THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORs: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PROVINCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington 17, D. C, VoL. XIII APRIL, 1950 No.2 MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 1 The philosopher and the poet are alike in this: both have to do with the wonderful. -St. Thomas, In I Metaph, 3, 55. ILOSOPHY must be queen or slave; she is queen over science when she is handmaid to faith, but when she has the audacity to pose as mistress to faith, she must become slave to science; this is the thesis of Max Scheler in his essay On the Nature of Philosophy. Philosophy lifts the spirit to touch the realm of being; it attempts to pierce the veil that hides the deepest in things, and leads to a loving participation in their essence by the way of knowledge. Philosophy is knowing and the philosopher a knower, Scheler writes, but to say, 1 This essay is a chapter of a book on certain aspects of the philosophical and :religious thought of some contemporary philosophers of Jewish origin, which will be published by Devin-Adair under the title of "Walls Are Crumbling." 135 186 JOHN M. OESTERREICHER as is the vogue, that its dealings are merely with the knowledge of things and that their essence is none of its concern, rests on no intellectual ground. It is pride, he asserts, which makes a philosopher maintain that philosophy can never lead into the precmcts of essence, for he fears that there he would have to recognize that the nature of the Prime Being may demand another, and a more adequate, way of participation than knowledge. Indeed, it might happen that the strict consequence of his philosophical thinking enjoins upon him a free subordination to this higher way; he may even be bidden to bring himself, with his inquiring reason, a willing sacrifice to this fuller but non-philosophical sharing which the Prime Being, by its very nature, might claim. Only pride can say that, no matter what this nature may prove to be, it will refuse this sacrifice; only prejudice can assert that all being has the character but of an object, and that knowledge alone can partake of it. 2 True, for Aristotle God was the " Thought of Thought," and the philosopher therefore the perfect man, his path the highest of human existence. But Christ came, and no longer could God, the Prime Being, be seen as a mere object of thought, for He acts, He loves, His Being is creative and merciful goodness. Hence acting with Him, loving 'with Him, became the gate to participation in the Prime Being, and philosophy, loyal to logic, rejoiced to minister to faith in Christ, in whom this participation was perfect, was union. The sage had· to move to second place, below the saint, and the philosopher to subject himself to the lover of God. Over and above its ancient dignity as queen of science, philosophy gained a dignity far more excellent, that of willing handmaid to the Saviour, a blessed handmaid, for " blessed are the poor in spirit." 3 But today philosophy is no longer seated thus between faith and science, Having broken this true relationship, it has set •" Vom Wesen der Philosophie und der moralischen Bedingung des philosophischen im Menschen (8rd ed.; Berlin; Der Neue Geist Verlag, Erkennens," Vom 1988)' pp. 66-79. • Ibid., p. 74-77; Matt. V, 8. MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 137 itself above religious truth only to bow low before scientific hypotheses. This reversal, an instance of a general overturn of values, Scheler calls the "revolt of the slaves in the intellectual realm." It seems a paradox that when philosophy limited itself it was unlimited; now that it admits no confines, it has no territory of its own. When it was preamble to faith, it knew it could penetrate to the roots of being, but now that it is subservient to one or the other science-geometry, physics, psychology-there is nothing it is sure of seeing. This is as it must be, says Scheler, for truth is such that it' falls prey to the darkness within man unless it humbles itself before the Primal Light. 4 In philosophy Plato saw moving the wings of the soul, Scheler recalls, the soaring upward of the whole of the human person. To the great philosophers of antiquity, philosophy was a lifting of the spirit, implying a moral approach: the conquest of merely practical-that is, ultimately, selfish-attention to the world. Scheler's view is close to this when he says that it is always our willing and doing which underlie our mistaken values; that it is always, somehow, wrong practice which drags down our consciousness of values and their ranks to its own leveL We must learn to will and to do what is good, more or less blindly, before we can see the good and will and do it with insight. 5 It is characteristic of man's natural view that he takes his little world for all the world, his immediate milieu for the universe. This milieu may be the particular surroundings an individual, of his race, of his people, or the general surroundings of natural man as part of his species. That his mind may rise above them and participate in being as it is in itself, says Scheler, the philosopher must relinquish, in principle, all that is merely relative to life or to himself as a living creature. Only by forsaking his milieu, the tangibles and intangibles of day, can he :reach philosophy's true domaino Scheler insists that there can be no philosophical knowledge without love, • Ibid., pp. 78-79. " Ibid., pp. 66, 88-89. 138 JOHN M. OESTERREICHER humility, and self-mastery. The love of the whole spiritual person for the Absolute Value, the. Absolute Being, breaks through the shell of his surroundings. The humiliation of his natural ego leads man from accidentals to the whatness of the world. His mastery of the many impulses that go hand-in-hand with his sense-perception looses the fetters of his concupiscence and leads him from mere opinion towards an adequate knowledge: 6 Scheler's insistence that the purity, measure, strength, and growth of our philosophical knowledge are tied to virtue, that the theoretical and moral worlds are essentially and eternally knit together/ continues the line of Christian philosophy. St. Thomas indicts pride as a hindrance to knowledge, for the man who delights in his own excellence soon tires of the excellence of truth. 8 And St. Augustine, though speaking of religious knowledge, says that those who do not seek truth with all their hearts can not find it, but that from its lovers it can not hide. They must heed: " Ask and it shall be given you, seek and you shall find, knock and it shall be opened to you," and: "Nothing is covered that shall not be revealed"; in all this quest, it is love that asks, love that seeks, love that knocks, love that unveils the eyes, and love it is that gives perseverance in the truth. 9 Again he says: "Let love be in you, and the fullness of knowledge must follow." 10 I Much of Scheler's work shows the love for the Absolute and the humility before the objective world which he demands. His was an unusual mind, to which all things spoke; so awake was it that every and any circumstance served and stimulated his thought. He was a philosopher not only in the study or the classroom but at all times; every remark of his, whether in the • Ibid., pp. 102-108. "Ibid., pp. 99, 108. 8 Summa Theol., II-II, q. 162, a. 3 ad l. 9 De Mor. Eccl. Cath. XVII, 31 (PL 82: 1824). Cf. Matt. vii, 7; x, 26. ' 0 In Ps. LXXIX, 2 (PL 36 : 1022). MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 189 coffee shop or at a ball, in the theater or on the street, bore a philosophical note, betraying a genius that went directly to the uniqueness of every situation and lifted out its general significance. 11 Socrates called himself a" gadfly" and a" midwife"; Scheler, to describe his way of thinking and of presenting his thought, called himself a puppeteer. He had his philosophical equipment -the world and his· with him, as a strolling player his cabinet. The vagrant mummer needs no preparation, no atmosphere, none of the appurtenances of the big theater, nor did Scheler require any special setting; given an ear, he became creative and set his ideas dancing. He might be seated with a companion, his head canted to the side, watching on the unfolded stage of his spirit the drama of the world. He looked aslant at his puppets' play, which was his own, and always with half an eye for the listener--or better, the spectator. And again and again, by an interjected Wie? or Nicht wahr? he assured himself of his companion's attention and of the effect of his play. It was truly magic; in an instant he could transform his surroundings and fill the room with his ideas; he made present the things of which he spoke and visible what is often called "abstract." What he evoked fr9m the realm of spirit came, and now and then there gleamed in his eye an unchastened joy that he was so obeyed. 12 However, what made Scheler so powerful also made him vulnerable; his genius was his weakness. His spoken word had strength and freshness,. the dew of the spirit was on it, but his written style was often clumsy and overladen, so that he said of himself: "I have the word, but not the sentence." 13 He was indeed lavishly gifted; ideas came to him without labor, flaming in his mind like lightning, and it was this immense fecundity that persuaded him to neglect, even to disdain, intellectual toil. He would not spend the effort to verify his sources, to sift and 11 Dietrich von Hildebrand, " Max Scheler als Persoenlichkeit," Zeitliches im Lichte des Ewigen (Regensburg: Josef Habbel, 1932), pp. 368-369. 12 Ernst Kamnitzer, Erinnerung an Max Scheler (unpublished memoir). 18 Ibid. 140 JOHN M. OESTERREICHER weigh his thoughts, to examine and test them oil every side, but rather moved on to new problems. For instance, some of his intuitions on love were profound, but his presentation is never complete, never rounded, giving always only one aspect, almost to the exclusion of others. He showed little care for his sources; quoting, for example, the words of St. Paul: " Beggars enriching many, paupers possessing all things," 14 he attributes them to St. Francis of Assisi.15 He had also little concern for the consistency of his own thought. In his Formalism in Ethics he says: " Knowingly to will evil as evil is entirely possible," and adds that he does not " subscribe to the saying of Thomas Aquinas, ' We will all things under an aspect of good ' (Omnia volumus sub specie boni) ." 16 (The pairing of these two sentences ·suggests that Scheler did not fully understand this principle; indeed, not a few of his objections to St. Thomas are based on misunderstanding.) Some years later, however,_ in an essay On the Task of German Catholics after the War he said, and without accounting for his change of mind: " Evil is but a consequence of a free act of the will performed sub specie boni." 17 Here is another example of his inaccuracy. In Sympathy, its Essence and Forms he writes: " St. Francis was a swom enemy of Scholasticism and its doctrine of the aristocratic-hierarchic . order of being." 18 Nearly every word in this sentence is wrong. St. Francis' awe for wisdom found expression in his child-like reverence for the written word. Whenever on the road he found a scrap of writing, he picked it from the dust and preserved it with care. Once when he was told, partly in jest, that a paper he had thus saved wasfrom a pagan author, he replied that it "2 Cor. vi, 10. 15 Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik (2nd ed.; Halle a. d. 8.: Max Niemeyer, 1921), p. 278. 18 Ibid., p. 608. 17 " Soziologische-Neuorientierung und die Aufgabe der deutschen Katholishen nach dem Krieg," Schriften zur Soziologie und W eltanschauungalehre,III/I (Leipzig: Der Neue Geist Verlag, 1924), p. 204. 18 W eaen und Formen der Sympathie (2nd ed.; Bonn: Friedrich Cohen, 1928), p. 106. MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 141 mattered not, for all words, of pagans or of others, stemmed from God's wisdom and spoke of God, from whom are all good things" It was his very love of wisdom that made St. Francis abhor learning for its own sake and the universities of his time as seats of haughtiness and error. 19 This hostility to learning as a ware Scheler distorts into enmity to Scholasticism, to which alone he ascribes a doctrine held in the Church long before Scholasticism was born. Moreover, the context of Scheler's remark seems to indicate that he had in mind Aristotelean thought, which, at the time of St" Francis, had not become part of Scholastic philosophy" Many a page and many a thought of Scheler are marred by such deficiencies. His want of discipline is all the more startling in its contrast with the virtues he knew necessary for the philosophical act. This discrepancy was rooted in an inner disharmony, a discord not to be understood save through the reverence every soul merits" He saw, and saw again, and saw anew, where others passed blindly; inundated with impressions, he was always tempted to trust them too far, to surrender to them, and it was often their novelty that appealed to him, who in a way stayed always a child. His relationship with the world remained too much one of wonder; it was essentially knowing, learning it. But infinitely more is asked of us-to rest and persevere in the known, to be permeated by truth and given to it lovingly, to mortify ourselves for its sake, to conform our wills and adjust our lives to the light we see. All this was difficult fo:r Scheler, for in his early youth he had been indescribably spoiled; he had, as he said himself, never learned to wilL Dietrich von Hildebrand, long a friend of Scheler, applies to him Lessing's word, so telling of modern unrest: If God were to offer him eternal and absolute Truth in one hand, or the everlasting desire for it in the other, he would grasp desire and say, Truth is for Thee alone. Scheler's philosophy at its best totally disavows this choice, and yet, deplorably, it .does corre10 Father Cuthbert, 0. S. F. C., Life of St. Francis of Assisi (London: Green and Co., pp. 154. Longmans, 142 JOHN M. OESTERREICHER spond to a trait of his character, a deep restlessness which darkened his life.20 Max Scheler was born in Munich on August 22, 1874, the son of a Jewish mother and a Gentile father, who, for the sake of marriage, had adopted Judaism. Thus Scheler was born a Jew, but he grew up with no religious formation. His first acquaintance with the spiritual world was through the Catholic maids who served in his home, but it was not until, at the Gymnasium, he met the priest who taught religion, that it gripped his interest. In him he met a world different from the pagan which surrounded him, the world of the Absolute. 1n his priestly character, his dedication to God, Scheler must have glimpsed, as through an opening door, the world of grace and divined the phenomenon of holiness, of which in later years he was to speak so strongly. And he must also ·have sensed the motherly arms of the Church, her peace, to which he turned at the age of about fourteen. After completing his work in the Humanities at the Gymnasium, he studied in Berlin, where Dilthey, Stumpf, and Simmel set the intellectual tone; from there he went to Heidelberg and later to Jena to study under Eucken, and stayed on as a University lecturer. In 1907 he returned to Munich to teach at the University, where the most significant period of his life was to begin. His constant intellectual communion with the "Munich School "-the followers of Lipps who had attached themselves to Husserl-and later in Goettingen with Husser! himself inspired him to truly productive work and encouraged him, by temperament a teacher, to write and to make his great and specific contribution to the history of thought. From the time he left the Gymnasium until· his transfer to the University of Munich, Scheler's life had been under a dark shadow, which seems never to have been entirely lifted from him. He entered a civil marriage with a ·woman, divorced and much older than he, who tried, first to dominate, then to ruin him. But back in Munich he freed himself from this bond, •o Von Hildebrand, "Max Schelers Stellung zur katholischen Gedankenwelt," op. cit., p. 86i. MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 148 which brought him pain and unhappiness from the first moment. A few years later he was to say: The more guilt grows, the more is it hidden from the guilty; but the more humility increases, the more visible becomes even the smallest trespass. 21 This had been his own experience. Having broken the chain of sin, his remorse grew; stronger became his sorrow for having forfeited the life of grace and greater his longing to regain the mercy. of God. In these years, he often visited the Benedictine Abbey in Beuron, which he had known while he was still at Jena, to breathe its peace, and it was there, in 1916, that Scheler returned to the faith of his boyhood. "I have made my confession; I have come back to the bosom of the Church," he rejoiced. "I am infinitely happy, and I know I owe this to the Blessed Virgin.'' Maerit Furtwaengler, whom he had married a few years before and whose love had borne him, followed him into the Church. Though his dl;!sire to be a full member of the Church was at that time genuine, nonetheless he was never more than an enthusiastic and admiring onlooker, to whom the sacramental order, for instance, was an object of the greatest philosophical intere&t, but nothing he could live for long. With his heart remaining restless and divided, he embodied the ill of modern man. And yet it was Scheleranother sign of the contradiction he was-who was the relentless critic of modern man, who " groaning, walks beneath a burden of his own manufacture, his mechanisms; his limbs heavy and only the earth before his eyes, he has forgotten his God and his world.'' 22 Unsparingly Scheler castigates him who, having lost the great confidence in being which is part of his wholeness, is by creed a skeptic, meeting the world with a priori distrust. He is without boldness and generosity, he makes achievement and usefulness the measure of persons and things and never ending activity disguises the void of his soul, he replaces love of creation and joy in its riches with anxiety to defeat it as his "Reue und Wiedergeburt," Vom Ewigen im Menschen, p. 40. "Versuche einer Philosophie des Lebens," Vom Umsturz deT Werle (2nd ed.; Leipzig: Der Neue Geist Verlag, 1928), Vol. II, p. 190. 21 02 144 JOHN M. OESTERREICHER enemy. While the integral man looks at the objective world with undisturbed and love-led devotion, knowing that the human mind, created by God, the fount of wisdom, can grasp the essence of things, modern man doubts the powers of his mind as a matter of principle; driven by a deep-seated hostility to the world, he considers it a terrible " mush," out of which his activity must make sense. He uses it for purposes of his own and determines it quantitatively, never ceasing to comP.are and striving to surpass. For all that his thinking seems so complex, he has in truth relapsed into the primitive. Never before have his motives been so infantile; the biggest, the fastest, the newest, the most powerful, are his ideals. These are the things a child enjoys: the giant in the fairy tale, the spinning top, shoes shining and conspicuously new, the drum that beats the loudest; and these are also the things the crowd seeks after, for it is a bigger child. With modern man allowing the crowd to shape his soul, the end is a state in which all copy all.23 Alive to man's integral and rich humanity, Scheler was enraged by the caricature of him that had been rising on the historical scene since the end of the thirteenth century. At times Scheler's speech had a passion almost prophetic, and had he been true to his insight, he would have earned the title " prophet against the times." Every Christian has a prophetic vocation, he said, but the prediction of the true prophet is not absolute, because he will not lose sight of man's freedom. True, he cries: I foresee judgment; come it must, save you repent and turn to God, and He in His mercy turn His judgment from you. The prophet cries out, but it is the historic reality that preaches. In the blood and misery of the times, he hears the warning voice of God, and refuses to predict ease, to hold out dazzling visions of paradise. He is perforce a prophet of grief, of doom, but not of despair. Time and again the prophets of the Old Covenant spoke of a remnant to be spared, from which would spring new ••" Die christliche Liebesidee und die gegenwaertige Welt," Vom Ewigen im Menschen, pp. 180-181; "Der Bourgeois," Vom Umaturz der Werte, Vol. II, pp. 271, 276. :MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 145 life, and this promise of a remnant is rekindled whenever the days of a culture grow short. So St. Benedict, when Christian life was imperiled by the great city, went from Rome to Subiaco; while outside ancient culture was being ground under foot, he preserved within his monasteries its noble fragments, together with the ideal of Christian perfection. 25 In his best years it was Scheler's desire-indeed, it was his calling, though fulfilled but in part-to undeceive modern man, who thinks he has fared well in this world; to show that the day of wrath is upon him unless he change heart; and implicitly, to call on the remnant to carry the true values over the abyss into which man is about to throw himself. IT Strange to say, for his dissection of the modem ethos in his essay on The Role of Ressentiment in Moral Systems 26 Scheler uses the blade Nietzsche forged: his emphasis on ressentiment, which Scheler defines as a self-poisoning of the soul caused by systematic repression, as opposed to moral conquest, of hostile emotions like hate, spite, envy, jealousy and revenge, and leading to a more or less permanent deformation of the sense of values. Only there, says Scheler, will ressentiment grow where aviolent emotion goes hand-in-hand with a feeling of impotence, deriving from some physical or spiritual weakness, or from fear of those against whom the emotion is directed. It springs up most readily, therefore, in those in subordinate or inferior positions, in those who are dependent, who are ruled, who serve. A virus malignant and most contagious, it may, however, spread widely and infect many others. 27 But we must add that every man, dependent on God, is tempted to kick against the goad of His authority and is thus open to the bitterness of ressentiment. If, says Scheler, the resentful man is unable to lift his oppres•• " Prophetischer oder marxistischer Sozialismus? " Schriften zur Soziologie und Weltanschauungslehre, III/2, pp. 17-18, 28-24. 28 1912, revised 1915. ••" Das Ressentiment im Aufbau der Moralen," Vom Umsturz der Werte, Vol. I, pp. 51-62, 55-66. 146 JOHN M. OESTERREICHER sive feeling of inferiority by action, he seeks another outlet for his painful tension in falsehood. He drags down the values that depress him in others, or else blinds himself to them; furthermore-and this, Scheler points out, is the main work of ressentiment-he either falsifies values as such or pretends they are illusory, for if their validity or existence be denied, there can remain no high qualities to depress him. Or he may come to say that the good is that which he wants, the offspring of desire. The depreciation of values to the level of one's desires or abilities is by no means the normal fulfillment of the sense of values; it is, on the contrary, the chief cause of moral blindness, deception, and illusion. The possibility of resignationthat a man, having lost the power to obtain a good, can yet acknowledge its worth, proves the sense of value independent of ability or desire. 28 "There is no refuge from another's excellence save love," Scheler quotes Goethe, 29 and takes care to state that it would be utter folly to think that in a given situation an individual is forced to succumb to ressentiment, a phenomenon which cannot be understood without understanding the process of :repression. For, as Scheler might have said, the further the soul departs from the realm of the spirit, which is the realm of freedom, the more subject it is to laws approaching the purely biological. Strongly felt weakness, depression engendered by impotence, anxiety, and intimidation: these are the repressive forces which make the hostile emotions shun the clear light of day. Having first inhibited their expression, fear and frailty push the emotions from the conscious plane into darkness, so that the individual or group stirred by them is no longer aware of their secret work. The inhibition finally spreads so far that the impulse of hate, envy or revenge is crushed the moment it wishes to arrive at our inner perception. On the other hand, the store of buried emotions draws each fresh emotion, incorporat28 Ibid., pp. 70-74. •• Wahlverwandschaften, ll, 5. MAX SCHELER AND THE FAITH 147 ing it into its mass, so that each repression eases the way for the next and speeds the whole process. 30 In this process of repression, the image of the original object of hostility is, as it were, blotted out. I may hate someone, and know the reason very well: the act that harmed, or the feature that pains me. In the measure that I repress my hate-which is, of course, something totally different from overcoming it by moral energy, in which case my hate and its object are both fully present to my mind and any hostile emotion is checked by virtue of a clear ethical judgment-it detaches itself more and more from its specific ground, and in the end from the person hated. It aims :first at any of his qualities and actions, perhaps at his way of walking or laughing, or his taste in music, at anything which expresses his personality, and further, at people, even at things and situations, associated with him. Finally, the impulse may break away altogether from the person who hurt or oppressed me, and become a negative attitude towards certain qualities, no matter who bears them, or where or when, and whether he treats me well or ilL Thus I may come to hate a whole group or class or nation. I may even come to hate or torment mysel£.31 Having thus examined the phenomenon of ressentiment, Scheler asks what it can contribute to the understanding of value-judgments, whether those of individuals or of periods, and towards the understanding of entire moral systems. It is evident in itself, he says, that from it there can never spring genuine judgments, but only false and deceived, for true morality rests on an eternal hierarchy of values. There is an ordre du coeur (Pascal) which moral genius uncovers in the course of time piece by piece; its grasp and gain are historic, but never the order of moral values itself. Far from being the source of value, ressentiment is that of revolt, of the overthrow of the eternal order in man's mind. Nietzsche himself, the skeptic and 30 " Das Ressentiment im Aufbau der Moralen," Vom Umsturz der Werte, Vol. I, pp. 88-89. 81 Ibid., pp. 89-9!i