THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EmToRs: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PRoVINCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: Sheed and Ward, Inc., New York City VoL. VIII JANUARY, 1945 No.1 PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY T I HE latest newcomer to the philosophical forum has been proclaimed by its adherents as " a philosophy of the person." Personalism, announced in two continents as a complete philosophy, is, according to its exponents, the answer to the need of the hour, and already claims the support of respectable philosophical authority. It envisages the problem of personality in its. broadest perspective, placing it within the framework of a complete philosophical system. From this central concept it seeks a solution of the problems of knowledge and being, of psychology and axiology. Primarily, it presents an interpretation of reality. From the point of view of development, we may distinguish two phases: naive Personalism and critical Personalism. Naive Personalism is simply the primitive, unphilosophical interpretation of reality, the product of a mind in Comte's "theological stage" of human development. Having once made the distinction between subject and object, it sees everything under the aspect of person1 JOHN A. CREA VEN ality. In the background of the world of objects it places demons, gods, spirits of various kinds. Clearly, such a view is the antithesis of impersonalism. But its uncritical procedure is obviously insufficient to safeguard vital human values from the attacks of impersonalism. To achieve its object, it needs a rational explanation and development, which it finds in critical Personalism. 1 Critical Personalism, endeavoring to safeguard vital human values, is eclectic: it retains what seems true in the conclusions of naive personalism and impersonalism. From the former it takes its teleological view of the universe which sees in it an orderly system of autonomous and purposive beings, organized in a hierarchy of persons. From impersonalism it borrows its scientific concepts and its " synoptic " or synthetic method. 2 The synoptic method, so common in Personalism, is a reflection of modern trends in psychology. In effect, the principle underlying the method declares that we can know an object as a whole of parts, or as a part of a whole, or as both. William Stern, the German personalist, has developed the theory of synopsis in both directions. He has insisted that everywhere precedes analysis, and that synopsis reveals or contains more than analysis can ever discover. The former thesis he takes as proved by the Gestalt psychology. The totality of our inner experience-the Ego or " I "-is itself a unity, for synopsis is the normal mode of experience: elements are but abstractions from it. In his criticisms of the " Elementarist " psychologies, he has insisted that analysis, as a work of dissection, can never discover a Gestalt quality, which disappears as soon as it is resolved into its elements. Again, synthesis, by working upon a previously known whole, can discover therein a new form: by altering the contour, the lines, the lights and the shades it can discover a new Gestalt and a new beauty. But synopsis is also a knowledge of an object as a part of a 1 Cf. W. B. Thorp, " Mechanism or Personalism," The Personalist, XIII, pp. 2 Lewis W. Beck, "The Method of Personalism," 'The Personalist, XIX, 1989, p. 871. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 3 whole. " To regard every object as a whole is to neglect the essential partiality of every object except the universe itself." 3 Though an object may be, metaphysically, an individual, this does not prevent it from being related by activity to another individual of which it is a subordinate part. Personalists, then, insist on the necessity of synopsis as a method of knowledge. Our earliest as well as our latest concepts, they teach, deal with things as wholes: with situations which are wholes; with ourselves as members of a social order; with our inner life, which reveals itself as a whole. The mind perceives situations as wholes, and there is comprehension before it is expressed in articulate language. In his " personalistic " psychology, Stern has exploited to the full the method of synopsis. " The methodological requirement," he tells us, " that scientific psychology always preserve the correlation between part and whole, salience and ground, analysis and totality, applies without exception." 4 Thus the search for elements is replaced by a probing for " wholes," on the principle that everything mental is either a whole or a part of a whole. The quality of wholeness does not necessarily exclude an internal multiplicity of parts: these simply lose their character of independent parts, capable of existing by themselves. Stern repeatedly insists that the meaning of the part is found only in the whole, and he has extended the partwhole relationship further than most pluralistic philosophers. The synoptic method takes account of the relation of who-les to more inclusive wholes (e. g. that of man to society},. wiiliout reducing the former to the status of a mere homogeneous part. When one whole transcends another, the meaning of the latter is not necessarily exhausted in its character of part. The use of the synthetic method is not without its difficulties. Underlying Stern's method is the theoretical assumption that everything mental is at the same time personal, and everything personal is a whole or a part of a whole. This assump• Lewis W. Beck, art. cit., pp. 874-875. • W. Stern, General Psychology, pp. 14-15. 4 JOHN A. CREA VEN tion seems to be a presupposition of the Gestalt and of all structural psychologies. But it is an assumption that must not be made too easily. To assume a Gestalt everywhere is to fall into the fallacy of over-simplification. Reality is complex and is not readily fitted into preconceived mental moulds. To ascribe every element to a Gestalt is to endow many things with qualities which they do not really possess. The synoptic method is really a process of abstraction which substitutes for the complex .Pattern of relationships found in the real order another purely theoretical and schematic system of relationships. It is an error of oversimplification to identify the latter with that which obtains in reality. II Every philosophical system must present a theory of ultimate reality. And for Personalism the chief task is the presentation of a " metaphysics of the person," the ultimate principle of reality. But as epistemology logically precedes metaphysics, the philosopher must first elaborate a theory of knowledge. 5 For the Personalist, epistemology furnishes the basis for a theory of the person and, in this role, forms an essential part of his system. Stern goes even further. The " Erkenntnistheorie," which stands at the beginning of his Critical Personalism, is much more than an introduction: it fulfils the important function of providing a scientific basis for his concept of personality, and is even made to justify his conclusion that the world consists of unitary, purposeful, self-active beings who may be designated as " persons." In this conclusion he sees a most important consequence of his personalist epistemology. Personalists who follow the tradition of Bowne develop an epistemological doctrine which they call " personal idealism." They hold that there is a real object of knowledge and that thought and thing are not to be identified as in Hegelian idealism. This they term the insoluble " dualism of thought • Cf. F. van Steenberghen, Epistemologie, pp. 44, 50. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 5 and thing." 6 Cognition implies this dualism: without it, knowledge in any intelligible sense would be impossible. To know an object implies that the object exists independently of my knowing it. This might be called the common-sense standpoint: my thought of an object differs from the object itself. While refusing to identify thought and thing as far as the human mind is concerned, Personalists view the world " not only as independent of man but as in a certain sense objective to God Himself." 7 The real criterion of the dualism of thought and thing is found, not in the disparity between the experienced object and the real object, but in their " otherness." Though the attribute of " otherness " is attributed to the real object, as opposed to the mind, Personalists inconsistently assert that the material world has no extramental reality. Again, though the external world possesses no extramental reality, epistemological dualism is safeguarded, in their view, by regarding the soul as distinct from God, and the world as a vast " system of stimuli." This system of stimuli is represented as, in a certain sense, objective to God, as well as to man. However, the precise nature of this " objectivity " would seem to call for clarification. Personalists find it difficult to explain how the world (call it " system of stimuli " or " medium of communication ") can be external and objective to man and yet possess no extramental reality. Nor is it clear in what precise sense the world is external and objective to God. But the world does exist independently of us; we discover it and we apprehend it, but we do not create it. Its exact nature we cannot know, but we recognize its causality as something external to ourselves. 8 Bowne asserts that the sense-world, in so far as it is articulate, is a thought-product. While Absolute Idealism identifies thought with thing, Personalism believes that objects do not pass away when we cease to think of them, neither do they suffer change with the fluctua6 A. C. Knudson, The Philosophy of PMsonalism, p. 100 ff.; B. P. Bowne, Theory of Thought and Knowledge, p. 296 ff. 7 A. C. Knudson, op. cit., p. 99. 8 Knudson, op. cit., pp. 103-110. Bowne, Personalism, p. 68. 6 JOHN A. CREAVEN tions of our thought. The dualism of thought and thing is inevitable. The world exists independently of us, but we can never know its essential nature. Personalists deem that it may even be a divine thought or system of thoughts. The world, without rational principles, is an inarticulate, fleeting flux. This discontinuous impression is interpreted into an abiding self, with the aid of a priori principles of mind. Bowne regards as an illusion the belief that there is an " absolute system of reality," with which our thought must correspond in order to be true. Reality is nothing more than the contents of consciousness. We can, therefore, reject the extramental universe of unreflecting thought, for it is impossible to define the world apart from intelligence. We remain in the world of personal experience, convinced that this world can never be explained on the impersonal level. The world of experience can be explained only through a rational, spiritual principle which reproduces it for our thought. 9 This position of Personalists is akin to that of Santayana and the so-called " critical realists." Our belief in the existence of other minds and so of society is a reasonable hypothesis for the explanation of our experience, but can never be empirically verified. Experience gives us certainty but not knowledge. Experimental verification, without the interpretative activity of reason, condemns us to solipsism. The supposed objectreference of experience, which to the naive-minded establishes a prima facie case for realism, is really nothing more than a " knowledge-claim." Experience becomes knowledge only when it is rationally organized, and refers beyond the fleeting experience to something else. III We should note here that Personalists have not discussed certain questions which concern the very foundations o£ epistemology. We must now formulate them in order to give our evaluation a more fundamental character. What is "knowl0 Bowne, op. cit., pp. 107-lH!, 160. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 7 edge " in general? What does the term imply in the philosophy Does my knowledge of Personalism? Have I "knowledge"? attain to "truth"? The issues raised by Personalism do not entail a discussion of the critical problem nor an evaluation of the various attempted solutions. But it should be pointed out here that, on the Thomist side, a noteworthy contribution to critical epistemology has been made by L. NoeU 0 His so-called " immanent " method is calculated to throw much light on the critical problem and may serve as a critical scientific supplement to the theory of the Personal Idealists. The appeal of such a method to the Personalist should be obvious: starting from an immediate fact of consciousness, it proceeds technically by way of critical reflection and of universal methodic doubt to establish the fundamental conditions of knowledge and of scientific construction. 11 St. Thomas was no stranger to such a method. "(Veritas) wgnoscitur ab intellectu secnndum quod intellectus reflectitur s,upra actum suum, non solum secundum quod cognoscit actum suum, sed secundum quod cognoscit proportionem ejus ad rem." 1 .2 Logically, this is the primary fact: " I know something" and "I know that I know it." This is akin to Descartes' " Cogito " but there are important differences in the implications and interpretations of the respective starting-points. Setting off from these immediate data of consciousness, present to the knowing subject, philosophical reflection may rebuild the edifice of human knowledge from what is most easily known. In this way, we may attain to a true critical and metaphysical realism, and at the same time show that to start from thought is not necessarily to eliminate things, and hence that the ego-centric predicament of modern idealism is in no way inevitable. St, Thomas, in various contexts, takes a more general view of ·the fact of knowledge as a certain aspect of living beings. :For Noel's doctrine, cf. his Le Realisme lmmediat. Cf. L. Noel, Le Realisme lmmediat, passim. F. van Steenberghen, temologie., pp. 1-8. 12 St. Thomas, De Veritate, q. 1, a. 9. 10 11 Epis- 8 JOHN A. CREA VEN In this sense, it is true to say that the existence of one being for another, which begins on the animal level and is perfected with man, is precisely what we mean by knowledge. 13 Natural objects exist but in no way adapt themselves to the external world. They are endowed with a principle of life by virtue of which they move and grow. The external world does no more than permit or prevent their movements of growth or expanSIOn. But when we ascend from the mineral world and the domain of vegetative life, we see that knowledge first appears with the animal kingdom. The movements of animals are not wholly explicable by their own internal principle of life. They reach out to influence and be influenced by their environment. The actions of an animal in search of prey are evidence of this. Something outside the animal exists for the animal and many complicated actions are performed to bring it within his grasp. One living being becomes aware of another being. The being which knows is, in the first place, its own essence. But in so far as it knows, it becomes something more. It becomes in a manner the object known. Knowledge then essentially means that into the knowing being there enters another being previously existing for itself. As St. Thomas puts it: "Cognoscentia a non-cognoscentibus in hoc distinguuntur, quia noncognoscentia nihil habent, nisi formam suam tantum, sed cognoscens natum est habere formam etiam rei alterius; nam species cognita est iJJ cognoscente." 14 The difference between that which is never anything but its own essence and that which is, on the contrary, capable of becoming other things, is precisely the difference between the material and the spiritual. " The limitation of the form is due to matter," says St. Thomas. And while the material element in a being restricts or limits it, the spiritual element, on the contrary, enlarges and amplifies it. Hence the gradation of being depends on the varying proportions of spirit and matter. Man is, in a certain manner, capable of becoming all things by his senses and intelligence. "Anima est quodammodo omnia." 13 Cf. E. Gilson, Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, p. 262 ff. "Summa Theol., I, q. 14, a. 1, ad Resp. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 9 Having placed the problem of human knowledge in its broadest perspective, we may now consider the personalist solution. The same fact of knowledge presents itself to us under two different aspects, according as we envisage it from the point of view of the contribution of the object known, or from the aspect of the knowing subject. Personalists consider chiefly the objective point of view. We shall see that their view is idealistic, for the world is not really independent of mind but is constructed by the creative activity of thought. The dualism, so frequently asserted but so rarely explained, is designed to place a real distinction between thought and thing, between idea and object. From the personalist exposition, it is difficult to determine what is implied by this dualistic doctrine. The failure of Personalism here is due largely to the fact that a dualism is asserted to exist between two realitiesthought and thing, idea and object-which are not precisely defined. That th(i)re is a real object of knowledge must be granted. But in what form is it to be conceived? This problem is not settled by a priori theories of the nature of man. Only reflection on our own conscious knowing processes can reveal to us anything concerning the nature of their object. St. Thomas, following Aristotle, holds that being is the first intelligible concept attained by our minds. We can perceive nothing, or conceive nothing, otherwise than as a being; and it is only when we have thus perceived or conceived being that we can determine the nature of the object apprehended. Being, says St. Thomas, is the first intelligible concept and the proper object of the intellect. " Ens est proprium objectum intellectus et sic est primum intelligible." 15 The intellect knows that its judgment is true by a critical reflection upon its act. The intelligence, by reflection, discovers its true nature, which is to conform itself to things: " in cujus natura est ut rebus conformatur." For St. Thomas, a real world exists and is intelligible: its intelligibility permits it to be apprehended by us in sensations and perceptions. 16 15 Summa Theol., I, q. 5, a. !l, ad Resp. 16 De Veritate, q. 1, a. 9. 10 JOHN A. CREA VEN Personalism has not offered a consistent theory of the nature of the object of knowledge. It affirms the dualism of thought and thing, that the thing is an " other " to thought. Mind and its object are asserted to be two distinct realities: the mind apprehends external reality. Such statements are sufficient to satisfy the most ardent realist. But when this doctrine is further developed, it furnishes difficulties which can scarcely be less than contradictions. Thus, while the world " manifestly exists independently of us," and ." the dualism of thought and thing is ... ineradicable," the world is denied any extramental reality. 17 Again, while reality is not something predetermined by the human mind-while, rather, it is " something revealed to us through sensations and perceptions," something discovered but not constructed, "something other than our thought of it "-yet it is asserted that the dualism of thought and thing is not a " fundamental metaphysical one." 18 In short, the dualism turns out to be a quite unintelligible compromise between monism and pluralism, a shadowy distinction hovering somewhere in the misty region between " otherness " and metaphysical dualism. In such a doctrine, it is difficult to understand the status of the object in relation to mind. If we would trace the source of these contradictions, we should note first the nominalistic trend of the whole personalist epistemology. The abstract and universal have no existence apart from the individual and the concrete. Bowne regards our thinking as mainly symbolic and our class-terms as mere logical symbols. Allied with this Nominalism is the attempt to combine an idealistic view of the world with a dualism of mind and object. In the opinion of personal idealists, matter, as an object of sense-experience and of scientific investigation, is not ontologically real. True, metaphysical reality is not composed of substances, whether material or spiritual, active or passive, which somehow persist through time. On the con17 18 Knudson, op. cit., pp. 103-104. Ibid., pp. 106, 113. Bowne, Theory of Thought and Knowledge, pp. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 11 trary, all reality is personal and is constituted by the unifying activity of consciousness. There is no such thing as a real world, possessing extramental existence. For Personalists, the physical world has a purely phenomenal character and an existence which is secondary and instrumental. Hence the inconsistent solution of the critical problem. On the one hand, it emphatically asserts a dualism of thought and thing, seeing clearly that only on this basis is it possible to offer a consistent theory of knowledge. On the other hand, this dualism must permit an idealistic view of the world. The objective world must not be given an existence entirely independent of mind, in such a fashion that it should exist whether minds apprehended it or not. The external world must be one that " exists only as it is conceived." 19 As a consequence of this double allegiance, the dualism becomes unintelligible. Beyond the repeated assertions that it exists, that it is " inescapable," " ineradicable," but not " metaphysical," no illuminating account is offered which would define its precise nature. The mere dogmatic assertion of the existence of a dualism of thought and thing is logically insufficient to found it as a philosophical doctrine. The confusion of the personalist position should make it clear that the only consistent solution of the problem of knowledge lies in realism, asserting ·a metaphysical dualism, in which mind and its object are two ontologically distinct realities. This doctrine Personalists are obliged to reject by the exigencies of their system, which contains the fundamental principle of the creative activity of thought. IV Personalists reject the realistic starting point of St. Thomas, according to which the mind apprehends an objectively existing order. To do full justice to the claims of human reason, they deem it necessary to assign to it a very full and independent role. Reason must be active, a constitutive factor in the world. Hence the cardinal principle of personal idealism19 B. P. Bowne, Metaphysics, p. 5. JOHN A. CREAVEN that thought-processes are primarily creative. Reality is, in a sense, revealed to us through our sensations and 'perceptions; they are the " media " through which it is " given " to us. Thus we are brought into contact with it, we become aware of it, through external stimuli. There is in our knowledge an element which is " given," which we do not create, but which comes to us from without. The raw material of thought in the sensibility is due to external stimuli. But apart from this initial impulse, thought is creative rather than receptive. The structure of our knowledge is due to mind-the mind constructing nature. The extreme position is taken by Carr that both the structure of our knowledge and its contents are determined by the mind. 20 To nai:ve thought the world exists as it is perceived. No distinction is made between primary and secondary qualities. The object seems to determine completely the knowing process. With the appearance of error, however, doubt arises: the doubting mind begins to distinguish the " apparent" from the " reaL" Next arises the question of the true nature of things, and this leads to metaphysical speculation. As a result, we are confronted with a double standard-that of the senses and that of reason-and thus we face the problem of their relative value. Personalists reject the ancient and medieval systems of epistemology because of their " crudely :realistic foundations." Such systems, it is alleged, made the object the determining factor in knowledge, while the subject became the passive The mind was represented as recipient of this determination. a tabula rasa, and the figure of the seal and wax was employed to illustrate the perceptive process. The medieval epistemologists, in general, subordinated the knowing process to the object in such a way that the reality of the object was supposed to be given in thought itself. 21 In opposition to such a view, Personalists uphold the creative activity of thought. Regarding Kant as the first philosopher to conceive thought 20 H. W. Carr, "Imagination op. cit., p. 119. 21 Knudson, and Reason," The Personalist, XII (1931), p. 90. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 18 as creative, they rely chiefly on the Critique of Pure Reason to furnish a basis for their epistemology. Pre-Kantian philosophy, in their view, over-emphasized the receptive function of the human mind, because knowledge was regarded as something wholly " given " to us. In sense-experience, we received impressions from without and in reasoning we either brought to light what was implicit in the sensory data, or brought to consciousness what was innate in the human mind. There was a diversity of views as to the nature of the external stimulus; but it was generally held that sense-perception implied a realistic view of the world. Sense-experience was produced in us by some power external to ourselves rather than by the mind itself. The doctrine of creative thought-activity is designed to place the senses in thorough subordination to reason. The most effective means of achieving this is the denial of all ultimacy, all self-sufficiency, to sensations and perceptions. They are represented as thought-products, having no definite content until they are articulated in thought. This was precisely the contribution of Kant. In the Critique of Pure Reason, the sensibility, as the passive recipient of external stimuli, can yield nothing but fleeting impressions, lacking coherence and all intelligible content. Sensations, of themselves, without the impress of thought, lack unity and identity. l'hey constitute merely the raw material of thought, its abstract presupposition. As soon as they become definite enough to be called sensations of anything, they already have the character of thought impressed upon them. Sensations, perceptions and memory images are products of thought activity. The passive sensibility has no power to produce sensations or perceptions of a definite character. What it contributes is inarticulate. By this doctrine, Kant hoped to establish firmly the supremacy of reason against the claims of sense. His rationalism took away from sense the last shred of cognitive independence, and reduced it to complete inactivity. Whatever cognitive value it seems to have is due to a priori principles of thought. 14 JOHN A. CREA VEN Pre-Kantian philosophy is arraigned by Personalists on the charge of conceiving reason as a purely passive and receptive faculty, and of allowing too great a share of independence to sensations and perceptions. As might be expected, the major portion of the criticism is reserved for Aristotle. His theory of knowledge conceived reason as firmly anchored in sense, and failed to make any sharp distinction between senses and reason. The function of reason was to read off; or interpret, the universal concepts which are implicit in sense-experience. Indeed, it is asserted that his doctrine is " saved " from empiricism and sensism only by a declaration that the intelligence, as a faculty, is as original as the sensibility. And the failure of modern Thomists to deal sympathetically with Kant's philosophy is attributed to their adherence to the " sense bound " epistemology of their master, Aristotle! 22 For Personalists, Kant's greatest contribution to philosophy was his rejection of the passivity of mind and his emphasis on the creative activity of thought. He showed that a priori, structural principles of thought, the categories, give form and meaning to our experience. They introduce order into the fleeting impressions of the sensibility. Aristotelians always ascribed a dangerous independence to sensations, perceptions and memory-images. These- preceded thought and had a certain independence of it. In all these strictures on Aristotle, there is room for a better understanding of his doctrine of the universals and of the abstractive activity of the intellect. We must bear in mind that it is ever on the question of the metaphysical status of the universals that he is at pains to stress his departure from Plato's doctrines. While this is so, it is, perhaps, possible to admit some truth in the assertion that he never completely succeeded in freeing himself from the ultra-realism of his master, though he was quite conscious of all the difficulties inherent in the latter's doctrine. 28 Perhaps, too, he did not completely harmonize the Platonic unity and eternity of essences •• For such criticisms, cf. Knudson, op. cit., pp. ff. •• Cf. Regis Jolivet,' La Notion de la Substance, pp. 86, 804. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 15 with their existence in many individuals. Nor does he consistently distinguish metaphysical essences from physical substantial forms, using the term" form" (eiSos, t-topcp.q),to designate now the one, now the other. But in his view, all existence is concrete and individual; the individual only has existence in the real order. The universal, as a universal, exists only in the apprehending mind. The universals are not, as Plato asserted, self-subsistent, substantial entities. In particular, being and unity, the widest of the universals, are not substances. The polemic which he directs against hypostatization of universals (as in the Platonic forms) is one of the leading notes of the Metaphysics. The world in which we live is, for Aristotle, a world of concrete individual things, acting and reacting on one another. In contemplating these individuals we become aware of certain characteristics common to many of them. These characters are, for Aristotle, as real and objective as the individuals themselves. They are not, in any sense, mental constructions. In his criticisms of the Platonic Forms, he warns us that we credit them only with that existence proper to universals, viz., they exist only as attributes of individuals. We must not fall into the Platonic error of positing a separate world of universals. The mere operation of ideas cannot explain .our world, which is one of change and becoming. And in this connection, too, we should recall the celebrated Aristotelian distinction between first substance and second substance-a distinction which is strangely ignored by Personalists. First substance is individual: this man, this house. It neither exists in a subject nor is affirmed of one. Second substance is universal and is called substance only by analogy. It is affirmed of a subject, as a predicate, but nevertheless does not inhere in a subject. 24 The universals are affirmed only of first substances: " Peter is a man." The universal, "man," expresses the nature of Peter but does not inhere in him as a subject. The Aristotelian doctrine of moderate realism was adopted •• Cat. 5 (fla 11); ibid. (flb 15) ;· ibid. (Sa 7). 16 JOHN A. CREA VEN by the mediaeval Scholastics. In his Commentaries on the Metaphysics of Aristotle, St. Thomas writes: "Nihil est in rerum natura existens, sed tantU?n in consideratione intellectus abstrahentis communia a propriis." 25 Again: "Sed universale est commune multis, hoc enim dicitur quod natum est multis inesse, et de multis praedicari." 26 v It should be quite clear at this stage that Personalism is committed to an idealistic view of the world. If the structure of knowledge is built up from within mind itself, then the existence of an extramental world is a mere assumption. Many of the qualities commonly attributed to such a world (e. g., color, sweetness, bitterness) have no extramental existence. Since these secondary qualities have no counterpart in reality, the perceptual world cannot be a replica of the external world. We can never perceive any world other than the one we construct. The world I perceive, Bowne tells us, is the world I construct-this is true of all perception. But though they regard the external world as phenomenal, Personalists are agreed in asserting the reality of the self. Here personal idealism parts company with Kantian phenomenalism. For Kant rejected a knowledge of the noumenal self and taught a doctrine of a shadowy Ego. He rejected as mythical the existence of noumena, or things-in-themselves (Dinge-an,-Sich) . But since phenomena are effects, it is very natural to seek their causes. Kant rightly held that the categories are valid only in their application to the objects of a real or possible experience; but he erroneously restricted experience to sense-experience and to physical sensations. For the Personalist, it embraces also the domain of self-experience, or self-consciousness. The categories acquire their full meaning only in their application to an Ego. The category of causality, for instance, can imply nothing more than the self-conscious efficiency of a •• Lib. XI, lect. fll74. •• Lib. VII, lect. XII, 157fl. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 17 free intelligence. 27 If the self is real it must be active: reality and inactivity are incompatible. A self wholly passive would have no substantial reality; its reality is manifested in and through its activity. Thinking is of the essence of the soul, and only in so far as thought is creative does it form a constitutive part of the world. Personalists find the ultimate theoretical basis for the reality of the self in the creative character of its thought-activity. Thought, which is essentially a creative process, requires as a fundamental condition the existence of a self which endures, and which remains identical throughout the successive changes of mentallife. 28 For the Personalist, the world does not exist as it is perceived. This was the " old " theory which borrowed all its force from the supposed immediacy of perception. The perceived world contains something more than the real world. The latter (which, for Personalists, is a system of stimuli) is in some way incomplete without mind. Indeed, if we follow to their logical conclusion the arguments of the personal idealists, we should be obliged to hold that the world has no existence apart from knowledge. Its existence, if it possesses any, is purely embryonic, or instrumental: it exists in order to be known. Our minds fashion nature: the world is a thoughtproduct. We have here touched upon a fundamental vice in the personalist epistemology. It is pervaded by a tendency to set up constitutive principles of thought anterior to all experience. This tendency is a legacy from Kant, and, as in the Critique of Pure Reason, it leads to an idealistic view of the world. Kant changed the emphasis on the receptive character of human thought and made mind a creative and determining factor in the manufacture of experience. Personalists adopt his doctrine to "save" human reason from sensism. In their view, if reason is to be safeguarded, it must be assigned a very full and independent role. It must be conceived as active, a constitutive factor in the world. This preoccupation with the •• Bowne, Personalism, pp. 108-104. 2 •• Knudson, op. cit., pp. 186-188. 18 JOHN A. CREA VEN vindication of reason is largely due to a failure to understand the traditional Scholastic doctrine of moderate realism. In this doctrine, reason is certainly not subordinated to sense, and hence there is no danger that by accepting it we are capitulating to sensism. In the Thomist epistemology, our ideas are derived from the senses and thus from things, but by the operation of a spiritual faculty; and so are different from sensations and images. But though essentially different from sensations and images, our ideas are abstracted from them by the operation of a spiritual faculty. The mind is active but its activity is not creative. It does not impose its own subjective forms upon the data of experience. The essential activity of the human mind is an abstractive one, drawing from the data of experience the essential qualities or knowable elements of things and utilizing them in the formation of a universal concept. Sensists likewise hold that our ideas are derived from the senses, but, in their view, the senses are, of themselves, sufficient to produce them; ideas do not differ essentially from sensations and images. Personalists accept the Kantian doctrine of the sensibility and of the categories of the understanding. In their reconstruction of the Critique of Pure Reason, they are led to present an idealistic view of the world, but at the same time cannot steer clear of many of the contradictions inherent in the Kantian system. The most serious of these contradictions has been noted already in discussing the alleged dualism of thought and thing. It has to do with the existence of things-in-themselves and their relation to the knowing faculties. The crucial question for epistemology, and one which stands at the parting of the ways of idealism and realism, is: Does the human mind apprehend an objectively existing order? Or is this order fashioned by mind itself? To this all-important question, Personalism has no consistent answer to offer. In defending a dualism of thought and thing, it would seem to imply a belief in the existence of things-in-themselves as an " other " to thought. But this dualism is subjected to quali- PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 19 fications that are incompatible with a realistic view of the world. The source of this difficulty is to be traced to an allegiance to Kant's critical philosophy. The Critique of Pure Reason rejects the possibility of a knowledge of things as they are in themselves. 29 The intuitions with which all knowledge begins contain nothing real, nothing as it is in itself, nothing beyond phenomena, or the modes in which things affect us. "All 01,1r knowledge," says Kant, "begins with sense, proceeds thence to understanding and ends with reason, beyond which . nothing higher can be discovered in the human mind for elaborating the matter of intuition and subjecting it to the highest unity of thought." 30 The sensibility receives impressions from transcendent, unknown objects. These intuitions are first determined by the a priori forms of space and time, and are then further formed by the categories of the understanding into scientifically conceived things. Thus arise the synthetic a priori judgments which are valid, for the universal element in each is a determinable law of the mind, the application of which can be known a priori. The necessary and predictable character of experience is due to the subject. But the objects determined by the categories are not noumena but phenomena, that is, the real intuited spatially and temporally. Phenomena, to which alone our knowledge extends, are but the appearances of things, the modes in which they affect us. That which lies beyond phenomena is the noumenon, the Ding-an-sich. For Kant, every real object is a physical object, and as real object can be apprehended only by an intuition. Must we then abandon all effort to know noumena, to attain the Dinge-an-sich? The theoretical reason, indeed, fails to give us any knowledge of things as they exist in themselves. It can tell us nothing of the deepest truths of reality: God, freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul. These truths it can never apprehend, for they can never become phenomenal. But lest " our unavoidable ignorance with regard to things in 29 Cf. Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental Doctrine of Elements, I, Transcendental Aesthetic. •• Ibid., Transcendental Dialectic, II, A. QO JOHN A. CREAVEN themselves" should prove too irksome, lest the necessary limitation of our theoretical cognition should unduly gall us, Kant hastens to reassure us that the practical reason supplies the deficiency. The practical reason, for Kant, is not the reason strictly so-called, but the will, which prescribes and decrees. The Ding-an-sich is, therefore, not known but believed. 'We need not relinquish such truths as the freedom of the will, or the existence of God, because they lie beyond the ken of the speculative reason. Such truths are possible, and since they are the basis of our moral life, :reason confidently believes them. The assent to such truths is granted, not because of theoretical evidence but because of the practical claims of the mmal life. " I must, therefore," said Kant, " abolish knowledge to make rooni for belief." 31 The " ambitious attempts to demonstrate the immortality of the soul from the simplicity of the soul's substance, or to deduce the existence of God from the conception of an " ens realissimum," must now be abandoned. The practical reason demands that man lead a morally good life, and such a life is impossible unless certain metaphysical truths be admitted. The practical reason, therefore, postulates these truths. They are accepted, not because of a theoretical conviction founded on objective evidence, but because of a certain invincible moral persuasion, a "faith." 32 The resulting position is that " no one will be able to boast that he knows that there is a God and a future life. . . . My conviction (scil. of these truths) is not logical but moral certainty; and since it rests on subjective grounds (of the' moral sentiment) I must not even say: It is morally certain that there is a God, etc., but: I am morally certain; that is, my belief in God and in another world is so interwoven with my moral nature that I am under as little apprehension of having the former torn from me as I am of losing the latter." 33 The necessity of obeying the moral law forces me, according to my interests, to believe in the existence of God, of immortality, etc., as this is the sole CritiqueJ of Pure Reason, Preface. Critique of Practical Reason, Part I, Book 2, 2, vii. •• Critique of Pure Reason, Canon of Pure Reason, Ill. 31 32 PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY condition on which my moral end could agree with all other moral ends and so have practical validity. Hence Kant ends by elevating faith above reason and grants primacy in matters suprasensible and metaphysical to faith, in which assent is a necessary supposition of reason, ultimately due to will. Hence the categories do not extend our knowledge beyond phenomena: they do not lead us to a noumenal knowledge of what is given in sensation. Of themselves they are empty; in order to be valid they must be :filled by experience, and all the content that experience can put into them is phenomenal. " The understanding a priori," says Kant, " can never do more than anticipate the form of a possible experience; and, as nothing can be the object of experience except the phenomenon, it follows that the understanding can never go beyond the limits of the sensibility. As phenomena are but representations, the understanding refers them to a something as the object of our sensuous intuition. This means a something equal to X, of which we do not, nay, with the present constitution of our understanding, can not know anything." 34 This something is the noumenon, the transcendental object, the Ding-an-sich or thing-in-itself. In the Kantian system, the status of this real object is very difficult to determine. The Personalist position is, perhaps, even more obscure. The nature of the physical world remains a mystery, unsolved by the metaphysicians of the school. Whether it exists in itself (as the Kantian Ding-an-sich) is not clear, though this seems unlikely, since all extramental reality is denied. Personalists have, after Kant, radically changed the whole conception of the nature of knowledge. Instead of a vision, or seeing of the object, knowledge is now a fashioning of the object out of the raw materials supplied by the sensibility. It is a product of a blind synthesis of a priori categories of the understanding with the sensible intuitions furnished by the sensibility. Such a theory fails in the test of critical reflection. It contradicts the immediate testimony of consciousness according to 34 Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental Doctrine of the Faculty of Judgment, Chap. III. JOHN A. CREA VEN which we apprehend objects which are external to us but which we do not construct in the Kantian sense. If there is to be knowledge in any intelligible sense, it must be of something for which the subject's act of knowing cannot in any way be held responsible-something not created by the mind's action, and, in so far as not created, revealed to it. In our perception of the external world, there is indeed a degree of " fashioning " or " construction " which it would be arbitrary to deny. Our cognition of an object here and now perceived is completed, developed and given fuller detail by means of objective elements formerly perceived. But this elaboration of our cognition is very different from the creative activity of thought upheld by personal idealists and by Kant. The latter makes the object of knowledge of construction resulting from the imposition of a priori forms of the understanding on the data of the sensibility. It is assumed by Personalists that Kant has forever settled the question of the nature of knowledge; whereas, in reality, his solution of the critical problem is full of artificialities and contradictions. An adequate basis for a concrete Personalism is not to be found in Kanes transcendental idealism. VI For the Thomist, the person is in its acts and it is only by a study of the intellectual activity of man that we can hope to arrive at a knowledge of his nature. Now, every act of intellectual knowledge is at once a revelation and aB active possession of the ego. To know is to affirm that things are, that the real exists; it is also to possess, in an imm3¥ent fashion, the object known. All intellectual knowledge, then, whether the object be the ego or the non-ego, is fundamentally an Ieh denke, a consciousness. If we consider knowledge of consciousness of the self, this proposition is self-evident; for in self-consciO«sn.essthe person possesses itself in spiritual fashion, an:d is actively present to itself. This further implies that the ego, to a certain extent, constructs itself by its activity. The human personality is not given, in actu primo, as a form whiGh is com- PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY fl8 plete and perfect, with its character of selfhood completely achieved. It is by its own activity, and chiefly by intellectual activity, that the person perfects and develops itself. We can say then, with truth, that, in a certain sense, knowledge is constitutive of the human ego. Without cognitive activity, the human individual could, be considered as an ego; but it would be difficult to conceive the peculiar selfhood of a person constituted by the mere fact of individual existence. 'Vhat is true of knowledge considered as consciousness of the self is equally true of knowledge of the non-ego. The active assimilation of the forms of other beings by the ego is a perpetual affirmation of ourselves in the representation of another. This fact differs radically from the conclusion of Stern that our epistemological nature compels us to think of the world in the form of personality. This is a view which borrows all its force from the Kantian doctrine of the nature of the human mind and which, apart from this doctrine, is quite invalid. Reflection on our cognitive activity shows that an intellectual act reveals to us immediately only the existence of the self which knows. Thought, then, reveals the existence of an ego which perfects itself and possesses itself with a certain autonomy. This autonomous possession of the self, which for idealists is absolute, is, nevertheless, tempered by a certain dependence. Thought does not construct its judgments as it pleases; it is subordinated to truth, which dominates it. The mind conforms itself to the real order which is apprehended. It is so constituted that it must affirm what objective evidence reveals as true. And what the intellect affirms as true for itself, it feels constrained to affirm as true for all thought in every circumstance. In this way, and not from the Kantian "categories," arise our universally valid judgments. Truth, which is given as something objective, is the object of a disinterested attitude on the part of mind. In the second place, our intellectual knowledge carries an abstract and universal import, a source of both perfection and JOHN A. CREAVEN imperfection. Abstract concepts have the unique property of being applicable to an indefinite number of individuals. In seizing their essence, immutable and meta-empirical, the intellect comprehends in a simple unity a multiplicity of things. But this comprehension noes not extend to the individual aspects of things nor to their concrete character, and so it is schematic and imperfect, in consequence of the limitation of human intellect. 35 Under one aspect, then, our thought appears as an unlimited desire of knowledge. From another aspect, it appears as an imperfect act. As a thinking being, man is interested in everything, in the external world as well as in his own interior world; in beings material and spiritual, in facts and the relations of facts; in passing phenomena and in the unchanging essences of things. To define the objective amplitude of the object o£ knowledge, one cannot do better than say with St. Thomas that it is commensurate with being itself, with truth. But while intellect is thus an unlimited desire for truth, it is, at the same time, essentially limited in act. The intellect restricts itself to a particular aspect of the universe-a limitation imposed by the present condition of the union of soul and body. But it must never be conceived as shut up in the shell o£ solipsism. Its essential nature is to apprehend an objectively existing order: "in cujus natura est ut rebus conformetur." VII Thomism, in keeping with the Aristotelian tradition, sets out from the data of common experience. By reflection on man's intellectual activity, it abstracts the concept of being-byparticipation, which ultimately enables the intellect to affirm with certitude the existence of a Being subsistent in Itself. With the aid of many metaphysical principles, it constructs a hierarchy of all reality. Confirming the evidence of everyday experience, it teaches that the universe is a diversified and harmonious whole. The universe is made up of many different •• St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I, q. 55, a. S, corp. PERSONALISM, THOMISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY 25 substances, distinct from one another. This "pluralism" of St. Thomas stands in uncompromising opposition to all forms of monism. At the very beginning of its philosophy, Personalism departs from Thomistic thought. St. Thomas begins his system by affirming that there is a coincidence betweenthe laws of knowing and of being, and proceeds to construct a realistic synthesis. Personalism, on the contrary, builds its system on Kant's transcendental idealism, and never arrives at a consistent solution of the nature of reality. Thomism envisages a universe of things, which have being in various degrees. At the head of the hierarchy, it demonstrates the existence of a God ..o is being, but who is distinct from the universe and everything in it. The latter are creatures and are beings only by participation. Personalism is born of the idealist tradition and partakes of all its defects. With its doctrine of Nominalism, it distorts the essentially abstractive character of human knowledge, and by upholding the primacy of practical reason, it bases all our knowledge ultimately on a faith which can receive no validation from without. Faith is its own justification. Intellect is completely subordinated to will and is rendered incapable of attaining logical certitude. " The mind," says Bowne, " not driven by any compulsion of objective facts, but rather by the subjective necessity of self-realization and self-preservation." 36 For Thomists, on the other hand, human personality has two levels on which it can transcend the limits of its own nature. On the cognitive level, it can become, in a manner, all things, by enriching itself with their forms. On the appetitive level, man is capable of embracing every object that the intellect exhibits to him as good or desirable. The position that " life is richer and deeper than logic " is entirely in harmony with the Thomistic view of human nature. Man is not only, or chiefly, an abstract speculator. He is a living totality with practical needs and interests to which he must adjust himself in order to live a full, h1,1.man life. His practical necessities and theo36 B. P. Bowne, Theism, p. 27. 26 JOHN A. CREA VEN retical interests intermingle. The practical demands of social relations, the claims of a community life, as well as the exigencies of the material part of his being, constitute a large part of man's life. Human knowledge is not, then, a bare activity of intellect. It involves the whole man and requires . the co-operation of man's environment. It is an aspect of a general situation, of which the state of mind is only an element, though a very significant one. We may not overlook the physical elements in knowledge. In Personalism there is a lack of an orderly account of the knowing faculties, based on psychological investigation. There is ari absence of a systematic exposition of the different grades of knowledge, of the distinction between rational and sense knowledge. Personalists do not attempt a proper criticism of sensation, a task which is essential to epistemology. Yet only on such bases can we build a truly scientific treatment of knowledge. The Thomist knows very well that the knowledge-process is very complex. Into the " knowledge-situation " there enter objects known by their bodily activities, the bodily organism with its nervous system and senses, and the intellect. There is no such position as that of a bare, isolated intellect, directly confronting its object. The object of knowledge relates itself to the complete human self. JoHN A. CREAVEN, S.M. A. Dromantine CoTlege, Newry, Co. Down, N. Ireland THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING B y changeable being in general we here understand every- thing which is capable of successive motion or change such as that which we perceive by our senses. Various names are employed to designate this object. It is called sensible reality, or that which is perceptible by sense. It is called the sensible universe, or the whole consisting of things perceptible by sense. We speak of it as the material and the physical universe or nature" that is, the whole which consists of things capable of successive motion or change. We call it the corporeal universe, or the whole consisting of extended parts. We call it the sensible world, or the venerable whole perceptible by sense. We name it the cosmos, that is, the whole which consists of many different parts disposed in an orderly way and constiiuting a beautiful system. Through our sensory experience we are aware that there is something which appears changing and various. Sensible objects appear and disappear independently of our will. That which appears to us has the aspect or reason of being: it is something not only sensible but also intelligible. We apprehend the disappearance of an object from our experience as something opposed to being, and called non-being. We judge that being is not non-being, and thus we divide non-being from being. We understand that a being such as the self is undivided or one, and that one being is divided or distinct from anything else which we experience, as the self is distinct from our sensory activities. We experience many sensible objects, especially the objects of touch, as things opposed to our knowledge of them. We sense them acting sensibly upon us. So:me of thes€ objects are pleasant and we enjoy experiencing them. Others are painful and excite cmr grief. We cannot sense si.mply at will. Fre- 27 28 W. H. KANE quently we can touch that which. we choose to touch or escape that which we dislike by reaching for it or withdrawing or otherwise moving ourselves. The sensible world appears and acts sensibly as being distinct from our knowledge of it. In particular we are aware of the self, and we know that the self is not only something sensible but also something permanent and distinct from our knowledge of self. Through sensory experience and through our knowledge of being and non-being we know that objects of our knowledge are somehow distinct from our knowledge itself. Non-being can exist only in our knowledge, and as an object known, whereas the cosmos manifestly is in itself or has being of its own. We can initiate certain changes in the sensible world, and we understand some of the reasons for the things which we make, such as clothing and houses. When producing works of art we proceed from definite principles to certain ends. In this respect human art seems to imitate nature working through determined means to certain ends, as birds make nests for their young, and their young grow feathers for protection and for flying. Hence it seems that the cosmos is a work of intelligence and can be understood by us. The pageant of the changing world in which we actively participate excites our admiration and curiosity. Sometimes we observe it with wonder, and ask the solemn question: What is it? What is this reality which- undergoes sensible change? What manner of being is this, whose parts come sensibly into being and sensibly cease to be? What is its very essence? From what is it made? This question gives birth to philosophy, because the cosmos is the first reality which challenges the power of human reason to achieve a clear understanding of all that is. We are convinced that we understand a thing which has principles, causes or elements when we know what its principles, causes or elements are. Our scientific knowledge of a subject is derived from certain first principles which are the necessary sources of the being of the subject, or of its becoming, and of its bein.g understood by us. The first principles of THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE 29 BEING changeable being in general, and the principles of our scientific knowledge of changeable being, can be manifested by reasoning from the data of sensory experience and from certain general truths, such as the principles of non-contradiction and sufficient reason, and particularly from the principle which we state by saying that as a changeable being appears and acts sensibly, so it is. The first principles of a changeable being can be manifested conveniently after we have attained a general understanding of the numerical and specific degrees or distinctions which are to be found in the sensible world. Hence we shall consider in the first place the degrees or distinctions of changeable being in general, and then the first principles of a changeable being. I THE DEGREES OF CHANGEABLE BEING IN GENERAL Concerning the degrees or distinctions of changeable being in general, there are two questions to be decided: 1. Whether changeable being is one or many numerically? 2. Whether changeable being is one or many generically and specifically? 1. WHETHER CHANGEABLE BEING IS NUMERICALLY ONE OR MANY? Difficulties It may seem that changeable being is numerically one, for the following reasons. (I) Changeable being is known by us through our sensory experiences. By sensory experience, particularly by touch and vision, we apprehend something which appears to be extended without interruption. Therefore changeable being is one continuous whole. (2) Changeable being is the cosmos. The cosmos seems to be a great organism. composed of many part's having different properties and activities by which the whole moves itself to its own perfection. Therefore changeable being is numerically one. 30 W. H. KANE (3) Changeable being is the sensible universe or reality. But reality, or all that is, is one. Therefore changeable being is numerically one. Solution It is evident that there are in the world many colors, sounds, odors, tastes and tactile qualities, many changes in these qualities, and many movements perceptible by sense. Beings such as these sensory phenomena are called accidents. Through our knowledge of various changes which occur in us, we know that the self is distinct from the activities and other accidents by which the self is modified. Our walking does not leave us and go on without us, but requires the self as the subject in which it exists and to which it gives a secondary mode of being, that of locomotion. This is true also of our seeing and thinking, and of our color, warmth and figure. Our accidents inhere more or less permanently in ourselves. They do not exist simply, or have their being simply in themselves. But we are aware, especially through our free activities, that the self exists simply, and does not inhere in any subject. A being which is primary inasmuch as it exists simply in itself, not inhering in another, and which is the subject in which accidents inhere, is called a substance. When we inquire whether changeable being is one or many numerically, we are asking whether the whole world is one sensible substance, or consists of many substances which are absolutely distinct from each other. We know through our sensory consciousness that the self pertains to the sensible world. We can move and touch our head, arms and legs, and we are sure that these are parts of the self. Through our intellective consciousness we are aware of our individual being, that is, of the unity of our substance distinct from our activities and other accidents. We know that we are composed of many sensory parts which are parts of one and the same substance. By our sensory and intellective consciousness we know that the self is at least a part of the world, that we apprehend the world from within it, and that we have THE FffiST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 31 need to employ sensory experience and reasoning in order to understand the world. The self is either the whole substance of the world, or one substance among many. From ordinary experience it is clear that the self is not the whole substance of the world. We have sensory experience of many objects which we apprehend as distinct beings who are similar to the self and able to manifest their own thoughts and desires by means of sensible signs. The distinction between the self and another seems most evident when we are aware that our thoughts and desires are opposed to the thoughts and desires of the other. The unity of the self is manifested by the manner in which we operate. Anxiety disturbs our digestion; strenuous exercise impedes our use of reason. One intense operation impedes another within us, and this shows that all our operations proceed from the same source. Our vegetative life is the substrate of our sensory life and nourishes the organs of sense. Our sensory life is the substrate of our rational life, and somehow nourishes the life of reason. All of our parts with their various properties and activities are ordained to one higher activity which is that of our rational life. We can determine whether a whole of which we have experience is one substance or many by the way in which it appears and acts sensibly. That which appears and acts as a primary unit undivided in itself and distinct from all other things is one substance. If distinct properties appear in distinct parts, if no common property pervades the parts, and if the properties and activities of all the parts are not united and directed to a higher activity, then these parts are distinct substances. The world presents to our sensory experience many parts which appear and act as primary units having distinct properties and activities which are not united and directed to a higher activity. For example, the various beings which we call a dog, a bird and a tree appear and act as primary units. Things such as these are not mere groups of phenomena without any substance, because accidents require substance in which to exist, and because the sensory properties and activities of each are unified W. H. KANE from within. The numerous parts of the world which appear and act as primary units are disposed in an orderly way, and some promote the welfare of others, but the properties and activities of all the parts are not united and directed to a higher activity of the world as a whole. Hence changeable being or the sensible world is not one substance numerically, but consists of a multitude of substances which are absolutely distinct from each other. Reply to Difficulties (1) We achieve a scientific understanding of changeable being by reasoning upon the data of sensory experience with the aid of certain general truths. Material substance is perceptible through its sensible accidents, such as color and figure, but we apprehend a substance more perfectly by reason than by our senses. Our sensory consciousness is not sufficient to manifest all the parts or the exact limits of our own substance. Vision seems to be more refined than touch, yet even with the aid of a microscope we cannot observe the ultimate parts of sensible things so as to see whether their parts are continuous. But from sensory experience and the principle of sufficient reason we know that the sensible world consists of many parts which appear and act as primary units and which are distinct substances. Many distinct bodies or extended substances appear and act separately, and manifest that they have distinct terminations of their parts. Distinct bodies are discrete, not continuous. Hence the world is not one continuous whole. A house which is made from. many stones or bricks and pieces of wood is not one substance. Each polyp in a branch of coral exhibits all the parts and activities of a complete animal, and is an individual substance. A malformation in which the principal parts of the normal type are multiple is not one substance but many. A crystal of sugar has similar parts which cohere, and is an individual substance. (2) We have sensory and intellective consciousness of the self as an organism. From our knowledge of self and of other THE FffiST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 88 individuals like the self, we know that an organism is one sensible substance composed of different parts which it can employ as organs or instruments to move itself from within, as we move ourselves when we walk, or when we nourish ourselves and grow. The cosmos is not one substance but a whole consisting of many substances which are absolutely distinct from one another. Hence the cosmos is not an organism in the same manner or sense in which the self is an organism. Nor does the cosmos move itself simply, because it is not one being simply, or an individual substance. A family, tribe or nation is a union of many rational organisms, and does not manifest any operation higher than the rational activities of its members. A society is composed of primary units or individual substances, and is not itself a primary unit but a secondary one. A herd, flock or colony of brutes does not manifest any operation higher than the instinctive activities of its members, and is not one substance but a union of many. Ships, engines and other machines are composed of distinct substances which are united from without in such a way that one can be moved by another. Mechanical devices are secondary units, not primary ones, and they do not move themselves simply. (8) We apprehend the sensible universe not only by our senses but also by our intellect. Many accidents are perceptible by sense, but relations, such as similarity, equality and kinship, are purely intelligible accidents. Substance as such is a manner of being which is intelligible, not sensible, although we apprehend material substances through their sensible accidents. Substances are beings and units simply, or in the primary sense of the terms; whereas accidents are beings of a being, and are called beings and units in a secondary sense. From experience it is evident that the universe is not one substance or accident. Nevertheless, each being is one numerically, and the cosmos itself appears to have a certain unity of composition and of order, inasmuch as some material substances promote the welfare of others. The sun, for example, by its light and heat is of benefit to organisms. 3 34 W. H. KANE The consideration of being as such and of unity does not pertain to philosophy of nature, but to metaphysics. In philosophy of nature we consider only that which is proper to changeable being. Being as such and unity are purely intelligible and most universal, and are considered in the most universal science. 2. WHETHER CHANGEABLE BEING IS SPECIFICALLY ONE OR MANY? Difficulties It may seem that changeable being is one specifically, and does not consist of groups of substances which differ according to generic and specific degrees of perfection, for the following reasons. (1) Changeable being consists of many sensible substances. All sensible substances are material ones. Therefore changeable being is one specifically. (2) Materiai substances are known by us through precise experience. Such experience seems to manifest only moving particles, or matter and motion. Color to be due to the motion of particles or waves which strike our eyes and excite our nerves. Sound seems to be an undulatory motion in the air or some other medium. Heat seems to be a vibratory motion of molecules. The larger bodies are composed of many molecules, and these seem to consist of discrete particles which are disposed in empty space. Therefore all material substances are of one species. (3) Substances which do not perceptibly differ from each other are of one species. It seems that physical substances are so similar that they could all be arranged in a series in which adjacent substances would not perceptibly differ from each other and in which there would be no gaps. Therefore all physical substances are of one species. THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 35 Solution We know that the cosmos consists of a multitude of individual substances. Each observable substance possesses a number of sensible accidents which it presents as a group to our perception and through which the substance manifests itself to us. From experience we know that many individuals, for instance, human beings,. have similar sensible accidents, and are types of the same class or group of material substances. Other individuals, as a dog and a bird, manifest typical accidents or sensible properties which are abruptly distinct and are types of different groups. In regard both to structure and to function, we human beings appear to be most abruptly distinct from all other types. Our bodies are delicate and naked, and we must use reason and art in order to preserve ourselves and to attain ·the things which we require to perfect ourselves and be happy. We are conscious of some of our immanent actions, particularly of our sensations, emotions, thoughts and free activities. l,;Ve can manifest our sensory and rational life to others by means of sensible signs, not only by gestures, facial expressions and exclamations, but also by words and works of art which we produce deliberately and freely diversify. We observe that there are in the world many types of organisms which are clearly different from ourselves and from each other. Each of these types appears to act in a manner which is regular. For instance, robins have a similar call and build similar nests. Only the human is versatile and manifests the sensible signs of rational life. No other type of organism constructs and communicates with boundless variety. The organisms which we call brutes exhibit the signs of sensory life and possess organs more or less similar to our own. The horse and the dog have eyes and ears, and can move themselves toward or away from things which they seem to sense from a distance and to remember. Other types of animals, as the oyster and the earthworm, are less complex in structure 36 W. H. KANE and appear to sense only objects of touch and taste, not objects of sight and hearing. The organisms we call plants do not manifest the signs of sensory life and do not appear to have sensory organs. Yet the plants manifestly move themselves by growing, or increasing their quantity from within, and by producing new individuals of their types. There are many material substances which appear rigid or stable in structure and which do not appear to have parts by which they can move themselves or manifest the signs of organic life. Among these we find various types with sensible properties which are abruptly distinct and clearly different, such as those which we call marble and salt, iron and gold. Thus through experience we know that the world consists of many types of substances with sensible properties which are abruptly distinct and clearly different. By means of its sensible properties a changeable being manifests to us the nature of its substance. H there were no intrinsic reason for a substance to have certain accidents, or no necessary connection between a substance and any of its accidents, then definite types of substances would not be found in different and changing environments. In nature we do not find the typical human head joined to the body of a dog, but to the human body. The malformations which occur among the various organisms are contingent and exceptional, whereas the typical forms recur as a rule through many generations. As a changeable being appears and acts sensibly, so it is. Each definite and stable type in the world requires as its sufficient intrinsic reason a certain kind of substance. As a changeable being is, so it is apt to appear and to act sensibly. The specific nature of an observable substance is manifested to us through its sensible properties or accidents which are abruptly distinct and clearly different from those of other types. Clearly distinct types, such as a man, a horse and an oak tree, exhibit different properties and activities, which are not merely impressed upon them from without but proceed from within the substances themselves. Therefore these types are different in substance, that is, they THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 37 are individuals of distinct species. Hence changeable being is not one specifically, but consists of groups of substances which differ in specific nature. We find in the world various orders or kingdoms of living and non-living bodies. Human beings constitute the order of intellective or rational organisms. Animals and plants constitute distinct orders of sensitive and vegetative organisms. Among the non-organic bodies there are orders of compounds and the elements. By means of our intellective life we humans can control and freely diversify some of our activities. We can preserve and perfect ourselves, and can enjoy both sensory goods and the goods of reason. The brute animals can preserve and perfect themselves organically, and can enjoy sensory goods; but they do not appear to enjoy rational goods, such as humorous incidents, beauty, moral virtue, art and science. Man performs rational activities in addition to sensory and vegetative functions. Brutes do not exhibit the sensible signs of rational life. As a changeable being appears and acts sensibly, so it is. Man acts in a manner which surpasses sensory activities. Hence the specific nature of man or the intellective order is essentially more perfect than the sensitive orders and natures. The plants can grow and perfect themselves organically, but they do not exhibit sensory activities. Hence the animals are more perfect than the plants. The non-organic substances tend to preserve themselves by means of their physical properties, such as hardness and crystalline structure; but they cannot move themselves by means of their parts. When they are moved from without, they act on other bodies in ways which are typical of their species, as acids and metals act on each other. Hence the plants and the other organisms are more perfect than the non-living substances. The clearly distinct and typical organic structures in the various types of organisms are signs of specific differences, because these parts are not contingent accidents but are integral and necessary parts of the substances. The brutes manifest their specific nature especially by their instinctive behavior. 38 W. H. KANE Among the animals we can distinguish many genera and a great multitude of species by contrasting their typical organic structures, the degrees of perfection in their sensory life, and their instinctive behavior. Types of the more perfect species of animals, such as the cat, dog, robin, alligator, frog, trout, honey bee and squid, possess the higher senses, either vision or hearing or both. These animals can sense things which are at a distance and can move themselves with respect to such objects. Types of the less perfect species, such as the clam, earthworm, starfish and jellyfish, lack the higher senses and are simpler in structure and in sensory functions. Among the plants we can distinguish various genera and a multitude of species by contrasting the perfections of their typical organic structures and vegetative functions. The mosses and ferns, the grape and the apple are clearly distinct and different in regard to their typical structures and functions. There are many types of non-living substances which have abruptly distinct properties. By means of their color, odor, taste, crystalline form, freezing point, boiling point, and other observable and measurable properties, we can distinguish various genera and many species of compounds and the elementary bodies, for instance, sugar, water, oxygen, the electron and the proton. Among the properties of a compound there are some which are intermediate between those of various elements, and a compound is somehow composed of various elements. Hence compounds are more perfect than the elements. Thus we see that changeable being consists of distinct orders of substances which differ according to generic and specific degrees of perfection. A human being is one substance which is not only intellective but also sensitive and locomotive, vegetative and corporeal. Man possesses in himself the general perfections which are characteristic of the lower orders of nature, and so man is a microcosm or a little world. However, it is clear that the human does not possess the perfections which are typical of the horse or the oak tree, or of any other specific type. By THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 39 means of philosophy of nature man tries to assimilate the specific perfections of all natural bodies in a cognitive way. Reply to Difficulties (I) All material substances are of one kind inasmuch as they are changeable beings and pertain to the general order of nature or the cosmos. From their different sensible properties it is clear that material substances do not all pertain to one special order or genus or species. (2) The cosmos is manifestly rich in the number and variety of things which it contains. Color, sound and heat are accidents of material substances by which these substances act on each other and on our senses. A hot substance can heat a cooler one, and a sounding body can produce a similar sound in another body. When hot or sounding bodies act upon our senses we can sense their own heat or sound more or less perfectly. We perceive that heat and sound are abruptly distinct and different. Things which are abruptly distinct and clearly different are specifically distinct. Hence heat and sound are not of the same species of sensible activity or motion, but are specifically distinct qualities. Some individual substances, especially organisms, are composed of many molecules which are parts of one and the same substance, and are not distinct substances. Molecules which are individual substances are composed not only of particles but also _of an extended field, which is something physical. Even the electron and the proton have properties which are clearly distinct and different. There is much more in nature than homogeneous matter and motion. These are not sufficient reasons for the great variety of substances with different properties and activities which constitute the world. (3) The cosmos consists of many different types of substances which are disposed harmoniously and constitute a complete whole. In regard to the whole as a system there are no conspicuous gaps or defects. But between the living and the non-living, between the sensitive and the non-sensitive, and 40 W.H.KANE between the rational and the non-rational there cannot be an intermediate type of substance. There are gaps between the abruptly distinct and clearly different types of organisms, compounds and elements. Yet within each organic species there is considerable variety among the individuals, and the varieties of one species are similar to those of several other species in accidental respects and in generic perfections. The gaps between the distinct orders and genera are somewhat filled by more general perfections, by distribution, and by accidents which are more or less similar in different types. For example, the ivy and grape vines have some accidents and generic perfections which are similar, and the ape resembles man in some respects. But types such as these have sensible properties which as a group are abruptly distinct and clearly different, and are not one but many generically and specifically. II THE PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING IN GENERAL Concerning the principles of changeable being in general there are five questions to be decided: 1. Whether a changeable being has first principles? Whether the first principles are contraries? S. Whether there are only two or three first principles? 4. Whether one of the first principles is purely potential? 5. Whether there is only one actual principle in each changeable substance? 1. WHETHER A CHANGEABLE BEING HAS FIRST PRINCIPLES? Difficulties It may seem that a changeable being does not have first principles from which it exists and is made, for the following reasons. (I) That which is created out of nothing does not have first principles from which it is made. Changeable beings were created out of nothing by the Author of nature. Therefore changeable beings do not have first principles from which they are made. THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 41 (2) That which is or exists does not seem to have principles from which it exists and is made, because a being cannot be made from itself, nor from another being which already exists, can something be made from nothing by natural power. Changeable beings already exist, and their motion, heat and light seem merely to pass from one to another. Therefore changeable beings do not have principles from which they are and are made. (3) A principle is something which is first and from which something else proceeds or follows. One is prior to many. Therefore there is only one principle. (4) That which is divisible without limit seems to have an infinite number of principles, because a being exists and is made from the things into which it can be resolved or divided. Changeable beings are extended and are divisible without Therefore changeable beings have an infinite number of principles from which they are made. Solution We use the term principle in a wide sense to signify any source or origin from which a thing proceeds. Some principles are extrinsic to that which proceeds from them, as an artist who is painting a picture is extrinsic to the picture which is being painted by him. Other principles are within that which proceeds from them and are the intrinsic sources from which a thing exists and is made, as the wood is an intrinsic source of the table which exists and is made from the wood. By the first principles of changeable being we understand the intrinsic and fundamental sources from which any changeable being exists and is made. Through experience we know that many things in the world are newly made. Organisms can generate new individual substances, and they can become corrupted and changed into certain non-living substances. These in turn can be changed into other substances which are specifically different, as wood can be changed into ashes. Changeable beings appear to be capable a W. H. KANE of change, not only with respect to their accidents, but also fundamentally or substantially. We notice that changeable beings, as they are made in the course of nature, appear to exist and to be made from some antecedents, not from mere nothing. Things which are produced by natural change appear to proceed from intrinsic principles from which they exist and are made) as ice appears to proceed from water and from whatever else is required as an intrinsic principle from which ice is formed. That which is newly made is distinct and different from its antecedents, and appears to exist and to be made from principles which are distinct and different from each other, somewhat as the color purple appears to proceed from the colors red and blue. Yet it is clear that neither everything nor all kinds of things are required as intrinsic principles from which any individual changeable being exists and is made. Something brown is not generally required as a principle from which something is made sweet, nor is gold required as a principle from which water is made. Moreover, the sensible properties and the proper activities of a changeable being are limited in number, and appear to proceed from a limited number of intrinsic principles. Furthermore, some things proceed from others, as the color green proceeds from the colors yellow and blue, or as compounds proceed from elements; whereas the principles of a changeable being are the sources from which a changeable being exists and is made. Hence not all things are intrinsic principles. Thus we see that a changeable being exists and is made from intrinsic principles which are limited in number and are distinct and different from each other. Certain of these intrinsic principles do not proceed from others, because the number of principles in a changeable being is limited; nor do they proceed from each other, because they are different. Things which do not proceed from others, nor from each other, but from which any changeable being exists and is made are the intrinsic and fundamental sources or first principles of a changeable being. Therefore a changeable being has first principles from which it exists and is made. THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 48 Reply to Difficulties (1) The questions concerning the creation of a being out of mere nothing pertain to metaphysics, not to philosophy of nature, because these questions concern being as such, not changeable being exclusively. In the course of nature changeable beings are not made out of mere nothing, but from certain antecedents, and so they have first principles for which they exist and are made. (2) Sensible motions and qualities such as heat and color are accidents, not substances. Accidents do not have their being in themselves simply, but in a substance, and the same accident numerically does not pass from one substance to another. Through experience we know that a hot substance can act upon a cold one and can make it more or less hot. When such a change takes place, the same heat numerically does not pass from one substance to another, nor is some new heat made simply, because heat is not a substance, and is not apt to be or to be made simply. In this case, a cold substance is made hot, and some heat is newly made or made more intense in a substance which already exists and which is capable of becoming hot. Similarly, the motion of the self when we walk is not made simply, but is newly made in the self. Inasmuch as a being is something actual it cannot be made, because it already is. Through experience we know that change takes place, and that changeable beings are newly made. A changeable being is not made from mere nothing in the course of nature, nor from an antecedent being inasmuch as this is something actual. Between an actually determined material being and mere nothing there is a certain medium which is a potential principle, or something which is capable of receiving a new determination, somewhat as a cold body can become hot. (3) One is prior to many inasmuch as it is an extrinsic principle from which many things proceed, as an artist is prior to many works of art which proceed from him, or as a divisible whole is prior to the parts into which it can be divided. But that which is made as things are made in the course of nature 44 proceeds from more than one intrinsic principle, and so many intrinsic principles are prior to such a one. (4) Changeable beings appear to be composed of extended parts into which they can be divided. Yet each natural body is limited in its extension or quantity, and the individuals of a species do not vary indefinitely in regard to their quantity. Human beings, for example, can be large or small, but within limits of size. Through experience we know that natural bodies cannot be divided indefinitely without a change in species taking place. A man can have his arms and legs cut off and remain a man, but he cannot have his head cut off and remain a man, nor is an amputated arm or leg a human being. Hence there are certain first and substantial principles which are required for a man to exist and to be made. Similarly, all natural bodies have first principles from which they exist and are made. 2. WHETHER THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF A CHANGEABLE BEING ARE CONTRARIES? Difficulties It may seem that the first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are not contrary to each other, for the following reasons. (1) Things which are extremely distant and different from each other and which pertain to the same genus are called contraries, such as the red and the blue, the sour and the bitter. Something sour can become red, although sour and red are rather disparate than different from each other, and are not contraries. Therefore the principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are not contrary to each other. (2) Contraries are positive things, such as sweet and salt. A changeable being can be made from principles, not all of which are positive things. Something dark can become bright, although the dark seems to be merely the absence of light. Therefore the principles of a changeable being are not contraries. (3) The first principles from which a changeable being exists THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 45 and is made do not proceed from each other. Contraries can proceed from each other, as black can proceed from white, and white from black. Therefore the first principles of a changeable being are not contraries. (4) Contraries such as blue and yellow oppose and resist each other, and cannot coexist in the same body or in the same part of a body, at least not in intense degree. The first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made coexist in the same changeable substance. Therefore the first principles of a changeable being are not. contraries. (5) Changeable substances are not contrary to each other, because they are abruptly distinct in species and cannot be changed as colors or sounds can be changed from one extreme to another. The first principles from which a changeable substance exists and is made are :fundamental or substantial principles. Therefore the first principles are not contraries. Solution We know through experience that material substances can be modified accidentally and that they can be substantially generated and corrupted. We notice that bodies whi!ih are hot or cold do not heat or cool other bodies which are equally hot or cold. We find that moving bodies do not act on other bodies which are moving with similar velocity and direction. It is clear from experience that change does not take place indiscriminately. We do not observe that anything whatever proceeds from anything whatever, except by accident: when something is present which is not required for a particular change. A man who is a carpenter may become a writer, although it is not necessary that one be a carpenter in order to become a writer. The world appears to consist of changeable beings which are produced in a certain order :from principles of a certain character and which are corrupted in a certain order. We observe, on the one hand, that when something becomes black, it is made so from something not black. Yet it is not 46 W. H. KANE made from anything whatever which is not black, such as sweet or hot, because things which are neither sweet nor hot can become· black; but it is made so from something white, or of another color. When something becomes hot, it is made so from something cold or cool. When a statue is carved, it is produced from something which was crude or unformed. VVhen stones or other things are placed in order, the order is made from things which were scattered. When a compound is made or an ovum fertilized, the combination is made from things which were uncombined but suited for union. On the other hand, when something ceases to be black, it becomes white or another color. When something ceases to be hot, it becomes cool or cold. When something ceases to be formed, it becomes unformed. When bodies cease to be ordered, they become scattered. When a compound or organism becomes corrupted, it is changed into things which are uncombined. From experience it is evident that changeable beings are made from principles which are dissimilar and properly opposed to each other, and that they become corrupted into their proper opposites. Moreover, that which is made and which becomes corrupted does not exist before it is made, nor after it becomes corrupted. Hence that which properly becomes something else, as the white or non-black becomes black, or as the cold becomes hot, involves the non-being or opposite of that which is made; and that into which something becomes corrupted, as the combined becomes uncombined, involves the non-being or opposite of that which becomes corrupted. Things which are dissimilar and properly opposed to each other, as white or nonblack and black, cold and heat, order and disorder, union and disunion, are said to have contrary characters, and are called contraries. Changeable beings exist and are made from principles such as these. Therefore the first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made have contrary characters and are contraries. Reply to Difficulties (1) The intrinsic principles from which a changeable being proceeds are those which are required for its being and being THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 47 made. In order that something can become red, it is necessary that it be contrary to red, but it need not be sour. Hence the sour as such is not a principle of something which exists and is made red, but in this respect is merely accidental. (2) Contraries in the strict sense of the term are positive things, such as sour and bitter tastes, or red and blue colors. Yet things such as heat and cold, light and dark, are called contraries in a wide sense of the term. The first principles of a changeable being are contraries in the wide sense. (3) Contraries can proceed from each other inasmuch as they can succeed each other in a subject or substance, as black can succeed white in a subject which is white. But black itself is not composed of the non-black, nor white of the non-white. Contraries do not proceed from each other in the sense that one is composed of the other. The first principles of a changeable being do not proceed from each other, or are not intrinsically composed one of another, because they are the fundamental contraries and are opposed to each other as light and dark. (4) Blue and yellow are contraries in the strict sense, and they exclude one another in the same subject. A green can from yellow and blue, not inasmuch as these are yellow and blue, but inasm,uch as they are non-green, because that which properly becomes something else includes the non-being of that which is made from it, whereas that which already is does not become. Blue and yellow as such are extrinsic terms from which something becomes green. Anything which is nongreen, or contrary to green in a wide sense, can become green. Likewise, when something round becomes square, the round figure is an extrinsic term. The square is not intrinsically made from the round as such, but from the non-square and the square figure. The first principles of a changeable being are contraries in the wide sense, and are opposed as non-green and· green, or non-square and square. Principles such as these .exclude one another from themselves, and one is not composed of the other; but they are included in that which proceeds from them and which is intrinsically made from them. 48 W. H. KANE (5) Material substances of different species are not contrary to each other in the strict sense, because they are abruptly distinct, ·somewhat as triangles and squares are distinct. But if we consider the properties of various substances, and particularly their differences, such as living and non-living, sensitive and non-sensitive, they are contrary to each other in a wide sense. The first or fundamental principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are not contraries in the strict sense, but in the broad sense, somewhat as dark and bright. 3. WHETHER THERE ARE ONLY T'\VO OR THREE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF A CHANGEABLE BEING? Difficulties It may seem that there are not three first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made, for the following reasons. (I) Each changeable being exists and is made from its own principles. There are changeable beings of many different kinds, and organisms particularly appear to be very complex and to be made from many principles. Therefore there are very many principles of a changeable being. (2) The first principles of a changeable being are contraries. Only one thing is contrary to another. Therefore there are only two first principles of a changeable being. (3) The first principles of a changeable being are the fundamental sources from which it exists and is made. A changeable being can be made from a subject and one form, as something dark can be made bright. Therefore there are only two first principles of a changeable being. (4) A changeable being is made from the principles into which it can be resolved. Each changeable being can be resolved into a subject and a form, as hot water can be resolved into water and heat. Therefore there are only two first principles of a chap.geable being. THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 49 Solution Through experience we know that the principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are contraries in a wide sense, such as cold and heat, or dark and bright. But if cold is merely the absence of heat, and dark merely the absence of light, it does not seem that a changeable being can be made from them. Heat does not act on coldness and make it hot, nor does light act on darkness and make it bright, because contraries are not intrinsically composed one of another, and because that which is newly made in the course of nature requires some positive antecedent from which it exists and is made. Moreover, heat and color are accidents. They do not exist in themselves, but exist and are made in a subject or substance. Changeable substances also are made in the course of nature, and it seems that they cannot be made from the mere absence or privation of something substantial, together with only one positive principle. Hence it seems that there must be a third principle which is the subject of the contrary principles from which a changeable being exists and is made. When we examine things . which are made or modified in nature, it appears that there is always a subject in which change takes place and from which something is made or which becomes modified. We notice that a changeable being can be made either according to some accidental mode, as cold water can be made hot, or according to its very substance, as ashes are made. Hence things are not said to be made in only one sense of the word, but in many senses, according to the diverse things which are made. We observe that a change takes place between two terms, that is, from something to something else. When some water is heated or an apple turns red, it is the same water that was cold which becomes hot, and the same apple that was green or yellow which becomes red. There is somthing which remains throughout the change, namely, the water or the apple. There is also something which does not remain throughout the change, namely, the contrary of heat or of red, because the water is 4 50 W. H. KANE no longer non-hot after it becomes hot, and the apple is no longer non-red after it becomes red. Something which remains throughout a change cannot be the same, at least in concept, as something which does not remain. Hence the non-hot which becomes hot, or the non-red which becomes red, has two aspects, one of which remains and the other does not remain throughout a change. Likewise, when something which is nonsweet becomes sweet, or when the non-round becomes round, there is something involved which has two aspects, one of which remains and the other does not remain throughout a change. Something which thus remains throughout a change is called the subject of the change. The term from which a change proceeds and which does not remain after the change is completed is the opposite or privation of the term to which the change tends. The positive term to which a change tends and which is newly made in the subject of the change is called the form, for example, heat or redness. Some changes proceed from a positive term or form to the privation of the form in the subject, as when hot water becomes cold, or something bright becomes dark. Changeable substances are made when organisms and compounds are generated. The making or production of a thing involves the beginning of its being; and so only that which did not exist fundamentally or substantially before it was made is made simply. A human being, or a dog, or any substance which is generated, was not merely not a human being, or a dog, or any substance before it was generated, but was not simply, or did not exist. Hence when a substantial change takes place in nature something is made simply. However, we observe that new substances are generated from something antecedent, such as seed or elements, somewhat as a green proceeds from a yellow and a blue. When a new substance is generated, it seems that there is always a subject which remains throughout the change and which was deprived of a substantial form which is newly made in the subject. Moreover, when we examine the ways in which changeable THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 51 beings are made, it is clear that there is always a subject from which they are made. Certain things are made by a change of feature or figure, as a smile or a posture; others are made by addition or confluence, as a river from many streams; others by subtraction or erosion, as a mountain or valley; others by composition, as compounds and the higher organisms; others by division, as the lower organisms; others by growth, as leaves and feathers; others by alteration, as the color and odor of flowers and fruits. From all these cases it is clear that whatever is made in the course of nature is made from a subject which was deprived of a form which is newly made in the subject. In ordinary speech we sometimes designate the subject of a change and the form to which a change tends without expressing the privation which is involved. We say, for example, that some water becomes hot, or that a pumpkin turns yellow. We express the subject, the privation and the form when we say that a dark body becomes illuminated, or that a sick man becomes well. From this analysis we can determine the number of the first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made. The principles which constitute a changeable being are the positive things from which a changeable being exists and is made, and which are in the thing which is made. Everything which is made in the course of nature exists and is made from a subject and a form, and consists of a subject and a form, because a changeable being is composed of the things into which it can be resolved, and each can be resolved into a subject and a form, somewhat as hot water can be resolved into water and heat. Hence the first principles which constitute a changeable being are a subject and a form. But the subject from which a changeable being is made has two aspects: the positive and the privative, somewhat as a flower without an odor, or an apple without red. The subject, inasmuch as it is something positive, is a component principle from which a changeable being both exists and is made, some- W. H. KANE what as a statue exists and is made from marble or bronze. The privation of a form which can be made in a subject does not remain in the thing which is made, as the marble does not remain unformed after the statue has been carved from it. Hence privation is not a component principle of a changeable being. Yet a changeable being proceeds from a subject that is deprived of a form which can be made in it, as a red apple proceeds from one which is non-red, and a yellow apple from one which is non-yellow. Even when a subject has a certain form, for instance, an apple with the color green, it is deprived of an opposed form, such as red. But an apple as a subject merely happens to be deprived of red, and the marble happens to be deprived of a figure which can be made in it. Likewise, any subject with a certain form happens to be deprived of another form which it can receive. A changeable being neither exists nor is made without privation of some form. Hence privation is a principle from which a changeable being exists and is made, although it is a principle by accident, inasmuch as the subject happens to be deprived of a form which can be made in it. Thus there are two first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made, and of which it is composed, namely, the subject and the form. There are three first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made if we distinguish privation, which is a principle by accident. The principles are contraries if we consider the subject with privation as one principle, opposed to the form which is the term to which a change tends, somewhat as something cold and heat are contraries, or something non-red and red. But privation and form are not found without a subject. Moreover, the subject and the form are not contraries, because they coexist as component principles of a changeable being. The first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are not contrary to each other simply, but only by reason of privation in the subject; nor are they simply two, because the subject has two aspects, the positive and the privative, and these with the form are three principles. THE FffiST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 53 Reply to Difficulties (I) At this point in philosophy of nature we inquire concerning the first principles of changeable being in general, and we use particular instances only for the sake of general analysis and illustration. The proper principles of various kinds of changeable beings are considered in special parts of philosophy of nature. Through experience we know that certain changeable beings, particularly the higher organisms, are very complex in structure. An organism has many accidents, such as color, figure, density, heat and powers of operation, and is composed of many organs and elements. However, only the fundamental sources from which a changeable being exists and is made are its first principles in the strict sense of the term. The principles which do not proceed from other principles, nor from each other, but from which any individual changeable being exists and is made are a subject with privation and a form. (2) The first principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are not mere contraries without a subject. They are contraries and a subject in which a privation and a form succeed one another. (8) The subject from which a changeable being exists and is made is always deprived of certain forms, because even when it has one form it lacks others which it is capable of receiving, somewhat as an apple which happens to be green or non-red can become red. Hence privation is also a principle, although by accident. (4) The constituent principles from which a changeable being exists and is made are the subject and the form, because these are the positive and essential components of all that is made or generated in the course of nature. But a subject which has one form always lacks others which can be made in it. The privation of a certain form in a subject is required for a changeable being to be and to be made, because that which already is does not become, nor is something made from mere 54 W. H. KANE nothing by natural power. Hence privation, which is the lack of a form which can be made in a subject, is also a principle. 4. WHETHER THE FIRST SUBJECT IS PURE POTENCY? Difficulties It may seem that the first subject from which a changeable being is and is made is not a purely potential principle, for the following reasons. (1) Changeable beings appear to be and to be made from a material subject, such as water or air. A material subject such as water is an actual principle. Therefore the first subject from which a changeable being is made is an actual principle. (2) The first subject from which a changeable being is made is something real. Everything which is real seems to be actuaL Therefore the first subject is an actual principle. (3) The first subject from which a changeable being is made is something which receives the form which is made in it. Anything which receives a form seems to be an actual principle, as the wax which receives the form of a seal. Therefore the first subject is an actual principle. (4) The first subject from which a changeable being is made is something which cannot be generated or corrupted by natural power. Something which cannot be generated or corrupted by natural power seems to be the true and actual source of changeable beings. Therefore the first subject is an actual principle. (5) The first subject from which a changeable being is made is something good, because good things, such as organisms and compounds, are made from it. The good is something actual, because that which is not actual seems to pertain to defect or evil, which is the opposite of good. Therefore the first subject is something actual. (6) The first subject from which a changeable being is made is really the same as privation. Privation is not a potential THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 55 principle, but the absence of form, or non-beingo Therefore the first subject is not a purely potential principle. Solution We know through experience that new individuals of the various species, both living and non-living, are generated in the course of nature, and that changeable beings are changeable simply or substantiallyo It is clear, on the one hand, that a substance which actually exists cannot be made, because it already is. On the other hand, it is clear that a substance cannot be made from mere nothing by natural powero If new substances were made from mere nothing in the course of nature, a stone or a horse or any other substance could be made in the same way, and a subject with special dispositions would not be required for the production of a substance of determined species. From experience we know that an antecedent subject with special dispositions is required for the production of water, and of a dog, and of each specific type of natural body. Hence new individual substances are made from some primary or substantial subject which is capable of receiving a new substantial actuality and of losing the substantial actuality which it previously had. The substantial actuality of the antecedents from which a new substance is generated is extrinsic to the one which is newly made, which is distinct and different from its antecedentso A subject which is capable of receiving a new substantial actuality, and of losing the one which it previously had, of itself has neither the one nor the other. Therefore new individual substances are made from a primary subject which of itself lacks substantial actuality, which it is capable of receiving and which can be made in it. Such a subject is a first and purely potential principle, It is a first principle because it is a subject which of itself lacks the first or substantial actuality, and so it is not made from or composed of any other principle. It is a purely potential principle because it is capable of receiving a substantial actuality which can be made in it and which it does not have of itselt Hence the first subject 56 W. H. KANE from which a changeable being is and IS made potential principle. IS a purely Reply to Difficulties (1) Both accidental and substantial changes occur in the course of nature. The subject of an accidental change is an actual substance, such as water or iron. When an accidental change takes place, as when water becomes hot, there is nothing which is made simply, because the same substance continues to exist after an accidental change is completed in it. An existing material substance or natural body, which is the subject of accidental changes and of accidents which are made with it and in it, is called second matter. Second matter is itself a changeable substance which is and is made from its own first subject and substantial actuality. When a substantial change takes place and a new organism or compound is generated, an individual substance is made which did not exist before it was made. The first subject from which a changeable substance exists and is made is a purely potential principle, because it is something which is capable of receiving a new substantial actuality and of losing the one which it previously had. This subject is called first matter, because it is the first subject from which a changeable being exists and is made, or the first subject of change. (2) That which is simply real in nature is second matter, such as a man or a horse. Second matter is a subject which already has its substantial actuality or being, and so it does not receive its being simply through anything which is made in it or added to it. From second matter a new substance can be made only by accident, inasmuch as the one which is actual is not the one which can be made from it, somewhat as a black body can become white by accident, inasmuch as it happens to be non-white. A body does not remain black after it becomes white, nor does a changeable substance rema:in the same, individually or specifically, after it has been changed substantially, as the wood does not remain after it has become ashes. THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 57 A changeable being is made properly from its own component principles which are in it after it is made, whereas it is made only by accident from something which is not in the one which is made. When a new substance is generated, it is made properly from first matter, that is, from a subject which of itself lacks substantial actuality, and which receives its being or becomes actual through something which is newly made in it. First matter is something real in nature, qecause it is a component principle of a changeable substance. It is not an actual being, but a potential one. It is not a complete substance, but the purely potential part of a changeable substance. The first subject of change or first matter is a certain medium between mere nothing and an actual being. This subject is something which of itself lacks substantial actuality, and is not of itself apt to exist, but is ordained to existence through the substantial form which is made in it. First matter and substantial form together constitute a complete changeable essence which is apt to exist. When a substantial change takes place, a new substance is generated from the potentiality or first matter of one or more substax:..::eswhich previously existed, and the other or others become corrupted. In this way the generation of one substance is the corruption of another, and first matter always has a substantial form. (3) The subject which receives accidental fqrms is an actual substance or second matter, because accidents do not have their being simply in themselves, but in a substance which exists simply in itself. The subject which receives a substantial form is something which of itself lacks substantial actuality and is a purely potential principle. First matter receives a substantial form in a purely passive way, through the action of an extrinsic principle,. and the matter exists with dependence on the substantial form which it receives. (4) We say that something is true when we know that it is genuine or conformed to its standard. In particular we say that a judgment or statement is true when we know that it corresponds to the thing concerning which the statement is 58 W. H. KANE made. We know through experience that changeable substances are made simply in the course of nature and that they are not made from mere nothing. A new substance cannot be made intrinsically from a subject which of itself has substantial actuality, because that which already is a substance cannot become one simply. Hence changeable substances are made from a subject which of itself lacks substantial actuality, and which is a purely potential principle. This subject, or first matter, cannot be generated in the course of nature, because every generation requires a subject, and first matter is the first subject from which a changeable being exists and is made. First matter can be corrupted by accident, inasmuch as it was deprived of a certain substantial form which it no longer lacks after it has received the form, as something non-green becomes corrupted when it becomes green. But first matter cannot of itself become corrupted, because it is the term of corruptive change, and the changeable or corruptible substance is already corrupted when it is reduced to first matter. Hence the principle which cannot be generated or corrupted in the course of nature is not the substantial actuality of a changeable being, but its substantial potentiality. The world endures because generation and corruption are concomitant. New substances are generated from the first matter of other substances, and these antecedent substances become corrupted. First matter is not of itself knowable, because things are and are knowable through their formal or actual principles, whereas first matter is the subject which receives a substantial form, and is som8thing which of itself lacks all form and actuality. Yet we can know first matter by analogy or proportion. We know, for example, that wood of itself lacks all the artificial forms which can be made in it. But the wood sometimes has one form, for instance, that of a table; and sometimes it has another form, for example, that of a chair. Hence wood is distinct from all the artificial forms which can be made in it. We know also that the wood sometimes becomes ashes. Hence something which exists under the form of wood sometimes exists under form of ashes. Thus, something which THE FffiST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 59 is in wood and in ashes, and which is something distinct from the form of wood and from the form of ashes, is in a natural substance somewhat as wood is in a chair or. table. Yet first matter is not an individual substance, such as the wood. First matter does not of itself have form or unity in act, but is a being and unity only inasmuch as it is potency with respect to a substantial form, which it receives in a purely passive way, on which it depends for its actuality, and through which it is knowable. (5) Anything which is desirable is said to be good. From experience we know that everything seeks to preserve its own being and to achieve its own perfection. Hence a complete substance is that which is good, whereas the distinct perfections which a substance has or seeks are that by which it is good. First matter is not of itself good, because it is a purely potential principle. Nevertheless, first matter has an aptitude for good, inasmuch as it is a subject which can receive a substantial form by which it has actual being and perfection. In this respect first matter is distinct from mere nothing, which cannot receive a perfection. First matter is not desirable for anything which it has of itself, but it is inclined to a substantial form by which it is perfected. Even when first matter has one form it is inclined to all other forms which it is capable of receiving, and in this sense it always desires substantial forms. First matter is not evil, because evil is opposed to good, whereas the matter is not opposed to the form by which a thing exists and is good, but is. inclined to the fgrm. Moreover, first matter is useful for the substantial form which is made in it and for the substance which is made from it. (6) By privation we understand the absence of a certain form in a subject which is capable of receiving the form. Privation is distinct from negation, because negation is the absence of a form without a subject capable of receiving the form. A stone is said to be blind in the negative sense of the term, whereas a man is blind in the privative sense of the term. When a privation is considered as the mere absence of a 60 W. H. KANE form, it is distinct from the potential principle or first matter, because the absence of a form is itself non-being, whereas first matter is non-being only by accident, inasmuch as it happens to be deprived of a certain form. Moreover, first matter is a certain medium between nothing and an actual being, and is a being inasmuch as it is potentially a changeable being. Furthermore, first matter is an essential part of a material substance, is inclined to substantial form and perfection, and is useful for the form and for the material substance. But a privation is not a potential being, nor is it inclined to a form and perfection, because it ceases when the form is produced. Hence privation, unlike matter, is opposed to being and to good, and pertains somehow to evil, which is the opposite of good. Yet first matter has privations, because even when it has one form it is deprived of all the others which it is capable of receiving, and which it seeks or desires because it is capable of receiving them, not because it is deprived of them, since it is deprived of them only by accident. Still, first matter does not desire the forms without being deprived of them, because desire is always for something which is not possessed. Hence we must say that first matter has two aspects, namely, potency and privation. First matter is really the same as privation, because the matter or potency is something real, and is potentially a changeable being, whereas the privation is the absence of substantial forms in and including the matter. A certain privation is required for a change, and matter always has privations of the forms which it does not possess. But the privation of a form ceases when the form is made in the subject. Hence a changeable being is not composed of privation. Privation is only by accident, a first principle from which a changeable being exists and is made, inasmuch as the matter happens to be deprived of a certain form which it is capable of receiving. But first matter of itself is a first and purely potential principle from which a changeable being exists and is made, and which is in the one which is made, because it is the subject which receives a substantial form. THE FIRST PRINCIPLES 5. OF CHANGEABLE WHETHER THERE IS ONLY ONE SUBSTANTIAL CHANGEABLE BEING 61 FORM IN A SUBSTANCE? Difficulties It may seem that there are many substantial forms in a changeable substance, for the following reasons. (1) A changeable substance is composed of the principles from which it is made, and into which it can be resolved. Compounds and organisms seem to be made from various substances, and they can be resolved into substances of many specific types. Therefore there are many substantial forms in a changeable substance. (2) Many substantial forms are produced from the matter of a changeable substance, because many specific types are generated, at least in part, from the matter of each one. Whatever is produced from matter was contained in the matter. Therefore there are many substantial forms in a changeable substance. (3) When new substances are made in the course of nature, their substantial forms do not come from without, but either were in the matter or are made from nothing. Something cannot be made from nothing by natural power. Therefore there are many substantial forms in a changeable substance. Solution A first actuality or substantial form, which is something distinct from first matter, is required as a component principle from which a changeable substance exists and is made in the course of nature. When a new substance is generated, a new substantial actuality is manifested by new individual or specific sensible properties. For example, when some wood is burned, the wood becomes corrupted and ashes are generated. Such a change is not the total conversion of one or more substances into new substances. If this were the case, one substance would be entirely corrupted and another would be produced from mere nothing. But substances are not produced from 62 W. H. KANE mere nothing by natural power. Hence something of the antecedent substance remains in the one which is newly generated. The substantial actuality of the antecedent substance does not remain, but the substantial potentiality or first matter remains and receives a new actuality. A changeable being is not made from first matter alone, because first matter is a purely potential principle. Hence a substantial form distinct from first matter is required as a component principle from which a changeable being exists and is made. The substantial form of a substance which has been generated was not merely hidden in the antecedent matter from which the substance was generated. If this were the case, a new substance could not be made simply, because that which already is cannot be made. The substantial form itself is not the whole substance of a changeable being, because material substances are naturally changeable, whereas that which already is an actual substance does not become one simply. Moreover, if the substantial form were the whole substance of a changeable being, it would be entirely corrupted and a new substance would be made from mere nothing when a substantial generation takes place in nature. But we know from experience that natural changes require a subject, and that something from an antecedent substance remains in the one which is newly altered. Furthermore, a new substance cannot be evolved from the matter of an antecedent substance unless another substantial form is made in the matter. If the substantial form of the new substance was actual in the previous substance, then nothing is made simply; if it was merely potential, then it could not appear actual if nothing new is made in the matter. Hence the individual substances, both living and non-living, which are made in the course of nature are composed of a substantial form together with first matter. By observing the manner in which a changeable being appears and acts sensibly, we can determine whether there is only one substantial form from which it is and is made. Each individual substance appears and acts as one being simply. The THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 63 unity of a human being is especially clear from the fact that, although we are very complex in structure and perform many different operations, yet one intense operation, such as attentive thinking or swift running, impedes other operations such as hearing or digestion. This would not be the case if the first actual principle of all our operations were not essentially one. Moreover, we are conscious of the self as one being simply, which lives and moves and understands. A changeable being cannot be one simply unless it is made from one substantial form, because it has its unity from the same principle from which it has its being or actuality. Furthermore, we notice that generation and corruption are concomitant in nature. The generation of one substance involves the corruption of another or others. When a new substance is generated, the first subject of the change loses the substantial form under which it previously existed and receives another substantial form, individually or specifically distinct from the one which it had. Hence there is some incompatibility between distinct substantial forms which prevents them from being together in the same individual substance. The incompatibility between distinct substantial forms comes, in the first place, from the nature of a substantial form as such. A substantial form is the actuality by which first matter is actualized. It is the first actual principle from which a changeable being is made simply and is apt to exist in itself and to be the subject of accidental forms. A substantial form is the first actuality which is in a substance and which underlies all the other actualities in the substance. A substantial form gives being simply, whereas an. accidental form gives being in a certain manner, such as round, white or hot. When the first matter receives a new substantial form, the one under which it previously existed is expelled, because only one substantial form supplies the actuality which is absolutely first, from which a changeable being exists and is made simply. In the second place, distinct substantial forms are incompatible and cannot coexist in the same subject because each 64 W. H. KANE is apt to constitute, together with the first matter, a complete essence which is distinct from all others individually or specifically. Reply to Difficulties (I) A changeable substance is composed of the principles which are in it after it has been made, and into which it can be resolved properly, not by accident. An individual substance is one being simply, or a primary unit, and is not composed of many complete substances. A compound or organism is made by accident from various types of elements or other actual substances, inasmuch as the first matter of these substances happens to be deprived of a substantial form which can be niade in it. A new substance is made properly from its own constituent principles, which are the first matter and a new substantial form. Likewise, a compound or organism can be resolved by accident into substances of various types, each of which is made properly from first matter derived from the previous substance and from a new substantial form. The substantial forms of the substances from which a compound is made do not remain actual in the compound, because there is only one substantial form in an individual substance. As types of different species are unequal in perfection, so different substantial forms differ in perfection. The more perfect form includes in itself the general perfections of the less perfect, somewhat as the number five includes two and three, or a pentagon includes three angles and two more. (2) When a substance is produced from something in which it was contained actually, as when a coin is produced from a purse, nothing is made simply, because the substance already existed before it was produced in this manner. But when a substance is generated in the course of nature, a being is made which did not exist before it was made. A changeable being is made properly from first matter which remains from a previous substance and from a new substantial form. The substantial form of the new substance was not contained actually in the THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 65 matter of the previous substance, because the new substance is made simply. First matter is of itself pure potency, and has a merely passive inclination or proportion to substantial forms. The substantial forms to which first matter is of itself passively inclined and proportioned are contained potentially, not actually, in the passive potency of the matter, somewhat as the movements to which our power of running and jumping is of itself inclined and proportioned are contained potentially, not actually, in the active potency of the locomotive power. The potency of first matter extends to all the substantial forms which are dependent upon matter in order to exist and to be made, although each substance requires certain dispositions in the matter from which it is made and forms succeed one another in matter in an orderly way. A substantial form which is dependent upon matter in order to exist and to be made is contained within the scope of the potency of matter, and is made by the change by which the matter is moved or changed from potency to actuality. Such a form is said to be produced or educed from the potency of matter. A substantial form which is not dependent upon matter in order to exist is not contained in the potency of matter in such a way that this form can be produced from matter, or made by a change by which matter is moved from potency to actuality, but only in such a way that matter can be united to it. In a special part of philosophy of nature proof is given that the human substantial form, or the intellective soul, is not dependent upon matter in order to exist. (3) From our experience of the works of nature and of human art, it is clear that the forms of the things which are made do not come from outside the matter but are made in the matter by the action of competent agents. When a statue is carved, the form of the statue is made from nothing of itself. Likewise, when a substance is generated, a substantial form becomes actual which previously was not, and is made from nothing of itself. Yet forms are not made without an antecedent subject. Moreover, a changeable substance is that 5 66 W. H. KANE which exists and is made simply in the course of nature. A substantial form which is dependent upon first matter in order to exist and to be made is not made simply, because it is not a complete substance. It is not that which exists and is made simply, but the first actual principle from which a changeable being exists and is made. Such a form was contained in the potency of matter, and when the substance which has been made from it becomes corrupted, the form ceases to be actual and becomes potential, or returns to the potency of matter. By natural power something cannot be made from mere nothing, that is, from the absence not only of a form but also of a subject capable of receiving the form. Through experience it appears that a substance whose substantial form is contained in the potency of first matter can be produced from the matter by natural power. Hence first matter and a substantial form which is contained in the potency of matter cannot be entirely diverse, but in some way are one. When a substance is generated from the potency of first matter, something which is in potency becomes actual. Hence first matter is potentially something which the substantial form is actually. First matter and the substantial form are not of themselves complete substances, but together they constitute a substance which exists and is one simply. Hence first matter and the substantial form are one inasmuch as together they constitute one changeable being. But a being cannot be one simply, or a primary unit, and yet be made from many principles; unless one principle from which it is composed is purely potential, and the other is a first actual principle or a substantial form, because a being exists and is one simply by reason ofits first actual principle. There is only one first actual principle or substantial form in one substance. The substance, or that which exists simply in itself, is the subject in which accidental forms inhere. Hence first matter and the substantial form are united immediately, without any intrinsic bond distinct from themselves by which they are held together, somewhat as a smile is united to a face. First matter and the substantial form are joined by THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF CHANGEABLE BEING 67 the action of a competent agent, which moves the matter from potency to actuality, or which, as in the generation of a human being, disposes the matter and applies it to the substantial form. First matter and the substantial form together constitute the essence of a changeable being which is made simply, and which is apt to be in itself and to be the subject of accidental forms. w. H. KANE, 0. P. Dominican House of Studies, River For est, Illinois SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY T HE system of education which generally prevails in English-speaking countries bears many traces of the positivistic past in which it was developed, and has produced an atmosphere or mental outlook which, though favorable to the progress of the physical sciences, is definitely alien, if not hostile, to any proper appreciation of philosophic thought. Most people learn the rudiments of physical science and mathematics at school, but remain in absolute ignorance of even the very nature of philosophy; whereas, in many continental countries, philosophy figures conspicuously in the scholastic curriculum, with the result that the students can face life with a broad and universal outlook denied to those who have become acquainted with only one attitude and approach to the problems of life, and who turn to science to afford them the explanation of the univers.e. A public opinion which is unfavorable to, because ignorant of, philosophy has thus been created, and the philosopher has practically no common ground on which he can meet his public. For most people, philosophy is regarded as a sort of abstract theorizing about the facts of science, to whose methods and criteria it is bound. In practice this attitude, which is not only that of the man in the street but of many scientists also, amounts to a denial of philosophy as a distinct and independent branch of knowledge; and the philosopher comes to be regarded as a man who, through indolence or incapacity, shirks the detailed research of science, and contents himself with speculations or hypotheses built upon the facts which scientists have discovered at the cost of so much labor. In an attempt to explain the position of the philosopher in relation to the scientist, the following pages have been written. The distinction between the scientific attitude and the philo68 SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 69 sophical attitude 1 can only be rightly understood in the light of the historical causes which are responsible for their confusion. This historical retrospect will introduce us to the properly philosophical doctrine as to the relation of the sciences to philosophy; and in conclusion we will exemplify our conclusions by applying them to certain subjects on which science and philosophy seem to be in conflict. We can trace back the movement which substituted science for philosophy to the Renaissance, 2 but it is above all in the doctrines of Descartes that we can see the germs of the whole later development both of science and of modern philosophy. To Descartes is due the antithesis " nature-spirit " which was to dominate later philosophy, thus giving it an anthropocentric trend, and setting it on the high road to idealism. His concept of man as a mysterious union of two complete substances, one spiritual, the other extended, each endowed with its own independent life and in opposition to the other element, led to the regarding as the real man the thinking " I," the soul, whose essence is pure thought, and which has no direct contact and interaction with the body in the acquisition of knowledge. Knowledge, therefore, cannot begin in the senses, and sensation itself is a form of thought, so that other animals than man are pure machines; our real ideas are infused by a kind God, whose veracity is sufficient criterion of truth for us. Hence the proper method of knowledge is not discursive reasoning, but intuition; we have certain primitive ideas, clear and evident to the original vision of the mind, and deduction is but the process of combining these intuitions. But knowledge represents reality; 1 Modern usage of the word " scientific " cloaks an equivocation which may lead people to regard philosophy as " unscientific." The word " science " is now generally only applied to the body of the positive sciences; and in distinguishing the scientific and philosophical, we mean that philosophy is distinct from these sciences, with methods and aims specifically its own. But philosophy is a science in the technical sense of the word, and more perfectly than the particular sciences, as we hope to make clear in the course of this article. 2 The medieval Platonists, especially Robert Grosseteste, had already arrived at some kind of pan-mathematicism; cf. C. Dawson, Mediaeval Religion, London, 1984, Sheed and Ward, pp. 81-99. 70 A. J. MCNICHOLL and thus we get to the fundamental principle of the Cartesian philosophy: that the real is not to be defined in relation to existence, as the traditional school held, but as that which appears to the mind with clarity and distinction. 3 By thus creating an artificial chasm between soul and body, and by denying that the body is an essential instrument of the soul in the acquisition of ideas, thus contributing to its perfection, Descartes restricted knowledge to a pure activity of the soul, which consists principally in elaborating the ideas which it has received from God, and seeing them all in the fundamental intuition of the " I " in the " cogito," and of God. This not only opened the door to the later ontologism of Malebranche and, through the appeal to the veracity of God and the denial of the power of the senses to reveal the existence of things to us, to the later scepticism of Sanchez, Bayle, Hume and the Encyclopedists; above all, it led to that absolute idealism which is so prevalent today. By confining knowledge to the strictly immanent sphere of the mind, by making the idea the term of knowledge (a theory that had already appeared in Occam and Pereira), and by reducing knowledge to the intuition of clear, evident and irreducible elements, he cuts it off from all contact with external reality, and transforms it into a merely subjective process which does not measure itself on its object, but rather measures objects by itself. Kant had only to develop this doctrine, by asserting that the understanding fashions its own object, without, however, giving it being, and that we cannot know anything but the phenomena or empirical manifestations of things in so far as they affect us. But if we cannot know the external world as it really is, only our subjective representations of it, there is no reason for affirming its existence; all that we can know with certainty is our own reality. So Fichte was at least logical in transforming the mysterious and unknowable " ding an sich " into the pure "I," the necessary principle of the non-ego, the phenomenal 3 The fundamental position which this principle occupies in the philosophy of Descartes is well brought out by Mgr. F. Olgiati, La Filosofia di Descartes, Milano: "Vita e Pensiero," pp. SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 71 world, which it produces spontaneously and unconsciously. By this pantheism he thought to solve the nature-spirit antithesis, but in reality he denied nature by reducing it to spirit. Schelling sought to unite both nature and spirit in the transcending Absolute, the common and identical ground of contraries, and of which all things are but phases or manifestations. Hegel in his turn criticized this doctrine as leaving unexplained the transition from the Absolute to the opposing poles of nature and spirit. A rational process was necessary to account for the transformation of the primary ideal ground of reality into its different modifications; and so he furnished the metaphysical frame of this universal becoming, by which the real, which is thus identified with the rational, evolves itself dialectically into all things. Thus we get the first extreme solution to the dualism of Descartes, an absolute idealism and subjective pantheism, with all its innumerable consequences in the religious, social and political orders. A more immediate, and, in our present question, more important consequence of the Cartesian theory of knowledge is that if all knowledge is purely subjective and independent of external reality, there can be only one form of knowledge; there can be no real distinction between the sciences, and there can be but one method in acquiring knowledge. Philosophy is indeed the love of wisdom, but wisdom is the one and universal science, the total explanation of things, whether physical, mathematical or metaphysical. Beneath the apparent diversity of the sciences there lies a profound unity, for " all the sciences united together are nothing else than the human intellect, always one, always the same, however varied the subjects to which it is applied." 4 If science is one, there is but one universal method, essentially the same for physics, metaphysics and mathematics; and this consists in resolving, by means of the famous four rules, all knowledge into its primary constituents, the clear and evident ideas about which the mind cannot entertain any doubt. The relative or derived ideas are •" Regulae ad Directionem lngenii," Ia Regula (Adam et Tannery, Oeuvres de Descartes, Paris, L. Cerf, Vol. X, p. 860, 7-10). 72 A. J. MCNICHOLL to be resolved into those absolute ideas whose objects cannot be divided into a greater number of clear and simple natures. The method is hence one of decomposition of things into their absolute elements, and then a new composition of them, by combining these elements to form the relative or derived things; it is a method of intuition with regard to the clear and distinct elements, and of reasoning with regard to the composition of these elements. There is a great affinity between this and the Kantian method which transforms metaphysics into an enumeration and classification of the a priori elements of the mind; and such a numerical process tends to extend the mathematical method to all branches of thought. By postulating one method for both science and philosophy, Descartes really denied the essential difference between them, and changed metaphysics into an introduction to mechanics, medicine and moral science; while the philosophy of nature became identified with the physical sciences. He thus set in motion that cu:rrent of thought that was to lead logically to the position of Comte, Taine and Spencer, who asserted that philosophy is but the sum of the particular sciences in their organic connection, thus denying the reality of philosophy as a distinct science. This attitude is very common today, in practice if not in theory. It is assumed that the scientific method is the only valid approach to the interpretation of the universe, and that philosophy is OJ;Ily a sort of abstract physics, or, at most, a science whose duty it is to classify the different sciences, and to order systematically the data afforded by the physical sciences. It is thus made to depend entirely on the positive sciences, and is forbidden to advance any independent views on the nature of things; it may aid in forming those hypotheses by which we try to unite and explain scientific data, but this does not really add to our knowledge. Philosophy is made so dependent on the sciences that without them it has no real value, and strictly philosophical problems can be solved by an appeal to science. 5 5 How widespread was this conviction may be seen from the fact that om SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 73 The philosophy of the spirit, or the subjective side of the Cartesian system, is thus seen as an absolute intellectualism, a proclamation of the autonomy and absolute independence of the intellect; independence of the sensible origin of ideas, leading to an exaggerated intellectualism; independence of the object as the rule of knowledge, leading to a universal mathematicism; and independence of reality as the term of knowledge, leading to idealism. M. Maritain has well described this theory of knowledge as " angelism," 6 for these are the characteristics of the knowledge proper to the angels. 7 But the objective side of Descartes' philosophy, his philosophy of nature, was to lead to no less direful results. Just as the essence of the soul is thought, the essence of material things is extension and movement; matter is nothing more than geometrical extension, and even the most different phenomena are but the result of changes in position and figure, and of motion. 8 The clear and evident elements, to which all our notions about the external world can be reduced, are extension and movement; 9 and so the universe is a machine, where everything is the result of figure and motion, and physics is nothing more than geometry and mechanics. This position was not only to lead to positivism, by claiming to interpret the world in terms of motion and extension alone; it also led to a completely deterministic view of nature, which is nothing less than a doctrinaire mechanism. Nothing is to be admitted unless it can be proved by reason, unless it provides complete rational satisfaction; and that which affords this rational satisfaction in the philosophy of nature is mechanism, which completely accounts for the constitution and behavior of all natural bodies, animate and inanimate, for all universities still grant the degree of "Doctor of Philosophy " to those who have qualified in purely empirical science. 6 Trois Reformateurs: Luther, Descartes, Rousseau, Paris, 1925, Plon-Nourrit, p. 78. 7 Cf. St. Thomas, Summa Theologica, Ia Pars, q. 54-58. • Principia Philosophiae, I, 53, 63; II, 4, 27; (Vol. VIII, p. 25, 12-27; 30, 26-31, 12; 42, 4-22; 55, 4-11). • Cf. S. V. Keeling, "The Mechanism of Descartes," Philosophy, Jan., 1934, pp. 51-56. 74 A. J. MCNICHOLL matter may be reduced to space, and all vital activity, excluding thought, to locomotion. 10 This mechanism was already contained in germ in the Cartesian method; but its express formulation helped greatly in furthering the claim of positivism and mathematicism to embrace all reality within their spheres. The identification of corporeal substance with extension also marked the first step in that movement which ended in the denial of substance altogether. If the only correct and true way of knowing nature is to treat it as being composed entirely of extension and motion, the science of nature must disregard the notion of substance; and once it is granted that this science deals with everything that is real, the notion of substance is not only disregarded but rejected. The very definition of substance which Descartes formulated led to this same result, although, strangely enough, he affirmed that substance was the only reality, in denying the reality of accidents as distinct from their subject. Accidents for him were but modes or determinations of substance in its proper line. 11 The affinity with Spinoza is evident. By making God the only substance and the only reality, Spinoza was but completing the work begun by the father of modern philosophy, and contributing no less effectively to banish the idea of substance from the science of finite or created being. There is also a similarity of method between these two philosophers, for Spinoza expressly applied the geometrical method to metaphysics and moral science, thus subordinating them to the mathematical study of nature. It has been well said that Spinoza stands in the same relation to Descartes as Hegel does to Kant, for he also did but draw the principles of his predecessor to their logical conclusion. But in the former case, the transition was effected mainly through the occasionalism of Malebranche. The Cartesian dualism between soul and body was developed by Geulinx into an anthropological occasionalism which nai:vely regarded the soul and the body in the manner 10 Principia Philosophiae, IV, 198, 199 (Vol. VTII, p. 14); and M editationes de Prima Philosophia, 3rd Med. (Vol. VII, p. 43, 10-45, 8) 11 Cf. Principia, I, 61-64 (VIII, 16-31, 31). SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 75 of two clocks ticking in harmony; a doctrine which recalls the pre-established harmony of Leibnitz. But :Malebranche extended this occasionalism to all things, making God the sole cause, and reducing creatures to the state of utter passivity, since they are but instruments and channels of the activity of God. As the concepts of cause and substance are so closely related that only a substance is a cause in the ontological sense of the word, Spinoza could claim the authority of :Malebranche for his assertion that there was only one cause and one substance. The result was, of course, a universal determinism, the denial of free will, of metaphysical causality, especially of final causality, of the reality of finite substances, and hence of personality. We may thank Spinoza for showing us in advance what to expect when we apply the mathematical method to the study of all reality. This intellectualist, or rationalist, movement on the continent, which led to pantheism and idealism, and, in Kant, to the denial of metaphysics as a science, was paralleled by the empirical movement in England, which was to lead to positivism and materialism, and to a no less complete rejection of metaphysics in favor of the empirical sciences. These two movements, so widely. different in character and consequences, have a common origin; and they may best be summed up as the full flowering of the seeds of Cartesian philosophy, planted· in the more speculative soil of continental thought, and in the practical and empirical soil of English thought. Modern continental thought has been described as the conclusion of a syllogism, of which Descartes formulated the major premise: " Nothing is true or real, except what is clear and evident to the mind." Kant provided the minor premise: " But only that is clear and evident to the mind which the mind produces of itself." The inevitable conclusion, "Nothing is true or real except what is produced by the mind," sums up the fundamental idea, the principle of immanence, which is at the base of modern continental idealism and pantheism. But the English philosophers, inclined by nature towards the practical and empirical, subsumed a different minor premise under the major 76 A. J. MCNICHOLL of Descartes; they said: "But nothing is clear and evident except what the senses tell us, and hence has reference to matter." The logical conclusion is positivism, tinged by a materialistic outlook. Bacon had set this process in motion by his criticism of deduction as a source of knowledge, and by attempting to construct an empirical philosophy on the principles of the new scientific method, by means of induction alone. In practice this meant that philosophy comprised only logics and physics, while metaphysics, psychology and ethics were transferred to the sphere of revelation. Hobbes went a step further by applying this system to all philosophy, especially to ethics, and to politics. Reality for him was identified with what is corporeal, all activity is reduced to local motion, and substance is transformed into body. Thus philosophy is held to be the science of corporeal being, metaphysics is rejected as useless, and the sole instrument or means of knowledge becomes sensible experience and observation. Even thought is reduced to sensation, since the intellect is only the imagination using general terms; and man is disintegrated into a bundle of faculties and movements, having no substantial foundation, merely united in the " I '' by a consciousness which is nothing more than sensation. There is no room, of course, for free will in this conception of man; and sensualism, with its consequent hedonism in ethics, and individualism and absolutism in politics, is at last proposed as a philosophical system in England. If Hobbes was the moralist of the empirical school, Locke must be regarded as its representative in metaphysics. Though siding with Gassendi against the general doctrines of Descartes, and rejecting his innate ideas, his theory of knowledge has much in common with that of Descartes; but he modified it in restricting the intuition to the relations between ideas, which are only general images, and in making experience the sole fount of knowledge. He applied to the study of the mind what Bacon had laid down for the study of nature, and his contempt for deductive reasoning is well in the line of the Baconian tradition. It followed that we cannot know the essences of things, SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 77 and that the so-called secondary qualities are altogether subjective; we can only know the primary qualities, such as extension, bulk, figure and motion, and our notion of substance is entirely subjective, since it is a collection of images of those qualities which are always found united. This sensualism is the logical premise of the later materialism advanced by Voltaire and the Encyclopedists, by Condillac and Comte; but later English philosophy stands, like Locke himself, rather undecided between spiritualism and materialism. It refused to be either fully spiritualistic or fully materialistic, and preferred to guard an attitude of aloof reserve, if we except the extremes marked by Berkeley, on the one hand, and by such convinced materialists as Priestley and Toland on the .other. To Locke also is due that critical aspect which appeared in English philosophy, since he inquired into the powers of knowing and the conditions of certitude; and this attitude was to exercise, through Hume, a great influence on Kant. But if we call in question the objective existence of the secondary qualities, we should logically deny that of the primary qualities, since our perception of both pertains mainly to the senses. So Berkeley put forward the opinion that both were purely subjective; and since they comprise the sum total of corporeal reality in the positivistic and Cartesian systems, he maintained that external nature existed only in so far as it was perceived by the mind. All reality is produced by the soul, whether this soul is that of man or that supreme soul that we call God; the real world is the world of mind-images produced in us by God, and the world of our representations of things is only an ideal and subjective world. The only true substance is ideal, or rather, it is either God or the soul; that which we call substance is merely a subjective representation, which has no reality outside the mind in which it is conceived. Berkeley thus showed how close is the affinity between empiricism and the subjectivism of Kant. The denial of the reality of substance as distinct from its sensible accidents, on the ground that the mind cannot pierce beyond and beneath such accidents, if it does 78 A. J. MCNICHOLL not lead to scepticism, will naturally carry us into either subjectivism or pantheism. In Hume we see the principles of empiricism carried to such logical conclusions. He reduced the internal experience admitted by Locke to external sensations and looked upon ideas as especially lively images, whose function it is to unite and separate the materials furnished by experience. No wonder that this doctrine aroused Kant from his dogmatic slumber, and suggested to him his concept of the pure a priori reason, which was to result in a scepticism as devastating as that of Hume. This empiricism was logical in denying causality, for observation, the only source of knowledge, cannot reveal more than an empirical succession and co-existence of phenomena, and only a substance can be a cause. The denial of the reality of substance also premised the denial of metaphysics as a science of being, the denial of free will, and the denial of the human personality as a substantial principle of man's being and activity. We are presented with the doctrine that the mind is a succession or a stream of perceptions somehow :floating about and united in the void that we call man; nothing is left of objective reality but the phenomena that can be known by the senses. This is pure pan-phenomenalism. This concept of man found an echo on the continent in Condillac, who taught that all psychic activity is but a form of sensation, and that the ego is a collection of sensations which are present to the consciousness, either as now affecting us, or as recalled by memory. The voice of common sense was lifted in Scotland in protest against these extreme exaggerations, but the current was too strong to be stemmed. Hamilton proposed this doctrine again, by asserting that the ego is but a collection of states of which one is conscious. From this time onward metaphysics is definitely abandoned as a science, or is confused with the critical study of the value and conditions of knowledge. Cosmology, or the philosophy of nature, is identified with the physical sciences. is being gradually transformed into pure mathematics, and ethics is considered as pertaining to religion or mysticism, if it is not SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 79 subordinated to the sociological sciences. All that is left of philosophy is an empirical and denuded psychology, which may admit the existence of a mind, but then only as the theater of of certain operations. More generally, however, conscious life is entirely neglected in this study, and the theme of psychology has become the sensitive and vegetative side of man. This movement is praiseworthy in that it brought to light many elements of empirical psychology which had hitherto been more or less neglected; but from the beginning it was tainted with positivism, and gradually led to identifying psychology with biology, physiology and sociology. The modern psychologists are interested only in reflexes, behavior, conduct, and the measurable correlations between the different forms of spontaneity and reaction. This is due to a large extent to Herbart and the English school, who treat of vital activity as a mathematical associationism of sensations. Psychology has thus become purely external; the psychology without a soul of Ribot has given way to a psychology without consciousness, where all the attention is turned to the exterior aspect of man. Many theories now in favor are frankly sensualistic, such as behaviorism and parallelism, which see no real distinction between mental activity and cerebral physiology; while Spencer tried to give the scientific doctrine of evolutionism a philosophical signification by applying it to the psychic life. When philosophy has been reduced to such meager and rudimentary proportions, and linked up intimately with the physical sciences, the field is free for the positive sciences to claim the sole right to interpret reality and to discover the nature of the universe. The application to philosophy of the mathematical method by Descartes, and of the inductive method by Bacon, has led to this positivistic attitude. Among many scientists today it is a firm conviction that the only real knowledge or science is that which proceeds by observation, classification and analysis of particular sensible facts, and by determining, through induction, the laws which unite sensible phenomena. We can only show how unfounded is this opinion by examining the nature of sci- 80 A. J. MCNICHOLL ence in general, and setting forth the general relations between the positive sciences and philosophy. 12 The confusion that reigns in the world of science today is the price the moderns are paying for the rejection of metaphysics, the only science which can unify the sphere of knowledge and classify all the sciences according to their proper objects and methods. Once this unifying principle of all thought was abandoned, the world of science was split into several independent and water-tight compartments having no contact with each other and having no means of coordinating their findings in order to see their full significance and their repercussions in other branches of thought. Thus the way was prepared for any one particular science to claim the supreme position in the hierarchy of knowledge and the last word about the nature o£ the physical universe. This is precisely what has happened. We are now confronted with two great movements, positivism and mathematicism, in which the empirical sciences and mathematics respectively have put forward their claims to be supreme and to have the whole of reality as their object. Metaphysics is, as it were, the governing political power in the scientific state; it was the object of attack by its subordinates, and when it was overthrown the result was, as usual, a civil war between the rival scientific factions themselves. The fundamental points of positivism have "been well summed up by Dr. Fulton Sheen 13 under the following four headings: 1) The experimental method is the only valid and scientific one; 2) Its object embraces the totality of accessible truths; 8) The concrete is the sole 12 If we have insisted, in this brief historical summary, on the gradual elimination of the notion of substance, and therefore of cause and free will, it is these notions are intimately connected with our present problem; for the denial of substance and causality means that nothing is real except the sensible qualities, extension and movement; and since the positive sciences deal expressly with these, the way was prepared for the complete domination of thought by the mathematicophysical sciences of today. 18 The Philosophy of Sciencfll, Milwaukee, 1984, The Bruce Publishing Co., p. 17. As representatives of school he quotes Dr. D'Abro, of Yale, The Evolution of Scientific Thought from lfewton to Einstein, and B. Russell, The Scientific Outlook. SCIENCE AND PIDLOSOPHY 81 form of reality, hence every kind of knowledge that departs from empirical data has no objective value; 4) Experience is the only reason that can justify the adherence of the mind to any truth. With the amazing rise of the mathematical sciences, this positivistic view was, in many instances, either rejected or modified, and we are now witnessing the apotheosis of mathematics in the claim of the mathematicians to be the only accredited guides in the explanation of the nature of the physical world. The mathematical philosophy of science is summed up by Dr. Sheen 14 as that doctrine which holds that nature is composed of those ideal forms of reason which constitute the object of mathematics. Philosophy is denied any certitude of its own, only that which comes from facts, or mathematics applied to facts. It is only a synthesis of the sciences expressing a personal attitude towards life, a sort of mysticism allied to a metaphysical vision of the world. 15 By applying mathematical principles to the explanation of the physical world, the comparatively science of mathematicalphysics was created, and its theoretical physics is frequently regarded as the last word of reason about reality. Its philosophy of science, among its most extreme advocates, IS a combination of positivisim and mathematicism. Underlying this positivistic, and, to a lesser extent, the mathematical philosophy of science, we can detect a group of pre-scientific prejudices, such as the denial of the reality of substance and of the intelligible essence of things, and the denial of the distinction between the intellect and the senses. That the intellect is essentially distinct from the senses will be readily admitted by most human beings, for it is quite evident that there is some essential distinction between man and the other animals. 16 There are many proofs that the intellect is an 14 Ibid., p. 18. As representatives, he quotes Sullivan, The Basis of Modem Science; Eddington, The Nature of the Physical World (but we do not think that this is quite just, as we hope to show later on in this article); and Jeans, The Mysterious Universe. 15 Cf. Sir A. Eddington, The Nature of the Physical World, chap. 15. 16 Dr. Arnold Gehlen (Der Mensch: seine Natur und seine Stellung in der Welt. 6 82 A. J. MCNICHOLL immaterial faculty, while the senses are material, but we do not propose to enumerate them here, as they may be found in numerous philosophical works and nothing is to be gained by beating a dead horse. It is legitimate, even necessary, that the scientist proceed as if there were no intellectual beings and admit only what can be observed by the senses; for the particular sciences deal with the sensible phenomena alone, and their method is one of induction and observation, or, in natural history, of enumeration and classification. Experience is the sole guide for the scientist, and observation is the gateway through which scientific data must pass to be incorporated into the body of science. 17 But to exalt this methodological principle into a doctrinal one, by asserting that all reality is narrowed down to that particular region that can be perceived by the senses, is quite unjustifiable and amounts to denying the possibility of all science. The very first requisite of science is that it be intellectual, if not in its method at least in its formal constituents; we should certainly be very much surprised to see an assembly of cows, or even apes, gathered together to discuss the latest developments of the quantum theory. This does not mean that all knowledge is intellectual, for brute animals possess real knowledge, though merely sensible; but that organized form of knowledge which we call science is made up of conclusions arrived at by the intellect from the observation of reality and by deduction from first principles, and hence necessarily postulates a rational faculty (except in purely spiritual beings, who, by intuition, see the conclusions in the principles without having to deduce them) and can only pertain to man, in so far a11 he is gifted with intellectual powers. Science is hence primarily intellectual and therefore speculative, and the practical sciences are only Berlin, 1940, Part I) shows that even in his embryonic stages man is anatomically and physiologically different from and superior to even the highest animals. 17 Cf. Sir Arthur Eddington, The Philosophy of Physical Science, London, 1989, Cambridge University Press, Chapter I, especially p. 10: "Every item of physical knowledge must therefore be an assertion of what has been or would be the result of carrying out a specified observational procedure." SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 83 analogically so called, and are more correctly termed arts. All knowledge is an immanent activity; and science, being the most perfect form of knowledge/ 8 is necessarily immanent, a perfection of the intellect. As such it must be proportionate to the nature of the intellect, that is, immaterial and spiritual, and must have reference primarily to an intelligible object. Only such an object can insure that necessity and universality which true science postulates, and only the spiritual intellect can guarantee the participation of science in such essential objective characteristics. Hence any doctrine that denies the existence of supra-sensible knowledge and supra-sensible realities by that very fact teaches that all science is impossible. The principle of causality, which is the only stable basis of induction, falls to the ground; our knowledge is limited to the study of contingent beings as such, and can never attain the necessity and universality which science demands. Kant has shown that sensible experience, of itself, can never reveal such necessity and universality. I do not think that it has ever been seriously denied that science must have this character of universality, even in the particular sciences. The botanist does not build up a science about this particular flower which he is examining under his microscope, but on the enduring characteristics of this type of flower, and its permanent place among the classified forms of plant life; nor is the doctor concerned with the particular qualities of the body which he is dissecting, except in so far as they lead him to knowledge of the human body in general. But the problem of explaining how science attains this universality has always agitated the human mind, since Plato postulated the existence of the world of ideal and subsisting forms, until our own day. Such universality must not be merely subjective, for, if the object of science is mutable and can change into something else, we cannot build up a secure and certain form of knowledge about it. The individual, as such, is mutable, 18 For the moment, we do not distinguish between science and wisdom, but include both under the generic term " science." 84 A. J. MCNICHOLL and therefore cannot form the object of real science; and the world in which we live is composed of individual and contingent things. It is this aspect of mutability which has most impressed many minds, from Heraclitus to Bergson, and has led to varying forms of scepticism. But the world is not altogether contingent, for what is mutable supposes that which endures, since a thing must be before it can change; and it is this element alone, some intrinsic. necessity in the inmost constitution of beings, that can render science possible. This element is what we call the nature or essence of beings, that substantial principle which gives a thing a definite place in the hierarchy of being, which differentiates it from all other beings as regards its specific properties, and which underlies the sensible phenomena by which it manifests its nature and can therefore be known. It is an indivisible ontological entity; which cannot be known directly by empirical observation. Although it is unknown to the experimental sciences, it is far more real than the sensible properties with which these sciences deal. It is the reason for those stable relations which the sciences seek to discover among the sensible manifestations of things, and the ultimate ground of the consta:Qcy of certain operations under definite conditions. 19 Considered in its individual and particular existence in the world of external reality, the essence is indeed singular, and cannot form the object of science; but when it is spiritualized in that vital act of intentional union and psychical identification which we call knowledge, it acquires a manner of existence corrresponding to that of the intellect, for a thing as known in the concept has the very same existence as the act itself by which it is known. The intellect, when informed by the intelligible likeness of the object, becomes the object known, in a psychical assimilation and conformation. By means of the concept, the object known can thus participate in the uni19 In this respect, Bergson is right in saying that experimental science cannot penetrate to the real nature of things, and that this can only be '21 The modern distrust only divided Christendom into different theological camps but destroyed the unity of philosophical thought, by rejecting the philosophia perennis that had been the common patrimony of all Christians. It thus paved the way for divergent theories of life, and for conflicts on the most vital and important questions. No wonder that the man in the street is led to believe that there are no common principles underlying life and its problems, and thus adopts a practical attitude which consists in, facing each problem as it comes and in the best way possible. SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 125 and the value of intellectual knowledge is consequently doubt. If we would characterize pre-modern essential difference from modern thm.ight, we would say the former was abstractive, informed by the process tion, whereas modem thought is mainly inductive and empiricaL122 That is why metaphysics, and philosophy could be so cultivated in the past and is so neglected Metaphysics is the assertion of the power of the mind to to the realm of essences underlying the sensible phenomena, to penetrate within the data of sensible experience to intelthus ligible necessities which surpass all sense-knowledge, to attain to super-experimental knowledge of absolute certainty. H being as such is the object of the intellect, it is in the science of being as such that the intellect is most true to itself and most certain. But we are not gifted with an insight into the nature of things; and only by a long and arduous process can we ascend from the visible and concrete, by means of the intelligible causations implied in the world, to the full vision of the transcendental realm of eternal and changeless truth, The task of unifying the partial and complementary views of reality into one final and supreme synthesis, by which all beings may be contemplated in their prototype and source and all judgments seen in the supreme principle of thought, will take us a lifetime, even though others have already traced out the path. This final intuition has ever been the aim and end of philosophers as well as of mystics, and Bergson has shown that it can only be gained at the price of years of intense study and devotion to truth, But the prize is worth the struggle, and the joys of contemplation are sweetest of all. vVe find that the good in itself is not useful, because it transcends that which we call useful, because it is super-useful, and that it is of far more value to us than those limited goods which serve us. 12 ,2 Cf. Mgr. F. Olgiati, "Italian Neo-Scholasticism and its Relation to Other Philosophical Currents," in Present Day Thinkers and the N eJW Scholasticism, edited by John S, Zybura, Ph. D., St. Louis and London, l9Z6, Herder, Part H, ch. 8. 126 A. J. MCNICHOLL M. Maritain gives expression to this thought, saying: " What we need is not truths which serve us, but a truth which we serve; for truth is the food of the spirit, and we are spirits by the better part of ourselves. The useless metaphysics orders our speculative and practical intellect, not an order such as the policeman enforces, but an order springing from eternity. It gives man his balance and movement ... it unravels to him in all the extent of being, the authentic values and their hierarchy. It centers his ethics; it gives to the universe of his knowledge its just place, assuring its natural limits, and the harmony and subordination of the different sciences; 123 and that is more important for man than all the luxuriant fruitfulness of the mathematics of phenomena, for what does it profit a man to gain the whole world, and to lose the rightness of reason." 124 Physical science will make many errors and its true progress will be greatly retarded if the validity and necessity of a supporting metaphysics is not recognized. The contempt for this supreme science which one so often meets among scientists arises from a complete ignorance as to its true nature and leads to indescribable confusion and to the most absurd aberrations. The scientist uses, in the actual exercise of his science, many philosophical notions which he takes for granted, such as the existence of things independently of thought, the possibility of knowing them in some way, and the necessity of the supreme principles of reason. He has a certain idea of the nature of his 12 " The need for this function of metaphysics is stressed by Hutchins, op. cit., pp. 99, 101: "Metaphysics, then, as the highest science, ordered the thought of the Greek world, as theology ordered that of the Middle Ages. One or the other must be called upon to order the thought of modern times. . . . Both are totally missing today. And with them has gone any intelligible basis for the study of man in his relations with other men. . . . A similar degradation overtakes natural science. If the world has no meaning, if it presents itself to us as a mass of equivalent data, then the pursuit of truth for its own sake consists of the indiscriminate accumulation of data. . . . We believe, then, that if we can gather enough information about the world we can master it. Since we do not know precisely which facts will prove to be helpful, we gather them all and hope for the best. This is what we call the scientific spirit." 124 Les Degres du Savoir, pp. 9, 10. SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 127 science and its position in the hierarchy of knowledge, and supposes that his ideas are distinct from the objects which he considers. This pre-philosophy may be rudimentary and unconscious, but it is none the less real for that. If the only science which can justify these presumptions is held in contempt, physical science itself will suffer and will be deprived of all its reference to objectivity. 125 The sciences also have reference indirectly to the being of things as to the foundation of the explanatory representations which they elaborate. Since they depend on observation, and thus on the intuition of the senses, they, like the senses, declare implicitly the existence in the world of hidden ontological structures, which, however, transcend the scope of science. 126 In an era of countless inventions and great material advancement, dominated by the gospel of progress, it is but natural that we should be inclined to neglect the ancient philosophers who have spoken for all time. We are so impressed by the progress of the sciences that we assume that similar progress has been made in all the other fields of thought, and we think it a waste of time to read anything but the most modern books or to discuss anything but the current events. 127 We thus cast 125 There are signs that scientists are coming to recognize the need of metaphysics from a purely scientific point of view. Sir Arthur Eddington's book, The Philosophy of Physical Science, seeks to formulate the philosophy to which scientists stand committed by their practice. The recent developments of science force scientists to inquire into the nature of the knowledge they try to obtain and to invesigate the scope and validity of the observational processes used in science. Sir Arthur, however, is mistaken in thinking .that epistemology pertains to science. He realizes that it treats of the nature of knowledge (pp. I, ZZ, etc.) and sometimes says that it is a part of philosophy. In other places (pp. 18, 49, sqq.) he says that it is a part of physics. This is in direct contradiction with what he has said on the scope of physical science, which is concerned with measurements and does not treat of the nature of things. 126 Cf. Maritain, op. cit., pp. SOl, SOZ. 127 Cf. Hutchins, op. cit., pp. Z4, Z5, Z6: "Our notion of progress is that everything is getting better and must be getting better from age to age. Our information is increasing. Our scientific knowledge is expanding. Our technological equipment in its range and excellence is far superior to what our fathers or even our older brothers. knew. . . . In intellectual fields we have no hesitancy in breaking completely with the past; the ancients did not know the things we know; they 128 A. J. MCNICHOLL aside the grand intellectual heritage of past ages, as if only the moderns had anything of importance to say to us, as if they alone had the monopoly of eternal truth. We forget that human nature is essentially the same now as when Aristotle walked in the cloisters of the Lyceum, or when Aquinas was lost in contemplation in his narrow cell; that nature presented the same problems then as now; and that truth founded on the essences of things is as unchanging and eternal as the essences themselves. A perverted sense of values has led us to regard what is new as what is better, and what is more detailed as more profound. The craze for innovation, which has characterized the world since the reformers broke away from all tradition, has fostered this false notion of progress, and in the search for novelty we have lost what had already been acquired. " Those who were eagerly grasping at new truths were almost indifferently dropping certain older truths. This is the constant Nemesis of what we call 'Progress.' Any new, or even rediscovered, truth is, for the moment, more important for us than what we already know. Men will die to make a very small discovery; but when it is made, and securely our own, it falls into its proper place, and is seen to be far less important than some of our former knowledge." 128 Man directs his life to the attainment of happiness, and applies his knowledge to reaching those conditions which will realize this happiness. Experience and such application add to the sum of knowledge, and most instruments are perfected through experience. But things are had never seen steam engines or aeroplanes or radios, and seem to have little appreciation of the factory system. Since these are among the central facts of our lives, how can the ancients have anything to say to us? The tremendous strides of science and technology seemed to be the result of the accumulation of data. The more information, the more discoveries, the more inventions, the more progress. The way to progress was therefore to get more information. The sciences broke off from philosophy, and then from one another, and that process is still going on. . . . We begin, then, with a notion of progress, and end with an anti-intellectualism which denies, in effect, that man is a rational animal." For a penetrating discussion of the nature and value of progress, the reader is referred to Christopher Dawson, Progress and Religion, London, 1938, Sheed and Ward, Unicorn Books. 128 Noyes, op. cit., p. 59. SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 129 not only discovered during this gradual process; they are also forgotten. 129 " The advancement of knowledge in one direction does not necessarily mean that we have added to our knowledge as a whole. The human mind is so eonstituted that, when it acquires a new truth, it sometimes drops, not only an old error, but an old truth." 130 Time not only brings new knowledge, it also tests the enduring power and inner vitality of truth once acquired. No philosophy has stood this test better than the philosophia perennis, initiated by the Greeks and welded into a magnificent synthesis by St. Thomas Aquinas. Apart from its inherent power to satisfy the deepest cravings of the mind after truth, to solve modern problems, to assimilate all the new findings of lasting philosophical value, as well as to impart a deeper significance to modern scientific theories/ 31 its survival and development down the ages and its amazing spread in our own day are signs of its eternal truth. The body of old and disproved scientific theories has been cast off, but it never was an essential, or even an integral, part of the philosophical system, just as the scientific theories of today, or of tomorrow, do not form part of our philosophy. The soul of this philosophy remains the same, though the body. of scientific thought which it informs renews itself from age to age. We do not claim that nothing new or important has been said since the Middle Ages; there is no philosophy that has not some truth in it, and many old truths have been considerably developed in their applications since the days of the Scholastics. The philosophia perennis is a signpost, not a boundary, as P. SertiUanges has said. Its eternal principles are directive of life and thought and its assimilative force is inexhaustible. It is as if the great philosophers of the past were content, nay, ardently inspired, to formulate these unchanging truths which are vitally necessary to man in his quest for truth and in his practical life, leaving Cf. Hilaire Belloc, "Progress," in Studies, Dec. 1920, pp. 497-511. op. cit., p. 137. point, cf. J. Maritain, Le Docti'JUr Angelique, Paris, 1930, Desclee, " 1 On this ch. 3: "L'Apotre des Temps Modernes." 1 ·2 • 130 Noyes, 9 130 A. J. MCNICHOLL to later ages the task of developing the particular sciences, a task which only centuries of detailed research could fulfil. It will be distasteful to the modern mind to be asked to return to these great pioneers of thought, who have never since been surpassed. The labor of separating the grain from the chaff, the underlying truths from the scientific theories invoked as examples, and the strangeness of the terminology, which, despite its literary crudeness, was exact, 132 make this return doubly difficult. But this task has been performed, and is still being continued, by men who have dedicated their lives to opening up to the world this unfailing well of truth. It is from this well that we have drawn in these pages in order to outline the respective positions of philosophy and science, and to indicate that the old philosophy and the new science are not antagonists but partners in the common quest of truth. A. J. McNICHOLL, O.P. St. Mary's, Tallaght, Dublin, Ireland 18 °Cf. Prof. G. Santayana, in Zybura, op. cit., p. 74: "The fixity and clearness of the Scholastic vocabulary are a relief from the Babel of figurative terms and perverse categories confusing modern philosophy, and making the despair of anyone who wishes to think cogently and not to be misunderstood." BOOK REVIEWS Carmelite and Poet: A Framed Portrait of Saint John of the Cross, with his poems in Spanish. By RoBERT SENCOURT. New York: The Macmillan Co., 1944. Pp. xiii + 274, with index. $3.00. Previous reviewers have judged that, although this book was written with genuine enthusiasm, it is "too wordy and woolly," contains a few historical errors, adds nothing to the extensive literature on the saint, and exhibits a considerable lack of theological background. It is unnecessary for us to cover this ground again. Instead, we shall try to indicate the fundamental weakness in the author's portrayal of St. John as a mystic. We shall not, therefore, comment upon Mr. Sencourt's conception of St. John the poet. It is our belief that the author of Carmelite and Poet has failed to grasp the doctrinal unity binding the saint's works into one; nor has he understood the supernatural principle of grace operating as the basis of the saint's teaching. This has resulted in a poorly "framed portrait" of St. John of the Cross as the great mystical doctor. St. John's doctrinal unity is apparent in his four major works, which form the " summa" of his teaching and are undoubtedly authentic: The Ascent of Mount Carmel, The Dark Night of the Soul, The Spiritual Canticle, The Living Flame of Love. In addition, there are poems, letters, and maxims. Although a number of the letters have been lost or destroyed, nevertheless we have, in the four above-mentioned works, the complete teaching of the saint of Carmel. Scholars disagree as to their chronological order, but that matters little. All the works were written within a few years of each other, and St ..John was in full possession of his complete doctrine when he began to write. What is to be- noted is the logical sequence in which we have listed the books. The saint is inflexibly logical; and his works, therefore, demand attentive and repeated reading. So carefully are they knit together that only constant study, as he himself warns us (The Ascent, Prologue, n. 8), will reveal the train of thought that runs a straight course through them. But what is this thread of doctrine that so harmoniously weaves through St. John's works and makes of them a whole? It is his teaching on the meaning of perfect union of the soul with God, and a thorough description on how to arrive there. The frontispiece of the critical edition of The Ascent of Mount Carmel, which is also reproduced in the English translation of Peers, contains an original sketch by St. John showing the road to perfection and the summit that is to be reached. In this allegorical 131 132 REVIEWS sketch is contained, the central theme of his whole doctrine. AH his works either the summit of the mount, or the path leading to iL We grasp their value when we reflect that the Carmelite friar, having reached the summit of perfection, now looking down explaining the direct that leads to the top of the mount and pointing out the two side-paths, hall' way up the mountain, that lead to thick entangling forests and impassable hills beyond which there is no advance. That St. John teaches only one direct way to the summit and only one type of divine union (and that mystical), which he also calls the state of perfection, can be proved from the fact that his description of divine union is one and the same in all his works. By this union he means simply the conformity of the creature's will with the will of God. Not any conformity, but conformity is the summit of Carmel toward which we dimb. Even in The Ascent, this is the goal placed before generous souls. But the saint does not teach that all souls must reach the same high degree, or that the union is realized in the same manner by all. " The state of this divine union consists in the soul's total transformation, according to the will, in the will of God, so that there may be naught in the soul that is contrary to the will of God, but that, in all and through all, its movement may be that of the will of God alone" (The Ascent, B. I, Ch. n, n. cf. Ibid., B. H, Ch. 5, n. 3) .1 This perfect conformity is not the work of man alone. It demands more than ascetic labor: it calls for the infused movements of the Holy Spirit, if a perfect soul is to be forged. Thus, this state of union has an element of passivity about it that makes it mysticaL " Wherefore the functions of the memory and of the other faculties in this state (of union) are all divine; for, when at last God possesses the faculties and has become the entire master of them, through their transformation into Himself, it is He Himself who moves and commands them divinely, according to His Divine Spirit and will; and the result of this is that the operations of the soul are not distinct, but all that it does is of God, and its operations are divine" (The Ascent, B. III, Ch. n. 8). Writing some time later in The Living Flame of Love, the saint holds tenaciously to the same explanation. " All the movements and operations which the soul had aforetime, and which belonged to the principle and strength of its natural life, are now in this union changed into divine movements, dead to their own operation and inclination and alive in God. For the soul, like the true daughter of God that it now is, is moved wholly by the Spirit of God, even as St. Paul teaches, saying: That they that are 1 All quotations from St. John are taken from Peers, E. Allison, The Complete Works of Saint John of the Cross, translated from the critical edition of Silverio de Santa Teresa, 0. D. C., London (l934), 3 vols. REVIEWS 133 moved by the spirit of God are sons of God Himself" (S. II, n. 34; cf. The Spiritual Canticle, XII, 10; XXVII, The union is the same in all his works. The Ascent and The Dark Night merely point out the goal while explaining at length the way to. it. The Spiritual Canticle and The Living Flame, on the other hand, relate ex professo the experiences of the soul that enjoys the perfect union with God on the summit of the mount. We have insisted upon this logical connection because there are some spiritual writers who claim that the union with God described in these works is not a union identical in nature. If their opinion were true, then there would be no doctrinal unity in the works of St. John. He would be explaining two different unions with God, one which may be termed ascetical, and the other, mystical. There would be then two different roads, the ascetical as described in The Ascent, and the mystical as described in The Dark Night. The practical conclusion would be that those not called to the mystical life should content themselves with the teaching of The Ascent alone. But it is clear from our quotations that the end pointed out in The Ascent is identical with that of The Living Flame. Mr. Sencourt admits doctrinal unity in broad outline, but he fails to explain precisely what it is. Nor does he give a clear idea of the nature of the divine union, which we have discussed above. From his discussion of the relation between The Ascent and The Dark Night, it seems that he is unaware of their complementary necessity on the road to perfection. What is the relation of The Ascent to The Dark Night? Both explain the way to union. Both point out the straightest path leading to the summit. They form, in reality, one single treatise. Both explain the nights, that is, the detachment from creatures and self that the soul must undergo to reach union with God. This purgation, which leaves the soul arid and without consolation, is rightly described as a period of darkness, a night. There are two nights-the night of t4e senses and the night of the spirit-which correspond to the sensitive and the spiritual parts of human nature. Each night has an active and a passive aspect. When the soul is the predominant agent in the purification of the senses or the spirit, the action is called active purification. When God is the predominant agent, it is called passive purification. The active purification is explained in The Ascent, the passive in The Dark Night. The first thirteen chapters of the former explain the active purification, and since this is the work of beginners, it is the easiest to understand. Due to this ready intelligibility, some stop reading here in the belief that this part is meant for all, but the remainder only for the select few. They fail to see that The Ascent and The Dark Night are so related that the teaching of both is necessary for divine union. The two works are not different roads leading to different goals; they are not parallel, but complementary. Nor 184 REVIEWS does The Dark Night merely repeat more extensively what was said in The Ascent. The Dark Night explains the passive purification without which the soul could not advance to the summit. " And the divine effects which God causes in the soul when He has granted it this habit, both as to the understanding and as to the memory and will, we shall not describe in this account of the noul's active purgation and night, for by this alone the soul does not completely attain divine union. We shall speak of these ·effects, however, in treating of the passive night, by means of which is brought about the union of the soul with God" (The Ascent, B. III; Ch. 2, n. 14). Mr. Sencourt has not perceived this essential relation. He regards The Dark l'{ight as a more elaborate exposition of what was said in The Ascent. " The saint felt he must go over the ground once more " (p. 136) . The author, however, does not bring out the fact that the passive purification is a complementary and necessary step in the soul's ascent. Indeed, he seems to place so much emphasis on the passionate poetry of The Darlc Night that he overshadows the predominant purpose of the saint's writings: " To direct the soul through all its natural and supernatural apprehensions in purity of faith to divine union with God" (The Ascent, B. II, Ch. 28, 1). It will easily be seen from our previous exposition of the saint's teaching why we must reject the theme of Transcendence and Immanence which Mr. Sencourt has inserted therein. By the way of transcendence the mystic goes directly to God, stripping himself of all the joy he might find in created things. But, having arrived at the state of union, he sees all beauty in God, and through God all created beauty, which before he relinquished and now begins to enjoy. In a burst of enthusiasm Mr. Sencourt writes: "Try as he might to put by the beautiful things he loved, and so worship the invisible alone, he was aware that he loved them still; they opened his secret raptures" (p. 147). St. John, as we have seen, admits only one way, that of total abnegation. Even in The Spiritual Canticle and The Living Flame, he recalls his advice of a negation that he elaborated in the other two treatises. But one must understand this total abnegation. John does not demand a suppression of the sensitive life, but its perfect ::;ubjection to the spiritual life. Even on the way to God (way of transcendence, to use Sencourt's phrase) the sensible and the beautiful may be used as long as we are not attached to them, and they lead us to God. Therefore, at least here there is no room for the theory of transcendence and immanence. We come now to our second observation. How does the soul climb the mount and unite itself to God? Is it capable of uniting itself to God under its own power? The nature of the divine union is difficult to understand. It is a union in Faith and Charity. One must experience it, we are REVIEWS 135 told, in order to understand it fully. But, since mysticism depends on dogma for its interpretation, we can at least know the theological background which St. John used to explain it. It is here that Sencourt leaves the reader confused. As we have said, for St. John union with God is a mystical state, that is, a state in which the soul is passive under motions of the Holy Spirit. It is a union in the supernatural order, the attainment of which is above all the efforts of man. Catholic theology teaches that man lives in a supernatural state destined for a supernatural end, the vision of the Triune God. This state and end, therefore, is a pure gift of God to which man by nature has no title. Sanctifying grace is the divine quality which lifts the soul of man above the natural order, makes him a consort of divine life, an adopted son of God; and it is the seed of glory. But even as a son of God man cannot lift himself up into the mystical state of union. This, too, is another gift of God. Man might prepare himself but God gives Himself to whomever He wishes and whenever He wishes (The Dark Night, B. I, Ch. 9, n. 9). Theologians differ as to whether this mystical union described by St. John, which he also calls the state of perfection, is the ordinary terminus of all those who reach sanctity, or whether it is an extraordinary gift reserved for a select few. Yet they all agree that it is a special divine gift above the natural power and needs of man. It is here that Christian mysticism differs from all forms of natural or diabolical mysticism. There are, for example, natural mystics who have many good qualities. Many of their characteristics resemble those of the Christian mystics. They retire from the world, seek solitude and silence, curtail sensible pleasures, undergo painful purification of the soul, meditate by their natural powers on the beauty of nature and the greatness of God. They even aspire to a contemplation of the divine nature which they know from natural reason, but this effort is usually crowned with tension and exhaustion. For them contemplation is an end; for the Christian it is only an attitude of the soul; love of the Triune God is the end. Furthermore, these natural mystics use expressions, aspirations, and other forms of prayer which are almost identical with those of the Christian mystics. This should not surprise us, since Christian mysticism does not destroy human nature, but supposes it, perfects it, and transforms it. Yet in spite of these similarities these natural mystics remain deprived of grace and of a divine call, and by their own effort they are incapable of attaining to the intuition of, and union with, the Trinity. Strive as they might, they can never attain supernatural Faith and Charity by their own efforts in o!'der to enter into the very life of God. We should never bf: deceived by mere resemblances. Now it is precisely this distinction that Carmelite and Poet fails to evaluate properly. To be sure, Sencourt admits a distinction between the 136 REVIEWS natural and the supernatural. In his Introduction he reminds the reader tl1at Christian mysticism is unique. But in the body of the book his loose modes of expression give the impression that the author has not understood the matter. Sencourt, lost in the wonders of the saint's poetry, tends to obscure the theme of the poet by concentrating on the resemblances that are found in common with some English poets (p. 219). A true portrait might justifiably include these resemblances, but it certainly would sharply distinguish them, depicting in fuller color the unique position of Catholic mysticism. Natural contemplation of beauty, no matter how intense, that finally results in mental quietness, does not lead to sanctity in divine union. It has only a resemblance to Christian contemplation. The mental quiet in natural mysticism can be acquired by human effort. The prayer of quiet mentioned by St. Teresa and St. John is a gift of God beyond the grasp and the power of unaided human nature. It is misleading to say: "The better way can never be learned except by those who have made effort enough, or endured enough, to have their nerves tired out " (p. 150) . The framed portrait by Sencourt lacks firmness of shape and outline because the author lost sight of and failed to understand the central theme that runs through the major works of St. John: The direction of souls to divine union with an explanation of all the natural and supernatural (visions, ecstasies, etc.) apprehensions of the soul along the way and in the highest degree of union. Our criticism of Carmelite and Poet has been of necessity completely adverse because we have limited it to what we believe is fundamental to an understanding of the mystic. It would appear from Mr. Sencourt's Introduction that he was well aware of the path he had to follow-indeed, he approached his task with genuine enthusiasm. It is regrettable that he has not succeeded in achieving his purpose. REv. KILIAN HEALY, 0. Carm. Whitefriars Hall, Washington The Judgement of the Nations. By CHRISTOPHER DAwsoN. Sheed & Ward, 1942. Pp. 2£2. $2.75. New York: Most books, if they are not reviewed as soon as they are published, need not be reviewed at all. Others, either because of the authority of the author or the importance of the content, can always be profitably considered. In the case of the present work, it is fortunate that we can consider it now and ask some questions about it that might have been more disturbing and more easily dismissed if they had been brought up sooner. REVIEWS 187 I Mr. Dawson's intention in this his latest work is clearly practical in nature-to heal the dissension and disunities of nations through a return to the love and service of God. It includes an analysis of the forces that brought about the present diseased state of the world and a discussion of the measures necessary to bring about a cure, if that is possible. Western civilization has reached a judging point in its history: it has two alternatives-a continuation on the path to destruction or a complete Christian renewal. The work has two main divisions: the first part exposes the historical forces which brought European civilization to its present state (The Disintegration of Western Civilization); the second part is more patently theological and attempts to show the Christian principles that must underlie any enduring and just civilization (The Restoration of a Christian Order). The scientific and technological advances of the last few centuries have become the primary instruments of the greatest effort ever attempted to destroy and subjugate man; consequently the present crisis is unequalled by anything in history. There are two reasons for this. First of all, the nations that are making the greatest bid for power ever attempted have weapons, both physical and psychological, unknown to previous conquerors. Secondly, the civilization which is threatened with destruction is a Christian civilization, whose fall would be incalculably more disastrous than the fall of the Roman Empire. In the face of this totalitarian drive for power, liberal humanism, the secularized version of Christianity, which was the enemy of the last century, is no longer to be regarded unqualifiedly as an enemy. It is also threatened by the new enemy, an enemy so menacing that in its presence the partial conflicts dividing Western civilization acquire a different aspect. For now the very existence of our whole culture is at stake; in such a situation cooperation with any elements that uphold freedom is to be desired. The great danger of the present war is that in the very struggle democracy will suffer defeat from within. For it is possible that the exigencies of the present moment may force the democratic nations to organize their life on totalitarian lines. At stake is the civilization built on Christian principles and the western ideal of liberty. This war is a war for democracy; the author is careful, however, to exclude from this any idea of equalitarianism. " Still less are we fighting for the squalid prosperity of the economic liberalism of the last century. What we have to defend is, to quote Cardinal Lienart's words, 'a human and Christian civilization built with infinite patience,' a work to which many races and schools of thought have contributed century after century" (p. fl4) . 188 REVIEWS The author lays emphasis on the fact that the present world conflict is basically a conflict between contrary conceptions of the natural law and their consequent public moralities. Luther's view of the natural law is the force behind German culture, while Calvin's view, which, according to Dawson, is fundamentally identical with the Catholic conception, is the spiritual inspiration behind Western democracy. "This Lutheran tradition with its strange dualism of pessimism and faith, other-worldliness and world affirmation, passive quietism and crude acceptance of the reign of force, has been a most powerful forc.e in the formation of the German mind and the German social attitude " (p. 43) . "Here Luther's cult of force and his ' natural law of irrationalism ' becomes transformed into the cult of militarism and of a non-moral or super-moral Machtpolitik" (p. 44). Part of Mr. Dawson's thesis is that modern democracy is peculiarly the product of Calvinism and the free churches. Thus the Cromwellian commonwealth was the starting point of the new civilization which stressed freedom of conscience and the person as absolute rights bestowed by God and nature. In America, the Calvinism of New England led to the pronouncement of the rights of man in our Constitution and inaugurated political democracy. Summing up, the author says: "Thus the modern Western belief in progress, in the rights of man and the duty of conforming political action to moral ideals, whatever they may owe to other influences, derive ultimately from the moral ideals of Puritanism and its faith in the possibility of the realization of the Holy Community on earth by the efforts of the elect. While the German combination of realism and mysticism, of external discipline and internal anarchy, which is so alien to our way of thought, has its roots in the Lutheran world view with its concepts of the mighty forces of irrational nature and irresistible grace '' (p. 51) Mr. Dawson places the ultimate cause of the disunity of our civilization in the fact that religion, which should be a unifying force, is itself in a state of disunity. It is this religious disunity that is the cause of our secularized civilization. This, he maintains, is a unique problem in world history, " the problem of a state of dislocation between religion and culture; in other words, the problem of a secularized culture " (p. 97) . The banishment of the Christian Faith doomed Europe to disunity and collapse, for Europe, unlike, for example, China or India, has no natural bond of unity; the spiritual community of the Church furnished the only bond. The author carefully separates the ideological basis of from the many variegated manifestations which have passed under this somewhat ambivalent name. He finds this basis in the ideal of freedom, which, rather than equality, has been the spiritual ideal of Western culture. His 0 REVIEWS 139 acceptation of the term freedom is not defined; he says merely that he does not mean the " lawless individualism of the barbarians." II The second part of Mr. Dawson's book regards the task of restoration from an explicitly theological viewpoint. The idea of a planned society is discussed. Because of the primacy of the Spirit, the author insists that the vitalizing power of any culture must come from its subordination to the spiritual. The failure of our secularized culture makes this more evident. The redeeming power of God's grace is efficacious to save not only individual sinners but also erring civilizations; the importance of this principle is paramount today for what is at stake is not the collapse of a Christian culture but rather the collapse of the secularized culture that has taken its place. The new state claims control of the whole of human life, and the inventions of science make this possible to an extent never before dreamed of by rulers of the past. "No human power can stop this progress to the abyss. It can only come about by a profound movement of conversion which brings the human spirit once more into vital relation with the Spirit of God " (p. 157) . Religious division, as has been shown, is one of the primary causes of the present world situation; Mr. Dawson concludes that a return to religious unity is a necessary condition for the restoration of the spiritual community of Europe. He holds that cooperation among the various religious bodies is essential and that such cooperation is possible on the basis of the traditions, beliefs, moral values, sacraments and forms of worship held in common. The theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity provide the best basis for unity in the intellectual as well as the spiritual sphere. More immediately, he is persuaded that our age is more favorable to Christian unity than any since the Reformation; for as their religion is becoming that of a persecuted minority, the pressure of hostile forces may well force Christians to unite against a common enemy; " or it may be that the Church will react positively to the situation by a fresh outpouring of the apostolic spirit, as Bl. Grignon de Montfort prophesied two centuries ago " (p. 182) . On the political level the problem is to find a center of unity between individual states and one world organization. The author suggests the creation of " not a League of Nations, but a confederation, a league of federations, based on community of culture and each organized as a society of nations of states with autonomous rights" (p. 214). But he finds the difficulties inherent in such a plan so great that they far exceed the scope of the politician or economist. " The reconciliation of the nations can only be accomplished on a deeper plane than that of political power or economic 140 :REVIEWS interest. It is essentially a spiritual task which demands the spiritual vision that is Faith and the spiritual will that is Charity" (p. Ill It is with some hesitation that we approach the critical part of our review; yet, after due consideration, we have been forced to the conclusion that this present work of Mr. Dawson is puzzling and disturbing. Many times it is difficult to recognize that the man who wrote Religion and the Modern State and Beyond Politics is also the author of The Judgement of Nations. The author's views in this book are sharply at variance with those advanced in previous works; moreover, there are numerous inconsistencies in the arguments advanced; most notable of all, there is a persistent vagueness and ambiguity, chiefly in the use of several important terms. We shaH start with the last point; the best example of this is the use of the term democracy. On p. the author means by democracy selfgovernment, based on the ideal of personal liberty, embodied in representative or parliamentary institutions. On p. 24, he says he does not mean by democracy merely political institutions. He calls democracy the spiritual heir of Christendom, then shows how it is a product of Calvinism and puritanism. Could not Nazism also be called the spiritual heir of Christendom, since, as Dawson points out, it is in many respects the product of Lutheranism? He then says that democracy is not an adequate name for the set of values we are defending; in another place he identifies democracy with our whole Christian civilization, and all that is good in it. In previous works Mr. Dawson has shown that liberal democracy is but another form of the universal tendency today toward the growing influence of the state in the life of the individual; it is the counterpart of the totalitarian state proportioned to the humanitarian traditions of the Western countries as Nazism is proportioned to the German militarist tradition, He has analyzed the extension of the function of the state and its growing demands upon the life of the individual to the point that the individual is more and more moulded by the dominant ideology of the state; and the ideology of the democratic state has been the primacy of economic ends. As he had well said elsewhere: "We can already discern the beginnings of this paternal-democratic regime in England and can see how all the apparatus of the social services-universal secondary education, birth control clinics, antenatal clinics, welfare centers, and the rest-may become instruments of a collective despotism which destroys human liberty and spiritual initiative as effectively as any communist or Nazi terrorism" (Religion and the Modern State. New York: Sheed & Ward, p. 106). "It may be harder to resist a totalitarian state which relies on birth-control REVIEWS 141 clinics and free milk than one which relies on castor oil and concentration camps " (Zoe. cit.) . There are, of course, many traces of his previous position on democracy interwoven with his new identification of democracy with Christian civilization; this only makes his present position difficult to understand. Previously Mr. Dawson has insisted on the distinction between English Parliamentarianism and French democracy, and emphasized the error that follows from a facile identification of the two. He has also said: "The truth is, unpalatable though it may be to modern ' progressive thought,' that democracy and dictatorship are not opposites or mortal enemies, but twin children of the great Revolution, and that the English political system is immune from the tendency towards dictatorship because it is not democratic in the full sense of the word, but rather liberal and aristocratic " (Beyond Politics. New York: Sheed & Ward, pp. 40-1). The same difficulty is found with the author's use of the term freedom. Nowhere does he give an adequate definition of his use of the word. And since he equates liberalism with freedom, this confusion extends to the former word as well. Mr. Dawson says that freedom or liberty is central in the Western tradition and hence in modern democracy. But one wonders to what kind of freedom he is referring. He says that it is not the freedom of economic individualism or lawless barbarism. His one positive statement is correct but limited: referring to a social order that has Christian freedom as its basis, he says: "This means that it must be a social order directed to spiritual ends, in which every man has a chance to use his freedom for the service of God according to his powers and gifts" (p. 185). But this one oblique statement seems hardly sufficient in a book that is primarily about the necessity of preserving this Western ideal of freedom. The necessity of an adequate analysis of the ChristiaFl ideal of freedom becomes more apparent in the face of the pernicious errors widespread in the modern world concerning its nature. Human freedom has been exalted to the status of a first principle; the very indeterminacy of the human will, which is properly an imperfection and as such is potent to draw down the divine mercy, has been glorified as a perfection. This is an abomination well calculated to cut off mankind from the divine mercy, for no one is less worthy of mercy than the "poor proud man.'' Has Mr. Dawson any assurance that he will not be understood to be speaking of this kind of freedom, which is the dominant conception of democratic society. It might even be thought that the Church sanctions this perverted doctrine of freedom, which is the fruit of man's pride and has more affinity with the French Revolution t1Ian with Catholic doctrine. In previous works Mr. Dawson had clear and definite views on the relation between individual freedom and state authority, and, consequently, on the relation between the common good and the individual good. (Cf. 142 REVIEWS "Catholic Doctrine of the State," in Religion and the Modern State.) In the present work he seems to have reacted against totalitarianism in such a way as to deny the truth that it distorts, that is, the principle of community, which is the force behind the totalitarian doctrine. He now places undue emphasis on the individual good and the freedom of the individual. At bottom his difficulty seems to involve an erroneous conception of the common good. Thus, he says: "Western democracy has been the will to erect a society which . . . protected . . . the freedom of the individual against the unlimited authority of the state itself." From one viewpoint this is but the outgrowth of defending the freedom of the individual against the unlimited authority of God Himself; just as totalitarianism is the outgrowth of the complete denial of human freedom from the Lutheran view of Divine omnipotence. Mr. Dawson quotes Burke with approval: "All the old countries of Europe were agreed on the common principle that the state is made for the people, and not the people conformed to the state, but England differed from the rest in that it made personal liberty a direct object of government and refused to sacrifice the individual to the community or the part to the whole" (p. 185). Both of these statements err in this, that they singularize the common good and thus make the common good and the private good alien goods, as though the common good were not the greater good of the individual, and as though the true private good could be opposed to the common good. The state becomes an alien power against which the individual must continually defend himself. In this the individualistic and totalitarian theories of government agree, for they both deny the community of the common good. Civil life becomes a warfare between two powers-individual freedom and the omnipotent state; either the state dominates the individuals or the individuals, with their individual good exalted to the status of an end superior even to the common good, dominate the state. IV Although Mr. Dawson is well aware of the various anti-Christian forces that have contributed to the breakdown of our culture, he also points out that " we cannot refuse all responsibility and put the blame on tl1e shoulders of the rationalists and anti-clericals. For ... the primary cause of the secularization of Western culture has been the religious divisions of Christians. Behind the present crisis in Europe there lie centuries of religious disunity and strife which have divided men's minds in the spiritual order itself and which have destroyed the bonds of charity which alone can transcend the conflict of material interests and the corporate selfishness of classes and peoples" (pp. 191-2). Now this is a point of the greatest importance· and one which does not begin to be sufficiently recog- REVIEWS 148 nized. Unfortunately Mr. Dawson's formulation does not evaluate with sufficient precision the nature and proportion of responsibility for the present crisis borne by the various elements in our culture. He does manifest the degree to which rationalism, liberalism, capitalism, and so forth, must be held responsible; he quite justly points out the greater responsibility borne by Christians. But he ignores the peculiar responsibility of Catholics, for whom there is no excuse, knowing, as they should, that they are called upon to be the leaven of the world. The degree to which the sins of the world are upon the members of the visible Church is not recognized. " And that servant who knew the will of his Lord and prepared not himself, and did not according to His will shall be beaten with many stripes. But he that knew not and did things worthy of stripes shall be beaten with few stripes. And unto whomsoever much is given, of him much shall be required: and to whom they have committed much, of him will they demand the more" (Luke, xii, 47, 48). There is a vital relation between the health of the world and the health of the Church. The one against the forces of evil latent in fallen human nature is the relatively small group of the faithful, whose function it is to supply the saving leaven which alone makes the earth pleasing to God. The saints, who are our models, always considered themselves, by their sins and infidelities, responsible for the sins of the world; nor can this be dismissed as exaggeration, since they alone among men see things as they are. And in this they are but imitating Christ, who, although sinless, assumed the burden of all men's sins. The saints alone, then, realized the tremendous responsibility placed upon the faithful, for the justice or mercy of God will be called down upon the world in proportion as Catholics pursue sanctity or mediocrity. v Mr. Dawson's failure to indicate the unique nature of the responsibility of Catholics for the disintegration of our civilization necessarily detracts from the adequacy of his analysis: it also has important bearings on the practicality of the remedies he proposes. Having shown that religious disunity is the primary cause of our secularized civilization, He advocates the cooperation of the various Christian churches on the basis of their common sacraments, moral values, traditions. He urges this most strongly, for, as he says, the dangers from the common enemies of Christianity are so great. He is also in favor of cooperation with all the scattered elements in our society which have the common ideal of freedom. Now these proposals are undoubtedly good and are of great importance for any Christian renewal; the difficulty arises when one asks how this cooperation is to be effected. I do not think that Mr. Dawson sees with sufficient clarity that this must originate with a revitalized unity within 144 REVIEWS the visible Church. For if the failure of Catholics to pursue perfection according to Christ's injunction, "Be ye perfect as your heavenly Father is perfect," is the ultimate cause of our present confusion, then any proposed reform must begin with those who by the dictates of their doctrine are obliged to take these words literally. For only the Catholic Church has the necessary means to bring about such a reform, i. e. her doctrine and her sacraments. It is futile to seek a unity with those outside the Church which we do not possess among ourselves; for such a unity would be based, not on the Faith, but upon some human concept commonly held. A speculative consideration of the question of the visible and invisible Church is certainly not required in a practical work. What is important is to know how to deal with individuals and for this there is only one answer: supernatural prudence is required. From St. Paul we learn that our first concern should be for Catholics: "Therefore while we have time, let us work good to all men, but especially to those of the household of faith " (Gal. vi, 10). And elsewhere he says, "our own first/' Now this clearly does not exclude cooperation with· those outside the Church, but rather facilitates it in two ways: first, the example of the love Catholics bear one another would prompt others, weary of the dissensions of the world, to unite themselves to the Church; secondly, as charity grows within us we shall know how best to deal with those outside. For love has a way of communicating itself and charity has means of persuasion unknown to natural justice. Further if we recognize the extent of our own responsibility for religious division, that too will be communicated to others rather than a self-righteousness which only drives men away. Moreover, it does not seem wise to conceal in any way the fact that Catholics can will world to Christ and His Church. nothing less than the conversion of These criticisms are the more difficult to make the more clearly it is seen that Mr. Dawson's purposes are the highest. Moved by that Charity that prompts the Catholic intellectual to use all the intellectual disciplines to bring about a return of the modern world to Christ, he has utilized the matter of history and politics to bring about a reconciliation of the modern world and Catholic doctrine. It is only in the light of this intention that Mr. Dawson's difficulty can be understood. In previous works he has shown that he is well able to analyze and evaluate liberal democracy at its true worth; elsewhere he has given a splendid account of the nature of Christian freedom (cf. Dublin Review, July, :. hence it is clear that his present treatment of these matters cannot be laid to lack of knowledge. We feel rather that it is owing to a dislike of what might seem self-righteous criticism in time of peril. This could have been avoided if Mr. Dawson had seen the full extent of Catholic responsibility for the crisis, that any criticism of liberal democracy is more truly a criticism of Catholics. REVIEWS 145 From a theological viewpoint, the modern world is divided between two heresies: one, totalitarianism, denies human freedom in favor of unlimited authority of the state; the other, liberal democracy, exalts human freedom to the status of an absolute principle. This is but a reflection of a deeper problem that has persisted throughout the history of the Church-the reconciliation of the omnipotence of God and the freedom of the human will. The relation between the individual and the state is an imitation of the relation between the individual soul and God, and as one denies, theoretically or practically, the freedom of the will or the omnipotence of God, he will have totalitarianism or liberalism. Once again we can lay the confusion of the modern world on the shoulders of Catholics, for very few Catholics have practically resolved the problem of reconciling the claims of divine omnipotence and free will. VI There would seem to be a basic error at the root of each of the above criticized positions. The author is trying to reconcile Western ideals as they are understood today with Catholic doctrine. Yet in so doing he treats the Church and those forces with which he advocates cooperation as equals. He seems not to see, or, at least, to point out that in any cooperation the Church must take the lead, whether others know it or not. Thus, Mr. Dawson, taking them as equals, effects a merger of the two doctrines to such a degree that neither is recognizable. Liberal democrats will fail to find an expression of their concept of freedom, and Catholics will fail to find any definition of the nature of Christian freedom; there is simply freedom used in an indeterminate and uncritical way, subject to any interpretation the reader wishes to give it. Given the audience for whom the work is intended, there can scarcely be any doubt as to the meaning they will take. The only reason Mr. Dawson gives for his changed attitude towards liberalism, liberal democracy, humanitarianism, and so forth, is the emergence of the totalitarian threat to all human values, in face of which liberalism must be regarded as an ally. But difficulties to this position arise when one realizes that liberal humanitarianism and the "new paganism '' are not essentially diverse, but rather one in principle, for both regard man as ultimate. The new hordes of destruction have merely progressed further along the road, having recognized and accepted the incapacity of the isolated human will to preserve the ideals of freedom and justice. Indeed, Mr. Dawson treats it as a revolution against the false hopes of humanitarianism. " The new revolution is a movement of disintegration and despair which derives its strength from the liquidation of the ideals on which the nineteenth century world had set its hopes." 146 REVIEWS Accordingly, while every effort should be made to exploit the good in liberal philosophy, indeed, this is a duty incumbent upon Catholic thinkers, cooperation with such a force holds the gravest dangers, as exemplified by the present work; it must be done with the greatest circumspection and with the " wisdom of the serpent." Above all, such cooperation cannot be of equals. Liberals should be shown that the ideals they still cherish belong properly and originally to Catholic doctrine, which is where the liberals got them from in the first place, and that they can be attained only by the power within the Church. It is undoubtedly the providential meaning behind the collapse of liberal hopes-a proof that of themselves men cannot preserve ·a just and stable civilization. It is getting to a point where anyone who refuses to recognize this truth can be accused of wilful blindness. Whether Liberals will recognize it or not will prove a test of their good will. Unity with other Christians must be accomplished in a similar way, leading to their conversion and not merely to good fellowship; moreover, such unity can be the fruit of a greater unity within the Church and a further development of doctrine adulterated by our long sojourn in Egypt. Adverse criticism of this work should not be taken as an indictment of Mr. Dawson's work as a whole. Probably no contemporary writer has performed such valuable services for the Church; we have tried to emphasize that the present work has been criticized only in so far as it departs from his previous works. It seems clear that this work represents the impact of the war upon Mr. Dawson's thought; for this reason it is outside the continuity of his thought and it is to be hoped that he has not adopted permanently the positions he takes here. Much that is good in his other works is present in this one. Most notable of all is his uncompromising insistence upon the extent to which the present crisis must be attributed to spiritual causes and the inadequacy of. anything but the power of the Spirit to save our civilization from complete collapse. No writer has shown more powerfully and persuasively the doom which inevitably awaits any culture that places its trust in man rather than in God. WILLIAM Washington, D. C. P. DAVEY BOOKS RECEIVED Bennet, 0. The Nature of Demonstrative Proof. (The Catholic University of America, Philosophical Studies, Vol. LXXV.) Washington: Catholic Univ. of America Press, 1943. Pp. 97. Crowe, M. T. The Moral Obligation of Paying Just Taxes. Washington, D. C.: Catholic University Press, 1944. Pp. ix + 175, with index. Doolan, A. Philosophy for the Layman. Dublin: Irish Rosary Office, 1944. Pp. with index. 7/6. Dunney, J. H. Church History in the Light of the Saints. Macmillan, 1944. Pp. 465, with index. Gheon, Henri. Secrets of the Saints. Pp. 406. $3.00. New York: New York: Sheed & Ward, 1944. Joan, Sr. M. and Sr. M. Nona. Guiding Growth in Christian Social Living. Washington: Catholic Univ. of America Press, 1944. Pp. 308. Kelly, V. J. Forbidden Sunday and Feast-Day Occupations. Washington, D. C.: Catholic University Press, 1944. Pp. !ll9, with index. Krikorian, Y. H. (Ed.). Naturalism and the Human Spirit. Columbia Univ. Press, 1944. Pp. 397. $4.50. Lamarche, M.-A. Projections. New York: Ottawa: Editions du Levrier, 1944. Pp. $1.00. Lewis, D. B. W. Ronsard, His Life and Times. Ward, 1944. Pp. 340, with index. $3.50. New York: Sheed & Maritain, J. The Dream of Descartes. (Trans. by M. L. Andison.) York: Philosophical Library, 1945. Pp. £20. $3.00. New Pegis, A. (Ed.). Essays in Modern Scholasticism. Newman Book Shop, 1944. Pp. Md.: Westminster, Peguy, C. Men and Saints. New York: Pantheon Books, Inc., 1944. Pp. 303. $U5. Perkins, M. Speaking of How to Pray. Pp. 276. New York: Sheed & Ward, 1944. Sheen, F. J. Seven Pillars of Peace. New York: Charles Scribner's & Son, 1944. Pp. 112. $1.75. 147 148 BOOKS RECEIVED Sturzo, L. Inner Laws of Society. 314. New York: Kenedy & Sons, 1944. Pp. $3.50. Watkins, E. I. Catholic Art and Culture. New York: Sheed & Ward, Hl44. Pp. Qfl5, with index. $4.50. Wedel, F. Between Heaven and Earth. New York: Philosophical Library, 1944. Pp. $3.00. Winzen, D. $1.00. Symbols of Christ. Keyport, N. J.: St. Paul's Priory, 1944.