THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDIToRs: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PRoVINCE OF ST. JoSEPH Publishers: VoL. XXI The Thomist Press, Washington 17, D. C. OCTOBER, 1958 No.4 SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOl\fAS A concept of consciousness would seem to be an Integral part of a theory of knowledge as well as a crucial element in any theory of human nature. Our capacity to know ourselves is necessarily bound up inextricably with the question of our capacity to know in general, and in turn underlies many such problems as those of self-realization and the validity of self-criticism, the nature of psychological personality, the foundation of ethics and morality, and other related points. Traditionally accepted as an evident object of psychological study, both by philosophers and early empirical psychologists, the notion of consciousness began to suffer a certain diminution in the latter half of the nineteenth century, until in some schools of thought its reality came to be wholly denied. At the same time, through the influence of psychoanalysis, the 415 416 MICHAEL STOCK important role of the unconscious mind was made strikingly manifest, and the question of the respective influence of conscious and unconscious motivation became a central issue in psychology and ethics. At the present time, with the reality of consciousness generally accepted again, and some of the early over-statements of the force of the unconscious somewhat modified, the time seems ripe for an extensive investigation of the relationships obtaining between the conscious and unconscious spheres of men's minds. In this context, it seems useful to state more fully the ideas on consciousness held by St. Thomas, not only because his insights are hound to be of value in discussing current problems, but also because such doctrine should be explicitly understood if many of the implications of Thomistic psychology and moral theology are to be fully appreciated. Certainly many aspects of the doctrine of consciousness have been treated in one form or another, but, so far as I know, there is no complete and exhaustive statement. In working towards such a statement, it seems useful to sketch first, as in general outline, a broader conspectus of the points which will have to be raised and solved before an integral statement can be offered. For the sake of analysis, the matter may be divided under three main headings; the questions of strictly sense consciousness, the questions of purely intellectual consciousness, and the questions of intellectual reflection on the senses. Our immediate purpose here is to raise and discuss some of the problems involved in sense consciousness. By way of preliminary notes, some of the ambiguity which attaches itself to the notion of consciousness should be removed. In common usage, consciousness often means nothing more than knowledge, for instance, when we ask someone whether or not he was conscious of some noise or sight. For St. Thomas, however, consciousness always had a note of cognitive complexity about it; it was knowJedge as applied to something. 1 1 " Nomen enim conscientiae significat applicationem scientiae ad aliquid; unde conscire dicitur quasi simul scire." De Ve:rit., q. 17, a. l; cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 79, a. 18; ll Sent., d. q. a. 4. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 417 In the moral order, it was knowledge applied to deliberate actions as they measured up to or failed to measure up to rules of reason and Faith; what is today called conscience. This moral consciousness was necessarily founded on psychological consciousness, which, in its strictest sense, was knowledge of knowledge, or the awareness of an act of knowledge. It thus involved two elements-an apprehension of some knowable object and a separate cognitive realization that that object was apprehended. By extension, however, the word " consciousness " could be used to signify the things of which one has consciousness, that is, the things known which are known to be known. 2 By extension, again, in another direction, ness may signify the· act of being aware of other psychological states or operations besides those which are cognitive, that is, the actual awareness of emotions, feelings, performances and the like. Under this aspect, the object of consciousness goes on to include, and indeed as a most important and central and in a sense essential element, the awareness of the knowing self, for consciousness reaches its perfection when the knower is revealed to himself in his act of knowledge and in his other vital actions. 8 Consciousness, for St. Thomas, always indicates an operation, never a habit or power. States of consciousness are more or less continuous series of acts of consciousness, and may vary in duration, intensity, clarity, extension, distinctness and in other qualities, ranging from total unconsciousness as in comas, through various grades of partial consciousness, to alert attention. For consciousness is by no means a homogeneous state of activity opposed simply to unconsciousness; men seem rather to live in a state of more or less fluid balance between conscious and unconscious motivations, thoughts, drives, emotions, judgments, moods and persuasions. A valid description, therefore, • " Quandoque enim conscientia sumitur pro ipsa re conscita . • . Dlud quidem secundum usum loquentium esse videtur ut conscientia quandoque pro re conscita accipiatur, ut cum dicitur: Dicam tibi conscientiam meam; id est quod. est in conscientia mea." De Verit., q. 17, a. I. • Ibid., q. 1, a. 9. 418 MICHAEL STOCK of man's mind cannot confineitself exclusively to the conscious nor to the unconscious. The problems of the mind must be set in the context of degrees, limits and qualifications, and mutual influences. In this light, the analysis of consciousness ought to be prosecuted, beginning, as seems convenient, with the lower senses in which, although the factor of actual consciousness is slight, the raw materials of all knowledge and of eventual full consciousness are prepared . .ANALYSis OF CoNSCious AcTIVITY AT THE SENSE LEVEL A. Coosciowrness of the objects and activities of the senses 1. How the external senses are involved in coosciousness Since all human knowledge begins in the senses, a reflexive examination of the functioning of human consciousness may be reasonably initiated with the analysis of the role of the external senses. External sense knowledge is not, of itself, conscious knowledge, for it does not extend beyond a simple apprehension of the sensible qualities in the environment (or within the sensing subject considered as environment with respect to the sense activity in question) . Thus it is purely awareness of other things, outward looking and saying nothing of selfawareness, simple, without depth, without organization and, in fact, not even perfectly possessed of objectivity. It is, therefore, an act of cognition but not of consciousness, entering into the order of consciousness, when it enters at all, purely as an object. For sense consciousness on the part of the external senses would involve man in knowing, by means of these senses, that he senses and what he senses-the fact and the nature of the fact. And such is not the activity of the external senses, for their own activity presents none of the factors which they themselves are ordered to apprehend. Seeing, hearing, feeling, etc., are not themselves c;olored or sounding or hard or soft objects; they are thus hidden to the external senses.4 If man, • "Sensus non sentiunt sine exterioribus sensibilibus," II de Anima, Iect. 10, 875. § 85•. Cf. lect. 12, SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 419 therefore, had only his external senses, he could apprehend well enough, but he could not know that he was apprehending. 5 2. The role of the common sense We enter for the first time into the area of consciOusness when we look to the function and activity of the common sense, for here is a faculty which can know knowledge, which can be aware of psychological activity. 6 This is evident from the words of St. Thomas concerning the functions of the common sense. " For the common sense is a certain power in which terminate the transformations of all the senses." 7 It is the power which is the root from which flow all the external senses as from an energizing source. 8 Standing thus as the common point of reference for the external senses, it knows the objects they apprehend, and knows that they apprehend them-that they are acting, and how. Therefore, it is the sense by which man senses that he senses, giving him his first awareness of his own sensitive activity, uniting and binding the various activities of the senses by consciousne.ss in the one sentient subject. 9 a". .. a (sensu communi) percipiantur intentiones sensuum; sicut cum aliquis videt se videre. Hoc enim non potest fieri per sensum proprium, qui non cognoscit nisi formam sensibilis a quo immutatur." Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4, ad • Since this is not the place for an " ex professo " treatment of St. Thomas' psychology, we will not enter into the arguments for the number and nature and functions of the various senses, unless it seems necessary for our purpose. The evidence and justification of his basic psychological conceptions belong to a more general treatise in psychology. Our purpose is satisfied when we outline the nature of consciousness as it follows from the concept of the structure of the soul as St. Thomas proposed it. 7 II de Anima, lect. 18, § 890. 8 " Attribuitur autem ista discretio tactui non secundum quod tactus est sensus proprius, sed secundum quod est fundamentum omnium sensuum, et propinquius se habens ad fontalem radicem omnium sensuum, qui est sensus communis." Ill de Anima, lect. 8, § Cf. also Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4, ad 1. 9 " Unde oportet ad sensum communem pertinere discretionis indicium ad quem referantur; sicut ad co=unem terminum, omnes apprehensiones sensuum; a quo etiam percipiantur intentiones sensuum, sicut cum aliquis videt se videre • . . a sen'su communi, qui visionem percipit." Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4, ad " Sicut in ipso homine patet quod sensus communis, qui est superior quam se11sus 420 MICHAEL STOCK Moreover, because it is the focal point of all the external senses, it is able to discriminate among them and their objects, discerning not only black from white, as the eye can do, or sweet from bitter, as the tongue can do, but also sweet from white and black from bitter, which neither tongue nor eye can do, and any sensible quality whatsoever from any other. 10 Thus St. Thomas posits two functions in the common sense: to perceive all the sensible qualities already separately apprehended by the several external senses, and to perceive them in a certain unity, for it is itself one single power, and also-presupposing the first-to discriminate among the many sensible qualities, comparing and judging them among themselves. We have, therefore, in the activity of the common sense, a truly conscious process. 11 Besides these functions of the common sense, by which it formally enters into the process of consciousness, insofar as it senses the operations of the external senses, there are two other contributions it makes to consciousness, not by being an act of consciousness, but by providing an element in the cognitive structure which is essential to consciousness in one way or another. Merely to provide material for other acts of knowledge, that is, to enter into the content of consciousness, is by no means peculiar to the common sense. What is special about its contribution in this order derives from its particular role in regard to the external senses. In the first place, the common sense is the only internal power which is in direct and immediate contact with the external senses. It is, therefore, the one power which can provide proprius, licet sit unica potentia, omnia cognoscit quae quinque sensibus exterioribus cognoscuntur .... " Ibid., I, q. 57, a. 2.-Cf. Ill de Anima, lect. 8, § 612. 10 " Quia discernimus aliqua virtute, non solum album a nigro, vel dulce ab amaro, sed etiam album a dulci, et unumquodque sensibile discernimus ab unoquoque et sentimus quod hoc sit per sensum." Ill de Anima, lect. 8, § 601. 11 It is true consciousness, but not proper According to St. Thomas, consciousness is reflective activity, which is the knowing of knowledge, and this can be twofold, proper or improper. It is proper if one power know itself or its own act, improper if one power know the act or object of another power. Cf. Ill Sent., d. 28, q. 1, a. 2, ad 8. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. •THOMAS 4!U man with data which forms the basis for distinguishing external sensations of reality from internal imaginings. This specialty of function will be investigated later in more detail, 12 and is only mentioned here to highlight its importance. For without the common sense, man might be conscious, but his consciousness would be distorted, unable to mark off clearly what comes to him from external reality and what rises from within himself subjectively. Again, the common sense refers external sensations to the sensing subject. We do not mean that the common sense is perfectly and formally aware of these acts as acts of the sensing subject. What we mean is that, by uniting the several acts of sensation arising in di.fierent organs in its own single perception, it provides an effective evidence that they are related to each other as the several facets of the activity of one sensing subject. This evidence points to the subject underlying the several sensations, if there is another sense with the power to perceive it. 13 It is probably because of this role which the common sense plays in regard to revealing the unity of the sensing subject that St. Thomas will say of its activity not merely that we know we see or hear through the common sense, but also that through its activity we know that we live, indicating not simply the effects of living but the interior fact itsel£.14 Briefly, then, to summarize what has been said of the common sense: this power in man is one which sees, hears, feels, .etc., all the sights, sounds, touches, etc., which are first sensed by the external senses. It is, as it were, an internal eye and ear and tongue and finger, possessing the sensitivity of all the other senses. Being a single receptive center for all their separate activities, it collects their several impressions into one common matrix of sense activity, in which it can discern them one from another and refer them all to the one sensing subject. Being thus oriented towards the outside reality apprehended 18 See p. 484. See p. 441. .. "Sensu enim communi percipimus nos vivere." II de Anima, lect. 18, § 890. 12 422 MICHAEL STOCK by the external senses, it provides grounds for distinguishing reality from imaginations. 3. The functions of the other internal senses There is, however, more to sense life than this. We know of images in our imagination, perceptions of the memory and of instinct. How do these pertain to consciousness? Primarily these powers give knowledge of the things we know through the external senses, but under an elaboration and an aspect proper to themselves. The imagination knows sensible objects as reproduced within the sensing subject, removed from the context of time and place, freed from the context in which they were first apprehended. Memory perceives sense objects as things belonging to a part of the past, definite or indefinite, but always as past. Its proper object is the intention of pastness, referring sensed objects to the context of things already experienced. 15 The cogitative power or particular reason, which corresponds to the power of instinct or estimation in brute animals, also apprehends an intention, the intention of singularity by which a mass of sensible data is designated as a singular quiddity or thing. 16 All of these activities belong to the content of consciousness, perceptible to anyone who engages in introspection even superficially. The question which must be raised now, however, is whether or not there is an element of subjective or active consciousness in the operations of these powers. Do they know knowledge? Before trying to answer this question it will be useful to investigate more fully the function of the internal senses. a. Imagination When man's senses apprehend some object in his enVIron16 For a discussion of St. Thomas' conception and use of " intentions," see H. D. Simonin, 0. P., "La Notion d' 'intentio' dans I' oeuvre de Saint Thomas d'Aquin," Rev. de Sc. Phil. et Theol., XIX (1980). 16 Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING T(J ST. THOMAS 428 ment and are impressed with its sensible qualities, these qualities impress not only the particular senses in question but also, and with a certain elaboration 17 the internal power of imagination/8 and in fact this may occur whether or not he is conscious of the act of sensing. 19 Once impressed in the imagination, the image is conserved as in a treasury, and can be evoked or reproduced henceforward. Thus the imagination differs from the external senses and the common sense, since these can act only in the presence of the sensible quality, and cease to act with its removal, while the imagination, once impressed with thequality sensed, can recall it even when the object originally possessing it has disappeared, thereby giving all sensible objects a kind of second life, or capacity to live and re-live for the benefit of the sensing subject. 20 Moreover, in the imagination, the objects sensed are freed from the context in which they were originally apprehended and are capable of being elaborated or of being combined among themselves in an almost unlimited variety of new formations, 21 which might exist in a reality never seen, or in no reality at all, or in a reality proposed for future accomplishment. 22 This is the functioning of the 17 " ••• una vis imaginationis se extendit ad omnia quae quinque vires sensuum cognoscunt et ad plura." l Cont. Gent., c. 65, in the middle. '"Imagination is a certain movement produced beyond the order of the external senses by their own activity. It is a "movement made by the senses in act." IV Metaphys., lect. 14, § 69S; Ill de Anima, lect. 6, § 655-659. 19 For a.n excellent description of the elements which may enter the imaginative content without having been first consciously perceived, see Le Subconscient, Iere Serie, Iere cours: Nature et Action du Subconscient, P. Reginald Omez, 0. P., 1949. (Unpublished). •• " Vis enim imaginativa est apprehensiva similitudinum corporalium, etiam rebus absentibus quarum sunt similitudines." Summa Theol., I-ll, q. 15, a. 1. 21 " Sicut etiam in speculativis aliqui sunt bene inquirentes, propter hoc quod ratio eorum prompta est ad discurrendum per diversa, quod videtur provenire ex dispositione imaginativa.e virtutis, quae de facili potest formare diversa phantasmata." Ibid., II-II, q. 51, a. S. 22 " Vis imaginativa potest formare diversorum sensibilium formas; quod praecipue apparet dum imaginamur ea quae numquam sensu percepimus." De V erit., q. 10, a. 6, ad 5. " In imaginatione autem non solum sunt formae rerum sensibilium secundum quod accipiuntur a sensu, sed transmutatur diversimode, vel propter aliquam tra.nsmutationem corporalem, sicut accidit in dormientibus et furiosis; MICHAEL STOCK creative imagination, which belongs to the sense power in question insofar as it operates under the direction of reason, and it has extensive influence in all human activity. 23 For by this disposition of images under the direction of reason, the great creative works of fine and practical art are patterned and executed, while in everyday life, speech, gesture and most ordinary activity is formed imaginatively before being acted out. b. Sense Memory The role of memory is to perceive the past. 24 Among the wealth of images in the imagination, dissociated from time and place, and seeming to live in an independent and freely evolving existence, there is need to keep record of the order of images as they were perceived, if experience is to be a useful part of man's psychological equipment. To fashion experience into a useful tool man must have such order in the elements of sense knowledge that he can recall what come before and what come after, what is associated with another in spatial association, what image is of a thing seen before in a certain context of time and place, and what is new.25 It is memory which fashions vel etiam secundum imperium rationis disponuntur phantasmata in ordine ad id quod est intelligendum." Summa Theol., 11-11, q. 178, a. !!. ••" Apprehensio autem imaginationis, cum sit particularis, regulatur ab apprehensione rationis, sicut virtus activa particularis a virtute activa universali." Ibid., 1-11, q. 17, a. 7. •• " Vis autem memorativa retinet, cuius est memorari rem non absolute, sed prout est in praeterito apprehensa a sensu vel intellectu." De Memoria, lect. !!, § S!!l. •• Although the sense memocy is generally treated after the discussion of the imagination in psychological textbooks, and is so treated here, it would probably be erroneous to think of its function as following upon that of imagination,- as if it functions only after the imagination has functioned. Actually, the sense memocy seems to be closer to the external senses than the imagination, since it recalls perceptions in the order and context in which they originate, while imagination takes the images without this order and context. From the point of view of object, then, memory seems more closely allied _to the external senses than imagination. This observation seems confirmed from the point of view of psychological structure, for St. Thomas seems to make the memocy pertain to the common sense in some way. "Unde concludit quod memoria sit intellectivae partis animae, sed per accidens; per se autem primi sensitivi, scilicet sensus communis." Probably SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 4&5 this order of images, for the function of memory is to recognize, among the things we .apprehend, those which we perceived before, and to evoke the record of things apprehended as they were apprehended before.28 Thus there seems to be a certain complexity of act in the memory's perception of the past. There seems to be a difference, for instance, between recollection, by which an incident recalled from the past is cited by memory as being in a certain context of time gone by, and recognition, by which an object presently known is known as having been previously perceived. In the first case, the excitation to act is internal, often from a voluntary intention, and the reference of the act is as of an act simply looking back to time past. In the second case, the excitation is external, and the reference is of the thing presently perceived to the same thing as perceived in the past. In the first case, then, the term of the knowledge seems to be primarily the perceptions themselves-this perception is this perception as it was had in the past. In the second case, the term of the knowledge seems to be primarily the things knownthis thing, presently perceived, is the one perceived in the past. Here the note of" being perceived" seems to be secondary, in the intentional order, to the thing perceived. And yet it cannot be denied that in either case, the crucial factors are the perceptions. The past perception is crucial because the past, with which the present is connected and to which it is referred in an act of memory, is a past which manifestly depends on having been perceived. There is no other way in which a sensible object could become an object of memory if it were not perceived at least once before.27 The the original sense impressions move both imagination and memory immediately, in order of time and nature, and with the images so supplied, each goes on its separate way. These problems, however, will come to the fore in the discussions on the interplay of the senses below. •• Cf. de Memoria, lect. 5, §§ 868-869. 11 Non enim memoramur ea inquantum in praesenti eorum scientiam habemus, sed per se memorari non contingit ante factum tempus, scilicet antequam inter- MICHAEL STOCK present perception is crucial because there is no way by which the past perception can be presently observed except through a present perception, for the act of memory exists in the present, spanning past and present by making the past reappear in a present act. This is done, of course, by an image, which is conserved from the past and reformed in the present, when the external sensible or perception of it is no longer present. Whence St. Thomas remarks that memory depends on phantasms. 28 Therefore, in its act of recollection, memory involves a present perception (of some object) referred to the past as having a real identity with a perception of the past, and differing only in time. Its act could be expressed in the sentence: This, the present perception, is a perception already had in the past. In its act of recognition, memory involves a perception of a thing present, referred to the same thing perceived in the past, and this could be expressed: This, the thing perceived, was perceived in the past. Thus the power of memory falls on perceptions and on things perceived.29 The object of memory is an image, similar to that of the imagination 30 but endowed with its peculiar intention, which is a relation to the past as has been described above, of the thing perceived now, or of the present perception, to its perception in the past, or to the thing perceived in the past, as of before and after in time, near or far from each other in place, veniat tempus medium inter notitiam prius existentem et ipsam memoriam." Ibid., lect. 4, § 854. •• "(Memoria) non autem est sine phantasmate. Sensibilia enim postquam praetereunt, a sensu non percipiuntur, nisi sicut in phantasmate •••. Unde per se memoria pertinet ad apparitionem phantasmatum." Ibid., .ect. !!, § 8!!0. •• " Praeteritio potest ad duo referri: scilicet ad obiectum quod cognoscitur; et ad cognitionis actum. Quae quidem duo simul coniunguntur in parte sensitiva, quae est apprehensiva alicuius per hoc quod immutatur a praesenti sensiblli; unde simul animal memoratur se prius sensisse in praeterito, et se sensisse quoddam praeteritum sensibile." Summa Theol., I, q. 79, a. 6; ad !!. •• The imagination, memory and cogitative powers receive and retain the same or similar images, but under different formalities. " Si autem dicatur quod hie homo non sortitur speciem ab ipsis phantasmatibus, sed a virtutibus in quibus sunt phantasmata, scilicet, imaginativa, memorativa et cogitativa. . .. " 11 Cont. Gent., c. 78, just before the middle. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 427 familiar, therefore, or new, etc. Memory is formed on the basis of these intentions among the images of sensible reality, conserving them in an interconnected matrix of experience, or in a connecting web of things and perceptions inex..,ricably bound up with one another. Moreover, in virtue of these interconnections, memory serves man in the act of deliberate recollection or reminiscence, in which a man begins with some part of his remembered experience as an initial point for inquiry of other parts of experience which have been temporarily lost to evocation, but which he plans to regain along the paths of association, as directed by reason. 31 c. Cogitative power The cogitative power, which is also called the particular reason, and which corresponds to the estimative power in brute animals, is a sense power which perceives and collects individual intentions, that is, it perceives not simply the sensible quality as apprehended by the external senses, but also the concrete individual so qualifi.ed.32 The sensible species or image formed in the cogitative is made, like that in the imagination and memory, of the sensible qualities as apprehended by the external senses, but over and above its sensible content, it contains a reference or relationship to the individual possessing the qualities sensed, and to that individual as such. It is the peculiar function of the cogitative to grasp or perceive this relationship, which is called a singular or individual or particular intention, and is not apprehended by any other sense 33 Cf. de Memoria, c. lil. •• "Si vero apprehendatur (aliquid) in singulari, utputa cum video coloratum, percipio hunc hominem vel hoc animal, huiusmodi quidem apprehensio in homine fit per vim cogitativam quae dicitur etiam ratio particularis, eo quod est collativa intentionum individualium." II de Anima, lect. 13, § 396. "Et ideo quae in aliis animalibus dicitur aestimativa naturalis, in homine dicitur cogitativa, quae per collationem quandam huiusmodi intentiones adinvenit." Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4. •• "Necessarium est ergo animali quod percipiat huiusmodi intentiones, quas non percipit sensus exterior." Summa Theol., I, q. 78; a. 4. "Licet intellectus operatio oriatur a sensu, tamen in re apprehensa per sensum intellectus multa cognoscit quae 81 428 MICHAEL STOCK Hence the intention is called an unsensed intention. The object, therefore, of. the cogitative is· the " thing "-this or that individual thing, which first impressed the sensing subject with its sensible qualities through the external senses and is subsequently perceived by the cogitative, through and under the sensible qualities, as their concrete possessor. Naturally, the thing as known by the cogitative does not have the force and precision of " thing " as known by the intellect, for the cogitative is not an abstracting power. Nevertheless, there is a quasi-abstraction in the function of the cogitative, for it is precisely the irtdividual intention on which its power falls and for this reason-,its object can be as the quiddity of a particular thing-the quiddity of the particular thing as particular.84 The significance of what this grasping of individual intentions entails has no small importance in regard to an understanding of the workings of sentient life. All animals act for two purposes: to stay alive and to reproduce. So all their knowledge is ordered to finding food to eat and water to drink, to avoiding dangers and enemies and to. securing mates and protecting offspring. But the knowledge which is limited to sensible qualities is entirely insufficient to accomplish these purposes; sensible qualities themselves do not feed or. hurt or help in reproducing. It is the thing which has these qualities which helps or hinders the animal. Hence the animal must have some cognitive power which· enables him to discern the thing under the qualities, and this is the estimative power. So the estimative in animals is ordered to perceiving those things which are terms or principles of action and passion in it according to sensus percipere non potest. Et similiter aestimativa, licet inferiori modo." Idtnn, ad 4. •• " Sensus autem exteriores ipsa sensibilia accidentia, communia scilicet et propria, habent pro suis per se obiectis. Quidditas autem rei particularis in partiCulari non ·spectat ut per se obiectum ad illos sensus exteriores, cum quidditas ipsa sit et non accidens; nee ad intellectum pertinet ut per se obiectum eius propter suam materialitatem. Ideo quidditas rei materialis in ipsa sua particularitate est obiectum rationis particularis, cuius est conferre de intentionibus particularibus." De Prine. Irulividuationia. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 429 its species, and so also the estimative is the cognitive principle of its appetites. 35 Hence, for the brute animals, the individual intentions of the estimative always involve aspects of concrete utility or harm, or of gratification or repugnance, amicability or hostility, in reference to the species and organic conditions of the sensing subject, for on such factors depend such utilities and hostilities, etc. 36 But man's life has its animal purposes and more. His sensing powers are ordained not only to self-preservation and the preservation of the race, but also to apprehending and preparing the materials on which his intellect and reason can work. So the cogitative in man is not limited to perceiving the useful or harmful individuals in his environment, but any and aU individual things. 37 More light is thrown on the nature of these individual intentions from the remarks St. Thomas makes about the power of the cogitative to perceive the sensible "per accidens." 38 He says that when we see a colored thing, and perceive it as a singular object, the perception of the singular is per accidens •• " Aestimativa autem non apprehendit aliquod individuum, secundum quod est sub natura communi, sed solum secundum quod est terminus aut principium alicuius actionis vel passionis; sicut ovis cognoscit hunc agnum, non inquantum est hie agnus, sed inquantum est ab ea lactabilis; et hanc herbam, inquantum est eius cibus. . . . Naturalis enim aestimativa datur animalibus, ut per earn ordinentur in actiones proprias vel passiones, prosequendas, vel fugiendas." ll de Anima, lect. 18, § 898. 36 Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4. •• It is interesting, in this light, to recall that brute animals apparently cannot discern an individual as such in their environment unless it moves. This is a fact which bullfighters and hunters stalking animals take into account. Man, however, can discern things whether moving or at rest. •• St. Thomas distinguishes the per se proper sensible of a sense, which is apprehended only by one particular sense, such as color by sight, and the per se common sensible, which is apprehended by more than one sense, such as motion by sight and touch, and the per accidens sensible, which is not apprehended at all by the sense to which it is per accidens, but is apprehended by some other power at the time when the sense in question apprehends its per se sensible, as when we see a man moving and say that we see a living man. The powers which concur with one sense in cases of per accidens sensation are another sense or the cogitative or the estimative or the intellect. Cf. II de Anima. lect. 18, §§ 884-886, 895. 480 MICHAEL STOCK to the seeing, and the power concurring with sight in this perception is the cogitative power .39 The cogitative, therefore, falls directly upon the singularity or thingness of an object that is seen or heard or otherwise perceived in its sensible qualities by the external senses, e., on the particular quiddity as such. To continue, however, in the development of the nature and function of the cogitative, we find that it not only apprehends individual intentions, but it also composes and divides them, making a kind of collation, that is, a collection of intentions assorted according to their kinds. 40 In other words, the cogitative is a power capable of making judgments, not indeed in the full and formal sense in which the intellect makes judgments, but in a virtual sense and .within the limits of concrete and sensible data. That is to say, the cogitative actually composes two or more individuals into a kind of unity based on their similarity, and adds subsequent similar individuals to the aggregation, so that the cogitative eventually grasps not only this singular individual, but also this kind of individual, in the •• "Viso igitur quomodo dicantur per se sensibilia, et. communis et propria, restat videndum, qua ratione dicatur aliquid sensibile per accidens. • . . Quod ergo sensu proprio non cognoscitur, si sit aliquid universale, apprehenditur intellectu; non tamen omne quod intellectu apprehendi potest in re sensibili, potest did sensibile per accidens, sed statim quod ad occursum rei sensatae apprehenditur intellectu. . . . Si vero apprehendatur in singnlari, utputa cum video coloratum, percipio hunc hominem vel hoc animal, huiusmodi quidem apprehensio in homine fit per vim cogitativam." Ibid., §§ ?95-896. · •• " Et sic singnlaribus se immiscet mediante ratione particulari, quae est potentia quaedam sensitivae partis componens et dividens intentiones individuales quae alio nomine dicitur. cogitativa .... " De V erit., q. 10, a. 6. (This text, as given, is an emendation of the Marietti edition, according to text presently approved by the Leonine Commission, Santa Sabina, Rome. Cf. footnote, p. 9ii!, " Experimentum and some related problems according to St. Thomas," Fergol O'Connor, 0. P. Angelicum Dissertations, Rome, 1956). "Quia cum virtus cogitativa habeat operationes solum circa particularia, quorum intentiones dividit et componit. . . ." II Oont. Gent., c. 78. " Sensus autem indicium de quibusdam est naturale, sicut de propriis. sensibilibus; de quibusdam autem quasi per quamdam collationem, quam facit in homine vis cogitativa, quae est potentia selisitivae partis, loco cuius in aliis animalibus est existimatio naturalis; et sic iudicat vis sensitiva de sensibilibus communibus et de sensibilibus per accidens." De Verit., q. 1, a. 11. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 481 sense of a general group attained under one sensible species. And, consequently, it attains also to the distinctions among individual types, since it separates individuals into their different groups, and knows them as different. The result is experience-knowledge caused by many apprehensions of one thing on the part of the cogitative, retained in the storehouse of the cogitative, which is memory .41 This power of collation belongs to the cogitative insofar as it serves under the power of universal reason: in brute animals the judgment of singulars is accomplished by natural instinct. In man, indeed, there is something of this natural estimation too, but for the most part, the cogitative seems to lack the determination of the estimative, and consequently its limitation, and to be universalized, by participation of universal .reason, and at the same time, dependent on such reason for the full acquisition of value determinations. 42 So a sheep knows that grass is its food by a natural estimation; man learns what is food for himself partly by natural estimation and partly by experience informed by reason. In other words, man is not sufficiently equipped on the sense level to make an adequate judgment of what is good or bad for him by natural instinct. He has certain more o:r less vague perceptions which need to be perfected and completed by a collation of incidents leading to experience, and especially by intellectual knowledge generated from this experience. 43 Hence man's cogitative power 41 " Supra memoriam autern in hominibus ... est e:x;perimentum, quod quaedam animalia non participant nisi parum. Experimentum enim est ex collatione plurium singularium in memoria receptorum. Huiusmodi autem collatio est homini propria, et pertinet ad vim cogitativam, quae ratio particularis dicitur: quae est collativa intentionum individualium .... Modus autem causandi (experimentum) est iste: quia ex multis memoriis unius rei accipit homo experimentum de aliquo, quo experimento potens est ad facile et recte operandum." I Metaphys., Iect. l, §§ 15 and 17. "Ad apprehendendum autem intentiones quae per sensum non accipiuntur, ordinatur vis aestimativa.-Ad conservandum autem eas, vis memorativa, quae est thesaurus quidam huiusmodi intentionum." Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4. •• " Sed quantum ad intentiones praedictas (sci!. singulares) differentia est; nam alia animalia percipiunt huiusmodi intentiones solum naturali quodam instinctu, homo etiam per quandam collationem." Summa Theol., loc. cit. •• This is not to say that brute animals do not also acquire some perfection 482 MICHAEL STOCK can be said to lack a perfection which the estimative has, but it is more than compensated for this lack by being free to participate in the perfections of a higher order. The final points to be made about the cogitative also concern its relationship with this higher order of reason. Since man's mind is not endowed with innate ideas, but depends on what he knows from the senses, the functioning of sense knowledge in man must be considered as ordered principally to providing the matter for intellectual knowledge, and not simply to providing the cognitive elements of his animal life, for whenever a lower order is ordained to the service of a higher order, its service to the higher order is more important, in the order of finality, than the accomplishment of its proper role. So the sumni.it of the sensitive order is the point at which it immediately serves the intellectual order, and this point in man is the function of the cogitative, preparing phantasms .to be instruments of the active intelligence." These phantasms present to the intellect an adequate picture of the external, sensible . world, containing all that the several external senses have perceived, bound together in the proper objects, in the context of space and time, and with the complexity and variety of detail which numerous similar perceptions conserved in memory can provide, in other words, the complete, sensitive synthesis implied in the word " experience." From this matter, the intellect draws its ideas. 45 But, since the intellect depends on of knowledge by experience. However, their capacity for such. added perfections is slight, and always limited within the bounds of the end set for instinct. " Et, quia ex multis sensibus et memoria animalia ad aliquid consuescunt prosequendum vel vitandum, inde est quod aliquid experimenti, licet parum, participare videntur. Homines autem supra experimentum, quod pertinent ad rationem particularem, habent rationein universalem, per quam vivunt, sicut per id quod est principale in eis." I Metaphya., lect. 1, § 15. •• " Virtus cogitativa non habet ordinem ad intellectum possibilem, quo intelligit homo, nisi per suum aetum quo praeparantur phantasmata ut per intellectum agentem fiant intelligibilia actu, et perficientia intellectum possibilem." II Cont. Gent., c. 78. 68 Nam sicut ex multis memoriis fit una experimentalis scientia, ita ex multis experimentis apprehensis fit universalis acceptio de omnibus similibus: Unde plus SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 483 phantasms not only in the acquisition of ideas but also in any subsequent use, the cogitative enters necessarily into all intellectual considerations, and hence must be subject to direction from the intellect, so that its own activity will be conformed to the purposes of the higher power, and not vice versa. Hence St. Thomas says that the cogitative by its very nature is moved and directed by universal reason. 411 . And, beyond this, if the cogitative is a sine qua non of any intellectual operation, it is essentially necessary in any intellectual operation which is carried through to a singular conclusion, for the intellect by itself knows the universal, and by itself is out of contact with the world of concrete things and actions. Hence, whenever science is to be applied to particular facts, and whenever the practical reason operates in either a prudential judgment or a work of art, the function of the cogitative must enter in, to join the universal order to the singular. 47 This can all be summed up in the phrase " knowing the individual as existing under the conimon nature." For the cogitative which perceives the singular subject of sensible qualities as its proper object, also moves the power of reason, whose proper object is the universal, to grasp the universal concept entailed in the singular subject. In turn, the cogitative is moved by the power of reason when reason refers its concept back to the singular subject through the image in the· cogitative. In this sense the cogitative knows, for example, " this man " or " these men " as the concrete realities represented in the universal concept "man "-the individuals under the common nature. 48 habet hoc ars quam experimentum; quia experimentum tantum circa singularia versatur, ars autem circa universalia." I Metaphys., lect. 1, § 18. •• " Ipsa autem ratio particularis nata est moveri et dirigi in homine secundum rationem universalem, unde in syllogisticis ex universalibus propositionibus concluduntur conclusiones singulares." Summa Theol., I, q. 81, a. 8. •• Ibid. " Universalem vero sententiam quam mens habet de operabilibus, non est possibile applicari ad particularem actum nisi per aliquam potentiam mediam apprehendentem singulare, ut sic fiat quidam syllogismus, cuius major sit universalis, quae est sententia mentis; minor autem singularis, quae est apprehensio particularis rationis; conclusio vero electio singularis operis." De Verit., q. 10, a. 5. ••" Nam cogitativa apprehendit individuum, ut existens sub natura communi; 484 MICHAEL STOCK And finally, it can be noted that in syllogisms composed entirely of singulars, the whole formality of the act belongs to the cogitative, although virtually the intellect is acting, for the terms are all singulars, which are known only to the cogitative but the activity of formally composing and dividing must be derived from the higher power. So it is, in any temerarious judgment, such as: John likes Mary, Tom likes Mary, John likes Tom. And if it seems remarkable that any such act can belong to the sensitive power, the reason must be sought in the functional unity it attains with the intellect, by which it participates something of intellectual power, and rises markedly above the limitations of strict sensitive activity. 49 Hence the role of the cogitative, or particular reason, is of critical importance in understanding human knowledge and human consciousness, both because it is the peak of sense activity and because it forms the nexus between the orders of sense and intellect. Man's .dual nature, and its functioning, must remain a mystery unless we understand the pivotal functions in which the higher and spiritual part enters into intimate and dynamic union with the activities of the lower and animal part. These pivotal functions are precisely those of the cogitative. 4. The dynamism of the internal senses The functioning of the internal senses cannot be rightly understood by the static and disconnected analysis given above, until the interactions and interplay of the several faculties are considered. The fact of the matter is that the four internal senses act together in so close a harmony that it is more difficult, in a sense, to see their distinctions than it is to see them quod contingit ei, inquantum unitur intellectivae in eodem subiecto; unde cognoscit hunc hominem prout est hie homo, et hoc lignum prout est hoc lignum." II de Anima, lect. Ul, § 398. •• " Nihilominus tamen haec vis est in parte sensitiva; quia vis sensitiva in sui supremo participat aliquid de vi intellectiva in homine, in quo sensus intellectui coniungitur." Ibid., § 397. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 485 as a kind of unity. 50 Nor is it strange that there is a high degree of complexity and subtlety when we remember that these senses do not accomplish their purpose until they complete the picture of external reality in all its ramifications and in all its unities, whether, as in the case of brute animals, to serve as the sum total of cognitive activity by which their whole life is directed, 51 or, as in man's case, to serve as apt material for inspection and meaningful interpretation by intellect and ·reason.52 And yet the faculties which accomplish this complete picture are limited to contributing each one only a particular element to the final composite .. Therefore, the totality of their action must entail a highly elaborated interplay of function, with mutual assistance one to the other, and a kind of mutual intercourse of sensible. knowledge; all as smooth and natural as if it were the simple action of a simple power. Of all this interplay, man has a kind of general awareness at the level of internal sensation and perception, and for all this an accounting should be given. a. The process of elaboration in regard to the external object The account of the interfunctioning of the internal sense faculties can be viewed from several different aspects, and sho.uld be so viewed, for the matter is so complicated that it demands some kind of division. Several different principles might be used as the basis for division; the one that seems •• " Posset aut alicui videri quod ex his quae dicuntur, quod phantasia et memoria non sunt potentiae distinctae a sensu communi, sed sint quaedam passiones ipsius. Sed Avicenna rationabiliter ostendit esse diversas potentias." De Memoria, lect. i, § S!ll. 01 Vita animalium regitur imaginatione et memoria: imaginatione quidem, quantum ad animalia imperfecta; memoria vero quantum ad animalia perfecta. . . . Accipitur autem vivere pro actione vitae, sicut et conversationem hominum vitam dicere solemus. In hoc vero, quod cognitionem animalium determinat .per comparationem ad regimen vitae, datur intelligi quod cognitio inest ipsis animalibus non propter ipsum cognoscere, sed propter necessitatem actionis." I Metaphys., lect. 1, § 14. •• " Vires apprehensivae interius praeparant intellectui possibili proprium obiectum." Bumma Theol., I-II, q. 50, a. 4, ad S. Cf. II Cont. Gent., c. 73. 436 MICHAEL STOCK most useful is the one based on the division of consciousness into three degrees, according to the manner in which it approaches the limit of simple cognition on one hand and the limit of perfect self-consciousness on the other. Closest to the lower limit of simple apprehension of an object are the activities of the internal senses which bear directly on an object known, in such a way as to complete the direct knowledge of the object in all the dimensions possible to the sense order. The second and middle degree of consciousness is that in which the object is known in the context of other internal sense knowledge. If the first degree can be called, with all due reservations, purely objective consciousness, the second can be called objective-subjective consciousness. The third and highest degree of sense consciousness, which may be called purely subjective, is that in which the content is· wholly a matter of internal sensations. In this third degree, the intention of the sentient subject is turned directly to his internal sense operations, without explicit reference to the object; in the first degree it is turned to the object, without explicit reference to the operations, in the middle degree, it is turned to the object in the context of internal operations. Approaching the problem of the interfunctioning of the internal senses from the first point of view, we can take a simple object of knowledge and see how the total sensible character of it is placed together and gradually given depth by the combined operations of the senses. This procedure should throw into relief several psychological dynamisms. In the first place, there is the " direct " line of development of the knowledge we have of the object, wherein each sense faculty performs its proper operations in regard to the object, and in so doing, shows its dependence on the acts of the other facufties. In such a line of development, the act of one presupposes and rises from the act of another, and, consequently, reflects on the act of the other. When we say that it reflects on the act of another, we mean that it knows, under its own proper light, the object which SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 487 was first known by the other, and knows it in the perfection in which it was known by the other. But, since the sense in act is the sensible in act, it can be said to know the act of the other. In another sense, o£ course, it does not know the act of .the other, that is, it does not know the act of the other as an immanent movement proceeding from within a power by which it has the form of another as of the other--.,.such a subtlety could not be grasped by a sense power. We are limited, therefore, at this stage of the analysis, to saying that the one power knows the act of the other just insofar as its object in act is its act. From what is implied in this direct line of development we should be able to see one of the lines of sense consciousness, and consequently the primary parts of the content of sense consciousness and the powers which are actively responsible for them. As has been seen above, the sense knowledge which has been apprehended by the five external senses as so many fragments of sensation is received in the common sense, where it attains to a certain objective and subjective unity, that is, the several qualities apprehended by different senses are referred to each other as associated in one originating source, so that, for instance, we know that the red apple is smooth and sweet, while the seeing, touching, tasting, etc., are associated· as of one subject. For the knowledge that the sweet apple is red implies the fact that the seer tastes. Moreover, since these qualities do not exist as simple, vague and indefinite, but are rather defined and limited as the qualities of bodies of a certain size and shape, size and shape are known along with them, and also the other common sensibles, motion and rest and number, for when we know a thing precisely, we know it in its limits, and hence know its limiting factors. We also know the immediate consequences of these factors, and thus time is known from motion/ 8 and also space, place and position from sizes and shapes. 54 Then all these elements, of which we are •• Cf. De Memoria, lect. !!, § 819. •• We do not wish to digress into an analysis of the development of perception, 488 MICHAEL STOCK aware at the level of common sense, reverberate into the imagination, in a manner less vivid but more permanent, whence they are subject to recall again and again. 55 However, simultaneous in time with the operation of the common sense described above is the perception of the cogitative, bearing upon the individual as such involved in the complex of quality apprehensions, for the cogitative perceives as a recognizable whole the individual thing hitherto apprehended in a more . or less compact association of qualities. And, with the operation of the cogitative, the object, now grasped in its essential sensible completeness although not in total completeness, and in its context of time and place becomes memorable, for the memory stores the intentions perceived by the cogitative at the time the cogitative acts, and recalls them for its proper act of memory at some later time. To sum up, therefore, the line of consciousness involved in this particular psychological. dynamism: there is the common sense conscious of the objects and acts of the external senses, the cogitative moved to its act by and in the act of the common sense, the imagination similarly moved by the common sense, and the memory moved by the act of the cogitative .. Nevertheless, the import of this dynamism from the point of view of consciousness formally taken, or self-consciousness, is not great, for in all the operations mentioned, the focus or intention of the act is on the object precisely as object, and since it pertains more to the knowledge of the content of consciousness than to the precise factor of the activity of consciousness. Our purpose is served by a general summary of the principal elements of which we are sensibly conscious, in reference to the sense power which makes this possible. Questions of third dimensional perception, of motion and rest, of the localization of the object, of causality, etc., are interesting but somewhat aside from the point. Even mere Interesting although further from the point would be an analysis of the respective claims of the associationists and the Gestaltists. It would seem, for instance, highly rewarding to inquire whether or not the truth that lies in the associationist position is that which the present as the apprehensions of the exterior senses and the common sense, while the truth of the Gestalt analysis is embraced in the scholastic doctrine on the perceptions of the cogitative. But this, as we say, would lead us far afield. 66 cr. p. above. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 439 not on the acts, even when one act depends on the other. It is, indeed, necessary to see this dynamism as it is, for it is the primary element in human knowledge, and the direct sensitive operation which must be posited as a preamble to reflex sensitive knowledge, and indeed it contains, as has been seen, the germ of reflexive knowledge, but to find this reflexive character more fully developed, we must look further. b. 1'he concatenation of present apprehensions and internal perceptions The nature of sense knowledge is not such that man takes up an object and inspects it until he has exhausted its sensible content and then lays it aside and takes up another. Along with the work of inspecting the object, which was described immediately above, there is a concomitant play of internal sensation, provided by past experience, in which cogitative and memory have the major part, and general appreciation, which is the work of imagination. If the process of inspecting the object can be said to answer the question: What is this object, these secondary processes can be taken as answering the question: What does this object mean to me in the light of what I already know? Manifestly, this is a more subjective question, and for this reason, the secondary process under investigation here has been designated as subjective-objective. Under this heading the relation of the internal senses to the external senses must be reconsidered, and seen, not simply as the internal senses are moved by the object as externally apprehended and then operate to perfect the perception of the object, but also as they enlarge and enrich the direct perception on the basis of the past accumulation of sense knowledge, and how, indeed, they might color or distort its perception. Then, after considering how present perceptions are linked with the accumulated perceptions from the past, the question arises as to how these elements can be kept distinct and unconfused, that is to say, how man is conscious of the distinction between present external reality and present internal imaginings. In 440 MICHAEL STOCK investigating this question, we are manifestly in the midst of the problem of self-consciousness in the sense order. To work with an example, a man can, for instance, walk into the ruins of an historic place, and, if he is sufficiently instructed, can begin to reconstruct it in his imagination, restoring it to an earlier splendor, peopling it with characters from the past, seeing and hearing the flow of imaginary action. Seeing especially well preserved details in the present ruin would reinforce the strength of the imaginary scene and give new impetus to the imagined reconstruction, but discordant notes could destroy the whole illusion. Such imaginary processes provoked and sustained by present apprehensions, or again, disturbed and distracted, are not uncommon. In such a situation, it is clear that the present apprehension moving the imagination starts it off on a series of images according to its own laws of association, and that subsequent apprehensions can reinforce or distract this flow of imagery. It should be noted, however, that in his more complete accounts of imagination-external sense interplay, St. Thomas includes the intermediate operations of the common sense, for nothing reaches the internal senses unless it has passed through the common sense. So, it is more strictly correct to say that the imagination is moved by the complex of external sense-common sense activity, from which the imagination receives its impulse to move as from one single power. 55 For this reason also the imagination is called a "passion" of the common sense, and common sense is called its "root." Whenever, then, we speak of the internal senses as being moved by either the external senses or by the common sense, we mean that, in either case, they are moved by both together. 5 7 Hence the activity involved •• We say "as from one single power" because the activities of external sense and common sense are not simply coordinated but are subordinated, the former to the latter. 67 " Phantasia autem, secundum quod apparet per huius immutationem secundariam, est passio sensus communis: sequitur enim totam immutationem sensus, quae incipit a sensibilibus propriis, et terminatur ad sensum communem." De Memoria, lect: !t, § 819. "Similiter autem sensus communis est radix phantasiae SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 441 is this: the external sensible quality actuates and is received in and apprehended by the external sense. When the external sense acts, becoming the form sensed, it activates the common sense, which receives and perceives the quality and the fact of external sense activity. Finally, the act of the common sense activates the imagination, which in turn receives and perceives the quality sensed, and holds it subsequently as in a· treasury from which it can be reproduced. The normal course of activity, then, is from sensible to external sense to common sense to imagination; one single sensible form existing in all these powers according to their different modes, having been passed from one to the other without losing its original character, but rather new modes of existence in the different cognitive faculties. 58 Given this as normal sense activity, two questions arise: how are species in these different powers distinguished one from the other, so that man knows what is real and what is imaginary? And, is this process of reverberation of sense image reversible? Man normally has no difficulty in distinguishing what belongs to external reality and what belongs to his internal sense activity, especially imagination; in maintaining his connection with reality and so avoiding illusions or hallucinations. He does not suffer alienation from his senses except in sleep or when violence is done, for example, in the development of mental disorders. 59 For St. Thomas, the key to this power of distinguishing reality from subjective imagination is in the operaet memoriae quae praesupponunt actum sensus communis." Ibid., § Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 78, a. 4, ad S. . •• Species quae est in imaginatione, est eiusdem generis cum specie quae est in sensu, quia utraque. est individualis et materialis. . . . Et ideo . . . species sensibilis imprimit speciem imaginariam." De S1Jirit. Oreat., a. 10, ad 17. " ... una potentia .ab alia movetur, sicut imaginatio a sensu. Et hoc quidem possibilis est, quia formae imaginationis et sensus sunt . eiusdem generis; utraeque enim sunt individuales. Et ideo formae quae sunt in sensu, possunt imprimere formas quae sunt in imaginationem, quasi sibi similes." Q. D. de Anima, a. 4, ad 1. •• Cf. Summa Theol., 11-11, q. 178, a. S. 442 MICHAEL STOCK tion of the common sense.60 Thus in analysing the different states of consciousness occurring in sleep, he states that it is the imagination which functions when we dream in sleep, and it functions more or less vividly and coherently depending on the depth of the sleep. But the depth of sleep is measured according to the degree to which the common sense is bound, since the binding of the common sense is the cause of sleep. However, in the lightest phases of sleep, the common sense partly returns to operation, so that man can make some kind of a judgment distinguishing realities which he senses from his dream images, although not perfectly. It follows then that the full operation of common sense allows man to distinguish clearly and adequately between dream states and reality .61 It is not necessary to conclude that the common sense itself performs this act of distinguishing, but only that its operation is vital to the right performance of the action. 62 The act of discerning belongs rather to a higher sense power, which is conscious of the workings of the common sense and of the imagination, and distinguishes them one from the other, as long as both are working. There are certainly many clues given to distinguish the two: the sensations of externals are more vivid, more coherent, they fill the scope of vision more completely, are not so much subject to flux and, finally, are susceptible to proof through touch, which seems to be the sense hardest to. deceive. And that is why people pinch them•• See p. 4!U above; where this point is first mentioned. 81 "Si antem (in somno) motus vaporum fuerit modicus, non solum imaginatio remanet libera, sed etiam ipse sensus communis ex parte solvitur; ita quod homo iudicat interdum · in dormiendo ea quae videt somnia esse, quasi diiudicans 'inter res et rerum similitudines. Sed tamen ex aliqua parte remanet sensus communis ligatus; et ideo licet aliquas similitudines discemat a rebus, tamen semper in aliquibus decipitur." Swmma Theol., I, q. 84, a. 8, ad •• In the text cited above, one could make " Btm8U8 communis " the subject of the verbs " cliacernat" and " decipitur," and interpret the words to mean that this sense is the judging power. On the other hand, "homo" be the subject of these verbs, as he is of the verb " iudicat," so that it is " homo " who discerns and in some things is deceived, and this seems a preferable ii:tterpretation, since in no place is the common sense assigned awareness of the content of imagination. which it must have if it is to distinguish imaginings from sense realities. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 443 selves when something amazing is happening, to prove that they are not dreaming. This higher sense is probably the cogitative. 68 The second question asked above, namely, whether or not the process of reverberation is reversible, so that the images produced in the imagination normally excite the common sense, and so reproduce themselves in the power through which they originally reached the imagination, has already been answered implicitly. Normally this would not happen, for it is contrary both to the nature and to the purpose of sensation. It is contrary to the nature of sensation because the senses have their own proper active principle, which is the external object outside the psychic order towards which their passivity is naturally ordered, 64 and as the external senses are made to be moved by external objects, so the common sense is made to be moved by the external senses, and not by the imagination. It is against the purpose of sensation for, unless the common sense normally operates directly and immediately and without interference upon the evidences of the external senses, the orientation towards reality, which is the whole purpose of knowledge, is necessarily distorted. Normally, then, the imagination does not reverberate back into the common sense. Whether, when violence has been done to the sentient being, the sensitive organs can be so disturbed as to allow a reversion of the normal development of sense knowledge, remains a question. Amputees, for instance, report feelings of pain from missing limbs. This may be interpreted as meaning that something in the imagination is being reported as if it were perceived by the common sense at a time when it •• Cf. p. 456 below. •• " Sed iste modus receptionis non facit vere sentire. Quia omnis potentia passiva secundum suae speciei rationem determinatur ad aliquid activum speciale: quia potentia, inquantum huiusmodi habet ordinem ad illud respectu cuius dicitur. Unde, cum proprium activmn in sensu exteriori sit res existens extra animam, et non intentio eius existens in imaginatione vel ratione; si organum sentiendi non moveatur a rebus extra, sed ex imaginatione vel aliis superioribus viribus, non erit vere sentiendi." Summa Theol., Suppl., q. 82, a. 8. 444 MICHAEL STOCK could not originate in external sensation, and when the common sense is itself in all other respects operating normally, that is, is not bound by sleep, drugs, etc. On the other hand, the source of the deception could be in the severed nerve which normally reported sensations from the external sense to the common sense, and, in this light, the deception would not be proceeding from an interference on the part of the imagination. This second explanation seems to accord better with the ideas of St. Thomas. In discussing the manner in which imaginary visions are caused by physical disturbances, he sees the cognitive processes initiated by physical commotions in the external sense organs, even though they are not apprehending their proper objects, insofar as traces left in the external senses from previous sense activity are excited by these commotions and passed on to the internal organs where sensible images are aroused, as if the common sense were moved as it is ordinarily moved by a normal external sense apprehension. Some dreams are caused in this way, and some hallucinations. 65 Again, the violence may be seated immediately in the internal sensing organs, as in cases of mental disorders,. and here again hallucinations are produced. Such a hallucination might come from an intrusion of imaginary species into the common sense, where they pass themselves off as realities after the mode of apprehension proper to the common sense, or they may come from an impeding of the operation of the common sense coupled with a vehement and intense motion of the imagination, in such a way that the cogitative power is deceived into taking fantasy 65 "Manifestum est au tern quod apparitiones imaginariae causantur interdum in nobis ex locali mutatione corporalium spirituum et humorum. Unde Aristoteles, in libro De Somno, assignans causam apparitionis somniorum, dicit quod, ' cum animal dormit, descendente plurimo sanguine ad principium sensitivum, simul descendunt motus ' idest impressiones relictae ex sensibilium motionibus, quae in spiritibus sensualibus conservantur, et ' movent principium sensitivum,' ita quod fit quaedam apparitio, ac si tunc principium sensitivum a rebus ipsis exterioribus mutaretur. Et tanta potest esse commotio spirituum et humorum, quod huiusmodi apparitiones etiam vigilantibus fiunt: sicut patet in phreneticis, et in aliis huiusmodi." Ibid., I, q. 111, a. 8. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 445 for fact. St. Thomas observes the fact that men can take imaginations for realities and does not think it impossible that this can come about through an actual invasion of the external sense organs by phantasms. 66 It seems, therefore, that the normal process of sensation develops in one direction only, from the external senses up to the imagination. In abnormal cases, however, the process may be reversed because of violence done to the sense organs. So much then, for the present, for the concatenation of present sensations and internal imagery-how the one affects the other and how man keeps them distinguished. We must also consider a similar concatenation of the other internal senses with external apprehensions. For if we . change slightly the example given above of a man walking into a scene concerning which he has strong imaginative connections, and have him instead walking into a scene from some earlier time in his own life, for example, revisiting the place where his youth was spent, we find an interaction of apprehension and memory similar to that which obtains between apprehension and imagination. For some details will provoke and incite strong currents of memory; others might distract him from the memorative process. The question then which must be raised is this: how does the memory interact with external sensations. It was stated above that when the cogitative power has apprehended an individual from and in the sensible data associated by the common sense, the individual becomes memorable, that is, having been once apprehended, it can be recalled by the memory as having been apprehended in the past. This is in line with the statements which have been made about the memory as the storehouse of the intentions apprehended by 66 " Deceptio· autem in nobis proprie fit secundum phantasiam, per quam interdum similitudinibus rerum inhaeremus sicut rebus ipsis, ut patet in dormientibus et amentibus." Ibid., I, q. 54, a. 5, in contr. " ... si organum sentiendi non moveatur a rebus extra, sed ex imaginatione vel aliis superioribus viribus, non erit vere sentire .. Uncle non dicimus quod phrenetici et alii mente capti, in quibus propter victoriam imaginativae virtutis fit huiusmodi defluxus specierum ad organa sentiendi, vere sentiant, sed quia videtur eis quod sentiant." Ibid., Suppl., q. a. 8. 446 MICHAEL STOCK the cogitative. 67 When, therefore, St. Thomas says that the memory is rooted in the common sense,68 it seems that this should be understood as the remote root of the memorative act, while the proximate root is the act of the cogitative. Thus the succession of apprehensions which is the basis for the apprehension of time is remotely the succession of common sense apprehensions and proximately the succession of cogitative perceptions. Therefore we do not say " I tasted sweet after I tasted acid and before I tasted bitter," but " I ate my cereal after I drank my grapefruit juice and before my coffee." When, therefore, as in the example given above, a man walks into places where he has been in the past, and his memory is stirred by the things he presently apprehends, the psychological dynamism at work is a movement from the external senses and common sense through the cogitative to the memory. And the difference between this activity and the activity which is provoked when a man walks into unfamiliar surroundings is that, while unfamiliar things striking the memory become memorable, familiar things striking it are recognized, that is, they provoke an intentioned image, and the intention of the image is as of an image already seen in the past. Again, comparing the relation of memory to the external senses with the relation of imagination to external senses, in the latter case the sensible image apprehended externally itself actuates or moves the imagination, while in the former case, the intention perceived by the cogitative in the external sensations moves and informs the memory. The basic difference between these two effects of the externally apprehended sensations, namely, that they move the imagination to produce a simple sensible image while they move the memory to an intentioned image lies in the two ways in which an image can be taken. For example, an animal painted on a canvas is both a painted animal and an image of a real animal; •• Cf. p. 449. •• " Similiter autem sensus communis est radix phantasiae et memoriae quae praesupponunt actum sensus communis. De Memoria, § 89!9!. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 447 one thing, that is, which can be viewed from two aspects. So an image in the senses can be taken simply in itself or as the image of some real thing. In the first way, the image is a product of the imagination, in the second way, it is considered as something we have previously seen or heard or learned, and this is the way in which it informs the memory .69 The question, therefore, which was raised concerning the imagination and the external senses, namely, how man distinguishes the operations of the one from those of the other, is not so acute in the case of the memory and the external sensations, for in the first case the objects were essentially the same, namely, simple sensible images, but in the second case there is a fundamental difference in the objects, that is, the difference between simple images and intentioned images. This explanation, however, does not so much finally settle the problems of the relation of the memory with the other faculties as open the doors to new problems. For instance, as St. Thomas points out, a man can forget something which in fact happened to him, or can consider something that never happened as if it happened to him, if he looks at images that should refer him to the past as if they simple images, or on simple images as if they were affected by the intention of pastness. 70 The investigation of this problem, however, must wait, for, at this point, it is only the structure of consciousness itself which is under question; the question of the nature of its defects follows later. Another question which will be taken up later in its proper place is the question of the direct interaction between memory and imagination, when a man remembers that he imagined. 71 A third problem, however, which might be raised can be investigated at this point, and that is the question of whether or not the memory depends in its proper act on the proper act of the imagination. In the analysis above, the operation of the imagination was not considered necessary •• See de Memoria, lect. 8, §§ 840-841. •• Cf. ibid., §§ 844-847. 01 Seep. 449. 448 MICHAEL STOCK for the formation of a memorable apprehension, nor for its recollection. However, St. Thomas, in discussing the various levels of animal sensitivity, says that the memory follows the imagination, so that animals which have no imagination cannot have memory either .72 The solution of this problem seems to lie in the distinction which must be placed on the word " imagination." St. Thomas uses this word in two senses; in one sense it means the power of imagination itself, as it is a separate internal sense power, while in another sense it means the power to form images, and so considered, is a power pertaining to the three internal sense powers-imagination, memory and cogitative. This distinction can be seen in places where St. Thomas compares the memory with the imagination, when he speaks of the soul remembering after the mode of images, but not of simple images which are apprehended by the imaginative power, but of images as of another thing previously known, which is the object of memory/ 8 and is more explicitly evident in places where he distinguishes the several internal senses.74' In summary, then, it seems that the principal element in the working of sense consciousness which has been isolated in this investigation of subjective-objective consciousness is the role of the cogitative in distinguishing the operations of external sense and imagination; the other inter-sense dynamisms mentioned do not seem to contribute much to self-consciousness although they are important to know for a complete understanding of sense operations. c. The interplay of the internal senses The third and final point of view to be taken in this consideration of sense consciousness is that of the interplay of the three higher sense power.s among themselves. This, as has been said, can be called the subjective consideration, for in these •• " Memoria enim sequitur phantasiam, quae est motus factus a sensu secundum actum. . . . In quibusdam animalibus ex sensu non fit phantasia et sic in eis non potest esse memoria." I Metaphys., lect. !!, § 10. •• Cf. de Memoria, lect. 8, § 841. •• Cf. ibid., lect. !!, § 8!!1. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 449 interactions the relation of the internal senses to the common sense, through which they reach to external reality, is not being considered, but rather their relations among themselves, and especially as these relations contribute to self-consciousness in the sense order. It is here also that we can approach the question of total sense consciousness, that is, the question of the power or powers to which can be attributed the knowing of all sense activity in a unity. Here, then, are questions not so much of the objects of sense activity as of the acts themselves, that is, of the acts taken as objects. For the memory stores not only the intentions perceived and combined by the cogitative power in regard to external objects, but also the fact of the cogitative's activity; since we can remember how often and when we perceived such and such an individual. In the same way, we can remember that we imagined, and so the operation of imagination is an object for the memory, and finally, and most curious of all, when we consider the limitations of a sense power, we can remember that we remembered. Likewise the cogitative can operate upon the acts of the memory and of the imagination, for it is a part of our experiential knowledge, upon which we rely in practical actions, that we imagine and remember, and, indeed, that we cogitate. Going back and forth, therefore, among the activities of the internal senses, we find them immensely ramified among themselves and reflecting on the activity of one another, and while we must admit that all this is a matter of consciousness, it is not so easy to determine how much each of the different powers contributes to the totality of the general sense awareness of sensitive activity. To take up these several points, one by one, beginning with the interrelationship of the imagination and the memory, it is evident that we can remember that we have imagined as well as we can remember that we have seen or heard this or that external object. We must therefore admit that a connection exists between the memory and the imagination similar 450 MICHAEL STOCK to that between the memory and the common sense, so that the operations of the former are as much subject to recollection and assignation to time past as those of the latter. Thus the activity of the imagination must be subject to being perceived by the cogitative as an individual activity, and, once so perceived, the memory can store and recall the imaginative operation. Hence there is a manifestly self-conscious activity on the part of the cogitative 'and the memory upon the acts of the imagination. Besides this connection of consciousness, there seems to be also a connection between imagination and cogitative and memory similar to that between common sense and themselves, namely, that an act in one is capable of provoking an act in another. This does not involve consciousness, strictly speaking, for the act of the one need not be known as such by the other-nothing more seems to be involved than simple excitation of one power to act by the act of another power. Such an interaction indicates a certain affinity between the three higher internal powers, which, on consideration, seems to follow from that one characteristic they have in common, which is the use of the expressed species or image as terms of their acts. While the external senses cannot act except in the presence of their object, and the common sense cannot act except upon the actual sensations of the external senses, the three higher internal senses necessarily act without contact with the external object, terminating their cognitive operation in an image which they themselves produce. This image, of course, is the expressed species, in which and through which the object is grasped. These internal senses, therefore, are freed from one of the limitations imposed upon the external senses and the common sense, and, in virtue of their freedom, can be actuated it seems, not only from external sensible reality but also by internal and subjective stimulations from each other. Thus a series of day-dreaming imagery can be aroused from a recollection, and an item in a day-dream can lead to a recollection, or cogitations can be the cause or effect of imaginings, SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. 'I'HOMAS 451 The three internal powers seem able to pass an image around once it is evoked in one of them, with each of them performing its proper function in regard to it. 75 Thus the cogitative and the memory are related to the imagination, both as being conscious of its acts and as being influenced by its acts. They are, however, even more closely related to each other. As St. Thomas says: "But in men that which comes close upon memory, as will be said below, is experience .... Experience is from the collection of many singulars received in memory. This kind of collection, however, is proper to man, and pertains to the cogitative power, which is called particular :reason; which is collative of individual intentions as universal reason is of universal intentions." 76 The dynamism involved here is the one which has been mentioned several times before, namely, that the cogitative supplies the memory with the material for its operations, for the memory is like a storehouse of individual intentions. But, besides this contribution of the cogitative to the memory, there must be involved a reverse contribution of the memory to the cogitative, for there could be no collecting of individual intentions and no experience if earlier intentions conserved in the memory were not turned back to the cogitative to be aggregated with the 75 Cf. de Verit., q. 13, a. 3, ad 4. Here St. Thomas, speaking about the manner in which purely spiritual visions can be remembered in the sense memory, explains that the intelligible species in which the vision is formed can assume to themselves sensible species, that is, particular forms and intentions, either in the memory or in the imagination, and by their instrumentality, be conserved in the sensible memory. There is involved, then, a simple interdependence of memory and imagination, apart from their mutual dependence on the external senses. In another context, he states even more explicitly that an image can proceed from the memory to the imagination: "Visio vero corporalis non procedit tan tum a specie exterioris corporis, sed simul cum hoc a sensu videntis; et similiter visio imaginaria non solum procedit a specie quae in memoria conservatur, sed etiam a virtute imaginativa." Here the species conserved in the memory has the same effect in causing a sensation that the appearance of an external body has on the external senses. " Similiter etiam in visione imaginaria invenitur primo species in memoria reservata; secundo ipsa imaginaria visio, quae provenit ex hoc quod acies animae, idest ipsa vis imaginaria, informatur secundum praedictam speciem." Summa Theol., I, q. 98, a. 6, ad 4. 70 1 Metaphys., Iect. l, § 15. MICHAEL STOCK new perceptions. For the building up of experience is not a simple accretion of perceptions, but an operation on the part of the cogitative by which it perceives a kind of unity among many instances, and for such an act, the whole of the past must be joined with the experiences of the present, in a present operation. Similarly, the process of reminiscence depends on the mutual interaction of the cogitative and memory, 77 for reminiscence is an operation which begins with something remembered and proceeds by way of inquiry from this as a principle to some other point which was temporarily forgotten. So reminiscence arises from memory and terminates in memory, and, proceeding by particular reasoning, can pinpoint its path by intermediate memories. Hence in reminiscence there is a continual interplay of the memory and the cogitative. 78 Hence the functioning of the memory as the storehouse for the cogitative differs from the functioning of the imagination as the storehouse for common sense, for in the former case the objects stored are returned to the faculty storing them, but in the latter case this is not so. And in this difference, it would seem, we can find the solution to the problem of how these sense powers know their own acts. The precise problem at issue is to explain how a sense power knows its own act, since, in the psychology of St. Thomas, a sense power cannot reflect on its own act. Taking up the case of how man can remember that he remembers, we could first offer the solution that a remembrance of remembering is accomplished in the intellect, which, as will be seen, reflects upon all the activities of the senses. And this is indeed true, for a part of what anyone might mean when he says that he remembers that he remembers would generally stem from an intellectual awareness of sense activity. But if this were all 77 " Anima in corpore non potest . . . reminisci nisi per virtutem cogitativam et memorativam, per quam phantasma praeparantur." II Cont. Gent., c. 81, a little after the middle . .. Cf. de Memoria, lect. 4, §§ 856-857, 860-862, 864. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS AC.CORDING TO ST. THOMAS 458 that were meant, the act of remembering would not be taken in its strict and proper sense, for such a sense pertains to the act of the sensitive memory .79 And this does not seem to be exactly what is meant when a man says that he remembers that he remembered, for those words seem to signify an act which is strictly in the sense order. If you are asked: Did you remember to speak to X, the affirmative answer would seem to refer to a sensible action of recollection. Further evidence of the fact that this act of recollection is formally in the sense order seems offered from animal behavior, for in learning a process involving a series of choices, an animal must reject and select alternatives which it learned previously to reject and select. This seems to involve remembering that it remembered before. To place the problem now more accurately: how can we explain that the memory remembers its own act, since it cannot be stimulated by its own act of remembering when it has the act. The solution seems to lie in the peculiar relationship mentioned above existing between the memory and the cogitative power, whereby the acts of one another are referred back and forth. In this mutual reflection, the memory first receives and stores the intentions perceived by the cogitative, and later delivers them up, as part of experience, to a new cogitative act, in which the items remembered are combined with new present perceptions. Now when this new act of combination is completed and relegated to the memory, the object remembered would be a complex of past perceptions and newly completed perceptions, all in a unity, but with the note that the past perceptions were delivered up to the cogitative to be combined with the newer ones. That is to say, in the complex now referred to memory, some of the elements are known as having been recently perceived, some as more remotely perceived. For it is evident that we can discern in any area of experience, the different times at which the different elements were apprehended. But thus the memory is perceiving certain perceptions •• Cf. de Verit., q. 10, a. 2: "Whether there is memory in the mind." 454 MICHAEL STOCK as having been of the past, and, since its own act is to know a past apprehension as past, it is perceiving its own act, or remembering that it remembered. In a similar way, the cogitative power can perceive its own acts of perceivin3 individual intentions, not by means of the acts themselves, but insofar as its previous acts stored in the memory are proferred as such, namely, as so many acts of perceiving singular intentions. So it seems that the senses can attain, by mutual cooperation, to a somewhat complete consciousness in their own order, similar, salvatis salvandis, to the consciousness the intellect can accomplish by itself. d. Conclusion Thus the psychology of St. Thomas concludes to a kind of reverbation of sensible images from the external senses to the sense memory and cogitative power, and a somewhat complex interaction of the same images among the powers. i. Summary of sense interplay Briefly summing up the several kinds of interactions, we find: The external senses move the common sense by simple reverberation 80 and in consequence of this, the co:mmon sense knows the acts and objects of the external senses, since its whole cognitive value is focused upon them. So we say that the common sense has cognitive reflection on the external senses. At the same time, the common sense, as moved to act by the external senses, in turn moves the imagination, by a reverberation which is described as a storing of images. The imagination, then, reflects on the external senses by what may be called an operative .reflection, that is, the imagination depends for its act on the act of the external senses, and knows •• We do not wish to leave this term entirely vague, so that it is more obscuring than clarifying. As used here, it means the causality exercised by a sensible image in one power in regard to exciting another power to act. The act of the other power is similar to the act of the first power, following the principle that every agent works for its own similitude, but from it in accordance with the principle that whatever is received is received according to the mode of the receiver. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 455 the objects that they know, but does not know them precisely as they are objects of the external senses, nor does it know the act of the external senses. Finally, there normally is no reverberation of image from imagination to common sense. This could be expressed in graphic form thus. 81 EXTERNAL SENSES COG!iA'I'IIIE --At the same time the external-common sense combination reverberates to the cogitative, and so the cogitative has an operatively reflexive act on these senses, and the imagination also reverberates to the cogitative, so that we have another operative :reflection from cogitative to imagination. Then, since the reverberations from imagination differ in mode from those from the common sense combine, the cogitative can distinguish the objects and acts of the one from those of the other, that is to say, it has cognitive reflection in their .regard, thus: COGITAT!IIE 01 ME MOllY indicates reverberation; c====> indicates cognitive reflection; ;-------.!-> indicates operative reflection. 456 MICHAEL STOCK Finally, the cogitative reverberates into the memory, where its perceptions are stored, and gives rise to operative reflection of memory on cogitative. Since, however, the memory returns its contents to the cogitative, there is a reverse process of reverberation and operative reflection. On the strength, moreover, of this reciprocity, the cogitative is enabled to know the memory's acts as such, because they come to it under their own peculiar modality, and the memory the operations of the cogitative, so that their is mutual cognitive reflection. Finally, as a consequence of this cognitive reflection, these two sense powers achieve an indirect cognitive reflection upon their own acts and objects, as was explained above. Thus: EXTERNAL SENSES IMAGINATION The fact which emerges prominently from this conclusion is the pre-eminence of the cogitative in man's sensitive life in general, and in his sensitive consciousness in particular. It is the only sense power which has cognitive reflection on all of the other powers directly, and on its own act indirectly; the only power, then, which can effectively serve as the center and source of the general awareness of sensation in all its manifestations, and provide, at the same time, the unitive factor which evidently obtains in sense life. When we consider, then, the operations of the cogitative, along the several somewhat complicated lines detailed above, we can begin to see how the total and all-embracing awareness of sensation is built up, even though the several elements that enter into the total are apprehended or perceived initially by distinct sense powers, each operating in its own separate organ and focused on its own proper object. External reality, our own apprehensions thereof, perceptions of the past, experiential appreciations, concomitant imaginings are all coordinated and integrated into a complete SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. 'l'HOMAS 457 representation of the sense world as it is and as it is sensibly known under the master influence of the cogitative. 82 It remains now to consider the mode of this consciousness. ii. The mode of causality in the interplay of the senses Given, then, the fact of a general sense awareness of sensitive activity among the internal senses, the question arises as to the nature of the causality which underlies these interactions. There seem to be two possibilities. The first is that in which the activity and the object of one sense should serve as the object of another sense, just as the sensible qualities of external reality serve as the objects of the external senses. The other is that the activity of one power provokes or stimulates the activity of the other power, after the manner in which any agent educes an effect in a patient. A third explanation, namely, that a sense power could be aware of its own activity has been excluded by St. Thomas, when he says that " it is impossible that any power using a corporeal organ should reflect on its own act, because it is necessary that the instrument by which it knows itself should fall as medium between the power itself and the instrument by which it knew properly." 83 That is to say, if a power is to know its own act, it cannot be informed by its own act after the manner in which matter is informed by a form, for there is no medium in such a union. To know its own act, a power must be informed by the act, and united to the act, in such a way that its own act informs it immaterially, as an object of cognition, and such an information is only possible if the power is entitatively immaterial. 82 There are, of course, other elements in sense activity to account for. and principally the awareness of the self or the sensing subject, and the awareness of affective activity. Of these, something will be said later. •• Ill Sent., d. !i!3, q. 1, a. !i!, ad 8. Again, as he points out in regard to the impossibility of a proper sense knowing its own act, " it is not possible that any material thing should transmute itself; but one is transmuted by another." "Non est autem possible quod aliquid materiale immutet seipsum; sed unum immutatur ab alio." Summa Theol., I, q. 87, a. 3, ad 3. 458 MICHAEL STOCK Neither does St. Thomas hold that the internal sense powers know the activity of the external senses, and their own activities, as external objective realities proferred for their inspection. He reserves this type. of cognition for the activities of the external senses on their objects and of the intellect on the object presented by the internal senses-wherever, that is, there is a bridge over distinct orders, namely, the orders of external reality and sensation and the orders of sensation and intellection, between which there is need of a " light," either physical light or the light of the active intellect, to immaterialize the object up to the grade of immateriality of the cognitive power. But within the order of sensation itself, he does not hold for this type of contact. 84 What he holds for is rather a kind of interaction in which one power, by virtue of its own activity, stimulates or moves another power to its proper activity, and so, by a series of reverberations, the objects sensed by the external senses are grasped in all their complexity by the mutually interactiong play of all the internal senses. Thus he says: " One power using a corporeal organ can know the act of another power insofar as the impression of the lower power redounds into the higher, as we know that sight sees by the common sense." 85 So, as a match can light a piece of wood and the wood can light a piece of paper, and each one burning burns in accordance with. its own nature, so the initial sense impression stimulates a succession of impressions in the •• " Intellectus autem possibilis recipit species alterius generis quam sint in imaginatione; cum intellectus possibilis recipiat species universales, et imaginatio non contineat nisi particulares. Et ideo in intelligibilibus indigemus intellectu agente, non autem in sensibilibus alia potentia activa." Q. D. de Anima, a. 4, ad 5. Whenever St. Thomas speaks positively of thiS kind of cognitive reflection, he mentions only those two cases. " Nulla potentia potest, aliquid cognoscere non convertendo se ad obiectum suum ut visus nihil cognoscit nisi convertendo se ad colorem. Unde, cum phantasma se habeant hoc modo ad intellectum possibilem, sicut sensibilia ad seusum ... numquam (intellectus) actu aliquid considerat ... nisi convertendo se ad phantasmata." De Verit., q. 10, a. 2, ad 7. Cf. II Cont. Gent., c. 67: "Phantasmata movent intellectum possibilem sicut sensibilia sensum." Also in Boet. de Trin., q. 6, a. 2. •• Ill Sent., d. 28, q. 1, a. 2, ad 8. SENSE CONSCIOUSNESS ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS 459 diffol. cit., p. 553). 81 Mediator Dei (loc. cit., p. 555): " Incruenta enim ilia oblatio, qua consecrationis verbis prolatis Christus in statu victimae super altare praesens redditur, ab ipso solo sacrerdote perficitur, prout Christi personam sustinet, non vero prout Christifidelium personam gerit." Address of 2 Nov. 1954 (loc. cit., p. 667): "Ubi nulla sit proprie vereque dicenda potestas sacrificandi nee inveniatur proprie vereque appellandum sacerdotium." •• Cf. Address of 2 Nov. 1954 (lac. cit., p. 668): "In sacrificio activas quasdam partes habere possint et habeant." 530 COLMAN O'NEILL Peter 2: 9, though it is essentially different from that of the celebrant. 83 He makes it clear by the whole emphasis of Mediator Dei that the principal activity of the faithful in the liturgy is that of the moral and theological virtues. Again and again he insists that the chief element in the liturgy is interiorly conceived worship, that there is no opposition between " objective " and " personal " devotion, that the faithful take part in the Eucharistic sacrifice " with such active devotion as to be in the closest union with the High Priest," that the faithful offer themselves as victims. 84 In all of this he echoes the traditional teaching handed down by the Council of Trent. Yet there is some even more intimate way in which the faithful are involved. As is clear from statements of popes and theologians, argues Pius XII, the faithful actually offer the Divine Victim, though in a manner different from that in which the priest offers.85 They hold this privilege by reason of their baptism which makes them members of Christ the Priest and imprints on them a " character " by which they are appointed to the worship of God and share in the priesthood of Christ. 86 Given that the priest, acting in the person of Christ, has placed the Divine Victim on the altar and is offering it to the Father, the faithful may in their own way share in this offering and for two reasons; first, because they offer the sacrifice through the priest, and secondly, because they offer it with him. 87 They offer through the priest (per sacerdotis manus) because 88 Cf. ibid. (loc. cit., p. 669): "Negari vel in dubium vocari non debet fideles quoddam habere sacerdotium, neque hoc parvi aestimare · vel deprimere licet. . . . At quaecumque est huius honorifici tituli et rei vera plenaque significatio, firmiter tenendum est, commune hoc omnium christifidelium, altum utique et arcanum, sacerdotium non gradu tantum sed etiam essentia differre a sacerdotio proprie vereque dicto .... " •• Cf. Mediator Dei (loc. cit., pp. 580-537, 55!l, 557). •• Cf. ibid., p. 554: 'Christifideles etiam divinam offerre hostiam diversa tamen ratione dicendi sunt '; quoting Innocent Til, De sacro altaris mysterio, ill, 6, and St. Robert Bellarmine, De Missa, I, cap. 27. •• Cf. ibid., p. 555: "Baptismatis lavacro generali titulo christiani in Mystico Corpore membra efficiuntur Christi sacerdotis, et ' charactere ' qui eorum in animo quasi insculpitur ad cultum divinum deputantur; atque ideo ipsius Christi sacerdotium pro sua conditione participant." •• Cf. ibid., p. 556. THE RECIPIENT AND SACRAMENTAL SIGNIFICATION 531 the priest acts in the name of Christ considered as Head and as offering in the name of all the members. They also offer with the priest (una cum ipso sacerdote). In explaining this, Pius XII is concerned principally with the content of the offering, or what it signifies on the part of the offerers. The faithful, uniting "their sentiments of praise, entreaty, expiation and thanksgiving with the sentiments or intention of the priest, indeed with those of the High Priest himself," make a spiritual offering of themselves which is caught up into the very oblation of the victim. The self-offering of Christ and that of the faithful are united, says Pius XII, by the priest's external rite and so presented to God the Father. 88 He goes on to develop the function of the external rite in unifying the spiritual offering of Christ and that of the faithful. The external rite of worship must of its very nature be a sign of interior worship; and what is signified by the sacrifice of the New Law is that supreme homage by which Christ, the principal offerer, and with him and through him all his mystical members, pay due honour and veneration to God. 83 The broad outlines of a solution are marked out in these papal documents. The most significant elements, in the light of St. Thomas' teaching on sacramental worship, are the attribution of an undefined function to the baptismal character in the offering of the faithful, and the recognition of the central, unifying position of the visible species which signify the sacrifice. Some recent solutions Theologians, for the most part, have been content to repeat without very much comment the phrases found by the popes for expressing the faithful's part in the Mass. They have insisted on the priest's mediation and, though they have paid their respects to Pius XII's reference to the baptismal character, the majority of them thinks of it as nothing more than a moral •• Cf. ibid., Zoe. cit.: ". . . ut eadem in ipsa victimae oblatione externo quoque sacerdotis ritu, Deo Patri exhibeantur." •• Cf. ibid., loc. cit. 532 COLMAN o'NEILL power, a right to take part in the sacrifice of the Church. The faithful "associate" themselves with the offering by faith. 90 This solution denies the problem. To offer the sacrifice of Christ by faith it is not necessary to have the Mass. It is something in itself non-sacramental, implicit in every act of virtue. The offering by the faithful at Mass must be specifically connected with the sacramental1·epresentation of Calvary. For theologians who hold that Christ, using the minister as his physical instrument, actually offers the Mass the problem must be to associate the faithful's intention of taking part in the sacrifice with the offering of Christ himself in such wise that the external sign of his worship (that is, the sacramentally immolated Body and Blood) may be also the sign of the faithful's worship. However, almost without exception, contemporary theologians of this school are content to state the matter in these terms and to add that it is in virtue of the baptismal character that such an association is possible.91 This 9 ° Cf. S. Tromp, S. J., "Quo sensu in sacrificio Missae offert Ecclesia, offerunt (the priest offers, but "in persona Christi fideles," Periodica 80 (1941) pp. et fidelium "); G. de Broglie, S. J ., " Du role de l'Eglise dans le sacrifice eucharistique," Nouv. rev. th., 70 (11148) pp. 449-460 (that Christ should worship in the Mass is ' un non-sens '; the priest's offering is the faithful's offering); id., "La Messe, oblation de Ia communaute chretienne," Greg. SO (1949) pp. 534-561; F. Palmer, S. J., "The Lay Priesthood: real or metaphorical?," Theol. Studies, 8 (1947) pp. 579 f.; id., "Lay Priesthood: towards a terminology," ibid., 10 (1949) pp. 850 (liturgically, the faithful offer only through the ministry of the priest: a mediate offering); J. Rea, The Common Priesthood of the Members of the Mystical Body, Washington, 1947, pp. G. Bauer," Das heilige Messopfer," Divus Th., Freib., 28 (1950) pp. 25-28; J. McCarthy, "Notes," Irish Eccl. Rec., 88 (1955) p. 208; W. A. Kavanagh, I...ay Participation in Christ's Priesthood, Washington, 1935 (Cf. RSPT 25 (1986) pp. 757, 758). An account of various unorthodox solutions is to be found in J. Brinktrine, "Das Amtspriestertum und das allgemeine Priestertum der Glaubigen," Div. Th., Freib., 22 (1944) p. 808, also in La teologia e i laici, L'Osserv. Romano, 15 Sept. 1954. •• Cf. e.g., A. Kolping, "Der aktive Anteilung der Gliiubigen an der Darbringung des eucharistischen Opfers." Div. Th., Freib., 27 (1949) pp. 869-880; Y. Congar, 0. P., Jalons pour une theologie du laicat (Coli. "Unam sanctam," n. 20), Paris. B. Durst, Das W esen ... , 1958, pp. 246 f., esp. p. 292 (cf., however, p. pp. 61 f., develops the matter considerably, suggesting that the faithful participate in the Mass in two ways: making the offering of the Body and Blood the sign of their interior self-oblation, and also offering "ministerially," by reason of their baptismal characters, the worship of Christ on the cross. This appears a false THE RECIPIENT· AND SACRA:!'.1ENTAL SIGNIFICATION 533 amounts to a restatement in explicitly Thomistic terms of the essential words of Mediator Dei. 92 A solution The solution is to be sought in the relation between the Eucharist and the baptismal character. In these terms the problem is to be formulated: how does his baptismal character enable the individual Christian to designate the double consecration as the sacrificial sign of his charity? It is to be observed first of all that sacramental offering of the Body and Blood by the celebrant already signifies in a certain sense the worship of the faithful in so far as it signifies the mediatorial worship of Christ, the Head of the Mystical Body, since his worship virtually, as the source of all merit, includes the worship of all Christians. In exactly the same way the worship of all Christians was expressed outwardly on Calvary; and this universality attaches to the Mass in so far as it is identical with Calvary. The Mass adds nothing to the merit of Calvary. What it does add, precisely as the sacrifice of the Church, offered by men, is the actual signification of the charity of those who participate, which was signified on Calvary only as included in Christ's charity, and which has now been derived from Head to members in such a way that it is formally theirs. It is at this point that a certain clarification can be achieved using St. Thomas' principles. The Mass is not a natural sacrifice; it is sacramental, the sacrament of a natural sacrifice. Although, therefore, all those who believe in Christ may " offer " by faith and charity the sacrifice of Calvary, only those who have received the sacrament of baptism may offer the Mass in the sense of designating the double consecration as the sacrificial sign of their charity, since baptism is the "gate-way to the sacraments." The sacramental Body and Blood, under the species of bread and wine, can actually signify the charity only of the baptized. dichotomy (see below). Moreover, the interpretation of the instrumentality to be attributed to the baptismal character does not correspond to the teaching of St. Thomas as set out above. •• Cf. above, n. 88. 534 COLMAN o'NEILL This is made clearer when the sacramental form of this sacrifice is considered. In conformity with the circumstances of its institution it takes the form of a meal. This is a central idea with St. Thomas, taken from the Scriptures, referred to explicitly a number of times, and implicit in the essential concept of the Eucharist as food. 93 Participation in the sacrifice is confined to those who may receive food from the table; that is to say, to the baptized; 94 and it is the character that formally gives the power of receiving. 95 It is because the sacramental signs of the sacrifice of the Mass take the form of food that they can serve as the sacrificial sign of the charity of the baptized and, formally, only of the baptized. The species of bread and wine contain the Body and Blood of Christ as the Food of the soul and hence they signify the effect of that Food, namely, the unity of the Church in charity. This is an Augustinian theme that St. Thomas never tires of repeating. 96 It is only a short •a Cf. Summa Theol., III, q. 66, a. 9, ad 5: "In sacramento Eucharistiae commemoratur mors Christi inquantum ·ipse Christus passus exhibetur nobis quasi paschale convivium, secundum illud I Cor. 5: 'Pascha nostrum immolatus est Christus; itaque epulemur ' "; q. 80, a. 10, ad 2: "In hoc sacramento traditur nobis memoriale passionis Christi per modum cibi "; q. 78, a. 6: Utrum agnus paschalis fuerit praecipua figura huius sacramenti; q. 80, a. 6: "mensa Dominica"; I Cor., c. 11, lect. 4, 5 passim, e. g., lect. 5 (654): "Offertur specialiter hoc sacramentum sub specie panis et vini. Primo quidem, quia pane et vino communius utuntur homines ad suam refectionem .... " Eucharist is food: cf. III, q. 78, a. 1; a. 2; a. 8, ad 1; ad 2; q. 75, a. 5; q. 76, a. 1, ad 2; a. S, ad 1; q. 78, a. S, ad 1; q. 79, a. 1; a. 4, ad a. 5; q. 80, a. 6; a. 10, ad 1; q. 81, a. 8, ad 1; etc. •• Cf. III, q. 80, a. 6: "Cum enim quilibet Christianus ex hoc ipso quod est baptizatus, sit admissus ad mensam Dominicam ... "; q. 65, a. 8: "Sacramentum baptismi ordinatur ad Eucharistiae receptionem "; q. 67', a. 2; In Matt., c. 6, n. S (592): " Ex quo quis baptizatus est, ius· habet in isto pane"; ibid., c. 26, n. S (2178): " .•• Nulli non baptizato debet dari huiusmodi sacramentum ... immo infideles non debet admitti ad videndum istud sacramentum; unde in primitiva Ecclesia, quando multi erant catechumeni, recipiebantur in Ecclesia usque ad Evangelium, et tunc expellebantur." •• Cf. ill, q. 82, a. 1: " Sicut autem baptizato conceditur a Christo potestas sumendi hoc sacramentum, ita sacerdoti, cum ordinatur, confertur potestas hoc sacramentum consecrandi "; In Matt., c. 26, n. S (2178): "Sicut non conficeret sacerdos nisi consecratus, sic non debet alicui illud ministrari nisi baptizato "; ill,q.68. •• Cf. ibid., q. 67, a. 2: sacramentum ecclesiasticae unionis; q. 78, a. !l, Sed c.; a. 8, ad S: sacramentum caritatis; q. 78, a. 4; q. 74, a. 1, ad 1; q. 78, a. S, ad 6; caritatis quasi figurativum et affectivum; y. 79, a. I; a. 2; THE RECIPIEN1' AND SACRAl\iEXTAL SIGNIFICATION 585 step from this idea of signification of charity as an effect of the sacrament to that of signification of the charity of the faithful as directed towards, or animating, the sacramentsacrifice. It is a step which St. Thomas would have had no difficulty in taking, as witness such texts as those in which he says that water is added to the wine ·at Mass so as to signify the union of the faithful with Christ; though, in fact, he understands this again of the effect of the sacrament. 91 St. Thomas summarizes his teaching on the sacrament of the Eucharist: This is the sacrament of the body of Christ; but the body of Christ is the Church, which is raised up into the unity of a body from many faithful; hence this is the sacrament of the unity of the Church. 98 The application of this concept of the Eucharist to the sacrifice of the Mass is in the full tradition of St. Paul, I Cor. 10:16-21, and of St. Augustine in De civitate Dei, Bk. 10, ch. 6: This is the sacrifice of Christians: "many who are one body in Christ." This the Church clearly and frequently repeats to the faithful in the sacrament of the altar, where it is shown that in that which she offers she is herself offered.99 That is to say, what is offered is the Body of Christ which (since it is the Food of the soul) symbolizes the charity that unites all members of the Church. Consequently, the offering that the Church makes symbolizes in the ma11ner proper to an external act of religion the offering of herself, that is, of all the faithful. q. 80, a. 4; ad 1; a. 5, ad q. a. ad S; q. 88, a. 4; ad S; a. 5; I Cor., c. 11, lect. 5 (654); De art. fidei IV Sent., d. 45, q. a. S, sol. 1. Cf. ill, q. 74, a. 6: " ... ad significandum effectum huius sacramenti, qui est unio populi christiani ad Christum "; q. 74, a. 7; a. 8, ad q. a. S, ad 1: .n. 4 "Sangnini admiscetur aqua, quae significat populum "; In Matt., c. I Cor., c. 11, lect. 6 (684). 08 In Joann., c. 6, n. 6 (960). On the typically Augustinian reasoning of this text, with its direct transition from .,acramentum to res, omitting or referring ambiguously to the res et aacramentum, cf. P.-Th. Camelot, "Rea.Iisme et symbolisme dans Ia doctrine eucharistique de S. Augustin," Rev. sc. phil. theol., Sl (1947) pp. 894-410. •• De eivitate Dei, lib. 10, c. 6 (CCL 47 !!79). 536 COLMAN o'NEILL Only the baptized may thus participate in the Mass since the Eucharist can cause grace only in those who bear the baptismal character, and consequently can signify formally the charity only of such. The Mass is the sacrifice of those who have the power to receive the Eucharist. There is evidently a difference between the function of the baptismal character at Mass and the one that it has in reception of the sacraments. In the latter case it is required on the part of the subject for the perfection of the sacramental sign, the opus operatum. The Mass, however, is in no sense dependent on the faithful so far as the sacramental rite goes. The sacrament is perfected at the moment of consecration and this is solely the act of the celebrant. The sacramental power of the faithful is posterior to this (posterioritate naturae) . It enables them to make the sacrament-sacrifice the sign of their own charity. The baptismal character intervenes here in so far as the sacrament is of its nature suitable for signifying the charity only of those who may receive the Eucharist. Hence the character intervenes simply as a physical entity, as something implied on the part of the faithful by the sign. It gives validity to the individual's intention of participating in the Mass, as it does to his intention of receiving the sacraments; but in a different way. In the Mass there is no question of instrumental material causality. It is because the character is a permanent quality incorporating a person into Christ sacramentally-as one qualified to use the sacraments-that it enables its subject to use the Mass as the expression of his own charity. It is here that is to be noted the prime difference between the powers of the priestly and those of the baptismal characters in the Mass. Whereas the priestly character is effective independently of the moral disposition of the celebrant, the intention of participation that gains validity from the baptismal character is essentially an elicited act of religion. The celebrant offers the Body and Blood as the sign of Christ's redemptive charity. The baptized Christian offers them as the sign of his own worship. In this way the Church literally fills up what is lacking in the sufferings of Christ since the charity of her THE RECIPIENT AND SACRAMENTAL SIGNIFICATION 537 members is now explicitly signified by the identical sacrifice, sacramentally renewed, which on Calvary signified the charity of the Church only as included in Christ's. Though the Mass is in this way the sacrifice of all the baptized, it is in a special way the sacrifice of those who are present at its celebration. Indeed, since it is a sacrament, a sign, it is only those who are pl'esent who participate in the full sense sacramentally. The congregation, grouped together into one body, acknowledging the sole competence of the celebrant to perform the ritual which is to clothe their devotion, form around the altar a sign of the Mystical Body, subordinated to the priestly mediation of its Head. Personal assistance alone satisfies fully the demands of this sacranientalism. The faithful who are not present assist sacramentally by reason of their baptism and, further, by their public adherence to the Catholic Church. There are clearly varying degrees of participation to be distinguished here, and even heretics in good faith can be truly said to offer the Mass. Finally, there is a broad sense in which even the non-baptized, if they believe in Christ, may be said to offer. This, at least, appears to be a conclusion in harmony with St. Thomas' understanding of the influence of the Eucharist as extending as far as that of Christ himself.100 What St. Thomas says of receiving the Holy Eucharist spiritually and not sacramentally may be applied here.101 All those who believe in Christ may " offer " by faith and charity the sacrifice of Calvary. It follows that, since the Mass is identified with Calvary, those who believe in Christ, yet are not baptized, may also " offer " the Mass by faith and charity; but they can do this precisely in the measure that the Mass is identified with Calvary and is the sacrifice offered by Christ; not, therefore, formally as a sacramental sacrifice offered by the Church, since the sacramental signs do not belong to them. The sacrifice Summa Theol., III, q. 78, a. 8. Ibid., q. 80, a. 1, ad 8: "Aliqui manducant spiritualiter hoc sacramentum antequam sacramentaliter sumant. Sed hoc contingit dupliciter. Uno modo, propter desiderium sumendi ipsum sacramentum; et hoc modo dicuntur baptizari et mandu· care spiritualiter et non sacramentaliter illi qui desiderant sumere haec sacramenta iam instituta. Alio modo propter figuram. . . ." 100 101 538 COLMAN o'NEILL that they immediately " offer " by faith is the natural sacrifice of Calvary; only indirectly, therefore, can they "offer" the Mass. Such an " offering," by definition, can have no effect ex opere operato. Because the baptized faithful can offer sacramentally the sacrifice of Christ himself their worship takes on new and wonderful qualities. It procures the proper effects of sacrifice: in particular, it makes satisfaction for sin/ 02 and it placates God; 103 it honours him and procures the salvation of the living and the dead. 104 The effect or fruit of this offering can be measured only by God. What is certain is that it corresponds to the charity of Christ in proportion to the degree of charity of the individual members of the faithfuU 05 This second element is determined by many factors: actual presence at Mass, offering of a stipend, the quality of the intention of participating (actual, virtual, habitual), the fervour of the act of charity. Insofar as the fruit exceeds the strict merits of the individual it is ex opere operato, produced, that is, through the due performance of the prescribed ritual by the priest. To celebrate Mass, to procure the sacramental sacrifice of Christ, an ordained priest is sufficient. Much more is required -and is always supplied-if the Mass is to be truly the sacrifice of the Church. For that there is demanded o£ the faithfulpriests as well as laity-moral effort, a life of virtue, spiritual sacrifices-all that the Fathers insisted on when they spoke of the " royal priesthood " of the faithful. This immolation, writes Pius XII, 103 Ibid., a. 3; a. 6, ad 3; q. 49, a. 4. Ibid., q. 48, a. !l; ad l. Cf. IV Sent., d. 18, q. 1, a. sol. 1 (p. 554, n. 66). 105 Cf. IV Sent., d. 13, q. 1, a. 2, sol. 3, ad 3 (p. 556, n. 78): "Omnis nostra 10 • 10 • nostra actio per Christum perfici debt. Et ideo . . . oportet quod . . . Missa in Ecclesia celebretur "; III, q. 79, a. 5: "Quamvis haec oblatio ex sui quantitate [cf. ill, q. 48, a. 2] sufficiat ad satisfaciendum pro omni poena, tamen fit satisfactoria illis pro quibus ofiertur, vel etiam ofl'erentibus, secundum quantitatem suae devotionis, et non pro tota poena"; q. 49, a. 3, ad 2; " ... multo minor sufficit (poenalitas) quam esset condigna peccato, cooperante satisfactione Christi "; Cf. III, q. 49, a. 1, ad 4; a. 8, ad 1; Cajetan, De celebratione Missae, works out in mathematical proportions the fruit for the offerers and for those for whom they offer. taking into account the devotion of each. THE RECIPIENT AND SACRAMENTAL SIGNIFICA'l'ION 539 is not restricted to the liturgical sacrifice.... But, inevitably, it is when the faithful are taking part in the liturgical action with such faith and devotion that it may be truly said that their " faith and devotion are known to Thee," that their faith will more eagerly work by charity and their devotion grow more fervent. 106 The Mass ' means ' union with Christ: it presupposes such union, at least in an initial degree; and it promotes union. Today's Mass is consummated in the offering of tomorrow's Mass. 107 The daily sacrifice draws the whole life of the Church into the sacrifice of Christ, announcing the death of the Lord until he come. Conclusions I. Reception of the sacraments is an act of worship. The inner dispositions with which the subject approaches a sacrament are expressed outwardly by the opus operatum, not in its entirely (as such it is a common action of minister and subject and not, therefore, elicited by the subject alone), but by that part of it which is produced by the subject; in other words, by the reception of the sacrament. It is question here of the sacrament as sign, prior to its causality; and the intervention of the baptismal character, procuring valid reception, is presupposed. II. It is by reason of the faith of the Church alone that sacraments administered to m:1eonscious subjects are acts of worship. In the case of those who previously had the use of reason habitual dispositions on the part of the subject are implied in this act of worship. III. The act of reception is elicited by the remote dispositions for sacramental grace, which remain, at least virtually, at the moment when the sacrament acts. Both grace and the proximate dispositions for it are signified at this moment, not as eliciting the act of reception, but as the effect of the sacrament. 101 Mediator Dei, loc. cit., pp. 557, 668. 1.o• Summa Th6()l., ill, q. S!i!, a. 7: " .• fructum sacrificii ... quod est sacrificium spirituale." 540 COLMAN o'NEILL IV. The full opus operans of the subject consists in his remote dispositions and in his intention of receiving the sacrament. V. The sacrifice of Christ is sacramentally represented in the Mass under the form of a meal. Because the Body and Blood of Christ are thus present as food they signify not only the redemptive charity of Christ but also the charity of all those who have the power of eating Christ sacramentally. It is the baptismal character that gives this power; and hence it is it too that makes the faithful's intention of participating in the Mass valid. The offering of the Mass by the faithful consists, therefore, essentially in acts of charity. The character, as a permanent, sacramental incorporation into the Mystical Body of Christ enables its subject to designate the sacramental Body and Blood as the sacrificial sign of his charity. In the Mass the opus operatum is produced by the priest alone. It serves as the sign of the opus operans of the faithful. At Mass, consequently, the sacrifice of Christ signifies actually charity which on Calvary was signified only as included in Christ's, and which has now been derived to the members of Christ. VI. Personal assistance alone satisfies fully the sacramentalism of the Mass, but all the baptized can offer sacramentally by reason of their characters. In a broad sense, even the nonbaptized may 'offer' the Mass by faith and charity, in so far as it is the sacrifice of Christ, identified with Calvary. COLMAN O'NEILL, Dominican Houae of Studiu, Tallaght, Dublin, Eire 0. P. NOTES ON OUR CONTRIBUTORS MICHAEL STocK, 0. P., S. T. LR., PH. D., a graduate of the Pontifical Athenaeum Angelicum, is a Professor of Psychology at the Dominican House of Studies, Dover, Massachusetts. DAVID B. RicHARDSON, PH. D., a member of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Detroit, is engaged in teaching and in the preparation of a work on the philosophy of history. CoLMAN O'NEILL, 0. P., S. T. LR., S. T. L., formerly a professor at the Dominican House of Studies outside of Dublin, has taken up the post of Professor of Dogmatic Theology at the Institute Jesus Magister in Rome. EDWARD D. SIMMONS, PH. D. is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Marquette University. GERMAIN G. GRISEZ, M.A., PH. L. is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Georgetown University. 541 BOOK REVIEWS Man's Knowledge of Reality. By FREDERICK WILHELMSEN. Englewood with indices. $4.00. Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1956. Pp. It is probably true as far as textbooks are concerned that even a good one is at best only a mixed blessing. Nevertheless, considering the average size of the contemporary class, we must be alert to the appearance of any worthwhile textbook which may assist us in our teaching. Teachers of scholastic philosophy have for years watched for the appearance of an adequate textbook in epistemology. Their watch has, for the most part, been unrewarded. Because there is little agreement on the exact nature of epistemology and because any investigation into the mystery of knowledge is exceedingly difficult, only few attempts have been made to satisfy the need for a textbook in epistemology. Of these few perhaps the most significant {at least in English) has been Frederick Wilhelmsen's Man's Knowledge of Reality, published in by Prentice-Hall. In the two years since its publication this book has found favor with many, and in that time no other textbook in epistemology written by a scholastic has appeared to challenge it. Because of this it seems highly reasonable to predict not only continued but even increased use of this book in the philosophy curricula of our Catholic colleges. This is the situation which prompts this present critical review of the book. Man's Knowledge of Reality (subtitled An Introduction to Thomistic Epistemology) is proposed by the author not strictly as a textbook but more simply as an essay towards a Thomistic epistemology. Wilhelmsen requests that his work be evaluated first of all by the way it measures up to reality and secondly by the extent of its faithfulness to the philosophy of St. Thomas. There is no question but that he feels that if it measures up to the one it will measure up to the other. As for his brand of Thomism, Wilhelmsen declares himself outside of the school of the classical Commentators. That this is true is clearly seen in his own text and in his choice of the majority of his secondary references. Clearly Wilhelmsen owes most, as far as secondary sources are concerned, to philosophers who have repudiated the Thomistic authenticity of the teaching of Cajetan and John of St. Thomas. Wilhelmsen opens his book with the admission that there is no science which is uniquely epistemology. However, he insists that there is a philosophical investigation properly epistemological in nature, though the investi- 542 BOOK REVIEWS 543 gation is not limited to any one philosophical discipline. In fact, an evaluation of the several possible meanings of " epistemology " reveals for Wilhelmsen three valid meanings for the term. Histo.Jically, "epistemology" refers to the way men confront the critical problem. This is the first valid meaning. Secondly, "epistemology" can refer to an investigation linking the metaphysics of knowledge (itself not epistemology) with the psychology of knowledge (itself not epistemology). Finally," epistemology" (and here there are as many distinct epistemologies as there are distinct knowledges) can refer to the investigation of the conditions proper to the many different kinds of human knowledge. Wilhelmsen proceeds to order his book according to these three meanings of "epistemology." In Part I ("Metaphysical Realism") he confronts, and disposes of, the "critical problem." In Part II ("Judgment and Truth ") he moves from a general consideration of the metaphysics and psychology of human knowledge to a searching analysis of judgment, and thence to a consideration of truth and certitude. Finally, in Part III ("An Introduction to Epistemology of Speculative Science ") he considers generally the nature of speculative science and the classification of the speculative sciences. The result is, for the most part, a well ordered textbook maturely composed and proportioned to upper division students with a solid formation in the philosophy of man and metaphysics. Since the time of Descartes the " critical problem " has proven to be a stumbling block to philosophers, if not to philosophy itself. The compulsion to attempt philosophically to establish the right to philosophize has invariably driven the critical philosopher into a blind alley, leading him nowhere save further and further into his criticism. The history of philosophy since the seventeenth century yields example after example of the folly invested in asking and attempting to answer the question of how we move from our knowledge of things to the actual existence of things, of how we get out of our knowledge to the things we know. The fact is, of course, that there is no solution to the " critical problem." But, fortunately, neither is there a " critical problem ,; to begin with. Our primary cognitive experiences are not directly of cognition itself, but rather of things. What is directly given in our primary cognitive experience (i. e., the sensory-intellectual grasp of the actually present sensible existent) is not the mind, nor the thing existing in the mind, but the thing existing extramentally and other than the mind. The problem facing the epistemologist is, fortunately, not to prove the things that are known are but to show how things that are are known. Wilhelmsen is well aware of this and proceeds accordingly. However, while rejecting the "critical problem" as a false start philosophically he takes great pains to give an account of his rejection thereof. Chapters 2, 3, 4, and 5 are particularly forceful in exposing the false sophistication and futility of the critical position and in 544 BOOK REVIEWS establishing the fact of the evidence of being on which the non-critical approach to epistemology is based. Wilhelmsen points out that the critical approach which begins with thought itself is based upon the Platonic notion of man which splits man up into two entities, soul and body, each with its own operations essentially divorced from those of the other. The soul, in such an accidental composite can know essences, but not as concretized in concrete sensible existents. The body can know sensible existents, but only as sensible and not as existing. Being, in its true formality as that which exercises the act of existing, simply cannot be directly known by the Platonic man. Such a man could try to establish the fact of being, but he would be compelled to start without it. Such is the plight of any critical philosopher. The Thomistic notion of man, borrowed, of course, from Aristotle, allows for a direct knowledge of being. Man is one entity, composed of part-principles, body and soul; his cognitive acts are neither of body alone nor soul alone; they are his. By his senses he contacts the actually existing sensible thing and by his intellect in this one sensoryintellectual experience he contacts the existence of the existing thing. In this way he is directly cognizant of the first principle of both knowledge and reality, namely, being itself. Accordingly he begins to philosophize with the evidence of being. He knows, to begin with, that being is; and he need not try the impossible ta.Sk of establishing this on the basis of something prior to it. This non-critical position, which for Wilhelmsen is the only reasonable position and the position he ascribes to St. Thomas, is called " metaphysical realism." It is a position offering no answer to the " critical problem " precisely because it denies that there is a " critical problem." And this denial is based on the incontrovertible evidence of experience. What I know when I know things are these things existing apart from and other than my knowing of them. The fact that when I know them I know that I know them does not detract from the fact that the primary data directly revealed in my knowledge of existing things are these existing things. One may deny that this is his experience and assume a sophisticated position which involves the critical approach. But one need not; as a Thomist one cannot; in fact, as a philosopher destined sometime to penetrate the mysteries of being, one cannot; for originally to cut oneself off from the evidence of bemg is to preclude the possibility, no matter how ingenious the critique attempted, ever of reaching being in its true formality as that which is. Wilhelmsen completes Part I of the book with two interesting but, as far as their conclusions are concerned, rather ordinary chapters. In the first of these he establishes the fact that " being " signifies either as a verb or a participle and not as a noun; in the second he establishes the point that neither the subject nor the predicate, but rather the verb " to be," expresses the existence attained in judgment. BOOK REVIEWS 545 Since simple apprehension bears only on essence while judgment bears as well on the act of existing, and since reasoning is only for the sake of judgment, Wilhelmsen insists upon the primacy of judgment in an adequate epistemology. Accordingly, in Part II of his book, where he attempts to link the metaphysics of knowledge with the psychology of knowledge, the concentration is heavily upon that instance of knowledge which is the judgment. However, before getting into the question of the judgment there are two chapters devoted to ·knowledge considered generally, the one to its metaphysics, the other to its psychology. In what he refers to as an introduction to the metaphysics of knowledge Wilhelmsen begins by exthe " copy theory " of knowledge, which would explain knowledge in terms of some picture in the mind of the knower of the thing known. Pointing out the impossibility ever of knowing being if such a theory concerning knowledge is the fact, he warns against any misrepresentation or misunderstanding of the Thomistic theory as though it were but a variation of the "copy theory." This leads quite naturally into the highly metaphysical consideration of intentional being. In turn Wilhelmsen points out that knowledge is an extension of the knower; that the principle of knowability is immateriality; that the union between knower and known is a non-physical union; that in knowledge the known is re-presented to the knower (but not that knowledge is a representative of the known) in such fashion that it not only is (esse) in the first existence it has as a thing independent of knowledge but that it is present to (esse-ad) the knower in a second existence as an object of knowledge; and finally that knowledge is a pure sign, a formal sign, signifying the known to the knower without itself enjoying the status of being any thing. Wilhelmsen treats the psychology of knowledge as a review, briefly sketching the moments of ideogenesis through the operations of external and internal senses, agent intellect, and possible intellect. Stress is placed upon the fact that the species which informs the possible intellect after being abstracted from the phantasm through the light of the agent intellect comes ultimately from the thing in the real and is a " formal and existential ' prolongation ' of the form and being of the thing." The phantasm, which is to play a highly significant role in Wilhelmsen's explanation of judgment, is described as a " highly refined sensorial image which is the expression of the whole sensorial-perceptive process." Chapters 10, 11, 12, and 13 are the crucial chapters of the book. Here Wilhelmsen gets to the heart of epistemology, the theory of judgment. In turn he discusses the structure and meaning of judgment, the process of judgment, truth, and finally assent to truth and the verbum. Wilhelmsen does not speak of judgment simply as the second operation of the intellect, for he views it rather as a complex act involving both sense and intellect. Existence is found only in concrete singular existents; hence any knowledge 546 BOOK REVIEWS cut off from concrete singular things cannot bear on existence; but judgment bears on existence and so also on concrete singular things. The human intellect by itself contact the concrete singular thing, since the matter which makes it singular also makes it unintelligible; the intellect by itself can know only universal essences or the natures of individual things cut away from the individuation which is the condition for actual existence. A man judges by reflecting to the individual thing as represented in the phantasm produced through the action of thing upon the senses. He judges by thinking a nature (known in simple apprehension) as be-ing the nature of a subject presented in a phantasm. Wilhelmsen admits the traditional subject-predicate composition of the proposition. But he denies the classical explanation of this composition which explains subject and predicate as distinct objects of apprehension (i.e., two as meanings) known as identical in subject (i.e., one in existence). He argues both from his own experience in judging and from reason that the only intelligibility the subject can have in the propo!!ition is the meaning which is the predicate. Arguing (with seeming support from the texts of St. Thomas) that the intellect can be informed by but one species at a time and that the predicate is form of the subject, Wilhelmsen concludes to the impossibility of any meaning for the subject beyond the meaning given it by the predicate in any given proposition; and this, he says, is verified by his own experience. The subject is but " the finger of the intellect " pointing to something about which the predicate, " the voice of the intellect," says something. He admits, of course, that the man who judges may know more about the subject than expressed in the predicate. But he denies that this knowledge can be consciously articulated at the moment of judgment. He places it on the level of the Freudian prC-conscious, ascribing to the phantasm the task not only of presenting to the intellect the form which specifies the predicate in a given proposition but the mysterious task of symbolically representing the whole latent field of meanings which have been and might in future propositions be said of the thing which is the subject. In judging, then, one thinks a subject presented in a phantasm, which symbolizes a host of pre-conscious meanings belonging to that subject, to exist as formed by a predicate expressing a determinate mode of being, itself originally grasped by abstraction from this phantasm. But this is not the complete explanation of judgment. When we judge we not only know the existential information of subject by predicate, but we know that we know this. If the proposition which expresses this existential information measures up to reaiity then it is true. The final step in judging comes in the active commitment of the mind. upon sufficient evidence to the truth of the proposition it forms: ·This is the judgment most strictly considered: the act of assent precisely to the truth of the proposition formed. In the act of assent the mind says the truth, and this interior BOOK REVIEWS .547 and spiritual expression of the truth is the word of the mind or the verbum; this is the truth consciously expressed. The complete act of judging, then, involves apprehension of an essence or mode of being abstracted from existing individuals; reflection back to the phantasm and thence to an existing subject; the composition is a proposition of this essence as a form of this existing subject; insight into the conformity of this proposition with reality; finally, commitment to the truth of this proposition in an interior act of assent to it. These chapters on the epistemology of judgment, which in the opinion of the author are the very heart of this work, take up better than a third of the length of the book. They are followed by a final chapter in Part II of the book. This chapter is an uncommonly clear exposition of what for the most part is the common scholastic doctrine on certitude and its types, as well as opinion and error. The most significant contribution of the chapter is the effort made to explain the causality of error. A judgment is explained as true because it terminates in something which is not only a term of a relation but a subject of existence, while a judgment is explained as false when it terminates in something which is only the term of a relation. Part HI of Man's Knowledge of Reality includes but one chapter, "An Introduction to Epistemology of Speculative Science." Although the author excuses himself in the Preface for the brevity of the third part of his book it remains nevertheless a severe disappointment. Agree or disagree with Wilhelmsen in the first two parts of his work, nevertheless it is impossible not to admire the intensity with which he goes about his task of disposing of the " critical problem " and of probing the depths of the judgment. But in this final part there is a minimum of philosophical penetration and the obscurity which invariably follows upon excessive brevity. Some information is given, but the value of this is lessened by a questionable ordering of these points of information. The reviewer is tempted to suspect that somehow editorial surgery helped shape this part of the book into the form in which it was published. It bears unmistakable signs of a " cut and paste " operation of rather major proportions when compared with its much more imposing and penetrating predecessors. The points made in the final chapter, in the order in which they are made, are simply these: that knowledges are many; that they are distinguished into the practical and the speculative by way of a distinction in ends; that they can be distinguished according to diverse material objects; that they can be distinguished by way of diverse formal objects; that differences in method can distinguish them one from another; that as habits of the intellect they are distinguished by the mind of man; that " science " has acquired a new meaning in the modern world; that " science " in the traditional sense is knowledge through causes; that sciences differ according as their relations 548 BOOK REVIEWS to matter differ; that on the basis of a distinction in scientific objects in relation to matter there are three distinct types of intellectual acts corresponding to three different types of science, namely the abstraction of a whole which is proper to the sciences of nature, the abstraction of a form proper to mathematics, and separation or negative judgment proper to metaphysics. It is interesting to note that Wilhelmsen takes pains to reject the traditional teaching of the three degrees of formal abstraction as differentiating the speculative sciences after allowing almost anything else as a legitimate principle of scientific differentiation. Man's Knowledge of Reality represents a serious effort to satisfy the need for an adequate textbook in epistemology for English-speaking students. Its basic plan is sound. While denying that there is a " critical problem " one cannot in the face of the history of modern philosophy simply ignore the question. Recognizing this Wilhelmsen wisely begins his book by explaining the " critical problem " and by substantiating his rejection of it. After having taken care of this Wilhelmsen is prepared to enter into the epistemological investigation of knowledge. Here, as always, the proper order is from the more general to the more particular; and Wilhelmsen observes this order by treating first of knowledge in general and then of the division of knowledge into its types. His explanation and rejection of the " critical problem " is one of the strong points in the book. Granted he owes much to Gilson for the ideas expressed in the first part of the book, nevertheless, the expression of these ideas is his own; and, for the most part, it constitutes an effective exposition well calculated to get the thoughtful student safely past the Cartesian obstacle to fruitful philosophy. Another strong point in the book is Wilhelmsen's treatment of the "copy theory " of knowledge. Not only does he describe the position of the " copyists " well, effectively illustrating its futility and showing how unnecessary it is as an attempt to explain knowledge, but he very cleverly indicates the manner in which an unsuspecting common-sense realist might rather easily be reduced to an idealistic position by a dialectically skilled idealist. It has been the experience of this reviewer that many students are to a greater or lesser extent in fact victims of an intellectual seduction which turns them from a native realism to a sophisticated idealism. Wilhelmsen has done a service in indicating how easily the unwary can be trapped by the tempting thesis of the idealists, for here, as elsewhere, to be forewarned is to be forearmed. The decision to center the epistemology of knowledge in general around the judgment is a happy one. There is no doubt but that judgment has a primacy over both apprehension and reasoning. The stress on the importance of the phantasm in knowledge and especially in judgment is also to be commended. To divorce the operation of the intellect from the phantasm and the operations of the senses producing the phantasm is to introduce a split in man not warranted by the criterion of our experi- BOOK REVIEWS .549 ence. In stressing the intimate connection between the sensory and the intellectual in man Wilhelmsen has carefully avoided the psychological absurdity of speaking of faculties as though they themselves were agents acting. We all know, but unfortunately frequently speak and even teach as though we did not know, that the sense does not sense nor does the knows by way of sense and intellect. intellect understand but There are a number of difficulties which arise throughout the text, and which, to this reviewer at least, considerably lessen the value of the book. I shall discuss but three. The first of these is found in Part I of the book, and this one, though somewhat disturbing, is hardly sufficient to vitiate an otherwise excellent treatment of the "critical problem." Wilhelmsen proposes that for a Platonist the evidence of being would be lacking. What he means, it seems to me, is that if we were as Plato says we are we would not have the experience of being we do have. It is not because we are Thomists that we have the experience of being which grounds our epistemology, but rather it is because we are as Thomists say we are that this is true. It is the primary experience of being achieved in our sensoryintellectual experience of sensible existents which grounds us epistemologically-not our philosophical explanation for this experience. If this latter were true we would be reduced to a critical position, and one which, as for all critical positions, we could never defend. On what would I ground my philosophy of man if my philosophy of man were necessary as founding the integrity of my knowledge? Wilhelmsen has not intended to make the philosophy of man the starting point, but there is some danger that the student will mistake his point because of the manner in which he introduces the question of Platonic psychology. The second difficulty is far more serious and cannot be explained away on the basis of any factors simply semantic. Wilhelmsen's theory of the judgment, which is the central thesis of his book, involves as an indispensable part of it the teaching that only the predicate of a proposition is directly a bearer of meaning. The subject, though presented in a phantasm which may symbolically signify a great number of latent meanings hidden in the pre-conscious, has no conscious meaning in a proposition save that of the predicate said to inform it. Wilhelmsen argues to this from his own experience in judging and from the texts of St. Thomas where St. Thomas says that only one species at a time can inform the intellect and where he makes the point that the predicate is related to the subject as form to matter. It might seem that one cannot take issue with Wilhelmsen's own experience. However, Wilhelmsen himself would certainly be willing to admit that if this is not the experience of others as well as himself the argument from experience does not hold. To this reviewer it seems clear through experience and reason that whenever we are involved with a per se nota proposition the meaning of both subject and predicate must be con- 550 BOOK REVIEWS sciously articulated. How else can we see that the predicate is within the definition of the subject or the subject within the definition of the predicate than by knowing the intelligibility of both subject and predicate? Granted that this is not an example of the primary instance of judgment for Wilhelmsen, yet it is a legitimate instance of judgment and a legitimate proposition; and there is no indication in Wilhelmsen that his thesis on the strictly symbolic intelligibility of the subject does not apply to all judgments and all propositions. As for the texts of St. Thomas, there is no necessity to interpret them as Wilhelmsen does. Granted that only one species at a time can actually inform the intellect, yet there can be a composition within the unity of the species itself. Things two as objects of thought can be represented as united in subject in but one species. St. Thomas (Summa Theol., I, q. 85, a. 5, ad 3) tells us that the man is white means that " the man is something having whiteness" or, in other words, " man is identical in subject with the being having whiteness." Neither of these explanations of the meaning of the proposition would be the equivalent of the meaning Wilhelmsen would be forced to give the proposition, namely, that this thing (only pre-consciously grasped as man) exists as white. Granted too that the predicate is form of the subject, there is no need to push the analogy of matter and form too far. Prime matter receives the whole of its determination from substantial form, but second matter is determinate in the order of substance while determinable in the order of accidents. So also the subject can admit of a determination of its own while allowing for further determination from its predicate. If Wilhelmsen's doctrine on the proposition were authentically Thomistic we would be struck with a Thomistic epistemology itself destructive of Thomistic logic. Suppose that no subject of a proposition had a meaning save the meaning of its predicate. What would happen to syllogistic procedure? The first principle of categorical syllogism, namely, the principle of "triple identity," would be meaningless in the face of a syllogism built of propositions whose subjects had no meaning of their own. A third figure syllogism would not only involve only two terms, but the missing term would be the very middle itself. There is no room for a middle term which is but a " finger of the intellect " in the traditional logic to which St. Thomas subscribes unequivocally. If syllogism itself is impossible, a fortiori there can be no demonstration. But suppose it were argued that I have not established the impossibility of syllogism in Wilhelmsen's scheme of tfiings. Then surely I could establish the impossibility of demonstration as St. Thomas explains it. According to St. Thomas the major preniise of a strict propter quid demonstration is in the fourth mode of perseity, the minor in the first, and the conclusion in the second. To demonstrate involves a reflexive appreciation of these modes of perseity, and no one of them can be known save that both subject and predicate be recognized for the meaning each BOOK REVIEWS 551 in its own right is. The evidence seems clear: If Wilhelmsen . is right in his theory of judgment, St. Thomas is in error in his theory of syllogism and demonstration. The third difficulty I would like to point out occurs in the third part of the book. I have already indicated dissatisfaction with this section of the book. Here I would like to indicate one of my reasons for questioning its worth. Having determined to speak only of speculative science Wilhelmsen proceeds to discuss its division into types. His first division by way of material object is highly questionable. This is at best an accidental principle of division, a point not made by Wilhelmsen who leaves open the possibility that this division has as much significance as that by way of formal object. The divisions which follow are presented in hap-hazard order. No attempt is made to indicate that division by way of formal object, by way of relation to matter, and by way of scientific distinction are ultimately reduced to the same thing. In fact these are separated from. one another by divisions quite unrelated to them. All in all the treatment is exceedingly confused and calculated to mislead the student. It is clear that this section of the book should either have been omitted entirely or reordered and expanded before publication. After he has suggested multiple principles of division for speculative science and announced that the " ways in which the cake of intelligibility can be cut are potentially infinite " it is disconcerting to find Wilhelmsen reject the traditional doctrine of three degrees of formal abstraction as inadequate to the task of dividing speculative science. His reasons are four in number: (1) "St. Thomas never speaks of three degrees of formal abstraction." (2) "For St. Thomas the abstraction of a form is proper to mathematical science." (8) "St. Thomas' triplex distinctio ... is not an adequate principle for distinguishing one specific. science from another if these sciences exist on the same level of scientific necessity." (4) "The traditional ' three degrees of abstraction ' are utterly unable to place St. Thomas' philosophy of man within the hierarchy of science." None of these reasons is sufficient to demand the rejection of the traditional doctrine of the degrees of formal abstraction. As for the :first, St. Thomas does speak· of three degrees of abstraction or remotion from matter as constituting the formal objects proper to the three genera of. speculative science (In Boeth. de Trin., V, I, c., In De Sensu et Sensato, 1, n. 1; In VI Met., 1, nn. 1155-1165; In I Post. Anal., 41, nn. 861- 871; Sum'rna Theol., I, q. 85, a. 1, ad 2; In I Phys., 1, nn. I & 2; In Met., prooem.). As for the second, it is clear from the explanation of Cajetan's abstractio formalis and abstractio totalis that these are not the equivalent at all of St. Thomas' abstractio formae and abstractio totius. Hence there is no reason for scandal because St. Thomas limits his abstractio formae to mathematics while Cajetan would refer to physical, mathematical, and metaphysical abstrac- 552 BOOK REVlE,VS tion each as instances of abstractio formalia. Wilhelmsen points out that the "sciences of nature use the abstraction of a total essence (that is a complete essence: matter and form) ., but seems unaware that this complete nature can itself be considered as a form (In II Pkys., 5, n. 179: "Natura igitur speciei constituta ex forma et materia communi, se habet ut formalis respectu individui quod participat totam naturam ") so that what is an abstractio totius from one point of view is itself an abstractio formae from another. To say, as Wilhelmsen does at this juncture, that separatio is an abstraction only metaphorically is gratuitous and cannot be established. St. Thomas speaks of it as an abstraction in the very article Wilhelmsen would suggest in defense of his point (In Boetk. de Trin., V, 8, c.; cf. also Summa Tkeol., I, q. 85, a. 1, ad The difference between abstractio (as said even of separatio) and abstractio proprie (which is not said of separatio) is the difference between the general and the particular, not the metaphorical and the proper. The third criticism, which seems (curiously, for Wilhelmsen) to link Cajetan's " three degrees of abstraction " with St. Thomas' " three intellectual distinctions," is based upon the fact that neither can explain the specific diversity of sciences within a given genus. This may perhaps be so, though this is not as settled an issue as Wilhelmsen seems to indicate, but even so this does not rule out the three degrees of abstraction as a legitimate principle of generic differentiation for the speculative sciences. Wilhelmsen's final reason for rejecting the three degrees of abstraction supposes an essential unity for St. Thomas' philosophy of man. To my knowledge no such unity has yet been established, and hence, the objection stands as questionable. With none of his reasons adequate to the rejection of the doctrine of the three degrees of abstraction one is tempted to suggest that such a rejection is highly questionable. An evaluation of Man's Knowledge of Reality apart from its content, strictly taken, suggests a list of commendations on one side and a list of criticisms on the other. The typography is excellent. There is a detailed table of contents, plus an excellent marginal outline. Each chapter includes suggeste_d readings in St. Thomas and a brief bibliography of secondary sources in addition to a generous scattering of helpful footnotes. The author has added a general bibliography, an index of names, and an index of subjects at the end of the book. The book is extremely well written. The author has literary abilities .far beyond those of most philosopher-writers. Even in this difficult region of epistemology Wilhelmsen is, with rare exceptions, uncommonly clear and, with no exceptions, exceedingly interesting. From this point of view, certainly, the book is a welcome treat. Though the bibliographical suggestions are helpful it seems to this reviewer that those from St. Thomas are frequently insufficient to the task of substantiating the argument of the chapter and that the secondary references are extremely one-sided, representing for the most part what .553 BOOK REVIEWS might loosely be referred to as the •• Toronto school." The documentation, though impressive at first glance, is extremely sloppy. There is no set pattern for bibliographical references, and, what is worse, these are not always accurate. For example, Father Gerard Smith, S. J. is sometimes referred to as Gerald Smith, sometimes as Gerald Smith, S. J., sometimes as Gerard Smith, J. S., and sometimes, apparently per accidens, as Gerard Smith, S. J. In one bibliography (pp. 208 & 204) an article by Father Geiger is indicated as being in the wrong volume of the wrong year on the wrong pages of a journal not accurately named; an article by Father LeRoy is given an inaccurate title and situated erroneously as far as page numbers are concerned; neither Father Geiger nor Father LeRoy is listed as a Dominican, while Father Henle and Father Klubertanz are listed as Jesuits and Father Regis as a Dominican (Fathers Maurer, Owens, and Robert suffer the same privation as Fathers Geiger and LeRoy as far as religious designation is concerned) ; for all journals cited save one the volume number is given, with this one designated rather by month; finally for some of the authors full names and middle initials are given, for others no middle initials, for others only initials (while elsewhere in the book several of these same authors are designated differently than in this bibliography). All in all the documentation is disappointingly sloppy, and, while this may not seriously bother the ordinary undergraduate, it is sure to prove a stumbling block to the advanced student who will approach the book as an effort in scholarship. While there are parts of the book which are commendable and other parts which are questionable I would like to suggest, as a final point, that one might question not only some of what Wilhelmsen has included in the book but also what has been left out. True enough, he has promised in his Preface no more than an essay towards a Thomistic epistemology. Yet the book is presented by the publisher as a textbook for a course in epistemology. As such it seems to lack context-wise much of what ought to go into even a one-semester course in epistemology. No one teacher of epistemology would dare impose his syllabus on another. Yet it seems reasonable to expect that a course in epistemology will cover knowledge m general as well as the division of knowledge into its most significant types, with a reflexive investigation into the nature of these types and the methodologies proper to them and finally into the interrelationships between them. A course so conceived and executed would serve not only the end of epistemology itself as the speculative science of knowledge but would serve the well-being of all the sciences and, for the advanced college student, would serve as a true principle of integration shedding light and meaning upon the totality of his college program. For such a course Man's Knowledge of Reality by itself is hardly an adequate textbook. EDWARD Univernty, Milwaukee, D. SIMMONS 554 BOOK REVIEWS Insight: A Study of Human Understanding. By BERNARD J. F. LoNERGAN, S. J. New York: Philosophical Library, 1957. Pp. 815. $10.00. Leo XIII found scholastic philosophy in a sorry state. He called for a reconstruction in which the best of old scholasticism would be restored and completed by new thought. His motto for reconstruction implies that he recognized philosophy as a dynamic process; Leo did not confuse the love of wisdom with its attainment. The Leonine reconstruction has not proceeded rapidly and smoothly. Still, scholastic philosophy has neither stood still nor regressed. Historical studies have helped us to understand Aquinas and other scholastic doctors. For the interpretation of the medievals, we now demand textual studies made according to precise methods; we have thrown off the burden of the commentaries and the ad mentem summaries. Moreover, some excellent analytic studies concerned with particular points of doctrine have been made. Many of these. studies, it is true, have been ambivalent with respect to philosophic verification, sometimes using authority and slipping unconsciously into a traditionalism on philosophic issues. Still the monographic studies have made us aware of philosophic problems and we have developed some sophistication in thinking about them. There are some who see no need for any work besides the historical and analytical studies to carry on the Leonine reconstruction. Yet to others it seems we must still advance in two ways. First, we mu&t face the philosophic issues as they are now· presented. We must talk about what our non-scholastic colleagues are talking about and we must make ourselves intelligible to them. Second, we must present philosophic syntheses which can stand independently of any allusions to medieval texts or citations of authorities. This preface leads to my general evaluation of Insight. This book is genuinely and competently philosophic. It stands independently of any historical positions. It depends only on the readers' own experience and intelligence to validate its conclusions. Its appeal is not to a parochial audience. It is not written in scholastic jargon. It raises issues which are now interesting to non-scholastic philosophers and deals with these issues in a way which should be illuminating to them. I realize this judgment of the importance of the book is strong. But Lonergan's book is unusual. Insight deserves to be read and studied, discussed and criticized. This book:, I believe, is the first perfected philosophic product of the Leonine reconstruction. Insight might initiate a new era in scholastic philosophy. Using the act of the intellect as a point of departure, Fr. Lonergan has built a complete philosophic synthesis. We can indicate the content and BOOK REVIEWS 555 the order of the work by using the old titles for the systematic courses, although these labels are not appropriate to this book. Beginning with epistemology, Fr. Lonergan develops the main positions of a scholastic cosmology, ontology, rational psychology, ethics, and natural theology. In epistemology, Lonergan treats the types and sources of knowledge and error, certitude and degrees of certitude, and the grounding of first principles. He refutes scepticism, relativism, empiricism, and idealism. In cosmology, he treats change and its types and conditions, time and place, matter and form, causality in nature, contingency, and evolution. In ontology, he treats metaphysical composition, substance and accident, essence and existence, the transcendentals, the causes, analogy, distinctions, relations, and individuation. In rational psychology, he treats the cognitive and appetitive processes with special emphasis on the distinction between sense and intellect, the substantial unity of man, the spirituality and immortality of the soul, and freedom of choice. In ethics, he treats the main principles with respect to the end, the moral act, virtue, and law. He also makes interesting points concerning the common gnod and society. In natural theology, he treats the existence and attributes of God, divine knowledge and love, and creation. He also shows the possibility of miracles, revelation, a supernatural order, and the church. The scholastic will detect treatment of all these topics and will be comforted by the regul :ty and ease with which the right answers come. From this point of view, the book constitutes a well-integrated course in scholastic philosophy, including the philosophical portions of apologetics. Yet Insight is not a text-book, and the account I have given of its content according to topics hardly suggests the significance of the book. Indeed, it is difficult to convey briefly what Fr. Lonergan has done, since Insight is written in a dialectical pattern similar to that of a Platonic dialogue. Thus, while the ostensible subject of the book is insight, the act of the intellect, he manages to treat all the topics mentioned above by making his treatment of insight relevant to an ever-broadening context. Insight thus serves not as the subject of a monograph but as the referencepoint for building a philosophy. The structure of the book may be indicated as follows. By a long and careful development, the author prepares the reader to understand and affirm a group of absolute principles. The implications of these principles are then drawn leading to the range of conclusions mentioned above. The process of drawing implications, however, is not logical but dialectical. "What must be granted if the principles are granted in order to maintain the principles solidly, consistently, and unambiguously?" is the question which guides the construction. The book has two parts. In chapters I-X, the reader is brought to understand understanding as distinct from experience. In chapters XI-XX, the 556 BOOK REVIEWS reader is brought first to affirm his own existence as an intelligent knower and then to accept the developed position as an implication of his selfaffirmation. The first part can be divided into four parts. In chapters I-V, the author works from illustrative instances of understanding in mathematics and natural science to develop an understanding of the nature of understanding, different modes of understanding, and the conditions which are required for the occurrence of understanding. In chapters VI-VII, he analyzes the non-explanatory function of intelligence in common-sense knowledge, clarifying the limitations and imperfections of such knowledge. In chapter VIII, he considers substance and substantial unity, basing his treatise on the character of explanatory as distinct from common-sense knowledge. Finally, in chapters IX-X, he clarifies the notion of judgment as distinct from and added to mere apprehension. The second part of the book also can be divided into four parts. In chapters XI-XIII the author elicits from the reader an act of self-affirmation as an intelligent knower, and then explicates this act as a knowledge of being objectively real. In chapters XIV-XVII, using the notions of being and objectivity and the structure discovered in the knowledge process, the author builds an ontology of the structure of beings and of the concrete universe. He also presents a defense against any alternative metaphysics by showing how his position can interpret and place any other position. In chapter XVIII he develops the principles of ethics by extending the metaphysical structure to cover the reality of moral obligation as well as of actual existence. Finally, in chapters XIX-XX, working from the ideas of being and cause and ar.y affirmation of existence, he proves the existence of God and treats the problem of evil. This summary indicates the general structure and content of the work. I will now indicate the method of Insight by pointing out Fr. Lonergan's functioning principles. The principles he uses in developing the argument, not the ones he talks about, are three; the desire to know, the isomorphism of the structure of knowledge with the structure of what is known, and reflexivity. Man's desire to know is taken to be unconditioned and unrestricted. The satisfaction of this desire is considered to be an absolute value. Thus the desire to k;now serves as a term to which all knowledge is related and thereby unified. This desire also serves as a norm for judging acts of knowledge motivated by other desires. The desire to know is the means of transcending experience. Further, using this principle the author can blend speculative and practical considerations throughout the book. This blending is not confusing the two but uniting them by their joint origin in intellectual appetite. Beginning in chapters six and seven on common-sense knowledge, the author leads the reader to view rationality as a practical norm. Fr. BOOK REVIEWS 557 Lonergan can then treat error as malicious interference with the dominion of reason al'd cultural decline as the result of such viciousness. The starting point of apologetics is then the need for something to 1:ounteract the kingdom of darkness. The desire to know is the ultimate value-source of the adverse judgments which the author makes concerning other positions. The second principle, the isomorphism of the structure of knowledge with the structure of what is known, permits him to infer a metaphysics from one's self-affirmation, once that act has been explained so that it involves the acceptance of his theory of knowledge and objectivity. For example, the distinctions between experience, understanding, and affirmation ground the distinctions between matter, form, and existence. Using this principle, Fr. Lonergan begins from instances of insight, proceeds to an articulation of the process of knowledge, and then infers the general structure of whatever can be known, that is, of being. The content of the instances becomes insignificant in this procedure, and the metaphysical structure which is bierred can be posited independently of any special scientific theories. For metaphysics works from the structure immanent in knowledge as a process, using the processes of direct knowledge as data. Special sciences base themselves on empirical data and so must operate within metaphysical structure, although they are not determined by that structure within their own domains. The result is that all sciences are incorporated into a single systematic world-view, the multiplicity of ways of knowing with all their richness being maintained within the general framework. Reflexivity, the third principle used by the author, is difficult to explain. An example of the use of this principle in a classical text is Aristotle's defense of the principle of contradiction. That defense depends on the impossibility of communicating and therefore the impossibility of denying the principle if it is not accepted. Fr. Lonergan proceeds in a similar way, not with respect to the principle of contradiction but with respect to the structure of cognitive process as he has elucidated it. He maintains that his account is not subject to revision since any attempt to revise it would have to proceed according to the same process. Just as in Aristotle dynamic contrariety lies behind the principle of contradiction, so in Lonergan dynamic cognitive process lies behind the known structure of cognitive process. Reflexivity not only functions negatively, as a means of pointing out that the adversary is refuting himself out of his own mouth, but it also functions positively as a norm for construction. What one says in building his own position must be in accord with what one holds it possible to say on that position. On the other hand, to beg the question is a fallacy. Fr. Lonergan tries to be careful to meet the demands of reflexivity himself. He maintains that his conclusions are independent from the instances he uses, but not 558 BOOK REVIEWS from all instances. He also maintains that his conclusions can be reached without following his method, but not as clearly, completely, and effectively. Criticisms of Insight can be made from the point of view of rhetoric. The book would benefit from less explicitness and repetition and from many more self-references. Some of the sentences could be broken down. Occasionally the terminology is unnecessarily obscure, a glossary )night be helpful. The index seems accurate but I did not find it helpful. Of course, the usefulness of an index varies with different readers. All in all, as philosophical writing goes, Insight is a well-written book. Had Kant written as well, he would be more popular and better understood than he is. In Insight interpretations of many other philosophical writings are offered: The book is not intended to be a history. Historical allusions are used to clarify the position presented and to furnish grist for the dialectical mill, not to bolster the argument itself. Fr. Lonergan's use of history is like Aristotle's treatment of his predecessors. Many questions might be raised concerning the historical accuracy and adequacy of the author's statements concerning other philosophical positions. We restrict our questions here to the single problem of whether the philosophy presented in Insight is in agreement with the philosophy of Aquinas. Lonergan thinks his philosophy agrees with that of Aquinas. He recognizes that he has augmented the old with something new, developing a novel method, but he does not admit that he diverges substantially. In raising questions about this problem I do not presume that I solve it. To decide whether Insight conflicts with Aquinas' philosophy is a task for a very careful historical investigation. Two things should be kept in mind. First, Fr. Lonergan may not agree with Aquinas. Second, if he doesn't he could be philosophically adequate anyway. The author has published two series of articles in Theological Stu(lies, the last of which appeared in 1949. These articles were professed interpretations of Aquinas' writings. Fr. Lonergan wished to keep his history and his philosophy distinct. A fair method of attacking him on historical grounds, then, would be to attack the interpretation presented in the articles, using the development in Insight to clarify the intended interpretation. In this type of criticism, the following questions might fairly be asked of him. Is it not the case that a philosophy is constituted of method and arguments, not merely of conclusions? Do not conclusions have their meaning from the philosophic means used reach them? Is not the use of insight as a reference-point for unifying what is understood and the use of the desire to know as a universal reference-point a method diverse from that which Aquinas employed? Can isomorphism be reconciled with Aquinas' principle that the mode of understanding is not the mode of BOOK REVIEWS 559 being? Aquinas constantly used this principle against Plato. Does the relatim1ship which Fr. Lonergan posits between possibility, probability, and actuality accord with Aquinas' doctrine of being? Does Fr. Lonergan's doctrine of abstraction as an addition to the data accord with Aquinas' distinction between the potentially and the actually intelligible? H not, the doctrine of conception, definition, categories, form, and essence is also diverse. Does Fr. Lonergan's doctrine of judgment as the reflective grasp of the fulfillment of the conditions sufficient for fact accord with Aquinas' distinction between categorical and hypothetical propositions? If not, the doctrine of reflection, verification, modes of predication and analogy, and existence and action is also diverse. Does Fr. Lonergan's doctrine of science as the understanding and affirmation of correlations of data accord with Aquinas' distinction between understanding and reason? If not, the doctrine of inquiry and proof, the nature and division of sciences, intellectual principles and methods, and causal determination and order is also diverse. Do not the priority of intelligence to existence, the priority of self-affirmation to knowledge of the other, and the priority of dialectic to demonstration which Fr. Lonergan posits constitute a complete reversal of Aquinas' philosophy? Apart from the historical accuracy of the author's identification of his philosophy with Aquinas', one can examine and criticize Insight as an expressed philosophy. I think Fr. Lonergan should face the following questions and I believe he would have serious difficulties with some of them. How can necessary conclusions follow from contingent principles? Or, are cognitive facts necessary or metaphysical conclusions contingent? If the desire to know is somehow unconditioned, is not desiring to know a mere fact? Does the use of the desire to know as a principle require an equivocation on " unconditioned," i.e., on "necessary? " How can the principle of the isomorphism of the structure of knowledge with the structure of being be defended from a starting-point within knowledge as distinct from being? H every assertion requires that the fulfillment of the conditions of the fact be grasped, does not the assertion of the principle of isomorphism suppose the grasp of the fulfillment of conditions which is given only outside knowledge, i.e., which is unknowable? To put the question in another way, if it is necessary to go from the structure of knowledge to the structure of being, how can one justify the transit without begging the question? If one accepts the evaluative theory of judgment and the isomorphic principle, is it possible either to distinguish knowledge and being without opening an unbridgeable gap between them or to relate them without identifying them? How can knowledge be known as to its necessary characteristics independently of knowing the necessity of something which is not knowledge? Fr. Lonergan distinguishes between direct and introspective modes of cogni- 560 BOOK BEVIEWS tiYe process. Does this distinction presuppose that cognitive process is knowable independently of anything being known? If so, there must be u third mode based on the first two, and so on indefinitely. When levels are distinguished in this way they are not of themselves related but must be referred by an extrinsic act. But if there is no infinite regress, must there not be only one mode of cognitive process to which self-awareness is immanent but which is primarily intentional of the r>.on-cognitive? If is only one mode of cognitional process, is it not impossible without question-begging or paradoxes based on reflexivity to ground a metaphysics on the structure of knowledge? If things are what they are by being referred to insight, and if the whole philosophy is definite by being referred to the precognitive desire to know, how are relations what they are? If relations are not any " what " in themselves, what is their status? Relations are not things absolutely and they are not insights. If one distinguishes levels of the real to place relations, what about the relations between those levels? If relata determine relations and relations determine relata, what does it mean to say that insight determines both when insight too can be related? If insight is not related, then are we talking about human knowledge or about God? H we can't keep these distinct, can we keep anything distinct? This series of philosophic questions might be extended indefinitely, and it would be easy to find many small points to argue, but all the questions I have raised are really concerned with one issue. What that issue is may be suggested by the questions or it may be suggested by a historical allusion. It seems to me that the philosophy which Fr. Lonergan has constructed is closely akin to the position of Plato. Aristotle criticized Plato for separating the forms, and I mean to suggest by my questions the possibility of criticizing Fr. Lonergan in an analogous way. My questions are merely a reformulation of the old criticisms to meet the new formulation of dialectical philosophy. If Insight arouses counter-formulations as ingenious and competent as it is itself, Fr. Lonergan will have done us a considerable service. I believe that happy result may occur. And consequently I attribute that importance to the work which I stressed in the beginning of this review. GERMAIN Georgetown University, Washington, D. C. G. GRISEZ BRIEF NOTICES The Doctrine of the Trinity. By CYRIL C. Abingdon Press, 1958. Pp. 159. $3.00. RICHARDSON. New York: The intention of the author of this Protestant study of the doctrine of the Trinity, stated in his Preface, is to give "the leading doctrines of the Trinity as they have developed in the Church's thought, and to raise some basic questions about their validity." The book is an effort to demontrate that although we must make distinctions in the Godhead, they do not fall into a neat three-fold pattern, and that the traditional symbols of Father, Son and Spirit are ambiguous and even troublesome. The author's contention, which is stated explicitly in the Preface, is that Trinitarian doctrines have confused the real issues by admitting arbitrary distinctions in God, while at the same time attempting to reconcile the necessary contradictions by concealed ones. In the initial chapter, which explicitly gives the "point of view" of the author, the value of the " threeness " of the Trinity is questioned on the basis that there is an artificiality about it which breeds confusion. That the author's position is Unitarian is expressly denied, however; for it is not the paradoxical character of the traditional doctrine to which he objects, but rather the threefoldness. He regards it as undeniable, moreover, that God revealed Himself in terms of a "human person" i.e. Jesus of Nazareth. The doctrine is not found specifically in the New Testament; rather, it is a creation of the fourth century Church. If the reader should be inclined to defend the existence of the teaching in the New Testament, it would matter little, for it is claimed that the background of thought from which the New Testament symbols were derived left something to be desired, and that we should seek more satisfactory ways of expressing the "message." In the second chapter the author claims that it is generally assumed that the major problem is " the way in which God can be one person and yet three." He does not clarify by whom this is generally assumed. In lVIr. Richardson's view, however, the fundamental issue is the difference between the Father and the Son, the essence of which distinction is between God's beyondness (Father) and relatedness (Son). The nature of the symbolism clouds this distinction, however. Whereas "Father" gradually came to denote God in His absolute, transcendent glory, yet the title never could be emptied of its original content; the heavenly Father must be related to his children. The name "Father" poses an additional difficulty, 561 562 BRIEF NOTICES in that it implies begetting, or derivation of one mode of being (God liB related) from another mode of being (God as absolute). Why assume any priority? the author asks. Many other problems are said to evolve from this symbolism; e. g., the Father is thought of as Creator, but this seems more fittingly applicable to the Son, who is God in His activity. That the New Testament presents us with the dominant symbols of Father, Son, and Spirit is aBserted in the third chapter. From what has been said it is obvious that this does not mean that there is a Trinitarian doctrine in Scripture, although the existence of these symbols gave rise to the creation of the doctrine which came later. The blending of Jewish and Greek thinking in the New Testament is seen liB a source of difficulty, for, the writer claims, there is a fundamental discrepancy between the Hebrew notion of the Father and the idea of an abstract God who operates by His reason or Logos. Another troublesome idea traceable to Greek thinking is " the fecundity of the absolute " which leads, in Richardson's opinion, to the idea of priority in the Godhead. After the treatment of the New Testament doctrine of the Father, the idea of the Son is considered. Briefly, the thesis offered is that there is an evolution of the notion of the sonship of Jesus in the New Testament. Whereas, Richardson claims, in the Synoptics it means dependence of the man upon his heavenly Father, in St. John's Gospel a truly divine status is given to Jesus Christ. Since the word "Son" WIIB retained, however, it came to refer to a distinction in the Godhead itself, and the term haB remained " to plague Trinitarian thinking." The symbolism of the Spirit is said to pose special difficulties, for although the distinction between the Logos and Spirit is admittedly retained throughout the New Testament, they are, Richardson maintains, logically identical. The " Trinity of mediation," which makes the basic distinction between the Father and the Son one of mediation, is discussed in the fourth chapter. Attributed to Tertullian, this doctrine views the Father as the God of the philosophers, the Son as the One Who is encountered. The trouble with this doctrine, as Richardson sees it, is that the first term of the Trinity seems to be more really God than the second. It aBsumes that the Absolute can beget the mediator, but this, the author thinks, seems to imply inferiority in the One begotten. The aBsumption that there is derivation in the Trinity is seen as an. unwarranted and vain attempt to compose an essential paradox. As for the Spirit: the role of the " third term " seems ambiguous and irrelevant in the " Trinity of mediation." More oriented to the Scriptures in the author's opinion is the doctrine of the " Trinity of love," which is discussed in chapter five. Almost identified as the Roman Catholic Trinitarian doctrine, this is expressed somewhat liB follows: Because God is love, He must have an object of love, and because He is self-sufficient He must have an object of love BRIEF NOTICES 563 different from creatures. Hence the distinction between Father and Son. But, Richardson argues, the " modes of being in the Godhead " (his term for the distinctions in God) are such that they cannot love each other. The place of the Spirit in the Trinity is taken up in the sixth chapter. By such early writers as Athenagoras, the Spirit was often considered as a uniting bond between Father and Son, and this Richardson views as an attempt to compose the original paradox. St. Augustine is said to have developed this notion of Spirit as bond of union, and the modem Protestant student of Augustinianism, Karl Barth, quite decisively distinguishes the Son and the Spirit. The contrast Barth makes between these seems to be rooted in a distinction between God's revelation as objectively presented to us and as apprehended by us. Richardson argues, however, that the object-subject distinction stressed by Barth does not necessitate another distinction in the Godhead. His conclusion, anticipated in his earlier treatment of the Father and the Son, is that the Logos and the Spirit are really identical. That the practical man of faith has always tended to think of God as one Person manifesting Himself in a diversity of ways is contended in the next chapter, which deals with the "Trinity of revelation." Indeed, the Apostle's Creed was so formulated that one could view the matter in this uncomplicated way and still recite it sincerely. But whether such popular piety opened the way to Sabellianism or not, Richardson maintains that Sabellius failed to make an adequate distinction in the Godhead, and to understand the necessity for paradox in God. Even the recent attempts of the theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher to " rehabilitate " Sabellius seem to the author to miss the essential problem, which is not concerned with the manner in which God is revealed, but with the paradoxical fact that along with God's revealed (related) nature, there is His beyondness. The recent attempt of Claude Welch in the survey, In His Name, to reconstruct a Trinity on the basis of revelation is also rejected here, for the same reason. The last pattern of trinitarian theology discussed, which is treated of in chapter eight, is the "Trinity of God's activity." This is based, not upon the different modes of revelation, but upon the different elements in each of God's activities. This notion is attributed to Gregory of Nyssa, and is claimed to have been recently revived by Dorothy Sayers, in The Mind of the Maker. Besides his not unexpected objection that this treatment leaves out of account the absoluteness and beyondness of the Godhead, Richardson's argument is that such a Trinity is arbitrary, since we could, if we wished, detect innumerable aspects of God's activity. Why stop at three? The final chapter of the book deals with the meaning of the symbols !Father, Son, and Spirit. By this time it is abundantly, perhaps redundantly, clear that the author does not find the major Trinitarian patterns satis- 564 BRIEF NOTICES factory. Posing the question of whether any satisfactory Trinitarian doctrine can be reconstructed, he answers in the negative. What then is the value of the Biblical symbols Father, Son, and Spirit? It is replied that although they each express something which it is important for us to affirm, they overlap. They point beyond themselves to antinomies which demand other modes of expression. "Father," it is maintained, points to the transcendence of God, whereas "Son" indicates a relation between the heavenly Father and Jesus of Nazareth, within the terms of the Incarnation, and should not be forced back into the Godhead itself. Spirit refers to God's dynamic action. The three terms, which according to Richardson do not denote precise persons in the Trinity, are "ways of thinking about God from different points of view." They point to the necessity of making distinctions, the most basic of which is that between the absolute and the related character of God. Others follow: He is joy and suffering, rest and motion, solitary and yet in some sense of society, our ground of being and yet a person to be confronted. One thing definitely emerges: there is no necessary threeness in God. It would be absurdly redundant to belabor the point that the central theses of this book are opposed to the teaching of the Church. It would be a mistake, however, to dismiss this book as having no value for the Catholic reader. It has, of course, the value of exemplifying modern Protestant theological procedure. It gives, moreover, an interesting analysis of the Trinitarian views of such thinkers as Barth, Schleiermacher, Hodgson, and Sayers. Its greatest interest, perhaps, is its attempt to equate the inevitable paradox in the theologian's-or the philosopher's-statements about God with the mystery of the Trinity, which is not of man's making. That the author confuses the objective data of revelation with the subjective difficulties involved in contemplating the infinite is evidenced in the closing chapter in which it is claimed that the three " terms " are ways of thinking about God from different points of view. Revelation rloes not seem to be thought of as something given by God to man. Rather, one gets the impression that the doctrine is the result of a sort of reciprocal action, which " reveals " also-perhaps primarily-the mind's frustration in its groping for God. Certain difficulties present themselves to the reader. In the first chapter, for example, the author speaks of the "orthodox" view of Jesus of Nazareth, who is described as a "human person." One wonders what is meant by "orthodox." Again, in the second chapter, he states that the major Trinitarian problem is "generally assumed" to be how God can be one Person, yet three. By whom is this generally assumed? One of the most puzzling aspects of the book is the position of its author in regard to Biblical inspiration. In the fourth chapter he complains that the Church inherited the symbols, Father, Son, and Spirit, from BRIEF NOTICES 565 Scripture, and that because of its " rigid view " of Biblical inspiration it , was forced to work out its doctrine within their context. That the author's view is decidedly less rigid is indicated in the first chapter, where he claims that the measure of the New Testament writers' inspiration was greater than that of later theologians. It seems that there is only a difference of degree. The Biblical writers, moreover, have only a dubious advantage, for it is claimed that we profit by an advantage denied them, i. e. two thousand years of Christian reflection and experience. Therefore, we are told, we should indeed read them with humility, but we should try to express in more satisfactory ways the message they recorded. In other words, it would seem that although our inspiration is dimmer, we must be brighter. Our two thousand years of Christian experience apparently enable us to do great things, for we should "weigh the value of the New Testament symbolism and assess its adequacy." It is significant that the author does not make much of the scholastic distinction between person and nature. Despite his disavowal of Sabellius, there is a type of 1\fodalism here. The basic problem for Richardson is rooted in the fact that all thought about God involves paradox, which implies duality in the Godhead. The third mode or term seems superfluous -an undercover attempt at establishing a link between the contradictory modes, at resolving the unresolvable. The reader might with good reason be suspicious that the real issue with which Richardson is primarily concerned is a problem distinct from, although of course related to, the theology of the Trinity. For him, what the Trinity tries-and fails-to express is the paradox in our knowledge of God; it becomes in fact a sort of three-fold hypostasization of this. Reduced to a human attempt to express the apparent mysterious contradiction at the heart of all man's efiorts to know God, the doctrine takes on the aspect of a psychological device. The book seems to overlook the possibility that the Trinity could be more than this, that is, a revelation of God Himself. MARY F. DALY Archbishop Cushing OoUege, Brookline, M(l$sachusetta Occult Phenomena (In the Light of Theology). By A.Lo1s WIESINGER, 0. C. S. 0. Westminster: The Newman Press, 1957. Pp. 294 with index. $5.00. This scholarly work which is well written and excellently translated is divided into two parts. The first part deals with the theology and philosophy of the author's theory of occult phenomena and the second part applies 566 BRIEF NOTICES this theory to the phenomena themselves. This reviewer does not consider himself sufficiently skilled in either theology or philosophy to write a critical review of the first part. I shall content myself, therefore, with a description of the theory in terms as nearly those of the author as possible. It is the author's contention that occult phenomena, such as telepathy, second sight, the production of sounds (raps), and the movement of bodies otherwise than through muscular action, are due to the activity of a part or element of the human soul which he calls spirit-soul, and that insofar as this element is active, the soul is simply behaving after the manner of a pure spirit and showing a pure spirit's characteristics. It is the author's ultimate contention that this mode of action is a vestigial remnant of the preternatural powers with which our first parents were endowed before the Fall. There are, however, according to the author, abnormal states in which the life of the senses has been diminished, or cut out altogether, in which the life of the spiritual part of the soul is greatly intensified. In these it acts increasingly after the manner of a pure spirit, according to the author, and can receive communications from other spirits, such, for instance, as the angels. The fact that, while in this state the soul may still make a limited use of concepts built up on sense perceptions does not alter the fact, again according to the author, that its mode of behavior is radically different from that which it practices in its normal state, and that in this abnormal state it acts wholly after the manner of a pure spirit. All this makes it desirable, according to the author, that he should examine how actually the human soul is organized, and what is the exact relationship of this purely spiritual element with the other elements within it. Here the author states that he follows Catholic teaching, according to which the soul is a unity with the body and is its form; nevertheless, the soul is not wholly submerged in the body (non totaliter comprehensa) but reaches out beyond it. In other words, there is a part of the soul that is, so to speak, not actually wedded to the body. Modern writers, he states, have tended to relegate this part of the soul (if one may thus employas of necessity one must-a purely spatial terminology) to the subconscious. So far we have seen, he then continues, that there are certain powers within the human personality which must be accounted as abnormal, and from time immemorial the duality of our psychic functions has been recognized, so much so that two separate terms, and r.vEvp,a, have been invented to designate these two different aspects of our psychic activity. We are, however, not concerned here, he states, with two separate things but with a single entity, though this entity acts differently according to whether we find ourselves in our normal state or in one of the different kinds of natural and artificial sleep. To some extent the two merge in the subconscious, which both serves to store our sense perceptions and also BRIEF NOTiCES 567 records and gives effect to those acts of knowledge and of will which take place otherwise than through the bodily mechanism. The author then proceeds to prove his theory by stating that, whereas today the spiritual element in the soul can only function fully when the rest of the human personality is put out of action, this was not always so. In our first parents the preternatural endowment was fully present and active without the rest of the personality suffering any impairment. This was true both in regard to (A) the preternatural modes of knowledge and (B) the firmness of the preternatural will. In the Fall man, the author continues, lost his preternatural gifts (as well as the supernatural) but not his natural powers. Something, however, must obviously remain when these natural powers are destroyed by death or dimmed by sleep, since the spiritual part of the soul still survives, and that something consists of the vestigial remains of the spiritual powers originally enjoyed. The reviewer feels more competent to evaluate the second part of the book dealing with the practical application of the theory. This second part is a potpourri of naivete, contradictions, outmoded theories especially in psychiatry, interesting case reports, many dating back over 50 years or more, which are so intimately interwoven that any criticism, except that it be sentence by sentence, is almost impossible. This reviewer has no problems in accepting as factual most of the phenomena which are described. Telepathy, clairvoyance, hypnosis and diabolical possession, the phenomena of spiritualism and divination, are recognized as possible by those interested in the field of the occult. This second section makes very interesting reading but is replete with non-sequitur statements and contradictions "Most witches' dreams can be similarly interpreted e. g., on pages -those for instance which led the dreamers to declare that they had attended a witches' Sabbath and presumably experienced all the sensual delights that this implied. Such dreams were the remnants and the results of vivid day-time fancies, reinforced by the witches' salve. This last was composed of belladonna and opium and was well calculated to produce hallucinations. Today things are rather different; today our anxious Christendom dreams up visions of the mother of God. Since 1931 no fewer than thirty-one cases involving some three hundred alleged appearances of Mary have been the subject of ecclesiastical examination ·and the great majority have been completely rejected. From the eastern states there have come since 1945 some two thousand reports of miraculous happenings, prophecies and other forms of solace for displaced persons who have been driven from their homes. People find comfort in these things as they do in the eidetic phenomena described above. (Italics mine.) It would therefore appear that Christian morality is today on a somewhat higher level, although the belief in witches is still said to persist in such 568 BRIEF NOTICES places as the Luneburger Heide." Actually I see little resemblance between the witches' sabbath and visions of the Mother of God. On page 132, speaking of such conditions as cleptomania, pyromania, etc., he states: "The patients are really in a state similar to that of sleep; the actions of the soul are uncontrolled and uncontrollable." Below on the same page he states: "This last (bodily defects) is admittedly more difficult in the case of such notorious forms of neurosis as neurasthenia, psychasthenia, in which the actual nerves are in a diseased condition." These statements in which the italics are mine are not true. On page 146 he states, with apparent acceptance, the following about fortune tellers: "Let us, however, here note the fact that the cases of which we hear so often where a person is made aware of the death of another, are not to be accounted as telepathy, but as clairvoyance. \Ve may say the same thing of the utterances of fortune-tellers and of persons who predict the future from cards. Such people have much experience in putting themselves into a trance." On page 235 he states regarding hypnosis: "In this condition (of being hypnotized) it can also establish direct contact with the soul of another, receive that other's thoughts and combine them with the experiences that lie dormant in the subconscious. Proceeding from there, it can excite the actions of the body and influence it to an extraordinary degree. The body then performs involuntary motions, and experiences irresistible likes and dislikes, even in its vegetative life, which normally does not stand under the direction of the will. (Italics mine) "In hypnosis all this is intensified, the sensorium disappears completely, the mental cmmection with the hypnotist becomes perfect. Insane persons resist such connection, but nervous and hysterical people enter quite readily into it; in the main all persons are capable of being hypnotized, though they generally display some resistance to the first attempt; once they have been hypnotized, however, they lose this power of resistance. On this many moralists base their condemnation of hypnotism, insofar as by reason of it men lose their freedom of the will forever. This is so great a good that men have no right to part with it, particularly since, once lost, it can never be wholly recovered." The italicized statements are exaggerated half-truths which are not held· by· present-day experts. In fact, on page 240 the author corrects himself to a large extent by stating: " It would appear that even under hypnosis a residue of free will and morality remains, or, to put the matter psychologically, the influence of law and morality, together wtih the awareness of the will of God, are stronger for the soul, even in its state of extreme suggestibility, than the suggestion of a hypnotist." On page 241 he speaks of " cures " under hypnosis, a phenomena not recognized by medical specialists. Relief of symptoms is possible, but 569 BRIEF NOTICES this often leads to greater difficulties. On this same page he continues: " Under hypnosis sick people can see inside their own bodies, can declare the position of a foreign body, which can then be removed; also the nature of the necessary medicines can be discerned. One is strongly reminded of those people among the ancients who could diagnose and find the cure for illnesses in dreams. Thus, within certain narrow limits, " medical occultism," if the term is rightly understood, must be recognized as having certain validity. There are indeed great possibilities here for mankind, if the hypnosis can be made deep enough for correct impressions to be obtained under it." Most of this is too fantastic to comment upon. The above would serve as examples of what I would like to convey. The statements are documented, but it is the uncritical acceptance of the cases of others that this reviewer feels is the great fault of the book. The best section in the second part of the book is that on demoniacal possession. As interesting reading for the uncritical the book is recommended. For the more critical it is likely to prove quite frustrating and non-informative except, perhaps, in the bibliographical references which are abundant. Only four or five of these are in English publications. JoHN R. CAVANAGH, :M.D. Catholic Uni-versity of America, Washington, D. C. On the Philosophy of History. By JACQUES MARITAIN. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1957. Pp. 180 with index. $3.50. There have been few historians who, at one time or another in their study of the record left by man on earth, have not wondered, as did Henri Marrou, " Does the pilgrimage of mankind, triumphant and heart-rending by turns, through the duration of history, have a value, a fecundity, a meaning? " Yet historians, as a class, have almost unanimously rejected a philosophy of history. The closest most of them ever come to a philosophy is the adoption of an hypothesis to explain the trends of history such, for example, as the frontier theory of American history, or the theory that wax has been the great factor in human progress. But an all-embracing philosophy of history, which would answer the question proposed by Henri J\farrou, the generality of historians (including Marrou himself) deny. The charges leveled by Marrou against those who have attempted to evolve a philosophy of history would be subscribed to by most historians. And after reading some of the modern efforts to formulate such a philosophy, viz., the efforts of Hegel, Wells and Toynbee, who shall say that the charges are false? Marrou accuses the philosopher 570 BRIEF NOTICES of history of violating four canons of sound historical criticism: an oversimplified, arbitrary and uncritical use of the material; a determination to obtain an a priori explanation of the course of history; an ambition to develop an all-inclusive explanation of the meaning of history; a desire to make history conform to laws conceived by the philosopher. In brief, the historian accuses the philosopher of trying to make history; not to study it. And this, of course, is the greatest sin against his art that the historian can commit. It is not yet a proven fact that there can be such a discipline as a philosophy of history. That is to say, if one uses the term philosophy in the strict sense--" the study of things in their ultimate causes.'' And the present work does nothing to establish such a proof-if it does anything it strengthens the contrary opinion. The philosopher cannot work on history as he does on the cosmos, the nature of man, the nature and operation of the soul or God as He is known through nature. In the study of all these subjects the philosopher can prescind from Revelation and consider his subject in the light of reason alone. But how is it possible to consider history, which is the record in the world of Divine Providence, by the light of reason alone? Jesus of Nazareth, the central point of all human history, was not simply an historical figure such as Josephus tries to portray him by his passing mention. Had Jesus been but an historical figure He never could have loomed so large in the history of mankind. He would have been of no more importance than Judas the Galilean or Barabbas. But He was not just an historical figure. He was Jesus who is called the Christ, the only Son of the Eternal Father. No philosophy of history could be true which does not rest upon this revealed truth. And so it would seem that any " philosophy " of history must needs be a branch of theology. Even for the non-Christian a philosophy of history would seem well nigh impossible. For Hegel, the modern reviver of philosophy of history, was (witness his unholy trinity of thesis, antithesis and synthesis) more of mystical theologian than a philosopher, as were his followers Marx and Engels. The greatest philosopher of history of all time was St. Augustine, whose De Civitate Dei is the classic work on the subject. And where does philosophy leave off and theology begin in that great work? " In the mind of St. Augustine," says Maritain, "both wisdoms, the philosophical and theological, worked together.'' Would it not be more to the point to say they were inseparable, since all the philosophizing has a theological basis in the De Civitate Dei? This distinction of philosophy and theology as applied to history Mr. Maritain never quite makes clear. He does spend a great deal of spact" tilting with windmills, viz., " How can a philosophy of history be possible since History is not a science? " He has a fine critique of the " great irrationalist " Hegel. And once again he establishes the fact that Hegel was a mystical theologian rather than a philosopher-a theologian who BRIEF NOTICES 571 based his philosophy upon private revelation or intuition. But a cogent and convincing argument as to why there can be such a science as a philosophy of history: this is lacking. As in De Civitate Dei it is impossible to separate the philosophy in this book from the theology. To argue that a philosophy of history is possible because the light of reason alone is used to arrive at certain conclusions does not prove the right to independent existence of a philosophy of history as a separate discipline, for even in theology philosophy is used in an ancillary manner. But theology is not philosophy, for its conclusions are based ultimately upon Divine Revelation. And it would seem that no matter to what extent philosophy is used in the evaluation of the history of mankind, its conclusions must ·ultimately be drawn to theology and revelation. But if by the term " philosophy of history " one is not using the word philosophy in the strict sense, there certainly can be, indeed there must be, a philosophy of history. If the word philosophy is used (as it definitely is used by the moderns) to express a particular outlook on life, a frame of reference which includes both theology and religious belief, then a philosophy of history is inevitable and can only be avoided by the historian if he be content to be only a keeper of chronicles. This seems to be the sense in which Mr. Maritain uses the term, although he does, as I have stated, avoid, for the most part, a clear-cut definition of his approach. In the only instance where he attempts to distinguish the philosopher of history from the theologian, the distinction, to my mind, is invalid. Speaking of the great heresies, Mr. Maritain points out the difference (he claims) of the approach that would be taken to them as historical facts by the theologian and the philosopher: " The theologian of history will observe that in the course of time, and despite the -permanent impulse of such communities toward separation, a greater and greater number of those who are brought up in the religious communities involved are made, by reason of their good faith exempt from the sin of schism or heresy, so that these religious communities should not be called " heretical " or " schismatic," but simply " dissident." " The philosopher of history will be mainly concerned with the effects and repercussions of the spiritual events in question on the history of the world and civilization." It seems to me that this distinction would have a more valid application to the difference of concern between the speculative and practical theologian rather than between the philosopher and theologian. Mr. Maritain divides his work into four parts under the following titles: I. The Philosophy of History in General; IT. Axiomatic Formulas or Functional Laws; liT. Typological Formulas or Vectorial Laws; IV. God and the Mystery of the World. Under the heading of Axiomatic Formulas, which deal with the " functional relation between certain intelligible characteristics, 572 BRIEF NOTICES certain universal objects of thought-a functional relation which exists and which can be verified in one way or another at each step of the development of human history,'' Maritain lays down six laws: 1) "The law of twofold contrasting progress." This law has its clearest expression in the Gospel parable of the wheat and the cockle. It concerns the existence of both good and evil in history and, indeed, the contribution made by the Devil under the divine government to human progress. 2) "The ambivalence of history, which is a· consequence of the first law," and by which " at each moment human history offers us two faces. One face gives grounds to the pessimist, who would like to condemn this period of history. And the other gives grounds to the optimist, who would like to see the same period as merely glorious [but] no period of human history can be absolutely condemned or absolutely approved." According to Maritain, St. Gregory gave clear expression to this law when he wrote, " Men should know that the will of Satan is always unrighteous but his power is never unjust." However, the same claim cannot be made for the text from Habacuc (which is cited by the wrong chapter and verse), viz., "et egredietur diabolua ante pedes ejua." According to the best modern scholarship St. Jerome mistranslated " devil " for " lightning." But even in Jerome's interpretation this text would not confirm Maritain's law of ambivalence. 8) "The law of historical fructification of good and evil deals with the relation between ethics and politics." The gist of this law was expressed by the poet who wrote, " The mills of God grind· slowly but they grind exceedingly fine." Or as Maritain expresses it: " The good in which the justice of human societies bears fruit, and the misfortune in which the injustice of human societies bears fruit have nothing to do with the immediate and visible results; historic duration must be taken into account. . . . The achievements of the great Machiavellianists seem durable to us, because our scale of duration-measurements is an exceedingly small one, with regard to the time proper to nations and human communities. We do not understand the fair play of God, Who gives those who have freely chosen injustice the time to exhaust the benefits of it and the fullness of its energies." 4) " The law of world significance and history-making events " is still in the process of gestation in the mind of the philosopher. As Mr. Maritain expresses it: "I am still searching for the proper expression of a truth which I think I perceive but which seems to me to be rather difficult to formulate. My main difficulty has to do with the notion of the ' unity of the world ' or the ' unity of mankind ' and its true meaning." Mr. Maritain suddenly decides that he is a philosopher of history and not a theologian and that since " there is in the world nothing akin to the spiritual unity of the Church . . . we must take care not to think of these things in terms of theological concepts like that of the· " commllhion of BRIEF NOTICES 573 saints. " Although it seems entirely too simple a solution to the great problem that occupies Mr. Maritain's mind, I suggest that the expression for which he is searching (and which is not a theological concept) is "the brotherhood of man under the fatherhood of God." 5) " The law of prise de conscience " is the growth in awareness as the sign of human progress and as involving at the same time inherent dangers. 6) "The law of hierarchy of means" which consists of two laws: a) " the superority of humble temporal means over rich temporal means with respect to spiritual ends"; and b) . "the law of superiority of spiritual means of temporal activity and welfare over carnal means of temporal activity and welfare." Of Vectorial laws there are four: 1) "The law of the passage from the ' magical ' to the ' rational ' regime or state in the history of human culture." It concerns the passage of mankind from symbol or magical sign, which speaks primarily to the imagination, and ·logical sign, which speaks primarily to the intellect. £!) " The law of the progress of moral conscience," Maritain considers to be "a most important law in the philosophy of history. In its essence and even in its value the rectitude and purity of moral conscience are independent of the explicit knowledge of all particular moral laws." As stated, this law appears to be identical with synderesis, the first principle of morality but such is not the case, for further on the author states, " As a matter of fact, the precise knowledge of these natural moral laws-with the exception of the self-evident primary principle, good is to be done and evil avoided-is acquired slowly and with more or less difficulty. I would my that the, equipment necessary to know the particular precepts of the natural law exists within is made up of the essential tendencies and inclinations of our nature. But a very long experience is required to have the corresponding knowledge through connaturality take actual form. In other words our knowledge of moral laws is progressive in nature . . . and certain of these norms, like the law of monogamy, were known rather late in the history of mankind so far as it is accessible to our investigation." This statement is contrary to the teaching of Christ, for in the Gospel of St. Matthew 19:7-8, we read: "They said to him, 'Why then did Moses command to give a written notice of dismissal and to put her away? ' He said to them, ' Because Moses, by reason of the hardness of your heart, permitted you to put away your wives; but in the beginning it was not so.'" And what does Mr. Maritain mean by monogamy being known rather late in the history of mankind " so far as it is accessible to our investigation.'' Whose investigation? The anthropological authorities whom I follow, such as Schmidt and Cooper, do not agree with these findings. What authorities does Mr. Maritain follow? I am certain by that "our investigation " he is not implying that he is to be considered an authority on anthropology also. 574 BRIEF NOTICES Another error Mr. Maritain makes in his exposition of this " law " occurs on page 106 where he states: " We may cite a few of the other examples of this progress in moral conscience. One is the notion of the treatment to be given to prisoners of war. For many centuries, and even Christian centuries, it was considered quite normal to kill prisoners of war." I would ask him to specify the Christian century in which a Christian nation considered it " quite normal " to kill prisoners of war. Of the numerous footnotes he has in his book a great many are unnecessary. Where a footnote is demanded by the nature of the statement it is never to be found. Here, as in the statement above concerning monogamy, footnoting is a necessity. Another statement that cries for, at least, a footnote is one made on page 107: " The notion that human labor is impossible without the whip of destitution-a notion quite wide-spread in the nineteenth centuryseemed at that moment to be in accordance with the natural law. Even religion and a misreading of Adam's punishment in Genesis was made to contribute to this punishment." My question to Mr. Maritain: What religion? Whose interpretation? 3) "The law of the passage from 'sacral' to 'secular' or 'lay' civilization. The distinction between ' sacral ' and ' secular ' civilization has a universal bearing. Yet-by reason of the very distinction between th0 things that are Caesar's and the things that are God's-it is with Christianity that this distinction has taken its full historical importance." 4) " The law of the political and social coming of age of the people. This law ... deals with the progressive passage of the people in the course of modern history, from the state of subjection to a state of self-government in political and social matters." The last chapter of the book is concerned with God and the problem of evil. And here again Mr. Maritain seems to find it impossible to keep to a strict philosophy of history. For more than half the chapter is devoted to the Church as the Kinglom of God on earth. In this chapter, too, he makes one of those startling statements which no honest reviewer can pass without challenge. In a footnote on page 139 we are told that the novel " Grey Eminence " by Aldous Huxley which concerns the life of Father Joseph, the Franciscan adviser of Richelieu, is a " tragically true picture of a man who was a real contemplative in the spiritual order and a real Machiavellian in the temporal order." (italics mine) And that combination, I submit, is quite as impossible as a square circle. REGINALD Dominican House of Studies Washington, D. C. M. CoFFEY, 0. P. BOOKS RECEIVED Adler, Mortimer J. The Idea of Freedom. (A Dialectical Examination of the Conceptions of Freedom). Garden City: Doubleday, 1958. Pp. 716 with index. $7.50. Augustine, Saint. (D. W. Robertson, Jr., Ed.). On Christian Doctrine. (The Library of the Liberal Arts, no. 80). New York: Liberal Arts Press,_ 1958. Pp. 191. $.95. Barrett, William. Irrational Man-A Study in Existential Philosophy. New York: Doubleday, 1958. Pp. 278 with index. $5.00. Brehier, Emile. (Thomas Joseph, Tr.). · The Philosophy of PlotinUB. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958. Pp. 204 with index. $4.50. Brezzi, Paolo. The Papacy. Its Origins and Historical Evolution. Westminster: Newman Press, 1958. Pp. 281 with appendices. $8.50. Bugbee, Jr., Henry. The Inward Morning. State College, Penna.: Bald Eagle Press, 1958. Pp. 282. $5.00. Chroust, Anton-Hermann. Socrates, Man and Myth. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1958. Pp. 850 with index. $6.75. Cooney, Timothy. Ultimate Desires. New York: Philosophical Library, 1958. Pp. 100. $2.75. Drake, Henry L. The People's Plato. New York: Philosophical Library, 1958. Pp. 655 with index. $7.50. Else, Gerald F. Aristotle's Poetics: The Argument. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958. Pp. 670 with index. $11.00. Fernandez, Maria Angela. Un Lapso in la Historia del Pensamiento y de la Cultura Argentinas {1820-1880). Buenos Aires: Talleres Graficos D'Ambra, 1958. Pp. 128. Ford, S. J., John C. and Kelly, S. J., Gerald. Contemporary Moral Theology. (Volume One-Questions in Fundamental Moral Theology}. Westminster: Newman, 1958. Pp. 875 with index. $4.50. Fox, Ruth Mary. Dante Lights the Way. Milwaukee: Bruce, 1958. Pp. 889 with index. $4.95. Gilby, Thomas. The Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958. Pp. 888 with index. $5.00. Gorman, R. S.C. J., Mother Margaret. The Educational Implications of the Theory of Meaning and Symbolism of General Semantics. Washington: Catholic University Press, 1958. Pp. 195. Haley, C. S.C., Joseph E. (Ed.). Proceedings of the 1957 Sisters' Institute of Spirituality. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1958. Pp. 898. 575 576 BOOKS RECEIVED Higgins, S. J ., Thomas J. Man as Man: the Science and Art of Ethics (Revised Edition) . Milwaukee: Bruce, 1958. Pp. 598 with index. $4.50. Lepp, Ignace. From Karl Marx to Je8Wl Christ. New York: Sheed and Ward, 1958. Pp. 224. $8.75. Murphy, 0. P., William B.; Donlan, 0. P., Thomas C.; Reidy, 0. P., John S.; Cunningham, 0. P., Francis L. B. God and Hia Creation (Volume One of a College Theology Series). Dubuque: Priory Press, 1958. Pp. 516 with index. $4.95. McLelland, Joseph C. The Visible Words of God: An Exposition of the Sacramental Theology of Peter Martyr. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1958. Pp. 291 with index. $4.00. McNamara, O.P., Marie Aquinas. Friendship in St. Augustine. Fribourg: Fribourg University Press, 1958. Pp. 251 with index. Fr. 16.60/DM 16.-. Pieper, Josef. Happiness and Contemplation. New York: Pantheon, 1958. Pp. 124. $2.75. Reith, C. S.C., Herman. The Metaphysics of St. Thomas Aquinas. Milwaukee: Bruce, 1958. Pp. 420 with index. $5.50. Samuel, Otto. Die Ontologie der Logik and der Psyckologie-Eine Meontologiacke Untersuckung. Koln: Kolner Universitii.ts-Verlag, 1957. Pp. 886. 22. DM. Spinoza, Baruch. The Book of God. New York: Philosophical Library, 1958. Pp. 121. $8.00. Vogel, Arthur Anton. Reality, Reason and Religion. New York: Morehouse-Gorham, 1958. Pp. 219 with index. $8.00. THE GENERAL INDEX TO THE THOMIST VoL. XXI (1958) INDEX OF AUTHORS PAGE ALLERs, R. Review of The Character of Man by E. Monnier. . BEACH, J.D. Aristotle's Notion of Being. . --. Review of St. Tlwmas and the Future of Metaphysics by J. Owens. . BEcKLEY, Q. F. Review of The Catholic Church, U.S.A. by L. J. Putz CHROUST, A.-H. Review of Order and History, Vol. II: The World of the Polis by E. Voegelin. . CoLLINS, T. A. Review of He That Cometh by S. Mowinckel. . CuMMINGS,J. Review of The Christ of Faith by Karl Adam. . DE LETTER, P. Theology of Satisfaction. . DEWART, L. Review of Thought and Truth by M. Maisels. . GRISEZ, G. G. Kant and Aquinas: Ethical Theory. .. . -·--. Review of Insight: A Study of Human u,:W,erstanding by B. F. J. Lonergan. KANE, D. C. Review of Elements of Logic by V. E. Smith. KING-FARLOW, J. Value and "Essentialist" Fallacies. . LANGAN, T. D. Is Heidegger a Nihilist? . O'BRIEN, J. F. Gravity and Love as Unifying Principles. O'CoNNELL, D. A. Review of The Freedom to Read by R. McKeon and others. . O'CoNNOR,W. R. Review of Lay People in the Church by Y. Congar. O'NEILL, C. The Role of the Recipient and Sacramental Signification. 257, OEsTERLE, J. A. Theoretical and Practical Knowledge. . --. Review of Language: An Enquiry into its Meaning by R.N. 98 215 105 881 84 80 1 44 554 210 162 184 195 508 146 866 ANSHEN. RICHARDSON, D. B. The Philosophy of History and Historical Learning. . 487 RoVER, D. Review of Aristotle on Art and Nature by M. J. Charlesworth. . . . 877 RYAN, L.A. Review of The Transformation ofMan by L. Mumford. 891 SIKORA, J. J. "Integrated" Knowledge of Nature. 171 577 578 INDICES OF VOLUME XXI (1958) PAGE SIMMONS, E. D. Review of Man's Knowledge of Reality by F. Wilhelmsen. SLATTERY, M. P. Genus and Difference. . STocK, M. Sense Consciousness According to St. Thomas. ---. Thomistic Psychology and Freud's Psychoanalysis. WALKER, L. Review of The Coming World Civilization by W. E. Hocking. WASsMER, T. A. Freedom, Responsibility and Desire in Kantian Ethics. . 542 848 415 102 820 INDEX OF ARTICLES Aquinas, Kant and--: Ethical Theory. G. G. GRISEZ. Aristotle's Notion of Being. J. D. BEAcH. Being, Aristotle's Notion of--. J.D. BEAcH. . Consciousness, Sense -- According to St. Thomas. · M. STOCK. Desire, Freedom, Responsibility and -- in Kantian Ethics. T. A. WASSMER. . Difference, Genus and --. M. P. SLATTERY. . "Essentialist," Value and -- Fallacies. J. KING-FARLOW. Ethical, Kant and Aquinas: --Theory. G. G. GrusEZ. . Ethics, Freedom, Responsibility and Desire in Kantian --. T. A. WASSMER. . Fallacies, Value· and "Essentialist" --. J. KING-FARLOW. Freedom, Responsibility and Desire in Kantian Ethics. T. A. WASSMER. . Freud's, Thomistic Psychology and -- Psychoanalysis. M. SrocK. . Genus and Difference. M.P. SLATTERY. . Gravity and Love as Unifying Principles. J. F. O'BRIEN. . Heidegger, Is-- a Nihilist? T. D. LANGAN. . Historical, The Philosophy of History and -- Learning. D. B. RICHARDSON. History, The Philosophy of -- and Historical Learning. D. B. RICHARDSON. "Integrated" Knowledge of Nature. J. J. SIKORA. Kant and Aquinas: Ethical Theory. G. G. GRISEZ. Kantian, Freedom, Responsibility and Desire in -- Ethics. T. A. WASSMER. . Knowledge," Integrated"-- of Nature. J. J. SIKORA. ---, and Practical--. J. A. OESTERLE. 44 !il9 !il9 415 8!il0 848 162 44 8!il0 162 820 125 848 184 80!il 487 487 171 44 820 171 146 INDICES OF VOLUME XXI (1958) 579 PAGE Learning, The Philosophy of History and Historical --. D. B. RICH487 ARDSON.. 184 Gravity and-- as Unifying Principles. J. F. O'BRIEN. 171 Nature," Integrated" Knowledge of--. J. J. SIKORA. 302 Nihilist, Is Heidegger a --P T. D. LANGAN•. 29 Notion, Aristotle's -- of Being. J. D. BEACH. . Philosophy, The -- of History and Historical Learning. D. B. 487 RICHARDSON. 146 Practical, Theoretical and-- Knowledge. J. A. OESTERLE.. 184 Principles, Gravity and Love as Unifying--. J. F. O'BRIEN. Psychoanalysis, Thomistic Psychology and Ft·eud's --. M. STOCK. 125 Psychology, Thomistic-- and Freud's Psychoanalysis. M. STocK. 125 Recipient, The Role of the -- and Sacramental Signification. C. O'NEILL. 257' 508 Responsibility, Freedom, -- and Desire in Kantian Ethics. T. A. 320 WASSMER.. Role, The -- of the Recipient and Sacramental Signification. C. O'NEILL. 257, 508 Sacramental, The Role of the Recipient and -- Signification. C. O'NEILL. 257, 508 1 Satisfaction, Theology of--. P. DE LETTER. . 415 Sense Consciousness According to St. Thomas. M. STOCK. . Signification, The Role of the Recipient and Sacramental --. C. O'NEILL. 257, 508 1 Theology of Satisfaction. P. DE LETTER. . Theoretical and Practical Knowledge. J. A. OEsTERLE. 146 Theory, Kant and Aquinas: Ethical. G. G. GRISEZ. 44 Thomas, Sense Consciousness According to St. --. M. STocK. 415 Thomistic Psychology and Freud's Psychoanalysis. M. STOCK. 125 184 Unifying, Gravity and Love as-- Principles. J. F. O'BRIEN. Value and "Essentialist" Fallacies. J. KINn-FARLOw.. 162 INDEX OF BOOK REVIEWS ADAMS, K., The Christ of Faith. (J. Cummings) 80 ANSHEN, R. N., Language: An Enquiry into its Meaning. (J. A. Oesterle) 366 CHARLESWORTH,M. J., Aristotle on Art and Nature. (D. Rover) 377 CoNGAR, Y., Lay People in the Churtlh. (W. R. O'Connor) 229 HocKING, W. E., The Coming World Civilization. (L. Walker) 102 580 INDICES OF VOLUJ.VIE XXI (1958) PAGE B. F. J., Insight: A Study of Human Understanding. (G. G. Grisez) McKEoN, R. (and others), The Freedom to Read. (D. A. O'Connell) MAISELS, M., Thought and Truth. (L. Dewart) MouNIER, E., The Character of Man. (R. Allers) MowiNCKEL, S., He That Cometh. (T. A. Collins) . MUMFORD, L., The Transformation of Man. (L. A. Ryan) OWENS, J., St. Thomas and the Future of Metaphysics. (J.D. Beach) PuTZ, L. J., The Catholic Church, U.S. A. (Q. F. Beckley) SMITH, V. E., Elements of Logic. (D. C. Kane) VoEGELIN, E., Order and History, Vol. II: The World of the Polis. (A.-H. Chroust) . WILHELMSEN, F., Man's Knowledge of Reality. (E. D. Simmons) LoNERGAN, 554 195 220 98 84 391 215 105 210 381 542