THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: VoL. XXII The Thomist Press, Washington 17, D. C. JANUARY, 1959 No.1 ST. THOMAS AND THE ENCYCLICAL MYSTIC/ CORPORIS C scholars are universally grateful to his Holiness, Pope Pius XII, for the many clear and penetrating statements which he issued on both dogmatic and moral problems. It would be difficult to point to any one document as the most valuable and timely contribution to come from his pen; however, it is certain that the Encyclical Letter, Mystici Corporis, is among the most significant pronouncements made by his Holiness. Besides having given us a profound and scholarly treatise on a controversial topic, the Holy Father has succeeded in establishing a beautiful and delicate balance between the internal and external bonds which unite men to Christ in His Mystical Body. Therein lies the principal merit of this great Encyclical. In developing his treatise, the Pope is very generous in his praise of St. Thomas: ATHOLIC 1 MARTIN HOPKINS You are aware, Venerable Brothers, of the brilliant language by the masters of Scholastic Theology, and chiefly by the Angelic and Common Doctor, when treating this question; and you know that the reasons advanced by Aquinas are a faithful reflexion of the mind and writings of the Holy Fathers, who after all merely repeated and commented on the inspired word of Sacred Scripture. 1 In the light of this eulogy, it would be incongruous that we should find any irreconcilable discrepancies between M ystici Corporis and the doctrine of St. Thomas. We should have no anxiety, then, in submitting the works of the " Common Doctor "-in particular, his tract on the capital grace of Christ in the Third Part of the Summa-to a critical comparison with the papal Encyclical. It is the aim of this paper to institute such a comparison in order to offer solutions to certain real difficulties which have arisen especially with regard to St. 'J'homas's notion of membership in the Mystical Body in the wake of Jfystici Corporis. The following four points which His Holiness makes in the Encyclical will provide the basis for this companson: 1. The Roman Catholic Church and the Mystical Body of Christ are one and the same thing; i. e., they are coextensive. In fact, His Holiness offers the term " Mystical Body " as an ideal definition of the Church of Christ. 2 If Mystici Corporis has left any doubt as to the identity of these two terms, the Encyclical, Humani Generis, has emphatically cleared it up: Some say they are not bound by the doctrine, explained in our Encyclical letter of a few years ago and based on the sources of Revelation, which teaches that the Mystical Body of Christ and the Roman Catholic Church are one and the same thing .... These and like errors, it is clear, have crept in among certain of our sons who are deceived by imprudent zeal for souls or by false science.3 2. The soul of the Mystical Body is the Holy Ghost. 4 We 1 AAS. XXXV (1948), pp. 198-248. English by National Catholic Welfare Conference. (Washington, D. C., 1948), n. 85. This translation is used throughout. • Ibid., n. 18. • AAS. XXXXII (1950), p. 571. English translation by Paulist Press. (New York, 1950) nn. 42, 44. 'Myatici Corporis, n. 56. ST. THOMAS AND THE ENCYCLICAL "MYSTIC! CORPORIS" 8 cannot admit that the body and soul of the Church represent two different societies with diverse memberships. As His Holiness says: For this reason We deplore and condemn the pernicious error of those who conjure up from their fancies an imaginary Church, a kind of Society that finds its origin and growth in charity, to which they somewhat contemptuously oppose another, which they call juridical. But this distinction, which they introduce, is baseless.... There can, then, be no real opposition or conflict between the invisible mission of the Holy Spirit and the juridical commission of Ruler and Teacher received from Christ. Like body and soul in us, they complement and perfect each other, and have their source in our one Redeemer.... G 8. True membership in the Mystical Body demands that one possess three conditions: baptism of water, profession of the true faith, and submission to the authority of the Church. To be lacking in one or more of these qualifications excludes a person from membership. 6 Here the Pope is merely repeating the legislation of the Code of Canon Law: By baptism a person becomes a subject of the Church of Christ with all the rights and duties of a Christian, unless, in so far as rights are concerned, there is some obstacle impeding the bond of communion with the Church, or a censure inflicted by the Church. 7 4. There is definite evidence that His Holiness intends to identify the Mystical Body (i. e., the Roman Catholic Church) with the Church Militant. In the passage already cited from Humani Generis, he specifies Roman ·catholic Church, the term " Roman " ordinarily limiting the extension of Church to the visible portion. In Mystici Corporis, he explicitly limits his remarks on the Mystical Body to the Church Militant; 8 later on in the Encyclical, he adds: For nothing more glorious, nothing nobler, nothing surely more ennobling can be imagined than to belong to the Holy, Catholic, Apostolic, and Roman Church. In that Church we become members 6 8 Ibid., n. 64. Ibid., n. 22. Cf. C. I. C., Can. 87. "Mystici Corporis, n. I. 4 MARTIN HOPKINS of one Body that deserves all veneration, are guided by one supremely eminent Head; in it we are filled with one divine Spirit; in it we are nourished during our earthly exile with one doctrine and one Bread of Angels, until at last we enter into the one, unending blessedness of heaven. 9 POINT I: Identification of the Roman Catholic Church with the Mystical Body of Christ In comparing the first of these four points with the doctrine of St. Thomas, we find perfect agreement. At the very beginning of his tract on the capital grace of Christ, he states: " tota Ecclesia dicitur unum corpus mysticum per similitudinem ad naturale corpus hominis." 10 A little later on, he puts the two terms together, thus: corpus Ecclesiae mysticum. 11 Like the Pope, then, St. Thomas identifies the Church with the Mystical Body: for him the terms are coextensive. Both authorities use the words Church and Mystical Body interchangeably, and they shall be used thus throughout this paper. 12 PoiNT II: The Holy Ghost as the Soul of the Mystical Body In the Summa Theologica, St. Thomas describes the Holy Ghost as the " heart " of the Church: ... but the heart has a certain hidden influence. And hence the Holy Ghost is likened to the heart, since He invisibly quickens and unifies the Church; but Christ is likened to the Head in His visible nature in which man is set over manY That this term has the same force as " soul," however, is evident from St. Thomas's treatise on the Apostles' Creed, where he actually uses the word soul: • Ibid., n. 89. Italics mine. Summa Theol., IU, q. 8, a. l. 11 Ibid.; aa. 3, 4. 12 This identification of the Church and the Mystical Body of Christ must not be confused with the fact, to be treated under the next two points, that St. Thomas gives a much broader extension to the two terms than does the Sovereign Pontiff. 13 Summa Theol., lac cit., a. l, ad. 3. " ... sed cor habet qmimdam influentiam occcltam. Et ideo cordi comparatur Spiritus Sanctus, qui invisibiliter Ecclesiam 10 ST. THOMAS AND THE ENCYCLICAL "MYSTIC! CORPORIS" 5 We see that in a man there are one soul and one body; and of his body there are many members. So also the Catholic Church is one body and has different members. The soul which animates this body is the Holy Ghost. 14 Both the Pope and St. Thomas describe the Holy Ghost as the internal bond uniting each member to Christ and to each other. The Pope speaks of this bond as comprising faith, hope and charity through the " communication of the Spirit o! Christ" (the Holy Ghost, Who is) "the channel through which flow into all the members of the Church those gifts, powers and extraordinary graces found superabundantly in the Head as in their source .... " 15 In regard to the first two points, then, it is clear that there is no disagreement between the papal Encyclical and the teaching of the Angelic Doctor. It is on the third and fourth points that discrepancies appear, to the extent that one writer has affirmed that St. Thomas " would have written quite differently if he had the papal encyclical of Pius XII to guide him." 16 PoiNT III: Members of the Mystical Body In general, St. Thomas includes more individuals in his concept of the Church than does the Pope, as will be seen from the comparison which follows: 17 vivificat et unit; capiti autem comparatur ipse Christus secundum visibilem naturam, secundum quam homo hominibus praefertur." u Opusc. VII, a. 9. " Sicut vidimus quod in uno homine est una anima et unum corpus, et tamen sunt diversa membra ipsius; ita Ecclesia catholica est unum corpus, et habet diversa membra. Anima autem quae hoc corpus vivificat est Spiritus. Sanctus." 16 Mystici CorpOTis, n. 77. With regard to the use of "body" and" soul" in the Baltimore Catechism cf. The Homiletic and Pastoral Review, LI (1950-1951), p. 86. C£. also: Joseph C. Fenton in The American Ecclesiastical Review, "The Use of the Terms Body and Soul with Reference to the Catholic Church," CX (1944), pp. 4857; "Father Journet's Concept of the Church," CXXVII (1952), pp. 870-880. 18 John L. Murphy, The Living Christ (Milwaukee, 1956), p. 51. Cf. also pp. 52-58. 17 The fir8t two of these points will be taken up in detail later, with relevant texts. MARTIN COMPARATIVE HOPKINS EXTENSION OF THE TERJ.VI MYSTICAL BODY (=ROMAN CATHOLIC CHURCH) ST. THOMAS Pros XII 1. Extends membership in the Mystical l. Limits membership in the Mystical Body to the angels and blessed souls in heaven, and to the souls in purgatory. Body to the Church Militant. 2. Includes the just of the Old Testament, along with the faithful of the New Testament, in the Mystical Body. 2. Identifies the Mystical Body with the Catholic Church, which came into existence only with the death of Christ on the Cross. 8. Includes all who possess charity, without qualification. Hence, baptism of desire admits a person to the Mystical Body, and every one who is actually in the state of sanctifying grace must be included therein, whether Catholic, material heretic, or sincere pagan upon making a perfect act of contrition.'" In fact, St. Thomas admits incorporation into the Church mentaliter as well as corporaliter.10 8. Insists on baptism of water, together with true faith and submission to Church authority, as indispensable conditions of membership. While granting that one who lacks one or more of these conditions may be " unsuspectingly related " to the Mystical Body " in desire and resolution," he adds that " they remain deprived of so many precious gifts and helps from heaven, which one can enjoy only in the Catholic Church." •• 4. While listing faith as a title of membership, he is loath to admit sinners (i.e., those with faith but not charity) into the Church. He classifies them as "potential " members, though, conceding that they may also be called " imperfect " (actual) members because , of their unformed faith, united to Christ only secundum quid. 21 4. Grants sinners who possess the three conditions the status of members. His Holiness nowhere concedes varying " degrees " of membership in the Mystical Body, though he intimates that the amount of life among the members may vary.•• 5. Designates those who lack both faith and charity as potential members, with 5. Does not follow St. Thomas in the use of the term " potential " members. Summa Theol., III, q. 8, a. 8. Ibid., q. 69, a. 5, ad 1. so Mystici Corporis, n. 100. 21 Summa Theol., Ill, q. 8 a. 8, ad 2. In Ill Sent., d. 18 q. 2, a. 2, qcla. 2, sol. 2 ad 2 St. Thomas refers to sirmers as members of the Mystical Body aequivoce. •• Mystici Corporis, n. 28: "It is the Saviour's infinite mercy that allows place in His Mystical Body here for those whom He did not exclude from the banquet of old (Cf. Matt. 9: 11). For not every sin, however grave and enormous it be, is such as to sever a man automatically from the body of the Church, as does schism or heresy or apostasy. Men may lose charity and divine grace through sin and so become incapable of supernatural merit, and yet not be deprived of all life, if they hold on to faith and Christian hope. . . ." 18 19 s•.r. THOMAS AND THE ENCYCLICAL the exception of those who are already damned; these latter totalitcr desinunt ease membra Christi.•• This phrase, together with its context, indicates that St. Thomas is taking this potentiality as something very positive--a quasi-membership-based upon (a) the merits of Christ, which are sufficient to save all men; and (b) man's free will."' "MYS'l'ICI CORPORIS" 7 All individuals who lack any one of the three conditions are classed simply as non-members, even though they possess the extraordinary " relationship " to the Church mentioned above. In other w01·ds, the Pope does not consider this relationship either as a type of membership in the Church or as its equivalent, for he expresses the desire that they "enter into Catholic unity," since otherwise " they cannot be sure of their salvation." •• In the light of this comparison, it becomes clear that the Pope and St. Thomas are using different foundations for their divisions of membership. St. Thomas is taking the capital grace of Christ-especially charity-for l1is foundation; the Pope is using the three conditions mentioned above. To put it another way, St. Thomas defines membership in the Mystical Body in terms of the internal bond (or invisible element), whereas Pius XII designates membership in terms of the external bond (or visible element). St. Thomas, it must be remembered;is not speaking formally of the Church in the Third Part of the Summa; in fact, he has left us no strictly ecclesiological treatise. He is discussing the capital grace of Christ and its effects. He points out that the principal effect of the flow of Christ's grace into the souls of men is that it constitutes Christ as their Head, and makes them His members. Arguing from the revealed principles (I) that Christ is the Head of all men, and (fl) that the essential, internal basis of their union with Christ is His capital grace, St. Thomas proceeds to evaluate His headship in terms of that grace. Quite simply stated, the Angelic Doctor's teaching is this: Christ's headship-and, consequently, our union with Him-will be in proportion to the degree of habitual grace we possess. In line with this principle, he distinguishes three classes or degrees of union with Christ: that of the blessed in heaven •• Summa Theol., III, q. 8, a. S. •• Ibid., ad 1. •• Mystici Curporis, n. 100. 8 MARTIN HOPKINS through glory; of the faithful on earth through charity; and finally, of those united to Him through faith alone. 26 In grouping all of these individuals together and designating them as members of the Mystical Body of Christ, St. Thomas is following the example of some of the early Fathers of the Church, who frequently used the Pauline metaphor of body to describe the internal union of the soul with Christ. In using the term with this supposition, neither the Fathers nor St. Thomas meant to imply that no external, juridical bond was required for membership in the Church. They were primarily interested in developing the inner, organic aspect of our union with the Redeemer; they wrote as theologians, not as apologetes or canonists. It is a fact that, ever since St. Paul applied this figure to the Church, it has been used in a variety of senses to express several different types of Christ's headship over creatures. The principal types are: 27 1. The universal headship of Christ over all creatures by reason of His divine, exemplary causality as the Word of God. 2. His headship over the whole human race by reason of having died to save all men from original and actual sins. 3. His headship over all men who have believed, or shall believe, in Him as the Redeemer. This includes the Jews before the Redemption, as well as Christians after it. 4. His headship over all intellectual creatures who share in His grace in any manner whatsoever, whether essentially (as in the case of men), or accidentally (as in the case of the angels). 5. The strict, juridical headship of Christ, constituted by baptism of water, profession of the true faith, and submission to the authority of the Church. It was quite common among the Fathers of the first five centuries to speak of the fourth type of headship as the equivalent of the Mystical Body. St. Augustine, the great expounder of the mystical relationship between Christ and His Church, refers to the " whole assembly of Saints ... from Abel 26 As is indicated in the comparative schema, St. Thomas is inclined to classify those who possess faith without charity (i.e. sinners) as potential members. 21 John L. Murphy, op. cit. On pp. 45 ff. Father Murphy summarizes the types. ST. THOMAS AND THE ENCYCLICAL "MYSTIC! CORPORIS" 9 down to those who shall be born to the end " as members of Christ's body, the Church. 28 Here he is using the Pauline metaphor in a broad sense,29-the sense in which St. Thomas also used the term. And they do so with good reason, since the term was coined primarily to designate the internal, organic, supernatural character of the Church. For the next seven centuries this sublime doctrine saw little theological development; in fact, scarcely any significant progress was made until the Scholastics took up their pens in the thirteenth century. Although he was not the only one to write on this topic, St. Thomas has left a greater imprint on subsequent thinking and writing about the Mystical Body than any of his contemporaries. So beautifully and extensively did he treat of it that not only Pius XII, but other modern authors have been quick to recognize his contribution. The Abbe Anger has gone so far as to declare: St. Thomas took great care never to lose sight of the doctrine of the Mystical Body. Taking his work as a whole, particularly its most finished, maturest part, the Summa Theologica, one finds the Christian doctrine in all its purity set forth with precision and in such right sense that in many instances the Council of Trent had but to confirm the doctrine and exposition. 30 The history of the Church gives us an insight as to why St. Thomas and his contemporaries did not develop the juridical aspect of the Mystical Body. At that time there were few, if zs In Ps. 90, sermo 2; PL, XXXVII, 1159. •• Cf. John C. Gruden, The Mystical Christ (St. Louis, 1986), pp. 105, 158. He distinguishes between quasi-proper (strict, " mystical," juridical) sense and the figurative (broad, " metaphorical ") sense of the term Mystical Body. In a paper of this nature, it is impossible to trace the historical development of the doctrine in any detail; nor is it necessary. This task has been ably performed by a number of competent authors, among whom the work here referred· to-though written seven years before the Encyclical appeared-is outstanding. Fr. Emile Mersch's The Whole Christ (Milwaukee, 1986), Part I, is excellent for thf( development of the concept in Sacred Scripture. •• Abbe Anger. The Doctrine of the Mystical Body of Christ According ta the Principles of the Theology of St. Thomas. (New York, 1981), p. xvi. Cf. also J. T. Dittoe, 0. P., "Sacramental Incorporation into the Mystical Body." THE THoMisT, IX (1946), pp. 469-514. 10 MARTIN HOPKINS any, recognized material heretics. If a person denied an article of faith or rejected the whole of Christianity, he was considered to be a formal heretic or an apostate, guilty of sin before God. 31 \Ve can appreciate this attitude more readily when we consider the seemingly inescapable visibility of the Church within the civilized medieval world. Catholicism stood out as the overwhelming-virtually unique-embodiment of Christianity: the Roman Catholic Church was Christianity. It was inconceivable that a sincere individual, raised in such an atmosphere and tradition, could inculpably withdrawfrom the Catholic Church, or find God apart from it. With regard to infidels, St. Thomas admits the possibility of i.e., invincible ignorance of the true faith. a negative However, he conCludes that if such infidels die in that state, " damnantur quidem propter alia peccata, quae sine fide remitti non possunt." 32 Yet, he seems to be of the opinion that this will never be the case in the concrete; for, in discussing the question of what truths one must believe explicitly in order to be saved, he answers with reference to the salvation a man brought up outside the pale of civilization: Thus, if someone so brought up followed the direction of natural reason in seeking good and avoiding evil, it certainly must be held that God would either reveal to him through internal inspiration what had to be believed, or would send some preacher of the faith to him.S3 31 Cf. Summa Theol., II II, q. 11. St. Thomas does not distinguish between material and formal heretics; in fact, he concludes that pertinacious heretics are to be put to death. But it should be carefully noted that he puts those whom modem theologians designate " material heretics " within the Mystical Body, provided they are in the state of grace. This is in accord with his use of grace as the foundation of membership. •• Ibid., q. Hl, a. 1. •• De Vent., q. 14, a. U, ad. 1. "Si enim aliquis taliter nutritus, ductum naturalis rationis sequeretur in appetitu boni et fuga mali, certissime est tenendum, quod ei Deus vel per internam inspirationem revelaret ea quae sunt ad credendum necessaria, vel aliquem fidei praedicatorem ad eum dirigeret." He lends further weight to this conclusion when he states in the Smnma Theologiae I, H, q. 89, a. 6 that in his first human act, a man either directs himself to his true ultimate end (thus having baptism of desire), or else turns to a false ultimate end, thereby committing mortal sin. In the former case, the individual would evidently fit in ST. THOMAS AND THE ENCYCLICAL "MYSTIC! CORPORIS" 11 In the light of these points, it is evident that there wn.s not a great need in the thirteenth century of delving into the minimum external signs which a true Christian must possess. Hence, we can see more clearly the reason why St. Thomas and his followers devoted their attention almost exclusively to the internal bond of the union between Christ and His members, even to the extent of adjudicating membership in His Mystical Body in terms of habitual grace, especially charity. For the Scholastics, one's degree of grace provided an adequate (though, as we can see today, not a precise) index of membership, which -because of the nature of grace-would logically admit of degrees. It was not until the Protestant Reformation that the juridical aspect of the Mystical Body was developed to a degree comparable to the progress made by the Scholastics on the internal bond. In defending the Church against the Reformers, Catholic apologetes-among whom St. Robert Bellarmine stands outwere obliged to concentrate on the external, visible bond of the Mystical Body. Protestant Christianity furnished a palatable, albeit incomplete, substitute for Catholicism, and gave rise to a tradition which, with the passage of· time, made it possible for large groups of sincerely erring believers (referred to now as material heretics) to coexist in good faith with their orthodox brethren. This shift of emphasis from the internal to the external bond persisted down to the time of the Vatican Council to such a degree that modern theologians have deplored the lag in the development of the spiritual aspect of the doctririe.s• However, the liturgical revival which the turn of the century ushered in has been accompanied by a corresponding (perhaps among those whom Pius XII classes as being1 "related" to the Mystical Body: outside the Church, yet somehow united to it " in desire and resolution," and therefore capable of salvation. As we noted above, St. Thomas grants such a one the status of a member. We shall have more to say in our conclusion about thi3 mysterious, extraordinary union with Christ by one outside of His Mystical Body. •• Thus, Fr. Mersch speaks of a "resurgen('e" of the doctrine of the Mystical Body, op. cit., p. 556; and Fr. Dittoe, op. cit., p. 469, refers to it as "a doctrinal survival against naturalism and a spiritual revival in the face of indifferentism." But see also Fr. Fenton, "An Accusation Against School Theology," American Ecclesiastical Review, CX (1944), pp. 218-222. MARTIN HOPKINS one should say complementary) revival in this neglected area.. A flood of literature has appeared on the subject of the Mystical Body-most of it sound, but some entirely orthodox. 85 In the Encyclical, Mystici Corporis, His Holiness corrects the errors which have appeared. But his greatest and most enduring contribution is the delicate, harmonious blending of the internal with the external aspects of the mystery to give us the strict, Pauline concept of the Church as the Body of Christ. Recognizing the great synthesis of the Fathers and Scholastics, especially St. Thomas, the Pope integrates beautifully the mystical elements with the juridical elements. In stressing the unity of the Mystical Body, he shows that the visible ties uniting the Christian to Christ, and the invisible bonds to which they are ordered, are actually two aspects of the same organism.36 Finally, without underemphasizing the importance of the Holy Ghost with His grace and Gifts as the soul of the Church, His Holiness points out that membership in the strict, proper and univocal sense is to be defined in terms of the external or juridical bond rather than in terms of grace. 87 One can truly say that Pius XII has done for these two aspects of the Church what St. Thomas did for sacramental theology in carefully balancing the elements of sign and cause. 88 In fact, St. Thomas's tract on the sacraments offers a valuable precedent to what the Pope has accomplished. Following the medieval tradition, the Angelic Doctor distinguishes in each sacrament between the external sign, or sacrament, and the i11 necessity for positing the intellectus agens ,, (Summa Theol., I, q. 79, a. 3) . To the extent that the £active intellect which Professor .M:argenau adduces would be " autonomous " of sense data-" It is my own belief," he states, " that novelty can enter through reason as well as through sense "-to that very extent such an intellect could indeed be "£active" or "making" according to the dictates of human creativity, producing an order in irrational events where none existed before. On the other hand, to the extent that the intellect, face to face with reality, was in the position not of a "maker," but of an observer who views the nature which he does not make, to that extent one would avoid the possible ambiguity arising out o£ calling an intellect " factive," which, although it makes things intelligible, does not make the order in those things. Thus one understands why St. Thomas, while using the word facere of this intellect, nevertheless does not call it jactivus. In effect, he consistently emphasizes that the intellect face to face with reality does not make: ". . . There is a certain order which reason does not make, but solely considers, as is the order of natural things .... To natural philosophy it pertains to consider the order of things which the human reason considers but does not make-including under natural philosophy also metaphysics " (In Eth. Arist., I, 1. 1, no. 1-!2). " ... Human reason of the things which are according to nature is knowing only; but of those which are according to art, it is both knowing and making ... " (In Pol. Arist., Prooem., no. 2). " ... [Certain] sciences do not have a product, but knowledge only, as is .the case with divine science and natural science, whence they cannot have the name of' art,' since art is called '£active reason'" (In Boet. De Trin., 1. !2, q. 1, a. 1, ad 3) . Hence it is clear that in natural science or physics, which is the science of which Professor Margenau speaks, if his "£active intellect" is "making," it in no way resembles the function of the intellect as understood by St. Thomas. 78 PIERRE H. CONWAY Finally, mention must be made of the use of the word "passive intellect" by Professor Margenau as designating the counterpart of " factive intellect." Since the intellectus agens becomes the " factive intellect," it is assumed that by " passive intellect" is meant the intellectus possibilis. However, since St. Thomas notes an intellectus passivus distinct from the intellectus possiblis, and since it is precisely the confounding of these two which constitutes the Averroistic position, the position of St. Thomas should not be unknown. It is contained in the very same lectio in which St. Thomas discusses the initial positing of the intellectus agens by Aristotle, namely, In De Anima, III, I. 10. The need for distingishing between "possible" and "passive" intellects arises from Aristotle's statement: " When mind is set free from its present conditions it appears as just what it is and nothing more: this alone is immortal and eternal-we do not, however, remember its former activity because, while mind in this sense is impassible, mind as passive is destructible-and without it nothing thinks " (430a 20, Oxford transl.). If the agent intellect is taken as" separated " not only from a sense organ but from the body itself, and the possible intellect is identified with the " passive " mind which corrupts, then one has the Averroist position of a single separted active intellect for all men, and individual corruptible possible intellects-and thereby corruptible souls-for individual men. St. Thomas, in speaking of Aristotle's statement in this place that " mind in this sense (i. e., the intellectus agens) is separable, impassible, unmixed . . . in its essential nature activity," has these four characteristics for a single reason: the agent is more noble than the patient, and therefore the intellectus agens more noble than the intellectus possiblis. But the intellectus possibilis has already been shown to be the first three, i.e., separated, impassible and unmixed [in c. 4, 429a 15 sq.-' since everything is a possible object of thought, mind ... to know, must be pure from all admixture .. .']; hence this is all the more true of the intellectus agens which is in act with regard to the intellectus possibilis (In De Anima, Ill, I. 10, no. 732-3). This HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS 79 OF 1958 "separation" is separation from a bodily organ, since in order to know material things universally the intellect itself cannot be material. Both operations, that of abstracting the intelligible species from sense knowledge, and that of receiving them, terminate in a single knowing of the natures of material things: they are both, as Aristotle says, « within the soul." This whole intellectual section of man is separable, i.e., can survive the body, for, as Aristotle states, " while the faculty of sensation- is dependent upon the body, mind is separable from it" (429b). St. Thomas then expounds the words, " ... this alone is immortal and eternal . . . ," as follows: " And since in the beginning of this book he [Aristotle] stated that if there be any operation of the soul proper to it, the soul may be separated [i.e., Book I, 403a, 10: 'If there is any way of acting or being acted upon proper to soul, soul will be capable of separate existence '], he concludes that this sole part of the soul, namely, the intellective, is incorruptible and perpetuaL And this is what he set down above in Book H, namely, that this genus of soul is separated from others as the perpetual from the corruptible [413b ' ... Mind or the power to think . . . seems to be a widely different kind of soul, differing as what is eternal from what is perishable .. .']. But it is called ' perpetual,' not because it always was, but because it will always be. Whence the Philosopher states in Metaphysics XII that form is never anterior to matter, but the soul remains afterwards-not an ' soul, but the intellect [1070a 25: . The soul may be of this sort-not all soul but the reason ']." (In De Anima, Zoe. cit., no. 743.) If the intellective part of the soul, the agent and possible intellect, is " separable," i. e., immortal, while the body perishes, what then of that mind which " as passive, is destructible,'' i. e., the "passive" intellect? Actually, the "passive intellect" in this context represents the sense faculties, subject to the sense passions, as the impassible agent and possible intellect are not, and whose use is suspended with the destruction of the sense organs, and " without which," since all natural knowledge comes through the senses," nothing thinks" in the natural way. 0 • 80 PIERRE H. CONWAY Of this " intellect," which is really sense, St. Thomas says: "And therefore he states here that we do not remember, namely, after death, those things which we knew in life, since • mind in this sense is impassible,' i. e., that part of the intellective soul is impassible [namely, the agent and possible intellect], whence it is not the subject of the passions of the soul, such as are love and hate, reminiscence and such, which arise from some bodily passion. But the passive intellect is, corruptible, i. e., the part of the soul which is not without the aforesaid passions, is corruptible; for they belong to the sensitive part. Nevertheless this part of the soul is called ' intellect,' as it is also called ' rational, in so far as it partakes in some way of reason, by obeying reason and following its motion, as is said in Ethics I [1102b 30: ' ... The vegetative element in no way shares in a rational principle, but the appetitive, and in general the desiring element in a sense shares in it ']. But without this part of the corporeal soul, the intellect does not know anything. For it does not know anything without a phantasm, as will be said below [43la 15: ' ... The soul never thinks without an image]. And therefore, when the body is destroyed, there does not remain in the separated soul knowledge of things according to the mode in which it now understands. But as to how it then understands it does not belong to the present intent to diRcuss." (Ibid., no. 745.) From his comparison of it with the " £active intellect " (intellectus agens) it would seem that Professor Margenau must have conferred the appellation of" passive intellect," not upon the "passive intellect" of St. Thomas which Fr. Gilby does not appear to treat (except to mention in a footnote, p. 237, that the intellectus possibilis should not be translated as the ' passive intellect ') , but upon the " possible intellect," which in one place Fr. Gilby calls the " receptive intellect,'' possibly lending to Professor Margenau's tendency to call it the" passive intellect." The interesting part, however, is that while Professor Margenau's "passive intellect" which mechanically collates sense data without the intrusion of the novelty of reason, in no way resembles the intellectus possiblis which perceives, not HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1908 81 sense-data, but the universal intelligible order implicit in that data, it does very much resemble the "passive intellect" of St. Thomas, which is not an intellect at all, but a sense power under the aspect of a certain similarity to reason-for example, as in the case of the cogitative power or " particular 1·eason," which collates sensible singulars into a single experiential knowledge somewhat after the manner of the universal reason collating universals. St. Thomas says, in effect: " ... Experience is from the collation of several singulars received into the memory. Now such a collation is proper to men, and belongs to the cogitative power, which is called the 'particular reason,' which is collative of individual intentions as is universal reason of universal intentions" (In iVleta. Arist., I, l. 1, no. 15) . "And that singulars are of the nature of principles is plain, since from singulars the universal is derived. For from the fact that this herb conferred health upon this man one derives that this species of herb is able to heaL And since singulars are properly known by sense, it is necessary that man should have these singulars ... not external sense, but which he has called above' prudence,' namely, the cogitative or estimative power, which is called 'particular reason.' Whence this sense is called ' intellect,' which is concerned with sensible or singular things. And this the Philosopher calls in De Anima III the passive intellect, which is corruptible" (In Eth. Arist., VI, L 9, no. 1249. For a distinction between intellectus passivus and possibilis, Cf. Sumrna Theol., I, q. 79 a. 2, ad 2) . The " passive intellect " of Professor J'\iargenau, its function of collating data in an unthinking positivistic way, with a logic which shuts out inferences of reason, seems then, whether by coincidence or not, remarkably like the " passive intellect" of St. Thomas. But what can be said of his" factive intellect"? It does not have any counterpart in that intellective part of the soul, composed of the agent and possible intellect, with regard to the observation of nature from which natural science and metaphysics are derived, since the former in its rational function "makes," while the does not. Nor, fundamentaHy, can Professor Margenau's "factive intellect," PIERRE H. CONWAY to the extent that it implies a contribution of reason independent of the senses, be assimilated to intellect as conceived by St. Thomas at all, since it is a rigid principle for St. Thomas that aU natural knowledge originates through the senses: " ... It is impossible that our intellect according to the state of the present life in which it is conjoined to a passible body should understand anything in act except by turning to phantasms " (Summa Theol., I, q. 84, a. 7). So clear does St. Thomas make the point of the sensible origin of all natural knowledge in this life, that he is able to say, speaking of the very Questions on the knowledge of the intellect from which Professor Margenau borrows via Father Gilby: "Now the first thing which is understood by us according to the state of the present life, is the nature of a material thing, as has been stated a number of times above" (Ibid., q. 88, a. 3) . Since St. Thomas is at pains to underline the point that in this life all knowledge is initially derived from the senses, necessarily depends upon sense phantasms or images, and terminates primarily at the natures or quiddities of material things, it is perhaps well to list something of the dense sequence of these statements in a relatively short space: "The body seems necessary to the intellective soul most of all for its proper operation which is to understand, since according to its existence it does not depend upon the body" (Ibid., q. 84, a. 4). ". . . Each one is able to. experience within himself that when someone is trying to understand something, he forms certain phantasms in the manner of examples, in which he considers, so to speak, that which he is endeavoring to understand. Whence it is also that when we wish to have someone understand something, we propose examples to him from which he may be able to form phantasms in order to understand. . . . Now of the human intellect, which is conjoined to the body, the proper object is the quiddity or nature existing in a material thing; and through such natures of visible things it rises also to a certain knowledge of invisible things. . . . But we apprehend the particular thing [in which the nature of any material thing exists] by sense and imagination-and therefore it is necessary HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 83 in order that the intellect actually understand its proper object, that it should consider the universal nature existing in the particular thing" (Ibid., q. 84, a. 7). " ... The proper object proportioned to our intellect is the nature of a sensible thing. Now a perfect judgment cannot be given of any thing unless all the things which pertain to that thing be known. This is especially true should one be in ignorance of that which is the term and end of the judgment. Now the Philosopher says,' Just as the end of factive science is the product, so of natural science the end is that which is seen properly according to sense knowledge [De Caelo III, 306a 15: ' ... That issue, which in the case of productive knowledge is the product, in the knowledge of nature is the unimpeachable evidence of the senses· as to each fact ']. . . . The natural scientist does not seek to know the nature of a stone and a horse except to know the notions of those things which are seen by the senses. It is plain that ... there cannot be a perfect judgment in natural science of natural things if one does not know the sensible things" (Ibid., q. 84, a. 8). " ... Its (the human intellect's) proper function is to know a form existing indeed individually in corporeal matter, but nevertheless not as it is in this matter. But to know that which is in individual matter, not as it is in this matter, is to abstract the form from individual matter, which form the phantasms picture. And therefore it is necessary to state that our intellect knows material things by abstracting from phantasms; and through material things thus considered we arrive at some knowledge of immaterial things, just as conversely the angels know material things through immaterial things" (Ibid., q. 85, a. I). " ... The object of our intellect according to the state of the present life is the nature of a material thing, as was said above ... " (Ibid., q. 87, a. ad " ... According to the judgment of Aristotle, of which we have more experience within ourselves [than, namely, that of Plato whereby one knows through immaterial subsisting ideas], our intellect according to the state of the present life has its natural direction to the natures of material things-whence it understands nothing except by turning to phantasms, as is evident from what has 84 PIERRE Ho CONWAY been saido o o . It was shown above that the intellectus agens is not a separated substance, but a certain power of the soul, extending to the same things by act to which the intellectus pos:sibilis extends receptively: for, as it is stated [in De Anima III, c. 5, 430a 10], the possible intellect is that which is able to become all things, while the agent intellect is that which is able to make all things. Both intellects, therefore, extend according to the state of the present life solely to material things, which the agent intellect causes to be intelligible in act, and which are received into the possible intellecto . Our possible intellect is so disposed according to the state of the present life as to be informed the likenesses of material things abstracted from phantasms" (lbido, qo 88, a. l, and ad 2) . In the following Question 89, on the knowledge the separated soul, St. Thomas states unequivocally: " ... The manner understanding by conversion to phantasms is natural to the soul, as is to be united to a body; but to be separated from the is out of to without conversion to phantasms is out keeping with its nature" (Ibid., q. 89, a. 1) . At time the knowlinnate edge of the soul, says St. Thomas, " is not species, nor through species then abstracted, nor solely through species preserved [i. e., as habitual in the intellect, without accompanying phantasms preserved in sense memory] . . . , but through species participated through the influx of the divine the other sepalight, of which the soul is made partaker rated substances, although in a lower way " (Ibid., ad 3) o "It was stated that as long as the soul is united to the it understands by turning itself to phantasms" (Ibid., a. the acts the intellect by which in the present is acquired are through the turning of the intellect to are in the . sensitive powers " (Ibid., ao 5) . Professor lVIa.rgenaulikewise quotes from F:r. Gilby a passage from Question 85, a. 2, initial pu:rport is not to give a kind of primacy to the intelligible species themselves, as Professor Margenau would seem to favor, but whose conclusion, 0 0 • 0 HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 85 which is not included, goes as follows: " ... The likeness of the thing understood, which is the intelligible species, is the fonn according to which the intellect understands. But since the intellect reflects upon itself, according to the same reflexion it understands both its understanding and the species by which it understands. And thus the understood species is secondarily that which is understood, but that which is understood primarily is the thing, of which the intelligible species is the likeness" (Summa Theol., I, q. 85, a. 2), This is repeated: " ... The human intellect . . . is neither its understanding, nor is its essence the primary object of its understanding, but rather something extrinsic, namely, the nature of a material thing. And therefore that which is first known by the human intellect is such an object; secondly is known the act itself by which the object is known; and through the act is known the intellect itself, whose perfection the act of understanding is. . . . The intellect is able to know its act, but not first, since the first object of our intellect according to the present state is not any being and truth whatsoever, but being and the true considered in material things, as was said [q. 84, a. 7], from which it arrives at the knowledge of other things" (Ibid", q. 87, a. 3, and ad 1)" From all of the above it is clear that there is nowhere to be found in St. Thomas a counterpart of the " factive intellect ., which Professor Margenau adduces, in the sense of an intellect which can somehow produce thought independently of sensedata. Nor is it a question of whether such thought would be valid and objective: for SL Thomas it is downright impossible. There is no such thing, therefore in SL Thomas, as an " autonomous function of reason " (po 22), capable of " injecting into the stream of knowledge . " . elements of its own ., (Ibid.). Nor can there be "abstract principles-called metaphysical do not have their origin in the sensory part of our experience but spring from what Thomas would call the nature of man's rational soul" (p. 33). There can be no "leap " into an "ontological reality" (p. 36) where what is drawn from the intelligible species, the" mental states" (p. 37) , has any more content than that which may be strictly 86 PIERRE H. CONWAY derived or inferred from sense data. While it is true that " the intellect knows many things in the thing apprehended through sense, which the sense is not able to perceive " (Summa Theol., I, q. 88, a. 4, ad 4), beginning with the nature of the material thing, nevertheless this knowledge which arises from sense, never in the state of the present life reaches a point where the ties are cut with its sensible origin, where one may know without reference to phantasms: " ... Our intellect both abstracts intelligible species from phantasms, in so far as it considers the natures of thing in a universal way; and nevertheless it understands them in phantasms-since it cannot understand those things whose species it abstracts except by turning to the phantasms, as was said above" (Ibid., q. 85, a. 1, ad 5). Even should one rise above a " discontinuous model of motion " (p. to a description in " abstract mathematical terms " ( Ibid.) , one has not left the senses behind: " Our intellect is endowed to know species through abstraction from phantasms-and therefore those species of numbers and figures which one has not imagined, one cannot know either actually or habitually, except perhaps in general and in universal principles, which is to know in potency and confusedly" (Summa Theol., I, q. 86, From the foregoing it is clear, using the original citation from Fr. Gilby derived from Summa Theologica I, q. 84, a. 6, concerning the three approaches to intellectual knowledge, as a background, that just as Professor Margenau's "passive intellect," with its exclusion of reason, represents the mechanistic sensism ascribed to Democritus, so his " factive intellect," with its autonomous contribution to knowledge not extracted from sense, tends to represent the knowledge by participation of separated intelligible forms attributed to the Platonists. The former of these two " intellects " might certainly be related to the cogitative power or particular reason as understood by St. Thomas, although whether it is Professor Margenau's intention so to relate it, is not clear. The latter of the two, however, can in no way be related to St. Thomas' understanding of the intellect per se, since where Professor Margenau makes it distinctive HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 195S 87 of the "£active intellect" ·Somehow to be independent of the senses, St. Thomas could not be more explicit that it is the natural function of the intellect to abstract the intelligible species from sensible things as agens, and to receive those intelligible species of sensible things as possibilis. As a mattei· of fact, far from being a hindrance, the body with its senses is that which enables the human intellect, weakest in the order of intellects, to attain to a precision in knowing reality which it would not have of itself. While the angelic intellect because of its perfection does not require senses, the human intellect does: Now it is manifest that among the intellectual substances, according to the order of nature, the lowest are the human souls. It is the perfection of the universe which demanded that there should be different degrees in things. If therefore human souls were so instituted by God as to understand in the manner proper to the separated substances [i.e., without sense phantasms], they would not have perfect knowledge, but confused knowledge in common [. e., they would have knowledge of equal universality but of inferior precision proportionate to an inferior intellect]. In order, therefore, that they might have perfect and proper knowledge of things, they are thus naturally instituted as to be united to bodies, so that they may thus receive from sensible things themselves the proper knowledge thereof-just as uneducated men cannot be brought to science except through sensible examples. Thus, therefore, it is evident that it is for the greater good of the soul that it should be united to a body and understand through conversion to phantasms-and yet it can be separated and have another manner of understanding. (Summa Theol., I, q. 89, a. 1.) Consequently, it is necessary to say that the type of intellect envisaged by Professor Margenau in his "£active intellect," which is, so to speak, stimulated by the senses, but basically perceptive in a way transcending the senses, is really in St. Thomas' terms a type of angelic intellect, the very type that does away with the intellectus agens and its humble function. Such being the case, that is, in a human intellect which embraces not one, but both of the extremes envisaged by St. Thomas, namely, the purely sensory, and the purely intelligible -which sees the " desk " of Eddington as not one, but two- 88 PIERRE H. CONWAY there arises indeed a problem when it is question of relating the two. This problem is posed by Professor Margenau in terms of relating intelligibile "constructs" to sensory" percepts'' in the harmonious manner terminating in the experimentally validated scientific knowledge of " verifacts." To relate the two extremes harmoniously Professor Margenau proposes what he terms " rules of correspondence," which while not described in detail are basically understood as being connecting links between extremes, between " sense and reason . . . polar extremes of activity within the cognitive process " (p. 30) . Such a situation does not exist in the thought of St. Thomas, since not having begun with the two extremes, but rather with the " middle way " (p. 8) of Aristotle, he is not faced with the problem of combining them. In effect, human knowledge properly speaking is neither purely sensory, nor purely intelligible, but rather the intelligible knowledge of sensible things. For St. Thomas the same desk of Eddington is perceived in its sensible aspects by the senses; in its intelligible aspects, subsequent to abstraction, by the intellect. By the former it is perceived as a particular, sensible, material thing; by the latter it is perceived in its universal nature, not as a nature which exists apart, but as existing solely in individual things, separated by abstraction only. Speaking of the two " desks " of Eddington, one sensible, one abstract, Professor Margenau states that one cannot be understood in terms of the other: " To say that the desks are logically identical requires an understanding of A in terms of B and such understanding is wholly lacking " (p. . This St. Thomas would deny, affirming that it is impossible to understand the abstract desk in terms of anything but the concrete desk, since all knowledge of the former must be derived from sensible knowledge of the latter. This is not a matter of a priori proclamation: What does experience yield? Nothing but the. confirmation of this. It is the statement of the possibility of being able to do without sense that requires proof and confirmation. If one affirmed the abstract " desk" as different from the concrete " desk," one would be in error; it is only HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 89 because abstraction, in affirming the nature and leaving behind the individual material characteristics, does not affirm the abstract desk to be such in reality, but only in lmowledge, that truth is maintained and the two " desks " are seen, not as two independent realities, but as two views of the same reality-one sensory and individual, one intellectual and universal. Consequently, St. Thomas would not, as Professor Margenau does, distinguish" a push or a pull from Newton's' mass times acceleration'" as representing "ostensibly different kinds of experience " requiring an additional " rule of correspondence " to unite them (pp. 28, 29, 27) . The latter would be referred to the former, not as that which is intellectual to that which is sensible but simply as ' part ' to ' whole,' where, subsequent to universal abstraction, whereby one abstracts the universal ' push or pull ' from the singular sensible instances thereof, one then proceeds by formal abstraction to consider one part of that universal, e. g., the mass, separately from the others. first of all one considers the common nature while leaving behind, or " abstracting from," the sensible singular; then one considers the universal part by part, while leaving behind, or "abstracting from," other parts. If one affirmed this universal, or this part, as separately existing independent entities, one would be affirming a figment of the mind; but if one, for clarity's sake, only considers one without the other, that is abstraction -necessary for the dim mind of man. But the object of contemplation still remains, not the abstract universal, but ultimately the real singular, now better understood through the universal. Thus the angels, with better intellects than man; do not have a lesser knowledge of sensible singulars than men, but a better one: " ... One must not say that just as sense knows only corporeal things, so intellect knows only spiritual thingsbecause it would follow that God and the angels would not know coroporeal things. . .. But the superior power does those things which belong to the inferior power in a more excellent way" (Summa Theol., I, q. 84, a. l, ad 2). "There is a difference, nevertheless, in this [i. e., in the knowledge of sensible singulars] between angels and separated souls, for the 90 PIERRE H. CONWAY angels, because of the efficacy of their intellect, are able through such species [namely, infused species from God] not only to know the natures of things specifically, but also the singulars contained under the species; while the separated souls are able to know through such species only those singulars to which they are in some way determined ... " (Ibid., q. 89, a. 4). " ... Since the nature of the soul is below the nature of the angel, to which this manner of knowing [i. e., through infused species] is natural, the separated soul does not receive through such species a perfect knowledge of things, but a knowledge as though in common and confused. Just as, therefore, the angels are related to the perfect knowledge of natural things, so the separated souls are related to an imperfect and confused knowledge. But the angels know through such species with a perfect knowledge all natural things-since .,all thjngs which God produces in their proper natures, he produces in the angelic intelligence, as Augustine says" (Ibid., q. 89, a. 3). From all of this, therefore, it is clear according to St. Thomas, that the ascendancy of the intellect, far from removing one progressively from the knowledge of sensible singulars, actually causes those singulars to be known more and more clearly in their sensible singularity-for the simple reason that the perfection of knowledge is not measured by the degree of abstraction, which necessarily must overlook certain aspects of a thing, but rather by the closer and closer approximation to singular reality, which is that which exists. Clearly one cannot relate in matters physical Professor Margenau's "factive intellect," which substitutes its own insights for those derived from sense, with the reason of St. Thomas which, in natural science, "considers, but does not make " (In Eth., I, I. 1, no. 1) the order of natural things. Nor yet would it be fair to consider Professor Margenau's "factive intellect" as entirely independent of sense, since Professor Margenau not only decries a too hasty "leap " into the unfettered ontological realm with possibly disastrous consequences (p. 36) , but likewise he does not fail to point out the experimental verifications that have confirmed much abstract and mathematical reason- HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 91 ing: " The force of relativity springs from its postulate of invariance, quantum mechanics features principles of symmetry, and all these result in instances of empirical veridicality that are amazing " (p. 39) . It would be true to say that such verifications are not simply mere accessories, since, speaking of the most successful " theory " of the moment, that of relativity, it. is a fact that it had gained little currency even among the cognoscenti until the total eclipse of 1919 when there appeared to be actual verification of the curvature of space. The ultimate test, no matter what one says, of any theory, whether practical or seemingly most speculative, still tacitly depends upon some verification in the realm of observable reality, some explanation that adds intelligibility to observable things-" the unimpeachable evidence of the senses," as Aristotle says (De Caelo, III, 306a 15) . Thus Professor Margenau's " constructs " too, would naturally require some confirmation in the world of "percepts " before anyone would give much faith to their purely " ontological " buoyancy. Professor Margenau would possibly not be so respected as a philosopher of science dealing with "constructs," if his competency were not based on a proven ability to deal with " percepts," with practical scientific problems. There is, of course, in the realm of the intellect as understood by St. Thomas, an area where the" factive "element may enter. In effect, while St. Thomas, in dividing the sciences according to order in his introduction to Aristotle's Ethics, states of the order of natural things which are the subject of natural or physical science, that theirs is an order which reason" considers but does not make," he very definitely accords a factive role to reason in the other sciences mentioned: There is the order which reason, while considering nature, " makes in its own act," producing Logic or Rational Science; " makes in the activities of the will," producing JYioral Science; " makes in external things," producing the Mechancial Arts (In Eth., I, I. 1, no. . Such are the arts and sciences of things produced by men, whether syllogisms, moral acts, or jet planes. With respect to these, human reason is both "knowing and factive." These are, in contrast to the speculative sciences of natural things, the 92 PIERRE H. CONWAY practical sciences of things done by men, which are " operative according to the imitation of nature" (In Pol., Prooem., no. 2) . Obviously there is in these an undetermined element initially, which man then determines by his own judgment " according to the imitation of nature." Examples of these would be, for example, the rules of spelling or grammar in Logic; the form of a state, whether monarchic, aristocratic or democratic in Moral Science; the style of a house, whether angular or curved, in the Mechanical Arts. Here the will, provided it does not disregard what the intellect may say of the " unmakeable " aspects of things, has an area in which it can" make" things to its own conceptions. However, none of these areas in which a legitimate " making " takes places under the impetus, not of the " £active intellect," but of the will utilizing the powers of the intellect in the production of something, appears to correspond to that area where the " £active intellect " of Professor Margenau is at work, namely the realm of the understanding of the physical world, where according to St. Thomas the intellect is precisely not " £active." However, there is an aspect of the physical sciences as conceived of by St. Thomas where one finds something which might satisfy the ·characteristics of the " £active intellect " of Professor Margenau, and it is the preliminary inventive process in science as a forerunner to scientific certitude. Thus the mind is not able to go immediately and unerringly from problem to solution but ordinarily must first cast around uncertainly for the right answer. For example, in the case of the appearance of the motion o£ the planets, it is not possible immediately to trace out courses for them to which the appearances will then correspond. From the start of astronomy every astronomer tried to "invent," in the root sense of "discover" (from the Latin word invenire, ' to find ') some design or figure of the motion which would satisfy the appearances. This " inquiry " or search (from the Latin word inquirere, 'to look for') continued until the 16th century when Copernicus produced the design which has since continued to be accepted. In the fruitful process of leading up to his system there were certainly, throughout HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 93 the centuries, many previous " makings " and discardings of designs. This "inventive "-and one might well say "£active"process is very much a part of the physical science of Aristotle and St. Thomas, an almost indispensable prelude to any eventual certitude. Thus St. Thomas describes the twofold process whereby the mind proceeds first to a tentative conclusion in the order of inquiry, and then subsequently puts that conclusion to the test by seeing if it is in accord with what is known, and if it is the only possible conclusion able to be derived therefromsince as long as there may be other explanations equally capable of explaining the same appearances, one has not arrived at certitude that the explanation in question must be the true one: " ... Human reasoning proceeds along the way of inquiry, or invention, from certain things absolutely understood, and then again along the way of judgment returns in the process of resolution to :first principles, in the light of which it examines what has been found" (Summa Theol., I, q. 79, a. 8. Cf. also Q. D. DeVer., q. 15, a. 1, c). This twofold process of" invention" and " resolution " is further expounded when St. Thomas speaks of one of the ways in which " rational " is said of the procedure of natural science, namely, in the sense of proceeding by probable-or hypothetical-reasons: Another way in which this procedure is called ' rational,' is derived from the term at which one stops in the proceeding. For the ultimate term to which the inquiry of reason should lead is the understanding of principles, by the resolving of things into which, we judge. When, indeed, this is done, the process or proof is not called natural [or 'rational'?), but a demonstration. Sometimes, however, the inquiry of reason does not reach the final term, but comes to a stop in the inquiry itself-when, namely, there remains still to the one inquiring a way open to either of two contradictories. And this occurs when one proceeds by probable reasons, which are fitted to produce opinion and belief, but not, however, science. In this sense, then, the ' rational ' process is distinguished against the ' demonstrative.' And one can proceed ' reasonably ' in this way in any science, so as to prepare the way, through probable reasons, for necessary conclusions." (In De Trin .. I. 2, q. 2, a. 1, c.) 94 PIERRE H. CONWAY This " :rational " process, therefore, whereby one proceeds in the way of " inquiry " or "' invention " by casting around for possible explanations, which later will be put to the test by seeing whether the explanation may be seen to proceed from previously accepted principles, seems very much like Professor Margenau's" factive intellect," which, to some extent independently of sense data-as would be the case, for instance, if the intellect could not see in the sense data any necessary reference to some given cause-searches and inquires for explanations or " constructs," which, say what one will, will have currency and acceptance almost wholly on their ability to explain what appears, whether directly or indirectly, to the senses. A classic passage on the " inventive or inquiring reason," to which one has likened Professor Margenau's "factive intellect," at work is that in which St. Thomas speaks of the various theories propounded to explain the apparent motions of the planets: One must take into consideration that certain anomalies, i.e., irregularities, appear in the motions of the planets-namely, to the extent that the planets seem to be sometimes faster, sometimes slower; sometimes stationary; sometimes in retrogression. Now this indeed does not seem to befit heavenly motions .... And therefore :first Plato proposed this difficulty to Eudoxu8., an astronomer of his time, who then endeavored to reduce the irregularities of this sort to a right order, by assigning diverse motions to the planetswhich likewise the subsequent astronomers have tried to do in various ways. Nevertheless it is not necessary for the suppositions which they found (' invented ') to be true--for although, on the basis of such suppositions, the appearances are saved, one cannot, nevertheless, for that .reason state these suppositions to be true, since perchance the appearances with regard to the stars may be saved in some other way, not yet comprehended by men. (ln De Caelo, II, 1, 17, no. 451.) The relationship of "inventive reason " to " judicative reason " is set forth by St. Thomas in his Prologue to the Exposition of the Posterior Analytics, where, in the course of dividing up the Organon of Aristotle, he also divides reasoning. HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 195& 95 Arriving at the third act of the mind, which is reasoning strictly speaking, he proceeds to divide it into three processes which he likens to three processes in nature previously described. In the first, one arrives through necessary reasons at the certitude of science; in the second, through probable reasons at belief or opinion; in the third, through defect, at fallacy. He says therefore of the first two: That part of Logic which serves the first process is called Judicative, since judgment [in the resolutory process] is with the certitude of science. And since certain judgment of effects cannot be had except by resolution to first principles, therefore this part is called the Analytics, i.e., 'resolutory.' ... The second process of reason is served by another part of Logic, which is called Inventive. Now finding is not always with certitude. Hence, concerning those things which are found [' invented '], judgment [by resolution] is required in order for there to be certitude. Just as in natural things, in those things which occur for the most part, there is a certain degree to be considered-since the stronger the power of nature, the more rarely does it fail in its effect-so also in that process of reason which is not with complete certitude, there is found a certain difference of degree, accordingly as one approaches more or less to perfect certitude. By means of this process, occasionally, even if one does not obtain science, one nevertheless obtains belief or opinion because of the probability of the propositions from which one proceeds. . . . (In Anal. Post., Prol., no. 6.) In Professor Margenau's terms, in the case of calculations by the " £active intellect " involving cases where " no finite set of observations enables theory to predict the place where an electron will strike the screen " (p. 17) , where " the motion of the smallest particles was found to be subject to the laws of large numbers, any individual instance showing evidence of intractible caprice" (ibid.), where "the electron ... should be described in abstract mathematical terms which suppress, in general, the reference to a specifiable position " (p. 25) , in such cases, then, it does not seem to be stretching a point to say that such calculations, those, for instance, of the motions of the tiny electron, in all their tentative uncertainty and vagueness, fall 96 PIERRE II" CONWAY very nicely into the same area where St. Thomas locates the equally tentative calculations of the courses of the much larger planets, namely, in the realm of " inventive reason!' This is the reason which frames hypotheses, the reason which casts around for some kind of an intermediate figure or construction such as that which links i:he squares on the sides with the .square on the hypotenuse in the Pythagorean Theorem. But how are these tentative solutions or conclusions, at the moment at best only the probabilities of dialectics, turned into the certitude of science? For Aristotle and St. Thomas they must be resolved back to first principles. What does this mean? It means that one must show that the answer one has arrived at must be the only possible there is no longer a path " to either of two contradictories,'' that the solution is necessary, i.e., cannot be otherwise" How is this done? This is done by showing that the conclusion, first happily discovered by the " inventive " process of trying various possibilities and hypotheses, is now seen to be the one which necessarily follows as the only possibility from certain, self-evident principles. " ... The whole certitude of science arises from the certitude of the principles: for the conclusions are then known with certitude when they are resolved into the principles " (Q" D" De V erit", q. 11, a. 1, ad 13)" Such principles are known through themselves: " These immediate principles are not known through any extrinsic middle, but through the knowledge of their own terms " (In Post" Anal", I, l. 7, no. 8) " The terms, in turn, are known through the senses: ", " " From sensible things there is had memory, and from memory experience,.and from experience the knowledge of those terms which, once known, there is known those common propositions which are the principles of the arts and sciences " (In 11leta", IV, L 6, no" 599)" «From the very nature of the intellectual soul it befits man that immediately upon knowing what • whole ' is and what 'part' is, he should know: 'Every whole is greater than its part '-and likewise with other [first principles]" But what ' whole ' is and what ' part ' is, he is not able to know except through intelligible species :received from phantasms" (Summa Theolo, I-II, q" 51, a. 1). Thus two HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 97 things are involved in the Thomistic concept of science: 1) That the principles from which the conclusions derive be the ones from which they do so with necessity of consequence, as the conclusion in the case of the Pythagorean Theorem necessarily follows from what has been previously established with regard to the congruence of triangles; 2) That the principles themselves be necessarily true, i.e., be derived from sense knowledge and having a necessary relationship between subject and predicate-as the concepts of ' whole ' and ' part' are universals derived from material things, and the very nature of 'whole ' is to be greater than ' part.' It is at this point, the point of resolution, that St. Thomas loses Professor Margenau. For Professor Margenau does not hold as irrefragable either that all propositions must be ultimately traceable for their data to the senses; or that the most basic principle, namely, the principle of contradiction even only on the purely logical plane, cannot be contradicated: "The discovery of non-Euclidean geometries and their use in physical explanation, the discovery of many different systems of logic including those which affirm a tertium datur [as against the 'excluded middle or third ' implied in the principle of contradiction], together with many of the abstract pursuits just mentioned, have deprived us of confidence in a priori proofs. The conclusion seems inescapable that no proposition, formal or otherwise, carries within itself complete assurance of its truth " (p. 40 Parenthesis mine). Professor Margenau has already affirmed the possibility of the " £active intellect " introducing " autonomous " elements of " novelty " not derived from sensedata, in which he has radically separated himself from St. Thomas, and now, furthermore, he calls into doubt even the purely logical irrefragability of first principles such as the principle of contradiction, making the separation, if possible, even more complete. At this point it would seem permissible to assess Professor Margenau's presentation of St. Thomas and state that it cannot be called representative. Professor Margenau's interpretation represents an entirely different outlook. An outlook such as 98 PIERRE H. CONWAY that in the first place natural intellectual knowledge need not stem from the senses, and in the second place that the knowledge itself need not conform to first principles as classically understood, is completely incompatible with St. Thomas, whether as fact or only possibility. The "£active" and "passive " intellects which Professor Margenau presents as suggested by St. Thomas in no wise represent the intellectus agens and possibilis of St. Thomas. They do not do so most basically because the " factive " and " passive " intellect thus presented do not represent two stages-the abstractive and receptive-of a single intellectual knowledge, but rather two different knowledges, deriving from two different potencies, namely, reason in one case and sense in the other. Even should one assimilate Professor Margenau's "passive" intellect, not to the intellectus possibilis, but to the intellectus passivus of St. Thomas, " which is the particular reason, L e., the cogitative power along with the memorative and the imaginative" (Summa Theol., I-II, q. 51, a. 3) , and the " factive " intellect with the " inventive " process St. Thomas, there still remains gulf between of reason the two outlooks. The gulf consists in the fact that for Professor Margenau the whole natural content of the " factive " intellect, no matter how understood, does not depend upon the data received from the " passive " intellect, whereas for St. Thomas all intellectual processes originate from the senses, which in turn originate from external reality. This has as a consequence that intellectual knowledge is fundamentally a knowledge of external things, objective reality, and as a corollary that any denial of first principles is not simply a piece of logical audacity, but the denial of reality itself. At this point, too, it seems permissible to speculate as to that which appears to underlie the viewpoint exposed by Professor Margenau. One point that is forcibly presented therein is the dichotomy between knowledge derived from the senses and the breadth of intellectual knowledge, resulting in what St. Thomas would consider a Platonic attitude. This would appear to be the outlook engendered by the initial Cartesian doubts as to the reliability of the senses, and the subsequent Kantian affirmation HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 99 as to the total incapacity of the senses to represent the true nature of things. Thus, to scientists like Einstein, in the Evolution of Physics, the true meaning of reality would seem to be something impenetrable, lying beneath the unrevealing surface of the senses, and the mind would be engaged simply in building models or " constructs " to harmonize with the appearances while remaining in the dark as to their objectivity -to use the image of Einstein, we are like people looking at the face of a clock and speculating as to what sort of internal machinery makes it run, without ever being able to find out. This sort of outlook, which not only leaves a free hand to the intellect, but actually obliges it to act on its own, independently, seems substantially that implied in the " £active intellect" of Professor Margenau. But possibly even more is implied in the " factive intellect," the intellect which because of the inadequacy of the senses is necessarily " on its owno" In effect, if the senses do not reveal the nature of things, and if one has no other direct contact with the outside world, on what rational grounds may one presume there is an intelligence behind the surface of things? there are none-and granted the supposition that the senses do not necessarily represent the nature of things, there are none-then one finds oneself in a world where the only known intelligence is the human intelligence, where the first order introduced into the ostensibly unordered universe is that devised by the human intellect. Such an outlook is not optional, but unavoidable if one considers the universe solely as material and as the selfsubsistent, self-explaining reality, devoid of intellect, but out of which, in the course of random evolution, the human intellect has now evolved at this particular stage of events. From such a point of view, the universe is basically unknowable, unordered, and all the order there is, is the order created artificially by the human intellect and superimposed upon or attributed to the basically amorphous and unintelligent cosmos. From such a point of view, if things are unpredictable beyond a very short range, it is not due to there being in an ordered universe some things which a:re intrinsically contingent and vacillating, nor to 100 PIERRE H. CONWAY any weakness on the part of the intellect, but simply to the fact that there is basically no order in the universe, no determined sequence of things, to start with. If things happen as predicted it is merely the result of a happy sequence in things which has come about by chance for no particular reason, has no particular significance, nor any sure duration. Although Professor Margenau does not deny nor affirm that there may be a causative Intelligence responsible both for us and the surrounding cosmos, nevertheless the picture he traces in his final section of the outlook of modern science vis-a-vis St. Thomas, seems compatible with such an outlook, the outlook that the incertitude of knowledge and predictability is due primarily, not to weakness of intellect, but to the basic indeterminacy of an unintelligent universe itself. Professor Margenau begins with a survey of the contemporary outlook, objecting to the pedestrian view of science and science courses as no more than a " catalogue of dead but certified facts" (p. 45); scientific laws as "inductive generalizations of observational experience, never as bold conjectures, as ideas defying the knowledge of their day ... " (ibid.). To such a view, research is "like the solving of a picture puzzle " (p. 48), and the universe itself simply a somewhat larger puzzle, which in the optimists' view some day" will be solved and the happy millenium will begin" (ibid.). This is, of course, the deterministic, 19th-century view of science, to which Professor Margenau now opposes a concept of science as " progressive, . . . a scientific problem is never completely solved, ... research continually reforms and alters the picture which was thought at an earlier time to be already finished" (ibid,). Now the good teacher will strive to turn this into a " quest for meaning " (p. 46) , meaning which goes beneath the surface of the facts, illuminating them; he will," in a spirit of adventure, suggest Joule's a:p.d 1_\,fayer'sexciting conjecture as a captivating idea and then verify it instance by instance " (p. 49) . How does science grow under such an impetus? Professor Margenau devotes six pages, to describing the process according HENRY MARGENAU; THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 101 to the analogy of a crystal, starting from the liquid state: " Every element of liquid moves in random fashion, and if the pattern of motion is made visible it is observed to have the existential beauty of irregularity and caprice " (p. 50) . Predictions do not attain detail; the order is "short-range order, a correlation function falling to zero beyond the second or third neighbor to a given molecule" (ibid.). When to the "amorphous liquid mass," " small crystalline fragments known as seeds" are added, crystallization, with its pattern'' clear, orderly and predictable" may be stimulated (p. 51). Says Professor 1\fargenau in explanation: " I think of human experience as the amorphous liquid mass, of science as a crystalline growth which imparts order to the shapeless mass" (ibid.). To the unordered liquid state which is human experience, and where predictability extends only a few short steps, belong the " domains vaguely formalized as ethics, politics, history and religion . . . a large part of sociology, economics, anthropology and pyschology; it is present in the so-called biological sciences and, in a certain measure, in the physical sciences as well " (pp. 52-3) . Where " short-range order "prevails, that is, in the experiential domain as yet unregularized by science, the " philosophy adequate to the character of primary experience is existentialism" (p. 53), presumably in its role of branding any appeal to fictitious universal law a cowardice, and sternly admonishing each to be a law unto himself. Btit to the extent that the crystallizing, regularizing effect of science extends, even though in unpredictable directions, in the amorphous experiential mass, what has one the right to expect? " There is no end to the process of growth. The shapeless matrix of our experience is unlimited, and the crystal will never span it all" (p. 54). The puzzle will never be completely solved; there will always remain uncrystallized areas as yet impervious to science: " What I foresee is an infinite crystal growth into an amorphous domain whose volume is likewise infinite yet vastly greater" (ibid.). Beyond the regularized world of the "rationalist " will always lie the unregularized world of the "existentialist": no matter how far the former 102 PIERRE H. CONWAY advances, the latter still stretches out beyond him; the knowing is always encompassed by the unknowing. Sometimes the wrongly crystallized even recedes back to the liquid state again: " wrong " knowing returns to unknowing again. How does St. Thomas fit into all this? How is he seen through this vista? Professor Margenau in conclusion perceives him " almost in an attitude of benediction " upon the concept of an infinitely growing rationalization of things, always encompassed and contained, one might say, by an even more infinite area which escapes rationalization. Why should St. Thomas bless this concept? It is felt that he would because he, too, was a great crystallizer, but at the same time, in dynamic fashion, saw the trajectory of truth as always transcending the limits of the present-in distinction to those who wish to " admire nothing but the fixed structure of his system . . . invest him with an aura of final and eternal truth " (p . .56) . Professor terminates his Aquinas Lecture with an excerpt paraphrased from Summa Theol., I, q. 14, a. 8, ad 3: "Natural things lie midway between God's knowledge and ours. Human science derives from them, and they derive from God's own vision." These words indicate, says Professor Margenau, that the saint himself ascribed final and eternal truth to God, " holding that man must search for it in indirect and derivative fashion " (p . .56) . Little exception could be taken to these words. According to St. Thomas, this might be called the " way of discovery," or via inventionis, at its best: " For according to the path of discovery [or ' invention '], we arrive through temporal things at the knowledge of eternal things, according to the word of the Apostle, The invisible things of God are clearly seen, being understood by the things that are nwde " (Summa Theol., I, q. 79, a. 9). However,' St. Thomas does not stop there, but rather affirms that once one has arrived at a knowledge of eternal things through temporal things, one can then in the " way of judgment," use that knowledge of eternal things to judge temporal things with certitude: " Now in the path of judgment, from eternal things once known we judge of temporal HENRY MARGENAU; THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 108 things, and dispose temporal things according to the notions of eternal things" (ibid.). This reflexive certitude is noted again elsewhere: " ... Sensible effects, from which natural [science] demonstrations proceed, are more known to us in the beginning. But when we shall have arrived by means of them at the knowledge of first causes, from the latter there will appear to us the ' reason for which ' [propter quid] of those effects from which the demonstrations 'that it is so' [quia] are proved" (In De Trin., 1. 2, q. 1, a. 1, ad 9) . In other words, having first proceeded from effect to cause in a quia demonstration, the intellect through its knowledge of first causes, is now able to perceive something of the proper reason of the original effects, to know the propter quid. However, this does not mean that certitude is not had until one has arrived at a grasp of divine science or metaphysics, for it is already possible in the science of temporal things, in natural science and mathematics: " ... Necessary (and therefore certain) knowable things are also found in temporal things, concerning which are natural science and mathematics" (Summa Theol., Zoe. cit., ad 8. Cf. also Q. D. De Ver., q. 15, a. 2, ad 8). However, the certitude which can be had of natural things in natural science or physics, and which applies to the cases where the natures of things have been perceived, and necessary relationships-as in the proposition, " All sensible change requires three principles: subject, form and privation "-need not extend to all of those things, and especially to contingent things which are intrinsically uncertain as singulars. When it comes to such, one is in the " way of invention or discovery " again, having only probability about the outcome of singular contingent effects: " Now there are certain things in which it is not possible to have a resolution such that one arrive at the nature [quod quid est], and this because of the uncertainty of their being, as is the case with contingent things as contingent. Whence such things are not known through their essence [quod quid est], which is the proper object of the intellect, but in another way, namely, through a certain conjecture about those things concerning which full certitude· cannot be had " (Q. D. 104 PIERRE H. CONWAY De Ve·r., q. 15, a. 9l, ad 3). But if one cannot have certitude about contingent things as contingent, that is, for example, when a contingent singular cause is in the process of producing a singular contingent effect, one can have certitude not only about necessary things, but also about contingent things in the universal order: " ... Contingent things may be known in two ways. One way is according to universal notions; the other way, as they are in particular. For the universal notions of contingent things (as for example the concept of sensible change) are immutable, and according to this aspect demonstrations are found and the knowledge of them belongs to the demonstrative sciences. For natural science is not only of necessary and incorruptible things, but also of corruptible and contingent things " (In Eth. Arist., VI, I. 1, no. 1123) . To return to Professor Margenau's original representation of the status of human knowledge vis-a-vis the surrounding world in terms of the analogy of a spreading crystal in an amorphous liquid, it is clear that this analogy lends to the idea of a world which is not just unknown and unordered to us, but unknown and unordered in itself: reason is not in it, we impart reason to it-" science ... imparts order to the shapeless mass." In effect, Professor J\fargenau has referred-and just how figuratively is not certain-to his subject-matter as having " the existential beauty of irregularity and caprice." The idea of the source of intelligibility that seems to fit best in this picture is that of the human reason as a little island in the midst of the irrational, gradually extending its rays into the hitherto shapeless mass. It is true that Professor Margenau terminates his lecture with reference to God as the source of the natures of things, but it is not quite clear! whether he is affirming an over-all divine order, or simply underscoring what he considers to be St. Thomas' denial of there being any final truth in things. Needless to say, St. Thomas holds that there can very definitely be final truth in things perceived, and not only in the necessary things, but even in the contingent things. Thus the truth once attained need never be modified: " ... The intelligible species which are in the possible intellect cannot be HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 105 corrupted by anything contrary, since nothing is contrary to the consideration of intelligible things. . .. The habit of science in so far as it is in the intellect remains in the separated soul. ... Nothing prevents someone who is less good from having some habit of science in the future life which someone who is better does not have" (Summa Theol., I, q. 89, a. 5. and ad 2). Plainly, then, for St. Thomas, things can not only be known definitively in this life, but once known they are known for good. . St. Thomas, therefore, has an entirely different picture, not only of the human intellect, but also of the world around him, than does Professor Margenau. Nor is this an accident. In effect, the idea of an amorphous world of the senses to which the human intellect imparts order, to which some of Professor Margenau's images lend themselves, naturally implies two different levels of thought-a sense level devoid of intelligibility, an intellectual level which adds reason to the basically irrational. On the other hand, the idea of a world of the senses which represents an order already there, instituted by the divine mind producing things according to a pre-conceived order, naturally implies a single unity of knowledge-sense knowledge which contains within itself in a potential state (actualized by the agent intellect) the outlines of an intelligible order received, upon abstraction, into the possible intellect. Since the order is already in the universe, the unintelligibility, as states Aristotle, derives more from us than from the universe: " Perhaps, too, as difficulties are of two kinds [i. e., subjective and objective], the cause of the present difficulty [in investigating the truth of things] is not in the facts, but in us. For as the eyes of bats are to the blaze of day, so is the reason in our soul to the things which are by nature most evident of all " (Metaphysics, II, 993b 5, referred to by St. Thomas in, for example, loc. cit., l. 1, no. 284; S. 11., I, q. 1, a. 5, ad 1; Contra Gentes I, c. 3; II, c. 77; III, c. 25; In De Trin., I. 2, q. 1, a. 4, c.; De Spir. Creat., a. 10, ad 7; In L. De Causis, Proem., n. 4.) But what kind of order is there in the universe? If it is not 106 PIERRE H. CONWAY a random, unintelligent affair, but the product of a divine mind, then must not everything happen with a rigid, undeviating determinism? So the determinists thought, when they first unearthed unsuspected order and predictability in the universe. Such was the determinism of Laplace, although in a God-excluded world. But it was not the determinisim of St. Thomas, which allowed for both necessary and contingent events, for certainty and uncertainty. Consequently when the world of Laplace toppled with the appearance of relativity, quantum mechanics, the uncertainty principle, the non-rigid world of St. Thomas did not topple. Ironically, however, the extremist deterministic view which was to supersede the more easy-going world of St. Thomas, has now, on the recognition that some things, which it said were determined, were actually undetermined, led to a precipitation toward the opposite extremist view, that nothing is determined, that everything is random. But the system of St. Thomas, having had before, and having still, adequate accounting for chance and indeterminism, had no need for such drastic house-cleaning-which now, alas, has to find a way to consider even what appear to be maddeningly regular and determined events as somehow irregular and undetermined. And what is the world-view, the Weltanschauung, of St. Thomas that allows for the harmonious coexistence of both the determined and the undetermined, the predictable and the unpredictable, the certain and the probable? It is succinctly expressed in the view of nature to which St. Thomas aptly compares the matching processes of reason in his Prologue to the Exposition of the Posterior Analytica: In the acts of nature there is found a threefold diversity. For in certain of them, nature acts with necessity, in such a way that it cannot fail. In certain other acts nature operates for the most part, although it can at times fail in its proper act. Whence, in such circumstances there must be a twofold act: one which is for the most part, as when from seed there is generated a perfect animal; the other when nature fails in that which is according to it, as when from seed there is generated something monstrous because of the corruption of some principle. HENRY MARGENAU; THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 107 And these three are also found in the acts of reason. For there is a certain process of reason which induces necessity, in which it is impossible for there to be a defect of truth; and through such a process the certitude of science is acquired. There is another process of reason in which, as in the greater part, truth is arrived at, not, however, having necessity. The third process of reason is that in which reason deviates from the truth because of a defect in some principle which should have been observed in reasoning. (In Post. Anal., Prol., no. 5.) Clearly, \vith such a concept of the universe as this, and with types of reasoning to parallel it, allowing both for certain and rigidly predictable events, and uncertain and at best only probably predictable events-and, as the exceptions which destroy the unanimity of the latter, the absolutely unpredictable accidents-one is able to assimilate and integrate all the varied events which cross the threshold of human consciousness. Such is the world of St. Thomas, a world where the necessary and the unpredictable live side by side, and in which, ii one is attentive, one need not be thrown into a panic by failing to distinguish one from the other. But does not such a world, with its frank admission of random and chance alongside the determined and the necessary, introduce an element incompatible with the tenets of divine omniscience? For divine omnipotence does not require of those who acknowledge it the denial of their senses or reason-and reason reveals the presence of chance or hazard. In effect, to deny it, to deny the possibility of something occurring which has no predictable per se cause, is to place oneself in the impossible situation resulting from the deterministic position that every effect must follow from some definite given cause, such that, the adequate cause having been posited, the effect must necessarily follow: the history of every event is a sequence of per se causes. This is described by Aristotle as follows: " Will A exist or not? It will if B happens; and if not, not. And B will exist if C happens. And thus if time is constantly subtracted from a limited extent of time, one will obviously come to the present. This man, then, will die by violence, if he goes out; and he will do this if he gets thirsty; and he will get thirsty if something 108 PmRRE H. CONWAY else happens; and thus we shall come to that which is now present, or to some past event. For instance, he will go out if he gets thirsty; and he will get thirsty if he is eating pungent food; and this is either the case or not; so that he will of necessity die, or of necessity not die " (Meta., VI, . In other words, if an ultimate event may be traceable to the causes which immediately preceded it, as necessary causes, conversely the one who posits the first cause is, by this per se chain. the cause of the ultimate event: the one who puts the condiment in the food which makes one thirsty, is the cause of the death of the man who meets his end when he walks out of the door to get a drink and runs into robbers. It is necessary, therefore, if one is not to involve oneself in the unrealistic system entailed by determinism-the very determinism of Laplace who theorized that if one knew the exact position of every particle and every force in the universe at a given moment, one could predict with absolute certainty the state of things at the succeeding moment-that one recognize alongside the necessary, the contingent: alongside that which cannot not be, that· which is able not to be-for example, a cause which, though acting may not produce its effect. As St. Thomas concludes from .the situation expounded by Aristotle, "Now this is impossible, namely, that all future events come about with necessity. Therefore those two suppositions are impossible from which this situation follows: namely, that every effect whatsoever have a per se cause; and that once the cause is posited, it be necessary that the effect be posited. For from this would follow what has already been stated, that of any future effects certain causes would have already been posited (since future events would not only be reduced to the present, as in the example given; but likewise, present events would be reducible to causes in the past: thus the future has already been caused in the past with iron-bound necessity" (In Meta., VI, l. 3, no. Therefore the overthrow of determinism by the introduction of uncertainty is a triumph possible only for a line of thought previously wedded to determinism, a triumph denied HENRY MARGENAU: THOMAS AND THE PHYSICS OF 1958 109 Aristotle and St. Thomas since they had already definitively excluded determinism from the start. But having excluded determinism from the start, how then do Aristotle and St. Thomas arrive at a predictable ordered universe? They do this in a progressively ascending process. In effect, they first point out that events which may be chance and unrelated on a lower level, may be intended on a higher level: thus, the simultaneous blooming of two flowers in a flower-bed is accidental and unpredictable so far as the relation of the two flowers to each other is concerned-there is nothing in one flower that allows one to pre