THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PRoviNCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington 17, D. C. VoL. XI OCTOBER, 1948 No.4 THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION T HERE exists a rather curious discrepancy between the very lively interest taken nowadays in apologetical, oecumenical, and other works which by their very nature tend to result in conversions to the Catholic Church, and the almost complete lack of reflection among Catholics on the problems connected with these conversions. This lively interest hardly needs demonstration. It can be measured, for example, by the numerous stories of converts which are being published and read and which furnish the principal material for psychological studies of conversion (Starbuck, James, DeSanctis, Th. Mainage, 0. P.) The lack of theological reflection is shown, among other instances, from the fact that the Dictionnaire de Theologie Catholique does not even mention the word conversion; the Dic·tionnaire Apologetique de la Foi Catholique and the Lexicon Fur Theologie und Kirche have only very short articles on the subject and they are more historical than theological. In this study, we intend only to examine some of the theological problems related to conversion and indicate certain solutions; all of these problems could not be studied in one article. 409 410 C. F. PAUWELS It must be noted immediately that the word " conversion " can have several different meanings, all of these meanings having some connection between them. The different uses of the same word have been the cause of much confusion in the psychological study of conversion as we understand it. Conversion can mean (and it is in this sense that we write of it) a change of religious conviction, and notably the acceptance of the Catholic faith. It indicates a motion to something new from something old; therefore it has a counterpart in apostasy, and if we attend to the fact that as an old conviction is given up a new one is acquired we note that every conversion can be called an apostasy. Conversion in this first sense, however, implies something more than a merely intellectual act, for whoever accepts the Catholic faith enters the Catholic Church and intends to live a Catholic life. In another sense, conversion may mean the justificatio impii, the change from a bad life to a good one. In this sense, conversion has been the object of numerous theological studies, and has been considered by St. Thomas 1 and the modem authors. The latin term, conversus, has been used to designate a laybrother in the same sense. It should be noted that a conversion to the Catholic faith always implies some change from a bad to a good life, in this respect at least that the Catholic standards of good and bad must be accepted with the faith; therefore, almost every convert, even if he could be called a good Christian before his conversion, has to make some changes in his manner of life. Still, one can be a bad Catholic and a sinner at the same time, and such a one needs the justificatio impii without needing any change of faith. On the other hand, many non-Catholics are already in a state of grace before they are converted to the Catholic faith. Hence a connection between these two kinds of conversion is not only possible, but necessary. In a third sense, conversion may mean a change in religious life without any change of faith. This kind of conversion is studied by ascetical and mystical theologians. 2 We call it a Summa Theol., I-II, q. 113. 'Cf. Garrigou-Lagrange, The Three Ways of the Spiritual Life, London, 1 THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 411 conversion when a man changes from a humdrum religious life to a more serious one, from carelessness about venial sin to a systematical endeavor to reach perfection. Although this kind of conversion implies no change in religious conviction and is thus very different from the first kind, it should be noted that the acceptance of the Catholic faith, which is the fullness of revelation and grace, must bring about in the life of good Christians who are in a state of grace before conversion a growth in intensity of religious life. Finally, Protestants have a special notion of conversion which can not be fully treated here. We can call it an offspring of Luther's teaching on the fides salvifica; it means no change in religious conviction but is the beginning of a more consciously religious life. Professor Starbuck has studied these conversions in his famous book The Psychology of Religion. He notes carefully that such conversions ". . . are true of a specialised class, chiefly Protestant, American members of professedly Christian communities. They are not necessarily true of savages or statesmen or Catholics or persons living in a different historical epoch." Notwithstanding his caution, his conclusions on the age of conversion and the influence of puberty are often applied to conversions to the Catholic faith. * * * In this study, we are interested only in conversions to the Catholic faith, and from the theological, not the psychological, approach. The theologian has to look to the theological cause of conversion, the grace of God. He is the only person who has a right to speak of this grace. Further, he is the only person who can define exactly what a conversion to the Catholic faith is, for every motion is known from its goal and only the theologian can say what the faith truly is. Too, he alone can speak of a right and a wrong way to come to the faith. The doctrine on the nature of faith and especially the treatise on the genesis of faith must be used in the study of conversions. The historian can tell the story of conversions and, by comparison, he can find some general laws about the way in which 412 C. F. PAUWELS they usually happen. The psychologist can study conversions as facts of conscious human life and he can look for the influence of subconscious processes. Neither of these, however can claim the right to judge extrapsychic, superhuman causes. On the other hand, the theologian needs the help of both historian and psychologist if he wishes to do more than give only abstract speculations on faith and conversions. From revelation he can deduce what faith is and the relation of faith to the grace of God, but if he wishes to speak of different kinds of conversions, the different ways by which God brings His children to the truth and the Church, he must turn to actual facts. Working in a priori fashion, he can only suggest possibilities. Before discussing the use of these facts, we must point out an important conclusion: the theologian alone can judge when to speak of true and when to speak of false conversions; he must therefore sort out the facts according to his own standards. This conclusion may seem rather arrogant especially to psychologists. We do not mean to deny that psychologists too can judge about true and false conversions, but they can judge only according to a psychological pattern and this does not coincide with the theological pattern. We have said that a conversion always has its counterpart in an apostasy in that when a man accepts the Catholic faith he, at the same time, casts off his former convictions. To a psychologist when a Protestant becomes a Catholic. abjuring his Protestantism, it may seem the same thing as when a Catholic becomes a Protestant, abjuring his Catholicism. He may call both facts conversions, study them side by side, and speak of them being true or false conversions in a psychological sense. To a theologian, however, the first is a work of grace and the second the work of sin; he will never call the second fact a conversion. Furthermore, the theologian must consider whether a man becomes a true Catholic in the right manner, whether he has the real faith and whether he came to it in the right way. For instance, George Tyrell, the Modernist leader, is always called a convert from Anglicanism to Catholicism. In view of his later life and evolution, the theologian must consider two possibilities: Tyrell THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 418 may have been a true convert and afterwards gave up his faith, or perhaps he never was a true convert and a good Catholic; he may never have believed in the true Catholic manner, or his motive in becoming a Catholic may have been false or unsound. In special cases, like Tyrell's, it may be impossible to come to a certain conclusion, but it is the theologian's exclusive right to judge. When he has received the necessary facts from historians and psychologists, it is the theologian's task to analyse them and interpret them in the light of the workings of divine grace. Grace, of course, can not be experienced. We can only believe in it, but from theological analysis we can be sure that some of our actions, as, e. g., to believe, to love our enemies, can be done only with the help of grace. The theologian searches the stories of converts for actions of this kind; he may find that they have not been appreciated properly by the converts themselves and that they have been passed over by historians and psychologists to whom they had no meaning. The converts, even if they are making an effort to retail the entire truth, will tell their stories as they remember them. It often happens that facts which are of little importance to the theologian made the strongest impression upon the convert. The event which, to the theologian, marked the moment of the infusion of the faith is often forgotten and passed over. All this is so because grace is not experienced but is rather believed. There are some conversions which are conversions such as those of St. Paul and St. Augustine, and in latter times of Alphonse Ratisbonne and Paul Claude!. In these cases, the converts themselves, the historian, psychologist, and theologian will consider the same moment decisive. But there are many other conversions, long drawn-out affairs with, apparently, no decisive crisis; of these the conversion of Cardinal Newman is outstanding. It can also be that a phase may appear important in the eyes of the convert without being, in the theologian's eyes, the real turning point. Such might be the moments in which a man realizes that his boyhood religion is false or when he hears that his closest friend is to become a 414 C. F. PAUWELS Catholic. The Dutch convert, Pieter van der Meer de Walcheren, a friend and follower of Leon Bloy, confesses that he can not tell the moment in which he first made the act of faith, but he best remembers the moment when for the first time he knelt down and made the sign of the cross. Father Bede Camm tells of a moment in Maredsous chapel when he almost heard the devil saying, "What kind of nonsense is this? Do not pray to the Virgin; go back to your work! " 3 These moments claim the attention, not only of the converts themselves, but of the historian and psychologist as well, because they are of chief importance to the conscious spiritual life. The theologian, while acknowledging their relative importance, will look elsewhere for the precise moment of conversion, the infusion of the faith. St. Augustine's case furnishes another complication. His was a double conversion; the Manichee turned Catholic, the sinner became a saint. At the same time he had to face an intellectual and a moral conflict; this is not uncommon. In such cases, the moral conflict being more vivid and more emotional may often claim more attention; hence it will be better remembered afterwards, while the theologian concentrates not upon the conflict but upon the actual conversion. * * * When studying the beginning and growth of faith in converts, the theologian needs to keep in mind the possibility that they may have had divine faith even before they had the thought of becoming Catholics. Catholic doctrine admits the possibility of being in a state of grace without belonging to the visible Catholic Church, and since sanctifying grace is always accompanied by the supernatural virtues one may have divine faith while yet outside the church. The formal object of divine faith, the reason why we believe is God's revelation; the proposition of this revelation by the Church is considered by theologians to be a necessary condition of faith, but it does not belong to its formal object. Hence, real faith is possible to nonCatholics. • "De l'Anglicisme au Monachisme," Collection Pax, 1930, p. 98. THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 415 In such cases, conversion can not be called the acceptance of the Catholic faith in the most obvious sense, that is, in the sense that the convert had no divine faith at all before his conversion. Conversion consists in believing that the Catholic Church is God's work and has God's mandate to teach and propose His revelation with authority. It means beginning to believe through the Church. As it implies believing every article of faith the Church proposes, the convert will have to believe much more after his conversion than before; this, however is only a change in the material object of his faith and a secondary effect of his conversion. These changes in the material object of the faith can be very different in different conversions. In the case of a liberal Protestant, it many mean that he, for the first time in his life, has to believe in the divinity of Jesus Christ, His redemptive mission, the Holy Eucharist; in the case of the Anglo-Catholic, it may mean fewer additional articles of belief. Therefore, it is possible that the question of the Church and of believing through the ministry of the Church will appear more or less important to the converts themselves. To find the real Jesus is more important than to find the real Church, but to find the true Church is more important than to acknowledge the Pope. It is, therefore, not only easily understood, but it is quite right that some converts will insist on the material, and others on the formal, change in their faith. But the theologian will always consider the acceptance of the faith through the Church as the essential feature of conversion. Thus far, we have spoken of conversion chiefly as a fact of the intellectual order; believing is an act of the intellect, moved by the will. Conversion, however, entails more than this. A convert acquires a new religion and becomes a member of the Catholic Church. As a Catholic, he henceforth receives God's grace through the ministry of the Church and chiefly through the Sacraments. Previously he may have b('!en in a state of grace and may have received abundant grace from God, but henceforth he will receive this grace in an entirely different manner. This, again, is something which is withdrawn from the 416 C. F. PAUWELS consciousness of the converts themselves; they will not note it and it will never be studied by psychologists. It is, of course, much more important that they receive God's grace than that they should know about it, but the theologian has to insist on this aspect of the convert's membership in the Church. A story like Msgr. Benson's that he was received into the Church without feeling or experiencing any special emotion has, therefore, very different meanings for psychologist or theologian. For the same reason it is supremely important to the theologian whether or not the convert was validly baptized before conversion. Psychologically, this may be negligible, something of no consequence, and certainly less important for the conscious process of conversion than the actual beliefs one had before conversion. Practically, of course, it has to be decided whether the convert must be baptized conditionally. But to the theologian it means that the convert, even before his conversion, may already have been able to receive the sacraments and, through them, God's grace; radically, he may have already been a member of the Church and conversion may only be a claiming of native rights. In Holland and elsewhere in Europe, there are some converts who strongly object to the use of the term conversion. They prefer not to be called converts; they say they are " reunited " and not " converted." Some priests agree with them, and we must concede that a term with four different meanings has its difficulties and may imply less pleasant and somewhat humiliating associations. If we should consider the possibility of a new and different term (which might prove hard to find) it would have to be applied to those who were validly baptized before conversion. * * * In every study on conversion which is historical or psychological, there is an attempt to classify conversions in several species. It can be questioned whether the theologian can copy these classifications or whether he should make his own. Some distinctions are plainly psychological or historical. For example, THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 417 if the question of subconscious influences is taken as a norm, it is a purely psychological standard. If we ask whether a conversion concerned one individual soul or whether it entailed a group, the question becomes historical. The theologian, however, must take his norms of classification from the Catholic notion of faith and, more particularly, from the notion of faith through and in the Catholic Church (fides divina et Catholica.) We believe that special stress should be laid on the question as to how the divinity of the Catholic Church becomes evident to the convert. Sudden converions make the story of one convert very different from other stories; they furnish one decisive, critical, often dramatic, moment as the obvious climax. They mean everything to the historian who at the same time is a good storyteller; they may give precious indications to the psychologist who wants to speak about the unconscious or the subconscious. The theologian, however, must note that every conversion has its own critical moment, even if it passes unobserved by the convert. It is imposible to grow gradually into the Catholic Church or to acquire the faith gradually; the influence of grace is instantaneous, but the moment need not be dramatic. Further, the theologian is certainly interested in whether a conversion to the faith is accompanied by the justific;atio impii, the conversion to a better life. This circumstance, too, makes a great difference in the story and the study of it. Though it makes conversion more difficult, inasmuch as the faith itself then clearly implies moral demands, it has no direct influence on the conversion to the faith itself; it only makes a man more open to the aspect of the sanctity of the Church. A conversion must be studied and classified from the terminus ad quem and not from the terminus a quo. Therefore, it seems that the fact of one having been a heathen, or Mohametan, or a Communist, or an atheist before becoming a Catholic can not in itself be a norm of classification to the theologian. The terminus a quo has its influence on the story of the convert; the ways to the Church can be very different and principally by reason of their starting-points, but to the 418 C. F. PAUWELS fact of conversion itself the starting-point need not be of great importance. However, we must admit the real possibility that the terminus a quo may create a kind of predisposition to see the divinity of the faith and the Church under one certain aspect. For example, the fact that one has been a Communist may mean that he is attracted to the Church in her social teaching and activity. On the other hand, it is of paramount importance to the theologian whether the convert actually had the faith before conversion; this fact, we believe, will give the first really theological norm for classification. Here we do not mean faith in any modern, vague sense; we mean faith in the true Catholic sense, that is the acceptance of mysteries on the authority of God. Obviously there is a great difference between the man who for the first time in his life has to accept something he does not understand, on God's authority, and the man who is already accustomed to bow his head to God's authority. This difference is psychological but is much more theological. The divine authority of the Church as seen in its various aspects can and must furnish the theological norm for further classification. Here the theologian certainly does not mean that the divinity of the Church can be demonstrated by various apologetical arguments and that these arguments will be the norm of classification. These arguments can give only a natural preparation for the faith, but the faith itself is infused. The divine mystery of the Church, however, has many aspects which the light of the faith can show, and so the converts by their very faith will come to the Church in various ways. For instance, Sigrid Undset, the great novelist, writes about her conversion: " We want, above all, teachers who can teach us something; we need leaders who have the real power to command and prohibit;,and we desire to look up to One to Whom we can pour out our confidence and admiration, and also our love." The Dutch politician, Dr. Henry P. Marchant, gave to his story the motto, V eritas liberabit nos, " The Truth will make us free." While Cardinal Newman was a man of too many sides and of too versatile an intellect to be easily classified, there is a signifi- THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 419 cant fact with regard to his classification. During his illness in Sicily he could protest, " I will not die because I have not sinned against the truth," but he did not become a Catholic before having solved for himself the intellectual difficulty as to how the Catholic Church of his own day could be the same as his beloved Church of the Fathers. Most converts are, in some way, impressed by the sanctity of the Church, but in different forms. Sheila Kaye-Smith, the English novelist, was affected in her conversion by considering the Catholic Saints in the centuries after the Reformation. She was struck by the contrast between St. Francis de Sales, St. John Vianney, St. Ignatius Loyola, the two Saints Theresa and the foremost religious figures of her own Anglican Church who were no more than " worthies " and a source of acrimonious dispute in their own church. F. Vernon Johnson, England's famous missionary preacher, was first repelled and then singularly attracted by the story of St. Theresa of Lisieux; this forced him to ask himself about the value and truth of this Catholic faith which gave to the young Carmelite such strength and grace. Quite a different aspect of the sanctity of the Church made G. K. Chesterton write that he became a Catholic, " to get rid of my sins." 4 Again, very different are the many stories of converts who received their first real impression of the Catholic Church from nuns in hospitals. The beauty and charm of the Catholic faith can also be shown to be superhuman and divine. Here, however, we have to be very careful; there are many things to be admired in Catholic life which are human and accidental. We should be very skeptical about conversions founded upon the splendor of the ceremonies in St. Peter's or on the quiet and intimate beauty of Christmas in a Benedictine monastery. But, on the other hand, the poet, Alfred Noyes, has shown how the masterpieces of the greatest poets, when compared with Catholic doctrine, receive a more abundant splendor. In this way we see really divine beauty, but we must not poets, painters, and other artists to be brought to the Catholic Church mainly 'Autobiography, London, 1987, p. 829. 420 C. F. PAUWELS in this way. The Dutch painter, Dom Willibrord Verkade, who afterwards found peace and happiness in Beuron' s art and beauty, found truth and faith in a poor village church in Brittany. Professor Gerard Brom has noted that the Dutch poet, Joost van den Vondel, who loved splendor in the Renaissance style, never saw the pomp of Mass in a Cathedral; he went to Mass in little places. Truth, sanctity, and beauty, then are three general aspects of the faith and the Church; through these can appear to converts the divinity of the Church. Next to these, we sometimes observe that a particular dogma or institution proves the decisive factor. Some converts are first convinced that God has taught or instituted one special thing; afterwards they find that one thing existing only in the Catholic Church. In this way the monks of Caldey can be said to have become Benedictine before they were Catholics; they found that Benedictine life in accordance with the authentic traditions is possible only in the Catholic Church. * * * More species of conversion could be found but we believe those already described to be the principal varieties. There is, however, an element in the Catholic doctrine on faith which may give a different standard for classification. In Catholic theology the act of faith is always called an act of the intellect. To believe means to accept something as true, and an act of faith, for a Catholic, is never a vague feeling but has some proposition as its object. In Catholic theology there is another element; faith is an act of the intellect, but the intellect moved by the will. The proposition or truth accepted by faith is not seen in itself and hence it can not move the intellect by its own strength. The will must influence such an intellectual act; hence we may further distinguish species of conversions in relation to the motives of the will. In the stories of some converts, we find that the sense of duty toward God is more apparent, while in others there is more consciousness of happiness accruing to the convert himself. We do not intend to stress or exaggerate this opposition. Catholic THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 421 theology will never acknowledge a conversion as true, if the sense of duty towards God is entirely lacking; on the other hand, no convert expects to find only unhappiness, misery, or disappoinment in the Church. Catholic morals have their principles in something between pure eudaimonism and the categorical imperative of duty, and we must have towards God a love which at the same time is a love of friendship and a utilitarian love in the highest sense. Therefore, to become a Catholic is at the same time a sacred duty towards God and a real happiness to the convert. Yet, in one's conscious thinking, one of these two may dominate and become more apparent. We have, then, two different, but not absolutely opposed, kinds of conversion. St. Paul, who after seeing Christ's glory only asked, " Lord, what do You want me to do? " can be called an example of the first. The Duch convert, A. J.D. van Oosten, who after his conversion wrote a brochure entitled "The Joys of the Convert" may be called an example of the other. This new classification intersects the other we have already enumerated. Truth, sanctity, and beauty can be viewed as something to which it is a man's duty to conform, but they are at the same time something very good to a man. To someone like St. Augustine, who was acutely unhappy in his sins and who was really desiring sanctity, or to a man who is troubled with questions on the meaning of life, Catholic sanctity by grace and Catholic truth are a glorious answer to difficulties. On the other hand, Cardinal Newman's sermon on" The Parting of Friends," his last sermon as an Anglican, clearly indicates that the truth meant to him a very stem call of duty. While we are speaking of the motives of the will, we must mention the fact that often less idealistic and religious motives can play a part in conversion. The thought of conversion can cross one's mind for the first time in connection with love for one who is already a Catholic. In certain circumstances, to become a Catholic can mean better chances for one's career. And there can be other motives. The theologian has to insist that such motives can never bring about a conversion; they can only furnish an occasion, an accidental inducement. So, motives 422 C. F. PAUWELS like these, or motives of fear and compulsion can not be a standard for classification of true conversions. * * * Every conversion is a story because it is something which takes some time in a man's life. Even if the conversion itself is sudden, the convert had a terminus a quo, a religious life before his conversion, which can throw a light on his conversion and must be told and studied, even when it is purely negative. In most cases, however, a conversion is a fact with a long preparation and it may be in process for several years. Conversions, too, have a sequel, less known to psychologists because seldom told by converts who usually close their narration with their entry into the Church .. This sequel is really part of the story because it takes some time to realize all the consequences implied in conversion and to feel truly at home in the Catholic Church. The theologian's first object of consideration is the grace of faith and, particularly, its infusion. The first thing, then, that he notes about conversion stories is that the sequel to a conversion presents a practical problem; it belongs to the confessor, the religious guide, rather than to the student of theological problems. The convert has received the grace of the faith, and he must ·face the consequences. These must be worked out by pastoral care; they do not present the theological problem presented by the beginning and preparation of a conversion. Such problems have a negative and a positive side. Msgr. Kinsman, Episcopal Bishop of Delaware who became a Catholic, spoke afterwards of a " de-anglicanising " and a " romanising " process. This must be true of every convert; he has to cease being a Protestant, or a Jew, or an atheist, or whatever he was, and he has to become a Catholic. The second part must, of course, always be a work of grace; the first part, however, though meant by God's Providence to lead a person ultimately to the Church, can be brought about by purely natural causes. In this respect, a conversion can happen in two ways. One can start doubting the truth of one's former religion because one is attracted to the Catholic Church. Here the theologian THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF CONVERSION 428 judges if it be an immediate work of grace, provided one is attracted to the Church in the right way. But the former religion can be lost or, at least, doubts can be entertained about it for quite other reasons. In such a case, a person being at a loss might begin to look around and be attracted to Catholicism On the other hand, a person might drift; losing confidence in orthodox Protestantism, he might become skeptical and then turn to atheism, finally coming to the true Church. Then the grace of faith need not have a direct influence on the negative part, the ceasing to be a Protestant. So a heathen might lose his primitive religion by simple contact with civilisation. In Cardinal Newman's case we see that his confidence in Anglicanism suffered a bad jolt from the affair of the Jerusalem bishopric long before he began to think of becoming a Catholic. In these cases it is the theologian's work to search for the moment when the positive work of grace began, though he may not be able to indicate it precisely. He can not trust the judgment of the converts themselves; to them it is one long story in which they thankfully see the finger of God's Providence. Nor can the historian or the psychologist help; this study is the realm of the theologian. At the end of the story there awaits a knotty problem of a special nature. A convert has to believe and then he has to be baptised. These two belong together. When he believes, he should be baptised in order to be a member of the Church in which he believes. Generally, before the Sacrament of Baptism there will come the Baptism of desire. A convert is not baptised immediately when he firmly and supernaturally believes. Theologically speaking, conversion is a wide subject with many problems. Here we have only mentioned a few of them and pointed to possible solutions, but it seems to us that it is a very neglected field. Even the psychological study of conversion is done mostly by non-Catholics and with disastrous results. It is our hope that more theological reflection will be given to this important matter. F. PAUWELS, O.P. c. Dominicanenkloo&tef', ZwoUe, N etherlanth. ON ANALOGY The present paper is an attempt to clear up some of the problems involved in the traditional theory of analogy as presented by the Thomistic school. The two main ideas behind the formal developments offered here are: (1) analogy is an important discovery, worthy of a thorough examination and further development, (2) contemporary mathematical logic supplies excellent tools for such work. This paper is, as far as the author knows, the first of its kind; 1 it deals with a difficult subject in a sketchy way; what it contains is, therefore, not meant to be definitive truths, but rather proposals for discussion. The approach to the problems of analogy used here is the semantic one. This is not the only method, but it would seem to be both the most convenient and the most traditional. As a matter of fact, it is difficult to see how equivocity, which is and must be treated as a relation of the same type as analogy, can be considered except by the semantic method. Also, St. Thomas Aquinas examined analogy in his question concerning divine names and the title of Cajetan's classical work is "De Nominum Analogia." It will be taken for granted that the reader has a good knowledge of classical texts of St. Thomas and Cajetan, and of the content of the Principia M athematica; 2 no reference 1. INTRODUCTORY. 1 The author is, however, indebted to the late Fr. Jan Salamucha and to J. Fr. Drewnowski who were the first to apply recent Formal Logic to Thomistic problems. The present paper may be considered as an attempt to formalize some of the opinions expressed by them. Cf. Mysl katolicka wobec Logiki wsp6lczesnej (Polish = The Catholic Thought and Contemporary Logic), Poznan 1937 (with French abstracts) and J. Fr. Drewnowski, Zarys programu filozoficznego (Polish= A sketch of a Philosophic Programme), Przeglad Filozoficzny, 37, 1943, 3-38, 150-181, 262-292, especially pp. 95-98. (There is a French account of this important work in Studia Philosophica (Lwow) I, 1935, 4ii1-454. • A. N. Whitehead and B. Russell, Principia Mathematica, e<1d ed., Cambridge 1925-1927. 424 ON ANALOGY 425 will be made to these works, except for some laws used in the proofs. Other more recent topics of mathematical logic needed for the theory, as, e. g., plural relations, 3 semantics,• etc., will be explained. The main results of our inquiry are: (1) an exact definition of univocity, equivocity, and analogy of attribution; (2) proof of the principles of contradiction and of excluded middle for univocal and equivocal names; (8) a metalogical examination and exact translation of the formula " analogy itself is analogical"; (4) proof that a syllogism in Barbara with analogical middle terms, if analogy is defined according to the alternative theory, is a correct formula; (5) criticism of the alternative theory; (6) definition of analogy of proportionality by isomorphy; (7) proof that a syllogism in Barbara with analogical middle terms, if analogy is explained according to the isomorphic theory, is a correct formula; (8) a suggestion that contemporary Logic uses analogy. Incidentally other results are reached, which may have a more general relevance: (1) the foundations of a semantic system, useful for Thomistic Logic, are sketched; (2) a generalised table of relevant semantic relations between two names is given; (8) the formal validity of a syllogism in Barbara, as opposed to its verbal correctness, is defined; (4) a rudimentary analysis of causality, as understood by Thomists, is supplied. The fundamental notion of our theory is that of meaning, described by the following formula:· " the name a means in the language l the content f of the thing x " (symbolically: "S (a, l, f, x) .") The situation symbolized by "S (a, l, f, x) " will be called a "semantic complex." In spite of its simpilicity the semanitic complex merits a detailed comment. 2. MEANING. (1) By " name " we understand here a written word or other written symbol. It must be emphasized that a written • Cf. R. Carnap, Abrias der Logistik, Wien 1929, pp. 48-45. ' Cf. A. Tarski, Der W ahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen, Studia Philosophica (Lwow), I, 1985, 261-405. 426 I. M. BOCHENSKI symbol is just a black mark (a spot of dry ink) on paper. As such (materialiter sumptum) it is a physical object which occupies a given position in space and time. It may happen, therefore, that two names, e. g., a and b have the same graphical form (symbolically I (a, b), where "I" suggests " isomorphy ") but we cannot speak correctly of " the same " name which occurs twice, e. g. as middle term in a syllogism. In that case we have always two different names of the same graphical form. (2) Every relation of meaning implies a reference to a language. This is obvious, for the same name may mean one thing in one language and something quite different in another. Moreover, it may have no meaning at all in another language. If the mention of a language is omitted in classical definitions, it is because the authors writing during the Middle Age and the Renaissance thought of the only one language used at that time, Latin. (3) What we call "content" is what classical Thomists called "ratio." This ratio is always conceived as something determining the thing whose content it is; even in case of substantial contents (as "substance" and similars) we conceive them as such and St. Thomas explicitly teaches that in this case we always have to do with a quality in a broader meaning (including "substantial quality"). (4) Finally, the " thing " means the same as the " res " of the Thomists, namely the subject to which the content connoted by the name belongs. This is, at least if the logical analysis is pushed sufficiently far, an individual. The relation S gives rise to several partial relations and partial domains. We are not going to investigate them here, as they are not relevant to our theory. We shall note, however, that the relation S allows some elegant definitions of some important semantic terms. Let Dn'R be the class of all Xn such that there is at least one X1, one X2 · • • Xn-1, one Xn+1, one Xn+2 · • • xm (m being the number of terms of R) such that R (xl, X2, • •. 'Xn, • •• 'Xm). We shall call Dn'R "the n-th domain of R." We put now: ON ANALOGY fJ.l. nom= Dt.D/S = Dt.a{ (3l, f, x)S (a, l, f, x)} fJ. 2. lin= Dt.D/S = Dt.l{ (3 a, f, x) S (a, l, f, x)} fJ. 3. rat= Dt.Da'S = Dt.f< (3 a, l, x) S (a, l, f, x)} fJ. 4. res= Dt.D4'S = Dt.x{ (3 a, l, f) S (a, l, f, x) }. 427 The above definitions define the classes of names (2.1), languages (2. 2), contents (2. 3) and things (2. 4). 3. ANALOGY A RELATION INVOLVING TWO NAMES. We contend that analogy, as well as univocity and equivocity, is not an absolute property of one name, but a relation involving two names at least. If this seems contrary to tradition, it is because of the use the classical authors made of the formula "the same name": they meant two names of the same form, but spoke, for the reason mentioned above (§ 2), of a single name. If, however, our considerations about the names are admitted, we are compelled to say that no single name is, strictly speaking, univocal, equivocal, or analogical. A single name may have a clear meaning or a confused meaning; but it has always one meaning only, and it is not possible to speak about identity or diversity of its meanings, which is required, if we have to define univocity, equivocity, or analogy. 4. THE 16 RELATIONS BETWEEN TWO SEMANTIC COMPLEXES. Now if our relations involve two meaning names, they must be relations between two semantic complexes; and as the nature of these relations depends on the relations holding between the terms of both complexes, they will be octadic relations, each complex being a tetradic relation. The general form of such relations will be consequently the following: R (a, b, l, m,f, g, x, y), where a and b are names, l and m languages, f and g contents, x and y things, while we have S (a, l, f, x) and S (b, m, g, y). The question ·arises now, how many relevant relations are there of the above type. This depends, evidently, on the number of dyadic relations between the terms a-b, l-m, f-g and x-y. Such dyadic relations are very numerous, indeed, 428 I. M. BOCHENSKI infinite in number; but for each couple two relations only are relevant, namely, I (a, b) and ,..._,I(a, b) for names; l = m and l =I= m for languages; f = g and f =I= g for contents; x = y and x =I= y for things. Thus there are 16 and only 16 relevant relation between two semantic complexes. The following table enumerates them: No. 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. a,b I I I I I I I I l,m =I= =I= =I= =I= f,g =I= =I= =I= =I= :z;,y =I= =I= =I= = =I= No. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. a,b ,.._,I ---I ---I ---I ---I ,_,I ---I ---I l,m =I= =I= =I= =I= f,g :z:,y =I= =I= =I= = =I= =I= =I= =I= = =I= This table should replace the traditional division of names into univocal, equivocal, and synonyms .. As we are, however, not interested in the establishment of a full semantic theory, we shall not define all 16 relations, but only the first four which are directly relevant to the theory of analogy. 5. DEFINITION OF UNIVOCITY AND EQUIVOCITY. These four (octadic) relations, which we shall name "R1," "R2," "Ra," and " R4," are defined as follows: 5.1. 5. 2. 5. 3. 5. 4. R 1 (a, b, l, m, f, g, :z:, y) · = Dt.S (a, l,f, :z:) • S (b, m, g, y) ·I(a, b) ·l=m· f=g·:z:= y R2 (a, b, l, m, f, g, :z:, y) · -=Dt.S(a,l,f,:z:) ·S(b,m,g,y) ·I(a,b) ·l=-m·f=g·:z:=;by R 8 (a, b, l, m, f, g, :z:, y) · =Df.S(a,l,f,:z:) ·S(b,m,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·l=m·f=;bg·:z:=y R4(a, b, l, m, f, g, :z:, y) · = Dt.S (a, l, f, :z:) · S (b, m, g, y) ·I(a, b) ·l=m· f=Fg·:z:=;by 5.1. is the definition of names which are semantically identical in spite of being (physically) two names. We may call them " isosemantic " names. 5. 2 is the definition of univocal names: quorum (x andy) nomen est commune [i.e. I (a, b)], -ratio autem significata (f and g) est simpliciter eadem (f =g). ON ANALOGY 429 5. 3 is again the definition of names which have the same denotation, but a different connotation; we may ·term them "heterologic" from X6yos =ratio. Finally 5. 4 defines the equivocal names: quorum (x and y) nomen est commune [i.e. I (a, b)], ratio autem significata simpliciter diversa (f =F g). In all cases l = in, i. e. both languages are identical. This being so, we may drop " l = m " and put " l " for " m " in the above definitions. The definitions of univocity and equivocity will now run as follows: 5. 5. Un(a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · 5. 6. nr.S (a, l,f, x) · S (b, l, g, y) ·l(a, b) · x=;i=y· f=g Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = nr.S (a, l, f, x) · S(b, l, g, y) · l(a, b) · x=;i=y· f=Fg = We have used "Un" to suggest "univoca" and "Ae" to suggest "aequivoca we also changed, for technical reasons, the order of the two last factors. The following laws, which are immediate consequences of 5. 5, will be needed in the latter parts of this paper: 5.7. 5.8. Un (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · :::::) · S (a, l, f, x) Un (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) ·:::::) · S (b, l, f, x). 6. pARTIAL DOMAINS AND RELATA. Each of OUr relations Un and Ae being heptadic, contains (A) = 7 hexadic, G) = 21 pentadic, ( l) = 85 tetradic, (J) = 85 triadic and (p = 21 dyadic partial relations, together 119 (120 with the full relation). We may denote them by" Un "resp. "Ae "followed by two figures: one above, indicating the type of the partial relation (e. g. "Un 5 " for a pentadic partial relation of Un), another below, meaning the place which it occupies among partial relations of the given type-the whole between paren"will mean the second among the pentheses. E. g." tadic partial relations of Un. Moreover, each of these partial relations gives rise, exactly as the whole relation does, to many partial domains and relata. The n-th domain of the relation R will be symbolized, as above (par. 2), by "Dn'R" and the n-th class of relata of R by 430 I. M. BOCHENSKI "ag ..'R." There are 120 such domains and 120 such classes of relata. We shall not define them all; the scope of the above remarks was only to show how ambiguous the common language is when we use it to speak about univocity or equivocity and, of course, about analogy. We shall, however, use our notation in order to define the traditional terms " univoca " and " aequivoca." We need here first a definition of the following partial dyadic relations: 6.1. = Dt.XY{ (3 a, b, l, f, g) Un (a, b, l, f, g, x, y)} 6. fJ. = Df,xy{ (3 a, b, l, f, g) Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) }. We can no\V define the classes called " univoca " and " aequivoca" which we shall name "uni" or "aeq ": 6. 3. uni = Dt.F' (Un 6. 4. aeq = Dt.F' If this would appear too generic, we may use triadic relations, including the language as a term: 6.5. (UnJ 1 ) = Dt.lx•Y{(3 a, b, f, g) Un (a, b, l, f, g, :ll, y)} 6.6. (Aeal) = Dt.l:llY{(3 a, b, l, g)Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y)} 3 AA A and consequently: 6. 7. unil = Dt.D't (Unft) U D'2 6.8. aeql=Dt.D't(Aeft) U D'2(AeJ1). 7. THE PRINCIPLES OF CONTRADICTION AND EXCLUDED MIDDLE. Other important laws of our theory are two formulae which will be called, respectively, "the law of contradiction" and "the law of excluded middle for univocal and equivocal names." We mean by the first that no two names can be univocal and equivocal in respect to the same language, couples of contents and of things. By the second we mean that if such names are not univocal, they must be equivocal, and conversely. It should be clearly understood that this is true only in respect of some determined contents meant by the names, moreover that these 481 ON ANALOGY names must be of the same form and the things they mean must be not-identical. For nothing prevents two names from being univocal in respect of f- g and, at the same time, equi vocal in respect of h- j, if f =/= h or g =/= j; also, if the names do not mean the contents involved, they are neither univocal nor equivocal in respect of them. The last two conditions follow from our table (in par. 4). Consequently, we state our principles in the following form: 7.1. (a,b,l,f,g,x,y): S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y·-::J -::J · ,_ [Un (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y)] 7.2. (a,b,l,f,g,x,y): S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y·-::J -::J · Un (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) v Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y). Proofs: 5 (1) p -::J ,-.J (pq · p ,_ q) (axiom) (2) p -::J · pq v p ,-.J q (axiom) (3) ,-.J (f =g) · = (4) by (1 (5) Df. • f =F g (definition) S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y: -::J -::J: ,_ (S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y·f=g): : S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x'=;l=y· ,-.J (f=g): . S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y f=g ) puttmg p ' -- q =7.1 by (4), (3), 5. 5 and 5. 6 with the rule for adjunction of quantifiers. (6) S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y: -::J -::J: S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y· f=g·v v · S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=;l=y·,-.J (f=g) by (2) with the same substitutions as for (4) (7) =7.2 • The method used is that of the Principia M athematica; therefore what we call "proof" is rather a sketch of a proof. Rigorous proof could be, however, easily built along the lines given here. (This applies to all proofs contained in the present paper.) 8 482 I. M. BOCHENSKI by (6), (3), 5. 5 and 5. 6 with the rule for adjunction of quantifiers. The law of excluded middle shows that the classical Thomists were right when they named their analoga " aequivoca a consilio," considering them as a subclass of the class of aequivoca, and that some modern Thomists are wrong when they put analogy as a third class coordinated to univocity and equivocity. Incidentally it may be remarked that the authors of the Principia M athematica used an exact translation of the " aequivocatio a consilio " when they coined the expression " systematic ambiguity." As a matter of fact, they were treating of analogy. Analogy will be, according to the above analyses, a heptadic relation between two names, a language, two contents and two things (at least). The names will be of the same form; the things must be different. How the contents are related we must still investigate. If we suppose that the answer to that question is expressed by " F ," the generic definition of analogy will be the following: 8. 8.1. ON THE GENERIC NOTION OF ANALOGY. An(a,b,l,f,g,x,y) ·= =nr.·S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=Fy·F. Moreover, using 7. 2 we may say that analogy is either a kind of univocity or a kind of equivocity. According to the Tradition it is certainly not the first. Thus it must be the second. We may put therefore: 8.1J. An (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = nt. · Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) ·F. The question arises now, if there is a factor G such that F would be identical with the product of G with another factor, say H.., G being identical in all kinds of analogy, Hn different for each; the definitions of the successive kinds of analogy would be constructed by putting in 8. 2 for" F" first" G · H1," then "G · H2" and so on. If it be so, we could say that the name " analogy " is univocal; if not, i. e. if there could be no common factor G, it would be equivocal. ON ANALOGY 433 As a matter of fact some well known Thomists asserted that the name "analogy" is an analogical name, i.e. (according to 8. 2) an equivocal one. We are not going to discuss this assertion, but limit ourselves to a correct formulation of it. This requires, however, some preliminary steps. 9. EXPANSION OF THE THEORY TO HIGHER LEVELS. We must first note, that we are already dealing with a situation that is far more complex than that which is met in classical Formal Logic. As a matter of fact, all artificial symbols of any system of contemporary Formal Logic belong to the same semantic level, namely to the object language, i. e. each of them means some object, but none of them means a symbol of an object. But in the theory developed above we are using symbols belonging to a higher level, namely our symbols " a " and "b," which are names of names, i.e. symbols of symbols. In order to supply the last sentence with a more definite meaning, let us introduce the following recursive definition: (1) the object language is the first level; (2) a language such that at least one term of it is a symbol of a symbol belonging to the n-th level, but none is a symbol of such term, is the n + 1 level; (3) a relation holding between objects of which at least one is of the n-th level, and none is of the n + 1 level, is of the n-th level. It will appear that our a, b and also S, Un, Ae etc. are of the second level; consequently the names of these will belong to the third level. Now when we say that " analogy " is an analogical name, the word "analogy" is a name of An; thus it belongs to the third level. We have to investigate if and how are we allowed to extend our theory to that level, for everything we said until now was clearly situated on the second level. Let us note first that the laws of the third level would be, as far as structure is concerned, exactly similar to these met on the second. For if we say that " analogy " is analogical, we mean that two names, say A and B mean in our new language (which is, by the way, the third level), the rela- 484 I. M. BOCHENSKI tions Anl and An2 of the objects (al, bl, zl, fl, gl, Xl, yl) and (a2, b2, l2, f2, g2, X2, y2). The last two may be considered as classes; but there is nothing to prevent us from considering them as objects, as the relations An1 and An2 are true contents of them. Let us put " X " for the first and " Y " for the second. We shall obtain the following exact formulation of the thesis " analogy is analogical ": AN (A, B, L, An1, An2,X, Y). Here all symbols (except the parentheses and comas) are different from those used in the former paragraphs; and yet the structure is not only similar, but strictly identical with the structure of An (a, b, l, f, g, x, y). It is also clear that the whole of our previous analyses might have been repeated on the third level. We would reach a theory, whose terms and meaning would be different from the theory we developed above, but whose structure would be completely identical. This suggests an important remark. Analyses of such kind involve the use of the idea of structural identity, or isomorphy. Now, according to the theory we shall propose, this means analogy of proportionality. It seems, consequently, that we cannot treat adequately the problem of the generic notion of analogy without a previous examination of analogy of proportionality. 10. ANALOGY OF ONE-ONE ATTRIBUTION. Among the several kinds of analogy there are only two that are really relevant: analogy of attribution and analogy of proportionality. Two names which are related by the first will be called " attributively analogous"; similarly, two names related by the latter will be called " proportionally analogous." We are starting with the first kind. Here again there is one relation called " analogia unius ad alterum "-in our terminology " one-one analogy " (symbolically " At ") -and another 485 ON ANALOGY called .. analogia plurium ad unum," here " many-one analogy " (symbolically " A tm ") . Let us begin with the first, which is the more fundamental. We ha.ve two things, x and y and two contents, f and g; the names a and b are equivocal in regard to them, but there is still another characteristic: x is the cause of y or y the cause of x. Writing "C (x, y)" for "x is the cause of y " we shall have: 10.1. At (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = Df. Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) a (a;, y) v a (y, x) 0 0 0 This is, however, rather unsatisfactory, for the connection of f and g is not shown, the relation of causality being not analysed. We cannot, of course, give a complete analysis of this highly complex notion here. We shall note only that the relation of causality is a pentadic relation which holds between two things, two contents and a peculiar dyadic relation between the things; e. g. the food is the cause of the health of the animal, if and only if there is a content f (health) present in the food (x) such that, if a peculiar relation R (here: of being eaten) is established between a; and the animal (y), another content g (the health of the animal) appears in y. Writing " C (f, x, R, g, y)" for this relation we shall have: 10. fJ. At (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = Df. Ae (a, b, l, f, g, X, y) v a (g, y, R, f, x). 0 0 (3R) 0 a (f, X, R, g, y) v The alternative is necessary, according to the traditional doctrine, as there may be an analogy independently from the direction of causality. 11. ANALOGY OF MANY-ONE ATTRffiUTION. The second kind of analogy of attribution is clearly derived from the first. The many-one analogy holds, namely, between two names a and b, if and only if there is a third name c, such that both a and b are attributively analogous (according to 10. 2) with c: 11.1. Atm(a,b,l,f,g,x,y) · =»t. · (3 c,h,z) ·At(a,c,l,f,h,x,z) ·At (b, c, l, g, h, y, z). · 486 l. M. BOCHENSKI Let x be food, y-urine, z-animal, j, g, h-the contents called "health" of, respectively, x, y, z, and a, b, c-the names of these contents. There will be a many-one analogy of a in respect of b. We may still distinguish four further subclasses of this class of analogical names, for in 11. 1 we may have either (1) C(f, x, R, h, z) · C(g, y, R, h, y) C(f, x,R, h, z) · C(h, z, R, g, y) (3) C(h, z,R, f,x) · C(g, y, R, h, z) (4) C(h, z, R, f, x) · 0 (h, z, R, g, y). -or -or -or U. CONDITIONS OF ANALOGY OF PROPORTIONALITY. Th'ere are, according to tradition, two conditions for this kind of analogy: the contents must be non-identical, i.e. we must have equivocity; still, the syllogism having as middle terms a couple of proportionally analogous names must be a correct formula. This is secured, according to classical writers, by the fact that these middle terms mean something " proportionally common " in both cases, or that there is an analogatum commune containing in confuso the contents meant by both names. It seems at first, that these requirements are contradictory: for, if the meanings of the two names are quite different, one can hardly see how a syllogism with them as middle terms may be a correct formula. As a matter of fact, not only is there a logical theory capable of fulfilling both requirements without contradiction, but it seems even that there are two such theories. It seems, namely, that one theory is suggested by the " proportionaliter commune," the other by the " confuse." We shall call the former "isomorphic," the latter "alternative theory.' As far as is known to the writer, St. Thomas used the isomorphic theory, while the alternative seems to be originated by Cajetan. 18. THE ALTERNATIVE THEORY. The central idea of the alternative theory may be explained as follows: we have to do with three names; one of them means the content f, the other the content g, f and g being the analogata particularia; the ON ANALOGY 487 third name means the analogatum commune, namely, the alternative of f and g, symolically f U g. We shall give to that expression a sufficiently clear meaning by putting 13.1. [f U g]x· =Dt. · fxv gx. A rather complex situation arises here because of admission of three names: this makes an expansion of our previous formulae to three complexes necessary, and the basic formula for analogy of proportionality becomes a relation of 10 terms. Once a definition of this form is established, the (heptadic) relations analogous to Un and Ae will appear as partial re!ations of the general one, and the verbal formulae as elliptic. We shall not, however, define this general relation in that way, as, for several reasons, to be explained later (par. 16), the whole alternative -theory appears as inadequate. But we are going to investigate the validity of a syllogism in Barbara with proportionally analogous middle terms. For the use in that inquiry we define the analogy of proportionality (Anp) according to the alternative theory as a heptadic relation in the following way: 13. Pl. Anp (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = Dt. · Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · (3 h) · f = [g U h]. This is a partial relation contained in the full relation of analogy described above. 14. ON FORMAL VALIDITY OF SYLLOGISM. If we wish to investigate the validity of a syllogism with analogical middle terms we meet a serious difficulty unknown in current Formal Logic. For in current Formal Logic it is always supposed that a formula which is verbally valid is also formally valid; the reason of this supposition is that all terms used in current Formal Logic are univocal symbols. Here, however, the situation is different, as we have to deal with analogical names. We need, consequently, a distinction between the verbal and formal validity of a formula; moreover we need to know when a verbally valid formula is also formally valid. This is by no 488 I. M. BOCHENSKI means a universal rule, as the case of the syllogism with equivocal and non-analogical middle terms shows. We are not going to investigate the problem in its full generality, but we will limit ourselves to a single case, the syllogism in Barbara. We shall first construct two languages: (1) A first-level univocal language. This will be the language of the theory of classes, interpreted as a Logic of contents. In it the mode Barbara will run as follows: f c g. h c f. ::J . h c g. (2) A second-level analogical language. This will contain all symbols used until now (small Latin letters being sometimes substituted by small Greek letters and indexes being added to them) , with addition of the following: (i) " II "; a formula composed of " II " followed by " a," followed by " b " will be interpreted as meaning the formula "a C b "; (ii) " + "; a formula such as " II + a + b " will be read: " a formula composed of II followed by a, followed by b "; (iii) " e T "; "Fe T " will be read: " F is a true theorem." The proofs will be developed in a second-level language, containing as subclasses the above two. We shall proceed as follows. Given the (second-level) premises A and B such that A e T ·BeT, we wish to prove that the (verbally correct) conclusion C (of the same level) is a true theorem, i. e. that C e T. We translate A and B into the first-level language, apply to the result the laws of classical Formal Logic and obtain a conclusion, which we re-translate into the second-level language; if we are able to obtain C e T in that way, the formula" if A e T ·BeT, thenCe T "is clearly a valid formula and the formal validity of the mode, whose premises are A and B, and the conclusion is C, is proved. We put as a law of translation the intuitively evident: 1.1,..1. S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y): ::J :II+a+beT·e==·fCg. With the help of 14. 1 we can easily prove that a syllogism in Barbara with univocal middle terms is a formally valid formula; but we camiot prove it if the middle terms are either ON ANALOGY 489 purely equivocal or attributively analogical. Alongside of 14. 1 --. we shall need still another law of translation for cases where an existential quantifier is involved: 14. 2. (3 h) · S (a, l, [f U h], x) · S (b, l, g, y): : (3 h) . [f h] c g. u This seems to be also intuitively evident. 15. THE VALIDITY OF THE SYLLOGISM IN BARBARA WITH ANALOGICAL MIDDLE TERMS ACCORDING TO THE ALTERNATIVE THEORY. In such a syllogism the middle term of the major premise is analogical with regard to the middle term in the minor premise, the situation being this, that the former means alternatively by the latter and some other content. This syllogism, is a valid formula. The proof is rather cumbersome, because of the existential quantifier; we shall however give here a developed sketch of it. In the first place we need two theorems analogous to 5. 7 and 5. 8. These may be proved as follows: (1) Anp (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · == · Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · (3 h) · f = [g U h] [by 13. 2] (2) =·S(a,l,f,x) ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) ·x=Fy· . f¥= g. (3 h) . f = [g h] [by (1) and 5. 6] (3) ==· (3 h) ·S(a,l,f,x) (4) = · (3 h) · S (a, l, [g U h], x) · S (b, l, g, y) ·I (a, b) · u ·S(b,l,g,y) ·l(a,b) · ·x¥=y·f=Fg·f=[g U h] [by (2) and *10. 24 Principia Mathematica.] ·x=Fy·f=Fg [by (3) and *13.12 Principia Mathematica.] (5) ==· (3h)S(a,l,[gUh],x) 15.1. Anp (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · · (3 h) S (a, l, [g U h], x) [by (5) and "p = qr · · p q "] · (3h)S(b,l,g,y) · · (3h) ·x=Fy·f=Fg [by (4) and *10. 5 Principia Mathematica.] 440 15. !2. I. M. BOCHENSKI Anp (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · => · S (b, l, g, y) [by (5) and "p = qra · => · p =>. r," dropping the quantifier]. We enumerate now the five hypotheses of the syllogism in Barbara with analogical middle terms, explained according to the alternative theory: H1. II+m1+a1eT H2. IT+ b1 +m2e T H3. Anp (m1, m2, l, P-1> p.2, x, y) H4. Un (al> a2, l, a 1 , a2, z, t) H5. Un (b1, b2, l, {31, f32, u, v). The proof of " II + b2 + a2 e T " runs as follows: (1) (3 h) S (m1o l, [p.2 U h], x) by H3 and 15. 1 (!2) S (al> l, al> z) by IJ4 and 5. 7 (3) (3 h) · [P-2 U h] C a1 by (1), (!2), H1 and 14. 2 (4) (5) S (b 1, l, f11o u) by H5 and 5. 7 S (m2, l, p.2, y) by H3 and 15. 2 (6) {31 c /J-2 by (4), (5), H2 and 14.1 (7) {31 C P-2 · (3 h) · [P-2 U h] C a1 by (6) and (3) (8) (3 h) · {31 C P.2 · [P-2 U h] C a1 by (7) and *10. 35 PM (9) (3 h) · {31 C a1 (10) {31 C a1 by (9) (11) S (b2, l, /31, u) byH5 and 5.8 (12) S (a 2 , l, a1o z) by H4 and 5.8 (13) II + b2 + a2 e T · = ·{31 C a1 II+ b2 + a2 e T by (11), (12) and 14.1 (14) u by (8)' "f c g. [g h] c j . => . f c j" and *10. 28 PM by (10) and (13) Q.E.D. 16. CRITICISM OF THE ALTERNATIVE THEORY. Jt has been shown that a syllogism in Barbara with analogical middle terms, defined according to the alternative theory, is a formally ON ANALOGY 441 valid formula. This is, however, the only advantage of this theory. Not even all requirements of Theology and Metaphysics in regard to the syllogism can be met by means of it. For a syllogism of these sciences has not only analogical middle terms, but also analogical major terms; e. g. when we write " if every being is good, and God is a being, then God is good," not only " being," but also "·good " must be analogical. 'But this means, according to the alternative theory that HI,. in par. 15 should be replaced by If so, instead of (3) we would obtain only (3 h) · U-t2 U h] C [cx2 U g] which does not allow us to draw the conclusion (14). Neither can we try to in vert the order of " f " and " g " in 15. 1 ; in that case the syllogism would become valid, but the major term in the conclusion would have an alternative meaning, which can hardly be admitted. Moreover, the theory has other inconveniences. First, the very definition of analogy, as sketched in par. 13, is highly unsatisfactory. By saying that two names are analogical if and only if there is a third name meaning alternatively the contents meant by both, we do not show any intrinsic connection between the contents involved; and every couple of names would be analogical, according to that definition, for we can always introduce into our system a new name, defined precisely as meaning the said alternative. Secondly, there are serious gnoseological difficulties. The situation with which we have to deal, is the following: two names are given, and while we know the meaning of the first by direct experience, we do not know in that way the meaning of the second. In order to be able to use that second name correctly, we must supply it with a meaning correlated in some way with the meaning of the first. Now the alternative theory allows nothing of the sort: it only says how we can deal with middle terms having alternative meanings, when both meanings are already known. 3 442 I. M. BOCHENSKI These remarks do not lead to the complete rejection of the alternative theory; but they seem to show that it is at least incomplete and should be completed by another theory. The present author believes that this was the position of Cajetan. 17. THE ISOMORPHIC THEORY. This theory is based on the following considerations: the " proportionaliter eadem " suggests that there is an identity, not between the contents meant by both analogical terms, but between some relations holding between the first (f) and its thing (x) on one side, the second (g) and its thing (y) on the other. The texts of St. Thomas Aquinas are clear enough here. The said relations are, however. not identical; this is also a traditional thesis, strongly emphasized by all classical Thomists. We may therefore admit, as a first approximation, that, while being non-identical, they are both contained in the same relation. The definition of analogy of proportionality would run, in that case, as follows: 17.1. Anp (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = Df. • Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · {3 P, Q, R) · fPx · gQy · P =;&= Q · P <: R · Q <: R. This is, however, not satisfactory. For if 17.1 would be the definition of analogy of proportionality, there would be a material univocal element; analogy would allow us to transfer to the other name some material relations found in the meaning of the first. Now St. Thomas Aquinas and Tradition are quite clear as to the negation of such univocity. But 17.1 can be corrected by the affirmation that the common element in both relations is formal, i. e. consists in the isomorphy of these relations. The definitions becomes: 17. An (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · = nt. · Ae (a, b, l, f, g, x, y) · · 3 P, Q) · fPx · gQy · PsmorQ. This is what we mean by "isomorphic theory." It is strongly supported by the fact that St. Thomas Aquinas uses for illustration of his doctrine mathematical proportionality, the only mathematical function he possessed and a function which makes one immediately think of isomorphy. One may think, perhaps, that if this be analogy of propor- 448 ON ANALOGY tionality, the meaning of our sentences about spirit, God etc., would be extremely poor, indeed limited to some very few formal relations enumerated in the Principia M athematica. But this is not so. It is true that we cannot, as yet, give exact formulations of many formal properties involved in relations used by Metaphysics and Theology; the reason, however, is not the lack of such formal properties, but the very undeveloped state of Biology and of other sciences, from which the Metaphysician and the Theologian must draw his analogical names (and contents). An immense progress in speculative sciences would arise out of a formalization of these disciplines. And yet, even in the actual state of knowledge, where only Mathematics, i. e. the poorest of all sciences, is formalized, we can show, the difference between the Principle and the Father by purely formal means--as, evidently, the first is transitive, the second intransitive. 18. THE EXISTENTIAL INTERPRETATION OF THE MODE Barbara. H the isomorphic theory is admitted, a peculiar interpretation must be given to the mode Barbara with analogical middle terms. Let us consider the following substitution: " if all being is good, and God is a being, then God is good." According to the isomorphic theory the only common element meant by the two" being "and the two" good" is a product of some formal relations, say P in the first case and Q in the second. But if it is so, the major must be interpreted as follows: " for all x: if there is an f such that fPx, then there is a g such that gQy "; the minor will be interpreted in the same manner by the formula " for all x: if there is an h such that hRx, then there is an f such that fPx." From this we draw the conclusion " for all x: if there is an h such that hRx, then there is a g such that gQx." This would mean: " if there is an x such that h is the Divinity of x, then there is a g such that g is the Goodness of x." The law used here is: 18.1. (x) · (3 f)fPx :J (3 g) gQx : (x) · (3 h) hRx :J. (3 f) fPx : :J : (x) · (3 h) hRx :J (3 g) gQx. This is a correct formula of the Logic of predicates. 444 I. M. BOCHENSKI The remarkable result of the existential interpretation is that the Thomistic idea of analogy becomes sharply formulated in a very anti-univocal sense. For, we do not know, as a result of our reasoning according to 18. 1, anything except that there is something (undetermined as to the content) which has to God the set of quite formal relations Q. And yet, the talk about God's goodness is clearly meaningful; moreover rigorous demonstrations concerning it are possible. 19. THE VALIDITY OF THE SYLLOGISM WITH ANALOGICAL We are going to show now how, in such theory, a syllogism in Barbara is a formally valid formula. We meet here, however, two formal difficulties. First we note that isomorphy, being a relation between two relations, cannot be, as such, treated as a relation in which these relations are contained; now this seems to be necessary if we wish to construct a correct syllogism with analogical middle terms, interpreted according to the isomorphic theory. This difficulty may be, however, obviated in the following manner. Isomorphy implies the identity of a series of formal properties of the relations involved. These formal properties are different in each case of couples of isomorphic relations; but for each of them in concreto a product of such properties may be determined. E. g., in some cases both relations will be included in diversity and will be transitive; in other cases they will be intransitive and assymetric etc. Now each of these properties may be conceived as a relation in which the given isomorphic relations are contained. This can be done by introducing in the system the name of a new relation, which is treated as a primitive term, but whose meaning is determined by an axiom. E. g. for symmetry we will put a relationS and determine the meaning of "S" by the axiom (x, y): xSy · xSy xSy. The product of such relations would constitute the relation in which both isomorphic relations are contained. 6 MIDDLE TERMS ACCORDING TO THE ISOMORPHIC THEORY. =· • The author is conscious that the proposed solution is highly un-orthodox; he 445 ON ANALOGY The other difficulty is strictly operational. It will appear that we shall need an expansion of our 17.2 in order that the name of the common relation R, in which the relations P and Q are contained, might be treated as an argument of "Anp." If so, a new relation must be defined, namely an octadic relation containing as terms, alongside of the seven stated in 17. 2, also R. We shall define it as follows: 19.1. Anp (a, b, l, f, g, x, y, R) · = vr. · Ae (a, b, l,f, g, x, y) · · (3 P, Q, R) · fPx · gQy · P =I= Q ·P =I= R · Q =I= R · · P C: R · Q C: R · R e Form. By " Form " we mean the class of all formal relations, as described in par. 17. There will be three laws of translation, analogous to 14.1: 19. 2. Anp (mto m 2 , l, p.1 , p.2 , x, y, P) · Anp (a 1 , a 2 , l, 0:1o o:2 , z, t, Q): =:) =:):II+ m 1 +a, e T · ==· (x) · (3 f)fPx =:) (3 g)gQx. 19. 3. Anp (b 1 , b 2 , l, {3 1 , {32, u, v, R) · Anp ( m 1 , m 2 , l, p.1 , p.2 , x, y, P) : =:) =:):II+ b, +m2e T·=· (x) · (3 h)hRx=:) (3f)fPx. 19. 4. Anp (b1o b2, l, {3,, f3z, u, v, R) · Anp (a,, az, l, o:,, 0:2, z, t, Q): =:) =:) : II+ b 2 + a 2 e T · = · (x) · ( 3 h) hRx =:) ( 3 g) gQx. Our hypotheses are Hl. II+ m 1 + a 1 e T H2. II+ b, + m 2 e T H3. Anp (mto mz, l, p.,, p.z, x, y, P) H4. Anp (a,, az, l, o:,, 0:2, z, t, Q) H5. Anp (b,, b2, l, {31, {32, u, v, R). The proof of " II + bz + a2 e T " runs as follows: (1) (x) · (3f)fPx=:)(3g)gQx by H3, H4, H1 and 19. 92 (2) (x) · (3 h) hRx =:) (3 f) fPx by H5, H3, H2 and 19. 3 (3) (x) · (3 h) hRx =:) (3 g) gQx by (1), (2) and 18.1 would be glad to find anything better. It must be remembered, however, that the whole difficulty is purely operational; it seems intuitively evident that once there is a common property, the syllogism is valid. 446 I. M. BOCHENSKI (4) IT+ b2 + a2 e T ·==· (x) (3 h)hRx by H5, H4 and 19. 4 (5) n + b2 + a2 e T (3 g)gQx by (4) and (3) Q.E.D. ON ANALOGY IN RECENT LOGIC. While the classical Thomists used analogy in Ontology and Theology, but not in Logic, recent writers seem to make a constant use of it in Formal Logic. We noticed already that the authors of the Principia M athematica re-invented the very name used for analogy by the Thomists (par. 7) and that analogy appears in the construction of Semantics (par. 9). The last phenomenon is connected with the theory of types. It is known that, in order to avoid contradictions, we are bound to divide all objects treated by Logic (or all logical expressions) into classes called "types." The formulae used in each type have quite a different meaning, but exactly the same structure as the formulae used in another. This means that the formal properties involved are identical i.e. that we have to do with analogy, at least if the isomorphic theory is accepted. The question arises as to why analogy has penetrated the domain of Formal Logic. The answer seems to be given by the theory of Prof. H. Scholz, who says that recent Formal Logic is nothing else than a part of classic Ontology. 7 As a matter of fact, recent Formal Logic generally deals, not with rules, but with laws of the being in its whole generality; most of the laws contained in the Principia M athematica, e. g., as opposed to metalogical rules, are such laws. If this is so, it is not to be wondered at that some consideration must have been given to analogy, for "being" is an analogical term and so are the names of all properties, relations, etc., belonging to being as such. One curious feature of these developments is that the highly trained mathematical logicians who had to speak about analogy, spoke about it in a very loose and inexact way. 7 H. Scholz, Metaphysik als strcnge Wissenschaft, Koln 1941. ON ANALOGY 447 What, for example, the Principia M athematica contains on the subject is far more rudimentary than the classic Thomistic doctrine. Yet, recent Formal Logic, once applied to the language itself, supplies superior tools for the elaboration of that notion. The present paper is believed to contain only a very small sub-class of the class of theorems on analogy, which may and should be elaborated by means of recent Formal Logic. I. M. BocHENSKI, 0. P. University of Fribourg, Fribourg, Switzerland. THE BASIS OF THE SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREED0.\1 [Third Installment] I. THE SuAREZIAN TEACHING ABOUT HuMAN FREEDOM IV. THE FREE ACTS I. The Nature of" Free Use." 124 We have seen the Suarezian teaching on the nature of liberty, its characteristics, its subject, its relation to divine movement and divine freedom, to created intelligence, and to created necessary acts. We have also seen that freedom to be real requires not only the free faculty but the free use of that faculty as well. With that use we shall now concern ourselves. Suarez indicates that the very use of free will consists in indifference. He appeals to the Council of Trent, 125 for the Council, as we have seen, declares liberty is in the power of indifference. The use, therefore, of liberty is the use of that power. If a man is incapable of the use of this power then he lacks the indifferent power. Man, then, is naturally capable of the free use of the free faculty and in the exercise of human actions he retains this use; otherwise all his acts are outside his nature. 126 It is certain that there is in us liberty such that in the very instant in which we freely operate, the potency retains its indifference. 127 An act in which the power is determined is not free for, Suarez repeats, the act of the will does Cf. Opus. Primum, Liber I, cap. 1-4. Trent, Sess. 6, can. 5 (Denz., n. 815), cap. 5 (Denz., n. 797), and can. 4 (Denz., n. 814). 126 (Si) homo ex natura sua incapax est usus libertatis a nobis expositae . . . sequitur non solum carere hominem usu libero suorum actuum sed etiam carere interna facultate (Opus. Primum, cap. I, nn. 6-7). 127 Sit ergo primum hujus materiae fundamentum certissimum dari in nobis talem libertatem quae in ipso usu humanorum actuum indifferentiam . . . habeat ... quod ipse usus sit cum indifferentia quam retinet potentia etiam in ipso instanti in quo libere operator (Ibid., n. 8). 12 ' 125 448 BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 449 not haYe the note of freedom immediately, but from the faculty which actually exercises freedom in the very act. If either power (of acting or of not acting) is not proximately expedited for act the act is not free. 128 The free act of willing can be impeded (though the potency remains free) because: a) God's concursus is not or b) because the object is not proposed. In neither case is the consequent non-act free. 129 The free act of not-willing, on the other hand, cannot be impeded by the object (for the object can move the will only insofar as the will is born to be moved by it), but it can be impeded by God, ·whose infinite power can overcome the creature's finite capacity for both willing and not-willing. 1 so 2. God's Causality With Regard to Free Acts. Every act depends immediately on God, Who gives being not only to the faculty, but to the operation as well. God acts in our acts, even with immediacy of supposit as well as with immediacy of power. The effect comes forth by one and the same act from God and from the creature; the very act of will is one act flowing immediately and per se not only from us but also from God and this, Suarez adds, is the teaching of St. Thomas. 131 God causes this action immediately through His will or power, not through some other action in the creature, for to act another action is given. Through one and the same action God, together with the will, influences the act or the term of action. 132 Ibid., cap. 2, n. 5. Potest autem ilia facultas quoad potestatem volendi impediri vel ex parte objecti per ignorantiam vel inconsiderationem . . . vel ex parte potentiae si fingamus privari omni concursu (Ibid., n. 10). 130 Quoad potestatem nolendi vel non volendi non potest impediri usus libertatis ex parte objecti ... potest tamen impediri ab aliqua exteriori causa ... quia in voluntate Iibera duplex sit potestas ad volendum scilicet et non volendum neutra eorum et infinitae virtu tis; ergo in utraque potest superari a Deo (Ibid., nn. 11-12) . 131 Suarez cites III cont. Gent., cap. 70 and Summa Theol., I, Q. 105, a. 5. 132 lnfluit Deus immediate in opera Iibera voluntatis nostrae . . . tam divina virtus quam substantia seu suppositum per seipsum proxime et immediate influit ... effectum una et eadem actione a Deo et creatura tanquam a causa prima et secunda prodire . . . (Deus) non potest autem esse causa actionis per aliam quae in creatura sit sed immediate per suam voluntatem vel potentiam; qua ad actionem non est actio ... per eadem actionem influit Deum cum volunate in actum sen terminum illius actionis (Opus. Primum, Zoe. cit., cap. 4, nn. 3-5). 128 120 450 THOMAS U. MULLANEY For Suarez, God's concursus is not previous to, or distinct from, the human act, for it is the act of the second cause; it is the act as of God acting and concurring with that cause-and nothing can be previous to itself. Since concursus is the very act, it is concerned not with the principle of the act but with its effect, it gives the principle (in our case the will) nothing. In the case of transient actions that is clear since they are not received into the agent anyway, and confer nothing on the agent. It is true also of immanent acts, such as those of the will. Concursus regards the will not as it is a principle of such an act but as it is a subject about which such an act is concerned. Hence concursus confers on the wiil nothing by which it is aided, inclined, or strengthened to acting, because through this action the will is not constituted in first act, but in second act, and therefore it supposes in the will whatever is necessary to acting .133 A classic objection is that this action is an effect of divine action, and therefore through the divine action something previous is done to the will by which it is aided in eliciting its act. The consequence is proved by this, that action cannot be the immediate cause of action. 134 Suarez answers by a distinction. The divine act can be two-fold: ad intra or ad extra. An act ad intra, not properly an action, is an act immanent in God which is not as a means to a term to be produced externally, but rather is to that term as a principle of acting, or as applying the divine omnipotence. An act ad extra is an action received into a creature and is the proper means (via) to the effect and term of the action of the created cause. It is the dependence by which the effect depends on God as on its first cause. Suarez, taking divine act as an act ad intra, says that the action of the creature is an effect of divine action, but the consequence is to be denied, for action taken in this sense 183 Generalem concursum sic . . . non esse aliquid distinctum vel praevium ad actionem causae secundae . . . quia ostensum est hunc concursum esse eamdem actionem causae secundae . . . eadem actio non potest esse praevia ad seipsam. . . . Concursus non versatur circa voluntatem ut est principium talis actions sed ut est subjectum ... concursus nihil voluntati confert quoad agendum juvetur, etc. (Ibid) ., n. 6) . 1 "' Ibid., n. 7. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 451 (immanent) can be a principle of action properly so called (transient). Taking divine action as act ad extra the act of the created will is not an effect of divine action; it is rather an effect of the divine will and power. The created action depends not on the action of God, but on God Himself and His power immediately, just as it depends on the created will. God's act ad extra is not prior to the action of the creature for it is the very same thing as that act of the creature. However, it is prior by nobility.i 35 Granted God's influxus in the effect, is there needed in addition some influx in the second cause itself? 138 Some answer in the affimiative; some previous entity is required in the second cause to move or determine it. Two schools advance this answer: I) those who say God moves the will through a true action in it by imprinting on it something by which it is forally determined to such an action; 2) those who maintain God moves the will not by imprinting something intrinsic but rather by an extrinsic quasi-effective motion based on the natural subordination and sympathetic response of the lower cause to God. The first school teaches that the will cannot act without such motion, but given it, the will acts necessarily, but by necessity of consequence and of supposition. The will, this school maintains, cannot resist such determination; by it, it is formally determined prior to operating to do one thing; the voluntary act is from the will effectively but the determination is actively from God alone. Yet this school argues that liberty is not destroyed by such motion, for God moves strongly, but also sweetly and proportionately. Suarez sees a difficulty in reconciling the "sweetly" with this school's notion of strongly, but the followers of this school urge all to believe what cannot be understood. 137 136 In illo (sensu, i. e. actus ad intra) verum est antecedens sc. actionem creaturae esse effectum divinae actionis . . . in hoc autem sensu negatur consequentia . • • hoc modo utcndo nomine actionis posset actio ab actione manare . . . loquendo de actione ad extra, negandum est antecedens . . . nonpendet actio creaturae ab actione Dei sed . . . ab ipso Deo ejusque voluntate et potentia •.. in hoc sensu actio Dei non est prior actine creaturae . . . prioritate causalitatis •.• in re sit omnino eadem actio (Ibid., nn. 7-8). 187 Ibid., cap. 6, nn. S-5. 180 Ibid., cap. 6-6. THOMAS U. MULLANEY Suarez answers that the will in order to act freely, does not need any special help of God (distinct from the will's act itself) by which it is given something previous to its act in addition to its permanent active power. 188 He states that this is the teaching of all theologians except Thomists, and even of some of them; he also says that it is according to mind of St. Thomas, who teaches that in all created agents only two things are required for act, the agent's own power and God's motion. 139 By the latter, concursus in the Suarez' sense must be understood, else three things are required. From reason, Suarez argues against a previous motion showing, as we have already seen, that the essential subordination of second causes to the first cause is amply safeguarded by simultaneous concursus. Why require another divine action? It is required to attain the effect of the creature neither immediately nor mediately (as a previous condition), therefore, it is not required at all. It cannot be required immediately, for God immediately influences the effect through simultaneous concursus. If required mediately it influences not the effect but the second cause itself as an application, motion, compliment, or determination of this cause. 140 Now none of these is necessary. An application to act surely is not necessary since there is sufficient application through the proposition of the object. Supposing all other requirements to act as given, just how could pre-motion apply to the will, since on the supposition it has its object already presented through the judgment of reason? The only thing left is that the act itself be the term of the motion, but this application is imagined to be prior to that act. 141 138 Voluntatem Iiberam ad suum actum liberum efficiendum non indigere speciali influxu Dei distincto ab ips() actu . . . quo ei aliquid ad actionem praevium conferatur, distinctum etiam ab ejus virtute activa permanente, naturali vel infusa (Ibid., cap. 6, n. 1). ••• Ibid., n. 2. Suarez cites Summa Theol., 1-11, Q. 109, aa. 1-8. uo llle (concursus i.e. simultaneous) etiam satis est ut causa secunda sit subordinata primae non per accidens sed per se et essentialiter (Ibid., n. 8) . 141 Postquam voluntas habens praesens objectum per judicium rationis . inquiritur quid sit necessarium ex parte Dei. . . . Dices terminum (hujus applicationis) esse actionem causae secundae . . . sed . . . applicatio dicitur esse aliquid in causa secunda praevium ad actionem (Ibid., 6-7) . BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 453 Neither is a motion required by the will previous to its act. :Motion requires a term, but this motion has none that Suarez can determine. It cannot be the act of the second agent, for if it were and the will passively receives this then only God would be active in producing the act. The only other possibility is a fluid quality, produced in the agent, but a quality, which, as we shall see, is purposeless. We should note, however, that the Aristotelian maxim, " whatever is moved is moved by something other than itself," adduced in proof of this pre-motion means simply that created agents are moved insofar as they receive from another their power of acting (which is continually conserved in them), and application of that power to the object. It does not mean that they receive a motion of that power. 142 The created will needs, in the third place, no complement in order to act. It is impossible for it to receive such a complement unless outside the ordinary course its act is intensified, extended as to objects, etc. Every power by nature is surely adequate to its own act. Fire is adequate to produce heat; no fluid quality is needed to help it to do so. Again, supposing such a quality as necessary and given it in the will, God's simultaneous concursus is still necessary. Given both motions, the will either needs yet another pre-motion, or it does not. If it does, then the process must proceed to infinity. If it does not, then the first pre-motion is not needed, either, for: 1) on the supposition some second cause (that, namely, to which the quality is already added) does not need pre-motion, hence second causes do not by nature require it; 2) if, from the form of the agent plus this quality, the second agent's power is complete why could not God give creatures permanent powers equal u• Eodem enim modo inquirendum est quem intrinsecum terminum habeat haec motio ... non est .•. immediate ad actionem causae secundae ... (quia) fieret actionem ipsius voluntatis . . . a solo Deo fieri et voluntatem solum passive ad ipsam concnrrere .... Axioma illnd (omne qlod movetur ab alio movetur) in hoc creatum non agit nisi virtutem agendi ab alio accipiat, habere verum quod etc. . . ." At vero post receptam et conservatam virtutem et factam applicationem passi vel materiae sufficientem, sit necessaria nova motio in agente ut agat, neque est verum neque ab Aristotele alicubi in hoc sensu traditum (Ibid., nn. 9-11). 454 THOMAS U. MULLANEY to this combination of power plus quality? Certainly that would not be contrary to the efficacy of the divine power, and would show God to be even more liberal in communicating His power to creatures. One cannot argue that this quality is incommunicable as something innate to the second cause, for even now the second cause has, in a stable and permanent way, its powers of acting, but has it from the actual influx of the first cause which gives and conserves it. This complement could likewise be given permanently and not merely transiently. Since, whether permanent or transient, it comes from God, we can hardly understand what a transient quality can accomplish that a permanent quality cannot achieve. 143 In the fourth place, no excitation of second causes is necessary, at least not because of the subordination of second causes to the first cause. In some agents excitation is required but for other reasons; in those cases it is achieved by other second causes (as an odoriferous body emits its odor only when heated) . The proponents of this " exciting quality " cannot explain its nature, or agree on its subject. 144 In general, Suarez summarizes, all arguments for a previous perfecting quality are to be rejected. The argument that the second cause always acts as an instrument of the first cause and needs a transient motion or completing of its power does not prove. In the first place, it is not universally true that instruments need this motion. Heat can be an instrument of fire or even of the soul in producing a new substantial form; ""Non solum superfiuum sed etiam impossible videtur aliquid sub ea ratione compleri sub qua jam completum est; sed causa secunda (in ordine causae secundae) supponitur completam virtutem habere (Ibid., n. 13) . . . . Quis (inquam) credat virtutem solis ad illuminandum in ordine causae secundae incompletam esse? Aut visum optime dispositum et perfecte informatum specie adhuc indigere alio extrinseco complemento? (Ibid., n. 14). Si (causa secunda cum complemento sub discussione) non indiget alio auxilio ... idem dici poterat de ipsa secunda causa ut praecise constituta sua naturali virtute agendi . . . tum quia jam damus quamdam causam secundam quae non requirit alium concursum . . . tum quia . . . au non potuit Deus dare creaturae virtutem . . . ita perfectam ut haberet ex se totam illam efficacitatem? (Ibid., n. 16) ... ergo ex hac parte nulla est major repugmmtia in communicanda hac virtute permanente quam sit in virtute fluente (Ibid., n. 17) . "' Haec excitatio a causa prima •.. etiam est sine fundamento adinventa (Ibid., n. 18). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 455 yet it does not act in virtue of pre-motion received into it as is per se evident. The same is true of an image in the imagination acting as an instrument in the production of an intelligible species. The usual instances cited as exemplifying the necessity of pre-motion in instruments are artistic instruments. But in them a special motion is required not precisely because they are instruments but because of of place required for their operation-but that is not true of all instruments. Secondly, this argument from instrumental causes does not conclude simply because second causes, properly speaking, are not instrumental but principal causes. They are said to be instrumental with respect to God by a certain comparison and to emphasize their imperfection and dependence on God. 145 There remains finally the question of predetermination. 146 Here Suarez' purpose is to show: 1) that second causes in general do not need to receive determination from the first that the nature of some causes, as free, cause to act; and does not demand it either. Second causes in general do not require predetermination. Surely secondary natural agents by their very forms or natural properties are determined to one thing, and have no intrinsic indifferences; how could fire, for instance, need something in addition to its nature to determine it to heat things rather than to freeze them? If one objects that some natural agents, the sun, for instance, are capable of many effects and must be determined to this one rather than to that, the answer is that the point under discussion is overlooked in the objection. Such determination as that does not pertain to the subordination of second causes to the first cause. Physically speaking, such determination is always made by the assistance and concurrence of other second causes, efficient or material, with which or us Dla generalis propositio de instrumentis assumpta . . . de motu recepto in instrumento, non est in universum vera. . . . Neque argumentum quod in hac re fieri solet de instrumenlis artis est efficax ... quia tota actio horum instrumentorum fit, vel deferenda aliquod corpus per varia loca ... vel compellendo aliud a Guo loco : .. Deinde ... causae secundae non sunt proprie ... instruments sed causae principales in suo ordine (Ibid., n. 18). ue Ibid., cap. 7. 456 THOMAS U. MULLANEY about which these "indetermined" second causes act. 147 One can conceive a case (though it does not exist) in which determination through second causes would be impossible. Then either no effect would follow or else God would determine the cause, not because of its subjection to Him, but because of its peculiar need for it pertains to the general providence of the first cause that He assist those second causes which are in need. In such cases the determination could be brought about by some previous reality added to the cause, but it need not necessarily be brought about in that way. 148 The objection, " second causes need to be determined to produce this individual effect" is of no real weight. The determination to this individual effect comes either from the peculiar dispositions of the subject, the conditions and circumstances surrounding the operation, or from the will of God alone. This latter implies no predetermination imprinted on the second cause, for the determination of divine concursus is sufficient to account for it. The determination to an individual effect, if it is a special reality, must act either by impeding the power to other individual effects, which is incredible, or by adding something to the power which efficiently draws the second cause. Applied to free causes this would clearly destroy liberty. If one applies it to natural causes it is a matter of small importance, though it does seem to be an unnecessary multiplication of realities since the same effect can be achieved by limiting simultaneous concursus to this individual. 149 147 (Causae naturaliter agentes) ... ex vi suarum formarum sunt determinatae ad unum ... ergo non indigent nova forma aut novo impulsu quo determinentur (Ibid., n. 1) . us Pertinet enim ad generalem providentiam causae primae ut secundis indigentibus subveniat. . . . In eo casu licet non repugnet determinationem fieri per aliquid necessarius (Ibid., praevium superadditum causae . . . non tamen est hie n. 2). uo Negamus ... hanc determinationem fieri a causa prima per aliquam actionem praeviam circa' causam secundam, aut ei aliquam rem imprimendo ... quia sola determinatio divini concursus sufficit ad hanc determinationem . . . aliter igitur potest haec praedeterminatio excogitari per modum additionis et augmenti virtutis activae. . . . Necesse est quod talis determinatio tollat libertatem quoad specificationem. . . . De causis naturalibus si quis ita sentire voluerit parum nostra refert (Ibid., nn. 4-6) . BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 457 The nature of some second causes, as free, does not require predetermination either. 150 The usual argument for this predetermination is simple enough: A definite effect cannot proceed from an indifferent and undetermined cause. But the will, given everything necessary on the part of the object, the intellect, and the will's own power, is indifferent to this or that effect. Therefore, before it definitely elicits an act it must be determined by God. The determination cannot be from any other second cause, since none has efficiency over the will. If the objection is raised: " This proves that even God can do nothing unless He is first determined by another," the proponents of predetermination answer that God is so perfect He determines Himself without being determined by anything above Him, and that is something which is true only of God. If the created will determines itself in the same way it is not in that respect, subject to God. 151 Suarez' criticism is that this opinion supposes the indifference of the human will to be passive and negative rather than active and positive. It receives determination prior to its act and so does not determine itself, but is passive; likewise it is indifferent in the sense that it is capable of either determination but actually has neither, and so is negative. Suarez repeats that this position leads to a denial not only of free acts, but even of man's free faculty.m The Suarezian position is that a faculty, which is positively and actively indifferent, as the master of its act can, of its own intrinsic power, determine itself to its act. The proposition: " An indifferent power cannot of itself produce a determined effect," would be true of a power which is indifferent by reason of some imperfection in itself or of some defect in the conditions necessary for its act, but hardly of a power indifferent from its very perfection. 153 Ibid., cap. 8. '"'Ibid., nn. 1-2. '"" Supponunt qui ita argumentantur totam nostrae voluntatis indifl'erentiam passivam esse et non activam et negativam potius quam positivam . . . (In hac positione) indifl'erentia tantum passiva est ad recipiendum nimirum hanc vel illam determinationem. . . . Non erit indifierens positive per actum eminentem seu virtualem ... inde aperte sequitur voluntatem non esse liberam (Ibid., n. 4) . ua Potentiae quae de se est positive et active indifl'erens tanquam dominum sui 100 4 458 THOMAS U. MULLANEY Self-determination is not repugnant, for to be indifferent in first act and determined through second acts is not repugnant as is clear from the examples of God's will. One act does not necessarily involve the negation of the other as it is not repugnant for primary matter to indifferent in passive potency and to be actuated or determined through one formal act. Neither does it involve any infinite power, since this active power, the will, can be participated from a superior power and in dependence on it. God's infinitely perfect liberty is distinguished from ours in this: He is essentially free and no potentiality, composition, or imperfection is involved in the use of His freedom. 154 Arguing positively, Suarez says that determination of the will not only need not be, but cannot be, from any agent extrinsic to the will, or from any reality previous to the act of the will, for the determination of the will is formally and physically the very act of will. What else can it be? Certainly it is something intrinsic to a man. It cannot be in the intellect, for that faculty can move the will only. objectively. Surely it is not in the lower faculties. If the determination is anything at all, then, it must be in the will. Since it is there it can only be the act for it cannot be a habit or something in the order of first act, since the will of itself is sufficiently constituted in first act. There is no medium between first and second act, so the determination can be only second act. Again, a thing is voluntary only if it: a) is the voluntary act; or b) supposes a voluntary act. Now determination of the will does not suppose a prior voluntary act; if it is to be voluntary at all it must be the act of the will.m actus potens est sua intrinseca virtute cum generali concursu primae causae sese ad suum actum determinare (Ibid., n. 5) • . . illa propositio: Potentia indifferens non potest ex se producere determinatum effectum ..• esset vera in causa indifferente ex imperfectione virtutis, vel ex defectu conditionis requisitae ad agendum, non autem in causa indifferente ex perfecta et eminente virtute (Ibid., n. 6) . 1 "' Hujusmodi facult.Bs et modus agendi nee in sese involvit repugnantiam •.• quia unus actus non includit necessaria negationem alterius sicut materiam primam. • . . Nee est cur requirat infinitam perfectionem aut virtutem ... quia potest esse participata a SUJMlriori virtute (Ibid., n. 7)" . ... Voluntatem •.. determinari nihil aliud est quam velle; ergo non potest esse BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 459 Suarez explains that the will does not act because it is determined from outside (aliunde) but rather it wills because of this that it determines itself, but in such wise that the causal note indicates the formal not the efficient cause. In the line of efficient causality, for the will to be determined is the same thing as for it to effect its volition or nolition. In the line of formal cause, however, it remains determined because it continues to be affected by this act of will rather than by another. In this sense there is no repugnance in sa;}'-ing that the will is determined because it wills, although it is not determined except by willing, because there is here implied the formal cause, not the efficient. Most properly, however and without any equivocation the will is said to determine itself by willing, and to will by determining itself. From this it is clear how the will can be both indifferent and determined. It is not determined in first act, but can be formally determined by second act, and when it is determined in second act it cannot, as to that state be at the same time indifferent, though it retains its indifferent faculty .158 Physical predetermination destroys indifference both of specification and of exercise, and therefore is incompatible with liberty. Suarez considers first the freedom of specification.157 The use of liberty implies a two-fold power: 1) the power to omit the act while retaining the power to place it; and 2) the power to place the act while retaining the power to omit it. Now, then, if this predetermination is necessary for operation the will cannot move without that influx. So long, therefore, as ab extrinseco agente sine ipsa nee potest esse aliquid praevium ad ipsum velle, quod sit causa efficiens ejus. . . . Si ergo determinatio est aliquid oportet ut sit in ipsa voluntate . . . talis determiilatio nihil aliud esse potest praeter actum secundum; neque cogitari potest medium inter actum primum et secundum (Ibid., n. 9). 11 " Quo fit ut .•• non ideo voluntas velit quia aliunde est determinata sed potius ideo velit quia seipsam determinat 'ita tamen ut in ea caussli nota indicetur causa formalis, non efficiens • • • in hoc sensu non est repugnantia in ilia locutione: Yoluntas determinatur quia vult quamvis non determinetur nisi volendo ... sine ulla aequivocatione dicitur voluntas sese determinare volendo et velle, sese determinando (Ibid., n. 10) • 107 Ibid., cap. 9. 460 THOMAS U. MlJLLANEY God does not give the determination to the will, it is not in the power of the will to operate. The motion and determination are free with regard to God, but not with regard to man. Moral responsibility for not acting is thus impossible when man receives no determination, or when man is determined to volition the fact that he does not choose the object cannot be attributed to him. 158 Some escape this conclusion by arguing that without this determination the will can act, though it never shall. The answer of Suarez is that, on the supposition, the will is in fact insufficient to determine itself; therefore it cannot in any true sense act without this determining factor. If the determination is the ultimate complement of the will, the will's power without it is remote and physical, not proximate and moral, such as liberty requires. 159 Others try to defend determination by saying that it is in man's power to get this determination. Hence if he lacks it, the lack is imputable to him. Now if it is in power it is subject to his will; his will therefore can either do something to get it, or it can do nothing. If the latter, it is not in his power at all. If he can do something to get it how shall we account for the act done to get it? Either he needs predetermination to that act or he does not. If he does, we go tripping along ad infinitum, or else come at last to some determination which is altogether from outside a man, and how the act proceeding under it could be in the will's power is inconceivable. If a man does not need predetermination to the act by which he wins predetermination, then the will does not (simply speaking) require predetermination by reasons of its subordination to the first cause. To say the will does nothing positive but '"" Si determinatio ilia est . . . necessaria . . . ergo sine illo influxu non potest moveri voluntas . . . ergo nunquam ipsum velle est in potestate ejus nisi prius Deus . . . determinationem tribuat quod solum est in ejus potestate et arbitrio. Unde ipsi Deo Iibera esse poterit hominis motio et determinatio, non autem ipsi homini (Ibid., n. !!) . Interrogo an in eo casu sit illi voluntati moraliter tribuendum quod nihil voluerit. Certe id aflirmari non potest (Ibid., n. S) . 109 Si non habetur nee haberi potest omnis potestas quae voluntati attribuitur erit mere physica et remota non autem proxima et moralis quae ad usum liberum et culpam necessaria est (Ibid., n. 4). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 461 merely allows itself to be determined settles nothing. By allowing itself, it can be doing nothing, for to do anything it already needs (on the supposition) determination; or if the" allowing" is something the will must already be determined to it and that previous determination is in God's hands alone.160 In summary, if determination is in God's power alone the will is passive as regards it; and a passive power cannot be a free power. To introduce some kind of disposition and say that through its mediation the will has power over its determination does not help for two reasons: 1) we must account for that disposition; and 2) it is ridiculous to require a disposition in man for all the natural concursus of the first cause and for all acts of will, even trifling ones.161 Suarez shows, secondly, that physical determination militates against freedom of exercise/ 62 because determination implies a form impressed on the will which with the will completes the proximate principle of the voluntary act. It is: a) determimition because it not only inclines to one thing as to specification but also altogether determines the will to the exercise of the act (otherwise it is not real determination but only a modification, which, like charity, or any other habit, inclines us to one thing); b) physical determination because: i) it is a physical cause of the act which is physically in the will; ii) to distinguish it from moral determination, such as persuasion. Now such physical determination means the act cannot be free as to 100 Quomodo erit in potestate illius hominis habere illam determinationem a Deo . . . ? Aut enim aliquid. potest facere voluntas quo obtineat a Deo illam determinationem, vel nihil agere potest. Si nihil facere potest, ergo non est in potestate ejus habere illam. . . . Si autem aliquid potest libere facere, . . . si requiritur determinatio (ad illud volendum) vel proceditur in infinitum vel sistendum erit in aliqua determinatione quae omnino ab extrinseco veniat. . . . Si non requiritur ilia determinatio ad primum opus . . . concluditur voluntatem indifferentem et nondum determinatam ab e.xtrinseco agente posse se libere determinare • . . (et) illam determinationm non esse per se necessariam ad operandum (Ibid., nn. 6-7). 181 Voluntas autem dicitur concurrere passive ... potentia 'passiva non satis est ad liberam potestatem. Ridiculum est . . . ad actus omnes volendi etiam circa res minimas dispositionem ex parte hominis requirere, praeter ipsammet cooperaticnem liberam (Ibid., n. 8). '""Ibid., capp. 10-11. 462 THOMAS U. MULLANEY exercise (nor as to specification either, as a consequence) for the will is not free with respect to this determining reality. It is not free to receive it (for the will is passive as to receiving it) nor, having received it, to use it or not, for given it, the will can no longer not-operate. Always one part of the power required for indifference and liberty is impeded; hence, freedom is taken away. The common answers to this difficulty (that the will can not-operate in the divided sense, or that it is of itself indifferent even though with this determination it cannot not-operate, and such indifference is enough to preserve freedom) are inadequate. The first answer diverts consideration from the use of liberty, which is the question, to the free faculty. Even there, those who use this answer are mistaken, for in fact determination such as they suppose destroys even the freedom of the power. The second answer implies liberty is a passive power, which is simply to be denied/ 63 Suarez interprets the council of Trent 164 itself to teach that God does not predetermine us, for the Council says of God's motion that the will can cast it off (quippe qui illam alijicere potest) and again that the will can dissent from that motion (posse dissentire si velit) . The Council is certainly speaking of prevenient motion and in the composed sense, for no one can cast off what he does not have or which is not offered to him. According to the Council, then, it is required for liberty that in the composed sense the will under God's motion can not-act. 165 163 Determinatio physica dicitur esse forma quaedam voluntati impressa quae cum ilia complet principium proximum actus ... dicitur ... esse determinatio voluntatis ... quia omnino determinat illam ad exercitium actus (Ibid., cap. 10, n. 1). Ex tali determinatione sequitur actum non esse liberum quoad exercitium . . . neque ... quoad specificationem ... quia respectu illius determinationis voluntas nostra non est Iibera; nam ad i!Iam recipiendam . . . mere passive se habet; post receptam autem illam necessario prodit in opus ... semper ergo habet (voluntas) impeditam alteram partem illius potestatis ... et ita tollitur usus libertatis (Ibid., n. 2) . Prima enim responsio ab usu ad facultatem liberam divertit . . . Secunda ... solum ponit libertatem in passiva indifferentia quod est illam funditus destruere (Ibid., nn. 8-4). 16 ' Suarez quotes Trent, sess. 6, cap. 5 (Denz., n. 797) and can. 4 (Denz., n. 814). 161 Est certum Concilium loqui de motione Dei praeveniente nostram voluntatem BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 463 Some ·authors, faced with this argument, Suarez continues, concede that given God's motion the will can resist and notoperate, but infallibly it never uses this power, and this is sufficient, they say, for efficacious motion from God and also for safeguarding freedom in man. This is in open contradiction to their origi"nal propositions, such as" given God's motion the will can not not-operate," and " given motion it is necessary to operate," propositions which they confirm by appealing to St. Thomas' dictum: " If God moves the will to something it is impossible for the will not to act." 166 St. Thomas simply cannot be understood to be speaking of the previous motion in the place cited; he is speaking of God's cooperative motion which, as we have seen, includes the very act. Since that motion includes act, it is clearly impossible that under it there be no acts. 167 If God efficiently moves us, we cannot resist; 168 therefore, we are not free. Again, we can ask whether or not this predetermination is subject to man's will in its use. If it is, it is not determination but inclination to act, something in the order of first act which leaves the will indifferent. If its use is not ... certum est loqui Concilium in sensu composito ... quia nemo dicitur abjicere nisi id quod habet aut quod ei offertur ... juxta Concilii doctrinam ... etiam in sensu composito necesse est ut maneat in voluntate potestas resistendi (Ibid., n. 5). 166 Summa Theol., I-II, q. 10, a. 4, ad Sum. Suarez both here (Opus. Primum, loc. cit., n. 6) and in the Metaphysics (Disp. Meta., disp. 19, sect. 4, n. 1) quotes St. Thomas as saying this though the words he quotes as St. Thomas' differ slightly in the two places cited. The Leonine and Faucher editions of St. Thomas read: "Si Deus movet voluntatem ad aliquid incompossibile est huic positioni quod voluntas ad illud non movetur. Non tamen est impossible simpliciter. Unde non sequitur quod a Deo ex necessitate moveatur." The Piana edition reads: "Si Deus movet voluntatem ad aliquid impossibile est poni quod voluntas ad illud non moveatur." The Codex Vaticanus 733 reads similarly: "impossible eat hoc poni quod, etc." The Vienna edition of 1478 and several codices (Palatinus 858; Vaticanus 782; Vaticanus 786) read not " incompossibile " but " impossibile." However, every edition we have seen adds "non tamen est impossibile simpliciter." ••• Locutus est (S. Thomas) de motione cooperativa quae, facta compositione, includit actum ipsum. At praedicti auctores ilium interpretantur de hac motione praevia (Opus., Primum, loc. cit., n. 6). 168 Ibid., n. 7. Suarez cites Romans ix: "Voluntas ejus quis resistet?" and Esther xiii: " Non est qui possit tuae resistere voluntati." 464 THOMAS U. MULLANEY subject to the will, then second act flows by natural necessity; the will cannot not-operate. 169 Suppose that the created will by its very nature requires this determination, then creatures have no free acts, and moreover lack any free faculty. For the will without the extrinsic determination is not proximately apt to choose anything. Therefore the faculty does not by its nature demand the free use of operating (for it cannot of its very nature demand two repugnant conditions for operation) . Therefore it is not free, for free powers do demand free use. Moreover, the will can only be passively indifferent if it needs determination; and a passively indifferent thing (like the hand) is not free. 170 Suarez begins then to expose his own opinion on how God's concursus does, in fact, fall on our free acts, and in exposing how, without resorting to predetermination, our wills' subordination to God can sufficiently and exactly be preserved he gives, he says, the best possible argument against deterniination. 171 Now it is clear that whatever God operates He operates through His will, for God's omnipotence is an attribute rationally distinct from His will. His omnipotence operates nothing unless the intellect precedes as directing, and the will as applying. Now God can influence man's free act in two ways: I) by willing absolutely that such an act be placed by such a will at this time, and in this way. Such an act of will antecedes God's foreknowledge of the effect as future; it determines the will; God can will by an act which is conditional, not absolute, that this act be placed by the created will. The condition is "if the created will determines itself to eliciting this act"; God, under the same condition wills to concur in the act, expecting, so to speak, the influx of the created will, for 160 Si ergo primum (i.e. si illa determinatio subditur usui libero voluntatis) ... illam non esse determinationem ad opus . . . sed esse ad modum cujusdam habitus ... qui de se ad unum actum inclinat (Ibid., n. 8). Si ... eligatur ... hanc praemotionem esse inseparabilem ab actu secundo ex natura sua . . . dicendum est actum secundum naturali necessitate ab ilia manare (Ibid., n. 10). 170 Dicunt hanc determinationem esse necessariam ex intrinseca natura creatae voluntatis; ergo sine ilia non est voluntas apta proxime ad aliquid volendum . . . ergo neque ex natura sua est facultas Iibera (Ibid., n. 18). tn Ibid., cap. 14. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 465 God wishes to accommodate Himself to us in such a way as not to injure our free will. In virtue of this divine will, God's omnipotence remains applied (applicata) to flow into the act of the human will, without any new act on God's part. This latter mode is the one Suarez accepts. 112 His arguments for it are: 1) it involves no repugnance. We see from experience that the sun, for instance, concurs in a general way with each of the secondary causes which depend on it; 2) it is most apt. The power of the will is above that of all other natural agents, and is not bound to any one thing. It is necessary that God's concursus have the same eminent, universal, and abstract character. Determination, says Suarez, is too restrictive for the will. Any concursus other than this would be repugnant to man's freedom, for it would imply that man would be indifferent in first act and yet determined in first act, a clear contradiction since determination and non-indifference are the same thing. 173 Appealing to Scripture in support of this kind of premotion, Suarez sees in such passages as: " God left man in the hand of his own counsel," 174 an indication that after God's concursus there is yet room for man's deliberation, which would not be true if concursus determined man. Scripture, it is to be noted, is speaking of a proximate and moral power, and of God's indifferent concursus proposed and offered. Support of his position is common among Scholastics, Suarez thinks. St. Thomas does ... Ibid., nn. 4-6. Duobus modis posse intelligi divinam voluntatem velle influere in actum liberum humanae voluntatis: primus ... simpliciter et absolute volendo ut talis actus a tali voluntate fiat . . . et hunc modum hactenus impugnavimus. Alius . . . est Deum non ·absolute, sed quasi sub conditione velle ut hie actus fiat a voluntate creata ... et sub eadem conditione velle influere ... expectando ... influxum creatae voluntatis. . . . Ex vi autem hujus divinae voluntatis, ita manat applicata divina omnipotentia..ad influendum in actum humanae voluntatis, ut hac influente. . . . Deus etiam influat (Ibid., n. 5) . 173 Cum potestas liberae voluntatis sit veluti superior et eminentior caeteris naturalibus agentibus . . . necesse est ut hie concursus cum eadem eminentia, abstractione et universalitate (ut sic dicam) tribuatur (Ibid., n. 7). In hoc involvitur contradictio quod . . . eadem potentia . . . agat determinata et non determinata ... indifferens et determinata ab alio in actu primo, i.e. non indifferens nam haec duo idem sunt (Ibid., n. 8) . 1 " Ecclu. xv. Opw. Primum, loc. cit., n. 9. 466 THOMAS U. MULLANEY not expressly teach it, but on the other hand " he nowhere affirms that God of Himself and by His efficacious will alone determined to one act the concursus to be given the human will by determining the will to it." 175 The Angelic Doctor says without distinction that the knowledge of future things in their causes is conjectural. 176 Were he of the opinion that God efficaciously predeterinines our wills he would have held that God knows our future acts in the predetermination of His will. As it is, he derives the certitude of God's knowledge of such things from their presence to eternity. Again he teaches that God's general concursus does not consist in determining the will to one thing, but that God of Himself confers concursus which is indifferent and ordered to the general object of the will, namely good. "Without this universal motion man can will nothing," which clearly implies that God's motion as God's is indifferent; with this general concursus the will is determined through reason and liberty. 177 St. Thomas says explicitly that by grace God sometimes moves certain people, but he does not say that He ever, predetermines anyone. St. Thomas clearly teaches that God so moves our wills that He " does not determine them necessarily to one thing." 178 Suarez cites other places in St. Thomas, 179 but the three mentioned above contain his strongest points. 180 "" Divus ergo Thomas . . . nullibi affirmat Deum ex se et sola sua efficaci voluntate ad unum actum determinasse eum concursum quem erat exhibiturus voluntati humanae praedeterminando earn ad ilium (Ibid., n. 10). 178 Suarez cites Summa Theol., I, q. 14, a. 18; Actually St. Thomas says there that God knows contingent things as they are actual, i.e. He must know them in some other way than they are· in their secondary causes, as contingent. 111 I-II, q. 9, a. 6, ad Sum. The universal motion spoken of by St. Thomas is given to the will as a nature, to move it as a nature. To subsequent free motions man determines himself through reason as St. Thomas points out. The fact that the will needs a universal motion with regard to a universal object does not militate against the fact that the liberum arbitrium needs a determining motion for God provides for each thing according to its nature. 178 This is the very crux of the matter. God moves us, not violently; God determines us, without necessitating us. 17 °For example he appeals to Q. D. de Verit., q. 5, a. 5, ad lum; Q. D. de Pot., q. 8, a. 7, ad 18um; III Cont. Gent., c. 78, etc. 180 Opus. Primum, loc. cit., nn. 10-11. BASIS OF 'SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON· HUMAN FREEDOM 467 The objections against such concursus Suarez reduces to four capital difficulties: 181 1) It supposes that God applies His will and power to concurring with the creature in a confused, general way, which is imperfect; 2) it implies that God influences the created act in a blind, ignorant way unless He concurs before hand and so knows what the creature will do under concursus; 8) the creature determines God to operating this act rather than that, which is absurd for the higher determines the, lower and not vice versa; 4) God would cooperate as a natural agent according to the need of the second cause, and by a transient action which passes into the second cause, and all of that would indicate very imperfect causation. 182 The general answer to these objections is simple; God knows everything which second causes can do, with this or that concursus. Even more wonderfully, God foreknows not only what they can do but even what they would do if they were procreated with this particular help or occasion to do such or such a thing. This mediate knowledge is very properly attributed to God, as the Fathers and the Holy Scriptures testify. The fact that it is difficult for us to understand is no valid argument against it. Given this knowledge in God, then, His will destines things to their ends and selects for them means suitable to their natures. 183 From this Suarez proceeds to answer the objections in particular. To the first, there is no confusion in the way" in which God applies His will and power to concurring, for God foreseeing the results of His concursus offers His help for this individual act. This is not predetermination, for God, by a similar act, offers the will concursus sufficient for the other acts of which the will is capable. Nor is the effective act of giving 181 Ibid., cap. 15. Ibid., n. 1. (Divina cognitio) reprn.esentat quidquid per causas secundas, et voluntates creatas cum hoc vel illo auxilio et concursu fieri potest. . . . Sed quod mirabilius est non solum cognoscit Deus anteriore scientia . . . quid omnes voluntates possint facere sed etiam quid facient si cum hoc auxilio vel occasione ad hoc vel illud volendum procreentur. . . . Hac ergo supposita scientia in Deo accedit divina voluntas quae res singulares in suos fines destinat, et media eligit (Ibid., n. i). 181 181 468 THOMAS U. MULLANEY concursus absolute; an implicit condition is always included " if the will consents." 184 To the second objection he answers that God is not ignorant of the result of His concursus before giving it, for by mediate science He already knows the will's act. 185 To the third objection he notes the determination of the first cause can be understood in a two-fold way: a) the application by which God orders His omnipotence to helping the second cause, and concurring with it; b) the determined created action proceeding from the divine will and power, cooperating with the human will. The first of these is from the free determination of the Divine will; the human will is not its cause. However, some aspects of this determination can be accounted for by the objects or the human will, since by its very nature it demands this mode of operating. 186 The second, the determined action, receives its determination from the created cause; not that this creature is the sole effective cause of its determination, but in that cause is found the proper and proximate reason for the determination. It is the proximate cause which determines the action to this species, this time, etc. All this argues not to imperfection in God, but to very great perfection, since He has devised such a way of safeguarding created free causality. In the instant in which God, as first cause, actually influences, is understood to have previously (by a priority of nature) a determination by which His will is ready to concur in this or that act. His will is indifferent only by a universal and absolute indifference, and determined (conditionally) to co18 ' Deus enim distinctissime praevidens omnes hos actus ... distincte ac definitive vult ad hunc vel ilium, et sic de caeteris, praebere concursum seu offerre quantum in ipso est ... tamen quia Deus etiam praevidet quem actum ilia voluntas effectum sit . . . Deus . . . concursum offerat, ideo Deus determinate . . . vult cum ilia concurrere ad talem actum . . . nee ilium absolute velit sed cum dependentia ejusdem actus a proxima causa ... et includendo in se implicitam conditionem: Si ipsa consentire voluerit (Ibid., n. 3). 18 " lbi.d., n. 4. 186 Ex parte autem objecti vel humanae voluntatis reddi potest nonnulla ratio hujus determinationis nimirum quia ex natura sua postulat hunc operandi modum (Ibid., n. 5). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 469 operating with the created cause, so that if the latter acts, God necessarily acts by a necessity of supposition. Now the created will in the instant in question is altogether undetermined. There is absolutely no necessity about its infl.uxus; the act begins solely from its indifference of liberty, when and as its wills. For this reason, the determinateness is assigned to it as to its proximate root, though divine concursus is clearly necessary that liberty effectively cause the determinateness. According to causality, neither first nor second cause has any priority of nature, for neither acts on the other, but each acts on the effect; neither applies the other or causes it to do something by reason of this concursus. The first cause can be called prior in causiiJg, inasmuch as it gives and conserves the being of the second cause, effects the conditions or motions preceding the action, concurs in a more outstanding way, and so forth. 187 To the fourth objection Suarez teaches that God does act necessarily, but the absolute necessity that His power act is based on a supposition; viz., the previous determination of His will to act. To say God's action is transient is of no great importance; the cardinal point is that God causes that act immediately and hence the created action is an act of God, for action is a thing as it proceeds from its cause, or the dependence of an effect on the agent, and the created action has this respect to God. That God have transient action in His effects argues no imperfection in Him but places in creatures perfection presupposed in God. 188 181 Verissimum est actionem illam accipere determinationem suam a proxima cauoa sen voluntate humana . . . quod humana voluntas sit propria et proxima ratio illius determinationis. . . . Proxima vero causa . . . suo influxu determinat actionem ad hance speciem, ad hoc tempus, etc. (Ibid., n. 5). Deus ... solum est indifferens universali quadam et absoluta indifferentia; determinatus tamen quasi sub conditione ad cooperandum creaturae ... creata voluntas in illo priori naturae est omnino indeterminata et nullam habet necessitatem influendi . . . et ideo in earn tanquam in radicem proximam haec determinatio revocatur (Ibid., n. 6) . Si prioritas naturae sumatur proprie secundum causalitatem . . . neutra harum causarurn priusquam alia influit; quia neutra influit in aliam ... et neutra applicat aliam aut facit illam facere ex vi hujus concursus (Ibid., n. 7) . 18 ' Ibid., n. 8. 470 THOMAS U. MULLANEY There remains one really important difficulty. 189 From Suarez' thesis it seems to follow that God does not have a perfect providence with regard to our free acts, that He does not predefine them by an absolute and efficacious decree of His will before He sees that those acts should be placed by our will with His concursus. The objection seems very strong, for if one answers by saying that God does, by His absolute decree, predefine our acts, it follows then He efficacio1:1slymoves us to the defined acts and this seems to be the very same thing as the predetermination Suarez has argued against at such length. 190 Here then is a dilemma. The answer requires some preliminary discussion. By predefinition Suarez means " a certain eternal decree of the divine will by which it absolutely establishes that something be done in time." This decree " precedes foreknowledge of the future act " and by it God absolutely decrees the act, and therefore ordains the means through which it shall be brought about. 191 This predefinition is not contrary to our liberty. It is incredible and unworthy of God that God could not predefine our acts. To say that He cannot is to limit His power too greatly and to suppose that all free acts are outside His efficacious intention. We can distinguish a two-fold physical predefinition: internal, which God establishes in His own will, not that through it He immediately affects or predetermines the second cause, but only that in Himself He has a defined and absolute intention of some end and by reason of it He applies apt means so that the thing is infallibly brought about as it has been predefined. The second is external, which reaches out to the external effect with such efficiency that it physically determines the human will to its act. The first of these we shall simply call predefinition; the second predetermination. 192 190 Ibid., n. 1. Quoddam aetemum decretum divinae voluntatis quo absolute statuit ut aliquid fiat in tempore ... proprie dicit decretum antecedens praescientiam futuri actus, quo Deus absolute decrevit ut (homo) haberet ilium (actum) et ideo ordinavit media per quae fieret (Ibid., n. 2). 192 In hac divina praedefinitione . . . distinguere nos possumus quamdam esse praedifinitionem internam qqam Deus in sua voluntate statuit, non ut per earn 189 191 Ibid., cap. 16. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 471 This predefinition is reasonable, Suarez points out, since, supposing God's determination that such and such an effect take place, it is certainly to be brought about by God's power in that one way which infallibly insures the result. God will do neither more nor less than is necessary. Since a predetermination of the human will would take away the very freedom through which, on the supposition, God has determined that the effect should proceed, He does not give so efficacious a motion as that. Neither does He just preordain a series of causes with which He sees the decreed act will be placed by us. With regard to our good acts, He can also preordain the very act. This predefinition does not destroy freedom of exercise, as predetermination does. The latter is certainly unnecessary since a moral motion plus science by which God sees that, given these circumstances, the rational appetite will consent to this act is sufficient. God predetermines us by an act which is like an intention and of itself produces nothing external, since God's will operates through His omnipotence and not, immediately, of itself. Since it neither imperates nor uses the created will it brings no physical predetermination to bear on it. The fact that the means to the end are somehow contained in God's intention of the end argues nothing against the case; predefining the act through such a means does not predetermine but moves the will in a fitting and efficacious way, which God sees is so accommodated to this will that it will infallibly be attracted to consenting. 193 immutet causam secundam immediate, aut illam determinet . . . sed solum ut in sese definitam et absolutam intentionem habeat alicujus finis ••• aliam vero esse aut cogitare posse praedefinitionem . . . quae cum tali tantaque efficacia . . . exeat ut voluntatem humanam physice determinet. . . . Priorem vocabimus praefinitionem sen praedefinitionem; posteriorem vere, praedeterminationem (Ibid., nn. 5-6) . 198 Ex vi illius decreti solum (Deus) applicat suam potentiam ut illo modo efficiat . . . quia ad intentum finem obtinendum infallibiliter sufficiat. . . . Contingere potest ut . . . praedeterminatio physica repugnet cum illo decreto, ut in actibus liberis praefinitis contingit; et tum . . . ex tali praedefinitione . . . repugnaLit sequi; quia impediret libertatem, quae simul cum actu praedefinita erat. . . . Sufficit alia motio (i.e. alia a praernotione) moralis cum communi concursu adjuncta conditionata scientia. . . . Praedefinitio non imperat illi (voluntati humanae) nee utitur ilia (Ibid., nn. 8-9). 472 THOMAS U. MULLANEY The differences between such predefinition and Thomists' predetermination are many: 1) predefinition is also a will of this means which means move the free will contingently, though infallibly from God's foreknowledge; predetermination requires no means other than the efficacy of the very determination which, determining the will, overpowers it; 194 2) predefinition defines the act with regard to the mode in which the second cause operates, so that its object is the act as it is to be done by determination of the free will itself; the object of predetermination is not only the act but also its mode, i. e., the physical determination through God's efficacious motion; 3) predefinition abstractly considered (prescinding from the application of the accommodated means) is neither immediately active ad extra nor applicative of divine power (though the predefinition in reality is the same as the determining of the means, the mind can make the precision) ; while predetermination is of itself active; 4) by predefinition God's concursus is not changed, but the will so governed that it infallibly uses it; predetermination so changes concursus that the latter uses the will rather than the other way round. 195 That predefinition, on the other hand, leaves us free as to exercise is clear; it merely applies a means by which the will is infallibly attracte9, though it can still not-operate. Of course the human consent is certain from divine foreknowledge. The connection between predefinitioa_ and the execution of act is founded precisely in this divine foreknowledge plus providence, attracting by moral motion, and not in the physical efficacy of a decree determining the will to one thing. Suarez notes that: 1) predefinition is not, simply speaking, antecedent to the use of liberty; it supposes preknowledge of it as a future conditional thing and falls on that free consent as it is to be induced through 1 "' (Praedeterminatio) non requirit aliud medium quam suam effieaeitatem, qua st'cum rapit voluntatem, determinando illam (Ibid., n. 10). 10 " Praedefinitio abstracte concepta . . . non sit immediate aetiva ad extra nee applieativa potentiae divinae donee intelligatur determinata ad tale medium . . . praedeterminans voluntas per seipsam est aetiva vel applieativa potentiae divinae ad vim ... ex vi (praedeterminationis) necesse est variari eoneursum Dei talemque praestari ut ille potius voluntate utatur quam voluntas illo (Ibid., n. 10}. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 478 the means which, as God foresees, will infallibly bring it about; and 2) given it the will can, simply speaking, not-act. This power is not a power to resist God's will, for: a) God's will does not immediately move the human will; b) He sees the act to be placed in such a way that it can be impeded. What would be repugnant is not that God foreknow both that I shall do this and also my power not to do it, but that this be predefined and not take place. There is no potency for the latter. This repugnance, Suarez adds, comes not only from the causality and power of the supposition but from this that the foreknowledge supposes this future use of freedom, grantedthe conditions. The necessity, then, is only that when a thing is, it be.' 96 Predefinition leaves freedom of specification unharmed. Many of our acts are not predefined, yet we have ordinary the definition, concursus for them. The latter does not nor is it given through predefinition, because such definition is not required by reason of the subordination of second to first cause. 197 We consider now the various kinds of human acts; they can be either natural or supernatural. Nat ural acts, again, are either good or bad, a distinction which has no place with regard to supernatural actions since all evil voluntary actions can be placed by the natural power of the will. We shall now consider natural acts and evil acts, then good acts. 198 It is certain in the first place that God does predetermine the will, or in any way incline it to this formal element of sin. Suarez thinks it de fide, certain that God does not excite us, 196 Praedefinitio . . . applicat medium quo ita moveatur liberum arbitrium ut revera possit non operari . . . quamvis ex divina praescientia certus sit et infallibilis consensus liberi arbitrii ... in priori praedefinitione fundatur connexio (cum actu) et necessaria consecutio in divina praescientia, adjuncta providentia, morali modo attrahente ... praedefinitio haec non est simpliciter antecedens usum libertatis, quia supponit praescientia ejus ... sed supponens aliquo modo usum libertatis, cui sese accomodat (Ibid., nn. 11-18). 197 Esse plures actus humanos ad quos Deus, . . . concurrit, etsi eos non praedefiniat. . . . Concursus generalis non datur per hanc praedefinitionem neque ad ilium est necessaria (Ibid., n. 14). 198 Ibid., Liber II, Introductio. 5 474 THOMAS U. MULLANEY or move us by moral motion to morally bad acts. St. James implies this. 199 Again, the Council of Trent defined: "If anyone shall say that it is not in the power of man to make his ways evil, but that God operates evil works just as He does good works, not only permissively but also properly and per se; so that Judas' betrayal is no less His work than the calling of Paul, let him be anathema." 200 The Council speaks of " evil works " making no fine distinction between the work formally and materially regarded. It outlaws the opinion that God operates such things and does not say, for example," save in a material way." To argue that God causes sins materially but not formally is therefore unjustified. He would not only give His concursus, He would even determine it to this act; what more could be required for Him to be its cause? To say God is the cause of material sin and not of the formal sin is meaningless. If God so determines man to act in these circumstances it is impossible that the act be anything but a sin, as, for example, to determine Judas to betray Christ with his knowledge of, and attitude to, Christ, and his dispositions, would have been precisely to determine him to sin. 201 It is even true that God never moves our wills by this moral motion (exaltations, persuasions) to any act, even though it be indifferent or good in itself, with the positive intention that man take from it the occasion of doing evil, that is, of eliciting another act which man could elicit only evilly. While this is not so expressly of faith as the first proposition, it seems suffieiently certain that the contrary is erroneous. Such an intention is intrinsically evil and therefore is repugnant to the divine 199 "For God is not a tempter of evils and he tempteth no man" (James, i, IS). Cfr. Opus. Primum, Liber II, cap. nn. 5-6. 200 Sess. 6, cap. 6 (Denz., n. 816). 001 Neque hie (in verbis Concilii) locus relinquitur distinctioni de materiali et formali. . . . lmo cum posito materiali necessaria consequatur formale . . . nunquam hoc est in potestate Iibera voluntatis (Opus. Primum, loc. cit., n. (In suppositione praedeterminationis) Deus est directe et per se causa illius malae voluntatis . . . ex intentione sua praedeterminante influxum suum ad talem volitionem ... quid ergo amplius requiri potest ut vere ac proprie dicatur causa illius peccati (Ibid., n. 10). Quid enim est Deum esse causam materialis peccati et non formalis? (Ibid., n. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 475 goodness. Again, if God could directly intend an evil and He could immediately move us (morally) to it for that would be no worse than intending evil. Now we cannot conceive God in His goodness soliciting us to sin, therefore neither does He intend our sins. 202 God does not move us morally to sin; Suarez goes further and says that even predefinition to evil acts is repugnant. He argues from Scripture, for example, " Non Deus volens iniquitatem tu es." 20 z The Second Council of Orange declares: "Not only do we not believe that some are predestined to evil by the divine power but also, if there are those who wish to believe so great an evil, we, with all detestation, call them anathema." 204 Since predestination and predefinition differ only in name, the teaching of the Church is clear. 205 He also argues from reason: it is evident that God cannot intend eviJ.2°6 When Scripture seems to speak of God exciting men to particular sins it must be understood as either a negatibn of concursus or as an excitation to sins through a good operation which will be the occasion of ruin, which ruin God foresees and permits, though He does not intend it. 207 Even more certainly, Suarez concludes, predetermination to sin by God is impossible. What God can do in using evil wills is to have presented to them some object so that the will, of itself actually determined to evil, tends to this object. Even this, however, is regularly done, Suarez thinks, not by God immediately but through the devils whom God orders to apply certain objects rather than others. This, of course, is to order a lesser evil, for it limits the diabolic powers. Even as to sin which is punishment for a previous sin God gives only permission. The reason is that while punishment is good, evil cannot be done that good may come of it; God is not even a true cause of the hardening of sinners, certainly not through any positive Ibid., cap. 8, nn. 1-2. Psalm V. 20 ' III de Praedestinatione 202 203 (Denz. # 200) . Opus. Primum, loc. cit., cap. 4, nn. 1-3. 206 Ibid., nn. 9-12. ••• Ibid., cap. 5. 205 476 THOMAS U. MULLANEY action and direct intention of this effect. This hardening is sinful for it is an inhering in evil, a voluntary impenitence and resistance tlo God's call. Such things are attributable to God permissively only. He hardens hearts, blinds minds, and deserts men only insofar as He, as punishment for previous sins, does not give the grace by which these things could be avoided. The occasions by which such conditions are brought about God permits or causes not as they are occasions of evil, but as good things from which God foresees evil will result; Lut that event is due only to human malice. 208 Yet God has providence of evil acts in particular. This does not mean that God provides that sins be, in the sense that He decrees, intends, or procures them. Yet sins fall under divine providence, and providence is concerned about them in some way. God gives the necessary concursus, not that they be but that they can be, in order that freedom be safeguarded in all respects. Knowing from all eternity that they will be, God ordains them, providentially, to punishment or to some other effect. 209 Of our good acts, God is, simply speaking, the author. He not only concurs in them as he does in sins, He intends them per se; for their sake He gives to the will a very powerful propensity to that which is right and reasonable. To good acts, all laws and precepts, all rewards and punishments, are ordered. God directly and per se influences as to the good; He provides that such acts be, and procures their being placed. That God by an absolute decree, previous (in nature) to His foreknowledge of future things, predefines these good actions is not a matter of faith nor is it a theological conclusion. Theologians hold various opinions on the matter. . More probably, Suarez 208 Constat voluntatem hominis non praedeterminari physice ad actum malum a voluntate Dei efficaci (Ibid., cap. 8, n. 5) . Potius dicendum est Deum applicare voluntatem ad minus malum quam ad malum . . . atque hoc ipsum (ut ego existimo, regulariter non fit a Deo immediate sed per angelos ... malos (Ibid., n. 7). Deum obdurare . . . quia in poenam praecedentium delictorum nee dat gratiam qua cor emolliat, nee lumen (Ibid., nn. 9-10). 209 Verissimum est Deum habere providentiam malorum actuum in particulari. . . . Nam Deus providet auxilium seu concursum necessarium ad actum malum non quidem ut ille fiat sed ut fieri possit (Ibid., n. 10). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 477 thinks, some good acts are so defined and others are not, depending on God's good pleasure and the things He intends. 210 The question of the predefinition of indifferent human acts does not really arise, since divine providence is concerned with individual acts. No individual act is ever indifferent; it is good or bad-good from a good end and bad either from a bad end, or no end at all, for an act specifically indifferent, ordered to no end is by that fact sinful. God is, therefore, not its author; He neither predefines it nor excites to it. He can however, move us to indifferent acts for a good end, and we can place the act and never intend the end. In that case the act is from God, though its indifference or uselessness is not from Him. It does not seem repugnant to Suarez that God could move us to a specifically indifferent act through which He intends an end, yet not move us to will that end. In general, however, he thinks. it better to say that God moves us only to good acts; that any acts be indifferent He merely permits and influences through His ordinary concursus. 211 'Ve come now to the question of supernatural acts and the special help required for them. 212 It is clear that a gratuitous and supernatural aid for such acts is required. 213 This aid (actual grace) admits of many divisions; 214 for Suarez' purpose however, the most important is the distinction between that named sufficient and that named efficacious.215 Sufficient grace he describes as that which prescinds from any actual effecting and includes its negation. The efficacious 210 Horum (actuum bonorum) simpliciter auctor est Deus . . . propter illos dedit voluntati potissimam propensionem naturalem ad id quod honestum est ... an vero Deus praefiniat absoluto decreto praescientiam futurorum antecedenter ut hi actus boni . . . naturales fiant non est res ad fidem pertinens. . . . (Aliqui dicunt) quosdam praefiniri, quosdam non item. . . . Quem dicendi modum ut probabiliorem eligimus (Ibid., n. 11). u 1 Individuo nullus est actus indifferens. . . . Potest autem interdum Deus movere ad talem actum faciendum propter bonum finem et homo suo arbitrio eligere actum et omittere finem a Deo intentum (Ibid., n. 12) . 212 Ibid., Liber III. 213 Ibid., cap. "" Ibid., capp. 4-5. ou Ibid., cap. 6. 478 THOMAS U. MULLANEY is always sufficient; but a sufficient cause need not be efficient; e. g., if it is sufficient in one line of causality and the necessary cause in some other line is wanting. For us, sufficient aid is that which is enough (satis) for effecting (ad efjiciendum) a supernatural act, but yet does not produce it, not because the aid is insufficient, but because of the will's freedom. 216 That such sufficient grace is given to men is of faith. God Himself testifies that He has done all that was sufficient for the salvation and conversion of sinners. "What is there that I ought to do more to my vineyard, that I have not done to it?" 217 The Fathers and the Councils of the Church also witness to this. 218 Just what sufficient grace is, is disputed. Some say it is sufficient so that man can act, but not sufficient to this that man act. 219 This is rejected by Suarez who argues that with regard to a sufficient aid, two elements must be distinguished: I) what is formally given; the term or end of the aid given. What is formally given to man through sufficient grace is the power to act; but its end is the act. Sufficient grace is sufficient for the power (ad posse) if the formula is understood of the formal effect, not if understood as the term. Potency is not given for the sake of power, but for the sake of operation. Any sufficient grace is sufficient for operation. As man is commanded to do things and not merely to be able to do them, so the help given him is sufficient that he accomplish them (if he wills to) and not merely that he be able to do so. Any principle that is, simply speaking, sufficient must have all the power necessary for the act. If something more is needed where is the sufficiency? This is to be understood, of course, of aid which is approximately sufficient for acts. no Sufficiens gratia praescindit ab actuali effectione ejusque rtegationem includit . . . quidquid est efficax esse etiam sufficiens; potest vero e converso causa esse sufficiens et non efficax, i.e. actu efficiens . . . erit ergo auxilium sufficiens quod satis est ad efficiendum supematuralem actum ilium tamen non facit, non ex insufficientia auxilii sed ex libertate voluntatis (Ibid., n. 1) . 217 Isaias v, 4. us Council of Orange, can. 25 (Denz. nn. 198-200); Trent, sess. 6, c. 5 (Denz. n. 797) and c. IS (Denz. n. 805); cfr. Opus. Primum, Liber III, cap. 6, nn. 2-5. 110 Ibid., n. S. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 479 A man who does not actually have all the aids necessary as principles is yet said, sometimes, to have sufficient grace. This is meant in a remote and potential sense. That it be true even in that sense, however, a man must be able to do something to obtain that aid which is proximately necessary, by praying, for example. and doing all he can. God will not be deaf to such a man. A difficulty here arises in relation to infidels and Christians who have fallen into serious sin. They seem altogether unable to arise from their condition, so how have they sufficient grace for conversion, Suarez answers that as long as the infidel remains untouched by gratia excitans he does not actually have sufficient help, and his not placing supernatural acts is not imputable to him. In other ways, however, he can be said to have sufficient grace in universal causes (the preaching of the Church, Redemption of Christ) or because God illuminates everyone, even him who does nothing worthy of the illumination. As to the Christian sinner, he has sufficient help for he has God ready to aid him as often as his will, excited by faith, applies itself to his conversion. 2 " 0 It is clear, then, that the nature of sufficient grace does not demand that man actually receive it into himself as concursus. The latter is given only in the very operation; and it is not the very ratio 220 Quod formal iter datur per auxilium sufficiens est posse; terminus vero seu finis propter quem datur est velle seu perficere. Cum ergo dicitur auxilium su£ficiens dari ad posse ... si intelligatur quasi de formali effectu auxilii, verissimum est; ... si autem intelligatur de fine ... falsum est; nam potentia ... datur ... proter operari; imo non potest dare primum sine secundo (Ibid., n. 3). Est igitur de ratione auxilii sufficientis ut ad operandum sufficiens est . . . quodcumque auxilium detur, si ultra illud est necessarium aliud per modum principii alterum non poterit esse sufficicns simpliciter, sed ad summum in aliquo genere (Ibid., n. 4). . . . Contingit enim hominem non actu habere omnia haec auxilia necessaria ... et nihilominus dici habere auxilium sufficiens; sed illud intelligendum est remote et in potentia. . . . Ut vero hoc etiam sensu habcat homo auxilium sufficiens necesse est ut sit in potestate ejus aliquid facere ad obtinendum illud auxilium quod proxime sufficit (Ibid., n. 5). (Respcctu infidclis) quamdiu hie motus (auxilii excitantis) actu non fit in homine non habere hominem auxilium sufficiens in actu ... neque ... in potestate sua intrinseca ... fidelem peccatorem habere sufficiens auxilium adjuvans ... quia habet Deum paratum ad jumndum ilium quotipscumque liberum ejus arbitrium per fidem excitatum sese ad suam conversionem applicaverit (Ibid., n. 6) . 480 THOMAS U. MULLANEY of sufficient help that it actually operate. It is in man's power that sufficient help become concursus; for when man applies himself to operation, God enters in. 221 The existence of efficacious help is certain; " No one can come to me unless the Father Who sent me draw him." 222 What this efficacious aid is, is disputed. Heretics say it is a divine motion which necessitates the will, without which the will cannot act; they deny any merely sufficient aid. On the other extreme, some Catholics say divine aid is called efficacious from the effect; no grace is ex se efficacious, but all grace is called either efficacious or sufficient depending on whether man wills to cooperate or not. Since this opinion is difficult to reconcile with the words of Scripture and with those of St. Augustine, Suarez adopts the view that grace is called efficacious because it offers to the will most efficacious powers. Concursus cannot properly be called efficacious help for it is not so much efficacious as the very effecting; in it, sufficiency and efficacy cannot be distinguished, and it always has the very same conjunction with the effect. Only help which is a principle of operation admits a division into sufficient and efficacious. Suarez describes efficacious grace, then, as that principle of grace which has peculiar force and efficacy to induce the human will to consent. 223 Since efficacious aid is given in order that a man will one thing deterrninately, its efficacy seems to consist in a certain power to determine the will to this act. Some theologians teach that the efficacy consists in this power to determine, in a physical way, as we have seen earlier with regard to God's 221 Concluditur non esse quidem de ratione auxilii . . . sufficientis ut homo actu et in se recipiat . . . concursus, quia non est de ratione sufficientis principii ut actu operetur; illud autem auxilium non datur nisi in ipsa actuali operatione voluntate nostra applicante se ad opus statim ac Deus infiuit (Ibid., n. 7) . ••• John vi. ••• Nunc u.t probabilius et verius statuimus auxilium non dici efficax quia facit, sed etiam quia vires praebet efficacissimas voluntati ... hoc nomen . . . non proprie attribuatur illi auxilio quod est per modum concursus. . . . Solum ergo datur ilia divisio (sufficiens et efficax) de auxilio per modum principii. Est ergo auxilium efficax illud gratiae principium quod peculiarem vim et efficaciam habet ad inducendam humanam voluntatem, ut consentiat (Opus. Primum, Liber lll, cap. 6, n. 8). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 481 motion in the natural order. This is rejected by Suarez for two reasons: . a) it is opposed to the sufficiency of grace and hence also to liberty of specification; b) it is opposed to liberty of exercise. 224 It is opposed to the sufficiency of God's other help. Sufficient grace is truly sufficient if the will chooses to cooperate; hence physical determination is On the other hand, if physical determination is necessary for supernatural acts, it follows that the unconverted do not have a grace even sufficient for conversion. Even Protestants see this point and deny any sufficient grace; it is all efficacious for them. 225 To answer that sufficient grace gives ability to act (posse 'velle) but determination is necessary only to the actual operation is no answer. By the teaching of the defenders of physical determination the efficacious motion is the ultimate complement of the power in which it inheres; it is therefore necessary to it that it have the ability to act. Any aid short of determination is, then, not sufficient, for the principle of the act would remain incomplete. 226 Some of Suarez' opponents, he says, seeing the force of this argument, say that it is in the power of a man who has sufficient grace to have efficacious grace too, if he does not resist; man never lacks efficacious grace except by his own free sin. VVhile in itself it is true that whatever is necessary to man's salvation is somehow in his power, the principle can hardly be consistently enunciated by defenders of determination. This efficacious aid is said to be a supernatural entity which God causes in us without us, for it is not our vital act but a power previous to act. Since it is infused it does not ••• Ibid., capp. 8-9. ••• Auxilium quod dicitur sufficiens est vere et realiter ad hoc sufficiens si liberum arbitrium . . . cooperari velit. Si hujusmodi auxilium hoc sensu efficax ut physice . . . praedeterminans sit simpliciter necessarium, . . . sequitur eos, qui non convertuntur, non habere sufficiens auxilium ut convertantur (Ibid., cap. 8, n. 1). ••• ... dicti auctores docent auxilium hoc efficax esse ... veluti complementum ultimum virtutis ·necessariae ad agendum; ergo non solum est necessarium . . . ut voluntas velit, sed etiam ut velle possit . . . ergo . . . auxilium quod hoc non includit non potest dici sufficiens etiam ad posse (Ibid., n. 2). 482 THOMAS U. MULLANEY depend on us. It can be said to depend on our wills only by reason of some disposition in us, given which, God grants that aid, and only then. Yet that there be such a disposition Suarez thinks impossible. 2.27 The supposed disposition could be imagined to be either positive or negative; there are no further possibilities. Both are repugnant. The positive could only be a good act and indeed a supernatural one (since a natural act is not a sufficient disposition and especially not an ultimate and necessitating disposition to grace), yet it is unheard of that to contrition, say, or to the first will to believe, such an ultimate disposition is necessary Again, for this preparatory good and supernatural act divine determination is necessary, therefore another earlier disposition must have been in man to receive that predetermination and so ad infinitum If one wishes to defend predetermination one cannot maintain that free consent making it efficacious is in man's power, for the possibility of a negative disposition is advanced by practically no one. 228 Predetermining grace is opposed to the exercise of freedom. Suarez speaks of gratia excitans here, reasoning that if it is true that this grace, which more than other precedes our wills, does not predetermine us, it is certainly true of other graces. His argument from reason is simple Gratia excitans moves man to consent only by illuminating him (objectively) or by touching his affections through certain imperfect and indeliberate motions of fear, affection, or joy. Neither of these ways of moving the will is sufficient to determine it physically. There227 • • • hoc ipsum principium quod in hac responsione confitetur non potest cum ipsa sua assertione consistere . . . hoc auxilium efficax dicitur esse qualitas seu entitas quaedam supernaturalis quam Deus efficit in nobis sine nobis; ergo quod nobis infundatur talis qualitas non pendet a nobis . . . ut a cooperante illam entitatem (Ibid., n. 6). ••• Positiva dispositio esse tantum potest per actum . . . qui debet esse bonus (non naturalis) . . . hoc est inauditum scilicet, quod ad contritionem v. g. sit necessaria alia ultima dispositio; et multo minus verisimile erit id dicere de attritione, vel de prima voluntate credendi ... addo ... ad priorem actum ... necessarium esse divinam praedeterminationem . . . Praedetenninatio ergo ad ilium actum non erit in potestate hominis; alioquin . . . infinite proceditur (Ibid., nn. 7-8). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 483 fore gratia excitans does not predetermine us. The minor premise will bear some comment. The first part is clear: outside the beatific vision no particular object determines the will, especially not as to exercise of the act. Besides, an intellectual judgment can physically determine the will only by reason of a prior free act from which the determining act necessarily follows. By the second part of the minor premise (that the touching the appetitive part of man through imperfect motions of fear, joy, etc., does not determine the will physically) Suarez shows that these motions are imperfect, certain velleities only which cannot of their own force determine the will to give absolute consent. The will is never determined by one act to place another unless there is a necessary connection between them.229 The next appeal is to the Council of Trent which says that man can assent or dissent when God touches his heart through the illumination of the Holy Ghost; in other words, he is not determined by it. But the Council previously calls this same illumination gratia excitans. Therefore, gratia excitans does not determine us. 230 Note that the Council speaks in a general way of gratia excitans. To say the declaration means that exciting grace gives power to act, though with that grace alone such an act will never be placed, is unjustified, among other reasons because the Council is speaking of a true potency which often is reduced to act. Therefore, it speaks rather of act than of potency when it says man can if he wills to do so; it speaks of an excitation by which man is converted. Such a movement is always called efficacious. Some answer, "Well, the Council says man can resist. But even where the will is determined, it can resist though it does not, of course." To this Suarez replies that in the composed sense (that is, given ••• ... extra visionem beatificam nullum particulare objectum determinat voluntatem, praesertim quoad exercitium actus ... illi motus . . . in suo ordine sunt imperfecti ... ergo ex intrinseca illorum vi non potest voluntas physice determinari ad plenum et absolutum consensum praestandum (Ibid., cap. 9, n. 8) . 280 (Concilium) definit, tangente Deo cor hominis per Spiritus Sancti illuminationem, quod paulo antea excitantem gratiam vocaverat, posse hominem . . . dissentire (Ibid., n. 2). 484 THOMAS U. MULLANEY the determining grace), the will can not simultaneously dissent (on the supposition that grace determines) for what determines a thing does not leave it undetermined. If the opposition admits that in the composed sense the will can not-consent, well and good; all Suarez intends is that grace . of itself by its own power does not necessarily induce consent. But if one says: "man can dissent but never will," he is mistaken. Man not only does not do contradictory things, he can not do them. If, then, he necessarily consents by reason of this grace he cannot join dissent with that grace. The lesser cannot overcome nor impede the greater. But efficacious grace (on the hypothesis) is greater than the will since it necessarily induces its act. Therefore, the will does not and can not impede it. One might say: " As the Council declares, given grace one can dissent, but only in the divided sense, i. e., without that grace it could dissent." But the point is, Suarez rerefuses it) is plies, the Council says he who has the call the one who dissents, not he who lacks the divine call. It is, therefore, speaking ofthe composed, not of the divided, sense. Again, without the grace one does not dissent; rather one does not consent, i. e., there is a negation of any act, not the placing of a negative act. Liberty in this divided sense is common to all agents; to place human freedom in such liberty is to deny the specific reality of human liberty. 231 In order to operate supernaturally it is not required that gratia excitans bring even a moral predetermination, i. e., a certain vehement propensity which, leaving in the faculty a 881 ••• Concilium loquitur de vera ... potentia quae in actum saepe reducitur, ... imo potius de actu quain de potentia agendi loquitur . . . potentiam ad consentiendum determinatam posse dissentire (sensu composito) ... est aperta repugnantia et contradictio; nam forma physice determinare potentiam . . . nihil aliud est quam ex vi sua . . . necessario secum afferre seu conjunctum habere consensum . . . quod simul sit consensus et dissensus . . . est impossibile . . . homo non solum nunquam efficit contradictoria, sed nee facere potest. . . . Item vis inferior non solum nunquam vincit superiorem sed neque vincere potest ... sed ilia gratia efficax dicitur ... tam potens ut necessario inducat suum actum; ergo voluntas creata ... illam ... neque impedire potest ... non dicitur (a Concilio) dissentire qui caret vocatione, sed qui illam habet et respuit . . . plane facit sensum compositum (Ibid., nn. S-4) . BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 485 real power to resist, yet usually or even always leads to the effect. The reason this is not required Suarez thinks is clear; if it were necessary for the effect, then it alone is sufficient grace, and ordinary grace lacks something required to produce the effect. Hence those who do not believe all the articles of faith when they are called to faith are not sufficiently called, a proposition Catholics dare not concede. If moral determination is in any way required physically or morally then most men in sinning are not fully free or fully culpable; for most men are not so determined (since determination works its effect practically always). Since man needs no determination to act naturally neither does he need it to act This is not to deny the possibility of moral determination. When man acts with a very evident judgment that this act is expedient and its contrary unfitting he is so determined. Thf' devil can so vehemently induce men to evil acts that, morallj speaking, they cannot refrain from consent without God's grace; even more surely, then, God can predetermine us morally to good. Just what predetermination of this kind is, in each case, is hard to decide. There is a certain minimum divine call which is, simply speaking, necessary that man be converted if he minimum by communiwish it. God can give more than cating a greater light, exciting a more intense act or drawing the will more strongly in other ways. Yet the will sometimes remains equally indifferent and the effect equally contingent to both possibilities; sometimes, again, the man's conversion is more difficult, but often the will, because of the efficacy of the call, or the abundance of the grace, is rendered (as if in first act) more inclined to consent. Then we say the will is morally determined; it can be so determined more or less. 233 282 Necessaria non sit (praedeterminatio moralis) ad ... supernaturalem actum humanum . . . quia alias nulla gratia excitans quae non efficeret in homine hanc moralem determinationem esset in suo ordine auxilium sufficiens. . . . Voluntas moraliter praedeterminata ... aut nunquam ... aut vix et raro dissentit (Ibid., cap. 10, n. 1). 288 Ad actus malos potest daemon tam vehementer inducere hominem . . . ut nisi gratia Dei juvetur moraliter non possit sese continere quin consentiat; ergo multo magis potest Deus ... ita illuminare hominem et affectum ejus inclinare ut 486 THOMAS U. MULLANEY This determination admits even of a grade, Suarez thinks, in which the connection between grace and free consent is a moral infallibility which can, simply speaking, be said never to fail. God so comprehends the will that He can infallibly make it consent. Even the devil and other men can do this, so why not God? Yet the infallibility is not absolute, since liberty still remains and so it is not impossible that the effect be not produced. 234 What then is efficacious grace? Besides gratia excitans the will needs gratia adjuvans. The latter affects the act in a physical way more than gratia excitans does. This assisting grace is called cooperating insofar as, together with the will, it is a principle of eliciting the act; insofar as it precedes the act by priority of nature it is called prevenient grace; insofar as it is infused by God alone it is called operating grace. 235 Suarez' first point is that there is inhering in us no kind of assisting grace, operating or cooperating, i e., something which is neither a habit nor an act, though for the first supernatural acts which precede the habits he admits as probable a kind of fluid first act, though it does not determine us. 236 The opinion that there is in us a determining aid which is neither habit, nor act, he sees as without foundation in the Fathers, the Councils, or St. Thomas. 237 Neither the subordination of second cause to first, nor the indifference of the will requires extrinsic determoraliter eum ... determinat ... potest autem Deus uberiorem et majorem (vocationem) conferre ... quibus voluntas magis alliciatur (Ibid., nn . .5-6) . ••• . . . censeo posse perveniri in hac determinatione ad moralem infallibilitatem quae simpliciter dici possit nunquam deficere . . . quia Deus comprehendit capacitatem et inclinationem humanae voluntatis ... daemon sua tentatione potest ita hominem opprimere ut infallibiliter sequatur consensus nisi gratia Dei subveniat ... unus homo potest efficacissime ilium (alterum) pertrahere . . . quid ergo non poterit facere Deus? (Ibid., n. 7). ••• Ibid., cap. l!i!, n. 1. ••• Opinio quae ad eliciendos primos actus supernaturales qui non eliciuntur ab habitibus ponit aliquam gratiam adjuvantem et inhaerentem voluntati per modum actus primi 'fluentis probabilis est, dummodo talis actus . . . in auxilio sufficiente includatur et absque physica praedeterminatione ponatur (Ibid., n. !i!) . ••• Suarez cites Summa Theol. I-ll, q. 8, a. !i! as supporting the teaching "nullam esse gratiam per modum actus primi nisi habitum." Cf. Opus. Primum, loc. cit., n. 8. BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 487 mination; the Councils and the Fathers have never founded the necessity of grace on the indifference of the will, but rather on the weakness of fallen man, or on th,e deficiency of his powers. Granted, for example, a will informed by charity and granted the object sufficiently proposed, man has a sufficient principle of loving God, given concursus proportioned to the grace. Such expressions as: "God makes us will (Deus facit ut velirnus) ," "God operates the act of will in us (operatur in nobis velle) ," and others of like import Suarez interprets to mean that grace excites, morally rules, and directs our steps. Our cooperation and free consent are required for such works, though God is the principal cooperator. 238 His second point is that, even admitting this kind of grace, one can not hold that it physically predetermines the will prior to the second act of the will: the efficiency of grace cannot be found in any such characteristic as that. And why not? Because such determination would destroy the freedom through actual indifference; Suarez appeals here to reasons given earlier and adds that this predetermination to one thing is in a proximate cause inasmuch as this cause is constituted in first act. But necessity in acting is precisely determination to one thing in the cause, inasmuch as the cause is constituted in first act. Man, therefore, by such determination would be constituted a necessary and not as a free agent. The major premise is clear: the determination is something prior to second act, its cause, which constitutes the will as completely ready to act. It is, then, first act. The minor is evident from the very terms. 239 One cannot argue that, granted this determined entity 238 Ex subordinatione causae secundae ad primam non esse necessariam talem virtutem fluentem. . . . Haec omnia (locutiones Sacrae Scripturae) dicta sunt ratione gratiae excitantis et moraliter regentis; ... quatenus vero nostra cooperatio et liber consensus requiritur, tribuuntur Deo ut principali cooperatori (Ibid., nn. 4-5). ' 239 Dla deductio eodem modo in his actibus supernaturalibus facienda est, qua earn supra ... in communi fecimus de actibus liberis voluntatis ... praedeterminationem ad unum (si est) esse in causa proxima quatenus constituta in actu primo ad efficiendum; nihil autem est aliud necessitas in agendo nisi determinatio ad unum in causa, quatenus est in actu primo constituta; ergo per illam determinationem constituitur homo in ratione agentis necessarii et non liberi (Ibid., n. 6). 488 THOMAS U. MULLANEY in the will, the will is yet free, because of its greater power; this determination, on.the supposition, is superior to, and overcomes, the indeternpnateness of the will. God's infinite power can quasi-force the will but a created being, such as this grace is said to be cannot do so.240 Suarez argues that the Council of Trent was clearly opposed to this doctrine of determination; the answer that Trent speaks only of gratia excitans and not of assisting grace (gratia adjuvans) he rejects. He maintains that the Council felt and taught implicitly that: 1) the power to resist any motion prior to act is of the very nature of liberty; 2) no antecedent motion can so determine the free will as not to leave in it the power to resist the motion. The Council says: " Nor does man do nothing at all reC'eiving that inspiration; indeed, he can refuse it." Now the word "do" here means to do something which proceeds from one's own will and reason, i.e., freely. The will, then, in assenting to grace is not merely passively determined to one thing. The Council says: "The free will moved and excited by God," etc.; since " motion " is used broadly it comprehends any divine motion which precedes man's consent, even gratia adjuvans. Implicitly, then, the Council taught that any motion which does not destroy liberty leaves the power of resistance in the will, a power, Suarez adds, which premotion denies (in the composed sense, of course, and as the will is proximately disposed for act) .241 To Suarez it is clear that no supernatural aid given to man as a principle of consent to an act physically predetermines him to that consent. But what of concursus itself he asks. It is quite evident that it does not predetermine the will, either; for while concursus in itself can determine the will formally, it .. 0 Omitto vix posse intelligi qualis est ilia entitas quae inhaerens voluntati ita sit illi superior ... ut vincat et superet indifferentism ejus ... ut ipsum (objectum) non possit non efficaciter . . . determinare voluntatem . . . non ergo facile intelligitur quomodo possit earn quasi agere. . . . Deus enim propter infinitam vim activam ... habet hanc vim (Ibid., n. 8) . "" Ergo implicite docet (Concilium) hanc potestatem (resistendi) semper relinqui in omni motione antecedente, quae libertatem non tollit; ergo e contrario praemotio, quae hanc potestatem aufert impedit libertatem (Ibid., nn. 9-U). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 489 cannot do so without the will. This concursus is the voluntary act itself; it cannot be, therefore, unless the will is operating. Action surely does not predetermine the agent to acting, but formally constitutes him as acting in second act. 242 Even considering concursus in its root, i. e., in the divine will, Suarez continues, it is true that it does not predetermine the. will. Concursus so considered is conceived as an act of God ad intra, which supposes no preknowledge of man's cooperation, an act which proceeds from God's absolute and efficacious will by which He efficaciously determines the created will to consent to a determined supernatural act, not by impressing on the human will any reality prior to act, but only by drawing it. Suarez applies here what he has already said of the impossibility of such determination in the natural order. What was said there applies here; this position denies the reality of free acts. 243 He adds, however, the following considerations. If such an act of God's will is necessary in order that man can act then man can not act in a supernatural way when he does not so act. When he does not act he is not determined by God's will to act; therefore, power to act is It solves nothing to say that man has it in his power infallibly to receive this determination by negatively allowing himself to be moved by God. This negative disposition is a negation of something positive, i. e., of a voluntary act which is in the will's power, for as a free disposition, it supposes that its opposite is possible to the will. That act would be either good or bad. If bad, it would follow that when a man sufficiently excited (by gratia excitans) to make an act of faith, does not commit some other sin infallibly he will be determined by God "'" Auxilium igitur hoc prout in homine recipitur potest quidem formaliter determinare voluntatem, non tamen sine ilia; . . . nee determinare illam potest prout nunc loquimur ... quia auxilium non est nisi ipsamet actio voluntatis quae principalius a Deo est (Ibid., cap. 13, nn. 1-2). ••• Ibid., nn. 3-4. •u Aperte sequitur (ex hac opinione) non esse in potestate hominis supernaturaliter operari, quando actu non operatur. Probatur, quia cum homo non operatur non determinatur per voluntatem Dei praedeterminantem; ergo . . . neque est in potestate hominis facere (Ibid., n. 5). 6 490 THOMAS U. MULLANEY to believe. This conclusion is contrary to our faith, for one to whom the faith is sufficiently proposed can, in fact, will not to believe. If the act were good it follows that God would determine this man to believe for the precise reason that the man does not place a good act, which is ridiculous. Again, as any act of man's is because God premoves him, so the negative disposition is because God does not premove him. Thus the very negation is not free but necessary. In the third place it is absurd that the ultimate disposition to God's most efficacious supernatural help should be the lack of some natural act, even more absurd than supposing the disposition to be a positive, though only natural, act. 245 The truth, according to Suarez, is that God wills the acts of men's wills as conditional; i.e., He does influence on the condition that the human will cooperate. But what is efficacious grace if it is not physical predetermination? The word " efficacious " can be taken in three different ways, as naming: 1) any power or faculty of acting, especially one having some special energy, even though the power is not acting; in this sense, sufficient grace .is truly efficacious; 2) a power of acting as actually conjoined to its action; in this signification grace can .not be said to be efficacious without the consent and free determination of our will; 3) a grace which not only can effect and does effect, but is effective in such a way that it always infallibly has the actual effecting joined to it. 246 Efficacious grace in this third and proper sense does not formally include concursus; if it did it would in no wise differ from efficacious grace taken in the second sense of actual conjunction with the effect. Formally this aid is a principle of "' 5 Erit ergo alicujus actus .... Vel ergo ille actus est bonus vel malus: si bonus sequitur determinare Deum voluntatem . . . hominis . . . quia non operatur alium actum bonum, quod ridiculum est; si vero sit actus malus, ergo, quoties ille homo . . . sufficienter excitatur . . . non committit aliud peccatum infallibiliter determinabitur a Deo ut velit; consequens autem est falsum et contra doctrinam fidei (Ibid., nn. 6-8). ••• Tertio modo potest gratia appellari efficax non solum quia effectiva est, neque solum quia actu efficit; sed quia ita est effectiva ut semper habeat infallibiliter conjunctam actualem effectionem (Ibid., cap. 14, n. 4} . BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 491 operation, not an operation. Infallibly it brings on the act and consequently (not formally) it has the conjoined actual help which is concursus and even the cooperation of the will. As St. Augustine saw, it consists in a certain calling, which pertains to operative grace. Its efficacy, for St. Augustine, consists in two things: 1) that God gives it from the firm intention of converting or saving men, an efficacious election; 2) that God calls man at such a time and in such a way as is accommodated to the effect intended by God, viz., man's conversion. Hence, St. Augustine names this call " congruous." 241 In what does this congruity consist? Some have thought " it consists in a certain proportion which exists between such an illumination or inspiration effected in such a way by God in a man of such complexion, nature and condition; for God most accurately comprehending all these things in any man if his heart is touched in this way he is softened and consents." 248 While it is true that God's efficacious call sometimes consists in something specially accommodated to the man which God operates in the man (as the call of St. Paul), yet that is not required for a call to be efficacious; otherwise, those not called \vith this special call, would not have a sufficient call. Again, mere congruity is not sufficient for efficacy, for it induces of itself only moral certitude that the act will follow, whereas truly efficacious help must be so infallible that the non-position of the act is repugnant and contradictory. 249 ... In gratia efficaci non debeat formaliter includi auxilium illud quod est per modum concursus. . . . Igitur gratia efficax formaliter constituenda est in aliquo auxilio quod sit per modum principii ... et consequenter etiam habet conjunctum actuale auxilium quod est ... concursus (Ibid., n. 4). Consistit efficacia hujus ... gratiae (ex doctrina S. Augustini) in duobus. Primum est quod a Deo datur ex proposito ... convertendi vel salvandi hominem ... secundo necessarium est ... ut Deus tali tempore et modo hominem vocet qui sit ad efiectum . . • atque hinc Augustinus ... hanc vocationem congruam appellat (Ibid., nn. 6-7) . ••• Ibid., n. 7. ••• Licet verum sit saepe vocationem efficacem fieri hoc singulari modo . . tamen neque id requiri potest ut necessarium ad vocationis efficaciam . . . ; quia alias qui non ita vocaretur non haberet vocationem sufficientem neque etiam ilia congruitas satis est ad illam efficaciam (quae) tanta esse debet ut implicet contradictionem aliquando deficere (Ibid., n. 8). THOMAS U. MULLANEY The efficacy of God's call consists in this that "God, in His infinite wisdom seeing what each cause or will shall do in every event and occasion, if placed in it, also knows when and to which vocation each will shall give assent if it (the call) is given (to the will). Whence, when He wills to convert a man He wills also to call him at that time and in that way in which He knows he will consent, and such a vocation is called efficacious because although of itself it does not have an infallible effect, yet inasmuch as it is subject to such divine knowledge infallibly it shall have it" (the effect). The efficacious grace can be with or without the special congruity; its efficacy is moral, not physical, and is to be sought not in the vocation itself but rather as if proceeds from God and is under His direction. It implies not necessity (which regards the cause), but certitude and infallibility, which look to foreknowledge. The will shall never resist it, though it can, since foreknowledge does not remove the power of doing the opposite of what is foreknown. 260 Suarez' arguments from reason for the convenience of this doctrine, are: I) the efficacy of grace can be explained in no other convenient way; 2) this doctrine is most apt in conciliating freedom with grace. We have already seen that. He adds, however, that the efficacy ought to be proportioned to the causthe efficacy should be ality of the call, which is understood in a.moral sense, too. To liberty moral persuasion is by no means repugnant; nor is infallibility, since that quality is not from a cause but from the supposition of a future thing as a true and knowable object. Nor does this explanation of the efficacy of grace deny the ••• Efficaciam bujus vocationis in hoc consistere quod Deus, infinita sua sapientia, praevidens quid unaquaeque causa seu voluntas in omni eventu et occasione operatura sit, si in ea constituatur, etiam cognoscit quando et cui vocationi sit unaquaeque voluntas assensum praebitura si ei detur. Unde quando vult hominem convertere vult etiam ilium vocare illo tempore et modo quo novit ilium consensurum, et talis vocatio appellatur efficax quia licet ex se non habeat infallibilem effectum tamen ut subest tali scientiae divinae infallibiliter est illam habitura. Unde bane efficaciam ... neque esse spectandam in ipsa vocatione secundum se ... sed prout progreditur a Deo et est sub intentione ac scientia ... ejus (Ibid., n. 9). BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 498 sufficiency the grace in those who are not converted, for the non-conversion can come from their will alone. It is to be noted that efficacious and sufficient grace do not differ in this that the former has any reality, or motion, or quality which a non-efficacious call has not. 251 There is a difference on God's part in that He foresees the .effect in one and not in the other; but man has the power " to make God foresee that he will consent to the call"; so it is in his power to have an efficacious call. What determines that this man be called by God at a time when God foresees that the call will be respected? The will of God is the only answer. Nor can one say," But on this theory there might be some one whom God foresees will never cooperate with grace; such a man could never be called efficaciously by God." God's infinite power and wisdom can find a way to reach every one, by extraordinary means at least. If one insists that it could happen that man resist every call (though, morally speaking, it never happens), we must admit it; metaphysically or logically speaking there is no inconvenience in this proposition. 252 Divine omnipotence is safeguarded by this fact that God could efficaciously convert such a man by impeding the use of his freedom. 001 Neque etiam (repugnat libertati) infallibilitas quae oritur ex praescientia, quia ilia ut sic non est ex causa, seu ex suppositione antecedente, sed ex suppositione ipsius rei futurae in ratione objecti veri et cognoscibilis (Ibid., n. U). Gratia efficax praeveniens usum liberi arbitrii prout a nobis explicata est nullam rem, qualitatem aut motionem necessario requirit, quae non possit includere vocatio non efficax (Ibid., n. 14). ••• Ex parte autem Dei antecedit praescientia effectus in uno et non in alio; tamen haec ipsa differentia non est ex solo Deo sed etiam ex libero arbitrio; nam in potestate hominis . . . est facere ut Deus praesciverit ipsum consensurum vocationi ... atque ita est in potestate ejus habere efficacem vocationem (Ibid., n. 14). Cum infinita sit Dei potentia et sapientia, qua novit omnia auxilia et omnes modos quibus potest voluntatem hominis ad aliquid inclinare, impossible est quin aliquem praevidea'.t, quo tandem homo consenturus est si ei applicetur. . . . Quod si quis • . . contendat totam hanc impossibilitatem solum esse moralem, atque adeo non implicare contradictionem quod oppositum accidat . . . ideoque simpliciter admittendum esse posse ita accidere, metaphysice seu logice loquendo respondetur totum hoc verum esse ... inde nihil sequitur contra divinam omnipotentiam sed solum sequitur voluntatem vere ac proprie manere liberam . . . (Deus) posset illam (voluntatem creatam) convertere quo vellet, impediendo libertatis usum (Ibid., u. 16). 494 THOMAS U. MULLANEY Let us now summarize. The doctrine which maintains that efficacious grace is efficacious by reason of a reality which physically determines the created will to act denies, Suarez repeats, the sufficiency of grace in those who de facto are not converted. Such efficacious grace is necessary in order to act; therefore, if one does not receive it he lacks something which is altogether necessary in order to operate. It follows that God expects the impossible (since He fails to give some men the help necessary to meet His demands) and that either omission of these good acts is not imputable to men, or else that God blames men for not doing the impossible. 253 The answer " without efficacious grace man has grace which is sufficient, sufficient to be able to act, though not sufficient to act " Suarez refutes for 1) God orders us to do things, not to be able to do them; hence He ought to give grace sufficient not for " ability to do" but for the doing; 2) He wills not only that man can be saved but that he be actually saved, as St. Paul says; hence He gives men grace sufficient actually to save them; 8) the Thomists' idea of sufficient grace is not even sufficient for "power to act"; it leaves the faculty not proximately expedited for act but only remotely and physically empowered. The distinction is, moreover, without basis in any of the Fathers or older theologianS. 254 To answer, on the other hand," It is in a man's own power to have efficacious grace such as we describe, and if a man does not have it, it is his own fault," simply opens up further difficulties. The grace can be in man's power only by reason of some prior act or disposition. What of that act or disposition? It cannot be natural; that is Pelagianism. Suppose, then, it is supernatural; is efficacious grace needed to have it? If it is we ••• Doctrinam hanc (de efficacia praedeterminante) prout in illa sententia explicata est non posse in concordiam redigi cum hoc principio . . . dari hominibus qui nolunt ... auxilium sufficiens ... ad agendum. Itemque sequitur Deum praecipere homini impossibilia {Opua. Tertium, nn. 15-17). ••• Deus non praecipit homini ut possit operari sed ut operetur. . . . Deus non tantum vult ut homo possit salvari sed ut salvus fiat ... ergo ad hoc dat auxilium sufficiens . . . qui nee habet nee habere potest quae necessaria sunt ad operandum non solum non habet auxilium ut faciat sed nee etiam ut possit moraliter et proxime loquendo (Ibid., n. !U) • BASIS OF SUAREZIAN TEACHING ON HUMAN FREEDOM 495 can go on to infinity; if it is not, then why is such determining grace needed for any other act? 255 Secondly, predetermining grace is opposed to liberty. Under such grace the non-position of the act is impossible; the placing of the act then is not free since, as Trent says, the use of freedom requires the power of dissenting from the divine motion. And the words are meant in the composed sense, since one cannot throw off something he does not have. Moreover, the will is merely passive in receiving the motion, and the passive is not free. Yet this does not imply that God cannot predefine our supernatural acts and induce the will in a moral way. The will by the mere fact of being subordinated to the First Cause does not need grace. Even for the Fathers the necessity of grace arises from other fonts, e. g., the repugnance of the appetite, the deficiency of our powers, and their lack of proportion to the true end of man and the means to it. 256 From predetermination follows the absurd conclusion that God premoves and predetermines the will to evil, for the will is quite as indifferent to evil acts as to good, and just as subordinated to the First Cause in effecting evil as in effecting good. Thomists, according to Suarez, should conclude that God efficaciously determines and moves us to evil, that without this determination one cannot consent to evil, but given it one can not not-consent. If God's efficacious motion to good depends as to its distribution on God's will, so does His motion to bad objects. 257 255 Naturaiis esse non potest . . . si autem est supernaturalis interrogo an ad ilium sit necessarium auxiiium efficax praedeterminans necne; nam si necessarium est ... ad alteram dispositionem procedendum erit ... etiamsi in infinitum procedatur . . . si . . . non est necessarium . . . idem dicendum erit de quoiibet alio actu (Ibid.) 256 Dicitur ... voiuntatemque nostram ... ab eo (auxiiio) ita determinari ad unum actum, et ad exercitium illius ... ut impossibile sit voluntatem ... non operari ac consentire; ex quo manifeste fit ilium consensum non esse liberum (Ibid., n. 25). Nunquam reperitur in sanctis Patribus quod fundent necessitatem gratiae ... neque in sola subordinatione causae secundae ad primam (Ibid., n. 29). 257 Videtur ... sequi Deum esse auctorem mali actus vere ac proprie non permitten do soium sed etiam praemovendo ... quia voluntas ex se tam est indifferens ad maios actus efficiendos sicut ad bonos, et in eorum effectione tam subordinate primae causae ... ex duobus hominibus hunc facit (Deus) consentire (in actum malum), ilium dissentire, soium quia vult (Ibid., n. 24). 496 THOMAS U. MULLANEY To say to all this, " Yes, God moves us to evil, but to evil materially taken, not formally," is not acceptable to Suarez. The two elements are inseparable; the intention of the agent tends to this human act from which the deformity of the act cannot be separated, and God's will must bear on such an act absolutely (on the supposition), and not merely conditionally. Those who argue from Our Lord's words: "No one can come to me unless the Father draws him," to physical determination should conclude that Judas could not have betrayed Christ unless the Father had drawn him to will it. If this and similar passages mean that our wills can do nothing without God's general motion, then nothing can be drawn from them about the excellence of supernatural acts and grace itsel£.258 On the conciliation of this notion of grace with God's efficacy, Suarez first lays down certain propositions; then he shows their conformity with man's freedom. The propositions are: 1) Man by the unaided power of his free.will and without the assistance of divine grace can work no supernatural good, no pious deed conducive to attaining eternal life, nor can man even keep the natural law over a long period of time without grace. 2) Grace not only assists man, but excites him; it precedes man's operation and excites him to act well. This beginning of our salvation is worked in us, without any merit of ours and without our free cooperation, or any disposition. This " calling " is gratia operana, through which Go