because I’ve never been a friend of constricting anyone: I have tried to encourage everyone to get closer to the Lord, while respecting each soul as it is, with its own characteristics. Ask Him to work his designs in our life: not only in the head, but in the heart and in all our external activity.”30 In this way, Monsignor Escrivá offers his sons and daughters a path of spiritual freedom, which is not the same as a path devoid of demands: “You are contemplative souls in the midst of the world,” he says, and uses this beautiful formula: the “heroism without noise of your ordinary life.”31 The vocation of the laity in the world requires this contemplative attitude, without which it would lose its proper supernatural character, making it impossible to transform the world: “If not, they will not transform anything, but they will be transformed; rather than Christianizing the world, the Christians will become worldly.”32 The difficulties that come from ordinary life are not to be invoked against this doctrine. On the contrary, the common life is perfectly suited to look in it for the means of the life of prayer. “The street”— he writes in a letter of 1959—“does not prevent our contemplative dialogue; the bustle of the world is, for us, a place of prayer.”33 The sense of divine filiation carries with it the sense of God’s presence. Never will St. Escrivá cease to insist on this truth of faith and its spiritual fruitfulness: “It is necessary to be convinced that God is near us continually. . . . And he is here like a loving Father. He loves each of us more than all the mothers in the world can love their children, helping us, inspiring us, blessing . . . and forgiving. . . . It is vital to be imbued, to be saturated with the knowledge that the Lord, who is near us and in heaven, is Father and very much our Father.”34 It is not difficult to see to what extent this is consistent with the teaching of Vatican II about the vocation, the holiness, of the baptized and in particular the vocation of the laity. Ibid., no. 249 (translation revised). RHF, 29850 (p. 3). 32 Postulación de la Causa de Beatificación y Canonización del Siervo de Dios Josemaría Escrivá de Balaguer, Sacerdote, Fundator del Opus Dei, Artículos del Postulador, Rome 1979, nos. 212–13. 33 Josemaría Escrivá, Carta, (January 9, 1959). 34 The Way, no. 267. Cf. also Furrow, no. 658 (translation revised). 30 31 Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1061 *** Following what has been presented until now, I would like to propose some reflections on the demands of the life of faith in the context of the new evangelization. Faith encounters in its path demands and obstacles that depend on its own nature and that recur in each new generation. But there are also unique challenges of each particular era. The latter will attract our attention in the first place. After the symbolic event of the fall of the Berlin Wall in 1989, one often speaks of the end of the age of ideologies. The formula is only partially accurate. In fact, it ignores the traces that the Marxist ideology has left in spirits, as well as the wounds whose severity will be appearing successively. But above all it tries to indicate the global checkmate to a system considered from the cultural point of view. And, indeed, the Marxist ideology, taken here as a finished model, but not unique, of ideology, translates the will of the instigators of society and of the State to give to its own project and its justification the value of an absolute that would be imposed on all members of society. For this reason, the totalitarian power cannot be conceived without including its ideological dimension. Their representatives considered themselves, according to the famous formula of Stalin, as engineers of souls. Having put their hands in teaching and in the mass media, with an impressive propaganda apparatus, with the support of terror and intimidation, they expressed the need to convince at all costs, and regardless of the means used. The totalitarian power, whose ideology was auto-qualified as scientific, had to be the proprietor of beliefs, and the people subjected to such power would have to share such convictions unanimously. The consensus thus obtained, in large part fictitious and feigned, replaced the truth. Ideologies are lies and illusions that impose themselves or are imposed on the community, so that the ideological era meant the triumph of pseudo-truth because the lie is a false claim that at all costs is intended to pass as real. It is much more than a simple mistake. And hence the decline or collapse of ideologies, whose deception suddenly becomes clear, brings with it a crisis of the meaning of truth. If what we had been taught as true was false and deceitful, where do we find truth? Are we facing an illusion? In such context, the temptation of nihilism is very strong. Because ideologies have perverted the very notion of truth, the current crisis of culture is essentially a crisis of truth. 1062 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. For these reasons, and with the prospect of the new evangelization, the apostles have to be witnesses of the truth: testimonies, first, of the virtue of faith. It is worth recalling here the words of Jesus: “You will know the truth and the truth shall set you free” ( John 8:32). And since the crisis of truth also reaches the field of culture, the witness of the truth, who has an intellectual vocation, must be present in the domains of philosophy and metaphysics. Ideology mimics the truth. Therefore, its fall can help weaken and obscure the meaning of truth. Other sectors of our culture can cooperate to this same end. If the modern era has been able to develop the very idea of ideology, it is due undoubtedly to the fact that the political power had the means to put pressure on spirits much more effectively than in the past. But it stems also, and more radically, from the fact that a latent crisis concerning the idea of certainty already existed for some time. The notion of certainty is distinct from that of truth: someone possesses certainty of a truth. Certainty indicates the quality of possession, the assimilation of truth by a subject. A certain truth is a truth that no argument could pull out of the spirit. Thus, certainty means the property of truth by which this can be imposed in an indisputable way to the spirit. While the truth expresses the relationship of conformity of the judgment with the known reality, certainty is the effect of the truth, the nature of its location in the subject that knows: there are certain truths and probable truths. The truth is imposed with certainty when the spirit discovers its evidence, immediate or mediate. Then the object is made present to the spirit. Now, in modern culture, there has been a shift of emphasis, whose importance should not be underestimated: opposing the very nature of things, certainty has taken the lead on the evidence of truth. First of all we have sought certainty. From this have been derived two consequences. The first is a characteristic form of rationalism. The how of knowledge has been sought before anything else; the perfect possession of the object has become a criterion of truth, excluding in this way, from the field of knowledge, all imperfect knowledge of the truth. And this is why human reason has been closed in itself. The second consequence can be found in the opposite direction. The urgent quest for certainty that puts at the forefront the subjective aspect of knowledge has opened the way to the psychological substi- Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1063 tutes of certainty. Devoid of any connection with the truth, certainty has become a reassuring subjective attitude. And through this door have entered the ideologies. Without any wondering about its foundations, what is certain has been pursued just because it is comforting. The issue is of concern to the witness of truth in a direct way. Indeed, theological faith carries with it a relationship between evidence and certainty that has no equivalent in the order of human affairs. Usually, the degree of certainty depends on the degree of evidence. In theological faith coexist the absence of evidence and the perfect firmness of certainty, and this because the act of faith is based on a motive stronger than the natural evidence of reason—namely, the authority of God that reveals and its supreme veracity. So there is, without a doubt, evidence as a basis of faith, but evidence that is given us through a mediator: “No one has ever seen God. The only Son, God, who is at the Father’s side, has revealed him” ( John 1:18). The witness of truth must be fully aware of the specificity of theological faith. St. Escrivá teaches: “Faith is a supernatural virtue which disposes our intelligence to give assent to the revealed truths, to say yes to Christ, who has given us a full understanding of the saving plan of the Blessed Trinity.”35 These lines illuminate the behavior that is expected of us. *** The realm of ideologies has been that of “certainties” that already no longer had truth as a cause. That is why they have been interpreted as answers, in the individual and social sphere, to the need for security. “Certainties” would be in this sense lies, thanks to which we would defend ourselves from the tragic aspect of our existence, subject to the inexorable law of time and expiration. This resource having failed, man should learn to live without certainty; skepticism and relativism would, thus, be the foundations of a new wisdom. On behalf of such an attitude, of resigned despair, believers will be accused of being either fanatics or anachronistic beings who strive to hold on to the old certainties. This new cultural context calls for a remarkable testimony of faith and of its novelty. It is necessary to make clear that the certainties of the believer come from divine truth, the source of meaning, peace, and joy. Such testimony will dissipate prejudices and obstacles if its expression is authentically evangelical. 35 Friends of God, no. 191 (from homily given on October 12, 1947; translation revised). 1064 †Cardinal Georges Cottier, O.P. In effect, the witness to the truth has to face a double hurdle: that of the soothing certainty that no longer is referred to truth, and the corresponding rejection of certainties as illusions that man has to learn to do without. *** Crisis of truth, temptation to skepticism. A third challenge appears in the path of the new evangelization: that of syncretism. What has been said so far does not yet cover all the trends that appeal to our world. Along with the inclination that leads to nihilism, there is also need to confront a diffused and wild religiosity and the largely new problems posed by the encounter between Christianity and non-Christian religions. Vatican Council II, through Nostra Aetate, has opened the doors to an interreligious dialogue that does not turn out to be exclusive of the missions. But a strong temptation arises when one is open with sympathy to the positive elements of other religions, to lose sight of the specificity of Christianity and the universality of salvation that it obtains for us: “Nor is there any other name under heaven given to the human race by which we are to be saved” (Acts 4:12). The temptation of syncretism consists in considering that the various religious experiences are in essence identical, historical religions being but mere contingent manifestations. Christianity appears then as one religion among others. Such temptation seduces many spirits, and even if it is in an attenuated form, it exerts its influence also in some theologians. Faced with this challenge, which is a great provocation for the coming century, it is essential and vital that the witness of truth be convinced of the transcendence of the Christian faith, of its uniqueness. Its specificity depends on the personal relationship established with the person of Jesus Christ, Son of God made man. We now recall the insistence of Monsignor Escrivá on the supernatural aspect, as well as his insistence on the life of union of the believer with Jesus. Let us also remember his sense of the Eucharist and, through homilies that he has left us, his constant and very specific invitation to the sequela Christi. The daily meditation on the Gospel and the participation in the liturgy of the Church leads the disciple to that familiarity with Jesus, who is at the center of our faith. The witness of truth is thus impelled to deepen the awareness of his identity as son of God in the only-begotten Son. It would also be appropriate to recall the deep Marian devotion of St. Escrivá, as well as his love for the Church. Prayer and the Fundamental Structure of the Faith 1065 We are thus faced with a rich treasury that the architects of the new evangelization are invited to use to be up to the tasks that await N&V them. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1067–1081 A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology in the New Evangelization1 Khaled Anatolios University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, IN The very notion of a new evangelization immediately provokes a sense of excitement and ready assent in the hearts and minds of many sincere Christians. But in reflecting on the intellectual task of the new evangelization, it seems appropriate to probe more analytically into the attractiveness of this notion. While the rationale for evangelization should not at any time require justification, the fact that, at this moment in the history of the Church and the world, we are impelled to qualify that evangelization as needing to be new requires closer scrutiny. Why is it that we now feel the need to speak of a new evangelization? Notwithstanding all the cogent and compelling explanations that refer to the need for Christians to respond to the steadily increasing hegemony of a secularist worldview, I would like to suggest that there is an even deeper reason why many Christians respond to the call for a new evangelization with great enthusiasm and joy. I believe that the deepest ground for this joy is that the Gospel itself is essentially and incorruptibly new and that whenever we are moved to authentically welcome its message, we are impelled first and foremost to proclaim its undiminishable newness. This clarification allows us to properly identify the contrast of old and new implicit in the notion of a “new evangelization,” especially 1 An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Unite States Council of Catholic Bishops conference on “The Intellectual Tasks of the New Evangelization: Catechesis and Theology,” in September 2013. 1068 Khaled Anatolios insofar as it considers itself as responding to modern secularism. In the very last analysis, this contrast cannot be between an old proclamation of the Gospel and a new one. Rather, what is ultimately at stake is the proclamation of the ineradicable newness of the Gospel over against the oldness of what the fourth evangelist calls “the world,” which is not the created world as such, but precisely the posture of self-sufficiency that characterizes all kinds of secularism, both modern and ancient. We desire and need a new evangelization, first and foremost, because we need and desire a new world, a new heaven, and a new earth, and we know that the content of this newness is present only in Christ. As Irenaeus put it, “He brought all newness in bringing himself.”2 In light of these considerations, it seems to me that the theological foundation of the new evangelization must begin by properly locating the designation of newness within the scriptural contrast between the essential “oldness” of the world, to the precise extent that it resists the newness of Christ, and the unsurpassable newness of Christ himself that redeems and restores this old world. In the Old Testament, we see the foundation of this contrast in the psalmist’s opposition between the radical corruptibility of the material creation and the undiminishable vitality of Israel’s God: Long ago you laid the foundation of the earth, and the heavens are the work of your hands. They will perish, but you endure; they will all wear out like a garment. You change them like clothing, and they pass away; but you are the same, and your years have no end.3 Human beings, despite their divine likeness, are also perishable and, again, the psalmist contrasts the corruptibility of the human condition with the immutable and undiminishable vitality of God’s love: As for mortals, their days are like grass; They flourish like a flower of the field; For the wind passes over it, and it is gone. . . . 2 3 Irenaeus, Against the Heresies 4.34.1, in Contre les Hérésies: Livre IV. ed. and trans. A. Rousseau, B. Hemmerdinger, L.Doutreleau, and C. Mercier. Sources Chrétiennes 100 (Paris: Cerf, 1965), 846 (my own English transltion from the Latin). Ps 102:25–27. All biblical quotations are taken from the NRSV translation. A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1069 But the steadfast love of the Lord is from everlasting to everlasting.4 In Second Isaiah (Isa. 40–54), we find intimations that the abyss between human corruptibility and the unflagging newness of divine life will one day be bridged over. In the midst of Israel’s exile, the prophet announces in the name of Israel’s God: Do not remember the former things [τὰ πρῶτα], Or consider the things of old. I am about to do a new thing; Now, it springs forth, do you not perceive it?5 But it is not until the New Testament that it becomes fully manifest that the new thing that God has done is nothing less than to utterly merge the essential newness of his indestructible divinity with our perishable humanity in the God-Man, Jesus Christ. In an allusion to the prophecy from Isaiah, the book of Revelation concludes the New Testament with a vision of the universal sovereignty of God’s newness: Then I saw a new heaven and a new earth; for the first heaven and the first earth had passed away, and the sea was no more. And I saw the holy city, the new Jerusalem, coming down out of heaven from God, prepared as a bride adorned for her husband. And I heard a loud voice from the throne saying, “See, the home of God is among mortals. He will dwell with them; they will be his peoples, and God himself will be with them; he will wipe every tear from their eyes. Death will be no more; mourning and crying and pain will be no more, for the former things [τὰ πρῶτα] have passed away.” And the one who was seated on the throne said, “See, I am making all things new.”6 If we turn from a consideration of the scriptural witness to a discernment of the signs of our own times, we find that there is a surprising expanse of common ground between the worldview of the Gospel and that of postmodern secular culture. Even if modern secuPs 103:15–17. Isa 43:18–19. 6 Rev 21:1–5. 4 5 1070 Khaled Anatolios larism does not acknowledge the redemptive newness that Christ has brought, it recognizes at least the oldness and tiredness of a Christ-less world. Quite independently of the judgment of the Gospel, secularism itself declares the human condition to be not young and vigorous, but rather old and fatigued. As Charles Taylor has amply and voluminously shown, disenchantment, pervasive malaise, and a sense of decay has pervaded the rise of modernity since the Enlightenment.7 Our advanced technological expertise, which has undeniably resulted in the production of many new things, nevertheless has not only not renewed the earth itself but has enabled us to measure its rapid demise with ever-increasing alarm, much of it caused by our irresponsible use of that same technology. But the oldness of humanity goes beyond a misuse and depletion of natural resources. One of its distinctly modern expressions is a sense of disgust at the whole sad story of human history, with its dispiritingly pervasive cruelty and injustice punctuated by episodes of boundless savagery. This sentiment was famously expressed by James Joyce’s modern-day Ulysses, Stephen Daedelus, who complained, “History is a nightmare from which I am trying to awake.”8 In a similar vein, the English novelist D. H. Lawrence spoke of the collective broken heart of modern humanity, saying that we “have become repulsive to one another. . . . [We] smell in each other’s nostrils.”9 It is to this sense of deep malaise and incapacity for genuine vital hope that the new evangelization must speak, and I am convinced that the spontaneous excitement generated by the very notion of a new evangelization is due to the fact that it offers the prospect of a deliverance from the despair of living in a materially and spiritually depleted and senile world that seems to lack any credible resources for renewing itself. If it is true that the foregoing is at least a partial account of the present meeting-point between the world’s need and the Gospel’s promise, we can now ask what should be our conception of the nature and proper method of a theology that would be of service to the aspiration for a new evangelization. We can begin our response to this question by defining theology, from the perspective of the new evangelization, precisely as ordered discourse on the newness of 7 8 9 Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007). James Joyce, Ulysses (New York: Random House, 1961), 34. D. H. Lawrence, “Introduction to Bottom Dogs, by Edward Dahlberg,” in D.H. Lawrence: Introductions and Reviews (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 121. A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1071 Christ and of the renewal of all things in Christ. Similarly, catechesis can be conceived as the initial communication of this message of how, in Christ, the old has passed away and a new heaven and new earth are now taking shape in our midst. From this point of view, the fundamental criterion that distinguishes authentic and correct theology from distortions and aberrations can be characterized as the preservation of the essential and objective newness of Christ. This clarification preempts any inclination to overlook the riches of the Church’s tradition in the name of a misconceived desire for superficial newness and enables us to recognize that the high points of this tradition are in fact precisely those that witness most authentically to the newness of the Gospel and partake of its perennial vigor and imperishability. Throughout the tradition, we find classic instances of theologies whose conformity to the newness of the Gospel is evidenced by the fact that they remain fresh and vital despite the passage of time; they do not seem to grow old. In our efforts to construct a theological discourse for our own time that is an authentic witness to the essential newness of the Gospel and thus serviceable for the Church’s new evangelization, we can benefit greatly from learning from these classic theologies. We turn to them not with the assurance that they are infallible in every detail but simply with the recognition that they have proven to be built on the solid rock of the new terrain of the authentic Gospel. Certainly, the theological reflections of the Church fathers would be widely acknowledged as exhibiting this vital character of evangelical newness, and I do not think it is merely coincidental that the present call for a new evangelization coincides with a renewed interest in the theology of the Church fathers. But what is the best use that the new evangelization can make of patristic theology? I do not think it would be sufficient merely to repeat patristic formulations of the Christian mysteries, though these are certainly luminous sources for meditation. Rather, what is most necessary and foundational for the project of a new evangelization is to retrieve the patristic method of theological reflection, which was so successful in unpacking key elements of the newness of the Gospel. It is true that patristic theology is not entirely homogeneous, and it would be valid to speak of patristic methods of theology rather than of a single method. But we can also recognize a certain unity of approach within variations of individual styles among the great patristic theologians. Perhaps the most methodologically self-aware account of patristic theology is Origen’s Preface to his On First 1072 Khaled Anatolios Principles, written in the third century. It bears the unmistakably distinctive character of the great Alexandrian theologian, but its exposition of the fundamental structure of theological method would be substantively shared by all the great fathers of the Church. In Origen’s prescription for authentic Christian theology, we can locate three key features that, in my judgment, should also be integral to a modern theology and catechesis that aspire to be of service to the new evangelization: a commitment to the absolute primacy of Christ, a proper conception of the normativity and generativity of tradition as animated by a dialectic of receptivity and activity, and an openness to the comprehensive range of the truth of the Gospel. The Primacy of Christ The first sentence of the preface to Origen’s On First Principles lays down the foundation for theological enquiry as follows: “All who believe and are convinced that grace and truth came by Jesus Christ, and who know Christ to be the truth (in accordance with his own saying, ‘I am the truth’) derive the knowledge which calls people to lead a good and blessed life from no other source but the very words of Christ.”10 There is much to unpack in that one sentence that is relevant to both catechesis and theology in the service of the new evangelization. First, Origen is telling us that the properly Christian experience of encountering Christ is precisely to encounter Christ as Absolute Truth. It would follow, then, that the task of catechesis must be to present Christ as this absolute norm, Christ as the Truth not just in some theoretical sense but quite practically and existentially, as the exclusively sovereign source of the way to “a good and blessed life.” The task of theology, then, is simply to apply this absolute and unique normativity of Christ to the whole extent of our knowledge of reality, whether theoretical or practical. Anyone who has even dabbled in Origen’s writings will immediately recognize that Origen does not mean that Christian theology should make no use whatsoever of any knowledge that is not derived explicitly from positive revelation. Rather, he is really making the very same point that the contemporary Roman Catholic theologian Bruce Marshall makes when he speaks of the “epistemic primacy” of the Church’s identification of Jesus Christ as Lord. Speaking in the idiom of analytic philosophy, Marshall explains that the epistemic 10 Origen, On First Principles, pref. 1, trans. G. W. Butterworth (Gloucester, MA: Peter Smith, 1973), 1. Hereafter, I will refer to this work as simply “Principles.” A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1073 primacy of Christ means that “when it comes to the epistemic relation between beliefs—when it comes to deciding what is true—the identification of Jesus which relies on the church’s canonical narrative must have primacy. . . . If identifying descriptions of Jesus in the church’s canonical narrative are held true, then the sentences by which we identify and describe other things must, if we are to hold them true, at least be compatible with (that is, not contradict) the sentences by which we identify and describe Jesus.”11 For his part, Origen is presuming the Aristotelian definition of a science (ἐπιστήμη) as based on first principles that cannot themselves be interrogated, lest there be an infinite regress of interrogation rather than an ordered construction of a positive body of knowledge.12 Christian theology must seek its very first principle in the encounter with Jesus Christ as the Truth in person and as the criterion by which all claims to truth are to be tested. This does not mean that Christian theology can be content to be irrational and obliviously unperturbed by the demands and agitations of human reason. It is the Church’s proclamation of Christ itself that asserts that the proper functioning of human reason is a certain participation in Christ, who is Truth and Wisdom. But the striving of reason must always be guided and normed by the Church’s identification of Christ as the Truth. Only in this way will the essential newness of the Gospel be preserved. The Role of Tradition After identifying the starting point of theology as an encounter with Christ as Truth, Origen goes on to explain that the words and teachings of Christ are comprised not only of the utterances of Jesus in his humanity but in fact of the entire Christian Scriptures—the Old Testament that proclaims Christ in the mode of prophecy and the New Testament in which Christ speaks both in his own person and in the apostolic witness. Yet Origen, who is arguably one of the greatest biblical exegetes of the Christian tradition, immediately recognizes that the mere recourse to Scripture does not of itself guarantee a continuity with the Truth of Jesus Christ. And that is because this Egyptian theologian of the third century was no less aware than the contempo11 12 B. Marshall, Trinity and Truth (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 116. See Aristotle, Posterior Analytics 2.19.99b17–100b17. See also Brian Daley’s “Origen’s De Principiis and Scriptural Interpretation,” in Nova et Vetera: Patristic Studies in Honor of Thomas Patrick Halton, ed. John F. Petruccione (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1998), 3–21. 1074 Khaled Anatolios rary philosopher Paul Ricoeur of what the latter calls “the conflict of interpretation.”13 Origen notes: “Many of those, however, who profess to believe in Christ, hold conflicting opinions not only on small and trivial questions, but also on some that are great and important.”14 For Origen, this inherent possibility and, indeed, perennial actuality of a conflict of scriptural interpretation necessitates recourse to a standard of judgment that will again prevent an endless regression of interrogation and unmediated disagreement. Origen refers to this standard of judgment as “a definite line and unmistakable rule [regula/κανών].”15 This canonical principle is supplied by the living witness of the tradition of the Church, which Origen presents not as an alternative or rival source of revelation, but rather as enabling and safeguarding the authentic contents of the scriptural witness to Christ as the Truth. For Origen, to reject the continuity of tradition and Scripture is to be in danger of straying from Christ as the source and content of Truth and reverting to ambiguous and unreliable extra-Christian accounts of truth: For just as there are many among Greeks and barbarians alike who promise us the truth, and yet we gave up seeking for it from all who claimed it . . . after we had come to believe that Christ was the Son of God and had become convinced that we must learn the truth from him; in the same way when we find many who think they hold the doctrine of Christ, some of them differing in their beliefs from the Christians of earlier times, and yet the teaching of the church, handed down in unbroken succession from the apostles, is still preserved and continues to exist in the churches up to the present day, we maintain that that only is to be believed as the truth which in no way conflicts with the tradition of the church and the apostles.16 We see from the last sentence that Origen has moved in the space of just a few paragraphs from affirming the identity of Christ and 13 14 15 16 For Ricoeur’s exposition of this notion, see, for example, his essay, “Existence and Hermeneutics,” in The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1974), 3–24. Principles, pref. 2 (p. 1). Ibid. Ibid. (p. 2). A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1075 the Truth to asserting that the determination of the contents of this truth must be in conformity with the tradition of the Church. It is clear that, for Origen, there is no tension at all between these two statements. The truth of Christ, which must be appropriated as a personal experience on the part of each believer, is mediated through both Scripture and tradition. But it would be both anachronistic and an actual distortion of Origen’s conception to see tradition as merely a record of propositional pronouncements that pass judgment on disputed questions. For Origen, tradition is many-layered and contains different gradations of explicitness and normativity. It is a generative and not merely a conserving principle, and therefore the activity of theological investigation and enquiry is integral to the living flow of tradition: The holy apostles, when preaching the faith of Christ, took certain doctrines, those namely which they believed to be necessary ones, and delivered them in the plainest terms to all believers, even to such as appeared to be somewhat dull in the investigation of divine knowledge. The grounds of their statements they left to be investigated by such as should merit the higher gifts of the Spirit and in particular by such as should afterwards receive through the Holy Spirit himself the graces of language, wisdom and knowledge. There were other doctrines, however, about which the apostles simply said that things were so, keeping silence as to the how or why; their intention undoubtedly being to supply the more diligent of those who came after them, such as should prove to be lovers of wisdom, with an exercise on which to display the fruit of their ability. The people I refer to are those who train themselves to become worthy and capable of receiving wisdom.17 Part of the background of this passage is Origen’s struggles with the phenomenon of Gnosticism. The Gnostics divided the human race into three categories: the materialists; the psychics, or soul-like; and the pneumatics. They thought of themselves as the last category: they were the spiritual people in whom indwelt a spark of the pleroma and who had access to a secret knowledge that would lead them back to their spiritual homeland. For these Gnostics, ordinary Christians 17 Ibid., pref. 3 (p. 2). 1076 Khaled Anatolios were the middle group, the “psychics,” who were misled by the plain meaning of the Scriptures and by the doctrines and sacraments of the visible Church. It was Irenaeus who waged a massive battle against the Gnostics in the second century, insisting that the contents of the Gospel were given freely and openly to the whole human race. It is ironic that modern readers sometimes discern a Gnostic flavor in a passage like the one just quoted above when Origen was certainly adopting an Irenaean (anti-Gnostic) approach. As we can see clearly in this passage, for Origen, however high and deep may be the reach of any individual’s contemplation of the mysteries of Christian revelation, the foundation of this contemplation must be the basic doctrines that are “delivered in the plainest terms to all believers.” For our own purposes, we can say that the content of the Church’s catechesis must be the foundation and norm for all theological contemplation. To suggest otherwise, that the content of catechesis is in any way separable from that of sophisticated investigation and enquiry, is to revert to a Gnostic schema that separates a class of “fleshly” people from the self-proclaimed pneumatics.18 Nevertheless, for Origen, the articulation of these basic doctrines does not put a stop to thought and enquiry but is indeed a creative and fruitful provocation to further questioning, investigation, and contemplation. Of course, such questioning does not put the basic doctrines themselves into question, which would be a betrayal of the epistemic primacy of Christ, but rather probes into the inexhaustible luminosity of what is revealed. For Origen, what we would call theology is exactly this activity, which is both a human labor and a gift of the Spirit. The fruit of this graced activity is wisdom, which is a participation in the Word and Wisdom that is Christ himself. Origen does contend that there are particular individuals who are especially endowed with such wisdom but, apart from his affirmation 18 This point has been made by Joseph Ratzinger in response to the claim that “the pastoral office . . . preaches for the faithful but does not teach for the theologians,” to which he answers, “but such a divorce of preaching and teaching is most profoundly opposed to the essence of the biblical message. It merely rehashes that division between psychics and gnostics, whereby the so-called gnosis of antiquity had already tried to secure for itself a free zone, which in reality placed it outside the Church and her faith”; see Ratzinger, “The Spiritual Basis and Ecclesial Identity of Theology,” in The Nature and Mission of Theology: Essays to Orient Theology in Today’s Debates, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995), 62. A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1077 here that this is a wisdom whose foundational principles are universally shared by all Christians, he makes it clear elsewhere that those gifted with this wisdom are called to share its fruits liberally with those who cannot procure these fruits by their own labors.19 At the heart of Origen’s view of tradition is a certain dialectic between receptivity and activity in which the former always has the initiative. It seems to me that this dialectic determines the proper mutual ordering of catechesis and theology. The reason that receptivity is the primary movement is simply that the truth of Christ, the Truth that is Christ, is not constructed by human activity but simply received. Both Scripture and tradition are primarily vehicles for receiving the Truth of Jesus Christ, and the task of catechesis is to introduce others into this stream of receptivity. At the same time, this receptivity itself calls forth an active dynamism that seeks to travel ever farther and deeper into the fullness of the life in Christ. We are disposed perhaps to be bemused by Origen’s explanation that the apostles kept silent about the rationale of certain doctrines in order to provide diligent lovers of wisdom “with an exercise on which to display the fruit of their ability.” Yet, a more general familiarity with Origen’s work would lead us to see that he conceives of such exercise as an exertion that is the same as the impulse of desire for the divine Beloved.20 Tradition, for Origen, is not just a repository of information or legal judgments, but rather a storehouse of provocations for the play of a searching desire. The tradition of the Church presents to us the truth of Christ both as a gift freely given and gratefully received and as an inexhaustible field for an active, loving contemplation. In their authentic forms, both catechesis and theological investigation participate in this dialectic of receptivity and activity within the flow of tradition. Catechesis must always motivate its audience towards an ever deeper contemplation of the Christian mysteries, while theology is bound to anchor its investigations in catechesis and to present itself as a seeking within the unfathomable depths of the faith that has been already found and received in the universal teaching of the Church. Preserving the newness of Christ in the consciousness of the Church requires the careful maintenance of this dialectic of receptivity and contemplative activity. It requires, in the first place, a dogmatic fixity that distinguishes authentic features of Christ’s presence from spurious 19 20 See, for example, his Commentary on John 1.43. See Commentary on John 1.23. 1078 Khaled Anatolios ones. But the fixing of these parameters does not put an end to our seeking and searching and questing, but rather stimulates them all the more, illuminating the horizon of Christ’s presence as containing all the newness of the new heaven and new earth. A new evangelization must therefore look to the Church’s tradition as both defining the contents of the newness of Christ and as inviting us to an ever-new seeking for the fullness of that newness. The Comprehensive Range of the Gospel Consistently with his own prescription for the proper conduct of theology, Origen goes on in his preface to On First Principles to outline the primary doctrines of apostolic teaching. In the first place, these doctrines confess the Church’s Trinitarian faith: in the one God who is the “Father of our Lord Jesus Christ”; in Jesus Christ, begotten of the Father before all creation, who emptied himself and became human, suffered, died, and rose from the dead; in the Holy Spirit “united in honor and dignity with the Father and the Son.”21 Then, Origen outlines the Church’s basic doctrines on the destiny of the human person, on the existence of angelic and demonic beings, on the creation of this world from nothing, and that the Scriptures have both a literal meaning and a hidden spiritual meaning. Finally, Origen concludes his methodological preface by placing the theological task within a hermeneutical circle or a dialectical movement that goes back and forth between the parts and the whole of Christian revelation. The theologian’s work is to connect individual doctrines so as to discern the whole vision adumbrated by Christian revelation and then to apply this vision of the whole in order to understand further the individual doctrines. It is again worthwhile to quote his own words: Everyone therefore who is desirous of constructing out of the foregoing a connected body of doctrine must use points like these as elementary and foundation principles, in accordance with the commandment which says, “Enlighten yourselves with the light of knowledge.” Thus by clear and cogent arguments he will discover the truth about each particular point, and so will produce, as we have said, a single body of doctrine, with the aid of such illustrations and declarations as he shall find in the holy scriptures and of such conclusions as he shall 21 Principles, pref. 4 (p. 2–4). A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1079 ascertain to follow logically from them when rightly understood.22 Origen’s conception of the unity of theology offers an important corrective to a modern tendency toward fragmentation and division, a tendency that is inimical to an authentic proclamation of the Gospel, whether in the mode of catechesis or theological investigation. On this point also, Origen’s position is anticipated and illumined by Irenaeus’s struggles with the Gnostics. In this struggle, one sees a titanic clash between two antithetical world-views, one that privileges otherness, division, and separation as the ultimate hermeneutical key to the meaning of reality and one that privileges unity and harmony. The Gnostic world-view explained reality in terms of a series of irreconcilable antitheses: the divine pleroma and this world that was created by a delinquent lower god; spirit and matter; different human natures; the visible Church with its Scriptures and sacraments and the esoteric Gnostic gospel; and the fleshly Jesus and the Christ from the divine sphere. In contrast to this fundamentally oppositional world-view, Irenaeus’s theological vision insists on the unity and harmony of God and the world, of matter and spirit, of the visible Church and its mystical reality, of the plain sense of Scripture and its spiritual meaning, and of the vicissitudes of human history and the recapitulation of this history in Christ. Our postmodern temperament is more spontaneously inclined to the Gnostic world-view than to the Irenaean: we privilege otherness and diversity and are suspicious of unity and meta-narratives. Ultimately, the Christian view of reality is one that discerns a Christological unity that both preserves and harmonizes distinctions, such as we find in the great theological vision of Maximos the Confessor in the seventh century.23 But such a vision is based in the first place on the hearing and proclaiming of the Gospel as providing a comprehensive and unified view of reality. The Gospel does not tell us just a bunch of things about God and the world; it proclaims the reconciliation and recapitulation and renewal of all things in Christ. The manifold phenomena of reality are thus gathered up in the single mystery of Jesus Christ, who brings to actualization the unity of all creation with the holy Trinity. Such a vision does much more than merely affirm the internal logical coherence of the Gospel as a system of teaching; 22 23 Principles, pref. 10; Butterworth, 6. For one of his classic treatments of this theme, see his Ambiguum 7. 1080 Khaled Anatolios it also affirms the value and meaning of this world and its history as enfolded by the proclamation of the Gospel. The new evangelization would be very well served by taking account of Origen’s conception of the task of theological reflection as ordered toward a unified and comprehensive view of reality. A program of new evangelization can legitimately address many distinct issues that happen to be controverted in our time: human sexuality, social justice, the evolution of creation, and so on. But it cannot be merely reactive in addressing these issues in a piecemeal fashion because the power of the Gospel is seriously undermined when we see it merely as a set of responses to a long list of human quandaries and dilemmas. Rather, the power of the Gospel resides in the first place, as we have been saying, in its announcement of a new heaven and a new earth whose common and unified content is the newness of Christ himself. The new evangelization must be oriented ultimately to this comprehensive Christological vision that Origen insisted was the necessary goal of all theological reflection. Conclusion I suggested at the outset of this paper that what ultimately motivates the current aspiration for a new evangelization is something that goes deeper than the recognition that Christians must redouble their efforts to proclaim the message of the Gospel in the midst of a secularism that increasingly encroaches upon the world-view of even self-proclaimed Christians. I believe that this deeper motivation is the inspired realization that the essential newness of the Gospel needs to be proclaimed urgently as an antidote to a pervasive, albeit often unconscious, sense that just as the earth we live on seems long past its prime, so humanity itself seems increasingly incapable of aspiring to a future that transcends the nightmare of history and actualizes its noblest aspirations. This situation makes it imperative that Christians authentically proclaim the fullness of newness that Christ has brought into the world. The Christian tradition offers invaluable resources for this proclamation. Taking Origen’s methodological preface to his On First Principles as paradigmatic of the patristic approach to theology, I have proposed three features of this approach that seem to me to be indispensable to our contemporary efforts to proclaim anew the newness of Christ. First, we must steadfastly claim the epistemic primacy of Christ as the fundamental critical principle of Christian discourse. Second, we need to look to the tradition of the Church both for canonical safeguards A Patristic Reflection on the Nature and Method of Theology 1081 for this Christological critical principle and for inspired provocations toward the ever-deeper questing for the fullness of the new life in Christ. Finally, our proclamation of the Gospel must endeavor to enfold every aspect of human reality within its horizon, which is always nothing less than the horizon of a new heaven and a new earth that extends even into the heart of the ever-new and incorruptible life of the Father, N&V the Son, and the Holy Spirit. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1083–1098 Liturgy and Vocation Michael Heintz Mount Saint Mary’s Seminary Emmitsburg, MD Perhaps one way of defining “liturgy” is to understand it as a restored participation in the original created order. That is, by the grace of Christ, the New Adam, humanity can reclaim its Adamic vocation as priest. By the grace of baptism, Christ extends his own priesthood, sharing it with all who are born again by water and the Spirit. The baptized thus share in the unique Priesthood of Christ, which restores—and elevates—the original priesthood shared by Adam and Eve. God, as Irenaeus was to argue strenuously against Gnostic theorizing about cosmic origins, creates everything ex nihilo, out of his own goodness, and not from any need or compulsion; creation is not the result of the malevolence of a lesser deity or cosmic mismanagement on the part of an inept inferior power. The distinction central to Gnosticism—matter versus spirit—is trumped in Christian theology by a more fundamental one unavailable to the Gnostics: between created reality, comprising both matter and spirit, and the one, good God, himself distinct from but not disinterested in his creation. Creation, fashioned by the very Logos of God, “through whom all things were made” ( John 1:3, RSV), has a meaningful purpose and end. The entire created order is meant to reflect, by its very status as created, the goodness of the good God and thereby offer him glory. It is the very vocation of creation to glorify God. In this sense, the created cosmos is also a sacrament; that is, it is patent of the glory of the Creator and indeed points to him. Rational creation—encompassing both humans and the angelic orders—is to perceive God’s glory reflected in, by, and through all created things and freely to 1084 Michael Heintz order its own act of grateful praise to God. It is precisely in this way that rational creatures glorify their Creator, seeing the goodness and beauty of God’s handiwork (including their own literally marvelous existence) and glorifying God. As the French Oratorian Louis Bouyer put it most elegantly, the very heartbeat of the cosmic order is heard as the graced reciprocity of divine agape and humanity’s free— and genuinely free precisely because graced—eucharistia: Across this continuous chain of creation, in which the triune fellowship of the divine Persons has, as it were, extended and propagated itself, moves the ebb and flow of creative Agape and of created eucharistia. Descending further and further toward the final limits of the abyss of nothingness, the creative love of God reveals its full power in the response it evokes, in the joy of gratitude in which, from the very dawn of their existence creatures freely return to the One who has given them all . . . like an infinitely generous heart, beating with an unceasing diastole and systole, first diffusing the divine glory in paternal love, then continually gathering it up again to its immutable source in filial love.1 This created response, which Bouyer calls “created eucharistia,” is itself, of course, graced—the synergy of divine and human freedoms is made possible (one might even say forged) by the fire of the Spirit—for as the Apostle would chide the cliquish Corinthians, “what do you possess that you have not received?” (1 Cor 4:7). Of course, our own erratic life of prayer and the muddles of a fallen existence betray the fact that this heartbeat may not echo as clearly in our quotidian experience as Bouyer describes. But what he is describing is, of course, the original order intended by God that, despite being skewed by sin, is to be restored finally in Christ, who alone has revealed agape in its fullness. Sin—our own unreflective self-referentiality that distorts our perception of ourselves, of others, of the world, and that leads us to see God as perhaps simply not quite to be trusted, as a wily and invisible competitor for the glory we seek for ourselves—has occluded our perception of the cosmos and wreaked havoc on our imagination. The primal, sacramental nature of all that is created by God is lost on the fallen imagination, which sees things as just that—things, and no longer as signs. 1 The Meaning of the Monastic Life, trans. K. Pond (New York: P. J. Kenedy and Sons, 1955), 29 (translation revised slightly). Liturgy and Vocation 1085 Augustine, in his De doctrina christiana, argued that signs are of course also things, but in the sacramental economy it is equally important to remember that res are very much also signa. And when things no longer point to or speak of their Creator, they quickly become opaque obstacles, then substitutes, and finally idols. Ironically, the fallen imagination falters not in seeking too much from life, of aiming too high, but in settling for far too little, of aiming too low, of being willing and desirous of being satisfied with any of the various things that are meant to lead us through themselves to their Creator, and as a consequence, it both misapprehends and misuses them, simultaneously losing sight of their Creator and ours and of our true vocation and end. In short, our imagination itself needs conversion. The language enshrined at the Council of Trent—that the divine image in humanity has certainly been disfigured but not destroyed, that our wills are weakened and our intellect darkened by sin—is, of course, quite helpful in diagnosing our own inabilities and instabilities in the orders of thought and action. But perhaps another way of talking about the effect of the Fall is to say that our very imagination has been warped by sin and that it too needs grace and healing. Blessed John Henry Newman wrote of the importance of the “sacramental principle” in his own grasp of the faith: the visible world is charged with significance, manifesting unseen realities available to the eyes of faith.2 Yet, as he observed in one of his University sermons, “the influence of the world, viewed as the enemy of our souls, consists in its hold upon our imagination”3 ; he refers of course to the “world” in the Johannine sense, much as Paul uses the term “flesh,” to express the corrosive and distorting effects of self-love and the desire for domination that reign in this age.4 But with the coming of Christ in the flesh, this cosmos has begun to regain its sacramental power—this was precisely what 2 3 4 See Apologia Pro Vita Sua, ed. D. DeLaura (New York: Norton, 1968), e.g., 34. See also John R. Connolly, “Newman’s Vision of Holiness in this World,” in Newman and Life in the Spirit: Theological Reflections on Spirituality for Today, ed. J. R. Connolly and B.W. Hughes (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress, 2014), 145–65, esp. 155–57. “Human Responsibility, as Independent of Circumstances,” in Sermons, Chiefly on the Theory of Religious Belief, Preached before the University of Oxford (London: Francis and John Rivington, 1844), 139 (this sermon was preached November 4, 1832). See the superb treatment of these themes in Louis Bouyer, “The Two Economies of Divine Government: Satan and Christ,” in God and His Creation, ed. A. M. Henry (Chicago: Fides, 1955), esp. 469–75. 1086 Michael Heintz was at stake in the iconoclast debates of the eighth and ninth centuries—and glimpses of the age to come, the victory of agape and glory of Christ’s Kingdom, can be discerned even here and even now. Fr. Robert Imbelli’s recent book Rekindling the Christic Imagination is to be highly recommended in this regard: it is an extended meditation that makes splendid use of art, literature, and music as occasions and vehicles of theological reflection, pointing us ultimately to the “Love that moves the sun and the other stars.”5 Central to the thought of G. K. Chesterton, particularly in Orthodoxy and in The Everlasting Man, was to call for a re-enchantment of the imagination. Our imaginations, wounded by sin, have been further hampered by what Joseph Ratzinger would call the reduction or constriction of logos to the narrow confines of the empirical sciences, whose canons and modalities exercise an often unimaginative but growing hegemony over the academy.6 Grace brings not only enlightenment to the intellect and strengthening to the will but also re-enchantment to the imagination. Inasmuch as Truth nourishes the intellect and Good powers the will, so it is that Beauty can ravish the imagination. While modern science may classify humans as homo sapiens— beings of the genus homo literally specified by the capacity for rational thought, and whereas Karl Marx was to reduce humans to homo faber, those whose life, value, and meaning were to be identified with their capacity to produce or construct,7 the Orthodox émigré liturgiologist Fr. Alexander Schmemann has contended that the noblest definition of humanity is as homo adorans: rational beings, the full actualization of whose potentialities is to be found in the praise and worship of Almighty God.8 As created by God, we are made to worship; it is built into the very fabric of our nature: not only are we equipped for it, but it is the deepest and fullest expression of our humanity, of creatureliness at its best. It is not simply that humans have a capacity for worship—even anthropologists and sociologists might acknowledge or even highlight that phenomenon—but that worship of God is the 5 6 7 8 Rekindling the Christic Imagination:Theological Meditations for the New Evangelization (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 2014). See his Introduction to Christianity (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2004), 74–79, and the study of logos in his thought by Christopher S. Collins in The Word Made Love: The Dialogical Theology of Joseph Ratzinger (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 2013). Ratzinger’s analysis is typically shrewd (see, for example, Introduction to Christianity, 72–73). For the Life of the World (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s, 1973), 118. Liturgy and Vocation 1087 fulfillment of our humanity; we are most truly and fully who we are when we are adoring God. In the language of St. Thomas, it is the point of contact where divine and human beatitudo can be genuinely shared: our prayer, our worship, enabling a created and graced participation in God’s own beatitude. Now, in a fallen eon, this is played out in curious, if ultimately unsurprising, ways. To put it bluntly, if we are not striving to worship God, since we worship by default, as it were, then any number of things take the place of the one, true God in the pantheon of our psyche: our career, our convenience, our relationships, our comfort, our pleasure, our security, all of them of course tied to our selves by the first-person pronoun. The self-assertion and self-promotion enacted by our first parents in the garden is re-enacted, recapitulated, in our own grasping and clingy affections and aspirations. The idols we construct or erect for ourselves actually disable genuine beatitude, and so are continually knocked down and replaced in a futile striving for the very thing closer to us than we are to ourselves and yet hidden to us, occluded by our own swollen self-love. If the Scriptures begin by revealing the Adamic priesthood and the sacramentality of the cosmos, they conclude by showing us just what our true telos will be, accomplished proleptically, in Christ. While for many readers the Book of Revelation, the Apocalypse, has functioned as something of a Michelin Guide to the end of the world, so much so that, in contemporary parlance, to speak of “apocalypse” is to speak of chaos, disaster, and destruction, the fact of the matter is that the “revelation” being made in the letters addressed to the seven churches is not principally the coming “events” rocking the first century Roman world (or, for that matter, our own), but rather what is unseen and unknown to the oppressing pagan powers and cosmic principalities yet available to the baptized: the victory of the Lamb. The book is less about plagues, trumpets, vials, seals, and woes and much more about witness and worship: martyria, latreia, and the privileged nature of that witness as worship. Arguably, the most fruitful reading of Revelation is to see at the center of the work what is revealed to John the visionary in chapters 4 and 5. The veil is lifted, and the eternal worship of God and the Lamb is, for a moment, made visible to the persecuted churches of Asia Minor (and subsequent generations of listeners and readers). What is being revealed is that, in the face of the horrors of persecution and the seeming ascendancy of evil, the victory is already won: it is accomplished and effected by a love that is willing to suffer, by 1088 Michael Heintz the Lamb who is also the Lion of the Tribe of Judah, and communicated, made both real and available, in the Church’s liturgy. In fact, the center panel of the Ghent altarpiece, which depicts the heavenly worship of the Lamb that is described in Revelation and in which our earthly liturgy participates, captures with splendor what the Second Vatican Council affirmed as the Church’s fullest identity, being gathered around the altar, praising and adoring God in Christ. One of the most beautiful manifestations of this mystery each year is the Chrism Mass during Holy Week, which really is a snapshot of the Church most fully in act, one might say: as James Joyce had described the Church Catholic, “here comes everybody,”9 which is only a modern Hibernian rendition of St. Ephrem’s maternal image of the “big church with the big lap”10 —lay, religious, priests, deacons, the elect of the catechumenate, and the entire local Church together celebrating the Lamb’s Supper under the presidency of the Bishop. The telos of redeemed creation is thus revealed and glimpsed even now, a telos made possible by a divine economy whose power is agape and whose wisdom is subversive to all that fallen minds can conceive or construct. Further, those who follow the Lamb, who still bears his wounds, not only witness this love made visible; what is more, they are made capable of sharing it, participating in it, and uniting themselves to it. Their love, their sacrifice, can participate in and be made one with his unique and all-sufficient sacrifice, and—in and through the liturgy—it already is. The key to their (and our) experiences, the key to the meaning of all things, is precisely the One who is worthy to break open the seals and unravel the scroll. If we seek meaning, we need look no further than to the Logos (meaning)-made-flesh, who is simultaneously the fullest revelation of agape, of what this meaning looks like concretely: crucified love. Within what biblical scholars refer to as Jesus’s “high priestly prayer,” part and parcel of John’s account of the Last Supper, he prays for his disciples and those—like us—who will believe because of them. The mission of the Son in the temporal order is to give glory to the Father, a glory shared fully and eternally with his Son and now refracted in the created order by the Incarnation, a glory now illumined by the Cross and Resurrection. Our vocation, the vocation 9 10 From Finnegan’s Wake (1939). Hymns against Heresies, 2.16–17, quoted in Simon Tugwell, “Revelation and Human Experience,” New Blackfriars 60 (1979):500–15, at 509 (it is worth noting that its original context for St. Ephrem was anti-Marcionite). Liturgy and Vocation 1089 of those called to be sons and daughters in the Son, is to participate by grace in that mission. This, in theological terms, is what the fifth chapter of Lumen Gentium meant when it spoke of the “universal call to holiness.” It means nothing more—but also nothing less—than a created participation in the Eternal Son, a genuinely filial (and not merely metaphorical) relation to the Father through the Son, in the Holy Spirit: this is what divinizes our humanity; this is what St. Thomas meant by beatitudo, not as a passive state, but as an active participation in the triune life of God. This is what the liturgy and the entire sacramental economy communicates in and through the Church: it reveals to us and makes possible our share in this eternal relation to God the Father, a deeply personal and abiding communio. The Son’s mission is to glorify the Father and to implicate his followers, literally to enfold them, to clothe them, in this glorification and in his own priesthood (hence the baptismal garment11). In turn, the Father glorifies the Son, and those who live in him. Christ, the new Adam, restores and elevates that original vocation of the old Adam in and through his own created human nature. How is it, precisely, that the Son “glorifies” the Father? In Johannine language, the “hour” of Jesus and his “glory,” anticipated throughout his ministry by the seven signs chosen and highlighted by the Evangelist, coincide on the cross. The supreme sacrifice—one to which all the sacrifices of the Old Law pointed and that they anticipated and from which they take their true meaning (much of the second-century bishop Melito’s hymn on the Pasch sees all the rituals of the old as somehow participating in the one perfect Pasch of Christ12 )—the perfect and complete act of worship is discovered in Christ’s self-gift to the Father on our behalf. Christ is, at this moment, as the fifth Paschal Preface says, “the priest, the altar, and the lamb of sacrifice.” Crucified, paschal love, self-donation, the Son’s agape, is the essence of this glorification. For Christians, the Cross is always, as Bouyer would say, illumined by the resurrection, but the 11 12 Being clothed in the baptismal garment (in which Christ’s priesthood is quite literally “implied”) also communicates his very life. See the dated but still valuable study by J. Quasten, “The Garment of Immortality: A Study of the Accipe vestem candidam,” in Miscellanea Liturgica in onore di Sua Eminenza il Cardinale Giacomo Lercaro (Rome: Desclée, 1966–67), 1:391–401, although he perhaps gives too much attention to pagan precedents and inadequate weight to the Pauline theology of Rom 13:14 and Gal 3:27. See G. S. Hall, Melito of Sardis: On Pascha and Fragments (Oxford: Clarendon, 2012). 1090 Michael Heintz only way to that life is through that self-gift; there is nothing whatsoever magical about it.13 Just as the Son, by such love, glorifies the Father, so the Father glorifies the Son, whose risen life witnesses that glory and communicates this risen life to his disciples. To speak of vocation as participation in the Son’s glorification of the Father means that the essence of our vocation must be self-gift, a crucified, paschal love like Christ’s. In the tenth book of his massive City of God, Augustine engages in a lengthy reflection of the nature of sacrifice, culminating in a discussion of the sacrifice of Christians. He makes very clear that God does not need any of the things offered to him in sacrifice: “Far from needing cattle or any other earthly or corruptible thing, we must believe that God does not need even the righteousness of men and women; for it is men and women, not God, who benefit from the worship rightly offered to God. No one says he does any service to a spring by drinking from it or to a light by looking at it.”14 Still, what is it that these external sacrifices are meant to represent or engender? Simply put, it is charity, the twin-love of God and of neighbor with reference to God that forms the heart of Augustine’s view of the Christian life: We can see now that these sacrifices are to be understood as symbolizing the love of God and the love of one’s neighbor. . . . Thus, true sacrifice is offered in every act which is intended to unite us to God in a holy bond: this means that every act directed toward our final good that makes true happiness possible for us. . . . True sacrifices are acts of mercy, whether toward ourselves or our neighbors, when they are referred to 13 14 “So we see how this life can and must become a preparation for eternity: first of all by becoming an anticipation of it, through the effective presence here on earth of the charity which will blossom into life eternal. It is admittedly a paradoxical kind of anticipation: in eternity, life with God, life in God’s love, will be nothing but life, and superabundant life; here and now it implies the Cross, and can only be achieved through the Cross. For the Christian, however, the Cross is already illuminated by the resurrection. Even the Cross itself is glorious when seen from inside, as the earthly fulfillment of what Christ brought to it, the love of God. The Christian’s cross, like Christ’s, is a victory, still hidden, but already visible to the eyes of faith”; see Bouyer, Christian Initiation (London: Burns and Oates, 1960), 116. City of God 10.5, trans. H. Bettenson (London: Penguin, 1972), 377 (revised slightly). Liturgy and Vocation 1091 God, and these acts of mercy are intended to liberate us from our misery and bring us true happiness. This being said, it follows that the entire Redeemed Community, that is, the congregation and fellowship of the saints, is offered to God as a universal sacrifice, through the Great Priest who offered Himself in His suffering for us—in order to make us the Body of so great a Head—in the form of a servant (Phil 2:7). For it was this “form” that He offered, and it was in this “form” that He was offered, because it was precisely in this form that He was the Mediator. In this “form” He is both priest and sacrifice. Thus the Apostle Paul exhorts us to offer our bodies as a living sacrifice, holy and acceptable to God (Rom 12:3) as the spiritual homage that we owe Him. . . . For we ourselves are that whole sacrifice.15 What God desires, or requires, is that we make a gift of ourselves in and through the Body of his Son, which is the Church. As Augustine concludes: “This is the sacrifice of Christians who, though many, make up one Body in Christ. This is the sacrifice which the Church continually celebrates in the sacrament of the altar, a sacrament well-known to believers, where it is shown to the Church that she herself is offered in the very offering she makes to God.”16 This is an expression of the admirabile commercium—the marvelous exchange—first spoken of in the Epistle to Diognetus17 in the second century and later enshrined in the liturgical texts of the Christmas Octave, an expression not only of the mystery of the Incarnation but also of how that mystery is celebrated and experienced by Christians in the sacrament of the altar. What God offers us is nothing less than himself. What he asks of us is nothing less than ourselves. In this exchange he communicates to us his own divine life, and he who was rich but became poor for our sake freely imparts to us poor creatures his own richness. In a recent article, Fr. Michael Lang has argued that one must read this particular text from Augustine carefully in its context as apologetic over and against pagan sacrificial systems, as Augustine was often cited by the sixteenth- and seventeenth-century reform15 16 17 Ibid., 10.5–6 (pp. 379–80; revised slightly). Ibid., 10.6 (p. 380; revised slightly), cited in the Catechism of the Catholic Church, at § 1372. Epistle to Diognetus 9; the otherwise unknown author wrote ca. AD 180. 1092 Michael Heintz ers as witness to the effect that external rites are unnecessary and that the internal, personal dimensions of this self-gift are what truly matter. While Fr. Lang’s analysis is clear, perceptive, and helpful, I would further posit that those who are tempted to juxtapose external ritual and internal disposition vis-à-vis the Eucharist are apt to miss their vital connection. It is precisely the Eucharist that forms in us the capacity for self-gift, for paschal love. If the external rites remain simply symbolic acts, tokens of a love accomplished long ago, a passion play meant to stir our hearts to a similar love, then, to paraphrase Flannery O’Connor, “to hell with them.”18 But if they are in fact efficacious signs, signs that truly accomplish what they signify, then it is the sacrament of the altar that both enables and forms in us this capacity for paschal love. It is actually his love with which we love because we eat it, we drink it, and we assimilate it: his love becomes our love. Our ineffectual love is taken up into his own, efficacious love, and, to use Augustine’s language, we ourselves are offered in the very offering we make to God. Our self-gift is united with his self-gift, our feeble and often feckless sacrifices to his one, all-sufficient and perfect sacrifice, and our participation at the altar capacitates us to love as he loves, to die as he died so as to live through him and with him and in him (is this not—rather than maudlin displays of sentimentality and quasi-canonizations—fundamentally the theology of the Order of Christian Funerals?). The Eucharist is, then, the culmen at fons, the source and summit, because our love finds both its origin and its telos in Christ, dead and risen. The mission of the Church is not simply to proclaim the good news, to bring information hitherto unavailable to more and more people. It is rather to communicate his very life to the world. Ours is a Church of Word and Sacrament, the latter simply the enacting or embodiment of the former. What is communicated in the sacraments is the Word: the Word-made-flesh. I have referred repeatedly to the language of vocation throughout this essay, and I have done so in a way that makes clear the multivalent quality of the term. If, in fact, one were to ask a gathering of Catholics what their vocation is, I suspect the great majority would immediately refer to their state of life: married, single, vowed religious, or 18 Her precise words, in reference to discussion of the Real Presence, were, “Well, if it’s a symbol, to hell with it”; found in a letter to Betty Hester written on December 16, 1955; see The Habit of Being, ed. Sally Fitzgerald (New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux, 1988), 125. Liturgy and Vocation 1093 ordained. A few theological sophisticates might offer a correction to that and indicate that their fundamental vocation is holiness of life. But I would like to suggest we consider vocation in concentric circles, the most fundamental of which is not our particular state of life, nor even our baptismal vocation to holiness of life, but our very existence itself: our life is itself a vocation. None of us exists by our own will or choice, and each life is a precious calling-into-being by the Supernal Love that crafted all things into existence out of nothing. In one sense, it is quite obvious, and yet it is imperative that we start here: with the utter gratuity of our being, a wonder and marvel captured and pondered by the Psalmist in the Psalm 139. It is the fundamental Christian distinction,19 between God and all else that is, everything else that is created and thus dependent for its existence on his gracious will alone, the distinction that undercuts all Gnostic, Manichaean, and Albigensian dualisms of matter and spirit and that should underline and reinforce the utter gratuity of all vocation: at every level, in every concentric circle, we start with a gift, not something that is “just there,” that can explain itself, much less justify itself. The revised translation of the Roman Missal makes clear that what we offer God is nothing but what we have first received: “Blessed are you Lord God of all creation, for through your goodness we have received the bread we offer you, fruit of the earth and work of human hands, it will become for us the bread of life.” These words, frequently prayed sotto voce or covered by music, capture crisply the essence of the admirabile commercium: we present what we can muster, itself merely what we have first received. In exchange, God’s Spirit transforms that humble, simple gift, much as it transformed that lowly maiden’s fiat, and offers us to us the fullness of his own divine life, the Word-made-flesh anew under the appearances of the very bread and wine we have offered. The essence of the vocation to holiness is, as I have suggested, to participate in the eternal Son’s temporal mission, the glorification the Father. As Irenaeus had taught, this glorification is found in the full actualization of our created humanity: gloria Dei vivens homo. But he also goes on to specify more clearly what that means: the life of the human is the vision of God. There is no autonomous creaturely 19 See Robert Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), who argues not only that this is the Christian distinction, but also that this distinction affects every aspect of Christian doctrine and practice in a very particular way. 1094 Michael Heintz or human flourishing apart from the very vision of God. And, for Irenaeus, there is no knowledge of the Father apart from the Son: what is visible or seen of the Father is the Son.20 In short, there is no holiness that is not Christocentric, and our glorification of the Father happens precisely through the Son, in our becoming, by the action of the Spirit, sons- and daughters-in-the-Son and offering ourselves to the Father with his Eternal Son. Our becoming disciples and bearing fruit glorifies the Father, and this happens only to the degree that we unite ourselves to the Son in his self-gift, his paschal love, a self-gift that, now that the Son has ascended and is seated at the Father’s right hand, is indeed eternal.21 This is what it means, following the Letter to the Hebrews, to say that Jesus has an eternal priesthood: in the risen and glorified Jesus, now ascended to the Father, our Adamic humanity has achieved its true end, and the priestly vocation intended by God in his creative design is now fulfilled in Jesus, while not yet in us. Further, the eternal self-giving of the incarnate Son to the Father, in which the baptized are called to an ever-deeper participation, is not static, but dynamic. As the biblical theologian François-Xavier Durrwell wrote during the great biblical ressourcement of the mid-twentieth century, with a kind of oxymoronic panache, Christ is “fixed forever in his redemptive act.” He goes on: Christ will never leave behind the immolation and that new life; his existence is fixed forever at the moment of the Redemption. The five wounds he showed his disciples are not merely the receipt for our ransom inscribed upon his body, but the wounds of a death from which he will never recover. . . . The life of glory is a perpetuation of his death; the fire of the Spirit which consumes him keeps him as an eternal holocaust. The Lamb of God stands in glory and is surrounded by hymns 20 21 For example, Adversus haereses 4.6.3: “Et propter hoc Filius revelat agnitionem Patris per suam manifestationem. Agnitio enim Patris est Filii manifestation [Thus, the Son reveals knowledge of the Father in manifesting himself. For knowledge of the Father is the manifestation of the Son]”; in Adversus Haereses, Fontes Christiani 8/4 (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder, 1997). See also the incisive study of M. C. Steenberg, On God and Man: Theology as Anthropology from Irenaeus to Athanasius (London: T&T Clark, 2009). See Douglas Farrow, Ascension Theology (London: T&T Clark, 2011), who argues that the Ascension is integral to a full appreciation of the Paschal Mystery. Liturgy and Vocation 1095 of triumph, but he is still slain. . . . That ever actual glorifying action coincides with Christ’s death, and thus keeps the Savior forever at the moment of his death to the world, at the high point of giving himself to the Father. . . . The Church, identified with Christ finds this salvation of the Resurrection because she is incorporated into the Savior, not in this or that moment of his life—Bethlehem, Nazareth, the roads of Palestine—not yet in a heavenly existence subsequent to the act of redemption, but in the act of Redemption itself. She is the Body of Christ in one precise, and henceforth, eternal, moment, in the moment when the redemption takes place, in the moment of his death on the cross, when Christ was glorified by the Father.22 As an eternal self-gift, this act of the Son is fixed but not frozen; it is dynamic but unrepeatable. At our baptism, when we are plunged into the dying and rising of Jesus, we are capacitated for this paschal love. And this paschal love, this self-gift, which is both engendered by and participates in Christ’s agape while refracted differently in the various states of life that adorn and enrich his earthly Body, the Church, is nonetheless one and the same for married, vowed religious, single, and ordained. In the economy of grace, no gift, grace, or vocation is given that is not given precisely for others. As Paul told the Corinthians, “If we are encouraged, it is for your encouragement” (2 Cor 1:6). That is, there is no gift given by God simply or merely for the recipient. In fact, the moment one mistakes the gift for a possession, when one clings to what is meant as gift as if it were solely for oneself, one simply recapitulates the sin of Adam and Eve. No, in the economy of grace, every gift is bestowed never solely or even primarily for the recipient, but upon the recipient precisely for others. Our sanctification will be accomplished in our “paying forward” the gift, not in preening ourselves over it like a coveted award or spiritual honorarium. And what is true of any particular grace or divine gift is equally true of vocation. No one is called to marriage for herself or himself; they are called for the sanctification of their spouse and children; no man is called to diaconal or priestly ministry for himself, but for the good of the Body, the Church; no contemplative religious is called simply so that he or she can stockpile merit or catalogue their experiences as they trundle along the unitive way (recall that both 22 In the Redeeming Christ (Notre Dame, IN: Christian Classics, 2013), 5–8. 1096 Michael Heintz Teresa of Avila and Thérèse of Lisieux wrote only under obedience, for their superiors discerned that their experiences were not granted to them principally for themselves, but for others). We can ponder, in the concrete terms of our own life, for example, what this might look like. Those called to marriage are called to sanctify their spouse; those to priesthood, to sanctify their spouse, the Church—and, it is important to note, not a “reified” Church or an abstract husband or wife, but the actual people to whom one is espoused, in all their quirky individuality and fragile human particularity; so that, whether it is in marrying Walburga or Clovis or being assigned to St. Swithun’s-by-the-Swamp, there is where holiness is to be found. The degree to which we edify, literally “build up,” others into the Body of Christ, the more we assist them in their own bearing fruit and becoming better disciples, the more indeed we participate in the Son’s glorification of the Father, and the holier we, too, become. But this is almost, as the saints would have us know, as an afterthought. Our baptismal vocation—the second concentric circle to which I have referred—is holiness of life. Its essence is self-gift, a participation in Christ’s self-gift, which is why the Eucharist and participation in the sacrament of the altar is considered the fullness of Christian initiation. The Eucharist forms in us this charity, this agape or paschal love, and enables us, by participation, to make a genuine gift of ourselves. This self-gift is, however, necessarily cruciform because, in a fallen cosmos, every self-gift, even graced, must labor against sin’s bloated and ingrown torpor. Christ crucified reveals what real love looks like in a sinful cosmos. For, when pure love, divine love, agape, enters a world turned in on itself, a world whose operating system is self-love (precisely what St. Paul means by “flesh” and Saint John by “the world”), closed off by fear from any other possibility, such pure love is neither fully received nor fully reciprocated. In such a fallen and rebellious cosmos, that pure love, divine love, encountering indifference, denial, and rejection, is not welcomed with humility and delight but is refracted in suffering. Such pure love can be expressed fully in a sinful and contorted world only as sacrifice. For rational creatures whose will is wounded—that is, for us—real love, self-gift, agape, will always involve some kind of dying; it will necessitate sacrifice. Further, there is no Christian state of life—married, vowed, ordained, or single—that does not require self-gift or that is not animated by paschal love. It will of course look somewhat differ- Liturgy and Vocation 1097 ent—a married couple with children in the suburbs; a Carthusian solitary in Vermont; a parish priest in Boise; a single person living and working in Chicago—each is called to holiness in a way particular to the demands of their circumstances and the promises and commitments each has made. But the love in which each participates is none other than Christ’s love poured into our hearts by the Holy Spirit. And as different as these individuals or any individuals may be from one another, that love as such is the vinculum, the bond that binds the Church together, that links them and relates them one to another even if they have never met, or even if they live in two different millennia. I conclude these reflections with a brief meditation on one of the most ancient vocation stories in Christian history. It happened on a beach shortly after the Lord had risen. It is found in the tail end of the Fourth Gospel. And it is precisely about the vocation to love: When they climbed out on shore, they saw a charcoal fire with fish on it and bread. Jesus said to them, “Bring some of the fish you just caught.” So Simon Peter went over and dragged the net ashore full of one hundred fifty-three large fish. Even though there were so many, the net was not torn. Jesus said to them, “Come, have breakfast.” And none of the disciples dared to ask him, “Who are you?” because they realized it was the Lord. Jesus came over and took the bread and gave it to them, and in like manner the fish. This was now the third time Jesus was revealed to his disciples after being raised from the dead. When they had finished breakfast, Jesus said to Simon Peter, “Simon, son of John, do you love me more than these?” He said to him, “Yes, Lord, you know that I love you.” He said to him, “Feed my lambs.” He then said to him a second time, “Simon, son of John, do you love me?” He said to him, “Yes, Lord, you know that I love you.” He said to him, “Tend my sheep.” He said to him the third time, “Simon, son of John, do you love me?” Peter was distressed that he had said to him a third time, “Do you love me?” and he said to him, “Lord, you know everything; you know that I love you.” [ Jesus] said to him, “Feed my sheep. Amen, amen, I say to you, when you were younger, you used to dress yourself and go where you wanted; but when you grow old, you will stretch out your hands, and someone else will dress you and lead you where 1098 Michael Heintz you do not want to go.” He said this signifying by what kind of death he would glorify God. And when he had said this, he said to him, “Follow me.” ( John 21:9–19) The seemingly insignificant detail—a charcoal fire (anthrakian)— sets the scene, and the tone. Peter, if you recall, had just recently, after three direct inquiries, vehemently denied knowing Jesus, and he did so while warming himself in the company of others, at a charcoal fire (anthrakian, John 18:18). Jesus’s dialogue with Peter here is taking place on two different planes. They are, as it were, speaking in two different registers, and actually about two different loves. It is easy to forget that while, lexically, agape may have been available in the ancient vocabulary, at least in its form and content, Jesus brings something utterly new to its meaning. Jesus asks of Peter’s love using the verbal cognate of agape. Peter replies using a different term but one with a noble pedigree, philein, a verb ironically that Aristotle had once associated with loyalty. Jesus repeats his question, and Peter musters his reply, again using the verb philein. The third time, in a move that recapitulates in microcosm the humble accommodation of the Incarnation, Jesus adopts Peter’s term, philein, as if to say, “I will meet you where you are to be found, but do not expect to stay there,” as Jesus goes on to indicate how Peter would himself one day participate in the mystery of his own crucified, agapic love. In the end, God will accept whatever it is we can muster. And he will give N&V us what we cannot. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1099–1111 The Seminary and Western Culture: Relationships that Promote Recovery and Holiness James Keating Institute for Priestly Formation Creighton University Omaha, NE “The fault line of our culture . . . is that we have been willing to sacrifice objective truth in order to save subjective freedom, understood particularly as freedom of choice by an autonomous self. . . . This fault line will eventually erode our civilization from within, just as the willingness on the part of Marxist societies to sacrifice personal freedom for social justice (. . . brutal equality) eroded those societies.”1 This quote from Cardinal Francis George, echoing ideas of St. John Paul II, highlights the corrosive effect the autonomous self can have upon culture when such autonomy is that culture’s supreme principle. In contradistinction, he raises the example of Marxism, as well. These remarks from Cardinal George were written in 2008; and by our current time, not only had the North American population been long tutored in autonomy by the popular culture, but also its government and professions had begun tutoring the populace in Marxist principles as well. For example, the United States Government promulgated the Affordable Care Act, undermining religious freedom as it sought to impose a universal duty for employers to provide abortifacients, as well as other contraceptives, in their health care benefits. A weakening of religious freedom was also recognized within the culture as government leaders 1 Cardinal Francis George, O.M.I., The Difference God Makes (New York: Crossroad, 2009), 68. 1100 James Keating narrowed their articulation of such from the “right to religious freedom” to the “right to worship.”2 Similarly, the triumph of gay marriage in the US Courts created a cultural condition wherein individuals find it more burdensome to refuse to cooperate with same sex weddings, leaving private businesses exposed to punishment for not assisting homosexuals with the supplies or services they need to legally wed and celebrate such a wedding.3 In Canada, further individual freedoms were sacrificed for “justice” when the Ontario College of Physicians and Surgeons declared that physicians had to refer women to doctors who would perform abortions if, in conscience, the referring physician could not himself or herself perform such a procedure. It was declared by the College that referring clients to such abortion providers was not cooperation with evil, since no woman should ever be refused an abortion and be given no alternative for her “care.”4 In the area of the triumph of the autonomous self, it has become a sign of “intolerance” to make moral judgments about the sexual behaviors of others. When the archbishop of San Francisco attempted to update his teachers’ moral clauses as contingent upon further employment, 80 percent of the teachers employed by the archdiocesan school system revolted. Apparently, even if one is employed by the Church, subjective freedom trumps truth.5 2 3 4 5 “Religious Liberty vs. Erotic Liberty—Religious Liberty Is Losing,” January 12, 2015, on Albert Mohler’s official website (copr. 2002–2016), last accessed August 8, 2016, http://www.albertmohler.com/2015/01/12/religious-liberty-vs-erotic-liberty-religious-liberty-is-losing/. See also Paul Moses, “Freedom of Worship vs. Freedom of Religion,” Commonweal, February 22, 2012, last accessed August 6, 2016, https://www.commonwealmagazine.org/blog/ freedom-worship-vs-freedom-religion. Alyssa Newcomb, “Washington Florist Sued for Refusing To Provide Flowers for Same Sex Wedding,” ABC News, April 10, 2013, last accessed August 6, 2016http://abcnews.go.com/Business/washington-florist-sued-refusing-provide-flowers-sex-wedding/story?id=18922065. Michael Swan, “Ontario Doctors Must Refer for Abortions, Says College of Physicians,” The Catholic Register, March 5, 2015, last accessed August 6, 2016, http://www.catholicregister.org/item/19833-ontario-doctors-must-referfor-abortions-says-college-of-physicians. Kevin Fagan, “S. F. City Attorney Argues Against Archbishop’s Morality Clauses,” SF Gate, March 6, 2015, last accessed August 6, 2016, http:// www.sfgate.com/bayarea/article/S-F-city-attorney-argues-against-archbishop-s-6119697.php. “Hundreds of San Francisco Catholic School Teachers Urge Archbishop To Remove Morality Clauses,” Huffington Post, March 4, 2015, last accessed August 6, 2016, http://www.huffingtonpost. com/2015/03/04/san-francisco-catholic-teachers-morality_n_6799864.html. The Seminary and Western Culture 1101 This strangely divided culture where the autonomous self reigns alongside governmental and institutional attacks on the individual conscience in the name of “justice” calls for a profound deliberation on the part of seminary formation staff. What kind of formation is needed today so that these future priests may preach the Gospel to such a culture and, at the same time, “recover” from such a culture themselves? Such recovery may be necessary due to a man’s exposure to either the ideology of subjective freedom over truth or an understanding that “justice” warrants the undermining of freedom of conscience (or to both). Beyond these two distortions of public life, recovery may also be needed because of the personal “wounds” present in seminarians as they disentangle themselves from popular culture to enter formation: gaming addictions, addictions to pornography, effects of parental divorce upon maturation, drug or alcohol use, a history of unchaste behaviors, resistance to authority, and so on. Men interested in entering the seminary should, of course, not be admitted if addictions are present or serious emotional wounds remain from aspects of their upbringing. However, even those not-so-burdened may carry the marks of a culture that gives a man little or no guidance on personal freedom or how to appropriate a way of life marked by spiritual discipline. This article will first look at the Catholic understanding of culture and its importance for forming character and then notice what unique features of seminary formation offer ways to both engage culture and be healed of its deleterious effects. How Does the Church Understand Culture? Culture arises from man’s self-understanding regarding the use of reason and freedom. In this way, culture is basic: it is present and is established wherever man endeavors to express what he has judged to be the meaning of existence.6 Due to freedom and sin, this judgment is not infallible and cultures can be corrupt or anemic in expressing values that carry truth and beauty to the persons being formed within them. Therefore, culture contains and conveys the values of any current epoch. Culture necessarily carries with it morals and religious meaning and patterns of whom or what is to be worshipped. The Book of Wisdom gives a primordial view of culture when it says, “And in your 6 For more on the meaning of culture, see Robert Barron, “To Evangelize the Culture,” Chicago Studies, last accessed August 6, 2016, http://chicagostudies. org/Barron_Evangelization_Article. 1102 James Keating wisdom [You] have established humankind . . . to govern the world in holiness and righteousness, and to render judgment in integrity of heart” (Wis 9:2–3). Such was noted by the Pontifical Council for Culture: [Culture] is the whole of human activity, human intelligence and emotions, the human quest for meaning, human customs and ethics. In a pastoral approach to culture, what is at stake is for human beings to be restored in fullness to having been created in “the image and likeness of God” (Gen 1:26), tearing them away from the anthropocentric temptation of considering themselves independent from the Creator. . . . Man always exists in a particular culture, but it must also be admitted that man is not exhaustively defined by that same culture. Human nature is itself the measure of culture and the condition of ensuring that man does not become prisoner of any of his cultures, but asserts his personal dignity by living in accordance with the profound truth of his being.7 In the educational and political culture, many subscribe to postmodernism, where language has little or no meaning and so Catholicism’s approach to objective truth and even the existence of a “human nature” is irrelevant and passé. From a faith perspective, Western culture can become wearying to live in because it carries in its institutions and governments a “radical emancipation of man from God” and, therefore, from a clarity regarding truth. In the end, the truth is relativized, as in the case of postmodernism, or narrowed, as in the case of scientism. Could it be possible that one reason seminary enrollment has increased in the twenty-first century is the spiritual fatigue carried in Western men as they labor to breathe in the culture’s thin air of unmoored reason passing for philosophical inquiry? While cultures corrupt, they are never intrinsically evil, since the Church and others who perceive that truth is accessible to human reason hold such absolute denigration at bay.8 While cultures are subject to change and decay, the primacy of Christ is an unquenchable source of life (cf. Col 1:8–12; Eph 7 8 Pontifical Council for Culture, Towards a Pastoral Approach to Culture (1999), §2, quoting Pope John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor (1993), §53. See Thomas Woods, Jr., How the Catholic Church Built Western Civilization (Washington, DC: Regnery, 2005), 9–10. The Seminary and Western Culture 1103 1:8). As bearers of the absolute novelty of Christ to the heart of different cultures, Gospel missionaries incessantly exceed the limits of each individual culture, without allowing themselves to be ensnared by the earthly visions of a better world. Since the kingdom of Christ is not of this world (cf. John 18:36), the Church does not take away anything from the temporal welfare of any people. Rather, she fosters and takes to herself, insofar as they are good, the abilities, the resources and customs of peoples. In so taking them to herself, she purifies, strengthens, and elevates them.9 The Church (and therefore its future priests) loves the culture it is living within.10 Despite a culture’s challenges, one cannot simply critique culture; one also has to behold the beauty of what humans create and sustain within any given historical epoch. “A culture is transformed only by those who love it, just as individuals are converted only by evangelizers who love them. . . . The best way to evangelize is through witness and the practice of holiness. . . . The saints will always ratify what is best about a culture, and they will always properly critique what is demonic about it.”11 Holiness, the search to remain in unceasing union with the Trinity and bear the fruit of such union to the culture, provides the best platform from 9 10 11 Pontifical Council for Culture, Towards a Pastoral Approach, §4. Second Vatican Council, Presbyterorum Ordinis (1965), §19: “Since human culture and also sacred science has progressed in our times, priests are urged to suitably and without interruption perfect their knowledge of divine things and human affairs and so prepare themselves to enter more opportunely into conversation with their contemporaries.” Cardinal George, The Difference God Makes, 58. Pope John Paul II highlights the ambivalent nature of our current age regarding moral values in culture in Pastores Dabo Vobis (1992), §§8–9. He also mentions there the progress that some cultures can embody as they move beyond certain ideologies and how new generations affirm what is good and noble about the human vocation: “First of all, mention should be made of the decrease of certain phenomena which had caused many problems in the recent past, such as radical rebellion, libertarian tendencies, utopian claims, indiscriminate forms of socialization and violence. It must be recognized, moreover, that today’ s young people, with the vigor and vitality typical of their age, are also bearers of ideals which are coming to the fore in history: the thirst for freedom; the recognition of the inestimable value of the person; the need for authenticity and sincerity; a new conception and style of reciprocity in the rapport between men and women; a convinced and earnest seeking after a more just, sympathetic and united world; openness and dialogue with all; and the commitment to peace” (§9). 1104 James Keating which to both affirm and critique the culture. The way of holiness is the way of priestly formation. And yet, holiness is cautiously held as an “ideal” on some seminary faculties who see such as “premature” for seminarians or simply a poetic way of encouraging what is real but not yet relevant. However, if seminary formators would invite men to relentlessly relate all that they need to the One who desires to give them all that is needed, then the very ground for holiness is fixed. This reality of a providential God is itself mediated by the spiritual vulnerability possessed by formators in their duty to facilitate human and spiritual maturation in seminarians. This vulnerability can be secured by way of the laudable commitment of rectors to encourage universal spiritual direction for their faculty and formation staff. Similarly, maturation in seminarians can be achieved only through their hospitality to the truth as it is mediated by the relationships that are the seminary (God, staff, teachers, peers). The seminarian, like the culture, needs to be receptive to the truths God wishes to impart about himself and about those aspects of each man that need both purification and affirmation. The Formation of Holy Priests as a Response to Culture: Recovery by Way of Relationships of Love and Truth One of the consistent themes in priestly formation is the goal of forming integrated men. To be integrated is to have suffered in one’s own body the coming together of theological truth, prayerful availability to God in all things, moral maturation, and pastoral charity. This integration occurs through the suffering that happens in a man over time as his ego makes room for theological truth and the needs of the poor, prayer as his very breath, and moral and emotional conversion as his ready disposition. Most basically, seminarian formation facilitates a capacity to undergo repentance over any refusal to love and to welcome healing around any incapacity to receive love. The relationships within the seminary are a progressive conspiracy by God and staff to bring the seminarian deeper into reality and disabuse him of any habit of hiding in culturally acceptable fantasies. These fantasies could be nesting in disproportionate use of technological devices, escapist behavior in entertainment or food or sex; they could be neurotically sought after in a the search for influence, power, “success,” or an independent spirit. As the Program of Priestly Formation indicates, a seminarian leaves fantasy, enters reality, and is sustained in it only if he suffers the coming The Seminary and Western Culture 1105 of Christ and endeavors to remain in him (John 15:4).12 To remain in him is to exist in reality. To remain in him and, therefore, exist in reality is to be a man who is spiritually formed.13 Such a formation is a suffering of detachment from both the imaginary visions within the mind and heart and the objective fantasies that are communicated to a man by culture. The man who “remains” in Christ is free. Only those who commune with the source are free (John 15:5). Such communion allows a man to see that any one culture does not exhaust the meaning of one’s own being. If successful seminary formation is a progressive “breathing together” in the Spirit (con-spiracy) by those who want to be brought deeper into reality, then what moves a man to such depths? Primarily, it is the capacity of a seminarian to entrust himself to the Spirit in and through the relationship he forges with his formators. If a man wants to recover from the culture that has wounded him, then he needs to be able to stand the pain of self-examination. Such pain is borne well only because the seminarian “remains” in Christ and decides to entrust the truth about himself to the formation staff—even if this means that no vocation to priesthood is discerned. The seminary, viewed as a set of relationships, aids seminarians in recovering from the culture by having them seek freedom from all that binds them to ideology,14 or in the realm of spiritual progress, all that binds them to lies about themselves or their relationship with God. One enters the relationships that are a seminary, of course, to seek priesthood, but a man cannot assume that, once he is “set free” ( John 11:44), an 12 13 14 United States Council of Catholic Bishops, Program of Priestly Formation, 5th ed. (Washington, DC: USCCB, 2006), §115:“Since spiritual formation is the core that unifies the life of a priest, it stands at the heart of seminary life and is the center around which all other aspects are integrated.” See also §108. John Paul II, Pastores Dabo Vobis, §45: “Spiritual formation . . . should be conducted in such a way that the students may learn to live in intimate and unceasing union with God the Father through his Son Jesus Christ, in the Holy Spirit. Those who are to take on the likeness of Christ the priest by sacred ordination should form the habit of drawing close to him as friends in every detail of their lives. They should live his paschal mystery in such a way that they will know how to initiate into it the people committed to their charge.” See Vatican II, Presbyterorum Ordinis, §8: “In building the Christian community, priests are never to put themselves at the service of some human faction of ideology, but, as heralds of the Gospel and shepherds of the Church, they are to spend themselves for the spiritual growth of the Body of Christ.” 1106 James Keating ordination date will be given.15 A man enters seminary to hear the voice of Christ call. But he cannot listen if he is bound to lies about his identity or enmeshed in habits that prevent him from receiving the consolation of Christ’s own voice, a voice carrying truth in love. If the seminarian becomes free enough to hear Christ call and then becomes a priest, he will then, as a sacrament, descend upon the culture to affect it by way of his freedom, a freedom that is a binding to Christ. In this man’s very communion with Christ is the source of his public witness. Without seminary facilitating this realignment of what binds a man, the priest would simply be a citizen of his time, possessing no more fecund imagination than one found within the limits of politics, economics, entertainment, and higher education (and the insipid values found therein). Instead, through faith and faith’s profound unity with the eternal wisdom given by God to the Church, the priest, if he remains disciplined, can breathe air that freshens culture. This air is circulated by God by way of the altar and then is circulated in culture through witness. The priest is an intellectual, but not in the sense of being defined by the theories learned in a university. He is an intellectual who measures all thought against the Incarnate Word, the Logos, and Reason-Itself-Become-Flesh. This kind of thinking is, in its essence, the result of prayer, not calculation. As Pope Benedict XVI noted, “the faithful expect only one thing from priests: that they be specialists in promoting the encounter between man and God. The priest is not asked to be an expert in economics, construction or politics. He is expected to be an expert in the spiritual life.”16 From this expertise, the priest shares the mind of Christ with the culture by way of this study and his own affective and spiritual maturation.17 Being a man of prayer, however, does not guarantee either intellectual acumen or facility with the knowledge 15 16 17 There are men in the seminary who resist formation out of fear of the pain of conversion, a small fraction simply trying to “play the game” and “get through,” and then another portion of the population who are sincere but slower in welcoming the truth about themselves unto needed conversion through intimacy with the Trinity. What possibly new and creative ideas can seminaries develop to minister to these men who truly want to mature but, through no ill will on their part, cannot cooperate just now? Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Clergy,” Warsaw Cathedral, 25 May 2006, last accessed August 8, 2016, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/ speeches/2006/may/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20060525_poland-clergy. html. See James Keating, “Theology as Thinking in Prayer,” Chicago Studies 53.1 (2014): 70–83. The Seminary and Western Culture 1107 and experience necessary to guide people in the spiritual life. This comes about only through the integrated formation previously noted. To be integrated is to have suffered in one’s own body the coming together of theological truth, prayerful availability to God in all things, moral maturation, and pastoral charity. Such integration is a remedy for any of the dark influences or partial truths conveyed from the culture to a man. In this integration, a man suffers the reorientation of habits, the purification of desires, and the healing of any intellectual bias or partisan ideology as he bathes in the singular resources that make up the reality and relationships of the seminary: spiritual direction, human formation, intellectual formation, pastoral competency, liturgies, private prayer, spiritual reading, exposure to the lives of the saints, fraternal or peer correction, the example of mature priest role models, self-discipline and virtue, development in prudence, temperance, chastity, immersion in Scripture, and, finally, guidance from one’s bishop. Such a structure of relationships mediating truth and inviting conversion is, of its very nature, a sign that the seminarian is loved by both God and the Church. Such a structure bears on it the capacity to convey truth to the man as a remedy to any lies or bias he carries within his heart. Such love and truth must be actively received by the man himself, since it is acknowledged that the structure and content of seminary alone are not sufficient to heal someone. A man cannot become holy if he passively exists within the set of relationships that is seminary. It is Christ himself whom the relationships are communicating when both the formators and seminarians make themselves available to truth and love. It is Christ who converts and heals the seminarians and replaces their bias or ideology with a new mind, one beyond the limits of culture (1 Cor 2:16; Isa 43:19; Rev 21:5). When the seminary exists in a circulation of grace and vulnerability to one another in truth, then the seminarians cannot remain dull from unthinking participation in culture but, instead, come alive by way of “unveiled faces” gazing on the beauty of the Lord (2 Cor 3:12–18). It is God who humanizes the culture through the vulnerability of those who allow themselves to be affected by him. It is the priest whose work is to impart a life that is more than human: “We become fully human when we become more than human, when we let God bring us beyond ourselves in order to attain the fullest truth of our being.”18 18 Pope Francis, Evangelii Gaudium (2013), §8. 1108 James Keating The Formation of Holy Priests as Missionaries to Culture: Eternal Wisdom in a Time of Autonomy and Imposed “Values“19 In the face of all the different and, at times, contrasting cultures present in the various parts of the world, inculturation seeks to obey Christ’s command to preach the Gospel to all nations, even unto the ends of the earth. Such obedience does not signify either syncretism or a simple adaptation of the announcement of the Gospel, but rather the fact that the Gospel penetrates the very life of cultures, becomes incarnate in them, overcoming those cultural elements that are incompatible with . . . Christian living, and raising their values to the mystery of salvation which comes from Christ.20 In their own way, priests carry a true missionary spirit, and they open people to a larger vision of reality in an era that diminishes the world of wonder and establishes meaning only in a narrow band of “more of the same.” This lack of wonder leads to a bored and boring culture, even though its activities are frenetic.21 It is bored and boring because much of its activities flow more from the individual ego and less from the love relationship with God. The Gospel, received as flowing from the sacramental ministry of the clergy,22 ends this imprisonment and opens people to a wider field of living: participation in the mysteries of Christ. The priest, in other words, opens and guards the doorway to divine love. It is this divine love that establishes culture upon a firm foundation whereupon reason can be ordered toward truth and action ordered toward goodness and holiness. By presiding at the origin of all human flourishing, the adoration of God in the celebration of the Paschal Mystery, the priest dedicates his life to seeing that love, his own 19 20 21 22 See USCCB, Program of Priestly Formation, §110: “Seminarians are to have a spiritual formation grounded in Trinitarian communion that leads them to solidarity with others, especially those most in need, a commitment to justice and peace, a reciprocal exchange of spiritual and material gifts, and an authentic missionary spirit expressed in a willingness to serve where needed.” John Paul II, Pastores Dabo Vobis, §55. See Jean-Charles Nault, O.S.B., The Noonday Devil (San Francisco: Ignatius 2015), 120. See Aidan Nichols, O.P., Yves Congar (London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1989), 83: “[The hierarchy] must teach, yet the laity must ‘receive’ their teaching—not in the sense of conferring on it a . . . validity by their assent, but of rendering it fruitful in the Christian life of the entire body.” The Seminary and Western Culture 1109 and his people’s, does not run cold (Matt 24:12). Such adoration transforms persons and deepens their participation in reality. Thus culture is re-aligned by these fruits of adoration and wonder.23 The ascendancy of subjectivity and freedom, so characteristic of our modern age, is plunging us constantly into a climate of anthropocentrism which is aided and abetted by a mediating culture which closes the individual in on himself and keeps him from achieving a liberating communion. . . . There is perhaps nothing more urgent today than a new evangelization of contemplation, if we wish a return of the sacred to produce salutary results in our contemporary culture. . . . A new inculturation of the Gospel can only arise from the intimate encounter of man in the flesh with the Word of Love which calls him and ravishes him, rooting him in Jesus Christ.24 This is the highly specific work of the priest—first to suffer an encounter with the Word of Love in his own flesh, which is seminary formation at its best, and then to facilitate this same path for his parishioners. In so doing, the priest identifies himself as one who is not ashamed of the Gospel, not reticent to breathe the supernatural, and, thus, eager to lead others into a communion with Christ by a disciplined contemplation of the beauty of his actions. This beholding of the actions of the Christ, which began for the Church with the Incarnation and continues now in its sacramental life and in the lives of the saints, allows persons to be affected by the truth carried in such actions. Being so affected, the person is established as such a one in culture and becomes, at first, a curiosity, maybe a threat, but optimally, an occasion of grace. The priest spends his entire life dedicated to mediating spiritual sustenance to lay people so they can have the courage to give such witness. By way of his own formation, a priest can guide others through the way of no longer accepting a culturally imposed identity as exhaustive of one’s dignity and meaning. As the priest has first suffered a recovery from culture, he may be able to reach his parishioners and awaken within them a new Christic imagination. This Christic imagination replaces the anemic cultural tutoring that furnishes a mind with only 23 24 Hans Urs von Balthasar, Prayer (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1986), 104–05. Marc Ouellet, “Hans Urs von Balthasar: Witness to the Integration of Faith and Culture,” Communio 18.1 (Spring 1991): 124–25. 1110 James Keating a political, economic, and entertainment imagination. The Christic imagination is new and rightly theological, born of the contemplation of Christ’s own actions that gracefully come to inhere in the mind and move the will to a dedicated mission to culture: witnessing to the baptized life. Such a mind is now substantial as a result of the grace of contemplating Christ and suffering his coming by way of the sacramental life and moral conversion. Discerning Cultural Recovery The effects of being disproportionately formed by “this passing age” (Rom. 12:1–2) upon a seminarian’s thinking and character have to be eased in seminary if that seminarian is to be one who is directed by the Spirit from within. In seminary, a man is intentionally placed within a set of relationships that conspire to mediate an encounter between Christ and that seminarian. For various reasons—some intentional, others not—some seminaries may order their relationships primarily in accord with the customs of academia. This type of reductionism is fought against right at the heart of the Church, in both Pastores Dabo Vobis and the Program for Priestly Formation, which both advocate that a man be immersed into a communion of relationships, relationships that mediate an encounter with Christ. Seminary is a conspiracy of relationships that relentlessly encourage a man not to settle for an ideological view of his own formation. Seminary is not simply school, not simply counsel, not simply charitable work, not simply prayer; seminary is the orchestrated facilitation of an encounter with the living, loving Word mediated through the four areas of formation, and all ordered toward a man’s participation in the one priesthood of Christ. One area of formation alone does not take the ascendancy, as all are to be vulnerable to the heart of priestly formation: unceasing communion with the Word. With such integration the seminarian is fully oxygenated—as the Spirit circulates freely through spiritual direction, pastoral work, academics, and human formation. One might argue that the most vital role of the rector is to see that a man is being formed by an encounter with Christ and not simply served by specialists in any one area (academic, spiritual, human maturation, pastoral training) of competency. A personal way seminarians can show they love the culture they live in and wish to further evangelize it is to render their hearts completely available to formation. In this way, the culture is gifted with one more man mature in both spirit and affect. In facilitating a seminarian’s integration of affective and spiritual maturation with The Seminary and Western Culture 1111 pastoral and academic competency, the seminary sends a man of wholeness and peace into the culture. In so doing, the seminary gifts the culture with a man who can be sought after as a spiritual and moral leader, one who has suffered peace and healing in his “bones” and wishes to share this way of life with those who are still embedded within any of the negative values of popular culture. When seminarians (as well as formators) agree to suffer the integrative and creative tension of all four areas of seminary life, seminary becomes an antidote to cultural ideology. This tension, never to be relaxed, but only suffered, is the genius of Catholic seminary formation as it seeks to purify any cultural pollution irritating seminarians and replace such with the breathable “spirit” (Hebrew ruah) who N&V carries only life ( John 10:10; 6:63). Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1113–1131 Aquinas on the Spirit’s Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology1 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas Rome, Italy The last few decades have seen a renewed interest in Dionysius the Areopagite as mystical theologian and in Thomas Aquinas as spiritual master. Ressourcement figures such as Hans Urs von Balthasar resurrected Dionysius the mystical author, while Servais Pinckaers, Jean-Pierre Torrell, and others have deepened our vision of Aquinas’s teaching on the spiritual life.2 Curiously, the few studies that have compared Dionysius and Aquinas have been done by metaphysicians interested in divine naming.3 The favorite Dionysian theme 1 2 3 Part of the present article includes modified excerpts from my recent study The Mystery of Union with God: Dionysian Mysticism in Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2015). A previous version of this paper was delivered at the “Dominicans and the Renewal of Thomism” conference organized by the Thomistic Institute in Washington, D.C., on July 1–5, 2013. Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 2, Studies in Theological Style: Clerical Style (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1984), 144–210; Servais Pinckaers, La vie selon l’Esprit: Essai de théologie spirituelle selon saint Paul et saint Thomas d’Aquin, Amateca 17.2 (Luxembourg: Éditions SaintPaul, 1996); Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 2, Spiritual Master, trans. Robert Royal (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2003); Torrell, Christ and Spirituality in St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. Bernhard Blankenhorn (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011). Thierry-Dominique Humbrecht, Théologie négative et noms divins chez saint Thomas d’Aquin, Bibliothèque Thomiste 57 (Paris: Vrin, 2005); Fran O’Rourke, Pseudo-Dionysius and the Metaphysics of Aquinas (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005). 1114 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. of union with God in the dark cloud of Mt. Sinai has received little attention from Aquinas scholars.Yet, the dark cloud has a clear place in Thomas’s theology of union with God. That theology rests on multiple pillars, including the doctrines of the invisible missions of the Son and the Spirit, the virtue of charity, and the Spirit’s seven gifts. Aquinas links the Areopagite’s Moses on Mt. Sinai with the Spirit’s gift of understanding and, likewise, the mystical experience of the Areopagite’s teacher Hierotheus with the gift of wisdom. Yet, no one has studied in an extensive way how Thomas’s teaching on these two gifts of the Spirit relates to the Areopagite’s classic work, The Mystical Theology. I wish to consider Aquinas’s doctrine of the gift of understanding in relation to the Areopagite’s Moses in darkness. I will argue that Thomas’s theology of the gift of understanding includes a significant threefold transformation of the Dionysian doctrine of mystical union: first, Aquinas emphasizes the positive knowledge of God accessible to us (kataphatism); second, he reinserts concept-bound and imagebound thought within the height of cognitive union; and third, he shows how this summit of union can be attained by the saint who has not learned the technicalities of divine naming. However, I will argue that, despite these doctrinal modifications, Aquinas still owes much to the Areopagite for his own vision of hidden union with God. This study proceeds in three steps. First, I will summarize the Areopagite’s teaching on Moses being joined to God in darkness. Here, I follow the work of patrologists such as Ysabel de Andia, René Roques, and Paul Rorem.4 Second, I shall mention some key aspects of Thomas’s theology of the Spirit’s seven gifts in general. Third, I will analyze Aquinas’s teaching on the gift of understanding in relation to the Dionysian Moses. I shall conclude by proposing some consequences of this teaching for Dominican spirituality. Pseudo-Dionysius on Moses in Darkness Dionysius employs the figure of Moses in the dark cloud on Mt. Sinai to symbolize union with God or the summit of the spiritual life. The Mystical Theology begins with a prayer: “O Trinity, beyond being, 4 Ysabel de Andia, Henosis: L’union à Dieu chez Denys l’Aréopagite, Philosophia Antiqua 71 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1996); René Roques, “Denys l’Aréopagite,” in Dictionnaire de Spiritualité, vol. 3, ed. Charles Baumgartner (Paris: Letouzey et Ané, 1957), columns 244–86; Paul P. Rorem, Pseudo-Dionysius: A Commentary on the Texts and an Introduction to Their Influence (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1993). Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1115 beyond divinity, beyond goodness, and guide of Christians in divine wisdom, direct us to the mystical summits [logion] more than unknown and beyond light. There the simple, absolved and unchanged mysteries of theology lie hidden in the darkness beyond light of the hidden mystical silence.”5 Dionysius introduces his discussion of the disposition needed to receive the Trinity’s uplifting power. God’s gifts elevate the mind to contact with the divine reality that the sacred oracles reveal. In the Dionysian corpus, the mystical summits or oracles usually refer to the revelation transmitted in Sacred Scripture. The oracles can also refer to the words of the liturgy.6 Dionysius the hierarch guides the disciple to the right interpretation of Scripture’s divine names and the correct understanding of liturgical symbols. He leads the disciple to a climax where all interpretation runs into a wall and the mind falls silent in the presence of God. Dionysius then presents Moses ascending Mt. Sinai with the elders or priests. The context is liturgical, for the patriarch resembles a Syrian-rite bishop celebrating the Eucharist.7 In the Book of Exodus, chapter 24, the patriarch and priests go up to “God’s place.” Dionysius explains this metaphor: “The most divine and highest of what is seen and intelligible are hypothetical logoi of what is subordinate to that beyond-having all. Through these is shown forth the presence of that which walks upon the intelligible summits of its most holy places. And then Moses abandons those who see and what is seen and enters into the really mystical darkness of unknowing.” 8 God’s 5 6 7 8 Dionysius Areopagita, De mystica theologia 1.1 (PG, 3:997A–B); see The Divine Names and Mystical Theology, trans. John D. Jones, Medieval Philosophical Texts in Translation 21 (Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 1980), 211. All English translations of Dionysius are taken from Jones’s translation in this edition. For the critical editions, see Dionysius Areopagita, Corpus Dionysiacum I: De divinis nominibus, ed. Beate Regina Suchla, Patristische Texte und Studien 33 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1990), and Corpus Dionysiacum II: De coelesti hierarchia, De ecclesiastica hierarchia, De mystica theologia, Epistulae, ed. Günther Heil and Adolf Martin Ritter, Patristische Texte und Studien 36 (Berlin:Walter de Gruyter, 1991). The best complete and literal translation of the Dionysian corpus, although based on the pre-critical edition, remains The Works of Dionysius the Areopagite, trans. John D. Parker (London: James Parker, 1897). Dionysius Areopagita, De divinis nominibus 1.1 (PG, 3:587–88A); de Andia, Henosis, 1–3 and 240. Rorem, Pseudo-Dionysius, 102 and 190–92. Dionysius Areopagita, De mystica theologia 1.3 (PG, 3:1000D–01A; Jones ed., 214). 1116 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. place stands for the summit of positive human knowledge about God. Such knowledge derives from God’s operative presence in the world, also called the operative powers. These powers are the object of the affirmative divine names. Because the transcendent God is beyond every human concept and discourse, God’s place does not represent the highest form of knowledge.9 The Old Testament patriarch then continues his ascent of the holy mountain, going beyond God’s place or beyond the realm of God’s powers, and penetrates darkness: “And then Moses abandons those who see and what is seen and enters into the really mystical darkness of unknowing; in this he shuts out every knowing apprehension and comes to be in the wholly imperceptible and invisible, being entirely of that beyond all—of nothing, neither himself nor another, united most excellently by the completely unknowing inactivity of every knowledge, and knowing beyond intellect by knowing nothing.”10 Darkness signifies the silent state of the contemplative’s intellect. Earlier in the text, Dionysius explains that the God hidden in darkness is beyond all affirmations and negations.11 The positive divine names refer to God’s action in creation, while the negations recall that God remains above his operations. The negative divine names are also employed below the stage of total noetic silence. The proper use of both affirmative and negative divine names is an essential precondition to attain union. Both types of naming fall short of union. For, any act of naming remains bound to a discursive mode of understanding, while union is beyond all mental discourse. Moses ascends by negations so as to transcend them.12 The patriarch leaves behind God’s metaphorical place and goes out of himself in order to attain union. The contemplative’s mind lets go of its own act of understanding, for this act cannot attain the divine mystery sought.13 In darkness, Moses knows God by unknowing. Darkness is also a paradoxical expression for God’s transcendence, so 9 10 11 12 13 De Andia, Henosis, 345–47 and 358–59. Dionysius Areopagita, De mystica theologia 1.3 (PG, 3:1001A; Jones ed., 214). Ibid. (PG, 3:1000C). De Andia, Henosis, 392–93. Dionysius Areopagita, De mystica theologia 1.1 (PG, 3:1000A); René Roques, “Contemplation, extase et ténèbre chez le Pseudo-Denys,” in Dictionnaire de Spiritualité, vol. 2.2, ed. Charles Baumgartner (Paris: Letouzey et Ané, 1949), cols. 1899–1900. Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1117 that darkness refers to a positive reality.14 God’s light is called darkness because his limitless essence exceeds our grasp. Moses knows “nothing” insofar as unknowing surpasses all previous insights about God’s operations. Hence, this is a knowing “beyond mind.” Here, God directly teaches the mystic about divine incomprehensibility. This highest knowledge is not the result of a human noetic act, but of spiritual light flooding the mind.15 Union occurs in silence, for its “object” is the ineffable God. Dionysius describes union with God as a kind of cognition. As a good Platonist, he was convinced that knowledge is always participatory.16 The mystic moves beyond his or her own thoughts and words about God so as to be joined to the unutterable divine Word. The highest gifted knowledge causes union. Mystical contemplation is passive, not because the contemplative practices a passive method of meditation, but because the grandeur of the gift can only be received in a passive way. Active human knowledge remains stuck within human limitations. Thus, mystical union is a sheer gift that cannot be taught.17 God alone fully empties the mind by filling it with his light. Let us note the anthropological foundation of the Areopagite’s mystical doctrine. Partly inspired by Proclus, he proposes what we might call an “exterior anthropology.” For Dionysius, the soul begins its ascent not by going to the God hidden within or to the memory of forms, but by grasping the meaning of the biblical divine names and liturgical symbols.18 Material mediations such as icons and biblical metaphors pertain to the beginning of contemplative ascent and serve the need of the soul’s “impassioned” or lower part that naturally strives for symbols. Having satisfied the soul’s lower part, contemplative ascent continues in the soul’s higher or “passionless” part. Here, unified thoughts are the proper aim. Cognition mediated by the senses eventually becomes an obstacle 14 15 16 17 18 Dionysius Areopagita, Epistula 5 (PG, 3:1073A); Dionysius, De mystica theologia 1.1 (PG, 3:997B). De Andia, Henosis, 351 and 431; Henri-Charles Puech, “La ténèbre mystique chez le Pseudo-Denys et dans la tradition patristique,” Études Carmélitaines 23 (1938): 39–41. De Andia, Henosis, 401, 417–18. Ibid., 431. Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord, 2:160–61 and 180; Paul P. Rorem, Biblical and Liturgical Symbols within the Pseudo-Dionysian Synthesis, Studies and Texts 71 (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1984), 56. 1118 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. to union.19 Consequently, contemplative ascent passes through a highly structured series of symbols and names that reveal their luminous content to those who are properly disposed to receive them.20 Aquinas on the Seven Gifts in General Thomas learned the Areopagite’s Mystical Theology from his teacher Albert the Great around the year 1250. Both Dominican friars displayed a fascination with Dionysius. Albert commented on the entire Dionysian corpus, while Thomas kept his notes of Albert’s lectures for the rest of his life. Aquinas also composed a commentary on the Divine Names, yet he never commented on the Mystical Theology. Still, I will argue that Thomas’s late theology of the Spirit’s gift of understanding proposes a very original appropriation of Dionysian mysticism. But first, I need to review Aquinas’s mature approach to the metaphysics of the Spirit’s seven gifts.21 First, the seven gifts are seven distinct habitus that dispose various faculties of the soul to receive the Spirit’s motion for the sake of assisting one of the virtues. These seven habitus or gifts may be described as an essential property or component of sanctifying grace. Hence, these gifts constitute an enduring metaphysical modification of the believer’s faculties.22 Second, the Spirit’s action in the gifts is gratuitous. This action does not occur according to our decision.23 The Spirit blows where he wills. Here, the classic metaphor of the sailing ship remains instructive: the sails are like the seven gifts, while the Spirit’s action is like the wind.24 Third, like the virtues, the 19 20 21 22 23 24 Dionysius Areopagita, De divinis nominibus 4.11; Dionysius, Epistula 9.1; René Roques, L’univers dionysien: Structure hiérarchique du monde selon le Pseudo-Denys, Théologie 29 (Paris: Aubier, 1954), 202 and 235. Dionysius Areopagita, De divinis nominibus 3.3; Roques, L’univers dionysien, 119, 203, and 209. Recent scholarship has shown a considerable evolution in Aquinas’s doctrine of the seven gifts in general. See, for example, Cruz González Ayesta, El don de sabiduría según Santo Tomás: Divinización, filiación y connaturalizad, Teológica 92 (Navarra: EUNSA, 1998); Ulrich Horst, Die Gaben des Heiligen Geistes nach Thomas von Aquin, Veröffentlichungen des Grabmann-Institutes 46 (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2001), 41–69. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae (hereafter, ST) I-II, q. 68, aa. 1, 3, and 5 (Ottawa: Commissio Piana, 1953; all citations from the ST are from this edition, and all English translation is my own). Aquinas implies this at ST I-II, q. 68, a. 3, corp.; a. 4, corp. John of Saint Thomas, Cursus Theologicus, In Iam–IIae: De donis Spiritus Sancti, Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1119 gifts as habitus can increase or decrease in intensity.25 That is, we can progress or decline in docility to the Spirit. Fourth, Aquinas refers to the gifts’ operations as acts of the virtues and the gifts.26 As Pinckaers has noted, Thomas implies that the Spirit’s motion in the gifts strengthens the virtues.27 Thus, greater docility to the Spirit leads to growth in the virtues, which enables a new spontaneity. Progress in the spiritual life involves the double spiral of an increasing docility to God and a greater capacity to act virtuously. This helps to explain why Aquinas’s discussion of the seven gifts does not mention passive spiritual states.28 The operation of any one of the seven gifts does not occur at a spiritual level beyond the virtues, nor does this operation substitute for the activity of the virtues. Finally, Thomas follows Augustine as he links each gift of the Spirit with a particular beatitude. The beatitudes are the Spirit’s gifts in act. The beatitude of the pure of heart corresponds to the gift of understanding. Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding Now that we have an overview of the seven gifts and the Spirit’s movement through them, we can consider the gift of understanding in particular. I will first signal some major themes in Aquinas’s teaching on this gift and then proceed to a textual analysis of article 7 of question 8 in the secunda secundae of the Summa theologiae. First, Aquinas distinguishes the gift of understanding from other gifts of the Spirit by an appeal to the distinction between the intellect’s first and second act (i.e., apprehension and judgment). The gifts of knowledge (scientia) and wisdom (sapientia) involve a cognitive judgment, while the gift of understanding involves apprehension.29 This division has perplexed Thomas’s commentators because apprehension is not a complete noetic act, for we do not attain truth without judgment. However, we can solve this problem if we consider that the gift of understanding sharpens apprehension, which in turn assists the virtue of faith in its act of judgment. Admittedly, this solution is not explicit in Aquinas, but it may be the only solution that does not contradict the text of Aquinas. 25 26 27 28 29 Collectio Lavallensis (Québec: Armand Mathieu and Hervé Gagné, 1958), no. 174. ST I-II, q. 68, a. 3. ST I-II, q. 69, aa. 1–2; II-II, q. 19, a. 12, ad 1. Servais Pinckaers, Plaidoyer pour la Vertu (Paris: Parole et Silence, 2007), 321. ST I-II, q. 68, aa. 1, 3, and 8. ST II-II, q. 8, a. 6. 1120 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. Second, the gift of understanding’s operation is not about reasoning from premises to conclusions. Rather, this gift’s operation is characterized by the mind’s completion or repose. It grants a better grasp of “the first principles of gratuitous cognition.”30 These first principles are essentially the articles of faith, by which Aquinas means the heart of Scripture’s teaching. That is why question 8 of the secunda secundae often links the gift of understanding to a deeper cognitive penetration of the articles of faith.31 The Creed summarizes the articles of faith. Third, we cannot yet directly grasp the greatest mysteries of faith such as the Trinity and the Incarnation, for this would require the face-to-face vision of God. Thus, Aquinas assigns to the gift of understanding a negative or “remotive” function: this gift enables us to see more clearly what the mysteries of faith are not.32 In other words, this gift’s actualization removes errors and foreign accretions from our manner of conceiving the mystery of God and his central saving acts. We are dealing with a kind of negative apprehension, a rather paradoxical notion. We are now ready to consider our key Summa text (II-II, q. 8, a. 7). Here, Thomas explains the beatitude of the pure of heart and the knowledge of “what God is not.” Aquinas fleshes out the details of the gift of understanding’s negative or remotive function thus: Two things are contained in the sixth beatitude, as in the other beatitudes: one by mode of merit, namely, purity of heart; another by mode of reward, namely, the vision of God, as was said above. And each pertains to the gift of understanding in some way. For purity is twofold. One is a preamble and a disposition for the vision of God, which is the affect’s purification from disordered affections; and this purity of heart occurs through the virtues and gifts that pertain to the appetitive power. But the other purity of heart is as perfective in view of the divine vision; and this is the purity of mind purified of phantasms and errors, namely, that the things which are proposed about God not be taken by the mode of corporeal phantasms, nor according to heretical perversities. And the gift of understanding brings about this purity.33 30 31 32 33 ST II-II, q. 8, a. 6, ad 2. ST II-II, q. 8, aa. 2–3. ST II-II, q. 8, a. 2, corp. ST II-II, q. 8, a. 7, corp.: “in sexta beatitudine, sicut et in aliis, duo continentur: unum per modum meriti, scilicet munditia cordis; aliud per modum praemii, Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1121 Thomas divides the sixth beatitude into two parts: “Blessed are the pure of heart” signifies a purification of affect and intellect, while the phrase “they shall see God” designates this gift’s reward (I will explain the term “affect” shortly).The first part of the beatitude signals a disposition for a reward, and the second part signals the reward itself. In this life, the saints already begin to receive a reward, for they see God indirectly.This vision is nothing other than knowing “what he is not,” a phrase that evokes the Areopagite’s Moses in the dark cloud. The saints in glory see God directly or face-to-face. The saints on earth enjoy an imperfect reward, while the saints in heaven have a perfect one. Those who have not yet attained heroic virtue must still pass through the Spirit’s purifying action. I now come back to the first part of the beatitude. Thomas treats purity of heart as the doorway to the vision of “what God is not.” Aquinas proposes a two-fold purity. The first kind of purity comes through the gifts that pertain to the appetitive powers—namely, the will (or “rational appetite”) and the passions. He summarizes these faculties or powers by the term “affect.” For example, the Spirit’s gift of piety helps to reorder the will’s inclination by intensifying our filial affection for God as Father. The actualized gift of understanding presupposes that some spiritual progress has occurred in the will and the passions with the help of the Spirit’s other gifts. The re-ordering of appetites (that is, various “affects”) constitutes a first, essential step toward the vision of “what God is not.” A second kind of purity of heart perfectly prepares for the indirect vision of God, and this involves the removal of phantasms and errors. Here, Aquinas refers to the Spirit’s motion in the gift of understanding that is available to all believers in grace.34 Thomas applies the Avicennian notion of disposing and perfecting causality to the purification of the appetites and that of the intellect. The distinction between disposing and perfecting causes is primarily metaphysical, not temporal. 34 scilicet visio Dei, ut supra dictum est. Et utrumque pertinet aliquo modo ad donum intellectus. Est enim duplex munditia. Una quidem praeambula et dispositiva ad Dei visionem, quae est depuratio affectus ab inordinatis affectionibus; et haec quidem munditia cordis fit per virtutes et dona quae pertinent ad vim appetitivam. Alia vero munditia cordis est quae est quasi completiva respectu visionis divinae; et hoc quidem est munditia mentis depuratae a phantasmatibus et erroribus, ut scilicet ea quae de Deo proponuntur non accipiantur per modum corporalium phantasmatum, nec secundum haereticas perversitates. Et hanc munditiam facit donum intellectus.” See ST II-II, q. 8, a. 4. 1122 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. The conviction that contemplative ascent requires progress in the moral virtues is omnipresent in ancient philosophy, patristic theology, and medieval thought. Certainly, Dionysian union presumes such moral progress. Aquinas links this progress with the first type of purification of the heart: the will and the passions are the proper seat of the cardinal virtues. Now, Thomas’s Sentences Commentary explicitly links the beatitude of the pure of heart with the Mystical Theology’s exhortation to Timothy to be purified of “errors and phantasms and spiritual forms” so as to ascend to union with God.35 Such language overlaps with our Summa text on purity of heart. More specifically, it overlaps with the second kind of purity. So Dionysius is a source for Thomas’s explanation of perfected purity of heart. The actualized gift of understanding brings about this purity. But how Dionysian is Aquinas’s Areopagite? At the beginning of the Mystical Theology, Dionysius presumes that Timothy’s “impassioned” part of the soul has been satisfied in its inclination to sensible images by contemplating God in material creation and liturgical symbols. The Areopagite also holds that the “passionless” part of the soul (the noūs) seeks knowledge beyond sensible images. For Dionysius, the mind can operate without images or phantasms.36 The contemplation of sensible or image-bound objects such as icons or biblical metaphors ultimately constitutes an obstacle to mystical union. Such aids for contemplation are necessary stepping-stones to union, but as one progresses, these must be left behind. Likewise, Moses must wholly transcend the contemplation of God’s names. He should surpass all thoughts and finite noetic objects that mediate knowledge of God. Thomas limits the Dionysian claim that one must let go of all sensible images in the ascent to knowing “what God is not.” Instead, he calls for the avoidance of theological error in the way that we understand God. It is striking that Thomas shows little concern for the contemplative’s mode of consciousness. The doctrinal intention behind Aquinas’s modification to Dionysius emerges more clearly by a consideration of the human subject being discussed in question 8, article 7. Dionysius addresses himself to a contemplative advanced in learning: the Mystical Theology follows the Divine Names, being composed precisely for those who have grasped the teaching of the Divine Names. It is also presumes that 35 36 In III sent. d. 34, q. 1, a. 4, corp. Roques, L’univers dionysien, 235. Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1123 the same reader no longer needs images to contemplate God. The beginning of the Mystical Theology instructs Timothy on the proper reaction to the coming of God’s light (“abandon all sensation and all intellectual activities”). Aquinas’s exposition on purity of heart, however, refers to the Spirit’s work available to all who are in grace. Avoiding heretical error with the Spirit’s help precisely describes the gift of understanding’s operation that is available to all in grace, not just to clerics or monks. The new human subject of purification calls for a new reading of Timothy’s noetic object. First, Thomas’s discussion of the pure of heart sidesteps the Areopagite’s counsel to let go of finite intelligible objects. Dionysius wants to transcend intelligible objects, for these represent God’s powers active in the cosmos. The divine names refer to God’s powers. But Thomas insists that these names refer to God’s very own substance or essence.37 Dionysius seeks union beyond naming, unlike Aquinas. Second, for Thomas, the pure of heart avoid erroneous interpretations of the mysteries of faith contained in Scripture. Thomas posits a refined contemplation of Scripture whose object is broader than in Dionysius. Aquinas’s contemplative ponders not just God’s biblical names but all of Scripture, especially the central mysteries of faith. The pure of heart behold and correctly understand God’s many saving acts, and not just his most perfect names. Suddenly, history and the creaturely, temporal realities through which God saves us take on a whole new importance. Third, in Thomas, the removal of error leaves standing biblical affirmations. That is, remotions improve our grasp of the intelligible content that Scripture transmits by its description of God and his operation. For Aquinas, remotion only makes sense if it qualifies some type of affirmation.38 Remotion does not negate the saving 37 38 ST I, q. 13, a. 2. Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de potentia, q. 7, a. 5, corp: “intellectus negationis semper fundatur in aliqua affirmatione: quod ex hoc patet quia omnis negativa per affirmativam probatur; unde nisi intellectus humanus aliquid de Deo affirmative cognosceret, nihil de Deo posset negare. Non autem cognosceret, si nihil quod de Deo dicit, de eo verificaretur affirmative. Et ideo, secundum sententiam Dionysii, dicendum est, quod huiusmodi nomina significant divinam substantiam, quamvis deficienter et imperfecte: quod sic patet. Cum omne agens agat in quantum actu est, et per consequens agat aliqualiter simile” (“An understanding of negation is always founded in some affirmation, which is thus clear, in that every negative is proven through an affirmative. Hence, unless the human intellect were to know something 1124 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. mystery or divine name being contemplated. Rather, it corrects our misconceptions thereof. In this sense, ascent to God by the gift of understanding does not end the mind’s gaze upon God’s positive attributes or other mysteries of faith. Timothy’s and Moses’s silent mind almost drops out. Contemplation’s object and its mode of operation go hand in hand. One needs an active mind in order to ponder biblical affirmations about God and his saving deeds. Fourth, as already suggested, the function of phantasms changes. By the gift of understanding, the Spirit acts so that “the things proposed about God not be taken by the mode of corporeal phantasms, nor according to heretical perversities.” Thomas shifts the focus from the direct object of the mind’s gaze and its mode of operating to the intended noetic content or doctrine about God. By the beatitude of the pure of heart, the Spirit removes corporeal or finite modes of being from our way of understanding God’s nature and action. Thomas’s shift away from an image-free mode of noetic operation recalls that he cannot follow the Dionysian doctrine that noūs operates without images, a doctrine presumed in the Areopagite’s advice to Timothy. Aquinas refuses to make an exception to the Aristotelian principle that the pilgrim’s complete act of knowing must return to phantasms.39 Even the Spirit’s direct action in the seven gifts does not overcome the natural mode of knowing proper to an embodied rational being with one substantial form. The mind’s operative capacity rooted in a single substantial form is proportioned to sensible things.40 The Spirit’s special motion in the seven gifts does not overturn nature’s capacities, but rather stretches them. That 39 40 affirmatively about God, it could not negate anything of him. But it would not know if anything which it says of God could be affirmatively verified of him. Therefore, according to the teaching of Dionysius, it must be said that such [affirmative] names signify the divine substance, although deficiently and imperfectly, which is thus clear. Since every agent acts inasmuch as it is in act, and consequently acts something similar [to itself] ”); in Quaestiones disputatae, vol. 2, ed. P. Bazzi, M. Calcaterra, T. S. Centi, E. Odetto, and P. M. Pession (Rome/Turin: Marietti, 1965); English translation is my own. See also Gregory P. Rocca, Speaking the Incomprehensible God: Thomas Aquinas on the Interplay of Positive and Negative Theology (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2004), 67 and 303. See ST I, q. 84, a. 7; q. 86, a. 1; II-II, q. 15, a. 3; q. 180, a. 5, ad 2. Richard Schenk taught me years ago that the doctrine of the unicity of substantial form is crucial for Aquinas’s entire theological project. See also Gilles Emery, “The Unity of Man, Body and Soul, in St. Thomas Aquinas” in Trinity, Church, and the Human Person: Thomistic Essays, trans. Therese Scarpelli (Naples, FL: Sapientia Press, 2007), 209–35. Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1125 is precisely what we would expect from Aquinas, given his way of relating grace and nature.41 Article 7 of question 8 continues with a discussion of the reward given to the saints through the gift of understanding. Thomas thus proceeds from the first part of the beatitude to the second, from purity of heart to the vision of God, from the removal of errors and phantasms to the obscure height of contemplation. He now explains the gift of understanding’s perfect act here below. The text parallels Moses’s ascent of Mt. Sinai in the Areopagite’s Mystical Theology. Aquinas’s Sentences Commentary makes this parallel with Dionysius explicit, while it remains implicit in the Summa. The last part of the corpus in our main article reads thus: The vision of God is twofold. One is perfect, through which God’s essence is seen. The other is imperfect, through which, although we do not see what God is, we still see what he is not; and in this life the more perfectly we know God, the more we understand him to exceed whatever is comprehended by the intellect. And each vision of God pertains to the gift of understanding, for the first [vision pertains] to the consummated gift of understanding, as it will be in heaven; but the second [vision pertains] to the imperfect gift of understanding, as it is possessed on the way [by the pilgrim].42 This passage closely resembles the Sentences Commentary text on the same beatitude, which mentions the Mystical Theology.43 The Sentences 41 42 43 We cannot say with certitude whether or not Aquinas clearly perceived the distinct stages of contemplative ascent as conceived by Dionysius. Given the medieval scholastic way of treating authorities, disagreements often remain under the surface. Still, I strongly suspect that Thomas had a fairly complete grasp of the Areopagite’s own doctrinal intention. Also, I maintain that Thomas’s extensive modification of Dionysian mystical doctrine (whether conscious or not) bears much fruit, as will become evident below. ST II-II, q. 8, a. 7, corp: “duplex est Dei visio. Una quidem perfecta, per quam videtur Dei essentia. Alia vero imperfecta, per quam, etsi non videamus de Deo quid est, videmus tamen quid non est; et tanto in hac vita Deum perfectius cognoscimus quanto magis intelligimus eum excedere quidquid intellectu comprehenditur. Et utraque Dei visio pertinet ad donum intellectus, prima quidem ad donum intellectus consummatum, secundum quod erit in patria; secunda vero ad donum intellectus inchoatum, secundum quod habetur in via.” In III sent. d. 35, q. 2, a. 2, qla. 2, corp. 1126 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. Commentary states that Moses knows God as separated from all and above all. Our Summa text mentions knowing “what God is not” and that God exceeds our comprehension. The present passage quietly appropriates at least three key elements of the Areopagite’s Mystical Theology. First, our text presents maximum apophatic cognition as a gift, a key Dionysian doctrine. For the Areopagite and for Aquinas, God directly acts in the mystic’s intellect in a new way. Indeed, the Summa doctrine of the Spirit’s seven gifts emphasizes in a special way our dependence on God’s immediate motion to attain perfect knowledge of God. The Spirit’s efficient causality directly causes the act of negation or remotion, as he infuses remotions into the saint’s mind. These remotions are not infused intelligible species, but infused acts of negation that sharpen our grasp of what is known via revelation. Thomas’s doctrine of infused negations is almost certainly original. We find it neither in Albert nor in other thirteenth-century commentators of Dionysius. Second, the context of our passage shows that Aquinas remains focused on the gift of understanding as a means to penetrate more fully the articles of faith. Therefore, knowing “what God is not” with the Spirit’s aid surpasses the metaphysician’s knowledge that God’s quiddity exceeds all that we understand of him. Like Dionysius, Thomas posits a properly gifted or supernatural form of knowledge, even as he uses highly philosophical terms and concepts. For Aquinas, Jesus’ baptism, passion, and resurrection, Pentecost, and other revelatory events provide the most excellent divine effects whereby our graced minds attain indirect glimpses of Christ’s divinity and the Trinity.44 Our illumined grasp of these effects must itself be purified of misleading notions. Thus, knowing “what God is not” can involve more than acknowledging that God exceeds whatever we know of him or that he is incomprehensible. Indeed, the metaphysician can already know this without faith. Yet, knowing God’s quid non est perfectly in this life means knowing all of his attributes attained by reason and grace. Revelation unveils the Trinity and other perfections that, in turn, enable us to know God as greater even than our mode of understanding these perfections. Hence, we come to know ever more fully the God-creation difference. By the Spirit’s work, the saint knows the divine mystery correctly, even though he or she may not be able to explain it as well as the theologian. 44 ST I, q. 12, a. 13. See the luminous comments on this theme by Charles Journet, Connaissance et Inconnaissance de Dieu (Paris: Egloff, 1943), 93. Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1127 Third, because the reward of each beatitude belongs to holy men and women, Thomas follows Dionysius as he assigns to a spiritual elite the divinely given cognition of “what God is not.”45 Yet, within this doctrinal similitude, a key difference emerges. For Aquinas, the Spirit infuses a knowledge of God’s excellence in all who have progressed well in grace. The Areopagite’s mystic must learn how to affirm and negate all divine names before penetrating darkness. Thomas sees the need for purification from erroneous notions about God before coming to know “what he is not,” but he does not maintain the need to attain an explicit understanding of all divine names before reaching the mystical summit. For Dionysius, the highest union seems to belong mostly (or perhaps exclusively) to bishops and monks, a stance that Thomas does not take up. Clearly, Aquinas considers the contemplative and religious life better dispositions for union than lay life, but he does not place perfection in the Spirit’s gifts beyond the reach of the laity. They too can arrive at the top of Mt. Sinai, the place that symbolizes knowing “what God is not.” The Spirit’s motion in the gift of understanding is not directly linked to theological study, although study constitutes a precious aid along the way. Aquinas thus arrives at a major accomplishment—namely, a doctrine of mystical ascent by knowledge that is available to all.46 As noted previously, Thomas insists on the intellect’s need to return to phantasms. This stance is linked with his refusal of the Areopagite’s meta-conceptual contemplation. That is, even though the height of graced knowledge in this life is not limited to the intelligible content communicated by concepts, Thomas is convinced that our cognitive acts always employ concepts in some way. This distinction is crucial: the concepts we use in contemplative ascent are not adequate, yet their function is essential. That is why Aquinas does not call for an active suppression of concept-bound noetic activity in mystical ascent. Nor does he present the Spirit’s action in the gift of understanding as a graced silencing of concept-bound knowing.47 Indeed, 45 46 47 See ST II-II, q. 8, a. 7, ad 3, which seems to refer to I-II, q. 69, a. 2. On this point, one might compare Aquinas to Meister Eckhart, whose vernacular preaching proposed a path toward perfect mystical knowledge for the laity and the unlearned, a knowledge not simply caused by charity (though inseparable from it). I thus argue against the interpretation of Jacques Maritain, Distinguish to Unite or the Degrees of Knowledge, trans. Gerald B. Phelan (London: Geoffrey Bles, 1959), 688–93, and Charles Journet, Connaissance et Inconnaissance de Dieu, 116–18 and 138. For a critique of Maritain on this point, see Charles 1128 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. such total noetic silence is incompatible with Thomas’s doctrine of the imago Dei, where the perfect knowledge of God involves the production of an interior word.48 This “word of the heart” necessarily includes concepts and concept-bound truth judgments. But why does Thomas quietly insist that the summit of contemplation must include image-bound and concept-bound ways of knowing? The ultimate answer to that question comes in his essentially kataphatic theology, which is wholly centered on God’s revelation. Thomas holds fast to the Aristotelian principle that every negation presupposes an affirmation. As we saw above, without affirmations, remotions are meaningless. In mystical ascent, the affirmative names of God are qualified, not cleared away. Such a doctrine Dionysius cannot accept. Now, in the context of Aquinas’s theology of the gift of understanding, the affirmations especially concern the articles of faith revealed in Christ. The gift of understanding perfects the virtue of faith. This gift sharpens faith’s grasp of God’s revelation, of God’s self-manifestation that truly gives us a glimpse of the divine face. A refined knowledge of God’s historical revelation in Christ presupposes cognitive acts that employ phantasms and concepts, since public revelation occurs in the sensible world, especially in the life of Jesus. The Areopagite’s Moses moves beyond history and into a new knowledge that is no longer derived from God’s visible coming in the flesh, even though Dionysian interior illumination never contradicts God’s public revelation. For Aquinas, Scripture and the Creed are like the enfleshed voice of God without which the mystic cannot hear anything at the summit of knowledge. For Thomas, the highest knowledge about God integrates acquired and infused cognition. At the summit of Mt. Sinai, the contemplative ponders the affirmations about God and his saving deeds as transmitted in Scripture and the Creed, yet God’s interior light enables an ever-sharper penetration of those revealed mysteries. Aquinas brings the entire economy of salvation into the contemplation that occurs in the dark cloud! To my knowledge, no interpreter of Dionysius before Thomas had ever done that.49 48 49 Morerod, “La mystique dans l’épistémologie de Jacques Maritain,” Nova et Vetera (French) 83 (2008): 121–50. I agree with Ambroise Gardeil, who posits concept-bound cognition for the gift of understanding; see his La Structure de l’Âme et l’Expérience Mystique, vol. 2 (Paris: J. Gabalda, 1927), 161–64. ST I, q. 93, a. 7. The function of the articles of faith in the theology of the gift of understanding shows that Aquinas’s modification of Dionysian mystical ascent involves Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1129 Aquinas’s Moses in darkness thus ponders the heart of Scripture and the Creed with the full engagement of his intellect and imagination. Such contemplation provides the perfect prelude for Moses’s descent to the people of Israel at the bottom of Mt. Sinai, where the patriarch transmits God’s law. In other words, Aquinas’s Moses looks very much like the friar preacher who contemplates and then passes on to others the fruits of his contemplation. Because Aquinas’s mysticism grants an essential role to Scripture and the Creed at the height of contemplation, he can offer a mysticism for the preacher. None of this is to say that charity is secondary in Thomas’s mysticism.50 We have only pondered one pillar of Aquinas’s mystical theology. Indeed, Thomas holds that the height of union with God also requires acts of charity, yet charity needs to be guided by the intellect. The gift of understanding constitutes a most excellent and necessary help in the ascent of love. Perfect union includes graced acts of knowledge and charity. Practical Consequences for Dominican Spirituality A synthetic and historical analysis of Thomas’s theology of the Spirit’s gift of understanding sheds light on what Aquinas can contribute to Dominican spirituality. Here, I would like to accentuate some elements that are already present in the Dominican spiritual tradition. First, unlike Dionysius, Thomas seems remarkably unconcerned with the contemplative’s mode of consciousness. Aquinas spends little time on the technicalities of pondering God through images or on how to avoid a great multiplicity of thoughts. He remains remarkably silent about the Areopagite’s highly structured way of ascent through distinct stages of contemplation, from images to words to the wordless gaze. Second, the doctrine of the gift of understanding seems tailormade for a spirituality centered on lectio divina. Here, I take the term lectio divina to refer both to a prayerful study of God and his saving deeds and to a meditation on Scripture. Thomas reminds us that silent, wordless prayer need not constitute the height of contempla- 50 far more than the substitution of Aristotelian anthropology for Dionysian anthropology. Rather, the transformation is caused by philosophical and theological doctrines, including a vision of the purpose of the Incarnation and of God’s Word. Aquinas’s mystical theology is firmly rooted in Christology and a theology of revelation. Charity’s essential place in a doctrine of union emerges in many parts of his corpus, including ST II-II, qq. 23, 27, and 45. 1130 Bernhard Blankenhorn, O.P. tion. Of course, sometimes charity burns more fervently in silence, yet with an anthropology centered on the unicity of substantial form, we should have no inferiority complex when, during a time of lectio divina, we find ourselves constantly coming back to the words and images of Scripture in order to focus our minds. The pilgrim’s mode of knowing always remains bound to concepts and images, for it remains bound to mediations. The mediations are good; they are for us! Third, Thomas’s doctrine of the gift of understanding helps us to grasp how preaching (especially liturgical preaching) can be a form of mystagogia. For Aquinas, mystical ascent comes through progress both in love and in knowledge: the two advance together. While spiritual progress also requires continual purification of the passions, such growth ultimately remains a disposition for greater charity and saving knowledge. The mind’s ascent into the dark cloud comes through an ever-sharper grasp of the central mysteries of faith. If preaching is to assist the lay faithful in their spiritual progress, then preaching cannot have moral instruction or moral exhortation as its sole focal point. Rather, preaching must also be focused on the great mysteries that are summarized in the Creed. Preachers assist the Holy Spirit’s interior work of noetic purification that comes in the gift of understanding by correctly expounding on the doctrines of the Trinity, Creation, the Incarnation, and the Paschal Mystery. As preachers unfold Scripture’s and Tradition’s positive teachings about the triune God and his saving work, they make accessible the biblical affirmations concerning God and his saving design. The Spirit then infuses negations so as to wipe away believers’ misconceptions of the saving mysteries being proclaimed. The Spirit crushes the intellectual idols that linger in the minds of the faithful. Yet, these infused negations need affirmations in order to function. Consequently, the more preachers expound on the central mysteries of faith, the more they offer platforms from which the Spirit-guided believer can ascend to noetic union with God, and hence to loving union as well. In other words, preachers function somewhat like hierarchs. They first contemplate the great mysteries revealed to Israel and in Christ and seek the guidance of the Spirit who smashes their own conceptual idols. They then pass on the fruits of contemplation by explaining the way in which Scripture and Tradition affirm who God is and what he has done to save us. Such learning and docility to the Spirit’s motion already purify these affirmations from various errors. Aquinas on the Gift of Understanding and Dionysius’s Mystical Theology 1131 Yet, preachers cannot crush every conceptual idol in the minds of their hearers, since the latter’s backgrounds and experiences are often different from those of the preacher. Only the Spirit can complete the work of removing from believers’ minds diverse misconceptions about God’s public revelation. Then they too can enter the dark cloud, even if they have not studied the doctrine of analogy. And like contemplative preachers, they need not simply remain on Mt. Sinai and ponder the ineffable God. Since the Spirit still engages their minds and imaginations in the dark cloud as they ponder the divine mystery, the highest contemplative knowledge about God is not just a secret for the mystic alone, but also an infused word or a wise insight that can be shared. For, any believer who advances in holiness can imitate Moses and descend the holy mountain so as to pass on the message of the saving mysteries. They can transmit these mysteries more effectively through the help of the highest mystical encounter, for union with God usually brings a knowledge that can be partly put into words. Thus, mystagogical preaching forms contemplatives who evangelize. I suspect that most Dominicans (and others) already live this Thomistic spirituality. Aquinas’s theology of the gift of understanding helps to articulate with greater insight and clarity that which the N&V Dominican heritage proposes.51 51 I am grateful for the helpful comments of an anonymous reviewer, which allowed me to improve this essay. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1133–1151 Freedom and Heteronomy: Maximus the Confessor and the Question of Moral Creativity Adam G. Cooper John Paul II Institute for Marriage and Family Melbourne, Australia Of the many circles within which Maximus the Confessor is invoked as an authority, one that merits particular attention in recent studies lies in the field of moral theology. While criticisms emerging from the disciplines of historical and systematic theology have sometimes held up Maximus’s staunch defence of the doctrine of two wills in Christ as an embarrassing but typically Byzantine example of theological hair-splitting, not a few scholars have lauded the way the Confessor’s expositions on the topic, particularly in his reflections on Jesus’s prayer in the Garden of Gethsemane, may contribute towards a clearer understanding of the nature of human volition and its moral actualization. One example of this positive appropriation may be seen in an article by New Zealand theologian Ivor Davidson subtitled “The Ontological Dynamics of Incarnational Intention.”1 Davidson takes issue with criticisms that allege that, by ascribing two wills to Christ, Maximus and the traditional proponents of dyothelete Christology end up with an implausible account of Jesus’s conscious subjectivity. Besides asking too much of a Christological method whose interests and anxieties were more metaphysical and theological than they were physiological or psychological, the error in such allegations, argues Davidson, lies 1 Ivor J. Davidson, “‘Not My Will But Yours Be Done’: The Ontological Dynamics of Incarnational Intention,” International Journal of Systematic Theology 7.2 (2005): 178–204. 1134 Adam G. Cooper in regarding our own fallen experience of volition as humanly normal and, therefore, as the adequate criterion of what Christ’s experience of volition ought to be like. Drawing on Maximus’s evolving concept of “gnomic” will (γνώμη) and the rationale behind his eventual denial of its presence in Christ, Davidson exposes the superficial and illusory character of freedom as it is commonly conceived in many contemporary moral theories. If Maximus’s idea of freedom includes “the kind of self-determination appropriate to our real status as God’s creatures,” then, according to Davidson, “the diverse factors that complicate and impede such authentic direction—the kinds of factors, we might say, that have been highlighted in later modernity’s demise of confidence in the stability of a choosing self—are testimony to the reality that humans are not in practice half so free as might be supposed.”2 Another example of Maximus’s dyothelete Christology being enlisted in the service of moral theology is found in a still more recent (2007) essay by American Ian A. McFarland entitled “Willing is Not Choosing: Some Anthropological Implications of Dyothelite Christology.”3 McFarland similarly argues that Maximus’s assignment of will to the category of nature rather than to hypostasis “challenges the idea that willing is the source or ground of individual identity (hypostasis).” And, he continues, “if identity is not reducible to the will, then the will’s lack of freedom with respect to sin either now or in glory may not constitute the kind of threat to human integrity that modern Westerners are inclined to fear.”4 The mode of willing that characterizes the gnomic will, as McFarland interprets Maximus, is incapable of securing human fulfilment on its own because it is “in itself empty, directionless and (therefore) mutable.”5 True human freedom is realised not in an unlimited range of possible choices, nor even in the ability to make such choices, but in “a direct and undeviating orientation to God.”6 A third example of this recent appropriation of Maximus’s dyothelete Christology in the field of moral theology appears in the “action theory” of Italian theologian Livio Melina.7 According to Melina, 2 3 4 5 6 7 Davidson, “Not My Will But Yours Be Done,” 194. Ian A. McFarland, “Willing Is Not Choosing: Some Anthropological Implications of Dyothelite Christology,” International Journal of Systematic Theology 9.1 (2007): 3–23. McFarland, “Willing Is Not Choosing,” 4. Ibid., 20. Ibid., 17. Livio Melina, The Epiphany of Love: Toward a Theological Understanding of Christian Action (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2010), 90–91. Freedom and Heteronomy 1135 behind Thomas Aquinas’s recognition that Christ’s humanity was not simply the passive instrument utilized by the divine Logos, but was rather the principle of actions that were fully human, free, and salvifically meritorious, lies the wealth of the Eastern Fathers’ Christological reflections, and not least the distinction made by Maximus between thelêsis, understood as the natural capacity to will, and boulêsis, understood as the subjective actuation of that capacity in this or that particular way.8 For Melina, this means that, “even if the will’s natural dimension is the indispensable foundation of the freedom of action, it is not yet enough to explain it: spiritual nature founds but does not determine freedom. Action that is truly free not only implies the determination of the spiritual faculties [such as reason or will] . . . but also involves the personal subject taking a stance.”9 This notion of “taking a stance” in Melina’s action theory cannot be thought of outside an interpersonal relational structure. A human being “takes a stance” not simply with respect to certain things, but above all with respect to certain persons. According to Melina, human action always bears this interpersonal character: “the human act demands to be a personal act.”10 The descriptor “human” here refers to its being purposeful and voluntary action, that is, its emerging from the common human faculties of reason and will. The descriptor “personal” refers to the specific mode in which such purposeful and voluntary action takes place, a mode whose character always includes “an interpersonal dimension” and whose defining and ultimate goal is a communio personarum, a communion of persons.11 This is what Melina means when he asserts that “only with the appearance of the beloved” is the human act “complete in its final [i.e., personal] determination.”12 On the face of things, the invocation of Maximus as a supporting authority seems to be more justifiable in the first two examples with Davidson and McFarland but less so in the third example with Melina. Unlike Davidson and McFarland, Melina does not engage in a direct exegesis of Maximian texts but, rather, relies on several 8 9 10 11 12 On Aquinas’s appropriation of the patristic legacy on this topic, see Paul Gondreau, “St. Thomas Aquinas, the Communication of Idioms, and the Suffering of Christ in the Garden of Gethsemane,” in Divine Impassibility and the Mystery of Human Suffering, ed. James F. Keating and Thomas Joseph White (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2009), 214–45. Melina, Epiphany of Love, 91. Ibid. Ibid. Ibid. 1136 Adam G. Cooper secondary studies, freely synthesising their results with his Thomistic and Blondelian-inspired version of Christian personalism.13 Moreover, rigorous historical research has made us more wary about readings of Maximus and other ancient thinkers who, utilizing such terms as “nature” or “person” or “intellect”’ or “will,” unwittingly import into the language of the Fathers a conceptual content derived from much later developments in theological history and indicative of interests sometimes far removed from the Fathers’ actual thought.14 But having said that, my sense is that Melina’s appropriation of Maximus’s insights on the nature of human volition and freedom has more going for it than may seem to be the case at first. For Melina, human freedom consists in “the power to introduce novelty into the cyclical time of history, breaking the pre-established schemes of physical laws and natural inclinations.”15 His instinct in interpreting Maximus is to avoid any reduction of morality and freedom to the practical calculation of moral values from cognitively accessible universal principles and, instead, to presuppose that the specifically Christological aspect in the Confessor’s analysis of human action says something crucial about the realization of all human freedom: it “only occurs in reference to the will of a person: the beloved, the Father.”16 In other words, human action is free not just when it conforms to the general logos of human nature, but when it arises in the mode of radical love for another person, a mode whose concrete embodiment, being personal and unique and exposed to all the variables of interpersonal freedom, will always be creative and new. 13 14 15 16 In this context, Melina cites the work of R. -A. Gauthier, “Saint Maxime le Confesseur et la psychologie de l-acte humain,” Recherches de Théologie Ancienne et Médiévale 21 (1954): 51–100. Elsewhere, Melina has also collaborated with Rome-based Maximian scholar P. -G. Renczes, publishing the latter’s essay “La gloria del Padre e pianezza dell’umano: L’apporto di Massimo il Confessore a una precisazione dell’antropologia teologica dei Padre,” in Il bene e la persona nell’ agire, ed. L. Melina and J. -J. Pérez-Soba (Rome: Lateran University Press, 2002), 147–57. See the recent summary of this issue by Alexis Torrance in “Personhood and Patristics in Orthodox Theology: Reassessing the Debate,” Heythrop Journal 52 (2011): 700–07. On this question, it may be apt to mention Vladimir Lossky’s remark that “the quest for a Christian personalist anthropology in the Fathers is certainly worthwhile,” even if it must be “pursued with care” (reported in ibid., 705). Melina, Epiphany of Love, 4. Ibid., 91. Freedom and Heteronomy 1137 What I want to do in the present article, therefore, is to revisit Maximus’s theological exegesis of the scriptural accounts of Christ’s prayer in Gethsemane with a view to judging whether the creative appropriation of his anthropology along the lines outlined by Melina is justified. I shall begin by turning to a number of familiar and well-studied passages to see whether they might yield any fresh insights when approached with three particular questions in mind. The first concerns the extent to which Maximus maintains the integrity of Christ’s singular subjectivity, representing all of Jesus’s speaking, acting, and suffering in such a way that we encounter in them one and the same personal “I.” The second question concerns the creative and novel character of Christ’s speaking, acting, and suffering, the extent to which we encounter in them a completely new actuality that reveals what it means to be God, and what it means to be human in a surprising and hitherto unexpected way. The third concerns the integration of instinct and intention, the extent to which Christ’s conscious acts of will incorporate, and do not oppose, even the most instinctive human impulses and natural inclinations. With the discussion generated by these three questions, I shall proceed to offer an assessment of the possible merits in Melina’s line of interpretation. Singularity of Subject We begin by asking to what extent Maximus maintains the integrity of one and the same personal “I” of which is properly predicated all of Jesus’s speaking, acting, and suffering, particularly those manifested in his Gethsemane prayer. Exegesis of this narrative event appears in a number of places in Maximus’s writings, but most of the focus in secondary studies centres on its appearance in three Opuscula (3, 6, and 7) and the famous Disputation with Pyrrhus, texts that date from a brief period in the Confessor’s African sojourn between AD 642 and 645, subsequent to the publication of the Imperial Ekthesis (638) and prior to the Imperial Typos (647/8).17 Maximus’s chief concern in 17 Traditional ascriptions of authorship and dating for the Disputation with Pyrrhus have recently been questioned by Ryan W. Strickler, “A Dispute in Dispute: Forgery, Heresy, and Sainthood in Seventh-Century Byzantium,” (master’s thesis, University of Kentucky, 2013). Elements in Strickler’s case may deserve attention in the broader field of Maximian historiography but are not really relevant to the concerns of the present article. For the scholarly consensus on context and dating, see Polycarp Sherwood, O.S.B., “An Annotated Date-List of the Works of Maximus the Confessor,” Studia Anselmiana 30 (1952): viii–64; 1138 Adam G. Cooper these texts is not to answer the kinds of questions we moderns might typically raise of this narrative event, but to respond to the assertion made by the Ekthesis that any attribution of two activities to Christ would imply two wills and that to attribute two wills to Christ would be to envision a virtual two-personed Christ in which the divine and human elements were at best juxtaposed. The wording of the Ekthesis indicates an implicit intention to exclude any interpretation of the Gethsemane event that would find in it an internal struggle in Christ between “God the Word,” who “wished to fulfill the salutary suffering,” on the one hand, and on the other, “his humanity,” which “resisted his will and was opposed to it.”18 In putting it this way, the Ekthesis brought to the surface a hermeneutical question of abiding importance for both Christology and theological anthropology: how are we to reconcile what appear to be two conflicting desires in Jesus? “Father, if it be possible, let this cup pass from me.” Here, the object of desire is avoidance of impending suffering and death. “Yet not my will, but yours be done.” Here, the object of desire is the accomplishment of the Father’s will, which in this case seems to necessitate existential crisis.19 The idea that Jesus experienced an internal affective conflict seems to be at odds with an understanding of virtue as an excellence arising from the harmonious, rational integration of our various inclinations and desires. Any such conflict would seem to be more a symptom of the kind of volitional uncertainty and unruly appetitive disintegration that characterize humanity’s fallen and wounded state and that Maximus sums up in the word gnomê. As is well known, Maximus, while insisting on a duality of wills in Christ, rejected any notion of a natural opposition between them.There is nothing inherent in human nature that opposes its Creator. But that left him with the challenge of making sense of 18 19 Guido Bausenhart, In allem uns gleich ausser der Sünde : Studien zum Beitrag Maximos’ Des Bekenners zur altkirchlichen Christologie : mit einer Kommentierten ubersetzung der “Disputatio Cum Pyrrho” (Mainz: Matthias-GrünewaldVerlag, 1992); Pauline Allen and Bronwen Neil, eds., Maximus the Confessor and His Companions: Documents from Exile (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2002), 14–18; and Pauline Allen, ed., Sophronius of Jerusalem and Seventh Century Heresy:The Synodical Letter and Other Documents (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2009). Ekthesis. This is my own translation of the Greek text found in Sophronius of Jerusalem and Seventh-Century Heresy: The Synodical Letter and Other Documents , ed. Pauline Allen (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2009), 214. The Gospel of Luke repeatedly expresses this sense of “divine necessity” behind Jesus’s mission with the impersonal verb δεῖ; see Joseph A. Fitzmyer, The Gospel according to Luke I–IX (New York: Doubleday, 1970), 179–80. Freedom and Heteronomy 1139 what has been called the “graphic realism of Jesus’ initial resistance and his coming to a final resolve in the Gethsemane prayer.”20 Studies of Maximus’s attempts in these texts to interpret Jesus’s Gethsemane prayer have clarified the prominence he gives to the active role of Christ’s humanity in the resolution of this resistance. Ever since Marcel Doucet’s criticism of von Balthasar’s over-dramatization of the duality between the Logos and his assumed humanity, interpreters have rightly located the drama of resolution and obedience within Christ’s human volitional complex.21 In his studious monograph on the topic, Demetrios Bathrellos fairly sums up scholarly consensus by asserting that, in Opusculum 6 especially, Maximus offers “a piece of meticulous and insightful exegesis” in which he points out “in an unambiguous way that it is the Logos as man who addresses the Father in Gethsemane.”22 But is this an adequate explanation? True enough, Maximus does use the “as man” formula once, right near the end of Opusculum 6: “Having become like us for our sake, he who is God by nature said to God the Father in a fittingly human manner, ‘Let not my will but yours prevail,’ since, possessing the fullness of the Father’s will, he also has a human will as man [ὡς ἄνθρωπος].”23 But it seems to me that we do not have here a simple ascription of Jesus’s prayer to the Logos “as man.” At stake here is not just a moot point in Maximian interpretation, but a much wider issue in Christology. While a survey of texts from the history of patristic Christology attests to the ubiquity of the formulations “as God” or “as man” used to qualify Christ’s various activities for the sake of a certain dogmatic precision, this way of speaking arguably falls short of accounting for the full depth and drama of Christ’s passion, whether in Gethsemane or elsewhere. It was against such a mathematical dividing up of Christ’s various 20 21 22 23 Paul M. Blowers, “The Passion of Jesus Christ in Maximus the Confessor: A Reconsideration,” Studia Patristica 34 (2001): 361–77, at 367. See Marcel Doucet, “La Volonté Humaine du Christ, Spécialment en son Agonie: Maxime le Confessuer, Interpréte de l’Écriture,” Science et Esprit 37.2 (1985): 123–59, esp. 135–36. Demetrios Bathrellos, The Byzantine Christ: Person, Nature, and Will in the Christology of St Maximus the Confessor (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2004), 147. Opusculum 6 (PG, 91:68C; all translations from this text are my own). Notice here how Maximus embellishes the words of Jesus with the verb ἰσχυσάτω (“prevail”), which does not appear in the Synoptics. 1140 Adam G. Cooper actions into those that he performed “as God” and those that he performed “as man” that Cyril’s Third Letter to Nestorius, endorsed by the Council of Ephesus (431), required that all of Christ’s actions and passions be attributed to the one subject, “the one enfleshed hypostasis of the Logos.”24 Elsewhere, in commenting on the Gethsemane event in Opusculum 7, Maximus does indeed use the “as God” and “as man” formulations a number of times. But it is not clear to me that he means them to be regarded as virtual subjects of predication, nor even as simple qualifiers. His intention can be better understood, I think, by turning to study their appearance in Ambiguum 5, a text dating from before the full-blown outbreak of the Monothelete controversy. It is here, while defending the coherence and applicability of the Christology of Dionysius the Areopagite, that Maximus proposes what I regard as his profoundest insights into the mystery of Christ’s person and action. The central thesis of Ambiguum 5 is that, while Christ is essentially divine and essentially human, the circumstances of the hypostatic union have impacted his existence and activity in such a way that his divine nature can no longer be accounted for in purely divine terms, nor his human nature in purely human terms: “He exists neither as a mere human being, nor as bare God.”25 Thus, when Maximus uses the “as God” and “as man” formulas, they must be interpreted with this thesis in clear view. So when he says, “As God, he [Christ] was the moving principle of his own humanity, while as man, he was revelatory principle of his own divinity,”26 the point he wants to make is that one and the same subject, the incarnate Logos, is involved in each and every one of his actions both “as God” and “as man” simultaneously. The characteristic properties of both natures are manifest at the existential level in one way or another in each particular, concrete act of the one person. Maximus’s preferred way of expressing this exchange of properties in Christ is to say that he did human things in a divine way and divine things in a human way.27 24 25 26 27 Norman P. Tanner, ed., Decrees of the Ecumenical Councils, vol. 1 (London: Sheed and Ward, 1990), 56. Ambiguum 5, lines 33–43. English translation from this work is my own and done from the critical edition of the Greek text in Maximi Confessoris Ambigua ad Thomam una cum Epistula Secunda ad Eundem, ed. Bart Janssens, Corpus Christianorum Series Graeca (hereafter, CCSG) 48 (Turnhout, BE: Brepols, 2002), 20–21. Ambiguum 5.192–93 (CCSG, 48:28). See further Adam G. Cooper, The Body in Saint Maximus the Confessor: Holy Flesh, Wholly Deified (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2005), 127–56. Freedom and Heteronomy 1141 Something similar, I believe, is going on in the formulations of Opuscula 6 and 7. In these, Maximus is at pains to bring out the dual or theandric character of all of Christ’s actions, even those that seem most markedly human. In Opusculum 7, for example, while discerning in the two parts of the Gethsemane prayer a reference to two distinct wills, he nevertheless builds into his “as man” and “as God” formulations this cross-over reciprocal qualification: “For it appears that the same as man, who is also God by nature, wills in accordance with the economy that the cup pass, and in this he typifies what is human. . . . And again it appears that as God, being also a human being in essence, he wills to fulfill the economy of the Father and work the salvation of all.”28 He continues again: “It is made clear then that as man, being God by nature and acting humanly, he willingly accepts the experience of sufferings for our sake. And it is again made clear that as God, being by nature a human being and acting divinely, he naturally exhibits the signs of his divinity.”29 It is from both these sufferings and these signs, Maximus concludes, that “the same one is recognised as being at the same time [ὁμοῦ] both God and man.”30 The Confessor’s emphasis here and throughout the treatise seems to be on avoiding reducing this or that action of Christ to one enacted by him either “as God” or “as man” and on, instead, predicating actions to Christ both “as God” and “as man.” He champions this double predication over against the pious but misguided Monothelete tendency to credit certain actions to Christ only “as God.” “For if,” Maximus argues, “it is only as God that he willed these things [hunger, thirst, weariness, and so on], and not the same as man, then either the body has become divine by nature, or the Logos has changed his nature and become flesh by loss of his own divinity.”31 The same train of thought seems to be operative in Opusculum 6. There Maximus considers three ways of reading the first part of the Gethsemane prayer, the petition, “Let this cup pass from me.” The first is to understand it as a prayer arising “from the man who is like us” (ἀπο τοῦ ἀνθρώπου . . . τοῦ καθ’ ἡμᾶς), a characterization Maximus explains in terms of a will that “often resists and contends with God.”32 But such an interpretation would not fit the second half of the 28 29 30 31 32 Opusculum 7 (PG, 91:84C). Ibid. Ibid. Ibid. (PG, 91:77B). Ibid. 6 (PG, 91:65BC). 1142 Adam G. Cooper prayer, in which the same subject does not oppose but acquiesces to God’s will. A second possible interpretation is to attribute the petition to “the eternal divinity of the Only-Begotten Son,” but this would either introduce a division of will between the Father and the Son or ascribe the wish to avoid the cup also to the Father, which would negate the intelligibility of the prayer altogether. The third way of understanding the petition, a way that Maximus commends, is as belonging to “the man we know as Savior” (τοῦ κατὰ τὸν Σωτῆρα νοουμένου ἀνθρώπου). Quite possibly it is this phrase, with its mention of anthropos, that would lead interpreters to say that Maximus here ascribes the prayer to Christ “as man.” But the crucial “Savior” part of this phrase for Maximus necessarily includes what is proper to Christ’s divinity, for as he says a little further on, it is God’s very nature to will our salvation.33 To ascribe the petition to “the man who is Savior” is in effect to ascribe it to the man who is God, which is altogether different from ascribing it to Christ simply “as man.”34 The Creative Newness of Christ’s Action The second question I want to explore concerns the creative and novel character of Christ’s actions, the extent to which we encounter in them a completely new actuality that reveals what it means to be human in 33 34 Τοῦτο γαρ αὐτῷ φύσει καθέστηκε θελητόν. “This object of will” (Τοῦτο θελητόν) is a reference back to the immediately previous clause, to “our salvation”; see ibid. (PG, 91:68B). Thomas Weinandy has argued that all of Christ’s actions and passions should be predicated of him “as man” and none of them “as God”: “If the Son of God is man and has identified himself as man, then, it seems to me, that he exists, as incarnate, totally within the parameters or boundaries of all that is human. Thus the Son of God not only has a human body, soul, intellect, will, and emotions, etc., but equally he also has an integral human ‘I,’ a psychological centre within which all of these are expressed and experienced. The human ‘I’ of Jesus is the human psychological self-consciousness of the divine Son. He thought, spoke, and acted as well as underwent all his experiences from within the limits of his human ‘I.’ When Jesus said ‘I,’ it was truly the Son of God saying ‘I’ in a fully authentic human manner”; see Thomas G. Weinandy, Does God Suffer? (Edinburgh: T and T Clark, 2000), 209–10. But if this is so, then in what sense can we say that Jesus is divine? Only nominally? If really and ontologically, this seems to challenge the exclusive integrity of the human “I.” In short, Jesus must be able to say both “I am a man” and “I am God”; both the divine and the human must coincide in his “I.” Put another way, the divine “I” is concealed (and thereby revealed) in the human “I.” If it is asked what it is in the first part of the Gethsemane prayer that manifests his divinity, one need only be reminded of the fact that this is a prayer addressed to God as “Father,” a form of invocation proper to the divine Son. Freedom and Heteronomy 1143 an entirely fresh and hitherto unexpected way. For this, we may refer first of all to a typically Maximian theme brought out so well by Paul Blowers in his essay on the Confessor’s “passiology.”35 Blowers suggests that a richer and psychologically more compelling exposition of the Gethsemane prayer can be found in the two other Opuscula (3 and 7) and the Disputation with Pyrrhus, especially when they are illuminated by passages in the earlier Ambigua ad Ioannem and the Quaestiones ad Thalassium. Above all, Blowers’s reconsideration highlights the expression often employed by Maximus that speaks of the way Christ makes “use” (χρῆσις) of typically human passions such as the fear of death, indeed even death itself, so as to transform them into redemptive and life-giving instruments. To speak of Christ “using” his fear of death for salvific purposes should not be thought of in the sense of Christ opting on some occasions to “use” his human attributes and opting on other occasions to use his divine attributes, thereby effecting a kind of break between the person who does the “using” and his two instrumental natures.36 Rather, it seems more akin to the way, for example, a person might harness the initial motions of anger that sometimes arise in him, allowing them to propel him towards acts of justice or courage instead of allowing them the kind of undisciplined free reign that would more likely end up in acts of injustice or self-pity.37 Moral failure or success arises not at the level of the initial affective motion, but in its respective appropriation, deployment, or “use” in this or that purposeful action. Similarly, there is in principle a blameless, even a positively “good” impulse embedded in our natural aversion to pain and death; indeed, its absence would normally indicate some sort of psycho-physical abnormality. Moral evaluation applies not to its presence as such, but to how it is used. Another context in Maximus’s writings in which the novelty and freedom of Christ’s action comes to light is again in the fifth Ambiguum ad Thomam. In discussing the meaning of the disputed 35 36 37 Blowers, “The Passion of Jesus Christ in Maximus the Confessor.” Davidson criticizes this conception in Hans Schwartz (“Not My Will but Yours Be Done,” 198). Maximus envisions the positive use of impulses such as anger and desire in Orationis dominicae expositio, lines 520–60 (CCSG, 23:113) and, of course, in the famous passage of Quaestiones ad Thalassium 1, lines 5–40 (CCSG, 7:47–49), where desire, pleasure, fear, and grief are transformed into virtuous dispositions in those “who take captive every thought in obedience to Christ” (2 Cor 10:5). 1144 Adam G. Cooper Dionysian phrase “a certain new theandric activity,” Maximus argues that Christ fully manifested what we recognise as our common human nature, but he did so “by way of new modalities that are not ours.”38 On this basis, Maximus can say that “there is nothing human [in Christ] that, on account of its supernatural modality, was not also divine.”39 By renewing human nature, by pioneering it afresh and making of it a gift available to all, Christ shows how human action in its free and fulfilled state properly introduces into history an utterly singular and unexpected quality that transcends all “normal” and predictable schemes of natural causation. With respect to the Gethsemane prayer, then, this means that Christ really did feel the properly human aversion to death, for there would be something wrong with a being that did not at some level resist its own destruction. Yet, he experienced this aversion not in a way that might drive him to seek refuge in selfish or escapist behavior, but in a uniquely transcendent way—that is, in God’s way—and therefore in a way that serves for human salvation. Through this unique mode of appropriation by Christ, the natural human fear of death, which so often takes the concrete form of a crippling power or overwhelmingly impulsive drive, was thereby granted a new, supernatural quality as “a precious resource of salvation and deification.”40 In this way, summarizes Blowers, Maximus envisions Christ in the garden as “pioneering” for all human beings “a new and edifying mode” of the common human aversion to death, one that does not curtail or frustrate human aspirations but enables their ultimate fulfilment.41 Integration of Instinct and Intention The third question that calls for our attention concerns the integration of instinct and intention, the extent to which Christ’s conscious acts of will incorporate, rather than oppose, even the most instinctive human impulses and inclinations. In two statements in Opusculum 7, Maximus affirms that Christ’s natural human will “was not opposed to God,”42 38 39 40 41 42 Ambiguum 5.184 (CCSG, 48:28). Ibid., 5.173–74 (CCSG, 48:27–28). Blowers, “The Passion of Jesus Christ in Maximus the Confessor,” 369. Paul M. Blowers and Robert L. Wilken, St Maximus the Confessor: On the Cosmic Mystery of Jesus Christ (Crestwood, NY: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2003), 112n7. Opusculum 7 (PG, 91:81D). Freedom and Heteronomy 1145 but then in referring to the movement from the stance of aversion expressed in the first part of the prayer to the stance of agreement expressed in the second part of the prayer, says, with reference to that aversion, that he “turns against it” (ὥρμα κατ’ αὐτοῦ).43 A solution to this problem has been helped greatly by the recognition that the terms used for “will” in many passages do not denote the rational appetite exclusively, but sometimes include reference to the lower appetitive and instinctive impulses. For example, in Opusculum 3, Maximus defines thelêma as a natural desire for being, which he explains is not a conscious psychological longing, but a kind of constitutive, organizing energy within a being that orients it toward its own actuation and fulfilment.44 Again in Opusculum 1, Maximus defines “natural will” (physikon thelêma) as a power that “holds together in being” the various properties of a nature.45 As Bathrellos summarises the wider textual evidence, “the will is a unity of instinctive and rational elements.”46 This assertion is set over against the thesis of both von Balthasar and Marcel Doucet, who hold that Christ’s repulsion in the face of death was “not simply a blind, vital drive to stay alive, but intelligent willing.”47 Of course, Doucet was himself critical of von Balthasar on this issue. Already back in 1985, Doucet rejected von Balthasar’s dramatic rendition of the duality of wills in Christ in terms of a symmetrical, face-to-face struggle and its resolution in advance, as it were, by the overarching will exercised by the Logos in becoming human to begin with. Von Balthasar’s approach is well illustrated by his translation of the phrase ὥρμα κατ’ αὐτοῦ with “he does violence to his own will” (Er «stürmt gegen seinen eigenen Willen an»).48 Such an approach, Doucet argued, leaves no room for the possibility of speaking of a real submission and obedience on the part of Christ’s human will. There can be no radical contrariety in Christ. If there is an internal tension, it is played out not between the Logos and his humanity, but within 43 44 45 46 47 48 Ibid., (PG, 91:81B). Ibid., 3 (PG, 91:45C). Ibid., 1 (PG, 91:12C–13A). Bathrellos, The Byzantine Christ, 145n273. Hans Urs von Balthasar, Cosmic Liturgy: The Universe according to Maximus the Confessor, trans. Brian E. Daley (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2003), 264. Cf. Doucet, “La Volonté humaine du Christ,” 135 (quoted by Bathrellos, The Byzantine Christ, 145n273). Von Balthasar, Kosmische Liturgie: Das Weltbild Maximus’ des Bekenners (Trier: Johannes Verlag, 1988), 266 (Cosmic Liturgy, 268). 1146 Adam G. Cooper the dynamisms of Christ’s human will itself, between the natural “velleity,” the instinctive tendency to conserve one’s own being, and the concrete act of will that brings such velleity into submissive obedience to God.49 The “fighting against” that Maximus speaks of, says Doucet, takes place “in his humanity, or more precisely, in his human will.”50 Yet, to my mind, the two claims need not be so keenly opposed. It is not legitimate, at least not without imposing a neo-Kantian interpretation on Maximus, to dismiss the non-rational or instinctive element of will as irrelevant to Christ’s self-determination, as Bathrellos seems to do.51 Here von Balthasar’s proposed solution to the problem of opposition seems to me to make certain sense not only of Maximus’s thought but also of the exigencies of the human reality. In an intellectual being, argues von Balthasar, natural desire is always, “at its root, an intellectual desire.”52 The implications are twofold. First, spirit or intelligence not only is operative in a human being at the level of conscious acts of choice but penetrates all the way down to qualify in some way even the deepest instinctive drives. Second, concrete determinations of will always arise out of the intelligent but as yet unfulfilled complex of affects and desires that mark our psychophysical constitution. Of course, precisely therein lie both our unity and our vulnerability. In Christ, however, this same complex of natural drives, says Maximus, “does not precede and lead the will, as happens with us,”53 but is itself the result of a higher act of will, the will of the Logos who, in becoming incarnate, gives his humanity existence and, within the limits of a purposeful salvific project, freely makes his own the full range of its natural motions. In this way, says von Balthasar, Christ’s natural fear of death “was itself supported by his underlying hypostatic freedom, which supported his whole nature. His hypostatic identity, therefore, bears and results in the natural opposition of the two natures, and in its supreme personal disponibility [to the Father’s will] it dissolves the opposition between them to the same degree that it brings them into being.”54 In embracing and making his own the nature he assumed, the 49 50 51 52 53 54 Doucet, ‘La Volonté humaine du Christ’, 136. Ibid. See Bathrellos, The Byzantine Christ, 123. Von Balthasar, Cosmic Liturgy, 264. Οὐ γὰρ προηγεῖται ἐν τῷ Κυρίῳ καθάπερ ἐν ἡμῖν, τῆς θελήσεως τὰ φυσικά; see Disputatio cum Pyrrho (PG, 91:297D). Von Balthasar, Cosmic Liturgy, 266. Freedom and Heteronomy 1147 Logos personally willed and affirmed all its finite proclivities and vulnerabilities, including those that “naturally” move it in a certain healthy and blameless direction, but which in the circumstances of the saving economy would require modal re-configuration. In essence, these inclinations are human. In their modal actualisation and determination by Christ, they are rendered divine.55 Maximus can thus speak of Christ, in the very moment in which the instinctive human aversion to death arises in him and comes to expression in prayer, “turning against” the inclination manifest in this aversion. The intensity implied by this verb “turning against” is softened if we compare it to parallel expressions in the immediate context that speak of “setting aside” (ἀθέτησις), “surrendering” (ὑποκλίνω), or “constraining” (συνελαῦνω) this inclination in order to bring it into union with the saving plan of the Father.56 For von Balthasar, all of this can only make sense inasmuch as this natural inclination is “from the start, already in submission.”57 In submission to what? Only to the will of the Logos? This is how von Balthasar has it. Must we not also add: “and also to the will of his human nature”? But this would be to fall into the trap again of ascribing actions or events to this or that nature in a way Maximus never quite permits. While he affirms the presence of a human will, its decisive determination, its concrete actualization, is never an act of a nature, nor even of a mere man, but always that of a singular subject who is the humanized God.58 As Maximus asserts in Opusculum 3, it is the overarching salvific skopos of the Incarnation that functions as the decisive personal orientation within which Christ’s shrinking from death is integrated. Since the Son of God became a human being not primarily to suffer but to save, his natural aversion to suffering does not stand intrinsically opposed to the saving divine will, nor is it simply reigned in by a higher act of bare human volition, but arises as a normal motion of natural inclination that, in Maximus’s words, is “shaped by and brought into concordance with the interweaving of the natural logos with the mode of the economy.”59 55 56 57 58 59 Opusculum 7 (PG, 91:81D). Ibid. (PG, 91:80D–81A). Von Balthasar, Cosmic Liturgy, 269. See Opusculum 4 (PG, 91:60A): ὡς ἄνθρωπος οὐ ψιλός, ἀλλ᾿ ἐνανθρωπήσας Θεός. Opusculum 3 (PG, 91:48C). 1148 Adam G. Cooper Concluding Application What I have been doing in the discussion up until this point is trying to visit a number of well worked-over Maximian problems in order to generate some thoughts that will better allow us to judge the validity of one particular appropriation of Maximus’s dyothelete Christology in the field of moral theology. It is my sense that all three areas of discussion open up insights that lend themselves to an interpretation of morality and human action along the lines indicated by Melina. My purpose in this concluding section is to recall briefly two aspects of Melina’s thought outlined in the introduction and see how they may dovetail with what we have gleaned from Maximus.The first was Melina’s notion that human freedom consists in “the power to introduce novelty into the cyclical time of history, breaking the pre-established schemes of physical laws and natural inclinations.”60 The second aspect was Melina’s sense that the specifically Christological aspect in the Confessor’s analysis of human action says something crucial about the realization of all human freedom: that it “only occurs in reference to the will of a person: the beloved, the Father.”61 It seems to me that the first of these two points fits well with what we have said about the Maximian notion of Christ as pioneer of a new and saving modality of human action. Christ performs human activities “in a way beyond the human.”62 He thereby inaugurates a new level of human freedom, actualizing everything that is proper to human nature, but “by way of new modalities that are not ours.”63 This is not to envisage freedom as totally autonomous and self-designing. Christ’s freedom simultaneously transcends and affirms the limitations of our common human nature and bodily structure. There is much in the normal course of human experience that unfolds unavoidably as a matter of natural necessity. In Christ, however, these dynamisms provide the crucial ground and trajectory for creative and renovative action. Herein lies an obvious difference between Christ’s affectivity and our own fallen proclivities. A stable disposition to perform good acts relies upon the impetus provided by the affections and desires. In the unvirtuous person, however, such affections and desires lack the appropriate order and temper, and thus, instead of impelling him 60 61 62 63 Melina, Epiphany of Love, 4. Ibid., 91. Ambiguum 5.73 (CCSG, 48:23). Ibid., 5.184 (CCSG, 48:28). Freedom and Heteronomy 1149 toward the good, they tend to dissipate his energies and impede the singleness of heart, the clarity of purpose, and the connatural instinct for good called for by the moral situation. When faced with impending pain or evil, our natural fears and desires often tend to exercise a compelling and sometimes turbulent influence on our intentional choices. In Christ, by contrast, all these affections and desires are actively harnessed and spontaneously integrated into the free and creative actualization of a purposeful salvific project. As Maximus puts it: By freedom of will [ἐξουσίᾳ γνώμης], he turned the passions of nature into active deeds, though not as consequences of natural necessity, as they are in our case. Moreover, possessing what belongs to us, he passed through the passibility of our nature and, by his freedom, proved that there was moving in him that which in our case tends to bring about a seditious turbulence of will. That which with us is naturally present as a mover of will [γνώμης κινητικὸν: something that puts gnome into motion] is rendered by Christ’s freedom something movable by will [γνώμῃ κινητὸν].64 In Maximus’s mind, this lack of necessity in Jesus is a consequence of his virgin birth, by which his human nature comes into being not by a law of natural necessity but by the free and supernatural act of the Word.65 The validity of the second point becomes clearer when we supplement our findings with an observation whose importance is only hinted at by Maximus but that seems to me to be of peculiar relevance to the integration of Christ’s natural human desires and their actualization within an interpersonal, filial modality. It has to do with the role of prayer as the concrete means by which this integration and actualization take place. On several occasions in the passages under discussion, Maximus alludes to Jesus’s act of prayer in Gethsemane as the means by which he manifests his humanity in all its weakness and constrains it to union with the Father’s will.66 But 64 65 66 Ibid., 5.163–67 (CCSG, 48:27). In this earlier work, Maximus clearly still attributes gnome (deliberation) to Christ. Yet, the point made here remains essentially applicable even when one denies gnome to Christ. See also Ambigua ad Iohannem 41 (PG, 91:1309A). See, e.g., Opusculum 7 (PG, 91:80CD—81A) and Opusculum 6 (PG, 91:68C). 1150 Adam G. Cooper what Maximus does not seem to reflect on—at least in the Opuscula—is the filial mode in which this prayer is expressed as a personal address to God as “Father.”67 The concrete content and intention of the prayer corresponds exactly both to Christ’s filial identity and to the motion of his normal human desires. Thus, Christ in Gethsemane is what a human being looks like when all his natural capacities and propensities are actuated in a divine way, or more specifically, in the way proper to the relation that pertains between the Son and the Father.68 Those capacities and propensities that might, in other cases, lead to actions that undermine this relation are, in Jesus, drawn into the ambit of filial communion with the Father and effectively made to actualize his universal saving purpose in history precisely through the medium of intimate (though agonizing) prayer. In a similar way, Melina proposes that human action is essentially—that is, according to its Christocentric telos—filial and interpersonal. The knowledge that guides particular moral actions is discovered not in an objective cognitive recognition of a universal norm and subsequent conformity to it, but rather relies on a “creative moral insight” born from within the subjective and particular conditions of a concrete “I-Thou” relationship.69 To say that human moral action is filial is to say that it has its origin and end in the reciprocal love of God the Father and his Son in the freedom of the Spirit. The proper horizon against which human action must be compared or measured is not human nature, in the first instance, nor even the divine will, but filial communion with the Father. Only by insertion into this filial relation does human action come to full flower. 67 68 69 However, in his Commentary on the Lord’s Prayer, Maximus takes up a prominent patristic topos in highlighting the fact that only the Son properly calls God “Father,” so that it is only by grace of adoption that human beings, for whom God is properly called “creator,” can also call him “Father”; see Orationis dominicae expositio 258–69 (CCSG, 23:71). “Jesus exhibits the nature and character of God in the only way in which they can be absolutely and perfectly exhibited in the context of human behaviour, namely in such a relationship as properly belongs to man over against God, the relationship of glad and willing filial obedience”; see C. F. D. Moule, “The Manhood of Jesus in the New Testament,” in Christ, Faith and History: Cambridge Studies in Christology, ed. S. W. Sykes and J. P. Clayton (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1972), 95–110, at 101. On this notion of “creative moral insight,” see Stephen A. Dinan, “The Particularity of Moral Knowledge,” The Thomist 50 (1986): 66–84 (referred to by Melina, Epiphany of Love, 59). Freedom and Heteronomy 1151 Whether or not these reflections satisfy a strict exegesis of Maximus’s writings, they encourage us to penetrate the letter of his texts in order to get nearer the mystery they surely try to express. Maximus’s account of Gethsemane teaches us that human beings actualize their freedom not in the mode of decisions whose rightness is deduced in advance through a detached and rational grasp of the truth in all its blazing objectivity, but in actu, in the mode of an interpersonal communion within which desire, born of love, is wholly captivated by the Father’s redemptive purpose for broken humanity. This in turn leads us to think again about the meaning of Christ’s obedience, which the Confessor, in connection with the Christ hymn of Philippians 2:5–11, links especially to the Gethsemane event.70 It consists not simply in external conformity to a heteronomous divine command, nor in a heavy-handed and forceful coercion of unwilling impulses in a direction that they are bound to resist, but in an active interpersonal union of two desires, two freedoms. In short, Christ’s obedience in the garden is essentially an embodied form of love, the love between the Son and the Father. This obedience opens the way for our historically acquired alterity to God to be healed of its divisive and alienating quality and, through its inclusion in the loving and fruitful alterity of the divine persons, to attain the communion with God that, from the beginning, has defined the human vocation. N&V 70 Opusculum 6 (PG, 91:68C). Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1153–1174 Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy: Revisiting a Continuator of Thomas Aquinas Domenic D’Ettore Marian University Indianapolis, IN Introduction Thomas Sutton (1250–1315) has been called the “Prince of the primitive Thomists.”1 A contemporary of John Duns Scotus at Oxford in the first decade of the fourteenth century, Sutton was among the first participants in Thomist-Scotist dialogue, as he and Scotus responded to each other’s oral and written teachings.2 Twentieth-century scholarship on Sutton’s doctrine of analogous naming was initiated in 1959 by Joseph Przezdziecki,3 whose article served as a point of reference for Bernard Montagnes’s 1963 study of Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine of analogy and for the 1990s and 2000s articles by E. J. Ashworth and Mark Henninger. Each of these works draws principally or exclusively A. Kremple, La Doctrine de la Relation chez Saint Thomas: Exposé historique et systématique (Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1952), 29. For information about Sutton’s place in early Thomism, see Frederick Roensch, Early Thomistic School (Dubuque, IA: The Priory Press, 1964), 44–51 and 73–78. Roensch says that Sutton “represents a high point in the progress of Thomism and occupies a position of superiority in matters of doctrinal analysis among his fellow Dominicans” (ibid., 51). On his life and works, see also Gyula Klima, “Thomas of Sutton,” in A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia and Timothy B. Noone (Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 2003), 664–65. 2 Joseph J. Przezdziecki briefly treats the evidence that Sutton and Scotus knew of and responded to each other’s work in “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique of the Doctrine of Univocity,” in An Etienne Gilson Tribute, ed. Charles O’Neil (Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 1959), 190–92. He draws the conclusion that Sutton’s “masterly intervention” did much to check the spread of Scotism at Oxford (ibid., 208). 3 Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 189–208. 1 1154 Domenic D’Ettore from Thomas Sutton’s Quaestiones ordinariae 32 and 33.4 Przezdziecki, Ashworth, and most of all Henninger provide excellent summaries of significant portions of Quaestiones ordinariae 32 and 33. In the first part of this paper, I relate salient portions of Sutton’s doctrine and an interpretation controversy between Ashworth and Henninger. In the second part, I draw attention to an untreated but important aspect of Sutton’s doctrine of analogy: how demonstration proceeds through analogous terms. I use Sutton’s arguments in this context to support Henninger’s interpretation against Ashworth’s and then to go beyond Henninger by proposing a resolution to the apparent contradiction in Sutton’s position that Ashworth’s interpretation attempts to address. I draw the further but related conclusion that Montagnes was closer to the mark than Ashworth credits him when Montagnes describes Sutton as a precusor to Cajetan in his use of analogy of proportionality.5 Thomas Sutton on Analogy, Its Modes, and Its Application Across the Categories and to God and Creatures Joseph J. Przezdziecki—Introducing Thomas Sutton and His doctrine of Analogy Przezdziecki summarizes the main arguments that Sutton presented in the objections section of Quaestiones ordinariae 32 for the univocal pred4 5 An alternate title for this work is Questiones disputatae 35. Roensch puts its composition at 1295 (Roensch, Early Thomistic School, 50). Mark G. Henninger follows Schneider, editor of the 1977 edition of Sutton’s Ordinary Questions, and dates them between 1305 and 1310; see Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” The Thomist 70 (2006): 540. Given the extent to which Sutton is responding to Henry of Harclay’s own Quaestiones ordinariae, which were written between 1300 and 1312, I find the later dating more probable, see Henninger, “Henry of Harclay,” in A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2003), 305. All translations are my own. All of my citations of Sutton’s Quaestiones ordinariae are taken from the edition published in Zur Diskussion uber das Problem der Univozitat in Umkreis des Johannes Duns Skotus, ed. Michael Schmaus (Munich: Bayerische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1957) (hereafter, Schmaus). There is a difference in question numbering between Schmaus’s edition and Przezdziecki’s. What is Question 32a in Schmaus is Question 33 in Przezdziecki. Consequently, question 33 for Schmaus is question 34 for Przezdziecki, and so forth. See Bernard Montagnes, La doctrine de l’analogie de l’être d’après Saint Thomas d’Aquin (Louven, BE: Publications Universitaires, 1963), republished as The Doctrine of the Analogy of Being according to Thomas Aquinas, trans. E. M. Macierowski (Milwaukee, MI: Marquette University Press, 2004), 119 and 142–43. Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1155 ication of a conceptus communis of “being” and other names across the categories and of God and creatures.6 Rather than addressing Sutton’s responses to particular objections, Przezdziecki turns his attention to Sutton’s respondeo, which begins with Sutton’s account of why some were led to believe, mistakenly, that there is a common signification of “being” across the categories and of God and things. According to Sutton, this view arises from the similarity “being” bears toward a genus, and it is dispelled by showing how “being” lacks the commonality that characterizes a genus term. Sutton employs the standard argument that “being” is not a genus found in chapter 25 of part I of Aquinas’s Summa contra gentiles, among other places. The concept of a genus cannot be included in the concept of its difference. But the concept of “being” is included in every concept. Hence the concept of “being” cannot be divided by a difference as any generic concept can.7 Furthermore, “being” cannot be a species, difference, property, or accident because it is more general than any species and it is predicated in quid.8 Since “being” is not predicated in the manner of a genus, species, difference, property, or accident across the categories or of God and things, “being” is not signified univocally of these and it has no conceptus communis.9 The name “being” is not said purely equivocally in these cases, however, but analogously. Sutton writes that “being” is predicated primarily of substance, and of accidents only by their relation to 6 7 8 9 Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 192–98. Sutton provides numerous objections. In the numbering provided by Schmaus there are thirty-three objections in Quaestiones ordinariae 32 (see Schmaus, 24–32). There is some difficulty in numbering them, since Sutton interjects replies to objections and then rebuttals to those replies within the objections. Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 199–201; Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 32 (Schmaus, 33–34). The concept of a genus cannot be included in the concept of a difference because, then, the whole species would be expressed in the difference. “Being,” however, is included in every concept, since what lacks being is nothing. For a brief statement of this argument see Thomas Aquinas, In V metaphysicorum, lec. 9 (Marietti no. 889; Marietti edition, 238b). Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 201; Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 32 (Schmaus, 34). See also the summary of this argument presented in Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 544–46. Here, I follow the example of Henninger and merely mention that Sutton’s arguments against univocity in Quaestiones ordinariae 32 assume a point Scotus denies— namely, that a term is univocal if and only if it is predicated according to one of Porphyry’s five predicables. 1156 Domenic D’Ettore substance.10 Regarding “being” said of God and creatures, he adds that, since God is being essentially and others are being by participation, there is an even greater distance between creaturely being and divine being than there is between accidental being and substantial being. Since there is not univocity in the case of “being” said of substance and accident, even less could there be univocity in the case of God and creatures.11 The salient point so far is that, according to Sutton, there can be no univocal signification where there is no common concept. There is no common concept where a name is said by diverse significations, as occurs in the cases of “being” and other names said across the categories and of God and creatures.12 Where there is a single ratio or concept, there is univocity. “Being” is analogous to the ten categories, and so there are ten concepts of “being,” one for each category.13 10 11 12 13 Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 202; Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 32 (Schmaus, 34–36). Ibid., 203–04; Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 32: “Ulterius sciendum est, quod ens dicitur analogice de deo et de quocumque alio. Deus enim dicitur ens essentialiter, quia est suum esse subsistens habens omnem perfectionem essendi. Sed omne aliud dicitur ens per participationem, quia nullum aliud est suum esse nec habet omnem perfectionem essendi, sed participat ipsum esse et partialiter habet aliquam essendi perfectionem secundum gradum determinatum ad genus et ad species et multo longius distat esse cuiuslibet creaturae ab esse divino, quam esse accidentis cuiuscumque ab esse substantiae, propter quod multo minus potest ens dici de deo et creatura univoce quam de substantia et accidenti. Respectu enim dei alia sunt magis non entia quam entia [Further, it must be said that ‘being’ is said analogously about God and about every other thing. For God is called ‘being’ essentially, because He is His esse subsistently having all the perfection of being. But every other thing is called ‘being’ by participation, because no other is its esse nor has all the perfection of being, but participates its esse and has some perfection of being partially, according to a determinate grade to a genus and to a species. And because the esse of any creature is a much longer distance from the divine esse than the esse of any accident from the esse of a substance, being is much less able to be said univocally about God and creature than about substance and accident]” (Schmaus, 38). For more from Sutton on this point, see Quaestiones ordinariae 32, ad 12 (Schmaus, 40), and 32a, ad 3 (Schmaus, 58). See also, Thomas Sutton, Quodlibet 2, q. 3 ad 4, in Quodlibeta, ed. Michael Schmaus (Munich: Bayerische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1969), 183–84. See especially the respondeo to question 32: “Dicendum est igitur, quod ens, prout dicitur de rebus decem praedicamentorum, habet decem significationes, secundum quas dicitur de eis analogice [It must be said therefore that being, insofar as it is said about the ten categories, has ten significations according to which it is said about them analogously]” (Schmaus, 36). Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1157 Any concept of categorical being refers either to a determinate category or indeterminately to this or that category. God and creatures are even more diverse than substance and accident. So, just as there is no common concept of “being” said of the diverse categories of being, there is no common concept of “being” or any other name said of God and creatures.14 Przezdziecki’s summary resumes at the respondeo of Quaestiones ordinariae 33 (question number 34 in Przezdziecki’s numbering), where Sutton offers his explanation of the four kinds of equivocation by design as derived from Boethius. These are: (1) similitudo, (2) proportio, (3) ab uno (from one), and (4) ad unum (to one). For similitudo or imitation, Sutton gives Aristotle’s example from Categories 1.1a, that of “animal” said of a man and a picture of a man. Sutton explains proportio with the standard examples from Aristotle’s Metaphysics 5 of analogous principles including “unity as the principle of number,” “a point as the principle of a line,” “the spring of a river,” and “the heart of a body.”15 He adds that proportio is the proper sense of analogy and that analoga is the same as proportio. (Following Przezdziecki’s example, I will use the expression “analogy of proportionality” to refer to this second mode of analogy henceforth.) For the third mode, ab uno, Sutton offers the example of the name “medical” said of a book and a tool. Here the name “medical” descends from medicine to things related to the art of medicine. The fourth mode, ad unum, occurs when diverse things receive a name by their reference to one. Here he gives the standard examples of the ways the name “healthy” is used in reference to the health of an animal, and he adds that the name “being” is said of substance and accidents in this mode.16 14 15 16 See note 11. Aristotle, Metaphysics 5.1.1012b34–1013a17. Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 204–05; Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 32a: “Quae autem sunt aequivoca a proposito, dividuntur quadrupliciter. Quaedam enim sunt aequivoca a proposito secundum similitudinem, quaedam secundum proportionem, quaedam ab uno, quaedam ad unum. Aequivoca a consilio secundum similitudinem dicuntur ut homo et quod pingitur ad similitudinem hominis, quorumque utrum dicitur animal. . . . Secundo modo aequivoca a consilio vel a proposito, scilicet secundum proportionem, dicuntur, ut cum principium dicitur de unitate, quae est principium numeri, et de puncto, qui est principium lineae, et de fonte, qui est principium fluvii, et de corde, quod est principium in animali, et istud exemplum aequivocorum posuit Aristoteles in V Metaphysicae et bene dicuntur aequivoca secundum proportionem et propriissime, quia proportionaliter dicuntur de diversis. . . . Tertio modo aequivoca a proposito dicuntur aequivoca ab uno, quia scili- 1158 Domenic D’Ettore Przezdziecki observes that, at this point in the text, Sutton has yet to claim that one or some one of these kinds of equivocals by design or analogy is suitable for names said commonly of God and creatures. Indeed, Sutton allows that names can be predicated of God and creatures by each kind of analogy, but it is the second kind of analogy, proportionality, which is both furthest from pure equivocity and characteristic of divine names.17 As treatment of this point is much more extensive in Henninger’s piece, I close my summary of Przezdziecki’s article here. Absent from Przezdziecki’s account is any discussion of the difference between Sutton’s treatment of the kind of analogy suited to names said across the categories and names said of God and creatures. Likewise absent from Przezdziecki’s article are any questions of Sutton’s relative fidelity to Aquinas or any of the other questions posed by subsequent scholars concerning whether the analogy of proportionality (i.e., Sutton’s proportio) applies to “being” said of God and creatures as it does for other pure perfections such as “wise,” “just,” and so on. Mark G. Henninger, S.J.—Thomas Sutton’s Modes of Analogy Revisited Henninger’s article stands out for its detailed attention to the different modes of analogy presented by Sutton and its comparison of them to the positions expressed by Aquinas at different periods of his writing.18 17 18 cet descendunt ab uno aliquo ad multa, de quibus dicitur aliquod nomen aequivoce, ut a medicina dicitur medicinalis liber, in quo scribitur de scientia medicinae. . . . Quarto modo dicuntur aequivoca a consilio ad unum, quando scilicet diversa referuntur ad unum et ex hoc dicitur de illis nomen idem, sicut sanum. Nam cibus dicitur sanus et farinatum sanum et exercitium sanum et urina sana, quia referuntur ad unum finem, scilicet ad sanitatem animalis, et hoc modo ens est aequivocum ad substantiam et ad alia praedicamenta, quia ens dicitur de quantitate et qualitate et ceteris praedicamentis accidentium, prout habent habitudinem ad unum, scilicet ad substantiam, quae est primum ens, non tamen tamquam ad unum finem, sed tamquam ad unum subiectum” (Schmaus, 71–72). For a similar account in Thomas Aquinas’s writings, see Sent.eth. 1, lec. 7, in the Leonine edition vol. 47/1 (1969), 26–27, lines 168–213. Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton’s Critique,” 205–07. Pages 542–60 of Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” summarize some objections and replies from Quaestiones ordinariae 32, as well as the argument in the respondeo. For the limited purposes of this article, I prefer the summary of Przezdziecki, but I find no disagreement between the Henninger and Przezdziecki in their interpretations of Sutton’s arguments. Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1159 Henninger himself professes the developmental thesis defended by B. Montagnes and J. Wippel, which Henninger summarizes as follows: “We know that the complexities of analogy and its use in a number of contexts stimulated Aquinas to rethink and deepen his theory during his career. While discussing the problem of the divine names, Aquinas in his early works used a form of the analogy of attribution, while in De Veritate (1256–59) he argues for another type of analogy, that of proportionality. Finally in his later works, such as De potentia and the Summa Theologiae, he quietly abandons the views of De Veritate and returns in the main to his earlier opinion.”19 Translated into the terms used by Sutton and so far in this article, the developmental thesis holds that the earliest writings of Aquinas use analogy ad unum (the fourth mode of analogy) to explain the divine names. His De veritate experiments with what Sutton called proportio and is commonly called analogy of proportionality (the second mode of analogy). Aquinas’s later works abandon that experiment, returning to analogy ad unum to explain the divine names.20 Henninger investigates Sutton’s reasons for continuing Thomas Aquinas’s De veritate experiment.21 Sutton discusses the diverse modes of analogy in Quaestiones ordinariae 33, where the question is: “whether names, which are said about God and creatures, are said univocally about God and crea- 19 20 21 Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 538. On the developmental thesis, see G. P. Klubertanz, St. Thomas Aquinas on Analogy: A Textual Analysis and Systematic Synthesis (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1960), 94: “The absence of any subsequent text which teaches proper proportionality between God and creatures constitutes strong evidence that St. Thomas quietly abandoned this doctrine after 1256”; and John F. Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being, Monographs for the Society for Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy 1 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2000), 555. This thesis is challenged in Joshua Hochschild, “Proportionality and Divine Naming: Did St. Thomas Change His Mind about Analogy?” The Thomist 77 (2013): 531–58. Henninger draws the conclusion that Sutton is “an able ‘continuator’ of Aquinas” on analogy, while arguing that Sutton’s reasons for championing the analogy of proportionality for names said of God and creatures are not those given by Aquinas in De veritate and that he does not have the same interest in the true form of analogy and intrinsic denomination as is expressed by Thomas di Vio Cajetan (“Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 574). 1160 Domenic D’Ettore tures.”22 Sutton opens by presenting the alternative that such names are said either univocally or in some way equivocally23 and proceeds to argue that there is at least one kind of equivocation that is close enough to univocity to account both for how names are said of God and creatures and for why many mistake such names for univocal names. Following Henninger’s example, I will now consider Sutton’s reasons for rejecting all but the second of the four modes of analogy for the divine names. Sutton tells his reader that the “common position” about the divine names is that they are said by order or respect to one (ad unum) in the way that “healthy” is said of diverse things by relation to one.24 Names are said of both God and other things because all created things have order to God as to their cause. Hence, God is the one something in relation to which others receive a common name. As Henninger observes, the common opinion seems to be endorsed at times by Aquinas (especially in the De potentia, Summa contra gentiles, and Summa theologiae passages on names said of God and creatures).25 Against the common position about how names are said of “God and other things,” Sutton points his reader’s attention to the consideration of the “signification of names, according to which analogy is principally attended.”26 Although God’s justice or wisdom is causative of a man’s justice or wisdom, a man is not called “just” or “wise” because he has order to the justice of God or the wisdom of God.27 22 23 24 25 26 27 Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33: “utrum nomina, quae dicuntur de deo et creaturis, dicantur univoce de deo et creaturis” (Schmaus, 63). Ibid. (Schmaus, 71). Ibid. (Schmaus, 76–77). Aquinas says that names are not said of God and creatures in the way that “ens” is said of quantity and quality (called the analogy of “many to one” in the Summa Contra Gentiles and the Summa Theologiae, and “two to a third” in the De potentia), but rather, in the way that “ens” is said of substance and accident (i.e., by the analogy of “one to another”); see Summa contra gentiles (hereafter, SCG) I, ch. 34, in Leonine edition vol. 13 (1918),103b ; De potentia VII, a.7, corp., in Quaestiones disputatae, 2 vols. (Turin/ Rome: Marietti, 1965), 2:204b, and Summa theologiae (hereafter, ST) I, q.13, a. 5, corp., in Leonine edition vol. 4 (1888). Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33: “ad significationem nominum, secundum quam principaliter attenditur analogia” (Schmaus, 77). Ibid.: “Non enim ideo dicitur homo iustus vel sapiens, quia habet ordinem ad iustitiam dei vel sapientiam dei sicut ens dicitur de quantitate propter hoc, quia est entis, quod est substantia [For therefore a human is not called just or wise because he has order to the justice of God or the wisdom of God as being is said about quantity due to the fact that it belongs to a being which is a substance]” (Schmaus, 77). Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1161 Furthermore, although the names in question are all first imposed on creatures and later attributed to God, they are not said about God to signify His relation to other things.28 According to Sutton, these considerations exclude both analogy ab uno and analogy ad unum as candidates for use in the analogous signification of names to God and creatures.29 Henninger notes the central importance Sutton gives to signification in determining the mode of analogy suitable to a given instance and sees this as a difference between Sutton and Aquinas.30 The relations of causality and dependence make no difference by themselves for what kind of analogy is in use. What matters, according to Sutton, is the primary versus the secondary significations of the term. Since God is not called wise to signify a relation to creatures, nor vice versa, the name “wise” is not said of God and creatures by analogy ad unum (or ab uno). After rejecting the ad unum and ab uno modes of analogy for expressing the signification of names said of God and creatures, Sutton proceeds to do the same for similitude, the analogy of imitation (which Henninger calls “resemblance”). All things have some analogous resemblance to God, but the resemblance is not what is signified 28 29 30 Sutton does not deny that, even in analogy of proportionality, one analogate receives the name by priority and others by posteriority. Indeed, he writes specifically in Quaestiones ordinariae 33: “Secundum enim quod res sunt nobis magis notae, secundum hoc prius nominantur. Magnitudo autem est nobis magis nota quam alia et ideo prima pars magnitudinis dicitur principium per prius et in aliis dicitur per posterius [For insofar as things are more known to us, they are first named. Now magnitude is more known than others and therefore the first part of magnitude is called ‘principle’ first and it is said per posterius in others]” (Schmaus, 75). Proportionality differs from the other modes insofar as the posterior analogate receives the name absolutely and not only through a relation to the prior analogate. I see no conflict between Sutton’s position on proportionality and the interpretation of Aquinas’s position found in Hochschild, “Proportionality and Divine Naming,” 547–50. Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33: “. . . prius imposita fuerunt rebus aliis, deinde fuerunt attributa deo, non tamen sic, quod dicerentur de deo ad significandum habitudinem eius ad res alias et ideo videtur, quod proprie loquendo non dicuntur ista nomina analogice illo modo scilicet ad unum nec etiam illo modo, quo aliqua dicuntur analoga ab uno [they were first imposed on other things, then they were attributed to God, nevertheless not such that they were said about God for signifying His relaton to other things and therefore it seems that, properly speaking, those names are not said analogously in that way, namely ad unum nor even in that way in which some are called analogs ab uno]” (Schmaus, 77). Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 564–65. 1162 Domenic D’Ettore by the common name. There is a resemblance of human wisdom to divine wisdom and human goodness to the goodness of God, but it is not because of this resemblance that a man is called good or wise.31 There appear to be two problems with this kind of analogy. First, it would require knowing God prior to knowing creatures. Since we do not know God prior to knowing creatures, it would be false to say that perfections first known and named of God are afterwards said of creatures when they are found to imitate God. The man must be known and known to be an animal before what imitates him (for example, a picture or reflection) can be recognized as imitating him and called an “animal” by imitation of the man. Secondly, the picture of a man no more has the perfection of being an animal than medicine has the perfection of being healthy. So naming due to similitudo as such does not involve naming essentially, in contrast to the divine names.32 What’s left and the option Sutton embraces is the second mode of analogy, which he calls alternately proportio and analogy properly speaking.33 Sutton is quite liberal with his examples of names said 31 32 33 Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33: “Nec etiam dicuntur ista nomina ilIo modo, quo aliquo dicuntur analoga secundum similitudinem, sicut animal est analogum ad hominem et ad illud, quod pingitur ad similitudinem hominis. Quamvis enim omnes res habeant aliquam similitudinem ad deum, ut sapientia hominis ad sapientiam dei et bonitas hominis ad bonitatem dei, non tamen propter hoc dicitur homo bonus vel sapiens, quia habet similitudinem bonitatis dei et sapientiae dei [Nor even are those name said in that way in which some are called analogates according to likeness, as animal is analogous to a human and to that which is painted to the likeness of a human. For although all things have some likeness to God, such as the wisdom of a human to the wisdom of God and the goodness of a human to the goodness of God, nevertheless, a man is not called good or wise because of the fact that he has the likeness of God’s goodness or God’s wisdom.]” (Schmaus, 77). See Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 566. This seems to be Aquinas’s reasoning against using the model of how “animal” is said of a man and a picture of a man for names said of God and creatures in De veritate, q. 2, a. 11, ad 8, in Leonine edition vol. 22, 1/2 (1970), 80b, lines 271–80. E. J. Ashworth mentions this passage to show that thirteenth-century authors were familiar with the fact that the medieval Latin usage of the word “analogy” did not correspond with the Greek use of the same term, and she cites similar observations from James of Viterbo (a contemporary of Sutton’s) and Gerard of Harderwyck in the fifteenth century; see Ashworth, “Suarez on the Analogy of Being: Some Historical Background,” Vivarium 33.1 (1995): 55–56. Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1163 analogously of God and creatures in this way.34 I mention here a few. A man who knows the highest causes is called “wise.” God knows the highest causes perfectly and therefore ought to be called “wise.” A man who has knowledge of things through their proper cause is called “knowing.” God knows the order of all causes and effects in the most perfect way and so ought to be called “knowing.” A man is called “just” if he gives to each one what is his own. God most of all gives to each his own, since God wills all the things required for the things that He wills. Sutton concludes that all other names that abstractly signify a perfection are said of God and creatures analogously in this way, and these analogous names are furthest from pure equivocation and closest to univocation.35 Henninger clarifies the distinction between Sutton’s understanding of analogy in the context of the categories and his understanding of analogy in the context of the divine names. In the categorical context, Sutton follows the “common opinion.” The name “being” is said by analogy ad unum of substance and accidents in the same way that the name “healthy” is said of an animal and medicine or urine. The divine names are said by analogy of proportionality. In both 34 35 Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33: “Relinquitur igitur, quod nomina dicta de deo et de rebus aliis dicantur quarto modo, scilicet secundum proportionem, prout hoc nomen principium dicitur de unitate et de puncto et de fonte, ut dictum est, et hoc facile est manifestare de singulis nominibus. Sicut enim homo cognoscit altissimas causas et ideo dicitur sapiens, ita deus cognoscit altissimas causas perfecte et ideo merito debet dici sapiens. . . . Similiter sicut homo habet cognitionem rerum per propriam causam et ideo sciens dicitur, ita deus omnium causarum et effectuum ordinem cognoscit modo perfectissimo et ita propter talem proportionem debet dici sciens. . . . Similiter etiam sicut homo habet cognitionem principiorum absque discursu, ita et deus omnia cognoscit absque discursu et ideo sicut homo dicitur intelligens, ita etiam deus. . . . Adhuc sicut homo dicitur iustus, qui tribuit unicuique, quod suum est, hoc autem maxime deo convenit, quia ex hoc, quod vult aliquid, vult ei omnia, quae ad ipsum requiruntur. Illa enim sunt quasi debita ei, ut habeat. Sic secundum proportionem talem deus dicitur iustus” (Schmaus, 77–78). Sutton’s examples of proportional naming in Quaestiones ordinariae 33 closely follow SCG IV, ch.12, in Leonine edition vol. 15 (1930), 47a–b. Each of the proportions that Sutton gives refers to a kind of activity. This point is addressed independently of Sutton in Norris Clarke, “Analogy and the Meaningfulness of Language about God,” in Explorations in Metaphysics: Being—God—Person (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1994), 131, and J. F. Ross, Portraying Analogy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 164. Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33 (Schmaus, 78–79). 1164 Domenic D’Ettore contexts, however, Sutton follows the same rule for determining the kind of analogy used, which is the order of the signification of the names. If the name is imposed on one to signify its relation to one, then it is said by analogy ad unum. Since such a relation is not signified in the context of the divine names, a different kind of analogy must be at work there. Analogy of proportionality alone properly captures the proportionally similar significations of names such as “wise” and “just” said of creatures and of God. The final portion of Henninger’s paper briefly addresses concerns raised by Ashworth in her 1994 article on Sutton. Since Ashworth published further on the topic in 2008. I conclude my first part of this paper with a consideration of her two pieces together. E. J. Ashworth—Sutton Revisited, Revised, and Questioned E. J. Ashworth first discussed Sutton’s Quaestiones ordinariae 32–33 in detail in her 1994 article “Analogy and Equivocation in Thomas Sutton, O.P.,”36 and she returned to the same topic with some revision in her Les Theories Analogie over a decade later in 2008.37 Her work stands out from Przezdziecki’s and Henninger’s primarily through her argument that “being” said of God and creatures is an exception to Sutton’s rule that names are said by analogy of proportionality between God and creatures. She also argues that Sutton’s understanding of analogy of proportionality differs from Cajetan’s in a way that undermines Montagnes’s claim that Sutton was a precusor to Cajetan.38 Towards the conclusion of her 1994 article, Ashworth seems to have caught Sutton in a contradiction. As we have seen, Sutton employs analogy ad unum for “being” said across the categories and analogy of proportionality for the divine names. When explaining why some mistakenly thought that the divine names are said univocally of God and creatures, Sutton asserts that analogy of proportionality is, as Ashworth puts it, “furthest from pure equivocals and the 36 37 38 E. J. Ashworth, “Analogy and equivocation in Thomas Sutton, O. P.,” in Vestigia, Imagines, Verba: Semiotics and Logic in Medieval Theological Texts (XII–XIV Century), Acts of the XIth Symposium on Medieval Logic and Semantics, San Marino, 24–28 May, 1994, ed. Marmo Costantino, Semiotic and Cognitive Studies 4 (Turnhout, BE: Brepols, 1997): 289–303. E. J. Ashworth, Les théories de l’analogie du XIIe au XVIe siècle (Paris:Vrin, 2008). Henninger echoes the distinctions Ashworth makes between Sutton and Cajetan without further elaboration (“Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 574). Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1165 nearest to univocals.”39 So it seems as though Sutton is committed to holding that the analogy between God and creatures, an analogy of proportionality, is closer to univocity than the analogy across the categories, an analogy ad unum. In Quaestiones ordinariae 32, however, he had apparently claimed the opposite. I quote the text Ashworth refers to directly: “For just as every name said about God and about creatures is said of them analogously, so too the ratio of each such name belongs to God and to others analogously and the ratio of such a name cannot be partly diverse and partly the same, but the whole ratio is analogous, although in creatures the ratio of the name sometimes is partly the same and partly diverse, for example, the ratio of ‘man’ belonging to a true (man) and to a picture (of a man).”40 In addition to this text, one can recall the passage mentioned above in which Sutton says that there is a greater distance between the being of God and the being of creatures than there is between the being of substance and the being of accidents. According to Ashworth, Sutton is asserting that the name “being” is more equivocal when said of God and creatures than when it is said of substance and accidents. If Sutton is not contradicting himself, “it seems to follow,” Ashworth remarks, “that the divine names are very different from ens which is more equivocal when said of God and creatures than it is when said of substance and accident.”41 Ashworth develops this point in her later treatment of Sutton in Les Theories Analogie, where she proposes that Sutton distinguishes three different cases of analogy. First, there is analogy of attribution to one for “being” said of substance and accident. Second, there is another analogy of attribution for “being” said of God and creatures, but this time an analogy of attribution that is further from univocity than in the first case for the reasons stated above. Third, the other Divine Names are said by analogy of proportionality.42 39 40 41 42 Ashworth, “Analogy and Equivocation,” 297. Ashworth is referring to Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33 (Schmaus, 78–79). Thomas Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 32: “Sicut enim omne nomen dictum de deo et de creaturis dicitur de eis analogice, ita ratio cuiuslibet talis nominis convenit deo et aliis analogice et non potest ratio talis nominis esse partim diversa et partim eadem, sed tota ratio est analoga, quamvis in creaturis ratio nominis quandoque sit partim eadem et partim diversa ut ratio hominis veri et picti” (Schmaus, 40); see Ashworth, “Analogy and Equivocation,” 296. Ashworth, “Analogy and Equivocation,” 297. See also her brief treatment of Sutton on this point in “Suarez on the Analogy of Being,” 57. See Ashworth, Les théories de l’analogie du XIIe au XVIe siècle, 52–53: “He makes a distinction between three cases. The first case is that of the word ‘being’ said 1166 Domenic D’Ettore Henninger disputes Ashworth’s reading of Sutton, noting the intention expressed by the titles of the articles and Sutton’s express statement that analogy of proportionality applies to “all those names which absolutely signify perfection,” which presumably includes “being.”43 Furthermore, Henninger observes that, although Sutton does not give an example of how “being” is said analogously of God and creatures, “we can easily construct a sentence that illustrates the analogy of proportion for being on the model of Sutton’s sentences for the other divine names: ‘As a caused substance, not being in another, is being per se formally, so God, neither being in another nor being caused by another, is being per se formally and causally.’”44 It is certainly striking that Sutton neither gives his own statement of how 43 44 about substance and accident. In this context, the word is an equivocal by design and an example of the analogy of attribution. The second case is that of the word ‘being’ said about God and creatures. In this context, the word is much further from univocity than the same word said about substance and accidents. God exists by His essence, whereas creatures exist by participation. Consequently, there is nothing that can be common to the two. There is no ratio that is partly the same and partly different, but there is one ratio that is entirely analogous. These remarks suggest the presence of a return to the analogy of imitation. However, the word ‘being’ said about God and creature is always an example of the analogy of attribution. The third case is that of the divine names such as wise, just, and good. Sutton holds that these names are analogous, but, differently from words such as ‘being’ and ‘healthy,’ their significations do not contain a relation. One does not say that a human is just because his justice is connected to the justice of God, whether by causality or by resemblance. The only type of analogy that is appropriate in this case is the analogy of proportionality. When we are saying that a human is wise, this is because he knows the highest causes, and when we say that God is wise, this is because He knows the highest causes perfectly. In other words, we make a comparison between the relation existing between the knowledge of a human and the objects of his knowledge and the relation of God and the objects of His proper knowledge, and we employ the same word ‘wise’ about the two relations. The word found by analogy is a fifith term, as in the Posterior Analytics. Sutton adds that we have a tendency to believe that the words ‘wise,’ ‘just,’ and ‘good’ are univocal because, unlike the word ‘being,’ they are very far from equivocals and very near to univocals.They resemble the word ‘principle’ (principium), which also is very far from equivocal and very near to univocal” (My translation from the French.)” See Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 570. See also Alessandro D. Conti, “La composizione metafisica dell’ente finito corporeo nell’ontologia di Tommaso Sutton,” Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 2 (1991): 326. Henninger, “Thomas Sutton on Univocation, Equivocation, and Analogy,” 571. Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1167 “being” is said by proportionality of God and creatures in the way he does for the names “wise,” “just,” and “liberal” nor expressly states that the name “being” is an exception to the rule of proportionality among divine names. Now although Henninger rejects Ashworth’s solution, he admits the “tension” in the text she observed, and offers no resolution to save the consistency of Sutton’s position.45 In the final portion of this paper I will explore an additional problem with Ashworth’s solution to the apparent conflict in Sutton’s text, emerging from his treatment of the fallacy of equivocation, and then propose a solution to the difficulty she observed. Analogy of Proportionality and the Fallacy of Equivocation There are two passages in his Quaestiones ordinariae 33 in which Thomas Sutton presents Scotist objections to the use of analogous terms in demonstrative reasoning. The first passage argues that analogous terms cannot avoid the fallacy of equivocation any more than purely equivocal terms. The objector gives a standard example of the fallacy of equivocation: “Every dog is a land animal; a star is a dog; therefore, a star is a land animal.” The objector asserts that the same fallacy occurs in a syllogism employing a name analogously, offering the example of “everything healthy is an animal; medicine is healthy; therefore, medicine is an animal.”The conclusion follows that nothing could be proven or known about God through creatures if we posit that those names are predicated analogously, any more than if they are said equivocally.46 In answer to this objection, Sutton grants that use of analogous terms can result in sophistical reasoning, but he adds that one can use terms analogously in a demonstrative argument when the analogous 45 46 Ibid., 573. Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33, arg. 5: “Praeterea sicut aequivocatio pura impedit illationem, ita et analogia. Sicut enim haec est fallacia aequivocationis: Omnes latrabile est canis, sidus caeleste est canis, ergo sidus caeleste est latrabile, ita et haec est fallacia per vim analogiae: omne sanum est animal, medicina est sana, ergo medicina est animal. Ergo si ponamus illa nomina praedicari de deo et creaturis analogice, nihil potest probari nec cognosci de deo per creaturas, sicut nec potest, si dicantur pure aequivoce. Relinquitur ergo, quod pure univoce dicantur de deo et creaturis” (Schmaus, 65). This is the same example that appears in Peter of Spain, Tractatus Sextus, in Summulae Logicales cum Veroriis Parisiensis Clarissima Expositione (Hildesheim / New York: Georg Olms Verlag, 1981; repr. of 1572 Venice edition), 181. See also the treatment of the fallacy of equivocation by Aquinas in De fallaciis, ch. 6, no. 650, in Opuscula Philosophica (Marietti edition, 1954), 228b. 1168 Domenic D’Ettore terms are “analogous by proportio.” He repeats the familiar example from Metaphysics 5: as the heart relates to the whole animal, so the spring relates to the whole river. The heart is the principle of the animal, and likewise, the spring is the principle of the river; the heart and the spring are principles analogously. Sutton then adds the following example of a Natural Theology demonstration: Thus, God is whatever is absolutely better that He be than He not be. But it is altogether better in creatures to be wise than not wise, free than not free, living than not living, just than not just, and so on about other things which carry perfection absolutely without defect. Therefore, God is living, wise, free, just and so forth. For those names signify perfection absolutely, as far as that which is principal in their ratio, although they carry some imperfection as regards what is less principal, and, therefore, they are said of God by removing that which is of imperfection.47 In other passages, Sutton explains that what is imperfect about these perfections is that they are qualities or habitus in creatures. And as qualities or habitus, they express a certain imperfection that must be removed when the names are said of God.48 Sutton leaves it to his reader to infer that the ratio of a name carrying imperfection is analogous by proportionality to the ratio of the same name with the imperfection removed, and that such analogously similar rationes are used without equivocation in a demonstration. 47 48 Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33, ad 5: “Ad quintum dicendum, quod in analogis, sicut convenit arguere sophistice, ita convenit in eis arguere bene et demonstrative, praecipue in analogis secundum proportionem sic: Sicut se habet cor ad totum animal, ita se habet fons ad totum flumen. Sed cor est principium animalis, ergo fons est principium fluminis. Et similiter convenit ex perfectionibus creaturarum necessario probare perfectiones dei, quamvis analogice conveniant deo et creaturis. Sic deus est quidquid absolute melius est ipsum quam non ipsum. Sed melius est omnino in creaturis sapiens quam non sapiens, patens quam non patens, vivens quam non vivens, iustum quam non iustum et sic de aliis, quae important perfectionem absolute absque defectu. Ergo deus est vivens, sapiens, patens, iustus et sic de aliis. Ista enim nomina significant perfectionem absolute, quantum ad illud, quod est principale in eorum ratione, quamvis aliquam imperfectionem important, quantum ad id, quod est minus principale et ideo removendo illud, quod est imperfectionis, dicuntur de deo” (Schmaus, 81–82). Ibid., 32a, ad 3 (Schmaus, 58). Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1169 The other demonstration-based objection takes up the argument from motion. It would be sophistical to argue that God is the “first mover” unless “mover” is said according to the same ratio of both God and other movers.49 Sutton responds that the name “mover” is said about God analogously by analogy of proportionality and that, where names are said in this way, demonstration proceeds just as it does when the names are said univocally because analogy of this kind is so close to univocity.50 Notice that Sutton does not deny that there are four terms in a Natural Theology demonstration. Indeed, his doctrine that no name signifies God and creatures through the same concept requires that any Natural Theology demonstration employ four terms. Consider his own example mentioned above. Major Premise: It is absolutely better to be wise. Minor Premise: God is whatever it is absolutely better that God be. Conclusion: God is wise. The name “wise” in the major premise cannot signify the wisdom proper to God because the perfection of wisdom in creatures carries 49 50 Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33, arg. 25 (Schmaus, 70). While the objectors are unnamed, one can see a resemblance to an objection found in John Duns Scotus, Ordinatio I, dist. 3, pt. 1, q. 1–2, nos. 38–40 (in Opera Omina, Vatican edition, 3:25–27). Unless the terms carry the same meaning when said of God and creatures, calling God a mover or wise is like calling God a stone (or calling a star a land animal). For a brief summary of all five arguments Scotus gives for univocity, see Luis Alberto De Boni, “Duns Scotus and the Univocity of the Concept of Being,” in New Essays on Metaphysics as Scientia Transcendens, ed. Roberto Hofmeister Pich, Textes et Études du Moyen Âge 43 (LouvenLa-Neuve: Fédération Internationale des Instituts d’Études Mediévales, 2007), 102–12. For a fuller description of all five arguments presented within the context of Scotus’s overall cognitional theory, see Mary Beth Ingham and Mechthild Dreyer, Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus: An Introduction (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2004), 38–47. Sutton, Quaestiones ordinariae 33, ad 25: “hoc nomen motor . . . dicitur de deo et aliis analogice secundum proportionem . . . et in talibus valet probatio ex creaturis ad deum in omnibus, quae nullam imperfectionem important principaliter . . . quia talis analogia propinqua est univocationi, propter quod tenet probatio, sicut in univocis [the name ‘mover’. . . is said about God and other things analogously according to proportion. . . . and in such cases the proof from creatures to God is effective in all things that principally carry no imperfection . . . because such analogy is near to univocation, on account which the proof holds just as in univocals]” (Schmaus, 87). 1170 Domenic D’Ettore the imperfection of being a quality (and non-qualitative wisdom cannot belong to a creature, or that creature would be subsistent wisdom—presumably, Sutton assumes with the Aristotelians that Natural Theology does not discover the wisdom of God through prior knowledge of subsistent wisdom). The name “wise” in the conclusion cannot signify through the same concept as it does when it signifies creaturely wisdom, since then it would falsely attribute imperfection to God. The name “wise” cannot signify through the same concept in both the major premise and the conclusion, since then it would signify univocally. So the name “wisdom” in the major premise signifies through the ratio proper to creatures and in the conclusion through the ratio proper to God. The syllogism has four terms: absolutely better to be, God, the quality of wisdom, and subsistent wisdom.51 Now Sutton says that such a syllogism is not an instance of the fallacy of equivocation because the two rationes of the name “wise” are analogously similar by a proportionality that is close enough to univocity to mediate demonstration. The ratio “the quality of knowing the highest causes” is analogously similar to the ratio “subsistently knowing the highest causes perfectly,” and this similarity is enough for demonstration. It is here that I see in Sutton’s doctrine the precusor to Cajetan’s that Montagnes took it to be. In the De nominum analogia chapter addressing the same Scotist objections, Cajetan explains that the fallacy of equivocation is avoided when terms are said by analogy of proportionality because “whatever belongs to one, also belongs to the other proportionally; and whatever is denied about one also is denied of the other proportionally: because whatever belongs to a similar, in that similar thing, also belongs to that other thing to which it is similar.”52 His point is that proportional likeness of signification 51 52 That the syllogism has four terms, not three, is clear if we replace the term “wise” in the minor and in the conclusion with the concepts signified by the word “wise” in those propositions. Said of creatures, the concept of the term “wise” signifies the quality of knowing the highest causes. Said of God, the concept of “wise” signifies subsistent knowledge of the highest causes. The syllogism would then appear as follows: “It is absolutely better in creatures to possess the quality of knowing the highest causes. God is whatever it is absolutely better to be. Therefore, God is subsistent knowledge of the highest causes.” Thomas di Vio Cajetan, De nominum analogia 10.106: “eo quod quidquid: convenit ulli, convenit et alteri proportionaliter; et quidquid negatur de una, et de altera negatur proportionaliter: quia quidquid convenit simili, in eo quod simile, convenit etiam illi, cui est simile, proportionalitate semper servata”; see Scripta Philosophica, ed. P. N. Zammit (Rome: Angelicum, 1934), 80–81. Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1171 in the rationes of the names is sufficient for an inference to be made from what properly receives one ratio to what properly receives the other proportionally similar ratio. In the case of the demonstration that God is wise, it is legitimate to infer from the qualitative wisdom of creatures to the proportionally similar subsistent wisdom of God. Or to put the point negatively, it would be false to deny that there is in God something that answers proportionally to the wisdom found in creatures.53 Cajetan makes explicit what Sutton’s treatment had left implicit. Two things cannot be both similar and dissimilar at the same time and in the same respect. This holds not only for univocal commonalities but also for the proportional similarity that both Cajetan and Sutton propose to recognize in the diverse ratio53 This point would be easier to make and understand if the authors provided a set of non-theological examples of demonstrations with analogous terms to explain how their principles work in the more-known-to-us cases. Sutton provides one example in Quaestiones ordinariae 33, ad 5: “Sicut se habet cor ad totum animal, ita se habet fons ad totum flumen. Sed cor est principium animalis, ergo fons est principium fluminis [As the heart relates to the whole animal, so the spring relates to the whole river. But the heart is the principle of the animal; therefore, the spring is the principle of the river]” (Schmaus, 81). For the purposes of this article, consider the position of someone familiar with how the terms “motion” and “activity” apply to physical objects and who has just learned that stock prices are not physical objects but social constructs with no concrete physical manifestation. Now, this person hears someone say that “the stock price is moving.” From her prior experience, she knows that “what is moving is active.” She could bring these two propositions together into the syllogism “what is moving is active; the stock price is moving; therefore, the stock price is active.” The sense of terms “moving” and “active” in her major premise, drawn from experience of physical objects, is clearly not identical to the sense of these terms in the minor premise and in the conclusion. However, it does not follow that her syllogism commits the fallacy of equivocation unless she supposes that the terms must be used in exactly the same sense. She can recognize that the terms in the major apply in some similar yet different sense to the stock price and reasonably conclude that something similar but different is happening to the stock prices as happens to rocks and animals in motion. Since we do in fact learn to use the terms “moving” and “active” about stock prices in ways proportionally analogous to the way we first learned to use the terms about physical objects, we can recognize that forming such as syllogism could in fact be someone’s entry into discovering the analogous sense of a term or set of terms. I see Aquinas as employing the term “motion” in reasoning similar to my example here in his In I libros posteriorum analyticorum, lec. 41 (Marietti edition, 300a), where he reasons from the conditions for the unity of a physical motion to the conditions for the unity of a demonstrative science. Suggestions of better and easier examples would be much appreciated. 1172 Domenic D’Ettore nes through which names are said of God and creatures. Since it is true that similar things agree in that in which they are similar, and since these analogates are proportionally similar, I would say that Sutton’s account of proportio analogy, in which the analogous term is predicated according to different but proportionally similar rationes, gives at least a strong preliminary answer to the Scotist objection to demonstration through analogous terms.54 I also propose that Sutton’s treatment of demonstration through analogous terms provides additional reasons for rejecting Ashworth’s interpretation of his doctrine of “being” said of God and creatures. If “being” is not said of God and creatures by analogy of proportionality, then being could not be demonstrated to belong to God any more than wisdom could be. And Sutton clearly holds that God’s being is demonstrable. Ashworth’s solution to the apparent contradiction adds to the problems within the text rather than solving them. That said, if Ashworth’s solution fails to save him, Sutton may still be trapped in his apparent contradiction. Recall that the trouble lies in Sutton’s claim that the ratio of the name “being” when said of God and creatures is not partly the same and partly different, but entirely analogous. This seems to suggest that “being” is more equivocally said of God and creatures than it is when it is said across the categories, which would conflict with Sutton’s later statements about divine names belonging to the kind of analogy that most closely approaches univocity. I think the problem dissolves on further consideration of what Sutton means when he says that the ratio of the name is entirely analogous when said of God and creatures. We have a clue as to what Sutton means by “entirely analogous” in the contrast case provided in the text. The ratio of “man” said of a true man and a picture is partly the same and partly different. The example here is an analogy of imitation. Now, where is the sameness and where is the difference here? Recall that, for Sutton, analogy is a matter of the order of signification of a name. What is partly the same in the signification of the two things receiving the name “man” is the proper ratio of the true man, which is signified essentially in the one case and is signified relationally in the other. The same partially similar, partially diverse significations can be found in the case of “being” said of substance and the other categories. The 54 I do not suppose that it would satisfy the Scotist on the Scotist’s own terms. I think, instead, that it provides a rational defense within Thomism to the external criticism from the Scotist. Thomas Sutton’s Doctrine of Analogy 1173 ratio of “being” proper to substance is signified diversely in each case: essentially of substance, and by relation to substantial being of the other categories.55 Turning then to God and creatures, we can notice how the manner of signifying the analogates changes. Neither the ratio of “wise” proper to God nor the ratio of “wise” proper to creatures is signified relationally when the name “wise” is predicated of the other. The same holds for the name “being.” The essential signification of “being” to created substances and the essential signification of “being” to God are analogous. Their significations are not partly the same and partly different, as in the other modes of analogy, where the signification of one appears as part of the signification of the other. The similarity between the significations is the proportionality between the rationes taken as distinct wholes.56 The significations are entirely analogous. Just as the entire ratio of the name “wise” predicated of creatures is analogous to the entire ratio of the same name predicated of God, the entire ratio of the name “being” predicated of created substances is analogous to the ratio of the name “being” predicated of God. Conclusion Thomas Sutton neither contradicts himself, makes an exception for the name “being” said of God and creatures, nor renders himself unable to engage in demonstration from creatures to God. When he denies in Quaestiones ordinariae 32 that the ratio of the name “being” is partly the same and partly different when it is predicated of God and creatures, he is not asserting that its signification there is further from univocity than its signification across the categories. Rather, he is anticipating the distinction he will make in Quaestiones ordinariae 33 between the different modes of analogy and their suitability for the divine names. In 55 56 This is not inconsistent with Aristotle’s Metaphysics 5, in which he includes all the categories within the division of being per se. Granted that “being” according to its absolute consideration belongs per se to all the categories, even so, since substance is found in the definition of each of the accidents, it is contained in the signification of the name “being” when “being” is predicated of accidents. See Aquinas, In V metaphysicorum, lec. 9 (especially Marietti no. 885; Marietti edition, 237a–238a), and In 7 Metaphysicorum, lec. 1 (Marietti nos.1258–1259, Marietti edition, 317b). To borrow a phrase I have heard used many times by J. F. X. Knasas, “the sameness is in the difference.” The reason why one entire ratio is analogous by proportionality to another entire ratio is that what makes them the same is inseparable from what makes them different. 1174 Domenic D’Ettore interpreting Sutton in this way, I am making connections that he does not explicitly make himself. This does not distinguish my approach from Ashworth’s, but it does better save the overall coherence of Sutton’s position. Thomas Sutton’s doctrine of analogy is partly the same and partly different from the doctrine professed by Thomas Cajetan nearly 200 years later in the De nomina analogia. Ashworth is right to note that Sutton applies the analogy of proportionality only to names said of God and creatures and sees analogy ad unum as suitable for “being” across the categories. In this respect, Sutton clearly gives the analogy of proportionality less work in metaphysics than Cajetan does.57 However, Sutton’s use of the analogy of proportionality to answer Scotist objections to demonstration through analogous terms shows that he anticipates Cajetan more than Ashworth grants. It is not merely that analogy of proportionality captures the signification of the names in ways that other forms of analogy cannot that suits it to the divine names. Proportionality’s distinct manner of signification also makes demonstration possible where other modes of analogy would lapse into the fallacy of equivocation. Cajetan’s explanation in De nominum analogia 10 is more thorough than Sutton’s replies to objections in Quaestiones ordinariae 33, but the “prince of primitive Thomists” and the great scholastic commentator employ the same mode of analogy, pointing to the same properties that belong to that mode to answer the same objections. The thought of one anticipates the thought of the other, and both provide strong reasons for a Thomist Natural Theology to employ analogy of proportionality for N&V names said of God and creatures. 57 On analogy of proportionality’s role in metaphysics and its direct application across the categories, see especially Cajetan’s De Nominum Analogiae, chs. 3–5. On Cajetan’s overall position, see Joshua Hochschild, The Semantics of Analogy: Rereading Cajetan’s De Nominum Analogia (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame Press, 2010). Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1175–1192 Creation ad imaginem Dei: The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory Steven A. Long Ave Maria University Ave Maria, FL Introduction This essay attempts to show that three things often thought to be opposed—the dynamism, relationality, and teleology of the image of God in man toward grace and glory; a strict distinction between nature and grace; and the doctrine that man has an obediential potency to friendship with God and supernatural beatitude—are not only not opposed but are actually necessarily related elements of a coherent and true theological synthesis. To do this requires, first, a few words about the immateriality of the rational soul. Second, I will consider St. Thomas’s teaching that the imago dei in man principally consists in the intellectual nature, describing and responding to criticism of this view as insufficiently relational and separated from grace. Third, I will argue that what constitutes the obediential potency for grace and glory in man is in fact what principally constitutes the imago dei—namely, the intellectual nature itself. Here too, I will offer brief responses to criticisms reducing obediential potency merely to miraculous transformation or asserting that intrinsically supernatural beatitude is already the natural end, that man has a strongly unconditional natural desire for supernatural beatitude and, so, there is no need for an obediential potency for grace and glory. Finally, I will conclude by observing that St. Thomas’s theological synthesis of nature and grace provides the strongest possible foundation for the relational dynamism of the imago dei in man and that this synthesis establishes simultaneously the initial dignity of man as capable of natural and supernatural good and 1176 Steven A. Long the greater perfection of acquired dignity that consists in achieving such good. This is a quick march through a vast territory, rather than a complete account of any one point, and so it is more like a cavalry ride around the field of battle than like a complete campaign. But I hope my remarks may at least indicate the elements that enter into Thomas’s account and how they are generally interrelated. The Positive Immateriality of the Rational Soul It has always been true that materialism as such constitutes one of the errors simply incompatible with Roman Catholic faith. It is defined Catholic teaching that the soul is spiritual and immortal and that God is pure spirit. Likewise, it is progressively clearer throughout the modern epoch that the metaphysical reliance on material evolution as sufficient to explain the differentiated forms of being—and in particular to explain the cognitive and volitional aspects of human life—is incoherent. The argument against any type of thoroughgoing materialism certainly has a foundation in the work of St. Thomas Aquinas, but it traces back to classical Greek philosophy and has been articulated in varied forms by modern authors such as C. S. Lewis (e.g., in Miracles) or contemporaries such as Thomas Nagel (in Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False). Were intellectual objectivity to be considered merely a material accident of evolution, we could have no sufficient warrant for holding the adequation of mind and reality that is required even for the truth of evolutionary theory. This is manifest in many ways. First, for example, is the commonplace argument that intellectual activity proceeds through universal concepts and applies to being as such universally, such that a wholly physicalist account must, by its very nature, somehow square the circle and reduce universality to physical particularity. What is at stake here is not only the universal mode of conceptual knowledge—already something irreducible to physical particularity and, so, irreducible to neurophysiology—but also, and even more critically, the adequation or conformability of mind to being. As St. Thomas puts it, “as sound is the first audible, being is the first intelligible.”1 Thus, any denial that being is universally intelligi Summa theologiae (hereafter, ST) I, q. 5, a. 2, resp. Unless otherwise noted, all English translation from the works of Aquinas is my own work done from the Navarre edition of the Latin, from which all Latin quotes are also taken. 1 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1177 ble leaves precisely nothing intelligible, since there is nothing outside of being. The very principle of non-contradiction in its chief and metaphysical formulation—that being is not nonbeing—is, according to St. Thomas, the basis for the logical principle of non-contradiction that one does not speak meaningfully in simultaneously affirming and denying the same of the same (Summa theologiae I-II, q. 94, a. 2). In referring to the logical principle of non-contradiction, he adds “quod fundatur supra rationem entis et non entis” (“which is based on the nature of being and non-being”). This is a universal principle pertaining to being as such, and if it were not, then fundamentally there could be no such thing as objectivity because the mind would have no root capacity to conform to what is the case. But the capacity to conform to any physical structure or state of affairs is not itself merely a physical structure or state of affairs. The capacity universally to conform to what is the case cannot be reduced to a particular or set of particulars in space and time. As Thomas argues, the perfection of intellectual knowledge exists in inverse ratio to materiality.2 Without the immaterial capacity of human intention to extend As Thomas puts it in ST I, q. 84, a. 2, resp.: “Relinquitur ergo quod oportet materialia cognita in cognoscente existere non materialiter, sed magis immaterialiter. Et huius ratio est, quia actus cognitionis se extendit ad ea quae sunt extra cognoscentem, cognoscimus enim etiam ea quae extra nos sunt. Per materiam autem determinatur forma rei ad aliquid unum. Unde manifestum est quod ratio cognitionis ex opposito se habet ad rationem materialitatis. Et ideo quae non recipiunt formas nisi materialiter, nullo modo sunt cognoscitiva, sicut plantae; ut dicitur in II libro de anima. Quanto autem aliquid immaterialius habet formam rei cognitae, tanto perfectius cognoscit. Unde et intellectus, qui abstrahit speciem non solum a materia, sed etiam a materialibus conditionibus individuantibus, perfectius cognoscit quam sensus, qui accipit formam rei cognitae sine materia quidem, sed cum materialibus conditionibus”; “It follows, therefore, that material things known must exist in the knower, not materially, but rather immaterially. And the reason of this is because the act of knowledge extends to things which are outside the knower: for we know even things that are external to us. Now by matter the form of a thing is determined to some one thing. Thus it is clear that knowledge is in inverse ratio of materiality (that the ratio of knowledge of itself is opposed to the ratio of materiality). And consequently things that are not receptive of forms save materially, have no power of knowledge whatever—such as plants, as the Philosopher says (De anima 2.12). But the more immaterially a thing has the form of the thing known, the more perfect is its knowledge. Therefore the intellect which abstracts the species not only from matter, but also from the individuating conditions of matter, has more perfect knowledge than the senses, which receive the form of the thing known, without matter indeed, but with material conditions.” 2 1178 Steven A. Long universally to being, to conform to whatever is the case, particular physical states and conditions are mute. Even if the neural activity of the human brain were known by God himself to constitute in itself a perfect map of the universe, this would not constitute human knowledge, since we would never have direct contact with the thing known, only with our own brain states, which accordingly could never adequately be judged as to their capacity to conform to anything beyond—or even including—themselves. Only if man possesses the immaterial capacity intentionally to be what he is not— to conform understanding and judgment directly to real nature—is the problem escaped. The situation with materialism is as if one were locked from birth in a room whose floor was a topographic map of the state where one lived, but one had no contact of any kind with the outside world: one would be in no position to confirm that the floor really were a topographic map or to know its accuracy if it were thought to be one. We are in no position to say that brain states are simply equivalent to knowledge of reality unless we are capable of comparing brain states with reality, which would permit us to judge of the relation between our understanding and the real evidence. This requires a universal capacity transcending brain states and any particular physical nature. In the absence of such a capacity, it is impossible to know adequately even that there is such a thing as a state of the brain or that brain states are adequate to model themselves. The extensive project to reduce intellectual and volitional power and act to neurophysiology is often spoken of as a vast and gradual effort whose outcome in vindicating the fundamentally physical nature of intellectual knowledge as a foregone conclusion. But this appears similar to the likewise vast and gradual project of reducing human moral experience to astrological influence because both projects offer us mere correlations in the place of explanations. But were brain states simply identical with the reality of intellectual knowledge, no labor of correlation would be necessary. Things are really identical only when everything true of one is true of the other. But the property of a universal concept is not identical with a physical particular, and more importantly, the power of the mind to conform to universal being, a power that must be universal on pain of implying the impossibility of objectivity, cannot be identical with any neural function. Thoroughgoing materialism or physicalism cannot give a sense to its correlations that is so much as intelligible on its own premises, let The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1179 alone adequate to the requirements of theoretical explanation. The immateriality of intellect and will, whose formal objects are universal truth and universal good, is the chief indication of the spirituality of the rational soul. Imago Dei and Obediential Potency I have spent so much time on relatively introductory aspects of philosophic anthropology because, according to St. Thomas Aquinas, the imago dei in man consists principally in the intellectual nature. It is not accidental that those who deny what is essential to the imago dei are poorly situated to appreciate Christian revelation. Imago Dei and Relationality Thomas writes (ST I, q. 93, a. 8, resp.): “Thus the image of God is found in the soul according as the soul turns to God, or possesses a nature that enables it to turn to God.” He refers to “that in which the image chiefly consists, that is, the intellectual nature [my emphasis]” (ibid., a. 3, resp.) and teaches that: “So we find in man a likeness to God by way of an ‘image’ in his mind; but in the other parts of his being by way of a ‘trace’” (ibid., a. 6, resp.). As he puts it more fully: While in all creatures there is some kind of likeness to God, only in the rational creature is found a likeness of God in the mode of an “image” as is explained above; whereas in other creatures we find a likeness in the mode of a “trace.” But that whereby the rational creature excels other creatures is the intellect or mind. Thus it remains that neither in the rational creature is the image of God to be found except in the mind. But in the other parts the rational creature may possess, we find the likeness of a “trace,” as in other creatures to which, according to such parts, the rational creature can in this way be likened.3 ST I, q. 93, a. 6, resp.: “Respondeo dicendum quod, cum in omnibus creaturis sit aliqualis Dei similitudo, in sola creatura rationali invenitur similitudo Dei per modum imaginis, ut supra dictum est, in aliis autem creaturis per modum vestigii. Id autem in quo creatura rationalis excedit alias creaturas, est intellectus sive mens. Unde relinquitur quod nec in ipsa rationali creatura invenitur Dei imago, nisi secundum mentem. In aliis vero partibus, si quas habet rationalis creatura, invenitur similitudo vestigii; sicut et in ceteris rebus quibus secundum partes huiusmodi assimilatur.” 3 1180 Steven A. Long The imago in man is not perfect—for the perfect image is found only in the Divine Word—but rather it is analogical.4 As Thomas says, it is like the image of the king stamped in the alien medium of a coin.5 For Aquinas, the image of God in man principally consists in the intellectual nature. Although the imago of conformity involves the intellect as turning to God and conforming to him, prior to this and foundationally, there is what has come to be called an imago of representation (possessed by saint and sinner alike) that is the foundation in human nature rendering such spiritual conformity to be possible—the essentially spiritual nature of the soul: “that in which the image chiefly consists.” This, however, is only equivocally the direction in which much recent thought about the imago has developed. Precisely because of its relational dynamism and teleological ordering to grace and glory, there has been a tendency to consider the image of God in the human person to be first and fundamentally relational, precisely for fear that rooting it in human nature, substance, and being will ineluctably distort and render impossible the genuine further ordering in grace. Such a view of the imago dei as foundationally constituted by the intellectual nature—understood in terms of the philosophic analysis of being and substance—has come to be thought of as a distortion of the nature of the person. Pope Emeritus Benedict XVI in particular has encouraged more focus on the human person as inherently and constitutively relational, in accordance with the understanding of the purely relational character of the divine persons in the Trinity. This view suggests that philosophic conceptions of the person—insofar as they are not rooted in the Trinitarian mystery—are distortive. Then-Cardinal Ratzinger, in his famous essay “Concerning the Notion of Person in Theology,”6 describes the concept of person as “a product of Christian theology” deriving from two questions: “What is God?” and “Who is Christ?” In this famed essay, he describes the early struggle to avoid depicting Christ as suffering defect inasmuch as he lacked human personhood while possessing human nature and being a divine person. He identifies the great Christological heresies all as modes of implying that Christ must have lacked something essentially human. He then writes: ST I, q. 93, a. 1, ad 3. ST I, q. 93, a. 1, ad 2; a. 6, ad 1. 6 Joseph Ratzinger, “Zum Personenverständnis in der Theologie,” in Dogma und Verkündigung (Munich: Erich Wewel Verlag, 1973); trans. as “Concerning the Notion of Person in Theology,” Communio 17.3 (Fall, 1990): 439–54. 4 5 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1181 I believe that if one follows this struggle in which human reality had to be brought in, as it were, and affirmed for Jesus, one sees what tremendous effort and intellectual transformation lay behind the working out of this concept of person, which was quite foreign in its inner disposition to the Greek and the Latin mind. It is not conceived in substantialist, but as we shall soon see, in existential terms. In this light, Boethius’s concept of person, which prevailed in Western philosophy, must be criticized as entirely insufficient. Remaining on the level of the Greek mind, Boethius defined “person” as naturae rationalis individua substantia, as the individual substance of a rational nature. One sees that the concept of person stands entirely on the level of substance. This cannot clarify anything about the Trinity or about Christology; it is an affirmation that remains on the level of the Greek mind which thinks in substantialist terms.7 The editors of Communio, glossing the decided emphasis of then-Cardinal Ratzinger on transferring the relational language of the Trinity to the human person, added to the start of his essay the small descriptive line, “Relativity toward the other constitutes the human person. The human person is the event or being of relativity.”8 Years ago, I had a very interesting exchanges with Dr. Kenneth Schmitz,9 who, perhaps inspired by this tendency of thought articulated by then-Cardinal Ratzinger, undertook to propose an account of the human person framed in language that he admitted St. Thomas reserved exclusively to the divine persons, the language of “subsis Ibid., 448. Ibid., 439. 9 Cf. my “Reply” in The Thomist 61.3 (July 1997), which is my response to 7 8 Kenneth Schmitz’s “Created Receptivity,” which in turn had responded to my “Personal Receptivity and Act: A Thomistic Critique,” from January of 1997, which had criticized his “The First Principle of Personal Becoming,” The Review of Metaphysics 47.4 (June, 1994), and also referred to earlier discussion amongst Fr. Norris Clarke, S.J., Dr. David Schindler, and myself in Communio. One sees this anthropological thesis (that the human person ought be deemed a “subsistent relation”) in Schmitz’s The Texture of Being: Essays in First Philosophy, ed. Paul O’Herron (Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2007), in the section titled “The Person as Subsistent Relation” (123–26, within chapter 7, “Created Receptivity and the Philosophy of the Concrete”), in which he admits, “I recognize that this term is privileged by St. Thomas for the divine persons of the Trinity” (ibid., 123n59). 1182 Steven A. Long tent relation.” This notion of person as a purely relational reality is not unconnected with the related but distinct view that nature as such is so thoroughly related to grace as to be a mere limit concept or dialectical notion providing no normative content for theology distinguishable from grace. Thus, the idea of a natural preamble to faith—the praeambula fidei—is often transformed to a knowledge that is intrinsically postfactum (“after the fact”) of revelation and grace. We move from the natural order as bearing the impress of the divine wisdom in the eternal law—primordial revelation—to a view of nature as if it were something purely conceptual, designating a possible “space” to be filled with grace but lacking normative content, what elsewhere I have called elsewhere a “vacuole for grace.”10 Of course, one sees this emptying of the ens creatum in the work of Karl Rahner and—at least in his book The Theology of Karl Barth— in Hans Urs Von Bathasar, who expressly indicates his approval of Rahner’s idea of nature as merely a residual or limit concept.11 The proposition that nature is not a residual or limit concept, not merely a placeholder for grace, lacking all ontological density, but rather a momentous reality, and moreover a reality manifesting primordial revelation and the eternal law—a theonomic or divinely ordered reality—is a philosophic and theological affirmation strongly in tension with this “relationalist” tendency of thought. Either nature, substance, and being are presupposed by grace and revelation or they are not, and either they are to some degree intelligible (even after the Fall) in terms of their proportionate ends in precision from revelation, or they are not. This is not to say that revelation cannot cast light upon nature, but only that nature is intelligible. When Gaudeum A “vacuole,” by the way, is not merely a biological term: it is an English term taken in from the French and means a “small vacuum,” although this usage is no longer included in our dictionaries, which are losing thousands of words as our culture reduces its cognitive repertoire and minimalizes its sense of “literacy” (a fit subject for another day). 11 See Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Theology of Karl Barth, trans. Edward T. Oakes, S.J. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992), 299: “Here a few critical comments on Rahner’s position come to mind. Of course, the concept of pure nature as a ‘residual concept’ is both possible and even unavoidable in theology if we want to maintain a real correlative counterpoint to grace and the order of grace. We ourselves have attempted the same thing earlier by fashioning a ‘formal concept of nature’ in the same sense by a kind of subtraction process.” But the idea that nature is an invisible unknown reachable only by “subtracting” grace or through treating nature as a “residual concept” does not rise to the level of the observation that human nature is not sanctifying grace. 10 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1183 et Spes famously describes Christ as revealing man to himself, this is clearly not meant to suggest that, prior to revelation, men confused themselves with porcupines. Rather, Christ the Incarnate Word reveals to man the profundity of which human nature is capable in relation to God, a profundity in divine friendship of which we would be unaware lacking revelation. Doubtless the philosophic account of the human person is incomplete, precisely insofar as it abstracts from the supernatural destiny of man. Yet, for Thomas, the understanding of man’s supernatural destiny presupposes, incorporates, and preserves the truth of the created natural order with its proportionate and proximate ends as distinct from the ultimate and supernatural end.12 With the overwhelming preponderance of Fathers and Doctors, St. Thomas holds that man is created in grace from the beginning. Yet, he also holds that this creation in grace presupposes the ontological subjectivity of the ens creatum as specified by proportionate ends, so that within this initial moment of creation, there is, in one specific respect, a priority of created nature. In any case, the idea that the imago dei is constituted in man by his relation to God appears to be demonstrably false. It suggests something that is true—namely, that the imago dei is relational and dyanamic and that it is providentially ordered to blossom in grace and in glory. But however important relationality is to our understanding of spirit, there is something else that is most evidently prior to relationality—namely, being and substance. Real relation presupposes the realities related. If there is no creature, then there is no real relation of the creature to God. Nonexistent, nonsubstantial creatures do not and cannot have real relations of any kind, much less a real relation to God. If they are to have such real relation to God, they must first be: they must exist and be subjects of being possessed of a certain ontological density. It follows that, whatever relationality the imago dei in man has, this relationality is founded upon being and substance and thus can be no substitute for them. God has no real relation to the creature, inasmuch as God is infinitely perfect and stands in no relation of dependence upon his creation: he is not essentially changed through creation. St. Thomas writes that, considered as active, creation designates only the divine nature in itself with a conceptual relation to the creature; but consid See, e.g., ST I, q. 75, a. 7, ad 1. There is a very long list of references one might site. 12 1184 Steven A. Long ered as passive, the relation of createdness is a quasi-accident in the creature, founded upon the being of the creature as received from God. 13 Manifestly, something cannot be really in a creature if the creature really does not exist. To have being from another is necessarily to have being. It follows that, since nonexistent beings do not have real relations, it is impossible for the creature to be constituted by its relation to God. Being, substance, and nature are not constituted by their relation to God; they are constituted—caused—by God. Without a real created subject of being, there is simply nothing to be related. The being, substantiality, and nature of the creature is thus absolutely presupposed by the creature’s relation to God. Accordingly, we see that mere Greek substantialism has rather more to offer than might at first have met the eye. It is precisely the understanding of being, substance, and nature that is the foundation for the doctrine of the imago dei and that renders possible its relational, dynamic, and teleological character. The spiritual nature of the soul, understood as constituting a certain deficient but real analogical image of God in man, is ordered in grace to become the imago Christi, and finally the imago gloriae, the image of God in the glory of the beatific vision. But does not the natural foundational character of the imago dei seal it off from its dynamism and teleology in grace toward In II sent. d. 1, q. 1, a. 2, ad 4: “Si autem sumatur passive, sic est quoddam accidens in creatura, et sic significat quamdam rem, non quae sit in praedicamento passionis, proprie loquendo, sed quae est in genere relationis, et est quaedam habitudo habentis esse ab alio consequens operationem divinam: et sic non est inconveniens quod sit in ipso creato quod educitur per creationem, sicut in subjecto; sicut filiatio in Petro, inquantum recipit naturam humanam a patre suo, non est prior ipso Petro; sed sequitur actionem et motum, quae sunt priora. Habitudo autem creationis non sequitur motum, sed actionem divinam tantum, quae est prior quam creatura”; “If, however, it is taken passively, then it is a certain accident in the creature and it signifies a certain reality which is not in the category of being passive properly speaking, but is in the category of relation. Creation is a certain relation of having being from another following upon the divine operation. It is, thus, not inappropriate that it be in the created thing, which is brought into being through creation, as in a subject. In the same way, sonship is in Peter insofar as he receives human nature from his father, but [sonship] is not prior to Peter himself, but rather follows upon the action and motion which are prior.The relation of creation, however, does not follow upon motion, but only upon the divine action, which is prior to the creature”; English translation from Aquinas on Creation, trans. Stephen Baldner and William Carroll (Toronto: Pontifical Institute for Medieval Studies, 1997), 77. 13 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1185 the supernatural end of the beatific vision? The answer is no, because this foundational sense of the imago dei is the obediential potency of the human creature for grace and glory. Imago Dei and Obediential Potency The doctrine that man has an obediential potency for grace and glory has been severely criticized, and of course complete response to such criticism would require wider scope than this present consideration affords. One may, however, point out the character of the doctrine, its importance within theology, and the evidence that seems to confuse certain principal criticisms. First, there is the nature of obediential potency. In ad 13 of article 10 of De virtutibus in communi, St. Thomas addresses an objection to the effect that acts are of the same genus as their potencies but that creatures, by definition, lack potency for divine acts. However, inasmuch as creatures have different passive potencies in relation to different active agencies, a purely passive obediential potency for acts achievable only with divine aid is intelligible. As St. Thomas writes, “accordingly we say that the whole creation is in a certain potency of obedience, according as the whole creation obeys God to be able to receive in itself whatever God wills.”14 St. Thomas argues that water and earth have diverse passive potencies in respect of the diverse active agencies of fire, the heavenly bodies, and God.15 These diverse passive potencies vis-à-vis different active agencies are partially rooted in the natures involved. It is important to note that Thomas argues that obediential potency applies to infused virtue: For just as something is able to be done by water or earth by the power of the heavenly bodies, which cannot be done by the power of fire; something can be done by the active supernatural power that cannot be done by the active natural power; and in this sense we say that in the whole of creation is a kind of obediential power, insofar as every creature obeys God in receiving whatever God wills. Thus from them something is Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de virtutibus, q. 1, a. 10, ad 13: “et secundum hoc dicimus quod in tota creatura est quaedam obedientialis potentia, prout tota crea tura ob edit Deo ad sus cipiend um in s e quidquid Deus volu erit.” 15 See ibid. 14 1186 Steven A. Long able to be done by the supernatural active power that cannot be done by some active natural power. And according to this, we say, that in every creature there is some potency of obedience, such that every creature obeys God in receiving in itself whatever God wills. Thus then in the soul something is in potency, which is produced and reduced to act by a connatural agent, and in this way the acquired virtues are in potency. In another way something is in potency in the soul that is not produced through being brought forth in act unless through divine power; and in this way are there potencies for infused virtues in the soul.16 Contrary to Etienne Gilson (in his later work17) and historically many others (e.g., the Franciscan school), obediential potency is not merely the susceptibility of the creature to miraculous transformation—not merely the capacity of water, under divine agency, to become wine—although this is the lowest type of obediential potency. Were the lowest type of obediential potency the only type, obediential potency could not pertain to the relation of nature to grace. However, specific obediential potency is different from mere susceptibility to miraculous transformation because it refers to a specific range of actuation that the active agency of God can bring forth from a nature. One sees this specific obediential potency in Summa theologiae III (q. 1, a. 3, ad 3), where Thomas expressly answers an objection regarding the capacity of human nature for the “greatest grace” of union: “It should be said that a double capacity may be Ibid.: “Sicut enim ex aqua vel terra potest aliquid fieri virtute corporis caelestis, quod non potest fieri virtute ignis; ita ex eis potest aliquid fieri virtute supernaturalis agentis quod non potest fieri virtute alicuius naturalis agentis; et secundum hoc dicimus, quod in tota creatura est quaedam obedientialis potentia, prout tota creatura obedit Deo ad suscipiendum in se quidquid Deus voluerit. Sic igitur et in anima est aliquid in potentia, quod natum est reduci in actum ab agente connaturali; et hoc modo sunt in potentia in ipsa virtutes acquisitae. Alio modo aliquid est in potentia in anima quod non est natum educi in actum nisi per virtutem divinam; et sic sunt in potentia in anima virtutes infusae.” 17 Cf. Letters of Etienne Gilson to Henri de Lubac (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1988), 81: “Strictly speaking, it is applicable only to miracles, where nothing in matter either prepares for, expects, or makes the phenomenon possible; in general (your excellent quotes on p. 244), all nature is in a state of potentiality to whatever it may please God to do with it, provided that this is not, in itself, contradictory or impossible.” 16 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1187 found in human nature. One according to the order of the power of nature which is always fulfilled, because He gives to each being according to its natural capacity; another indeed according to the order of divine power, which every creature obeys implicitly. And to this pertains this capacity.”18 The capacity he speaks of is the capacity of human nature for the grace of union with the divine Person of the Word. If even the hypostatic union is to be understood in terms of obediential potency and as not implying the miraculous transformation of human nature into a different principle, then clearly there is a strong case for the proportionate application of obediential potency with respect to all lesser instances of grace. Although the lower instances of mere miraculous transformation are “common,” the more profound way that a nature can implicitly obey divine power is clearly in regard to that which God alone can bring forth in and from the nature without changing it. Both the passages indicated above exhibit and share this ratio. God’s power extends to all things, but what he can do with any nature is not merely “change” it substantially and miraculously, but bring forth some other act—to which it has no simply natural potency—from and through it without miraculously transforming its nature. The nature is in both the loftier and the inferior instances of obediential potency—both the case of miraculous substantial transformation and of interior elevation to a nobler act without substantial transformation—passive with respect to what is brought about, obeying the divine power. However, in the second case, we see that that to which the subject stands in a relation of obediential potency is brought about in and through it without altering its nature—as, for example, with respect to the infused virtues—and is most pertinent to the higher life of grace. Thus, the vastness of the divine power in relation to diverse natures specifies different ways it may operate on and in creatures. Furthermore, the aforementioned mode of created obedience to divine power seems a deeper and more proper sense of “obedience.” To obey merely in the sense of being transformed, so that the original subject of obedience no longer exists, is clearly an inferior form of ST III, q. 1, a. 3, ad 3: “Ad tertium dicendum quod duplex capacitas attendi potest in humana natura. Una quidem secundum ordinem potentiae naturalis. Quae a Deo semper impletur, qui dat unicuique rei secundum suam capacitatem naturalem. Alia vero secundum ordinem divinae potentiae, cui omnis creatura obedit ad nutum. Et ad hoc pertinet ista capacitas.” 18 1188 Steven A. Long obedience. “Obedience” is a term that a voluntarist might reduce to divine force majeure, but there are many reasons why one might think Thomas would be reluctant to do this even though this is a common mode in which sensible creatures may be said to obey the divine power. In fact, while the lower form of obediential potency—susceptibility to miraculous transformation—is seen throughout the visible lower creation, in the invisible higher creation, the manner in which the creature stands in a potency of obedience to the active agency of God concerns the capacity for grace, infused virtue, and glory. Thus, while the sensible examples of the lower stratum of “obediential potency” proliferate, it bears recollecting that, for Thomas, there are more species of angels than of physical things19 and that the sense of “obedience,” for Thomas, is interior motion conforming to intellective command (command is an act of the intellect and not of the will). Thus, obedience properly speaking is not a voluntarist posit, and so it would be strange were “obediential potency” to be reducible to the lowest instance of obedience wherein things are miraculously transformed to other things (a use of “obedience” seemingly by extrinsic attribution) rather than interiorly elevated through their passive potency to activation by a nobler principle. God can raise up sons of Abraham from the very stones, but were he to do so, they would no longer be stones, but human beings. By contrast, owing to the possession of essentially spiritual powers of intellect and will—by reason of the possession of human nature—the human person is able to be elevated in grace to friendship with God. Man does not cease to be human—as the stone would cease to be a stone—by being elevated to the divine friendship. The stone as such cannot be elevated by grace to be a friend of God—even though, in some analogical sense, all creatures desire and love God in their natural motion—because the stone lacks a rational soul. To become a friend of God, it must cease being a stone. Human persons do not lose their humanity by being elevated in grace to the divine friendship. This potency to be elevated by and in grace is not a natural potency because there is no proportionate active power of nature enabling the creature to be so elevated. Thomas is very clear that even angelic will cannot be inclined toward the supernatural apart from supernatural aid. To speak of a natural desire implies some proportionate active power in man because natural desire is for the proportionate natural good, a principle taught universally by St. Thomas (this is something See ST I., q. 50, a. 3, resp. 19 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1189 denied by Henri de Lubac, but without adequate consideration of the texts). There are many instances, but one notes, for example, Thomas’s words in question 4 (“on hope”) of Quaestiones disputatae de virtutibus: “It should be said that the proportionate good moves the appetite; for those things are not naturally desired that are not proportionate. But that eternal beatitude is a good proportionate to us, this is from the grace of God; and thus hope, which tends to this good as proportionate to man to possess, is a gift divinely infused.”20 In Quaestiones disputatae de veritate (q. 14, a. 10, corp.), Thomas contrasts the supernatural finis ultimus with natural good, writing of the supernatural good: ‘‘The other is the good which is out of all proportion with man’s nature because his natural powers are not enough to attain to it either in thought or desire.’’ One cannot, apart from grace, according to Thomas, even desire God as supernatural beatitude, because no finite nature is proportioned to this good, Quaestiones disputatae de virtutibus, q. 4 [De spe], prooem., a. 1, ad 8: “Ad octavum dicendum, quod bonum proportionatum movet appetitum; non enim naturaliter appetuntur ea quae non sunt proportionata. Quod autem beatitudo aeterna sit bonum proportionatum nobis, hoc est ex gratia Dei; et ideo spes, quae tendit in hoc bonum sicut proportionatum homini ad habendum, est donum divinitus infusum.” Cf. ST I, q. 62, a. 2, resp.: “Sicut enim superius dictum est, naturalis motus voluntatis est principium omnium eorum quae volumus. Naturalis autem inclinatio voluntatis est ad id quod est conveniens secundum naturam. Et ideo, si aliquid sit supra naturam, voluntas in id ferri non potest, nisi ab aliquo alio supernaturali principio adiuta”; “For as was said above, the natural motion of the will is the principle of all that we will. But the natural inclination of the will is to that which is fitting according to nature. And thus, if there be something above nature, the will is not able to be inclined toward it unless by the aid of some other supernatural principle.” It is very clear here that the natural motion of the will is the principle of all that is willed, and that it cannot be inclined to anything higher without divine aid. Desire is “inclination” and “motion”—not accomplishment, but inclination. This is one reason (there are many) why, on Thomas’s teaching, the natural desire for God is not identical with the desire for supernatural beatitude, although the natural desire for God is such that it is more than fulfilled in supernatural beatitude. Note ST I-II, q. 62, a. 2, ad 3: “Ad tertium dicendum quod ad Deum naturaliter ratio et voluntas ordinatur prout est naturae principium et finis, secundum tamen proportionem naturae. Sed ad ipsum secundum quod est obiectum beatitudinis supernaturalis, ratio et voluntas secundum suam naturam non ordinantur sufficienter”; “To the third it should be said that reason and will are ordered to God naturally as principle and end of nature, but according to the proportion of nature. But to the object of supernatural beatitude reason and will are not sufficiently ordered according to nature.” 20 1190 Steven A. Long and all natural desire as such is specified by created realities.21 The natural desire for God reaches the one and only God materially, but formally it does not know what it is seeking, reaching him only under a disproportionate and deficient incognito. It reaches God as Cause of these effects, yet it is not even an accident in God to be the cause of these effects, inasmuch as creation does not change God, God is not dependent upon creation, and God infinitely transcends creation. Some have argued that the voluntas ut natura, the will as a nature, has the inner life of God for its object. But St. Thomas unmistakably teaches that no finite nature or power is naturally proportioned to God in himself—God is not universal good in the sense in which this is the formal object of the will because perfection can be added to the good in general, whereas to God’s substantial and actual universal perfection, no essential addition is possible. It is man’s rational soul that renders him capable of elevation in grace. It is the rational soul, with its powers of intellect and will specified by universal true and good, that render the human person able to be elevated to the beatific vision. Here too, one must be careful. It is common to speak in a somewhat misleading way: man is ordered to universal true and good; but God is subsistent universal true and good; so therefore, it is thought that man is simply naturally ordered to God. But man is not naturally ordered to the beatific vision, but solely through the supernatural principle of grace. Man is naturally such that he can be elevated by God to the divine friendship and finally to the beatific vision. The natural universality of intellect and will are, in a sense, horizontal. The intellect extends to universal being, not all at once, but serially, sequentially, and distributively: it knows in a universal way (through universal concepts) and extends to universal being. But this is for the human person to be able to know created goods without any material limitation on the side of knowledge as such (that is, it may be that some evidence is not available to us, but the intellect will extend Of course, this is also clear from Thomas’s comments in De malo q. 5 a. 3 resp., where he argues regarding the limbo puerorum: “Pertinet autem ad naturalem cognitio- nem quod anima sciat se propter beatitudinem creatam, et quod beatitudo consistit in adeptione perfecti boni; sed quod illud bonum perfectum, ad quod homo factus est, sit illa gloria quam sancti possident, est supra cognitionem naturalem”; “Now it pertains to natural knowledge that the soul knows it was created for happiness and that happiness consists in the attainment of the perfect good. But that that perfect good for which man was made is that glory which the saints possess is beyond natural knowledge.” 21 The Obediential Potency of the Human Person to Grace and Glory1191 to any evidence that is available and we can inquire even when evidence is scant). The picture is the same with the human will, which can incline toward various goods without being commanded by any because it moves to the good under the form of reason, which is universal, as the will is appetitus sequens formam intellectam.22 As finite good is not universal, no finite good can simply of itself compel the will, and so the will is objectively free in choice. However, all this is vastly different from the idea of a unique knowledge and love of the infinite God. This is literally that knowledge and love about which Thomas frequently quoted the treasured lines from 1 Corinthians 2:9 (Douay Rheims): “Eye hath not seen, neither has ear heard, neither hath it entered into the heart of man, what God has prepared for those who love Him.” Even to desire this supernatural beatitude in union with the triune God requires the aid of grace. As Thomas points out, the beatific vision exceeds every purely natural capacity, whether of man or angel (Summa contra gentiles III, ch. 52), exceeding all natural capacity to know. Since the desire for God is specified by natural knowledge of God in finite created effects (for the will is nothing other than inclinatio sequens formam intellectam [“inclination following the form understood”]; see Quodlibet 6, q. 2, a. 2), it follows that natural desire for God does not truly know what it desires, whereas graced desire—which truly is on the way toward knowing what it desires—is rooted in the reality of God himself.23 Quodlibet 6, q. 2, a. 1: “motus voluntatis est inclinatio sequens formam intellectam.” Likewise Summa contra gentiles, III, ch. 26: “motus voluntatis est inclinatio sequens formam intellectam.” See also ST I-II, q. 8, a. 1, where he clearly argues that “ad hoc igitur quod voluntas in aliquid tendat, non requiritur quod sit bonum in rei veritate, sed quod apprehendatur in rationi boni”; “Thus that the will tend to something does not require that it be good in the reality of the thing, but that it may be apprehended as good.” Note that, for the will to tend toward anything as good, it must do so by virtue of an apprehension of the mind. 23 One notes the words of Jacques Maritain: “But this desire to know the First Cause through its essence is a desire which does not know what it asks, like the sons of Zebedee when they asked to sit on the right and on the left of the Son of Man. ‘Ye know not what ye ask,’ Jesus replied to them. For to know the First Cause in its essence, or without the intermediary of any other thing, is to know the First Cause otherwise than as First Cause; it is to know it by ceasing to attain it by the very means by which we attain it, by ceasing to exercise the very act which bears us up to it”; in Approaches to God, trans. Peter O’Reilly (New York: Harper, 1954), 109–10. See also: “It is necessary that there be in 22 1192 Steven A. Long Man’s obediential potency for grace, when actuated by grace, reveals the profundity of his own nature as capax dei, capable of divine friendship. The similitude of the stained-glass window illumined by the sun’s rays well bespeaks the character of the doctrine of obediential potency applied to the relation of nature and grace. The stained-glass window, were it cognizant, could not “know what it was missing” were it never to irradiate its bright colors under the influence of the sun. It would be a window, still, and neither fail to be part of the whole structure of which it would form an integral part, nor lack its own participation in the good of the whole as a specific perfection. Yet, its nature stands properly revealed only under the extrinsic causality of the sun’s illumination: seeing it so illumined, we know what stained glass truly is for. Just so does Christ reveal the profundity of man as capable of divine friendship with himself. Conclusion The Incarnate Word reveals man to himself. Far from rendering revelation and grace and the dynamism of the image of God in man to grace and glory impossible, it is the dignity of created human nature that it may be elevated in grace. This initial dignity, rooted in the spirituality of the human soul, is further ordered to the even more crucial acquired dignity of conformity with the divinely ordained order and with God himself, and it is adequately understood only in relation to the common good, both naturally and supernaturally. This second dignity is greater and even more crucial than the first, for we may have the first dignity in this life—that of the imago of representation—and nonetheless live discordant lives. And we may have this first dignity in the next life and burn with preternatural fire in alienation from, and eternal loss of, God. The initial dignity of man (the representative imago) is ordered to, and specified by, an order of progressively more transcendent or common goods in nature and in grace and is ordered to become for us the imago gloriae, the image of glory, in the celestial city of beatific vision. In this sense, we may say that only the classical account of the imago dei provided in the work of St. Thomas Aquinas adequately founds and defends the relational dynamism of the imago N&V dei to grace and glory. man an ‘obediential potency’ which, answering to the divine omnipotence, renders him apt to receive a life which surpasses infinitely the capacities of his nature” (ibid., 112). Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1193–1212 Alimentum Pacis: The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas John Meinert Our Lady of the Lake College Baton Rouge, LA Thomas Aquinas’s theology of peace rarely receives the attention it deserves in current scholarship.1 This might give someone following the secondary literature the impression that Aquinas either is unconcerned with peace or has nothing noteworthy to say. However, this would be far from the truth. Aquinas was quite concerned with peace. For example, commenting on the Psalm 33, he states that, if your neighbor is fighting against you, “then it belongs to you to seek peace,” and if your neighbor is seeking peace with you, then “you should pursue it too.”2 In another place, he calls peace “intensely enjoyable.”3 He even calls peace the last of all goods and the For two notable exceptions to this trend, see Heather McAdam Erb, “Interior Peace: Inchoatio vitae aeternae,” in Wisdom’s Apprentice: Thomistic Essays in Honor of Lawrence Dewan, O.P., ed. Lawrence Dewan and Peter A. Kwasniewski (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2007), 260–81, and Matthew Tapie, “For He is our Peace: Thomas Aquinas on Christ as Cause of Peace in the City of Saints,” The Journal of Moral Theology 5.1 (2016): 111–28. 2 Super Psalmos 33 (Parma edition, 1863), no. 13: “Secundo quantum ad proximum dicit, inquire pacem et cetera. Sed contingit aliquando, quod habes proximum qui impugnat te, et tunc tuum est inquirere pacem; et ideo dicit, inquire pacem . . . Quandoque vero contingit, quod habes aliquem qui inquirat a te pacem, et tuum est tunc sequi eam.” Unless otherwise noted, all translations of Latin are my own. 3 Ibid., 36, no. 8: “Haec enim pax est valde delectabilis.” 1 1194 John Meinert general end (finis) of the mind.4 Indeed, according to Aquinas, all desire peace. Every single person, by desiring anything, de facto desires peace.5 These examples alone show both that Aquinas is concerned with peace and that the secondary literature has failed to explore some noteworthy claims by Aquinas. The purpose of this article is not an exhaustive treatment of peace in St. Thomas. Its purpose is much more circumscribed: to explore and expose the connections between supernatural peace and the Eucharist in the thought of Aquinas and thereby fill a lacuna in English Thomistic literature.6 Put simply, the thesis of this paper is that, since the Eucharist is our re-presentation of and participation in the sacrifice of Christ on the Cross and the very sustenance of charity, it is both the cause of and the nourishment for true peace (the right order found preeminently in Christ himself ). In short, according to Aquinas, the Eucharist efficiently and exemplarily causes peace because it efficiently and exemplarily causes charity, the direct efficient cause of peace.7 Such a conception between peace and the Eucharist deserves renewed attention not only because the connection between peace and the Eucharist is traditional in Christianity (indeed, one of the traditional names for the Eucharist is “peace”), 4 5 6 7 Super II Cor 1, lec. 1.1 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953), no. 8: “Ultimum autem omnium bonorum est pax, quia pax est generalis finis mentis. Nam qualitercumque pax accipiatur, habet rationem finis; et in gloria aeterna et in regimine et in conversatione, finis est pax. [However, the last of all goods is peace because peace is the general end of the mind. For however peace is defined, it has the concept of an end. In eternal glory, government, and in one’s manner of life, the end is peace.]” Summa Theologiae (hereafter, ST) II-II, q. 29, a. 2, corp. (unless otherwise noted, all citations are from the Leonine edition); In de divinis nominibus (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1950), ch. 11, lec. 2. In arguing my thesis, I will draw on Spanish, Latin, and French texts from the mid-twentieth century that explore the connection between the Eucharist and peace in Aquinas. See the pieces by Santiago Ramirez (“La Eucaristia y la Paz Individual en la Teologia de Santo Tomas de Aquino”), Adolphus Hoffman (“Eucharistia ut Sacramentum Pacis secundum S. Thomam”), Godefridus Geenen (“L’adage Eucharistia est sacramentum ecclesiasticae unionis dans les oeuvres et la doctrine de S. Thomas d’Aquin”), and Ephrem Longpré (“L’Eucharistie est le sacrement de la paix mystique”) in La Eucaristía y la Paz. XXXV Congreso eucarístico internacional 1952: Sesiones de estudio, vol. 1 (Barcelona: Planas, 1953), 171–83 (Ramirez), 163–67 (Hoffman), 275–81 (Geenan), and 158–62 (Longpré). See also Gilles Emery, “Le fruit ecclésial de l’Eucharistie chez saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Nova et Vetera (Swiss) 72 (1997): 25–40. The structure of my argument is taken from Ramirez. The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1195 but also because it both brings another interlocutor to current debates over the nature and cause of peace and sheds a different light over the whole Thomistic moral synthesis, a synthesis seeking peace.8 The Ratio of Peace In beginning to explore the connections between peace and the Eucharist, it is necessary first to specify what Aquinas means by peace. Scanning the Thomistic corpus, one finds many different definitions: the removal of impediments to attaining the good, rest of the will in the fullness of good and immunity from all evil, putting things in right order, harmony with ourselves and others, the quiet of the mind in the end, ordered harmony, security against the loss of goods, tranquility of mind, tranquility arising from order, and the cessation of all desire.9 Yet, 8 9 The Eucharist goes beyond what most secular sources think of as peace (lack of conflict) in that it causes both (1) a deeper external peace between humans by uniting them (concord) around the true separate common good of the universe (God) and (2) the full notion of peace (internal order) by strengthening charity in its participants. De veritate, q. 22, a. 12, corp. [on the removal of impediments to attaining the good] (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953); Super Rom 1, lec. 4 (Turin, IT: Marietti edition, 1953), no. 70: “Tunc enim erit perfecta pax, quando voluntas requiescet in plenitudine omnis boni, consequens immunitatem ab omni malo [For then there will be perfect peace, when the will rests in the fullness of all good and as a result is free from every evil]”; ST II-II q. 45, a. 6, corp. [on putting things in right order]; Super II Thess 3, lec. 2 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1963), no. 89: “Pax enim consistit in duobus, ut scilicet homo concordet ad seipsum, et ad alios [For peace consists in two things, man’s harmony with himself and with others]”; Super Gal 1, lec. 1 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953), no. 11: “pax, quae est quietatio mentis in fine [Peace, which is the quieting of the mind in the end]”; Super II Tim 2, lec. 4 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953), no. 80: “Pax autem importat ordinatam concordiam [However, peace conveys well-ordered agreement]”; Super Rom 2, lec. 2 (Marietti no. 204): “Non enim potest esse pax hominis perfecta quamdiu aliquis timet se amissurum bona quae habet, sed tunc aliquis habet veram pacem cordis, quando habet omnia quae concupiscit et ea perdere non timet [For there cannot be perfect peace as long as man fears losing some good which he has, but only can someone have true peace of the heart when he has all that he desires and does not fear losing anything]”; Super Gal 6, lec. 5 (Marietti no. 376): “Pax, inquam, qua quietentur et perficiantur in bono. Pax enim est tranquillitas mentis [Peace, is said to be that by which humans are quieted and perfected in the good. For peace is tranquility of the mind]”; Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1952), no. 1962: “Sciendum est, quod pax nihil aliud est quam tranquillitas ordinis: tunc enim aliqua dicuntur pacem habere quando eorum ordo inturbatus manet” [It should be known that peace is nothing other than tranquility of order. Those are said to have peace whose 1196 John Meinert Aquinas’s most common definition by far is borrowed from Augustine: “tranquility of order.”10 It is likewise under this definition that all the others can be subsumed.11 While tranquility and order constitute peace together, the causally prior of these two elements is order. Tranquility is dependent on order, but not vice versa. What Aquinas means by “order” is a kind of relation and unity of parts based on a reference to a common good that organizes and unites them as principle of that order.12 Put simply, there can be no peace without some kind of proper order, the proper relation of humans to each other, to God, and within themselves.13 The second central concept is tranquility or rest (quietudine). This denotes not only the lack of conflict caused by proper order (within oneself, between people, and with God) but also the rest of all psychological faculties in the good. In short, there can be no peace if the heart remains restless. In fact, the two aspects of peace, tranquility and order, are so interdependent that Aquinas often gives only one element of the standard Augustinian definition. One cannot have proper order without it producing tranquility, and tranquility is only truly and lastingly found in proper order. On the basis of this ratio, ordered tranquility, one can see why Aquinas identifies two interdependent spheres of peace: interior and exterior. Exterior peace, or “concord,” is the ordered willing of one object together with others. It implies a mutual concurrence in a good and, thereby, a lack of conflict between parties inasmuch as that good unites them; both parties will a good together, and it, in turn, serves as the principle of their relation, the source of their unity. Without unity, there can be no peace, and without a good around which two concur, there can be no unity. 10 11 12 13 order remains undisturbed]; Super I Thess 1, lec. 1(Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953), no. 6: “Et pax quae est finis, quia tunc est pax, quando appetitus totaliter pacatur [And peace is the end because peace occurs when the appetites are totally subdued].” ST II-II q. 29, a. 1, corp.: “pax est tranquillitas ordinis.” For Aquinas’s dependence on Augustine in this regard, see Erb, 266. Order includes harmony within oneself, with others, and with God, thereby precluding conflict and providing security in the good. Tranquility is the lack of conflict resulting from this order and includes the rest of all faculties in the good. ST I, q. 42, a. 3. Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1962): “In homine autem est triplex ordo: scilicet hominis ad seipsum, hominis ad Deum, et hominis ad proximum: et sic est triplex pax in homine. [In man, however, there is a triple order: to himself, to God, and to neighbor. Thus, there is a triple peace in man.]” The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1197 Yet for Aquinas, “ordered tranquility” goes beyond mere concord.14 It includes order within the individual as well: “man’s heart does not have peace, even if he has what he wants, since there still remains something for him to want which cannot be had at the same time.”15 To have interior peace, three things must obtain: one must have the highest good one desires, the highest good one desires must be able to bring complete rest, and all one’s faculties must be ordered toward it.16 In other words, one’s hierarchical relation of goods must be able both to bring rest and to preclude conflict between desires. This is possible only by becoming part of a larger order, by directing all desires to a single good that gives rise to the order.17 Only in this way can interior conflict be precluded. Hence, peace denotes the appetituum unius appetentis unionem,18 even the natural ones.19 The Analogicity of Peace Given the pliability of the ratio of peace,20 one can see that peace must be an analogous concept for Aquinas.21 The analogicity of the concept of peace, which mimics the analogicity of the term “happiness,”22 allows Aquinas to distinguish five types of peace: perfect supernatural, imperfect supernatural, natural, worldly/temporal, and false. 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 Full peace includes concord and goes beyond it. For full peace, one must have concord, since tranquility or rest includes a negative notion of being without hindrance, of attaining the good easily and quickly. Attainment can be hindered by external elements, and so the full notion of peace must also have concord, a mutual seeking of the good. But such disturbance, for Aquinas, seems to only apply to the lower appetites, and thus interior peace should not be thought absolutely to require concord. Indeed, he claims that the highest part of the mind could rest in the good in this life and remain undisturbed. ST II-II, q. 29, a. 1, corp. Ibid. In de divinis nominibus, ch. 11, lec. 1: “Dicuntur autem aliqui homines habere pacem, quando voluntates eorum concordant in uno: sic enim unus alteri non adversatur. [However, men are said to have peace with another when their wills are in harmony about one thing. Thus, one is not against another.]” ST II-II, q. 29, a. 1, corp. ST II-II, q. 29, a. 2, ad 1. For the historical influences on Aquinas’s conception, see Erb. For Aquinas’s thought on analogy, see John Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2000), 75–85. Super Rom 1, lec. 4 (Marietti no. 70): “Aliud autem, scilicet pax, est ultimum quod in beatitudine perficitur [Peace, however, is the last gift of God because it is perfected in beatitude]”; Super II Cor 1, lec. 1 (Marietti no. 8). 1198 John Meinert The full meaning of peace, like that of virtue,23 obtains only supernaturally. Aquinas claims that a proper relationship with God is necessary for true peace because, interiorly, only God serves as the sufficient good for calming and ordering all desires: “For peace consists in two things, such that a man be in harmony with himself and with others. Neither can be had sufficiently without God. For without God a man does not have harmony within himself, much less with others, because a man’s affections are in harmony with themselves when what is desired for one suffices for all. Nothing but God can do this. . . . For anything else other than God is not sufficient [to quiet] for all [desires], but God is sufficient.”24 Likewise, externally, since humans are united by a common good, the most common good, God, will bring the most unity: “Men are not united amongst themselves unless it is by something held in common, and this is especially God.”25 On the basis of this, Aquinas claims that “from that profound [source] in which peace exists [God], it flows first and most perfectly into the beatified, in whom there is no disturbance of guilt or of punishment. Consequently, peace flows into saintly men, the holier he is the less he suffers disturbance of the mind. . . . Now because our hearts are not able to be without disturbances unless with God, it is necessary that [peace] comes from him.”26 Indeed, Aquinas claims that God is peace, the God of peace, and “the giver of peace.”27 “This peace consists in the love by which God 23 24 25 26 27 Brian Shanley, “Aquinas on Pagan Virtue,” The Thomist 63 (1999): 553–77. Super II Thess 3, lec. 2 (Marietti no. 89): “Pax enim consistit in duobus, ut scilicet homo concordet ad seipsum, et ad alios. Et neutrum potest habieri sufficienter nisi in Deo: quia sibi non concordat sufficienter nisi in Deo et minus aliis quia tunc affectus hominis concordat in seipso quando quod appetitur secundum unum, sufficit quantum ad omnes, quod nihil potest esse praeter Deum. . . . Quaecumque enim alia, praeter Deum, non sufficiunt ad omnes, sed Deus sufficit.” Super II Thess 3, lec. 2 (Marietti no. 89): “Item homines non uniuntur inter se, nisi in eo quod est commune inter eos, et hoc est maxime Deus.” Super Phil 4, lec. 1 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953), no. 159: “Ab isto profundo in quo est pax, derivatur primo et perfectius in beatos, in quibus nulla est perturbatio, et nec culpae, nec poenae, et consequenter derivatur ad sanctos viros. Et quanto est magis sanctus, tanto minus patitur perturbationem mentis. . . . Quia vero cor nostrum ab omni perturbatione non potest esse alienum nisi per Deum, oportet quod per ipsum fiat.” In de divinis nominibus, ch. 11, lec. 1; lec. 2: “Dicit ergo primo quod hoc primo dicendum est quod Deus, ipsam pacem per se, consideratam in abstracto . . . non est enim aliqua pax creata per se subsistens [God is himself peace per se The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1199 loves us.”28 Peace is obtained by submitting to and obeying God.29 Yet, God cannot have this integrating function, the highest good sought,30 which wards off all conflict, without habitual grace (and especially the virtue of charity caused by habitual grace).31 As Aquinas says, “without sanctifying grace one cannot have true peace, but only apparent [peace].”32 In this sense, peace is appropriated to the Holy Spirit, “since he is love, which is the cause of peace.”33 True peace (supernatural peace), the pax ecclesiae,34 can be divided in turn into imperfect and perfect. Perfect peace, the full proper order of things (including with God, with one another, and within oneself ), the complete cessation of desire and freedom from all evils, can be had only in the beatific vision. Yet, an imperfect participation in this type of peace can be had in this life.35 It is imperfect in full concord (external peace), since even though all love God as the highest good, those in the Church have differing opinions about God in small matters, in aliquibus parvis.36 The peace of the Church on earth is imperfect in interior peace, since “even if the soul’s principal movement rests in God, still there remain certain obstacles, both within and without, that disturb this peace.”37 Neither of these negate the true peace of the earthly Church, which belongs to the appetites and not the mind, but neither will be present in heaven. These imperfections are simply another way of saying that the peace that believers 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 and taken in the abstract . . . for created peace is not something which subsists per se]”; Super I Cor 14, lec. 6 (Marietti no. 877); Super Rom 15, lec. 3 (Marietti no. 1191): “dator pacis.” ST I-II, q. 113, a. 2, corp.: “Quae quidem pax consistit in dilectione qua Deus nos diligit.” Super Rom 5, lec. 1, (Marietti no. 382): “Let us have peace with God, that is by submitting ourselves and obeying him.” In de divinis nominibus, ch. 11, lec. 1: “Et quia divina pax causat unitatem in rebus, ideo concludit quod omnia suo modo desiderant divinam pacem, inquantum etiam est omnium unitiva.” Super Col 3, lec. 3 (Turin, IT: Marietti, 1953), no. 163. ST II-II, q. 29, a. 3, ad 1: “Et propter hoc sine gratia gratum faciente non potest esse vera pax, sed solum apparens.” Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1961): “Spiritui vero sancto, cum sit amor, qui est causa pacis, pax appropriatur.” See also Super Rom 8, lec. 1 (Marietti no. 618). Super I Cor 12, lec. 3 (Marietti no. 750). Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1962). ST II-II, q. 29, a. 3, ad 2. ST II-II, q. 29, a. 2, ad 4: “Quia etsi principalis animae motus quiescat in Deo, sunt tamen aliqua repugnantia et intus et extra quae perturbant hanc pacem.” 1200 John Meinert have on this side of heaven is imperfect in activity, although it is continuous (a foretaste) with heavenly peace.38 Another type of peace in Aquinas is natural peace. Certainly, Aquinas does not use this term (as far as I am aware), but he does imply its existence. For natural peace to obtain, the common good sought must be authentically good, not merely apparently so.39 Any true good sought (without the aid of grace) that brings people together, that causes unity, can cause a type of concord, a degree of external peace and internal rest.40 Natural peace and its accompanying partial quieting of the appetites can be had by any and all; it does not require grace.41 This includes, but is not limited to, what Aquinas calls “the peace and quiet of enjoying temporal things.”42 The peace and quiet caused by temporal things, inasmuch as it falls under natural peace, requires a virtuous natural use of those things. Another type of peace is what Aquinas calls “worldly peace,” pax mundi, or “temporal peace,” pax temporalis.43 In one sense of this term, Aquinas simply means peace (natural or supernatural) had in this world.44 This use of the term is not a separate type of peace, but reduces to either imperfect supernatural peace or imperfect natural peace. A second sense of worldly peace must be distinguished from all those types outlined above because Aquinas claims that both the good and evil share this peace.45 Imperfect natural peace and imperfect supernatural peace require virtue; they cannot be had by those who are vicious inasmuch as they are vicious. Worldly peace (in the 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 ST I-II, q. 3, a. 1, corp. This seems to be the necessary interpretation of Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1964), where Aquinas claims that the peace Christ gives is perfect. De malo q. 11, a. 1 (Marietti edition, 1953); ST I-II, q. 18, a. 5. Another way of stating this is to say that both the natural law and the civil law produce a type of natural peace. See Erb, 265–66. This could still obtain even in the most pessimistic interpretation of Aquinas on the power of fallen humans without grace. All must at least admit the following possibilities: not only “building houses and planting vinyards” but also “friendship” and “conservation of citizenship.” See ST I-II, q. 109, aa. 2 and 5, and ST II-II, q. 23, a. 7. Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1964): “Nam pax mundi ordinatur ad quietam et pacificam fruitionem temporalium.” The differences between these two terms should not be exaggerated. Aquinas seems to use both freely to describe any peace had in this world. See Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti nos. 1963–64). Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1963). Super I Tim 2, lec. 1 (Marietti no. 59). The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1201 second sense) can be enjoyed by those who are vicious. Hence, it seems that another sense of peace must be distinguished. As Aquinas uses the term pax mundi (in the second sense), it seems to refer primarily to the lack of conflict inter patrias et intra patriam.46 It is this sense of worldly peace that is distinguished from the peace of Christ in three ways and could even help people to sin.47 This sense of peace requires no real concord, or only the thinnest shred of concord, and no real virtue on the part of the subject. As such, worldly peace in the second sense is also counterfeit peace, pax simulata;48 it gives no true rest. Nevertheless, Aquinas holds that this type of peace exists to allow the good of contemplation and the possibility of evangelization.49 In other words, it is still distinct from the final sense of peace. The final sense of peace is a concord found because of a merely apparent good.50 This type of peace is separate from natural peace, since natural peace involves a real common good. It is distinguished from the pax mundi in the second sense because the peace of this 46 47 48 49 50 Gregory Reichberg, “Aquinas’s Moral Typology of Peace and War,” Review of Metaphysics 64.1: 467–87, at 472–79. It is certainly also true that intra patriam (and maybe also inter patrias) peace falls under natural peace, since there is a true political common good sought by all. For more on the primacy of the common good, see (among many others) Stephen Brock, “The Primacy of the Common Good and the Foundations of Natural Law in St. Thomas,” in Ressourcement Thomism: Sacred Doctrine, the Sacraments, and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Romanus Cessario, O.P., ed. R. Hütter and M. Levering (Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2010): 234–55. Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1964); Super I Tim 2, lec. 1 (Marietti, no. 59). Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1964). Super Psalmos 14 (Parma no. 8): “ Vacate et videte. Hic finis est pacis. Finis pacis temporalis, secundum philosophum, est contemplatio veritatis. Unde pax est utilis finis vitae activae, et pax ordinatur ad contemplationem. Et secundum Augustinum, Christus procuravit pacem Romani imperii, ut apostoli discurrerent per totum mundum. Et ideo dicit ex quo est tanta pax, vacate et videte. Unde patet quod Deus dat pacem ut non vacent malis operibus, sed contemplationi veritatis. [Empty yourself and see. Here the end is peace. According to the philosopher, the end of temporal peace is the contemplation of truth. Hence, peace is the practical end of the active life, and peace is ordained to contemplation. And according to Augustine, Christ procured the peace of the Roman empire so that the apostles could travel through the whole world. And for this reason he says empty yourself and see, namely by which is such a peace. Whence, it is clear that God gives peace not that we may be idle in evil acts, but that we may contemplate the truth.]” Aquinas seems to suggest a more independent end for temporal peace in Super Ioan 14, lec. 7 (Marietti no. 1964). Hoffman, “Eucharistia ut Sacramentum Pacis,” 163. 1202 John Meinert world is not necessarily sinful and can be used for good. This final sense of (false) peace is necessarily sinful; it is the semblance of peace caused by unity in malice.51 Order based on a merely apparent good might seem to be peace; there is a kind of concord and a kind of internal order. Yet, given Aquinas’s metaphysics, the concord and rest found in something evil cannot be true peace, for peace is a function of unity and unity can only be found in the good. Evil is parasitic on the good and thus parasitic on unity and peace. In addition, evil can never quiet the appetite. Hence, Aquinas says that “peace consists in the rest and union of one’s appetites, and just as one can desire the good simply speaking or a merely apparent good, so too peace is able to be either true or apparent. Indeed, peace is not able to be without the true good since every evil, though it seems good from some angle and so quiets the appetite in part, has so many defects that the appetite remains restless and disturbed.”52 Charity and Peace The second step in the argument and the vital middle term is the virtue of charity. Peace is the proper effect of charity. This takes very little establishing in Aquinas: “From charity immediately follows peace.”53 Aquinas even dedicates an article directly to the topic of “whether peace is the proper effect of charity” and answers “yes.”54 Supernatural peace is the proper effect of charity because charity is the direct efficient cause of the twofold union of peace: “The union of men in one object and the union of all appetites in one object.”55 In short, charity effects the union of appetites within a human and between humans. It is because of this that charity is said to be the bond of the whole spiritual edifice.56 Charity and its principal act, to love,57 are the efficient causes of the true concord between humans. Charity unites humans in true 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 Super Rom 12, lec. 3 (Marietti no. 1010). ST II-II, q. 29, a. 3, corp.: “quia pax consistit in quietatione et unione appetitus; sicut autem appetitus potest esse vel boni simpliciter vel boni apparentis, ita etiam et pax potest esse et vera et apparens, vera quidem pax non potest esse nisi circa appetitum veri boni; quia omne malum, etsi secundum aliquid appareat bonum, unde ex aliqua parte appetitum quietet, habet tamen multos defectus, ex quibus appetitus remanet inquietus et perturbatus.” Super Col 3, lec. 3 (Marietti no. 164): “Ex caritate mox oritur pax.” ST II-II, q. 29, a. 3, corp. Ibid. ST II-II, q. 4, a. 7, a. 4. ST II-II, q. 27, a. 2, corp. The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1203 friendship, since it provides a bond based on love of God in which one wills the other’s good as one’s own. Truly, this is concord. It makes believers love their neighbor as themselves and “makes us want to do his will even as our own.”58 On this basis a true community of friendship, a true concord, is formed. Charity is also the efficient cause of the true ordering of one’s own desires. It brings them into an ordered unity by serving as the form of the other virtues; it makes goodness itself (God) the object of action.59 Put simply, charity transforms all other good habits and desires by referring them to its end (thereby also playing a formal role). All the other virtues and goods thus find relation to each other by their relation to God under the guidance of charity, and this precludes conflict. In addition, only charity loves God directly and only God sufficiently quiets all desire. True rest, the cessation of all desire, can come only when there is no good beyond the one possessed. In Aquinas’s metaphysics, no other object could serve this function of both ordering and quieting. Given that charity effects the twofold formality of peace, peace is called one of the acts of charity.60 In saying this, Aquinas does not mean that peace is one act among others such that sometimes charity enacts peace and at other times it is beneficent or fraternally correcting. As Cajetan notes, Aquinas’s language should not be taken literally. Peace is the result of charity and charity’s primary act, to love.61 As such, peace is a type of formality that qualifies all truly 58 59 60 61 ST II-II, q. 29, a. 3, corp.: “Aliam vero, prout diligimus proximum sicut nosipsos, ex quo contingit quod homo vult implere voluntatem proximi sicut et sui ipsius.” ST II-II, q. 25, a. 1, corp. ST II-II, q. 29, a. 4, corp.: “Cum igitur pax causetur ex caritate secundum ipsam rationem dilectionis Dei et proximi, ut ostensum est, non est alia virtus cuius pax sit proprius actus nisi caritas, sicut et de gaudio dictum est. [Therefore, since peace is caused by charity, which is itself the very definition of love of God and neighbor (as was said above), peace is most properly the act of charity and not of another virtue, just as was said about joy.]” ST II-II, q. 28, prol.: “Deinde considerandum est de effectibus consequentibus actum caritatis principalem, qui est dilectio. Et primo, de effectibus interioribus; secundo, de exterioribus. Circa primum tria consideranda sunt, primo, de gaudio; secundo, de pace; tertio, de misericordia. [Next we will consider the effects following from the principal act of charity, which is love. First we will consider the interior effects and second the exterior. As for interior effects we will consider first joy, second peace, and third mercy.]” See Reichberg, “Aquinas’s Moral Typology,” 473. 1204 John Meinert loving actions and not simply one set of them.62 Wherever there is charity, there are acts of love, and wherever there are acts of love, there is peace. On the other hand, charity is not the only virtue relevant for the seeking of true peace, even if it is the direct cause. The virtue of justice is quite important as well, not as directly effecting peace but as a dispositive cause, as warding off the disturbances of peace. Justice does not bring about peace directly, but it helps prepare for it and preserve it. As Aquinas says, “peace is especially disturbed when one man does not give to the other that which is owed to him.”63 This is even true for the peace of the Church.64 Wisdom is another virtue important for peace. According to Aquinas, it belongs to charity and the appetites “to have peace” (habere pacem) but to wisdom “to make peace” ( facere pacem).65 Wisdom makes peace by putting things in proper order.66 In this way wisdom should not be thought of as extrinsic to peace in the way that justice is. Wisdom is seated in the intellect and judges connaturally what belongs to proper order.67 Without wisdom, peace would not only be disturbed, but would never exist at all. The Eucharist and Charity The next step in the argument is to connect charity, the proper cause of true peace, to the Eucharist.68 Such a connection is easily established 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 See Cajetan’s commentary on Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae II-II, q. 29, a. 4, in Opera omnia iussu impensaque Leonis XIII P.M. edita [Leonine edition], vol. 4 (Rome: Ex Typographia Polyglotta S.C. de Propaganda Fidei, 1888), 239: “For it seems that peace signifies formally the consequent perfection of the act of charity by which God and neighbor are loved. Because of this perfection it is not an absolutely distinct thing from the act of charity, but is either the act itself (that is the union of appetites in one thing), or the relative quality following from it.” Super Rom 14, lec. 2, (Marietti no. 1128): “Per hoc enim pax maxime perturbatur, quod unus homo non exhibet alteri quod ei debet.” Super II Cor 12, lec. 3 (Marietti no. 750). ST II-II, q. 45, a. 6, ad 1. ST II-II, q. 45, a. 6, corp. ST II-II, q. 45, a. 2, corp. The citations in this footnote are taken from Emery, “The Ecclesial Fruit of the Eucharist in St. Thomas Aquinas,” 161n29. The English translation can be found in two places: in his Trinity, Church, and the Human Person: Thomistic Essays (Naples, FL: Ave Maria Press, 2007): 155–72, and in Nova et Vetera (English) 2 (2004): 43–60. ST III, q. 73, a. 3, ad 3; q. 74, a. 4, obj. 3; q. 78, a. 3, obj. 6 and ad 6; q. 79, a. 4, ad 3; q. 80, a. 5, ad 2; cf. q. 78, a. 3, ad 6 (“Hoc autem The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1205 in Aquinas: the Eucharist is nothing other than a re-presentation of the sacrifice of Christ. Now, the sacrifice of Christ is the instrumental efficient cause of charity. Hence, the Eucharist is also.The Eucharist effects charity by incorporating believers into Christ and likening them to Christ in its two-fold causality as sacrament and sacrifice:69 “It has the nature of a sacrifice inasmuch as it is offered up; and it has the nature of a sacrament inasmuch as it is received.”70 As sacrifice, the Eucharist causes charity by reconciling humans with God and by exemplarity. As sacrament, the Eucharist causes peace by uniting the recipient with Christ, from whom charity flows.71 By re-presenting the Passion, the Eucharist effects charity in a twofold manner. First, it is the very power by which the sacramental aspect (the reception) obtains its effect. The Passion is re-presented, and thus, the effects of the Passion obtain: Christ’s sacrifice is the efficient cause of our salvation,72 merits the salvation of all, is the proper cause of the forgiveness of sins, delivers believers from Satan’s power and reconciles with God, and gets rid of the debt of punishment. Hence, the Eucharist effects the same things (as one can see by the overlay of questions 48–49 and 79 of the tertia pars of the Summa theologiae). These effects include both charity itself and what is necessary to preserve it. Second, the Eucharist as sacrifice causes charity by re-presenting the efficient cause of our salvation. It is in 69 70 71 72 est sacramentum caritatis quasi figurativum et effectivum [However, this (the Eucharist) is the sacrament of charity as though both signifying and effecting it.]”); q. 79, a. 1, ad 1; q. 81, a. 1, ad 3; q. 79, a. 1; q. 81, a. 1, ad 3. ST III, q. 49, aa. 2–3. I divide the effects of the Eucharist this way following Ramirez (“La Eucaristia y la Paz Individual,” 179–80). ST III, q. 79, a. 5, corp.: “In order to do this, it is fitting to treat the Eucharist under its double aspect, sacrament and sacrifice. Again, as stated earlier, these should not be thought of as separate lines of causality producing diverse effects, but rather different ways to conceive that which the Eucharist contains versus what it signifies, in what the Eucharistic power terminates directly vs. what is there concomitantly. These diverse lines of causality should not be thought of as disparate; all are simply aspects of the one sacrament. Indeed, the sacramental power is not diverse from the passion, i.e. the sacrificial aspect.” As Aquinas notes, “this sacrament may be considered that from which it has its effect, namely Christ there presenting his passion there represented, and that through which it works its effect, namely the receiving of the sacrament and the sacramental elements” (ibid., a. 2, corp.). Both of these translations are taken from the Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1947). In de divinis nominibus, ch. 11, lec. 3. ST III, q. 48, a. 6. 1206 John Meinert the re-presentation of the sacrifice of the Cross that we see the exemplar of supernatural Charity: Christ’s love poured out in sacrifice.73 This serves the dual function of both exciting the virtue of charity by showing what great love God has for humans and informing believers of what exactly the proper content of supernatural charity is.74 By containing Christ, the sacramental reception of the Eucharist effects charity in a threefold manner such that “perfected in union with the suffering Christ . . . the Eucharist is called the sacrament of charity, which is the bond of perfection.” 75 First, the believer is conformed to Christ’s charity: “Just as by coming visibly into the world he brought the life of grace into it . . . so by coming to men sacramentally he causes the life of grace.” 76 By the sacramental reception of Christ himself, “grace is increased and the spiritual life perfected and made whole by union with God.” 77 The increase of grace breaks forth in the soul as charity. Yet, this is not only conformity in a generic sense: the reception of grace in the Eucharist is the very reception of Christ’s grace and, thus, of his charity.78 In receiv ST III, q. 48, a. 6, ad 4; q. 46, a. 3, corp. ST III, q. 46, a. 3, corp.; Super Ioan 6, lec. 6 (Marietti no. 963); Bruce Marshall, “The Whole Mystery of Our Salvation: Saint Thomas Aquinas on the Eucharist as Sacrifice,” in Rediscovering Aquinas and the Sacraments: Studies in Sacramental Theology, ed. Matthew Levering and Michael Dauphinais (Chicago: Hillenbrand Books, 2009), 63–64: “The Eucharist has the very same effects as the Passion itself.” 75 ST III, q. 73, a. 3, ad 3: “Sed Eucharistia est sacramentum passionis Christi prout homo perficitur in unione ad Christum passum. . . . ita Eucharistia dicitur sacramentum caritatis, quae est vinculum perfectionis.” 76 ST III, q. 79, a. 1, corp.: “Qui sicut, in mundum visibiliter veniens, contulit mundo vitam gratiae, secundum illud Ioan. I, gratia et veritas per Iesum Christum facta est; ita, in hominem sacramentaliter veniens, vitam gratiae operatur, secundum illud Ioan. VI, qui manducat me, vivit propter me.” 77 ST III, q. 79, a. 1: “Per hoc autem sacramentum augetur gratia, et perficitur spiritualis vita, ad hoc quod homo in seipso perfectus existat per coniunctionem ad Deum.” 78 ST III, q. 8, a. 1, ad 1: Super Ioan 1, lec. 10 (Marietti no. 202): “Nota, quod haec propositio ‘de’ aliquando quidem denotat efficientiam, seu originalem causam, sicut cum dicitur, radius est vel procedit de sole; et hoc modo denotat in Christo efficientiam gratiae, seu auctoritatem, quia plenitudo gratiae, quae est in Christo, est causa omnium gratiarum quae sunt in omnibus intellectualibus creaturis. . . . quae scilicet de me procedunt, adimplemini, participatione sufficientis plenitudinis. [Note that the preposition ‘from’ signifies the efficient or origin cause, just as it is said that a ray of light proceeds from the sun. Being thus it signifies that in Christ is the origin or author of grace because the fullness of grace, which is in him, is the cause of all graces which are in every intellectual creature.]” 73 74 The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1207 ing the Eucharist, believers can begin to love as Christ loves. Second, under the manner of its giving food, the Eucharist in its sacramental aspect is also the proper cause of charity. The Eucharist sustains, augments, restores, and delights. It sustains charity by sustaining the supernatural life of the believer, removing the impediments to the activity of charity (venial sin), and protecting the life of charity by protecting against future sins. It augments the life of charity just as the assimilation of food augments the body as it is growing. It restores the fervor of charity by removing the impediments to charity’s activity and thus renews it. Finally, it moves the believer to acts of charity—that is, love of God and neighbor. In short, “This [sacrament] does for the life of the spirit [and thus for charity] all that material food and drink does for the life of the body.”79 Finally, the species under which Christ is given signifies, but does not contain, the ultimate effect of the sacrament, ecclesial unity. Indeed, ecclesial unity is the direct effect of the sacrament, the res sacramenti, yet it is brought about by charity, which Aquinas also calls the res of the sacrament.80 For these reasons, Aquinas claims that “the Eucharist is said to be the sacrament of Christ’s charity expressed, and ours made,”81 and “the proper effect of this sacrament is the transformation into Christ through love.”82 The Eucharist both symbolizes our charity and brings it about (in both habit and act) and is thus called the sacramentum caritatis.83 The Eucharist and Peace The final step of this argument is connecting the Eucharist to peace. The Eucharist is the instrumental efficient and exemplar cause of charity, and charity is the efficient cause of supernatural peace.84 Hence, the Eucharist is the proper cause of supernatural peace. It causes the ST III, q. 79, a. 1, corp.: “Et ideo omnem effectum quem cibus et potus materialis facit quantum ad vitam corporalem, quod scilicet sustenat, auget, reparat, et delectat, hoc totum facit hoc sacramentum quantum ad vitam spiritualem.” 80 For the best treatment of the Eucharist in relation to ecclesial unity, see Emery, “Le fruit ecclesial.” 81 In IV sent. d. 8, q. 2, a. 2, qc. 3, ad 5: “Eucharistia dicitur sacramentum caritatis Christi expressivum, et nostrae factivum.” 82 Ibid. 83 ST III, q. 78, a. 3, ad 6; ST III, q. 79, a. 4, corp. 84 Hoffman, “Eucharistia ut Sacramentum Pacis,” 164: “Eucharistia est causa efficiens illius duplicis unionis.” 79 1208 John Meinert twofold notion central to peace, unity with God and neighbor.85 Such is Aquinas’s conception. As sacrifice, the Eucharist causes peace by re-presenting the very cause of peace, Christ’s sacrifice on the Cross. This re-presentation causes peace by both efficient causality and exemplarity. The Eucharist as sacrifice causes peace by efficient causality, since the very purpose of Christ’s Incarnation was the restoration of peace. Christ is he who “came to restore all things to a state of peace and calm.”86 He did so by his death: “The passion itself was the maker of peace.”87 It is this very Passion that is numerically identical with the sacrifice of the Eucharist, identical quoad substantium and different quoad modum. Put differently, the very cause of peace is represented in the Eucharist, for Christ is present as priest, victim, and peace offering.88 Likewise, in the Passion re-presented, we see the ultimate example of love, the maker of peace: “If you seek an example of love: ‘No one has greater love than this . . . [to lay down his life for his friends].’ This is Christ on the cross.”89 As an exemplar of love, the sacrifice of the Cross is also an exemplar of peace, not in its full form without disturbances, but as it exists in this world and in its proper cause. In this way, as re-presenting the very cause of peace, the Eucharist effects unity both interior and exterior: “To cure [the disturbances of peace] Jesus offers them the peace of reconciliation with God . . . which he accomplished by his suffering.”90 As sacrament, the Eucharist also causes both exterior and interior peace. The Eucharist causes concord by ordering the diverse appetites of people to desire and seek one good: worship and love of God. The relevance for external peace and the Eucharist can be seen most clearly by separating the threefold signification of the sacrament: sign, sign and reality, and reality. According to the “sign alone,” one sees that the Eucharist signifies its ultimate effect of ecclesial unity: “Our Lord has proffered his body Ibid. ST III, q. 44, a. 4, ad 3. 87 Super Matt 16, lec. 3, (Marietti edition, 1951), no. 1398: “Sed ipsa passio pacifica fuit.” 88 ST III, q. 22, a. 2, corp. 89 Collationes Super Credo in Deum, trans. and ed. Nicholas Ayo with introduction (Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock Publishers, 1988), 72 (this translation is from the Leonine edition: “Si enim exemplum queris caritatis, ‘maiorem caritatem nemo habet’ etc.: hoc Christus in cruce”). 90 Super Ioan 20, lec. 4 (Marietti no. 2532). 85 86 The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1209 and his blood in those things which, from a multitude, are reduced to unity, since the bread is one single reality made of many grains; while the wine is one single drink made of many grapes.”91 From a multitude, the Eucharist brings forth a single reality.92 Under the second aspect of the Eucharist, the “sign and reality” (res et sacramentum), one also finds the production of concord. The Eucharist makes the Church, since “by this sacrament the members of the Church are united to their head.”93 It is by Eucharistic realism that one has ecclesial peace. In the third level of the sacrament, the “reality” (res tantum), one finds the reality of ecclesial peace and unity in full relief. Since one enters into true communion with Christ, believers are “mutually united by [him].”94 The ultimate effect of the Eucharist is the mutual union of the members of Christ with one another. In short, the Eucharist is called the sacrament of unity and of peace.95 The Eucharist brings about a union of wills around the highest good, the very notion of true concord.96 Although it should not be thought of as a different effect from the communal (since both are caused and lived by charity), the Eucharist as sacrament also causes interior peace by communicating to the recipient a participation in the very peace of Christ and ultimately of God himself.97 According to Aquinas, not only was Christ’s time the time of greatest peace, did he come to restore peace, and is peace found in his coming, but Christ is also the way of peace and a share ST III, q. 79, a. 1. ST III, q. 73, a. 3, corp. 93 In IV sent. d. 8, q. 1, a. 3, qc. 1, sc 1. 94 ST III q. 73, a. 4, corp. 95 Garrigou-Lagrange concurs and claims that, according to Aquinas, the Eucharist causes peace by uniting all Christians in the profession of one faith. In other words, the Eucharist is like supernatural wisdom and teaches the proper ordo of life, an order necessary for true peace. Likewise, it unites the hearts of all the faithful by strengthening charity, which is the very bond of the Church. Furthermore, all the members of the Christian family are united in the Eucharist in common worship. The diverse classes are united as well as the diverse peoples. All this can only be accomplished by causing charity; see Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, De Eucharistia: Accedunt de Pænitentia Quaestiones Dogmaticæ: Commentarius in Summam Theologicam S. Thomæ (Turin, IT: R. Berruti, 1943). 96 The citations in this footnote are taken from Emery, “The Ecclesial Fruit of the Eucharist,” 161n27. ST III q. 67, a. 2; q. 73, a. 2, s.c.; q. 73, a. 4; q. 80, a. 5, ad 2; q. 82, a. 2, arg. 3 and ad 3; q. 83, a. 4, corp. and ad 3. 97 In de divinis nominibus, ch. 11, lec. 1. 91 92 1210 John Meinert of the very peace of Christ is communicated to believers in the Eucharist:98 “Christ is called the God of peace because he is the giver of peace and one who loves. . . . He is also the author of peace. . . . He also dwells in peace.”99 In short, God pours peace into the world through Jesus Christ.100 Put simply, Eucharistic reception communicates the peace of Christ by uniting the believer to Christ. Union with Christ in the Eucharist not only brings humans together externally but also properly orders the subjective desires and faculties toward God the Trinity, the one supreme good. Now, as we saw earlier, union with God is the sine qua non of true interior peace. Hence, the Eucharist is the true cause of peace. Put another way, the Eucharist augments and moves toward peace because of what it contains.101 Eucharist not only causes peace directly by uniting humans to God and ordering their faculties and desires ad unum. It also wards off the impediments to peace, obstacles both within and without that disturb proper order and rest.102 The Eucharist forgives venial sin, which diminishes the fervor of charity and thus peace. It preserves from future sins, sins that would disorder the soul and diminish peace. It even indirectly counters the fomes of sin, the very inclination to sin, which is a cause of conflict. Likewise, it forgives punishment, which is contrary to the will achieving the good and, thus, contrary to peace. Finally, the Eucharist wards off the outward assaults of demons who hinder proper love of God and neighbor, the very foundations of peace. By strengthening charity, the love of God and neighbor and source of unity, the Eucharist both causes peace directly and wards off all the agents of conflict.103 Put differently, the Eucharist sustains and restores peace.104 Super Psalmos 13 (Parma no. 5). For more on the ontological exemplarity of Christ see Thomas Ryan, Thomas Aquinas as Reader of the Psalms (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2000), 81–105. 99 Super II Cor 13, lec. 3 (Marietti no. 540): “sed ideo Christus dicitur Deus pacis, quia est dator pacis et amator. . . . Ipse etiam est auctor pacis. . . . Ipse in pace habitat.” 100 In de divinis nominibus, ch. 11, lec. 3. 101 ST III, q. 79, a. 4; Hoffman, “Eucharistia ut Sacramentum Pacis,” 164. 102 Hoffman, “Eucharistia ut Sacramentum Pacis,” 166. 103 At least inasmuch as these are contained in the Church and in the mind. See Super Phil 4, lec. 1 (Marietti no. 159); Emery, “The Ecclesial Fruit of the Eucharist,” 162–63; and ST II-II, q. 29, a. 3, ad 2. 104 Hoffman, “Eucharistia ut Sacramentum Pacis,” 164. 98 The Eucharist and Peace in St. Thomas Aquinas 1211 Certainly, the peace attained by the Eucharist, both internal and external, is imperfect in this life; the perfect peace of Christ is only in the life to come. But here also one can see the deep resonances between the Eucharist and peace. Indeed, it is no coincidence that both show the tension of realized eschatology. The peace believers have now is the in-breaking of perfect peace and a participation in the very peace of Christ. As Aquinas says, “everlasting peace, spiritual peace, begins here and is completed there.”105 The Eucharist likewise causes the other virtues necessary for peace. This obtains not only efficiently by its augmenting of habitual grace, which breaks forth in the soul as the infused virtues, but also by exemplarity. For example, the liturgy teaches wisdom. Inasmuch as the Gospel is proclaimed at the liturgy, it informs the believer of true order, for “truly, the purpose of the Gospel is peace in Christ.”106 Aquinas claims that “the advantage [his] teaching gives is peace.”107 The Eucharist also concerns justice but goes beyond it by charity. It teaches the participant not only to give the other his due but also to desire the other’s due as if it were one’s own. Given these resonances between the Eucharist and peace, it does not seem to be a stretch to say that the very purpose of the Eucharist is peace. This was shown above but could also be argued in multiple ways. For example, the purpose of Christ’s coming was to bring peace, which was accomplished by the sacrifice of the Cross. Now, that same sacrifice is numerically identical with the Eucharist, and hence, the Eucharist too has the same purpose: to bring peace. Another way of arguing this would be to follow Aquinas’s claim that the purpose of this sacrament is its use by the faithful, their sanctification.108 Now, sanctification is simply another word in Aquinas for living proper order, since the saint is “one who has peace amid this life, even in spite of troubles.”109 Hence, the purpose of the Eucharist is to bring peace between all without distinction and to give the heart rest without end. Moreover, since all the other sacraments are ordered to the Eucharist as an end, all the sacraments are ordered toward peace.110 Hence, I do not think it is a stretch, even though Aquinas Super II Thess 3, lec. 2 (Marietti no. 89). Ibid. 107 Super Ioan 16, lec. 8 (Marietti no. 2174): “utilitas doctrinae est pax.” 108 ST III, q. 60, a. 5; q. 63, a. 6. 109 Super Ioan 16, lec. 8 (Marietti no. 2174). 110 ST III, q. 65, a. 3, corp.; In IV sent. d. 8, q. 1, a. 2, qc. 2, ad 4: The Eucharist 105 106 1212 John Meinert never calls the Eucharist the sacrament of peace, to say it is implicit in N&V his thought. The Eucharist is truly the food of peace.111 “has all grace and all the effects of the others sacraments singularly.” One might also say that the Eucharist is relevant for natural and worldly peace in the following way. One who desires an effect desires its necessary cause. Now, since Christ is the sole cause of perfect peace, and since all desire peace by desiring anything whatsoever, all implicitly desire Christ in the Eucharist by desiring anything whatsoever. Of course, this would be an elicited desire. 111 Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1213–1238 God, the University, and Human Flourishing Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas Rome, Italy The most widespread conception of the nature and function of the university today is that it is a place where research and teaching takes places in order to advance the economic and political well-being of the society it exists to serve.1 Economic and political interests that come to bear on universities lead to a favoring of research-led universities in which researchers focus their energies on narrow areas of specialization. Success, as measured in economic terms, Thus, Michael Oakeshott writes: “Somehow or other the idea of a university in recent years has got mixed up with notions such a ‘higher education,’ ‘advanced training,’ refresher courses for adults,’—things admirable in themselves, but really very little to do with a university. And it is time something was done to unravel the confusion. For these ideas belong to a world of power and utility, of exploitation, of social and individual egoism, and of activity whose meaning lies outside itself in some trivial result of achievement—and this is not the world to which a university belongs. It is a very powerful world; it is wealthy, interfering, well-meaning. But it is not remarkably self-critical; it is apt to mistake itself for the whole world, and with amiable carelessness it assumes that whatever does not contribute to its own purposes is somehow errant. A university needs beware of the patronage of this world, or it will find that it has sold its birthright for a mess of pottage; it will find that instead of studying and teaching the languages and literatures of the world it has become a school for training interpreters, that instead of pursuing science it is engaged in training electrical engineers or industrial chemists, that instead of studying history it is studying and teaching history for some ulterior purpose, that instead of educating men and women it is training them exactly to fill some niche in society”; seeThe Voice of Liberal Learning: Michael Oakeshott on Education, ed. Timothy Fuller (New Haven, CT / London: Yale University Press, 1989), 103. 1 1214 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. depends on such specialization.2 Economic and political influence seeps its way down to undergraduate education as well. Alasdair MacIntyre explains: “Undergraduate education has by now become largely a prologue to specialization and professionalization, and prestige in providing undergraduate education for the most part attaches to those institutions that prepare their students most effectively for admission to prestigious graduate programs. So the curriculum has increasingly become one composed of an assorted ragbag of disciplines and subdisciplines, each pursued and taught in relative independence of all the others, and achievement within each consists in the formation of the mind of a dedicated specialist.”3 Catholic universities do not, by and large, furnish an exception to the rule. They “often mimic the structures and goals of the most prestigious secular universities and do so with little sense of something having gone seriously amiss.”4 To many people, it will not at all be clear that anything has gone amiss with third-level education. The more prestigious a research university becomes, the more funding it draws down. In effect, it becomes a good business corporation. Successful students can also entertain good career prospects. This is surely a win-win situation, is it not? Those who have received nothing more than this kind of education will no doubt answer in the affirmative precisely because they lack the range of vision afforded by a liberal arts education. MacIntyre contends that they are, in fact, blind to the disasters that this kind of education has wreaked on the world: “A surprising number of the major disorders of the latter part of the twentieth Indeed, in contemporary society, the university itself constitutes an important economic entity. As Ronald Barnett writes, “In any estimation . . . higher education is big business”; see The Idea of Higher Education (Bristol, PA: Society for Research into Higher Education / Open University Press, 1990), 3. 3 Alasdair MacIntyre, God, Philosophy, Universities: A Selective History of the Catholic Philosophical Tradition (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2009), 173–74. See also Gerard Loughlin, “Theology in the University,” in John Henry Newman, ed. Ian Ker and Terrence Merrigan (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 230: “Today’s university no longer offers a unified education, for there is little consensus as to what this might entail, little sense of a shared culture for which it might fit people. Today universities offer vocational courses, but little or no sense of vocation, of being called to a way of life, let alone a way of life for others, and through others for God. Today universities seek merely to meet the tastes of their customers and the whims of their paymasters. Today the university lies in ruins.” 4 MacIntyre, God, Philosophy, Universities, 179. 2 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1215 century and of the first decade of the twenty first century have been brought about by some of the most distinguished graduates of some of the most distinguished universities in the world and this as the result of an inadequate general education, at both graduate and especially undergraduate levels, that has made it possible for those graduates to act decisively and deliberately without knowing what they were doing.”5 Examples he adduces include the Vietnam War, United States policy towards Iran for more than half a century, and the present economic crisis. While MacIntyre does not argue exhaustively for this claim, he does offer a short illustration of it by way of reference to the genesis of the recent economic crisis.6 While I agree with MacIntyre’s claim, I cannot attempt a substantiation of it in this article. What I write does, however, presuppose the idea that the results of modern specialized education are not as happy as we would wish. I will argue that this situation is due to the fact that university curricula are not structured so as to reflect the nature of the universe. Many will no doubt find this claim to be very strange. Nevertheless, I contend that successful human agency depends on action respecting the natures of things. Attaching a pair of wings will not enable me to fly, but getting on an airplane will because those who designed and built it have respected the laws of aerodynamics. A university curriculum that prepares students to deal with the nature of reality as it is will more likely produce well-functioning citizens and a more harmonious world than a curriculum that is dictated simply by economic interest. In this regard, I contend, we have much to learn from St. Thomas Aquinas and John Henry Cardinal Newman. While I do not wish to claim here that Newman simply represents a working-out of Thomas’s thought, he, like Thomas, is an Aristotelian and his thought can be related to Thomas’s in important respects.7 With respect to the subject at hand, Newman’s educational theory can be construed as a phenomenological expression of the metaphysical foundations offered by Thomas. To state this perceived relation is not of course to argue that Newman consciously elaborates his ideas concerning university Alasdair MacIntyre, “The Very Idea of a University: Aristotle, Newman and Us,” New Blackfriars 91 (2010): 17. 6 See ibid., 17–18. 7 Thus, Newman tells us, “While we are men, we cannot help to a great extent, being Aristotelians,” and indeed, “in many subject-matters, to think correctly is to think like Aristotle”; see John Henry Cardinal Newman, The Idea of a University (New York: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1925), 109–10. 5 1216 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. education with Thomas’s metaphysical construal of reality in mind. The influence of Aristotle on both of them and a shared thirst for truth nevertheless effect a certain convergence between a view of university education derived from Thomas’s thought and the detailed reflections concerning the same topic penned by Newman. In addition to the relationship that I posit between Thomas and Newman as between metaphysical foundation and phenomenological expression, it will also become evident that Thomas’s philosophy of mind and understanding of prudence support MacIntyre’s contention that a university curriculum constructed in line with Newman’s vision would yield benefits for society that are currently not generally available. In what follows I will first of all follow Aquinas in asking about the origin and end of the universe, and of human existence in particular, for these questions confront the most basic structure of reality. In the first section, I will therefore consider his second proof for the existence of God and the notion that God is the ultimate end of human striving. Central to these considerations is the notion of the impossibility of infinite regress in causes that are essentially ordered to each other. The implications of these inquiries for the general design of university curricula will then be considered by drawing out the educational implications of various aspects of Thomas’s thought and by the light of Newman’s reflections.8 In particular, it will be argued Thomas, of course, did not apply the principles of his thought to the issue of the kind of curriculum best suited to a Catholic university. One can, however, point to the founding and governing document of Thomas Aquinas College, A Proposal for the Fulfillment of Catholic Liberal Education, for an example of what a curriculum constructed according to Thomistic educational principles might look like (last accessed August 3, 2016, http://www.thomasaquinas.edu/sites/ default/files/a-proposal-forthe-fulfillment-of-catholic-education.pdf). See especially ch. X, “The Curriculum” (49–56), whose introductory comments state that “the curriculum of this college introduces the student to a comprehensive study of theology, philosophy, mathematics, language and experimental science through reading and closely discussing the greatest scholarly works in these fields” (49). The affinity of this Thomistically constructed curriculum with Newman’s educational philosophy is striking and, I contend, bears out one of the arguments of this article; namely, that Newman’s educational theory, in effect, furnishes a phenomenological expression of the metaphysical foundations offered by Thomas. For another example of a curriculum constructed along the lines envisaged in this article, see the curriculum of Wyoming Catholic College (last accessed August 3, 2016, http://www.wyomingcatholiccollege.com/academics/curriculum/index.aspx). The weakness of A Proposal for the Fulfillment of Catholic Liberal Education 8 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1217 that an educational curriculum that reflects the structure of reality will establish those conditions that promote the moral well-being of the student and, by extension, society in general. On its own, however, such a curriculum is unlikely to be sufficient. Also required is an attendant ethos that facilitates student appropriation of the demands of the curriculum, enables them to give practical expression to them in their decision-making, and habituates them in doing so. Given the common religious orientation of both Thomas and Newman, it seems reasonable to apply the general philosophical arguments of this article to the specific context of Catholic universities. The fact that Newman has already done so provides an illustrious, widely-accepted precedent. At any rate, a philosophy of education that had no real application to a specific educational context would not be of any great value to anyone. God as the Origin and End of All that Exists Thomas begins the Second Way (Summa theologiae I, q. 2, a. 3) with an observation of empirical fact: “In the world of sense we find an order of efficient causes.”9 This incontrovertible fact is, however, not self-explanatory; it stands in need of explanation in terms of something else. Otherwise, something could be its own cause and, therefore, would precede itself, a state of affairs that is obviously impossible. Christopher Martin explains the next step of the argument as follows: “Anything which is a system of parts related by efficient causality, in which parts are effects, is itself an effect—something which cannot be the efficient cause of itself, and which requires an explanation in terms of a relation (as distinct from the college for which it seeks to offer philosophical underpinnings!) is the absence of any consideration of the role that the ethos of an institute plays in the education its students. The present article aims to offer a corrective in this regard. 9 The following discussion is based on Kevin E. O’Reilly, “Efficient and Final Causality and the Human Desire for Beatitude in the Summa Theologiae of Thomas Aquinas,” The Modern Schoolman 82 (2004): 33–58, at 34–36. The scope of the present article does not allow an extended critical account of Aquinas’s “second way.” For a more critical and speculative engagement with the “five ways” see, e.g., C. J. F Martin, Thomas Aquinas: God and Explanations (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1997); Anthony Kenny, The Five Ways (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969); Joseph Owens, St.Thomas Aquinas on the Existence of God: Collected Papers of Joseph Owens, C.Ss.R., ed. John R. Catan (New York: SUNY, 1980), 52–131; Thomas A. F. Kelly, Language, World and God: An Essay in Ontology (Dublin: Columba Press, 1996), 177–82; and Edward Feser, Aquinas: A Beginner’s Guide (Oxford, UK: Oneworld, 2010), 62–130. 1218 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. to something else.”10 Of course, the series or system of causes referred to is the universe. As a series of effects itself, considered as a single whole, it constitutes an effect. It cannot therefore constitute its own cause; rather, it must be explained in relation to something apart from itself. One cannot, however, posit an infinite series of causes and effects. Such an infinity is an impossibility. Thomas argues that the series of causes must cease at some stage. Since what is prior in such a series is the cause of what follows, if it is eliminated nothing can follow. Since an infinite regress in the series of causes would mean the elimination of the first cause, neither intermediate efficient causes nor ultimate effect would be possible, all of which is plainly false according to Aquinas.11 Positing an infinite regress in the series of causes cannot explain the fact that there are causes and effects in the world. Thomas therefore concludes that there must be a first efficient cause, to which everyone gives the name God.12 There are, of course, objections to Thomas’s rejection of the possibility of an infinite regress.13 Such criticisms seem to be grounded in a failure to distinguish between per se causes and per accidens causes, as indeed Thomas himself does elsewhere when he writes that it is impossible to proceed to infinity per se in efficient causes. Thus, “there cannot be an infinite number of causes that are per se required for a certain effect; for instance, that a stone by moved by a stick, the stick by the hand, and so on to infinity.”14 However, Thomas continues: “It is not impossible to proceed to infinity accidentally as regards efficient causes. . . . Thus it is accidental to this particular man as generator to be generated by another man; for he generates as a man, and not as the son of another man. For all men generating hold one grade in efficient causes—viz., the grade of a particular generator. Hence it is not impossible for a man to be generated by man to infinity.”15 Thomas does not therefore reject the possibility of an infinite Thomas Aquinas: God and Explanations, 152. Martin critiques the objection that there could be parts of the world outside the system of efficient causality. 11 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae (hereafter, ST) I, q. 2, a. 2. Unless otherwise noted, all quotations from ST are from Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province, 5 vols. (Allen, TX: Christian Classics, 1981). 12 Ibid. 13 See, for example, Martin Henry, On Not Understanding God (Dublin: Columba Press, 1997), 126. 14 ST I, q. 46, a. 2, ad 7. 15 Ibid. 10 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1219 regress in the case of per accidens causes such as a’s being begotten by b, b’s being begotten by c, and so forth. To proceed to infinity however in the case of a per se causal series must be ruled out as impossible. We should note once again, as Patterson Brown observes, that “it is the composite causal series, and not the individual constituent causes, which Aquinas is contrasting as either per se or per accidens in the above quotation.”16 It is imperative to understand that it is on account of being hierarchically ordered that a series of causes does not allow an infinite regress. As already noted, an infinite regress is possible in the case of per accidens causes. Thus, for example, one man can beget another, who in turn begets a third, and so on, ad infinitum. However, the question concerning what makes a man to be a man and, as such, capable of begetting another man cannot be answered by appeal to per accidens causes that are on the same level as he is. We are therefore compelled to attribute to a superior being the cause of man’s existence precisely as a man capable of begetting another man. The causal explanation of this being requires, in turn, the existence of a being superior to it. Since an infinite regress in per se causes is impossible, there must be a first term, a term that, as Gilson remarks, “will, in fact, virtually contain the causality of the whole series and also of each term composing it.”17 The notion of the impossibility of an infinite regress of causes crops up again in the course of Thomas’s treatise on beatitude (ST I-II, qq. 1–5), where the principal focus is on final causality:18 “If, in a number of causes ordained to one another, the first be removed, the others must, of necessity, be removed also.”19 Since the final cause or end constitutes the first of all causes, if it were removed, the exercise of efficient causality would be annulled. As Thomas delineates the point: “If the agent were not determinate to some particular effect, it would not do one thing rather than another: consequently in order that it produce a determinate effect, it must, of necessity, be Patterson Brown, “Infinite Causal Regression,” in Anthony Kenny, ed., Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Anthony Kenny (London: Macmillan, 1969), 217. 17 Étienne Gilson, The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. Edward Bullough (Cambridge, UK: W. Heffer and Sons, 1924), 63. 18 The following discussion is based on Kevin E. O’Reilly, “Efficient and Final Causality and the Human Desire for Beatitude in the Summa Theologiae of Thomas Aquinas,” The Modern Schoolman. 19 ST I-II, q. 1, a. 2. 16 1220 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. determined to some certain one, which has the nature of an end.”20 In contrast to other beings that achieve their ends on the basis of an innate natural appetite, human beings determine their own ends by virtue of the will/rational appetite. Thomas’s consideration of whether human life is ordered towards an ultimate goal (ST I-II, q. 1, a. 4) occasions further reflections on causality. Once again, he rules out the possibility of an infinite regress in a system of efficient causes, since “then there would be no first mover, without which neither can the others move, since they move only through being moved by the first mover.”21 He applies this logic to the case of final causality in relation to the intention of the agent: if what originally moves desire were taken away, desire itself would not be moved. As Thomas explains: “The principle in the intention is the last end; while the principle in execution is the first of the things which are ordained to the end.”22 As in the case of efficient causes, infinite regress is impossible in the case of final causes. Indeed, in the absence of an ultimate end, deliberation would never cease and no action would ever be accomplished.23 Such a state of affairs clearly does not obtain. While Thomas invokes notions of causality many more times throughout his treatise on beatitude, it would be redundant for the sake of the present argument to outline these occurrences. In brief, we can say that Thomas appeals to the notion of the impossibility of infinite regress with regard to both efficient and final causality in order to establish the existence of God both as the efficient cause of all that exists and the final cause of all that exists. As such, God is the ultimate object of both intellect and will. Thomas’s proofs for the existence of God and his reflections on God as the final end of human striving, moreover, support the contention that the human intellect and will possess a potentially infinite capacity despite the contingency of our finite and created condition: “The object of the will, i.e. of man’s appetite, is the universal good; just as the object of the intellect is the universal true.”24 God has inscribed within the human soul a Ibid. ST I-II, q. 1, a. 4. 22 Ibid. 23 Thomas is here concerned with things that possess an essential order of dependence. In this case of accidental causes, an infinity of proximate ends and of steps leading to a particular end would be possible. See also ST I, q. 46, a. 2, ad 7. 24 ST I-II, q. 2, a. 8. 20 21 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1221 structure according to which it is intrinsically ordered to the pursuit of Truth and Goodness. Our existential situation in the created ontological space between God as First Efficient Cause and God as Final Cause furnishes the context in which the life of mind unfolds. With these considerations in place we now turn to a consideration of the educational implications of God as both First Efficient Cause and Final End of the universe. If one understands the task of education to be at least in part to acquaint students with the truth of things and to facilitate and direct them in their desire for human fulfillment, then the existential fact of humans being situated between God as First Efficient Cause of all that exists and God as the Final End of all that exists provides the overarching context within which education must unfold. Any approach to education that ignores or attempts to jettison the reality of this existential situation distorts the nature of education and, in so doing, undermines the efforts of students in their search for authentic happiness in this life. The investigation of the universe in its manifold aspects constitutes an examination of the effects of the First Cause. All these effects tell us something about their Creator. Newman understands the relationship of the universe to God as its creative cause in a similar way. Thus, as he puts it, while God’s being is infinitely separate from the universe, he has nevertheless “so implicated Himself with it, and taken it into His very bosom, by His presence in it, His providence over it, His impressions upon it, and His influences through it, that we cannot truly or fully contemplate it without in some main aspects contemplating Him.”25 The next section delineates Newman’s thought concerning the implications of this metaphysical position for the construction of the university curriculum. In brief, the curriculum ought to enlarge the intellectual horizons of students so that they can appreciate the interrelatedness of the manifold aspects of the universe in the light of their creative cause—God. Failure in this regard by cultivating early specialization by students will likely prevent the mind from attaining its specific perfection and entail undesirable consequences for society at large, as we have already suggested. Appeal to Thomas’s distinction between the speculative and practical intellect provides a theoretical grounding for this contention. Newman, The Idea of a University, 51. 25 1222 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. God and the Construction of the University Curriculum As proceeding from the Creator as their unique ultimate cause, all parts of the universe are interrelated. Newman expresses this idea when he concludes that all knowledge forms a whole, since “the universe in its length and breadth is so intimately knit together, that we cannot separate off portion from portion, and operation from operation, except by a mental abstraction.”26 With regard to the various sciences, Newman argues that they furnish “a logical record of this or that aspect of the whole subject-matter of knowledge.”27 He continues: “As they all belong to one and the same circle of objects, they are one and all connected together; as they are but aspects of things, they are severally incomplete in their relation to the things themselves, though complete in their own idea and for their own respective purposes; on both accounts they at once need and subserve each other.”28 MacIntyre makes the same point: “It is only through the relationships of the different parts of and aspects of the universe to God that its unity and intelligibility can adequately be grasped.”29 The unity and intelligibility of the universe with the interrelatedness of its parts has profound significance for educational philosophy, a significance that Newman astutely observes and expounds on at great length. In brief, as Avery Dulles states the point, Newman “argues primarily from the nature of the university as a seat of universal learning and from the interconnectedness of all truth.”30 Displaying a breathtaking breadth of knowledge of many disciplines as well as depth of reflection thereupon, Newman adumbrates the ways in which disciplines “complete, correct, balance each other.”31 Thus, he argues, “the conclusions of Anatomy, Chemistry, Dynamics, and other sciences, are revised and completed by each other.” He contin Ibid., 50. Ibid., 51. 28 Ibid. 29 MacIntyre, God, Philosophy, Universities, 175. 30 Avery Cardinal Dulles, S.J., Newman (London and New York: Continuum, 2002), 138. 31 Newman, The Idea of a University, 99. The section from which this quotation is taken, Discourse III.3, contains various other examples. Thus, for instance, Newman argues: “Did we proceed upon the abstract theory of forces, we should assign a much more ample range to a projectile than in fact the resistance of the air allows it to accomplish. Let, however, that resistance be made the subject of scientific analysis, and then we shall have a new science, assisting, and to a certain point completing, for the benefit of questions of fact, the science of projection” (ibid., 49). 26 27 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1223 ues in the same place: “Those several conclusions do not represent whole and substantive things, but views, true, so far as they go; and in order to ascertain how far they do go, that is, how far they correspond to the object to which they belong, we must compare them with the views taken out of that object by other sciences.”32 In “The Idea of a University,” Michael Oakeshott expresses this point in the following words: “The pursuit of learning . . . is a conversation. And the peculiar virtue of a university (as a place of many studies) is to exhibit it in this character, each study appearing as a voice whose tone is neither tyrannous nor plangent, but humble and conversable.”33 Logical consistency demands that one not limit the university curriculum of studies in the manner that is all too common nowadays in excluding religion. Newman appeals to our appreciation of the fact that knowledge assumes various forms. Different forms of knowledge are distinguished from each other on the basis of their appeal to sensory evidence, intuition, testimony, abstract reasoning, and so on. If, therefore, we were to limit our idea of university knowledge to that furnished by the evidence of our senses, for example, then ethics would have to be jettisoned; if intuition were our sole benchmark for authentic knowledge, then there would be no place for history; if testimony were the exclusive requirement for true knowledge, then metaphysics would not be entertained; and if abstract reasoning were the only measure of knowledge properly speaking, then physics would have to be omitted. No serious educationalist would entertain any of these possibilities, and so they should be deterred by the force of Newman’s argumentation from displacing religion from the university curriculum. This argumentation is couched in the form of a rhetorical question: “Is not the being of a God reported to us by testimony, handed down by history, inferred by an inductive process, brought home to us by metaphysical necessity, urged on us by the suggestions of our conscience?”34 Further on, he appeals to the idea that we have already outlined, namely that positing the existence of God has ramifications for the way in which the curriculum is constituted: “Admit a God, and you introduce among the subjects of your knowledge, a fact encompassing, closing in upon, absorbing, every other fact conceivable. How can we investigate any part of any order of Knowledge, and stop short of that which enters into every order? Ibid., 49. The Voice of Liberal Learning, 98. 34 Newman, The Idea of a University, 25. 32 33 1224 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. All true principles run over with it, all phenomena converge to it; it is truly the First and the Last.”35 Instantiated in a Catholic university context, religion naturally takes on the form of Catholic theology. If one accepts the Catholic faith as true, Newman’s logic demands that one subscribe to Catholic theology as an integral part of the university curriculum. A Catholic university “cannot teach Universal Knowledge if it does not teach Catholic theology.”36 It must be emphasized that this point, while it bears upon the teaching of revealed religion, is nonetheless philosophical in its import. The Catholic faith to which the university subscribes provides, as it were, the matter that is informed by the idea that religion should be accorded recognition in the university curriculum. Omission of any one subject in one’s educational trajectory is bound to affect the completeness of our knowledge in a way that is proportionate to the subject’s importance. In this view, a specialized range of studies does not result in an ability to survey reality with a sense of balance and make connections between its constituent parts. The breadth of vision that is the hallmark of an enlarged mind is lacking: “That only is true enlargement of mind which is the power of viewing many things at once as one whole, of referring them severally to their true place in the universal system, of understanding their respective values, and determining their mutual dependence.”37 The pursuit of intellectual excellence so that the mind will advance ever more and more to a vision of the height, depth, and breadth of the universe in the vastness of its expanse is what constitutes the essence of a liberal education. In contrast, as MacIntyre puts it, “to develop highly specialized knowledge only in one particular sphere, to focus one’s mind on only one subject-matter, may certainly be valuable, but it will not enable the mind to achieve its specific perfection and is apt to prevent the mind from doing so.”38 Indeed, when one discipline asserts its authority in an absolute way, it becomes an error.39 In this Ibid., 26. Ibid., 214. 37 Ibid., 136–37. 38 MacIntyre, “The Very Idea of a University,” 10. 39 See Newman, The Idea of a University, 74: “No science whatever, however comprehensive it may be, but will fall largely into error, if it be constituted the sole exponent of all things in heaven and earth, and that, for the simple reason that it is encroaching on territory not its own, and undertaking problems which it has no instruments to solve.” Angelo Bottone writes that, “According to Newman, all our knowledge must fit into a framework of connections and 35 36 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1225 situation the mind is prevented from attaining its specific perfection. Exclusive attention to one discipline will not only hinder the mind from attaining its specific perfection; it will, according to MacIntyre, also bring about undesirable results in society. In other words, speculative engagement with ideas does have its effects in the practical domain. Speculative engagement that does not reflect the true constitution of things will produce disastrous consequences. If MacIntyre is correct—and I suspect he is—we encounter here some kind of evidential support for Aquinas’s assertion that the practical intellect is an extension of the speculative intellect.40 By the same token, Aquinas’s doctrine provides a theoretical underpinning for MacIntyre’s position. According to Thomas, the practical reason presupposes the theoretical and is rooted in it. In effect, practical reason translates what is perceived by speculative reason into action. Obviously, therefore, this reality furnishes the measure of human action: since reality is the measure of reason in its speculative mode of activity and practical reason is grounded in and is an extension of speculative reason, it follows that reality is also the measure of practical reason and action. Practical reason is the measure of right action precisely because it has received this measure from objective reality by way of the speculative intellect, of which it (practical reason) is an extension. However, insofar as the speculative intellect is rendered deficient on account of too narrow and specialized a training, so too will practical reason be undermined in its efforts to effect actions that conduce to the true flourishing both of individuals and of society—on the presupposition that acting in accord with human nature and with the structure of reality in general conduces best to the attainment of human happiness, both of this life and of the next.41 It seems clear that human perception of reality is action guiding. An announcement that a bomb will definitely explode in ten minutes in the building that I and many others currently occupy, even withrelations by and through which they gain sense”; see The Philosophical Habit of Mind: Rhetoric and Person in John Henry Newman’s Dublin Writings (Bucharest, RO: Zeta Books), 28–29. 40 ST I, q. 79, a. 11, sc. 41 This presupposition finds expression in the following words of Goethe: “In our doing and acting everything depends on this, that we comprehend objects clearly and treat them according to their nature”; quoted in Josef Pieper, Living the Truth, trans. Lothar Krauth and Stella Lange (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1989), 108. 1226 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. out any request for people to evacuate the building, would doubtless lead to a complete exodus. The nature of the reality of an imminent bomb explosion translates into the action of leaving the building in pursuit of safety. Indeed, the constitution of reality as we perceive it informs our every action. However, the notion of “perception” is crucial, for this can be affected for good or bad in many instances by any number of factors. In this context, we are concerned with the way in which education can enhance or undermine it. In this regard, it seems clear that a purely specialized educational trajectory serves to distort one’s view of the overall shape of reality. Practical reasoning based on this kind of education, since it will fail to meet the criteria for success demanded by reality itself, will run the risk of failure, if not disaster, for the individual and/or society at large. Appeal to God’s efficient causality thus affords the rationale for an educational curriculum that is not overly specialized at too early a stage in the intellectual development of students. Human practical reasoning processes, however, are not mechanical: particular inputs do not necessarily result in predetermined outputs. Practical reasoning is, in fact, rendered highly complex and influenced for good or for bad by appetite, as we will see. Since the human appetite ultimately desires final beatitude with God as its Final End, a consideration of the educational implications of God as the Final End of human striving is in order. We now turn our attention, therefore, to Thomas’s consideration of the virtue of prudence, a consideration that necessarily makes reference to the notion of “right appetite.”42 Since prudence enables one to order appropriately the various goods of human existence in the light of the final end of beatitude, the cultivation of conditions that conduce to its proper development in the lives of students is of paramount importance in an educational curriculum that seeks to prepare them for life. This point, as was noted at the outset, all too often goes unappreciated in contemporary educational establishments and therefore merits an extended treatment in order to establish it firmly. A treatment of prudence, which is an intellectual virtue, also involves an account of its relationship to the other moral virtues. The implications of Thomas’s understanding of the relationship between prudence and the moral virtues for the educational enterprise are clear: any educational endeavor has moral implications on account of the intellectual nature of prudence and its unifying function with respect to the intellectual and moral virtues. ST II-II, q. 47, a. 4. 42 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1227 The Cultivation of Prudence In talking about that perception of reality that guides one’s conduct, we are clearly in the realm of Thomas’s understanding of prudentia. In this regard, appetite is crucial—or rather “right appetite”—for as Thomas argues, “it belongs to prudence . . . to apply right reason to action, and this is not done without a right appetite.”43 An analogy between speculative and practical reason is illuminating once we understand that the ends to which we are disposed furnish the principles from which practical reason takes its point of departure in its deliberations. Just as we are rightly disposed to the principles of speculative truth (such as the principle of contradiction) by the natural light of the active intellect, so too we are rightly disposed to the principles of the reason of things to be done by the rectitude of the will.44 In other words, the principles of the reason of things to be done are determined by the constitution of a person’s will. For, a person’s affective responses either facilitate or impede his prudential reasoning, determining to what degree the latter is in conformity with truth. This dynamic obtains regardless of which species of prudence is in question: what is directed to one’s own good (prudence simply so called), what is directed to the common good of the home (domestic prudence), or what is directed to the common good of the state or kingdom (political prudence).45 It is true that, while the other intellectual virtues can be possessed without moral virtue, prudence (the right reason about things to be done) “requires man to have moral virtue.”46 If this were all, however, we would have to agree with the idea that even the best liberal arts education cannot avoid producing intellectually brilliant and socially refined “gentlemen” who are nonetheless scoundrels. There is, however, significantly more to Aquinas’s conception of the relationship obtaining between prudence and the other moral virtues, for moral virtue has the character of virtue insofar as it partakes of reason. In other words, “moral virtue has the aspect of virtue, in so far as it partakes of intellectual virtue,”47—that is to say, insofar as Ibid. ST I-II, q. 56, a. 3. 45 ST II-II, q. 47, a. 11.Thomas’s assertion that there are three species of prudence points to his understanding that our knowledge of human nature and of what contributes to its flourishing is acquired on both an individual plane and a communal plane, a point to which contemporary educational practice might do well to pay attention. 46 ST I-II, q. 58, a. 5. 47 ST II-II, q. 47, a. 5, ad 1. 43 44 1228 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. it partakes of prudence. Thomas compares prudence to a genus that is operative in every species that falls under it.48 The relationship between prudence and the other moral virtues is one of dynamic reciprocity. As Josef Pieper puts it, “prudence, upon which all virtue depends, is in its turn dependent at its very fundaments on the totality of the other virtues, and above all the virtue of justice.”49 While the relationship of dynamic reciprocity between prudence and the moral virtues complicates matters immensely, it nonetheless remains clear that education conceived along Thomistic lines cannot be devoid of moral implications on account of the intellectual nature of prudence and its role in unifying the intellectual and moral virtues. As Reinhard Hütter explains, “since prudence is an intellectual virtue, its formation and refinement fall under the competency of a liberal arts education along Thomistic lines,”50 and this formation and refinement will in turn spread their influence among the moral virtues, “even as the sun has an influence over all bodies.”51 Education need not limit itself—indeed, it ought not to limit itself—to cultivating the intellectual virtues while completely ignoring the moral virtues. Attention to the moral virtues, if it is to have any existential import, cannot of course be constrained to explanations in lectures and books. It is indeed unlikely that such an approach would yield much, if any, success on its own. There is, however, the question of the ethos of a university and the manner in which this ethos is cultivated and brought to realization in the student body. The ethos of any human institution will reflect its apprehension of the meaning and value of human existence. In the case of a university, this ethos will have some degree of influence on students that is in some way related to their free choice to submit themselves to its formative influences. One fundamental formative influence is the way in which the curriculum is constructed. Thus, for example, the message proclaimed by a dedicated business college whose sole focus consists in turning out graduates who earn huge sums of money is likely to forge different qualities in many of its students than a liberal arts college whose aim is to form individuals who can savor the value of ST II-II, q. 47, a. 5, ad 2. Joseph Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1966), 15. 50 Reinhard Hütter, “God, the University, and the Missing Link—Wisdom: Reflections on Two Untimely Books,” The Thomist 73 (2009): 271. 51 ST II-II, q. 47, a. 5, ad 2. 48 49 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1229 all things because they have the breadth and depth of vision afforded precisely by this kind of education. In a specifically Catholic context, a code of moral conduct that is in accord with Catholic moral teaching serves to facilitate the practical expression of what is learned in the lecture hall and hopefully to habituate students to the living out of this teaching in their lives, lives that will ultimately make some impact on the wider society, however small that impact might be. Other elements that contribute to a distinctively Catholic ethos include the cultivation both of a sense of the importance of personal prayer and of a vibrant sacramental life. Again, these elements assist in imparting an experience and vision of the world that is at least implicitly communicated through the curriculum. To return to a fundamental thrust of our argument, however, the ability to appreciate and savor the true value of things is closely bound up not only with recognizing their interrelatedness on account of being effects of God as First Efficient Cause of all that exists but also with acknowledging their ordering towards God as the Final End of all that exists. For moral beings possessed of free will, the unity and intelligibility of the universe resides not only in the creative efficient causality of God but also in his final causation. In a Christian context, the manner in which we move toward God as our Final Cause receives a particular character in view of the teaching and example of Jesus Christ and the transmission of this teaching in the Church’s Tradition. As we return to the source whence we have come, the possession of free will means that we have the possibility of choosing among competing proximate goods or ends as we pursue the unfolding of our particular conceptions of what constitutes the good life. A tragic aspect of human experience is, however, the real possibility of being mistaken about what conduces to one’s objective flourishing or, indeed, of not being mistaken but nonetheless opting for some course of action that, on account of its disordered nature, deflects one’s trajectory towards God.52 As Thomas maintains, there are some finite goods that contain within them the capacity to deflect our attention from our Final End. Let us not be mistaken: wealth, power, fame, and so on are not bad things. They are goods. Wealth, in particular, This kind of action, in Thomas’s scheme of things, is nevertheless chosen under the rubric of the good. In other words, while the agent recognizes its objectively disordered nature, there is something in it that he finds attractive, something that will, in some respect, fulfill him. Anything we choose, we choose under the aspect of the good. 52 1230 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. when pursued appropriately, furnishes us with the one condition for the attainment of the relative happiness of this life and of the good of ultimate happiness to which all true goods in this life are ordered. To pursue any finite good as an end in itself, however, deflects one from the path that leads to the ultimate realization of one’s being in eternal beatitude. Such a pursuit also undermines the operation of true and perfect prudence that requires right appetite concerning the true end of human action.53 Thomas, in discussing whether prudence can be in sinners, distinguishes three kinds of prudence: false prudence, true prudence, and prudence that is true and perfect. The rationale for this division is based on the fact that the operation of prudence takes its starting point from the ends pursued by the moral agent. A prudent man is one who disposes well of those things that need to be done in order to attain a good end. False prudence entails disposing of such things in view of an evil end, an end that “is good, not in truth but in appearance.”54 True prudence is indeed concerned with an end good in itself, yet it is imperfect from a twofold source: “First, because the good which it takes for an end, is not the common end of all human life but of some particular affair; thus when a man devises fitting ways of conducting business or of sailing a ship, he is called a prudent business-man, or a prudent sailor. Secondly, because he fails in the chief act of prudence . . . [which is] to make an effective command.”55 True and perfect prudence, in contrast to the foregoing, “takes counsel, judges and commands aright in respect of the good end of man’s whole life.”56 It is only in the light of the ultimate end of human life that other more proximate ends can be ordered and appropriate means proportioned to those ends pursued—which ultimate end Thomas, like Newman, views in the light of Christian revelation. An educational curriculum that purports to prepare students for life cannot be true to its aim unless it is constructed in such a way as to reflect the structure of the universe in terms of its ultimate origin By “the true end of human action” I mean the end whose attainment conduces to objective human flourishing/happiness. As such, this end is ordered towards ultimate happiness or beatitude—that is to say, the vision of God in eternity. 54 ST II-II, q. 47, a. 13. Thus, continues Thomas, “a man is called a good robber, and in this way we may speak of a prudent robber, by way of similarity, because he devises fitting ways of committing robbery” (ibid.). 55 Ibid. (punctuation amended). On command as the chief act of prudence, see ST II-II, q. 47, a. 8. 56 ST II-II, q. 47, a. 13. 53 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1231 and end. In the case of a Catholic university, this aim receives further specification in the light of Christian revelation in keeping with the notion that grace perfects nature. Thus, Newman’s claims for the role of theology in the university certainly stand vindicated when viewed in a Thomistic light.57 If the educational curriculum is to be faithful to the structure of reality, it must grant to theology an overarching ordering role. As MacIntyre puts it in a discussion about Newman, “if the curriculum is to have the unity that it needs to have, if it is to disclose the unity of the order of things, then the discipline of theology is indispensable.” He continues: “For it is theology that provides the curriculum with its unity and we will not understand the bearing of the other disciplines on each other adequately, if we do not understand theology’s bearing on them and theirs on theology.”58 The next section of my present discussion turns to an examination of ethical considerations by Newman—a treatment analogous to the one we have just set forth—in order to show forth what ultimately results in a vision of university education that converges with a Thomistic account of the same. Contrary to a misunderstanding of Newman as envisaging education to be concerned merely with the formation of intellectual virtue and not moral virtue, he does in fact recognize the intimate connection between intellectual and moral formation and appreciates how the perfection or otherwise of the intellectual virtues has a bearing on the moral tenor of society in general. He is also aware of the distortions that inevitably attend a purely secular ethics and, therefore, of the need for faith—and hence for ecclesial jurisdiction over a Catholic university. This contention seems to be in line with the insights afforded by hermeneutical philosophy concerning the various factors that condition human knowledge, with the important caveat that Newman would regard faith as a criterion—indeed, the criterion—that secures the moorings of epistemic objectivity.59 Again, it must be emphasized that the vindication offered here is philosophical in nature, even though it bears on the place of theology in the university curriculum. 58 MacIntyre, “The Very Idea of a University,” 12. 59 For an engagement of Thomas’s thought with contemporary hermeneutical philosophy, see Kevin E. O’Reilly, “Transcending Gadamer: Towards a Participatory Hermeneutics,” The Review of Metaphysics 65 (September 2011–June 2012), 841–60. For a specifically theological treatment of Thomas’s thought with contemporary hermeneutical thought, see O’Reilly, The Hermeneutics of Knowing and Willing in the Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Leuven, BE: Peeters, 57 1232 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. The Practical Link between Knowledge and Religious Morality A superficial and incomplete reading of Newman’s The Idea of a University can easily make the mistake of discerning a subtle, but nonetheless very important, point of difference between educational philosophy as conceived by Newman, on the one hand, and a Thomistically conceived educational philosophy, on the other hand. Central to this erroneous interpretation is the following passage in which Newman writes, “Knowledge is one thing, virtue is another; good sense is not conscience, refinement is not humility, nor is largeness and justness of view faith. Philosophy, however enlightened, however profound, gives no command over the passions, no influential motives, no vivifying principles. Liberal education makes not the Christian, nor the Catholic, but the gentleman. . . . Liberal Education, viewed in itself, is simply the cultivation of the intellect, as such, and its object is nothing more or less than intellectual excellence.”60 If this is read in isolation from the broader context of Newman’s educational thought, it might seem that, for Newman, a university education concentrates on the formation of those intellectual virtues that perfect the intellect in its consideration of truth but can lay no claim to the cultivation of virtue. Newman goes on in “Discourse VIII” of the work, however, to argue that the intellectual culture in society exerts an influence upon our moral nature and “all upon the type of Christianity.”61 He lists a number of virtues that are the fruit of an intellectual culture—“veracity, probity, equity, fairness, gentleness, benevolence, and amiableness”62—albeit allowing that this culture requires “a soil naturally adapted to virtue”63 for these character traits to develop. In a striking turn of phrase, Newman writes: “It is enough to refer you, Gentlemen, to the various Biographies and Remains of contemporaries and others, which from time to time issue from the press, to see how striking is the action of our intellectual upon our moral nature, where the moral material is rich, and the intellectual cast is perfect.”64 Newman also recognizes that the cultivation of the intellect affects 2013). For a treatment of the hermeneutical dynamics of Newman’s religious thought, see Thomas K. Carr, Newman and Carr: Towards a Hermeneutics of Religious Knowledge (Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press, 1996). 60 Newman, The Idea of a University, 91–92. 61 Ibid., 189. 62 Ibid. 63 Ibid., 190. 64 Ibid. God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1233 not only the individual but society as well.65 In this regard, it is to be noted, as Angelo Bottone remarks, that “the intellectual recreations that are present in modern cities may lead to an advancement of the social ethical tone.”66 At the same time, however, Newman proves to be acutely aware of the distortions that inevitably attend an approach to ethics that prescinds from religion. The intellectualism that underpins it may well begin by repelling sensuality, but in fact “ends by excusing it.”67 Reason in fact needs faith if the morality that it inspires is not to go astray. As Newman puts it: “Under the shadow indeed of the Church, and in its due development, Philosophy does service to the cause of morality.”68 In contrast, when reason asserts its independence of faith, any system of ethics that it formulates and the moral education that it imparts “does but abet evils to which at first it seemed instinctively opposed.”69 Thus, while a university is, in essence, a place in which universal knowledge is imparted, so that its object is necessarily intellectual and not moral, it nevertheless cannot fulfil this end properly without the Church’s assistance. As Bottone explicates, while Newman “has stated his belief in the theoretical autonomy of knowledge from religious morality, he maintains that a practical link exists between the two.” 70 We have, in fact, two modes of access to the moral law that has its source in God. The first is by way of conscience that is inscribed within our nature, enabling us to discriminate right from wrong. The second is afforded to us by way of divine revelation that enlightens, strengthens, and refines. Thus, Newman contends: “Nature warrants without anticipating the Supernatural, and the Supernatural completes without superseding Nature.” 71 As Bottone See ibid., 189: “Cheap literature, libraries of useful and entertaining knowledge, scientific lectureships, museums, zoological collections, buildings and gardens to please the eye and to give repose to the feelings, external objects of whatever kind, which may take the mind off itself, and expand and elevate it in liberal contemplations, these are the human means, wisely suggested, and good as far as they go, for at least parrying the assaults of moral evil, and keeping at bay the enemies, not only of the individual soul, but of society at large.” 66 Bottone, The Philosophical Habit of Mind, 192. 67 Newman, The Idea of a University, 202. 68 Ibid. 69 Ibid. 70 Bottone, The Philosophical Habit of Mind, 193. 71 John Henry Newman, Rise and Progress of Universities, vol. 3 of Historical Sketches (London / New York: Longman, Green and Co., 1909), 79; also avail65 1234 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. comments concerning these two modes of access to the moral law: “They are interactive, recognising and bearing witness to each other.” 72 Hence Newman’s conviction that the Church necessarily ought to have an active jurisdiction over the university—otherwise there is the danger that has all too often been realized in practice since Newman’s time that the university becomes “the representative of the intellect, as the Church is the representative of the religious principle.” 73 In other words, a divorce between faith and reason ensues—to the detriment of both. As a result of this divorce, not only is natural reason and its expression in moral conduct adversely affected, but so also is the understanding of the faith. In brief, a university that operates on the basis of a divorce between faith and reason has a tendency “to view Revealed Religion from an aspect of its own,—to fuse and recast it, to tune it, as it were, to a different key, and to reset its harmonies,—to circumscribe it by a circle which unwarrantably amputates here, and unduly develops there.” 74 In this regard it is not sufficient even that “the whole of Catholic theology” should be taught in a university “unless the Church breathes her own pure and unearthly spirit into it, and fashions and moulds its organization, and watches over its teaching, and knits together its pupils, and superintends its action.”75 The contention that the Church should exercise jurisdiction over a Catholic university may be regarded, as Ian Ker points out, “as hardly more than a specific application of the general principle that a university is inevitably limited and defined by its concept of what constitutes knowledge and truth.” 76 Consequently, Newman’s insistence on ecclesial control ought not to be construed as being in any way sinister. He certainly does not envisage the university as being a mere instrument of the Church.77 His insistence on ecclesial authorable at http://www.newmanreader.org/works/historical/volume3/universities/chapter7.html (last accessed August 3, 2016). 72 Bottone, The Philosophical Habit of Mind, 194. 73 Newman, The Idea of a University, 215. 74 Ibid., 217. 75 Ibid., 216. 76 Ian Ker, John Henry Newman (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988), 389. 77 See Newman, The Idea of a University, ix: “The view taken of a University in these Discourses is the following:That it is a place of teaching universal knowledge. This implies that its object is, on the one hand, intellectual, not moral; and, on the other, that it is the diffusion and extension of knowledge rather God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1235 ity simply serves to remind us that “a university must teach all the knowledge it professes to teach—in accordance with its idea of what constitutes knowledge—unequivocally and without compromise.”78 Thus, while Newman’s position might seem at first sight to be simply theological, further reflection reveals its theological elements to be perfections of a basic philosophical stance with regard to knowledge and truth. It is arguably an instance of grace perfecting nature. Nature—in this case, university education—still remains, however; it is in no way annulled. Newman, in his University Sketches, indicates how he construes the practical structures of a university that would function according to his ideals. There it is clear that the university constituted according to his vision is structured in a collegiate manner. The various colleges within the framework of the university concern themselves with “the than the advancement. If its object were scientific and philosophical discovery, I do not see why a University should have students; if religious training, I do not see how it can be the seat of literature and science. Such is a University in its essence, and independently of its relation to the Church. But, practically speaking, it cannot fulfil its object duly, such as I have described it, without the Church’s assistance; or, to use the theological term, the Church is necessary for its integrity. Not that its main characters are changed by this incorporation: it still has the office of intellectual education; but the Church steadies it in the performance of that office.” See also Dulles, Newman, 141: “For Newman the university is not a mere instrument of the Church. It requires a measure of autonomy because it has its own proper end, distinct from that of the Church. Its specific aim is not the salvation of souls but higher education.” Further on, Dulles comments that the university “exercises sovereignty over the various disciplines, maps out their respective territories, and adjudicates disputes among them. But the sovereignty of the university, in Newman’s view is limited. Insofar as grace and revelation are superior to nature and reason, the Church, which is sovereign in speaking about these higher realms, has a certain authority over the Catholic university. The infallible pronouncements of the Church must be accepted without question” (ibid.). 78 Ker, John Henry Newman, 389. Elsewhere, Ker writes that Newman likens the Church and the university “to political organisms, where the many individuals are brought into unity, not uniformity, and where the conflict of the various parts ensures and enhances their own vitality. Both paradoxically bring peace and harmony out of the very rivalry which they encourage, by fostering ‘Private Judgment’ in the one case, and the different branches of knowledge in the other. Both preserve and promote freedom of thought not in spite of but by virtue of the authority which each exercises in defence of the whole circle of truth against individual aberrations and excesses”; see his “Editor’s Introduction,” in John Henry Newman, The Idea of a University, ed. Ian Ker (Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1976), lxxv. 1236 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. formation of character, intellectual and moral”79 among other things. Newman does not conceive a university without colleges or colleges standing alone as sufficient for the educational task as he understands it. Either the university or the college on its own would be “insufficient in itself for the pursuit, extension, and inculcation of knowledge.”80 The ideal would seem to be “a University, seated and living in Colleges, as possessing excellences of opposite kinds.”81 In My Campaign in Ireland, moreover, Newman indicates his appreciation of the role that an ethos of faith and devotion plays in the educational endeavor. Thus, he emphasizes the role of the university church and university preacher: “I cannot well exaggerate the influence, which John Henry Newman, University Sketches, ed. Michael Tierney (London / Newcastle-on-Tyne, UK: Walter Scott Publishing, 1903), 222. In this regard, Melanie M. Morey and John M. Piderit, S.J., point out that “The self-perpetuating and formative collegiate culture Newman describes has its modern parallels in residence halls in Catholic colleges and universities”; see Catholic Higher Education: A Culture in Crisis (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2006), 143. Morey and Piderit then proceed to echo concerns surrounding the health of these halls: “Senior administrators would acknowledge . . . that in many instances, modern residence hall living is a far cry from the positive reinforcement Newman describes. What appears to prevail in many residence halls is a shadow culture that is antithetical to Catholic teachings” (ibid.). Morey and Piderit consider two manifestations of this shadow culture: substance abuse (ibid., 145–46) and sexual intimacy (ibid., 146–48). As distinctive features of the wider culture in the contemporary Western world, neither would have posed the same difficulties for a Catholic university intent on maintaining its distinctive ethos in the time of Newman as they do for Catholic universities in our own time. Morey and Piderit conclude the section on substance abuse with the a Newmanian injunction: “The rules of a Catholic university should reflect the moral teachings of the Church, and the formation programs should invite students to understand the wisdom of these teachings” (ibid., 146). In concluding their discussion of sexual intimacy, they write: “Clearly, a Catholic university should act against . . . abuses, both to educate students about the teachings of the Church concerning intimacy and to uphold those teachings. . . .The Catholic university educates the whole person, and an important part of that educational mission involves helping students understand and appreciate relational justice, what constitutes appropriate limits and boundaries in relationships, the true meaning of relational intimacy and friendship, and the importance of lifelong commitment as the context for loving sexual expressions between man and women. When students disregard these norms, university authorities should act to support the Catholic culture” (ibid., 148). 80 Ibid., 221. 81 Ibid. 79 God, the University, and Human Flourishing 1237 a series of able preachers, distinguished by their station and their zeal, will exert upon the young men entering into life, externs and interns, and the students of various professions, who will constitute the mass of University residents.”82 He continues by stating that this institution “will force the University upon public notice, and raise it in public estimation by the presence of the most sacred of all schools, the school of faith and devotion.”83 As David Fleischacker comments: “[B]ecause of the close unity of culture and the university, university church and preacher are a profound center in which spiritual realities are illuminated in the context of faith and reason, and then brought forth into the horizon of a culture.”84 Conclusion If the argument I have put forward is correct, a Thomistic construal of the university educational enterprise will naturally flower in the manner envisaged by Newman, and his vision of university education presupposes a metaphysical vision that is essentially Thomistic. The Thomistic and Newmanian elements of the educational enterprise are related as foundation and phenomenon respectively. There can, however, be absolutely no guarantee that any curriculum that is predicated on a Thomistic understanding of prudence and construed along the lines proposed by Newman will produce virtuous citizens who will seek the good both of their society and of the whole world in the light of humankind’s ultimate destiny. It has certainly not been my intention to make such an untenable claim here. Recognition of the connection between the intellectual and moral virtues by way of prudence does, however, entail the necessity of putting into place in the curriculum components that will, if appropriated, conduce to the fulfillment of those conditions that are necessary for the true flourishing of students and, by extension, of society at large, as well as cultivating an ethos hospitable to the realization of these conditions in the lives of students. Most fundamental among all these conditions is the recognition of God as the First Efficient Cause of all that exists and God as the Final End to which all being tends. These conditions may well not be actualized in actual practice, but they will always remain at least John Henry Cardinal Newman, My Campaign in Ireland, part I: Catholic University Reports and Other Papers (Aberdeen, UK: A. King and Co., 1896), 24. 83 Ibid. 84 David Fleischacker, “The Place of Modern Scientific Research in the University According to John Henry Newman,” Logos 15 (2012): 110. 82 1238 Kevin O’Reilly, O.P. in potency to actualization. While these conditions may well not be actualized in practice, the cultivation of an appropriate ethos in the manner envisaged by Newman can be rightly considered an important—indeed, indispensable—facilitating factor. The absence of those curricular components that promote the conditions that are indispensable for that attainment of true human happiness simply means that they can never be translated into action and that the enterprises of individual lives, as well as that of the common good, will inevitably go astray, and perhaps badly so. The absence of an appropriate ethos inevitably vitiates the realization of the fruits that a well-structured curriculum is designed to cultivate. When both the suitable curricular conditions and appropriate ethos are in place, the seeds of hope for the future are sown, seeds that will likely bear some kind of fruit. Indeed, given the powerful influence that the university exerts on the shaping of society at large, a curriculum constructed according to the vision of reality espoused in this article (a vision that is shared in common by Aquinas and Newman, albeit articulated by them in quite different ways) and an ethos proportioned to the demands of the curricular structure and content (as implicitly contained in the principles of Thomas’s thought and as delineated by Newman) can only serve to safeguard and to N&V promote the moral fabric of society. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1239–1269 Brain Death and Organ Removal: Revisiting a High-Stakes Question1 Bernard N. Schumacher University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland The irreversible cessation of all brain activity as a criterion for death, including that of the brain stem, was suggested in 1968 by the now famous report of an ad hoc committee at Harvard Medical School. For several years now, this criterion has once again been the object of rather well-publicized critical reflection, chiefly in the Anglo-Saxon world and, more recently, in the German-speaking world. The German philosopher Ralf Stoecker has even gone so far as to assert, during his March 21, 2012, speech to the German Ethical Council (Deutscher Ethikrat): “To my knowledge there is no convincing argument for the validity of the concept of brain death, today even less than in 1997,”2 the year in which Germany authorized the removal of organs from a human being whose death had been certified according to this cerebral criterion. In opposition to those who say that medical science has succeeded in proving the appropriateness of the brain-death criterion, he concluded that “recourse to the concept of brain death today, moreover, is no longer sufficient to determine whether or not it is permissible to remove organs.”3 He My special thanks to my wife Michele M. Schumacher for her very insightful comments and to Michael J. Miller for his translation. 2 Ralf Stoecker, “Der Hirntod aus ethischer Sicht,” last accessed, August 2, 2016, http://www.ethikrat.org/dateien/pdf/fb-21-03-2012-stoecker-referat. pdf: “Es gibt meines Wissens kein überzeugendes Argument für die Gültigkeit der Hirntod-Konzeption, heute noch weniger als 1997.” 3 Ibid.: “Der Rückgriff auf die Hirntod-Konzeption heute ohnehin nicht mehr 1 1240 Bernard N. Schumacher therefore considers the debate about brain death “useless.”4 His position is not an isolated case. It is along the same lines as the stance taken by a number of Anglo-Saxon physicians, legal scholars, and philosophers who have expressed serious doubts as to the legitimacy of the brain-death criterion. “No plausible and coherent account has been advanced to explain why brain-dead patients are dead,”5 the American bioethicist Franklin G. Miller had explained three years earlier, following his colleague Robert D. Truog, who thinks that “the concept of brain death is seriously problematic.”6 The American philosopher Don Marquis ratchets up the rhetoric: “The orthodox legal definition of death is indefensible.” 7 Brain death is likewise described by the American bioethicist Robert M. Veatch as being “old-fashioned” and “less and less plausible,”8 all the more so because, as the American physician Ari Joffe notes, “When one examines the rationale for BD being death itself, it is surprisingly hard to justify.”9 This school of thought denounces the fact that the brain-death criterion was implemented in order to correspond to actual praxis. It is said to be, in the final analysis, a “legal fiction”10 or “convenient”11 ausreicht, um die Zulässigkeit von Organentnahmen zu klären.” Ralf Stoecker, “Der Tod als Voraussetzung der Organspende?” Zeitschrift für medizinische Ethik 58.2 (2012): 99–116, at 113: “fruchtlosen.” 5 Franklin G. Miller, “Death and Organ Donation: Back to the Future,” Journal of Medical Ethics 35.10 (2009): 616–20, at 619. 6 Robert D. Truog, “Brain Death–Too Flawed to Endure, Too Ingrained to Abandon,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 35.2 (2007): 273–81, at 280. 7 Don Marquis, “Abortion and the Beginning and End of Human Life,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics (Spring 2006): 16–25, at 21. 8 Robert M. Veatch, Transplantation Ethics (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000), 139. 9 Ari Joffe, “Are Recent Defenses of the Brain Death Concept Adequate?” Bioethics 24.2 (2010): 47–53, at 47. 10 See Seema K. Shah and Franklin G. Miller, “Can we handle the Truth?” American Journal of Law and Medicine 36.4 (2010): 540–85, at 542: “Instead, the determination of death has been modified to fit our current practices, thereby creating legal fictions. . . . invoking legal fictions about donors being dead [whole brain dead] when, in fact, they are alive or not known to be dead.” See also Stuart J. Youngner and Robert M. Arnold , “Philosophical Debates About the Definition of Death: Who Cares?” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26.5 (2001): 527–37, at 535: “We no longer need the fiction of brain death to facilitate termination of treatment.” 11 Peter Singer, Rethinking Life and Death: The Collapse of Our Traditional Ethics (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1994), 35. 4 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1241 along the lines of what the German philosopher Dieter Birnbacher very recently described as a psychological “strategy of suppression”12 or, as the German legal scholar Wolfgang Höfling put it, an “illusory self-deception.”13 The American physician Robert Taylor points out the fact that we know perfectly well that persons who are declared brain dead are actually alive but that we want to consider them dead. The criterion of brain death, these thinkers say, is ultimately a societal construct and not a truth based on reason and science.14 These authors wish to break the taboo that surrounds any questioning of the brain-death criterion. The refusal to take into consideration even the hypothetical possibility of an error in this regard was illustrated by recent medical-ethical guidelines issued by the Swiss Academy of Medical Sciences (Académie suisse des Sciences médicales, or ASSM) with regard to the “Diagnosis of death in the context of organ transplantation.”15 Why this silence and refusal even to reargue the legitimacy of the brain-death criterion? If we were to find that it was wrong (i.e. Dieter Birnbacher, “Das Hirntodkriterium in der Krise—welche Todesdefinition ist angemessen?” in Welchen Tod stirbt der Mensch? Philosophische Kontroversen zur Definition und Bedeutung des Todes, ed. Andrea Esser, Daniel Kersting, and Christoph G. W. Schäfer (Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 2012), 19–40, at 36: “eine Verdrängungsstrategie.” 13 Wolfgang Höfling, “Tot oder lebendig—tertium non datur. Eine Verfassungsrechtliche Kritik der Hirntotkonzeption,” Zeitschrift für medizinische Ethik 58.2 (2012): 163–72, at 169: “illusionäre Selbsttäuschung.” 14 Robert M. Taylor, “Reexamining the Definition and Criterion of Death,” Seminars in Neurology 17 (1997): 265–70, at 269: “The whole-brain criteria of death is also a social construct, distinct from biological death, created to serve a utilitarian social purpose.” See Marquis, “Abortion and the Beginning and End of Human Life,” 23 : “Consider now a brain dead patient in whom, with ventilator support, respiratory and circulatory functions continue. Because she is still a (minimally) integrated biological organism, she is still alive. Because to remove her vital organs for transplantation is to kill her, bioethicists have endorsed bad arguments for the view that such individuals are dead, in order to justify transplantation.” See also Alan D. Shewmon, “Brain Death: Can It Be Resuscitated?” Hastings Center Report, 39.2 (2009), 18–24, at 19. 15 Académie Suisse des Sciences médicales, Diagnostic de la mort dans le contexte de la transplantation d’organes: Directives medico-éthiques (Muttenz, CH: Schwabe, July 2011). These guidelines were approved by the Senate of the ASSM on May 24, 2011. Although the bibliography mentions the famous report by the President’s Council on Bioethics in the United States—Controversies in the Determination of Death: A White Paper by the President’s Council on Bioethics (Washington, DC, December 2008)—which enters into the debate, the substance of this report is not analyzed at all. 12 1242 Bernard N. Schumacher illegitimate), people often say, it would have disastrous implications for the removal and transplantation of vital organs at a time when we see an ever-increasing shortage of donors. On the other hand, the continuation of this practice would be tantamount to approval of putting living persons to death and, in the final analysis, of using them only as means to an end for the benefit of other persons—or to quote the very telling image of the German philosopher Hans Jonas, approval of engaging in the “vivisection”16 of a person under the best possible conditions so as to procure his organs and tissues. Indeed, the removal of vital organs presupposes, as a general rule, the death of the person; it is based on the Dead Donor Rule. As the ASSM explains, “when organs are removed, what is being manipulated is the corpse of a deceased person,”17 not a living human organism. This principle is based on the moral principle that requires us to treat every human being in terms of Kant’s second categorical imperative, as an end in himself and never merely as a means.18 No price can be set on a human being. He transcends any attempt to exploit him, as is reaffirmed throughout Human Dignity and Bioethics, the recent report issued by the Bioethics Council at the request of the President of the United States. Hence he should not be killed in order to guarantee the wellbeing of other persons. The recent report by the US President’s Council on Bioethics on the topic of death, published in December 2008, takes up the current controversy surrounding the brain-death criterion. Here is what it says: “If indeed it is the case that there is no solid scientific or philosophical rationale for the current ‘whole brain standard’ then the only ethical course is to stop procuring organs from heart-beating Hans Jonas, “Philosophical Reflections on Experimenting with Human Subjects,” in Philosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man (New York: Atropos Press, 2010), 107–33, at 131. 17 Diagnostic de la mort, 19: “lors du prélèvement d’organes, c’est le corps d’un défunt qui est manipulé.” 18 See Emmanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), 96: “Act in such a way that you always treat humanity whether in your onw person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end”; the German original can be found in Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten in Gesammelte Schriften, Königlichen Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 23 volumes (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1902), 4:387–463, at 429: “ Handle so, daß du die Menschheit, sowohl in deiner Person, als in der Person eines jeden andern, jederzeit zugleich als Zweck, niemals bloß als Mittel brauchest. ” 16 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1243 individuals.”19 Is this argument justified? Should we not reframe the debate so as to situate it exclusively on the ethical level by abolishing the requirement of the Dead Donor Rule, as Stoecker and Birnbacher suggest, following Anglo-Saxon thinkers of the utilitarian school? Or, on the contrary, should we not admit that the question of the ethical legitimacy of removing vital organs is based, after all, on a philosophical anthropology, ultimately on a definition of human death, which would be accompanied by scientific/medical thinking to determine the criterion that would enable us to be certain about the moment when death occurs? In order to determine more clearly what is currently at stake in the brain-death criterion associated with the removal of vital organs, I will present, in an initial section, very succinctly, the challenges to this criterion formulated particularly by those who defend the criterion of brain stem death and of neocortical death. (A third position, which I will not discuss here but which could be described as post-modern and relativistic, consists of letting each individual and each community freely choose the criterion of death that suits him or it best.) Then I will continue with what these positions imply with respect to the removal of vital organs. In my second section, I will develop a fourth position that is based mainly on the empirical study of cases of persons who are considered dead according to the brain-death criterion but who apparently continue to live; that is, they independently manifest an integral organic unity. I will discuss the validity of this new criterion of death based on the permanent cessation of circulatory and respiratory systems. Finally, citing the principle of precaution, whereby in a doubtful case one should decide in favor of the likelihood of the presence of a human life, I will study several consequences resulting from the removal and transplantation of organs. I will present first the arguments for shifting the debate from the anthropological and medical level to the ethical level exclusively, which involves abolishing the requirement of the Dead Donor Rule, thus making possible the removing of vital organs. However, this transfer to the ethical level paradoxically necessitates recourse to a certain anthropology. Distancing myself from such a position, I will suggest shifting the debate to the level of a discussion of therapeutic obstinacy (obstination déraisonnable), which accompanies the removal of organs in the particular situation of controlled cardiac arrest of persons who are considered brain dead. Controversies in the Determination of Death, 12. 19 1244 Bernard N. Schumacher Criteria for Death Based on the Death of the Brain Stem and Neocortical Death The brain-death criterion is based on the fact that the different parts of the brain (the brain stem, the neocortex, and the cerebellum) have stopped functioning irreversibly. Very swiftly, two camps formed that tried to call this criterion into question on the basis of a dualist anthropology. Their advocates presuppose a radical distinction between the human organism, on the one hand, and the human person, on the other. Those in the first camp say that death is above all a biological phenomenon corresponding to the irreversible cessation of the interactive functioning of the organism understood as a unity.20 Death occurs, therefore, when the brain stem definitively ceases to function by itself (brain stem death). This death occurs on the biological level only, not at all on the level of the spiritual faculties of the human being. Those in the second camp define death as the irreversible loss of what is essential not to the organism but to the person. They make a fundamental distinction between “human being” and “person.” As the American philosopher John Lizza puts it, “the criteria for the death of a person or human being will therefore be determined by the loss of whatever properties are deemed essential to the nature of persons or human beings.”21 This presupposes that a person is not defined by his corporeality but exclusively by the exercise of certain personal faculties, such as self-consciousness and reason, freedom and responsibility, and the ability to project oneself as a subject into the future and to express one’s interests consciously. A person is then considered as deceased when he no longer exercises these personal faculties and this state is irreversible—in other words, when his neocortex is destroyed—even if his physical organism continues to live. The American philosopher Jeff McMahan nicely summarizes this point of view. According to him, “it is entirely natural to say that a person dies when he ceases to exist [i.e., to have self- consciousness], See, for example, Charles M. Culver and Bernard Gert, Philosophy in Medicine (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1982); Fred Feldman, Confrontations with the Reaper: A Philosophical Study of the Nature and Value of Death (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1992); and David Lamb, Death, Brain Death and Ethics (London: Croom Helm, 1985). 21 John Lizza, Persons, Humanity, and the Definition of Death (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2006), 32. 20 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1245 even if his organism remains alive.”22 Such an organism would be, to use an expression of the American bioethicist Tristram Engelhardt, a “biologically living corpse.”23 What consequences can be drawn from this criterion of death based on a dualist anthropology that refers, in the final analysis, to a Lockean definition of the human person? 24 It would be permissible to remove organs from human organisms that were not or were no longer persons, for they would be considered dead on the personal level. This would mean not only anencephalic infants but also, Engelhardt emphasizes, “infants, the retarded, adults, and the senile,”25 as well as a human being in an irreversible “vegetative” state. In fact, because such human beings do not—or no longer—exercise the so-called personal faculties, they are considered as being merely human organisms and not—or no longer—as persons. Furthermore, the Dead Donor Rule would be respected, since we would no longer be dealing with a living person. The reason underlying the introduction of this criterion of the death follows from utilitarian pragmatism (among other things), for we are talking here about a direct, economic method: “The simplest way of achieving the desirable end of allowing organs to be taken from these infants,”26 the Australian philosopher Peter Singer emphasizes. Such statements go against common sense and are profoundly counterintuitive. Setting up a priori the veracity of a dualist anthropology that reduces the person to the actual exercise of a certain number of personal faculties, they introduce a fundamental inequality—which could even be called a Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2002), 425. He also writes that, “If one ceases to be a person in this sense [i.e. ceases to exercise self-awareness and reason], he or she ceases to exist” (ibid., 45). 23 H. Tristram Engelhardt, The Foundations of Bioethics (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1996), 248. 24 The Lockean person is defined by the exercise of self-consciousness, without regard for any substance, whether corporal or spiritual, see John Locke, “Identity and Diversity, ” in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, bk. II, ch. 27 (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), 328–48. For a critique of this dualist anthropological position that is explicitly based on John Locke’s definition of the person, see Bernard N. Schumacher, “La Personne comme conscience de soi performante au cœur du débat bioéthique: Analyse critique de la position de John Locke,” Laval théologique et philosophique 64.3 (2008): 709–43. 25 Engelhardt, Foundations of Bioethics, 250. 26 Singer, Rethinking Life and Death, 47. 22 1246 Bernard N. Schumacher new racism—within the human family and end up justifying the exploitation of the human being by his peers in the name of a new criterion: the non-exercise of those faculties. Death as Permanent Cessation of Circulatory-Respiratory Function Another frontal attack against the brain-death criterion follows when one takes into account a number of cases examined empirically by the American physician Alan Shewmon. He noticed that some persons— fifteen years ago he had counted 175 of them—who were considered dead according to the brain-death criterion would continue to live. As of the time of the publication of his research, the duration of their lives after diagnosis ranged from one week to more than fifteen years. He observed that these persons continued to activate some bodily functions that he deemed to be of the integrating sort for the benefit of the organism’s unity, thanks of course to the assistance of an artificial ventilator, but also of a feeding tube and nursing care. Among these functions are, in particular: (1) respiration (described by the American physician not as the circulation of air in and out of the lungs, which is the role assigned by the brain stem to the diaphragm, but as the metabolic exchange of oxygen and carbon dioxide, which proves to be more crucial to ensuring integrative unity), (2) nutrition (described by Shewmon not as something dependent on the mouth and pharynx as coordinated by the brain, but as the reduction of food into elementary forms that are burned to produce energy or assimilated into the structure of the body), (3) the heartbeat, (4) the circulation of blood, (5) digestion, (6) the maintenance of body temperature, (7) the ability to heal a wound, (8) defense against infections and foreign bodies, but also (9) the intrauterine life of a fetus and his or her birth. Moreover, healthcare professionals in intensive care units find that a large number of these persons who are brain dead sometimes require much less technological assistance, or even less care, than many sick or dying patients present in those same units. Furthermore, some persons who had been considered brain dead have left the hospital to go back home, where they receive from then on the care that they need.27 See Alan Shewmon, “‘Brainstem Death’, ‘Brain Death’ and Death: A Critical Re-Evaluation of the Purported Equivalence,” Issues in Law and Medicine 14.2 (1998), 125–45, at 138–39, and his “Brain Death: Can It Be Resuscitated?” 19. Concerning the intrauterine life of a fetus and its birth, see Patrick Yeung, Christopher McManus, and Jean-Gilles Tchabo, “Extended Somatic Support for a Pregnant Women with Brain Death from Metastatic Malignant Mela- 27 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1247 Shewmon states that a human being is defined from an anthropological perspective as a holistic, integrative unity within which the nervous, hormonal, and immune systems do not have the brain as their center. Hence, in order to function, not all the organs depend on the brain, although certainly it does foster the optimal exercise of the various integrative organic systems. The American physician explains that “far from constituting a ‘central integrator,’ without which the body reduces to a mere bag of organs, the brain serves as modulator, fine-tuner, optimizer, enhancer, and protector of an implicitly already existing intrinsically mediated somatic unity. Integrative unity is not a top-down imposition from a ‘central integrator’ on an otherwise unintegrated collection of organs. . . . Rather, it is a non-localized, holistic property founded on the mutual interaction among all the parts of the body.”28 A patient who is dead according to the brain-death criterion but whose organism nevertheless exhibits the activity of a certain number of bodily functions is not properly speaking considered dead, but rather as very sick or possibly as dying.29 Taking into consideration these empirical cases and interpreting these bodily functions as integrative are defended by two groups that cite several definitions of the human persons. Asserting that every human being is fundamentally a human person, the first group declares that a person is not dead until the moment when “the circulatory, respiratory, and nervous systems (the three most important vital systems of the body) have been destroyed.”30 It is interesting to note that the second group is made up of a number of advocates of the noma: A Case Report,” Journal of Maternal-Fetal and Neonatal Medicine 21.7 (2008), 509–11, and David J. Powner and Ira M. Bernstein, “Extended Somatic Support for Pregnant Women after Brain Death,” Critical Care Medicine 31.4 (2003), 1241–49. 28 Shewmon, “‘Brainstem Death’, ‘Brain Death’ and Death,” 140. 29 See Alan Shewmon, “The Brain and Somatic Integration: Insights into the Standard Biological Rationale for Equating ‘Brain Death’ with Death,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26.5 (2001): 457–78, at 464–72. 30 Michael Potts, Paul A. Byrne, and Richard G. Nilges, ”Introduction,” in Beyond Brain Death: The Case against Brain Based Criteria for Human Death (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press, 2000), 1–20, at 2–3. See also Michael Potts, “A Requiem for Whole Brain Death: A Response to D. Alan Shewmon’s ‘The Brain and Somatic Integration,’” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26.5 (2001), 479–91; Nicanor Pier Giorgio Austriaco, “In Defense of the Loss of Bodily Integrity as a Criterion for Death: A Response to the Radical Capacity Argument,” The Thomist 73.4 (2009), 647–59; and Finis Vitæ: Is ‘‘Brain Death‘’ True Death? ed. Roberto de Mattei and Paul A. Byrne (Oregon, OH: Life Guardian Foundation, 2009). 1248 Bernard N. Schumacher neocortical death criterion. The latter insist, however, on qualifying their position under the pretext of their anthropological dualism, saying that this alternate criterion of death applies only to the death of the human being, as characterized by his organism, and not at all to the death of the person. McMahan, for example, says that “brain death is neither necessary nor sufficient for the cessation of integrated functioning in the organism as a whole.”31 Besides the arguments citing Shewmon’s cases, one can moreover emphasize that the brain-death criterion implies that human life exists only when the brain is functioning. From this premise it follows that the human embryo would not be considered as a living individual until four to eight weeks after conception, but rather at most as an assemblage of various isolated organs.32 It is commonly admitted, however, in the case of the embryo, that we have before us a particular living human being characterized (1) by an integrative function that is not regulated by the brain and (2) by the inability to breathe, as McMahan33, Marquis34, Shewmon35 and even the embryologist Günter Rager agree in saying. The last-mentioned author explains that “the embryo directs its own vital functions autonomously from the zygote stage. It shows that it is a unified system capable of self-organization.”36 The embryo is more than a simple mass of cells because, from the moment of fertilization, it displays continuous development without quantum leaps. It “possesses the active potential of its further development. It will pursue that development by itself, McMahan, The Ethics of Killing, 429; see also 434. See also David DeGrazia, Human Identity and Bioethics (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 149. 32 This is the argument proposed by Hans-Martin Sass in “The Moral Significance of Brain-Life Criteria,” in The Beginning of Human Life, ed. Fritz K. Beller and Robert F. Weir (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994), 57–70, at 63. See also Baruch Brody, Abortion and the Sanctity of Human Life: A Philosophical View (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1976), 112. 33 See McMahan, The Ethics of Killing, 437, and his “An Alternative to Brain Death,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 34.1 (2006), 44–48, at 46. 34 See Marquis, “Abortion and the Beginning and End of Human Life,” 19–20. 35 See the position taken by Shewmon with respect to the Presidential Report Controversies in the Determination of Death in “Brain Death: Can It Be Resuscitated?” 20. 36 Günter Rager, “Données biologiques et réflexions sur la personne,” in L’humain et la personne, ed. François-Xavier Putallaz and Bernard N. Schumacher (Paris: Cerf, 2008), 97–114, at 100: “L’embryon dirige ses propres fonctions vitales, dès le stade du zygote, de façon autonome. Il montre qu’il est un système unifié capable d’auto-organisation.” 31 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1249 without depending on someone else for it.”37 As for the German philosopher Birnbacher, he explains that: If one defines—with Michael Quante—the essential characteristic of life, understood biologically, as self-organization with the help of external resources, then the processes of self-organization that occur in the embryo and the fetus with the help of the mother’s uterus are not substantially different from the processes of self-organization that occur in the body of a braindead person with the help of a mechanical ventilator. It would be contradictory to allow the organic life of the embryo and the fetus to be considered “genuine” life, but not the life of the brain-dead individual being artificially ventilated. Self-organization means that the parts of the organism work together in a coordinated way. This condition is likewise fulfilled in both cases. The process of self-organization in both cases depends on external resources for its maintenance.38 A third argument in favor of the thesis that a brain-dead human being is alive makes reference to the nervous system. As long as the nervous system is present in the tissues throughout the human organism, the latter can be considered living. Now, there is no nervous system in the embryo. One could nevertheless say that it is living Ibid., 103: “. . .possède la potentialité active de son développement ultérieur. Il la poursuivra par lui-même, sans dépendre pour cela d’un autre.” 38 Birnbacher,“Das Hirntodkriterium in der Krise,” 29–30:“Bestimmt man—mit Michael Quante—die wesentliche Eigenschaft des biologisch verstandenen Lebens als die Selbstorganisation unter Zuhilfenahme äußerer Ressourcen, unterscheiden sich die Prozesse der Selbstorganisation, die in Embryo und Fötus unter Zuhilfenahme des mütterlichen Uterus ablaufen, nicht wesentlich von den im Körper eines Hirntoten ablaufenden Prozessen der Selbstorganisation unter Zuhilfenahme eines Beatmungsgeräts. Es wäre widersprüchlich, das organismische Leben des Embryos und des Fötus als ‘echtes’ Leben gelten zu lassen, nicht aber das Leben des Hirntoten unter künstlicher Beatmung. Selbstorganisation bedeutet, dass die Teile des Organismus koordiniert zusammenwirken. Diese Bedingung ist in beiden Fällen gleichermaßen erfüllt. In beiden Fällen hängt der Prozess der Selbstorganisation zu seiner Aufrechterhaltung von äußeren Ressourcen ab.” See also Birnbacher, “ Der Hirntod—der Tod? ” Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 60.3 (2012): 422–23, at 422, and “Der Hirntod—eine pragmatische Verteidigung,” Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 16 (2007): 459–77, at 467–68. See also Michael Quante, Personales Leben und menschlicher Tod: Personale Identität als Prinzip der biomedizinischen Ethik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2002), 69–70 and 152–53. 37 1250 Bernard N. Schumacher inasmuch as it has the capacity in its ontological structure, in its very nature, to generate such a system. The presentation of Shewmon’s cases and their interpretation has had a profound impact, not only on some proponents of the neocortical thesis but also, and more particularly, on the recent report of the US President’s Council on Bioethics, Controversies in the Determination of Death. The members of this council acknowledge unequivocally that patients who have been diagnosed as having irreversibly lost all brain function but have a certain somatic integrity call into question the statement that their organism is nothing but a disordered collection of organs. Indeed, this report leaves no doubt about it: “If being alive as a biological organism requires being a whole that is more than the mere sum of its parts, then it would be difficult to deny that the body of a patient with total brain failure can still be alive, at least in some cases.”39 The contributors to the presidential report, however, did not intend to adopt the position developed by Shewmon. Having opted instead for a shift in emphasis in the criterion for death, they suggest considering a person dead by referring no longer to the notion of integration and to the erroneous supposition that the brain integrates vital functions, but rather to the essential work of the living individual. Hence, death occurs when the body in its organic unity irreversibly ceases to perform its function or its duty—“the fundamental vital work of a living organism”40 —in other words, when it is no longer capable of being open to the world and of acting to obtain what it See President’s Council on Bioethics in the United States, Controversies in the Determination of Death, 57. The report also clarifies (44–45) that “Patients diagnosed with total brain failure may retain certain limited brain functions (such as the secretion of ADH to regulate urine output), and they certainly retain enough somatic integrity to challenge claims that the body immediately becomes ‘a disorganized collection of organs’ once the brainstem is disabled. In addition, advances in intensive care techniques, displayed in cases of prolonged somatic ‘survival’ after ‘whole brain death,’ challenge claims that the body cannot continue in its artificially supported state beyond a short window of time.” 40 Ibid., 60: “With that account, death remains a condition of the organism as a whole and does not, therefore, merely signal the irreversible loss of so-called higher mental functions. But reliance on the concept of ‘integration’ is abandoned and with it the false assumption that the brain is the ‘integrator’ of vital functions. Determining whether an organism remains a whole depends on recognizing the persistence or cessation of the fundamental vital work of a living organism—the work of self-preservation, achieved through the organism’s need-driven commerce with the surrounding world.” 39 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1251 needs.41 The intention of most contributors was to say that the cases of brain-dead persons described by Shewmon fit this new definition [of when death occurs]. Thus they could be considered dead and their organs could be removed for the purpose of transplantation. One could make a counterargument, however, by saying that these persons still interact with the external world by dint of their ability to maintain the functions of blood circulation and digestion, and also that of growth. Although they surely have lost the exercise of self-consciousness and interaction with others at the moral and intellectual level, they have nonetheless not lost their faculties that are essential in staying alive, which necessarily involves interacting with their environment. One can likewise ask whether the intention that prevailed in shifting the criterion for death is not to be sought primarily in the pressure that is being exerted for the purpose of facilitating the removal of organs, because of a strong demand. Such an option would be counterintuitive because it seems to confirm the development of an ethic that is subject to the interests of those who are well. Our reflection on human death, but also on the criterion that allows us to determine the moment at which death occurs, ought to be entirely independent of the question of removing organs. The main question raised by the cases to which Shewmon refers is whether the presence of certain “subsystems of integration” really signifies the presence of integrated and interdependent organic life that is capable of coordinating vital functions. To answer it, we would have to define much more precisely the meanings of “organism,” “integrated vital function,” and “holistic”— terms that are the object of a conceptual reflection resulting from a philosophy of biology supported by a scientific approach. We would also have to clarify what we mean by respiration and nutrition and whether these functions are exercised under the control of the organism (understood as an integrative unity) or independently of any such control. Moreover, another question left hanging in the air is whether we can speak about a living organism when it is kept alive artificially thanks to the technology of an artificial ventilator. This refers back to the distinction between “artificial life” and “natural life.” Pieces of artificial equip Ibid., 61: “1. Openness to the world, that is, receptivity to stimuli and signals from the surrounding environment. 2. The ability to act upon the world to obtain selectively what it needs. 3. The basic felt need that drives the organism to act as it must, to obtain what it needs and what its openness reveals to be available.” 41 1252 Bernard N. Schumacher ment that allow the organism to continue to live, such as a cardiac stimulator, are not, strictly speaking, essential parts of the organism. Although they help regulate vital functions to some extent, they do not initiate their activity. This main question raised by the cases presented by the American physician is at the heart of the renewed interest that created the current debate. In the final analysis, this debate poses the question of whether artificial ventilation can be considered as a regulator of vital functions such that the organism is what actually controls them or, on the contrary, is the mechanical regulator that activates those same vital functions? In the latter case, the vital functions would be understood as a reaction, rather than as an action in which the principle of their activity is intrinsic to them. Indeed, we can think about the presence of a living organism as long as it possesses the potential to activate such vital functions by itself. If this is not the case, it would be better to speak about an “integrated machine,”42 which although it can function as though we were dealing with a living organism, could be considered as living only by analogy and metaphorically. It is ultimately a matter of determining whether the cases presented by Shewmon correspond to what can be described as organisms that instigate their integrative vital functions and interaction with the external world by themselves or, on the contrary, whether these functions and this interaction can be activated only by means of some mechanical assistance, in other words a cause outside the organism.43 Finally, one may wonder whether we should not define human death independently of technological advances such as the ventilator or the cardiac stimulator, but also artificial nutrition and hydration. Given that the question has not been broached definitively and that the study of the cases presented by Shewmon leaves room for a doubt that can be described as reasonable, we have a right to wonder This is the term employed by Georges Cottier (“machine intégrée”) in his “Questions for Neurologists and Others about Brain Death as the Criterion for Death,” in The Signs of Death: The Proceedings of the Working Group 11-12 September 2001, ed. Marcelo Sanchez Sorondo, Scripta Varia 110 (Vatican City: Pontifical Academy of Sciences, 2007), XXXVII. 43 See Quante, Personales Leben und menschlicher Tod, 156. See also Jason T. Eberl, “Ontological Status of Whole-Brain-Dead Individuals,” in The Ethics of Organ Transplantation, ed. Steven J. Jensen (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011), 43–71, at 58. Eberl defends the view that the persons described by Shewmon are dead because they lack the active capacity to exercise the vital functions of circulation and respiration. 42 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1253 whether it is not necessary to cite the principle of precaution, which is summed up in the adage “when in doubt, leave it out.” That is to say, in cases of doubt, the rule governing our action, as Jonas suggested together with the chairman of the committee that prepared the December 2008 report by the Presidential Council (ethicist Edmund Pellegrino), ought to be to lean prudently toward the side of life or, to be more precise, toward the likelihood of the presence of a human life.44 Some are against introducing this principle of precaution, citing Aristotle’s argument that one cannot have absolute certainty in ethical matters.45 Such a stance, however, leads to a shift in the debate. Indeed, the object of this discussion is not situated primarily on an ethical level, but rather on an anthropological and medical level, which then certainly has ethical consequences. Furthermore it is not necessary to require absolute certainty, because it is enough for there to be a reasonable probability that the human person is not dead at the time when he is considered brain dead. Hence we could declare that we are in the presence of a living organism. Practical Consequences Concerning the Procurement of Organs The implementation of the principle of precaution would imply that it would be problematic in present circumstances to continue the See Hans Jonas, “Against the Stream: Comments on the Definition and Redefinition of Death,” in Philosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man (New York: Atropos Press, 2010), 134–42, at 140: “We do not know with certainty the borderline between life and death, and a definition cannot substitute for knowledge. Moreover, we have sufficient grounds for suspecting that the artificially supported condition of the comatose patient may still be one of life, however reduced—i.e., for doubting that, even with the brain function gone, he is completely dead. In this state of marginal ignorance and doubt the only course to take is to lean over backward toward the side of possible life.” This passage corresponds to “Gehirntod und menschliche Organbank: Zur pragmatischen Umdefinierung des Todes,” in Technik, Medizin und Ethik: zur Praxis des Prinzips Verantwortung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1987), 219–41, at 233. We find a similar position expressed by the chairman of the President’s Council on Bioethics, Edmund D. Pellegrino, in his “Personal Statement,” which is appended to Controversies in the Determination of Death, 107–21, esp. 117 and 119. 45 See John Haas, “Absolute versus Prudential Certitude in Criteria for Determining Death,” Ethics and Medics 33.7 (July 2008): 2, and Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1.3.1094b24, trans. David Ross (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1986), 3. 44 1254 Bernard N. Schumacher practice of procuring organs from human beings who are brain-dead but nevertheless continue to live with the help of a ventilator. To do this would be to violate the fundamental Dead Donor Rule. A drastic reduction in the number of organs procured would follow, whereas the present supply is already generally insufficient to respond to the demand.46 In order to overcome this difficult situation, some propose abandoning anthropological and medical considerations and situating the debate solely on the ethical level, a shift that goes hand in hand with the abolition of the principle enshrined in the Dead Donor Rule. Truog summarizes their reasoning as follows: “The process of organ procurement would have to be legitimated as a form of justified killing, rather than just as the dissection of a corpse.”47 After presenting and critiquing the arguments in favor of abolishing the Dead Donor Rule, I will show that the patients mentioned by Shewmon are in a situation that could be said to result from therapeutic obstinacy. While citing the principle of precaution, as well as the Dead Donor Rule, I will argue that we should consider a person deceased when we observe brain death accompanied by cardiac death. Abolition of the Dead Donor Rule Since the debate is being shifted in this way, the central issue is no longer to say what human death is while citing an anthropological definition and thus determining, on the basis of a medical criterion, at what moment a human being is dead. The issue is rather, as the American philosopher James Rachels puts it, to determine “at what point is it morally all right to declare [the person] dead?” or “at what point is it morally all right to remove his organs?”48 With regard to the physician’s See, for example, James L. Bernat, “The Whole-Brain Concept of Death Remains Optimum Public Policy,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 34 (2006): 35–43. 47 Robert D. Truog, “Is it Time to Abandon Brain Death?” Hastings Center Report 27.1 (January–February 1997): 29–37, at 34. See also Seema K. Shah, Robert D. Truog , and Franklin G. Miller, “Death and legal fictions,” Journal of Medical Ethics 37.12 (2011): 719–22; Franklin G. Miller and Robert D. Truog, “Rethinking the Ethics of Vital Organ Donation,” Hastings Center Report 28.6 (2008): 38–46; and Norman Fost, “The Unimportance of Death,” in The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies, ed. Stuart J. Youngner, Robert M. Arnold, and Renie Schapiro (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999), 161–78. 48 James Rachels, The End of Life, (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1986), 42. 46 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1255 hesitation in deciding the “right” moment to unplug the ventilator, another American philosopher, Jonathan Glover, proposes shifting the question to the ethical level alone while disregarding the impossibility of determining with absolute certainty the time of death. Then it would instead be a matter of asking “whether or not we attach any value to the preservation of someone irreversibly comatose”49 (or, we might add, to the preservation of the persons described by Shewmon). This is the question that Stoecker posed to the German Ethical Council. In doing so, he merely endorsed the position of a number of Anglo-Saxon thinkers, such as Robert Veatch50 or Peter Singer, to whom the definition of death is not a scientific but an ethical matter. The Australian philosopher explains that the definition of brain death is “a convenient fiction that turns an evidently living being into one that legally is not alive. Instead of accepting such fictions, we should recognize that the fact that a being is human, and alive, does not in itself tell us whether it is wrong to take that being’s life.”51 Stoecker’s argument, the intention of which is to shift the debate to the ethical level alone, is based nevertheless on a certain anthropological approach. According to him, the brain-dead human being is considered dead from personal perspective—that is, in terms of the definition of the human person—but living from the biological perspective. The individual is situated in the gray area between death and life, a “twilight zone” that is “neither here nor there”:52 “What one quickly and effortlessly observes is the fact that these patients are still like the living in one respect—in their outward appearance and in many bodily functions—and in another respect are already like the dead—in their definitive helplessness and the hopelessness of their situation. . . . These [brain-dead] patients are in personal terms like the dead, and in other respects like the living.”53 Jonathan Glover, Causing Death and Saving Lives (New York: Penguin, 1982), 45. He continues: “Do we value ‘life’ even if unconscious, or do we value life only as a vehicle for consciousness?” 50 See Robert M. Veatch, Death, Dying and the Biological Revolution: Our Last Quest for Responsibility (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1976–1977; rev. ed. 1989). 51 Singer, Rethinking Life and Death, 105. See also Birnbacher, “Das Hirntodkriterium in der Krise,” 36. 52 Ralf Stoecker, “Das Transplantations-Trilemma als philosophische Aufgabe,” Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 60.3 (2012): 426–27, at 427: “Hirntote Patienten befinden sich in einem Vagheits-Bereich; halb sind sie noch am Leben und halb schon tot.” 53 Stoecker, “Der Hirntod aus ethischer Sicht”: “Was man schnell und mühelos 49 1256 Bernard N. Schumacher The argument that Stoecker proposes in favor of procuring organs from a brain-dead human being consists of stating first—while paradoxically using an anthropological criterion—that, even though he is alive on the biological level, he is dead on the personal level. In other words, he is no longer alive at the level of what the German philosopher describes as being “the normative meaning of life.”54 From this it follows, therefore, that one could not harm him in the least by removing his organs. Moreover, the recipient of the organs would benefit from them more than he does: “It is no longer possible to cause them pain or joy. . . . And because it is no longer possible to do them harm, or to deprive them of any future, and because on the other hand the organ recipients profit considerably from the transplantation, one may remove organs from them, and do so, even though it leads to the termination of their condition between life and death and makes dead people out of the brain-dead.”55 This argument is based on an unproved a priori assumption: If a feststellt ist, dass diese Patienten in der einen Hinsicht noch wie Lebende sind–in ihrem äußeren Anschein und vielen körperlichen Funktionen–und in der anderen Hinsicht schon wie Tote–in ihrer definitiven Ohnmacht und der Aussichtslosigkeit ihrer Situation. […] Diese Patienten [hirntote] sind in personaler Hinsicht wie Tote sind, in den anderen Hinsichten wie Lebende.“ See also Stoecker, “Der Tod als Voraussetzung der Organspende?” 106, 111, and 112. We find a similar argument penned by Ruth Denkhaus and Peter Dabrock in “Grauzone zwischen Leben und Tod: Ein Plädoyer für mehr Ehrlichkeit in der Debatte um das Hirntod-Kriterium,” Zeitschrift für medizinische Ethik 58.2 (2012): 135–48, at 142. Shah, Truog, and Miller defend a similar point of view: “People who are ‘brain dead’ maintain a host of life functions that a corpse cannot. This condition of profound brain damage is like death because both states are marked by the permanent loss of consciousness and the ability to interact with others. Given that most people would see no point in maintaining life support for patients in this condition, they are ‘as good as dead,’ making it reasonable to treat them as if they were dead so that their organs can be used to save the lives of others. It therefore makes sense to treat a diagnosis of ‘whole brain death’ the same as death for the purpose of determining when organ donation is legally permissible” (“Death and legal fictions,” 720–21). 54 Stoecker, “Der Tod als Voraussetzung der Organspende?” 111: “die normative Bedeutung des Lebens.” 55 Stoecker, “Der Hirntod aus ethischer Sicht“: “Man kann ihnen nicht mehr wehtun oder ihnen Freude bereiten. . . . Und weil man ihnen kein Leid mehr antun, sie keiner Zukunft berauben kann und weil auf der anderen Seite die Organempfänger erheblich von der Transplantation profitieren, darf man ihnen Organe entnehmen, und das, obwohl es dazu führt, dass sie ihren Zustand zwischen Leben und Tod beenden und aus den hirntoten tote Menschen werden.” Brain Death and Organ Removal 1257 particular human being has no conscious interest that is deliberately expressed (and therefore empirically observable) in staying alive, no harm would be done to him by killing him, since none of his interests would be violated. In other words, in the name of an ethic of interests, we can move beyond the Dead Donor Rule. We find a similar proposal penned by Birnbacher, who discusses the case of the brain-dead person while continuing to consider him alive: “In contrast to the case of a typical victim of killing, organ donation here entails no loss of subjectively experienced time of life for the organ donor. Since all brain functions are irreversibly lost with brain death, all functions of consciousness are lost too. A temporal difference between the occurrence of brain death and the occurrence of biological death does not mean that this difference can be experienced somehow. This objective difference has no subjective counterpart. Whether or not one equates brain death with death— consciousness is irreversibly gone with brain death.”56 Birnbacher’s argument is based on the a priori assumption that, from the ethical perspective, only the exercise of a conscious mental life has any value. A human existence irreversibly deprived of it would have no value: “Not the preservation of the life of the organism, but rather the preservation of the life of consciousness is undoubtedly a good in practically any ethical system.”57 Although acknowledging that the human beings described by Shewmon are alive, the German philosopher declares himself to be in favor of keeping the brain Birnbacher, “Das Hirntodkriterium in der Krise,” 37: “Anders als bei einem paradigmatischen Tötungsopfer bedeutet die Organspende für den Organspender keinen Verlust an subjektiv erlebbarer Lebenszeit. Da mit dem Hirntod alle Hirnfunktionen irreversibel erloschen sind, sind auch alle Bewusstseinsfunktionen irreversibel erloschen. Eine zeitliche Differenz zwischen dem Eintritt des Hirntods und dem Eintritt des biologischen Tods bedeutet nicht, dass diese Differenz irgendwie erlebt werden kann. Diese objektive Differenz hat kein subjektives Gegenstück. Ob man den Hirntod mit dem Tod gleichsetzt oder nicht–das Bewusstsein ist mit dem Hirntod irreversibel verlorengegangen.” Richard Zaner uses similar arguments in his plea for the procurement of organs from anencephalic infants, while clearly insisting on the presence of interests that must be exercised: “Finally, where there are no neurological supports for personal, conscious life, there is no reason to suppose that an individual has interests of its own, in the strict sense in which the person does”; see his “Anencephalics as Organ Donors,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 14.1 (1989): 61–78, at 67–68. 57 Birnbacher, “Der Hirntod—eine pragmatische Verteidigung,” 474: “Nicht die Erhaltung des organismischen Lebens, sondern die Erhaltung des Bewusstseinslebens ist ein von so gut wie keinem ethischen System bezweifeltes Gut.” 56 1258 Bernard N. Schumacher death criterion for an ethical reason, because it attributes maximum certitude to the irreversible character of the loss of the exercise of a conscious mental life. What we do to a living human organism that is considered brain dead has no importance, given that we cannot deprive it of a conscious life. “The brain-death criterion,” Birnbacher explains, “is not an adequate criterion for death, but rather a criterion for mental death, which is not simply speaking identical to death yet is primarily relevant from ethical perspectives.”58 In order to be able to say that a subject has been wronged, the two German philosophers and those who propose abolishing the Dead Donor Rule highlight a central requirement, namely the presence of conscious mental life, accompanied by the exercise of interests; this implies, logically, that it would be permissible to procure organs not only from a brain-dead human being but also from any human being in a similar situation. Think, for example, of those who are in a so-called “vegetative”59 state or of an anencephalic infant—a recommendation made, incidentally, by Robert D. Truog,60 Don Marquis,61 Norman Fost,62 and Jeff McMahan. The last-mentioned explains that “because an anencephalic infant has neither the capacity nor the potential for consciousness, it is not a bearer of interests. Nothing can matter, or be good or bad, for its sake. Nor can it have rights or be an appropriate object of respect. If, therefore, the view for which I have argued is correct, it is difficult to see what objection Ibid., 475: “Das Hirntodkriterium ist kein adäquates Kriterium für den Tod, sondern ein Kriterium für den unter ethischen Gesischtspunkten primär relevanten, aber mit dem Tod simpliciter nicht zusammenfallenden mentalen Tod.” See also Birnbacher, “Der Hirntod–der Tod? ” 423. He explains however that this certitude about the loss of conscious life is not attained in the case of a human being in a so-called vegetative state or in the case of an anencephalic infant. It follows, in his opinion, that one could not, from an ethical perspective, procure their organs. 59 See Ronald E. Cranford and David R. Smith, “Consciousness: The Most Critical Moral (Constitutional) Standard for Human Personhood,” American Journal of Law and Medicine, 13.2–3 (1987), 233–48, at 246–47. See also Marquis, “Abortion and the Beginning and End of Human Life,” 23, and Fost, “The Unimportance of Death,” 172. 60 See Truog, “Is it Time to Abandon Brain Death?” 34: “Individuals who could not be harmed by the procedure would include those who are permanently and irreversibly unconscious (patients in a persistent vegetative state or newborns with anencephaly) and those who are imminently and irreversibly dying.” 61 See Marquis, “Abortion and the Beginning and End of Human Life,” 23–24. 62 See Fost, “The Unimportance of Death,” 172. 58 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1259 there could be to taking the organs from a living anencephalic infant for transplantation—apart, of course, from objections based on the interests and rights of the parents.”63 If we wanted to argue consistently from these premises, which for these two German philosophers, among others, are based on the lack of an interest and of a future that would make sense for the subjectivity of the individual, one could likewise mention the possibility of removing organs, as Fost64 recommends, from persons who are in the terminal phase of their life or suffering from a fatal illness, or even, as Veatch65 speculates, from persons who wish to commit suicide or from others who have been sentenced to the death penalty. The procurement of organs in these cases, however, would be possible only if the donor freely gave his so-called “informed” consent. As for Miller and Truog, they propose replacing the requirement of the Dead Donor Rule with the more central requirement of consent.66 Finally, one might ask whether it would be possible also to procure organs from human beings who cannot or can no longer consent to it, delegating the consent then to a relative or friend who is capable of making the decision. This would be the case with very young children, newborns, or persons with a severe and irreversible mental handicap or in the late stages of Alzheimer’s disease.67 McMahan, The Ethics of Killing, 451. See also Robert C. Cefalo and H. Tristram Engelhardt, “The Use of Fetal and Anencephalic Tissue for Transplantation,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 14.1 (1989), 25–43. 64 See Fost, “The Unimportance of Death,” 174. 65 See Robert M.Veatch, “Abandon the Dead Donor Rule or Change the Definition of Death? ” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 14.3 (2004), 261–76, at 269. 66 Miller and Truog, “Rethinking the Ethics of Vital Organ Donation,” 44. They also defend the ethical possibility, in some circumstances, of procuring organs from persons who are in good health, provided that they give their consent. See also Franklin G. Miller, Robert D. Truog, and Dan W. Brock, “The Dead Donor Rule: Can It Withstand Critical Scrutiny?” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35.3 (2010), 299–312, at 308. Their argument is based on the assumption that what the subjective will desires can be authorized, provided that it does not involve a third party. 67 Robert M. Veatch mentions cases that follow from the first principle of consent—it would make permissible the procurement of organs not only from brain-dead or irreversibly unconscious persons by killing them, but also from infants and those with profound mental handicaps—but he explains that the implementation of this principle would be very complicated at the legal and societal level; see “Transplanting Hearts after Death Measured by Cardiac Criteria: The Challenge to the Dead Donor Rule,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35.3 (2010): 313–29, at 327. 63 1260 Bernard N. Schumacher Critique of the Call for the Abolition of the Dead Donor Rule Stoecker’s position, like that of his Anglo-Saxon predecessors, relies chiefly on an a priori assumption that can be challenged seriously: in order for harm to be done to someone, it is also necessary for him to be able to experience it and capable of expressing an interest.68 Now, in order to be sure of the presence of an interest and of possible harm, they presuppose that the following statement is true: What one cannot observe empirically does not exist. Such a postulate implies, in fact, a reductively behaviorist perspective. Indeed, if a human being does not consciously express a particular interest that is empirically observable, that does not necessarily imply that he does not have such an interest. Two arguments illustrate this. On the one hand, although we do not presently have the technological means allowing us to register the presence of a mental life and, therefore, of subjective interests in persons who are in a particular situation such as one in a so-called “vegetative” state, this does not imply de facto that such a mental life quite simply does not exist. Rapid technological advances may allow us to detect, in the more or less near future, the presence of this mental life suited to expressing interests. On this topic we might mention, by way of example, this recent fact: it was possible to enter into communication with a person—thirty-nine-year-old Scott Rowley—who has been in a so-called profound “vegetative” state since an automobile accident that occurred twelve years ago, and for his part, he expressed interests.69 In the second, more fundamentally argument, one can assert the presence of interests that are constituent of a human being independently of their concrete exercise. Consider the hypothetical case of a person in a so-called vegetative state who was filmed while relieving himself. The film was later shown. The average person’s sense of common decency would be offended by that because such an act would profoundly harm the interest of that human being if he was considered as an end in himself. Such an interest is constitutive It is very interesting to note that this a priori assumption is also at the basis of the thesis recently developed by Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva in favor of euthanasia for newborns, or what they call “post-natal abortion.” Their argument also implies the possibility of removing and transplanting the vital organs of these newborns, provided their parents give their consent; see “After-birth abortion: why should the baby live?” Journal of Medical Ethics online, February 23, 2012 (doi:10.1136/medethics-2011-100411). 69 Determining whether or not Scott Rowley really is in a so-called vegetative state is of secondary importance here. 68 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1261 of a human being, even if he were not conscious of it; it is present even in the case where the human being is in a state that makes him unable, or else never has been able, to exercise such an interest consciously. The harm that is done him is not based on a conflict with his subjective interest, but rather on a constitutive interest of his as a human being, based on his ontological dignity. Such an interest exists independently of any act of consciousness by the subject or of its empirically observable concrete expression. The question of whether or not the human being subjectively feels the harm that is done him in procuring his organs is not the factor that determines the ethical value of that act. The central question, rather, is whether harm is done him if someone procures his organs. This leads ultimately to the question of whether the death of a human being is an evil in itself.70 Moreover, as I already said, the abolition of the Dead Donor Rule based on the theory of subjective interests and the legitimacy of organ transplantation applies not only to the human beings described by Shewmon or to those who are brain-dead, but rather it de facto implies the lawfulness of killing any human being who is in a similar situation, anyone who does not exercise personal interests and self-consciousness. Proponents of abolishing the Dead Donor Rule agree with the defenders of neocortical death here. The effect of this would be to introduce subtly a sort of justification of slavery within the human species based on the principle of utility: in the final analysis some human beings—such as newborn infants, severely mentally handicapped persons, or senile ones—would be reduced to supplying a bank of living organs destined for other human beings. Stoecker’s proposal, therefore, is to introduce a third category: a fluctuating or intermediate state between death and life. This obliges him to make a distinction between two categories: biological human life strictly speaking and so-called “personal” human life. Describing different types of human existence—biological, biographical, interactive, and phenomenal—he asserts that a human life has a normative value insofar as all these elements are present and actualized. If one of them were to be missing, he explains (without however providing explicit arguments), the normative value of the life would vanish. From then on, one could remove the individual’s organs: “Only if he has already lost his life in this sense, we might say, can his organs See Bernard N. Schumacher, Death and Mortality in Contemporary Philosophy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 182–212. 70 1262 Bernard N. Schumacher be removed. . . . The fundamental ethical assumption about life and death therefore applies only in instances where all the signs of life are present.” 71 The introduction of this “neither-here-nor-there” state presupposes a dualist anthropology, one that is explicitly defended, moreover, by proponents of brain stem death and neocortical death. Contrary to the latter, who try to justify this dualist anthropology by citing mainly John Locke as the source of the positions from which they deduce these ethical consequences, Stoecker relies on a theory of moral values. He assigns normative value only to the second type of human existence, so-called “personal” life, which includes the presence of organic life, unlike the first type of human existence, which is situated solely at the level of the organism and is devoid of the constituent elements of so-called “personal” life. The distinction advanced by Stoecker, which we find also in Birnbacher’s writings, actually results from a very debatable ethical choice and by no means from an anthropological reflection accompanied by a biological and medical approach. This approach does not warrant the presence of an intermediate state, since the death of a human being is defined as the radical denial of the various faculties or capacities that constitute organic life. As the German philosopher Andrea Esser neatly explains, “the biological understanding of the terms ‘life’ and ‘death’ allows for no intermediate state, no fluctuating state and no gray area.” 72 The proposal of Stoecker and Birnbacher to abandon the field of medical science and that of philosophical anthropology so as to situate reflection about death exclusively on an ethical plane while specifically no longer requiring compliance with the Dead Donor Rule in order to procure vital organs raises another fundamental problem: one might say that this is an epistemological error. Indeed, if a human being were to consider one day, from the subjective viewpoint, that he no longer had a future in which to accomplish his goals, his inter Stoecker, “Der Tod als Voraussetzung der Organspende?” 111–12: “Nur wenn er das Leben in diesem Sinn schon verloren hat, will man sagen, darf man ihm die Organe entnehmen. . . . Die ethische Grundannahme über Leben und Tod gilt deshalb nur dort, wo alle Merkmale des Lebens erfüllt sind.” 72 Andrea M. Esser, “Menschen sterben als Personen,” in Andrea Esser, Daniel Kersting, and Christoph G. W. Schäfer, Welchen Tod stirbt der Mensch? (Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 2012), 221–42, at 234: “Das biologische Verständnis der Begriffe ‘Leben’ und ‘Tod‘’ lässt kein Zwischenzustand zu, keinen Schwebezustand und keine Grauzone.” 71 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1263 ests, the continuation of his existence would be deprived of meaning. Such a situation—just like the ones described by Shewmon—does not imply however in any case that such a human being is de facto dead. Indeed, the definition of human death, which results from a philosophical anthropological reflection—just like the criterion allowing the determination of the death of a human being, which for its part results from a scientific medical reflection—implies no ethical value judgment. In fact, neither the definition of death nor its criterion can determine what sort of existence—with or without self-consciousness—is or is not worth the trouble of living. These are two radically different sorts of discourse. The quality of life, to which Stoecker and Birnbacher implicitly refer, which is based on a utilitarian, consequentialist ethics, cannot be a pertinent criterion for analysis in an investigation into the nature of death any more than it allows us to determine whether life is still present in a particular individual, or in other words, whether he is dead. Similarly, we have here also two distinct sorts of discourse when we speak about human life in general and about the quality of a human life and of its value. In short, the question of whether a human being is dead can be debated and one can answer it without asking whether his life seems desirable to him from a subjective viewpoint. Such an anthropological thanatological reflection is in no way related—Stoecker’s dogmatic statements notwithstanding—to “desperate attempts” to find out whether a person in a particular situation is deceased. Even though it is a difficult endeavor, it is better to continue, in the name of the principle of precaution, to conduct research at the scientific level to try to identify with as much certainty as possible the criterion that allows us to declare that death has occurred. Furthermore, this research is based on a philosophical anthropological foundation, which in any case is not a “useless” and “superfluous” 73 speculative endeavor. Quite the contrary, ethical reflection is, in the final analysis, conducted within the framework of a philosophical anthropology with human nature as its object, and more particularly human death. Therapeutic Obstinacy Some have claimed—wrongly, in my view—that the only possible way to continue procuring organs from brain-dead persons is to shift the Stoecker, “Der Tod als Voraussetzung der Organspende?” 115: “Die verzweifelten Versuche,” “überflüssig”; and 113: “von der fruchtlosen Hirntod-Debatte” [that is based on an anthropological approach]. 73 1264 Bernard N. Schumacher debate to the ethical level. This shift not only causes several problems in argumentation but also has consequences that defy common sense. Is it therefore necessary to stop removing organs from brain-dead persons, given that they are alive? I do not think that it is right to raise the specter of an organ shortage. Indeed, we could consider that the life of these living persons, who are dead at the cerebral level, would have ended if no one had decided to intervene. They would be, from a certain perspective, “dying” persons who were being kept alive with the help of artificial assistance, regardless of whether these life-sustaining procedures are conducted inside or outside the person’s organism. One may ask whether we are not looking at a situation that could be described as therapeutic obstinacy or disproportionate treatment. Indeed, the means employed would be both extraordinary and disproportionate. It is reasonable to postulate that a patient who is alive but brain-dead could have decided, while still capable of it, based on a so-called “informed” prudential judgment, that if he were ever in such a situation, the methods involved in his care and treatment would be disproportionate in relation to the therapeutic benefit that they would bring him personally. He could decide to be placed on a “do not resuscitate” (DNR) in the event that he is diagnosed with total brain failure. If he were to consider rationally that this care brought him no significant benefit, he could legitimately decide to discontinue the treatment, and even (in the case under discussion) to unplug the ventilator, so as to die a natural death. The patient, indeed, has a fundamental right to refuse any medical treatment that is perceived as disproportionate, the right not to be the prisoner or slave of medical techniques that only postpone death.This right to die, to use an expression of Jonas,74 which is expressed by the voluntary cessation of treatments, thus allowing the human being to die, is to be distinguished from the act of putting oneself to death (euthanasia or assisted suicide). This right comes into play when the person realizes that the care being lavished on him is not aimed at his cure and brings about no improvement, not even the slightest, of his state of health. Remission is no longer possible; his situation is, from the human perspective, desperate, devoid of hope. His state can fairly be likened to the state of a prisoner who is condemned to death with no chance of pardon.75 See Hans Jonas, “The Right to Die,” Hastings Center Report 8.4 (1978): 31–36. See Bernard N. Schumacher, “L’espérance au cœur de la vie humaine. Enjeux autour du malade d’Alzheimer,” in Alzheimer: une personne quoi qu’il arrive, ed. Thierry Collaud, Véronique Gay-Crosier, and Magdalena Burlacu (Fribourg: Academic Press, 2013), 45–66. 74 75 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1265 The fundamental right to refuse to continue treatment requires, however, consent on the part of the patient. This consent is different from what Trugo and Miller, or Birnbacher, think it is in the context under discussion. According to them, it would make no difference whether death occurred as the result of shutting off the ventilator or procuring organs from human organisms that are considered alive because the ultimate criterion lies exclusively in the consent of the patient or of his proxy, regardless of the requirement of the Dead Donor Rule: “With such a consent, there is no harm or wrong done in retrieving vital organs before death.” 76 The harm or the wrong done to someone depends ultimately no longer on the act committed—insofar as it concerns only this specific person—but solely on whether or not his consent is respected.77 This right to die within the context of therapeutic obstinacy can be chosen by the patient at the time, or else anticipating a situation, for example the one described by Shewmon. If however it should happen that the patient not only is no longer capable of making such a judgment but also never made it in advance, everything would depend on the prudential judgment (combined with common sense) of his family, of his friends, or of his personal caregiver. However, if the patient and his family, his friends, and his personal caregiver were to consider the means being employed proportional and ordinary, the care would have to be continued. This position is worthwhile, provided that we specify what we mean by ordinary and extraordinary measures in difficult cases. There are situations in which the line between them is not clear. There is no pat solution. Indeed, as Aristotle nicely puts it, particular Robert D. Truog and Franklin G. Miller, “The Dead Donor Rule and Organ Transplantation,” New England Journal of Medicine 359.7 (2008): 674–75: at 675. See also Miller and Truog, “Rethinking the Ethics of Vital Organ Donation,” 44: “The key protection is consent, along with the requirement for a valid decision to withdraw life support: organs should not be extracted without the valid consent of either the donor or an appropriate surrogate decision-maker.” See also Birnbacher, “Das Hirntodkriterium in der Krise.” 77 We find a similar position in the thesis defended by the French philosopher Ruwen Ogien, who speaks about victimless moral crimes and recommends avoiding the use of the word “immoral” “to evaluate anything in our lifestyles, our thoughts, our actions, that concerns only ourselves and what we do between consenting persons”; see L’Éthique aujourd’hui: Maximalistes et minimalistes (Paris: Gallimard, 2007), 23: “immoral” . . . “pour évaluer tout ce qui, dans nos façons de vivre, nos pensées, nos actions, ne concerne que nousmêmes, ce que nous faisons entre personnes consentantes .” 76 1266 Bernard N. Schumacher cases “do not fall under any art [technique] or precept [traditional prescription]. . . . The agents themselves must in each case consider what is appropriate to the occasion, as happens also in the art of medicine or of navigation.” 78 The decision to be made depends on prudential practical wisdom, acquired by experience, that connects general rules to singular situations. In every case, one ought to respect the so-called informed consent of the patient who in conscience refuses to prolong particular treatments that he deems extraordinary, that do not contribute to a therapeutic result that is significantly beneficial to him. This choice, however, must not be influenced in any way by any pressure whatsoever with a view to procuring organs, not even in the name of the principle of solidarity and compassion. This comes down to separating the two aspects clearly: the decision to stop the treatment that maintains the vital functions must be made before any reflection as to the possibility of donating organs. Moreover, it is necessary that the situation in which the living person described by Shewmon finds himself be irreversible—in other words, that is not possible for his brain to perform again a minimum of its functions independently of artificial assistance. The possibility of considering the lawfulness of unplugging a ventilator that is sustaining a living person who is brain-dead by citing therapeutic obstinacy does not resolve, however, the question about organ transplantation. One proposal would be to procure a patient’s organs—in the specific case of persons who are alive but brain-dead—after the determination of cardiac death—that is, “cardiac arrest”—since the circulatory and respiratory functions have ceased. Two categories of persons are commonly distinguished: first, those who have suffered a sudden heart attack, a situation described as “uncontrolled cardiac arrest,” and second, those who have decided to stop their treatment and whose death by cardiac arrest is then expected after a more or less brief interval, a situation described as “controlled cardiac arrest.” The procurement of organs from a person whose heart has stopped and who has previously given his consent is carried out after the determination of the irreversibility of the cardiac arrest. The waiting period before procurement currently varies (commonly between two minutes, according to the Pittsburg protocol, and ten minutes, according to the Maastricht protocol). The short delay allowed by the protocols raises a series of ethical Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 2.2.1104a7–10 (p. 30). 78 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1267 questions, however.79 First of all, the two-minute interval does not allow a certification with absolute certitude of irreversibility; in other words, it does not guard against the Lazarus effect, the “resurrection” of the person whose heart spontaneously begins to beat again.80 Proponents of this interval say that the medical personnel respect the patient’s decision that no one should intervene for the purpose of reversing the state in which he finds himself—in other words, of reviving him. Nevertheless, in the case where the patient could have revived by himself and yet his organs had been procured, we would have to declare that he had been put to death in order to procure his vital organs for the benefit of another person. To date, Joanne Lynn and Ronald Cranford81 point out, we have no empirical studies proving with absolute certainty how long after the cessation of circulation a spontaneous recovery of that circulation could occur. However, one could follow Shewmon in proposing, so as to have a maximum assurance not going against the Dead Donor Rule, an interval anywhere from twenty to thirty minutes before any authorization to procure organs, to which one would previously have administered a medication so as to preserve them better. This time lapse does not seem to pose a problem of deterioration in the quality of the organs, whether we are speaking about the liver, kidneys, lungs, or even the heart.82 The claim that such an intervention would amount to killing a person, given that these organs are still alive, can be refuted on account of the fact that the personal organism is already deceased at the moment of procurement. Indeed, as the American philosopher Christopher Kaczor83 explains, we are no longer dealing with an See Truog and Miller, “The Dead Donor Rule and Organ Transplantation,” and James M. Dubois, “Non-Heart-Beating Organ Donation: A Defense of the Required Determination of Death,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 27.2 (1999): 126–36. 80 Although a small study suggests that two minutes of absent circulation is sufficient to certify death, see Michel A. DeVita et al., “Observations of Withdrawal of Life-sustaining Treatment from Patients who Became Non-heart-beating Organ Donors,” Critical Care Medicine 28.6 (2000): 1709–12. 81 See Joanne Lynn and Ronald Cranford, “The Persisting Perplexities in the Determination of Death,” in The Definition of Death: Contemporary Controversies, ed. Stuart Youngner, Robert M. Arnold, and Renie Schapiro (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999), 101–14 and 108–09. 82 See Christopher Kaczor, “Organ Donation following Cardia Death: Conflicts of Interest, Ante Mortem Interventions, and Determinations of Death,” in The Ethics of Organ Transplantation, 95–113, at 112–13. 83 See ibid., 113. 79 1268 Bernard N. Schumacher organism that is an integrally functioning whole, but rather with the functioning of various organs that are not integrated into a unified whole. We find such a proposal, presented in very general terms, in the writings of Jonas: “The artificial ventilation is stopped first and then time is allowed in order to determine the definitive absence of all signs of life, and only then does the removal of organs begin. Since the delay is short, this would still result in usable material, but the conditions would no longer be optimal, and the yield would probably be smaller as a result.”84 This proposal, if implemented, would make it possible to reconcile respect for the patient’s will and the requirement of the Dead Donor Rule. Conclusion The recent debate calling into question the criterion of brain death does not lead automatically to the prohibition of organ procurement, nor does it justify any organ procurement whatsoever, provided that the requirement of the Dead Donor Rule is abolished. The proposal of advocates of neocortical death, which consists of shifting the debate to the ethical level exclusively and basing decisions on a consequentialist utilitarian approach, citing the serious shortage of vital organs available, subtly introduces a hierarchy among human beings—in other words a frontal attack on the fundamental equality of all human beings. Such a shift would imply the exploitation of some human beings and would lead to regarding others, and more particularly those who are extremely frail and dependent, as “the freshest material for organ transplantation,”85 while justifying this on the basis of the theory of the gift or even setting up a moral imperative in the name of a compassion that would oblige someone to give parts of his body to a third person who would be more capable of making good use of them—in other words, an ethics that viewed organs in terms of profitability. For my part I would say that there is no pragmatic difference with regard to organ procurement if we consider Shewmon’s research. Hans Jonas, “Gehirntod und menschliche Organbank,” 239: “[D]aß man zunächst die künstliche Atmung einstellt, dann die Zeit läßt, um die endgültige Abwesenheit aller Lebenszeichen festzustellen, und danach erst mit der Organentfernung beginnt. Das würde, da die Verzögerung kurz ist, immer noch brauchbares Material erbringen, aber die Bedingungen wären nicht mehr die optimalen, die Ausbeute daher wohl geringer.” 85 Hans Jonas, “Techniken des Todesaufschubs und das Recht zu sterben,” in Technik, Medizin und Ethik: zur Praxis des Prinzips Verantwortung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1987), 242–68, at 260: “frischsten Materials für Organverpflanzung.” 84 Brain Death and Organ Removal 1269 Indeed, in the great majority of human organisms that are suffering from irreversible brain damage that leads to brain death, we observe significant damage to the cardiovascular system also, which is then incapable of functioning autonomously and without assistance. In more particular cases, those of the persons described by Shewmon, we could say that they are in a situation resulting from therapeutic obstinacy, and thus we could propose the cessation of treatment that would lead to their death, provided that the person in question (or at least his family, his friends, or his caregiver) had given consent in advance. Nevertheless, in this hypothetical situation, in order to be sure that one does not kill a person for the purpose of procuring his organs, we could envisage the requirement of a twofold diagnosis: determination of brain death accompanied by determination of cardiac arrest. N&V Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1271–1291 Christology in Context: Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White, O.P., The Incarnate Lord* Guy Mansini, O.S.B. Saint Meinrad School of Theology St. Meinrad, IN Catholic Christology in the Twentieth Century From the restoration of scholasticism in the nineteenth century to the 1960s, Catholic Christology was a happy house unto itself. The person, natures, faculties, grace, knowledge, and work of Christ were expounded from Scripture, illuminated by the Fathers, and understood with St. Thomas (or maybe Scotus). There were happy in-house and never-to-be-concluded conversations: why the complete and perfect humanity of Jesus does not make a created person, whether we ought we to impute one or two acts of existence to the hypostasis sunthetos of Christ, whether the impeccability of Christ is intrinsic or extrinsic, and so on. There was an important recovery of patristic and medieval soteriology, a soteriology antecedent to the pressures exerted on the theology of the atonement by late medieval and then subsequent Lutheran and Calvinist pictures of a Christ who bears the punishment his Father metes out to him in our place. But the conversation was not without innovation inspired by modern philosophy and psychology. There were questions on the relation of the human consciousness of Christ to his person, about the psychological unity of Christ, and concerning whether one or two psychological egos are to be recognized in him. Notwithstanding such engagements with modernity, it was more important to know something about * The Incarnate Lord: A Thomistic Study in Christology (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2015). 1272 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. St. Margaret Mary Alacoque than about Albert Schweitzer because it was more important to justify devotion to the sacred humanity of Jesus than to consider the quest for that humanity historically known. Modernism (and magisterial suppression of Modernism) significantly retarded the critical reception of historical critical New Testament studies. As to engagements with non-Catholic Christians, it was more important to know something about the great monophysite patriarch Severus of Antioch than about the genus maiestaticum, but the first only for historical reasons, not because one was going to talk to present day Armenians, while the second could be safely ignored altogether, since one was concerned with neither historical nor contemporary Lutheran understandings of the communication of idioms. The restoration reached a sort of climax in which old things were both developed and newly perfected, such as at the Gregorian University in Bernard Lonergan’s De Verbo Incarnato (1964), surefooted methodologically, stunning in its conceptual clarity and rigor, orderly in its marshalling of Scriptural and patristic proof, and brilliant in its systematic understanding of the hypostatic union, the consciousness and knowledge of Christ, and the work of Christ according to the “Law of the Cross.” The destruction of this house was the work especially of Karl Rahner, S.J., and Hans Urs von Balthasar, beginning in the fifties and continuing for twenty years after the Second Vatican Council, as volume after volume of the Theological Investigations appeared in German (1954–1984), crowned with Foundations of Christian Faith (German, 1976) and matched by volume after volume of The Glory of the Lord (German, 1961–1969) and the Theo-Drama (German, 1973–1983). The dismantling was not direct, but the joint message was that it was no longer important to maintain the house. Of course, they had many helpers in what was commonly understood at the time to be a necessary work of theological liberation and maturation: despite their own metaphysical commitments and attention to dogma, Rahner and Balthasar were a sort of bridge to a more complete liberation from scholasticism (which meant at least some attachment to classical ontology) so as to enter into Enlightenment maturity (an historicism that told us why a dogmatic formula that formerly was useful was meaningless today). Rahner re-conceived Christology as the uttermost limit of a transcendentally constructed theological anthropology, a framework hospitable to almost whatever the New Testament scholars told us about Jesus of Nazareth. Balthasar, on the other hand, was a much Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1273 more serious reader of the New Testament than Rahner. And he did not subject dogma to the acid of Enlightenment historicism, as even the later Rahner was wont to do. But in the vast project he embarked on of subsuming the whole of Western philosophy and theology into the form of Christ, he gave an architectonic place to the way in which Karl Barth related the economy of salvation to the Trinitarian processions. And not withstanding his diligent attention to Scripture and dogma, the effect was largely to remove any metaphysical constraint on what we say, not only about the relation of Father to incarnate Son, but also about Father and Son within the Trinity. Balthasar thus ensured a break in the continuity of Christological discourse within the Catholic Church perhaps more radical than did Rahner. The spirit of things after the Second Vatican Council, moreover, abetted the dismantling of scholasticism already long desired by the figures surrounding what Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange called “la nouvelle théologie.” The coin was Pietro Parente’s, but Garrigou-Lagrange gave it polemical punch: he did not have to wait for Fergus Kerr to observe that Henri de Lubac seemingly planned his books “in order to destroy neoscholastic theology.” Notwithstanding its traditional endorsement of St. Thomas for theological education in Optatam Totius (1965), therefore, wherever the Council was understood to be a product of “the new theology,” it was just as widely understood as permission to wave a final good-bye to the thirteenth century and its Leonine reviviscence. Since the Council, and apart from many questionably orthodox (and therefore ecclesially useless) offerings that rewrite John 1:14 to tell us the flesh became Word, there have been some workman-like Christologies from Catholics that dutifully recapitulate the New Testament, some with more and some with less attention to critical studies, that report the councils and fathers, that may have a chapter on the middles ages, but also that concede the description of Christ’s knowledge to exegetes and proceed to some round-up of soteriology that does not do much more than speak of Christ’s solidarity with sinners and of the Cross as especially the manifestation of God’s love for us (which it surely is), but often with no authorial enthusiasm for the classic doctrinal elaborations of the atonement such as are to be found in St. Anselm and St. Thomas. More excellent are the worthy essays in Christology from Roch Kereszty, O.Cist., James T. O’Connor, and Thomas Weinandy, O.F.M.Cap. They recognize that revelation is not a report of our experience, they accept the normative rule of dogma, and they are serious about soteriology. But they no longer 1274 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. aspire to produce “théologie comme science,” as Marie-Dominique Chenu styled it in his historical appreciation of the thirteenth century, and to which Lonergan really did aspire even in the twentieth. The Incarnate Lord: A Thomistic Study in Christology After the destruction by Rahner and Balthasar and the earthquake of the Council and its reception, it seems there can be no such thing as a Christology in continuity with the pre-conciliar pattern. “There is no going back,” and so on and so forth. And anyway, for what reason would we want such a thing? But, surely, an obvious reason is plain enough at a moment’s consideration. It should be urged that there can be no real breaks, no real and unbridgeable gaps, that divide the discourse of the Church about Christ into incommensurable quantities. What one age makes of Christ cannot be severed from what another age says of him—this, in fact, Balthasar himself saw very clearly. How otherwise could it be true that Christ is the same yesterday, today, and forever (Heb 13:8), if the Church hears one thing in one age and another in a second? It cannot be the case, therefore, that the Thomist tradition of theology either is consigned to the past or must be thought at best to run on a parallel track with what such men as Rahner and Balthasar put in motion. Such a scenario has quite unacceptable ecclesial and even metaphysical implications. A second reason is equally weighty. We might want a conversation between the old and the new just because the pre-conciliar Christology in fact contains better resources with which to meet the concerns that moved such figures as Rahner and Balthasar in the first place. It may then turn out that the Christology of St. Thomas has the wherewithal to solve some of the puzzles in which contemporary Christology, Protestant and Catholic, lands us, such as the idea of a savior who does not know he is saving us, or of a human savior of a human nature for which, alas, we no longer know how to recognize in what its salvation might consist, or of a divine obedience that threatens to split the Trinity into three gods, or of an infinitely good God who is nonetheless interiorly conditioned by a history of evil. Of course, to knit up the raveled sleeve of Christological discourse thus and make of St. Thomas a contemporary interlocutor would take considerable skill and erudition. It is not just the old St. Thomas that has to be re-introduced, and in the detail it takes to have him say something up and down the line of Christological discussions. In addition, Rahner and Balthasar (as well as Schillebeeckx, Chenu, Pannenberg, Jüngel, and Moltmann, all these important and some- Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1275 times quite original and distinctive figures) must be brought forward, not in the broad strokes such as this review can hardly manage, but in detail. And the greater frame within which the modern discussion takes place, determined by modern historical studies and Enlightenment criticism (especially Kantian) of prior philosophical tradition, would also have to be in play, explicitly or in the background. It would take a lot, in other words, not only to prosecute Leo XIII’s program today—vetera novis augere et perficere—but to execute the program we also need—nova veteribus corrigere et complere. Thomas Joseph White addresses himself to both programs in The Incarnate Lord: A Thomistic Study in Christology. It may seem the second is more prominent, but in fact the old is appreciated and better understood in comparison, and sometimes in sharp contrast with, the new. On the other hand, his labor is more evident in showing us that St. Thomas offers a better way to think about the issues of contemporary Christology. This way has not only to correct error but also to show us how to meet the widespread contemporary demand to see in the obedience of Christ and the very manner of his saving death and resurrection, such as the New Testament describes them, the adequate manifestation of Trinitarian reality. This way has also to show how to welcome historical studies within a theological science already possessed of its own method. The first claim of White’s book is that the correction of error and the fulfillment of systematic demand about obedience and Trinity cannot be accomplished without welcoming a metaphysical ontology into the service of the gospel. The second, related claim is that Christology, while it must be historically informed, has first of all to be framed by revelation and the reception of revelation by faith. Historical studies are the fuel but not the engine of Christology. New Testament Ontology and the Modern Parameters of Christology This book is not a proposal or a mere essay, but a fully developed and, in its own order, complete argument. White therefore lays his guns very carefully, or, to change the metaphor, pours his footings broad and deep and accomplishes two important things, one in his Introduction, the other in his Prolegomena, before ever he constructs his argument in detail. The introduction of the book demonstrates the necessity of an explicitly ontologically informed Christology from the New Testament, hence its title “The Biblical Ontology of Christ.” The 1276 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. demonstration is informed by the work of C. F. D. Moule, Richard Bauckham, Simon Gathercole, James Dunn, Larry Hurtado, and others. He adduces four pieces of evidence. First, the New Testament asserts that a pre-existent Son of God, his Word and Image, became man. Therefore, the New Testament itself invites us to contemplate the unity and distinction of Father and Son in one God. Second, the man Jesus is asserted to be the Lord, ruler, and judge of the world, things proper to divinity. Third, not only are divine things such as the creation of the world predicated of the man Jesus, but human things such as suffering and death are predicated of the Son of God. These second and third things together adumbrate the insight captured in St. Cyril’s talk of a “hypostatic union,” which conceptualizes the ontological basis according to which divine things predicated of the man Jesus and human things predicated of the Logos, the Son of God, are literally and not metaphorically said. Such New Testament doctrines pass well beyond the limits of a “functional Christology” and require us to think out the reality and being of Jesus of Nazareth both in relation to the transcendent God of creation and in relation to us men made in his image. Though the predications are literal, they require for their coherence a metaphysical reach that can keep straight the analogical character of language that speaks of both God and his creatures. Fourth and last, the man Jesus is presented to us as the exemplar of humanity, as that man in whom can be found no more perfect or excellent instance of humanity. This, too, requires a metaphysical exercise, a metaphysical appreciation of a nature, human nature, that is not conceived in a nominalist way, but such that the real discernment of human capacities and powers is one thing with the conception of their fulfillment and end. The introduction assures us that, when we take up St. Thomas’s metaphysically sophisticated Christology, we shall not be leaving behind the mystery vouchsafed us in the New Testament, but going deeper into it and in a way that it invites of itself. The introduction establishes the necessity of a metaphysically informed Christology. The Prolegomena ask whether that is possible today, given the parameters of modern Christology. They are two. First, there is the contemporary prominence, even preeminence—a methodologically authoritative preeminence—of New Testament and early Christian historical studies. Second, there is the anti-metaphysical challenge of Emmanuel Kant. According to the first, Christology’s point of departure is not the New Testament understood as itself a word of revelation, but the critical reconstruction thereof and Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1277 the historically determined shape of early Christian thought. According to the second, if the proto-Catholicism of the New Testament demands a metaphysically informed contemplation of the Christ, the demand cannot be met. There is, then, all the more reason to shift to historical grounds pioneered in the German Enlightenment. Thus White’s prolegomena asks “Is a Modern Thomistic Christology Possible?” The Prolegomena situates the prospects for a renewed Thomist Christology between two responses to the twin challenges posed by historical studies and by Kant, those of Friedrich Schleiermacher and of Karl Barth. It closes by outlining how a Thomistic Christology can engage these responses. Schleiermacher stands at the head of a host of modern theologians who let modern, reductive historical studies trump dogma. The consequence of this decision is likewise paradigmatic: Schleiermacher concludes that the divine and saving word Jesus speaks to us arises from a consciousness of God than which no greater can be conceived or desired. While some who follow Schleiermacher in granting history hegemonic theological rights try, by hook or by crook, to make the Church’s Christological dogma somehow conform to the results of historical critical studies, Schleiermacher does not, and in this he is more evidently conformable to the Kantian parameter of modern theology. If ecclesial Christological doctrine demands a hospitality to a metaphysical point of view even to be understood, a properly modern theology cannot itself then be hospitable to dogma. Schleiermacher proves himself to be a more consequent thinker than Barth, who provides the second paradigmatic response to the twin modern challenges. Unlike Schleiermacher, Barth denies the rights of historical critical studies within theology: dogma trumps history, the Bible itself has no interest in historical certitude, and Christians are moreover forbidden by their adherence to faith alone to be interested in such questions. But like Schleiermacher, he takes Kant to show the impossibility of natural theology. He understands the Kantian limits on reason to be the limits of fallen man to speak of God: there is no indestructible capacity belonging to man to speak truly of God. But he welcomes a sort of revealed metaphysics, some of the articulations of which he finds in Friedrich Hegel, with which to do justice to the demands of both Bible and Church dogma. While Catholics have thought that the ancient metaphysical patterns linking the world of our experience to a first principle could be pressed into the task of articulating and understanding dogma, Barth walks a seemingly simpler, but in the end more difficult, path. It seems 1278 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. simpler in that the revealed word of God must bring with it its own metaphysical resources, worked out in the post-Kantian but still Christianly inspired discourse of German idealism. But it is a position of which it is difficult to iron out all the wrinkles, the chief one of which is discerning what Christ has to say to us and what Christ does for us that is not already implied in the very fact of our having proceeded from a God who realizes himself in and through us. The disparate paths of Schleiermacher and Barth unite in finding no way to speak of Christ except in univocal terms: Schleiermacher’s Christ differs from us only by degree, not in the constitution of his being; and Barth’s Christ shows in his humanity an obedience that is verified also in the Trinity. Both end up making the consciousness of Christ foundational for understanding his being among us. The similarities of Schleiermacher and Barth to one another are much greater than their dissimilarity to Aquinas. How is a Thomist word to be inserted into this framework? As to the relation of historical studies to theology, White connects us with his Dominican predecessors, Ambroise Gardeil and R. Garrigou-Lagrange, on the object of Christology formally and materially considered. Formally, it is what God reveals about Christ by the words and deeds recounted in the economy of salvation and stored up in the Bible. But materially considered, Christ can be approached by history, too. Therefore, while theology judges the offerings of historical studies relevant to the contemplation of Christ, just as St. Thomas teaches in the first question of the Summa (a word for Schleiermacher ) it also needs to make use of them (a word for Barth). Why must it use them? It must do so for two reasons, one apologetic and one systematic. White illustrates the latter with N. T. Wright’s discussion of sacrifice and the intention of Jesus facing his death. This is not a historical word it is prudent to ignore. It helps us execute the Christological task. As to the former (the apologetic), it is not the case that theology should be unconcerned with linking the word of revelation with the antecedent concerns and questions of reason still un-illuminated by faith. In giving an account of our hope, as the New Testament urges us to be prepared to do (1 Pet 3:15), we have also to be prepared to say why it is reasonable to believe that God has spoken and reasonable to believe we have a trustworthy account of the culmination of that word in the life, death, and resurrection of Jesus. It is a mistake to conceive of the word of God as a sort of nuclear explosion that levels everything at ground zero and blows away every human structure. There is a receptivity to the word, natural before supernatural, that Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1279 has also to be respected and which the word of God does in fact respect. This issue is taken up in a different way in the body of the book when White examines Barth’s refusal of the analogy of being. There remains the second, metaphysical challenge of modernity. White has already treated this issue at length in Wisdom in the Face of Modernity: A Study in Thomistic Natural Theology, which undertakes to install St. Thomas’s natural theology and deployment of analogy in the twenty-first century. There, he first answers charges originating with the views of Kant and Heidegger that Thomist metaphysics is onto-theological, then adjusts some of the infelicities of previous presentations of the analogy of being to be found in Catholic thinkers such as Etienne Gilson, Jacques Maritain, and Rahner, and finally outlines a reconstructed Thomist metaphysics and natural theology in the last ninety pages. The prolegomena of The Incarnate Lord, for its part, offers a brief but illuminating word a Thomist might speak to the metaphysical issues raised by both Schleiermacher and Barth, a word that, modo scholastico, distinguishes between primary and secondary acts. The metaphysical invitation of the New Testament will have us understand the union of humanity and divinity in Christ according to first, substantial act, the divine act of existence according to which the Word subsists in a human nature. The union cannot be accomplished on the level of operation, of consciousness and knowledge and will. Such a union would not save the communication of idioms. On the other hand, the consciousness and will of Christ can and do express the filial character of the one person who now subsists in human nature. It is rather we who are united to God at the level of operation, and in this light, the vision of God Christ enjoys in his humanity ensures that he is exemplary for us not only now in our consciousness of and obedience to God, but also in anticipating the end held out to all who are saved in Christ, a vision in which human nature reaches a fulfillment beyond and divinely perfective of it according to its radical possibility as made in the image of God. The introduction tells us the New Testament requires a metaphysically astute Christology; the prolegomena shows how such a thing, in its Thomist variety, would relate to modern Christology. The demonstration that a metaphysically informed and historically wise Christology can meet the issues that Rahner and Balthasar and company tried to meet better than they did is the burden of the ten chapters that follow. 1280 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. Three Contributions of The Incarnate Lord Each chapter in this volume can be read on its own, and many certainly have been, since they have already appeared in journals. The volume does more than put previously published material between two covers, however. For one thing, three chapters previously unpublished have been added so as to fill out a complete Christological itinerary from Incarnation to Cross and exaltation. In addition, there is a cumulative force to the succession of topics, both because of their relation to the two overarching issues of Christology in the contemporary age (that of the integration of modern historical studies into Christology and that of ontology after Kant treated in the prolegomena) and because they follow the order of topics in St. Thomas’s Christology in the Summa: from the one person of the hypostatic union, to the integrity of the assumed human nature, to the graced powers of Christ, and last, to the actions and events of the Paschal Mystery—passion and death, descent into hell, and resurrection. The presentation’s cumulative force comes in part, in other words, from the fact that it follows the method of a mature science (the via docendi), which moves from the priora quoad se to the priora quoad nos.That is,White’s discussion moves from the divine and human principles that constitute the incarnate Word in his being to their operation in the work of our salvation. Because of its engagement with many of the greatest modern theologians (Rahner, Wolfhart Pannenberg, Balthasar, Jürgen Moltmann, et al.), because of the care with which it has been framed between the concerns of Barth and Schleiermacher in the prologue, because of the richness of the appeal to St. Thomas in every chapter, the work as a whole is like listening to a great symphony, or like taking the back off of a Swiss watch and observing a complex, highly ordered movement and its regulation. There is a sort of aesthetic pleasure in appreciating the whole work. Three of the more important things White accomplishes are detailed in what follows. Close Encounters with Karl Barth There is a close engagement with Barth throughout the book: first, there is Barth on analogy in consideration of the natures of Christ (ch. 3); next, a vindication of the necessity of natural theology (ch. 4); and third, a consideration of the divine obedience of the Son within the Trinity (ch. 6). With regard to the topics of analogy and natural theology, this is a closer and more sustained engagement by a mature Catholic theologian than anything of which I know since Henri Bouillard, S.J. But Barth also figures in the chapter on abandonment (ch. 7, with Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1281 Balthasar and Moltmann); he is in the immediate background of the kenoticists treated apropos of the death of Christ (ch. 8, with Pannenberg, Eberhard Jüngel, Balthasar); and he figures in the chapter on the descent into hell (ch. 9, with Balthasar). That is to say, Barth figures in over half the book. Evidently, the topics of analogy and natural theology remain the foundational issues they have always been recognized to be. For Christology, how can one rightly assert the two natures of Christ of the Chalcedonian confession without the analogy of being? White formulates the Barthian objections to Thomist analogy with the help of Jüngel, which charge that it includes God within common categories of cause and being that do not escape the confines of creatureliness and treats him onto-theologically. White wonders politely about the ignorance of Thomist texts such accusations betray, but he patiently cites the relevant texts of Aquinas that deny that God is included in the subject matter of any human science, metaphysics included, that exclude him from the notion of ens commune, and that insist on the non-reciprocal relation between creature and creator according to which, while it is true to say that creatures are like God, it is by no means true to say that God is like anything. The demonstration of the necessity of natural theology for sacred doctrine is elegant. Must there not be some analogical understanding for us even to hear that the Word became flesh? It cannot be a Word like our words! White’s position amounts to insisting that the gratuity of God’s bestowal of a revealed knowledge requires a natural knowledge from which it is distinct. But, if the revelation of such things as the Trinity and the Incarnation is to be really heard by us in faith and therefore integrated into our up and running consciousness of what we already know about ourselves and our neighbors and the world, then such integration requires that we recognize it as the revelation it is. It remains in itself a gift of God and must be appreciated as such to be integrated into our knowing selves. This is to say that, in relating revelation to what we already know, we have to be able to contrast it to the non-revealed, natural knowledge we already possess. So, as White illustrates, if we assent to the truth that the Word that was with God in the beginning is God and became flesh, then, if we are to think this through as much as we can and as it deserves, we must be able to marvel at the sameness and greater difference there is between the divine Word and a human word. Or again, we have to think about what it means and what it could not mean to say that a divine person “becomes” something. This 1282 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. means, centrally, that we have to think it through in such a way that we do not make the ascription of the work of creation ( John 1:3) impossible. We would do that, for instance, by supposing that “becoming” here means change, by way of either diminishment or augmentation. For, if that is how the Word “becomes” flesh ( John 1:14), then the Word is being thought of as just one more thing within the world, and that is not coherent with thinking the Word as creating the world, which is to say being unconditionally responsible for the totality of its being. To think rightly of the divinity of the Word, therefore, “we must have an intrinsic natural capacity to recognize such revelation as something exceeding the scope of our ordinary natural powers of reflection and knowledge” (227). But if we can say how the knowledge of revelation is to be related to our natural human knowledge such that we can say we have really received the revealed word, then we are ineluctably engaged in the task of thinking about divinity just on its own, and thinking about it just on our own—that is, by force of our own native, natural powers. We are therefore engaged in a “natural theology,” which turns out to be a sort of subroutine required by faith itself within the all-inclusive theological program. This is of ecumenical moment: Thomists do not claim to be dragging something into theology from outside that we on our own think theologically useful; we are doing what revelation itself requires in order to complete its self-unfolding in sacra doctrina. We could put it like this: since God reveals himself, after all, we can appreciate this self-revelation as the revelation it really is only against a logically prior knowledge of him from the “outside,” as it were. Only with such a knowledge will the revealed knowledge of God be intelligible to, and so assimilable by us as what it is. And this logically prior knowledge is “natural theology.” Without such knowledge, the terms of revelation will either be indistinguishable from the terms in which we know the world or be some alien body whose equivocal claims cannot be related to what we are and what we desire. For White, the vindication of natural theology is just the flip side of the defense of the analogy of being. One of the most immediate consequences of the difference between St. Thomas and Barth on analogy shows up in the chapter on the obedience of Christ, where the question of the manifestation of the Trinity is addressed: does the economy constitute the Trinity, or is the Trinity constituted in view of the economy? These ways of construing things are invited precisely by seeing in the human Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1283 obedience of Christ a direct reflection of an identical and specifically divine obedience within the Trinity. Such a view collapses the difference between God and the world that analogy keeps open. Barth is right, of course, to see that the human obedience of Christ manifests the Trinity—but not in the direct way he wants. Rather, White reaches, with St. Thomas, for the distinction worked out most clearly by Maximus the Confessor and taken up by John Damascene, the distinction between logos and tropos, between the nature of something and its way of being, here, specifically, the distinction between the nature common to the Trinity and the tropos tes hyparcheos of the Son, his filial manner of receiving, but not in an act of obedience, all that he is from the Father. Without this precision, Father and Son have distinct wills, commanding and obeying, that tip the doctrine of the Trinity into tritheism. It is not only a divine obedience that Barth and his followers want to verify in God, but also other elements that classical Christology thought proper to the economy. Chapter 8 examines how the kenoticist Christologies of Pannenberg, Jüngel, and Balthasar understand the death of the Lord. With no other access to God, and no access to him by which to measure how we receive the revelation of Christ, such Christologies end up imputing not only a filial obedience but finitude and suffering to the divinity as well. Christ does not, therefore, conquer death by his divine authority and power in submitting to it, but rather only by exhibiting solidarity with us in our suffering, even to abandonment by God and the experience of hell, introducing suffering into divinity itself. White questions how such a dark God can really save or offer any comfort to us his worshippers. He brings to bear the categories of merit and efficiency in showing the power of the Cross for Aquinas and moreover explains how the theandric acts of Christ are permanently available to us in their saving efficacy. The Unity of Christ’s Agency as God and Man Christ acts to save us in charity, knowing what he does for our sake, and knowing that it accomplishes our salvation by the power of God. Without this known unity of his action on Christ’s part, without knowing as man what he is doing both humanly and as the Son of God, Jesus’s activity can be an occasion of divine beneficence but not its real instrument, an instrument befitting the knowing and self-conscious character of the humanity assumed by the Word to accomplish salvation. For Aquinas, it is just in this way that a divine person, the only Son, works through the human actions and passions displayed 1284 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. especially on the Cross to effect our salvation. It is one of White’s signal achievements to show the necessity of this unity, a necessity that the Gospels take every pain to point out to us (e.g., Mark 15:39—“Truly, this man was the Son of God”) but that much of modern Christology has denied or made obscure. The urgency of this task is evident if we think of Christian worship. In the third verse (originally the eighth of Paul Gerhardt’s text) of Hans Leo Hassler’s “Passion Chorale,” the Christian thanks Jesus for dying on his behalf and for his compassion for him, a sinner: “What language shall I borrow to thank thee, dearest friend, for this thy dying sorrow, thy pity without end?” On Good Friday, the Christian addresses the dying Jesus with these words in the very moment of his death. The prayer is not directed to the risen and exalted Christ, but rather places the Christian at the foot of the cross. The Christian thanks Christ as if thanking a friend—that is, as someone who does what he does knowingly and willingly for those whom he loves, among whom are certainly included those at Good Friday services. What must be true of Christ’s agency if this act of Christian prayer and devotion is itself to be genuine and not some make believe, to address the dying Christ with words truly descriptive of what he is doing? For Aquinas, Christ does what he does on the Cross with the intense love of supernatural charity, charity that he identifies as the supreme instance of friendship. Only Christ’s graced action, the charity with which he obediently responds to his Father, the charity with which he dies for sinners, a graced love just in that way exemplary for all Christians (Rom 5), will fill the bill. In the second verse, the Christian has already acknowledged that Christ dies on account of his (the Christian’s) sin. “What thou, my Lord, has suffered was all for sinners’ gain; mine, mine was the transgression, but thine the deadly pain.” The admirabile commercium is here confessed, and it is an exchange Christ knows full well. That is, Christ’s suffering is informed by the knowledge that what he does works for the sinner’s salvation. This is why he undertakes it; this is why he is the “dearest friend” in the third verse. The Christian therefore speaks to Christ as to one who knows what effect his suffering and death will have. What must be true of Christ’s knowledge if the Christian speaks to Him truly? What must be true is that Christ knows who he is in doing what he does. And for this knowing, he has to behold his Father humanly and know immediately and with certainty who he himself is. Without this, as White demonstrates in chapter 5, we are left with a sort Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1285 of gnoseological parallelism: Christ as God would know what is happening, but Christ as man could at best believe he was fulfilling God’s will, a God whom he likewise believed was his Father. To the contrary, we thank Jesus as knowing certainly what he was doing, and therefore doing it with all the greater charity. An infused or prophetic knowledge cannot supply what is needed here. Our debt of thanksgiving is not owed to another wayfarer, one who cannot act beyond the limits of a wayfarer’s confidence and trust in God, but to the God who died for us, of whose death as God therefore he had humanly to be conscious and conscious of what it was effecting. If there is a disconnect between the divine person acting humanly and the human perfection in the lines of knowing and willing, then we cannot really pick up the words to Hassler’s chorale as our own. The traditional Catholic doctrine on Christ’s human knowledge of God is required to make the Christian’s prayer a true prayer. This doctrine of the immediacy of Christ’s vision of God also makes his own prayer true, even the standard of all prayer to God. It certainly does not mean that his own prayer and obedience are less real, some fiction played out for our sake, but rather the contrary: he can deliver himself in prayer to the Father more completely, more profoundly than any prophet or apostle precisely because of the vision—knowledge enables and illumines action, and greater light does not mean lesser devotion or a feebler motion of the heart. Rather, in his prayer and obedience, Jesus shows us a sonship in human form than which no greater can be imagined, for his human prayer and obedience now betray the tropos of his divine person more perfectly just because of the perfection of his human knowledge. The immediate vision of God that White defends does not obviate the infused and acquired knowledge of Christ Aquinas also maintains. On the contrary, the infused knowledge of Christ enables him to translate what he knows in immediacy and with certainty within the already revealed categories of salvation established in the Old Testament. His acquired knowledge enables him to complete that hermeneutical act for the very people with whom he lives and who are to be witnesses to his deeds and rememberers of his word. White returns to this theme in chapter 8, already touched on. In Pannenberg’s kenoticist understanding of the Cross, Christ delivers himself to death freely, and because of God’s fidelity, his death is salvific. White readily acknowledges the many merits of Pannenberg’s recapitulation of the New Testament data. Still, it is incomplete. The death of Christ itself is no longer a divine act—a humanly conscious 1286 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. act of someone who knows he is divine and knows that his actions will save for all time. It may be that, for Pannenberg, as for Barth, Christ’s obedience reveals his divine sonship to us. But what we cannot say is that Jesus knowingly lays down his life as the God-man (370). The divine will that this act will save remains extrinsic to the human act of Jesus, and we end up in a sort of soteriological Nestorianism: the two tracks of the divine intention of the Son of God and of the human intention of Jesus never meet undividedly and inseparably in one act. Rather, White argues, “Christ can choose to redeem the world freely in love only because he knows of the value of his sacrifice, and its meaning. His act of free self-offering requires that he know that he has been sent by the Father for our salvation, but it also requires that he know who he himself is who is making the offering” (356). The Thomism we thought we knew shows an unexpected contemporaneity and power when White closely contrasts it with modern greats. The contemporary gnosiological and soteriological Nestorianisms delimited in chapters 5 and 8 are echoes of the more original Nestorian temptation. For there is also the first verse of Hassler’s Chorale to be made good, where Christ is addressed: “O sacred Head, now wounded, with grief and shame weighed down, now scornfully surrounded with thorns, thine only crown.” If the head really is “sacred,” and if also the grief and anguish are wounds of a similarly sacred sensibility and will, what must be true of the ontology of Christ? As we know, what must not be true is Nestorianism. This, too, has been an issue in contemporary Christology, and White deals with it in his first chapter. Karl Rahner, White explains, wanted a Christology that returned us to a serious consideration of the human freedom and agency of Christ. Rahner thinks this is prevented, however, by the view that the humanity of Christ is the instrument of the Word, for this obscures the humanity of Jesus in its freedom and autonomy. Moreover, it is precisely the human agency and historical consciousness of Christ that should disclose his divine identity. Rahner thinks to meet both issues by a “Christology of consciousness” in which the created grace with which Christ’s humanity is endowed and which flowers in the immediate vision of God becomes the grace of union itself: Christ’s human act of surrender to God in the fullness of his awareness of God is, for Rahner, the very act of God being among us, and in this way the divinity of Christ is revealed. While acknowledging Rahner’s intention to say nothing to impugn the Church’s Christological Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1287 dogma, White situates Rahner’s response to the invitation of a greater historical attention to the human career of Jesus against other attempts antecedent and subsequent to Rahner, medieval and contemporary, to found the union of divinity and humanity in Christ in the order of grace and the graced second acts (operations) of the man Jesus—that is, in the broadly Nestorian way of speaking of Christ. But the head of Christ is not sacred unless the grace of union is the uncreated person of the Son subsisting in his human nature. Thence it follows, as White observes, that the humanity of Jesus is indeed the instrument of the Word: a way of exercising agency is, as it were, a sort of organon of the agent. But it does not follow that this instrument is therefore changed and loses its native freedom, and nor does it follow that he can no longer be understood to reveal (but not constitute) himself and his divinity in the categories of first-century Palestinian Judaism. Theological Anthropology A third contribution is White’s consideration of the relation of Christology to theological (and therefore also philosophical) anthropology. In the first place, and logically prior to insisting on the analogical understanding of the two natures of Christ, he argues for the necessity of a philosophically available concept of nature by which we can appreciate what Christ does and does not bring to us. This was the topic of chapter 2. But White returns to philosophical anthropology at the end of his volume (chapters 9 and 10, on Christ’s descent into hell and his resurrection from the dead). There have been two desires, launching two theoretical projects, that have challenged the way in which classical Christology illustrated and governed basic tenets of the Church’s theological anthropology, which may be summarized as follows. Christ’s death is the separation of his soul from his body—for Thomists, of his unique substantial form from his body. His soul continues to exist, since it is strictly immaterial and subsistent, between his death and his resurrection. Like all human beings, Christ has completed the trajectory of his human life; he has run the course and finished the race: after death, there are no mission-defining decisions left for him to take, nor could his soul naturally compass such decisions in its disembodied state. His descent to the abode of the dead is not the completion of his mission as deed, but consists simply in the announcement of his victory to those in hell, purgatory, and the place of the just. Christ’s resurrection, on the other hand, means that his humanity is made 1288 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. whole: body and soul, both of which remained hypostatically united to the Word, are rejoined, and rejoined in the state of glory. Only so is Christ’s victory realized in himself, and only so is our own final hope manifested to us in convincing form. His completed and glorified humanity is no longer an instrument of meriting grace or of vanquishing the devil, but it nonetheless continues as the instrument of the application of already merited grace to all who seek him with a sincere heart. He intercedes for us according to the merit already won on the Cross. Two modern desires, however, subject this view, both as to Christ and to our own imitation of his pattern (a death which imitates his as completing our destiny, an interim state like his between death and resurrection, but in which no reversals or conversions or apostasy is possible, and resurrection) to serious strain. A first desire is to maintain the possibility of God’s offer of saving grace through Christ to sinners after death. This requires man’s freedom to be conceived in such a way that it does not complete itself in this life and that it can complete itself, as perhaps finding an even better space of responding to God, in a disembodied existence where freedom is still to be exercised. Of course, one can postulate whatever is needed for such a state of affairs to be realized. If one’s view of man’s nature precludes a determining exercise of freedom after death, then one can suppose that the possibility is supplied by some preternatural gift giving the wherewithal to continue the journey of freedom. Or one can suppose that death always delivers us to the Christ who has (logically) preceded all men in the exercise of human freedom, such that death always consigns us to him, either in his glory or in a sort of atemporally available experience of the distance sin establishes between God and men. There, finding Christ with him in his alienation from God, the sinner finds also a sort of last offer of grace in solidarity that cannot be refused. White enables us to see the difficulties with such a view. Thinking about man’s condition after death is always difficult, but this view seems more ad hoc than most, and with little connection to a tradition earlier than Karl Barth’s Church Dogmatics. What exactly is the nature of man? And is embodiment a necessary factor of human perfection such that we make or break ourselves now, in time, and thence forever? Such anthropological constructions fashioned to make freedom still determinative after death do little to make us take this life seriously. Second and more importantly, White alerts us to the high price we pay in forfeiting any consummation of meaning and Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1289 moral direction to human freedom in this life, for he reminds us of the kinship of this forfeiture with Duns Scotus’s view of the relation of human to divine freedom, where it is not man’s rejection of grace but God’s decision to stop offering grace that determines our destiny. A second modern desire is to re-conceive the event of death in such a way that the interim state of dis-embodied souls, the idea of which is distrusted paradoxically at one and the same time as both mythological and yet philosophically indebted to Greek philosophy, is completely avoided. Thus there is postulated the idea of an instant and not-to-be-delayed “resurrection in death,” which Rahner and Balthasar have both welcomed. This view obviates the problem of a disembodied human freedom, but it, too, has hidden costs. First, once again, it is a whistle while passing the graveyard: we avoid the fearsomeness of death and the very idea of an existence that is only ghostly and incomplete—which is to say, this view de-potentiates the existential seriousness with which we should face death. Second, it has its own philosophical background, to be found in Kant’s view of the distinction of the empirical from the transcendental subject. What is really and only decisively important is what happens beyond the veil of sensibility and the categories of understanding in the noumenal realm where we see realities face to face. But again, this amounts to devaluing this life as the final place of mission, decision, destiny. Third, what happens to Christ’s resurrection on this view? Does he rise twice, empirically and noumenally? We should rather think that his resurrection as reported in the Gospels confirms this life as the venue in which human reality is completed and perfected. His resurrection, re-uniting body and soul, illustrates rather the truth of the theological anthropology to be found in the Catechism of the Catholic Church. Christology Is Not History The volume’s conclusion,“Why Christology Is Not Primarily a Historical Science,” reprises the argument for an ontologically informed Christology by showing the inability of a wholly hermeneutically governed Christology, such as that of Eduard Schillebeeckx, to resist the depredations of modern Nietzscheans like Jacques Derrida and Michel Foucault. Schillebeeckx finished his career as a sort of pure instance of what White thinks is wrong with Christology today: disavowal of classical metaphysics and entrance into Enlightenment historicism. But without express metaphysical sophistication, Schillebeeckx has no defense against the charge that he, too, is engaged in only a superficial 1290 Guy Mansini, O.S.B. semiotic exercise, and perhaps some form of the will to power. White confronts these postmodern views with the arguments of Alasdair MacIntyre (Three Rival Versions) and Aristotle (Metaphysics IV). Under the title “Inevitable Scholasticism,” he again reasserts the relevance of metaphysics to Christology, showing how the narratives that are the object of Schillebeeckx’s hermeneutically minded Christology presuppose the time-transcending scope of the human mind. The more ambitious object of this conclusion of the book’s argument, however, is to the effect that the Christology White envisages deserves to be called “science” according to the very notion Aristotle gives this term at the beginning of Western high culture. This is a common aim of the Thomistic Ressourcement Series to which White’s volume belongs. Would not that reestablish a sort of diachronic healing of memory? What Chenu gave us as a historical, time-bound and culture-bound artifact, White gives us a perennially and time-transcending possibility. What are the chances here? How can Christology, whose subject is an individual and particular man, be the subject of a science that deals with the universal and gives explanations of human hopes that are truly causal? The chances are the chances of faith. White takes up this medieval objection in the form it took in the eighteenth century, the “ugly, broad ditch” between the contingent facts of history and the necessary truths of reason that Gotthold Lessing could not leap. But according as Christ is man and God, and according as there is a revealed science of God, Christology is also certainly a science, one whose object includes the universal agent of redemption and the universal cause of our salvation, and one that the mysteries of the Incarnation, atonement, and resurrection give us to contemplate. Because Christ is also the exemplary cause of our salvation in his glorified humanity beholding God, Christology is also practical and, like theology generally, is the wisdom that unites both speculative and practical truth—both the way and the truth leading to life. In this light, White reminds us of Christology’s capacity to provide a framework in which every truth, not just philosophic but also scientific and historical, can find a home and recognize its relation to every other truth. Christology therefore embraces the natural lights of all the modern studies concerned with development across time—cosmology, New Testament historical studies, and a teleologically conceived ethics—and thus vindicates, as to the last mentioned discipline, the claim that theology is not only science, but wisdom. Review Essay of Thomas Joseph White’s The Incarnate Lord 1291 This evocation of the universitas artium et scientiarum in the last pages of The Incarnate Lord recalls the institutional, economic, political will it would take in the contemporary world to make White’s contribution a seed of a more abundant harvest, yielding thirty or sixty or a hundred fold. Catholic University Press, with its Thomistic Ressourcement Series, is a hopeful sign. Where to end? The clarity of White’s exposition and argument over very detailed and difficult ground is wholly admirable. Also, the courtesy with which he engages all his interlocutors and discusses all positions is a model for how theological disputation should be carried out. What, after all, is theology for? This is a book of high ambition and deep seriousness. White is not interested in being original or in winning points; he is interested in displaying the ever-contemporary wisdom of St. Thomas. He is interested in helping us all behold the Christ more truly and with greater love, and he is interested, insofar as a theologian can think himself to be, in winning souls. The IncarN&V nate Lord is an apostolic work. Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1293–1340 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization: Hahn and Wiker’s Unmasking of Historical Criticism’s Political Agenda by Laying Bare its Philosophical Roots Jeffrey L. Morrow Immaculate Conception Seminary School of Theology Seton Hall University South Orange, NJ “The dismemberment of the Bible has led to a new variety of allegorism: One no longer reads the text but the supposed experience of supposed communities. The result is often highly fanciful allegorical interpretation.” —Joseph Ratzinger, The Nature and and Mission of Theology1 Scott Hahn and Benjamin Wiker’s Politicizing the Bible: The Roots of Historical Criticism and the Secularization of Scripture 1300–1700 is the single most important work to date in the history of modern biblical scholarship. As their subtitle, “Secularization of Scripture,” indicates, these authors particularly have in mind the ways in which the interpretation and the study of Scripture have been secularized over the course of centuries. Far too rarely in brief surveys of biblical scholarship has the role of politics and philosophy been addressed, let alone addressed adequately. In this more than 600–page book, Hahn and Wiker demonstrate how various political concerns and Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, The Nature and Mission of Theology: Approaches to Understanding Its Role in the Light of Present Controversy, trans. Adrian Walker (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2004), 65. 1 1294 Jeffrey L. Morrow undergirding philosophies shaped and guided the long process that led to the historical critical method of biblical interpretation. They situate this process within the broader historical, political, philosophical, and theological contexts in which historical criticism was formed. Moreover, they also situate the contributions of the major figures involved in this process within the context of their biographies, which proves so necessary for understanding this history. Hahn and Wiker consider an expansive and often neglected period within the history of modern biblical criticism.2 Although the authors do not divide the book into sections, I would divide it roughly into two parts (excluding the introductory first chapter and the concluding thirteenth chapter): the first part (chs. 2–7), lays the groundwork for the advent of historical criticism. The second part (chs. 8–12), shows key examples of the development of historical criticism as it evolved throughout the seventeenth century, laying the essential groundwork for the Enlightenment biblical criticism of the eighteenth century and what would follow that in the nineteenth century. First, Hahn and Wiker show how Marsilius of Padua’s and William of Ockham’s arguments justify the subordination of church to state, due to Marsilius’s Averroist philosophical underpinnings and Ockham’s nominalism. Following these two, such Averroist and nominalist philosophies would continue to undergird much of the future of historical critical exegesis. After this, Hahn and Wiker show how Wycliffe’s attack upon nominalism inadvertently supported the same sort of exegesis and subordination of church to state as had Marsilius and Ockham. Thus, for theological reasons (and philosophical reasons directly Scott Hahn and Benjamin Wiker, Politicizing the Bible: The Roots of Historical Criticism and the Secularization of Scripture 1300–1700 (New York: Crossroad, 2013); all parenthetical citations of page numbers without identification of source in the main text of the present article refer to this volume). For brief article-length overviews likewise emphasizing the political history moving from the medieval period into the nineteenth century, overlapping with some of the figures they study (Marsilius, Ockham, Machiavelli, Hobbes, Spinoza, and Simon), see Jeffrey L. Morrow, “Cut Off from Its Wellspring: The Politics Behind the Divorce of Scripture from Catholic Moral Theology,” Heythrop Journal 56 (2015): 547–58; Morrow, “Secularization, Objectivity, and Enlightenment Scholarship:The Theological and Political Origins of Modern Biblical Studies,” Logos 18 (2015): 14–32; Morrow, “The Modernist Crisis and the Shifting of Catholic Views on Biblical Inspiration,” Letter & Spirit 6 (2010): 265–80, especially 267–73; and Morrow, “The Politics of Biblical Interpretation: A ‘Criticism of Criticism,’” New Blackfriars 91 (2010): 528–45, especially 530–43. 2 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1295 opposed to Ockham), Wycliffe brought to English and, through his followers, to German soil the subordination of the church to the state for which Marsilius and Ockham had argued. Thus, the ground was set for the German and English Reformations that would soon follow. Next, Hahn and Wiker turn to Machiavelli, showing how he created a hermeneutic of suspicion in which, much like Averroës, he saw religion as a veil for more crafty political machinations of hypocritical rulers. From Machiavelli, Hahn and Wiker turn to Luther and the Protestant Reformation, where they indicate that Luther and his co-Reformers were inspired in part by the widespread corruption among clerical leaders within the Catholic hierarchy. Luther was a nominalist and self-identified follower of Ockham. Luther built on the groundwork laid by Marsilius and Wycliffe and inadvertently aided in the transformation of the public, civic realm into a secular realm in which state controlled church. After Luther, Hahn and Wiker examine the English Reformation of King Henry VIII, showing how his reforming policy built on all the influential figures previously discussed: Marsilius (directly through Henry’s advisors); Ockham (implied, through the German Protestant influence);3 Wycliffe (through the influence of the English Lollardy that had so shaped English nationalist aspirations and prepared the groundwork in Germany for the Reformation); Machiavelli (directly, through Henry’s advisors); and Luther (through the Protestant reforming agenda in England). They next turn to Descartes, expositing his role in effecting a great cosmological shift in which nature becomes mathematized and geometry emerges as the primary form of rationality, setting the stage for a secular cosmos devoid of God and the supernatural and, thus, preparing the ground for a fully secular biblical hermeneutic. Hahn and Wiker scarcely make mention of the influence of Ockham in the chapter on Henry VIII, but in light of their chapter on Luther (and Ockham’s clear and unambiguous influence on Luther), as well as Luther’s influence on Henry’s regime (and on the influence of Tyndale, which they mention), and in light of how influential Ockham (having taught at Oxford) was on English soil, they should probably have explored this indirect influence. The most they write is that “Tyndale repeated the complaints of Ockham and Luther about the use of allegory in scriptural exegesis” (Politicizing the Bible, 228), and buried in a footnote, “appeal to councils over the pope was found both in Ockham and in Marsilius” (ibid., 240n71). See also their comment that “Tyndale would seem to affirm an almost Pelagian understanding of the ability to fulfill the law (which looks quite similar to the quasi-Pelagian notion among nominalists that so enraged Luther)” (ibid., 230). 3 1296 Jeffrey L. Morrow Hahn and Wiker’s chapter on Thomas Hobbes begins what I suggest is the second part of their book. Hobbes’s contribution matters inasmuch as he provides a secularized exegesis that makes sense for an atomist-mechanist worldview. He was clearly influenced by Descartes and Machiavelli, and his exegesis supports the kind of state Henry VIII created. Moreover, his political exegesis helps lead to the next figure in Hahn and Wiker’s history, namely Spinoza. Hahn and Wiker not only trace the many influences on Spinoza’s thought (including Averroës, Machiavelli, Descartes, and Hobbes) but also situate him within his early radical Enlightenment context, showing how his work played an important role in the later Enlightenment. Spinoza tried to construct a scientific biblical exegesis that, like Hobbes’s hermeneutic and Descartes’s philosophy, attempted to bring peace to a Europe torn asunder by a violence they all identified as fundamentally religious in motivation. Hahn and Wiker move from Spinoza to a seventeenth-century critic of Spinoza, Fr. Richard Simon, who took Spinoza’s method as a starting point in order to critique Spinoza, challenge Protestant notions of sola Scriptura, and buttress Catholic tradition. Ironically, Simon in fact extended Spinoza’s hermeneutic and ensured its survival among biblical scholars in the future. After Simon, Hahn and Wiker examine the work of John Locke, illustrating how he built upon the methods of exegesis of Hobbes, Spinoza, and Simon, in order to support the politics in which he very actively played a part. After Locke, they finish their history with a look at the work of John Toland and the beginning of English Deist biblical exegesis, showing not only how Toland built upon the work of those that came before (e.g., Machiavelli, Spinoza, and Simon) but also how his conclusions demonstrate that the most radical effects of historical criticism in the nineteenth century were already in place, intrinsic in the methods themselves, at the end of the seventeenth century. Finally, Hahn and Wiker conclude by identifying some of the ways the history they have recounted plays out in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, primarily through the receptions of Spinoza and Simon, but also of Toland and, at least to some extent, Machiavelli. Their overarching argument “is that the development of the historical-critical method in biblical studies is only fully intelligible as part of the more comprehensive project of secularization that occurred in the West over the last seven hundred years, and that the politicizing of the Bible was, in one way or another, essential to this Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1297 project” (8).4 In roughly the first half of their volume, Hahn and Wiker show how the stage is set for the drama of historical criticism’s evolution. In the second half, they illustrate how specific exegetes operated within the intellectual and political world created by the figures discussed in the first half. Hahn and Wiker write with a clarity often missing in scholarly works, and this is doubly impressive because of the complexity of the issues discussed. By necessity, their large tome spans a host of seemingly unrelated topics, each thread of which ultimately fits together into the tapestry they are weaving: medieval theological debates about poverty and evangelical perfection; papal and clerical reform and corruption; the investiture controversy; the Latin Averroist reception of Aristotle; Machiavelli’s new politics of princely rule; the renaissance retrieval of classical literature; the selling of indulgences; attempts by state rulers to curb the flow of money leaving their realms; the dissolution of monasteries; the justification debate; theological controversies over the sacraments; the so-called “wars of religion” of sixteenth- and seventeenth- century Europe; Cartesian geometry; the creation of epistemology; the early modern revival of ancient Epicurean mechanistic atomism; Dutch Jewish heterodox intellectuals; the reception of Descartes in the Dutch Republic; the English civil wars; among many other topics. The narrative Hahn and Wiker create makes this book not only informative, insightful, and persuasive, but also a real pleasure to read. The scholar looking for a reference work spanning the history of biblical interpretation from biblical times through the twentieth century should turn to Henning Graf Reventlow’s four-volume work Epochen der Bibelauslegung.5 The scholar seeking a reference work that They explain that, “By politicization, we mean the intentional exegetical reinterpretation of Scripture so as to make it serve a merely political, this worldly (hence secular) goal” (Politicizing the Bible, 9). 5 Henning Graf Reventlow, Epochen der Bibelauslegung, vol. 1, Von Alten Testament bis Origenes (Munich: Beck, 1990); Reventlow, Epochen der Bibelauslegung, vol. 2,Von der Spätantike bis zum ausgehenden Mittelalter (Munich: Beck, 1994); Reventlow, Epochen der Bibelauslegung, vol. 3, Renaissance, Reformation, Humanismus (Munich: Beck, 1997); Reventlow, Epochen der Bibelauslegung, vol. 4, Von der Aufklärung bis zum 20. Jahrhundert (Munich: Beck, 2001). Each of these volumes exist in English translation: Reventlow, History of Biblical Interpretation, vol. 1, From the Old Testament to Origen, trans. Leo G. Perdue (Atlanta, GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2009); Reventlow, History of Biblical Interpretation, vol. 2, From Late Antiquity to the End of the Middle Ages, trans. James O. Duke (Atlanta, GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2009); Reventlow, History of Biblical Interpretation, vol. 3, Renaissance, Reformation, Humanism, trans. James O. Duke 4 1298 Jeffrey L. Morrow focuses on the history of Old Testament interpretation from biblical times through the twentieth century, for the most exhaustive treatment to date, ought to find Magne Sæbø’s edited multi-volume Hebrew Bible/Old Testament: The History of Its Interpretation.6 The scholar who wants more than a reference book, however, will profit greatly from Hahn and Wiker’s volume. In what follows below, I will comment in greater detail as I provide a more thorough overview of each chapter. The Pathos of Historical Criticism: Politically Interested Biblical Interpretation Chapter 1, “Getting to the Roots of the Historical-Critical Method” (1–16), serves as an introduction to the entire work. Hahn and Wiker begin by calling into question the objective neutrality of the historical-critical method, asserting that it has never been disinterested and neutral and that it has not always been articulated as such. From this preliminary discussion, they proceed to discuss the values and merits, as well as limitations, of a number of significant works that detail the history of modern biblical criticism.7 They use this helpful survey of (Atlanta, GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2010); and Reventlow, History of Biblical Interpretation, vol. 4, From the Enlightenment to the Twentieth Century, trans. Leo G. Perdue (Atlanta. GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2010). 6 Magne Sæbø, ed., Hebrew Bible/Old Testament: The History of Its Interpretation, vol. 1, From the Beginnings to the Middle Ages (Until 1300), pt. 1, Antiquity (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1996): Sæbø, ed., Hebrew Bible/Old Testament: The History of Its Interpretation, vol. 1, From the Beginnings to the Middle Ages (Until 1300), pt. 2, The Middle Ages (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2000); Sæbø, ed., Hebrew Bible/Old Testament:The History of Its Interpretation, vol. 2, From the Renaissance to the Enlightenment (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2008); Sæbø, ed., Hebrew Bible/Old Testament: The History of Its Interpretation, vol. 3, From Modernism to Post-Modernism (The Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries), pt. 1, The Nineteenth Century—A Century of Modernism and Historicism (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2013); Sæbø, ed., Hebrew Bible/Old Testament: The History of Its Interpretation, vol. 3, From Modernism to Post-Modernism (The Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries), pt. 2, The Twentieth Century (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2014). 7 For a comparable survey of primarily fourteen significant works (including six of the volumes surveyed by Hahn and Wiker) in the history of historical-criticism, see Jeffrey L. Morrow, “The Enlightenment University and the Creation of the Academic Bible: Michael Legaspi’s The Death of Scripture and the Rise of Biblical Studies,” Nova et Vetera (English) 11 (2013): 899–909 (particularly 899–900n6, 900n7, 900–01n9, 903n13, 904–05n18, 906–07n22, and 908n23) for a more thorough list of sources spanning the years 1933–2013 within the history of biblical scholarship. Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1299 nine of the most significant works in the field to help situate their present project, which they distinguish from everything that has come before.8 After this roughly five-page survey (2–7), they underscore one of the distinctive marks of their work, namely, that their study ends in the seventeenth century, where most other such studies begin. Although it is commonplace in textbook accounts of historical criticism to see the method as a product of the nineteenth century, scholars increasingly identify its roots in the eighteenth and seventeenth centuries. In Politicizing the Bible, Hahn and Wiker suggest deeper roots, extending the historical-critical genealogical tree into the fourteenth century, at the end of the medieval period. As they explain, “The late-eighteenth-century Enlightenment is not the beginning of the conflict, but the culmination of several centuries of a slowly building new . . . secular worldview” (7).9 Hahn and Wiker emphasize how the roots of historical criticism and modern politics are linked, for example, in figures such as Marsilius of Padua, Machiavelli, Hobbes, Spinoza, and Locke. In addition, they underscore how the secular political agenda works through the historical-critical method through the nineteenth century and beyond, using the example of Ernst Troeltsch’s programmatic discussion of such a method in which the supernatural is systematically excluded (10–11).10 They make explicit an implied point that, “In The nine main books Hahn and Wiker discuss in this portion are: Werner Kümmel, The New Testament:The History of the Investigation of Its Problems, trans. S. McLean Gilmour and Howard C. Kee (Nashville, TN: Abingdon, 1972); William Baird, History of New Testament Research, vol. 1, From Deism to Tübingen (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress, 1992); Rudolph Smend, From Astruc to Zimmerli: Old Testament Scholarship in Three Centuries, trans. M. Kohl (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2007); Henning Graf Reventlow, The Authority of the Bible and the Rise of the Modern World, trans. J. Bowden (Philadelphia, PA: Fortress, 1985); Reventlow, History of Biblical Interpretation, 4 vols.; John Sandys-Wunsch, What Have They Done to the Bible? A History of Modern Biblical Interpretation (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 2005); Sæbø, ed., Hebrew Bible/Old Testament, vol. 2; Pierre Gibert, L’invention critique de la Bible: XVe–XVIIIe (Paris: Gallimard, 2010); and Roy Harrisville and Walter Sundberg, The Bible in Modern Culture: Baruch Spinoza to Brevard Childs, 2nd ed. (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2002). 9 They include here a parenthetical explanation bringing attention to the role of the comma in this sentence: “it’s not a new secular as opposed to the old secular.” 10 They refer to Ernst Troeltsch, “On Historical and Dogmatic Method in Theology,” in Religion in History, trans. J. Adams and W. Bense (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress, 1991), 11–32. 8 1300 Jeffrey L. Morrow doing so, it removes Christianity as a political force, making of it at best a bearer of nondogmatic moral teachings that undergird the political order” (11). What is significant here is that the guiding presuppositions of this method predetermine how modern biblical interpreters use history. Hahn and Wiker make clear that what is unique to modern historical biblical criticism is not the various scholarly tools of textual criticism, philology, archaeology, and so on that it employs. Rather, “This union of tools with secularizing presuppositions constitutes what is almost invariably meant by the historical-critical method” (12). They conclude this first chapter with a four-page summary of the rest of the book (12–16). The Poverty Dispute and the Subordination of the Church to the State: The Contributions of the Latin Averroist Marsilius of Padua (ca. 1275–1342) and the Nominalist William of Ockham (1288–1347) Hahn and Wiker’s second chapter, “The First Cracks of Secularism: Marsilius of Padua and William of Ockham” (17–59), lays the groundwork for what will come later, both in the volume and in the history of modern biblical criticism. They begin their chapter with a brief yet necessary history of the Avignon Papacy (18–22), which is an essential part of the historical and political background to Marsilius’s and Ockham’s discussions of Scripture. The main context here is the Franciscan poverty debate—the debate over ownership and use among clergy, like the Franciscans, who took a vow of poverty but needed to use books and, thus, libraries, etc., for various aspects of their religious life, including study for preaching (21–22). Pope John XXII entered the theological fray by denying the distinction between use and ownership. Under his predecessors Gregory IX, Nicholas III, and Clement V, such a distinction was permitted, and under Nicholas, the idea was that the papacy owned the material possessions that Franciscans merely used. The conflict raged within the Franciscans between the Conventuals and the Spirituals. The Conventuals prudentially attempted to apply Franciscan norms to their current obligations, whereas the Spirituals were bent on reforming their order in the face of what they took to be abuses of de facto wealth and luxury among their brother Franciscans who had taken vows of poverty. John XXII demurred against the idea that the papacy owned these possessions, declaring that the Franciscans owned what they used. Moreover, upset with what he took to be the Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1301 Spirituals’ abuses against their vows of obedience he called them to obey (21–22). At the same time, John XXII was at odds with Ludwig of Bavaria. Different factions supported different candidates for rule over the Germanic regions. Some factions believed that Ludwig was the rightful German emperor, whereas others understood Frederick I to be the lawful German emperor and lent their support to him. In light of this irreconcilable dispute, John XXII requested that both Ludwig and Frederick abdicate rule, and he, John XXII, as pope, would take over temporal rule over the Germanic realms in the meantime. When John XXII reopened the poverty debate that his predecessor Nicholas had closed, Ludwig quickly condemned John as a heretic, using the Franciscan conflict with the pope as a political means of attacking the papacy.11 Another aspect to this conflict, not lost on Hahn or Wiker, is the actual wealth and luxury of the papal court in Avignon, which likely accentuated the sting of the Spiritual Franciscan critique. Although the Conventuals in general, and Michael of Cesena in particular, the Franciscan’s Minister General, would have likely applauded Pope John’s call to obedience for the Spirituals, they were outraged by his reopening what they thought had been a closed debate, resolved in their favor under John’s predecessor (18–22). Marsilius of Padua (23–39) and William of Ockham (39–57) found themselves right in the middle of these controversies, as they both came to reside under Ludwig’s protection from John XXII. It was with Marsilius that medieval Muslim Averroist philosophy became important and eventually exerted a significant influence on later biblical criticism. The Muslim philosopher Ibn Rushd or Averroës was an important and influential commentator on the work of the Greek philosopher Aristotle. Averroës noticed, as had others, that the teachings of the Qur’an were not always consistent with Aristotle’s thought. Thus, Averroës reasoned that truth is known differently depending on the different abilities of the one knowing the truth. Philosophers stand at the pinnacle of his hierarchy. What this Averroist notion entailed was the “superiority of the truths of natural reason to those of revelation” (23), and this led to what has For further background to this debate over Franciscan poverty in the context of debates about papal authority and infallibility, see James Heft, John XXII and Papal Teaching Authority (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1986), and Brian Tierney, Origins of Papal Infallibility, 1150–1350: A Study on the Concepts of Infallibility, Sovereignty and Tradition in the Middle Ages (Leiden: Brill, 1972), neither of which Hahn and Wiker use. 11 1302 Jeffrey L. Morrow been called the “double truth” approach of the “Latin Averroist” tradition. This Latin Averroism found an important home at the University of Padua, from whence it spread throughout Europe. Marsilius imbibed this philosophy while studying there, and later as rector at the University of Paris, which was another major Averroist center in the west (23–25). Hahn and Wiker examine Marsilius’s incredibly influential political treatise Defensor Pacis, an anti-papal work completed in 1324. They point out that Marsilius’s treatise was “revolutionary, a landmark philosophical document in the secularization of the West” (25). The politics of Marsilius’s work were grounded in reason apart from faith. His primary concern was to secure civil peace, which indeed became the main goal, the highest good, for Marsilius. Hahn and Wiker explain that, “Although Marsilius is evidently concerned with undermining papal authority in the political realm, his ultimate concern is the radical reordering of secular and sacred authority, so that the priesthood is firmly subordinated to political power” (26). Marsilius was relying on Aristotle to make this claim, but Aristotle as filtered through Averroës, and what is more, a very “truncated view” of Aristotle’s thicker description of politics (28). Marsilius’s use of the Bible in Defensor Pacis “serves the secularizing aim of Marsilius’s politics” (29). That is, Marsilius used Scripture whenever he was able to twist its interpretation to serve merely secular ends. In the end, the secular state Marsilius envisioned was to be in control of biblical interpretation (24–34). Moreover, for Marsilius, the state should have control of church offices so that the state can control ecclesiastical decisions (33–34). He additionally asserted a sort of early conception of sola Scriptura where the Bible supplanted church authority and tradition, but it was a Bible authoritatively interpreted, not by the individual, but the state ruler and state-appointed exegetes (32–34). In his view, the Old Testament no longer plays a role for Christians, nor should recourse be made to a spiritual sense of Scripture, only to a literal sense. These latter rejections are based on Marsilius’s understanding of how pro-papal exegetes used the Old Testament and allegorical interpretation to support the authority of the papacy (34–36). Marsilius never intended for the Defensor Pacis to remain a merely theoretical work, but rather it contained a practical means of subordinating the papacy to the state. Thus, Marsilius jumped on the contemporary Franciscan anti-John XXII bandwagon and, “Arguing on behalf of the absolute poverty of Christ and the Apostles through appeal to the New Testa- Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1303 ment, Marsilius sought to strip the papacy of temporal power so that a secular ruler could establish a purely secular rule” (37). William of Ockham would eventually join Marsilius, both literally under Ludwig’s protection, and ideologically, but with a different and more spiritual purpose. Ockham got into trouble with John XXII and fled Avignon, along with Michael of Cesena, to the protection of Ludwig, from where he attacked the papacy of John XXII and succeeding popes. Hahn and Wiker importantly observe, “Unlike Marsilius, Ockham does not subordinate the ecclesiastical powers to the political powers; rather, he attempts to reinstate, against later papal pretensions, the generally accepted medieval view that the sacred and the secular are two distinct powers” (40). Because Ockham saw an extraordinary need for church reform, he argued for the ability and necessity of secular rulers ruling over sinful prelates. Tied to this concept was Ockham’s emphasis on the role of biblical periti (experts) or specialists who should be in charge of biblical interpretation. This would play itself out later in the history of biblical criticism, especially in and after the Enlightenment. For Ockham, the specialist or expert is over a council, over the pope, and even over Catholic tradition, when it comes to biblical interpretation (44–47). Hahn and Wiker examine Ockham’s The Work of Ninety Days, A Dialogue, and Breviloquium. From here, they begin their discussion of Ockham’s nominalism (47–56), which will be important for later discussions, particularly in the Reformation. To their credit, Hahn and Wiker engage in the ongoing scholarly debate about whether or not Ockham was a true nominalist. They show, however, that the traditional use of nominalism to deny the existence of universals fits Ockham fairly well (47–56, 47–48n119, 49–50n123, and 53n130). In contrast with the Latin Averroists, Ockham describes God’s will operating in a way that appears arbitrary; there are no means of limiting God’s will and thus violating God’s absolute sovereignty (50–53). Through this discussion, Hahn and Wiker show how Ockham began to mathematize rationality, paving the way for later philosophers like Descartes who “would substitute mathematical forms as the new universals” (52): the vacuum created by Ockham and his nominalist philosophy would eventually be filled by mathematics, materialism, and so on (53). Like Marsilius, Ockham would place emphasis on the literal sense, but their literal sense differed from more traditional notions (as, e.g., found in St. Thomas Aquinas): for Marsilius and Ockham, the literal sense was a reading of Scripture wherein the words of Scripture 1304 Jeffrey L. Morrow signified particular realities, as the authors intended, in the way any other human work signified realities.12 Hahn and Wiker conclude this chapter by noting the rapidity with which Ockham’s thought would spread from the University of Paris throughout Europe. Disendowing the Church: John Wycliffe’s (ca. 1330–1384) Inadvertent Secularization of Exegesis Chapter 3, “John Wycliffe” (61–115), is another foundational chapter laying the groundwork for later Reformation exegesis. Hahn and Wiker show how Wycliffe’s metaphysical realism grounded his entire theo-political and exegetical project. Wycliffe was upset about the popularity of nominalist philosophy, but also with ecclesiastical corruption. Although Wycliffe never learned Greek or Hebrew, he thought such study was methodologically extremely important for proper biblical interpretation. In a very Marsilian and Ockhamite fashion, he passionately argued that the state had an obligation to control the civil realm and should thus take control of the Church’s temporal goods. As Hahn and Wiker explain, for Wycliffe, “reform of the sacred could only be achieved if the Church’s riches and temporal power were taken away by the civil secular sword” (66). It should not come as a surprise that his “works received a ready hearing among those in the royal court, for the king had every desire to control and divert payments flowing from England toward Avignon” (ibid.).13 Importantly, Hahn and Wiker contrast this with the example of Aquinas, for whom the doctrine of analogy emphasized the relationship between created realities in light of the Creator. They write, “Both human beings and God can signify according to the historical or literal sense, but only God, properly speaking, can signify in the spiritual sense for only He can create real things that signify other things. . . . God wrote allegories into creation itself ” (Politicizing the Bible, 55). On St. Thomas Aquinas’s biblical interpretation, and especially his understanding of the literal sense, see, e.g.: Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (hereafter, ST) I, q. 1, a. 10; Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de potentia, q. 4. a. 1; Aquinas, In Psalmos Davidis expositio, prooem.; John F. Boyle, “Authorial Intention and the Divisio Textus,” in Reading John with St.Thomas Aquinas:Theological Exegesis and Speculative Theology, ed. Michael Dauphinais and Matthew Levering (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2005), 3–8; and Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., Initiation à saint Thomas d’Aquin: Sa personne et son oeuvre, 2nd ed. (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires Fribourg, 2002), 41–45 and 84–85. 13 Although, Hahn and Wiker note that, “The English king did not want papal subsidies and tithes to cease, since in practice they were collected by royal officials who skimmed off half to three-quarters for the royal treasury” (Politicizing the Bible, 66n17). 12 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1305 Hahn and Wiker consider a number of Wycliffe’s works, particularly De Dominio Divino, De Civili Dominio, and De Officio Regis, wherein Wycliffe argues for the Church’s disendowment by the state. For Wycliffe, God granted dominion “on condition that the one exercising dominion is righteous” (ibid.). As with Luther’s later teaching on two kingdoms, Wycliffe made a distinction between two types of dominion, “civil” and “evangelical.” Based on his discussion in these works, he argued forcefully that, “the king can and should take away possessions of ecclesiastics if they are misusing them, or if the possessions themselves are inordinate, on the grounds that the unrighteous have no right of dominion—and further because disendowing the clergy returns them to their proper condition of Christlike poverty” (67). They turn next to a very important discussion of the development of a sort of English messianic nationalism that provides an essential context for understanding Wycliffe and, of course, what would later come in the English Reformation (68–71 and 74–75). Wycliffe must be situated within this broader context of rising English nationalism that moves the earlier Marsilian focus from imperial political power to Wycliffe’s concern for English national rule. When it comes to Wycliffe’s biblical exegesis, Hahn and Wiker examine his De veritate sacrae scripturae. For Wycliffe, Jesus is the true Word of God, and the scriptural texts are not, but merely are informed by Christ the Word (75–81). Wycliffe made it abundantly clear that he saw his metaphysical realism, his philosophy, as a necessary prerequisite for proper exegesis (81–86). It is from his philosophical position, informed by his socio-political context, that Wycliffe buttresses his arguments for the state’s forceful disendowment of the Church with passages from Scripture (86–88). Within this context, Wycliffe savagely critiqued religious orders, and particularly monasteries, that tied up so much land and represented, for Wycliffe, the Church’s corruption (89–91). “Court theologians,” such as Wycliffe were necessary, so he argued, to aid the state in its job of putting Church authorities in their proper place. Hahn and Wiker describe Wycliffe’s position thus: “The unsheathed sword of the temporal power is not merely for punishing thieves, murderers, etc., but also (among other things) to keep the clergy from grasping at the temporal sword or inordinate temporal holdings” (93). Hahn and Wiker conclude their chapter by clearing up some confusions concerning the so-called Wycliffite Bible and by showing how his views spread and thus paved the way for the Reformation 1306 Jeffrey L. Morrow and what would come in later biblical scholarship (95–115). Contrary to the popular opinion that the Wycliffite Bible was revolutionary as an attempt to bring the Bible into the vernacular, Hahn and Wiker show how the translation of Scripture into the vernacular (of which the Wycliffite Bible was not the first) was not so revolutionary, but was rather part of a much broader transformation of England’s culture involving the transition from French to English more broadly. Wycliffe almost certainly did not, in fact, translate the Wycliffite Bible; it was completed by scholars sharing Wycliffe’s views (95–102). In the end, Wycliffe’s ideas survived, particularly in Bohemia among those Bohemians who came to England during the Bohemian Queen Ann’s marriage to England’s King Richard II (105 and 107). In Bohemia, Wycliffite theology and exegesis exerted a tremendous influence on John Hus and his Hussite followers (107–10). Both movements, the English Lollards (followers of Wycliffe) and Bohemian Hussites, sparked violent revolution and were thus put down as threats to their respective states. Nominalists, whose philosophy was directly opposed to that espoused by Wycliffe and Hus, were instrumental in attacking Hussites. Hahn and Wiker conclude their chapter by making the important observation that, “although Wycliffe was a declared enemy of Ockham, insofar as he set forth an almost Marsilian argument he had the unintended effect (as did Ockham) of reinforcing the secularizing, politicizing thrust of Marsilius’s thought” (113). The Prince as Religious Dissembler: Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) and First Signs of a Hermeneutic of Suspicion Chapter 4 is entitled simply “Machiavelli” (117–46). Hahn and Wiker acknowledge that a chapter on Machiavelli appears, at first blush, to be entirely out of place in a volume devoted to the history of historical biblical criticism (117). Indeed, they note that, of the volumes they survey at the outset of their tome, there is only one text where Machiavelli is discussed, and that only in “a single paragraph” (13).14 Machia That paragraph can be found in Trond Berg Eriksen, “Some Sociopolitical and Cultural Aspects of the Renaissance,” in Hebrew Bible/Old Testament II, ed. Sæbø, 102. Hahn and Wiker are being generous (albeit accurate) in stating that Machiavelli is herein discussed in “but a single paragraph.” In fact, that paragraph mentions only the following about Machiavelli: “Only with Francesco Guicciardini (1483–1540) and Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) do we encounter a more modern form of historiography that concerns itself with how causes work together to produce historical events. . . . In Machiavelli the study of history was motivated by an interest in the natural regularities that 14 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1307 velli’s social and historical context in Florence of the latter half of the fifteenth century is essential to understanding his oeuvre and, thus, his contribution to the later development of historical criticism. The universally recognized instances of the corruption of the papacy and of some members of the clergy constitute the necessary background to this social and historical context.15 Hahn and Wiker confess that, “in view of the notorious doings of the papacy and Church hierarchy during this period, religious hypocrisy had gone from being a scandal to an art. The damage done to the faith of the Church by the popes during Machiavelli’s lifetime is incalculable” (118), and they include a quotation that describes the papacy during this time as “a folly of perversity” (119).16 They lucidly show how Machiavelli universalized the hypocritical lives of his contemporary Renaissance popes to all religious leaders and how he read such religious hypocrisy back into the lives of biblical figures like Moses (122–23 and 131–46). That is, Machiavelli “assumes that all religion of any type is a façade for power” (122). Unlike what was to come later with figures like Spinoza, Machiavelli did not think such hypocrisy was always bad. In fact, he encouraged it. Machiavelli presents the reader with Pope Alexander VI as a paradigmatic prince (121–22). It was after being tortured during his imprisonment that Machiavelli would pen his The Prince (124–25). Significantly, he already had a wealth of personal political experience: he served as a secretary in Florence; as a formal representative of Florence, he had numerous dealings with Cesare Borgia, Alexander VI’s “ambitious and ruthless son” (124); he sought to create an effective army for Florence; he travelled to the German Holy Roman Emperor Maximilian I on behalf of Florence (124–25); and, perhaps most importantly, as a Florentine diplomat, he got to travel with Pope Julius II in battle. steer social and political processes. If factual accounts did not accord with a basic standard of accuracy, then one could not learn anything from history. Writers did not use history to exemplify wisdom they already possessed, but to find still hidden causal connections.” 15 On this, see, not only Hahn and Wiker’s discussion (Politicizing the Bible, 118–23), but also Eamon Duffy, Saints & Sinners: A History of the Popes, 3d ed. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006), 177–215; J. N. D. Kelly, The Oxford Dictionary of Popes (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1986), 250–58; and more recently, Mike Aquilina, Good Pope, Bad Pope (Cincinnati, OH: Servant Books, 2013), 100–10. 16 The quotation is from Barbara Tuchman, The March of Folly: From Troy to Vietnam (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1984), 52. 1308 Jeffrey L. Morrow Hahn and Wiker provide a very helpful analysis of The Prince (127–37) and Machiavelli’s Discourses on Livy (137–42) as they relate to the future of biblical studies. In The Prince, Machiavelli seeks to effect a transformation of politics from its ancient otherworldly orientation (as in Plato’s Republic) to a wholly this-worldly focus in which the “goal is the preservation of power” (128). In Hahn and Wiker’s words, “Machiavelli’s Prince is . . . the manual by which one unlearns Plato’s Republic” (130), but they proceed to show how it is much broader than that. Machiavelli seeks to secularize all politics for the very Marsilian goal of terrestrial peace. In order to do this, Machiavelli effects “a fundamental shift in the treatment of Scripture” (131). Biblical Moses is placed in the context of pagan political leaders, effectively secularizing his role within Scripture. Moses is no longer a leader called by God to mediate God’s covenant with the Israelites, but is transformed in Machiavelli’s exegesis into “a merely political leader” (131). Hahn and Wiker note that, because he was so inspired by Plutarch, Machiavelli was convinced that the biblical account needed a “corrective.” For Machiavelli, as Hahn and Wiker explain, the biblical account of Moses, in stark contrast to Plutarch’s histories, “does not appear to be the result of a careful sifting of multiple views of the same events, but presents itself simply as reporting what happened to Moses and the Israelites in their escape from Egypt and long trek to the Promised Land. Thus, the way is opened for exegetes to treat the Bible according to the mode of Plutarch. The sacred history must submit to a purification by reason, set critically against other historical sources. But in so doing, one can no longer treat it as sacred” (134–35). With his Discourses on Livy, Machiavelli consciously tries to create a modern critical history, where his “great labor is the recovery of history (or better, the pagan wisdom about history) shorn of the Christian overlay and interpretation” (138). Within this account, he shifts the question from religious veracity to its political utility (140). In Averroist fashion, Machiavelli sees religion as politically useful to keep order and control of a population, even though it is false. Whereas Averroës had a hierarchy of knowers (with philosophers at the top of the pyramid), Machiavelli focused on the political use of religion by princely rulers who use religious concepts to keep people in check. Thus, Hahn and Wiker consider Machiavelli to be “one of the earliest, and certainly the most influential, sources of the hermeneutics of suspicion” (144). They explain the way this will play out over time: Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1309 The biblical text contains a largely hidden message that only the wise can see. . . . But once we are enlightened then we too can interpret the text correctly. . . . To reason about Moses with Machiavelli means to offer an account of what really happened, appearances or reports in the text to the contrary. . . . The pattern set is one in which the philosophy, no matter how far removed it is from the assumptions of the biblical text, becomes the secret knowledge that allows the exegete to wield the exegetical threshing tool. . . . The task of the enlightened exegete, then, is to ferret out all the “real” passages—the ones that fit the philosophy—and reinterpret the rest, giving some other explanation for their appearance in the text. (145) Two Kingdoms Emerge: Martin Luther (1483–1546) & the New Exegesis of the Protestant Reformation Hahn and Wiker’s fifth chapter is “Luther and the Reformation” (147–219), and at over seventy pages, it is their largest chapter and could very well serve as a slender book on its own addressing the social, political, and historical context wherein the exegesis of the Protestant Reformation aided the movement toward modern historical biblical criticism. In this densely packed chapter, they deal with far more than simply Luther, including important discussions of the more radical Reformation represented by those like the Zwickau prophets (189–95, 200, and 209–12), Andreas Bodenstein von Karlstadt (189, 192–96, and 199–200), and Thomas Müntzer (190, 203, and 206–16). Hahn and Wiker begin this chapter by situating Luther in his broader nominalist context (147–50). They quote Luther’s confession of Ockham as both “the greatest dialectician” and his own “master,” among whose followers Luther numbers himself and whose teachings he claims to “have absorbed completely” (148). Such nominalism aided in Luther’s severing of faith and reason, which would lead to modern biblical scholars de-Hellenizing Scripture. Hahn and Wiker point out that, “ironically, in setting reason free in its own domain, nominalism contributed to its secularization, therefore duplicating the quasi-Averroist framework found in Marsilius of Padua” (149). They then discuss Luther’s life and early lectures on Aristotle, the Psalms, Romans, and Galatians (150–54). They next proceed to provide a very important historical discussion of the Reformation’s political context (154–57) that provides the essential lens for understanding the rest of the chapter, the Reformation, and all of the various political contexts of the theological and 1310 Jeffrey L. Morrow exegetical moves they see Luther and others making (154–219).17 At the outset, they approvingly quote the Reformation historians R. W. Scribner and C. Scott Dixon that, “from the very beginning, the question of religious reform was so inextricably linked to political issues that it could never give rise to an unpolitical Reformation” (154–55).18 The primary political context was an extension of the conflict between throne and altar already depicted in their chapter on Marsilius and Ockham. The Holy Roman Emperor Maximilian I had machinations of ruling the region that would become Italy, including the Papal States, but was also in conflict with the German electors, including Frederick III, Elector of Saxony and shortly protector of Luther. Frederick was also frustrated by the papal taxes and other financial revenue that was redirected to Rome and was likewise in conflict with his local bishops, most of whom were from the German nobility (155–57). Hahn and Wiker situate Luther’s Ninety-Five Theses and call to reform within the history of the call to reform already recounted, beginning with the poverty debate (158). They show how well the Theses fit within the guideposts of Catholic orthodoxy and assert that, “if Martin Luther’s criticisms of the Church had remained as they appeared in his ninety-five theses . . . there would likely have been no Protestant Reformation (or at least not one associated with Luther)” (158).19 The complicating economic and political factor was One of the few studies dealing with early modern contributions to historical biblical criticism that understands the role of politics and the Reformation is Travis L. Frampton, Spinoza and the Rise of Historical Criticism of the Bible (London: T&T Clark, 2006), especially 23–42, which Hahn and Wiker cite throughout (Politicizing the Bible, 217n323, 340n7, 342n11, 345n29, 348n42, 350n51, and 574). 18 The quotation is from R. W. Scribner and C. Scott Dixon, The German Reformation, 2nd ed. (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), 35. And further, in the attendant footnote wherein they provide this quotation’s citation(Politicizing the Bible, 155n39), they include another significant quotation from Reformation historian Martin Brecht: “From the very beginning in Wittenberg the monk Martin Luther was in a powerful political arena, even though at first he knew nothing about it. That he himself become a factor in this arena had religious and theological reasons. From the very moment when Luther appeared, speaking and acting independently, his involvement in a concrete political and social context also became inevitable”; in Martin Luther: His Road to Reformation, 1483–1521, trans. J. Schaaf (Philadelphia, PA: Fortress Press, 1985), 113. 19 They are able to say that because, as they point out, “Luther’s concern was originally with the abuse of indulgences” (Politicizing the Bible, 159), not with the doing away with indulgences or other Catholic teachings (ibid., 159, 17 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1311 that moneys for indulgences bled out of German regions and flowed to the papacy. Thus, Luther’s challenges to reform on the matter of indulgences fit conveniently into German national aspirations and into anger against Rome that had been fomenting for quite some time. Hahn and Wiker observe that, “unlike France and England, Germany had so far been unable to establish a kind of national church in which the monetary benefits remained largely within the realm” (160).20 They elaborate near the end of their chapter: “Without the desire for a national church, without national resentment between Italy and Germany, without German envy of the ‘national’ church of the French and the justified feeling that many Catholics were self-interested Romanists, without the protection of Romantic-messianic nationalists like [Ulrich von] Hutten, without the shield of the German princes, it is difficult to see how Lutheranism could have taken hold” (218). especially n55; here they quote several places within the Ninety-Five Theses where Luther writes favorably about indulgences—e.g., “Let him be anathema and accursed who denies the apostolic character of the indulgences,” found in thesis 71). On this, see also Gary A. Anderson, “Redeem Your Sins by the Giving of Alms: Sin, Debt, and the ‘Treasury of Merit’ in Early Jewish and Christian Tradition,” Letter & Spirit 3 (2007): 66–69n71. Regarding the Ninety-Five Theses, Anderson comments, “What emerges from this discussion is the significance of traditional acts of charity as opposed to the act of buying indulgences to assist in the refurbishing of St. Peter’s. Luther’s critique is not Church-dividing; he is at this point of his career a reformer within the bounds of Catholic thought” (ibid., 69n71). See also Anderson, Charity:The Place of the Poor in the Biblical Tradition (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 2013), 185. 20 See also William T. Cavanaugh, “‘A Fire Strong Enough to Consume the House’: The Wars of Religion and the Rise of the State,” Modern Theology 11 (1995): 397–420, especially 400–03. Cavanaugh writes, “There is a direct relationship between the success of efforts to restrict supra-national Church authority and the failure of the Reformation within those realms. In other words, wherever concordats between the Papal See and temporal rulers had already limited the jurisdiction of the Church within national boundaries, there the princes saw no need to throw off the yoke of Catholicism, precisely because Catholicism had already been reduced, to a greater extent, to a suasive body under the heel of the secular power” (ibid., 400–01). See also Cavanaugh, The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2009), especially ch. 3, “The Creation Myth of the Wars of Religion,” 123–80, where he revisits the thesis of his 1995 “Fire Strong Enough,” expanding it significantly (see particularly 166–70 regarding the discussion here). Although Hahn and Wiker do not cite these two works by Cavanaugh in this immediate context, they do cite both elsewhere throughout their volume (Politicizing the Bible, 12n45, 260n9, 338n226, and 570). 1312 Jeffrey L. Morrow It was with Luther’s turn to Scripture as sole authority (the Protestant principle of sola Scriptura) that the search for a method to replace Catholic Tradition became earnest (161–62). It was in the wake of theological divisions, each faction defending itself through Scripture, that Luther handed over the body to the state. Luther turned to the state, much like Wycliffe before him, to control the public secular realm (168). But it was with Luther’s understanding of the “priesthood of all believers” and grounding in no authority aside from Scripture that the peasants who rebelled saw Luther as their inspiration (169). Hahn and Wiker explain the upshot of Luther’s arguments, hinting at their trajectory: “Luther wanted to keep the papacy from claiming sole power to determine the meaning of Scripture as justification for its worldly use of power. But in conferring the power to interpret Scripture on all the laity, he inadvertently gave to secular sovereigns the kind of power over Scripture advocated by Marsilius and German nationalist humanists like Hutten, and also empowered multiple theological revolutions from below without a traditio to constrain them” (170). Hahn and Wiker likewise show how the declaration sola fide (justification by faith alone) became Luther’s hermeneutical key for unlocking Scripture’s meaning and, thus, how his idea of “promise” replaced the traditional role of typology (172–83). Upset with justifications of papal authority from spiritual exegesis, against which Ockham had earlier written as well, Luther severed Scripture’s intimate bond with the liturgy and erected sharp dichotomies between the “letter” and the “spirit,” the “law” and the “gospel,” and, importantly, the “Old” and “New” Testaments (174–77).21 Although Luther explicitly placed an exegetical emphasis on the literal sense, Hahn and Wiker caution, “it is misleading . . . to assume that the importance of Luther as an exegete is his focus on the literal account of Scripture; rather, his importance consists in substituting the dialectical mode of exegesis for the traditional fourfold meaning of Scripture” (177). Luther began to support state involvement in enforcing his version of orthodoxy. He found this necessary in the wake of the multiple radically diverse interpretations and positions that were emerging, at least ostensibly inspired by him (192–97). He began to realize, in Hahn and Wiker point out that, “in this dialectical hermeneutic, the Old Testament serves a largely negative function as law, rather than serving as the priestly, sacrificial foundation to be fulfilled in the New Testament” (Politicizing the Bible, 175). This will play out in significant ways in later historical criticism in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. 21 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1313 Hahn and Wiker’s words, that “the Bible in the hands of the masses is a dangerous thing” (194). Luther thus began to affirm a form of Erastianism wherein the state controlled the church, at least in the appointment of ecclesiastical officials (196). This is the origin of Luther’s doctrine on “two kingdoms,” church and state (201–06). Luther separated the realm of the secular from the realm of the sacred, as had Marsilius and Ockham before him, and thereby “contributed to the creation of an entirely secular political order” (203). Hahn and Wiker explain the upshot of Luther’s notion of two kingdoms: “Since Luther viewed political power as an ordained external force to keep sinners under control (rather than, as with Aristotle and St. Thomas [Aquinas], a positive order that helps perfect natural potentialities), his tendency (with Thomas Hobbes after him) was to view political order, no matter how harsh, as vindicated solely because any political order was better than the complete anarchy (the chaos of Satan) that would inevitably break loose without it” (204). Given this, it should come as no surprise that many German princes welcomed Luther’s teachings. After all, in the wake of the Peasant’s Revolt (which claimed to be inspired by Luther), Luther advised the civil rulers to demolish rebels without clemency. Specifically, he urged everyone to “smash, strangle, and stab, secretly or openly,” the peasants involved in the rebellion, “as a matter of Christian duty” (210).22 Again, as Hahn and Wiker make clear, “Luther’s doctrines did provide a way for German princes to break from Rome, and remain entirely in charge of the religion within their own peaceful realm, equally protected from the dangers of the likes of Karlstadt, Müntzers, and the Zwickau prophets” (210). To their credit, Hahn and Wiker concede that these princes may have had sincere doctrinal motives, but we cannot certainly know this, since such interior motives are private. Hahn and Wiker quote (213) from Scribner and Dixon on Luther’s reception and the sociology of the Reformation in Germany, a quote that includes an interesting political insight: After a brief period of mass enthusiasm, it [support for the Reformation] retreated to being a minority phenomenon. At a crude estimate, during the first generation of the Reformation, up to mid-century, and perhaps even during the second, probably no more than 10 per cent of the German population Hahn and Wiker take the first Luther quotation from Richard Marius, Martin Luther: The Christian between God and Death (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1999), 431. The second quotation is their own phrasing. 22 1314 Jeffrey L. Morrow ever showed an active and lasting enthusiasm for reformed ideas. Where massive numbers were “won” after 1526, to what became the new church, it occurred involuntarily, through a prince deciding that his territory should adopt the new faith. When we speak of the extensive hold “Protestantism” had on Germany by the second half of the sixteenth century . . . this was because there were large numbers of “involuntary Protestants” created by the princes’ confessional choices.23 Luther also adopted a notion that would develop over time within later biblical criticism, the idea of a “canon within the canon.” He explicitly exalted the Gospel of John, St. Paul’s epistles (particularly Romans, Galatians, and Ephesians), and 1 Peter, above all other portions of Scripture (197–201). After the Reformation, later within the history of modern historical biblical criticism, exegetes would move from Luther’s sifting through the canon to distinguish authentic books from less authentic (or even inauthentic) books, to sifting through individual biblical books themselves for the authentic “kernels.” Although Hahn and Wiker make no mention of Peter Abelard here, Luther’s task was doubtless already made possible by earlier works like Abelard’s Sic et non relating to the authenticity of sayings from Scripture and the Church fathers.24 They conclude, however, that, “despite Luther’s intentions, playing the authority of the princes against the papacy meant inadvertently giving the authority over interpretation to the secular powers” (217). This would prove to have a rather ironic result, as Hahn and Wiker point out: “Interpretive differences created a kind of industry of textual scholarship, producing more and more questions that only scholars had any hope of resolving. This had the interesting but entirely unintended effect of removing biblical interpretation from the hands of the common man to whom it had just been given, and handing it to academic experts, thereby creating an exegetical elite that duplicated the function of the Catholic traditio in defining interpretation authoritatively” (218). Scribner and Dixon, German Reformation, 34. Something similar can be said for the English Reformation, which Hahn and Wiker discuss in the following chapter. See, e.g., Eamon Duffy, The Stripping of the Altars:Traditional Religion in England 1400–1580 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2005). 24 For a critical edition, see Peter Abelard, Sic et Non: A Critical Edition, ed. Blanche B. Boyer and Richard McKeon (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976). See also the comments in Régine Pernoud, Héloïse et Abélard (Paris: Le Livre de Poche, 1970). 23 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1315 Disemboweling the Church: Henry VIII (1491–1547) and the Politicization of Exegesis in the English Reformation Chapter 6, “England and Henry VIII” (221–55), is an insightful look into the English Reformation, especially its intellectual roots and the ways in which this prepared the seedbed for what would germinate with historical criticism. It is often forgotten that historical criticism was born in the world of English Deism prior to entering the German academy in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. From the English Reformation (inspired in part by the German Reformation and the earlier Wycliffite trends of the Lollards in late medieval England) emerged the Deist biblical criticism that would later transplant itself into the academic culture of Germany in the Enlightenment and nineteenth century. As Hahn and Wiker maintain, “England becomes the filter through which earlier developments are handed on to the Enlightenment” (221–22). In this chapter, they succeed at situating King Henry VIII within his immediate context, especially the issue of the king’s “Great Matter,” his desire to marry Anne Boleyn (223–26, 230–36, and 245–51). Importantly, they point out that “the infamous divorce from Henry’s first wife was not the cause but the occasion for the creation of the official Church of England” (223). The king’s “Great Matter” has several ironies, not least of which is that Henry VIII had previously argued against divorce. The Christian ban on divorce was one of the chief marks, according to Henry, that set Christian marriage apart from non-Christian marriage (224). Henry entered into this early debate on account of Luther. Luther and other Protestant Reformers (including Philip Melanchthon and Martin Bucer) had been considering divorce and even polygamy (or at least bigamy) as permissible under certain circumstances (180–83). The infamous case the authors discussed earlier in their chapter on Luther involved Philip of Hesse’s desire to marry a second wife. The Reformers were able to make arguments in favor of divorce and bigamy precisely by de-sacramentalizing marriage. Henry VIII wrote a robust defense of marriage as a sacrament (224–25). Henry of course had numerous mistresses, and his “Great Matter” became so great when Anne Boleyn refused to be his mistress, settling for nothing less than the crown as his bride (225). In this chapter, Hahn and Wiker include a significant discussion of the early English translation of the Bible and the work of William Tyndale and how this fit within the context of the English Reforma- 1316 Jeffrey L. Morrow tion (225–31). Influenced by Luther and Melanchthon, with whom he spent time in Wittenberg, Tyndale propagated Protestantism from abroad. His English translation of Scripture became hugely influential but was suspect within Catholic circles because of the theological bent of his translation. As “Defender of the [Catholic] Faith,” Henry VIII opposed Tyndale’s translation. Because of the influence of Anne Boleyn, upon whom Henry had already cast his eyes, however, Henry VIII read (at least portions of ) Tyndale’s 1528 The Obedience of a Christian Man, which argued that a Christian had an obligation, laid upon them by none other than God, to obey his temporal sovereign, even over and against the papacy (226–28). Unsurprisingly, King Henry was most pleased with this treatise. A significant turning point in this history was when King Henry became convinced that he had biblical backing for annulling his marriage to Queen Catherine and taking Anne Boleyn as wife, namely Leviticus 18:16’s prohibition of taking a brother’s wife (since Catherine had been the wife of his late brother), with the added punishment that the couple in such a sinful state shall remain childless (Lev 20:21). Thus, Henry blamed his lack of a male heir through Catherine as due to God’s punishment for his having taken his brother’s wife, even though his brother was dead.25 This “Great Matter” unleashed a torrent of exegesis, both in England and on the continent, over what course Henry could and should take (231–36). Due to Anne’s becoming pregnant with Henry’s child, the king married her out of the public’s eye, and later, through the aid of Thomas Cranmer, then Henry’s appointed Archbishop of Canterbury, the English state annulled Henry’s marriage to Catherine (235–36). Hahn and Wiker point out the dramatic shift that took place with this action: “The state (rather than papal) annulment of Henry’s marriage marks the turning point at which the Church in England becomes the Church of England” (236). It is at this point that Hahn and Wiker examine the evidence that suggests the strong influence of both Machiavelli and Marsilius on Henry’s English Reformation (236–45 and 251–55). They underscore how some of the apologists of the Henrician reform policies utilized Machiavelli’s and Marsilius’s works, such as Richard Mori Hahn and Wiker note that, “in his exegesis, Henry apparently did not consider as an important counterargument Deuteronomy 25:5–10, where it is taken as mandatory that if a brother dies, a remaining brother ‘shall take her [the widow] as his wife’” (Politicizing the Bible, 231). 25 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1317 son, who “would freely use Machiavelli in helping to form and justify Henry’s policies,” and Thomas Starkey, who “would use Marsilius’s Defensor Pacis as the political template for Henrician reform” (237). Furthermore, many of these future apologists congregated around Reginald Pole in Averroist Padua, where they were immersed in such political philosophical discussions (237–38). Thomas Cromwell, one of the key members of Henry’s inner circle, was likely influenced by Machiavelli as well.26 Marsilius’s “influence was even more direct and pervasive” (240). Cromwell himself was responsible for getting Marsilius’s Defensor Pacis published in English (241). The Marsilian program of subordinating church to state found complete expression in Henry’s state church. Thus we see how Marsilius’s, Machiavelli’s, and Wycliffe’s combined influences set the stage in England for Henry’s reform, which would in turn lay the seedbed for Hobbes and the future Deist exegesis that would follow in the wake of Locke and Toland. Hahn and Wiker conclude with the observation that “we have then, in Henry, both in theory and fact, a Marsilian ruler, not an emperor but a national king, a man in both person and policy that brought the pages of the Defensor Pacis to life in England. . . . Henry provided an example of Machiavellianism as vivid as Pope Alexander VI” (254). Cosmopolis and the Twilight of the Scriptural World: René Descartes (1596–1650) and the Mathematization of Nature Chapter 7, “Descartes and the Secular Cosmos” (257–84), like the previous chapter, is more significant for laying the intellectual groundwork for the hermeneutics and exegesis that would develop in its wake than for Descartes’s particular use of Scripture, especially since, as Hahn and Wiker note, Descartes laid the Bible aside in his philosophical program. They point to the “great cosmological shift that occurs in the seventeenth century” (257) and place Descartes firmly within this context. In addition to the “modern cosmological shift” that Descartes helped to effect, this “father of modern philosophy” is also significant for them because he is a key figure in the new “focus on method” that will produce a “‘mania’ for method” (258). The upshot, in light of preceding Hahn and Wiker recognize that, although it is plausible, and perhaps likely, that Cromwell was exposed to Machiavelli directly (through reading), the Machiavellian Morison became a close collaborator with Cromwell, serving as his secretary, and also, like Cromwell, of Henry’s Privy Chamber (Politicizing the Bible, 237–40). 26 1318 Jeffrey L. Morrow chapters, is that “the new, secular political focus set forth by Marsilius and Machiavelli in the fourteenth and sixteenth centuries would finally have received a cosmological foundation in the seventeenth century. . . . Their politicizing of Scripture could now receive support from a new science of nature” (258). Hahn and Wiker set forth Descartes’s biography over several initial pages of their chapter (259–63), and one of its most significant factors, of which they take due note, is the immediate context of the “wars of religion.” When they turn to examine his Discourse on Method (263–80), they demonstrate how such strife, so often attributed to violent and intolerant religious factions, is the ultimate context for his method. In order to lay the proper groundwork for what is to come, especially with Hobbes and Spinoza, Hahn and Wiker are compelled to delve a little into Descartes’s philosophy. They show how his account of nature is “entirely mechanistic” (264). Hahn and Wiker note that there is no evidence of any sort of direct Averroist or Marsilian influence on Descartes, but they include a very useful discussion of what they term “illuminating similarities” between Descartes and both Averroës and Marsilius (265–66). They then proceed to examine Descartes’s method in order to highlight the ways in which it shaped modernity and thus effected the new cosmological understanding of the world in which seventeenth-century (and beyond) historical criticism would develop and operate. As they point out, Descartes’s method in his Discourse is nothing other than a strategy for achieving his goal of setting “both philosophy and humanity on a firm foundation” (266–67) unspoiled by violent conflicts like that through which he lived. Hahn and Wiker identify three key ways in which he effects modernity: “the mathematization, the mechanization, and the mastery of nature” (267). They argue that he effects this by creating a completely new approach to understanding the nature of mathematics: Descartes presents a way to unite algebra and geometry so that…geometric shapes and relationships can be translated into algebraic formulae, and then an even larger, more comprehensive class of algebraic formulae can be translated back into a symbolic geometry capable of representing all relationships of magnitudes…as ratios and proportions of lines, thereby creating a mathesis universalis….Descartes’s brilliance consists in imposing the theoretical conception upon nature….Descartes self-consciously Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1319 fashioned a mathematical ontology, stripping everything from nature but homogenous extension, so that there could be a simple identity between his mathesis universalis and nature…. Descartes’s revolution consisted in the substitution of mathematical forms for Aristotelian forms as the universals governing particulars….forms were not done away with; there was merely a substitution of mathematical forms for common-sense forms. (267–68) 27 In Descartes’s mechanistic universe, the miraculous began to seem impossible (274). So, even though Descartes did not apply his methodic doubt, his Cartesian skepticism, to the Bible, he cleared the way so that others could do this, and, as we will perceive especially in Spinoza, those who followed Descartes did do this. Hahn and Wiker unmask his methodic doubt, moreover, as a key to his strategy. He situates his methodic doubt in such a way that it appears naturally to follow his version of philosophy. In fact, however, his philosophy, his notion of mathematics, determines the necessity of methodic doubt (274–75). As they make clear, “the posture of doubt is inseparable from the method because it serves to remove the obstacles to Descartes’s unique union of mathematization, mechanization, and mastery” (275). This played out in nefarious ways in modern biblical criticism. Hahn and Wiker bring attention to the regrettable but undeniable fact that “the habitual posture of doubt ingrained by following Descartes’s method will become the unquestioned beginning point of many of the most prominent scriptural scholars toward the biblical texts” (275).28 They further explain how Ockham prepared the way for Descartes here: “In championing nominalism, Ockham removed the reality of universals that inhered in similar-looking substances, so that nouns like sheep, cow, dog, pig, and so on do not have real referents in nature. There is no common form or species that all sheep as sheep share. . . . Ockham thereby created an intellectual vacuum, removing species-name universals but not supplying anything in their place” (Politicizing the Bible, 268). 28 They immediately add here, “But the skeptical stance toward the Bible is one side of a two-sided coin, the other being mathematically defined rationality, a mechanical view of nature, and the new goal of the technical mastery of nature that provides a secular substitute for the kingdom of God.” 27 1320 Jeffrey L. Morrow Scripture’s Secular Exile: Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) and His Leviathan Chapter 8 is on Thomas Hobbes (285–338).29 At the outset of this chapter, Hahn and Wiker underscore how Hobbes represents a synthesis of what they have been discussing thus far in their volume. Hobbes “unified the purely secular aim of Marsilian and Machiavellian political thought with a secular cosmology needed to support it, and did so through an explicitly nominalist (mathematical-mechanistic) philosophy that focuses on the complete mastery of nature, especially human nature—all of which he put forth in the context of the particularities of the English political scene” (285). As with Descartes, the context for Hobbes was one of strife, both that of the bloody Thirty Years’ War, the last and bloodiest of the so-called European “wars of religion,” and that of the English Civil Wars, and thus his goal, as with Marsilius and Descartes before him, was terrestrial peace (285–86, 292, and 300). Hahn and Wiker include an important section dealing with the Epicurean background to Hobbes’s thought (296–99). Although this background is often overlooked in the literature, they are not completely alone in their assessment here. Notably, Arrigo Pacchi and Patricia Springborg’s work on the Epicurean background to Hobbes helpfully brought attention to some of these points. Hahn and Wiker do not cite Springborg or Pacchi, but had they, it would only have strengthened their analysis.30 As Hahn and Wiker point out, Hobbes was an intimate friend of the famous early modern Epicurean Fr. Pierre Gassendi (296 and 298). Hobbes thus became an important player in the revival of the “ancient materialist atomism” of earlier On Hobbes’s contribution to modern historical criticism, in addition to the sources Hahn and Wiker utilize, see also Jeffrey L. Morrow, “Leviathan and the Swallowing of Scripture: The Politics behind Thomas Hobbes’s Early Modern Biblical Criticism,” Christianity & Literature 61 (2011): 33–54, and relevant sources in the bibliography; Morrow, “The Bible in Captivity: Hobbes, Spinoza and the Politics of Defining Religion,” Pro Ecclesia 19 (2010): 285–99, especially 293–96, and sources in the footnotes therein; and Jean Bernier, La critique du Pentateuque de Hobbes à Calmet (Paris: Honoré Champion, 2010), especially 27–32, 46–48, 118–20, 126–33, and 144–49. 30 E.g., Patricia Springborg, “Hobbes and Epicurean Religion,” in Der Garten und die Moderne: Epikureische Moral und Politik vom Humanismus bis zur Aufklärung, ed. G. Paganini and E. Tortarolo (Stuttgart: Rommann-holzboog Verlag, 2004), 161–214; Sprinborg, “Hobbes’s Theory of Civil Religion,” in Pluralismo e Religione Civile, ed. G. Paganini and E. Tortarolo (Milan, IT: Bruno Mondatori, 2003), 61–98; and Arrigo Pacchi, “Hobbes e l’epicureismo,” Rivista critica di storia dell filosofia 33 (1975): 54–71. 29 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1321 figures like Epicurus and Lucretius, for whom terrestrial existence was our only form of life; there is no afterlife on this assumption (297). Hahn and Wiker proceed to examine Hobbes’s famous theo-political work Leviathan in great detail (299–336). They show how it was structured on Marsilias’s Averroist pattern, as Marsilius had constructed Defensor Pacis—and for a shared goal, earthly peace via a common means, obedience to the temporal ruler—universal emperor for Marsilius, local state sovereign for Hobbes (299–300). The work is divided roughly into two major parts, the first of which “is devoted to a thoroughgoing reductionist account of political life based upon Hobbes’s entirely self-contained mechanistic-materialist physics” (299), and the second of which is a biblical exegetical project used to bolster the conclusions set forth in the first part. Hobbes’s Epicureanism and nominalism reduced all of reality to atomic motion and left little room, if any, to spirits, and even if there was room left for spirits, said spirits are material (300–305 and 324–33). For Hobbes, “true science must be a nominalism modeled on Euclidean geometry” (304). As with Machiavelli before him, however, Hobbes understood the necessity of religion in order to maintain political power, thus he did not eliminate religion, but rather only the fear of consequences beyond physical life and death (such fear in which religion is rooted for Hobbes), beyond what a state sovereign can grant, and thus granting the sovereign full control over religion within the realm (306–309). In the second half of Leviathan, we find Hobbes’s exegetical project wherein he interprets the Bible to support his politics and philosophy and, thus, to place all temporal and spiritual power in the hands of the civil sovereign, declawing the Church of any real authority apart from the state (312–36). One key move Hobbes makes is placing all virtual interpretive and exegetical authority explicitly in the hands of the sovereign (315–17 and 319–22). This is significant, as Hahn and Wiker explain, when we turn, for example, to Hobbes’s questioning of the Mosaic authorship of the majority of the Pentateuch. For, as they rightly emphasize, “Hobbes’s real goal was not to undermine completely the authority of Scripture and traditional authorship, but to shift the question of authority from the text and authorship to the authority of interpretation (and hence to the authority of the interpreter, the political sovereign)” (322). One key to understanding Hobbes’s project, a key that is completely absent from Hobbes scholarship but that Hahn and 1322 Jeffrey L. Morrow Wiker have correctly identified, is the way in which Hobbes presents “the inversion of typology” (334–35). Hahn and Wiker explain that, “The flow of typology, properly understood, is forward in the Divine economy, toward the culmination in Christ. . . . Hobbes’s typology inverted the order, flowing not toward culmination and spiritual transformation, but backward, toward the reduction to some earthly, original meaning” (334). In this inverted typological exegesis, Hobbes hones Machiavelli’s method of selectively using pagan sources to understand Scripture and reduces biblical rituals and traditions to “pagan contamination” (335). His exegetical method would be further honed and built upon by others to come. Constructing a Scientific Exegesis as Modernity’s Battle Axe: Spinoza (1632–1677) within His Enlightenment Circle Their ninth chapter, “Spinoza and the Beginning of the Radical Enlightenment” (339–93), is a particularly important contribution, not only because of Spinoza’s central role in laying out a precise historical and philological biblical method, the outline of which would become foundational to historical criticism, but also because Hahn and Wiker emphasize how significant the intellectual context of the seventeenth-century Dutch Republic was for Spinoza.31 Too many scholars relegate Spinoza to an early inconsequential position within the radical Enlightenment. Happily, following Jonathan Israel, Hahn and Wiker recognize the full importance of Spinoza for the future Enlightenment and modernity.32 Hahn and Wiker begin with a brief overview of Spinoza’s biography (341–42). A few points are still open matters of debate within Spinoza scholarship, the most significant of which surrounds the reasons for Spinoza’s excommunication. Richard Popkin’s 2004 comments on this matter remain valid today, over a decade later: On Spinoza’s contribution to modern historical criticism, in addition to the sources Hahn and Wiker utilizes, see also Jeffrey L. Morrow, “Spinoza’s Use of the Psalms in the Context of His Political Project,” Interdisciplinary Journal of Research on Religion 11 (2015): 1–18; Morrow, “Historical Criticism as Secular Allegorism: The Case of Spinoza,” Letter & Spirit 8 (2013): 189–221, and sources in the footnotes therein; Morrow, “The Early Modern Political Context to Spinoza’s Bible Criticism,” Revista de Filosofía 66 (2010): 7–24; and Morrow, “Bible in Captivity,” 285–99, especially 296–99. 32 They rely especially on Israel’s Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752 (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2006) and his Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650–1750 (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2001). 31 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1323 “To this day we are not sure why he was excommunicated and what this actually entailed at the time.”33 To their credit, in contrast to so many Spinoza scholars who seem certain of the particular heresy for which Spinoza was excommunicated from the Sephardic Dutch Jewish community (denial of Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch, denial of Scripture’s divine inspiration, atheism, panetheism, denial of the immortality of the soul, etc.), Hahn and Wiker simply state that it was general (as the statement of excommunication itself was vague on this point). They nevertheless follow the majority of Spinoza scholars and affirm that “it appears certain that Baruch began to have doubts about his Judaism rather early and that he embraced the radical philosophy that would lead to his expulsion from the synagogue even while his father was still alive, but out of deference to him, kept it to himself ” (342). This is not patently clear by the evidence, even though it may be correct. Regretfully, Hahn and Wiker do not take into account the work of Odette Vlessing, who has made a very strong case that Spinoza’s excommunication could be explained quite apart from philosophical or theological positions.34 This is a minor quibble point and does not detract from their overall work. They then devote several pages to the various likely influences on Spinoza (342–60), beginning by showing Spinoza’s indebtedness to Descartes (342–44), Machiavelli (342–43), Maimonides, Averroës, and other Arabic authors (343).35 Spinoza’s Latin teacher, Franciscus Richard H. Popkin, Spinoza (Oxford, UK: Oneworld, 2004), 27. Popkin’s chapter devoted to Spinoza’s excommunication (27–38) is very good for getting a handle on the various scholarly positions. 34 E.g., Odette Vlessing, “The Excommunication of Baruch Spinoza: A Conflict Between Jewish and Dutch Law,” Studia Spinozana 13 (1997): 15–47;Vlessing, “The Jewish Community in Transition: From Acceptance to Emancipation,” Studia Rosenthaliana 30 (1996): 195–211; and Vlessing, “New Light on the Earliest History of the Amsterdam Portuguese Jews,” in Dutch Jewish History, vol. 3, ed. J. Michman (Assen, NL: Van Gorcum, 1993), 43–75. See also the comments in Yosef Kaplan, “The Social Functions of the Herem in the Portuguese Jewish Community of Amsterdam in the Seventeenth Century,” in Dutch Jewish History, vol. 1 ed. J. Michman and T. Levie (Jerusalem: Tel-Aviv University, 1984), 111–55. This is the position I take in “Early Modern Political Context,” 12–15 and 14–15n17, and is also the position of Travis Frampton (who follows Vlessing) in his Spinoza and the Rise of Historical Criticism, whose work Hahn and Wiker utilize. 35 Much more work still needs to be done on the Arabic (and particularly Muslim) philosophical influences on Spinoza. Hahn and Wiker cite the foundational study on this by Harry Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinoza (New York: Meridian Books, 1934), as well as two other works (one from Shlomo Pines 33 1324 Jeffrey L. Morrow van den Enden, may have been the figure who introduced the works of both Descartes and Machiavelli to Spinoza, although Spinoza may have encountered Descartes even earlier. The first book he published was on Descartes’s philosophy (342–43). Hahn and Wiker turn next to three other radical thinkers who were contemporaries that may have influenced Spinoza: Uriel da Costa (344–45); Juan de Prado (345); and Isaac La Peyrère (345–49).36 Da Costa was in the same Jewish community as Spinoza in Amsterdam. After his very public humiliation, he committed suicide. De Prado was also in Spinoza’s Jewish community, was one of Spinoza’s acquaintances, and was investigated by the leaders of that Jewish community the very same year that Spinoza was excommunicated, although de Prado repented shortly (within a matter of days) after Spinoza’s excommunication. Hahn and Wiker spend more time on La Peyrère than on these other two figures, even though La Peyrère was from France, because Spinoza owned La Peyrère’s infamous Prae-Adamitae, wherein La Peyrère put forward several exegetical and hermeneutical arguments (including the denial of the Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch) that would sound very much like what Spinoza attempted in his Tractatus Theologico-politicus. Moreover, in 1968 and one from Warren Harvey in 1981), but an engagement with more recent literature on this would only have strengthened their claims: e.g., Carlos Fraenkel, “Reconsidering the Case of Elijah Delmedigo’s Averroism and its Impact on Spinoza,” in Renaissance Averroism and its Aftermath: Arabic Philosophy in Early Modern Europe, ed. A. Akasoy and G. Guiglioni (Dordrecht, NL: Springer, 2012), 213–36; Fraenkel, “Spinoza on Philosophy and Religion: The Averroistic Sources,” in The Rationalists: Between Tradition and Innovation, ed. C. Fraenkel, D. Perinetti, and J. Smith (Dordrecht, NL: Springer, 2010), 58–81; Youcef Djedi, “Spinoza et l’islam: un état des lieux,” Philosophiques 37 (2010): 275–98; and Rafael Ramón Guerrero, “Filósofos hispano-musulmanes y Spinoza: Avempace y Abentofail,” in Spinoza y España: Actas del Congreso Internacional sobre «Relaciones entre Spinoza y España» (Almagro, 5–7 Noviembre 1992), ed. A. Domínguez (Almagro, ES: Ediciones de la Universidad de Castilla-La Mancha, 1994), 125–32. 36 On La Peyrère’s contribution to modern historical criticism, in addition to the sources Hahn and Wiker utilize, see Andreas Nikolaus Pietsch, Isaac La Peyrère: Bibelkritik, Philosemitismus und Patronage in der Gelehrtenrepublik des 17. Jahrhunderts (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2012); Jeffrey L. Morrow, “French Apocalyptic Messianism: Isaac La Peyrère and Political Biblical Criticism in the Seventeenth Century,” Toronto Journal of Theology 27 (2011): 203–13; and Morrow, “Pre-Adamites, Politics and Criticism: Isaac La Peyrère’s Contribution to Modern Biblical Studies,” Journal of the Orthodox Center for the Advancement of Biblical Studies 4 (2011): 1–23, and sources in the footnotes therein. Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1325 Hahn and Wiker agree with Popkin on the likelihood of Spinoza and La Peyrère meeting together in Amsterdam.37 Hahn and Wiker also discuss Spinoza within the context of the Dutch Collegiant radicals, in whose circle Spinoza emerged as the intellectual ringleader of sorts (350–56). They especially focus on Spinoza’s friends Adriaan Koerbagh (350–53) and Lodewijk Meyer (353–56). The most important point of this brief subsection is that it demonstrates how Spinoza’s work belongs to a much broader intellectual current, inspired in part by Cartesian philosophy, within the Dutch republic. Regarding Meyer’s work in relation to Spinoza’s, Hahn and Wiker observe that “Meyer’s Philosophia [S. Scripturae Interpres] and Spinoza’s Tractatus often traveled together in one book, a marriage that made perfect sense. Meyer provided the framework as a prolegomenon, and Spinoza. . . . spelled out the full consequences, consequences all the more radical precisely because of Spinoza’s radicalizing of Descartes” (355). I think this is basically correct, but Hahn and Wiker do not sufficiently take into account the ways in which Spinoza disagreed with Meyer’s work. James Samuel Preus, some of whose other works Hahn and Wiker use in this volume, has made a strong case that Meyer is one of the intended targets of Spinoza’s Tractatus, particularly where Spinoza opposes the exegesis of the medieval Jewish sage, Maimonides.38 Although Spinoza certainly applies his own radicalized brand of Cartesian skepticism to Scripture, the primary corrosive acid he employs, in sharp contrast to Meyer, is history. For this, Spinoza is more directly indebted to Francis Bacon than to Descartes.39 See Richard H. Popkin, “Spinoza and La Peyrère,” in Spinoza: New Perspectives, ed. R. Shahan and J. I. Biro (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1978), 177–95. 38 See J. Samuel Preus, Spinoza and the Irrelevance of Biblical Authority (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001), especially 34–202, and Preus, “A Hidden Opponent in Spinoza’s Tractatus,” Harvard Theological Review 88 (1995): 361–88, neither of which do Hahn and Wiker utilize in their text. 39 Although Hahn and Wiker do discuss the influence Francis Bacon exerted on figures throughout their volume (including Descartes and Hobbes, the latter of whom served as Bacon’s secretary), they do not discuss Bacon’s important background for understanding Spinoza at all in their otherwise very fine chapter treating Spinoza. Unfortunately, there is very little treatment in the scholarly literature of Bacon’s role in Spinoza’s method, despite the fact that Spinoza read Bacon and included in his overall method a historical method that clearly attempted to bring Bacon’s history of nature to bear on a history of Scripture (even to the point of using linguistic parallels to Bacon’s work). Much more 37 1326 Jeffrey L. Morrow Hahn and Wiker situate Spinoza’s pantheism, his collapsing of God with nature, within the context of his philosophy grounded in Euclidean geometry (357–60). Moreover, as did Averroës, Spinoza maintained a hierarchy of knowers and of knowledge. He divided knowledge into three types or levels. First, there was experiential knowledge, which he labeled “opinion” or “imagination.” The second level of knowledge is “reason,” which is mathematical, patterned on geometry. Finally, Spinoza labeled the third type of knowledge “intuition,” which is the highest form of knowledge. Much like Averroës, Spinoza thought that most people were only able to attain the first level of knowledge, “opinion” or “imagination” (360–62). This is important to keep in mind when we turn to Spinoza’s biblical hermeneutic in his Tractatus, as Hahn and Wiker explain: “By identifying God with nature and assuming that the order of nature was identical to the clearest, most certain science of mathematics, Spinoza completely and purposely eliminated supernatural revelation as a possibility. God’s essence is entirely revealed in nature; He is nature; therefore the highest science, the one that truly grasps God’s essence, is mathematical-mechanical natural science” (362). As with Hobbes and Descartes before him (and, we might add, Meyer too), the “wars of religion,” and particularly the Thirty Years’ War, provide the main backdrop for his work. Spinoza desired to create a scientific biblical hermeneutic in his Tractatus that would serve the earthly political goal of securing peace between warring religious-political factions (362–64). As Hahn and Wiker spell out, “the historical-critical method as originally designed by Spinoza is neither neutral nor scientific, but is rather the form of biblical studies scholarship needs to be devoted to this neglected influence. For the role of Bacon on Spinoza, see, e.g., Morrow, “Historical Criticism,” 202–03; Juan Francisco Manrique Charry, “La herencia de Bacon en la doctrina spinocista del lenguaje,” Universitas Philosophica 54 (2010): 121–30; Preus, Spinoza, 7n19, 24n73, 26n80, 38, 158n9, 159, 159n12, 161–68, 163n20–21, 181, and 195; Alan Gabbey, “Spinoza’s Natural Science and Methodology,” in The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, ed. D. Garrett (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 170–72; Edwin Curley, “Kissinger, Spinoza, and Genghis Khan,” in The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, 341n35 (Hahn and Wiker do utilize the version of Curley’s article from the 2001 reprinted edition of the companion in their chapter on Spinoza, at Politicizing the Bible, 342n13, 343n14, and 381n202); Alan Donagan, “Spinoza’s Theology,” in The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, 343; Donagan, Spinoza (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 16–17; and Sylvain Zac, Spinoza et l’interprétation de l’Écriture (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1965), 29–37. Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1327 that purposely transforms the Bible to act as a political support to keep order in a secular state” (364). When Hahn and Wiker turn to their analysis of Spinoza’s Tractatus (362–88), they clarify an important hermeneutical key for correctly reading Spinoza here, a key that is so often overlooked by Spinoza scholars. That key is Spinoza’s Ethics, which he began writing prior to his Tractatus. In fact, he interrupted working on his Ethics, which was never published within his lifetime but only posthumously, in order to pen his infamous Tractatus, which, as the provocative title of Steven Nadler’s recent work on it indicates, Spinoza’s contemporaries considered to be “a book forged in hell.”40 Hahn and Wiker emphasize how Spinoza’s philosophy as expressed in his then unpublished Ethics makes explicit what was only implied and ambiguous in his Tractatus (364–66). Once it becomes clear, as in the Ethics, that God is nature, then it becomes clear that miracles are impossible (364–65).41 Importantly, Hahn and Wiker explain how, for Spinoza, “since miracles are impossible, therefore the scientific exegete must look for another explanation of their common occurrence in Scripture” (365). This is precisely what Machiavelli did before Spinoza, as Hahn and Wiker explain in their treatment of Machiavelli earlier in their volume (e.g., 139–40 and 144–45). In light of this clear connection, in light of the fact that, as Graham Hammill notes, Spinoza was “one of Machiavelli’s most perceptive readers,” and in light of the fact that Hahn and Wiker shortly make a connection between Spinoza and Machiavelli regarding religion and the hermeneutic of suspicion (367), it is surprising that they do not make the parallel explicit between the two thinkers.42 Spinoza constructs his method in order to make “the highest revelation of Scripture moral,” and he then defines “morality in purely secular terms,” thus rendering “revelation superfluous, at least for the ‘enlightened’” (369). Within this overall project, one of the key shifts Spinoza effects, which will continue in later historical-critical exegesis that follows in his trail, is to move from any notion of “truth” Steven Nadler, A Book Forged in Hell: Spinoza’s Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the Secular Age (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011). 41 Hahn and Wiker point out that, “To those who have not read Spinoza’s Ethics (the very situation of the first readers of the Tractatus), the actual and only possible foundation of the assertion that miracles are impossible—that God is nature—was obviously not apparent” (Politicizing the Bible, 365). 42 Graham Hammill, The Mosaic Constitution: Political Theology and Imagination from Machiavelli to Milton (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012), 22. 40 1328 Jeffrey L. Morrow within the text to a focus on “meaning” (373–75). Spinoza then brings up “a seemingly endless list of historical questions that must be answered before the exegete can discover the meaning of the text” (375). He thus hopes to stop theology from entering into the political realm, by rendering such theology virtually impossible, or at most private. Hahn and Wiker summarize the import of Spinoza’s project: Democracy eliminates persecution by eliminating the distinction between orthodoxy and heterodoxy, wisdom and foolishness. Those who are highest on the Averroistic hierarchy, the philosophers, are protected from those who are lowest, the vulgar, by the public pretence that both philosophy and theology have been democratized. Yet, ironically, Spinoza takes away with one hand what he offers with the other, by making the analysis of Scripture possible only to the highly educated, the elite exegetes who are well versed in the original languages, history, literary forms, etc. To keep the elite from turning against the philosophers, Spinoza fashions an exegetical method that produces the conclusions that reduce Scripture to a merely moral prop for civil order, one that allows the greatest freedom for philosophy. In fact, since Spinoza’s philosophy ultimately defines the method, then the applied method serves to reaffirm Spinoza’s philosophy even without the exegete’s own knowledge or consent. (387–88) Critical History and the Dissolving of Scripture: Richard Simon (1638–1712) and Historical Criticism as an Apologia for Tradition? Hahn and Wiker tellingly entitle their tenth chapter “The Ambiguous Richard Simon” (395–423) precisely because Simon’s motives and his work appear so ambiguous.43 On the one hand, he appeared to be On Simon’s contribution to modern historical criticism, in addition to the sources Hahn and Wiker utilize, see Jeffrey L. Morrow, “Faith, Reason, and History in Early Modern Catholic Biblical Interpretation: Fr. Richard Simon and St. Thomas More,” New Blackfriars 96 (2015): 658–73; Dominique Barthélemy, Studies in the Text of the Old Testament: An Introduction to the Hebrew Old Testament Text Project: English Translation of the Introductions to Volumes 1, 2, and 3 Critique textuelle de l’Ancien Testament (Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 2012), especially 58–81; Bernier, La critique du Pentateuque, especially 33–41, 44–47, 49–69, 71–114, 117–26, 162–67, 186–208, 210–12, 214–16, 222–24, 277–79, and 281–84; Sascha Müller, Richard Simon (1638–1712): Exeget, Theologe, Philosoph und Historiker (Bamberg: Echter, 2006); Müller, Kritik und Theologie: 43 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1329 defending Catholic tradition against the more skeptical Spinoza and others, but on the other, he clearly took their work further, which had a long-lasting and corrosive effect both on biblical interpretation and on the tradition he was so adamantly trying to defend. Simon clearly built on Spinoza’s exegetical project, as Hahn and Wiker are well aware (395–99, 406–07, 411–12, and 421–23).44 The irony is that Simon’s Histoire critique du Vieux Testament was an attempt, at least ostensibly, to combat Spinoza’s exegetical method (396). Simon hoped to defend Catholic tradition and, at the same time, demolish the Protestant assumption of sola Scriptura (396–400). In order to do so, however, Simon took Spinoza’s arguments even further, multiplying problems with the biblical text (396–400 and 404–23). In many places, Simon followed the lead of La Peyrère, who, as Hahn and Wiker note, was a close friend of Simon’s ever since La Peyrère joined the Oratorians, for whom Fr. Richard Simon was a priest (397). Hahn and Wiker emphasize the novelty (within the Catholic tradition) of Simon’s approach: As it developed, the Catholic position in regard to Scripture’s seeming imperfections was that what seemed disunited and imperfect, proved upon humble, faithful, and prayerful reading—guided by the Holy Spirit and Tradition—to be whole and harmonious, containing hidden perfections under seeming imperfections. Various ways arose to explain apparent imperfections: exegetes had recourse to a complex account of divine accommodations, to literal and spiritual senses, and even to the notion of purposely-placed divine stumbling blocks in the text to trip up the prideful and draw the humble to closer examination. Against this, Simon accepted the surface incongruities at Christliche Glaubens und Schrifthermeneutik nach Richard Simon (St. Ottilien: EOS, 2004); Guy G. Stroumsa, “Richard Simon: From Philology to Comparatism,” Archiv für Religionsgeschichte 3 (2001): 89–107; William McKane, Selected Christian Hebraists (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 111–50; and Paul Hazard, La Crise de la Conscience Européenne, 1680–1715 (Paris: Boivin et Cie, 1935), 125–36. 44 See also the comments in secondary literature that Hahn and Wiker do not include: Barthélemy, Studies in the Text, 60–62; F. Saverio Mirri, Richard Simon e il Metodo Storico-critico di B. Spinoza: Storia di un Libro e di una Polemica sulla Sfondo delle Lotte Politico-religiose della Francia di Luigi XIV (Florence, IT: Felice Le Monnier, 1972), 29–84; and Paul Auvray, “Richard Simon et Spinoza,” in Religion, Érudition et Critique à la Fin du XVIIe Siècle et au Début du XVIIIe, ed. B. de Gaiffier et al. (Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1968), 201–14. 1330 Jeffrey L. Morrow face value—even rejoiced in them—so that the need for traditio became absolute. (398) One problem, as they emphasize, is that Simon’s use of tradition appeared arbitrary (399, 405, 410–12, 416–18, and 422). Hahn and Wiker include a very enlightening discussion of Simon’s reception (400–04) in England (among John Locke et al.) and in Germany (among Leibniz, Johann David Michaelis, Johann Salamo Semler, et al.). I think this subsection would fit better at the end of the chapter rather than where they have it positioned, but its inclusion is important because they show in it how influential Simon’s historical-critical work became in the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, which ensured its survival into the nineteenth century and beyond. Hahn and Wiker follow their subsections on Simon’s later reception with a helpful examination of Simon’s Histoire Critique du Vieux Testament (404–12) and of his Histoire Critique du texte du Nouveau Testament (412–22). In these works, and very much in line with Spinoza, “Simon shifted the focus of biblical studies from the substance of the text to the history of the text” (404). One significant move Simon makes, which will develop more completely in the later history of historical-criticism (and particularly form criticism), is to posit “a layered editorial history” for Scripture (405–06). Thus emerges the necessity of a skilled scholarly exegete in order to make sense of the tattered threads of Scripture. Indeed, Simon seems to imply that “only a scholar could plumb the depths of the text” (413). War, Espionage & Epistemology: John Locke (1632–1704) and the Politicization of the Bible Chapter 11, “The English Civil Wars, Moderate Radicals, and John Locke” (425–86), is the most dramatic and engaging chapter in the entire volume. Locke’s context is the English Civil Wars. Thus, Hahn and Wiker clarify many of the important historical, cultural, and religious factors necessary to understand this English context to Locke’s work. Parliament’s rebellion against the king, as they point out, “was neither simply an economic rebellion, nor a political rebellion, nor a religious rebellion, for all three were inextricably bound together, as inseparable in the minds and hearts of all parties as it was in their lives” (427). Locke’s family was found on the side represented by Parliament, which was basically “the new propertied class” (426–27). He was about ten years old when this First Civil War erupted (426–27). The Second Civil War found Locke at Westminster School, age fifteen (427–28). Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1331 Locke was studying at Oxford during the tumultuous transition from the Third Civil War and the chaos that ensued after Oliver Cromwell’s military rule (428). This context of violent strife and the “nearly anarchic radicalism” that was rampant throughout England profoundly shaped Locke, who proved himself “deeply influenced” by Hobbes’s Leviathan (426–33). Locke also was influenced by Robert Boyle (a prominent member of the Royal Society) who was another mechanist like Hobbes, popularizing Epicurean atomism in England (433–38). Locke’s political machinations forced him into exile as he was trailed by royal spies on the continent (440–41). Initially, he served as secretary for the Elector of Brandenburg on a diplomatic mission to the European continent (438), and he later became intimately acquainted with Anthony Ashley Cooper, who became the Earl of Shaftesbury. Locke even served as his personal physician (438). As a Whig, Locke was constantly involved in political plots and intrigue, including a plan for violent rebellion. Hahn and Wiker follow the work of Richard Ashcraft in identifying Locke as personally involved in the Rye House Plot, a plan to kidnap and then murder King Charles II (whom Locke earlier supported) and the king’s brother (440–41).45 In self-imposed exile, Locke remained in the Dutch Republic, within six years of Spinoza’s death (441–45). In the Dutch Republic, Locke was exposed to radical intellectual traditions, including Jean Le Clerc, the critic of Richard Simon who would become a good friend of Locke’s (441–44, 454, and 476–77). Locke likewise assiduously studied Spinoza and Richard Simon (444, 446, 454, and 476). It was also at this time that he created a private intellectual meeting group that involved figures in Benjamin Furly’s circle of intellectuals, a circle that “was even more . . . [radical] than the circle that had gathered around Spinoza” (444). It is in this radical intellectual context that Hahn and Wiker examine several of Locke’s works that are important for understanding his biblical hermeneutic: Epistola de Tolerantia (445–49); An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (449–55); First Treatise of Government (455–61); Second Treatise of Government (461–65); The Reasonableness of Christianity (467–75); and A Paraphrase and Notes on the Epistles of St. Paul (476–83).46 They point out that the first of these documents, Richard Ashcraft, Revolutionary Politics & Locke’s Two Treatises of Government (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986). 46 Locke’s Paraphrase covers Galatians, 1 and 2 Corinthians, Romans, and Ephesians. 45 1332 Jeffrey L. Morrow the Epistola is “not an abstract treatise, but a plea for toleration to an as-yet-unstable government in England” (445). Writing further they contend that the Epistola duplicates the sort of “political Averroism” of Marsilius’s Defensor Pacis through Locke’s particular call for toleration (445). As with Spinoza before him, for Locke, a core morality becomes Scripture’s central message for Locke, a morality that has been obscured by so much attention to doctrine (446). As Hahn and Wiker explain, for Locke, “rather than Scripture taking believers into the heart of profound mystery, where the actual events of sacred history reveal, as types, eternal and supernatural truths, the Bible became a kind of morality manual that, at its best, illustrated merely rational moral truths” (447). Locke’s vision of toleration required a secular governing authority and the complete privatization of religion (448). When Hahn and Wiker turn to Locke’s Essay, they emphasize the place into which this work fits within Locke’s overarching political plan: “the Epistola, the Essay, and the Two Treatises as well, are all part of Locke’s unified project. The goal of the Essay . . . was (at least in significant part) to maximize the realm of reason and minimize the realm of faith” (450).47 Locke is privatizing faith while uniting Cartesian rationalism with the empiricism of science.48 In the Essay, Locke devotes significant time to discussing the nature of reason. What he seeks to do is limit reason’s abilities and then expand the power and capability of this new anemic reason. For Locke, reason has to do with “our clear and distinct ideas,” and thus it is capable of judging revelation. If something cannot be clearly “sensed,” if it “is beyond sense,” then it is nothing but utter “nonsense” (451). Hahn and Wiker claim that, with Locke, “the principle of sola scriptura was therefore transformed into the principle sola ratio” (452). It is in his discussion of judging the authenticity of manuscripts (and his discussion here makes it clear he has the Bible in mind), that Locke is most indebted to Simon’s prior work with its multiple editorial layers (454–55). Hahn and Wiker point out: . . . a direct connection between Locke’s epistemology and his Averroistic plan for political tolerance. Reducing the status of They clarify, “ [the goal was] not [to] undermine [faith], but [to] minimize, since as Locke has already made clear, political order demands religious beliefs, albeit tamed and firmly circumscribed” (Politicizing the Bible, 450). 48 In the authors’ words, “Locke tried to effect a union of the rationalism of Descartes and the empiricism of Boyle, based on the atomist materialism of both (as shared by Galileo, Hobbes, and Newton as well)” (ibid.). 47 Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1333 revelation to the lowest kind of probability could become a scholarly project (much akin to Spinoza’s strategy of placing endless obstacles before the exegete), one that used the scholarship of those like Richard Simon to undermine the credibility of the text, thereby affirming the need for political tolerance. Yet, at the same time, these exegetical endeavors could provide at least a thin theism, largely constrained to affirming morality, so as not to remove the necessary help that religion gave to maintaining order in society. (455) In Locke’s First Treatise, we find the radical “assertion of natural individualism” that “displaced familial authority” and thus became “the governing metaphor of modernity” (460). Hahn and Wiker underscore how “this displacement signaled the historical shift that Locke himself was trying to effect, from political rule by family (monarch, nobility, father), to political rule by property; more particularly, from the kind of rule that defined pre-Civil War England, to the rule by the propertied class in Parliament that came (after a significant struggle) to define post-Civil War England” (460). His Second Treatise finished the job of the first, rooting all rights in what he took to be the fundamental right, namely private property (462). Hahn and Wiker suggest that Locke’s argument might be viewed “justly” as “a concise scriptural vindication of Bacon’s project to conquer nature for the sake of this-worldly comfort, and a crib of Boyle’s aims for the Royal Society” (463). Before turning to his works primarily on the Bible, Hahn and Wiker recount Locke’s role in the so-called “Glorious Revolution” (465–67). After the Rye House Plot failed, the English crown, on many occasions, attempted to capture Locke and bring him back to England for trial and punishment (465). Meanwhile, Locke was busy plotting a coup that would bring down King James II and place William of Orange in his stead (466). After the success, the “Glorious Revolution,” Locke was able to return to England a hero (466–67). Locke’s scriptural work was intended to minimize faith commitments to the barest minimum possible in order to further his political goals. Indeed, his Reasonableness of Christianity basically boils down to an apologetic for the notion that the only really important thing for which Scripture demands the adherence of faith is that Jesus was in fact the Messiah (468). With such a doctrinal reduction, there would no longer be any reason for violent religious controversies. The important thing for Locke was “civic morality” (471). Hahn 1334 Jeffrey L. Morrow and Wiker sum up his entire interpretive goal: “Jesus was reduced to being the Messiah so He could be a lawmaker-king, a miracle worker who confirmed the authority of morality for those incapable of philosophical demonstration. . . . His [Locke’s] main interest seems to be the utility of the Bible for keeping political order” (472). When Hahn and Wiker examine Locke’s work on the Pauline epistles, they show how he focuses at the outset on demonstrating how incredibly “obscure” Paul appears to be at first glance. Locke provided a solution to penetrating Paul’s apparent obscurity: he urged the readers to discard commentaries and just read the epistles themselves. He moreover cautioned against any attempt at a unified, we might say canonical, biblical interpretation. Rather, each text must be taken on its own, apart from the others (478–79). In his own commentary, which would prove incredibly influential, Locke prepared “the way for the later exegetical emphasis . . . on understanding the New Testament primarily as a witness to an early split between Judaizing and non-Judaizing factions” (480). His Pauline commentary was influential and paved the way for future Pauline scholarship. The great eighteenth-century German biblical scholar Johann David Michaelis penned the preface for the German edition of Locke’s Paraphrase (477). Exegesis as an Attack on Priestcraft: John Toland (1670–1722) and the Future of Historical Criticism Chapter 12, “Revolution, Radicals, Republicans, and John Toland” (487–541), shows conclusively how so many of the skeptical conclusions of late-eighteenth- and nineteenth- century historical critics were already firmly in place in the seventeenth century in the work of John Toland. Moreover, Hahn and Wiker maintain that “the radical conclusions of the historical-critical method were built into the method itself ” (487). In this final major chapter, they examine a number of Toland’s works, including: Letters to Serena (488–89); Pantheisticon (489–91); Clidophorus, or Of the Exoteric and Esoteric Philosophy (491–95); The Life of John Milton (501–02); Christianity not Mysterious (528–34); and Nazarenus (535–38).When they examine his 1704 Letters to Serena, they point out how Toland establishes a “method of equivocation” in his notion of “two doctrines,” the idea that the enlightened philosopher must hide some things from the more ignorant masses, which hearkens back to (possibly Locke), Spinoza, Hobbes, Descartes, Machiavelli, Marsilius, and, we might add, the Latin Averroist tradition more broadly (488–89). Toland continued his “method of equivoca- Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1335 tion” in his 1720 Pantheisticon, which attempted to explain Toland’s pantheism. In it, he clearly called for the enlightened philosopher to separate from the masses (489). Such an enlightened philosopher could “talk” with the people in the crowds but must “think” only with other enlightened philosophers (490). Toland’s 1720 Clidophorus continued his hermeneutical discussion of the role of his “double philosophy,” this time because of the threat of potential persecution (492). Toland was a careful reader of Machiavelli, and here Toland lashes out against priestcraft and religious hypocrisy, which Machiavelli had so praised as the dissembling necessary for a good ruler. For Toland, “priests prey upon the ignorance of the vulgar, spinning the people’s superstition into gold to put in their own pockets, and concealing their ruses by declaring them ‘Mysteries’” (493). Toland apparently hoped to construct a “civil theology” based on the “rewriting of the myths” and reducing supernatural to the natural (494–95). As did Locke, Toland spent time among “the most radical of intellectual circles” in the Dutch Republic (498). And as did Locke, Toland inserted himself into the active politics of his day. In particular, he became an apologist for the Hanoverian succession (503–505). As Hahn and Wiker highlight, Toland “desired to affect the political order” and also had, at the same time, become financially desperate (504). In this context, he “took it upon himself personally to educate the House of Hanover in his most radical ideas, as a kind of Platonic philosopher educating a future king or queen in the new civil theology . . . and . . . [he] began his intimate (if short-lived) relationship with Sophia [of Hanover] and her daughter, Sophie, the queen of Prussia” (504). Although he failed, Toland had “conceived the Hanoverian succession as the political means by which a new civic religion could be instantiated in England, one rerooted in pantheism but wearing the public face of a radically reformed Christianity” (522). Hahn and Wiker include a significant discussion of the clandestine skeptical literature then circulating in the Dutch Republic in radical intellectual circles; Toland was intricately involved as an important carrier of such clandestine literature (505–22). He mastered the art of “reconstructing an existing text to make it a bearer of revolutionary ideas” (508), including, for instance, an English translation of Giordano Bruno’s pantheistic Spaccio de la bestia trionfante (514–17). Bruno’s text “condemns all revealed religions in the name of reason, but does so under the guise of condemning pagan religion” (515). 1336 Jeffrey L. Morrow As did Spinoza and Machiavelli before him, Toland put forward natural explanations to explain away any apparent miracle in Scripture. Any explanation would do, so long as it was natural and not mysterious or supernatural (526). For Toland, reason alone was sufficient to understand Scripture, which must be studied as any other book. Moreover, since there was no supernatural, no miracles, nothing mysterious, there was no need for priesthood or priestly mediation. His assumptions here would govern the rest of modern historical criticism, with its transformation of the Bible into a book like any other, its refusal to allow for the supernatural, seeking out a natural (any natural) explanation in its place, and its view of priesthood as a devolution or corruption of what came before (532–33). Toland, as did later historical critical exegetes, would “reformulate history in terms of degeneration from rational religion to priestly superstition” (533). Hahn and Wiker argue that “Toland was himself not merely another moderate English divine continually blurring Christianity’s sharp doctrinal edges with Latitudinarianism until it shaded into the gentleman’s religion of deism—but rather part of a larger, radical international intellectual movement that had rejected Christianity” (505). Back to the Future: Historical Criticism from 1700–1900 and Beyond The book’s conclusion (543–66) clarifies a few points already brought up in the volume, but it also charts new territory as it hints at the ways in which the historical-critical method developed in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries grounded on the foundation discussed in the previous 540 or so pages. Hahn and Wiker do not shy away from linking the secularization of Scripture study from the “hypocrisy” and “corruption” on the part of “the Church” (543). They summarize the chapter contents rapidly (543–46). Then, they hint at ways in which the history they told plays out in the later centuries (547–66), starting with Gotthold Lessing (547), whose famous Wolfenbüttel Fragments, written by Hermann Samuel Reimarus (547–48), are popularly associated with the advent of historical Jesus research. Most scholars remain unaware of the influence the figures they already covered exerted on Reimarus, even though there is almost unanimous acknowledgement of Reimarus’s foundational role as a historical critic. Reimarus’s doctoral dissertation was actually on Machiavelli, and it was on the basis of this dissertation that he became a professor philosophy. Moreover, he was a close reader of Toland, setting “down his true thoughts only Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1337 in private,” as Toland had recommended (547). He further supported the Locke-influenced Christian Wolff. What Lessing published of Reimarus, however, were his more radical private views. Hahn and Wiker proceed to show how Reimarus was not alone in his radical views by walking through the influence exerted by Spinoza’s thought in Germany from the end of the seventeenth century and well into the eighteenth century (548–52 and 555–62). This was not only through more obscure (to historians of biblical scholarship) figures like Johann Georg Wachter (548–49), Matthew Knutzen (549), and Friedrich Wilhelm Stosch (549–50), but also through more significant figures within the standard histories of biblical scholarship like Johann Lorenz Schmidt (550–552) and Johann Salomo Semler (555–59), and thus Johann Gottfried Eichhorn (559–62). Schmidt, responsible for the Werthheim Bible, was the first to publish a German translation of Spinoza’s Ethics. Hahn and Wiker mention the almost completely ignored fact that Lessing, responsible for publishing Reimarus’s private comments on the New Testament and, thus, birthing the modern critical historical Jesus studies, completely assimilated Spinoza via Schmidt’s German text of Spinoza’s Ethics. As they explain: “Lessing took the Averroistic vertical hierarchy stretching from the vulgar to the philosophic, which Spinoza took to be ineradicable, and set it horizontally, so that the hierarchy was stretched through history, the vulgar gradually becoming enlightened as they moved from needing wondrous events and imaginative metaphors (i.e., biblical stories) in order to grasp philosophical truths indirectly, to the more advanced stage of embracing truths of reason directly” (552). Historical Jesus scholarship was to take another bound, again grounded in Reimarus, the Machiavelli specialist, through the work of David Friedrich Strauss (553–55). Hahn and Wiker then turn to Semler. Semler was a devotee of Richard Simon, whose work he brought into German translation, which the authors mention in their chapter on Simon (404), but which they regretfully neglect to mention when they actually spend time discussing Semler’s importance in their concluding chapter. Semler also published an edition of Meyer’s Philosophia in Latin (404 and 555), but Hahn and Wiker again neglect to mention here (555) the very relevant fact that they mentioned earlier (both 355–56 and 404) in their chapters on Spinoza and Simon, namely, that bound together with Meyer’s work, Semler placed Spinoza’s Tractatus in Latin. This is important, as the authors earlier noted, because it emphasizes the way in which Semler (and the others who juxtaposed 1338 Jeffrey L. Morrow these two texts in the same published bound volume) intended to see Meyer’s work as a prolegomenon to Spinoza’s (355). Hahn and Wiker also fail to mention here two significant facts they brought up in passing earlier, where they were less relevant (356), namely that Semler was incredibly influential on Lessing, and even more so on his student Johann Jakob Griesbach, who would set the Synoptic problem and the historical study of the Gospels on a whole new track with his version of the two-source hypothesis. Hahn and Wiker do mention here, however, one other significant influence Semler exerted that would have as great an effect on the historical-critical study of the Old Testament as Griesbach would have on that of the New Testament: Semler’s disciple (and student of Johann David Michaelis), Johann Gottfried Eichhorn. Eichhorn would set the early stage of the historical-critical study of the Pentateuch on a path that would lead ultimately to Julius Wellhausen’s formulation of the Documentary Hypothesis of Pentateuchal origins. Eichhorn was able to do this in part by his study of the Greek and Roman classics under Christian Gottlob Heyne. The other major “breakthrough” Eichhorn had, although Hahn and Wiker fail to mention it, is Eichhorn’s introduction to the work of Jean Astruc via Eichhorn’s teacher Michaelis. Astruc attempted to defend the Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch against the skeptics of the previous century (La Peyrère, Hobbes, Spinoza, and Simon). Astruc did this by positing hypothetical sources, based on stylistic differences, behind Genesis and the beginning of Exodus, which he maintained Moses used in composing those texts. Michaelis, who also adhered to the Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch, feared that Astruc had gone too far in dividing up sources based on such criteria. It was through Michaelis’s critique of Astruc that Eichhorn was able to redeploy Astruc to create further distance between the text of the Pentateuch, in its earliest stages, and Moses. Hahn and Wiker do mention other influences on Eichhorn, showing how close he was to Spinoza and Toland. They spell out how, for him, “prophecy becomes the vehicle for replacing revelation with entirely secular philosophy” (560). Eichhorn would have a considerable effect on shaping the future of the University of Göttingen, where he himself studied and where Wellhausen would later study and teach (561). Hahn and Wiker conclude this chapter, bringing their volume to a close, with an all-too-brief discussion of the role of the socio-political climate of Germany in the latter half of the nineteenth century (562– Averroism, Nominalism, and Mechanization 1339 65), situating the biblical work of Wellhausen (561–63) and Wilhelm M. L. de Wette (562–64) within this context. Wellhausen, a staunch Bismarck supporter, completed an exegetical project that fit well within the political climate of the time. Hahn and Wiker comment: A common feature running from Marsilius through Hobbes, Spinoza, and Toland was the denigration of the priesthood because the primacy of the priesthood implied a primacy of the sacred over the secular, the priest over the king. Whatever Wellhausen’s intentions, dividing the Old Testament up into four sources, JEDP, and casting the Priestly as a later, artificial constriction and deformation of an earlier, better form of worship, accomplished the very result, exegetically, aimed at by the most adamantly secular thinkers we have covered. In so doing, it would appear that Wellhausen functioned like Ockham and Luther, unintentionally aiding a purely secular reconstruction of religion. (562) Hahn and Wiker proceed to show how de Wette (an incredibly influential source for Wellhausen) had made similar moves much earlier in his work on the Old Testament, also pushing the institution of the Old Testament priesthood late, after the Babylonian exile. This section would probably be better placed prior to their discussion of Wellhausen. They include some reflections on the political function of Markan priority. These trends in biblical criticism in Germany at the end of the nineteenth century provide “exegetical support for a repudiation of Catholicism and an affirmation of Protestantism,” especially when it is understood how often the Old Testament priesthood was a stand-in for contemporary Catholicism (564). Concluding Reflections Politicizing the Bible stands in a class all of its own. To date there exist no volumes quite like this one. No one else has yet produced a book that accomplishes all of the following: traces the history of modern biblical scholarship prior to the eighteenth century (let alone into the fourteenth); examines the philosophical roots (Epicurean-atomist, Averroist, nominalist, Machiavellian, Baconian-scientific, Cartesian, Spinozan-pantheistic, etc.) of modern historical-criticism; traces the medieval influences in the context of the Franciscan poverty disputes; walks through the history of pre-Reformation and Reformation England to show how the seedbed was sown for later Deistic exegesis 1340 Jeffrey L. Morrow that would transplant to Germany; shows the role of the Protestant Reformation (beyond simply the new focus on sola Scriptura) on modern biblical hermeneutics; shows how each figure built upon the edifice constructed by earlier figures discussed; explain the role of the great cosmological shift in the seventeenth century (involving figures like Galileo, Descartes, and Newton) in creating a new context for biblical interpretation that would allow for historical-criticism; and, in addition to all of this, all the while tracing the political history in order to show how politics shaped the entire project so that the emerging secular study of the Bible was so often forged and used as an offensive weapon by various states in their battles with the Church over the bodies and souls within their realms. Some prior books have accomplished some of these tasks, but apart from Politicizing the Bible, none of them have accomplished all of them in a single volume. This is the first broad survey of the history of modern biblical scholarship that devotes entire chapters to figures such as Marsilius of Padua, William of Ockham, Machiavelli, Henry VIII, Descartes, and John Locke; most historians of biblical scholarship give these figures only a few passing comments, if they are mentioned at all. Hahn and Wiker have written a scholarly masterpiece that belongs on the bookshelves of any scholar interested in the Bible, the history of biblical interpretation, the history of modern biblical scholarship, historical-critical exegesis, theological biblical interpretation, the Enlightenment, the roots of Enlightenment philosophy, the intellectual roots of modernity, the German and English Reformations and their roots, historical church and state relations, or are interested in any of the figures Hahn and Wiker discuss in their massive tome. My only hope is that Hahn and Wiker write a sequel, at least from 1700–1900, if not through the twentieth century.49 N&V I owe thanks to Brant Pitre and Michael Barber for thinking through with me some of the issues raised here, and to Maria Morrow for critiquing a draft of this review essay. Portions of this review were already published (and are here reused with permission) in my much briefer review essay of Hahn and Wiker’s book in Journal of Theological Interpretation 8.1 (2014): 145–55. 49 Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 14, No. 4 (2016): 1341–1366 Book Reviews The Philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas: A Sketch by Stephen L. Brock (Eugene, OR: Cascade Books, 2015), xix + 195 pp. “Right now,” Father Stephen Brock observes, “there does seem to be some confusion about nature” (34). At that point in his new book, Fr. Brock is engaged in the task of making intelligible Aristotle’s understanding of nature as a principle and cause that makes certain things move, and he has just finished explaining that Aristotle took the existence of nature, or of things that act from such a cause, to be evident. It must be admitted, however, that “we can get confused even about such obvious truths” (ibid.). This kind of confusion is vexing not merely because we are happier when our thoughts are clearer and more in harmony with our experience of the world, but also because our confusion about matters that should be plain has a way of hindering us from receiving the saving truth of the Gospel in its integrity. If philosophy is, in fact, a “way to come to know fundamental truths about human life” (Pope John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, §5), then its ability to keep us from confusion about matters as foundational as what is and what is not natural is indeed precious.We ought, then, to prize philosophy “as one of the noblest of human tasks” (ibid., §3), and thus warmly welcome Fr. Brock’s invitation to consider it afresh through the eyes of one of its most appealing masters, St. Thomas Aquinas. The Philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas: A Sketch offers readers a tour of the Angelic Doctor’s thinking about nature and the created order that culminates in what Fr. Brock refers to as “reason’s glimpse of God” (109). In less than two hundred crisp and clear pages, he has achieved a work that his colleagues will envy, for it is at once both a satisfying presentation of Aquinas’s thought and a personal engagement with him as a philosophical companion. This “sketch” is an introduction and a survey that is also, and eminently, a work of original reflection. At each step of the way, the reader is offered a look at 1342 Book Reviews Aquinas’s thought that is both from the point of view of metaphysical wisdom (and sometimes explicitly theological wisdom) and firmly rooted in common experience and ordinary language. After an introduction entitled Manuductio that sets forth the work’s essential theme, Fr. Brock dedicates the first of his six chapters to an overview of Aquinas’s life and major works. The middle four chapters of the book are a march through the main topics of theoretical philosophy, beginning with nature and its principles, turning to the soul as a particular kind of nature, then examining the science of being and truth, and finally ascending to the consideration of “invisibles”—the human soul as subsistent form, the angels, and God. Only in the final chapter does Fr. Brock address Aquinas’s practical philosophy, and then decidedly from a metaphysical point of view, attending in particular to the role played by speculative philosophy in the defense and elucidation of the principles of ethics and politics. Aquinas’s considerable labor in the art of logic receives only a brief direct treatment in the chapter on metaphysics, but this is no omission. The art of arts is never far from view at any point in the book. To those readers who are broadly familiar with the literature on Aquinas as a philosopher, Fr. Brock’s decision to privilege a treatment of the theoretical over the practical will not surprise. For while it would be too much to say that there are works aplenty to serve as introductions to Thomas’s ethical thought, it seems fair to say that Fr. Brock has done a great service to the present generation of students by making the effort to introduce the features of Thomas’s thought that are less well known and, almost certainly, more foreign to most of us. The distinctive excellence of the book is captured in the introductory account of the nature and importance of manuductio, the “leading by the hand” of student by teacher that assists the one learning to pass from the knowledge of things more familiar to him, but in themselves less intelligible, to the knowledge of things further from the senses—even invisible—but more intelligible in themselves. This doctrine about the teacher’s task, grounded in the account of the natural way that human beings come to know, familiar from Aristotle’s Physics 1.1, shapes Fr. Brock’s book in three important ways. First, and most evidently, it provides the order for the book’s central, speculative chapters, which begin with a truth that is evident to the senses—namely, that things move, and progress in step-wise fashion to the truth that God is his own existence. Second, within those chapters, this doctrine guides Fr. Brock’s work as an expositor of Book Reviews 1343 Aquinas’s thought, as again and again he labors to make the particulars of that doctrine intelligible in light of what he takes to be the experiences that we all share, and even what he thinks our common intellectual custom likely to be. Third, this account of “leading by the hand” sheds light on what he takes the task of philosophy to be within the context of a Christian intellectual life that is ordered to the understanding of Divine Revelation. By the work’s end, philosophy—at least in the hands of Aquinas—has emerged as a most worthy and useful handmaiden to Sacred Theology. It will be worth savoring an instance or two of Fr. Brock’s art of teaching. An especially helpful one, to my mind, is his deft teaching-by-example of the difficult truth that the form of the thing known is present in the knower without its matter. Here he is exploring the general truth through an instance of sensation: “With your blue eyes you are seeing the black and white page. Nothing in you thereby is, or is even in the process of becoming, black and white. The blue in your eyes is only the blue of your eyes. But the forms of black and white in them are also the page’s forms. They are the page’s inasmuch as by them, the page itself is being seen” (65–66). Another characteristic bit of his teaching comes early in the book, when he is speaking about Aquinas’s tendency to be in dialogue with earlier thinkers. There he makes this distinction between the authority of a teacher and that of a commander: “Following a commander or lawgiver consists mainly in obeying, executing orders. This may sometimes require a clarification of the order’s meaning, or even of its purpose; but the point is to obey. Of course following a teacher also involves performing assigned tasks. But the point is to learn. And learning is very much a matter of asking questions. A good commander will allow some questions, but a good teacher welcomes, even provokes them” (4). In each case, as in many other similar discussions throughout the book, Fr. Brock effectively ties an important distinction or realization back to an everyday experience. As a result, one can say with confidence that, although the book certainly has its difficult passages due to the nature of its subject matter, on the whole it is remarkably approachable. It may, however, be worth saying something about what the book is not so as the better to locate its particular excellence. At the beginning of his fourth chapter, which is dedicated to Aquinas’s metaphysics, Fr. Brock quotes a well-known passage from the Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics on the order of learning, a passage that begins 1344 Book Reviews with the teaching that “boys should first be instructed in logical matters” (Brock, 83; Sent. eth. 6, lec. 7, no. 1211). He then offers a comment that helps to frame the whole of his book: “even though Thomas puts it [logic] first, I am only bringing it up now, because this book is not a course in Thomistic philosophy, but only a sketch of it, and because some of the (few) things that I want to say about his views on logic are easier to explain in light of things seen in the previous two chapters” (83–84). There is considerably more than meets the eye here. For, while there is, on the one hand, a plain admission that the book is not meant as a substitute for a course or curriculum in philosophy, there is, on the other, a gesture towards its essential characteristic: it is not at all an encyclopedic collection of Thomistic conclusions arrayed subject-by-subject for ease of reference. Quite the contrary, it is a deeply personal engagement with Aquinas as a philosopher that begins with our general experience of the world of moving things and proceeds to progressively more noble topics. And on every page, the concerns of the metaphysician are evident. Taken as a whole, Fr. Stephen Brock’s Philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas: A Sketch is an imposing achievement. He has been perseveringly in dialogue not only with Aquinas but also with all of his major interpreters from the past half century, as the footnotes and admirable bibliography amply demonstrate. It is the kind of book that one wants to put in the hands of seminarians, undergraduates nearing the end of their studies, and graduate students beginning theirs, not only because it conveys much truth but also because it provides an attractive model for how philosophizing ought to be done. The volume is especially strong in its treatment of nature, the principles of nature, and the soul as a kind of nature. In each case, the exposition begins with an explicit concern for our dominant intellectual custom, which is a materialism dominated by the imagination. Fr. Brock insists that his readers come to terms with the strangeness of Aquinas’s conception of nature, take note of what he means by form, and consider how attention to form—especially substantial form—opens up a vista upon the world that is different from the one gained from our physics, chemistry, and biology textbooks. His discussions of why animals are not best understood as machines, why the unity of living things needs to be contended with, and why sensing and knowing constitute new modes of being in the world are concise and compelling. Given all of the confusion about nature that surrounds us today, both outside and within the Church, this patient and accurate exposition of Aquinas’s view is timely indeed. And what makes it invaluable is Book Reviews 1345 that Fr. Brock is not content merely to describe Aquinas’s thinking; N&V he also subtly but unmistakably argues for its truth. Christopher O. Blum Augustine Institute Denver, Colorado Healing for Freedom: A Christian Perspective on Personhood and Psychotherapy by †Benedict M. Ashley, O.P. (Arlington, VA: The Institute for the Psychological Sciences Press, 2013), 352 pp. At the funeral Mass for Hans Urs von Balthasar, then-Car- dinal Joseph Ratzinger famously referred to the Swiss theologian named cardinal as the most cultured man of his time. A quarter of a century later, in surveying the work of Benedict Ashley, one wonders whether this Dominican priest might have been the most cultured man of our age. With his posthumously published Healing for Freedom: A Christian Perspective on Personhood and Psychotherapy, Ashley offers another parallel with the Swiss savant. Namely, Ashely provides a summary of his life’s work. While lacking the straightforwardness of Balthasar’s title—A Resume of My Thought—Ashley offers a no less comprehensive account of the central themes of his intellectual work. This accomplishment spanned three quarters of a century. In Healing for Freedom, Ashley meticulously lays down the foundation for a proper understanding of the human person. This understanding of the human person—body and soul—offers the only adequate foundation for both a sound psychology and practice of psychotherapy. As Romanus Cessario, O.P., has remarked: “There are no skyhooks for Father Ashley.” That is, Ashley eschews the transcendent philosophical program. He avoids leaps, jumps, and grand inferences. Like a skilled stone mason, Ashley instead constructs piece by piece a methodically argued description of the human person and his place in the created world. No part of natural science—be it a description of the function of the occipital and frontal lobes of the cerebrum or an analysis of the human lymphatic system—falls outside the scope of his study. Ashley delivers a comprehensive description of the human person from a physical, psychological, and spiritual perspective. The subtitle—A Christian Perspective on Personhood and Psychotherapy—requires proper interpretation. Admittedly, only the final of the nine chapters explicitly takes up the question of psychotherapy. 1346 Book Reviews However, Ashley points out that a proper exercise of psychoanalysis requires a sound understanding of the human person. As Veritatis Splendor reminds us, the truth about the good of the human person offers the only path to our understanding authentic human flourishing. Healing for Freedom unfolds in nine chapters. The first sets out three possible philosophical approaches to the human person: (1) dualist— such as found, to varying degrees, in Plato, Descartes, and Kant; (2) reductionist—found throughout the philosophical tradition in figures such as Zeno, Hobbes, Freud and, generally, behaviorists and determinists; and (3) the instrumentalist approach as found, most notably, in Aristotle and Aquinas. Dualists hold that the human being is composed of two natures, material and spiritual. Innumerable difficulties arise when these authors try to explain how a composite produces a single human being. Reductionists—influenced greatly in the modern period by the work of Charles Darwin—argue that human activity can be explained simply with reference to material causes. Instrumentalists, for their part, affirm the human being is a body-soul composite, though a unified substance in which the body is the material cause and the soul is the unifying formal cause. In the second chapter, Ashley pursues the human being as a bodysoul composite. He discusses the range of scientific disciplines from those that concern man in his material nature to those that address man as a spiritual being. Ashley explains that many of the present confusions in psychology result from a misunderstanding of its place among the scientific disciplines. A key distinction for Ashley discerns comparative psychology from personal psychology. Comparative psychology ranks as the highest discipline of natural science; it studies—even with the help of advanced technology—man in his animal nature. By contrast, personal psychology studies aspects of human behavior as a properly human phenomenon. Because personal psychology touches the immaterial in man, Ashely asserts that this discipline requires a “properly metaphysical analysis.” In chapters 3 and 4, Ashley describes what it means for the human being to be embodied. He provides a full description of the various bodily systems: circulatory, respiratory, lymphatic, digestive, endocrine, reproductive, skeletal, muscular, and integumentary. He does not take sides on the variety of evolutionary theories—for example, neo-Darwinian or the theory of punctuated equilibrium advanced by Stephen Jay Gould. In any case, Ashley holds that evolutionary theory explains only the material reality of man. No evolutionary Book Reviews 1347 theory can address how Ashley describes the human being as a bodysoul composite. Chapter 5 offers a comprehensive refutation of the position that no essential difference can be found between human and animal intelligence. Man stands at the juncture of the material and spiritual orders. As a living being, the human person requires proper knowledge of his psychology. Such a psychology must embrace the true nature of man as a per se unum, a substance of body and soul (see Catechism of the Catholic Church, §365). Ashley explains: “The human person thus exists on the borderline between the physical and spiritual parts of the universe, and so it must be studied first by comparative psychology (which is part of natural science) and second by personal psychology (which works by analogy from the results of comparative psychology)” (216). Ashley remains most well known in many quarters for his work in moral theology. In chapters 6 and 7, he summarizes his basic approach to moral matters: virtue-based moral reasoning, freedom viewed as a freedom for excellence, and a willingness to refuse accommodation to contemporary decadences. What is most consoling, Ashley provides a model for the healthy human person. Sound psychology depends upon such a model. Still, he explains: “Amazingly enough, one can read innumerable works on psychology and psychotherapy without ever running across any such model” (217). While agnosticism, or sometimes even outright hostility toward religion, may be commonplace among those working in the field of psychology, Ashley holds that religious faith affords a benefit to psychological health. He counsels psychotherapists to leave questions of ethics or spiritual direction to those expert in those fields. He rather encourages therapists to aid patients by assisting them to adopt a healthy and realistic outlook about themselves and their surroundings. In the final chapter, Ashley explains that the purpose of psychotherapy is “to heal the animal aspect of human psychology . . . so that it can normally serve the whole human person” (317). He insists on the need for all persons to adopt a worldview and value system that will strengthen their human psychological makeup. The elaboration of worldviews and value systems, however, properly belong to metaphysics and theology. The first principles of being and acting cannot be fabricated even by the best practitioners of psychotherapy. Neurosis remains one obstacle to a healthy psychological makeup. Ashley distinguishes neurosis from vice. He explains that “neurosis is a distorted habit of behavior at a psychological level below that of 1348 Book Reviews intelligence and freedom, which, however, limits and distorts intelligence and free behavior” (330–01). For this reason, sound psychotherapy—grounded in the truth about human freedom—offers the best possibility of healing neurosis. To return to the theme of Ashley’s intellectual output, each of the nine chapters summarizes some aspect of Ashley’s impressive literary corpus. Chapter 1, on the different models of the human person, recapitulates his significant but insufficiently known work Theologies of the Body: Humanist and Christian (1985). The second chapter’s defense of some of Aristotle’s claims in natural science recalls Ashley’s dissertation, “Aristotle’s Sluggish Earth” (1958). Both of these initial chapters address the division of the sciences—including comparative and personal psychology—which finds detailed explanation in Ashley’s important text on the foundation of metaphysics, The Way toward Wisdom: An Interdisciplinary and Intercultural Introduction to Metaphysics (2009). One also recalls his unrelenting defense of the River Forest position on the foundation of natural science as the basis for metaphysics. Chapters 3–5, which treat issues of natural science, draw to mind Ashley’s Choosing a Worldview and Value System: An Ecumenical Apologetics (2000) and his How Science Enriches Theology (2012). Chapter 6, on morality, corresponds to his insightful Living the Truth in Love: A Biblical Introduction to Moral Theology (1996). This chapter also offers a brief synopsis of biomedical and sexual ethics, and the several editions of Health Care Ethics, authored with Kevin D. O’Rourke, supply a fuller treatment. Ashley addresses issues surrounding gender roles and the diverse psychological makeup of men and women in his Justice in the Church: Gender and Participation (1996). His insights in this book inform chapter 7, on human communities, specifically in the discussion of gender. Chapter 8 analyzes the human person from the spiritual perspective. One thinks of Ashley’s works Spiritual Direction in the Dominican Tradition (1995), Thomas Aquinas: The Gifts of the Spirit (1996), and his short account of Dominican history in The Dominicans (1991). Throughout the book under review, Ashley offers strong criticism of authors with whom he has sparred throughout his intellectual career. He challenges the work of Germain Grisez, who eschews both the hierarchy of the goods in human life and the ultimate end of man in contemplation (222), Charles Curran, who gainsays the immorality of inherently non-procreative sexual acts (251), and Henri de Book Reviews 1349 Lubac, who, in Ashley’s view, fails adequately to distinguish between the natural and supernatural orders (287). Some insights in Healing for Freedom provide vintage Ashley. For example, as an outstanding Thomist, Ashley rightly states Aquinas’s original contribution to theories of knowledge: “In Aquinas’s own case it is often claimed that his original intuition, evident in his first philosophical work De Ente et Essentia, is the ‘real distinction of essence and existence.’ In my opinion, more fundamental still was his profound recognition that all our natural human knowledge rests on the senses, a point in Aristotle not clearly seen by earlier readings of the Stagirite, even by St. Albertus” (199). Father Ashley worked on Healing for Freedom at the end of his long life (1915–2013). While he supplies references to contemporary psychological literature, students will also benefit from the bibliographical references found in his other works. All in all, one receives the impression of a master who has sought—and found—the truth in every corner of human learning. For those seeking a grounding in a philosophy of the human person that addresses issues of psychology and psychological counseling, Healing for Freedom will serve as a welcome resource. Christians hold on good authority that the truth sets free ( John 8:32). Healing for Freedom takes it cue from this biblical passage. Father Ashley teaches us that authentic freedom arises only when one embraces the full N&V truth about the human person. Ryan Connors St. John’s Seminary Brighton, Massachusetts The Gospel of the Family: Going Beyond Cardinal Kasper’s Proposal in the Debate on Marriage, Civil Re-Marriage, and Communion in the Church by Juan José Pérez-Soba and Stephan Kampowski, trans. Michael J. Miller (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2014), 255 pp. Since the announcement by Pope Francis in 2013 of the Synod on the Family, the Church has found herself in the midst of a heated debate regarding a whole spectrum of issues pertaining to marriage and family. At the center of this debate stands Cardinal Walter Kasper’s speech entitled “The Gospel of the Family,” delivered on February 20, 2014. The speech was addressed to the Pope and some 1350 Book Reviews 150 cardinals gathered at the extraordinary consistory. Kasper’s speech advocating change in the Church’s practice regarding divorced and remarried Catholics caused an avalanche of responses centering on the Christian tradition of monogamous and indissoluble marriage, as well as on the nature of mercy, compassion, tolerance, personal identity, the common good, the purpose of theology, and so on. Juan José Pérez-Soba and Stephan Kampowski, professors of pastoral theology and of philosophical anthropology (respectively) at the John Paul II Institute for Marriage and Family in Rome, join the discussion in this book. Their key question is not whether divorced and remarried Catholics should be allowed to receive sacramental communion, but rather the question of human happiness. If, as they emphasize, “the goal of the sinodal work is to proclaim the Gospel of the Family in its total beauty” (33–34), one needs to ask a question: How can people find happiness and fulfillment in their lives? According to Pérez-Soba and Kampowski, monogamous marriage between a man and a woman answers the human quest for happiness and unlocks the mystery of divine mercy. The book, well researched and written in a forceful tone, examines the above-mentioned question in five chapters. The first chapter, written by Kampowski, analyzes the cultural setting in which the Gospel of the Family is proclaimed. Kampowski approaches the topic from the perspective of heuristic of fear as spelled out by Hans Jonas in his book The Imperative of Responsibility. The fear that Jonas speaks about is not a fear of something but rather a fear for something, for a great value that is in danger of being extinguished. For Kampowski, the value that is threatened by Kasper’s intervention is the exclusivity and durability of marriage. He locates Kasper’s efforts within the movement of the sexual revolution. The sexual revolution has emphasized that “the core of happiness in life is sexual happiness” and that a “lasting relationship is a health hazard” (27). Consequently, a society that follows this philosophy promotes a radical anthropological revolution that attempts to cancel out the truth of creation that human beings are born male and female and that “celebrates the condom as the redemption of human sexuality” (41). Yet, in such a sex-saturated culture, the Church is still seen as a moral authority and an interlocutor in moral debates. The Church must then recover the sense of beauty and preciousness of the Gospel message by emphasizing how the deepest aspirations of the human heart for love and affirmation are fulfilled. According to Kampowski, the Church is in danger of committing “assisted religious suicide” by Book Reviews 1351 giving up morally demanding aspects of her message, namely, that “sex is an expression of love,” that “true love wants to say forever,” and that love “requires constant labor.” Exclusivity, durability, and abstinence are not the means of stifling love and happiness, but rather the necessary means of the redemption of eros and of human beings. The second chapter picks up where the first one left off. In it, Pérez-Soba studies the redemption of human love by presenting it within the context of God’s covenantal relationship in which truth and mercy meet. According to Pérez-Soba, Kasper’s understanding of mercy as tolerance and leniency flattens out the concept of mercy. Mercy must be presented within the context of the covenant. Within this context, mercy “springs from love for the person in order to cure him from the sickness of infidelity that afflicts him and prevents him from living in the relationship with God” (82). The root of mercy, then, is not tolerance, but rather God’s passionate desire to overcome human misery, primarily sin and death, through a new gift that unites the sinner with God. Thus, indissolubility, Pérez-Soba emphasizes, is not in the first place a juridical requirement, as Cardinal Kasper views it, but rather it is a direct expression of God’s merciful love. In other words, “indissolubility does not result from a divine mandate that is added to marriage, but rather it is a quality of the personal union” (85) that is, according to Pérez-Soba, at stake. In the case of failed marriage, what needs repentance is not the failure itself “but the fact of having broken the sign of the covenant and of fidelity to Christ” ( John Paul II, Familiaris Consortio, §84). The change in practice advocated by Cardinal Kasper is not a simple juridical accommodation. Rather, the change of practice undermines the entire edifice of the Catholic doctrine based on God’s self-manifestation and his desire to lead his people to a more abundant life. Having elaborated upon the sacramental bond of marriage, PérezSoba moves on in the next chapter (ch. 3) to examine the patristic data used by Cardinal Kasper to advocate his theology of tolerance and leniency. In examining the experience of the primitive Church, Pérez-Soba emphasizes, one needs to bear in mind six things: (1) the Christian believers of the first centuries found themselves in a society with a high divorce rate; (2) many converts came from very diverse situations of life; (3) the previous tradition was lacking; (4) there was no difference between religious and civil marriage; (5) the sacramental aspect of marriage was not developed; and finally, (6) the Church needed to withstand the civil power that desired to impose its views on the her. Bearing in mind these six factors, Pérez-Soba studies 1352 Book Reviews the following texts: “Cannon 8 of the Council of Nicea,” Origen’s “Comment about the Matthean Exception,” St. Basil’s “Canon,” and some passing comments made by St. Gregory of Nazianzus and by St. Augustine. According to Pérez-Soba, Kasper’s presentation of the above-mentioned texts is one-sided and erroneous. It is based on questionable and partisan scholarship that manipulates and fabricates the data. So, Pérez-Soba concludes that the primitive Church, rather than promoting any sort of tolerance, forcefully witnessed “indissolubility, in opposition to the social custom of that era” in “a realization of the prophetic value of Christian marriage” (123). Chapter 4 considers the construction of the moral subject by means of action. In this chapter, Kampowski presents marriage as a remedy to the illness of “chronological atomism” so prevalent in contemporary liquid society (see the work of Zygmunt Bauman). Chronological atomism gives many people an impression of being the simple administrators rather than the artists of their lives. Yet, to “be an artist . . . one needs a project. To have a project, one needs a goal” (141). Quoting Maurice Blondel, Kampowski writes about that goal: “We do not go forward, we do not learn, we do not enrich ourselves except by closing off for ourselves all roads but one and by impoverishing ourselves of all that we might have known or gained otherwise. . . . I must commit myself under the pain of losing everything” (Blondel, Action, 4). Kampowski’s argument here resembles that made by Charles Larmore in his book entitled The Practices of the Self. For Larmore, authenticity means committing oneself and taking a stand. In other words, in order to be authentic, one needs a commitment. Marriage plays a preeminent role in making love a journey—a journey from affective union to real union. The journey of love heals as well as generates action, and consequently structures a Christian subject. The final chapter, written by Pérez-Soba, crowns the argument by proposing an adequate pastoral care of marriage and family, which he calls “the pastoral approach of accompaniment” (164). In spelling out his pastoral proposal Pérez-Soba draws heavily on the view of marriage preparation found in Pope John Paul II’s 1981 Familiaris Consortio. A person prepares for marriage from birth. The Church, as the evangelizing community, “must teach every person to love” by “profoundly changing the structures, especially in regards to the catechesis of children, pastoral care in schools, and youth ministry” (202). According to Pérez-Soba, Kasper’s approach, rather than Book Reviews 1353 analyzing the roots of the problem, tries to resolve the pastoral questions solely through a change of norm. This, according to PérezSoba, is an error. This approach breathes legalism. Paradoxically, Kasper, who accuses the Church of legalism, falls himself victim to it by presenting law as coming from authority (bonum quia iussum) rather than from the truth about the good of things (iussum quia bonum). The book finishes with an appendix that, in a certain sense, summarizes the book’s argument by providing answers to the thirty key questions that the authors have formulated for the members of the Synod on the Family. This short summary does not do full justice to this well-researched and profound meditation on a host of issues. Pérez-Soba and Kampowski present their material in a very coherent way, sifting the wheat from the weeds of Kasper’s argument. Their criticism of Kasper’s approach, though sometimes overly sarcastic, is a passionate call to the Church not to throw the baby out with the bath water. The call to marriage and family, though difficult, is a call that guarantees human flourishing and fulfillment. Family based on the indissoluble bond of a man and a woman is indeed a pearl of great price, N&V and one cannot sell it cheaply. Marek J. Duran Mundelein Seminary Mundelein, Illinois Memory in Augustine’s Theological Anthropology by Paige E. Hochschild (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2012), 272 pp. In Memory in Augustine’s Theological Anthropology, Paige Hochschild seeks to recover “the neglected significance of memory as the foundation for Augustine’s theological anthropology” (4). Indeed, it comes as a surprise to most of us in the field that Hochschild’s work, a revision of her 2005 dissertation, is the first book-length study of Augustine’s understanding of memory. As such, it is a useful resource for thinking about the main texts and the philosophical background related to this relatively under-studied topic. Hochschild’s main purpose in studying memory in Augustine is twofold: to contribute to the ongoing discussion of Augustine’s theory of knowledge and, more importantly, to demonstrate that, for Augustine, memory is at the heart of what it means to be a human being made in the image of God. Memory, Hochschild argues, “unites the embodied and intellectual aspects of human existence, 1354 Book Reviews and demands that the effects of grace pervade the whole person, both through the right ordering in relation to creation, and, prior to this, through a rightly ordered grounding in the divine” (167). The book is divided into three major parts: part I deals with Greek philosophical antecedents; part II deals with Augustine’s early works; and part III treats Augustine’s mature work on memory (in particular, Confessions 10–13 and De Trinitate 12–14). Hochschild’s approach in these three parts is both historical and exegetical. She wants to root Augustine’s understanding of memory in a “history of ideas,” primarily from the Greek philosophical tradition, but she also wants to give an account of Augustine’s own development on this question. Rather than abstracting the main ideas of Augustine and the Greeks, Hochschild analyzes particular texts within the context they in which were written. She moves through the major passages from major works on memory and exegetes them with nuance. In the first part of her study, Hochschild focuses on the “Platonist” influences on Augustine—Plato, Aristotle, and Plotinus in particular. While Augustine certainly had other philosophical influences (the Stoics or Cicero in his mediation of the Greek tradition, for example) it is these three, Hochschild argues, who lay the groundwork, who set the questions, and who offer the range of possible answers. Hochschild does not argue for strict parallels between any of these philosophers and Augustine, but rather for resonances. This allows her to situate Augustine within the “history of ideas,” arguing that, while Augustine is certainly most influenced by Plotinus (to whom he had the most access), many of his conclusions are closer to Plato and Aristotle. Part II treats Augustine’s early philosophical works from the time of his conversion up to his ordination in 391: the Cassiciacum dialogues, the treatises on the soul, and De magistro and De musica. In these, the topic of memory emerges gradually, first in relation to the nature of wisdom and then in thinking through how sense perception is related to wisdom. But it is in these dialogues that Augustine begins to realize the centrality of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo, as well as “the incarnational rationale for an anthropology founded on memory” (110). These insights point ahead to Augustine’s mature discussion in the Confessions. In Part III, Hochschild discusses memory in the Confessions, what she considers the heart of her study, as well as in De Trinitate. Book 10 of the Confessions famously deals with memory, and most scholars isolate this text from its context. Hochschild situates it in the overall Book Reviews 1355 work and ably shows how it is foundational for understanding the last three books, a perennial headache for Augustine scholars. Augustine’s discussion of memory in book 10 raises questions of how the temporal, embodied soul can have union with the eternal. This propels the argument into books 11–13: book 11 takes up the question of the relation between the temporal and eternal through the discussion of the Incarnation and the analogy of the inspired word of Scripture, and books 12 and 13 complete the trajectory by bringing to the fore the necessity of the Church as the locus of the reconciliation of the tensions between body and soul and between the temporal and the eternal. Indeed, for memory to function as the unifying factor of body and soul, and of both with creation and God, it needs “the memory of the Church” (153). De Trinitate has a goal similar to that of the Confessions: “a harmony and unification of the temporal and eternal in Christ, for the sake of spiritual peace” (189). What De Trinitate adds is a much more developed understanding of the Trinitarian image of God in man and faith in the incarnate mediator as the means of union with the Trinity. There is much to recommend in this book. The approach to Augustine’s philosophical background in part I is helpful for bringing out resonances that are often overlooked, such as Augustine’s continuity with Aristotle. Moreover, one appreciates any scholar who pushes back against the commonplaces that the Greeks were simple dualists and that Augustine follows them in this. Yet another benefit of the volume is it gathers most of the important passages on memory and analyzes them in one place, although the reader less familiar with Augustine’s works will want to have the original texts at hand, since much of Hochschild’s analysis presupposes intimate familiarity with the movements of the texts. Lastly, her contextual and exegetical approach to Augustine’s works enables her to avoid many of the pitfalls common to the discussion of memory, particular the frequent treatment of book 10 of the Confessions as an isolated philosophical treatise. Hochschild helpfully shows how book 10 logically flows into (indeed, requires) books 11–13 and shows how memory is ordered toward, and so must be understood within, the context of the Church’s memory. Throughout her discussion of Augustine’s works, Hochschild continually emphasizes how creation and the Incarnation are fundamental principles for all of Augustine’s thinking, especially on the question of anthropology. This, too, is a welcome change from other treatments of Augustine’s “philosophical” ideas that so often distort his thought by separating it from its properly theological 1356 Book Reviews context. All of this (and more) makes this volume a beneficial addition to the discussion of memory in Augustine. By way of critique, let me highlight two lacunae in her treatment. First is the oversight of Epistles 3–14, especially 7, in which Augustine discusses his understanding of the Platonist philosophers with Nebridius, including an important discussion of memory. These are essential texts in the history of Augustine’s developing thought on memory and the philosophical issues surrounding it. Moreover, they may very well modify some of Hochschild’s arguments on how Augustine interpreted Platonic recollection. Another oversight in Hochschild’s discussion of memory that which would have bolstered her argument is book 9 of the Confessions. This book, too, could be called a treatise on memory. Augustine remembers all of his dead loved ones: Verecundus, Nebridius, Adeodatus, and most importantly, Monica. Indeed, book 9 ends with Augustine remembering Monica’s plea that she be remembered at God’s altar (9.13.36). By analyzing this book, Hochschild could have further developed what I think was her most interesting point—and the point that most discussions of Augustine on memory completely miss: for Augustine, it is the Church’s memory that shapes memory and it does this by reminding human beings of God’s mindfulness of them. We are reminded of this when we celebrate the Eucharist, the memorial of Christ’s suffering and death. We are inscribed in God’s memory; he remembers us, even when we forget him; and we become aware of this in the Church, particularly in the memorial sacrifice celebrated at the altar. Perhaps this is why book 10—the traditional locus for thinking about Augustine on memory—ends with Augustine the bishop, in a sense, standing before the altar dispensing the Eucharist to the “the brethren” (10.4.5–6) who are admitted to this part of the work: “I think about the price of my redemption and I eat it and I drink it and I dispense it to others” (10.43.70).1 Addressing these lacunae would have strengthened her work considerably. Still, Hochschild has done a service by bringing together and carefully walking us through most of the major texts of N&V Augustine on memory. Jared Ortiz Hope College Holland, Michigan 1 My own translation from the Latin in Augustine: Confessions, ed. James O’Donnell, 3 vols. (Oxford, UK: Clarendon, 1992); available also online at www.stoa. org. Book Reviews 1357 Nature and Grace: A New Approach to Thomistic Ressourcement by Andrew Dean Swafford (Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 2014), xi + 220 pp. As the opening pages of this title appropriately recall, the topic of nature and grace touches virtually every theological and human question. Well aware of the implications of a doctrine so foundational to the Christian faith, Andrew Swafford’s recent volume offers a careful summary of the debate and a welcome contribution to its resolution through the theology of Matthias J. Scheeben. In his opening chapter, Swafford reviews the key schools at play in the nature-grace debate. Intrinsicism holds that man’s fulfillment lies only in and through Christ, with the result that a purely natural beatitude is impossible (6). The most notable figure of this tradition, Henri de Lubac, argued that man has a natural desire for the beatific vision and that any other final end would result only in man’s permanent frustration and suffering (14). Extrinsicism, meanwhile, counters with the observation that important questions concerning God’s justice and the gratuity of grace emerge if the beatific vision is taken to be man’s only possible end. Significantly, Pope Pius XII’s 1950 encyclical Humani Generis appeared to target de Lubac specifically in echoing the very lines of the extrinsicist tradition: “Others [de Lubac?] destroy the gratuity of the supernatural order, since God, they say, cannot create intellectual beings without ordering and calling them to the Beatific Vision.”1 On the other hand, Swafford recalls that, by the very next decade, the Second Vatican Council would weigh in on this issue “undoubtedly in favor of de Lubac” (15) by teaching that man has a single final end: “All are in fact called to one and the same destiny, which is divine.”2 Extrinsicism’s solution to the nature-grace relationship proceeds by insisting that man has two final ends—natural and supernatural— the latter accessible only by grace. God’s justice implies the debitum naturae, that he provide whatever is necessary for a creature to reach its natural end (10). Strictly speaking, God is not so much indebted to the creature as he is to himself and to the manifestation of his own divine wisdom in the natural order (10–11). Of course, the very creation of a thing is gratuitous, and in this way, one may speak of supernatural grace as “doubly” gratuitous because it elevates man over and above his specific nature (11). 1 2 Pope Pius XII, Humani Generis (1950), §26. Second Vatican Council, Gaudium et Spes (1965), §22. 1358 Book Reviews For the extrinsicist tradition, man’s capacity for the beatific vision cannot be described as a natural inclination, since its actualization would be due to the creature according to divine justice without the further elevation of grace. For this reason, the extrinsicist tradition employs the concept of “obediential potency” to account for the relationship between human nature and the beatific vision (15). Obediential potency itself has two distinct acceptations. “Generic” obediential potency can be seen in the case of a miracle and necessitates no real relation between the specific nature of the creature and its transformation. Contrary to this, “specific” obediential potency is rooted in the very nature of the creature in question: such an elevation is perfective of that particular nature, albeit in a way that transcends its natural powers (15–16). Chapter 2 offers an overview of de Lubac’s nature-grace theology in its historical and theological context. Reviewing the principal features of the intrinsicist tradition discussed in the introduction, Swafford recalls that de Lubac’s aim was to re-articulate a Christian humanism for post-war Europe (25). In de Lubac’s mind, the unconscionable events of this period showcase the disastrous fruits of atheistic humanism and the inability of the pure-nature tradition to respond adequately in this secularist milieu. He further argues that the pure-nature tradition actually abetted the rise of modern secularism, on account of its excessive emphasis upon the independent integrity of the natural order (37). Swafford exhibits great balance in his assessment of the various nature-grace schools in relation to St. Thomas. The Angelic Doctor “was certainly no exponent of the pure-nature tradition” (37), yet on the other hand, “there is abundant support in Aquinas for the intelligible distinction between man’s proportionate natural end and his disproportionate supernatural end” (40). As the author rightly observes, the exegetical question concerning Aquinas’s position “is largely insoluble, since it all depends on which texts are interpretively privileged over others. One set of texts lends support to the legitimacy of the pure-nature tradition, while others clearly favor de Lubac” (37). Leaving aside the exegetical question, Swafford proceeds to outline the rudiments of the pure-nature tradition in Tommaso de Vio (Cajetan), Francisco Suárez, and the controversy surrounding Michael Baius that “perhaps more than all else . . . spurred the rapid rise and enduring hegemony of the pure-nature tradition” (41). On de Lubac’s account, the pure-nature tradition may have offered a Book Reviews 1359 solution to the problems posed by Baius, but in so doing it played right into the hands of modern secularism (49). Concluding this chapter, Swafford notes that it is difficult to pin down de Lubac’s position, since he wishes to affirm the principal theses of all sides of the nature-grace debate. In concert with the pure-nature tradition, de Lubac ardently defends the real distinction between nature and grace, yet he simultaneously denies foundational elements of the extrinsicist school that would seem necessary in order to ensure this distinction. De Lubac justifies his playing on both sides of the field through recourse to paradox, which Swafford describes as the centerpiece of his overall position, the legitimacy of his theology of nature and grace standing or falling on its legitimacy (65). Swafford, for his part, incisively weighs in on the matter: “For this reason, we must ask whether this category of paradox is sufficient to hold together all the elements of his thought—or whether it is merely a case of special pleading, a sort of intellectual panacea, against which no serious objection can ever really be brought” (65). After a brief chapter (ch. 3) revisiting the foundational principles of the nature-grace debate, Swafford dedicates chapter 4 to reviewing Lawrence Feingold’s defense of the pure-nature tradition. In popular piety, one may say that “all is grace,” but Feingold asks whether this is not tantamount to affirming that “all is nature?” In other words, if the meaning of grace is extended to include all of creation, then the uniqueness of what is meant by “grace” loses its specificity (87). In an insightful citation from Edward Oakes—an author in whose thought this volume is deeply rooted—Swafford observes that the breakdown of the nature-grace distinction has led many to relativize the uniqueness of Christ by supposing that all religions give equal access to the transcendent (87–88). At this point, Swafford revisits in more detail several issues addressed in the volume’s opening chapter. In distinguishing “generic” from “specific” obediential potency, Feingold offers the story of Balaam’s talking donkey (Num 22:21–39) as an example of the former. While this miracle does not violate the law of non-contradiction strictly speaking, “specific” obediential potency obeys the law of non-contradiction in a much more narrowly defined sense insofar as, here, the elevation of the creature does not result in a change in its fundamental nature (91). Feingold therefore alleges correctly that “de Lubac’s neglect of this nuance shows his criticisms here to be largely unfounded, as they pertain only to generic obedi- 1360 Book Reviews ential potency” (92). In the same vein, Feingold likewise shows that de Lubac is incorrect to allege that the notion of the debitum naturae undermines the gratuity of creation (100). The pure-nature tradition does not maintain that God is dependent on the creature, but rather indebted only to himself and to the order that he has freely willed to establish (101). In a particularly poignant criticism of de Lubac, Feingold shows that he has drawn the guiding principle for his position not from Aquinas, but rather from Ockham, who shares his rejection of the debitum naturae. Presuming that God “can do with the creature whatever pleases Him” and that “God is not a debtor to anyone, but whatever He does to us is done from mere grace,” Ockham’s nominalism rejected nature’s objective intelligibility. As Pope Benedict XVI similarly observed of Scotus’s philosophy in his Regensburg Address, nominalism’s rejection of metaphysical realism goes hand in hand with voluntarism’s capricious God who is not bound by truth or goodness (103). Drawing on the thought of Servais Pinckaers, Swafford demonstrates that the debitum naturae precludes voluntarism—“not because God is dependent upon the creature or upon the categories of natural reason—but because He is the source of these very categories themselves” (105). For the pure-nature tradition, the debt of nature manifests and recognizes God’s freedom rather than restricting it. In the final section of his chapter on Feingold, Swafford rehearses the latter’s arguments in favor not only of the conceptual possibility of pure nature but also of the actual possibility of a purely natural end in this economy. St. Thomas considered limbo to be established Church teaching, and it is on this basis that Feingold proposes that purely natural happiness may be found within the present economy. For his part, Swafford believes that, “had it not been for the customary acceptance of the doctrine of limbo, [St. Thomas] would not have come so close to affirming the possibility of man’s purely natural end in the present economy” (115). Aquinas was well aware that pure nature has never actually existed due to the fact that the first man was constituted in a state of grace (115). Breaking with Feingold on this particular point, Swafford asserts that “the speculative question regarding man’s purely natural end . . . is probably not best adjudicated by recourse to the final state of limbo, since such a premise is less universally Book Reviews 1361 viable in the present context than it used to be in a previous era of the Church” (40; cf. 114). 3 Chapter 5 turns to Steven A. Long, whom the author describes as “much closer to the spirit of St. Thomas than is his fellow pure-nature advocate Lawrence Feingold” (40). Whereas the latter employs limbo as a premise in his argument defending the possibility of man’s purely natural end, Long is “much more sensitive to the fact that the concrete ordination of the present economy necessarily modifies the hypothetical possibilities of pure nature” (40). A purely natural end in this economy is precluded for two reasons. First, man is subject to the providential ordering of the eternal law, and in this economy, God has ordered human nature to the beatific vision. Second, the condition of sin is such that man needs healing grace even for the attainment of the natural good (115–16). According to Long, the root problem afflicting de Lubac’s naturegrace theology is the loss of the “theonomic” conception of the natural order (119). From a theonomic perspective, the natural order is hardly one of secular autonomy. Rather, the natural order is itself an expression of and always dependent upon the divine wisdom (120). That said, if one removes the full theonomic conception of the natural order and then attempts to utilize the pure-nature system of theology, then one will indeed end up reinforcing secularism, as per de Lubac’s charge (121). Long traces the origins of this deviant form the pure-nature tradition to Luis de Molina and the post-Enlightenment inheritance of the natural order as a causally closed system (121). The third and final section of Swafford’s volume (chs. 6 and 7) contains his proposal for reconciling the extrinsicist and intrinsicist traditions. After an always helpful review of his foregoing argument, the author introduces the figure of Matthias J. Scheeben, whose uniqueness as a thinker he pauses to consider at some length. Particularly interesting, even if it is not essential to the book’s argument, is Swafford’s depiction of Scheeben as being at home not only with St. Thomas but also with the Greek Fathers, Jesuit theology, and the 3 While agreeing wholeheartedly with the author on this point, one may wonder here whether the rejection of limbo as a viable solution could be better documented. For example, Swafford’s point is treated at some length in the International Theological Commission’s 2007 On the Hope of Salvation for Infants Who Die without Being Baptized, a work he does not mention in this volume. Another important and fascinating work from the Catholic tradition, Dante’s Divine Comedy would also be worth a brief mention here for its position vis-à-vis the suffering of souls in limbo. 1362 Book Reviews theology of Blessed John Duns Scotus, with whom he agrees in identifying the basis of the Incarnation in man’s deification rather than in sin (145–46). As Swafford writes, the distinction between nature and grace “is absolutely essential, in Scheeben’s mind, for the purpose of preserving the supernatural character of the Christian faith—a point which of course brings him squarely into accord with Feingold, Long, and the pure-nature tradition” (149–50). Like these thinkers, Scheeben describes man’s capacity for the beatific vision in terms of a specific obediential potency (156). Similarly for Scheeben, the “natural” desire for the beatific vision must be viewed as a mere “wish” (velleitas), the non-fulfillment of which does not entail suffering, since its object lies beyond the powers of one’s own agency (158–59). While allowing that certain texts would support the view that Scheeben accepted the possibility of a purely natural end in this economy, Swafford argues that seeing the natural end as a hypothetical rather than concrete possibility “better align[s] with the internal logic of Scheeben’s thought” (163). While he seems in certain passages to align with Feingold in being “at ease with the notion of limbo as a final state” (166), in other places he denies the possibility of man’s realization of a purely natural end in the present economy for reasons “more or less the same as Long’s given previously” (167). Swafford summarizes: “The divine ordination of the eternal law in this economy makes all the difference, since the failure to actualize God’s concrete ordination necessarily results in some kind of frustration and suffering” (169). Like de Lubac, then, Scheeben rejects the possibility of a purely natural end being realized in the present economy, yet, with the pure-nature tradition, he affirms its hypothetical coherence (ibid.). It is for this reason that Swafford believes Scheeben’s theology “is singularly poised to reconcile intrinsicism and extrinsicism” (194). A highlight of chapter 6 consists in its survey of Scheeben’s evocative theology of divine sonship. “For Scheeben,” Swafford writes, “this order of supernatural grace has such an ontological density that he goes on to speak of a certain ‘equality’ between man and God” (175).4 What de Lubac sought to secure by way of his teaching on man’s natural desire, Scheeben achieves by means of the Incarnation: “For Scheeben . . . the Incarnation brings about a permanent relation between the Eternal Son and all of humanity, and this relation 4 For an outstanding more extensive presentation of Scheeben’s theology of divinization, see R. Jared Staudt, “Substantial Union with God in Matthias Scheeben,” Nova et Vetera (English) 11.2 (2013): 515–36. Book Reviews 1363 pertains to the entire human race” (186). This union exists even prior to baptism, which itself “perfects, seals, organizes, completes, and consummates this union; but its foundation had been laid previously” (190). With powerful spousal imagery, Scheeben maintains that “no less than a nuptial union has taken place in the Incarnation between the Logos and the entire human race” (188). This way of speaking aligns beautifully with the Second Vatican Council when it states, “For by His Incarnation the Son of God has united Himself in some fashion with every man.”5 In this light, Swafford is spot on in connecting Scheeben with the intrinsicist insight that reality is, at its core, unabashedly Christocentric (194). In concluding, a final pair of noteworthy observations emerge from a reading of Swafford’s outstanding text. First, it has been remarked elsewhere that Swafford’s book should have stuck more closely to Scripture and Scripture’s categories for adjudicating the nature-grace debate.6 I believe that this is a rather simplistic objection, since Scripture itself no more resolves the precise relationship of nature and grace than it does the relationship of Christ’s two natures. That said, it would be outstanding if the author were to pursue additional work grounding the debate more thoroughly in the study of Scripture, “the soul of sacred theology.” 7 Second, the author intends his work to be a synthesis of the intrinsicist and extrinsicist traditions, yet its sympathies lie much more with the latter on the whole. While I tend to agree with Swafford’s argument and conclusion, more work remains in order to account for the great extent to which de Lubac’s theology has been incorporated into the postconciliar magisterium. The author certainly acknowledges that much of de Lubac’s theology was adopted by the Second Vatican Council and that his teaching was echoed many times over by Pope John Paul (61). The next challenge is to articulate how Swafford’s account is compatible with what he acknowledges to be a broader shift in the Church from the extrinsicism of pure-nature theology to the more intrinsicist alignment of N&V de Lubac (27). Matthew J. Ramage Benedictine College Atchison, Kansas 5 6 7 Vatican II, Gaudium et Spes, §22. Peter Leithart, “Nature and Grace,” First Things (blog), July 18, 2014, last accessed August 6, 2016, http://www.firstthings.com/blogs/leithart/2014/07/ nature-and-grace Vatican II, Dei Verbum (1965), §24. 1364 Book Reviews Irenaeus of Lyons: Identifying Christianity by John Behr (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2013), xii + 236 pp. Few historical figures are as relevant as Irenaeus of Lyons for the developmental identity of the early Church. The late-second-century bishop stands at the pivotal juncture of ecclesiastical authority in the West, at the intersection of orthodoxy and heresy, and at the center of the melee of theological factions. Although much of his biographical information eludes historians, his singular location in Church history is viewed as a pinnacle among obscure ecclesiastical leaders and at the epicenter of controversial forces that shaped Christian orthodoxy. Since he stands out in singular fashion, he has become an emblem with many faces: the marginalization of diversity, the target of gnostic advocates, and the champion of the apostolic tradition. Father John Behr falls in the last of these camps of historical interpretation, and his subtitle captures the milieu of religious self-discovery in which this Church father participates. Behr serves as Dean and Professor of Patristics at St Vladimir’s Seminary, where he is well known in patristic circles for his work on Irenaeus. He composed the “Formation of Christian Theology” series, in which he expounded Irenaeus’s ascetic and anthropological values. He provided a new translation of Irenaeus’s On the Apostolic Preaching and regularly appears on projects related to second-century Christianity. In this new work, he provides a comprehensive treatment of the work and person of Irenaeus. Throughout the book, Behr presents his subject as both an ancient and a contemporary figure, a truly catholic writer: “The context for the study of Irenaeus undertaken here has not only been the second century, but also our own times. . . . He is the most important theologian in the articulation of Christian orthodoxy to his time, and, arguably, thereafter” (206). In three large chapters, the work thoroughly condenses Irenaeus’s historical and theological contribution. It clearly and fairly lays out the situation of contemporary critical scholarship that prioritizes inclusivity in the tension with a catholic “Great Church” that prioritized exclusivity. The work faithfully “negotiates the complex relations between history and interpretation, faith and reason, and ancient texts as historical documents and as Scripture” (12). Throughout, Behr unmistakably acknowledges a non-catholic sector in the hybridity of early Christianity, first typified in Marcion, that functions to define a writer like Irenaeus as a genuine emblem of catholicity. Book Reviews 1365 In the first chapter, Irenaeus is considered for his roots in Asia Minor in the shadow of Polycarp and for his attention to the division in the West that sought leadership from Rome. Recently described as a “scion of the East” by J. A. Cerrato, Irenaeus is a crucial link in the early influence of the apostolic tradition between two halves of the Roman Empire, East and West. “If Rome, during the second century, was the crucible in which ‘orthodoxy’ was forged, it was Irenaeus, on the basis of the witness of the martyrs in his community and the tradition going back through Polycarp to John, who oversaw this process” (71). Behr posits Irenaeus as a figure who united a divided ecclesiology by advocating for both Quartodecimians who practiced a different dating for Easter and Montantists who promoted apocalyptic signs of the immediate return of Christ. While Irenaeus promoted them as members of the Church, he demoted gnostic leaders in his work Against Heresies through enunciating orthodoxy against them. The dual inclusion/exclusion approach is clearly centered on orthodoxy for Behr, who writes, “Irenaeus argues that his [gnostic] opponents, with their faulty exegesis and their mythmaking, have substituted another hypothesis and so created their own fabrication” (119). Behr positively compiles the pieces of Irenaeus’s elusive biography to construct a solid summary of his life, informed by the Moscow manuscript of Martyrdom of Polycarp, which places Irenaeus in Rome. He judiciously provides a chronology of the books of Against Heresies and the letters that is rarely seen. Perhaps surprising to some, he proposes that The Demonstration of the Apostolic Tradition is a later addition than Irenaeus “to reuse [Against Heresies] in the polemic against heresy” (68). Chapter 2 examines the significant contribution of Irenaeus’s extant writings. The literary and rhetorical structures of Against Heresies receive much attention, beginning with the use of the term “refutation” or “exposure” as a technique to overturn the case of the heretics who deserve marginalization (75). Behr proclaims one sentence in Against Heresies to summarize Irenaeus’s task (5.36.3), a Trinitarian demonstration of the will of the Father to restore the human race through his Son as intended at the beginning of Scripture (77). The Church father’s efforts to establish a framework for articulating orthodoxy are not presented as simplistic or one-sided, recognizing for Irenaeus, “The Scripture is not read merely historically but as a thesaurus, a treasury of words and images that fit together as a mosaic depicting Christ” (10). 1366 Book Reviews A significant contribution of Behr is the use of the primary sources to show an Irenaean intent to demonstrate orthodoxy as an epistemological hallmark for theological discernment. Rather than viewing heretics as victims of orthodox domination, Behr emphasizes a willful separation by heretics that allowed catholic churches to define boundaries with unity, peace, and toleration: “This was not a fellowship that tolerated anything and everything. . . . [Heretics’] self-chosen departure provided occasions for identifying the points at issue” (207). The rejection of this group was not only an issue of the deposit of faith, but of a community of interpretation. At the same time, Behr recognizes that catholic and gnostic thought develop simultaneously (47), both reacting to and conditioning each other. One would be remiss today either to ignore gnostic Christianity or to triumph “lost Christianities” as innocent nonconformists. The third and final chapter assesses Irenaeus’s theological vision. An apostolic understanding of Scripture, an application of the economy of God, the Christological activities in the Church, and the creation of humankind in the imago Dei all find predictable attention in Behr’s analysis. Providing a chapter entitled “The Glory of God,” he shows his own admiration for Irenaeus, letting the vein of the Church father’s theology flow on its own complex terms. One God, one Christ, and the human being are three themes in Irenaeus’s own exposition that course through this summary chapter on Irenaean theology. Sometimes overlooked in Irenaeus, the Holy Spirit is the agent who brings the original created order to redemption through the work of Christ, fulfilling a redeemed model of creation and anthropology. Just as Behr made the historical Irenaeus a contemporary figure, he could have related more Irenaean theology to the contemporary faith, as he does sometimes: “The life we now live in the body shows that the same body is indeed capable of receiving the eternal life of God himself ” (153). Like all Oxford series books, this work functions as a technical theological explication more than a worthy textbook below the graduate level. The most current scholarly summary of Irenaeus is found here, recognizing the most important contributors to the subject, while the bibliography is the best resource for Irenaean scholarship. Behr’s Christocentric presentation of Irenaeus’s theology is a model for all patristic scholars to remember that these ancient figures were N&V driven by faith more than by political or ecclesiastical gain. W. Brian Shelton Toccoa Falls College Toccoa, Georgia