THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORs: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PROVINCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: Sheed & Ward, Inc., New York City VoL. III APRIL, 1941 No.2 SOME SUGGESTIONS ON THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY I. IN WHICH PHILOSOPHY W IS DECLARED INDEPENDENT oF SciENCE ITH the rise of modern science a new problem has arisen for philosophy. How is philosophy to be classified among the other forms of knowledge? To many of our contemporaries, of course, this is no problem at all; science is the only form of knowledge; therefore, there is no need to classify philosophy. Accordingly, what for the philosopher was originally a somewhat academic question of' classification has now become a vital question involving the very existence of philosophy itself. It is this vital question which we wish to consider in this paper, our-purpose being to show not only that philosophy is independent of science, but also in what sense it is independent. At the outset we might call attention to a distinction between science and philosophy which has behind it something of the authority of commonsense usage. The scientist, it is said, strives for knowledge; the philosopher, for wisdom. Indeed, it is almost a truism today that while we may know far more than the 177 178 HENRY B. VEATCH ancients, we are anything but far wiser than they. Our science has made great strides in the last several centuries. Has our philosophy progressed likewise? For all of its plausibility this mere commonsense distinction between wisdom and knowledge can hardly be regarded as adequate evidence of the independence of philosophy from science. After all, what is wisdom? It is surely knowledge of a kind. Just how is that kind of knowledge which is wisdom to be differentiated from that kind of knowledge which is science? Perhaps we can differentiate them by saying that philosophical knowledge is rational, while scientific knowledge is empirical. With the one are to be associated methods that are a priori and deductive; 'with the other, methods that are a posteriori and inductive. But this will not do. Philosophy simply is not to be identified with Rationalism. This may have been done in the seventeenth century, but since that time too much water has gone under the bridge for us ever to try to do it again. Besides, so far as science is concerned, it is no more exclusively empirical than philosophy is exclusively rational. To be sure, science is empirical. Yet for all its empiricism, science is not for that reason non-intellectual and non-rational. Quite the contrary, the old superstition is now dispelled which says that the task of the scientist is merely to observe with his senses. In fact, if there should be found a scientist who still insists that all he does is to observe, we might quickly silence him by asking if that means that what he never does is to think. No, mere sensory observation is inadequate and incomplete, for so long as sense data are given but not understood, real knowledge has not been attained. Accordingly, it is one of the most striking features of the history of science that empirical observation is always supplemented by attempts at intellectual explanation. Consider the classic example of Kepler. As a result of his own and others' empirical observations, he established the law that the planets move in elliptical orbits. Here was a fact; it was simply so, and empirical observations proved it. Yet physicists and astronomers were not content with it as such. They insisted upon having an explanation of it; they THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 179 wanted to know why planets should behave in this way. Aristotle's physics could give no accounting of it. As for Kepler himself he was hardly more successful, his suggestion being that there was an angel attached to each planet which guided the planet in its elliptical course. Indeed, it was not until Newton proposed his laws of motion that anything like a real explanation was forthcoming. In other words, it would seem that a scientist is not content with the mere empirical knowledge that a thing is so; he requires also a rational understanding of why it is so. Perhaps, in the final analysis it is true that the scientist must be content with the "how" and cannot hope to attain the "why" of things. Nevertheless, up to a point and relatively, the scientist does seek to explain and to understand or, in other words, to know the "why" of things. Thus it is that hypotheses play the role that they do in sciences. For it is through hypotheses that what is empirically observed ·becomes rationally understood-at least relatively. Einstein's hypothesis was designed to account for the newly discovered data in the physical world, the evolutionary hypothesis for data of biology and geology, and so on with all the other hypotheses that are the stock in trade of every kind and variety of scientist. Moreover, as regards the notion that the method of science is purely inductive, that is easily disposed of. For one thing such a relation as that existing between hypothesis and data is by no means a merely inductive one. On the contrary, the significance of the hypothesis lies in the fact that the data can be regarded as following from it, or as being deducible from it. Indeed, it is only to the extent that there is deduction from a hypothesis that there is explanation by a hypothesis. And more generally, a careful analysis of the factors involved in the respective processes of induction and deduction certainly indicates that although there may be a real distinction between the two, there certainly is no separation between them. In fact, it may be taken as a reliable maxim that there is no deduction without induction, and no induction without deduction. With this the conclusion is inescapable: the empiricism of 180 HENRY B. VEATCH science cannot be considered as being a radical empiricism which excludes all rational reflection and intellectual insight. Nor must we forget our previous conclusion to the effect that the rationalism of philosophy is not to be identified with that sort of seventeenth century . Rationalism which vigorously denies . any authority to empirical, a posteriori evidence. Unfortunately, if such be our conclusions, we would seem to be more than ever baffied in our attempt to distinguish between the kind of knowledge that is philosophical and the kind of knowledge that is scientific. After all, if neither science is exclusively empirical nor philosophy exclusively rational, there would seem to be no hope of enforcing upon the two disciplines a requirement of suum cuique. Instead, the methods of both would seem to be pretty much the same. Still we must not be overhasty. It may turn out that even though both science and philosophy are empirical, it is to a fundamentally different kind of experience that each appeals. Not only that, but in the light of this possible difference in method, we may further discover a fundamental difference in object. At any rate, let us see if anything can be done towards drawing a distinction between the kind of experience the scientist appeals to and the kind the philosopher appeals to. A quotation from Santayana will clarify the issue: There is one point, indeed, in which I am truly sorry not to be able to profit by the guidance of my contemporaries. There is now a great ferment in natural and mathematical philosophy, and the times seem ripe for a new system of nature, at once ingenious and comprehensive, such as has not appeared since the earlier days of Greece. But what exists today is so tentative, obscure and confused by bad philosophy, that there is no knowing what parts may be sound and what parts merely personal and scatter-brained. If I were a mathematician I should no doubt regale myself, if not the reader with an electric or logistic system of the universe expressed in algebraic symbols. F'or good or ill, I am an ignorant man, almost a poet, and I can only spread a feast of what everybody knows. Fortunately exact science and the books of the learned are not necessary to establish my essential doctrine, nor can any of them claim a higher warrant than it has in itself; for it rests on public experience. It needs, to prove it, only the stars, the the THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 181 swarm o£ animals, the spectacle o£ birth and death, o£ cities and wars. My philosophy is justified, and has. been justified in all ages and countries, by the £acts before every man's eyes; and no great wit is required to discover it, only (what is rarer than wit) candour and courage. Learning does not liberate men £rom superstition when their souls are cowed or perplexed; and, without learning, clear eyes and honest reflection can discern the hang o£ the world and distinguish the edge o£ truth £rom the might o£ imagination. In the past or in the future, my language and my borrowed knowledge would have been different, but under whatever sky I had been born, since it is the same sky, I should have the same philosophy. 1 This passage from Santayana might well serve as philosophy's declaration of independence from science. Moreover, of interest in the quotation are not merely the reasons Santayana does give for philosophy's right to independence, but also the reasons he does not give. He does not maintain .that philosophy is distinguishable from science because it finds its evidence in pure reason rather than in experience. Quite the contrary, he maintains that it is precisely in experience that the philosopher does find his evidence. And yet the experience that the philosopher relies upon is not the same kind of experience that the scientist relies upon. Instead, it is what Santayana calls a public experience; it is an experience that has been common to all men in all times and in all climes; it is the kind of experience that makes possible the " spreading of a feast of what everybody knows." With such an experience contrast the sort of empirical evidence that the scientist bases his conclusions upon. It is not evidence that all men are familiar with. Nor is it material for a feast of what everybody knows. Rather it is the private property of those who can use microscopes and telescopes, who can handle charts and graphs, and who can find their way around in laboratories and on field trips. Thus it is that on the basis of Santayana's remarks we may state that the real difference between philosophy and science lies in the fact that 1 George Santyana, Skepticism and Animal Faith (New York: 1923), pp. ix-x. (With the permission of Charles Scribner's Sons.) 182 HENRY B. VEATCH the one uses a so-called common experience, while the other uses a special experience. 2 No sooner have we laid down this distinction between science and philosophy, than we have laid ourselves open to an obvious criticism. We shall be reminded that however much the distinction between common and special experience may serve to differentiate philosophy froin science, it serves equally to degrade philosophy by comparison with science. For common experience is by definition an experience which is crude and unrefined. Accordingly, it is argued that because common experience is crude and unrefined, it is inadequate. Because it is inadequate, science has long since discarded it in favour of a source of material which is more inaccessible, to be sure, but which is richer and more fruitful, none the less. Thus Dr. Franz Alexander criticizes Professor Adler: Mr. Adler reduces philosophy to reasoning about inadequate (common sense) observations, science representing at the same time reasoning about more adequate observations obtained by refined and improved methods of investigation . . . . . If Adler's definition of philosophy is correct, philosophy should be discarded in the proportion to which scientific knowledge progresses by the use of steadily improving techniques of investigations. 8 Accordingly, if these criticisms of common experience are sound, then the philosopher, whose distinction is that he relies upon common experience, must face a most embarrassing dilemma. Either he is hopelessly behind the times for the reason that he is working on material that the scientist has long ago exhausted and discarded; or he is hopelessly ahead of the times for the reason that he is trying to solve problems which only the scientist can solvet but which the present state of our data and material does not yet permit us to solve. There is however an answer to this criticism of common experience. The answer is that the criticism contains a non• This distinction between common and special experience is, of course, the one that Mr. Adler has so vigorously and persuasively argued for. 8 Mortimer J. Adler, What Man Has Made of Man (New York: 1937), preface by Dr. Franz Alexander, p. xii. (With the permission of Longman's Green & Co.) THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE .AND PHILOSOPHY 188 sequitur. For how does the argument run? It says that the trouble with common experience is that,. as experience, there is not enough of it. It is unrefined, inadequate, and incomplete. What is needed are more test tubes, microscopes, and precision instruments. With these it will be possible to gather more information. With this added information, light will be thrown upon the various unsolved problems of existence which as yet have been only toyed with in philosophical speculation, but which must eventually be solved through scientific investigation. Such an argument, however, is fallacious; the evidence as stated is sound, but it is not evidence of the conclusion drawn. Common experience is, from a certain point of view, experience that is crude and insufficient; that is true enough. It is also true that with the acquisition of more delicate instruments of observation men will be able to gather more information. But more information about what? Here is just where Dr. Alexander's criticism begs the question. He says that it will be more information about these fundamental and yet unsolved problems of existence which have so long occupied the attention of the philosophers. But we say that it will be more information about no such thing at all. Such added information as the scientist acquires will be added information about the field of science, but not at all about the field of philosophy. Likewise, the same answer may be made to the charge that the philosopher bases his speculations upon an experience that is crude and insufficient. Any philosopher must admit that his common experience would certainly be crude and insufficient for puposes of science, but this does not necessarily prove that it is crude and insufficient for purposes of philosophy. Accordingly, any criticisms of philosophy on this score do little more than beg the question. Moreover, there is something very interesting about this defense of common experience as an adequate basis for philosophy. It is interesting because it incidentally brings to light another ground of distinction between science and philosophy. Not only do these two differ in method, but now we can perhaps begin to see how they differ in object also. Thus we spoke of the field of philosophy and the field of science, and we said that 18'4 HENRY B. VEATCH what may be very informative about the one, will not necessarily be informative about the other. This is like saying that what is very important to know when you are building a house, may well be of very little importance when you are making a dress. In other words, the world of philosophy is as different from the world of science as the world of housebuilding from the world of dressmaking. More particularly, when we say that the scientist is concerned about one sort of thing and the philosopher about another sort of thing, what sort of thing do we mean? there is in the history of philosophy the familiar distinction between the world of phenomena and appearances on the one hand, and the world of noumena and real existences on the other. Why may we not appropriate this ancient distinction in order to make clear the difference in object between science and philosophy? If we want to know, then, why science requires such a quantity and variety of data, it is because the field of science is the field of sensory appearances. Similarly, if we want to know why philosophy requires nothing like so extensive or so refined an experience as science, it is because philosophy is not concerned with the world of phenomena and empirically observable events. Before we pursue any further this suggestion of a difference in object between science and philosophy, let us return once more to a consideration of the difference in method, and let us trace some of its consequences. The most important consequence is that if common experience really does suffice for purposes of philosophy, then philosophy is in no wise dependent upon special experience. If it is not dependent upon special experience, it is not dependent upon science. That is to say, the philosopher simply does not have to fuss and fret about keeping up with the Joneses of science. The reason for this is that all the advances in science result from new discoveries; and these new discoveries, by the very fact that they are new, do not represent an experience that is common to all men in all ages, but rather an experience that is peculiar to only a few research workers and special investigators in our own age. Moreover, there is a corollary to this. If philosophic truth, in THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 185 order to be acquired, need not wait for progress in science, so also it must be acknowledged that philosophic truth, once it is acquired, need not fear that it will ever be upset by future developments in science. Apparently, then, philosophy must no longer be looked upon as a mere poor relation hanging on the coattails of science·. It is a distinct and independent personality with an object and method of its own. n. IN WHICH PHILosoPHY Is LIKENED To MATHEMATICs IN ORDER TO BE CoNTRASTED WITH SciENCE Such is philosophy's declaration of independence from science. Unfortunately, in making the declaration, it may be thought that we have asserted things that are both extreme and contradictory. As an example of our extreme statements may be cited those assertions to the effect that the philosopher need pay no heed to the results of science, and that once a philosophic judgment is established, no possible scientific discovery can ever upset it. This surely is so extreme as to reduce our position almost to an absurdity. As an example of our contradictory a.ssertions may be cited our statement to the effect that philosophy is concerned with the noumenal and intelligible world. Now this is clearly incompatible with our earlier insistence that philosophy is not to be identified with Rationalism, and that the method of philosophy is undeniably empirical. However, it will not be difficult both to lessen these extremities and to resolve the contradictions. The former we shall attempt by showing that philosophic judgments are a priori and, for this reason, immune to either confirmation or refutation by future experience. The latter we shall attempt by showing that although the propositions of philosophy are a priori, they are not for that reason innate; consequently, there is a very definite sense in which they may be said to be derived from experience. In order to accomplish these ends, we shall make a comparison between philosophy and mathematics. The ground for the 186 HENRY B. VEATCH comparison lies in the fact that in both philosophy and mathematics the judgments are a priori. That is to say, they are universal and necessary; they represent what must be so and cannot be otherwise; they are such that their opposites are inconceivable. For instance, let us consider a few illustrations of such a priori propositions borrowed from mathematics and ]ogic. Thus we are told that it is inconceivable that a Euclidean triangle should not have its angles equal to two right angles, or that a and b should not be greater than a. Similarly, we know that it is inconceivable that a conclusion should be drawn from two negative premises, or that an attribute should both be predicable of a subject and not predicable o£ that subject at one and the same time and in the same respect. Here we have propositions that are truly priori, truly universal and necessary. Now with such propositions, contrast these: "There are ninety-two elements in the atomic table." " In all living organisms ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny." Here we have propositions which perhaps are true, but which differ from those which preceded in that they do not have the same kind, or at least not the same degree, of universality and necessity. 0£ the one sort of proposition the opposite is inconceivable; of the other sort the opposite is perfectly conceivable, even though that opposite may in £act be false. Thus there is nothing inconceivable about there being either more or less than ninetytwo elements. So far as we know, there are in fact just ninetytwo o£ them, but the number, for all we can see, might have been two or a hundred and two. Similarly, with the biological principle, there is nothing about the nature of a living organism as such that would seem to necessitate its having this peculiar property o£ retracing in its own development the development of the race. In this regard, the relation o£ a living organism to its property o£ ontogeny recapitulating phylogeny, and the relation o£ a Euclidean triangle to its property o£ having its angles equal to two right angles are as different as day and night. Furthermore, we say that future experience is relevant to such laws o£ chemistry and biology as we have just considered, a THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 187 but it is in no wise relevant to the mathematical and logical principles just considered. Thus as regards the ninety-two elements, there may well come a day when some additional elements may be discovered, or when some of the ninety-two already discovered may be reduced to others, thus lessening the total number. Never will there come a day when some future experience will reveal that in the realm of quantity a and b is not greater than a. In other words, so far as the proppsitions of mathematics and logic are concerned, they need neither hope for confirmation nor dread of refutation by future experience. It is in this sense that they are a priori. Nevertheless, to be a priori does not mean to be innate, whatever the Platonic, Augustinian, Cartesian tradition may insist to the contrary. We are not born with any knowledge of logic, mathematics, or metaphysics. Rather we learn of these things, as we learn of all things, through experience. The child comes to know that a straight line is the shortest distance between two points as a result of many pleasant discoveries, such as, how much shorter it is to cut across a lawn than to go around it. As. for a and b being greater than a, it does not take him long to realize this, considering how early he begins to persuade his parents that to have both his toys and a piece of candy is really much better than having just his toys. In other words, no matter what the purity of our a prioriknowledge may it is still from experience that we derive it. Nevertheless, the derivation is peculiar; it is psychological, not logical. That is to say, the experience from which an a priori principle is derived is in no sense evidence of the truth of the principle; rather it is only a stimulus which provokes an insight into the truth of the principle. In fact, it is like Newton and the apple; the apple fell on Newton's head, and lo, the theory of gravitation resulted. Now, had the apple not fallen, the theory of gravitation might never have occurred to Newton. That is hardly to be taken to mean that the falling of an apple on the great man's head is a necessary step in the demonstration of the theory of gravitation. Imagine opening the Principa and reading: " First go out into an orchard and wait until 188 HENRY B. VEATCH an apple falls on your head." Such an axiom would doubtless make the Newtonian theory more understandable to those of us who are mathematically ignorant; but, beyond this, its advantages would, it seems, be negligible. Now, what the falling apple was to the theory of graviation, that experience is to a priori propositions; it is what makes us think of them; it is not what convinces us of their truth and validity. Accordingly, it is in this sense that we say that in mathematics, logic, and philosophy, empirical observation is psychologically rather than logically relevant. Also it is in this sense that mathematical, logical, and philosophical knowledge may be said to be a priori but not iu.nate. Contrast knowledge in the natural sciences. Like mathematical, logical, and philosophical knowledge, it is not innate; but unlike them, it is not and can never be a priori. Moreover, because it can never become a priori knowledge, experience is essential to it, not accidental; that is to say, empirical observations are logically relevant, not just psychologically relevant, to the attainment of scientific knowledge. As evidence of this, consider the examples which we have already given of scientific judgments. " There are ninety-two elements." " In all living organisms ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny." Of such propositions the opposites are in no wise inconceivable. There is nothing in the nature of their subjects which would necessitate their having such properties. This much has already been shown. But if the properties and characteristics of things in the natural world cannot be inferred from a consideration of the nature of those things themselves, then what can they be inferred from ? The answer is, " From experience." Why there should be only ninety-two elements, we do not know. That there are only ninety-two elements, we learn from experience. Why in living organisms ontogeny should recapitulate phylogeny, we don't know. That it does so, however, we are assured by experience. In other words, not being able to understand the "why" of things in the natural order, experience would seem to .be the next best thing in that it teaches us the "how" of things. Since anything like a real understanding or THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 189 insight into the processes o£ nature is denied us, it is experience that is brought forward and used as a sort of stop-gap against the floods of total ignorance. Thus, in natural science, experience, instead of being a mere stimulus to an a priori insight into universal and necessary truths, is rather a substitute for a knowledge of such truths. Moreover, it is as genuine evidence and as an essential part of demonstration that experience functions in the natural sciences; it is logically and not just psychologically relevant to the attainment of truth. Are we, then, to infer from this that in the natural sciences sensation displaces reason ? After all, we have said that empirical observation serves as a substitute for intellectual insight. Is there not but one conclusion to be drawn from this? Scientific evidence is empirical; hence any such thing as rational evidence can be simply dispensed with in the investigations of nature. Such a conclusion, however, would be extreme. Indeed, it would be in actual conflict with what we have already most vigorously insisted upon. It was pointed out that just as philosophy requires experience, so also science requires reason, and yet this position demanded some qualification. In fact, we have already qualified it so far as philosophy is concerned; we have indicated in just what sense philosophy stands in need of experience. Apparently, then, we must now indicate in just what sense science stands in need for reason. That it does stand in need of it is obvious. Consider even the simplest empirical judgments: "This white thing before me is a sheet of paper " ; "This green thing in my hand is a fountain pen." Already in these apparently simple statements of fact the mere sense data have been transcended. To use the old-fashioned expression, they have been subsumed under a universal. To use a more modern expression, they have been put into a certain context, a context which makes possible their being linked and associated with other possible data. For example, if this really is a fountain pen in my hand, then it will have a point that is sharp to the touch; its holder will be round and smooth, except where it is threaded for the 190 HENRY B. VEATCH cap; it will have a certain hardness and yet will be hollow inside. These and any number of other sensible properties will attach to this object, if it is a fountain pen. In other words, the purpose of subsuming a datum under a universal or of putting it into a context is simply to fit it into the natural order of things. It is just this fitting of a datum into its proper place in the order of things that cannot be achieved by sensation alone; it is a task which only the reason can accomplish. In fact, were it not for the intellect and its power to generalize, the mere sense data themselves would be meaningless and insignificant. This interdependence of reason and experience in science can be illustrated in another way-in a way we have already used. It may be remembered that once before when we sought to show that the empiricism of science was not exclusive of the use of reason and intellect, we pointed out how scientists are constantly resorting to hypotheses. Thus it may often appear to be established empirically that things happen in a certain way (e. g., that the planets move in elliptical orbits). But this does not satisfy the man of science. He seeks a hypothesis that will explain their happening that way (e. g., Newton's hypotheses in the form of laws of motion). In other words, there would seem to be in the natural sciences a sort of upward and downward path, upward from the data to the hypotheses and downward from the hypotheses to the data again. These two paths, however, are traced by reason, not by sensation. Thus once more we find reason supplementing sense in such a way as to make the mere brute data meaningful and significant. Indeed, this business of subsuming a particular datum under a universal concept and this business of explaining an empirical correlation by means of a hypothesis are not radically distinct. Instead, they both represent the construction of hypotheses in order to account for something. Thus even the fitting of a datum into its context represents the employment of a hypothesis for purposes of explanation, for the context itself is a sort of hypothesis. Consider the data of greenness and smoothness and rectangular shape; these do not necessarily and universally THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 191 imply a fountain pen. Nevertheless, to say that theyt are a fountain pen does explain them and make them intelligible. Of course, there is always the possibility of error. It !pay be that the greenness and smoothness and rectangular are those of a pencil rather than of a fountain pen. We were deceived as a result of too hasty a glance, and it is through further examination that the mistake becomes apparent. Yet, right here we see the peculiar virtue of hypothesis. Even though it may be a false one, still it enables us to get hold of our data and manipulate them so as to set then in relation to other data. In this way future observations become relevant either as confirmations or as "infirmations " 4 of what we had supposed the original data to be. Hypotheses are thus indispensable to a knowledge of the empirical world; yet hypotheses are the creatures of reason, not of sense. Now we are ready to summarize our arguments and draw our conclusions as to the precise nature of the contrast between science and philosophy. Neither is exclusively rational; neither is exclusively empirical; and yet for all that, the two do not follow identical methods of investigation. Thus philosophy depends upon experience, and yet in a different way from the way in which science does. So also science stands in need of the activity of the intellect, and yet in a different way from the way in which philosophy does. In fact, we might almost say that in philosophy experience is but a means to the end of intellectual insight, whereas in science the activity of the intellect serves merely to set the stage for further empirical observations. Thus, as we have seen, for the philosopher, as for the mathematician, experience serves only as a stimulus; it is but psychologically, not logically, relevant to an intellectual insight into a priori truths. On the other hand, for the scientist the intellect serves but to fashion hypotheses; and of these hypotheses the sole function is to point back to the world of experience, and thus make possible new experiences. Consequently, whatever may be said of the importance of experience • For this usage, see Eaton, General Logic, page 545. 192 HENRY B. VEATCH to philosophy and of reason to science, it stili remains true that the ultimate arbiter and authority for philosophy is the intellect and for science the senses. These latest conclusions we can now use to reinforce some of our earlier ones. Consider, for instance, our earlier conclusion that common experience is adequate for philosophy, whereas only special experience suffices for science. ·We insisted that this was so, and we answered objections stating that it was not so. Yet we never stopped to explain why it was so. Why should philosophy be able to get along on common experience, while science requires special experience? The answer to this question " why " is now clear from what we know of the nature of scientific knowledge and the nature of philosophical knowledge. For if observation is but a means to the end of intellectual insight, then only so much observation is needed as will stimulate such insight. Once this is accomplished, the senses, having rendered their services, may be paid off and discharged. On the other hand, where empirical evidence is the end rather than the means, sensory observation is never finished; it soon goes beyond the confines of common, everyday experience and plunges ever deeper and deeper into those perpetually new and uncharted reaches of experience that are opened up through refined and special techniques of experiment and investigation. Moreover, there is another one of our earlier conclusions which we are now in position to reinforce. It was the conclusion that not only is the method of philosophy different from that of science, but also it is towards entirely different kinds of objects that the two activities are directed. Indeed, without this difference in object, the difference in method could hardly be sustained, for suppose we ask why common experience is sufficient for the philosopher? We have already answered that question: it is because for the philosopher experience is but a means to the end of intellectual insight. Suppose we then go on to ask why for philosophy intellectual insight is the end, whereas for science the end is empirical observation? The only answer is that philosophy, like mathematics, is concerned with the intelligible world, while science deals with the· phenomenal THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 198 world. Were this not so, all of our previous contentions would become dubious. It would no longer be possible for the philosopher to rely on common experience which is so very crude compared to the data and materials of the scientist. It would be actually absurd for the philosopher to pretend to be in no fear of future empirical discoveries upsetting his conclusions. However, this latter ceases to be absurd and the former ceases to be impossible, as soon as it is clearly recognized that the philosopher is not seeking to know the structure of the sensible world at all, but only of the intelligible world. That it is the intelligible world, rather than the sensible world, with which the philosopher is concerned becomes clear, as soon as the likeness of philosophy to mathematics and the interest of philosophy in the a priori are definitely established. lli. IN WHICH SOME EMPIRICAL OBJECTIONS ARE MET AND ANSWERED Philosophy has been classified with mathematics and differentiated from science. As a result, it has been possible to make clear the different ways in which philosophy and science rely upon experience, as well as the different worlds with which these two disciplines are concerned. Yet no sooner have we established these two points of difference, than we shall be told that our second point of difference, namely, the differentiation in object, is peculiarly suspect. For how can we blithely assert that philosophy is one thing, since it deals with the noumenal world, while science is another thing, since it deals with the phenomenal world? After all, suppose we ask ourselves why it is that so many of our contemporaries flatly refuse to grant philosophy any sort of respectable status independent of science. Is it not simply because the ancient myth of an intelligible world is thought to have been thoroughly deflated and debunked? What do we mean, then, trying to revive it in this post-Kantian era of enlightenment? In short, the issue, as presented to us by our empirically minded contemporaries, would be simply this: how can we 2 194 HENRY B. VEATCH appeal to the existence of a noumenal world as the source of philosophy's independence of science, when it was no less than the denial of the existence of any such world that has been responsible for the humiliation of philosophy and its reduction to a state of subjection to science? What we have said about the a priori character of mathematics, logic, and philosophy is all very well for mathematics and logic, but it will not do for philosophy. After all, mathematics and logic are not concerned with existence or with the real world of nature. They represent wholly arbitrary constructions of the mind. They are, as the moderns would say, purely" postulational" or, as Kant would say, purely analytic. Little wonder, then, that for them experience is only psychologically, and not logically, relevant. Little wonder that they need not submit themselves either to confirmation or refutation by experience. With philosophy it is a different matter. Philosophy does make assertions about existence, but assertions about existence can only be empirical. They can neither arise antecedently to experience nor maintain themselves independently of experience, once they have arisen. Every item of real knowledge, in fact, is traceable to experience and subject to revision by experience. Experience, in other words, is the be-ali and end-all of knowledge-at least, such is the contention. Once more we are up against an entrenched empiricism which simply denies any such thing as an intelligible world and bluntly challenges reason's right to pronounce upon the nature of things. Nor will it avail us to remind these empiricists that we are not defending any such thing as the old-fashioned pure reason, having explicitly rejected the Rationalist tenet of innate ideas. No, even that qualified rationalism which we have advocated, that rationalism which, though it insists that, ultimately, principles can be reached whose validity is in no wise dependent on sensation, nevertheless insists with equal vigor that all knowledge must have its origin and root in the evidence of the senses-even such rationalism would be rejected by our contemporary crop of empiricists. How, then, are they to be THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 195 answered? How can it be shown that there is such a thing as an intelligible world? Unfortunately, we must begin our answering and our demonstrating by admitting that there is one group of empiricists whom we cannot answer, and for whom we cannot demonstrate-at least not in this paper. That is the group which right now would seem to be strutting and fretting its hour upon the philosophical stage. Their favorite lines are replete with words about meaningful and meaningless concepts, and when they pronounce them, they strike an air of complete assurance. They tell us that to talk about any thing that cannot be felt or touched or in any way sensed is simply to talk nonsense. Thus if you speak to them of an intelligible world, they blandly reply that they have no idea what you mean. If you try to explain, they will cut you short and say that you cannot possibly explain what you mean since you mean nothing. If you insist that you do mean something and that you can prove that you do, they will calmly assure you that you are talking nonsense. If you then appeal to the authority of the great philosophers and wise men of all ages and urge that these men use substantially the same concepts and notions as yourself, they will simply say that that is so much the worse for the sages and the philosophers; they were talking nonsense too. "It is no use to argue," they will say," we have set up certain criteria of meaningfulness; now if anything fails to satisfy these criteria, even if it makes good sense to us, we will still know perfectly well that it is nonsense and will refuse to listen." Obviously, it is no use to argue with these empiricists. They will not be moved by either rhyme or reason, or, to use their own jargon, by either emotive meaning or sense meaning. It is not, then, to this brand of empiricist that we will address our arguments; rather, it is to that more robust and old-fashioned breed who might be quite willing to admit that the notion of an intelligible world is understandable enough, but who would be equally insistent that, however understandable it is, it simply does not exist. As for there being such a thing as a real order of nature, an order that is independent of our knowledge 196 HENRY B. VEATCH of it but that we nevertheless can know, at least partially, this is all just part and parcel of what our good old-fashioned empiricist takes for granted. In taking it for granted, he insists that this same order is an empirical order and can be known only through sensory experience. He will have none of this a priori, intelligible world stuff; that is a fiction; when you start talking about that sort of thing, you have ceased trying to know and have started to manufacture, and to manufacture mere cobwebs at that. No, if it is the real you want, the order of independent, stubborn facts, then stick to your sensory evidence and don't go wandering off into your a priori land of nod. Such is the counsel of our hardheaded, red-blooded man of experience. Yet, let us look a little more closely at some of these things that are part and parcel of what he takes for granted. He says that there is a real order of nature, an order which we do not create but which we know. What about this judgment that there is a reality, that something is real? Is this an empirical judgment in the ordinary sense t Well, why not call it empirical, if we suppose that it is our senses that bring us up against real, existing beings? We will grant that it is they who jolt us out of a mere idle contemplation of essences and into an honest confrontation of existences. Very well, then, the content of this judgment which we are considering certainly belongs to the order of facts and not to the mere order of logic. For what is this judgment other than the declaration that there is just such an order of facts; there is an order of nature; there is reality, being, and existence? ':Ve have here, most assuredly, a judgment about existence, an empirical judgment, if you like. Consider it for a moment. Compare it with other characteristically empirical judgments: " There are ninety-two elements." " There is evolution in nature." " Ours is an Einsteinian universe." At once, we see the difference. These latter judgments are in no sense inviolate. They are subject to revision and rejection, according to what future experience reveals, but not so the judgment that there exists something, that there is a real existence. Now can one THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 197 deny or challenge the existence of being ? How can one say that nothing is? Is not one's very denial of reality based upon a certain conception of reality? After all, one must ground one's denial somehow; and what other possible ground can one give than the very nature of things, the very order of reality itself ? Any such appeal to the nature of things or to the order of reality presupP:oses that there are things and that there is a reality. Put abstractly the point is this: the denial that being is must be based on a certain notion of what being is, but with any notion of what being is there is the notion that being is. In other words, even though it may be possible to doubt whether reality is this or that, it is altogether impossible to doubt whether reality is or is not. What, then, are we to conclude from all this in regard to the existence of an a priori and of an intelligible world? Well, even if we admit that the judgment that there is being is not a priori but empirical, still it must also be admitted by our empiricist opponent that this same judgment does not have many of the characteristics which are usually attributed to empirical judgments. There is nothing tentative or hypothetical about it. On the contrary, it is certain, and its truth is known to be absolutely immune to any sort of correction from future experience. This, however, would seem to answer precisely to the description which we previously gave of such modified a priori, intelligible principles as were to serve as a foundation for philosophy. At least, then, we would seem to have found a truly philosophical judgment, founded on common experience and yet transcendent of experience, in the sense that once it is established it has no need of submitting itself to further verification in experience. Before we can gloat too much over having turned the tables on the good old-fashioned empiricist, we must listen to the defense prepared in his behalf. For it might be urged that he of all people would not imagine that experience could ever disclose the fact that there was no being and no existence. On the contrary, his honest empiricist's doubts would not extend to questioning the being of being, but only to questioning 198 HENRY B. VEATCH the essence of being. That being is, is a proposition he would not challenge, but that being is this rather than that-or to put it into language more familiar and pleasing to him, that the order of nature is of this sort rather than that-is a proposition that cannot be known a prim and antecedently to all experience. Not only that, but even after experience has intervened, there can be no hope that the matter will be settled once and for all. Rather, the process of appealing to experience must continue. Thus, once experience has suggested a theory as to what the order of nature is, that theory must be verified and possibly modified by further experience. Then these modifications in turn must be verified and still further modified, and so on ad infinitum. Such a defense, however, is not sound. For its foundation it claims the distinction between the fact of existence and the nature of existence. However, to draw such a distinction by no means establishes the contention that it is for the philosopher to discover only the fact of existence, while it is for the scientist to pronounce upon the nature of existence. On the contrary, we have already seen for ourselves how the philosophic judgment that there is being leads directly and immediately to other philosophic judgments about the nature of being. For did we not show that this very empirical judgment which asserts that there is existence is different from other empirical judgments, and that its difference lies primarily in the fact that it can never be upset by future experience? What is it that makes it thus inviolate? Must it not be the peculiar nature of its subject matter? And what is it subject matter? Being. In other words, no sooner did we discover that there is being and reality, than we realized that being is of such a nature as to make this proposition immune to any sort of refutation. A knowledge of the " that " leads over at once into a knowledge of the " what," and a knowledge of existence into a knowledge of essence. Nor would the empiricist be able to rejoin that for the philosopher to ascertain only a single item in the essence of being is not much of an achievement, particularly since all the THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 199 remaining work of determining the nature of things lies within the competence of the empirical scientist. Quite the contrary, with the ascertainment of this one item in the nature of being, any number of other items immediately come into view. What about this very distinction between existence and essence? Originally the empiricist himself appealed to it, and quently we ourselves considered and discussed it. Is this distinction a scientific one? Is it merely empirical? Hardly, since, far from being a distinction which is simply a datum of sense, it is rather a distinction which is presupposed in any understanding of the data of sense. For how could one possibly consider or talk about the materials gathered from empirical observation without considering them under these two aspects or moments: they are, and they are something? Nor is this distinction between essence and existence comparable to scientific judgments insofar as these latter are tentative and subject to discard. Rather, it is absolutely necessary for us to conceive of being under these two aspects of existence and essence. If one supposes that it is not necessary, let him try to conceive the opposite. By his very act of conception, he refutes himself. This sort of polarity of essence and existence is not the only thing which is implied by the very notion of being itself. There are also other assertions about the nature of being which the philosopher can make witb. perfect legitimacy. Admitting that something exists, can we help admitting at the same time that whatever exists does exist, and that insofar as it exists and is something, it does not not exist and is not nothing? Surely these judgments cannot be denied, for, as Aristotle showed long ago, in denying them one must presuppose them: each thing is what it is, and insofar as it is what it is, it is not something else. Once more we find ourselves in the presence of judgments which have nothing to anticipate or dread in future experience. Call them a priori if you like. The fact is that they are not like scientific judgments; they are not merely tentative; they do not depend upon the authority of empirical observation; 200 HENRY B. VEATCH in short, the only thing to be said about them is that they are philosophical judgments. All this would arouse in our old-fashioned empiricist nothing but contempt. He would reply: " Once more you drag out the old battered principles of identity and non-contradiction and hold them up as exhibits A and B of philosophical knowledge. Well, let us end the argument once and for all and admit that these principles do represent philosophical knowledge. Admitting that, what does it prove ? It proves that philosophy is capable of what everyone has always admitted it to be capable of-a lot of cobweb spinning. For in virtue of the principles of identity and non-contradiction, one can construct a whole system of magnificently interwoven essences, and one can construct it all a priori too. Then when it is done, what does one have? Nothing but what one started out with-a lot of essences and no existence. No, if it is the real order of nature that you want to find, then you won't find it by building a lot of air castles on top of the principles of identity and non-contradiction. Instead, you will find it only by the slow and tedious process of gathering data, propounding hypotheses, and then going back to the data again for verification. Nor will anything ever be absolutely certain on the basis of such a method of procedure. Rather, everything will be merely tentative, and subject to revision by future experience." Unfortunately, this reply evades the issue. Originally the defense proposed for the empiricist was that however much it might be within the philosopher's province to establish the being of being, he still could not show a priori what the essence of being must be. In reply to this, we suggested that it could be known a priori that the distinction between being and essence was relevant to the nature of being, and that the principles of identity and non-contradiction were certainly of the very essence of being. Now we did not say that any more could be known of the nature and character of being, but we did say that this much could be. Nor has anything that the empiricist said served to upset this contention. Yet, if this is all that the philosopher can know of the essence THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 201 of being, and if everything else about reality falls within the province of the scientist to discover, then the philosopher's task is neither a very significant nor a very important one. However, this is not all that the philosopher can know. Nor is his further knowledge confined to mere essences, i. e., to a mere consideration of what might be as over against what actually is. On the contrary, the philosopher is able to know that certain essences are, that they exist. He knows, in other words, not just about natures, but about the nature of things; or, to put it still differently, he has knowledge not merely of essence but also of the essence of being, i. e., of the existence of essences. To make this assertion carry conviction, let us return once more to the consideration of those points which we suggested were simply taken for granted by the ordinary empiricist. It will be remembered that the admission which we attributed to him was. that there is a real, natural order of things, an order which men do not create but rather know. Involved in this admission is the judgment that there is being, that something really exists. Already we have shown how this judgment as to the fact of being is not a scientific judgment at all; and we have also shown how, close upon the heels of this judgment about the fact of existence, there follows a whole crowd of judgments regarding the nature and essence of being, which judgments are likewise in no way scientific. But the judgment that there is being is not the only judgment which is involved in the initial admission of the empiricist. There is also the judgment that there is knowledge. Besides, if one is going so far as to adillit that there is a natural order of things, then one must certainly accede to the judgments that there are things, that these things are many, and that these many things are subject to change and becoming. Once more we have certain judgments of fact comparable to the judgment that there is being. Suppose we ask what their basis and origin are. Are they scientific judgments? Are they a priori? Or just what is their nature? Certainly they cannot be a priori, since there is nothing about the nature of reality 202 HENRY B. VEATCH considered abstractly, and as such, that would necessitate tJhe existence of multiplicity, change, and knowledge. Yet there is no doubt of their certainty. For how can one deny that there is knowledge? To do so would be but to recommit the age-old fallacy of the sceptic who professes to have knowledge that there is no knowledge. Similarly, would one be any more likely to challenge the existence of multiplicity and change? Hardly; for, to borrow Plato's phrase, we may confidently assert that our father, Parmenides, has long since had violent hands laid upon him, and to come to his defense now would be to involve oneself in self-contradiction. For if there is no multiplicity, what of the opinion that there is? Does this not imply a difference between truth and illusion? Similarly, if there is no change, what may be said of the change from an ignorance of this truth to a knowledge of it ? Thus once again, we find ourselves in the presence of truths which, if not purely a priori, at least are not scientific judgments. For there is no tentativeness about them. There is no chance of their being discredited. Consequently, they are not like judgments to the effect that there are ninety-two elements in the atomic table, or that there is a gravitation of bodies. Not only that, but once these judgments of fact are laid down, there follow upon them any number of necessary judgments concerning the nature and essence of the things thus established. Thus no sooner is it established that there is knowledge, than further reflection proceeds to reveal something of what knowledge is. Knowledge, we learn, necessarily involves both the distinction and the identification of the knower and the thing known. How can this be and in just what sense is it so? These are questions that we learn the answers to only through still further rational reflection concerning what it is that knowledge is. Likewise, no sooner is it established that there is change, than further reflection discloses something of the nature of change. For example, we come to see how there must be a something that undergoes the change as well as a something that instigates and effects the change. In other THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 208 words, any fact of change involves a "from," a "to," an "of," and a "by." Does anyone doubt this? How can one? There is no way of characterizing change without being caught up by the prepositions "from," "to," "of," and "by"; they are a part of the very logic of the situation. You will retort: " All these prepositions are but indicative of the way we human beings use language and are in no sense indicative of the way things are." To which the reply is: " Human beings use language in that way because they think in that way, and they think in that way because that is the way things are. If one denies that thinking is thus in conformity with the order and nature of things, then one is denying that the order and nature of things can be known. But to profess to know that there can be no knowledge is self-contradictory, as we have already seen." Once more we find ourselves in possession of judgments concerning the nature of things which are certainly not like scientific judgments. They are universal and necessary; they are certain, not tentative; and they require nothing from future experience, neither confirmation nor " infirmation." 5 In short, they are philosophic judgments. How does it happen that there can be such philosophic judgments about the nature of knowledge, of essence, of existence, of change, etc.? That there are such judgments we have just seen. As to how there can be such judgments we perhaps do not yet see. However, is not the explanation to be found in the fact that there exists not only a phenomenal world knowable by the scientist, but also an intelligible world knowable by the philosopher? This is, indeed, an interesting conclusion, for it was no less than this very question as to whether there is an intelligible world or not that started us on the course of our arduous argument. Let us review briefly the issue as it then presented itself to us. What we had been trying to do for some time was to differentiate science from philosophy in terms of method. We had found that in general the methods of the two • For this usage, see Eaton, General Logic, page 545. HENRY B. VEATCH were alike; both made use o£ empirical observation and intellectual investigation. Specifically, however, the methods were different: in the one case, that of science, rational reflection was used as a mere means to secure further empirical data; in the other case, that of philosophy, empirical observation was but a means to the end of intellectual insight. Nevertheless, this difference in method between science and philosophy was not enough; it did not seem to be self-sufficient; it needed to be grounded upon a difference in object. What was this difference in object? It was the difference between the sensible world and the intelligible world, but no sooner had we reached this point in our discussion than the whole o£ our effort seemed to be rendered useless by the simple consideration that there was no such thing as an intelligible world. In fact, Kant denied the existence of any such thing, and most of .our present-day empirically minded scientists would certainly agree with him. Not only that, but they would go further and would argue that since there could be no difference between the object of philosophy and the object o£ science, there could be no difference in method. If there could be no difference in method, what possible difference could there be of any kind? Presumably there could be none. But as soon as it becomes impossible to differentiate philosophy from science, the fate of philosophy is sealed, for in our day science is fixed and established. Accordingly, if philosophy cannot prove its independence, it might as well become reconciled to its own nonexistence. Fortunately, however, philosophy need not become reconciled to its own non-existence. It does exist and does have a valid status independent of science. We have just proved it. For did we not cite examples o£ philosophic judgments, the validity o£ which could not be challenged, and the distinction o£ which from scientific judgments was apparent? Very well, then, just as the denial of an intelligible world leads to a denial of philosophy, so also an affirmation o£ philosophy leads to an affirmation of an intelligible world. For if there are real philosophic judgments that are in no wise scientific judgments, then the method THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 9l05 of the philosopher must certainly be different from the method of the scientist. If the method of the philosopher is really different from that of the scientist, that can only mean that the philosopher is investigating a different kind of thing from the scientist, viz., an intelligible world as over against a sensible, phenomenal world. IV. IN WHICH PHILOSOPHY IS LIKENED To SciENCE IN ORDER TO BE DISTINGUISHED FROM MATHEMATICS No sooner have we apparently attained our goal of distinguishing philosophy from science, both as regards method and as regards object, than we must l).eeds pause a moment to make sure that we have not overshot our goal. There is something suspect about this notion of an " intelligible world." Its associations are all with innate ideas and pure a priori reasoning. This, however, is bad company for us, considering that we have been at such pains to show how philosophic knowledge must begin with the data of common experience. In fact, even such judgments as those involving the law of identity and the distinction between essence and existence would have no truth Ol" relevance, unless there were a reality and an existence to which this law and this distinction could pertain. So also with the other judgments about the nature of knowledge, of change, and of multiplicity; unless there were such things as knowledge, change, and multiplicity, these judgments would have no bearing or import. How do we know that there are such things? We know it through common experience. In other words, however much it may be within the competence of the intellect to determine what and why things are, it is solely within the competence of sensory experience to establish the fact that they are. Consider this last conclusion. If it is common experience that assures us of the existence of those very objects which it is the task of philosophy to reflect upon, what about our earlier likening of philosophy to mathematics? Is mathematics the kind of knowledge that must rely upon experience to supply it 206 HENRY B. VEATCH with the actual objects of its investigation? To answer these questions, let us review our earlier conclusions. It may be remembered that it was through the supposed similarity of .philosophy to mathematics that we sought to distinguish philosophy from science. Science, we suggested, is dependent upon experience to a greater extent than, and in a different way from, mathematics and philosophy. In the latter, experience is only psychologically relevant to the knowledge that is finally acquired; that is to say, it stimulates such knowledge and provokes it, but is in no sense a part of it. In natural science, on the other hand, experience provides the very materials of scientific investigation; what the scientist knows about, in other words, are those very objects which are presented to him in sense experience. Let us take an example. In geometry we may draw a circle on paper to illustrate some of the theorems which we are trying to prove. Nevertheless, the geometer will insist that what we have drawn is not what we are talking or thinking about. The visible circle, that is to say, merely suggests the ideal circle and must in no wise be identified with it. Contrast the procedure in science. There the sense data which are gathered through experiment are, to be sure, unintelligible simply in themselves; for an understanding of them much more is needed than the mere experiencing of them; still, the understanding which the scientist is seeking is always an understanding of these same data and not of some ideal object merely suggested by the data. What of philosophy? Certainly it would seem to be much more like science than mathematics. Those objects which the philosopher meets with in common experience are the very same objects which he considers and tries to determine the nature of in later reflection. For example, it is through empirical observation that we come into contact with being and change. Yet that being which is characterized by the laws of identity and non-contradiction, and that change which we say necessarily involves the presence of four causes, are not a different being and a different change from that which we first came to be aware of in common experience. On the contrary, THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY fl07 they are identical. Hence we must accept the conclusion that in philosophy there is no such separation between the object experienced and the object known, as there is in mathematics. Not only that, but we can go further and can assert that, far from there being in philosophy a separation of the object known from the object experienced, it is rather through experience, and experience alone, that the philosopher assures himself of the existence of those very objects whose nature he is seeking to determine. That there is knowledge, that there is being, that there is multiplicity, that there is change-these are all judgments of experience. Of course, when it comes to knowing what being is and_what knowledge is and what multiplicity is and what change is, the philosopher must learn about these through intellectual reflection. Nevertheless, it may be said that philosophy resembles science and differs from mathematics precisely in its being concerned about existences and not merely about essences. Thus the philosopher wants to know, not simply what it is he is considering, but also that it is. Accordingly, he turns to experience as being the one way to existence. On the other hand, the mathematician seems indifferent to existence and so turns away from experience. For him it is sufficient to know the " what " without the " that " ; it is sufficient to know merely how his terms are used, and not whether things corresponding to them really exist or not. Thus it is that so many modern mathematicians describe their technique and procedure as being " postulational." If perchance there should be a mathematician who does not admit that his method is merely postulational, but who insists that a mathematical, non-empirical method can and does lead to existence, then inevitably he will fall into a sort of Cartesian idealism. It is this sort of idealism of which Professor Gilson has so brilliantly sketched the history and so tellingly exposed the fallacy. It consists in trying to make reality conform to our ideas rather than our ideas to reality. Thus Professor Gilson says: The primary consequence of Cartesian mathematicism, and that from which all the others fiow, was the obligation which he imposed 208 HENRY B. vEATCH upon the philosopher of always going from thought to being and even of always defining being in terms of thoughts. For the mathematician, the problem of essence always takes precedence over that of existence; the true circle and the true triangle are the definition of the circle and of the triangle, the figures empirically given in sensible experience being only approximations of their definitions. It is not by chance that geometry is the science of sciences for Descartes as for Plato. In every respect a systematic applicatien of the mathematical method to the real could have as its immediate result nothing but the substitution for the concrete complexity of things a certain number of clear and distinct ideas, themselves conceived of as being the veritable reality. 6 Again, he says: What is a circle, to the mind of a mathematician ? Is it this and that circle, such as I can imperfectly draw on a piece of paper or on a blackboard ? Obviously not-the real circle is the definition .of a circle, and nothing else. It may be that no material figure ever answered that definition in reality; what the mathematician is interested in is something different: the essence or true nature of the circle, as is to be found in its definition and only there. 7 Compare also this expose of the fallacies involved in confusing the method of philosophy with that of mathematics: Up to the time of Descartes, and particularly during the Middle Ages, it had always been admitted that philosophy consists in a conceptual transposition of reality. In this sense it is just to characterize it as an abstract conceptualism; but it is not just to accuse it of having reified its concepts; on the contrary, the constant method of the scholastic is to go from things to concepts, so that he needs several concepts to express the essence of a single thing, according to the multiplicity of the points of view that he adopts towards it, and also so that no one less than he is in danger of taking what he abstracts from the real for reality. To convince oneself of this, it suffices to consider the case of any substance whatever. For the scholastic, it is always matter and form, that is to say, two concepts; neither 'is the matter ·anything apart from the form, nor the form apart from the matter. The person who reified concepts is not St. Thomas but Descartes, and he could not avoid doing it as soon as he elevated concepts to the rank of ideas. • Gilson, Le Realisme Methodique, p. 54. • Gilson, The Unity of Philosophical Expe:rience, p. 153. THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 209 Abstracts of the real, he made of them models of which it is not enough to say that the real must conform itself to them but rather that they are the real itself. The distance which separates the two philosophers on this point strikes one forcibly when one considers that for Descartes every substance is known because it is reducible to the content of his idea, while for a scholastic every substance is unknown because it is a different thing from the sum of the concepts which we derive from it. 8 Apparently, then, rather than allow ourselves to be lured into the pitfalls of Cartesianism we had better shun all mathematical shortcuts to existence, and stick instead to the one and only way to get from essence to being, namely by experience. What now of our distinction between philosophy and science? Is it any longer valid? From what we have just said, it would appear that so far as its use of experience is concerned, philosophy resembles science and differs from mathematics. Yet from what we formerly said, it is clear that the real way to demonstrate philosophy's independence of science is to liken it to mathematics. In fact, all of the cardinal points of contrast between philosophy and science derive their force and plausibility from the apparent analogy existing between the methods and objects of investigation in philosophy, and the methods and objects of investigation in mathematics. For example, consider the contrast between philosophy and science which is based on the fact that for the philosopher experience is but a means to intellectual insight, whereas for the scientist the intellect is but an instrument in the acquisition of new empirical data. Obviously, this contrast cannot be even so much as understood, unless one appreciates the close resemblance between philosophy and mathematics. It is to the mathematician that one turns, if one wants a stock example of an investigator who uses experience as but a means, and for whom sense data act as mere stimuli to knowledge and not at all as materials for knowledge. Accordingly, if the philosopher is going to insist that in his case also experience is only psychologically, and not logically, relevant, he can do so only by admitting the analogy • Gilson, Le Realisma Methodique, p. 54-55. 3 no HENRY B. VEATCH between his method of knowledge and the mathematician's. Moreover, the same thing is true of that other contrast which we made between philosophy and science. It was the contrast based upon the difference between relying upon common experience and relying upon special experience. Yet, surely it would be to the example of mathematics that a philosopher would appeal, if he wanted to illustrate how a systematic body of knowledge could be erected on the foundations of mere common experience. After all; even a child has enough experience to know the first principles about figure and quantity. Similarly, in regard to the difference between the phenomenal and the intelligible worlds, this mode of contrasting philosophy with science is certainly to be understood after the pattern of mathematics. That is precisely what the mathematician does; he passes from the circle that is drawn on paper, the phenomenal, empirical circle, to the idea of the circle, the intelligible circle. In short, philosophy can be independent of science only by identifying its cause with the cause of mathematics. Yet from what we have said about philosophy's concern with existences, as over against mere essences, it simply is not possible to make an identification of philosophy's cause with that of mathematics. Does this mean, then, that philosophy cannot claim independence of science, after all? Hardly, for there is one point of contrast between science and philosophy which has been clearly brought to light in our previous discussions, and which, if we now analyze it more carefully, will definitely settle this question of independence. What we said was that conclusions in science are ever subject to revision and refutation, while conclusions in philosophy are immune to any correction by future experience. In short, scientific knowledge is only hypothetical, while philosophical knowledge is certain. Such is the contrast; but how it is to be explained? The explanation is this: In any sort of experience we first become aware that certain things are, and immediately thereafter we want to know what they are-that is, what their nature and essence are. Now philosophy actually succeeds in penetrating to the nature and essence of certain things. Thus the philosopher THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 211 not only discovers that being is; but he also discovers something of the nature of being, for example, that it is subject to the laws of identity and non-contradiction. Science is not so fortunate. Thus the physicist discovers that there is physical, atomic being, but not with absolute certainty. Nor can he know with absolute certainty what the nature and structure of atomic being is. To take another example, the philosopher knows that change is, and he also knows what is essential to all change. The biologist cannot know with absolute certainty that there is evolutionary change in all living beings, or even what such evolutionary change is, supposing that it is. Here, then, we do have a real distinction between science and philosophy. Moreover, it is a distinction through which all of our proposed distinctions between science and philosophy can be justified and explained. They can be justified and explained in such a way as to make it no longer necessary to bring in the analogy of mathematics. Take, for example, the contrast between science, as being that which uses reason as a means of attaining further empirical data, and philosophy, as being that which uses the empirical data as a means to intellectual insight. The ground for this lies simply in the fact that science never sees the essence of the given which it investigates; it never knows what it really is. Consequently, it must resort to hypotheses. What is hypothesis? A hypothesis is simply a kind of guess as to what the given is, and it is a guess which is made for want of a knowledge of what the given is. Of course, on the basis of the evidence at hand and of what we do see of the given, it may be highly probable that such a hypothesis does reveal the nature and essence of the given. Yet we cannot be certain that it does. As long as we cannot be certain about the essence, we can be almost certain that what we have considered to be the essence, i. e., our hypothesis, will some day have to be either altered or destroyed. Thus it is that the scientist must in all honesty seek out every scrap of evidence that would either invalidate or substantiate his guess. For that reason, the scientist's hypotheses are so constructed as to point to future experience, and it is in this sense that the scientist may 212 HENRY B. VEATCH be said to use reason simply as a means to the attainment of further empirical data. On the other hand, the philosopher does succeed in seeing the very essence of what is given in experience. He sees, in other words, not merely that something is but also what it is. This being so, there is no need of further experience. Certain knowledge has been attained, and certain knowledge, unlike hypothetical knowledge, is under no obligation to be referent to future experience. To be sure, in future experience you may find illustrations and examples of what you know with certainty, but you will never find proof or disproof thereof. Such is the sense, then, in which for the philosopher experience is but a means to intellectual insight. Similarly, as regards the distinction between a reliance upon common experience and a reliance upon special experience, it is clear how its basis is to be found in the distinction between certain knowledge and hypothetical knowledge. Why is common experience adequate in philosophy ? Because in that which is given universally and to all men, the philosopher actually finds those natures and essences which he is looking for. They are there; he sees them; and in seeing them, he acquires knowledge-knowledge that is certain and beyond refutation. Accordingly, having garnered from common experience enough material for the attainment of truth, it is unnecessary for the philosopher to in more materials which could add nothing but clutter and confusion. With the scientist, on the other hand, it is quite different. In common experience he can never find such a thing as an essence; instead, he finds only accidents. Accordingly, he gathers more data and his experience becomes more specialized. For all his specialization, he never finds anything but accidental features. For instance, he can succeed very well in determining the quantitative aspect of a thing. Moreover, as his experiments become ever more refined, his knowledge of the size and shape and speed of the thing in question becomes ever more accurate. Still, there is always something lacking. There is lacking that intimate knowledge of the thing's very nature which alone could make :possible an THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 213 understanding of just why there should be these particular quantitative manifestations rather than certain others. Without this understanding of why things must be the way they are, the task of the scientist is not yet complete: he does not yet have knowledge that is certain and beyond refutation. He must therefore continue his search ever further and further, for, after all, accidents are infinite in number, and to know all of them requires a process ad infinitum. Nevertheless, it is just this process which the scientist must carry on, because, so long as a certain knowledge of essences is unattainable, an ever more accurate and extensive knowledge of the accidents is in a sense an approximation to, in a sense a substitute for, this desired knowledge of essences. Apparently, then, it is the certainty of philosophical knowledge in contrast to the tentativeness of scientific knowledge that provides us with an infallible criterion of the distinction between philosophy and science. Moreover we have seen how this distinction maintains itself despite the many similarities between science and philosophy, and despite the impossibility of likening philosophy to mathematics in order to distinguish it from science. Yet, no sooner do we seem to have established our thesis of the independence of philosophy, than we find that independence threatened again, this time by the mathematicians rather than by the scientists. If certainty be the criterion of philosophy's independence of science, it would appear to be equally the criterion of philosophy's dependence upon mathematics. What is more characteristic of mathematical knowledge than certainty? Where could there be found a better example of certain knowledge than mathematics? Once more our effort to differentiate philosophy from both science and mathematics appears to be little more than an effort to steer between Scylla and Charybdis. If we try to distinguish philosophy from mathematics, we seem to be forced to liken it to science; if we try to distinguish it from science, we seem to be forced to liken it to mathematics. This seeining dilemma, however, is one that must simply be taken boldly by the horns. Suppose we adinit that the criterion of distinction between HENRY B. VEATCH science and philosophy is the certainty of the philosopher's conclusions. Suppose we also admit that the distinguishing feature of mathematics is the certainty of its conclusions. Still, this does not force us into any embarrasing admission of an essential similarity between philosophy and mathematics. The reason is that the certainty achieved in mathematics is not the same kind of certainty as that achieved in philosophy, for although the mathematician does achieve certainty, it still is not a certainty of existence. Rather, it is by means of a retreatfrom existence and reality that mathematics is able to bestow so high a degree of certitude upon its conclusions. As Professor Gilson has suggested, it is the ideal which is the standard in mathematics, not the real. Consequently, the mathematician pays heed only to the demands of his own definitions and postulates, and blithely ignores the stubborn exigencies of the data of sense. The philosopher, on the other hand, heeds only the exigencies of the given and tries to ignore as completely as possible whatever pertains merely to his own arbitrary definitions. In other words, the method of philosophy is a method of description rather than of construction. The true philosopher, shunning idealism, must never allow himself to confuse the task of knowing with the task of making. His goal must be one of submission to an independently real, not one of mastery over a purely human artifact. To put it in other terms, we may say that the true end for the philosopher is a knowledge of what it is that is, and not of what it is that is thought. Similarly, such certainty as he acquires may be said to be a certainty about things and not about mere ideas. Our thesis may now be considered as established: the philosophic quest is distinctive and unique; it is to be confused neither with scientific nor with mathematical investigations. Nevertheless, since the argument of this section has been devious and tangled, it might be well for us to summarize it. We began by pointing out how misleading it was to differentiate philosophy from science on the ground that philosophy examines an intelJ Iigible world while science examines a merely phenomenal world. Far from being a point of distinction, it was-shown how THE RESPECTIVE SPHERES OF SCIENCE .AND PHILOSOPHY 215 this is really a point of similarity between philosophy and science; it is in this precise respect that these two resemble each other and differ from mathematics. Both are concerned to know the nature of the very world that is given in experience, and neither is concerned about the nature of a world, which, instead of being given in experience, is merely suggested by experience. After this disclosure of the resemblance of philosophy to science, the question immediately presented itself as to the independence of philosophy from science. Could this any longer be maintained? That it could be, we tried to show by pointing to the certainty of philosophical conclusions in contrast to the merely hypothetical character of results in science. At the same time we were careful to distinguish the kind of certainty found in philosophy from the kind of certainty there is in mathematics: the latter is not a certainty about existence; the former is. V. SUMMARY .AND CoNCLUSION Having thus summarized our final section, it might be well for us to summarize our whole paper. In the first section, we stated the case for philosophy's independence of science. In philosophical inquiries a different method is used from that in science; reliance is placed on common rather than on special experience. Also in philosophical inquiries a different object is investigated, namely the intelligible world, in contrast to the phenomenal world. In the second section, we undertook to explain and justify what we had been content simply to present and affirm in the first section, namely philosophy's independence of science. This was done by comparing philosophy to mathematics. By this means it was possible to show that philosophical judgments were a priori, and hence independent of any conclusions that either had been or might be established as a result of the special experience of the scientist. At the same time, it was explained how, even though philosophic judgments were a priori, they were not innate. As a result, the method of philosophy was said to be an empirical method, having its origin in common experience-and this, despite the fact that 216 HENRY B. VEATCH the object of philosophy was the intelligible world. Having reached this point, we were forced in the third section to consider certain empiricist objections which challenged the possibility of any a prioriknowledge of reality, as well as the existence of any such thing as a;n intelligible world. In answer to these attacks we simply presented various philosophical judgments, which were clearly judgments about reality, and which at the same time were clearly a priori in the sense of being neither based on past scientific discoveries nor subject to correction by future ones. In other words, it is simply a fact that there are philosophical judgments, and that these judgments are not of the character of scientific judgments. However, with this as the conclusion of the third section, the questions still remained open as to whether the object of philosophy was not after all the intelligible world, and as to whether the method of philosophy was not essentially mathematical. In the fourth section both these questions were answered in the negative. Philosophy investigates the world of the empirically just as does science. Nor is the method of philosophy mathematical, the aim of philosophy being not so much to construct as to describe. Throughout the whole discussion our thesis has been that philosophy represents a different kind of knowledge from that of science. In the course of the paper we hope we have shown in what sense the one kind of knowledge is different from the other. There is still another question as to why there should be these different knowledges. 10 That they are different, and how they are different, we have seen. Why they are different is a question that must wait for another time. HENRY B. VEATCH Department of Philosophy, Indiana University, Bloomington, Indiana 9 This conclusion would doubtless have to be qualified in order to take account of the rather special case of natural theology. conversation Professor Gilson once remarked on how this now 1.o In a private arcltaic usage was once in respectable currency, notably in Bacon. THE DISTINCTIVE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING A Commentary on the "Summa Theologica," II-II, Q. 8 T I. THE GIFTS IN' GENERAL HERE is nothing in the purely physical order of things that affords a parallel to the action of the Holy Ghost on the supernatural life of man. Although at first sight symbiosis seems to be an apt concept to illustrate the relations of this sweet and mysterious Guest to His living temple, closer examination reveals so many awkward and misleading details that the example becomes nearly worthless. The algae in a lichen, or the intestinal protozoa in termites, contribute to their partner's nourishment in a state which makes it easier to assimilate, receiving in return food elements which unaided they could not obtain, and the craven crab in return for the seaanemone's protection carries it to pastures ever new. But in all this the most noticable point is the mutual aspect of the partnership; the quid JYTO quo is strongly emphasized. The indwelling of the Holy Ghost on the other hand is unilateral. It would be closer to say, with certain reservations, that man dwells in- the Holy Ghost, for while he contributes nothing to the self-sufficient Divinity, he receives much, and receives it all as a pure gift. Whence the Church on Pentecost sings of the Holy Spirit as " Gift of the most high God." The dependence of man on the Holy Ghost is manifold. His every act as well as his very being depend on Him, " For in Him we live and move and are." 1 He moves us to the particular good that we do, both in the physical and moral order, and that too, sometimes, in an extraordinary manner, as when the spirit of God " rushed " upon Balaam. 2 A fortiori, then, 1 Acts, xvii, • Numbers, xxiv, Yl17 218 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS He moves us in the supernatural order: " Likewise the Spirit helpeth also our infirmity." 3 But in this order there are two modes of action, human and divine. Under the influence of the Holy Ghost the infused virtues elicit their proper operations. These actions are from an intrinsic principle, are regulated by reason, whence comes the human mode, and in a sense are in our possession, for if, on the one hand, supernatural aid is required, on the other, man himself must determine for himself just what and how much he will do, so that in the words of St. Paul, " Every man shall receive his own reward, according to his own labor." 4 But, over, and above this, there is another sort of motion in which man is more acted upon than acting and is moved, in a manner entirely beyond his powers, to his supernatural end: " But when they shall deliver you up, take no thought as to what or how to speak ... for it is not you who speak, but the spirit o£ your Father who speaketh in you." 5 Jesus was led into the desert; 6 the minds of the disciples were opened. 7 These motions do not proceed from man according to the intrinsic principle of reason, after the human mode, but from an extrinsic principle, the Holy Ghost, after a manner that is superhuman and divine. They do not proceed from any deliberation on our part, although they are free, resulting from a particular impulse of the Holy Ghost activating special supernatural habits to which, nowadays, the.· word "gifts,; is reserved. 8 St. Thomas points out in the first article of question sixtyeight, where he is distinguishing the gifts from the virtues, that we ought to follow the manner of speaking of Holy Scripture which calls the gifts " spiritus," or breaths, " because they are in us by divine inspiration." ·a Father Gardeil 8 Romans, viii, 26. 'I Cor., iii, 8. • Matthew, x. 19-20. 8 Matthew, iv, I; Mark, i, 12; Luke, iv, I. • Luke, xxiv, 25. 8 G. M. Paris, 0. P., Dissertatio de Donis Spiritus Sancti in Genere (Turin: Marietti, 1930), p. 10. • Summa Theol., q. 68, a. I. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 219 remarks the richly-laden signification of St. Thomas' words. That " because "-secundum quod--in the mouth of a scholastic is the affirmation of an essence or the essential and immediate property of an essence, and not mere consequence.10 Inspiration signifies some sort of motion from without. Hence the essential note of the gifts of the Holy Ghost is that He is the mover, and not reason as in the virtues. Holy Scripture also speaks of the Spirit resting within us, for as St. John Chrysostom says: "Mter He comes, He remains, nor does He depart." Just as the moral virtues perfect the appetitive faculties by rendering them obedient to the commands of reason, so there are dispositions in the faculties of the soul rendering them obedient to the motions of the Holy Ghost. For to the degree that the moving principle is exalted, by that much more is it fitting that the subject be disposed to receive this motion so that there be a proportion between the mover and the one moved. And so, where the mover is most powerful, by His very motion almost He induces a habit in the subject if He moves him as one dwelling within him. 11 Of course, actual grace in sinners causes no habit to be formed, but this is where a sinner and a person in the state of grace differ. The just man has in himself habitual principles needing the motion of grace, which principles also habilitate him in the order of a well-disposed subject to every impulse of the First Mover and the Leader of minds to eternal life.12 So, as St. Thomas notes, because man is endowed with free will, he himself acts even under the action of the Holy Spirit, and requires a habit, a permanent disposition rendering him prompt to follow the motion of the Holy Spirit. 18 This is the narrowest and proper sense of " gift." In the thought of St. Thomas, the seven gifts enumerated by Isaias are distinguished among themselves according to the powers of man which they perfect. Four gifts are seated in Dictionnaire de Theologie Catkolique, Vol. 4, part col. 1775. Paris, op. cit., p. 51. 12 L. Billot, De Virtutibus Infusis (Rome: 1905), I, 183. 18 Summa Tkeol., I-II, q. 68, a. ad 2um. 10 11 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS reason: wisdom, understanding, knowledge, and counsel; and the remaining three in the will: fortitude, piety, and fear of the Lord. To further distinguish the intellectual gifts, St. Thomas encountered some difficulty. In his first attempt, he uses as his norms the distinction of the speculative and practica] reason, and the difference between the two acts of the intellect, apprehension and judgment. Within this frame, he places understanding in the speculative apprehension, wisdom in the speculative judgment, knowledge in the practical fudgment and counsel in the practical apprehension of truth. 14 Further thought led him to modify, not the distinction of the gifts, btit the basis for it, so that when he comes to the distinction of the gifts in particular, we find he has enlarged the office of the gifts without confusing the particular operation of each. "He wishes understanding to be penetrative of all, wisdom the judge of all through the very highest cause, knowledge likewise the judge through created or proper causes, and counsel likewise applicative of all to work; and follow this," says Cajetan, " because it is of a more divine ingenuity." 15 Ingenious though it may be to Cajetan, it does not at first glance offer a clear statement of the distinct office of each of the various gifts. Only by a careful scrutiny of St. Thomas will some light be shed on the difficulties. This paper proposes to establish the distinctive nature of the gift of understanding according to the mind of St. Thomas. II. THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING In treating of the gift of understanding, there are some difficulties to be borne in Inind and, if possible, answered as we go along. The first and foremost is that the operation of this gift is found most perfectly in the mystical states and cannot be well expressed in human language. As St. John of the Cross says, "Keep in Inind that these matters are beyond all words. The intelligence of pure truths requires for its proper explanation that God should hold the hand and wield the pen of the u Ibid., q. 64, a. 4; 15 Comm. in I-II, q. 68, a. 4. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING !il!ill writer." 16 The same excess of light that caused St. Thomas to leave the Summa unfinished leaves the operation of this gift indescribable, except in halting and inept terms. Further, it is necessary to distinguish understanding from faith, a difficult task because it seems that an act of faith can fill the office of the gift. To distinguish understanding from other intellectual gifts, moreover, is difficult because it cannot readily be shown just what act understanding exercises that the others cannot exercise. And, finally, because it is not bound to the state of the wayfarer, or of faith, we must explain what act it exercises in heaven when it is found without faith, to the aid of which, however, it was ordained in this life.17 The precise and detailed treatment of the gift of understanding is found in the eight articles of the eighth question of the Secunda Secundae of the Summa Theologica. In the first article, St. Thomas gives a purely nominal definition of what he means by the gift of understanding, sketches the similarities and differences between the natural and supernatural gift, and indicates broadly the objects to which the gift will extend. In developing these general notions, St. Thomas proceeds in the orderly fashion so characteristic of him. " Since the gifts are ordained to operation, it is fitting that they be distinguished according to their object, in which acts are diversified according to their species." 18 So in his following articles the principles . enunciated in Part One of the Summa Theologica 19 are applied. There are three ways to distinguish habits: by the active principles which give rise to them, by the natures to which they are ordained and in which they inhere, and by the operation to which they are ordained, that is, their formal object. In the first and third ways, the gifts in general have been distinguished from the virtues, and in the second way the intellectual gifts from those in the appetitive faculties. Now 10 11 Ascent of Mt. Carmel, Bk. II, c. fl6. Cf. John of St. Thomas, CurSUB Theologicus, I-II, disp. XVIII, a. 8 (Lyons: 1668). 18 10 III Sent., d. XXXIV, q. 1, a. 6. Summa Theol., I, q. 18, a. 2; q. 54, a. 2. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS it remains to employ the second and third ways to distinguish understanding from the three others: wisdom, knowledge, and counsel. Because of the external order of the questions, the first thing to notice is that understanding is linked in some way with the theological virtue of faith. This relation is the subject of the second article. Here is determined the relations of understanding and faith by delimiting their objects and therefore their sphere of action. Here also are described the proper and extended objects of the gift; so, in the third article the object by extension is discussed and also the faculty in which understanding is found._ Speaking of the faculty in which it is found, St. Thomas, in articles four and five, lays the psychological basis in the supernatural order which demands the gift. In the fourth, we find that charity is the raison d' etre of this gift, and in the fifth the utter dependence of the gift on grace is emphasized by a special discussion of unformed faith. Despite the fact that the virtue of faith, which is the rule and reason of the gift, remains in a truncated fashion without charity, yet understanding cannot remain to aid it. Now that the nature of the gift is fairly well established from its subject and object, it should be an easy matter, in article six, to distinguish it from the other gifts. And, :finally, according to his general plan in his special treatment of each gift, St. Thomas, in the seventh article, tops off his consideration of this gift with its corresponding beatitude and, in the eighth, considers the corresponding fruits of the Holy Ghost. The logical order of the whole discussion is evident and commends itself to us as the guide to follow as we progress. The gifts are all connected in charity and the Holy Ghost, 2{) just as all the virtues are connected in prudence and reason. This is perhaps the reason why St. Thomas finds it so hard to keep the notions proper to wisdom and knowledge out of his discussion of understanding. ·Terms like " regulate " and Summa Theol., I-ll, q. 68, a. 5. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING estimation " seem to savor of the gift of wisdom rather than understanding, and we shall try to explain them when we come to them. For the existence of the gift of understanding, St. Thomas is content to accept the authority of Holy Scripture. Although the text which he cites in the Sed Contra of the first article could cause some difficulty were it the sole foundation of the doctrine of the gifts, there are many other places in Sacred Scripture where the working of the Holy Ghost is indicated. Joseph is described as a " man full of the Spirit of God," because he interpreted the dream of Pharaoh. 21 Those who made the priestly vestments of Aaron were filled with the " spirit of wisdom," 22 and Beseleel was filled " with the spirit of God, with wisdom and understanding, and knowledge in all manner of work." 23 The " spirit " that inspired Moses was taken from him and given to seventy men, 24 and " when the spirit had rested upon them they prophesied, nor did they cease afterwards." 25 Many of the great figures of the Old Testament are noted as being blessed with a special spirit: " ... and Josue was filled with the spirit of wisdom ... "; 211 " ... and the spirit of the Lord was in him, (Othoniel) and he judged Israel."; 127 ". • • the spirit of the Lord came upon Gedeon ... "; 28 "the spirit of the Lord came upon Jepthe ... "; 29 ". . . the spirit of the Lord began to be with him (Samson) ... "; 30 " ••• the spirit of the Lord came upon David from that day forward . . . but the spirit of the Lord departed from Saul." 31 The sapiential works and the Psalms are filled with references to the gifts of wisdom and understanding: " I will bless the Lord who hath given me understanding."; 32 "Give me understanding and I will search thy law .... "; 33 Genesis, xli, 38. •• ExodUII, xxviii, 3. •• Ibid., xxxi, 3. •• Numbers, xi, 17. 21 •• Ibid., Deuteronomy, xxxiv, 9. 27 Judges, iii, 10. 28 ·•• Ibid., vi, 34. •• Ibid., xi, •• Ibid., xiii, 31 I Kings, xvi, 3. •• Ps., xv, 7. •• Ibid., cxviii, 34. 224 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS "By thy commandments I have had understanding. The classic text is from Isaias: " 84 And the spirit of the Lord shall rest upon him; the spirit of wisdom and of understanding, the spirit of counsel and of fortitude, the spirit of knowledge and of godliness. And he shall be filled with the spirit of the fear of the Lord. He shall not judge according to the sight of the eyes, nor reprove according to the hearing of the ears.35 Isaias pictures a perfect judge who, thanks to the special dignity and power that the spirit of the Lord will confer upon him, will give special attention to those so often neglected in the Orient. The effects that the permanent dwelling of the spirit produces are the qualities of an ideal judge: wisdom to know the true point of view; understanding, the gift of discernment, of judgment, to comprehend the circumstances and the other facts that can influence or determine the sentence; counsel, the art of choosing the means most proper in a given case; fortitude, making him superior to obstacles and respect of persons; knowledge of the law; and in all his actions respect for God, piety and fear of the Lord. 86 In most of these citations it is not clear either from the text or the context that the gifts of the Holy Ghost in their narrowest and strictest meaning are meant, but the whole series shows the operation of the spirit of God, the Holy Spirit, in a particular way. Isaias crystalizes the vague expressions of his precursors into a powerful and moving picture of the messianic Judge, and this picture under the skillful interpretation of the Fathers and Doctors, from Justin to Gregory, becomes the basis for the doctrine of the gifts in St. Thomas and the Church. As Pere Touzard remarks at the close of his article, " From the last Father of the Church to the Angel of the Schools is not far." 37 With this wealth of tradition as well as •• Ibid .• 104. Is., xi, 2-8. J. Touzard, "Isaie, XI, 2-3a et Les Sept Dons du Saint Esprit," Revue Biblique, VIII (1899), 250. •• Ibid., p. 266. 35 38 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 225 Scripture behind him, St. Thomas assumes the existence of the gift. His first concern is not to establish its existence, but to clarify the confusion involved in the term " intellectus " The term is taken from intus and legere, to read within, the intimate penetration of truth. 88 The word intellectus has many meanings in Scholastic language. It sometimes means the essence of the soul itself, because the soul may be denominated by its principal power. In the III de Anima and in many places of the Summa, those wonderful creatures we call angels are called I ntellectus or lntelligentiae. Again the word sometimes means that potency of the soul which enables it to know, as distinct from the will. This intellective potency is further divided into the intellectus agens and the intellectus possibilis. Very often it means a natural habit, one of the intellectual virtues, the habit of first principles. It may also designate one of the integral parts of prudence, a knowledge of present matters and a just estimate of some particular end in the light of ultimate principles which are accepted asperse known. And, finally, it signifies, as a gift of the Holy Ghost, a certain acute penetration of divine things. Here, 89 it means neither an intellective potency, nor a habit of first principles, but a habit divinely infused by which one so penetrates the mysteries of the Christian religion that he sees that the arguments which are opposed to them do not lessen their truth, whether he can solve the arguments or not. 4n St. Thomas gives various descriptions of what he means by the gift of understanding: it is" a supernatural light," 41 a" certain excellence of knowledge penetrating to the very core"; 42 it "implies a certain penetration of truth"; 43 its function is "to penetrate what is said." 44 A nominal definition joined to what he has taught on the gifts in general would be enough to answer the question St. Thomas poses in the first article, i. e., "Is understanding a gift 38 Summa Theol., IT-II, q. 8, a. I; q. 49, a. 5, ad Sum. •• Ibid., II-II, q. 8, a. I. •• Ibid., ad Sum. •o Sylvius, Oomm. in II-II, q. 8. •• Ibid., a. 5, ad Sum. •• Ibid., a. 6, ad 2um. " Summa Theol .• II-II, q. 8, a. I. 4 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS of the Holy Ghost ? " 45 He goes further, however, and shows something of the nature of the gift, its subject, and the objects to which it extends; in the answer to the first objection he expressly declares what he only implied in the body of the article, that the gift is necessary for salvation. By calling this gift a light, and comparing it with the natural light which is better known to us, he not only gives us a glimpse of its nature, but harmoniously blends the working of the supernatural in us with the natural. The background against which all this discussion must move is the fundamental principle that man is ordered to a supernatural Since man's knowledge begins from the sense and from something external, it is evident that his knowledge will penetrate to essences only to the degree of power that the light of his intellect enjoys. But the strength of this light is limited, and the depth of his penetration is determined by nature. To ferret out those things which though necessary because of his end, exceed his natural powers, man needs assistance from the same order as his end. This is the gift of understanding which is a supernatural light. For St. Thomas, man may enjoy three different lights, not always simultaneously, but varying with different individuals in different states. The highest of these is called the light of glory. This is found only in the just who are enjoying the beatific vision. It is a supernatural habitual quality, an augmentation of the intellective power " after the manner in which a potency is made more powerful to act through a habit inhering in it." 47 To see God face to face is far above the powers of any created faculty left to its own resources, and so God strengthens it by infusing this new light into the soul, not as a medium in which God is seen, but as an added perfection strenghtening the intellect to see God immediately. This light of glory is the culmination of another light which man can enjoy while on earth. Thomas calls it the light of grace. 48 It too is supernatural in origin, and a quality perfecting the soul •• Ibid., a. 1. •• Ibid., I-ll, q. 3, a. 8. "Ibid., I, q. 12, a. 5, ad lum. •• Ibid., I-ll, q. 109, a. 1. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 227 to know, in this life, things that are beyond the limits of its natural powers. There are at least two common forms that it takes-the light of faith and the light of prophecy. The latter is not a habitual perfection, but rather a vivid and fleeting glimpse of things to be revealed which comes and goes as God wills, in order that the things seen in its transient light may be passed on to mankind by the prophet. Nor does it presuppose charity in the soul. The light of faith is the result of a habit, the virtue of faith joining us to God, and lasts as long as faith remains. Not only does it extend the field of our knowledge by putting us in contact with truths which we could not otherwise know or assent to, but it contributes a new insight into the things with which the natural power of the intellect is engaged. This natural power of the intellect is also called a light, the natural light of man, or the natural light of the active intellect. We speak of intellectual light after the manner of corporeal light. Now corporeal light is the medium by which we see, and it serves vision in a twofold manner. On one hand, through it a thing only potentially visible becomes actually so, as while driving on a dark night, only that portion of the potentially visible countryside which the headlights illumine is actually seen. On the other, the power of sight itself is strengthened to see. By analogy then, intellectual light can be either the power of the intellect to understand, or also that by which something becomes known to us. 49 The light of the gift of understanding should have a place in this outline. It is not the light of glory despite the great similarities between the two. The light of glory once attained is inamissable, but since the gifts are founded in charity which is lost by mortal sin:, they too can be lost. We know from faith that while on earth, Christ enjoyed the beatific vision, and at the same time all the gifts. A posteriori then, they are distinct. And, finally, we have the famous dictum of St. Gregory, "No one, as long as he lives in mortal flesh, so advances in the strength of his contemplation, that the eye of his mind fixes •• Q. D. de Ver., q. 9, a. I. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS upon a ray of the uncircumscribed light; whatever is seen in this manner is not God Himself, but under Him." 50 We shall return to this question _later. Since the light of understanding is a supernatural light, it cannot be the light of reason, which leaves only the light of grace. As a matter of fact, a sober and objective examination of the first article will reveal that this is as far as St. Thomas cares to proceed. His argument concludes no further than the necessity for a supernatural light and is practically the same as the argument advanced for the existence of a light of grace: ... and those things to which we cannot conclude from first principles exceed the natural light of the intellect. Of this sort are matters of faith, future contingents, and the like, and therefore a knowledge of these truths cannot be had without a light of grace freely given, such as the light of faith or of prophecy or something of the sort. 51 And in the Summa, in answer to the question of whether a knowledge of truth is possible without grace, he says: . . . the human understanding has a form, namely, intelligible light, which of itself is sufficient for knowing certain intelligible things, those, namely, which we can come to know through the senses. Higher intelligible things the human intellect cannot know unless it be perfected by a stronger light, the light of faith or prophecy, which is called the light of grace inasmuch as it is added to nature. 52 Here in answer to the question whether understanding is a gift of the Holy Ghost, he replies: . . . the natural light of our understanding is of finite power; wherefore it can reach to a certain fixed point. Consequently man needs a supernatural light in order to penetrate further still so as to know what he cannot know by natural light; and this supernatural light given to man is called the gift of intellect ... 53 This is his general concept which St. Thomas, as he proceeds in 50 Homiliae XL in Ezeehielem, Lib. II, Hom. II, P. L. Vol. 76, col. 956. "'II Sent., d. XXVIII, q. 1, a. 5. •• Summa Theol., I-II, q. 109, a. 1, c. •• Ibid., II-II, q. 8, a. 1. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 229 his tract, trims, bends and polishes until the precise nature of the gift is apparent. There are three orders of being with unequal powers who can illumine the human mind. Man can enlighten another man in two ways. He can propose some object for consideration and so lead another to a knowledge of it, as when a guide points out some monument or inscription. But, as St. Thomas and Cajetan observe, this is not, properly speaking, illumination, but only locution. 54 For real illumination it is not sufficient to merely offer a truth; it must be offered as illumined by the mind of the one who presents it, as when a teacher illumines the mind of a student. This familiar process is thus described by Baiiez, There are two things required for the knowledge of truth,apprehension and judgment. Some truth can be hidden from the intellect either because the intellect is not strong enough to apprehend it since it is not proposed proportionately, or because it cannot make a certain judgment about it on account of the deficiency of light which is the proper principle of judgment. Whence it follows that the manifestation of truth can be twofold, either on the ;part of the apprehension, as when the master teaches the student to form a proper concept of some conclusion, using similar examples, distinctions, etc.; or on the part of the judgment, as when the master proposes to the pupil principles and means guided by which he can judge of the conclusion. 55 Referring to several pertinent passages from St. Thomas, 56 Baiiez continues: The intelligible principle to which the conclusion is resolved has the notion of intellectual light under which the intellect judges of the truth of the conclusion, 56 • Mention here of a passage from Cajetan will throw further light on the matter: There is in the teacher an active ordination of his proper concept •• II Sent., d. IX, q. 1, a. and 4um; cf. Cajetan, Comm. in I, q. 106, a. 1. •• Banez, Comm. in I, q. 106, a. 1. •• Summa Theol., II-II, q. 15, a. 1; Q. D. de Ver., q. 9, a. 1, ad ••• Banez, loc. cit. 230 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS illustrating and measuring to the student the thing conceived. The student applies his intellect to the formation of a concept corresponding to the concept of the same thing he has been shown, and so he participates in the superior light of the professor. Thus there comes to be, in some fashion, in the student a new light because of this participation by which he is actually illuminated. Thus the light of the student is intensified, because it becomes more efficacious for understanding. 57 Baiiez, discussing the same magistral illumination, comes to the same conclusion although he phrases it differently: The principles on which a demonstration is based are the instruments of the natural light, inasmuch as the natural light of the active intellect leads the possible intellect to assent to the conclusions under those principles by resolving the conclusion to those first principles. Whence it follows that the master, by proposing principles and means, properly strengthens the natural light of his disciple, not, indeed, increasing it intensively but extensively, since the natural light can now judge from the conjoined principles. And so from the natural light, the principle and the mean, one integral virtue is formed to judge of the conclusion. 58 This mode of illumination is of course impossible in the gift of understanding, because we are not given any species by the Holy Ghost to aid our understanding. But the whole process of magistral illumination is important in order to understand the next order. The second order of beings, the angels, can illumine those under them, whether angels or men, after the fashion of human masters and also by directly strenghtening the intellectual light of inferiors by uniting themselves with it. " Some say that an angel in no way teaches like a person offering light, which seems expressly against the words of Dionysius," 59 remarks St. Thomas. 6 ° Cajetan seems to be among the " some," for he describes and explains the angelic illumination after the manner of teacher and pupil, in which " the light of the inferior is intensified because more efficacious, although not properly intensified." This magistral illumination, as we have seen, is 67 Oomm. in I, q. 106, a. 1. •• Loc. cit. •• De Ooelesti Hierarckia, c. X. •• II Sent.. d. IX, q. l, a. 2, ad 4um. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 281 only indirect illumination, inasmuch as there is no direct tranfer of power or light but only a principle or a medium which will excite the inferior to act. This is not sufficient for Ba:iiez; according to him: In the illumination of an inferior angel, his light is strengthened not only by instruction but through an intellectual conjuction and union by which the light of the inferior and superior are joined together for one principle of knowledge of truth. 61 He is led to this by the teaching of St. Thomas-that the teacher strengthens the intellect of the learner "not by an active power as was said of the illumination of the angels ... 62 The mind of St. Thomas is, therefore, that the strengthening of the light of the inferior angel is not only with respect to an intelligible principle under which truth is manifested, but also with respect to some action proceeding from the active virtue of the superior into the inferior. St. Thomas teaches, moreover, that illumination of an inferior angel depends on the superior not only for reception but also for its conservation, just as the knowledge of a conclusion depends on an actual knowledge of the principles. 63 Therefore, there is required a natural influx of the light of the superior into the illuminated; otherwise knowledge of the inferior would be only in inception and not in conservation, as the teaching of a master in the mind of his student depends only in its inception on the master. The light of the superior must stay with the inferior because the intelligible object by its very nature exceeds the light of the inferior. Ba:iiez gives some examples of the union of diverse things forming one principle of operation without losing their own identity. The first is from color and light. Visible light does not inhere in color, but the light in the air makes the color in the wall actually visible, not only as the terminative object of sight, but also the motive object. It is colored light that is the unique integral principle · moving sight through visible species, yet the light is not the color, for in vision there is a natural subordination of color to light. There is another 81 Loc. cit. u Summa Theol.• I, q. ll7, a. 1. 88 Ibid., q. 108, a. 7, ad 2um. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS example from goodness in the intellect and will. Apprehended goodness, precisely as apprehended, is the formal motivating force of the object of the will, and is the form and the act of the will constituting with it one integral principle of volition, and although it concurs to produce the volition, it does not really inhere in the will, because of the natural subordination of the will to the intellect. Finally, in any act of knowledge, the intelligible species is the result of the partnership of phantasm and light of the active intellect, and yet the light does not inhere in the phantasm nor cause anything in it. So, when a potency, the intellect of an angel, is joined to a superior form, becoming with it one principle, the potency can still vitally elicit its proper operation with an increased power, intrinsically and intensively. The third order of beings who illumine man is God. God is alone and unique in His power. He can swiftly and perfectly enlighten man either permanently or for a time, not only by the indirect methods of men and angels, but by directly increasing the intellective power of man. The light of man's intellect in the first place is only a created participation, a circumscribed ray of the uncircumscribed light of the supreme !ntellect of God. 64 By the infusion of grace into the soul, man is united to God, and as a result of this divine habit in the soul, all its faculties are divinized and strengthened. As with all things that only participate their perfection, the closer tJ.\ey approach their source the stronger they become, and so the intellect in approaching God becomes stronger. When the Holy Ghost moves it, it seems to leave behind all the defects of being joined to a body, and seems to become angelic in the clarity of its intuitive judgments. Just as the inferior angel under the illumination of the superior becomes able to understand objects that exceed its ordinary powers, so the intellect, furnished with the light of the Holy Ghost in the gift of understanding, penetrates, grasps, and assents to supernatural truths which would present an impenetrable front to its natural •• Ibid., q. l!i!, a. !i!. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 238 powers. Again, like an angel, this power remains in the intellect only as long as the intellect is united to God by grace; once the mover withdraws, man relapses into the obscurity of faith. This in general is what is indicated to us by broadly comparing the gift of understanding to light. In the answers to the difficulties 65 St. Thomas starts to distinguish this generic notion of supernatural light. From the first, we gather only that it is superior to that by which we know common principles, and from the second we gather its intuitive super-rational and esssential character. The natural light of the human intellect is of a quality or a permanent form which makes it sufficient of itself to know some proportionate object, but this is not man's only means of natural knowledge. Joined to the light as instruments to a craftsman are the first principles of knowledge. 66 They are the first conceptions of the mind, known through and in their very terms without any discursus or reasoning. With their help the intellect is ready to apprehend and to penetrate its proper object-essences. St. Thomas says: There are different ways of apprehending essences. Sometimes the essence is apprehended immediately and not through those things which are wrapped around the essence; this is the mode of apprehension in separated substances, and so they are called intelligences. Sometimes again, the intimate core of a thing is not penetrated except by the things around it as through some kind of gateway; this is the mode of apprehension in men, who from properties and effects proceed to the knowledge of an essence. Because this process is discursive, the apprehension of man is called reason, although it terminates at the understanding of a thing, because its inquiry leads to the essence. Whence if there are some things which are apprehended at once without the operation of reason, we say that these things are understood, and not reasoned to; such, for example, are first principles which everyone approves as soon as he, hears. In the first way, the intellect is a potency, but taken in the second way, it is called a habit of first principles. Just as the human mind, moreover, does not penetrate to the essence of anything except through accidents, so also it does •• Ibid., I-II, q. 8, a. I. •• Q. D. de VeT.• q. 11, a. 8. 234 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS not penetrate spiritual things except through corporeal things and the likenesses of sensible things. Whence it is that faith, which holds spiritual things seen as in a dark glass, perfects the mind in a human mode and, therefore, it is a virtue. If, however, the mind is so elevated by a supernatural light that it is led to gaze upon spiritual things as they are in themselves, this is beyond human power. This is what the gift of understanding does; it so illustrates the mind concerning the things of faith that like first principles, they are proved the minute they are heard. This understanding is, of course, a gift. 67 Hence, when in answer to the second objection, 68 St. Thomas says that the super-added light has the same relation to things known supernaturally as natural light has to first principles, he definitely indicates that the distinctive note of the light of the gift of understanding will be the swift intuitive grasp it offers of spiritual things, by the illumination of the Holy Ghost without the burden of step-by-step reasoning. By comparing the gift of understanding to the habit of first principles in the natural order, St. Thomas does not mean to institute a comparison of the instrumental relation so much as to point out the nature of the act of the gift. The knowledge of first principles is gained without inquisition and argumentation, in which point human knowledge touches that of the angels although it does not equal it because we are still dependent on the senses.69 Indemonstrable principles are known at once, as soon as we hear the terms, for as soon we know what a whole is and what a part is, at once we know that every whole is greater than a part . . . and so, the knowledge of principles which become clear as soon as the words are known is conveniently called It is easy to make a mistake here that will distort the whole notion of the gift. Taking the words as they stand, it seems that a simple apprehension of the terms of the first principles is sufficient to generate the habit. Yet such is not the case. •• III Sent., d. XXXV, q. 2, a. 2. •• Summa Theol., I-II, q. 8, a. 1, ad 2um. •• Q. D. de V er., q. 16, a. 1. •• VI Ethic., lect. 5. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING First principles do not consist in the mere apprehension of terms, but in a composition of subject and predicate, an assent and a judgment. The knowledge of " whole" and the knowledge of " part " is indeed a simple apprehension, but to say that the whole is greater than its part is a judgment. This is but an application of the general doctrine that truth is in the judgment formally, and not elsewhere. 71 Like any other habit in an active potency, there must be an act of assent before we can acquire the habit of inclining us to do so. Now, with the gift of understanding, all this is lifted into the supernatural order. The light of this gift is not merely to apprehend the terms in which supernatural truths are proposed, but to apprehend correctly and then to compose and divide and so arrive at the truth without, of course, any long process of reasoning, which proceeds step by step until a conclusion is reached. By the gift, the mind is perfected in the apprehension of truth, not any apprehension, but that apprehension which pertains to the way of invention. 72 Invention is not what we understand by the term today, a novel application of the principles of mechanics to some problem, but it the name applied to a process of finding truth. In this discovery of truth we proceed in a human way from sense to memory, from memory to experiment, from experiment to first principles which are known immediately the terms are known; this process perfects the intellectual habit which is the habit of first principles. We proceed further in the same mode by advancing from these principles to conclusions. For this we are perfected in those things which are under reason by another intellectual virtue which is called science; in those, however, which are above reason, we have faith which is the inspection of divine things seen, as in a dark glass. To grasp what might be called the naked truth of spiritual things, is above merely human powers, and requires the gift of understanding which illumines the mind concerning those things heard through faith. 73 As John of St. Thomas says: Invention does not concern the simple apprehension of terms, but 01 Summa, Theol., I, q. 16, a. 2. n Ibid., 1-11, q. 68, a. 4. •• Ill Sent., d. XXXIV, q. 1, a. i. 236 JOSEPH IGNATIDS MCGUINESS inquires about some truth and the propositions that invention attains; for some things we learn; some things we find and so attain them, not learning them from others. What we learn are not simple terms and the apprehension of them, but propositions and truths, whether known from their terms or from argument; similarly, therefore, what we attain by invention are not only simple terms, but truths, and the propositions by which such truths are enunciated. 74 From the answer to the second objection/ 5 where the process of reason is contrasted with pure intellection, it is evident that propositions-truths-are meant, and not mere simple terms, because in the process of reason we start from some proposition that we understand and proceed by many steps to a conclusion, another proposition, which is now known to us in the light of the propositions we knew at first. By the light of first principles, we understand not terms but propositions, truths known through themselves, in which something is affirmed or denied of something else, e. g., "Whatever is, is; a thing cannot be and not be at the same time"; and the more subtle but still self-evident truths like," there cannot be many gods." Equally, then, by the light which is called the gift of understanding, we can grasp with intuitive ease the supernatural meaning of the objects of our knowledge. We shall now consider these objects. St. Thomas shows the objects to which the gift of understanding refers by analogy with the intuitions of the natural faculty. There are six categories of hidden things which the gift aids us to bring to light: the substance under its accidents; the sense beneath the words; the truth behind the symbol; the spiritual under its sensible appearances; the cause in its effect; and the effect in its cause. The first intuition is exemplified in the familiar story of Blessed John Dominici and Antonino Pierozzi, known to the world as St. Antoninus, Archbishop of Florence. What possessed the great Dominici, with his apostolic thirst for austerity u Oursus Theologicus, I-IT, disp. XVITI, a. 8. •• Summa Theol., I-IT, q. 8, a. 1, ad 2um. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 237 and reform, to even compromise with the pale, sickly, motherless lad whom the doctors promised would soon die of consumption, and promise him admission to the Order of Preachers should he commit to memory the Decretal of Gratian in a year? He must have seen beneath that unprepossessing exterior the stuff which properly handled would bring the glory of sainthood to the Order of the Church. Under the accidents he saw the substance. As for penetrating the sense of words and the spirit of the letter, St. Thomas gives the example of the disciples at Emmaus of whom St. Luke 76 says, " Then He opened their understanding, that they might understand the Scripture." Long before he had said to His followers, " Are you yet also without understanding ? " 77 This example of the disciples at Emmaus, though traditionally cited by nearly all spiritual writers as an operation of the gift of understanding, may lose something of its force when we recall that St. Thomas also uses it in his discussion of the gift of prophecy/ 8 where he calls it an example of a charism pertaining to St. Paul's "understanding of instructions." If given as a transient vision by which certain texts concerning Christ were momentarily illumined for the good of the young Church, it is a charism, but if it is a habitual quality remaining in the mind, then it is the gift. In the Acts, mention is made of Lydia, the prototype of all those pious souls " whose heart the Lord opened to attend to those things which were said by Paul." \''9 Many of the saints found in the highly symbolic language of the Old Testament the expression of their hidden mystical joys and delights. St. Thomas confessed," Never have I read a book that the Holy Spirit has not aided me to comprehend it, and to plumb the profundity of a mystery." 80 St. Antoninus places his whole discussion of the interpretation of Scripture under the title of this gift. It is the gift of understanding that makes us see the spiritual •• Luke, xxiv, 25. •• Matthew, xv, 16. •• Summa Theol., 11-11, q. 173, a. !il. •• Acts, xvi, 14. 80 Tocco, vii, 40. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS reality behind its sensible appearances. The villagers of Nazareth saw only a poor young carpenter laboring in a shop, but Mary, his Mother, saw not only the most perfect human soul that ever lived; she saw her God. This " seeing " is not through any medium, like a sign or a mirror or a footprint or an image, which usually links the apprehensive power and the thing signified; it is accomplished by the superabundant light of the gift of understanding, just as the light of the sun joins the power of sight and the thing seen.81 The world saw a common criminal dying between two of his kind on Calvary, but His mother with the eyes of her soul saw the redemption of the world depending on that sorrowful passion, and so she held herself upright at the foot of the Cross, and instead of sinking in the human grief of the holy women, she stood and shared the redemption of the world. Indeed, in the Blessed Virgin we :find this gift in a more perfect degree than in any other creature. As soon as the Angel announced to her the part she is to play in the redemption, she responded " How shall this be?" This was not disbelief, but the gift seeking to penetrate and to see the plan of God. Some writers attribute the Magnificat to this gift, since her clear perception of her prerogatives and her supernatural vocation so elevated her heart that it could not contain its joy. St. Albert, however, attributes the Magnificat to the gift of wisdom, because of his notion of the gift of understanding. 182 This is how he describes the gift in Mary: The gift of understanding is to know God in His image. Between knowing God in His image, without light, in the obscurity of faith, and knowing the uncreated light by uncreated light, without an image, there is a middle way to know in created light, without an image. Just as one of the extremes is of pure wayfarers, and the other of those in Heaven, so the middle pertains to the state in which Our Blessed Mother was. She, therefore, had this gift more perfectly than other creatures. 83 St. Antoninus, Summa moralis, IV, tit. 15, c. 18. •• Comm. in Evang. Lucae, i, 46. Opera Omnia (Paris: 1890-1899), XXII, •• Mariale, q. 64. Opera Omnia, XXXVIT, UO. 81 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 239 The saints too, knew how to see in every human creature the soul made to the image and likeness of God, and very often the Holy Spirit dwelling there. " Henceforth," says St. Paul, " we know no man according to the flesh." 84 There is a remarkable example of intuition in the life of St. Catherine of Sienna, when she prepared Nicholas di Toldo for his execution and accompanied him to the scaffold. The knife fell and I receive his head into my hands. I fixed my eyes on the Divine Goodness, and Lo ! I beheld as clearly as one beholds the sun, Him who is God and man. He was there and He received the blood . . . He received it and placed it in the open wound of His side, in the treasury of His mercy . . . Oh how lovingly He looked on that soul bathed in the blood made precious by being united to His own! Then Father, Son and Holy Ghost received him, and He was inundated with a joy that would have ravished a thousand hearts . . . Then I felt a delicious peace, and the perfume of that blood was so sweet to me, that I would not suffer them to wash away what had fallen over me.85 In this blood united to Christ through grace, Catherine saw the blood of the Lamb, and sought to plunge herself into the Sacred Side. So many other examples of the operation of this gift in an eminent degree are to be found in the life of this holy daughter of St. Dominic that Fr. Antoine Gardeil attributes this gift to her as her predominant characteristic: 86 By natural reason most men come to a knowledge of the existence of God, but by the light of revelation we know that God is one in three divine Persons. By the light of the gift of understanding we go on to contemplate in the Holy Trinity as far as we can in this life, what are the relations of Father, Son and Holy Ghost, how they are three Persons, how they are co-equal, co-eternal, how they differ only in their relations to each other, and so on. As Cardinal Manning says," The one phrase, ' the Word was made flesh,' contains the whole theology •• II Cor., v, 16. •• Letters, n. 97. •• The Gifts of the Holy Ghost in Dominican Saints, Trans. by A. Townsend, O.P. (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1987), p. 88. 240 JOSEPH IGNATIDS MCGUINESS "Of the Incarnation in all its treatises." 87 We see it expanded in the course of time-in the phrases of the Nicene creed: "God of God; . . . consubstantial with the Father"; in the Athanasian creed, with its more precise terms-the two natures, two substances, one Person, perfect humanity; and in the third part of the Summa and all the later theologians. Yet many a humble soul knows just as much as the theologians without all this study and science, like the monk Anthony of whom St. Augustine speaks. It is in the light of this gift that the poor and untutored solve the apparent difficulties of belief. To those who judge by the letter, or by outward facts, the sorrows and the miseries of the world seem to obscure its witness to the goodness if not the existence of God; the sorrow and miseries of the Church likewise seem to deny it is the kingdom of an all-powerful God; the evergrowing conquests of natural science are bent by some against the truth of revelation. How find the unifying thread of truth in all the advancements of our age unless by the superhuman light of the Holy Ghost? To penetrate all these chaotic and disturbing elements and find at their core the calm and majestic plan of God requires more than mere reason, handicapped as it is with distractions and imperfections. It requires the additional light of the gift of understanding to pierce the rind and find the sweetness of the fruit, to crack the shell and find the kernel of truth. 88 Whence it is evident why spiritual writers call this the gift par excellence of preachers and doctors in the Church. III. THE GIFT AND FAITH God has presented man with a sheaf of supernatural truths which he must know and act upon in order to reach his final end, and yet which exceed his natural powers of understanding. By faith, man accepts these truths and holds them firmly, yet it is an exterior adhesion in which the will bears all the expense, 87 H. E. Manning, The Internal Mission of the Holy Ghost (New York: Kenedy, 1904), p. 272. 88 Cf. M.-J. Friaque, 0. P., Le Saint-Esprit, Part ill, c. 7 (Paris: 1886). THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 241 the intellect remaining dissatisfied. Then, under the impulse of the Holy Spirit, the man with the gift. of understanding finds himself able to face these notions of revelation as easily as first principles in the natural order. He has found a new light enabling his mind to penetrate and to seize them quite clearly. How reconcile the shadows of the faith with the luminous evidence of the gift of understanding ? With the operation of the gift, is the faith going to disappear ? The reply is, of course, in the negative. By distinguishing the formal aspects of the objects of the virtue and the gift, we see how they can work side by side in the same subject without interfering with each other in this life. Faith has three formal objects. Its primary one is the revealed mysteries to which it clings and about which no positive intuition is possible in this life.89 The secondary object of faith is all the species of truths concerning creatures as ordained to God, and here the more light the better for the faith. Faith is said to have a third object only by extension, that is, inasmuch as it operates through charity in all moral acts. 90 As Father Garrigou-Lagrange writes, Faith makes us know God in a way which is still too abstract, too exterior, in speculo et in aenigmate, by excessively narrow formulas that must be multiplied. Hope and charity directed by faith share in the imperfection of faith. These two virtues of the will lack vitality and keep too much of the human manner as long as they are directed only by reason illumined by faith. With only the virtues, even though supernatural, man is like an apprentice who knows fairly well what he must do, but who has not the skill to do it in a suitable manner. Consequently the master who is teaching him must come from time to time, take his hand and direct it so that the work may be presentable. As we always remain apprentices the Holy Ghost must intervene habitually in our works that they may be perfect. That is why, unlike purely gratuitous graces, the gifts which make us amenable to divine inspirations as the virtues do to the directions of reason, should be permanent in us. (Summa Theol., I-II, q. 68, a. 3.) •• Theol., IT-IT, q. l, a. 1. •• Cf. Dictionnaire de Theologie Oatholique, Vol. 4, part 5 col. 1748. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS A soul can advance by the exercises of the virtues. In this it is active. Or by the inspiration of the Holy Ghost who breathes where and when He wills. Here the soul is docile, acting less than it is acted upon.91 St. Thomas says: The gifts are given in aid of the virtues by which the potencies of the soul are perfected to acts proportioned to a human mode, like faith which sees but only cryptically in a mirror .. ;92 The defects in a virtue are twofold. There are accidental defects, springing from some indisposition on the part of the virtue, which are remedied by augmenting the virtue. The more serious defects are the ones essential to the habit. This defect is remedied by a higher habit which is called a gift because given by God and exceeding the manner of human operation, like understanding which brings it to pass that we see in some way the things of faith clearly and limpidly. The defects of the faith come from the very constitution of man; His knowledge of faith has its origin in the sense, inasmuch as he knows the meaning of words proposed by the senses, but these fail in the representation of Him about Whom faith is primarily concerned. Faith, therefore, has not perfect knowledge.113 To faith pertain properly those things whose vision we shall enjoy in eternal life and through which we are led therc. 114 The only way we can attain them in this life is be believing, i. e., by having the will, on the authority of God, force the intellect to assent. " The argument from divine authority does not make the thing evident in itself." 95 The believer, who by the very fact that he believes does not see, is liable to confuse the sensible element with the spiritual, and fall a prey to illusions and errors. What knowledge he has, moreover, is bound to be superficial and fragmentary. He must 01 Christian Perfet:tion and Contemplation, Trans. by Sr. M. Timothea Doyle, 0. P. (St. Louis: Herder, 1987), pp. 281 fi'. •• In Isaiam, xi, 2. •• Ill Sent., d. XXIV, q. 1, a. 2, qt. 8, ad 8 um. •• Summa Tkeol., II-II, q. 1, a. 7. •• Ibid., q. 4, a. 1, ad -5um. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 248 search around and reason about the formulas which contain supernatural truth, unlike the angel who with a glance penetrates to the interior of things. Nor is the mind at rest, satisfied in this knowledge. "The perfection of assent is caused by the simple light of faith, but since this light is not perfectly participated, the imperfection of the intellect remains, and so it remains unquiet." 96 Finally, our love of God must partake of the imperfections of our faith; it is easier to love what we see than what we do not see. The gift, because of its superhuman mode of action is free from these defects, and when found in the same subject can supply for the deficiencies. With regard to the confusion of the spiritual with the sensible, St. Thomas says: There are two sorts of cleanness, one dispositive and a preamble to the vision of God, which is the purification of the affection from inordinate affections, and this is carried out by the virtues and the gifts in the appetitive faculties; the other cleanness of the heart is complementary, as it were, to vision, and this is the cleansing of the mind from phantasms and errors, in order that those things which are proposed of God be not taken after the manner of corporeal phantasms nor according to the perversion of heretics, and this cleanness is the work of the gift of understanding. Therefore, under the aspect of merit, the sixth beatitude, " Blessed are the clean of heart, for they shall see God," pertains to this Gift. 97 ll"'rom what we have said of the nature of this gift as a light, this is easy to see. The mind under the impulse of the Holy Spirit is helped over and past the obstacles of imagery to reach the truth at the heart of the propositions. The superficial and fragmentary nature of the knowledge of faith is assisted by the instinctive and clairvoyant flashes of the gift, with this reservation: We can understand a thing in two ways: in one, perfectly, when we attain to a knowledge of the essence of the thing understood and the truth of the statement understood (enuntiabilis intellecti) according as it is in itself; in another way, something happens to be •• Q. D. d6 Ver., q. 14, a. 1, ad 5um. •• Summa Theol., II-IT, q. 8, a. 7. 244 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS understood imperfectly when the very essence or the truth of a proposition is not known as to what or how it is, but nevertheless it is known that those things which appear externally are not contrary to the truth, inasmuch as man understands that he must not recede from the things of faith, because of what appears extrinsically ."98 The precise role of the gift of understanding then will be to aid the virtue of faith to overcome this defect without destroying its essential characteristic of blind assent. " Faith implies only an assent to propositions, but understandng implies a certain penetration of the truth." '99 This is seen by applying this distinction to what we have said above concerning the objects of faith. The gift .does not give a perfect and positive insight into the principles and primary object of faith, but only a negative and imperfect one, attacking the external impediments and obstacles that, by the very fact that we are still in the state of wayfarers, separate us from God. Yet even here, St. Thomas does not hesitate to say, " Even in this life, God can in some way be seen, the eye [of the mind] being cleansed by the gift of understanding." 100 Between God and ourselves are interposed the sensible formulas of revelation. But illumined by the light of the Holy Ghost in this gift, they become as it were transparent. As St. John of the Cross writes in the twelfth canticle: Then the soul call the faith crystalline because it makes the soul to see through the now transparent veils, the Saviour of men, because it is pure, clean of errors, empty of corporeal images, strong in divine truth. With Thy light Thou dost illumine me so that I may know all Thy truth; Thou art that Light above all light, which illuminates supernaturally the eye of my intellect, clarifying the light of faith so abundantly and so perfectly that I see that my soul is alive, and in this light receives Thee the true light. 101 •• Ibid., q. 8, a. S. •• Ibid., a. 5, ad Sum. 100 Ibid., 1-11, q. 69, a. 2,. ad Sum. 101 Dialogues, Trans. by A. Thorold (New York: Benziger, 1907), c. 167. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING As to the substance of the mysteries, we can perceive sometimes the motives of them, connections one with another, analogies, and their many harmonies. 1 {)2 Further than this we cannot go concerning the essence of God and the mysteries concerning Him directly. Even the imperfect knowledge that the gift offers is a great aid to faith, for by it, the little ones of the flock see that all the apparent difficulties are invalid. Even when one does not always know how to reply to objections, one knows that in spite of the multiple and complicated claims of error, the truth is there in its simplicity and its certitude. While heresies and negations based on scientific formulas try in vain to take the citadel of the fervent soul by assault, the soul intuitively clings to Catholic dogma. This is the explanation of the not infrequent phenomenon of the remarkable insight and appreciation of spiritual things found in unlettered and dullwitted men and simple women in whom however faith and charity flourish in a high degree. To these simple souls, neither the speculations of theologians nor the divine reasons are explicitly known; but by the gift of understanding they are so convinced of divine truths and so strengthened in the faith, that they are not in the least perturbed by the sophisms of heretics, the threats of tyrants, or the insidious snares of malignant spirits. Here, too, we see these rustic saints and humble women spending long periods in divine contemplation, scarcely able to interrupt most sweet colloquies of internal prayer and quiet; we see them able to deliver sound and integral judgments in doubtful matters because their appetites are correct; we see them savor eternal things and spurn the temporal. They rightly appreciate divine things, because their minds are crammed with the consideration of divine truths hidden from the wise and prudent and revealed to the little ones, for, as Christ and the Holy Ghost tell us, the conversation of God is with the simple-hearted. 1 {) 8 Billot, op. cit., p. 185. Cf. V. Contenson, 0. P .., Theologia Mentis et Cordis, Lib. VIII, Diss. II, c. Spec. 2 and 3 (Paris: Vives, 1875), ill, 526 fl'. 10 • 108 246 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS As for the secondary objects of the faith, " the effects of the Divinity through which man is helped to tend to divine fruition, Holy Scripture, for example, and all it contains," 104 access to such truths as these lies open through study, or through the teaching of other men, but, in a higher and easier and more salubrious mode, through the instinct of the Holy Ghost 105 " I am he that in an instant elevates a humble Inind to understand more reasons of the eternal truth than could be acquired by ten years' study in the schools." 106 The assent of the intellect to truth is of two kinds: in one the intellect is moved by the object whether it be known in itself, as in first principles; or in the light of other principles and The object, in other words, is really seen by the intellect, because it itself moves the faculty to knowledge. In the other way, it is moved not by intrinsic evidence on the part of the object, but by the will.107 The intellect cannot be deterInined either by the simple inspection of the terms of a credible proposition as by principles, nor from the light of other principles as in demonstrative conclusions. The will, however, chooses to determine the intellect, because of something sufficient to move the will but not the intellect. This is to believe. One believes the words of some man because it seems proper or useful, or, especially, when a reward of eternal life is proinised. The act of belief is unique among the acts of the mind. In the mere apprehension of things there is no assent, because the truth is not grasped as such, and assent is only the truth. In one who doubts, there is no real assent, nor is one who has only an opinion. The man with the habit of first principles assents to them, but without collation and therefore without a sort of reiterated intellectual activity called cogitation. The man with the habit of conclusions has both cogitation and assent, but the cogitation is the cause of the assent, inasmuch as from the Summa Theol .• II-II, q. 1, a. 1. Cf. Billot, loc. cit. 106 Imitation of Christ. Bk. III, c. 43, n. 3. 101 Summa Theol .• II-II, q. 1, a. 4. 10 • 105 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING collation of principles and conclusions, he resolved his conclusion into its principles, and now his intellect rests. In science the motion of reason begins with the habit of principles and ends in them. Cogitation and assent are not equal because cogitation leads to the assent and stops satisfied. In faith alone are cogitation and assent equal. Assent is not from the cogitation at all but from the will, but because the intellect is not in this manner terminated to one part of a contradiction as to its proper termthe vision of something intelligible-it remains unquiet. Its motion has no term and it still has a cogitation and an inquisition about what it believes. Whence it is that the intellect of a believer is said to be captive 108 because it is bound by another's terms as another's, and not as its own. Whence it is that there can arise contrary motions to that which it believes, unlike the states of understanding and science.109 The gift of understanding is a light added to the natural power of the intellect, enabling it to penetrate the truths of faith. Its formal characteristic is to apprehend and to know, whether perfectly or imperfectly. To understand, as distinguished from to believe, is always with some intrinsic evidence, whether positive or negative. The fact that in this life we do not attain perfect vision is not due to any defect in the gift viewed from its proper formal aspect, but because the matter is not duly disposed so that it be seen in itself, " for we walk by faith and not by sight." 110 Since the gift moves the mind, according to the illustration of the Holy Ghost, to rightly penetrate and understand things proposed to it, it demands evidence of itself and from its formal note, and takes it as far as it can from the matter proposed to it, positive and perfect in heaven, imperfect and cryptic in life under the shadows of faith. 111 II Cor., x, 5. Q. D. de Ver., q. 14, a. 1. 110 II Co-r., v, 7. 111 Cf. T. A. Vallgornera, 0. P., Mystica Tkeologia (Turin: Marietti, 89!!, n. 559. 108 109 I, JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS Now, this evidence is just what the intellect lacks in faith. The gift penetrates the very terms from which the truths of faith are constituted and discerns between truth and falsehood, between spiritual and corporeal things. It understands that spiritual things are not such as we gather from our phantasms and that, consequently, we must estimate them much higher than we see and know them to be. The gift of understanding, therefore, brings a certitude or a quietude in matters of faith. For this reason the faith which is a fruit of the Holy Ghost corresponds to the gift of understanding; the habit or theological virtue of faith is not the fruit of the gift, but a certitude of mind and a rest in the faith is this fruit. To the gift, therefore, pertains not a mere judgment of faith and assent, but a discernment of spiritual from material, supernatural from natural, truth from error, which it can achieve evidently, by at least negative evidence. " The gift of understanding is born to perfect every intellectual perception regarding faith, whether it precedes or follows the gift." 112 The fact that the object of faith remains obscure shows that the idea of light and illumination of the gift must be modified to some degree. It is not a light in the sense of glory, or even of faith's obscure light, but a limited capacity for the illuminating instincts of the Holy Ghost. The reason for its limitation, however, is not intrinsic to it; the motion of the gift is to see and penetrate under the instinct of the Holy Spirit. The fact that only when we have received the light of glory will we see God is what limits the lengths to which the Holy Spirit can impel us. The gift of understanding precisely as understanding implies vision, perfection, clarity. It is on the part of the object and the subject while the state of faith endures that the limitation comes. We must recall here what St. Thomas has written on the relation of the gifts to the virtues. He readily admits the superiority of the gifts over the intellectual and the infused moral virtues, because of the superiority of the motive power u• Cajetan, Comm. in II-II, q. 8, a. 7. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING fl49 in the former. But in comparing the theological virtues with the gifts, the latter must cede their place of eminence because it is more noble to be united directly to God by the virtues than to be moved obediently to that end by God, just as a man who already has his million is richer than another still working and saving for it. Faith is a regulative principle which even the Holy Ghost respects, and the obscurity of faith is the check on the illumination of the gift of understanding. Given an object not too sublime for its powers, however, the gift can do a perfect job. This object is, as we have seen, the secondary objects of faith, that is, all the truths concerning creatures as directed to the first truth. Holy Scripture and the history of the church are full of truths which we can understand perfectly. Examples are not wanting among the saints. St. Augustine tells us of how he sometimes received an instinctive and clear knowledge of a passage of scripture he had read many times before without perceiving there anything special. St. Teresa in her life naively tells of how much that she wrote seemed to be coming from someone else who understood it much better than she, 118 and that often, without knowing how, she understood the most profound verses of the Psalms while saying office. Many souls ignorant of human science find in the Scriptures meanings which escape the laborious investigations of exegetes and theologians. The writings of St. Catherine of Sienna, of St. Teresa, and in our day the pious and profound reflections of Sr. Elizabeth of the Holy Trinity, a Carmelite of Dijon, on the writings of St. Paul show that these matters may be understood. We have already seen other examples of the intuitions of this gift. To summarize: The gift of understanding has the same cause as the virtue of faith, God and grace; the same objects to penetrate as the faith to believe, the divine truths; the same medium of knowledge, the formulas of revelation. It differs from faith in its mode of knowledge which is divine in the gift and human in the virtue, and in its proper and specifying act 118 Life. c. 14.. 250 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS which is to assent on the authority of God in the virtue and to apprehend and to judge on evidence of truth and falsity in the gift. " Faith works through love," says the Apostle/ 14 and throws the whole field of human actions into the lap of faith. Besides its material and formal object, faith extends to the whole field of Christian practice, regulating it and drawing from the formulas of revelations luminous rules for the conduct of life which can be found nowhere else. The intratrinitarian relations, for example, provoked the saints to realize in themselves the virtues of which the relations are the exemplars. In other words they sought to make practical, workable, operable, the abstract and conceptual expressions of the faith. 115 0 Holy Trinity I have known in Thy light, which Thou hast given me with the light of Holy Faith, the many and wonderful things Thou hast declared to me, explaining to me the path of supreme perfection, so that I may no longer serve Thee in darkness, but with light, and that I may be the mirror of a good and holy life, and arise from my miserable sins, for through them I have hitherto served Thee in darkness. 116 Wherever the faith extends, so must the Holy Ghost assist with his gift of understanding. The gift of understanding extends also to certain actions, not as though these were its principal object, but insofar as the rule of our actions is the eternal law.117 We must be careful here not merely to note the argument and conclusion and pass on, because such a course will lead to a confusion of the gifts later on. The reason for the apologetic tone in extending the gift to operations is that it stretches the nature of the gift beyond intuitive inspection and judgment of matters of faith. To say that the gift extends itself is only a manner of speaking because understanding no less than the Gal., v, 6. Diet. Thea. Oath., art. cit., col. 1743. 118 Dialogues, loc. cit. 117 Summa Theol., ·II-II, q. 8, a. 3. 114 115 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 251 other gifts is primarily a passive habit, a disposition to follow promptly the instinct of the Holy Ghost. Just what particular gift prompts us to follow this motion depends upon the term to which we are moved. It appears that even St. Thomas had difficulty in determining the distinctive role of each of the intellective gifts, so closely are they joined in charity. In his consideration of understanding he revises what he had written on the gifts in general, and yet seems to confuse wisdom and understanding, judgment and perception. 118 There is only one phase of ou:r moral actions where the gift of understanding as we know it can operate. This operation consists in penetrating and grasping the provisions of the eternal law, which exceeds our natural reason, and in discovering in our human acts those regulations. 119 Once these principles are known, it is the office of wisdom to apply and to order them to our actions. This is his express teaching when he comes to treat ex p7ofesso of the gift of wisdom. In answer to the question whether wisdom is solely speculative or also practical, he answers: . . . the superior reason is deputed to wisdom, the inferior to science. The superior .... looks to supernal, that is, divine, reasons both by considering and by counseling, considering indeed according as it contemplates divine things in themselves, counseling moreover according as through divine things it judges of human acts, directing hu'11ULn acts by divine rules. Thus therefore wisdom as it is a gift from the Holy Ghost is not only speculative but practical. And in the answer to the third objection: .. to wisdom pertains :first a contemplation of divine matters which is a vision of the principle; and afterwards to direct human acts according to divine reasons. 126 St. Thomas had a special difficulty in this whole question. It is the first of his particular considerations of the gifts, and he had nothing except general notions to use. As he progressed, 118 Ibid. 119 Ibicl., ad Sum. 120 lbicl., q. 45, a. 8. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS he could use what he had written previously on other gifts for comparison and contrast, but here some confusion is inevitable. He insists however that the gift of understanding is primarily speculative, that is, ordained to the apprehension of truth, for the sake of truth and nothing more. For the rest, we can interpret him to mean that the gift of understanding can enter into the regulation of moral actions insofar as the knowledge of the meaning of the principles- of such actions can be, but not necessarily always is, due to the gift of understanding, while the actual regulation, and so forth, is left to the other gifts and virtues. Another source of possible confusion is the fact that the faculty which the gift of understanding perfects is the superior reason, a faculty perfected also by the gift of wisdom. But St. Thomas notes that there are two acts in the intellect, perception and judgment. 121 The former is perfected by understanding and the latter by wisdom and science. A good idea of the exalted role of this gift in our life can be gathered from considering just what faculty of the mind it perfects. The superior reason is, for St. Thomas, and before him for Augustine and Dionysius, that part of the intellect which contemplates the things of God. It is not that the intellect, being a simple, immaterial faculty, has parts, but that it has different relations to various objects giving it different acts which only appear to proceed from different faculties. The superior and inferior reason are distinguished thus: There are certain natures superior to a rational soul, others inferior. Since, moreover, everything understood is after the manner of the one understanding, the knowledge of superior things in the soul is inferior to the things themselves; but of inferior things, the knowledge of them is superior because in being known they have a more noble state of being than in themselves; and so there is a different relationship to both, and different offices. For according as it looks to superior natures, either contemplating their truth and nature absolutely, or drawing from them a reason and a quasi-exemplar of action, the reason is called superior reason; according as it looks 111 Ibid., a. !il, ad Sum. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING to inferior things either to be scrutinized in contemplation or to be disposed through action, it is called inferior reason. Each object, superior and inferior, however, is apprehended by the human soul according to the common note of intelligibility; the superior, as it is immaterial in itself, the inferior according as it is stripped from matter by the act of the active intellect. 122 And to show its dignity: . . among creatures such is the order that first are the angels and secondly the rational soul. Because the rational soul is joined to a body, the knowledge due it according to its own proper order is a knowledge which proceeds from sensible to intelligible things, and does not arrive at a knowledge of truth, except by a previous inquisition. Its knowledge, therefore, is called rational, but because the angel is purely incorporeal, not united to a body, the knowledge due his nature is truth apprehended without inquisition. Because of this he is called an intellectual nature. It is fitting, moreover, that in the human soul which is configured to the angels in the order of creatures, there be some sort of participation of intellectual power by which it apprehend some truth without inquisition, just as naturally known first principles are apprehended in speculative and practical matters . . . This power is conveniently called the spark for as a spark is a bit of light flying up from a fire, so this power is some small participation of intellectuality, in comparison to the intellectuality of the angels. 128 From the supreme part of rational nature, St. Thomas turns next to the supreme part of super-nature, grace and charity. IV. THE GIFT AND GRACE St. Thomas now comes to consider the relation of sanctifying grace and the light of understanding. He treats the questions from two angles, deciding in the fourth article that all who are in the state of grace have the gift of understanding, and then in the :fifth 124 because of the fact that faith is in those without grace, he further determines that only those in grace have the gift. Q. D. de Ver., q. 15, II Sent., d. XXXIX, q. 3, a. 1. 12 • Summa Theol., IT-IT, q. 8, a. 4 et 5. 122 123 254 JOSEPH IGNATIDS MCGUINESS By the infusion of sanctifying grace into the soul, the human will is rightly directed to the good. But because of the subordination of the will to the intellect, to be rightly directed to anything the will must first know it, or at least, of it. Therefore, the presence of grace requires some knowledge of the end, but as Cajetan, commenting on this article, immediately asks, why is not faith sufficient to supply that knowledge ? It is because of its imperfection which affects charity, as St. Thomas insinuates by bringing charity into the question in the very next line. If you ask why cannot faith informed by charity furnish enough knowledge, in answer Cajetan cites faith's imperfect participation in the divine lightSince an inferior participates to a lesser degree what is found in a superior, the light of faith, in bringing about the proper estimation of things in an intellect moved by a perfect will, is, as it were, intensified by the intensified light of the gift. A sign of this is that informed faith differs from formless faith, not on the part of the intellect, but on the part of the will. Since, then, formless faith lack the proper estimation of things which is found with informed faith, and this proper estimation belongs to the intellect, it is evident that this other light, that is of the gift of understanding, is added to the light of faith. 125 Whence it becomes apparent that charity is of great importance in this question. It is the medium of the demonstration that properly concerns the gift, for as St. Thomas says: Just as the Holy Ghost through the gift of charity orders the will of man in order that it be directly moved to some supernatural good, so also He illumines the mind of man that he might know some supernatural truth, to which the right will should tend. Therefore, just as charity is in all in the state of grace, so too is the The gifts are all infused into the soul at the same time as sanctifying grace, as St. Thomas will later teach. 127 Besides, as Maritain says: 125 126 Cajetan, Comm. in II-II, q. 8, a. 4. Summa Theol., II-II, q. 8, a. 4. Ibid., ill, q. 62, a. 2; q. 69, a. 4. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 255 Grace confers on us supernaturally the radical power of grasping the Infinite as object of our intellect; it gives us a new source of spiritual activity which has for its proper and specific object the Divine Essence seen in itself. By the vision to which grace proportions us radically, the creature becomes true God Himself, not substantially, but in the sense that it achieves that immaterial union which comes of the act of understanding. 128 By grace and the theological virtues God is rendered personally present to the soul. Even with the virtues of faith, hope, and charity, man is still a defective and at times impotent agent in this new order, and so God comes personally to elevate and direct him to his proper place. God's suave and harmonious way of doing things has placed in man qualities which dispose him to receive and to correspond with His motion, and which are proportionate to the virtues which rendered God present to the soul and, as it were, gave Him the opportunity for working it it. These are the gifts of the Holy Ghost. 129 Our charity renders us desirous of knowing God as He is, but this insistent curiosity is unable to tear aside the veils which prevent us from knowing Him immediately. Charity to be perfect, to be efficacious for salvation, requires knowledge, because the will is so constituted that if it is to wish well and correctly its object must be clearly seen and so presented to it. But it is not the nature of faith to know clearly. The knowledge that comes to us from the Church, Holy Scripture, the Fathers and Doctors of the Church is inadequate to translate to us the life of an Infinite Being with transcendent and ineffable perfections. Our intelligence, far from pentrating at first sight the affirmations of the faith, falls back in incomprehension. To think of God and to represent to ourselves what He is in Himself, we must try with great effort to transpose to Him the perfections of created realities and, as we have seen, we are prone to fall into material, temporal, and human notions. 130 128 Quoted by B. L., "Philosophie et experience mystique," in La Vie Spirituelle, Mai, 1926 (Suppl.), p. 167. uo T. Pegues, 0. P., Commootaire de la Somme Tkeologique (Toulouse: 1907-81), IX, 844. uo H. 0. Noble, 0. P., "Les dons du Saint-Esprit auxiliaires des vertus morales," in La Vie Spirituelle, XVI (1927), it6. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS The Holy Ghost, already in us by charity, supplies for the deficiencies of our knowledge, and fills our need for more knowledge by elevating our minds to new discernments and new judgments in the intellectual gifts. Hence it is the demands of charity, but imperfectly met by faith, that are the raison d'etre of the intellectual gifts. This is the meaning of St. Thomas here and accords with his teaching that the gifts are so joined together in charity, that no one can have charity without them and no one without charity can have them. 181 So, in a special sense, understanding is a light super-added by grace. The presence and operations of the gifts seem to be closely connected with foreknowledge and predestination, sufficient and efficacious grace. At the time when sanctifying grace is infused into the soul, the seven gifts of the Holy Ghost are also infused to constitute a perfect super-natural organism ready to be moved by the Holy Ghost in a manner beyond all human consideration. The Holy Ghost working freely activates His gifts in some souls and leaves them dormant in others," for the Spirit breatheth where He will," as our Lord said. 132 His instinct causes in us an action which is at once free, and therefore meritorious and infallible. That is to say, under His impulse we shall elicit acts which lead to salvation, and so the predestined are infallibly led to their goal. Faith, though it is a light making us see what we are to believe and uniting us to God in knowledge, is, nevertheless, in a deficient human faculty. The cogitation of which we spoke is unsatisfied, and its contrary motions may elude the rule of the will, so causing even the will to falter in its adhesion to God in love. Once the will is shaken, the other obstacles which are always present in man can gain strength and overthrow the subordination of man to God; sin with the loss of grace is the result. Hence, to heal the deficiencies in the union of the mind to God in faith, and in a sense, to insure that the actions of this mind will procure its salvation, the Holy Ghost must operate in that soul by the light of understanding, or it is lost. "Hence," 181 Summa Theol., 1-11, q. 66, a. 8. 18 " John, iii, 8. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 257 as St. Thomas says, " the gift never withdraws from the saints in things necessary to salvation." 133 As Billot pithily puts it: ... from the fact that habitual grace is not only necessary that man in the present state avoid sin, but also sufficient that he operate meritoriously, it does not in the least follow that it is sufficient to avoid sin and to persevere in justice once attained through the whole time of this laborious way . . . and the principal reason is that integrity of nature is not restored by habitual grace . . . Therefore as the Angelic doctor teaches a man in grace needs the aid of actual grace that he be moved by God to act rightly, because of the condition of the state of human nature. There remains a certain obscurity of ignorance in the intellect; we cannot fully know that which is expedient for us, "for the thoughts of mortal men are fearful, and our counsels uncertain." Therefore it is necessary that we be directed and protected by God who knows all and can do all things, which aid is not added to each and every act leading to salvation, but consists in divine instincts by which the mind is illustrated according to inborn needs and the various opportunities or circumstances. 18 ' The fifth article 135 is closely connected with this doctrine and might be said to be, next to the first, the most important article in the whole question. We have seen that the gift of q.nderstanding is an habitual disposition to receive the illumination of the Holy Ghost; that it is an aid to faith, giving negative evidence about the primary object and positive perfect evidence about secondary objects; that it extends its light to the principles of the moral sphere; that it is in all those in sanctifying grace; and now we have indicated the most profound and essential quality of the gift, its proper act in the strictest sense, which distinguishes it from all other illuminations, inspirations and instincts of the Holy Ghost. Unless the human intellect be moved to this that it have a right estimation of the end, it has not yet received the gift of understanding however much of the preambles it may know from the illumination of the Holy Ghost. 186 Summa Theol., 11-11, q. 8, a. 4, ad Sum. Billot, op. cit., p. 177. 185 Summa Theol., 11-11, q. 8, a. 5. 188 134 186Jbid. 6 258 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS Because of the pecularity of faith that makes it independent of charity and grace to the extent that it can be present without them, though in an imperfect manner, 137 the question naturally arises whether the gift of understanding can remain without them too. Since its object, the propositions of faith, remains in the graceless soul, why cannot the gift remain too. Just because all who have grace have the gift, it does not follow precisely that aU who have the gift have grace. The principle which is used to establish the negative answer is the one we have just quoted, that is, unless man have a right estimation of his end, he has not the gift, nor sanctifying grace either; therefore without grace there is no gift. The argument is somewhat involved, and the conclusion is the result of two different sets of reasoning. It is the office of the gift to perfect the soul by rendering it well disposed and easily moveable under the motions of the Holy Spirit; the light of grace which renders the soul movable to know is called the gift of understanding. But when this potentiality to motion is actually moved, just any motion is not sufficient; it must have a particular term to which it is directed. Its final cause is the apprehension of truth; its efficient cause, the Holy Ghost, moves it according to its formal cause, illumination, towards a term which will best serve grace and charity and perfect the soul, and this term is a right apprehension of truth which results in a right estimation of the end, i. e., beatitude with God. It is only a notion which proceeds according to all these causes that can be properly called the operation of the gift of understanding. A right estimation, therefore, is that to which the Holy Ghost most properly moves us in this gift. The perfection of the soul is also the work of sanctifying grace, inasmuch as grace places man in an order in which he can attain the end in which his ultimate perfection consists, the vision of God. In the natural order, our faculties are only proportionable to our last end, but by grace they are propor1 "7 Cone. Trid., sess. 6, can. 28. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 259 tioned to it. Grace so perfects man that while he has it he cannot err concerning his true end; he always has a right estimation of it. Once he errs, he loses grace, and so this right estimation is only in those who are in grace. St. Thomas, joining these ideas by means of this right estimation of the end which both demand, shows that without sanctifying grace, the gift is lacking. The objections m contain applications of the distinctive note of understanding found in the article. The nature of the specific action of the Holy Ghost in this gift leads almost inevitably to a comparison of the illumination which is the gift of understanding and the illumination which is prophecy. St. Thomas declares briefly that the illumination in prophecy is directed to the matters which were revealed to the prophet, while in the gift of understanding it is directed to a right estimation of the end. Prophecy is not a habit, but a light given in a transient manner to the prophet who acts on principles he does not see and, therefore, he does not need a firm and permanent habit to grasp them. He intends to form a vision either intellectual or imaginary, with certitude, although he has not in himself as clearly seen, the principle whence these visions are derived. Therefore it is :fitting that there be communicated to him from the outside a light by which the things he is to prophesy are manifested outside their principle. 189 The gift, however, and the motion of the Holy Ghost are not given to form some vision whether intellectual or imaginary about the things of faith, but to apprehend and to judge of the credibility and convenience of propositions which are in us habitually through faith. We know that these mysteries are worthy of belief and that any reason for denying them is erroneous, according to the right estimation of our end to which the Holy Ghost moves us. Prophecy is not regulated by faith and is found in infidels and those not in grace; 140 the gift is regulated by principles known under faith, although excited, 188 18 Summa Theol., II-II, q. 8, a. 5, ad Sum. ° Cf. John of St. Thomas, op. cit., disp. XVIII, a. 2. 100 Summa Theol., II-II, q. 172, a. 4. JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS known, and disposed by a special instinct, and is necessary to salvation; therefore it is habitually and permanently given, just as is faith and charity. In the answer to the third objection, 141 we have the final word on the distinction between faith and the gift of understanding. To faith it pertains to assent solely to principles, to the gift to penetrate them. This is most formal in the two, because pure and precise assent without any discussion, or investigation, or understanding of the intrinsic notes of the object pertains to faith. All the interior things of the object remain so hidden to it that only by reason of extrinsic testimony does it adhere or assent to the proposition of truth, and so it rests in assent. The gift tries to enter into, to penetrate to the interior of a thing, as when the Blessed Virgin asked the angel, " How shall this thing be ? " 142 There is no hestitation or doubt here, but the gift is striving for a fuller interior knowledge of mystery, to the extent possible in this life. Therefore, since they proceed from distinct motives and formal reasons, there are distinct habits of faith and understanding. V. THE EssENCE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING The phrase right estimation in all this discussion is liable to confuse a casual reader. In the first place, estimation implies not only judgment, but also a series of judgments wherein one thing is weighed against another, prices compared and finally a price put upon something; for example, it is the essence of charity to estimate its object as of great price. 143 We have denied any sort of judgment to the gift beyond a simple assent to truth. How then is this estimation attained ? Here is the whole point of not only the gift of understanding but of the other gifts as well. The man in whom the gifts are operating acts upon knowledge that is not attained by study, or by reasoning, or by any human operation. It is knowledge due 141 Ibid., II-II, q. 8, a. 5, ad Sum. 1 .. Luke, i, 84. tu Summa Theol., I-II, q. a. 8. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 261 entirely to the Holy Ghost who moves man to attain this true estimate of his end with the simplicity with which natural reason attains first principles. Man is moved to apprehend the truth concerning his end; he sees the terms in which it is expressed. It is one thing to say that one cannot have a right estimation without the gift of understanding and another to say that one cannot have the gift of understanding without right estimation. The first statement places the gift as a necessary companion of right estimation, even though it does not immediately appear that the gift is the sole cause of the right estimation, unless by further explanation. The second statement places the estimation before the gift, as if to say that the gift is the result of the estimation. Many have so interpreted the way St. Thomas expresses their relation. But there is no more necessary connection between understanding and estimation in the second statement than there is in the first. The words only say that in any subject where the gift is found there will also be a right estimation. The connection between them is not therein expressed. St. Thomas does however give an explanation further on. The motion of the Holy Ghost aids man to apprehend the truth about his end. Therefore, unless the mind be so illumined in apprehending truth that, as a result, it is moved to have a right estimation of the end, it is not precisely the gift of understanding. In other words, understanding, whenever present, produces this effect, right estimation, as well as others like the clear knowledge of particular truths. It is by accepting the statement, " no gift without right estimation," to mean that the estimation is the cause of the gift, and by joining it with the close relationship to charity that many theologians explain the act of the gift. Vallgornera, for instance, says: The gift of understanding does not sharpen nor perfect the mind as a result of study and disputation, and, as it were, metaphysically, but from a certain connaturality and union with divine things through charity. There are two ways we can have a knowledge of and judge of a thing; one way through investigation and study, JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS the other through experience and a connaturality with it. Just as a philosopher judges of charity in one way from his study of ethics and a discussion of the virtues, while a temperate man judges otherwise, that is from its connaturality to his continence and chastity, in like manner we can have a knowledge and judgment of supernatural and spiritual things either from study and discussion about those things, namely the precise illustration of the truth, or from a certain connaturality and affection, or experience of divine things, as Dionysius said of Hierotheus that he was not only learning but experiencing divine things. One experiences divine things when his affection is moved by the Holy Ghost in such a way that is above that which human modes and rules can measure; for the fact that someone operates from obedience and subjection to the motion of another makes him a patient or a recipient because he is obedient and subject. This is the doctrine of St. Thomas when he says that unless the human intellect be moved by the Holy Ghost to this, that it have a right estimation of the end, it has not yet acquired the gift of understanding, however much it understands the preambles to the faith from the illumination of the Holy Spirit. (Summa Theol., II-II, q. 8, a. 5.). Only the one who does not err about the end has a right estimation of it; he clings to it as the best possible good. This estimation is in only those having sanctifying grace, just as in moral matters a man has a right estimation of the end through the habit of virtue. Therefore the gifts which pertain to the intellect perfect it mystically, that is, affectively and by reason of a certain experimental knowledge and judgment of divine things; this experimental knowledge cannot stand without affection and taste by which divine things are united to us and quasiconnaturalized. The reason is that we cannot philosophize about these gifts except as is given in Scripture, which founds these gifts in some sort of affection and taste, as "Taste and see." (Ps., xxxiii, 9); "A new name written, which no man knoweth but he that receiveth it." (Apoc., ii, 17); "A good to all that do it." (Ps., ex, 10); and" ... the spirit of the Lord will rest upon him." (Is., xi, 2) . Therefore these cognitions, those of the gifts, are founded in the spirit of affection, not in any way whatever, but resting upon and united with us .... 144 This is the substance of all that John of St. Thomas says with much more fire and rhetoric, and following him, most of 1u Vallgornera, op. cit., n. 560. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING the French theologians, Thomas says, especially Gardeil. 145 268 John of St. Faith alone and naked leaves us in obscurity, and men therefore become bored and cannot persevere in contemplation of faith alone; they wander, they fall asleep, are bored because faith alone does not contemplate but blindly assents, and the heavens seem more overcast than opened . . . . From this we gather that it is necessary for the soul to break forth from the foggy mist of faith, and run to meet God through the illumination of the gifts of the Holy Spirit by which the mind, as if in golden vestments, is girt about with various colors, i. e., a multitude of spiritual sensations, and multiple knowledge of divine things. But because in this life faith cannot be illumined and shine on the part of the object, since it is always based on testimony . . . it remains for the soul captive in the bonds of faith to be illuminated by the flames of love. Therefore it is fitting that the gifts of wisdom, understanding, and knowledge proceed from love, be based on it, that they might dissolve the mists of faith. 146 He proceeds then to apply to understanding what St. Thomas expressly teaches of wisdom, and repeatedly says of understanding-that: the mind is illumined about divine things according as they are sensed within us and according to a connaturality and a certain affective union pertaining to the experience of divine things. 147 It is a very beautiful and makes excellent reading. It is based in part on the sound teaching of St. Thomas on the connection of the gifts and the nature of the gift of wisdom, but a doubt arises: is it the mind of St. Thomas on the gift of understanding? We are reminded of a remark of Father Ramirez," One must watch to see whether everything in John of St. Thomas is of St. Thomas, or whether there is not also something only of John." 148 To say that the gift of understanding penetrates divine 146 Cf. art. cit., in Diet. Theo. Catk. Also: La de l'OifTI,e et l'expirience mystique (Paris:. 1927)' n, 221. 1 •• John of St. Thomas, op. cit., a. 1. 101 Ibid., a. 8. 148 "i.Que es un Tomista?" in Ciencia Tomista, XXVII (1928), 188. 264 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS truths from a savory taste for them that is connatural seems to contravene the Aristotelian-Thomistic principle: nothing can be willed which is not first known. Further, it is not expressly taught by St. Thomas; indeed, it does violence to what he teaches not only here in the fourth and fifth articles but in the first article and in the Sentences. Finally, not only it is unsupported by his manner of speaking-always applying light and illumination to understanding, and to understanding alone among the gifts-but it contradicts what he expressly said in the Sentences. The relation of will to intellect, of love to knowledge is one of the corner-stones of the whole edifice of St. Thomas' teaching. Absolutely speaking, the will is inferior to and subject to the intellect because "the object of the intellect is the very reason of the appetible good; appetible good whose ratio is in the intellect, is the object of the will." 149 It is only in a particular consideration where the object of the intellect and will is of a higher order than they, that in willing the object the will becomes ennobled, while the intellect in knowing remains the same, whence the love of God is better than knowledge of Himr in this life. But the fact remains that were God not presented to the will by the intellect as a desirable good, He would not be loved. To say therefore that the love which already possesses a thing moves the intellect in some way to know it, is to invert the natural order of the two faculties. To say that we apprehend divine truths from an innate taste which comes from their possession by love is an implausible paradox. To apprehend something in the sense in which it is applied to the gift of understanding is to progress from a state of privation of truth to the state of possession. Just as no one gives what he has not, so no one receives what he already has. If divine truth is already present and sensed, it cannot be acquired by that sense. It is of course quite otherwise with the gift of wisdom whose acts are the application of knowledge already acquired to other things. Its knowledge is affective and not acquired by any uo Summa Theol., I, q. S!l, a. 8. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 265 study or reasoning, and the Holy Ghost moves it to apply this knowledge to divine and by extension to human things. If it is objected that faith supplies a sufficient knowledge for charity to start, and that charity outstrips faith in attaining union with God, whence it commands the gifts to search further, the doctrine of the fourth article seems vitiated. The whole argument rested on the one point that because charity needed knowledge with a more perfect light than faith, the gift of understanding was infused to feed charity, not as a consequent to charity, but in the words of St. Thomas, ". . . the will cannot be rightly ordained to good, unless there preexist some knowledge of the truth." The Holy Spirit " illustrates the mind to know supernatural truth to which the right will should tend." This can hardly be interpreted to mean that the will ordains the intellect to know the truth which it possesses. It would denote a grave defect in the order of his work, if St. Thomas were to treat of the formal aspect of a gift-as this connatural taste is for John of St. Thomas- 15 not where he is treating specifically of that gift, but thirty-five questions later, under the heading of another gift and expressly applied to that other gift. 1) Wisdom denotes a certain rectitude of judgment according to the eternal law. Now rectitude of judgment is twofold: first, on account of perfect use of reason, secondly, on account of a certain connaturality with the matter about which one has to judge. Thus, about matters of chastity, a man after inquiring with his reason forms a right judgment, if he has learnt the science of morals, while he who has the habit of chastity judges of such matters by a kind of connaturality. Accordingly it belongs to the wisdom which is an intellectual virtue to pronounce right judgment about divine things after reason has made its inquiry, but it belongs to wisdom as a gift of the Holy Ghost to judge aright about them on account of connaturality with them: thus Dionysius says that Hierotheus is perfect in divine things for he not only learns, but is patient of divine things. Now this sympathy or connaturality for divine things is the result of charity, which unites us to God, according to " He who is joined 160 Gardeil, La SfJructure de l'ame, II, 9!21. 266 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS to the Lord, is one spirit." (I Cor., vi, 17.) Consequently wisdom which is the gift, has its cause in the will, which cause is charity, but it has its essence in the intellect, whose act is to judge aright. 151 Are not these the very words which John of St. Thomas, without any warrant, applies to the gift of understanding? Even if this connaturality were common to both gifts, it seems more logical to speak of it in connection with the first, and then refer back to it, if necessary. Yet the only thing in common which St. Thomas mentions each time in its proper order, is charity, applying his general doctrine to each gift. This notion of affective union is to the notion of the gift of wisdom what the notion of light and illumination is to the gift of understanding. In the first article of this question the general notion of what this gift is like is laid down, and likewise in the forty-fifth question. Then, in the second article of both questions, this general notion is developed and limited by comparing it with the virtue to which it is attached, faith and understanding, charity and wisdom. Just as faith rules and measures the light of understanding, so charity rules and measures wisdom by giving it the experience for divine things through which it judges. Is it too much to expect that if this divine experience were also the foundation of understanding there would be some mention of the fact, even parenthetically, in either tract? The only mention of understanding is in one of the objections which tries to show that wisdom is superfluous. The answer is that they have different acts, that is, understanding perceives and wisdom judges-again that contrast between motion toward knowledge and motion away from knowledge already gained and toward other things. St. Thomas consistently speaks of wisdom as a judgment, the application of something known to something else, but he always speaks of understanding as a light, the Holy Spirit illuminating the mind. Nor does he ever interchange the terms. Now here in the tract on the gift of wisdom is there any mention of illumination except in relation to understanding and nowhere 161 Summa Theol.• ll-ll. q. 45, a. !!. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 267 in the tract of the gift of understanding is there a mention of connatural experimental taste. Light, illumination, illustration, are the terms always applied to understanding-'" supernatural light, ... the light superadded is to supernatural things, as the natural light to first principles." 152 " Understanding illumines the mind concerning things learned"; 153 "so also the Holy Ghost illumines the mind .... 154 " Intellectual light of grace is called the gift of understanding ... not yet attained the gift, no matter how much from the illumination of the Holy Ghost ... ; ... it is not illustration of the mind concerning a right estimation." 155 We have in the commentary on the Sentences certain expressions which reveal that here at least St. Thomas did not agree that taste enters into the gift of understanding. Because of the order of the master of the Sentences, wisdom is treated first and is followed by understanding. Note that his doctrine on wisdom has not been changed in the Summa. . . . the gift of wisdom has an eminence of knowledge through a certain union with divine things with which we are not united except through love, as he who adheres to God is one spirit with Him. . . . Wisdom presupposes dilection (the act of charity) as a principle and so is in the affection, but as to its essence it is in knowledge; whence its act here and hereafter seems to be to contemplate divine things, and then through them to judge of others, not only in speculative, but also in practical matters, in which judgment is taken from the end, and therefore against wisdom is folly which implies an error about the end. 156 Thus is, briefly and beautifully expressed, the nature of the gift of wisdom. Now, the next question is to consider understanding, and he says, as we have seen, that it is the gift which illumines the mind about things heard after the manner of first principles. Then the objection is raised that wisdom experiences delight about divine things, but so does understanding; therefore they are not distinct. He answers that Ibid., q. 8, a. 1. Ibid., a. 2. 154 Ibid., a. 4. 162 163 Ibid., a. 5. ••• III Sent., d. XXXV, q. S, a. 2, qt. 3. 155 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS any delight in understanding is a natural one caused by the congruity of the operation to the faculty operating; not however from a love of those things concerning which the operation is, as in wisdom. His general comparison of the two is this: Understanding names a simple apprehension; but wisdom is a sort of fullness of certitude to judge about what is apprehended, and therefore understanding pertains to the way of invention and wisdom to the way of judgment. But because judgment cannot be concerning things apprehended except through supreme causes, to which the wise man is united in mind, which union to divine things is through love; therefore, wisdom is principally concerned with divine things and has in them a delight caused by dilection. Understanding on the other hand is indifferent concerning all apprehended spiritual things, and in itself it implies, no delight from the love of the things apprehended. 157 For St. Thomas, then, however much the gift of wisdom may involve an experimental taste of the divine, the gift of understanding has none of it, except perhaps as a secondary effect of its operation. Understanding is, rather, a disposition by which man, under the illumination of the Holy Ghost, penetrates the propositions of faith and judges of their truth. It is interesting to note what St. Albert taught on this matter of the essential characteristic of understanding. Even though he was St. Thomas' best loved teacher, it would be folly to argue that since he taught Thomas and his doctrine is thus and so, therefore it is that of St. Thomas too. We know of too many divergencies in their thought to permit so groundless an argument. In this case, St. Thomas seems to agree with the simple forceful language of his saintly master. St. Albert, after exposing the nature of the gifts, raises the objection that on the authority of St. Augustine it seems that the office of the gift is to know God and to love and embrace Him, and therefore it is no different from wisdom. The answer is that although it has charity as a mover inasmuch as charity is the general mover in every good, nevertheless, it differs from wisdom, 167 Ibid. THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 269 because wisdom is in the taste (gustus) of goodness, as is often said, but understanding is in the contemplation of truth alone. 158 In his Compendium of Theology, he says, Wisdom and understanding differ because . . . by understanding God is known through illumination of things heard in Holy Scripture; by wisdom He is known by experiment. Likewise, through understanding we know God; by wisdom we taste his sweetness ... 1119 The two great masters then, are agreed on this, at least, that the knowledge of the gift of understanding is not affective but directly caused by the illumination of the Holy Ghost. VI. UNDERSTANDING DISTINCT FROM OTHER GIFTS Enough has been said about the objects and acts of the gift of understanding to permit a discussion of its distinction from the other gifts of the Holy Ghost. Briefly the gifts are seven in number: wisdom, a right judgment of divine things according to a certain connaturality with them; 160 understanding, a penetration and a grasp of the things to be believed; 161 knowledge, a certain judgment about revealed truths; 162 counsel, the immediate direction of God about those acts which lead to salvation; 168 fortitude, a firmness to overcome all obstacles and dangers in finishing the work we have begun; 164 piety, the filial affection for God; 165 and fear of the Lord, a reverence and subjection to God. 166 These are the seven habits which perfect all the faculties of the soul by making them sensitive and docile to the special inspirations of the Holy Ghost. Let us recall what was said in the introduction about St. Thomas' norms for distinguishing habits. There are three ways: by their active Ill Sent., d. XXXV, a. 10, ad 4um. Opera Omnia, XXVIII, 656. Compendium Theologicae Veritatis, lib. V, c. 46. This work has been attributed to Hugh of Strassburg, a disciple of Albert. 160 Summa Theol., 11-II, q. 45, aa. 3 and 4. '"'Ibid., q. 8, a. 2, Sed Contra; a. 6. '"'Ibid., q. 139, a. 1. 165 Ibid., q. U1, a. I. ••• Ibid., q. 9, a. 1. 100 Ibid., q. 19, a. 9. 163 Ibid., q. 52, a. 1. 158 169 270 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS principles, by the subjects of inherence, and by their formal objects. 167 Now, obviously, the active principle is the same in all the gifts-the Holy Ghost. So, only the two remaining ways will avail us here. St. Thomas proceeds to apply the second rule and so separates understanding from fortitude, piety, and fear of the Lord, because they by definition pertain to the appetitive faculties of our nature. In view of the difficulty to come, he cannot resist a human remark. This is manifest, says he, " but the difference of this gift from the other three which perfect the cognoscitive power is not so manifest." 168 There were some who sought to further distinguish the intellectual gifts according as they perfected the speculative or the practical part of man's intellect, and among them, St. Thomas himself was to be found for a time. 1il 9 But, meditation on the extensive part that faith plays in our lives led him to change his teaching so as to permit understanding to be practical 170 in a sense, and knowledge to be speculative. 171 The basis then for the correct distinction of the intellectual gifts, will be, not their subject, but their formal objects which are found in the supernatural knowledge of faith. Faith is, after all, the ordinary means of knowing God in this life. Special revelations and divine touches are not for all, but only for those whom God chooses to lead in this extraordinary way. The gifts are common to all the just, and so according as they assist and perfect different aspects of faith will the gifts be distinguished. St. Thomas recapitulates the essentials of faith: that it is an assent to things not seen, but heard; 172 that it is principally concerned with God as first Truth; 173 secondarily with certain creatures; 174 and finally, that it extends to the direction of human works 175 according to the Apostle's " Faith worketh by charity." 176 Ibid., I-II, q. 54, a. q. 18, a. Ibid., II-II. q. 8, a. 5. 169 Ibid., I-II, q. 68, a. 4. 170 Ibid., II-II, q. 8, a. 8. 171 Ibid., q. 9, a. 8. Ibid., q. 1, a. 4. Ibid., a. 1. 1 .. Ibid. 175 Ibid., q. 4, a. ad Sum. 176 Gal., v, 6. 167 1 .. 168 178 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 271 On the part of the things proposed to faith for belief, two things are required from us; :first, that these things be penetrated or grasped by the intellect, and this pertains to the gift of understanding; secondly, it is necessary that man should judge these things aright, that he should consider these things to be embraced and their opposites avoided. This judgment, when it concerns divine things, belongs to the gift of wisdom; if concerned with created things, it pertains to the gift of knowledge; :finally,if applied to individual actions, it comes under the gift of counsel.177 Therefore to each essential point of faith, there is attached a special gift. Had we not noted and discussed them, the problems raised by having understanding direct human affairs and produce a right estimation would make the distinction of the gifts here not so manifest. But, to repeat, understanding extends only secondarily to human affairs, inasmuch as it furnishes a grasp of the supernatural principles and laws governing them, the actual regulation of which is left to wisdom and counsel. Understanding produces a right estimation, as Cajetan says: because this estimation, and any other judgment, as regards perception, looks to the gift of understanding; as regards judgment it looks to wisdom or knowledge or counsel, just as assent looks to faith. 178 In the answer to the first objection, St. Thomas gives another way of distinguishing the gifts among themselves which was very common in his time-according to the vices which they opposed. This is the method of St. Gregory, and after him of some of the early Scholastics. The vice which is opposed to understanding is dullness, the opposite of sharpness. An intellect is said to be sharp when it is able to penetrate to the heart of things proposed to it. This is another similitude drawn from the sensible order. The eye is said to be sharp when it sees its object at a distance or is able to penetrate the smallest details. So it is with the intellect. Its object is, in a way, distant from it; it must know essences· through the medium of properties, and causes through their effects. 177 Summa Tkeol., 11-11, q. 8, a. 6. ••• Comm. in II-II, q. 8, a. 6. 272 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS Consequently, a man is said to have an acute sense in connection with his understanding if, as soon as he apprehends a property or effect of a thing, he understands the nature of the thing itself, and if he can succeed in perceiving its slightest details; whereas a man is said to have a dull sense ... if he cannot arrive at knowing the truth about a thing without many explanations; in which case, he is unable to obtain a perfect perception of everything pertaining to thct nature of that thing. 179 Folly is a perverse judgment about the common goal of life, and is opposed to wisdom. Ignorance is a particular defect, and is opposed to knowledge. Precipitancy is action without sufficient deliberation, and is opposed to counsel. Here we have the natures of the various gifts well marked out by contrast, and the penetration of understanding emphasized. A difficulty crops up again concerning faith. In the natural order, the one habit of intellect suffices to apprehend first principles and to assent to them, therefore in the supernatural order, since the articles of faith are its first principles no faith alone is sufficient to penetrate and assent, and therefore the -habit is superfluous. We deny the parity. The habit of intellect is a perfect participation of the natural iight of reason, and is able to do both, but faith is an imperfect participation of divine light, and cannot do both without divine aid. 181 It belongs to faith to assent to that knowledge conferred by grace, but it belongs to understanding to pierce in a supra-human way, the things that are to be believed. If the gift of understanding is both speculative and practical, it seems common to all the gifts, and therefore is not really distinct from them. The answer is that, while it is related to both speculative and practical knowledge, it formally looks to apprehension in them and not to judgment. But, we have already said that there is also a judgment in understanding, and so the difficulty stands. The judgment in understanding, however, is a discerning judgment which penetrates truth by separating it from error and falsehood, but the judgment in the 100 Summa Theol., II-11, q. 15, a. 2. Ibid., q. I, a. 7. 181 Cf. Sylvius, Oo:mm. in 11-11, q. 8. 180 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING other gifts is an analytic sort of thing resolving things by their causes, and it is this analytic judgment that St. Thomas denies to understanding. In judging things, we can proceed in two ways; first, by a resolutive or analytic judgment, when we judge of things through their causes or their effects, by resolving and reasoning upon them; the other way, by a simple discretive judgment, by which we judge that this is not that, or is not as that is, but has a different relation to that, which can be done through some comparison or reflection as does the intellect, or in a simple way as the senses, discern sounds and colors, etc. The gift of wisdom has a judgment concerning spiritual and supernatural things in a resolutive and analytical fashion through their highest causes, i.e., through an intimate union with God; knowledge, moreover, through inferior causes or effects, inasmuch as it considers creatures-faith judges an assent neither through causes or effects, but from the naked testimony of the teller. The gift of understanding judges neither by resolving nor by reasoning about supernatural truths from causes and by causes, but from a certain illumination of the Holy Spirit it discerns spiritual from corporeal things, at least in a negative way, and it separates from error things to be believed as true. For this judgment the evidence of argument is not required, because it does not proceed through causes or effects;. nor is there required a resolution of conclusions into their principles, because the gift like the habit of first principles is concerned with principles. It forms this judgment from the better and more acute penetration of the terms from which these truths are composed and their convenience among themselves and the inconvenience of errors. In natural things there are certain principles known to all and others known only to the wise because their terms are not easily penetrated by all, but only by the more acute, as, e. g., that spiritual substances are not in place, and that there are not many gods, because the perception and penetration of these terms depends on a comparison and collation with their opposites. Yet, nevertheless, the judgment of these principles is not made through collation and arguments, but from a pene7 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS tration of the terms brought about by comparison and collation. In like manner, by the impulse and illustration of the Holy Spirit the gift sharpens and elevates the mind to seize and penetrate the terms by which supernatural truths of faith are proposed, and from such penetration judges those truths to be believed, and rests in them. To the objection which is made from the words of St. Thomas 182 according to which wisdom and knowledge exclude argument, and therefore the gift of understanding cannot differ from them according as it is discretive and they discursive, John of St. Thomas replies, Admitted that the gifts of wisdom and knowledge are not discursive, there remains a djfl'erence between wisdom and understanding, because understanding is discursive neither on the part of the thing known nor on the part of the way of knowing, i. e., the knower, because it proceeds about principles by penetrating and apprehending them from a knowledge of the terms, and so the things known are not subject to argument, from the manner of knowledge it does not proceed fu a resolving manner, but by a simple judgment apprehends the truth. But wisdom.and knowledge proceed in aresolving manner at least on the part of the things known, because they proceed from causes, giving an account of the truth they know; although on the part of the knower they proceed without arguments-just as the angels have resolutive knowledge, inasmuch as on the part of the object they know things through their causes, although on the part of the knower they do not form arguments from many acts but by one act know cause and e:ffect.188 So, the gift of understanding remains distinct from all the others because it apprehends, grasps, and judges of divine truths, after the manner of first Speaking of the vices opposed to the gift/ 84 St. Thomas also mentions blindness of mind, and indicates there the dispositions and, indirectly, the circumstances which are most propitious for the operation of this gift. Blindness of mind is a privation of the principle of intellectual vision which is threefold: the light Summa Tkeol., 11-11, q. 8, a. I, ad lum. John of St. Thomas, op. cit., dis. XVIII, a. 4. 1 "' Summa Tkeol., 11-11, q. 15. 18 " 188 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 275 of reason, the light of grace, and intelligible princples through which a man understands other things. The first is never forfeited by the soul; the second is, sometimes, but its privation is a punishment rather than a sin; it is in the loss of the third that sin enters. Blindness of mind is opposed to the gift, and St. Thomas asked if is it a sin. This is the answer: That man does not attend to an intelligible principle whence other things are known happens in two ways. Sometimes it is due to the fact that a man's will is deliberately turned away from the consideration of that principle ... whereas sometimes it is due to the mind being more busy about things which it loves more, so as to be hindered thereby from considering this principle. In either of these ways, blindness of mind is a sin. 185 In a further article, he shows how this vice, and that of dullness, arises from carnal sins of lust and gluttony. 186 Hence, the dispositions for the operation of this gift on the part of man are abstinence and, above all, chastity. Further, from his consideration of conversion and aversion of the mind to some intelligible principle-some article of faith perhaps-it is evident that without such conversion, the Holy Ghost will not activate the gift. He accommodates Himself to the order of nature, and takes occasion to act in us from some external circumstances which turn our thoughts to things of God, from the reasonings we form in meditation, from hearing the word of God preached, from spiritual reading, from all actions which affect us well or ill, and above all in prayer .187 VII. THE GIFT IN HEAVEN One question remains to be considered before we can apply ourselves to summarizing St. Thomas' doctrine on the essential nature of the gift of understanding. He does not consider it here expressly, but the principles of a satisfactory solution can be gathered from other places in his writings. The question as already stated is what act, if any, does the gift exercise in heaven where it is found without faith. 185 Ibid., a. 1. 186 Ibid., a. 8. 167 Billot, op. cit., p. 188. 276 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS St. Thomas seems to teach that the gift of understanding becomes the light of glory, because he attributes the perfect vision of God in heaven to the gift. Vision is twofold: one is perfect whereby God's essence is seen; the other imperfect. . . . Each of these visions of God pertains to the gift of understanding; the first to the gift in its state of perfection as possessed in heaven, the second to the gift in its beginnings as it is possesssed by wayfarers. 188 He expressly speaks of vision whereby we see the essence of God as pertaining to the gift, but only the light of glory can elicit the vision of God; therefore the gift and the light of glory seem to be the same. Again he says: the gift of understanding whose office it is to apprehend spiritual things in heaven, stretches to the essence of God, by intuiting Him.lsa Is it not the light of glory which alone touches the essence of God by intuiting Him? Those gifts which have an object which in common with a virtue will remain in heaven will not remain distinct from those virtues from which they are distinguished only in imperfection and perfection of mode of operation, as is evident in faith and understanding, because the vision which succeeds faith pertains to the perfect gift.1'90 In other words, the gift in heaven is no different from the habit which effects the divine union, i. e., the light of glory. In spite of all this, we must say that in heaven the gift remains distinct from the light of glory, although it is regulated by it and the beatific vision. In this life, as we have seen, the gift is regulated and measured by faith, because by faith we are joined to truth, moved to believe by divine testimony, and illumined by the Holy Ghost to penetrate what we believe and to discern it from error. In heaven vision succeeds faith and therefore the gift will then be regulated by vision. In this life, understanding does not elicit the act of belief; in the next it will not elicit the vision. It presupposes the mind united to Summa Theol., II-II, q. 8, a. 7. III Sent., d. XXXIV, q. 1, a. 4. 190 Ibid .• d. XXXII, q. 1, a. 8, ad 6um. 188 189 THE NATURE OF THE GIFT OF UNDERSTANDING 277 God in some way, that the Holy Ghost may find it docile to be moved to understand the mysteries concerning Him. The gifts are compared to the theological virtues through which man is united to the Holy Spirit who moves him (in the gifts) as the moral virtues are compared to the intellectual virtues through which is perfected reason, the mover in morals.191 The gift, in its formal aspect, abstracts from faith or vision; it remains a disposition to be moved by the Holy Ghost to penetrate truth. St. Thomas has a special article on whether the gifts will remain in heaven/u 2 and answers that according to their essence they will be most perfect in heaven, because they perfect the mind to follow the instincts of the Holy Ghost, and in heaven man will be totally subject to God. Hence in heaven the gift will be regulated by the Vision. According to the matters in which they operated, they will not be found in heaven. Answering an objection, he remarks that the illumination of the mind will remain as the gift of understanding. However, the vision of God is not that by which we follow the instincts of the Holy Ghost, but rather that by which we possess, and are united to, Him. Therefore the gift and the light of glory are distinct. Moreover, in Christ we find all the gifts, and the light of glory as well, and so, obviously, the light of glory and the gift are distinct. It cannot be objected that the gift and the light of glory are distinct in Christ only because he was at the same time wayfarer and comprehender, but in ordinary wayfarers there are seven gifts and in comprehenders the light of understanding becomes the light of glory. The gift of understanding was either an obscure light repugnant to one in glory, or an evident and clear light. If obscure, it could not be found in Christ, as neither faith nor any imperfection in knowledge can be ascribed to Him. If clear and evident, there is no reason why the gift could not remain even after He ceased to be a wayfarer just as His infused knowledge remains, because it is perfect in itself and not repugnant to the light of glory. 191 Summa Theol., I-11, q. 68, a. 8. ,.•• Ibid., a. 6. 278 JOSEPH IGNATIUS MCGUINESS As for the expressions cited by some from St. Thomas, to show that the light of understanding becomes the light of glory, we understand them in the light of what St. Thomas has taught on the subjection of the gifts to the theological virtues. The perfect vision of God's essence belongs to the gift, not that the operation of the gift is the cause of the vision, but inasmuch as, after the vision is obtained, the gift can operate in all its perfection, no longer hindered by faith, but now regulated only by the clear vision of Infinite Truth which succeeded faith. The other two texts are to be understood in the same way, not formally but as consequences of the very vision itself. For St. Thomas says: The gifts which perfect us ill the contemplative life, [wisdom and understanding] will remain as to the acts which they had about their proper matter, but they will be perfected as to their mode, because no matter how much they were elevated in this life, they could not attain the heavenly mode. 193 So, just as with the gift of understanding, the Holy Ghost moves us to penetrate the mysteries of faith in an imperfect manner in this life, so in the contemplation of the essences of God as He is, the Holy Ghost will move us to see at last perfectly those things which escaped us here. " Now this is eternal life, that they may know Thee, the only true God." 194 Conclusion: The gift of understanding is a habit which renders us prompt to follow the impulse of the Holy Ghost. It is found in all who are in the state of sanctifying grace, and in them only. The essential notion of this gift is that in it the Holy Ghost illumines us by his light to penetrate and to judge with a simple assent the primary objects of faith imperfectly, the secondary object perfectly; not by any connatural taste but by directly strengthening our intellectual light; and by this it is distinguished from all other gifts. JosEPH IGNATIUS McGUINESS, Dominican House of Studies, W askington, D. C. 198 III Sent., d. XXXIV, q. I, a. 8. :1.u John, xvii, 8. O.P. SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES * I. INTRODUCTION 1. In the opening pages of Problems for Thomists: The Problem of Species/ I distinguished two senses in which philosophers use the word "problem": either "to signify an open question, an issue or dilemma not yet demonstratively resolved," or " to mean a question to which several contrary answers have been given, among which we are able to discriminate the true from the false." 2 Strictly speaking, the latter is a solved problem, and as solved it is no longer a problem for purely philosophical inquiry. It may, however, remain a problem for the philosopher in his role as historian of thought. There is both philosophical and historical interest in trying to account for the origin and persistence of theories we know to be false. But in the case of the unsolved problem, the primary aim is philosophical: it is to resolve an issue constituted by conflicting theories, each of which is possible, and neither of which is known to be true. I proposed the problem of species as a problem for philosophical inquiry because I thought I had found an unresolved opposition between two theories about the number and order of species, as discussed in the philosophy of nature. Let me these matters report at once the formulation which I made of this issue. With respect to the number of species (the number of specific distinctions among corporeal substances), the issue was between a first theory which supposed a small and definitely known number (more than three and less than ten), and a second theory which supposed a larger and not definitely known number. With respect to the order of species, the issue was between a first theory which affirmed a perfect hierarchical ordering but denied, in doing so, the presence in two proximately related specific natures of a common generic element; and a second theory ·which denied a perfect hierarchical ordering but affirmed the presence of a common generic nature in diverse species. 8 *An analytical outline of this article will be found on pages 878-9. For brevity, I shall hereafter refer to the book as The Problem of Species. I shall also have to assume that the reader of this article is somewhat familiar with matters under discussion in the book (New York, 1940), or in the series of articles published in THE THOMIST (Vol. I, Nos. 1, 2, 8; Vol. II, Nos. 1, 2) . • Op. cit., p. 1; THE THOMIST, I, 80. • This summary of the issue is, of course, too brief to be adequate. For a full summary, vd. op. cit., Chap. VI; THE THOl\U:ST, I, 481 ff. It must suffice here to point out that there is a connection between what each theory holds about the 1 280 MORTIMER J. ADLER The problem which I proposed as philosophical no longer seems to me to be a problem of that sort, because I now think that the issue between the two theories can be completely resolved. To state my present view more accurately, I should say that the questions about the number and order of specific natures can be demonstratively answered. This is more accurate because the issue cannot be resolved in favor of either theory as previously formulated. I might describe the situation as I now see it in either of two ways: (I) by saying that there is a third theory which is able to combine the truths contained in the first and the second theory a,nd, at the same time, excludes their errors-a sort of Hegelian synthesis of the halftruths contained in thesis and antithesis; (2) by saying that the first theory contained an accidental error, the rectification of which permits it to be proved, whereas the second theory is essentially erroneous and can, therefore, be completely disproved. Only the second of these two statements is really accurate, and therefore I must describe the situation in that way. The reader will see this to be the case when, later, he sees that the error made in the formulation of the first position is appropriate, but not essential, to its disagreement with the second position, so that when the first position is rectified by the removal of this error, it still differs from the second position on critical grounds. In contrast, the error in the second position is essential to its disagreement with the first position; hence, should that error be removed, the second position would be reduced to the first, in which case, of course, the problem would be solved, for there would no longer be an opposition of conflicting theories, but only one true account of the matters under consideration. 4 number of species and how it views their order. This is made plain in the exposition of the two theories in Chapters IV and V respectively. One other point needs to be made explicit: the second theory does not deny hierarchy in every sense, but only that perfect hierarchical order in which each member is specifically distinct from its proximate inferior or superior; thus, if oyster and cow are species of a generic brute nature, and along with other species of brute differ generically from man, the hierarchy of species is imperfect, even if all the species of brute are perfectly ordered inter se, for the highest of the infra-human animals would not differ specifically from man, but only generically. For brevity, I shall hereafter refer to the " first theory" and the " second theory," or the " first position" and the " second position," assuming that the reader will remember the essential points of opposition thus being indicated. •1n the book I considered the possibility of a third theory, combining the answer given by the first theory with regard to the ordering of specific natures, with the answer given by the second theory with respect to their number. Vd. fn. 167, p. 142; THE THOMIST, I, 440, fn. 167. But I now see that a third theory, so conceived, is impossible. The number of species which can be affirmed is limited by the principle of a perfect hierarchical ordering, which is the chief principle of the first theory. SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES fl81 It is also true to say that the issue, as I stated it, between the first theory unrectified and the second theory is a false issue. It is not surprising, therefore, that this false issue should have appeared to be irresolvable. It was ir.resolvable because it was false. If a man propounds a false problem, he cannot hope to solve it. It does not follow, of course, that every true issue is resolvable, for there may be some genuine problems which we cannot solve. But, fortunately for the philosophy of nature, the problem of species does not belong with the mysteries. When the true issue is stated, as between the second theory and the first theory rectified, that issue can be completely resolved in favor of the correctly formulated first position. Though the issue between the rectified first theory and the erroneous second is a true issue, in the sense that there is always an issue between truth and error, the problem of species is no longer a genuine problem for the philosopher of nature as such. All that remains of the problem now belongs to historical research in philosophy, for it is still worth while to explain, if we can, the origin and persistence of the false notions constituting the second position. Such historical explanations have philosophical value in so far as they help the philosopher to understand the truth better by knowing the causes of error. 2. It is not often that one achieves a clarification of intellectual difficulties so speedily and so completely. In so far as, in formulating the first position, I made the error which generated a false issue, I am, of course, responsible for some of those difficulties; but may I say, in partial extenuation, that I made this error in the course of working toward a true issue? H I had not been working in this direction, I might not have made the error; but then I also might not have discovered the true theory, made evident by a demonstrative resolution of the true issue. In short, there are real difficulties, not of my making, in the second theory of species-a theory of ancient origin, as well as currently prevalent. In one sense, there was no problem for Thomists in these questions about the number and order of species, because the true answers to these questions constitute a thoroughly Thomistic theory; but, until the true answers be demonstrated and the errors in the second position uncovered, there was and is a problem here for any Thomist who adheres to the second theory, because the difficulties intrinsic to that theory arise from its conflict with fundamental Thomistic truths. I can take the blame for having made an error, but I cannot take credit for its discovery. I owe, and wish to record, a debt of gratitude to those critics who, through really trying to understand the MORTIMER J. ADLER problem as I saw it, helped me to discover the error, thus enabling me to correct it and to reach the clarification and solution I am now about to present. Viewed objectively, it would have been better not to have made an error, but viewed subjectively, making this error became the occasion for a surer realization of the truth of the first position. And this course of events may be fruitful, not only for me, but for others who will learn from this adventure in thinking and discovery something about the constraining and regulative beneficence of basic Thomistic principles. There is no better sign of the objectivity of truth in a philosophy than the common obligations it imposes upon everyone who works under its aegis.e 3. Let me name the error at once. It consisted in denying a common generic element in two specific natures, proximately related as higher and lower; it consisted, furthermore, in regarding this denial as essential to the principle of a perfect hierarchical ordering of specific natures. As I originally formulated it, the first position contained this error. This error was called to my attention by the critic who asked how animal could be predicated of both man and brute, or of both man and cow. If I tried to answer this question in a manner quite consistent with my erroneous formulation of the first position, I would have to say that animal is predicated of man as genus, and of cow as species, for according to the first position, as unrectified, the sensitive nature, which is the generic element in human nature, is indifferently conceived by animal or brute; and since cow is merely a race or sub-species (an accidental concretion, not an essence) of brute, animal or brute, indifferently, signifies the whole specific nature of cow. My critic could then reply that if this account of the predication of animal be essential to the first position, then that position must be essentially erroneous, because it is impossible for one concept to be predicated of two others, both its inferiors, in the one case as genus, and in the other as species.6 • If I had not violated a Thomistic principle, I would not have made the error which prevented me from seeing the unblemished truth at once. Since I made the error willingly, I at fault, even though I may try to excuse the willful blindness by the excessive zeal with which I tried to adhere to a new truth I had just begun to see. I might almost say that what blinded me was the brightness of the new light. Though it in no way exonerates me, it is necessary to add that those who adhere to the second theory are guilty of the same fault-a violation of Thomistic principles. I hope that they, on their side, will also be able to profit from the insights consequent upon the rectification of my error. • This critic was Professor Anton Pegis of Fordham University. In conversations which we had, he insisted that he was raising not merely another objection to Position I, to be added to the seven others which I myself had raised, and five of which I showed to be completely answerable. Vd. op. cit., Ch. VIII; THE SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES 288 A second error followed; or, perhaps, we can regard the mistake I am now going to report as part of one and the same error. I t.hought that the first position had to deny a common generic nature, in order to hold to a strict hierarchy of specific natures; but I also realized that the logician's account of predication and of the ordering of concepts required the notion of a common genus. The logical account of species and genera seemed to me to be one which the first position had to acccept, as well as the second. Hence I was led to the false conclusion that whereas the second position could affirm a common genus in logical analysis and a common generic nature in the philosophy of nature, the first position could only affirm a common genus in logical analysis. I made this an essential point of difference between the two theories; and I formulated this difference by saying that, according to the first position, there was no " parallelism " between logic (concerned with the ordering of concepts) and ontology (concerned with the order of natures) .1 This obliged me to distinguish between two types of hierarchy: the "logical hierarchy " of concepts, in which there were common genera; the " ontological hierarchy " of natures, in which there were II, 106. Failure to meet this objection did not merely make the first position less likely to be true (which was the way I regarded the failure to meet the sixth and seventh objection against the first position) ; rather, he insisted, failure here was tantamount to the complete untenability of the first position. I now know that he was quite right, although at the time the difficulty he raised about the predicability of animal seemed to me to be necessitated by the most important point in the first theory-the very point in which the first theory seemed to adhere to a truth which tlie second theory violated, namely, that between man and the proximately inferior specific nature, whatever it be, only one essential perfection exist& as the basis of the specific difference. I shall subsequently show how this truth can be preserved without committing the error Prof. Pegis detected. I must add that in the course o£ writing the book, I was somewhat aware of the difficulty which Prof. Pegis later discovered. Vd. op. cit., fn. 153a, p. 128; and fn. 189, p. 218; THE THoMisT, I, 421; II, 189. I realized that I was departing from tradition in trying to use the word " brute " to- name the generic nature of man; and I realized that, however I might justify such verbal usage, I could never regard the concept brute as a genus predicable of mam., for rational brute is a false definition by self-contradiction. Yet, at the same time, I was unable to find a real distinction between what was intended by the concept animal, and what was intended by the concept brute, in terms compatible with the principle of a perfect hierarchy. Hence, in adhering to that principle, I felt I had to accept the difficulty of not being able to explain the facts of predication. • It will be seen at once how this mistake flows as a consequence from the initial error of denying a common generic nature. I made it obviously as a result of trying to adhere at once to two inconsistent principles: the principle of predication, on the one hand, and the principle of perfect hierarchy erroneously con-ceived, on the other. · Cf. fn. 6 11111pra. THOMIST, 284 MORTIMER J. ADLER no common generic elements. 8 These mistakes were called to my attention by the critic who charged me with violating some fundamental Thomistic canons about the relation of ens naturae and ens rationis within the analogy of being, such as verum sequitur esse rerum, or that the modes of predication follow the modes.of being. As made, the charge was inaccurate on only one point: what should have been said was that the first theory, as I conceived it, was guilty of these violations, and hence could not be at all tenable within the framework of Thomistic philosophy. All that the critic need have said was that the sharp discrepancy between a logical and an ontological hierarchy, apparently demanded by the first position, showed that the theory was impossible for a Thomist. 9 I have now stated the error, the correction of which has such fruitful results. 10 It might be thought that the force of the criticisms I have just mentioned would destroy the first position and leave the second in undisputed possession of the field; or it might be thought that the correction of the error indicated by these criticisms would reduce the first position to the second, thus comirig to the same 8 All of these errors, or parts of the same error, will be found explicitly enunciated in the summary of the main points of the first position as contrasted with the main points of the second. Vd. op. cit., Ch. VI; THE THOMIST, I, 381 ff. 9 This critic was Father Gerard Smith of Marquette University. In a review of my book, which appeared in Thought (Dec., 1940: XV, 59, pp. he obviously intended the criticism I have reported in the text; but I must confess that I did not get the real point of his review until after many letters had passed between us; in full truth, I should say that I did not get Father Smith's point until I was able to see it in the light of Prof. Pegis's criticism. Just as the several mistakes I have mentioned are parts of one error, so the points Father Smith and Prof. Pegis made separately are really parts of one and the same fundamental criticism. The inadequacy of my understanding of Father Smith's criticism-at a time when I had not yet perceived the error in my formulation of the first theory-is plainly revealed in a note I wrote on Ontology and Logic, in reply to Father Smith. Vd. Thought, March, 1941; XVI, 60 pp. 200-4. 10 I may have made other errors than this one, but so far as I can now see this is the only one which is relevant to the issue between two theories, in the philosophy of nature. about the number and order of substantial species. It was this one error which made the issue as I stated it a false issue; it is the correction of this one error which makes the issue not only true but resolvable. The question about the constitution of the essences of composite substances-which really is concerned with the precise way in which the notion of " common matter " must be interpreted, when it is said that common matter enters into the composition of such essences--is not relevant in the same sense, i. e., as determining a correct formulation of the issue, or its resolution. I think I have sufficiently shown why this is so (Vd., op. cit., pp. 14-17, and 168-176, esp. fn. 174; THE THOMIST, II, pp. 108-116, esp. fn. 173, p. 110); and M. Maritain agrees that the fact that I have postponed this question for later discussion is not a relevant point of criticism with regard to the issue about species (vd. " Concerning a ' Critical Review' " in THE THOMIST, III, p. 49). SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES 285 result-namely, a solution of the problem in terms of accepting the second theory as true. But neither of these two " possibilities " is in fact the case, precisely because the error is not essential to the formulation of the first position, especially not with respect to the very points on which its essential disagreement with the second position is based. On the contrary, far from destroying the first position, these criticisms have led to the correction of an accidental error; and far from this reducing the first position to the second, the correction rectifies the first theory in the line of its own essential truth, confirms it in its opposition to the second position, and resolves the issue by showing why the second theory must be rejected, and the first accepted. 4. Though I shall postpone until later an argumentatively adequate statement of the resolution, let me say at once how the correction came to be made, and how it is to be understood. Merely seeing the difficulties in my formulation of the first theory was, by itself, not enough. The criticisms which pointed out these difficulties could never, by themselves, have made me regard the difficulties as errors, for three reasons: in the first place, I saw an element of truth in the first theory which I could not surrender; in the second place, I saw that this element of truth was incompatible with points in the second theory; in the third place, I saw difficulties in the second theory which seemed to me as insuperable as any which attached to the first theory, if not more so. In this state of mind, I could not give up the first theory in spite of its difficulties, nor could I accept the second, because it had difficulties of its own. My criterion of judgment was simply this: until all the difficulties attaching to one theory could be removed, and until those attaching . to the other could be shown to be incurable errors, no resolution of the issue would be possible. In this state of mind, I entered into a series of conversations with M. Maritain while he was lecturing at the University of Chicago in January. As anxious as I to clarify matters which had become somewhat muddled by recent discussion, M. Maritain made two points: first, that he thought both theories must concur in affirming a common generic nature (in ontology) as well as a common genus (in logic); second, that he thought the second theory had to agree with the first theory's view of a perfect hierarchy of specific natures, in which each member is, in essential grade of being, higher or lower than a proximate inferior or superior, and in which no two specific natures are of coordinate grade in any respect except that in which all corporeal substances are of the same grade, namely, as corporeal 286 MORTIMER J. ADLER (i. e., as falling within the same natural genus, signified by the presence of prime matter in their substantial composition) . At once I found it difficult to see how the notion of a common generic nature could be compatible with a strict view of the hierarchical order of specific natures. This difficulty was removed when M. Maritain and I were able to formulate a conception of the genus as being doubly determinable even though the two species, resulting from the two determinations to which the genus was susceptible, had only one positive difference between them. This conception of the genus departs from the usual view which makes it determinable by two or '11Wre positive differences, such that each of the species within the same genus is constituted by the possession of a perfection diverse from the perfections possessed by the other species. In this new conception of the genus, there can be only two species dividing it, and they divide it according as one possesses a perfection which the other rejects; the genus is indeterminate with respect to this one perfection, but in two ways-both as to its possession and as to its rejection, and hence it can be common to the two species, even though they differ, inter se, with respect to only one perfection.U These two points which M. Maritain made had for me more drastic consequences than he himself, perhaps, envisaged. 12 The source of all these consequences was the insights which occurred as soon as we had succeeded in conceiving the genus in a way that was completely compatible with the principle of a perfect hierarchy. I realized then, first, that if the second theory had to agree to the first theory's principle of hierarchy, it could no longer hold on to the usual notion of common genus which was incompatible with strict 11 This brief indication of the new point, by which the error in the first theory was corrected, must suffice here. An adequate analysis of the point will be given later. Vd. Part III infra. It will be noted, furthermore, that although the point is here stated in logical terms, it holds as well for the ontological account of generic and specific natures, since once the error in the first theory is corrected there is no longer any discrepancy between the logical ordering of concepts (as genua, species, etc.) and the ontological order of natures (as generic, specific). 10 At the time he proposed them, M. Maritain suggested that, in the light of these points, each of the two opposing theories might be regarded as possible; for if it admitted a common genus, the first theory was no longer intrinsically impossible on Thomistic grounds; and even if it admitted the first theory's view of hierarchy, the second theory might still disagree with the first about the actual number of specific natures in the corporeal world. Hence, in M. Maritain's view, the issue between the two theories now largely turned on the question of the number of species-an issue which might be resolved some day by empirical evidences, or might never be resolved because of intrinsic limitations in human knowledge. In the latter case, the two possible theories would remain perennially in opposition in the philosophy of nature. SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES 287 hierarchy; hence, that if the second theory could not differ from the first with respect to the order of specific natures, it could not differ with respect to their number; in short, that once the two theories concurred in the principle of hierarchy, the second could not differ from the first on any essential point, without being intrinsically and incurably false. And, in the second place, I saw that as soon as the first theory's denial of a common genus had been corrected by conceiving a common genus in every way compatible with perfect hierarchy, then the first theory became completely devoid of difficulties: not only were the difficulties which my critics had raised no longer present in any way; 13 but, what was even more impres·sive, the objections which I myself had raised to the first theory (especially objection seven 14 ) could now be completely answered, whereas before they seemed completely unanswerable. By my own criterion of judgment, I was compelled, therefore, to conclude that the problem of species could be resolved; that the secoi,J.d theory, in so far as it continued to differ from the first, involved incurable errors which made it untenable on Thomistic grounds; that the first theory, rectified of an accidental error and, in consequence, free of all difficulties, was true. 15 5. I shall proceed in the following order. It is necessary to begin with some clarifications, both of the language we must use and of tangential matters. This must be done in order to prevent certain superficial misunderstandings which tend to obscure the whole problem. Then, I shall undertake an analysis of the notion of genus, showing, first, what conception of genus must be employed in the context of a strict hierarchical ordering of species; second, 13 That is, there is no longer any difficulty about predicating animal of brute and man, or of cow and man, within the framework of the first theory; nor is there any longer a lack of "parallelism" between logic and ontology, for there is no discrepancy whatsoever between a logical hierarchy of concepts, ordered as genus and species, and an ontological hierarchy of natures, ordered as generic and specific. Vd. fn. 11 supra. Hence, the objections raised by Prof. Pegis and Father Smith are fully answered: the rectified first theory does not violate the basic truth that modes of predication follow modes of being. 14 Vd. op. cit., Ch. VIII: pp. 204-206; THE THoMIST, II, 145-147. 15 The reader may wonder whether M. Maritain agreed to the drastic consequences which I thought followed from his own premises, and from the rectification of the first theory accordingly. I cannot answer that question definitely here; but later I shall report M. Maritain's reactions to the demonstrative resolution of the problem, which I presented to him at the end of our conversations. Vd. fn. 80 infra. Beyond that, it is for M. Maritain to speak for himself on these matters; it is my hope that he will soon write an article which will carry the whole discussion further-to what ultimate point I do not know, but I hope at least to the point of agreement about the truth of the first theory. 288 MORTIMER J. ADLER that there is another conception of genus which cannot be so employed; and, third, in terms of these two conceptions of genus I shall be able to state the opposition between the first theory as rectified and the second theory as still persisting in disagreement with the first. The true issue being clear, it can then be resolved: by showing why the second theory is untenable, and how the first theory is free from difficulties. The most important part of this demonstration will be to show that the very reasons by which the second theory is disproved are the reasons for the truth of the first theory. After the demonstration, I shall briefly discuss some of the consequences of the resolution, especially concerning the relation of logic to the philosophy of nature, for we shall find that there are two quite different logical orderings of concepts as species and genera, according as the principle of differentation is essential or accidental, and when these two sorts of logical hierarchy are properly distinguished we shall find that they image two sorts of ontological hierarchy-the order of real essences, or specific natures, and the order of accidental concretions, or racial natures. In a concluding section, I shall try to suggest a solution of the historical problem (the problem of the origin and persistence of a false theory) by indicating how the two different sorts of hierarchy became confused, first in logical analysis, and then in the philosophy of nature. II. PRELIMINARY CLARIFICATIONS 6. Like every other word in popular or technical usage, the word " species " is ambiguous in many ways. Like every other concept, truly possessed by the mind, the concept species is a single meaning, a single intention. Because social words are instrumental signs which signify through the passions of the soul, (primarily through mental words or concepts), they have meaning; the same word can have a variety of meanings according as it is imposed as a name upon different things, each, of course, as understood. Because mental words or concepts are formal signs, they do not have meanings; they are meanings or intentions; it is their very nature to signify their object; hence the mental word is never a name, for it does not need to be imposed in order to signify; and the concept cannot be ambiguous, for it cannot be any meaning or intention other than the one it is. Now if the word "species" were unambiguously used, if the word " species " were always used, even by philosophers, to signify what is intended by the concept species, the discussion of certain philosophical problems would be much simpler. But we know that that is not the case, and, furthermore, that we can never expect it to be. SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES That being so, we must make strenuous efforts to save discourse from the failures of communication which always threaten us because of the difficulties intrinsic to the use of language. And these difficulties are peculiarly acute in the case of such words as " species," "genus," "difference," etc., because of the peculiar character of the concepts through which these words sometimes signify, in one of their many usages. Let me explain. Concepts can be divided into two sorts: they either terminate the direct act by which the intellect understands real beings, or they terminate the reflexive act by which the intellect understands its own acts and the concepts, or so-called logical beings, which are involved in the intellect's direct acts of understanding. This is the basic distinction between the first and second intentions of the mind. Now, whereas it is true that certain concepts are purely and exclusively second intentions, it is not true that every concept, other than these, is purely and exclusively a first intention. The reason for this is simply that every concept, other than those which are purely second intentions, can function both in the mind's direct acts of understanding and in its reflexive acts. To make this plain, let us consider two judgments: (1) a judgment expressing an act of direct knowledge, such as "John is a man"; (2) a judgment expressing an act of reflexive knowledge, such as " man is a species (or a concept, a universal, a predicate, etc.)." In the first ·type of judgment, the concept man functions as a first intention, for it is that whereby we understand the real nature of this singular substance. In the second type of judgment, the same concept man functions, in a special way, as a second intention, for it is itself now the object being understood. I refer to the way in which the concept man functions as a second intention as " special " because it is not the same as the way in which the concept species functions as a second intention in the same judgment. The latter concept is a second intention in the primary sense of being that whereby we understand the ideal nature of this particular concept, the concept man. In short, just as judgments which express acts of direct knowledge are constituted by subjects and predicates, so also are judgments which express acts of reflexive knowledge; and just as both subject and predicate in the direct judgment must be first intentions, so the concepts, which are subject and predicate in the reflexive judgment, must both be second intentions. But only certain concepts can function as predicates in reflexive judgments. (These are such concepts as concept itself, predicate, universal, and, of course, the concepts traditionally known as the five predicables or the five universals, genus, difference, species, property, accident.) 8 MORTIMER J. ADLER All concepts other than these can function as subjects in reflexive judgments, but they can also function as either subjects or predicates in direct judgments. Furthermore, the concept which can function as either subject or predicate in a direct judgment, as well as the subject in a reflexive judgment, can never function as the predicate in a reflexive judgment; whereas, in sharp contrast, the concept which can function as the predicate in a reflexive judgment may also be able to function as the subject in such a judgment (as when we say " species is a universal ") but it can never function either as subject or as predicate in a direct judgment. This distinction between two sorts of concepts can be summarized as follows. Let us use the phrase " logical concept " to name those few concepts which are primarily and exclusively second intentions. And let us refer to all other concepts, which are primarily first intentions though they may also be the subjects of second intentional judgments, by using the word " concept " without qualification. It will be seen at once that whereas all concepts are logical beings, beings of the mind, entia rationis as divided against entia naturae, only some concepts, in fact a very small number, are logical concepts. 16 Furthermore, let us dis16 An interesting ambiguity in the word "logical " is discovered by comparing its two uses in this sentence. In its first use, the word " logical " signifies one of the divisions of being, and has a connotation closely related to that of the words " ideal " and " mental " as opposed to the signification of such words as " real " and " physical." In its second use, the word " logical " signifies that the concepts so described belong peculiarly to the science of logic. Logical concepts are the fundamental categories in terms of which the logician analyzes all concepts. The science of logic has its own proper categories of analysis, just as the science of metaphysics has its own fundamental terms, the transcendentals, which can be called " metaphysical concepts "; or just as the science of grammar has its own basic categories, i. e., the parts of speech, which can be called " grammatical concepts." There are, unfortunately, several meanings of the phrase " ens rationis." I am using it here to make the division between two modes of existence which any essence or res can exercise: real, or physical, and intentional, or mental. In this way ens rationis is divided against ens naturae according to the distinction between what exists in the mind (but can also exist apart from it) and that same thing (res) as it exists apart from the mind in the real order. But ens rationis is also distinguished from ens reale according to a different principle: that is said to be an ens rationis which can exist only in the mind and cannot exercise any real existence. John of St. Thomas divides entia rationis of this sort into two kinds: negations, privations, fictions, on the one hand, and relations of reason, or pure second intenA. 1.) As tions, on the other. (Vd. Cursus Philosophicus, Logica, Pt. ll, Q. I shall use the phrase " ens rationis " I shall mean only those concepts which have a fundamentum in re, and never those which have no fundamentum in re; concepts which have a fundamentum in re can be either first intentions or second intentions; and this is to say that I shall be considering only real things in so far as they exercise intentional existence under a primary or secondary mode of SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF SPECIES tinguish two modes of the second intention. According as a concept functions as the subject of a judgment in the second intention, it signifies itself as the object of thought. Let us speak of it as a second intention reflexively. According as a logical concept functions as the predicate of a judgment in the second intention, it signifies some aspect of the nature of the subject-concept which is the object of thought in this case. Let us speak of it as a second intention predicatively. (There is, of course, no need for a similar distinction between the subject-concept and predicate-concept of a judgment in the first intention; for in so far as both concepts are universals, both are first intentions predicatively, even though one may function as the subject of the judgmenU 7 ) Hence we can say that only logical concepts can function as second intentions predicatively (though they may also function as second intentions reflexively); whereas ordinary concepts (non-logical concepts in the precise sense already indicated) can never function as second intentions predicatively, but either as first intentions or as second intentions, but then only reflexively. 18 intellectual consideration. It is only in the first mode of distinction between ens naturae and ens rationis that ens is said analogically of the same res exercising a different esse (real or intentional) . In the second mode of distinction, ens is said equivocally, as John of St. Thomas points out; but I would exclude relations of reason (pure second intentions) from this equivocation, for they· are real things under a secondary mode of intellectual consideratiou, and therefore must be distinguished from negations, privations and chimerae. (Cf. St. Thomas, Summa Theologica, I, 16, 8 ad It is interesting, further, to observe that the division of the real into the actual and the possible is paralleled by a similar division of the rational into the possible and impossible (i. e., respectively capable and incapable of having a fundamentum in re); and that which is rationally possible, in this sense, i. e., capable of realization, may be either really actual or really possible, whereas that which is purely ideal in the order of reason can never be really actual. 17 All predications in the first intention are ultimately of first substances. The primary distinction, therefore, in the case of all judgments in the first intention is that between the singular and the universal judgment, according as the subject of the judgment is a singular or a universal term. The subject of a universal judgment is always a first universal intention predicatively, in the sense that that same concept can always be a predicate in a singular judgment, in which the subject-term is a singular, and not a universal, intention. That the judgment " man is an animal " is in the first intention can be seen in two ways: (I) Both subject and predicate are predicable of a singular term, such as" John." It is indifferent whether the grammatical form of the judgment be " man is an animal" or " men are animals." By the same criteria, "man is a speCies" is seen to be in the second intention because (1) the predicate is not predicable of any:·singular term, and " men are species " is nonsense. · 18 To be sure that these distinctions are plain, let me give a parallel analysis in the field of words,. with respect to the impositions. The first imposition of a word is as a name imposed upon that which is not a word, but a thing to be signified. MORTIMER J. ADLER There IS one further point which complicates the analysis of intentions. Just as it is true that the agent intellect is never not active, just as it is true that there is never an act of intellect unaccompanied by an act of imagination, or conversely, so also is it true that the human mind is always reflexive, by which I mean that there is never a purely direct or a purely reflexive act of the intellect. Whenever we understand anything, we also understand our act of understanding; and we can never understand our act of understanding unless our intellect is in act understanding something. 18 " Of course, the fact that there is never a temporal separation of direct and reflexive intellectual acts does not mean that we cannot discriminate between these two modes of intellectual activity; and this distinction is not purely analytical for it is a real distinction on the part of intellectual activity itself. Were this not so, we could never have discovered the distinction between the first and the second intentions of the mind. Thus, we are led to see that no concept is ever purely a first intention. 19 In every ordinary concept The second imposition of a word is upon another word, and not upon a thing; it is an imposition made for the sake of naming the class of words to which a given word can belong. Thus, in the sentence, "John is a man," both the word "John " and the word " man " are first impositions; but in the sentence " man is a noun," the word "noun" is clearly a second imposition. Now, in the latter sentence, the subject-word " man " is used to refer to itself as to that which is being talked about. As thus used, it is not a first imposition nor is it a second imposition in the same way that the word " noun " is. Therefore, we must distinguish two kinds of second imposition: a reflexive second imposition (i. e., the use of a word to refer to itself) a predicative second imposition (i. e., the use of a word to talk about another word). Now, the words which signify the concepts of grammatical analysis are the only words which are purely second impositions, i. e., capable of being used in the second imposition predicatively. (Cf. fn. 16 supra.) In contrast, all other words are primarily first impositions, although they can be used in the second imposition reflexively, when we try to talk about them as words, rather than use them to talk about things which are not words. The parallelism of these grammatical distinctions with the logical distinctions already made should be clear. In the judgment, "John is a man," the concept man is a first intention. In the judgment, " man is a species," the concept species is a second intention predicatively, whereas the concept man is a second intention reflexively. 18 • What is here said is equally true of first and second intellectual acts-