THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: VoL. XXVIII The Tho mist Press, Washington 17, D. C .. JANUARY, 1964 No.1 PAUL TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM I N RECENT years the Christian community has been blessed with an increasingly urgent sense of the unity of Christ's church. This has created a special interest in Protestant theology and led to an ever increasing number of irenically oriented studies. Such work has contributed much by pointing to the authentically Christian content of Protestant theologies, from the discussion of which one might hope for an improved unity of belief. There remained, nevertheless, an important reservation to a fully sympathetic and fruitful dialogue, for it was observed that true ecumenism can be expected as a result of discussions, such as those on justification, only when the meaning attached to such terms as God, creature, sin, and new being, has been, if not agreed upon, at least understood. 1 Most fundamentally, 1 Juan Alfaro, S. J., "Justificacion Barthiana y Justificacion Catolica," Gregorianum, XXXIX (1958), pp. 757-69; Henri de Lubac, S. J., " Zum katholischen Dialog mit Karl Barth," Dokumente, XIV (1958), pp. 448-54. 1 GEORGE F. MCLEAN this demanded an appreciation of the philosophical position which stood as their presuppositions or predeterminants; and there, lay a new level of divergence. Among Protestant thinkers these positions were generally those of recent philosophies reflective of man's contemporary dilemma, whereas among Catholic thinkers they were of a more traditional philosophy reflective of the rich insights of classical philosophy. With the opening of Vatican II, however, this difference more than ever before has been shown to be one of complementarity rather than competition. "The Council," said Pope Paul VI, " will build a bridge toward the contemporary world. . . . The Church looks at the world ... with the sincere intention ... not of condemning it but of strengthening and saving it." In this project the Protestant philosophical insight into man's contemporary religious dilemma becomes an indispensable element in any solution, and does so in a way which opens a dimension of ecumenism sufficiently profound to contribute to all others. For this reason the study of the basic religious philosophy of America's foremost Protestant theologian, Dr. Paul Tillich, takes on a special importance. His thought is contemporary, reflecting the modern dichotomy of subject and object in the manner of the existentialist movement. It is ·also Protestant, stressing the corruption of man and his distance from the Creator. The investigation of these facets of Tillich's philosophy will proceed by three stages. First, it will consider his evaluation of the nature and extent of the elements of individuation and participation in relation to previous forms of Christianity. Then it will analyse his conciliation of these two aspects in a philosophy which is religious, Protestant, and contemporary. Finally it will evaluate his contributions both in themselves and in relation to Catholicism. It can be hoped that the study of this recent adaptation of Protestantism to the contemporary scene will shed light on two matters of great interest and urgency. One is the nature of the religious problem expressed in present day thought. The TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 3 other is the nature of the religious system which can answer these demands. Both contributions should be of assistance to all in understanding that faith which was given for all days even unto the consummation of the world. I. NORMS FOR RELIGIOUS PHILOSOPHIES Paul Tillich is much concerned with the relation between subject and object. His concern extends from its contemporary modality to its fundamental nature. There has been a general consensus of opinion that the great tragedy of recent times has been the subjection of man to the objects he produces. Man is seen to be reduced to the state of an impersonal object. 2 We will be able to follow the analysis of this contemporary situation more completely below. For now, it is sufficient to note that it is a pressing manifestation of the fundamental polar relation of self and world, subject and object. Tillich considers this to be the basic ontological structure because it is the presupposition of ontological investigation, without itself being able to be deduced from any prior unity. Idealism has been no more successful in deriving the object from the subject than earlier naturalisms have been in reducing the subject to the state of a physical object. The polarity of the self-world or subjectobject structure is then something which "cannot be derived. It must be accepted." 3 The polar relation of these elements assumes delicate nuances according to the nature of the reality under consideration. This provides a very sensitive norm for evaluating any system of thought. The strength and weaknesses of a philosophy will appear clearly from the degree of its success in conciliating the • Paul Tillich, Theology of Culture (New York: Oxford University Press, 1959), pp. 91-94. • Systematic Theology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), I p. 174. Cf. "Participation and Knowledge, Problems of an Ontology of Cognition," Sociologica, Vol. I of Frankfurther Beitriige zur Soziologie, ed. Theodor W. Adorno and Walter Dirks (Stuttgart: Europiiische Verlagsanstalt, 1955), p. 201. "Being, insofar as it is an object of asking presupposes the subject-{)bject structure of reality." 4 GEORGE F. MCLEAN twin poles of subj.ect and object in its own area. Tillich applies this norm in the form of the polar notions of individualization and participation to various types of religious thought. 4 A study of his evaluation will provide an insight into his requirements for an authentic religion and reveal what elements of Protestant and Catholic thought he would retain in his own contemporary religious philosophy. While neither of the polar notions can be fully realized without the other, individualization will be analysed first. This element is implied in the constitution of every being as a self and points to the fact that it is particular and indivisible. As particular, the self maintains an identity separate from all else and opposite anything which might be related to it. As indivisible it maintains its identity by retaining the integrity of its own self center much as a mathematical point resists partition.5 One can hear the traditional definition of the individual in these notions. He does fail to extend this to the temporal order making self-affirmation something unique, unrepeatable, and irreplaceable. The infinite value of every human soul is a consequence of its" ontological self-affirmation as an indivisible, unexchangeable self." 6 While this individuality is an indispensable element in reality, it is a grave error to consider it without the polar element of participation. An exclusive insistence on the particular and unrepeatable brings with it the nominalistic breakdown in the philosophy of essence.7 This breakdown, in turn, becomes the source of a number of philosophical positions which have had great influence on religious ideas. One of the more important of the nominalistic consequences is the position that "only the individual has ontological reality; universals are verbal signs which point to similarities between individual things." 8 An• This is developed at length in The Courage to Be, Terry Lectures (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1952). • Syste'TTULtic Theology, I, pp. 170 & 174-75. Cf. "Participation and Knowledge," loc. cit., p. 201. • The Courage to Be, p. 87. 8 Systematic Theology, I, pp. 73, 97 & 177. 7 Ibid., p. 129. TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 5 other is the attribution of an element of indeterminacy to the divine and of radical contingency to finite beings. The epistemological expression of this nominalistic ontology is referred to by Max Scheler as controlling knowledge. In this the object is transformed into a completely conditioned and calculable " thing" to be studied with detached analysis by the methods of empiricism and positivism. In the ethical sphere it follows that the determination of ends is outside the competency of this knowledge, which restricts itself to the consideration of means and receives the ends from non rational sources such as positive tradition or arbitrary decision. These are the nominalistic results of a development of individuation without its polar element of participation. Concerning the relationship of medieval nominalism to Protestantism Tillich is particularly circumspect. He has written some of the strongest contemporary passages on the inevitability of the ontological question for the theologian. Nevertheless, he proceeds to detach the Reformers from their philosophical background and to make their religious experience the sole determinant of their system. 9 In this he manifests a decidedly different understanding of the Protestant phenomenon than Louis Bouyer who has recently written that " the Reformers no more invented this strange and despairing universe than they found it in Scripture. It is simply the universe of the philosophy they had been brought up in, scholasticism in its decadence." 1 ° Certainly, Luther's famous "Sum enim Occamicae factionis " must be given progressively less weight as he gradually dissociated himself from many of their positions. However, through such men as Biel, Trutfetter, and Paltz, he had been well introduced to the contemporary Occamist school, and it is not surprising to find him retaining much of its basic philosophical orientation. 11 Ibid., p. 21. Cf. Theology of Culture, p. 19. Louis Bouyer, The Spirit and Fcmns of Protestantism, trans. A. V. Littledale (Westminster: Newman Press, 1956), p. 158. This would be in general agreement with the work of H. Denifle, 0. P. and the research of Catholic scholars since. 11 Cf. note ISO infra., p. 46. 9 10 6 GEORGE F. MCLEAN If Tillich is slow to point to this fundamental connection of Luther with nominalism, he does not fail to appreciate the particular stress laid on individualization by the Reformer and especially by the theologians who followed him. But for Luther an immediate implication of this stress, and one so important that it alone would suffice to guarantee the purity of Christianity, was the rejection of an analogous, internal reality by which man supernaturally participates in the divine. In its place he substituted the mere imputation of the divine. This was something which Ockham had considered possible but insufficient to fulfill the requirements of faith. 12 A related expression of this accent on individualization is the development of the notion of personal guilt in the Protestant concept of the Fall into that of the total depravity of man's nature. This implies that· the power of communion with God has been not only weakened but lost. The result is that "man is separated from God, and he has no freedom of return." 13 It is true that these elements of individualization and guilt call for the notion of forgiveness as an element of participation. However, historical Protestantism has never managed to integrate these two elements. This integration was impeded for a century and a half by the way in which Calvinism and sectarianism stressed " the unconditional character of the divine judgment and the free character of God's forgiveness." 14 For this led to a separation between man and religious truth similar to that between an abstract subject and object. When at last there was a return to emphasis on personal guilt and perfection it only proved to be a step toward rationalism and romanticism in which the person was attributed such independent dignity 12 Martin Luther, Vorlesung uber den Riimerbrief, 1515-16, die Scholien, ed. J. Ficker (Leipzig: Dieterich, 192.5), p. 221. " Bonitas Dei facit nos bonos et opera nostra bona; quia non essent in se bona, nisi quia Deus reputat ea bona. . . . Perversa itaque est definitio virtutis apud Aristotelem, quod ipsa nos perficit et opus eius laudabile reddit." For a variant interpretation of this point and suggestions for further research see Paul Vignaux, " Sur Luther et Ockham," Franziskanische Studien, XXXIT (1950), pp. 20-SO. '"Systematic Theology, I, p. 2.58. " ThiJ Courage to Be, p. 182. Cf. ibid., pp. 114-18. TILLICH's EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 7 that the content of his reason or of his person lost all notion of participation in the divine. Thus it has gone with the various Protestant conceptions of man. An historical background of nominalism gave it an excessive individuation from which it has never managed to free itself. The insufficiency of this thought is realized by Tillich. He considers pure nominalism to be untenable because its radical individualism renders impossible the mutual participation of the knower and the known. 15 Thus the various forms of Protestant thought which have emphasized individualization almost exclusively tended by that 'very fact to cut themselves off from all meaningful contact with the divine. He feels that a mitigated, but none the less dangerous, form of this had already tainted the Catholic theology of. St. Thomas when it made of God an object for us as subjects. In logical predication this cannot be avoided. The error of Catholic and much orthodox Protestant theology on this point is seen to be its failure to reject the ontological implication by which God's holiness is negated and he becomes an object beside the subject, merely one being among others. 16 Much Catholic thought on the supernatural is criticized in this light. At no time has the exaggerated stress on individualization appeared as inadequate as it has in the contemporary context of meaninglessness. Neo-Protestantism, built on biblical criticism and the Ritschlian theological synthesis of modern naturalism and historicism, has been shattered. Its social foundations were destroyed by Marx, its moral grounds by Nietzsche, and its religious basis by Kierkegaard. 17 The question is no longer which values are true or how God speaks to us as individuals. Instead God has been pronounced dead " and with him the whole system of values and meanings in which one lived." 18 15 Systematic Theology, I, p. 177. In the ontological realm such radical individualization would remove all basis for the category of relation. The foundations of religion would thus be destroyed. '" Ibid., pp. 17!l-73 & 17 " The Present Theological Situation in the Light of the Continental European Development," Theology Today, VI (October, 1949), pp. 18 The Courage to Be, pp. & 8 GEORGE F. MCLEAN Thus the import of the traditional Protestant accentuation on the meaning of the individual, his sin and forgiveness, is lost because the contemporary question concerns the very possibility of itself. The problem which faces a present day religious philosophy is that of finding the divine through nonbeing in its most radical form, the anxiety of doubt and meaninglessness. Given this problem of individualization in the contemporary situation, we may now turn to its polar element of participation. Despite the history of its exaggerations, individualization remains indispensable for it provides the terms of the relation of man to God. But in order to have a basis for the relationship the corresponding element of participation must also be introduced. Participation points to "an element of identity in that which is different or of a togetherness of that which is separated. Whether it is the identity of the same enterprise, or the identity of the same universal or the same whole, of which one is a part, in each case participation implies identity." 19 The task of this element is twofold. First, it gives meaning and content to the individual, keeping it from being an empty form. It is then an essential perfection, proportionate to the being and its act. Thus when the individual is on the level of person, participation has the perfect form of communion. Second, participation provides the basis in reality for unity with God by expressing the presence of the divine. No religion can be without this without being reduced to a secular movement of political, educational or scientific activism. 20 It is the relationship to the divine which is expressed by the notion of participation. Tillich is certain that all religions have some form of this element of participation because there could be no real religion without it. However, he considers the notion of the presence of the divine to be developed in a special degree by Catholicism. 10 " Plll'ticipation and Knowledge," loc. cit., pp. 201-202. He terms the system which stresses participation mystical realism. •c " The Permanent Significance of the Catholic Church for Protestantism," Protestant Digest, III (1941), pp. 2.5-29. TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 9 This is expressed in two ways. One is the Catholic retention, even after original sin, of the integrity of human nature with its powers of reason and free will. Man thus remains the Imago Dei and retains some power to return to God. 21 In order to appreciate this aspect proper to Catholicism it is not necessary to accept the possible Pelagian implications of Tillich's statement of the Catholic position. It is sufficient simply to note the difference between the Council of Trent, Session VI, chap. 1, and Luther's notions of the total depravity of human nature, man's incapacity to do good, and forensic justification. 22 Another Catholic expression of the presence of the divine is its notion of sacrament. For Tillich "any revelatory experience transforms the medium of revelation into a sacramental object, whether it is an object of nature, a human being, an historical event, or a sacred text." 23 He vigorously points out the great loss which Protestantism has undergone in failing to develop, or even to retain sufficiently, this element. Protestantism needs the continuous influx of the sacramental in order to be more than a secular movement, and for this reason it needs the permanent corrective of Catholicism. 24 The correction could well be reciprocated, he feels, for Catholicism has trouble with some of the forms taken by its expression of participation. He observes a tendency to view the sacramental as more than Il!anifestation of the divine, to consider particular objects as divine in themselves. This impression made on others by Catholic devotion is the basis of the many accusations of idolatry. Here the purifying, prophetic "Protestant principle," would come forward to reject " the temptation of the bearers of the holy to claim absoluteness 21 Syste'ITUJ,tic Theology, I, p. fl59. •• Martin Luther, V orlesung iiber den Romerbrief, p. 178. " lgitur peccatum est in spirituali homine relictum; . . . quod qui non sedule studuerit expugnare, sine dubio iam habet, etiamsi nihil amplius peccaverit, unde damnetur .... Que non essent sine culpa (sint enim vere peccata et quidem damnabilia) , nisi misericordia Dei non imputaret." •• Syste'ITUJ,tic Theology, I, p. 139. •• " The Permanent Significance of the Catholic Church for Protestantism," loc. cit., pp. fl5 & 29. 10 GEORGE F. MCLEAN for themselves." 25 He finds two other difficulties with the Catholic realization of participation. One is the distinction between natural and supernatural, according to which the · special participation in the divine is realized outside the center of one's personality. He thinks of this grace as a substance alongside the person. 26 This would be a natural consequence from the more radical difficulty which consists in the conceiving of the divine as an object opposed to us as subjects. When God is reduced to this less than divine status of one being among others the possibility of participating in him is severely limited. 27 Thus, while participation has a place of honor in Catholicism, its particular realization is considered deficient. On the other hand, while Protestantism is considered to have much to learn from Catholicism on this point, it is not without its own realization of participation. As noted above, Tillich considers this element to be essential to religion as such. He considers it to be an important factor in the personal experience of Luther which, in the midst of the consciousness of guilt, encountered the divine in an immediate, personal relation of forgiveness. Luther expressed this by the phrases "he who is unjust is just" and "justification by faith." Tillich would express the same in the modern terminology of despair by " the courage to accept oneself as accepted in spite of being unacceptable." 28 He notes that this is not the courage to be as a part had by the public nature of· the sacraments; neither is it the resisting of authority or the transformation of Church or society. Rather, it is a personalism which stand.s between mysti·cism and individualism, affirming the individual self in its encounter with the divine person. This is the very life blood of Protestantism as a religion. He finds that it has been threatened with dissolution many times. Hardly had Luther's insight been attained when the attempts to reduce it to a theological system so stressed " the uncondi•• Systematic Theology, I, p. 227. •• Ibid., pp. 258-59. 07 Theology of Culture, pp. 18-21. Cf. Systematic ·Theology, I, pp. 172·-7t3. 28 The Courage to Be, pp. 63-64. TILLICH's EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 11 tional character of the divine judgment and the free character of God's forgiveness" that the personal situation was replaced by an objective, and then abstract, moral subject. 29 In this way the true existential insight of Protestantism was beclouded. This trend continued as Kant and Hegel developed the notion of the essential man in a supremely rational world. The development of such exaggerated hopes on the part of man's reason made the reaction the more pervading. Schelling's positive philosophy called for an evaluation of things according to the individual's historical situation rather than according to " abstract natures." J\llarx, Nietzsche, and Bergson found that the modern situation was far from realizing Hegel's reconciliation of man with himself. It was, in fact, reducing the individual to a mere object or thing, an empty space without significance except inasmuch as something else passed through it. Participation was gone and with it the person. Human existence had fallen into utter meaninglessness. It is this situation which has to be faced by anything which might be called contemporary Protestantism. As religious it must restore the element of participation in the divine. As Protestant it must keep this from being confused with any mere thing and relate it to the individual as personal forgiveness. At the same time it must be contemporary, facing the problem in the present context of meaninglessness. Religion today must not seek meaning or the participation which is its base beside the totalitarian extension of meaninglessness. It must delve into the meaninglessness itself and there find meaning. Only then can it be a contemporary Protestantism. II. TILLicH's PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM The varied elements which Paul Tillich intends to integrate in his contemporary Protestant theology are related to the notion of creation. For " the doctrine of creation is not the story of an event which took place 'once upon a time.' It is •• Ibid., pp. 12 GEORGE F. MCLEAN the basic description of the .relation between God and the world." so It includes the complex data concerning God, the production of his finite effects ex nihilo, and the response of man from this situation of meaninglessness. Tillich expresses the dynamic interrelationship of these elements in terms of an existential dialectic. He holds this to be the contemporary philosophy because it considers the problems and contradictions of present day existence and does this at a depth where the ontological principles of essence and existence and the epistemological principles of subject and object can be correlated. A complete discussion of the relation of essence to existence is identical with the entire theological system. The distinction between essence and existence, which religiously speaking is the distinction between the created and the actual world, is the backbone of the whole body of theological thought. It must be elaborated in every part of the theological system. 31 Let us see how Tillich's ontological analysis of the present situation reveals a dialectic which might well be termed a contemporary philosophy for Protestantism, since it goes beyond the question of the levels of being to consider their interrelation. It was observed at the beginning that Tillich insists on the polarity of subject and object as the point of departure for his analysis of reality because both members are presupposed for the ontological question. But if they provide his point of departure, he .leaves no doubt that he shares the modern concern to proceed to a point of identity where both subject and object are overcome. This recent concern is the result of the observation that man has been reduced to the status of a thing by allowing himself to be subjected to the objects he produces. 82 The strongest statement of this situation was made by Nietzsche, but the best known is Marx's description of the reduction of the worker to a commodity. Reality then must Systematic Theology, I, p. 252. Ibid., p. 204. 82 Theology of Culture, pp. 91-94. 80 81 TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 13 not be simply identified with objective being, for man must participate in some deeper principle or lose his value and individuality. However, to proceed to identify reality with subjective being or consciousness would be equally insufficient, for subject is determined by its contrast with object. Consequently, what is sought is a level of reality which is beyond this dichotomy of subject and object, identifying the value of both. The need for a point of identity and its function is better appreciated as one proceeds beyond the subject-object relationship to the investigation of either knowledge or being. "The point of procedure in every analysis of experience and every concept of a system of reality must be the point where subject and object are at one and the same place." 88 Thus the analysis of experience turns to the logos, the element of form, of meaning and of structure. In the knowing subject, or self, the logos is called subjective reason and makes self a centered structure. Correspondingly, in the known object, or world, it is called objective reason and makes world a structured whole. There is nothing beyond the logos structure of being. 34 It is, of course, possible to conceive the relation between the rational structures of mind and of reality in a number of ways. Four of these possibilities are represented by realism, idealism, pluralism, and monism. But, according to Tillich, what is of note here is that all philosophers have held an identity, or at least an analogy, to exist between the logos of the mind and the logos of the world. 85 Successful scientific planning and prediction provide a continual pragmatic proof of this identity. The philosophical mind, however, is not satisfied with the mere affirmation, or even the confirmation of the fact. There arises the problem of why there should be this correspondence of the logos in the subject with the logos of reality as a whole. This can be solved if the logos is primarily the structure of the divine life and the principle of its self-manifestation. For then •• The Interpretation of History, trans. Part I N. A. Rasetzki, Parts II, III & IV Elsa L. Talmey (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1936), p. 60. •• Systl!/matic Theology, I, pp. 156, & 85 Ibid., pp. 23 & 75-76. 14 GEORGE F. MCLEAN it is the medium of creation, mediating " between the silent abyss of being and the fulness of concrete individualized, selfrelated beings." 86 The identity or analogy of the rational structures of mind and of reality will follow from the fact that both have been mediated through the same identical divine logos. In this way " reason in both its objective and subjective structures points to something which appears in these structures 87 Logos but which transcends them in power and becomes the point of identity between God, self, and world. Of these three, the logos of God is central and is participated in by self and world as they acquire their being. Thus the logos of reason gives us a first introduction to the concept Tillich has of God overcoming the separation of subject and object to provide a deeper synthesis of the reality of both. This conclusion of the analysis of experience has definite implications for an analysis of being. For the identity is not merely an external similarity of two things to a third without a basis in the things themselves. The identification of subject and object is the divine and this is within beings. The only nonsymbolic expression of the divine is the term " being itself," 88 which, in relation to us, is the ultimate concern. But God is within beings as their power of being, as an analytic dimension in the structure of reality. 89 As such he is the " substance " appearing in every rational structure; the "ground " creative in every rational creation; the " abyss " unable to be exhausted by any creation or totality of creation; the "infinite potentiality of being and meaning" pouring himself into the rational structures of mind and reality to actualize and transform them. 40 God is then the ground not only of truth •• Ibid., p. 158. 87 Ibid., p. 79. •• Ibid., pp. 238-89. Cf. "Reply to Interpretation and Criticism," in The Theology of Paul Tillich, Vol. I of The Library of Living Theology, ed. Charles W. Kegley, and Robert W. Bretall (New York: Macmillan Co., 1956), p. 885. To this single nonsymbolic expression of the divine he has added severe limitations. •• Systematic Theology, I, p. 207. •• Ibid., p. 79. TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 15 but of being as well. In fact, he can be the ground of truth precisely because he is the ground of being. These ideas have had a long history in the mind of man. In the distant past the viewed the Brahman-atman both cosmically as the all-inclusive, unconditioned ground of the universe from which the conditioned emanate, and acosmically as the reality of which the universe is but an appearance. The absolute is the" not this, not this" (neti neti), "the Real of the real" (styasya satyam) .41 This line ofthought can be traced through Plato and Augustine to the medieval Franciscans and Nicholas of Cusa. Tillich is fond of relating· his thought to these older sources. The proximate determinant of his thought in positing this ontological principle of identity beyond the subject and object is Schelling. At the very first Schelling agreed with Fichte in making the "Absolute Ego " of consciousness the ultimate principle and reality. It is this consciousness which dialectically " becomes " the world of nature. But on further consideration Schelling failed to see the particular connection between the infinite Ego and the finite object. For this reason he moved the "Absolute Ego " from the conscious side of the dichotomy to a central, neutral position between and prior to both objectivity and subjectivity. 42 Thus the Absolute is now called not "Ego " but "the unconditional " and" identity." The is no longer subjective, but ontological. This is the insight of the early Schelling which Tillich readily accepts. Thus he traces the line of his thought in between, but distinct from, both the subjective idealism of Fichte and the objective realism of Hobbes. Both sides of the polarity must be maintained; the Unconditional will be equally the ground of subject and object. 43 Two important specifications must be added to this notion of a divine depth dimension beyond both subject and object. One II. i. 20 & IV. ii. 4, cited by T. M. P. Mahadevan, "The in History of Philosophy, Eastern and Western, ed. Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1952), I, pp. 62-63. .. Theology of Culture, p. 92. •• Systematic Theology, I, p. 171. 16 GEORGE F. MCLEAN regards the incapacity of limited beings to exhaust or adequately represent the divine. This indicates the radical individualization of the divine. The other concerns the way God is manifested in the essence of finite beings. This points to the way they participate in him. The first of these specifications which Tillich is careful to make concerning the point of identity of subject and object is that it is gnostically incomprehensible and ontologically inexhaustible, the former reflecting the latter. "This power of being is the prius which preceeds all special contents logically and ontologically." 44 It is not even identified with the totality of things. For this reason the divine is termed the " abyss " because it cannot be exhausted in any creation or totality of creations. 45 Human intuition of the divine always has distinguished between the abyss of the divine (the element of power) and the fullness of its content (the element of meaning), between the divine depth and the divine logos. The first principle is the basis of Godhead, that which makes God, God. It is the root of his majesty, the unapproachable intensity of his being, the inexhaustible ground of being in which everything has its origin. It is the power of being infinitely resisting nonbeing, giving the power of being to everything that is.46 This position of the divine as the inexhaustible depth dimension of reality is the basis of the distinction and individualization of God in relation to creatures. In the realm of being it implies what Tillich calls the Protestant principle, the protest against any thing being raised to the position of the divine. This extends to any creation of the church, including the biblical writings which it will not allow to be identified with the divine ground of all.47 No bearer of the holy may be permitted to claim absolute status for itself. · This reinforces the element of individualization which has always marked Protestantism as leaving man alone before God. •• Theology of Culture, p. 25. ••" Symbol and Knowledge: a Response," Journal of Liberal Religion, II (Spring, 1941), p. 208. Cf. Systematic Theology, II, p. 6. ' 6 Ibid., I, pp. 250-51. "Ibid., pp. 87 & TILLICH'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF PROTESTANTISM 17 In the order of knowledge this implies that, if man is to proceed beyond finite realities to an awareness of what is truly divine, he must leave behind the rational categories of technical reason. Such categories limit the infinite. They make God an object, " a" being among others rather than being itself. For this reason God cannot be conceptualized. 48 To say that God is the depth of reason is to refuse to make him another field of reason. In fact, he precedes the structures of reason and gives them their inexhaustible quality simply because he can never be adequately contained in them. Schelling has termed the divine the Unvordenkliche because it is "that before which thinking cannot penetrate." 49 It was the error of idealism to think that this could ever be completely reduced to rational forms. Tillich is protected from this error by his basic ontological observation of the various levels of reality. "There are levels of reality of great difference, and ... these different levels demand different approaches and different languages." 50 The divine is assigned to the deepest of these levels, and consequently, must be known and expressed in a manner quite different from that of ordinary knowledge and discourse. It is this same fact to which Tillich is referring when he introduces the dialectical relationship between these levels and speaks of the divine as the prius. Here too it will be necessary to proceed beyond conceptualization to an intuitive, personal awareness of the divine. This will be described below, but one thing is already clear. Since the categories are the basis for the objective element in knowledge and the means by which it is made common, the intuitive awareness will have to be personal and marked by subjectivity. The other specification made by Tillich concerning the depth dimension concerns its manifestation in the essences of finite beings. The notion of essence is found in some form in practi•• The Courage to Be, pp. 184-85. •• The Protestant Era, trans. James Luther Adams (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1948), p. 76. ••" Religious Symbols and our Knowledge of G