THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDIToRs: THE DoMINICAN Publishers: VoL. XX FATHERS OF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH The Thomist Press, Washington 17, D. C. JANUARY, 1957 No.1 THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY: FROM JUSTICE TO UMAN society has become for the modern world a very complex reality, far too intricate for the mind of any one man to know thoroughly. Consequently, it is rarely understood in its totality, in the basic structure that makes up its unity. Some know this phase, some that. Yet, the basic structure of society can be grasped since man can reflect on his experience and therefore can know the means and ends of his in the city. In reality, there are many ways to discover the basic totality of society, but perhaps the clearest way open for such a comprehension is by means of an analysis of the various aspects of law as it was set down and understood by St. Thomas Aquinas. It would be also possible to begin with the notion of justice, or of the common good, or of friendship; but these problems, as we shall see, are one; the starting point alone is different. In this analysis, the most striking 1 JAMES V. SCHALL thing to note about the treatment of St. Thomas is that, within the context of the problem as he saw it, he implicitly, if not actually, uses the political definitions and distinctions between state and society and their functions which have become such an important part of the thought of such excellent thinkers as R. M. Maciver, Jacques Maritain, Ernest Barker, J. T. Delos, and Johannes Messner. 1 In treating of law, Aquinas uses several ideas and terms which shall serve as our basic outline. Here, however, let it be clear that we do not wish to treat of the essence of law. This writer accepts the Thomistic doctrine as the true one consistent with rational psychology and ethics; that is, " an ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community, and promulgated." 2 Rather we wish to inquire about law as it exists in a society, what it commands, what it does, what effects it has. The most fundamental truth about human law is that it deals only with external, human acts. 3 These external acts must be ordered in such wise that the temporal peace and tranquillity of society be maintained. This is accomplished by regulating and prohibiting anything that could distu:rb the conditions of concord in society. St. Thomas calls this peaceful order the end of human law. "For the end of human law is the temporal tranquillity o£ the state, which end law effects by directing external actions, as regards those evils which might disturb the peaceful condition of the state." 4 Here it is necessary to inject some thoughts on terminology, for SL Thomas when dealing with the essence of law maintains in several in1 Cf. R. M. Maciver, The Modern State (London: Oxford University Press, 1946), esp. pp. l-22, and passi11;1,; Jacques Maritain, Man and the State (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), ch. 1; Ernest Barker, Principles of Social and Political Theory (Oxford, 1952), pp. 42 ff.; J. T .. Delos, 0. P., La Societe lnternationale (Paris, 1929), ch. 1; J. Messner, Social Ethics (St. Louis: Herder, 1949), bk. 3. 2 Summa Theol., I-II, q. 90, a. 4. 3 Ibid., q. 98, a. I; q. 91, a. 4. • Ibid., q. 98, a. 1. THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY stances that the end of law is the common good. 5 His idea seems to be this, that the principle according to which these external acts are regulated is the objective order of just relations without which a society cannot at all exist. Consequently, when speaking of the end of the law as the common good, he means the common good as a final cause by which particular external acts can achieve their end. ". . . Actions are indeed concerned with particular matters: but those particular matters are referable to the common good, not as to a common genus or species, but as to a common final cause, according as the common good is said to be the common end." 6 St. Thomas identifies this common good in other places as the intention of the legislator, meaning that it is the end for which he acts. 7 However, the end of law in the sense of temporal tranquillity refers to the effect actually achieved by the order of just relations in an existent society, The first and minimal :requirement of society, then, is the de facto order of men such that their actions with respect to one another be at least just. Consequently, law will command the acts of those virtues which have either directly or indirectly an effect on the external order. Those acts which have a relation ad aliud in the external order are the acts of justice. 8 The precepts of law, therefore, will embody the external acts of justice. "For the precepts of every law prescribe acts of virtue." 9 And virtues other than justice are embodied in law only insofar as their acts have an effect externally so that they can be considered as relating to justice. 10 If any given society establish and keep established this minimal order, it will have Ibid., q. 96, a. 4; q. 90, a. 2. Ibid., 90, 2, ad 2. 7 ". • • Legislatores ad hoc maxime tendere videntur, ut procu:rent utilitatem communem." In Etk., #1666. "Now the intention of every lawgiver is directed first and chie:lly to the common good." Summa Theol., I-II, q. 100, a. 8. • Summa Theol., II-ll, q. 58, a. 2; et a. 5; Ill Sent., d. 83, q. 2, a. 2, sol. 3, ad :3; etc. • Summa Theol., I-ll, q. 107, a. l, ad 2. 10 Ibid., II-ll, q. 58, !i!, 8, ad 3; a. !J, ad 2. 5 6 4 JAMES V. SCHALL the basic requirement for a healthy society. The organization or institution directly concerned with this order is the state or in St. Thomas' terminology, the prince. The state, therefore, is that section of a society which has the external order of just actions and relations as its direct end. " For a prince is ordained to this purpose that he keep justice, and as a consequence equality .... " 11 It is interesting at this point to compare this doctrine of St. Thomas with some more recent thought on this subject. If we remember that law finds its end, as was seen above, in the external tranquillity and peace and that the state looks primarily to this order, we will find the best modern thinkers giving strikingly similar definitions. For instance, Professor Mac! ver defines the state as " an association which, acting through law as promulgated by a government endowed to this end with coercive power, maintains within a community territorially demarcated the universal external conditions of social order." 12 Professor Barker notes that the " ... state exists for the great but single, purpose of law." 18 What he means by this is that the area of " legal action " is that of the state: ... legal action is a mode of treating things in general, things of all sorts and descriptions, religious or moral or educational or economic or whatever they may be, so far as they can be brought under a rule of law and thus made a matter of compulsory uniformity. Law touches and treats all acts-so far as acts are amenable to its touch and treatment. But it is only external acts which are amenable to such treatment. A rule of law is an order (ultimately issued ... by the community itself, but immediately issued by some organ which declares and enforces the sense of the community), to do, or to abstain from doing, a defined and definite external act: an order enforced, in the last resort, by another external act of physical coercion. 14 11 "Ad hoc enim princeps institutus est ut custodiat justitiam, et per consequens aequalitatem .... " In Eth., #1009. 12 Maciver, op. cit., p. 18 Barker, op. cit., p. 44. 14 Ibid., p. 45. THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY 5 The state, however, will be more or less perfect; it can progress or regress in its duty, for there is a whole range and hierarchy of just actions stretching from the prevention of murder and theft to establishing the norms for a universal just price. " ... The intention of the law is to make all men virtuous, but in a certain order, namely, by first of all giving them precepts about those things where the notion of duty is most manifest . • • • " 15 All problems of the external order may fall within the competency of the state in some sense at least, but it may very well be that in any given body of men very few of the factors that really constitute the good life will be realized. This total order of just relations in society is called the common good of the multitude, and it will be the end for which all civil laws are primarily intended. 16 Laws get their meaning and proportion from this end. "All laws are posited according as they are conformed to the political end .... " 17 This is not to deny, of course, that states de facto seek different ends and consequently establish different laws according to the way different peoples set up for themselves different goals or understandings of the common good; that is, virtue, or wealth, or world domination, or pleasure. However, as a matter of fact, the only legitimate understanding of the common good will be the one that aims ultimately as virtue. * * * * * Human law, we have held, deals with the precepts of the virtue of justice. But just how is law related to justice in reality? A man becomes just by performing just acts which performance involves both the intellectual act of specification and the actual volitional exercise of an act according to this specification. 18 This means that a man must see the objective justum (just, or better, right relation) in any of his acts. Now Summa Theol., II-II, q. 122, a. 1, ad 1; cf. a. 2. Cf. Ill Cont. Gent., c. 80; and Summa Theol., II-II, q. 47, a. 10, ad 2. 17 " Omnes enim leges ponuntur secundum quod congruunt fini politicae. . . ." In Eth., #1030. 18 Cf. Summa Theol., I-II, q. 51, a. 2; and In Eth., #250. 15 16 JAMES V. SCHALL these objective justa (right :relations) are in part determined by nature, that is by reason itself, and in part by positive ordination of society. 19 These relations which man recognizes to be de facto existing and operative are facts, and he knows that he did not make these relations solely by himselt He must, therefore, take them into consideration in his every action so that the action will be proportioned to his end. By seeing and acting according to these just relations he will be able to become a just and good man. Law is just the other side of this same reality. It looks to what man should do, not from the side of the individual person himself but from the side of the legislator who establishes these justa (right :relations) and debita (things due) for the common good and which man in his tmn discovers to be factors in his every action. What a man can discover from reason, therefore, namely that there are natural limits and guideposts for his actions in reason; he, ultimately, comes to see as commands of a lawgiver, either human as in the case of civil law or divine as in the case of natural or revealed law. In other words, a man can see from reason that there are ways for a human being to act, and he can discover in large measure just .what these ways are. He may not know why this is so, but he cannot escape the fact that it is so. However, when he progresses and discovers that these limits were not just accidental or arbitrary (assuming for the moment just human laws) and further, when he has come to see that they are commands of a lawgiver who in the case of natural law not only made the law but also the man himself; then he sees fully that the moral law is not simply a restriction or impediment, but a definite order to man's end, a road by which he travels and not a pit into which he has fallen. 2° Consequently, law commands that act be done which man from his point of view sees that it is in accord with his nature to perform, 19 Cf. In Eth., #1004 and 1019. •• Cf. Dom Odon Lottin, 0. S. B., Principeo. de Morale (Lonvain: I.'Abbaye du Mont cesar, 1947), Vol. I, p. 125. Editions de THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY 7 The formal cause of the human act is the dictate of reason which at the same time is the law as received in the subject and the ratio juris that man sees must be maintained in the act. The ratio juris, then, and the law are the same thing except that the law as such refers to the lawgiver. 21 The order of strict just :relations, therefore, the same reality will include the multiplicity of just human actions required for the existence of society and the basic laws by which these acts are enforced and ordered. I answer that, since the precepts of the law are ordained to the common good ... the precepts of law must needs be diversified according to the various kinds of community: hence the Philosopher (Polit. iv, 1) teaches that the laws which are made in a state which is ruled by a king must be different from the laws of a state which is mled by the people, or by a few powerful men in the state. Now human law is ordained for one kind of community, and the divine law for another kind. Because human law is ordained for the civil community, implying mutual duties of man and his fellows: and men are ordained to one another by outward acts, whereby men live in communion with one another. This life in communion of man with man pertains to justice, whose proper function consists in directing the human community. Wherefore human law makes precepts only about acts of justice; and if it commands acts of other virtues, this is only insofar as .they assume the nature of justice .... 22 The principle or end according to which these acts can be denominated just and good will, then, be the objective common good of the multitude. The effect of this order will be concord, the external peace. 23 And concord is the result of the effective establishment of special justice, i.e., commutative and distributive, among men. 24 This is why, incidently, the principle of revolution is found precisely here, in the failure to establish justice, for men do not long endure their unequal lot. We might ask at this point about the actual content of the ·•• Summa Theol., II-II, q. 57, a. l, ad 2. •• Ibid., I-II, q. 100, a. 2. Cf. also In Eth., #904-5. •• Ibid., I-II, q. 98, a. 1. •• Cf. ibid., I-II, q. 180, a. 2, ad 2; and q. 128, a. 5, w.l. 8. 8 JAMES V. SCHALL order of justa, what exactly does it embrace? The general term that St. Thomas and Aristotle use for this order is justum politicum or simpliciter justum. 25 The term is used to designate the order of justice in a perfect and self-sufficient community, a community looking to the fulness of human life. Such a community, however, can only be found among free and equal men so that the primary function of justice and law must always be the establishment and protection of equality and freedomthat is, the end and purpose of the justice that the law effects. Law is the dictate of reason by which the problems of what is just and what is right are settled, as it were, outside the contingent and turbulent exchange of ordinary human intercourse; it is the attempt to apply pure reason, reason abstract from passion and ignorance to human affairs.c6 Justum politicum, however, is a complex notion. It is a complex genus referring to an the just actions in the community no matter how these acts obtain their ratio of justice. Now these actions are subject to various divisions according to the various ways this same reality taken as a whole can be considered. Thus we can consider the complexus of actions accordthis ing to how the rightness in each action is case, some will proportional, some arithmetical, some will find their rightness measured in other ways, as in the instances of the potential parts of justice. Only the first two of these, however, the justa distributiva and justa commutativa, strictly pertain to society as such. 27 But we can also consider these self-same actions according to their cause or origin-then some will be just because they are natmally reasonable (justa naturalia), others will be just only because the particular community establishes them as such (justa legalia) .28 The legal justa (right relations) are always determinations of the natural precepts. 29 Therefore, some justa can be distributiva et naturIn Eth., #1004. Ibid., and 1009. 27 Ibid., #1005. That is as regulated by law in a society. 28 Ibid., #1018. •• Ibid., #10!'l3. 25 25 THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY alia, others distributiva et legalia, etc., but always justa legalia must be in accord with the natural justa. * * * * * In the Summa Theologiae, St. Thomas makes a division of the Old Law which proves very valuable in this regard. He divides the Old Law into moral, caeremonial, and judicial precepts according to the type of justa they contain. The moral precepts are the reasonable principles and their strictly reasonable conclusions both of which necessarily flow from the nature of man. 30 These moralia in turn can be divided according to the difficulty with which they are known-some are known to all (do good, avoid evil), some are known by most men ( the ten commandments), some are known only by the wise (no divorce), and some only to God. These precepts embrace man's relations both with God and with other men. Those which deal with man's relations to God are very general and must be determined by society to give unity and coherence to the acts of worship-such positive determinations are called alia. These sorts of justa, then, will be positive in cause, either by society in the natural order or by God Himself in the case of revelation. The determinations which deal with man's relations with one another are called judicalia. 31 There are, however, four types of relationships that men can have to one another: 1) prince to people, 2) citizens to one another, 3) people as a whole to another people, and 4) the domestic relationships. 32 These justa which deal with these relationships insofar as they are determinations of natural principles or conclusions will be positive in character. This, then, gives a fairly good conspectus of the content of the basic structure of just relationships in a society, what they must contain and deal with, the sources from which they will be designated just. Were this the sole meaning of the order of just relationships, Summa Theol., I-II, q. 100, a. l; q. 102, a. l, ad 3. Ibid., q. 101, a. 1; q. 104, a. l. •• Ibid., q. Hl4, a. 4. 80 81 10 JAMES V. SCHALL however, it would produce a barren and rigid society indeed. But the order of justa is, as it were, the foundation or basis of something far richer and more significant. Thus when a legislator commands, he primarily and initially commands an external act of justice in some sense, and the order of justa means exactly the external, objective order and unity of objectively :right relationships existing because of the efficient actions of men. This suffices to maintain and define the objective and minimal order of justice. But the legislator-be he the legislator of the natural or the positive law-has in mind not simply this act of a virtue, but he intends that virtue itself, the habit, be implanted in the citizen. This does not mean, of course, that every lawgiver in Washington or in London must recognize this truth and have it in his mind when making a law. St. Thomas is speaking about the nature of the law as such, what it must do from its very nature and what the legislator must do as a simple consequence of making the law. Consequently, that about which the law is given is an act of virtue-which is at the same time the rule of society and the act which is capable of inducing a habit in the man. The end, however, to which the precept is ordained is not simply that the citizen perform the act, but that he acquire the virtue. The intention of the lawgiver is twofold. His aim, in the first place, is to lead men to something by the precepts of the law: and this is virtue. Secondly, his intention is brought to bear on the matter itself of the precept: and this is something leading or disposing to virtue, viz., an act of virtue. For the end of the precept and the matter of the precept are not the same: just as neither in other things is the end the same as that which conduces to the end. 33 Therefore, under the strict precept of the law will be the virtuous acts that a man does, whether he does them willingly or not. The principle intent of the legal structure of society, none the less, is that man do these acts virtuously, that Is, •• Ibid., q. 100, .a. 9, ad THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY n because he sees their worth and not because they are commanded by coercion. This virtue, then, is what the legislator intends, though, strictly speaking, the external order of society will be maintained if the external commanded acts be performed from whatever motive. An act is said to be an act of virtue in two ways, first, from the fact that a man does something virtuous; thus the act of justice is to do what is right, and an act of fortitude is to do brave things: and in this way law prescribes certain acts of virtue.-Secondly, an act of virtue is when a man does a virtuous thing in a way in which a virtuous man does it. Such an act always proceeds from virtue: and it does not come under a precept of law, but is the end at which every lawgiver aims. 34 In this sense, then, the realm of virtue is very definitely a matter for society. Thus the existence of habitual moral virtue in the citizens is itself a common good, the common good of the many. There is also a human good, not common to many (in the sense of one common end), but belonging to an individual by himself, yet useful not to one only, but to many: for instance those things which all and each one must believe and observe, such as the articles of faith, the divine worship, and the like.35 This common good of the many is something which each one personally possesses, but whose operation and effect is shared by many. This is also sometimes called the order of (habitual) justice and virtue. 36 The effect and end of the whole order of justa, therefore, will be the making of men good, and in this way we can see the truth of St. Thomas' dictum: " ... He who seeks the common good of the many as a direct consequence must also seek his own good." 37 For it is in and through the order of external just relationships that men can become good, but their goodness is their own perfection. •• Ibid., q. 96, a. 8, ad 2; cf. also q. 92, a. 1. Cf. also LoUin, op. cit., p. 141. •• Ill Ccmt. Gent., c. 80. •• Summa Theol., q. 100, a. 8. •• Ibid., II-II, q. 47, a. 10, ad 2: " ... qui qnaerit bonum commooe mul.titudinis ex COiml!eqUenti etil!m quaerit bonum suum. . .. " 12 JAMES V. SCHALL There are, however, some further things to remember about this order of society. First of all, there are activities going on within society which cannot be strictly considered under the equality and debt due in strict justice. These activities have a correct measure, of course, but it is a relative one, or a least one that cannot be legislated accurately. For instance, we cannot actually give back to God, or to our native land, or to our parents all that is due to them. We must do something certainly, but the return will never be equal. Most of these relationships, in addition to the natural obligation, have further determinations of the divine or positive law by which certain definite acts must be placed so that they do in this sense fall within the pale of the legal and just structure of society, but the acts as such never fully repay the obligation really due. 38 Some human activities cannot fall strictly under justice for another reason, i. e., because the thing due is only due from a certain "goodness of virtue," or better, from the exigencies of virtuous intercourse. Here we must see that some things are absolutely necessary for human life on the part of the individual, such as the virtue of truth in man's words and actions. The thing due in this case is not something that can be measured or determined by a specific law, except perhaps in the case of civil contracts, yet society cannot exist without this honesty. Such is also liberality and affability which, while not absolutely necessary, nevertheless are the perfections of human communication without which society could not last-though again the thing due must be left to individual determination. 39 * * * * * None the less, we still have not penetrated to the depth of the Thomistic social position if we content ourselves with the making of the good man, or better, if we simply permit the man to make himself good. So if men are good, they will have reached their natural perfection in the sense that their lives •• Ibid., q. 80, art. unic. •• Ibid., q. 80, art. unic; and III Sent., d. 34, q. 1, a. THE TOTALI'fY OF SOCIETY 13 are well-ordered, naturally speaking, should death come, But in societal philosophy we look to the true perfection that society itself effects; for there is, as it were, something beyond virtue and that is friendship. In accord with our intention of exposing the full meaning of society from the basis of law, we discover that the principal intention of the law, as opposed to the intention of the lawgiver, is friendship. This is, ultimately, the most beautiful and most powerful gift that God has granted to men -and so it is that when we pass beyond human society we find that Aquinas conceives of charity as nothing more than friendship with God.' 0 Surely there is nothing which is at the same time more noble and more humbling than this. As the Apostle says (1 Tim. 1: 5) the end of the commandment is charity; since every law aims at establishing friendship, either between man and man, or between man and God, wherefore the whole Law is comprised in this one commandment, Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself, as expressing the end of all commandments: because love of one's neighbor includes love of God, when we love our neighbor for God's sakeY As Christians and as men, we cannot find a more truly profound and gratifying truth than this fact that our whole social and personal lives are ordained to friendship; for, even from our own limited experience, it is clear that friendship is the perfection of human living; and, as we believe, of divine living as well. Human law, therefore, in the mind of SL Thomas has as its ultimate intention, the friendship of men one to another. " ... The principal intention of human law is to create friendship between man and man .... " 42 The relationship between the establishment of the order of just relations, the common good of the multitude, and the existence of human friendship is, then, a causal one; for friendship presupposes justice even though it passes beyond it in its own sphere. The purpose of justice is primarily to establish equality, either proportional or arithSumma Theol., loc. cit., q. 23, a. 1; and Ill Sent., d. f.!'7, q. f.!, a. I. Summa Theol., I-II, q. 99, a. l, ad 2. 42 Ibid., a. 2. 40 41 14 JAMES V. SCHALL metical, among the members of society. When this. equality is established the function of justice ends, but that of friendship begins. And the reason for this diversity is this, that friendship is a certain union or society of friends, which cannot exist among those who greatly differ, but it should exist among those who approach equality. Wherefore, it belongs to friendship equally to employ the equality already established; but it belongs to justice to reduce unequal things to equal ones. When, however, equality exists, the work of justice is complete. And thus equality is the last thing achieved in justice, but it is the beginning in friendship. 43 Both justice and friendship, therefore, deal with the same reality, that is human communication, so that where there is justice there is a possibility of friendship. " ... Justice and friendship are about the same things. But justice consists in communication. For every sort of justice is to another (ad alterum) . ... Therefore, consists in communication." 44 And this must mean that the perfection of human societal communication is not justice, but friendship. This conclusion, therefore, shows that the philosophy of friendship and love is at the root of society; that is, it is the goal of any real human life in the city (the Aristotelian city, of course, not the modern monstrosities). Further, St. Thomas with Aristotle distinguishes the kinds of friendship according to two principles of logical division: 1) according to the kind of communication the friendship is based upon, and 2) according to the end of friendship, i.e., utility, pleasure, or virtue. 45 Of course, friendship based upon virtue is the highest of these, but we should not fail to understand the importance of the friendship of business relationships or of pleasure even. For example, commercial society in itself is a horribly cold and impersonal deity as anyone who has ever walked into say J. C. Penny's to purchase a pair of gloves can well testify. •• In Eth., #16S2. Ibid., .#1658. •• Summa Theol., ll-ll, q. 25, a. 6. u THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY 15 The exchange of money for the gloves is the just communication involved and of itself it is a very insignificant and heartless thing. But suppose the clerk in the store sees the customer coming and greets him with a smile and shows a real interest in the man about to make the purchase. The two have a pleasant exchange over the purchase or about a million other things, the customer then leaves and the two never see each other again. Yet, that exchange was a fine thing, it made something otherwise distasteful, a pleasant and human thing-society as a whole benefited as did both men because there was a real friendship based on utility surely, but still a friendship which lessened the tensions among men. Incidently, this is also a good argument for private property, especially in the form of human sized and owned stores where this sort of exchange is more likely to happen. Also such friendly communications form the starting point for the more perfect type of and a more real union among the members of society. In a order Christian charity gives depth and meaning to such friendship. This is not to deny, of course, that men are naturally friendly with one another in some sense, but it is difficult that this be more than passing, given human nature as it is since the Fall. 46 Philosophically, this type of utilitarian friendship is called by St. Thomas the " amicitia, quae aflabilitas dicitur," or friendliness. It is a potential part of the virtue of justice, having an object distinct from the other forms of justice, namely, the external requirements of human order and communication. And it behooves man to be maintained in a becoming order towards other men as regards their mutual :relations with one another, in point of both deeds and words, so that they behave •• " Potest enim esse aliqna amicitia cujnslibet hominis ad omnem hominem in quantum possrmt rommnnica:re aliqua lege .... " ln Eth., #1700. "Quia enim omnes homines conveninnt in natura speciei, omnis homo est naturaliter omni homini amicus." De Perf. Vitae Sp. (Parma; Vol. XV, p. 87), c. 14. Also Summ,a Theol., II-II, q. H4, a. l, ad 2. 16 JAMES V. SCHALL towards one another in a becoming manner. Hence the need of a special virtue that maintains the becomingness of this order: and this virtue is called friendlinessY There is a very definite distinction, of course, between friendliness and the friendship following on virtue. St. Thomas IS dear on this point, following the position of Aristotle: The Philosopher speaks of a twofold friendship in his Ethics. One consists chiefly in the affection whereby one man loves another and may result from any virtue .... But he mentions another friendliness, which consists merely in outward words or deeds; this has not the perfect nature of friendship, but bears a certain likeness thereto, insofar as a man behaves in a·becoming manner towards those with whom he is in contact. 48 Thus friendliness is not the friendship of virtue which stands at the very summit of societal life, but it has a very vital part to play in our daily lives. * * * * * However, the perfection of all human communication is friendship based on virtue. This perhaps sounds a bit unusual, but the truth of the matter is clear. A man who is, theoretically, perfectly good will be a very unhappy man without the friendship which follows upon virtue. For as we know, man's true happiness is not simply the possession of a good number of habits but in virtuous activity and indeed in continuous and pleasing activity. "But to be happy consists in continuous life and operation. . . . For he would not be virtuous who would not delight in the operation of virtue." ·49 And the peculiar and distinguishing thing about friendship is that it consists in the communication of virtue; that is, of all the highest powers of man: " The friendship which consists in the communication of virtue .... " 50 Thus the phrase of God that it is not good for men to live alone is not solely pertinent to the Summa Theol., II-II, q. 114, a. 1. Ibid., ad 1. 49 In Eth., #1894. Cf. also the whole first book of St. Thomas' Commentary. 50 Ibid., #1798. Cf. also #1946, Hi98, 1702, and 1724. 47 48 THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY 17 relationship, but in its own way it is of the very nature of every human relationship including the divine one: For no one would choose to live by himself always, that is alone, even after he had all other things, because man is naturally a political animal and is born with a natural aptitude to live with others. Therefore, since the happy man has those things which are naturally good for man, it follows that he should have those with whom he may live. It is dear, therefore, that it is better to live with friends and virtuous men than with strangers and people of any sort. 51 Consequently, from the communication of virtuous activity, there is established and secured the society of friends. 52 The communication in true friendship, therefore, is principally the one wherein man lives most fully since he operates according to the highest faculty, reason . . . . He [Aristotle] manifests that in which living consists. And he says that in all animals to live is commonly determined according to their sense potency. In men, however, it is determined according to the sense potency as to that which man has in common with other animals, and according to intellectual power as to that which is proper to himself. Every potency, however, is reduced to its operation, as to its proper perfection. Wherefore that which is of greatest importance consists in the operation, and not in the bare potency. For act is prior to potency .... And from this it is dear that to live for an animal or for a man principally consists in sensing or in understanding. 53 Thus in one sense, esse (to live) for man in this life is intelligere (to understand) .54 And friendship implies the fact that we come closest to the being and life of a friend precisely when we communicate thought and ideas; for being is what we Ibid., #1891. Ibid., #1899; also Ill Sent., d. 28, a. l. 53 In Eth., #1902 and 1908. 51 52 •• This statement needs to be understood, however, in the light of Summa Theol., I, q. 18, a. 2, ad 1: " ... Philosophus ibi accipit vivere pro operatione vitae.Vel dicendum est melius, quod sentire et intelligere, et huiusmodi, quandoque sumitur pro quibusdam operationibus; quandoque autem pro ipso esse sic operantium." The reference is to In Eth., #1908. 18 JAMES V. SCHALL naturally love. " This, however, is natural, namely, that each one should love his own being." 55 If the being of a friend is good; that is, if he is a good man, the highest manifestation of his being, his thoughts and his loves, will be most delightful to us. Therefore, just as someone delights in his own being and life by knowing himself, so to this fact that someone delight in a friend, he must simply know his being. 56 ••• If his own being is of its very nature a thing to be chosen by a happy man, insofar as it is naturally good and delightful; since, then, the being and life of a friend are in one's affections the next thing to one's own life, it follows that a friend is also a thing to be chosen by a virtuous and happy man. 57 We do need our friends, then, for our very highest endeavors. So it is that the principal act of friendship is. what St. Thomas calls " convivere " which consists in the communication of human ideas and ideals, and hence is the primary human stimulus to contemplation as well as the basic source of the new and vital thinking .required for the continuance and development of a people. Which indeed happens by living together according to the communication of words and the consideration of the mind. For in this manner men are said properly to live together, namely, according to the life which is proper to man, and not simply according as they eat together, as happens in the case of animals. 58 The joy and comm.radeship of friends is, then, found in their very intercommunication with one another. " ... True friendship desires to see the friend and causes a rejoicing in much conversation, towards which end friendship is principally ordained .... " 59 Thus there is a truth of the deepest and most profound nature in the observation that: " The supreme and •• In Eth., #1846. ""Ibid., #1909. •• Ibid., #1911. 58 Ibid., #1910. Cf. also Ill Sent., d. '!1.7, q. 2, a. '!l.; and Summa Theol., I-II, q. 28, a. 1, ad !i!. •• Ill Sent., d. £7, q. !i!, a. l, ad 11. THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY 19 ultimate product of civilization ... is two or three persons talking together in a room." 6 ° Consequently, society is absolutely dependent for its vitality and existence on its ability to effect adequate friendships among its people. This is why M. Maritain, following a suggestion of Father Phelan, has well said that friendship is society's "life-giving form!' 61 Of course, friendship cannot be commanded, yet it remains that it is the perfection and beauty of society. And so it is that St. Thomas beautifully remarks about law: " ... all precepts of law, especially those ordered to the neighbor, seem to be ordained to this end, that men love one another." 62 The love of friendship, moreover, is the love required by society because it alone of its very nature makes a society, a real relation between persons. But friendship adds two things (to amor): of which one is a certain society of the one loving and the one loved in love, namely, in order that they might have mutual love for one another and that they might know of their mutual love; the second is that they work from choice and not from passion .... Thus it is dear that friendship is the most perfect of those things which pertain to love, for it includes all the foregoing (loves, that is, desire of presence, dilectio, benevolence, beneficium, concord, amatio) . Wherefore in this category we must place charity which is a certain friendship of man to God through which man loves God and God man; and thus there is effected a certain association of man to God. 63 Friendship extends to the persons involved so that the terms of the relations are real persons and not accidents. This shows the nature of the real communication must be a mutual sharing of love and life among rational creatures. Friendship, however, cannot pertain (directly) to the virtues nor to any accidents for two reasons: Firstly, because friendship brings it about that man wishes to be a friend and to have good 60 In George Herbert Palmer, Self-Cultivation in English (Boston: Mifflin Company, 1909), p. 6. 61 Maritain, op. cit., p. 10. •• Summa Theol., I-U, q. 105, a. ad 1. •• Ill Sent., d. '1.7, q. a. l. Cf. Summa Theol., I-II!, q. '1.8, a. l. Houghton 20 JAMES V. SCHALL things. Accidents, however, do not have being (esse) per se, nor goodness per se, but their being (esse) and well-being (bene esse) belongs to them in substances. Wherefore, when we wish virtues and accidents to be, this is referred to the substances which we wish to be or to be well under those accidents .... Secondly, because friendship consists in a certain society, according to which the ones loved exchange love among themselves and do the same things and converse together. Wherefore friendship cannot be except towards something which is also capable of acting. And because activity (agere) does not belong to accidents, but to substances, therefore it is not possible that friendship be any virtue or accident.64 The ultimate and most perfect meaning of society, then, will be the acts of men who are friends with one another. Even on the material side of life friendship is necessary that society be perfected. We have already no_ted how business friendships are most valuable. On the other hand, friendships cause the material welfare of society to be better achieved, for they automatically proVide for the immediate relief of citizens in distress so that the humiliation and degradation that may come from say public and therefore impersonal relief is avoided by the love and aid of friends. 65 Thus, as a point of investigation, is not the need and existence of so much public aid in our society a good indication of a serious lack of real friendship among our people? Perhaps people do not have enough to help others, but that is the fruit of another problem, the problem of well-divided property in a modern nation. Aquinas reveals his recognition of these problems when he remarks that the intention of one of the Old Testament Laws was ". . . to accustom men to its precepts, so as to be ready to come to one another's assistance ... ," and he then adds " because this is a very great incentive to friendship." 66 A society, therefore, should actually have laws which command men to aid one another in their necessities both in order that •• Ill Sent., d. 9!8, a. I. •• Cf. In Eth., #1936-49!. •• Summa Theol., I-II, q. 105, a. 9!, ad 4. Also read ibid., ad I. THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY 21 friendships may arise from such natural aid, and in order that society will not have to burden itself with an excessive amount of works which in this life would be much better provided for by human beings in their own small circle of life. SL Thomas appears to make a distinction between what he calls political friendship and the true friendship of virtue. The problem is the one of the number of friends a man can have and of the basis or communication on which the friendship is founded. Obviously, men are not friends in the strict sense with everyone in a society. Sheer human limitation prevents this, for they neither know all of them, nor know them well enough to be true friends with them. However, citizens of a given state can be said to be friends none the less. Insofar as all the citizens of a state agree about the form of their ment and the nature of the society and culture in which they dwell; they can be called friends. The best examples of this are when two men totally unknown to one another sit down together on a train, both completely diverse in occupation, religion, place of residence, etc. Yet, both find themselves staunch democrats to the core, and as a result they find it easy to be friends. The same thing happens when two men of the same nation chance to meet on a foreign soil; they become as long lost brothers. Such agreement throughout society St. Thomas calls concord: ... political friendship, whether it be of citizens of one state towards one another, or among diverse states, seems to be the same as concord. And so also are men accustomed to speak; namely, that cities, or agreeing citizens, have friendship with one another. For political friendship is about useful things, and about those things which belong to human life, about which we say there is concord. 67 And such concord or friendship is something no society can long exist. Thus all political friendship is a of justice called friendliness or affability 67 In Eth., #1836. Cf. also especially #1924. JAMES Vo SCHALL treated above, that part, namely, which is concerned with the particularly political relationships, whereas friendliness includes all relationshipso Concord, when not used as a simple substitute political friendship, is a term generally attributed to the whole society or people, designating effect of political friendship among the people, though it could also refer to the existence of friendliness in generaL 68 The term, peace, adds additional note of personal internal peace and order to external peace or concordo69 * * * * * his understanding of the nature of SL Thomas, then, has shown his deep and penetrating grasp of the societal probat least, revealing the necessary distinclem by tions modern theorists have come to societyo He clearly society, life of the city, is shows, following Aristotle, the area that depends on human friendship; while the state, area of authority and justice in the city, aims at the external of human is the out these orders are both kept distinct and ordered to one another It will be profitable, therefore, to set down some sort diagram that we have found, comparing the Thomistic terms with of some more modern ones: 0 ST. THOMAS' TERMS REALITY l. The end of the Temporal law."" CoNCERNED tranquillity MoDERN TERMs and The sphere of the peace. state. The common good of the multitude. The area of strict justice. modern 2. The effect of the To make men personally virtu- The sphere of society; that is, law or the in- ous and goodo all the individual societies-"' Cf. above ftn. 23. •• Cf. all St. Thomas' treatise de Pace, Summa Theol., esp. II-II, q. 29, a. l. 70 It should be remembered that St. Thomas does not restrict himself always to one and the same term for one and the same reality. He of all authors must be understood in context. The point here is that he does use these specific terms for. the realities indicated, though he can and does use the same term for one of the other realities. Cf. ftn. 7. THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY ST. THoMAs' TERMS REALITY CoNCERNED tention of the The common good of the legislator. many. MoDERN TERMS familial, economic, educational, fraternal, athletic, religious, etc., within the order maintained by the state. 71 8. The intention of The area of habits and virtues. The bond of perfection of society. The perfect societal The friendship of men. the law. relation among men. Thus we can see somewhat better, it is hoped, the totality of societal life as it is found in all its ramifications. In concluding, however, it might be well to add a few notes about the function of the Gospel of Christ within the societal system. Natural justice and friendship, even of the highest sort, are simply not sufficient to the race of men as they exist under the present dispensation. Indeed, any intelligent understanding of ourselves and of our fellows will tell us that some· thing needs to be added to human beings to overcome the insufficiency of motivation and the lack of universal love which we find at the root of all societal friction. Some will, of course, say that this needs to be proved, but we wonder sometimes whether such objectors can really be serious. There is the whole course of history, and if that be not sufficient, there is that spectacle of potential destruction known as the modern world. 72 If more proof be needed, it is difficult to know what it could be. Here, however, there is no intention of treating the Christian dispensation from the aspect of eternal salvation and ultimate friendship with God, but rather we wish to treat of it from its effect on society-although it would vain to try to divorce totally the two considerations. The three major failings of natural society appear to be: 1) the inability to make men good, 2) the inability to extend 71 Remember that it is in these lesser societies that men actually live and act and hence acquire their perfection. The state is ordered to the maintenance of these societies intact and not to destroy them. Cf. Yves Simon, The Philosophy of Democratic Government (Chicago: U. of Chicago Press, 1951), pp. 36-71. 72 For a very illuminating discussion of the reality of man's Fall as it actually is seen in history see Herbert Butterfield's Christianity and HU!tory (London: G. Bell and Sons Ltd., 1949), 146 pp. 24 JAMES Vo SCHALL effective love and friendship to all men, and 3) the inability to order rightly men's interior intentions as well as his exterior dispositions" All societal evils can ultimately be placed under one or more of these points" Now the Christian law does not cease at the external act, but it passes beyond to order correctly man's interior acts and ideas, placing order at the very root of the matter" Thirdly, because man can make laws in those matters, of which he is competent to judge. But man is not competent to judge of interior movements, that are hidden, but only of exterior acts which appear: and yet for the perfection of virtue it is necessary for man to conduct himself aright in both kinds of acts" Consequently, human law could sufficiently curb and direct interior acts: and it was necessary for this purpose that divine law should superveneo 73 Also since man is a social animal needing other men, this relationship is most adequately attained by a mutual and sincere love which binds all men to one another" "" " . Since man by nature is a social animal, he needs assistance from other men in order to obtain his own end" Now this is most suitably done if men love one another mutually. Hence the law of God, which directs men to their last end commands us to love one another." 74 Moreover, the divine law is meant as a help to the natural law which latter also demands that men love one anothero 75 Further. The divine law is offered to man in aid of the natural law" Now it is natural to all men to love one another: a proof of which is that a man, by a kind of natural instinct, comes to the assistance of anyone even unknown that is in need, for instance by warning him, should he have taken the wrong road, by helping him to rise, should he have fallen, and so forth: as though every man were intimate and friendly with his fellow-man (VIII Ethic., 1, 3; 1155a). Therefore, mutual love is prescribed to man by the divine law. 76 73 Summa Theol., I-II, q. 91, a. 14. "'III Cont. Gent., c. 117. 75 " Sed praecepta moralis ex ipso dictamine naturalis rationis efficaciam habent ... quaedam sunt certissima, et adeo manifesta quod editione non indigent; sicut mandata de dilectione Dei et proximi .... " Summa Theol., I-II, q. 100, a. lll. •• Ill Cont. Gent., c. 117" THE TOTALITY OF SOCIETY We must also notice that the contemplation of divine things presupposes peace and tranquillity which are destroyed by a lack of love. Again. In order to apply himself to divine things, man needs calm and peace. Now mutual love, more than aught else, removes the obstacles to peace. Seeing then that the divine law directs men to apply themselves to divine things, we must conclude that this same law leads men to love one another. 77 Thus the highest effect of order on earth is true peace out of which springs true contemplation of God/ 8 It can be truly said, therefore, that a society of Christian men will come the closest to a perfect civil body on earth, since among them the sources of friction and hatred are most completely recognized and controlled, while the sources of human and divine love are most effectively encouraged and in operation. 79 In this whole matter of friendship and its perfection in the communication of thoughts and ideals, of dreams and hopes, we very often, it seems, permit ourselves to be confused and deceived. We live our lives as if these friendships were mere incidents or side issues to the main problems of human existence. Yet, the reality is quite otherwise. We live our lives for our friendships; they are the goals, not the means. Sometimes I think that the only modern man who really saw this truth as SL Thomas did was G. K. Chesterton, who in this as in so many things reflects conclusions which Aquinas propounded in a more philosophical, though certainly not more interesting way. Indeed, Chesterton's book on Charles Dickens is perhaps the best societal analysis ever written. It may be permitted, then, to use the concluding lines of this masterpiece for our own summation of the perfection of friendship in human life: The hour of absinthe is over. We shaH not be much further troubled with the little artists who found Dickens too sane for 77 Ibid. Cf. Summa Theol., q. fl9, aa. 1-4; also Ill Sent., d. fl7, q. 1, a. 3, ad 5. Cf. Hilaire Be!loc, Essays of a Catholic (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1931), pp. 2!15 and 297. 78 79 26 JAMES V. SCHALL their sorrows and too clean for their delights. But we have a long way to travel before we get back to what Dickens meant: and the passage is along a rambling English road, a twisting road such as Mr. Pickwick travelled. But this at least is part of what he meant; that comradeship and serious joy are not interludes in our travel; but that rather our travels are interludes in comradeship and joy, which through God shall endure for ever. The inn does not point to the road; the road points to the inn. And all roads point at last to an ultimate inn, where we shall meet Dickens and all his characters: and when we drink again it shall be from the great flagons in the tavern at the end of the world. 80 And again we see that Christianity has not been wrong in proclaiming that the friendships of men are the very means to the friendship with our God-he who loveth his neighbor hath fulfilled the law. So too, when Christ Our Lord wished to show to His Apostles His deep love for them, He could only say to them," No longer do I call you servants .... But I have called you friends, because all things I have heard from My Father I have made known to you." 81 And here we have it! God sharing His ideas and ideals with men-this is indeed the highest and most perfect act of friendship possible to us, His creatures. JAMES V. ScHALL, S. J. Georgetown University, Washington, D. C. 80 G. K. Chesterton, Charles Dickens (New York: The Press of the Reader's Club, 194fl), p. !'ll2. 81 John 15: 15. Cf. also St. Thomas' beautiful passage in Summa Theol., I-II, q. 65, a. 5. A COMPARISON OF THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OJ;-. HOPE HE problem of pure love is a recurrent one in various branches of philosophy. Whether it be the conflict between the ecstatic physical concept of love,' as derived from the philosophy of Aristotle and Plato, or the " egoism "' and " altruism " of psychologists, or the interested and disinterested love of the theologian, problem everything remains the same. Must man seek his own good he loves, or can he love something purely for its own sake without any reference to himself? Theologians take their stand in the matter according to answer to whether man love God in the impossible situation that He were not man's good. St. Thomas says man could not love even God under these circumstances. 2 Scotus, on the hand, because the love of benevolence is an act distinct from the love of concupiscence, maintains that even if God were not man's good, man would be able to love Him according to the affection of justice. 3 Because of the similarities in the nature of charity and of hope, both being acts of the will tending toward the good, any radical change in the concept of charity is naturally reflected in 1 Cf. Dom Gregory Steyens, 0. S. B., "The Disinterested Love of God," The Thomist, XVI (1953), 307-333, 497-541; also, Rousselot's The Problem of Love in the Middle Ages. 2 Summa Theol., II-II, q. !26, a. 13, ad 3: "Dato enim per impossibile quod Deus non esset hominis bonum, non esset ei ratio diligendi." Cf. I, q. 60, a. 5, ad 2: "Non enim esset in natura alicujus quod amaret Deum, nisi ex eo quod unumquodque dependet a bono quod est Deus." 8 Joannes Duns Scotus, Liber Ill Sententiarum, Opem, Tomus VII, P. I. II, Durand (Lyons, 1639), d. 27, q. un., !2: "Haec virtus (caritas) distincta est , .. similiter a spe, quia actus eius non est eoncupiscere bonum amanti, inquantum est commodum amantis, sed tendere in obiectum secundum se, etiamsi per impossibile circumscriberetur ab eo commoditas eius ad amantem. Hanc virtutem perficientem voluntatem inquantum habet affectionem justitiae, voco caritatem." 27 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN the concept of hope. In its widest acceptation, hope is the desire of something, together with the expectation of obtaining it. The conflict of ideas as to the nature of charity resulted in a difference of opinion as to which of these elements actually determines the nature of hope. This is the aspect of the problem that will be studied here. Traditionally, that is, according to the Scriptures, the Fathers and St. Thomas, the element of confidence or expectation is regarded as the distinctive characteristic of the virtue of hope. Within the last three centuries, however, there has been a growing trend toward the identification of hope with the element of concupiscible love, that is, the desire of God, not for His own sake, but because in Him we find our own happiness and perfection. Father DeLetter, in his study on "Hope and Charity," 4 attributes this change of concept to the combined teaching of the theologians, Duns Scotus, an English Franciscan, who lived from 1270 to 1308, and Francis Suarez, a Spanish Jesuit (1548-1617) . This new concept of hope identifying it with interested love made the virtue of hope the object of the attacks of many overzealous Christians who exaggerated the love of charity peculiar to the gospel. Although the basic Protestant doctrine of justifying faith, i. e., joyous confidence in the forgiveness of sin, would seem to be motivated by self-interest, both Luther and Calvin very illogically championed the cause of purely disinterested love and rejected as sinful whatever was done only through consideration of eternal reward, or "amor concupiscentiae." 5 There is, however, an inner connection between Luther's doctrine of justification and his view of love. Just as justification is the exclusive work of God and the will to purify oneself first by good works before taking refuge in Him is unwarranted presumption, so Christian love is not strictly concerned with the love with which we love God, but essentially with the love 4 P. DeLetter, S. J., "Hope and Charity in St. Thomas," The Thomist, XIII (1950) ' 204-248, 325-352. 5 Joseph F. Delany, "Hope," The Catholic Encyclopedia, VII (1913), 466. Condemned by Council of Trent, sess. 6, can. Sl, DB 841: "Si quis dixerit, iustificatum peccare, dum intuitu aeternae mercedis bene operatur: A. S." THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 29 with which God Himself loves. Luther will not refine and sublimate self-love but demands its total annihilation. Love, therefore, has no place in justification, which depends only on faith. 6 But this theory of love is less the triumph of absolute disinterestedness than the negation of our merits in order to exalt the merit of Christ alone. And because merit and reward are corresponding terms, the horror with which he regarded the pursual of meritorious works reflected on the pursual of a reward! Justification and salvation, therefore, could be the object of faith alone and our confidence in obtaining them must have the absolute certitude that faith requires. 8 Such a theory leaves no place for the virtue of hope as we know it. The fanatical rigorism of the Jansenists was the result of the strict application of the principle of completely disinterested love. Although in opposition to Protestantism, Jansenius permitted the seeking of heavenly beatitude, even considered as a reward, he insisted on the absolute disinterestedness of its motive considering it as a supreme means of glorifying God, and demanded of every Christian a perpetual act disintersted 9 charity. He reached this conclusion from his interpretation 10 of St. Augustine, who often uses the word " charity " in a very wide sense. He considered the love of hope, therefore, as morally bad and incapable of becoming good until transformed by charity into the love of friendship. 11 • Anders Nygren, Agape and Eros (London: S. P. C. K., 1953), p. 681. 7 S. Harent, "Esperance," Dictionnaire de Theologie Catholique, V (1924), col. 658. 8 Nygren, op. cit., p. 681. 9 Harent, op. cit., col. 658. 10 " The vision of God ought not to be loved by a Christian from any other species of love; in all the works of Augustine, as in Holy Scripture, there is not a trace of the idea that one may desire his salvation in virtue of a love different from that of true charity "-Augustinus, III De gratia Christi, 1. v, c. X, p. fl24 (Rouen, 1643), cited by Harent, DTC, col. 607. 11 Condemned DB 1300: "Intentio, qua quis detestatur malum et prosequitur bonum mere, ut coelestem obtineat gloriam, non est recta nee Deo placens "; DB 1303: "Quisquis etiam aeternae mercedis intuitu licet beatitudinis operatur "; DB 1407: "Totum deest peccatori, quando ei deest spes; et non est spes in Deo, ubi non est amor Dei." 30 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN The Quietists, on the other hand, conceding the goodness of hope, denied its necessity. Molinos claimed that hope is altogether incompatible with pure benevolent love.12 Quietism so concentrated on the imperfection of hope as to forget that the coming of a perfection removes only those imperfections which are its opposites. Since the imperfection of hope's love is not opposed to the perfection of charity's love/ 3 there is nothing to prevent us from loving God for two different reasons-both because He is good in Himself and because He is good for us. 14 Fenelon and the Semi-quietists limited the necessity of hope to the beginning stages of the spiritual life and claimed it is entirely foreign to the advanced spiritual state_15 The Quietists conceived of an habitual state of love of God so disinterested that fear of punishment and desire of reward no longer had any part in iU 6 St. Paul spoke of a desire to be " anathema " for the sake of his brethren. 17 St. Therese of Lisieux tells how reluctantly she recited the verse of the Divine Office, "I have inclined my heart, 0 Lord, to do Thy justifications for the sake of Thy rewards." 18 No doubt an act of pure love is possible, but an habitual "'Delany, op. cit., p. 466. Condemned DB 1332: "In hoc sanctae indifferentiae statu nolurnus arnplius salutern ut salutern propriarn, ut liberationern aeternam, ut rnercedern nostrorum meritorum, ut nostrum interesse omnium maximum; sed earn volurnus voluntate plena, ut gloriam et beneplacitum Dei; ut rem, quam ipse vult, et quam nos vult velle propter ipsurn." 18 Summa Theol., I, q. 62, a. 7, ad 1; II-II, q. 18, a. 1, ad 3. "Peter Lurnbreras, 0. P., "Hope the Self-Seeker," Cross and Crown (June 1951)' p. 183. 15 Delany, op. cit., p. 467. Condemned DB 1337: "In hoc statu anima arnittit omnem spern sui proprii interesse; sed nunquam amittit in parte superiore, id est in suis actibus directis et intimis, spern perfectam, quae est desideriurn disinteressantum promissionurn." 16 M. Molinos, Spiritual Guid!J, cited by Delany, p. 466. Condemned DB 1327: " Datur habitualis status arnoris Dei, qui est caritas pura et sine ulla admixtione rnotivi proprii interesse. Neque timor peonarurn, neque desiderium remunerationurn habent arnplius in eo partern. Non arnatur arnplius Deus propter rneriturn, neque propter perfectionem, neque propter felicitatern in eo arnando inveniendam." 17 Romans 9 :13. 18 St. Therese of Lisieux, An Autobiography, trans. Rev. Thomas N. Taylor (New York, 1926), p. 817. THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE Summa Theol., II-II, q. 180, a. 8, ad 2. Ibid., I-II, q. 34, a. L 21 Lumbreras, op. cit., p. 189. 22 Cf. Summa Theol., II-II, q. 27, a. 8, ad L •• R. Garrigou-Lagrange, 0. P., De Virtutibus Theologicis (Turin, 1949), p. 54,0. 10 20 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN I. THE EXPECTANT HOPE OF ST. THOMAS As a pre}iminary observation it may be well to note that this study does not involve two hopes, but two concepts of one reality, Christian hope, the essential notes of which are found in :revelation. Variety of concept often follows variety of approach to a subject, but the differences that result may be only apparent differences, having their root not in the subject itself, but in the point of view from which it is seen. In order to correctly evaluate St. Thomas' concept of hope, then, the virtue must be studied in its relation to man's progress toward his last end, for the principles of finality are the integrating factor of St. Thomas' moral system. 24 The act of hope, as described by St. Thomas, therefore, may not always be verified by conscious observance of our own psychological states, because his approach is on the deeper ontological level where real finality plays. With this in mind, we shall examine especially the texts of St. Thomas that deal with the act of hope that is common to hope both as a passion and as a virtue, as well as the formal object and the motive that specify theological hope. Hope exists on three different levels: the passion of hope, which resides in the sensitive appetite, hope which follows cognition and exists in the rational will, and the theological virtue of hope which elevates the will to a new mode of acting. Strictly speaking, hope in the second sense is not a virtue, for the will does not need a. special virtue to give it confidence with regard to some object within the natural capacity of the one willing. 25 Moreover, since hope pertains to things not possessed and human power can be frustrated, reliance on it cannot be sufficiently firm to establish natural hope as a virtue. 26 This study, which is primarily concerned with the theological virtue of hope, will be limited, therefore, to the consideration of its •• Ill Sent., d. £3, q. l, a. 1: "Prima autem mensura et regula omnium est divina sapientia; unde bonitas et rectitndo sive virtus uniuscujusque consistit secundum quod attingit ad hoc quod ex sapientia divina ordinatur." 26 Summa Theol., II-II, q. 'i!'i!, a. l, ad l. •• Ibid., I-II, q. 62, a. 3, ad 'i!. THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 33 supernatural aspect and to the act of the passion of hope insofar as the activity of hope on this level forms the basis for its supernatural activity and gives much valuable information concerning its nature. " For although the virtue of hope has a stability not found in the passion, it nevertheless remains true that it is known only by its acts, the exterior characteristics of which are stamped with the same frailty as those of natural hope." 27 The Notion of Hope in General Hope is a complex act that in some sense contains elements of love, desire, courage and confidence. Each of these elements is a response on the part of the subject to certain qualities that the object hoped for must possess. Because the object of hope appears as good, the subject tends toward it by love. This love takes the special form of desire because the good is future, in the sense that it is not yet possessed. Future is not to be understood here in its :relation to time, for hope and confidence can for object present or even if hoped-for event is not known with certainty. 28 For example, a penitent sinner who has been forgiven but not yet absolved, can still hope that has been pardoned, because he does not know with certainty that God has already forgiven him. So the object of hope is loved because it is good, and desired because it is absent. The object that provokes the act of hope, however, cannot be simply a good that is non-possessed, because hope rises in the irascible appetite, while love and desire are acts of the concupiscible appetite. Love and desire must precede hope, for nothing is hoped for which is not loved and desired, and thus the action of the concupiscible appetite is always presupposed in that of the irascible. 29 In order to arouse the irascible appetite, how27 Le Tilly, 0. P., L'Esperance, Saint Thomas D'Aquin, Somme Theologique (Tournai, 1950), p. 6: "Et si Ia vertu donne a I' esperance une permanence que ne comporte pas le sentiment, il reste cependant qu'elle ne se fait connaitre que par ses actes, dont les caracteres exterieurs sont frappes de Ia meme infirmite que ceux de !'esperance naturelle." •• Summa Theol., I-II, q. 40, a. l, ad 2. •• Ibid., I-II, q. 25, a. 1. 34 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN ever, the object must be not only good and non-possessed; its pursuit must also have the quality of arduousness that calls in the subject " a certain effort, and a certain raising of the spirit to the realization of the arduous good." 30 Hope, therefore, has a formal relation to difficulty, for at this point its object takes on a character essentially different from that the object of desire. Although difficulty, as such, can only impede the action of hope as a tendency toward good, it is a necessary quality of the good sought by the irascible appetite, the nature of which is to overcome difficulties, as it is the nature of concupiscible to delight good. And even for the concupiscible appetite, the difficulty, if it is conquerable, adds to the object a greater value, " un gout," 31 because the effort involved in attaining it. Hope, by a certain " erectio animi," or courage, fortifies soul against the discouragement that difficulty and uncertainty tend to evoke. This response to the arduousness its object is the characteristic of hope that finds frequent apt expression in the " Lift up your head! " of the Psalms. It differs from the courage inherent in the moral virtue of fortitude, because it is affective rather than effective. This follows from the difference in their objects: hope tends toward the difficult object to be attained, " arduum consequendum "; fortitude, toward the difficult feat to be performed, "arduum faciendum." 32 That is, hope braces the soul against its own weakness and despondency, rather than disposes it to attack exterior obstacles. Then, too, the courage of hope strengthens the soul in the pursuit of good, while that of fortitude assists in the attack against eviL When hope is intense, this courage produces daring 33 which, though not a part of hope, is numbered among its effects. 34 Thus the soul responds to a difficult good that it does not possess by desire and courage. 30 Ibid. 31 Le Tilly, op. cit., p. 196. 82 De Potentia, q. 6, a. 9, ad 11: "Ad undecimum dicendum quod objectum spei est arduum consequendum, non autem arduum faciendum." •• Summa Theol., I-II, q. 45, a. 3, ad 2. •• Ibid., ad 8. THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 3.5 The act of is not complete, however, unless the soul sees the difficult good as possible of attainment and can thereby toward it with confidence, no man hopes for is impossible, no matter much he may desire it. 35 The formality of the act of hope, therefore, arises from the possibility its object, because a future difficult that is its opposite, impossible of attainment, evokes not despair. when the object is seen as possible does it give :rise to hope. 36 Possibility gives to object its goodness and draws the irascible appetite in pursuit; it constitutes by explaining and limitarduous good formally as an ing its other qualities, makes it an absolutely irreducible to any other species. 37 This last quality of the object of hope a with that which makes it possible. Possibility supposes a force capable vanquishing the difficulties which oppose the possession of the object. regard to the possibility hope, a two-fold movement can arise, depending on whether the is possible to the own power or another's. In the first case, the movement is one simple hope (spemre); in the second, it is better characterised as expectation (expectare) .38 This, however, is not a specific difference, because the fact that the subject looks for help outside himself contributes nothing new to the act, neither energy to the tendency, nor certitude to the resulL Neither does it affect the object. Expectation differs from simple hope only an acci•• Ibid., q. 40, a. 1. 36 Ill Sent., d. 26, q. £, a. 3, ad 1: "Sed quia voluntas est possibilium et impossibilium; neque aliquis operatur propter aliquid quod est impossibile adipisci, quamvis illud appetat: ideo oportet quod voluntas ad hoc quod operari incipiat, tendat in illud sicut in possibile et haec inclinatio voluntatis tendentis in bonum aeternum quasi possibile sibi per gratiam, est actus spei." 37 Le Tilly, op. cit., p. 197: "C'est cette possibilite qui donne a l'objet sa bonte actuelle, et a Ia difficult!\ l'attrait special qui ebranle l'irascible vers la poursuite. La possibilite, caractere dernier de !'objet, le constitue formellement comme objet, explique et limite ses autres caracteres, et fait de lui un objet absolument irreductible a toute autre espece." 38 Summa Theol., I-H, q. 40, a. 2, ad L 36 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN in dental determination the subject, who keeps his eye not only on the good he hopes for, but also on the person from whom he looks for help. 39 The distinction is important, however, insofar as it serves to constitute the theological virtue of hope as expectant hope, because its object far exceeds the power of the subject and makes him look outside himself for the assistance that will make the object possible. The possibility of the object, moreover, enables one to hope for it with confidence, which is so closely allied to hope that it is often used interchangeably with it. " Such confidence we have, through Christ towards God, not that we are sufficient to think anything of ourselves, as of ourselves, but our sufficiency is from God." 40 St. Thomas, however, assures us that confidence itself does not denote a virtue, but rather a certain mode 41 This hope, i. e., hope strengthened by a strong strong opinion may be based on our another's promise, (whence its name, "confides"), or it may denote the hope of observed in ourhaving something because of what we selves or in others.'" St. Thomas is careful to specify that the object must possible or probable, but not necessarily certain. 43 It is quality of mere possibility which gives to the certitude of hope its unique character. It is not the same as the absolute certiU1de of faith/' which banishes doubt from the intellect, although hope is certain because faith is certain. The certitude of hope is rather an affective certitude which is opposed to mistrust or hesitation.' 5 The contrast between certitude imparts and that derived from hope can be observed in the 39 Ibid. H Cor. 3: 4-5. 41 Summa Theol., II-II, q. a. 6, ad 3. 42 Ibid., a. 6. •• Ibid., I-II, q. 67, a. 4, ad 3. 44 Council of Trent, sess. VI, cap. 13, DB 806: "Nemo sibi certi aliquid absoluta certitudine polliceatur, tametsi in Dei auxilio firmissimam spem collocare et reponere omnes debent." 45 Ill Sent., d. :w, q. 2, a. 4: "Q.uia certitudini fidei opponitur dubitatio; certitudini autem spei opponitur diffidentia vel haesitatio." 40 THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 37 firmness by which a Catholic believes that if he dies in the state of grace he will be saved, and hopes that he will die in the state of grace. In other words, the certitude of hope consists in the firmness and determination of the will to attain salvation 46 and not in the determination of a judgment that he will be saved. 47 This limitation is necessary in the certitude of hope, not because there is any uncertainty or deficiency in God's power or mercy, in which hope places its trust and on which we can rely with absolute confidence, but man is able through his free will to place an obstacle to the reception of grace. In other words, while the promise of the assistance of grace is absolute, the promise of salvation is conditionaJ.48 The genus of hope, therefore, is established from the essential qualities of the hoped-for object. 4 & If the object lacks any of these special characteristics, it will evoke not hope, but some related act. An evil object will call forth fear .•Joy follows if the good is present to the subject. If the good is future, but easy to attain, simple desire is the response of the soul. However, if the difficulty is so great as to be considered impossible of attainment, it will be despaired of rather than hoped for. The object of hope, whether it be considered as a passion or a virtue, must be a future good, difficult, but possible to attain. 50 •• Harent, " Esperance," DTC col. 613. •• On this point the Council of Trent (Sess. VI) denied the Protestant contention that we can and must be altogether certain of our salvation. The horror with which the initial Protestant position regarded the pursual of meritorious works was reflected in their denial of any hope of reward. They therefore identified faith and confidence (fiducia) and made hope rather an act of the intellect than of the will. Since man could not hope for blessedness through good works, the only thing left was to believe most firmly in the divine mercy and promises. Hope, then, had to have the absolute certitude of faith. Joseph F. Delany, "Hope,"' Catholic Encyclopedia (1913), VII, 466. •• Summa Theol., II-II, q. 18, a. 4, ad 3. •• Ibid., I-II, q. 54, a. Garrigou-Lagrange, op. cit., p. 13: "Habitus et actus specificantur et specie diversificantur ab objecto formali." •• Ibid., q. 40, a. 1. 38 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN level, the passion under the influence of grace, tending divine good, future because of the divine arduous because of the divine eminence and possible because of divine help. 53 Light will be shed on the nature of hope as a virtue by investigating its special role in the theological trio. St. Thomas 51 62 Ibid., q. 63, a. 3. Ibid., q. 62, a. 3. 53 Joannis a S. Thoma, Tractatus de Spe, Cursus Theologicus (Paris, 1886), VII, Q. 17, disp., IV, a. 1, n. 3. THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 89 bases the "deduction" of three distinct virtues on two ciples: the faculty from which the acts of the virtue proceed and the mode by which they adhere to the object. By the first deduction, he considers the intellect ordained to supernatural beatitude by faith; and the will, by hope and love. Faith gives us knowledge of our supernatural goal, presenting it as both good and possible of attainment, while by hope the will tends toward the good seen as possible and becomes conformed to it in the union of love. 54 Although in the natural order, the very nature of the will suffices to direct it toward its end, both as to the intention of the end and its conformity to it, 55 when the will strives for its Supernatural End, no power of its nature is adequate and the human appetite needs a virtue to enable it both to tend toward this end and to be conformed to it. 56 Moreover, these two acts are distinct, since the soul can tend to God by hope without being united to Him by charity, 57 for the act of hope is to expect future beatitude, whether from merits already possessed or from merits to be acquired in the future. This latter act, springing from unformed hope, is not presumption, for by it one hopes without charity to obtain salvation through charity, but not to obtain beatitude without charity. 58 Elsewhere, St. Thomas gives the special function of the three virtues, which each in its own way unite us to God, as: Faith is necessary, which causes the end to- be known; and hope, through which one is confident of attaining the last end, as something possible for the agent; and charity, which makes the end appear as a good for him who strives after it, inasmuch as it causes him to love it; otherwise he would never strive after it. 59 This manner of deduction makes us see the two sources from which hope takes its origin. It has an origin of knowledge •• Summa Theol., q. 62, a. 8. •• Ibid., ad 1. 56 Ibid., ad 1 and 8. •• Ibid., q. 65, a. 4. 58 Garrigou-Lagrange, op. cit., p. 7; also I-II, q. 62, a. 4, ad 2. 50 III Sent., d. 28, q. 1, a. 5. 40 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN derived from faith which makes us know the supernatural end to which God has called us and the supernatural helps promised to those who ask for them. In this sense, faith is the foundation of hope 60 as it is the foundation of the whole process of justification. The judgment of possibility which faith supplies produces the confidence that is so characteristic of hope. More important still, hope has origins of affection, by which we desire God for ourselves, for good is never hoped for unless it be desired and loved. Thus, knowing God by faith and desiring the good that comes through Him, the soul begins to love God 61 and obey His commandments. The formal motive of charity, God loved for his own sake, ennobles the imperfect love of concupiscence by referring it to His greater glory and purifying it of all disordered love of self. Then the soul by hope relies upon Him more and more, abandoning itself to His infinite goodness and mercy as a friend; 62 it thereby comes to love Him more, not only because of the benefits He bestows or promises, but also because He is good in Himself and better than His gifts. Thus there is a mutual interaction between hope and charity. 63 Hope by making the soul dependent on God's goodness leads it to love Him for His own sake. Charity, on the other hand, perfects hope, not only by making it meritorious, but also by freeing it from its imperfections by which it confides too much in human help or remissly in divine. The second " deduction " St. Thomas makes of the theological virtues brackets faith and hope according to their imperfect Hebrews 11 : 1. Summa Theol., I-II, q. 62, a. 4, ad 8. •• Ibid., II-II, q. 17, a. 8, corpus et ad 2. •• L'Abbe Combes in his penetrating analysis, "The Spirituality of St. Therese," (New York: Kenedy, p. 81) thus describes the reciprocal influence of the theological virtues in the life of the young Carmelite, whose genius in spiritual science L'Abbe Combes compares to the genius of St. Thomas in metaphysics and theology: "The trial was continuous and in two phases: the first, in which her faith and her hope defended, enlightened, purified, strengthened and preserved her love; the second, the shorter, in which her love, now arrived at its perfection and unshakably centred in its divine object, in its turn saves her faith and her hope. Thus did Therese attain, ... to a condition analogous to her starting point, but now purified from all mere sentiment and very nigh to heaven." 60 81 THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 41 mode of adherence to the object and further highlights the perfection of charity in this respect. Faith and hope adhere to the object as to a principle from which certain things accrue to us. Thus, faith makes us adhere to God as the source of truth, and hope makes us adhere to Him as the source of good. But by charity we adhere to God for His own sake. 64 By this deduction is seen the :real superiority of charity. This deduction is very near the heart of the question whether hope is a species belonging to the genus of concupiscible love or whether it is a distinct genus in its own right, merely presupposing the desire of God. If St. Thomas this article meant to establish the mode of adherence to the object as the absolute distinction between hope and charity, he would seem to approve of the inclusion of hope the genus of desire, especially if one considers it in conjunction with article 8, where, in giving the order of hope and charity according to their generation, he elaborates upon the perfect love of charity and the imperfect love to which hope pertains. This latter article, connects hope imperfect purpose establishing the superiority of charity and does not necessarily identify the two. Article 6, however, does present the mode of adherence to the object as a means of distinguishing hope from charity, but St. Thomas clearly specifies that by hope the subject adheres to the object in a mode peculiar to the virtue of hope, that is, by reliance on divine assistance to attain the good, and not merely by desire of that good. By hope we tend to God as the source of perfect goodness, and so God is the final cause of our hoping. But hope, which, even as a virtue, regards a difficult object, is formally caused by trust in divine assistance, which makes the object possible. This deduction, therefore, does not mean that hope is the acquisition of happiness o:r the desire for it; hope is rather reliance on God's help to attain this beatitude. The union with God produced by hope is the confidence we have in His helping power, 65 •• Summa Theol., II-II, q. 17, a. 8. 65 Ibid., a. 6, ad 3. 42 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN It is this close connection of hope concupiscible love that occasioned the attacks of Protestants, Jansenists and Quietists against this In opposing these heresies, it was necessary that the desire for a supernatural reward, whether as hope or as concupiscible love, be established theologically and canonically as both good and necessary, The love of concupiscence which pertains to hope is in no way inordinate since it desires no created reward, only the possession of God, and this only as ordained to God. By it I desire God for myself (mihi) for sake of God (propter Deurn) . It is, nevertheless, distinct from charity, although it tends to God as the last end and for God's sake. Charity loves God formally for His own sake (formaliter pmpter Deum) ; concupiscence loves God finally for His own sake (final iter propter Deum) . In other words, by concupiscible love, I desire salvation only as it i.s good for myself (ut bene sit solum mihi), while by charity, I desire salvation not only as good for me, but also that God may be glorified (non solus ut bonum nobis, sed ut bonum Deo) .56 Thus the love concupiscence for has a twofold relation to charity: antecedently, by which we desire God as our highest Good, and consequently, as a secondary act of charity, by which we desire God in a perfect manner, referring our salvation to Him as a friend, loved more than ourselves. 67 St. Thomas therefore says: " Hope presupposes a desire and is intermediate between love and desire." 68 God is loved by the love of concupiscence for the sake of something else (propter aliud) only in the sense in which the less perfect subject loves the Supreme Good by which he is perfected (propter finem ctti) . This is the sense of the words of the Creed: "Qui propter nos homines descendit de coeliso" The Incarnation is greater than our redemption and cannot be ordained to it as a means subordinated to an end. But in God's mercy, the Incarnation is ordained to our redemption as an eminent cause to its effect and to us as a perfectible object •• Garrigou-Lagrange, •• Ibid., p. 386. •• Ill Sent., d. q. op. cit., p. 3i'll. a. 3, q. ll. THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 43 on which God bestows His favor. 69 Thus, the love of chaste concupiscence seeks a reward, not so much as a reward, but, as Billuart says, we wish to see God that we may glorify Him eternally, being so disposed, that even if there were no beatitude to be hoped for, we would love and serve Him none the less.70 These two " deductions " of the theological virtues show a clearcut distinction between faith and hope, by reason of the active principles from which they proceed. But the distinction between hope and charity is not nearly so decisive, since both are acts of the will tending toward the Infinite Good. The ultimate specification of hope, therefore, can be arrived at only by a consideration of its formal object. As a theological virtue its object can be nothing less than God Himself, 71 which it has in common with faith and charity. The specification of their "habitus," therefore, will be determined not by a real difference in their objects, but by the different aspects under which God, the Supernatural End, is viewed and attained by them.' 2 The Specification of Hope Hope as expectation has a two-fold object: the good for which one hopes (quod) and the help by which that good becomes possible (quo) .73 Hope is directed toward eternal beatitude and all things necessary to attain it, e. g., grace, our daily sustenance. But everything created that is sought, even the beatific vision itself, is sought only that we might possess God Himself. Therefore, God to be possessed is the principal object, which arouses the movement of hope, orientates it and •• Garrigou-Lagrange, op. cit., p. " Sic Incamatio altior est redemptione nostra, et ideo ad redemptionem non ordinatur, ut medium subordinatum, ad finem cuius gratia, sed ex misericordia ad redemptionem ordinatur ut causa enimens ad effectum et ad nos ut ad finem, cui Deus vult gratiam scil. ad finem perfectibilem, non perfectivum." •• Cited by Garrigou-Lagrange, op. cit., p. 471: "intendimus videre Deum, ut eum in aeternum glorificemus, sic affectu, ut si nulla esset beatitudo speranda, nihilominus diligeremus ilium atque illi serviremus." 71 Summa Theol., I-IT, q. a. 1. u Ibid., II-II, q. 17, a. 6, ad I. 78 Ibid., a. 7. 44 SISTER MARY MICHAEL GLENN terminates iL It differs specifically from the object of charity, which is God lovable in Himself, and from that of simple desire, in that hope regards its object not merely as ou:r Supreme Good that is infinitely desirable, but as the supreme arduous good 74 which is impossible to any created power" Whatever makes this arduous good possible, therefore, will provide the ultimate formality of Christian hope. Divine assistance provides the essential reason for hoping; it thereby animates, sustains, directs, and therefore specifies, hope. 75 This intrinsic relation of the tendency of hope to the means by which its object is obtained can be observed in a sick man who desires health because it is good, but hopes for it because he relies on effective medicines or skillful doctors. Just as faith does not have the aspect of a theological virtue unless it adheres to the testimony of the First Truth, so hope, also, takes its specification as a virtue from the fact that it relies on the help of divine power to attain eternal life. It would be a vicious act, and opposed to the virtue of hope, to rely upon human or one's own power did Pelagians) to attain the perfect good. Garrigou-Lagrange expresses this principle in modern terms: The formal object of faith is the Fh·st Truth, by reason of which one gives assent to those things which are believed, and which constitute the materia! object of faith, so the formal object of hope is the help of divine power and mercy, on account of which the motion of hope tends toward the hoped-for goods which are its material object. 76 74 Ill Sent., d. 26, q. 2, a. £, ad 2: "Et secundum hoc spes est in homine principium omnium operationum quae ad bonum arduum ordinantur, sicut caritas omnium quae in bonum tendunt, et sicut fides omnium quae ad cognitionem pertinent." 75 Summa Theol., II-II, q. 17, a. l: "Inquantum igitur sperarnus aliquid ut possibile nobis per divinum auxilium, spes nostra attingit ad ipsum Deum, cujus auxilio innititur "; and a. 6: " Spes autem facit Deo adhaerere prout est nobis principium perfectae bonitatis: inquantum scilicet per spem divino auxilio innitimur ad beatitudinem obtinendam." 76 Garrigou-Lagrange, op. cit., p. 328. THE THOMISTIC AND SCOTISTIC CONCEPTS OF HOPE 45 In words, we hope to obtain God by the help of God, just as by faith we believe in Him because of Him. 77 Hope, therefore, is characterised by our reliance on God's help (Deus auxiliam), for we are not able to hope for beatitude with firm confidence except from him who we know is able and willing to give it. God alone can give eternal life and He must be willing to do so, for He promised to give it to those who believe in Christ 78 and He commands us to strive for it. For as the Council of Trent says, rephrasing St. Augustine, " God does not command the impossible, but commanding, urges us to do what is possible to our own power, and to ask for what is not, and then He helps that it may be possible." 79 In other words, the only reason for hoping that we shall enjoy beatitude is because God can give and wishes to give it to us. Moreover God is the only source of this assistance that brings us to beatitude, for the order of the agent must correspond to the order of the end, and only the supreme and supernatural agent can lead us to the ultimate supernatural end. God's help may be transmitted to us by the sacred humanity of the Savior and by Mary, the Dispensatrix of all grace, but the formal motive of theological hope is God always willing to help (Dieu toujours secourable), according to His goodness, mercy, fidelity, and omnipotence. All these perfections in this order are supposed by the formal motive: Deus auxilians. 80 However, since this help has the character of an efficient cause,S1 which implies the performance of an action and the bestowal of active assistance, 82 it is to Divine Omnipotence especially that we have :recourse in the very act of hope. All presupposed things are not sufficient, however, if God is not positively 77 R. Bernard, 0. P., La Charite, Saint Thomas D'Aquin, Somme Theologique, p. 315. 78 John 3: 16. •• Cited by Council of Trent, DB 804. 80 R. Garrigou-lLagrange, 0. P., La Synthese Th meaning rule of behavior and religion from religio meaning bond, i. e., the bonds which tie mankind to its creator. The author's discussion of God as a father-image (p. 37 fl'.) seems to overlook the frequently overlooked fact that God's authoritarianism is only a corollary which follows from His nature as a self-existent being. To equate God with authority is to lose the whole point of proof for the existence of God. Authority, eternity, infinity, transcendence, etc., aU follow from self-existence. Again, the discussion of imagination is extremely difficult to understand because the author does not set forth definitions or clarifications. He simply begins to discuss imagination. (p. 55) When he is speaking of the role of imagination in conjunction with intellect he is not too certain in his exposition. When the intellect is working, imagination is usually furnishing sense images to accompany the act of intellection. But the sense images need not be those of objects-they may be merely words. For example, in my own case, when I hear the BRIEF NOTICES 118 principle of identity enunciated I usually see the words printed on a page or on a blackboard: " A thing which is itself, is itself." On page 57 the author seems to confuse the roles of sense memory and imagination. On this same page, in discussing space relationship Doctor Biddle fails to mention that the imagination is controlled by the intellect. His notions of imagination at times approach those of David Hume. On page 59 the author's failure to define emotion leaves the reader at a disadvantage. He fails to distinguish between emotion and feeling. In fact he equates the two which adds to the confusion in this section of the book. On page 61 the author states: "Logical thinking is possible only when phantasy life is in order and under the guidance of the intellect." This is a good example of the many sentences which are difficult to understand. What he probably means by logical thinking is " thinking which is compatible with reality." Any logician knows that a syllogism could be constructed on premises which were unreal and which would lead to a perfectly logical conclusion insofar as the conclusion followed consistently from the premises. On page 67 there is another similar faulty expression: " The act of taking the life of a human being is, in itself, neither good nor bad." The author seems to deny any basis of morality in the natural law and makes morals a matter of local custom. " Behavior is good when it is directed toward goals which are socially or individually regarded as good, or toward the improvement or annihilation of that which is considered bad. The means by which the goal is attained must also be regarded as good." (p. 67) These are a few examples cited from many possibilities which show the difficulties of easy reading of the book. There are numerous minor inaccuracies, e. g., on page 10 it is stated that there are 6,500 psychiatrists in the United States which is about one-half the actual number. The author states that his theory of depth psychology was verified for him in a dream. He states in a footnote (p. 37-38): "While I was in the process of trying to correlate the concept of the phantastic bad mother with an analogous religious concept I had a significant dream. . . . The dream terrified me so that I awoke .... On going back to sleep the continuity of the symbols was the same, but this time I was hovering over a deep pit .... Upon awakening I realized that at last I had found a solution to my problem." It is of such dream stuff that Doctor Biddle's theory is made. The author's own theory of depth psychology which had its confirmation in his dream is based on the following ideas of the child's relations with his parents. In the author's own words this theory briefly is as follows: " The small child under age three views his parents and other adults as gigantic, all-powerful people. They can do infinite good or infinite harm to him. In the child's mind the parents have the power to gratify every 114 BRIEF NOTICES wish, or to annihilate him. But according to the logic of the child, a good person cannot do anything bad, and a bad person can do no good. When the father gratifies the child, the parent is regarded as ail-good; when he frustrates or displeases the child he becomes totally bad in the mind of the child. The child does not regard the gratifying father and the frustrating father as the same person. The same is true in the relationship of the child and the mother. Besides being real people the parents represent phantastic, illusory, or imaginary persons. The child, then, has, in addition to his real parents, a phantastic father and mother who are preposterously good, and a phantastic father and mother who are preposterously bad. No real person could ever hope to be as good as the phantastic good parents. The real parents, when invested with the qualities of the phantastic parents, become alternately extremely good or bad depending upon whether they are at the moment pleasing or displeasing to the child. The preposterous phantasies of the child are in a constant state of flux. When his gigantic real mother pleases and satisfies the child she is endowed with all the preposterous good qualities of the imaginary good mother. When she deprives or frustrates him she becomes in his imagination an annihilating bad mother. The real father is treated in a similar manner. When he does something which the child thinks of as good, the father is regarded as preposterously ail-good. When he is frustrating he becomes preposterously bad in the child's imagination." The .author himself raised the question as to whether his theories are merely gratuitous assumptions or whether they can be proven scientifically. He does not answer this question but states merely that they have proven practical as a means of therapy. His theory of the influence of childhood experiences which covers some twenty-one pages in the book is offered without any supporting evidence or attempted proof. In the opinion of this reviewer the author has failed to achieve his purpose. From the standpoint of scholastic philosophy the discussion is weak and at times faulty. From the standpoint of depth psychology nothing helpful is added and no attempt at proof is made. From the standpoint of at least the Catholic Religion the religious views presented are on the whole unacceptable. Beatitude. By REGINALD GARRIGOU-LAGRANGE,0. P. Translated by Patrick Cummins, 0. S. B. St. Louis: B. Herder Book Co., 1956. Pp. 381 with index. $6.00. In these days when we are reaping the fruit of philosophical relativism in ethical nihilism, it is of absolute necessity that we review constantly that philosophy of life which alone can perfect man socially, and that BRIEF NOTICES 115 theology which alone can show man the road to eternal life. It is therefore without hesitancy that we hail this translation of Fr. GarrigouLagrange's On Beatitude, Human Acts and Habits, which is his commentary on the first fifty-four questions of St. Thomas' Prima Secundae. The venerable figure of the author needs no introduction to Thomistic circles. Grown old in the fight to present St. Thomas in himself and not in the trappings of nineteenth century experimentalism, Fr. GarrigouLagrange has rendered signal service to Thomism, the Church, and to all who strive to preserve their sanity and integrity in an intellectual world gone mad. Yet, although we heartily welcome this most recent contribution by the eminent theologian, let us not err by excess, lest by injudicious zeal we betray the author's intention. This book is certainly a compilation of Fr. Garrigou-Lagrange's class notes for his lectures on the Prima Secundae. Since, then, their origin cannot be divorced from the text of the Summa, surely their purpose is not that they should be used as a text-book or manual apart from the same Summa Theologiae of the Holy Doctor. For thus to make use of this volume would be to render a grave disservice to the student of moral theology, and a betrayal of the author's life-long dedication to the Saint of the Schools. Used with the words of St. Thomas, the student or reader will benefit greatly from the explanations of more abstruse passages, the inclusion of positive theology, the opinions and controversies that have arisen, and the traditional interpretation of St. Thomas in their regard. This is the value and wisdom of Fr. GarrigouLagrange's Beatitude. In his commentary the author simply follows the course of the Prima Secundae from question one to question fifty-four. There is prefixed an introduction in which Fr. Garrigou-Lagrange exposes the nature of Moral Theology in its connection with the dogmatic part of the one science, as well as its relationship with other moral systems. Then he treats of beatitude as man's ultimate goal and purpose. Human acts are considered in their psychological and moral entities. Next is inserted a section on conscience, its nature and divisions, which summarizes the considerations of manuals in practical moral theoolgy. Finally there is a brief treatment of passions and habits. This is a work that could prove of inestimable value to the student or scholar, layman or cleric, who wishes to discover through the eyes of St. Thomas the true notion of moral theology and the only sane explanation of man. For this thanks are due to Fr. Cummins who has faithfully, if at times too literally, translated the amazingly clear latin of Fr. GarrigouLagrange. 116 BRIEF NOTICES The Role of the Laity in the Church. By MoNSIGNOR GERARD Chicago: Fides Publishers Association, 1956. Pp. 175. PHILIPS. Fathers Gilbert and Moudry have performed a real service for American Catholicism in translating this work of Monsignor Philips. The book is one that does not contain much that is new, yet it is a synthesis that is not readily available in English. Profound and extensive in treatment is this product of a speculative theologian, professor of dogmatic and mystical theology at the University of Louvain, and promoter of Catholic Action. That this is the hour of the the prelate establishes. He then proceeds to lay down the principles of Catholic Action, applying them to the laity's field of action. The chapter on the laity's power of Orders is thorough, but scientifically silent on many practical questions. The treatment of the laity and the magisterium is as concise and deep as any scholar could wish for. When dealing with the laity and Church government the author gives helpful indications for cooperation between the hierarchy and faithful. Catholic Action is something that never took hold in the United States as it did in the Belgium of Monsignor Philips, yet the chapter dealing with it is something that could benefit every active Catholic and worthy priest. The chapter on the Lay Apostolate and Allied Contacts sheds needed light on Church and State relations. The chapter concerning a lay spirituality leaves admittedly much to be demanded as does the conclusion. From this book every American cleric, religious, and intelligent layman could profit. It evinces a intellectual insight and prudential approach which we need in the United States in order to come of age or continue to flourish. This broad-mindedness is a reproach to a theology that is as narrow as a paper bound catechism. The jacket of the book states that it is theological not sociological. Y at Philips himself writes on page fourteen: " Our starting point is not purely sociologicaL" There is much of a sound sociological nature in this work. There is a noticeable lack of reference to an awakening of the laity in the United States. The interest shown in real theology the laity is proven by the success of the theological institutes conducted by the Dominicans in many places in the United States, by the Conventual Franciscans in Richfield, Minnesota, and the Institute of Adult Education at Catholic University. The students at the institutes are proving what Monsignor Philips writes on page 79: "No sincere intellectual will be content with a grammar school acquaintance of the vital questions, nor will anyone expect encyclopedic knowledge from him. The intelligence of an adult Christian is all that is required." A recurring theme in the work is the fact that theology is hard work because it must seek the truth avoiding extremes. BRIEF NOTICES 117 The translators deserve a word of praise as well as thanks. They have rendered a very readable translation and have given the data for English translations of foreign language references when possible. What is Catholicity? By PAUL H. HALLETT. Cleveland and New York: The World Publishing Company, 1955. Pp. Q54. This relatively slender volume, whose purpose in the words of its author is " to explain the principles that guide Catholicity and interlace its doctrine, worship, and discipline," (p. 30) contains a veritable mine of information about Catholicism. In the pursuance of his plan Paul H. Hallett, Associate Editor of The Register of Denver, states that he has closely followed Catholic textbooks on philosophy, moral and dogmatic theology used in seminaries for the training of priests. The range of topics covered is indeed wide, including the meaning of Catholicity, the origin and nature of the Church, "Catholic philosophy," Scripture, Dogma, Morals, the Sacraments, and Church Government. Plainly intended for the interested layman, Catholic as well as nonCatholic, and not for the professional scholar, the work necessarily runs very hurriedly through some points. Yet, some of the sections are noteworthy for their clarity and succinctness as well as for their accuracy. Of particular note in this regard are those dealing with the Commandments (Ch. XIV), Matrimony (Ch. XVII), and Tolerance (Ch. XX). However, the approach to many serious and profound matters is frequently simpliste and this detracts from the effect of the work. Chapter III, entitled "Between Faith and Reason: Thomism," undertakes an explanation of some of the fundamental philosophical tenets of Thomism, and it is here that the basic weakness of the work becomes apparent. Referring to Thomism as " simply sublimated common sense," the author insists that once a reader has become familiar with the technical terms of Aquinas " he will never fail to understand his meaning." (p. 53) Such optimism, though laudable in intent, can hardly impress those who have long sought correctly to interpret the teachings of the Angelic Doctor. Moreover, it is discouraging to see a recurrence of the equation of Thornism with Scholasticism and to find it defined as " the philosophy elaborated by Aristotle and perfected in the service of Christian truth." (p. 5!2) The discussion of some of the leading philosophical principles of Thomism is so compressed as to be almost unintelligible and is not calculated to impress favourably the careful reader. What, for example, are we to make of such a passage: " Every being is good. For every being is true, that is, is an object of the mind. A being that is not good for doing or receiving something could not be known. Moreover, every being, since it has some 118 BRIEF NOTICES degree of perfection, is desirable as an end or means, either by the human will, or at least by God as willed and approved by Him. Hence the axiom; good is being, being is good." (pp. 56-7) In connection with the problem, What is the best form of government?, there is another profoundly ambiguous and misleading statement. After stating (correctly I think) that such a question cannot be decided in the concrete by recourse to the natural law, the author goes on, without further clarification, to say: "In the abstract, however, the natural philosophy and tradition of Catholicity have certainly a preference for monarchy (in the United States the federal government is essentially a monarchy)." (p. 73) Certainly such a statement betrays "the precision of definition and tightness of logic and clarity of language " which the author holds to be the trademark of Catholic philosophy and theology. (p. 55) In the wealth of facts about Catholicism presented clearly and accurately in this work, it is perhaps not wholly fair to single out for mention some of the more obvious defects. Yet it is these defects which detract from the fulfilment of the basic aim of the book. From beginning to end this work emphasizes the reasonableness of all aspects of Catholicism, and the ease with which these reasonable aspects of our faith can be accepted and presented. Yet when some of the more fundamental problems are so ill presented in the work itself, it is difficult both to demonstrate their reasonableness or to obtain reasonable acceptance of them. Such inaccuracies as exist may have little direct ill effect upon the majority of readers of this book, those untrained in theology and philosophy, but they will gain little understanding of certain fundamental principles after a careful reading of the text. And those who have some training in theology or philosophy, whether Catholic or non-Catholic, cannot but be disappointed or pressed at these serious shortcomings. Perhaps a future edition of the work can correct or eliminate such portions as tend to defeat the basic and highly laudable purpose of such a book. BOOKS RECEIVED Bouyer, Rev. Lo·.1.is (tr. by A. V. Littledale). The Spirit and Forms of Protestantism. Westminster: Newman, 1956. Pp. 245. $8.75. Bruckberger, 0. P., Raymond Leopold. Toward the Summit. New York: P. J. Kenedy & Sons, 1956. Pp. 150. $2.75. Brunner, S. J., August (tr. by Ruth Mary Bethell). A New Creation. . New York: Philosophical Library, 1956. Pp. 148. $4.75. Ellis, John Tracy. American Catholics and the Intellectual Life. Chicago: The Heritage Foundation, 1956. Pp. 68 with index of Proper Names. $1.25. Ferm, Vergilius. Encyclopedia of Morals. New York: Philos. Library, 1956. Pp. 669. $10.00. Glutz, C. P., Melvin A. The Manner of Demonstrating in Natural Philosophy. Des Moines: St. Gabriel Monastery, 1956. Pp. 197. $8.00. Heinisch, Dr. Paul (tr. by Wm. G. Heidt, 0. S. B.). Christ in Prophecy. Collegeville; Minn.; The Liturgical Press, 1956. Pp. 277 with index. $6.00. Hourani, George F. Ethical Value. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1956. Pp. 275. $4.50. Johnston, Herbert. Business Ethics. New York: Pitman Publishing Co., 1956. Pp. 864 with index. $4.75. Kelly, David. The Hungry Sheep. Westminster: Newman, 1956. Pp. 260 with bibliography. $4.00. Leeming, S. J., Bernard. Principles of Sacramental Theology. Westminster: Newman, 1956. Pp. 704 with index. $6.75. McKenzie, S. J., John L. The Two-Edged Sword. Milwaukee: Bruce, 1956. Pp. 817 with index. $4.50. Marcel, Gabriel (tr. by Virginia and Gordon Ringer). Royce's Metaphysics. Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., 1956. Pp. 198 with notes. $4.50. Michalson, Carl (ed.). Christianity and the Existentialists . . New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1956. Pp. 219 with index. $8.75. Murphy, 0. Carm., Roland E. The Dead Sea Scrolls and the Bible. Westminster: Newman, 1956. Pp. II9. $1.50. Pontificia Universidad Ecclesiastica de Salamanca. El Evolucionismo en Filosfia y Teologia. Barcelona: Juan Flors, 1956. Pp. 252. Revesz, G. The Origins and Prehistory of Language. New York: Philosophical Library, 1956. Pp. 288 with index. $7.50. Sciacca, M. F. Saint Augustin et le Neoplatonisme. Louvain: Editions Nauwelaerts, 1956. Pp. 69. 65 Frs. b. 119 120 BOOKS RECEIVED Simard, Emile. La Nature et la Portee de la Method Scientifique. Quebec: Les Presses Universitaires Laval, 1956. Pp. 408 with index. St. Thomas Aquinas (tr. by Pierre Conway, 0. P.) Exposition of the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle. Quebec: La Librairie PhiL M. Doyon, 1956. Pp. 449 with index. $6.00 paper. Tamme, 0. P., Sr. Anne Mary. A Critique of John Dewey's Theory of Fine Art in the Light of the Principles of Thomism; Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1956. Pp. 139 with index. Todd, John M. (ed.). The Springs of Morality. New York: The Macmillan Co., 1956. Pp. 327. $6.00. Toynbee, Arnold J. An Historian's Approach to Religion. New York: Oxford University Press, 1956. Pp. 327 with index. $5.00. Van Laer, P. Henry in collaboration with Koren, C. S. Sp., Henry J. Philosophy of Science. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University, HM6. Pp. 180 with index. $3.75 bound, $3.00 paper. Weiser, S. J., F. X. The Holyday Book. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co., 1956. Pp. 208 with index. $3.00.