THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORs: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PRoVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: Sheed & Ward, Inc., New York City VoL. III OCTOBER, 1941 No.4 THE CONFLICT OF METHODS AT THE END OF THE MIDDLE AGES 1 T I ffiS PAPER will deal with an historical fact, which has been, to my mind, of major importance in the development of modern western thought: I mean the conflict of methods that, at the end of the Middle Ages and above all at the time of the new philosophy of Bacon and Descartes, caused modern Physics, the modern explanation of nature's phenomena, to seem radically and absolutely incompatible with Aristotelian metaphysics and scholastic philosophy. I should like briefly to examine the philosophical implications of this fact. Perhaps the conclusion thus attained may shed some light on the discussions of our age. The conflict of which I speak had begun in the Middle Ages-already in the 13th century. At that time it as a conflict between the schools of Oxford and the schools of Paris. The University of Paris was dominated by the 1 Paper read at the Ninth Conference on Methods in Philosophy and the Sciences, held at,the New School for Social Research, New York, April 27, 1941. 527 528 JACQUES M.ARITAIN Aristotelian reform whose masters were Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas; its main task was to build up a synthesis of traditional Christian thought by the light of a metaphysics and a theology renewed, as to their conceptual systematization, by the principles of Aristotle-of an Aristotle recast and baptized by Thomas Aquinas; its chief concern was, therefore, metaphysical and theological. The University of Oxford was. inspired, on the contrary, by the old Augustinian tradition, that is, in brief, by Platonism (by a Platonism in which many Aristotelian notions had a place); and, at the same time, the Oxonians were dominated by the desire of applying the Platonist-mathematical conception of the world to the explanation of physical phenomena. Both mathematics and experience were their guiding rules. Even in philosophy and theology, the influence of this logico-mathematical and empiricist trend of mind played a major part. Already Roger Bacon asserted: "It is impossible to know things of this world, unless mathematics is known." And it is from his pen that the term" experimental science" appears for the first time in the history of human thought. Later on, in the 14th Century, many Doctors of the University of Paris, John Buridan, Albertus of Saxony, Peter of Ailly, Nicole Oresme, were to accept in philosophy the Nominalist inspiration, at the same time to prepare in mechanics and physics the discoveries and the new concepts which characterize modern science. They were the precursors of Leonardo da Vinci and Galileo. II If we seek to bring to light the philosophical roots of the question, we must first note that Aristotelian metaphysics and the Aristotelian philosophy of nature-at least taken in their genuine significance, in their true structure-did not intend to explain phenomena, but to discover the ontological structure of things and the hierarchy of essences in terms of intelligible being. Starting from sense experience, they did not remain on the plane of experience, but tried to perceive the intelligible transsensible features of the nature of things thanks to an analysis THE CONFLICT OF METHODS 529 grounded on the first intuitions of the intellect, above all on the metaphysical' intuition of being; thus they conceived reality in terms of substance and accident, of qualities, of causes-that is, of the four genera of causes, the principal of which was final causality. Nevertheless, and that was the great misfortune of Aristotelianism, Aristotle himself and his mediaeval followers were not content with this ontological or properly philosophical analysis. Putting too great and too bold a confidence in the philosophical intellect and the philosophical tools, they naturally extended their ontological explanation of the supra-empirical structure of things into an of the empirical phenomena. In point of fact their philosophy of nature, as is well known, was both a philosophy of nature and a science, a scientific interpretation of the detail of phenomena. And this second part, the scientific part, was condemned to failure. Still, in the 17th Century, the treatises of philosophy contained explanations (or pseudo-explanations) of ice-crystals, of the rainbow, discussions on the vacuum, and so forth. Now I arrive at the point which matters most to the present issue. What is really new in the achievements of the science which became predominant in the 16th and 17th centuries, of "modern science," is properly speaking a physics of the physicomathematical type. (In other scientific domains which are not thus absorbed by mathematics, modern science doubtless owes its material or technical perfection, and an autonomous conceptual lexicon which permits infinite progress in the analysis of phenomena as such, to the attraction exerted by physicomathematics on the other kinds of knowledge, which henceforth see in the former the exemplar of knowledge.) In truth, the epistemological principles of the Ancients considered in their very nature could easily have adapted themselves to the new physics; the logical type to which that science corresponds, and of which astronomy was the best example during antiquity, theoretically had its place set down in the Scholastic synthesis of sciences. This logical type is that of a science in a sense intermediary between Mathematics 530 JACQUES MARITAIN and Physics, but actually mathematical as regards its typical mode of explanation, since what is jCYrmal and consequently specifying in it (its formal object and its medium of demonstration) is mathematical. The explanatory deduction is mathematical. Physical reality, although of prime importance to it as subject-matter, is basically, for it, a material reservoir of facts and verifications. And thus, while natural philosophy may be characterized as a physical knowledge properly philosophical and ontological, or metaphysical by participation, the new physics, on the contrary, according to the methodological principles of the Schoolmen, must be called a physical knowledge properly mathematical, or a science formally mathematical and materially physical: a forniula which, to my mind, condenses all its properties./ Doubtless the conception of physico-mathematics that the French physicist Pierre Duhem (and Hirn before him) defended was too mathematical and not sufficiently physical, nevertheless Duhem was right in thinking that phenomena can be analysed quantitatively without the existence of qualities being denied, and that the scientific method derived from Galileo and Descartes can be used without its involving in any way philosophical incompatibility with Aristotle's metaphysics. But in point of fact knowledge of a physico-mathematical sort was limited amongst the Ancients and the Schoolmen to certain very particular disciplines, such as astronomy or acoustics; their physics, as I previously noted, consisted in a natural philosophy (philosophical knowledge of physical data) which involved a physics of pure ·observation philosophically interpreted, and if certain medieval thinkers and scientists have been the precursors of physico-:mathematics, the idea of establishing a universal mathematical interpretation of physical reality by submitting the fluent detail of phenomena to the science of number nevertheless remained foreign to the majority of them. Therefore, on the day when quantitative physics, having its own specific character and possessed of its own exigencies, moved to take its place within the order of sciences and to THE CONFLICT OF METHODS 531 proclaim its rights, it was to enter inevitably into conflict with the philosophy of old-not only because· of the errors which vitiated the latter in the experimental field, but also, and this is more remarkable, because of the radical difference which separates-with respect to what is genuine and legitimate in each one of those two manners-the old manner of approaching physical realities from the new manner of approaching them. m The errors I have just mentioned and which vitiated the physics of old, singularly jeopardized, moreover, the position of the defenders of Aristotle. Indeed, as much as Aristotle's physics deserved, in the eyes of a Thomist, to be upheld in its first principles (the theory of matter and form, of the continuous, of time, of life, etc.) -in all that part which actually constitutes natural philosophy-just so much Aristotelian physics weak and insufficient in the part which tried to constitute an inductive science, and which applied to the experimental analysis of the detail of phenomena. Let us briefly mention here the errors in Aristotle's mechanics: the disregarding of mass in dynamics and the insufficient mathematical analysis of motion and of speed, the explanation of the motion of projectiles by the propagation in the air of a moving wave or by so-called antiperistasis-a concept owed not to Aristotle but to Simplicius-the belief in a difference of nature between celestial motion, considered as circular, and terrestial motion, considered as rectilinear, as well as between celestial bodies, considered incorruptible and terrestial bodies considered corruptible, the theory of heavy and light bodies; let us also mention the errors of the medieval physics in the designation of the simple constituents of bodies (the theory of the four elements), the errors about light (considered instantaneous), about the earth (for example, the denial of antipodes), and, above all else, the errors of the Ptolemaic system in astronomy. All these errors, however great they may have been from the point of view of positive science, in reality provided only 532 JACQUES MARITAIN ineffectual weapons against Aristotelian metaphysics and natural philosophy, for they were not necessary consequences drawn from the principles of Aristotle and were merely the result of oversimple inductions which interpreted :p.aturaJ phenomena in such a way as to conform to common appearances. But, at a superficial glance, it was all too easy to impute to the philosophy of the Ancients the wrongs of their science. And further, if on the one hand the hypotheses which treat of the configuration of the physical world have only a secondary and incidental importance for the pure intelligence, whose metaphysical certainties do not depend in the least on the map of the heavens, on the other hand these same hypotheseswithout speaking of their properly scientific value-are of capital importance to the imagination. In this respect the revolution caused in astronomy by the Copernican theory was to play in the history of ideas a part which cannot be too highly stressed. Widely exploited by the protagonists of mechanicist philosophy, dramatized by Galileo's condemnation, it has taken on amongst those thinkers who think as most men live, that is, within the senses, the value of a revolution in the metaphysical conception of the intelligible universe, while in truth it was but a revolution in the scientific· representation of the visible universe. Because it shattered century-old habits of imagination, it seemed to tear down all the science of the past; because it showed that sensible appearances had misled common opinion with regard to astronomy, it provided empirically-minded philosophers with a pretext for despising the natural intuition of first principles. Because it set back much further than did the Ancients the limits of the corporeal world, making the imagination by immensity, there was a rush to assert the infinity of the world, as though the ocean were not just as finite. as a drop of water. Because it made of the earth a tiny globe in the universe, and no longer the material center of the spheres, that doctrine of finality was declared outdated which held the human being as the ideal center of the creative intentions; as though the metaphysical hierarchy of essences were linked to the volume of the earth or to its position, and as THE CONFLICT OF METHODS 588 though the divine Intelligence should have taken less care of a little ball in motion than of a great pall at rest. Finally, while "humiliating" man in the corporal order by assigning him a habitat geometrically less honorable, it gave him the opportunity of exalting himself infinitely in the spiritual order, by considering himself as a sovereign thought which hovers over the abyss of a nature in which everything is blind necessity, and which measures it by its own knowledge. Thus the very thinkers who introduced into modern philosophy the principle of egooentricism and whose descendants were to make truth revolve around the human mind, were to profess a righteous indignation over the vanity of geocentricism, and wrapped themselves in their humility to banish from science the anthropomorphic consideration of final causes. If one imagines that the universe is finite and that all corporeal things are made for man, it is, wrote Descartes, " that instead of knowing the perfections which belong really to us, one attributes to other creatures imperfections they do not have, so as to raise oneself above them," 2 and that, " entering into an impertinent presumption, one wants to become part of the counsel of God and with him to take charge of managing the world, all of which causes an infinitude of vain worries and annoyances." The belief in final causes, Spinoza will say, derives only from the egoistic ambition of men " to use Nature for their own blind cupidity and insatiable avarice": whence a covey of illusions which could never have been dispelled " unless mathematics, which does not deal with final causes but only with essences and properties of geometric figures, had shown men another rule of truth." And Laplace will write: Seduced by the illusions of the senses and of selfishness, man long considered himself the center of stellar motion, and his vain pride was punished by the fear with which the stars inspired him. At last, several centuries of work have pulled down the veil which hid from his eyes the order of the world [it is a true revelation] ... then he saw himself on a planet almost imperceptible in the solar system, the vast extent of which is itself only a point in the s Letten to Elizabeth, September 15, 1645. 534 JACQUES MARITAIN immensity of space. The sublime results to which this discovery has led him are well equipped to console him for the rank it assigns to the earth, by showing him his own greatness in the extreme smallness of the basis which has helped him to measure the heavens .... IV To settle the conflict which set up the new physics against Aristotle's philosophy, would have required minds of exceptional vigor, capable of discerning behind the cloud of confusion of which we have just spoken, the essential lines and fundamental compatabilities of the two disciplines, at the very moment when both were least conscious of their limits-the old being in the midst of decadence and the new still in the process of formation. Unfortunately most of the Scholastics of the 15th and 16th centuries had fallen as far from the metaphysical wisdom of Thomas Aquinas as from the scientific initiatives of the 14th century, and, according to Melchior Cano's expression, knew only how to wield long sticks. As for the naturalists, captivated by their initial successes and deprived of metaphysical standards, it was not from them that one could hope for an equitable appreciation of the elements of the struggle. Both the former and the latter refused to distinguish in fact between natural philosophy and experimental science. The former, the Schoolmen, in spite of the warnings of St. Thomas, related the fate of Aristotle's metaphysics to that of the inductive hypotheses of antiquity, and the latter, the naturalists, confused the newly born mathematical physics with the most arbitrary metaphysics, with materialistic, hylozoistic, cabalistic, or pantheistic, and, especially, with mechanistic metaphysics. It is well to insist on this last confusion whose influence made itself felt on the entire development of modern science, and which, at the outset, completely hid from the initiators of the new physics the true nature of that science. Indeed they thought that they were determining the ontological causes of things, discovering the essence of bodies and the supreme reasons of the physical order, in short, setting up a natural philosophy; THE· CONFLICT OF METHODS 535 since they were working, and this because of the very nature of their science, with only quantitative standards, they were condemned from the first to admit only extension and motion as the principles of the corporeal world. Thus it is not enough to note that the physico-mathematical method was finally evolved by anti-scholastic thinkers, whom the very excess of their confidence in the application of mathematics to sense-perceived nature led instinctively to mechanism. We also must emphasize that the natural and irrepressible drive of the intelligence towards being and causes, when it met the physico-mathematical method must almost necessarily cause this discipline to be mistaken for a natural philosophy. It is because of this almost inevitable illusion that the new scientific method found itself from the very beginning, by virtue of the historical conditions of its genesis, quite ready to undergo the contamination of extraneous philosophies, and to become dependant upon a metaphysics like the Cartesian mathematism-an accident inversely resembling that which had linked Aristotle's metaphysics to the erroneous theories of the physics of old. But if physico-mathematics were a natural philosophy, if it made manifest the essences and causes at work in the corporeal world, then it would be a knowledge having the ontological essence of physical reality as its proper and specifying object; and from then on we would see subverted and destroyed the genuine structure of this science. It would no longer be a science jCYrmally mathematical and materially physical, it would become a kind of monstrosity, a science which would be at the same time jCYrmally physical and ontological as to its specifying objects and formally mathematical as to its medium of demonstration and explanation. The natural and necessary proportion between the end and the means, between the specifying object and the explanatory tools in knowledge would be broken. That implies that physico-mathematics would cease being a science properly speaking, and would rather become a kind of practical discipline, a kind of art applying to pure sensorial information gathered about the physical world, as to some 536 JACQUES .raw material, a method which elaborates them mathematically and draws from them regulating formulae for human practice and human industry. We may wonder whether modern civilization, in its bourgeois age, has not understood physics in this way. The Marxist epistemology with its integral practicism, does naught but push to extremes such a misconception of science. There is in the human mind no specific energy of knowledge (what the ancients called habitus), no intellectual virtue, in other words, no internal quality of science which corresponds to " science," thus conceived and put to work. Such a science, if it exisf;ed, would require of the physicist only a certain mathematical training (which could be nothing more than the habit or custom. of handling formulae) in combining experiments and in working over their results to submit them to the mathematical treatment. Yet as a matter of fact, it is, for some strata of our contemporary culture, science thus misconceived which is asked to supplant philosophical and metaphysical wisdom, and to supply the supreme food of the human mind. Thus truth is used for error, a delusive social myth is built up with the help of the sciences of phenomena, fallen from their true type, replacing philosophy in people's minds and, at the same time, conceived as essentially practical. Scientists themselves are clearly conscious of the object and limits of science, but in the common opinion of people, the false idea of science to which I allude does not imply any awareness of this very object and these very limits. It is not surprising that the pedagogical use of such a " science" so little cultivates reason in the masses which receive from it their educating influences. v But let us leave this parenthesis, and come back to the consideration of physico-mathematics in its genuine logical nature, and to the conflict that arose between this discipline and the traditional philosophical disciplines, at the time of the Renaissance and at the time of Descartes. If the reflexions and distinctions I outlined in this paper are well grounded, we see how THE CONFLICT OF METHODS 587 the long-existing dissension which, in view of the infirmity of human nature ordinarily separates metaphysicians from scientists, was then to become an irremediable opposition-existing as it did between metaphysicians attached to .the knowledge heritage of old, but in fact unfaithful to wisdom, unaware of the methodological limitations of philosophical or ontological explanation, and who wanted to set up a science of phenomena by means of their pseudo-philosophical formulae, and scientists dazzled by their new science, who wanted to set up a .prime philosophy by means of their figures. The struggle. having been brought onto the actual field of the study of phenomena, it was easy to foretell which would be the vanquished. To sum up, it is easily understood that for three principle reasons the intellectual world must almost necessarily at the outset of the modern era, have been the victim of a misunderstanding: 1) because of the introduction of quantitative physics, a new science legitimate in itself and in no way essentially incompatible with the old system of knowledge, but in actual fact in conflict with that system; 2) because of the confusion of the natural philosophy and the metaphysics of Aristotle, with the false hypotheses of the science of the ancients; 8) because of a fundamental error on the nature of physicomathematics, itself taken for a philosophical or ontological explanation of the world and made a fellow traveller of mechanistic metaphysics. In truth, there is no conflict between physico-mathematics and metaphysics or philosophy, because they do not only correspond to two fundamentally different methods of approaching reality, but also aim at two different fields of knowledge, two different formal and specifying objects within reality; each one has its proper object, its proper aim, its proper field, and therefore its proper means of analyzing the subject matter belonging in this field. Philosophy looks after essences and analyzes things in terms of being. Physico-mathematics looks after a mathematical reading or deciphering of phenomena. The two 538 JACQUES MARITAIN disciplines do not hunt on the same soil. Each one can develop ad infinitum on its own planr without encountering the other. Physico-mathematical analysis of sound can progress ad infinitum, on the plane of acoustics, without interfering with or entering into conflict with the artistic or poetic laws developing on their own plane of musical creation. Physico-mathematical analysis of the particles composing the atom can progress ad infinitum, on the plane of micro-physics, without interfering with or entering into conflict with the ontological analysis of corporeal reality and of intelligible properties of being, which analysis progresses for its part on the plane of philosophy of nature and metaphysics. Perhaps these considerations might help settle the discussions on teleology which play an important part in contemporary thought, above all in the biological domain, and to show how the concept of finality has to be removed, as an extraneous one, from experimental, particularly from physico-mathematical science, and at the same time to be maintained, as a legitimate and indispensable one, in philosophical and metaphysical knowledge. What seems to me to be essential in this matter, is to emphasize this fact, that there is a natural and inescapable proportion between means and ends, methods and objects, and that, every time we deal with genuine kinds of knowledge, the difference between m.ethods presupposes as its very reason, as its very root, a more fundamental and more enlightening difference between objects. JACQUES MARITAIN Columbia University, N6W York,N. Y. CHARITY AND THE SOCIAL ORDER T I. INTRODUCTION HE QUEST of man for unity and order is the mainspring of all that is history. For tranquillity of order his wars have been waged; for order of mind his art and culture ebb and flow; for unity with the Deity, there are his religions, his churches, his homes, his schools. This search for unity springs from his very nature. As an individual . substance man is one, and the whole world about him must contribute to that oneness, else it is meaningless. As a rational creature endowed with an intellect whose work is the perception of relationships, man seeks unity in order, the stuff of which relationships are made. As a being endowed with free will, always acting for an ultimate end of his own choice, an end which gives unity and purposiveness to his acts, man puts order into his world of activity. This continual quest of order on the part of man is admirably illustrated, perhaps through sheer contrast, in that vastly complex and somewhat disordered thing called society, the broad realm of man's activities with his fellow creatures. More particularly we refer to such activities of men as are the objects of the social sciences-the relations of man to the material necessities upon which depends his livelihood, and his relations to the various groups to which, of choice or necessity, he and his fellow men belong. Order requires a certain unity, and unity derives from a principle--a common source, a radical oneness. Socio-economic relations being so manifestly complex, having neither the concreteness of the visible creation nor the absoluteness of the spiritual world, have always challenged the ingenuity of man to discover or invent principles of social order. Nor has man shirked the task. There is, for instance, the individualist prin539 540 LOUIS A. RYAN ciple of Herbert Spencer: " Every man has freedom to do all that he wills, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man." 1 The class principle finds this expression in Karl Marx: " The economic structure of society is the real foundation on which rise legal and political superstructures and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness." 2 Totalitarianism, as explained by Benito Mussolini, accepts the state as principle: " Fascism conceives of the State as an Absolute, in comparison with which all individuals or groups are relative, only to be conceived in their relation to the State." 3 The racism of Hitler claims blood as the principle of social structure: " All that is not race in this world is trash. All world historical events, however, are only the expression of the race's instinct of self-preservation in its good or in its evil meaning." 4 A very recent and even more universalist social philosophy enuntiates its principle in the name of democracy which " is the plentitude of heart-service to a highest religion embodying the essence of all higher religions. Democracy is nothing more and nothing less than humanism in theocracy and rational theocracy in universal humanism." 5 More in the realm of reason is justice as the natural principle of society. It is stated thus by Aristotle: "Since in every art and science the end aimed at is always good, so particularly in this, which is the most excellent of all, the founding of civil society, the good therein aimed at is justice; for it is this which is for the benefit of all." 6 Nor does the Catholic Church, with her theology and supernatural philosophy of living, fail to propose a fundamental principle for the social order. It is charity, love of neighbor. H. Spencer, The Principles of Ethics (New York: 1897), II, 46. K. Marx, The Critique of Political Economy (New York: 1904), p. 11. • B. Mussolini, " The Political and Social Doctrine of Fascism," trans. from Enciclopedia Italiana. International Conciliation, No. 306 (New York: 1935), p. IS. 'A. Hitler, Mein Kampf (New York: Reynal & Hitchcock, 1939), p. 406. • The City of Man (New York: 1940), p. SS. 8 Aristotle, Politics (New York: Everyman's Library, 1921), Bk. III, c. 12, p. 88. Cf. Summa Theol., II-II, q. 79. a. 1. 1 2 C.ffARITY AND THE SOCIAL ORDER 541 "These things I command you, that you love one another": 7 this Christian principle of living-love, the fulfilling of the law-has been given modern application in the recent Papal encyclicals signifies sensitive life exclusively, though that includes the vegetative, and as man signifies the rational life, including both the vegetative and the sensitive, so Royal· signifies government which can be just exclusively in the way power is exercised, Republican signifies government which can be just exclusively in the way power is constituted, though that can include the justice of its proper exercise, and Democratic signifies government which can be just in the distribution of status, as well as with respect to the other factors. The hierarchy of governments is a moral hierarchy because the essential differences by which specification takes place are in the moral· order, i.e., they are elements of political justice. Cf. Part I, supra, loc. cit., p. 438, and fn. 24. THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 633 demonstrate the thesis, we must prove that the elements of justice, which we have used to specify three forms of government, are separable and cumulatively combinable, as specifying differences must be to set up a hierarchy, moral or naturaJ.9 1 But to defend its demonstrability, we had only to show that a moral gradation in forms of government does not violate the unity of the common good, as the end of political even though it involves a plurality of common goods, as diverse and unequal ends correlative with the diverse and unequal species of government. That has now been accomplished by the basic distinction between the ideal and the existential common good, between the common good as finis causa and the common good as finis effectus; for the unity of the former as an end is the single principle for distinguishing all good from all bad governments and states, whereas the plurality of the latter as ends (but now in a different sense, effectus, not causa) is correlative with the plurality of unequally just governments. As the objection pointed out, it would be impossible to specify forms of government as morally unequal by reference to a plurality of ends to be achieved, diverse and unequal ideal common goods. But, as we have shown, it is not impossible to specify forms of government as morally unequal by regarding them as correlative with a plurality of ends already achieved, diverse and unequal existential common goods. 92 We have shown that the 91 This will be the main work of Parts IV and V infra. •• Good is a transcendental term, predicable analogically rather than univocally. The analogy of, "goodness, like the analogy of being, involves an inequality among the various species or modes which it subsumes. Hence, whenever a number of things participate in an analogy, whether of being or of goodness, they must be ordered hierarchically. Vd. Summa Theologica, I, 5, 5; cf. 6, ad 3. The qualification of good by common does not alter the analogical character of good, any more than the qualification of being by corporeal alters the analogical character of the being that is said of corporeal substances · diverse in species. To say of each of the several distinct grades of well-being (of the specifically distinct kinds of state) that it is is a co=on good (existential, finis effectus), is to recognize the analogy of ·common goodness in which these diverse kinds of state participate, as the unequal members of a moral hierarchy. That the goodness which is convertible with the natural grade of being of a man and the goodness which is convertible with. the natural grade of being of a brute are unequal and analogical is a fact 634 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL necessity for this correlation lies in the functioning of governmental institutions as the principal means productive of the common good that is achieved at any The grade of goodness in the existing effect (the grade of the common good as finis effectus) must be proportionate to the grade of goodness in its productive cause (the grade of political justice in each form of government). And, finally, since forms of government are themselves intermediate ends in the political order, their specification by distinct elements of justice, separable and cumulatively combinable, also permits them to be viewed as a moral hierarchy of ends, in the sense of finis causa. 98 which should enable us to understand that the common good achieved in a Royal state and the common good achieved in a Republican state are unequal and analogical, even though in the first case the goodness is not the result of voluntary achievement, and in the second case it is. It might be more fitting, therefore, to compare the analogy of the common good with the analogy of happiness in which temporal .happiness and eternal beatitude participate unequally. It is a more perfect parallel, not only because the analogical goods being compared are; in both cases, the ends of voluntary action, but · also because the inequality of the ends achieved is proportionate to the inequality of the causes (natural and supernatural virtue, in the case of happiness; diverse forms of government, in the case of the common good) . And these causes are themselves unequally good within the analogy ot goodness, whether goodness be attributed to them as productive means or as intermediate ends. Finally, if one compare any existential common good with the ideal common good, the analogy is primarily with respect to their mode of being (actual and potential), and only secondarily with respect to their grade of goodness. Cf. Maritain, True Humanism, pp. 131 fl'.;.and St. Thomas, In Pol., VII, 3; Summa Theologica, 11-11, 61, I, ad I. •• That a form of government is· specified by principles of justice indicates that it is a bonum honestum, and that it can be an end having intrinsic moral worth, not merely a• means having extrinsic utility. As an end, a form of government may be either an already achieved good to be preserved, or an ideal good to be attained. In either case, a form of government is an end in the sense of finis causa, just as the common good as an end to be preserved or attained is finis ccMa;a, though in the first case it must also be existential and finis effectus. Political activity working for progress must, therefore, aim not only at an ideal common good (to be attained) and at the existential common good (to be preserved as a condition of progress), but it must aim also at an ideal form of government, correlative with the ideal common good to be attained, and at the existing form of government correlative with the existential common good to be preserved. Thus we see the sense in which a form ,of government, as existing or ideal, is a finis causa of political activity, as intermediate end and productive means. But this must not lead us to confuse the two ways in which forms of government can be ordered in a moral THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 635 6. Two things remain for discussion to conclude the analysis of the common good in the Theory of Democracy. The first is the problem of putting together the two classifications of government, of relating the generic distinction between good and bad government to the several specific distinctions among good governmental forms. 94 The second concerns the dynamism of political change, the steps of progress and the processes of corruption in the political order. 95 We shall treat briefly of these matters in the order indicated. 96 (1) The problem of relating the one generic and the three specific distinctions is focused by the ambiguity of the trahierarchy: primarily, though extrinsically, by correlation with the grades of existential common good which they effectively establish in being; secondarily, though intrinsically, as intermediate ends (finis causa), unequal because specified by principles of justice. The crucial difference between the Theory of Democracy and the traditional classification of governments should now be perfectly clear. According to traditional theory, there is only a generic moral distinction among forms of government: as rightly used or perverted. The several forms of government which can be good are specified by non-moral criteria: by the number of rulers, or by the aspect of the common good being ·emphasized. According to the first mode of specification, monarchy, is supposed to be best because most efficient in procuring and sustaining the unity of peace; according to the second mode of specification, the mixed regime is supposed to be best because combining the three aspects of the common good which each of the pure forms of government stresses; even so, the mixed regime is best because it most efficiently realizes all aspects of the common good. Hence, in neither case, is one form of government morally better than another, either intrinsically as a .bonum honestum, or extrinsically by correlation with a higher grade of achieved common good (note: not a fuller realization of the same, univocal, grade of common good) . Once forms of government are seen to be specified by principles of justice, once they are understood as the effective means for producing diverse existential common goods (as finis effectus), the classification of specific forms of government, and kinds of states, is radically shifted. It ceases to be a prudential ordering in terms of efficiency with respect to the same end; it becomes a moral ordering in terms of the achieved goodness of diverse ends, and in terms of the intrinsic worth of their correlative means. •• Vd. Part I, supra, loc. cit., pp. 96 Vd. ibid. The second of these problems is inseparable from the first, because the generic distinction depends on the ideal common good which is the end of progressive action, and progress itself must be understood in terms of the various grades of existential common good through the successive achievement of which a community is transformed from one kind of state to another, and better, kind. •• These matters will be more fully ·discussed in Parts IV- VI, infra. 686 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL ditional phrase: "rule for the common good." Aristotle and St. Thomas used the criterion expressed by this phrase to make the generic distinction. 97 But because neither Aristotle nor St. Thomas recognized the possjbility of specific moral distinctions among good forms of government, 98 they did not distinguish between the just exercise of political power (i.e., effecting an existential common good) as one of the three elements of political justice and the right use of political institutions (i. e., aiming at the ideal common good) as the trait which divides good from bad government generically. The phrase, " rule for the common good," -generalized to mean a just exercise of political power on the part of any political agent, not simply rulers or officeholders-has this ambiguity because of the fundamental distinction between the common good as finis effectus and as finis By making the generic distinction, according to this criterion, Aristotle departs from the Platonic ·ordering of the six forms of government from best to worst. " The true forms of government," says Aristotle, " are those in which the one, or the few, or the many, govern with a view to the common interest; but governments in which the rule is with a view to the private interest, whether of the one or the few or the.many, are perversions" (Politics, III, 7, Cf. ibid., III, 6, U79°17-!U; and also Ethics, VIII, 10. St. Thomas follows Aristotle on this point without modification. " If, therefore, a group of free men is governed by their ruler for the common good of the group, that government will be right and just .... If, however, the government is organized, not for the common good of the group, but for the private interest of the ruler, it will be an unjust and perverted government " (De Regimine ·Principum, I, 1) . 98 The very heading of Ch. of De Regimine Principum, I, " It is more expedient that. a multitude of men living together be ruled by one man rather than by many " (italics ours), reveals that St. Thomas makes subordinate distinctions among good forms of government in prudential .terms--in terms of their efficiency or degree of utility in achieving the one end that is the .same for all good forms of government. Cf. fn. 93 supra. Thus, he writes: , "It is manifest that what is itself. one can more efficaciously bring about unity than several. . . . ·Therefore, the rule of one man is more useful than the rule of many " (italics ours) . It should be noted, furthermore, that in this chapter, St. Thomas says that " the chief concern of the ruler should be to procure the unity of peace " (italics ours), whereas in Ch. 15, he speaks of the ruler's threefold concern; the establishment, the preservation, and the improvement of the common good. If the word " prpcure " as used in Ch. is intended to signify the improvement of the common good, as well as its establishment and preservation, then it would be difficult for St. Thomas to avoid the unhappy consequences of an ambiguous use of the criterion expressed by " rule for the common good." THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 637 causa. Failing to make that distinction, Aristotle and St. Thomas used the criterion expressed by this phrase, to divide true from perverted governments, but they used it in a sense which either emphasized the common good as finis effectus (Aristotle), or failed to exclude the common good as finis effectus (St. Thomas) .99 Hence the traditional analysis is not merely inadequate, but somewhat confused. We have used the criterion (just exercise of politwal power) as one of three separable and cumulatively combinable elements of political justice. We have symbolized it as the A factor; the B factor being just constitution of political power; the C factor being just distribution of political status .100 Our analysis will be as confused as the traditional account unless we can separate the A factor which, taken by itself, specifies the least perfect of the good forms of government, from the generic factor (still to be named and symbolized) that qualifies all good governments. 101 It may be thought that such separation is not necessary because, since the A factor is the minimal condition of justice in government, it must be possessed not only by the least perfect of the good forms, but by the superior forms as well. This would seem to be indicated by the symbolization of the three forms!: A (B, C); II: AB (C); ill: ABC. It appears that A is common to all three; hence, it may be asked, why is not this A factor the principle of the generic distinction between all the true forms and their perversions? There are two reasons why this is impossible. The first is that the three good forms cannot be morally specified or ordered in a moral hierarchy unless the common goods which are the achieved ends (finis effectus) of each are themselves diverse and unequal within the analogy of common goodness. That being so, the A factor is not univocal in the three cases; but a generic difference must be univocal, at least in so far as it •• Vd. fn. 76 and 98 supra. Vd. ·Part I, supra, loc. cit., pp. 418-422. 101 It was such inadequacy of analysis, with consequent confusion, that Father Farrell detected in Dr. Adler's original memorandum, The I{emonstration of Democracy. Vd. Part I, supra, loc. cit., pp. 1405 fl'. 100 638 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL divides one set of species from another; hence the presence of the A factor in the moral character of each of the three good forms of government cannot be the root of generic di:fferentiation.10a- The second reason is that, if the three specific factors can be separately corrupted in the perversion of the good forms, then it is at least conceivable that, in the perversion of III (specified by ABC) , bad forms of government will occur in which A is conjoined with the corruption of B or C or both. If we symbolize the corruption of the elements of justice by small letters, Democracy would seem to be capable of three degrees of corruption, indicated by ABc, Abc, and abc. That seeming to be possible, how can A be regarded as the root of generic . differentiation, since two of the three possible corruptions of Democracy retain the A factor? Hence, paradoxically, the attempt to use the A factor to make the generic distinction (because it is present in all three of the good forms) must result in the denial, or violation, of any generic distinction (because some of the perversions of the morally best form are also characterized by the presence of this same factor) . Our task, therefore, is double: we must not only formulate the generic criterion in a manner clearly distinct from what is signified by A, but also consider whether the perversions of Democracy, symbolized by ABc and Abc, are possible. The problem is solved by distinguishing the generic from the specific meaning of " rule for the common good," according as the common good is understood as existential or ideal, finis effectus or finis causa. In its generic signification, "rule for the common good " means that whatever elements of justice are present in the moral character of the specific forms of government are all being directed toward the end of progress; or, in other words, that political activity through governmental institutions (whether on the part of the primary agents, i.e., real persons, or on the part of the state) aims at the ideal common good to be achieved, as well as works for preservation of the ex' 02 The point here about analogy and univocity will be more fully· discussed very shortly. THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 639 istential common good for the sake of progress. In its specific signification, "rule for the common goo9." means that political power has been justly employed with the result that a common good, of some grade of perfection, exists; or, in other words, the A factor is indicated as the cause of the state's minimum wellbeing; hence, when this factor is the only cause of the state's well-being, the least perfect common good is achieved as a result; and when it is combined with one or both of the remaining factors (B and C) , the actual well-being of the state is increased -more perfect grades of common good are achieved. Since the common good must first be achieved, and exist in some grade, before it can be improved, or preserved for the sake of improvement-since, in the order of generation, the common good as finis effeatus is prior to the common good as finis causa 108 -the generic factor must be understood as qualifying each of the specific factors which is already present; for once they are present and effectively establish the state in some grade of wellbeing, they can also be directed to the state's improvement, i. e., its motion from a less to a more perfect grade of well-being. Therefore, the generic factor should be represented as an exponent which either does or does not qualify the significance of of the specific factors. The presence or absence of this exponent divides each of the good forms of government from its characteristic perversions, and thus all the good forms are univocally distinguished from all the corruptions. Let us summarize this analysis by using the letter x, as an exponential factor, to symbolize the generic criterion of political goodness. The three good forms of government will then be represented in the following manner, and the symbols thus interpreted. I: Ax (B, C): Royal government, through which the least grade of common good is effected by the just exercise of 103 This is 'not inconsistent with the fact that, in the logical order, i.e., the order of analysis, the common good as finis causa, being the source of generic distinction, must be prior to 'the common good as finis effectus, which is involved in the specific distinctions. 8 640 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL political power, A; and in which that achieved common good is also an end (finis causa) to be preserved for the sake of attaining the ideal common good. (Here the B and C factors are not corruptible for they have not yet come into being as political institutions; and, since they are non-existent, they cannot be directed to a further end; hence the exponential factor, x, does not qualify their significance.) II: AxB" (C): Republican government, through which the next grade of common good is effected by the just exercise of political power, A, combined with the just constitution of political power, B; and in which that achieved common good is also an end to be preserved for the sake of attaining the ideal common good. (What was said before about the factors in parentheses applies here.) III: AxBxcx: Democratic government, through which the highest grade of common good is effected by the just exercise, A, of justly constituted, B, political power, combined with the just distribution of political status, C; and in which that achieved common good is also an end to be preserved for the sake of attaining the ideal common good. The following commentary is necessary to interpret what is here set forth. The generic factor (symbolized by the exponent x) has univocal signification throughout. In every case, it is the same qualification of existing governmental institutionsthat political activity is being directed, through them, to the ideal common good (both by the work· of preservation and by the work of improvement). This univocity is not affected by the fact that the proximate stage of improvement is not the same in Case I and Case II, for example, because the ultimate term of improvement, the end which defines the motion of progress, is the same: the ideal common good, absolutely considered. Nor is it affected by the fact that it qualifies factors which are specifically distinct from one another, for the meaning of x remains the same whether it is the exponent of A or B or C: it signifies that a just constitution, achieving a certain grade of THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 641 common good, is directed beyond this achievement to the ideal common good not yet attained; or that a just distribution of status, beyond achieving a higher grade of common good, is similarly directed. The only difficulty here arises with respect to the meaning of x as applied to A. How can the A factor (just exercise of political power) ever exist apart from x (the direction of political activity toward the ideal common good) ? And, on the other hand, if the A factor be totally corrupted, i. e., totally lost, how can the state exist at all? If the least good state is one in which A is the only factor operating to effect a common good, then the total negation of this factor, symbolized by a, must result in the annihilation of the state, the non-being of a common good. Hence we see that the corruption of the Royal state, Ax (B, C), cannot be understood in terms of what is signified by a (B, C). There must, therefore, be a mean term between Ax and a. This difficulty is solved when we realize that, in the process of corruption, the B and C factors can be totally lost as well as diminished, whereas the A factor can only be diminished, but never totally lost, even though it approach the vanishing point; for when its vanishing point is reached, the state itself to be, and no common good remains to be mulcted for the private interests of the miscreants. Even the worst tyrant works against anarchy, and so long as he succeeds there must be some political action which keeps the state in being. Such action usually takes the form of obedience to the tyrant's decrees; and this action, on the part of the members of the community, is a just exercise of their political power, even though the decrees themselves are unjust and deleterious to the common good. When the justice of civil obedience reaches the vanishing point, civil war occurs, and the very being of the state is in peril. In short, whereas Ax signifies the just exercise of political power on the part of both rulers and ruled, the absence of x signifies that the rulers are exploiting the common good, and that the state continues to endure only because some of its members, i.e., the ruled, continue to act justly, even though the justice of their action must 642 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL be qualified by its relativity to an unjust state. 103 " Here, then, is the mean term between Ax and a, and we shall symbolize it by a. There is no problem about Bx and b, or Cx and c, for constitutionality or distributive justice may be totally lost.as well as attentuated. When Republican or Democratic governments undergo corruption, the negation of x first results in the attentuation of A (symbolized by a); concurrently there must be some attentuation of B and C (symbolized by B and C) ; and subsequently there may result the total loss of B and C (symbolized by b and c) . In other words, none of the elements of justice can continue undiminished when political action is no longer directed to the ideal common good; but neither can that element of justice which is ·an exercise of political power for the existing common good ever be totally lost; for if it be not sustained (by the action of the ruled, if not by the action of the rulers) , the political malefactors cannot aggrandize their private interests by despoiling or looting the fruits of the common good, convertible with the state's existence in some degree of wellbeing, however reduced or depleted that may be. To succeed in their nefarious enterprise, tyrants must obtain obedience and cooperation from the people they misrule, whether by force or guile, for without this wraith of justice, the bad state does not even imitate a political community, and the tyrant cannot privately profit at the expense of the common good/ 04 And, finally, we see that Ax has only an analogical unity of meaning as it occurs in the absence of B and C, i.e., with them 108 " Vd. Summa Theol., I-II, q. a. I, ad 4um. Cf. Ibid., q. 95, a. 4. Vd. also Politics III, 17, US7b 86-40. 1 "' Thus, we see the impossibility of the perversions of Democracy symbolized by ABc and Abc; and also the impossibility of the perversion of Republican government symbolized by Ab (C). Vd. p. 689 supra. As a matter of fact, even abc, aBC, aB (C), etc., are impossible. According to the aiJ.alysis given above, the only perversions which are possible in reality 1are: of AxBxcx, aBC, aBc, and abc; of AxBx (C), aB (C) and ab (C); and of Ax (B, C), a (B. C). These symbolizations h1dicate that when 'x is negated, the A factor must be attenuated, a, and the other factors which have already been realized, must either be attenuated (e. g., B) or lost (e. g., b). The negation 'of x causes a transformation in all of the factors to which it has been attached, but not the same transformation ill all at any given moment. THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 643 in potentiality, symbolized by (B) and (C); or as conjoined with the presence of Bx, or Bx and ex. (The same must be said for Bx in the absence of ex or conjoined with its presence.) This follows from the fact that the achieved common good is only analogically the same in these three cases. The just exercise of political power is not univocally the same in the case in which that power is also justly constituted and in the case in which it is not; nor is a just constitution of political power univocally the same in the case in which political status is justly distributed and in the case in which it is not. 105 105 The parallelism between the hierarchy of specific natures and the moral hierarchy of forms of government is thus fulfilled. Plants 'and brute animals are both vegetative, but animals are vegetative eminenter because their vegetative powers are conjoined, and elevated by cooperation, with the higher sensitive powers; similarly, both brutes and men are sensitive, but men are sensitive eminenter, because they are rationally sensitive. The addition of the sensitive to the vegetative, or the rational to the sensitive, nature is not an extrinsic conjunction, but a :penetrating and transforming one. We affirm 'this truth when we recognize that the powers of the lower nature are not present simply, but eminently, in the higher; and' this also means that plant and animal vegetation, brute and human sensitivity, are analogical, not univocal, by the analogy of inequality, of course, not the analogy of strict proportionality. The three species 1of soul participate in the generic nature of soul (as the principle of life), though unequally, because they confer less or more 'perfect grades of life upon the matter they inform. So the three forms of government participate in the generic moral quality· of goodness in political institutions, a quality which derives from the ultimate end (finis causa) being served; but they are unequally good because they effect less or more perfect grades of common good (finis effectus). Furthermore, no element of justice is univocally common to two or more forms, being present simpliciter in the inferior form and eminenter in the superior form. Finally, it should be noted that what is a specifying characteristic, differentiating a form of government from its inferior, is also an element further differentiated by the characteristic which specifies its superior: thus, just constitution is like sensitivity: as sensitivity both differentiates brute from plant life and also constitutes a nature that is subject to further differentiation by rationality, so the just constitution of political power both differentiates Republican from Royal government, and constitutes a form of government which can be further differentiated by the just distribution of political status. As only the animal nature is capable of being ·either rational or irrational (and, so being, is either specifically human or brutal), so only constitutional government can involve a 'just or an unjust distribution of citizenship (for there are no citizens in the Royal state), and is thus specifically either Democratic or Republican. supra. The fact 'that the hierarchy of living substances can be Cf. fn. 90 and perfectly represented by the symbols we have used to represent the hierarchy of 644 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL To complete our discussion of the generic and specific factors, in relation to and separation from each other, we turn now to the problems raised by political change. Let us first consider the processes of political corruption, and then the motions of progress. The primary cause of corruption is the same in every case, because all perverted forms of government are generically alike in being exploited for accidental, individual goods as the ultimate ends of action (finis causa), regardless of the difference in these institutions according to the specific form of the government being misused, and regardless of the difference in the type of accidental good, or of the particular role of the individual who his end in terms of it. What is univocally the same in every case is a turning away from the true end (i.e., the ideal common good as finis causa of political activity). What is not the same in every case is the apparent good toward which the political agent wrongly turns; nor need the political status or function of this agent be the same in every case. The secondary causes of corruption consist in the attentuation or total loss of the several specific factors of goodness in political regimes, with the important exception, already noted, in the case of the A factor, which can only be attenuated, not lost. When political agents turn away from the true end of political activity, they no longer seek to preserve the existential common good, in whatever grade it is effected by the existing institutions of government. Such preservation is never an end in itself, but only for the sake of progress. Furthermore, the preservation of the common good, as it exists, is usually incompatible with the effort to exploit it for private interests, except, as noted, in the extreme case in which the least degree of _government forms [Plant: A(B, C); Brute: AB (C); Man: ABC], with every consequence of such hierarchical ordering the same in both cases, should cause us to wonder how such a parallelism can exist, ·in view of the fact that the State is, ontologically speaking, an accidental being, and not a substance. Vd. M. J. Adler, "The Solution of the Problem of Species," in 'THE THOMIST, III, 2, 279-879. This is a metaphysical question of great interest, but it does not concern us here. We shall return to its consideration in Part VI infra. THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 645 common good must be preserved, in no more than an attenuated form, for the state itself to endure and for its fruits to be appropriated, rather than distributed. These things being so, corrupt forms of government can be distinguished specifically in the same way as the true forms are specifically distinguished. Each form of government is differently subject to processes of corruption, which are relative to the grade of common good achieved through its characteristic institutions, even though the primary, or generic, cause of corruption is always the same. The important point to remember here is that institutions cannot be perverted until they exist; elements of political justice cannot be attenuated or destroyed until, in the course of political change, they have first been realized. The retrogressive motion of political corruption must, therefore, be seen in relation to the progressive motion of political improvement. And this means that the more primitive a state is (the less justice that is achieved by such regimes) , the less susceptible it is to corruption. The more advanced a society is politically, the greater the opportunity for political decay, both in the variety of perversions and their extent. The following diagram summarizes this account of the stages and causes of political corruption. Good Governments I: Royal: Perverted Governments I1: a{B, C) II: Republican: A•B•(C) TII: Democratic: AxBxcx Note The letters in parentheses indicate potential factors, i. e., factors which have not yet come into existence. The italicized a indicates 646 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL the attentuation of the one factor which cannot be totally lost. The italicized B and C indicate the attentuation of these factors, whereas the small letters b and c indicate their total loss. The diagram makes apparent that the negation of the generic factor x does not always have the same effect. The effect varies according to the grade of common good already achieved, symbolized by the factors present in the character of the several good governments, and according to the extent to which corruption has taken place. The first degree of corruption always involves the attenuation of the A factor, symbolized by a, but thisis not the same on all three levels, for on level III, the attentuation of A is accompanied by the attentuation of B and C, whereas on level II, it is accompanied by the attentuation only of B; and on level I, the attentuation of A may be the sole perversion. Furthermore, whereas only one degree of perversion is possible with respect to I, two degrees are possible with respect to II, the second being the attentuation of A accompanied by the loss of B; and three degrees of perversion are possible with respect to III, the second being the attenuation of A, accompanied by the attentuation of B and the loss of C; the third being the attenuation of A accompanied by the loss of both Band C. The subscript numbers attached to the Roman numerals in the columns to the right thus signify the retrogressive stages through which a form of government can go in the process of corruption. The horizontal motion from left to right is the initial step of corruption, what we have called the direct, or first degree of, perversion; the oblique motion to the right and upward indicates the steps by which the corruption becomes more complete, approaching the vanishing point in every case. This diagram must not be misinterpreted as portraying the actual historic motions of political change, progressive or retrogressive. It is rather a purely formal map of the routes which such change can take. It indicates the main stages through which a political community can pass in developing or decaying, but it does not record the actual motions; nor could they be recorded in a simple diagram, for they are not ever uniformly progressive or retrogressive. Progress may occur either in the downward path in the left column, or by lateral motion from right to left, or by oblique motion from right to left and downward-the latter two usually being motions caused by violent revolution. We shall not pause here to describe the precise character of each of the perverted forms. That can be better done in Parts IV, V, and VI subsequently, when we undertake the fuller THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 647 analysis, as well as the demonstration of, the specificity of the three forms which can either be good or perverted. 106 Here suffice it to point out that the location of a form in the left or the right column is determined by the presence or absence (by negation) of the generic exponent x; and that the further location of each form on a given plane, according to its subscript number, is determined by the number of specific factors which have been attenuated or lost. The inequality of II1 and III2, or of I1, II2, and Ills, as perversions is proportional to the inequality of I, II, and III as good forms of government, though the order is inverse. As III is superior in goodness to II, because II lacks the C factor which III possesses, so II1 is not as bad as III2 because the loss of the C factor, once achieved, is worse than the mere absence of this factor, i.e., its being in potentiality; furthermore, the attentuation of the A and B factors is greater in III2 than II1. The partial equality of IL and III2 is indicated by their being placed on the same horizontal level; that III2 lies to the right of II1 indicates that it is a more extensive corruption, which is due to the fact that it is the perversion of a better state in the second degree. Finally, we see that the traditional saying, that the worst perversion of government is the opposite of the best, is abso106 Furthermore, the present account of political change is non-historical. As already pointed out (in the Note attached to the diagram), we are here concerned only with the formal analysis of the stages of progress or corruption-with the definition of the points between ·which such political change can take place. The traditional account of political dynamics is inadequate because its formal definition of the points between which ·change can take place is incomplete, due to the inadequacy in the traditional classification of good states and their perversions. Vd. fn. 107 infra. But the present analysis will be misunderstood if its attempt to be adequate formally is mistaken as an effort to be historically adequate. The motions of political history are never simply forward or backward; they are interrupted by all sorts of see-sawing back and forth; they are usually cyclical as well as rectilinear, and the composition of these two types of motion results in a spiral motion forward. Vd. "The Demonstration of Democracy," in the Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, XV: Note 47. In Parts IV, V, and VI of the present work, we shall not only deal concretely with the various types of perversion to which each good form of government is susceptible, but we shall also try to describe the actual motions of corruption as these have occurred, for the most part, in history. 648 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL lutely false. For if III be best, then the worst perversion is clearly Ills, which is the most complete corruption of the best. Speaking diagrammatically, the truth is that the worst is not the direct opposite of the best, but the furthest removed from the best. Even if we restrict our attention to the direct opposites (the first stages of perversion: III1, II1, and I1) , the traditional remark, made in terms of tyranny as opposed to monarchy (on the supposition that monarchy is best, for whatever reasons), still is false: for the direct opposite, or first perversion, of the best government is better than the direct opposite, or first perversion, of the least good government, in the same proportion as the best is better than the least good, and for the same reason: more elements of justice in the common good susceptible of decay, and more still retained in that first stage of corruption. The falsity of the traditional statement about the worst being opposite to the best follows from the falsity of the traditional analysis: its inadequacy with respect to specific moral distinctions, and its confusion of the two significations of "rule for the common good." Only on the sort of suppositions which make it possible to say that monarchy is the best form of government because rule by one is more efficient in effecting or improving the common good, can it be said that tyranny is worst, because one man can misrule, can despoil or exploit the common good, more efficiently than many. But if monarchy is not even a distinct form of government, because the numerical distribution of ruling offices determines only an accidental mode of government which can occur in any form, and if forms of government are not graded according to efficiency, but according to intrinsic elements of justice and the grade of common good these effect, then the worst perversion is furthest removed from the best form, and the direct opposite of the best form is the least perversion. 107 107 In fairness to Aristotle, it must be pointed out that he says, in one place, that the worst is furthest removed from the best (Politics, IV, even though, in another, he inconsistently says that the opposite of the best is worst (ibid., . St. Thomas, however, simply says that " the worst is opposed to the best," and therefore " just as the government of a king is the best, the govern- THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 649 Although the primary cause of corruption is the same in every case, i.e., the alienation of political action from its due end (signified by the negation of the generic exponent x), and although we can enumerate the secondary causes of corruption, in terms of the several specific factors which can be attenuated or lost, we cannot formulate the aetiology of progress merely by reference to the objectives of political activity. While it is true that the direction of political activity toward the ideal common good is a cause of progress; and even true that this is the essential cause, in so far as political developments are voluntarily and intentionally achieved; nevertheless, political progress may be prompted or facilitated by the operation of all sorts of accidental causes, such as improvements in the physical conditions of human life, alterations in economy, the discoveries and inventions which produce fundamental changes in the human community by altering the modes of communcation. There are also basic spiritual changes in human civilization, such as the advent and spread of Christianity, which transform the very atmosphere of political life, and condition every phase of political activity .108 Finally, political progress may be effected peacefully or it may depend upon resort to revolutionary violence; in the latter case, progress may consist in a motion from right to left in the diagram, horizontally, or obliquely downward; and such motions cannot be accounted for in terms of the x facment of a tyrant is worst " (De Regimine P1incipum. I, 3) . This statement is correct on St. Thomas's suppositions, indicated in the text above; but the suppositions are false. Apart from questions of truth and falsity, 'with respect to the traditional analysis and the one here being presented, the radical difference between these two analyses should be clear to the reader in terms of the radical divergence between the two accounts of political corruption. Just as the traditional theory seems to us to be inadequate in its understanding of progress, so does it fail to penetrate the manifold phenomena of corruption. Both are due to the same defects of analysis; unless the existential and the ideal common good are distinguished, unless specific moral gradations in forms of government are understood in terms of the common good as finis effectus, the motions of political change, forward or backward, cannot be rendered intelligible in the light of principles. Political dynamism is too complex to be formulated by a too simple classification of governments and their perversions. us Vd. "The Demonstration ·of Democracy," loc. cit., notes 51, 52, 53. 650 M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL tor. Our present discussion is, therefore, limited to the simple cases in which progress occurs as a downward motion in the left column, and in which the ideal common good, as an objective of political activity, is a cause, even though not sufficient by itself. Here, as before, our aim is analytical not historical. We shall return to historical considerations, and to the details of aetiology, in Parts IV, V, and VI. 109 With respect to progress, only one problem needs to be discussed here. It would appear, on the one hand, that the transition from the Royal to the Republican state, and the transition from the Republican to the Democratic state, are both progressive motions, though the ideal common good which terminates these two motions is not the same in both cases; and, on the other hand, it would appear that there can be no meaning to the exponential factor x (signifying the direction of activity toward the ideal common good) in the case of the Democratic state, for, this being the best state, the ideal is already achieved once it exists. These two apparent difficulties are aspects of the same problem. To remove them, we have to distinguish several senses in which the ideal common good can be understood as the term of progress. In the first place, we must distinguish between an ideal which is the proximate term of a progressive development and the ideal which is the ultimate term of all progress. According to the significance of the generic criterion of good political activity, a Royal state is not generically good unless it aims to supersede itself by setting up Republican institutions; and a Republican state is not generically good unless it aims to supersede itself by setting up Democratic institutions.no Now, then, the com109 Vd. fn. 106 supra. no In aiming to supersede itself the Royal state must work to create the conditions (economic, physical, educational, etc.), relative to which a better form of government (i. e., Republican) would be best; similarly, the Republican ·state must work to create the conditions, relative to which a better form of government (i. e., Democratic) would be best. The best government, absolutely speaking,· is also the form of government which is best relative to the best conditions. Vd. Part I, supra, loc. cit., pp. 432-435. Cf. Essay on RBpresentative Government, Ch. IV, wherein Mill argues that, although certain inferior conditions may justify Royal government THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 651 mon good which can be effected by Republican institutions is ideal relative to the existential common good of a Royal state; similarly, in the case of the common good which can be effected by Democratic institutions, in relation to the existential common good of a Republican state; these relative ideals are the proximate ends of progressive change. Beyond them is the absolute ideal-the ultimate end of such change. The plurality of such relative ideals does not violate the principle that the common good as finis causa must be one, in order to establish the unity of the generic distinction; because these relative ideals are subsumed by the absolute, as the ultimate term of motion subordinates the proximate terms, which are really only halfway marks that the motion traverses to reach its goal.m (i.e., nonconstitutional rule) as best relative to those conditions, a benevolent despot is one who not only acts for the present well-being of the community, but one who also seeks to improve the conditions of the people so that, in the future, Republican rather than Royal government will be the best relatively. 111 This distinction between the ,one ideal common good, as the absolute term of political progress, and the many ideal common goods, as the relative stages through which such development passes, must not be confused with the distinction between the best government absolutely and the best government relative to the contingent circumstances of an historic community. The relativity is not the same in both cases: when we speak of a government as being best relative to the contingent circumstances of a particular community, we are considering the grade of political institutions which can be achieved by this community at a given time; when we speak of the common good which is the next, or proximate, stage of political development, as being relatively ideal, we are considering, not the institutions which should now be achieved, but those which, should next be reached in the course of progress. That which is the best form of government absolutely, however, is also the form of government which is correlative with the absolutely ideal common good-the ultimate term to be reached by progress. In this connection, it should be noted that the progressive step from the least perfect state, A (B, C), to its proximate superior, AB (C), is only analogically, not univocally, the same as the step from the less perfect state, AB (C), to the most perfect, ABC. In the first case, constitutional government is instituted to replace the exercise of merely de facto power; in the second case, constitutional government is itself perfected ·by distributive justice with respect to political status, especially citizenship. Here there is '.a parallelism between evolution in the natural order and progress in the moral order, which accords with the parallelism between the natural and the moral hierarchies: the transition from plants to brutes entails the emergence of some cognitive power; the transition from brutes to men entails the perfection of cognition by the addition of reason. M. J. ADLER AND WALTER FARRELL In the second place, we must recognize that, although Democratic government is best absolutely, the pGlitical perfection it can effect may be less or more fully realized in the existential common good of the Democratic state. Hence, even when the Democratic state exists, the ideal common good may still remain to be achieved in its fullness. As a relative end, the Democratic state, in any degree of realization, is the proximate term of progress in the transition from the Republican state. .But the fullest realization of the political perfection that is possible under the Democratic form is the ideal common good absolutely, the ultimate term of progress which is the objective of good political activity in the Democratic state, as well as in inferior states.m This will always be the case because, in the nature of man's earthly condition, the ideal commonwealth will never be perfectly embodied in any temporal community. Democracy is not, like Plato's state, a city in the skies. It has already begun to exist on earth. But the conditions for its perfect flowering impose such a burden upon the weakness of the flesh, that the human spirit will struggle throughout the rest of history to bring Democracy to mature fruition. For when the ideal common good is fully achieved, when human potentialities for political life are perfectly actualized in the community of men, the motion of history must itself be at an end. The end which is the origin of every good intention is also the complete good in which execution culminates. WALTER FARRELL, O.P. Dmninican House of Studies, Washington, D. C. MoRT1MER (Part Ill will appear in the next issue.) 112 Cf. Part I. suJYTa, loc. cit., pp. 436-440. J. ADLER University of Chicago, Chicago, Illinois BOOK REVIEWS The City of Man. Issued by: HERBERT AGAR, FRANK AYDELOTTE, G. A. BoRGESE, liERMANN BROCH, VAN WYcK BROOKS, ADA L. CoMsTocK, WILLIAM YANDELL ELLIOTT, DoROTHY CANFIELD FISHER, CHRISTIAN GAuss, OscAR JASzi, ALVIN JoHNSON, HANs KoHN, THOMAS MANN, LEWIS MUMFORD, WILLU.M ALLAN NEILSON, REINHOLD NIEBUHR, GAETANO SALVEMINI. New York: The Viking Press, 1940. Pp. 113. $1.00. This very small book is described by its publishers as the outcome of collective thinking by a group of persons profoundly concerned about the future of civilization; it states their faith and hope. Though very small, the book is important by reason of the men and women who have sponsored it; the extended examination of it which will be given here has however, quite another basis than the importance of the editors of the hook. This work must be analyzed carefully, evaluated solidly and judged with unyielding justice, for its compact thesis represents one of the most serious intellectual threats yet to be offered to western civilization. Mechanically, and logically, the book is split into three parts: the :first is a" Declaration" which contains the thesis of the sponsors of the work; the second, a " Proposal," is a detailed plan for the furthering and execution of this thesis; the third, a "Note," gives the historical genesis of the Declaration and the Proposal. The book is much more intelligible if its parts are read in reverse order. The history is a plain matter-of-fact statement of the origin of the thesis, the Proposal, smacking somewhat of the grandiose and the utopian, is yet quite clear and orderly in the plans it lays down, while the Declaration, frankly apocalyptic, concentrates much more intensely on phrasing than on clarity of thought. * * * The story of the two documents (pp. 97-113), the Declaration and the Proposal, goes back well over two years and is dated by the catastrophes suffered by democratic countries beginning with Munich in 1938. The story begins with an exchange of ideas by a small group of friends; by May, 1939, the motives and intentions of this group had been stated in the form of a memorandum. Let it be said here that those motives and intentions were of the noblest. It was proposed to institute in America a " Committee on Europe " consisting of a small number of the most prominent intellectual and political exiles from Europe and a majority of American thinkers and scientists. It was hoped that the work of the committee " would supply 653 654 BOOK REVIEWS the statesmen of a period of reconstruction with decisive material in all fields of national and international affairs," even down to such details as the relations between the churches and the state, of the family and the city, eugenics, tradition and initiative in education, with a complete willingness to go into much greater detail if it should seem beneficial. The reasons that inspired the formation of this committee were decidedly concrete. There was the actual condition of Europe, the opportunity offered to America in its possession of confidence, optimism, American scholars, and prominent European personalities. More strong, perhaps, in its motive power, was the realization that the events of the past twenty years were in great part due to the action of a misled intelligentsia. Some reparation is certainly called for; this committee was visualized as offering the intellectual elite a chance to take their proper place and do their proper work in the affairs of the world. The leading committee was to consist of not more than fifteen men to be provided with staffs of scholars and students. Though the Memorandum was circulated among friends, the work was slowed down by the outbreak of war; soon it became obvious that there were many parallel efforts being made along the same line, but, because these somewhat rival efforts were not as sweeping in their consideration of what were considered essential criteria, the work of the original Committee was continued and a letter of invitation sent out in March, 1940. This letter outlined the motives and aims of the Committee to a limited number of prospective collaborators. A meeting of the Committee was held in May, 1940, at which the name was changed to a " Committee of Fifteen," a plan of work discussed, and a subcommittee appointed to draft the statement of the ideas and purposes which prevailed during this meeting. Another conference in August of 191.0 discussed the work of the subcommittee and· approved it as a Declaration and a Proposal-the remainder of this book. Here too, William Allan Neilson was elected chairman; his assistants, Herbert Agar, W. Y. Elliot, Lewis Mumford, and G. A. Borgese, secretary, make up the Executive Board. Before going on to the Proposal, there are several significant things to be noted in this historical note. First of all is the make-up of the Executive Board, with particular emphasis on the distinctive work of the particular officers. Another is the fact that the letter of invitation had among its original signers, Robert M. Hutchins; a name that henceforth disappears altogether. Then, too, there are many statements made in the course of the historical note that leave little doubt as· to which way the wind was blowing. It is noted, for example, on p. 106, that "no definition or redefinition of democracy is practically or logically tenable without its premise in a statement of fundamental religious beliefs." On p. 100 the opportunity of America was summed up in terms of American confidence, optimism, BOOK REVIEWS 655 scholars and European personalities-odd ingredients for the fundamental statement aimed at by the Committee. On p. 108 it is insisted that: At last the intelligentsia should be taken down to the earth from the midair between clouds and earth where it has hovered for centuries, content with the worship of undefined or approximately defined deities such as Justice, Freedom, Democracy, and be put to a real, steady, and substantial work through which those venerable and significant abstractions may become the pulp and nerve of practical statesmanship in a day to come. * * * The Proposal (pp. 75-96}, which is the working plan outlined in the second part of the book, takes the wraps off some of the dark horses that stalked the historical note, but not all the wraps. It proposes a supergroup of super-experts; not an original idea, by any means, but rather a haunting dream since the opening of the scientific era. Dr. Carrel proposed such a super-scientific group for quite another purpose in his Man The Unknown; undoubtedly other super-scientific groups will be planned again in the future when men come face to face with the difficulties that are outside the field of science. This particular super-group of super-experts is to consist really of four groups of experts working under the central committee. The experts are to study the four leading issues of American and world democracy, namely, the constitutional, economic, and international-all converging toward the common apex of freedom and the dignity of the human personality-and the common base which is moral belief and the religious faith of the community. The experts studying the constitutional issue will concern themselves with the relations between democracy and individual liberties. It is necessary to have a definition of liberty and a constitutional reform both in the field of liberty and duty and in the relations between legislative and executive power. These things cannot be founded but on the spirit of a new religion. The religious issue contemplates the relations between the community as a whole and the separate churches. It asks for definite tenets embodying the universal religion of Democracy, which shall underlie each and all of them. The e:Kperts then must investigate what limits are set by the religion of freedom and determine of what God we talk. They must determine what religious and ethical traditions are of greater or lesser value for the preservation and growth of the democratic principle. These same religious experts will explore the issue of education. The two, religion and education, are at bottom one and the same for " education in western democracy has been the substitute for a national and supra-national religion." The experts in economics will outline in detail the law of the common wealth, the era of distributive justice. The group on the international issue will call for a definite law of international, or supra-national, order and the sovereignty of mankind. We 9 666 BOOK REVIEWS need a universal law first promulgated to all humanity; it is entrusted to the good will of the groups progressively disposed to adopt it and then it is to be enforced on the rebels, finally to become the common peace and freedom of all the peoples of the earth. * * Coming from such a group of American thinkers, the Declaration (pp. Il-78) with which this book begins, is a momentous document. It begins with a statement of the world today, bitterly condemnatory of Nazism and ruthlessly critical of the decay of democracy in America. This latter is described as the disintegration of what had been a strenuous unity of thought and action, a rule for life and death, a faith militant and triumphant. Among the causes of the disintegration are mentioned educational relativism which doubted all values, science shirking spiritual issues and promising material delights while withholding the fulfillment of the promise to an ever imminent future, thus goading the masses to despair. America is held out as the hope of the world if it renews the faith and hope that once made it strong and takes a stand against the enslavers of Europe. The finger of accusation for the world's plight is pointed at the heralds of antichrist, irresponsible artists and scientists, intellectual leaders and their pupils,' the ruling classes and statesmen of the world, along with all contemporaries who accepted this culture and immersed themselves in it. The present peril and challenge is accepted as an ordeal by tyranny; in opposition to it is offered the ancient, imperishable dream of man. With this introductory material out of the way, the Declaration quickly gets down to the business in hand. The order of procedure is not at all evident; as far as long study can unearth it, it would seem to be about like this: (I) Affirmations on the goal of man, on war and peace, and on the City of Man (including its definition, structure, nature and history, method and genesis). (2) The total character of the City of Man and its place as the source of·morals. {3) Its religious and apocalyptic character. (4) The fate of the churches. (5) The common creed of the new religion. {6) Sociology and economics of Democracy. (7) The leadership of America. AFFIRMATIONS (pp. 20-27) There is no distinction between the individual and collective meaning and goal of human life. Both consist in progress and growth in intellect and action; for this an essential pre-requisite is universal peace. Man's 657 BOOK REVIEWS effort is, in fact, endless; there is no perfectibility which leads to an ultimate and unchanging perfection for mankind to live in happily ever after. Milleniums are the infinity of man's dream enclosed in brief myths, and each horizon opens into another. There is, however, a distinction between the perpetuity of chance and struggle and the inevitability of slaughter and arson. War is chaos and horror. It is now returning from standards of epic piety and chivalric honor to the indiscriminate atrocity of primal murder. Peace is the harmony of strong souls, not the fightless impotence of slaves; its price is readiness to fight. It is founded only on the unity of man under one law and government and is the sine-qua-non of advance beyond the present threat and ruin. The City of Man is a nation of Man embodied in the Universal State, the State of States, a necessity because the national states have built no eternal pattern of collective life. Its structure will preclude small nations, for these have freedom only as a gift from stronger states; and it will bar the giant states whose very size bids for the anarchy of violence and conquest. All centralized structures must fall into small federal units; all states, deflated and disciplined, must align themselves under the law of the world-state if the world is to have peace. It opposes universality to totalitarianism, republican unity to autarchic despotism; that this is feasible is indicated by the existence of the Swiss and American federations. Its method will be regional centralization ·which will distribute power to the smallest unit, and world-wide authority assuring the cooperation of all. These two· elements, the centripetal and peripheral, are essential to each other. With one or the other submerged, there results tyranny or chaos; together they give a working base for freedoman order that is strong and flexible. Before this State of States can come into existence, it is probable that there will be a greater spread of the area of destruction-. In the first stages of reconstruction there must be leadership with power enduring until the laggards in barbarism or inertia are educated to the full responsibility of their coming freedom. All men of good will will work to make the interval of preparation short; all will be ready when the heresy of nationalism is conquered and the absurd architecture of the present world is dismantled. Then there will be a Universal Parliament representing people, not states; a fundamental body of law for all the planet in matters of interregional interests; an elected President of mankind embodying, for a limited term, common authority and common law; and a federal force to strike at anarchy and felony. CITY oF MAN AS ToTAL AND A SouRcE oF MoRALS (pp. 27-82) Universal and total democracy is a principle of liberty and life which man's dignity opposes to total autocracy's principle of slavery and death. 658 BOOK REVIEWS There is no other principle of liberty and life possible because this alone combines law, equality and justice. This is the ancient hope of man, its unity resting on three principles. The first of these is universal participation in government; this is the foundation of law. The second is that the state is the agent of collective human purposes, the servant of the conunon good; the unity of the people is the permanent source of power. This is the foundation of equality. The third, the fundamental principle, is that democracy is a community of persons. Its vigor rests on the cultivation and discipline of the person; its quality is the quality of education which it imparts to citizens and exacts from them. This is the foundation of justice. The enemies of democracy now say that it rests on opinion, having no conviction; so it becomes necessary to make a new foundation on the rock of conviction. Such convictions as determine its character are that there is no liberty but one-the right, which is a duty, of making oneself and others free through absolute allegiance to the final goal of man; there is no comfort but one-pride in duty performed. RELIGious AND APocALYPTIC CHARAcTER (pp. 88-45) Democracy, as a harmony subordinated to a plan, a purposive organism, must be redefined. It can be so defined as the plenitude of heart-service to a highest religion embodying the essence of all higher religions. Democracy is hum'anism in theocracy and rational theocracy in universal humanism. In this new religion of democracy the value of the individual is ultimate; the community must be ordered to promote the welfare and fulfillment of each person. But there is no individual good life outside society and the single citizen must strive toward a communal good which is beyond itself as it is beyond any single community and any passing generation. Everything must be within, nothing against, nothing outside humanity. A dictatorship of humanity on the basis of law for the protection of human dignity is the only rule from which there is hope for life. The only means to attain this universality is positive legislation. That is the only means to describe the relations of individual rights and social duties. No liberty can be granted to whosoever threatens the divine spirit in man and above man. This universal democracy, in an interpretation suited to the modern mind, is the spirit Christ called the Holy Ghost. It is ultimately sacred; Christ Himself marked the limits of tolerance and charity when He insisted that blasphemy against the Holy Ghost (that is, universal democracy) will not be forgiven. This religion of the Holy Ghost is the spirit of the New Testament of which a United States president spoke saying there is universal belief in it. There is this belief, even in those who were never BOOK REVIEWS 659 under the direct influence of Scripture, who reject all transcendent belief and cling to rational knowledge and scientific experiment alone. This universal religion was anticipated by sages and saints of all ages; its substance matured out of whatever rose highest in man's speculations and hopes, through the prophets of Israel, the religious geniuses of Asia, Greek poetry and philosophy, Rome, the Catholic Church, the Protestant insurrection, Humanism, Renaissance, the revolutions, the era of liberalism down to the optimistic philosophies of enlightenment. Each and all contain humanity and redemption; each and all are comprehended under the allembracing and all-interpreting religion of the Spirit. No one of these reached the universality of the religion of the Spirit; but none wilfully conflicted with the basic tenets on which the world religion of the Spirit is founded. The Catholic Church is so serious an offender against this world religion that pious Catholics of former ages would have called its present state a Babylonian captivity; the saints and doctors against Avignon were more articulate than Catholics of today. Catholics who are freedom-loving and justice-loving, whenever they can awaken to the examples of braver ages, will see to it some day that humility in faith be no longer the lure to servility in politics and that allegiance to the City of God be disentangled from bondage to the Vatican City as a foreign potentate in feud or trade with other potentates. The Religion of the Spirit acknowledges the incorruptible of truth underlying the surfaces and errors of the separate confessions which have risen from the common ground of ancient and medieval civilization. In this acknowledgment is the foundation of religious freedom in democracy. Democracy, in the catholicity of its language, interprets and justifies the separate creeds as- its own vernaculars. FA'l'E OF THE CHURCHES (pp. 45-46) None of these vernaculars can take the place of the universal language which expresses the common belief of man. The latter explains and annexes all dogmas as symbols. The churches anathematize as heresy the symbolical meaning that is dogma's inmost truth. We shall not turn from a higher and vaster religion to lesser ones. The old cults will have the protection of democracy; no church can be officially acknowledged as a religion of the state; no church can be granted primacy or privileges above others, in fact, the desire for such is a measure of its inadequacy to the fundamental principle of democracy. Separation of church and state is the base from which arises the supremacy of world-humanism and world-democracy-the catholicity of the common creed which embraces and interprets every lesser faith. 660 BOOK REVIEWS THE CoMMON CREED (pp. 46-48) This common creed of the world religion is already in existence and to its center all higher minds already point. Its yoke is as easy as it is inevitable; its doctrines are as plain as they are undebatable. The doctrines of this common creed can be summarized in the following propositions: (1) A divine intention governs the universe, call it God, deity, Holy Ghost, Absolute, Logos, or Evolution. (2) The direction of this intention is from matter to life, from life to spirit, from chaos to order, from blind strife and random impulse to conscience and moral law. (8) In the universe we know, the human species is the spearhead of the divine intention; man is the necessary ally of "that power that makes for righteousness." (4) Man's growth, progress or evolution is toward the radiance of an angel. (5) If the divine intention is to be fulfilled, the pursuit of good under the inspiration of faith, hope, and charity must imply resistance to evil-battle when necessary. {6) Life is service and death a gate to life--whatever the destiny of the individual in the " undiscovered country." For individual life is humble in the knowledge of its limits under the all human dogma of fallibility. {7) Individual life has meaning only by participation in the unlimited past into the illimitable future; no one man or race or generation can embody the heritage and the promise of man. SociOLOGY AND EcoNOMICS (pp. 48-58) In general the sociology and economics of the new order are comprised in the tenets of the common creed just listed, in the Golden Rule and in Paul's injunction "Be ye members one of another." Religion or doctrine cloaking injustice and misery on earth under the promise of some transcendent bliss deserves Marx's scorn. Earth is a laboratory where the validity of the eternal ideas are tested under the limits of space and time; here and now the divine intention which governs the universe must be enforced in the field of action as it stands supreme in the heaven of the creed. In particular, this new sociological and economic order is the American dream. It is not capitalism, which made freedom the murderer of equality; it is not communism, which made equality the strangler of freedom; it is not resurgent feudalism or corpm·ative economy which promise peace and order in a compulsory fixity of everyone wherever birth or chance happened BOOK REVIEWS 661 to place him. In fact, corporations and guilds, as advocated by clerical and political groups of the Right, are pious nicknames of Fascism, lures for weary men anxious to be free from freedom. The American dream is none of these. It demands that all know that they have inherited the earth; there is no place for non-working owners above working non-owners. It demands awareness that the problem of production (which is one of power) is superseded by the problem of distribution (which is one of justice). It demands an economy that is pluralistic and flexible. The primary centers must be transferred from metropolitan centers to villages. There must be federal aggregations, each for a special purpose: of sport, industry, education, art, administration, trade. These could collect, around focal points, the energies radiating from smaller communities. The factory will take the place held by the military barracks in the pre-human era: youth will be enlisted for a limited term, learn in federal factories, in public works, and on communal farms the skill of production. Here slavery will be anathema an.d partnership the rallying cry. Distribution of service, assigning to each one his share of labor and leisure must make unemployment a forgotten nightmare. Private property must be admitted as biologically inevitable and socially useful. But the Bill of Rights must be supplemented by a Bill of Duties stating that no private property can be tolerated outside the framework of just social use; thus are limits set to the accumulation of wealth and its transmission. Morals will have primacy over economics, not vice versa. Injustice must be fought as soon as it rears its head; no quarter must be given to the paradox of moral man in immoral society, of poverty in the midst of plenty. Bread must know no fear; love and parenthood must unlearn fear and shame. AMERICAN LEADERSHIP (pp. 58-66) America has the necessary and inevitable mission to bring this new order and new religion about. No one else is strong and free enough to show the way to social reform and universal order. America is really chosen by objective circumstances of history for a privilege which is a service, a right which is a duty. Rulership by the wisest and strongest is the prescribed path to equality of all if the strong can learn wisdom and if the rulership is accepted in the spirit of reluctance and devotion that Plato suggests. In the family of nations a firm hand is required over the children to be matured, the sick to be cured, the maniacs to be confined, and the criminals to be apprehended. Yet the final goal can never be forgotten; justice, which is the common good, can never be perverted into the interest of the stronger. American leadership is world trusteeship. Pax Americana is a preamble to Pax Humana. * * * 662 BOOK REVIEWS Obviously the evaluation of such a document as the Declaration of this book is not easy and cannot be exhaustive; for the Declaration is, at the same time, political, ethical, religious, sociological, and economic. Perhaps it will be sufficient for an appreciation of the character of this product of collective thinking to examine some of the fundamental notions upon which the whole thesis is explicitly based. The sponsors of this declaration are, by explicit statement, working in the interests. of western civilization, of democracy, of humanity. Their condemnations of Nazism, Fascism, Communism and the abuses of democracy leave little to be desired in the way of scathing repudiation. They speak in terms long familiar and sacred to the peoples of the west: the dignity of man, the ultimate value of the individual, the common good, the divine intention directing the universe, justice, law, equality, freedom, and so on. If, by any chance, the Declaration they have here sponsored destroys or attacks these sacred things, then we can legitimately conclude that the majority of the signers of this Declaration have been duped by a cleverer mind; they have been sold a bill of goods altogether different from what they asked for. The imputation, in such a case, is not on their nobility of purpose, their sincerity, their courageous attack on crucial issues, but on their intellectual acumen. This declaration speaks feelingly of the dignity of man, the meaning of human life and the ultimate value of the individual. In actual fact, it denies dignity to man, meaning to life, and value to the individual. It insists, for example that the goal of an individual's life is growth and progress in intellect and action through endless effort with no individual attainment to mark its successful close. The individual is asked to strive endlessly that he might grow; though of course, as he gets old his growing will stop and as death comes there will be nothing to look forward to. Yes, it is said that life is a service and death a gate to life, whatever the destiny of the individual after death; but it is also insisted that individual life has meaning only by participation in the unlimited past into the illimitable future. It is said that the ·value of the individual is ultimate and the community must promote the welfare of each person; but it is also said that the. single citizen must strive toward a communal good which is beyond himself, that everything must be within, nothing against, nothing outside humanity. In other words, there is no individual goal to give individual meaning to an individual's life. The individual man exists only for a mass entity, a communal purpose. For him, there is no liberty but the right to make himself and others free by adhering with absolute allegiance to the final goal of man, that is, to a process of growth indistinct from that of the community, the end beyond himself. What of the dignity of man that is insisted on in the words of this Declaration? No basis is assigned for it; it is taken as. a fundamental BOOK REVIEWS 668 assumption. Yet the one basis possible for it is explicitly denied. A man has dignity precisely because he is a superior, he is in command of his own life to his own supreme purpose; he can use the things about him, while he can be used by absolutely nothing else in the universe. He has an end, an individual end, of his own; he is not the tool or instrument of some other end. This is precisely what is denied in this Declaration; the bright goals he thinks he is aiming at are dreams wrapped up in brief myths, milleniums. He exists, not for his own goal, but for the goal of that vague community called humanity; he is the necessary ally of some vague power; he has no liberty but to hold fast to this non-personal end that renders his life individually meaningless. He is, in actual fact, used by the community; and he exists for no other purpose. What of the freedom of man? According to the Declaration, its basis is universal and total democracy; there is no other principle. Thus the principle of man's freedom is something outside the individual, an extrinsic grant not a natural characteristic. It exists that man might work to the end beyond himself which is within humanity. That is not what the peoples of the west have meant by To them, freedom has meant the capacity to choose between means that lead to the individual goal which perfects the individual life; it has meant a natural capacity, one that flows from man's spiritual nature. To their minds, man, because he could know the universal truth, could desire the universal, unlimited good; so in the face of the partial, limited goods of the physical world he was free, free to ac·cept or reject their proferred goodness. It has been a freedom worth fighting for, one that could be defended against any odds for it could never be taken by assault; it could be lost only by surrender. What of the moral order upon which human life is based? If it have a religious source, then, according to the Declaration, it must come from the highest religion which embodies all higher religions, the religion of the Spirit, Democracy. But it need not have a religious source. In the concrete, then, it is stated that the foundation of law is universal participation in government; the foundation of equality is that the state is the agent of collective human purposes; the foundation of justice is that democracy is a community of persons. The words are familiar, but the concepts are altogether strange. By "law," the peoples of the west have understood reason's ordered precept to a common good or to the divine good; to them, its foundation has been the intelligence that is back of order, its force has been its reasonableness, its challenge has been reason's demand, its proof has been open to the mind of every man. Is the implication here that where there is no universal participation in government, there is no law? If so, this is a canonization of anarchy. To the men of the west, equality has flowed from the common nature of all men, from their undying spirits, each worth a king's ra.nSom, from the supremacy of their individual goals, 664 BOOK REVIEWS from their individual mastery of their own lives, from their natural immunity to being used as tools of anyone or anything, however great, however high-sounding, however organized; not from the fact that the state is the agent of collective human purposes. Equality, like freedom, comes from within man; it is not granted him from without. Justice, to us of the west, is not the result of democracy's peculiar nature; it is the demand of the mastery of the individual man. Each man has rights, not given him by an outside agency, but pertaining to his very person precisely because he has an end of his own and consequent obligations; he has important, individual things to get done, and he has the consequent right to do them unimpeded. The Declaration insists that there is a divine intention directing the universe. Yet it also insists that there is nothing outside, everything within, humanity. Among the names given this divine intention is that of Holy Ghost; yet the Holy Ghost is described as universal democracy; as a deity, universal democracy is ultimately sacred and Christ Himself forbade blasphemy against it. The divine intention, then, directing the universe is universal democracy which, as we are told, has never as yet existed. The words are familar, as always, but the concepts they cloak make their use a mockery to the intelligence of men of the twentieth century. I submit that on the basis of the words of this Declaration, its sponsors have attacked the meaning of human life, the dignity of the individual and his ultimate value, the moral code by which he lives, his freedom, his equality, his claim to justice, and the God in Whom he hopes. A mind clever enough to sell such a program of destruction to American thinkers would see deeply enough to discern the outstanding enemy of his thesis. He would concentrate the full bitterness of his attack on the Catholic Church as the unflinching defender of ·these things at whatever cost, in whatever age and against whatever enemy or combination of enemies. That is, as a matter of fact, what has happened in this book (pp. 40-48) . The basic error of the Church, it is said, is the identification of the Church as a temporal kingdom with the " kingdom of God " of Christian and prophetic expectation. Historically this is ridiculous. No Christian has ever supposed that the Kingdom of God did not exist during the early centuries when the Church had no slightest pretentions to temporalities and eked out its existence hidden in dark places like a hunted animal. No historian dates the beginning of the Kingdom of God from the gratuitous grants of land that originally made up the papal territory; no historian traces the foundation of the Kingdom of God to the benefactors who made those grants. No one made the mistake of thinking the Kingdom of God had gone out of existence during the long years when the Pope was the BOOK REVIEWS 666 prisoner of the Vatican with no more than a garden to call his own. Yet in all these times, the Church as a temporal kingdom did not exist. From this alleged, but utterly false, identification of the temporal kingdom of the Church with the Kingdom of God, it is maintained, comes the unwarranted aura of unqualified holiness, the historical usurping the sanctity of the eternal. Nothing could be farther from the truth. The holiness of the Church lies in the holiness of the divine truth of which it is the custodian, the hoiiness of the divine helps its ministers, and the holiness of those of its children who dare to follow the example of the Master without stint. The first two of these are holy because they are divine; the third, because these men and women have approached so close to divinity. Laid down as the fundamentals of the rest of the attack, these first two points are, as a matter of fact, abandoned in order that the political argument might be launched untrammeled. One gets the definite impression that these first two were really red herrings dragged across the argument to give it an air of objectivity; certainly they have nothing to do with the rest of the attack. The real charge is that the Church has been political, or rather that it has been on the wrong side of politics; the sponsors of this document are worried that it will be made a subordinate ally of the political plans of the Nazis and Fascists, whereas, according to their statement of the fate of the churches, it should be made the subordinate ally of the political plans of world democracy. The fact is, of course, that the Church is by its nature not political in this fashion or that, but super-political; its task has not to do with the states or nations or masses, but with individual men. The attack is suported by historical " evidence "-the Church has often proved Roman, French, Spanish, Austrian. The authors have perhaps forgotten that kingdoms were lost to the Church because it would not compromise the truth it guarded, that matters of faith and morals have come through the erosive action of two thousand years without a scratch of error or the false smoothness of defection. The Church is pilloried because its. spiritual totalitarianism was the pattern and tool of political totalitarianism. The inference is, of course, that political totalitarianism had never entered the mind of man until the Church appeared and then only in the two-thousandth year of its history. It is a tool and has hitched its wagon to the Fascist's star; for, of course, the papal condemnations of totalitnrian corruption of youth, of the philosophy of state supremacy, of the corruption of morals, and the violence of injustice are not to be taken seriously though they were paid for in blood and are still being made and still being paid for. Tears are shed over the fate of "Republican" Spain, though earlier in the book, and later, Communism is bitterly condemned; would all be forgiven if Communism changed its badge to Republicaliism? 666 BOOK REVIEWS Perhaps more important than the actual charges against the Church is the manner in which they are made. A whiff of incense is tossed in the face of the Church in the early pages of the book as the necessary smile of greeting to modem broad-mindedness. The actual attack starts off with a kind of objective calmness, though there is no delay in falsifying the charges; little by little the attack gains momentum and loses rationality until it comes to a climax of frothing madness, screeching to modem Catholics to revolt from the Vatican City as a foreign potentate in feud or trade with other potentates. The notion persists that the majority of the sponsors of this document were sold down the river. One wonders, reasonably, if they would conacioualy be partners to this sort of unfounded fury. The Syllabus of Errora, for example, is quoted as a challenge to the liberal world of the Reformation and the Renaissance and a contribution to political and social obscurantism. If all the sponsors had read the Syllabus of Errors, surely one of them would have thought to tabulate the subjects treated there and would have come up with this list of things defended: divine character of Scripture and its guardianship by the Church, revelation, the certitude of faith, the union of belief and action, the divinity of Christ, the· death and resurrection of Christ, the sacraments, the Church, the stability of truth and the independence of religious truth from the varying condition of science. Surely, had all of them read the Syllabus, some one of these thirteen sponsors would have questioned whether this papal document was a challenge to any kind of true liberalism. One wonders, reasonably, whether, had they not been duped, the sponsors of this document would have subscribed, to such foul phrases as: " The Fuehrers and enslavers can endorse some of these promises; if not of plenty, of equality in misery and of security in the dusk of the manger" (p. Sf.!). It it hardly consonant with the American temperament to hide the corruption of a truth behind the cloak of a sacred word, to indulge in a small boy's vulgarity by such blasphemous balderdash as the identification of the Holy Ghost with democracy, much less, tongue in cheek, call Christ as a witness to the blasphemy. For the rest, the document pretty well refutes itself. The sociological and economic programs suffered from the same defect that has haunted the socialist dream from the beginning, the defect inherent in the product of men who have been accurately described as amateurs. These authors have shown little knowledge of human nature; they are amateurs when they suppose that a world-wide power will be quietly laid aside once the reign of justice is established by force, that the reign of justice without blemish will be established on a world wide scale, that justice will be found where there is a universal governmental assignment of every detail of labor and leisure, that men can be adequately. ruled when there is no other law but civil law. 667 BOOK REVIEWS Fundamentally, the error of this book is a combination of the modem naively complete confidence in governmental action and the world-wide drift to totalitarianism. " Humanity " has been substituted for " Aryan Race" or "Communist Party," the scope is a little wider, but all else is unchanged; the individual is sunk in the mass, the single citizen's life is stripped of meaning, government is made a divinity with its own political religion whose opponents are heretics-criminals or maniacs to be dealt with accordingly; the mastery of truth, .of action, of life and death is in the hands of the human super-legislator. This book represents one of the earliest and most concrete conquests of Hitlerism in America. WALTER FARRELL, O.P. Dominican House of Studiea, Wa8hington, D. a. Philosophy for Our Times. By C. E. M. JoAD. London-New York: Th. Nelson & Sons, 1940. Pp. 367, with index. Written in an impressive and mostly non-technical language this book emphasizes the need of philosophical reflection in these our days. Mankind has a mastery of means and is ignorant of ends. Religion and, morals are falling into decay.· Psychoanalysis and other factors destroy understanding of the difference between good and evil, and preach the dangerous doctrine of the harmfulness of suppressing impulses. "Foreheads are defiantly low." The snobbery of culture has been replaced by the snobbery of anti-culture. It is a time which more than any is in need of philosophy. Philosophy has to provide a counterweight against the dreariness and essential indifference in regard to values characteristic of the scientific view. Dr. Joad then proceeds to analyze the world of commonsense and to point out the difficulties this view implies. The corrections and enlargement by science are neither ultimately nor exhaustively true. Science deals with only one kind of reality; it leaves out other aspects. Chap. IV states " that science tells us a little about some things and that there are no things about which it tells us everything." Also, science not less than commonsense presupposes the activity of the mind. This activity has to supply the principles for the interpretation of the behavior .of the things we experience. Since the materialistic cosmogony is demonstrably defective and science is unable to give a satisfactory account of mind, the world as envisioned by physics is essentially an abstraction leaving out everything of which science cannot· render a.Ccount. As mind, so value is excluded from the scientific world-picture. Nor does science ever explain that of which it renders account. The teleological viewpoint is forced on the observant mind by the facts themselves, but it is outside the scope of science. 668 BOOK. REVIEWS The reality grasped by science being incomplete, defective, and unsatisfactory, one has to look out for another view truer to reality and more satisfying to the !needs of the mind. Part IT, "Constructive,'' defends the notion of the reality of values. Contrary to the prevailing subjectivistic view, the author holds that values are objective and real. Truth and beauty are objective. The statement that truth is subjective must be given up as self-contradictory. If truth has no objectivity, this statement too, and all other statements become subjective and relative. That is, there is no truth at all. Appreciation of beauty and moral judgments lean never be exhaustively analyzed into statements about individual feelings of approval. There are ultimate values, namely Goodness and Truth and Beauty. Although salutary, health is no ultimate good, and much less ultimate are harmful false goods like money and power. In a long chapter of 20 pages the author attempts to show that there is an immediate and specific apprehension of values. His arguments are too long to be reproduced, but they deserve serious consideration. Once the objectivity of values is recognized, the position of hedonism in ethics becomes untenable, and a system of objective rules for the right conduct of life a necessity. One has to distinguish between pleasures, to make reason the judge of the goodness of appetition. Goodness and happiness cannot be achieved unless behavior. be controlled by reason. Politics refers to the same set of problems as does ethics. Politics has to determine the nature of the community in which the good life as revealed by ethics can be lived. The State is the political instrument for an ethical end. In itself the State is nothing. Absolutism which makes the State an,end in itself has to be rejected. Not power, imperial or military, not wealth, or liberty makes a State great. Liberty too may be misused. As criteria for'national excellence one may consider the provision of social services and the production of great men. There is a postscript, dealing with religion and man's need of it. Dr. Joad acknowledges that the existence of a personal God, revealing Himself to man 'is possible or even probable. He does not, however, belive that there is any philosophical proof for God's existence, and being concerned with philosophy only he omits further reference to the problem. Secondly, the need of the times is for a ;code of living; and the Christian churches seem to the author not capable of providing such a code adequate to the present situation. Thirdly, he declares himself unable to .see how a good God can be the creator of a world of suffering. It is not a little astonishing to see a penetrating mind stumble over such .trivial objections, the more so since Dr. Joad's ideas seem to lead inevitably into a theonomic conception of the world. RuDoLF ALLERs. Catholic University of America, Washington, D. C. BOOK REVIEWS 669 An Essay on Nature. By FREDERICKJ. E. WooDBRIDGE. New York: Columbia University Press, 1940. Pp. xii + 351, with index. $3.00. Not often does the student of philosophy come across a work whose main thought may be summarized in one short formula. It needs a wise mind and a clear one to coin a word which condenses and, at the same time, illuminates the thought of a lifetime with one single sentence. Professor Woodbridge is one of these rare minds. His last book is an impressive defense of metaphysics and of the supernatural by one who is essentially and thoroughly a naturalist. The supernatural is nature transubstantiated. Theology is science transubstantiated. Such is the eminent own formula and the briefest statement of his main idea. The supernatural is therefore not the goal of the quest for knowledge, but it is the justification and the foundation of the quest for happiness. Because transubstantiated, the terms of knowledge, they remain extrinsically and inevitably the same, refer to a different substance when used in the theological universe of discourse. This discourse is, however, not of the "ideal" but of the supernatural, that is, of being, no less than when we speak of nature. One feels tempted to apply to Professor Woodbridge's philosophy, although in a much modified way, the famous Kantian saying, that he had to destroy knowledge to make faith possible. With this author it is rather that knowledge had to be preserved for the sake of ensuring faith. Nature is what we perceive. There is no convincing reason for turning the percept into a symbol of something else. Our perceiving capacities are limited, but we become aware of these limitations only in perception. The dependence of knowledge on the organization of our bodies does not dethrone mind, nor do we lose our souls when we discover the use of words. Words and formulae do not represent a second world, truer than the one of percepts, and Sir Arthur Eddington's famous two tables are no argument at all, since Sir Arthur never in his life wrote upon a " scientific table." Scientific objects are, Professor Woodbridge contends, the most amusing fictions ever invented. Natural philosophy, being the reflections suggested to the mind by the perceived world, engenders mathematics and science. Natural science gives birth to scientific language; it is the source not the offspring of the latter. Without being a " naive realist," the author insists on the right of the visible world and the space which is its order. Light and space are the two great fundamental principles. All our knowledge ultimately rests on light and on space. Our language talks of them. They are laws of nature, as is time, and we are parts of the same nature. Again, our language pictures nature in its temporality. There are things that move; but there is no event "moving." Nor does the inability of man destroy nature's working. At a given moment the events of nature are synchronized, whether we can 670 BOOK; REVIEWS ascertain this or not. Causal explanation does not do away with teleology; they are not opposed but correlated. All our knowledge is bound up with time and thus with history. Neither mathematics nor language is" applied" to nature; they stem from 'her. We can never escape reality because we are reality too and because reality ia. Justifying nature's ways and knowing them are two different things. The only true problem is how to enlarge our knowledge of nature's ways. Morality pertains to nature not less than anything else, although nature'" does not intend moral order, but rather subtends it." Nature is the only object of knowledge, but there are things as necessary as knowledge 'to which not knowledge but faith is the adequate answer. Ceremonial cult is the expression of the acknowledgment of the supernatural, and religion is the personal acceptance of this acknowledgment. It is the pursuit of happiness which reveals the supernatural. The dualism of knowledgment and happiness is fundamental in human existence. Knowledge discovers nature, but does not justify it. This justification the mind demands, faith supplies. The supernatural is the justification of nature. RUDOLF ALI..ERs. Catholic University of America, Washington, D. C. E:x;perienceand Substance. By DEWITT H. PARKER. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1941. Pp. x + 871, with index. $8.00. The title indicates the two main sets of problems: experience refers to knowledge, substance to metaphysics. The general viewpoint is idealistic, although not without some peculiarities. The basic metaphysical conception is monadistic and finitistic. There is much of Kantianism, but it is modified so as to go farther beyond Hume than Kant himself does. Parallel to the idealistic trend runs a definitely antinominalistic and, therefore, antipositivistic strain. The latter becomes particularly noticeable in Chapters XXIV, dealing with the theory of relations and the problem of causality. Hume's solution is rejected because it does not afford any explanation of the note of necessity to all awareness of causal relations. These chapters also contain an interesting analysis of probability and of many of the statements, common. among philosophers of science, regarding the philosophical implications of modern physics, especially the relativity theory, the notion of statistical law, and the general bearing of science on philosophy. Substance is characterized by being subject, never independent, causally efficient, conserved through change. These characteristics apply to what Parker calls the matrix self; they do not apply to matter as conceived by materialistic metaphysics. Experience is substance, and substance is only an experience. Existence ,can be credited only to what is actually in ex- BOOK REVIEWS 671 perience, neither possible nor past events have existence, nor have universals existence apart from the concreta in which they are discovered. The universals are timeless objects, not however eternal. The eternal reveals itself to an examination of the levels of causality, of which there are three. There is first the personal level, secondly, the level of biological causation, and finally, underlying the other two, the physico-chemical level which is referred to as the " Omega system." The higher level depends in its and in its functioning on the next lower level. The lowest level, on which all being and eventing depends is the eternal level. Eternal and Omega system are identified. The reader, at this point, may recall that a similar notion has been proposed, under perhaps not dissimilar conditions of general mentality and problematics, once before in the history of human thought. This reviewer, at least, cannot help remembering the curious notion of David of Dinant who identified prime matter with God Himself. And back of David's mind there may have been a dilemma not unlike the one which apparently determines Professor Parker's somewhat startling assertion. The question is how to co-ordinate the fact that the inferior level undubitably conditions the functioning and the existence of the beings of the higher levels, on one hand and the equally impressive and evident ontological superiority of higher levels on the other. David and Parker solve the difficulty by locating, as it were, ontological eminence in the level of being which apparently is the most necessary and most general. But the relation of foundationthe higher being founded on the lower-is by far not the same as the relation of ontological superiority. Dr. Parker holds that metaphysics cannot do without the notion of God, as the source of being or of creation, the unifying factor keeping together the disparate elements of the universe, and as the "locus for truth." This God is very unlike the God of theology. Although the idea of providence is acknowledged, it is restricted by man's own efforts. Evil is considered as an inevitable feature of creation (which reminds one somewhat of certain ideas in Schelling's later philosophy). A short chapter summarizes the author's ideas on values, to which he devoted a volume some years ago. Value is seen as in relation to desire, whose satisfaction it is. This does not mean, however, that the interest nature of values, as in R. B. Perry's philosophy, is accepted. Rather, the relation between the two conceptions may be likened to the one obtaining between Kantian idealism and a psychologistic distortion of this philosophy, a view which would posit the origin of law and order of reality in the individual human mind and its functioning. Professor Parker's book is no easy reading. It raises difficult questions and deals with them in a manner too thorough for the casual reader. But 67!! BOOK REVIEWS it is an exceedingly interesting reading for any serious student of philosophy and for anyone who wants to find out how the modern mind wrestles with philosophical problems, old and new. The author's sympathy lies-if such a statement may be made in regard to the views of a philosopher-more with the problems of the Beautiful 4nd the Good than with those of mere knowledge. There is something- of the artist, especially of the -musician, in the way he looks at things, and also in the way he marshalls his ideas. Some chapters may not inaptly be compared to a piece with complicated counterpoint, something like a Bachian fugue. Goethe, in his later years, or any of his younger Romantic friends, would have spoken of Dr. Parker, probably, as eine musikalische Natur. But he is, for all this, a true philosopher whose ideas deserve serious consideration. However little one may agree with his fundamental viewpoints, there is much one may learn from his studies. His work may be recommended especially to all those concerned about the place of science within the totality of knowledge. RUDOLF ALLERS. Catholic University uf America, Washington, D. C. BRffiF NOTICES ANNOUNCING: A Dialectic of Morals: Towards the Foundations of Political Philosophy. By MoRTIMER J. ADLER. The Review of Politics, Notre Dame University, Notre Dame, Indiana. This latest work of Dr. Adler appeared originally in the pages of The Review of Politics. In it Dr. Adler proceeds "dialectically against those who say there is no moral knowledge; who say that good and bad, right and wrong, are entirely matters of opinion; who say, as a consequence, that might makes right in the sphere of politics." This dialectical treatment of morality is lively and interesting, for, as Dr. Adler says, "The dialectic of morals which I shall now proceed to outline is not an imaginary process. It is rather a distillation of actual arguments which President Hutchins and I have had with students in courses devoted to the reading of great works in ethics and politics." Publication is promised for October. Man's Triumph With God in Christ. By FREDERICK A. HoucK. St. Louis: with Index. Herder, 1940. Pp. Widespread ignorance, error and indifference in matter of religion, and large-scale atheistic trends in our modern life are the occasion of this latest book of Father Houck. A summary of the chapter titles-Knowability of God; The God-Man; Man, the Image of God; The End and Purpose of Man; The Mystical Body of Christ and Blissful Eternity-will indicate the book's scope as definitely broad. In spite of the excellent choice of sources, the same as the Council of Trent, the very breadth of the author's intention demands that some of these subjects receive sketchy attention. It is regrettable that St. Thomas is made to speak for himself in long quotations from the Summa Theologica and the Summa Contra Gentiles. While St. Thomas speaks the truth, very often it is a truth which, unexplained, will be unintelligible to the average reader. The Divine Crucible of Purgatory. By MoTHER MARY OF ST. AusTIN. Revised and edited by Nicholas Ryan, S. J. New York: P. J. Kenedy and Sons, 1940. Pp. viii + 185. $!U5. The reality of the fire of Purgatory is a paramount issue in this book. The first of its two sections is dedicated to the establishment of the conclusion that the fire is only metaphorical. As such, the sensible suffering of the souls in Purgatory is caused by infused knowledge, in a manner similar to the sufferings of the soul immersed in the "dark night." Just as the soul on earth is purified by this infused contemplation, so too the 678 674 BRIEF NOTICES souls in purgatory are purified and prepared for the beatific vision in much the same way. The meditations, which comprise the second and major portion of the book, trace and -describe the progress of the departed soul through the sufferings of the " dark night," the silence of the " twilight " and, finally, the soul's transformation and union with God. Comparisons to the sufferings of Christ and of the Church Militant add to the clarity and practicality of the meditations. The conclusion of the first section will undoubtedly be considered by many as untenable-and with reason-but the utility of the meditations for souls who already have a fair grasp of the principles of the ascetical life will be nuestioned by few. Science, Philosophy and Religion: A Symposium. New York: Conference on Science, Philosophy and Religion in Their Relation to the Democratic Way of Life, 1941. Pp. 443. $1.50. As most of our readers know, this volume contains the papers read at the Conference -On Science, Philosophy and Religion in Their Relation to the Democratic Way of Life, held in New York City, on September 9-11, 1940. Many of the papers are simply learned articles on their authors' special subjects, with a few introductory or concluding remarks on democracy. There are some very valuable papers, especially those by Finkelstein, Sorokin, Adler, Maritain, Van Wyck Brooks, and Johnson. The papers of this first conference give us very little opportunity of judging the success or failure of the itself. Success or failure can be judged only by those who were present at the discussion of the papers. Van Wyck Brooks, in his introductory paper, quotes a statement released to the press at the end of the conference by a special Committee; part of the statement reads as follows: " As the discussion at the Conference proceeded, it became obvious that the various groups of philosophers, as well as the scientists of different fields, were being drawn more closely together. The scientists who presented papers were able to issue a common statement of their views. The philosophers narrowed the area of disagreement among themselves. Thomists recognized the position of Logical Positivism as applicable to the field of science, though they denied its applicability to other fields. Logical Positivists seemed to recognize the right of Thomists and other philosophers to carry on their speculations and arrive at conclusions, but denied that the term " knowledge " could be applied to such speculations." In other words, the Thomists were able to grant much; the Logical Positivists were willing to grant nothing. Unfortunately, many of the philosophers and theologians were definitely on the side of the Positivists. However, it is good to know that a clear-cut division is appearing between those who maintain the validity of philosophical and theological knowledge, as knowledge, and those who deny validity to any type of thinking that it not positivisitic. BRIEF NOTICES 675 Sa{nt Thomas Aquinas. By GERALD VANN, 0. P. London: J. M. Dent & Sons, 1940. Pp. i.x + 182. 6s. Fr. Vann, leaning heavily on the historical researches of Gilson and Dawson, presents an interpretation of the actual position of St. Thomas Aquinas. To the Angelic Doctor he looks for the needed synthesis between eastern and western culture, for a corrective to the exaggerated contemplative and activist theories of these two worlds. To prove his thesis he is led to show that Thomas is not the chilly rationalist moderns portray him to be; in his life and teaching there is ample room for the intuitive, the contemplative, the mystical. The work gives a well-rounded picture of Thomas the man, of his intellectual environment and of the work he accomplished. This last section, which should have been the strongest part of the book, is really the weakest, for the nature of the non-rational elements of the Thomistic synthesis is too cursorily treated. Wars of Families of Minds. By WILLIAM L. BRY:AN. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1940. Pp. xv + 143, with index. $2.00. The title of this work expresses completely the author's intention in writing it: he shows that there are families of minds, the unschooled man, the scholar (who may belong to the sceptics, the scientists, or the philosophers), and the poets; he also points out that these families of minds are at war with one another. Numerous instances of intellectual combats are cited. The author seems to think that these conflicts are inevitable. He does not study the careers of those men who have been successful in many fields, although he does mention a few names. Most noticeable is the omission of the religious-minded, among whom many examples of harmony could have been discovered. In his Introduction, the author touches on the reasons for the division of human minds into families; they are valid reasons and should serve as the theme of frequent consideration for those who tend to become one-sided in their mental outlook. A Guide to the Intellectual History of Europe from St. Augustine to Marx. By FREDERICK B. ARTZ. Boston: Ginn & Co., 1941. Pp. xix + 140, with index. $1.75. The purpose of this volume is to enable the student to read and understand some of the most important books of the European intellectual tradition. There is a wide choice of books; the author prefaces each study with a few bibliographical references, then gives a list of questions on the sections of the books to be read. Unfortunately, the title is much too pretentious in view of the authors studied. Plato and Cicero are included before St. Augustine. Why not, then, Aristotle and the Bible? Roger Bacon is the only representative of scholastic thought. Such omissions may be justifiable; but, then, this is not a guide to the intellectual history of Europe. Rather it is an aid to the reading of certain important books in the western tradition. BOOKS RECEIVED Bradshaw, M. J. Philosophical Foundations of Faith. New York: Columbia University Press, 1941. Pp. xi+ 254, with index. $!!.50. Brennan, R. E., 0. P. Thomistic Psychology. New York, Macmillan, 1941. Pp. xxvi + 401, with index. $8.00. Burke, Kenneth. The Philosophy of Literary Form. Louisiana State University Press, 1941. Pp. xvi + 455, with index. $8.00. Ducasse, C. J. Philosophy as a Science. New York: Oskar Piest, 1941. Pp. xx + 242, with index. $8.00. Edman, Irwin and Schneider, H. W. Landmarks in Philosophy. New York: Reynald and Hitchcock, 1941. Pp. x + 1008, with index. $4.00. Einstein, Ira. The Ethics of 'J'olerance. New York: King's Crown Press, 1941. Pp. 87. $1.50. Farrell, Walter, O.P. A Companion to the Summa, I: The Architect of the Universe. New York, Sheed & Ward, 1941. Pp. 457, with index. $8.50. Frank, Philipp. Between Physics and Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1941. Pp. 288, with index. $!!.75. Galvao de Sousa, J. P. 0 Positivismo Juridico e 0 Direito Natural. Sao Paulo, Brazil, 1940. Pp. 101. Leclercq, Jacques. Marriage and the Family. (Trans. by T. R. Hanley, 0. S. B.) New York: Pustet, 1941. Pp. xx + 895, with index. $4.50. Les Methodes scientifiques dans l'education. 2ieme Congres annuel, 18-!!1 juin, 1941. Les Parents et l'en.fant. Ottawa: Les Editions du Levrier. Pp. 207. Magid, H. M. English Political Pluralism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1941. Pp. 100, with index. $1.25. Manchester, F. and Shepard, 0. Irving Babbitt, Man and Teacher. New York: Putnam's Sons, 1941. Pp. xiii + 887. $8.00. Niebuhr, Reinhold. The Nature and Destiny of Man, I: Human Nature. New York: Scribner's Sons, 1941. Pp. xii + 806, with indices. 2.75. Shute, Clarence. The Psychology of Aristotle. New York: Columbia University Press, 1941. Pp. xiv + 148, with index. $!!.00. 676 INDICES OF VOLUME III (1941) INDEX OF AUTHORS PAGE 279 ADLER, M. J. Solution of the Problem of Species 897,588 --- and FARRELL, WALTER. Theory of Democracy 95 ALLERS, R. The Intellectual Cognition of Particulars -' -. Review of The Philosophy of Physiccil Science by A. 885 Eddington . 887 ---. Review of Physics and Recility by K. Riezler . 507 Review of Man on His Nature by C. Sherrington . 667 Review of Philosophy for Our Times by C. E. M. Joad 669 Review of An Essay on Nature by F. J. E. Woodbridge . 670 Review of Experience and Substance by D. H. Parker . 564 ANDERSON, J. F. Two Studies in Metaphysics . 54 BoND, L. M. A Comparison Between Human and Divine Friendship 8 BRENNAN, R. E. Modem Psychology and Man . DELLA PENTA, J. C. Review of Adversity's Noblemen by C. E. 518 Trinkhaus . 450 EGAN, J. M. Meditation and the Search for God . ---. Review of The Steps of Humility of Bernard of Clairvaux. 891 Translated with Introduction and Notes by G. B. Burch FARRELL, W. and ADLER, 1\'[. J. The Theory of Democracy . . 897,588 --. Review of The City of Man . 658 McGuiNESS, J. I. The Distinctive Nature of the Gift of Under217 standing MARITAIN, J. Concerning a" Critical Review" . 45 --. The Conflict of Methods at the End of the Middle Ages 527 88 MULHERN, P. F. The Rejection and Protection.of Faith . MURPHY, T. A. Review of Greek Popular Religion by M.P. Nilsson . 167 ---. Review of From the Stone Age to Christianity: Monotheism and the Historical Process by W. F. Albright . 510 164 RYAN, J. K. Review of Language and Reality by W. M. Urban . RYAN, L. A. Charity and the Social Order: I . 539 ScHWARTZ, C. Review of A Companion to the Summa, Ill by Walter Farrell . 380 VEATCH, H. B. Some Suggestions on the Respective Spheres of Science and Philosophy . 177 WJ1ITTA.KER, J. F. The Position of Mathematics in the Hierarchy of Speculative Science . 467 677 678 INDICES OF VOLUME Ill {1941) INDEX OF ARTICLES PAGE Charity and the Social Order: I. L. A. RYAN . . 539 Concerning a "Critical Review." J. MARITAI.N . 45 Democracy, The Theory of--. W. FARRELL and M. J. ADLER . 897,588 Faith, The Rejection and Protection of--. P. F. MULHERN . 33 Friendship, A Comparison Between Human and Divine --. L. 'M. BoND 54 Man, Modern Psychology and --. R. E. BRENNAN . 8 Mathematics, The Position of -- in the Hierarchy of Speculative Science. J. F. WHITTAKER . 467 Meditation and the Search for God. J. M. EGAN . 450 Metaphysics, Two Studies in--. J. F. ANDERSON 564 Methods, The Conflict of -- at the End of the Middle Ages. J. MARITAIN . 527 Particulars, The Intellectual Cognition of --. R. ALLERS . 95 Philosophy, Some Suggestions on the Respective Spheres of Science 177 and --. H. B. VEATCH . Problem of Species, Solution of--. M. J. ADLER . 279 Psychology, Modern-- and Man. R. E. BRENNAN 8 Science, Some Suggestions on the Respective Spheres of -- and Philosophy. H. B. VEATCH . 177 Social Order, Charity and the--: I. L.A. RYAN . 589 Understanding, The Distinctive Nature of the Gift of --. J. I. McGuiNEss · 217 INDEX OF BOOKS REVIEWED ALBRIGHT, W. F. From the Stone Age to Christianity: Monotheism and the Historical Process (Murphy) . BURcH, G. B. The Steps of Humility of Bernard of Clairvaux (Egan) The City of Man (Farrell) . EDDINGTON, A. The Philosophy of Physical Science (Allers} FARRELL, WALTER. A Companion to the Summa, III: The Fullness of Life (Schwartz} . JoAD, C. E. M. Philosophy for Our Times (Allers) . NILSsON, M. P. Greek Popular Religion (Murphy) PARKER, D. H. Experience and Substance (Allers) RIEZLER, K. Physics and Reality (Allers) . SHERRINGTON, C. Man on His Nature (Allers} . ThiNKHAUs, C. E. Adversity's Noblemen {Della Penta) URBAN, W. M. Language and Reality (Ryan) . WoODBRIDGE, F. J. E. An Essay on NatuTe (Allers) END oF VoLuME Ill 510 391 653 885 380 667 167 670 387 507 518 164 669