THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: VoL. XXXI The Thomist Press. Washington 17, D. C. JULY, 1967 No.8 GEORGE EDWARD MOORE'S CRITICISM OF SOME ETIDCAL THEORIES I N HIS Logic and Language, Second Series, A. G. N. Flew termed George Edward Moore the doyen of British philosophy.1 Although he failed to attract popular attention as did certain of his contemporaries such as Ludwig Wittgenstein and Bertrand Russell, recognition of his stature as a " philosopher's philosopher" has been widespread and enduring. The time-spread of his activity is in itself nothing short of phenomenal: his first published work appeared in 1897, and the last lectures he published came from the press in 1957, the year before his death. 2 As a professor at Cambridge and long-time editor of Mind, he had ample opportunity to leave his mark on two generations of philosophers in the Englishspeaking world.3 Logic and Language, Second Series (Oxford, 1958), p. 2. • His Commonplace Book 1919-1953 was published posthumously in 1964. • Moore's autobiography may be found in The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, a colleciion of essays by various authors edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, !!nd ed. (New York, 1952), pp. 8-89. An account of Moore's final days appears in "George 1 9l60 GABRIEL FRANKS Moore has often been compared to Franz Brentano as a pivotal figure in the history of contemporary philosophy. Just as Brentano, by his rejection of the post-Kantian idealism of nineteenth century German philosophy, fostered and inspired such diverse movements as existentialism and the neo-empiricism of the Vienna Circle, so did Moore change the course of British philosophy by his rejection of the Hegelianism which flourished in Great Britain at the turn of the century .4 It was he who led his fellow-student at Cambridge, Bertrand Russell, to abandon idealism in 1898, and together they embarked upon a crusade which led far beyond the goals which either had envisioned or intended. Not only do the milder forms of logical and linguistic analysis which dominate British philosophy today derive from the orientation and method which was Moore's legacy to his followers. The more radical philosophy of the early Wittgenstein of the Tractatus, and of the logical positivism of A. J. Ayer and his disciples, are also generally regarded as having their origin in Moore's rejection of Hegelianism. 5 The fact that Moore never became well known beyond the comparatively narrow circle of professional philosophers in spite Edward Moore 1878-1958," by R. B. Braithwaite, in Proceedings of the British Academy, Vol. XLVII, pp. 298-809. • J. Laird, Recent Philosophy (London, 1986), pp. 188 and 129 fl'. Cf. also F. Copleston, S. J., "Contemporary British Philosophy," in Gregorianum XXXIV (1958); also Moore's " Preface " to his Principia Ethica, pp. x-xi. • For the relationship between Moore and the Logical Postivists, see A. Stroll, The Emotive Theory of Ethics (Berkeley, Calif., 1954); for L. Wittgenstein's dependence on Moore see the " Introduzione critica" to the Italian translation by G, C. M. Colombo, S. J., of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, pp. 18 fl'. See also M. White, The Age of Analysis (New York, 1955), pp. 21-26. In his" A Reply to My Critics" in The Philosophy of G. E. Moore. Moore wavered toward acceptance of the emotive theory of ethics of the Logical Positivists, but in a personal conversation I had with him on September 7, 1955, he told ine that he had definitely rejected such a view. This rejection is confirmed by A. C. Ewing, who has recently reported that at some date after 1958, Moore said that "he still held to his old view [that ethical statements have cognitive meaning], and further that he could not imagine whatever in the world had induced him to say that he was almost equally inclined to hold the other view." (Mmd, LXXI [196!!], p. 251.) MOORE'S CRITICISM OF SOME ETHICAL THEORIES fl61 of his great importance is partly due to the fact that his relatively conservative views about strictly philosophical problems were not the sort of thing of which headlines are madesomething which cannot be said, for instance, about some of Bertrand Russell's propositions concerning morality. G. E. Moore's lack of popular appeal was also due to the coldly serious manner in which he wrote. His books and articles are closely reasoned and seemingly repetitious. Professor Ferrucio Rossi-Landi has noted that In that tedious and pedantic manner of his, Moore examined a restricted number of particular questions, holding them under his nose like a myopic who reads without his glasses, without ever distracting his gaze from the tiny sector about which he has decided to busy himself.6 But if Moore's writings did not appeal to the general public, his work did attain some notoriety through the fact that his ethical system was studied and esposed by the Bloomsbury Group, a loosely organized society of avant-garde artists and writers which revolved around Virginia Woolf in the London of the twenties and thirties. Moore had no direct contact with the members of the Bloomsbury Group apart from the fact that several of its members had studied with him at Cambridge in the early years of the century. But although he himself deplored the manner in which his name had become associated with the group, it became inseparably linked with the activities and ideals of Virginia Woolf and her associates. 7 Moore's ethics appealed to this group, which constituted one of the most highly cultivated intellectual societies in the history of the Western world, largely because of the emphasis which he 8 F. Rossi-LDJldi, " L'eredita di Moore e la filosofia delle quatrro parole," in Rivista di Filoaojia, XL VI, n. 8 (1955), p. 807. 1 J. K. Johnstone, The Bloomburg Group (London, 1954), Chap. II. See also J. M. Keynes, Two Memoirs lLondon, 1949] pp. 8Jld the two volumes of the autobiography of Leonard \Voolf [Virginia's husband], Sowing [New York, 1960], pp. 44-164, and 169-171, 8Jld Beginning Again [New York, 1968], pp. 21, 24-!M, 40-42, 52, 187-189, 8Jld 148. It was Mrs. Dorothy Moore and various acquaintDJlces of Moore who infQrmed me that he was not entirely happy about the way in which his name had become so closely linked with Bloomsbury. GABRIEL FRANKS placed on aesthetic values as ultimate ends. But it cannot be denied that its members were also fascinated by Moore's implicit invitation to cast off certain aspects of Victorian mores. Although Moore wrote at least as much about problems which may be roughly summarized as being of an epistemological nature as he did about ethics, it is only with the latter that we will be concerned here. As to his epistemology, we must be content to point out here that he believed in a correspondence theory of truth and that the objects of reality consist principally of combinations of sense-data, though what may be the exact relationship which sense-data bear to the objects which they constitute and to knowing subjects is a problem which continued to puzzle him to the end of his days. 8 Though basically an empiricist, he was willing to admit the reality and existence of objects and qualities which do not appear to the senses. This latter fact is of the greatest importance to his ethical theory. Moore was neither a notably prolific writer nor one given to developing a system for system's sake. He himself has confessed that he would never have been roused to interest in philosophical problems had he not felt the need to refute what he considered the outrageous statements and propositions of various philosophers. 9 Nearly half of Moore's Principia Ethica (first published in 1903; reprinted 1922, 1929, 1948, 1951, 1954, 1956, 1959) , the work we shall consider here in greatest detail, consists of the 8 A synthesis of Moore's epistemology is to be found in A. White, G. E. Moore-A Critical &cposition (Oxford, 1958), Chap. VITI. Cf. J. Passmore, A Hundred Years of Philosophy (London, 1957), pp. 208-215, and D. Cleary "An Essay on G. E Moore" in The DCYI.lYnside Review, Vol. LXXXVI (1968), pp. 216-219. I should confess that I find the summary of Moore's epistemology as given in the text to be woefully inadequate, especially in view of Moore's constant shifts in position. Certainly he was not a mere phenomenalist except for a brief period around 1918 when he wrote " Some Objects of Perception " (Philosophical Studies, pp. 220-282), and, possibly, when he wrote Principia Etkica (see, e. g., p. 41). His final published pronouncement on the status of sense-data was a firm rejection of what he termed the Mill-Russell view (The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, pp. 581-82). • G. E. Moore, "An Autobiography," in The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, p. 14. MOORE'S CRITICISM OF SOME ETHICAL THEORIES refutation of various ethical systems. His later volume, titled Ethics (London, took the form of an exposition of the general tenets of utilitarianism, together with a correction of this doctrine. Moore's several other essays and articles which appeared in learned journals and which have reference to his ethical theory also evidence a more or less polemical character. I refer to the two essays, " The Conception of Intrinsic Value " and" The Nature of Moral Philosophy," which were published in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XI, (reprinted as Chapters VIII and X respectively the article" The Value of Philosophical Studies [London, of Religion," which appeared in the International Journal of Ethics, XII (1901); "Is Goodness a Quality?" which appeared in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XII, 1988 (reprinted as Chapter III of Philosophical Papers [London 1959]); his essay "A Reply to My Critics," which concludes the volume titled The Philosophy of G. E. Moore edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp (1st ed. Evanston, ed. New York, and numerous book reviews, in particular his review of Franz Brentano's The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong, which appeared in the International Journal of Ethics, XV (1905). In this paper concerning Moore's criticism of various ethical systems I shall follow the method of exposition used by Moore in his Principia Ethica, since this was his most complete treatment of the subject, but reference will be made to other works in those cases in which Moore later modified his theory. Moore begins his Principia Ethica with a general criticism of all ethicians of the past, and in his Preface he makes the ambitious statement, paraphrasing Kant, that he intends to write "Prolegomena to any future Ethics which can possibly pretend to be scientific." 10 He takes many philosophers to task first of all for failing to define the province of ethics/ 1 the scope of which he proposes to be not only human conduct, 10 11 G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge, 1908), p. ix. Ibid., p. 1. 264 GABRIEL FRANKS but human conduct insofar as it is good or bad. He maintains that " That which is meant by ' good ' is, in fact, except its converse ' bad,' the only simple object of thought which is peculiar to Ethics." 12 This leads to his next great criticism of the great majority of his predecessors in ethical investigation, namely that they have generally failed to distinguish between the two principle meanings of the word " good,'' which can signify either what is " good in itself " (or " intrinsic good ") or what is " good as a means." Although Ethics is concerned with good as a means (for all human conduct, according to Moore, is good only as a means for the attainment of intrinsic good) , it is necessary to ascertain the meaning of " intrinsic good," upon which all good as a means is dependent. Moore spent a lifetime trying to state clearly what he meant by " intrinsic good,'' 13 a process whicht was rendered particularly difficult by the fact that he maintained that it is an indefinable concept, and that the intrinsic goodness of things can be only known by intuition. 14 It is a non-relational quality 15 Ibid., p. 2. Moore refined his notion of " intrinsic good " especially in " The Conception of Intrinsic Value" (Chap. VIII of Philosophical Studies [London, 1922]) and in his" A Reply to My Critics." (The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, esp. pp. 554-611.) "Moore states that when he calls propositions about good " intuitions," he merely means to assert that they are incapable of proof; he implies nothing whatever as to the manner or origin of our cognition of them (Principia, p. x) . He compares the manner in which we know " good " to the manner in which we know " yellow " (Ibid., pp. 7 and 10) . In order to test the goodness of things by intuition, they are to be considered in isolation. The following text from Principia (pp. 83-84) will illustrate how the test is to be applied: " Let us imagine one world exceedingly beautiful. Imagine it as beautiful as you can; put into it whatever on this earth you most admiremountains, rivers, the sea; trees, and sunsets, stars and moon. Imagine these all combined in the most exquisite proportions, so that on one thing jars against another, but each contributes to increase the beauty of the whole. And then imagine the ugliest world you can possibly conceive. Imagine it simply one heap of filth, containing everything that is most disgusting to us, for whatever reason, and on the whole, as far as may be, without one redeeming feature. . . . The only thing we are not entitled to imagine is that any human being ever has or ever, by any possibility, can, live in either, can ever see and enjoy the beauty of the one or hate the foulness of the other. Well, even so, supposing them quite apart 12 13 MOORE'S CRITICISM OF SOME ETHICAL THEORIES which he describes as " non-natural," 16 which is dependent on, or derived from, the various good-making " natural " qualities of objects or states of affairs which Moore's described as " organic wholes." 17 Furthermore, intrinsic goodness is an " ought-implying characteristic," 18 or, in other words, to say that a thing is intrinsically good must entail that it ought to exist. 19 Or, to be still more precise, " A statement about obligation follows from the very nature of a statement about intrinsic value." 20 It is Moore's characterization of intrinsic good as being a non-natural quality which led him to make his principal criticism of many ethical systems, that is, that they commit what he termed the " naturalistic fallacy." This fallacy consists in the attempt to identify intrinsic good, a " non-natural " quality with some other " natural " quality or object. Although Moore had at least as much difficulty in :fixing the precise distinction between what he meant by a" natural" and a "non-natural" quality as he did in making clear the meaning of intrinsic good, what he means by the " naturalistic fallacy " is clear enough: it is the identification of intrinsic goodness with any other quality, characteristic, or object whatsoever. He made it clear even at the beginning of Principia Ethica that even if good were a natural quality, and the attempt were made to identify it with some other natural quality (whatever may be meant from any possible contemplation by human beings; still, is it irrational to hold that it is better that the beautiful world should exist, than the one which is ugly? Would it not be well, in any case, to do what we could to produce it rather than the other? Certainly I cannot help thinking that it would; and I hope that some · may agree with me in this extreme instance." It is interesting to note that Moore later rejected the conclusions of this intuition. (See note 47 below.) 16 G. E. Moore, "Is Goodness a Quality?" in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. XI, p. (Philosophical Studies, p. 16 Moore Principia, p. 13 fl. 17 Ibid., pp. It was suggested by H. J. Paton in his contribution to The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (p. 115) that Moore "would agree with the Provost of Oriel [Sir W. David Rossl that goodness is a 'totiresultant property.'" 18 Moore, "A Reply to My Critics," p. 605. 19 Moore, Principia, pp. 17 and 67 . •• Moore, " A Reply to My Critics," p. 575. 266 GABRIEL FRANKS by the term) , he would still call such an. identification an instance of the naturailstic fallacy .21 The naturalistic fallacy can occur under many forms. Moore reduces them to two groups, the first of which he terms metaphysical theories, the second of which he calls naturalistic theories. Naturalistic theories are then suddivided into theories which declare some natural object, other than pleasure, to be the sole good; and hedonism, the doctrine that pleasure is the only good-that good and pleasure are identicaP 2 Moore chose to discuss the naturalistic theories before taking up the metaphysical theories, and of the naturalistic theories he elected to examine the non-hedonistic varieties before taking up the question of hedonism itself. The philosophers who are hailed into court include J. S. Mill, W. K. Clifford, the Stoics, Rousseau, Herbert Spencer, and M. Guyau. Moore termed the first group of theories naturalistic because they identify good with some particular quality or object which exists in space and time-in the realm of nature. And the first of such theories is that which equates goodness with ' life according to nature.' Such a view he attributes to the Stoics (though he is of the opinion that in their case the theory is of a metaphysical rather than naturalistic nature) and Jean Jacques Rousseau. 23 In its most general form, this theory holds that whatever is natural is good. Moore points out that taken at its face value this proposition is obviously false, since there are many things in the world of nature (which he identifies with the visible universe) which are, in themselves, bad, for example, pain. He next suggests that such a theory may maintain that whatever Nature (with a capital" N ") has decreed must be good. This is rejected for two reasons: a) as an agnostic, Moore cannot identify Nature with an all-wise God, and hence can see no rea21 Moore, Principia, p. 14. Mary Warnock has pointed out in Ethics Since 1900 (London, 1960), p. 19, that while the name "naturalistic fallacy" may be misleading, for Moore " the true fallacy is the attempt to define the indefinable." 22 Ibid., p. 39. 23 Ibid., p. MOORE's CRITICISM OF SOME ETHICAL THEORIES 267 son why whatever Nature has ordained must necessarily be good, and b) if what Nature has decreed is taken to mean that that which is good is that which is normal, then this view must be rejected by reason of the fact that many abnormal things are better than normal things. For instance, the genius of Socrates or Shakespeare must be admitted to be better than the mediocre intelligence of the average man. 24 He suggests that the identification of what is normal with what is good came about through the observation of the fact that what is normal is usually better than that which is abnormal, but he maintains that it is clear that this is not universally true. A third suggestion he makes as to the meaning of " nature " in the phrase " life according to nature," is that it means the minimum of what is necessary for life. Apparently, he is in this case equating the natural with the primitive. By way of refutation he cites a dialogue of Lucian, in which it is pointed out how silly it is to hold that the life of lions and bears and pigs and wild Sythians is a greater good than that of civilized man. 25 The second sort of naturalistic ethics he undertakes to refute is cine which systematizes the appeal to nature by holding that whatever is more evolved in nature is the more perfect. Its champions would seem to hold that nQt only does evolution (especially in the Darwinian sense) show us the direction in which we are developing, but also shows us the direction in which we ought to develop. Moore cites Guyau and Herbert Spencer as partisans of this view. He notes that at one point in his Data of Ethics Spencer seems to indicate that his evolutionist ethics is based on hedonism, that the generalized conclusion may be drawn, in virtue of numerous individual observations, that what is more evolved always brings more pleasure into the world. As a matter of fact such a generalization would not show any strict causal relatonship between evolution and pleasure, but only that the progress of evolution and increase of pleasure have gone hand in hand in the past. Moore at•• Ibid., p. 48. •• Ibid., p. 45. 268 GABRIEL FRANKS tempts to show that Spencer actually held an evolutionistic and hedonistic ethic simultaneously, a position which would lead to contraditions. For example, Spencer seems to recognize in the increased production of life a mark of progress in evolution. Moore points out that it is quite possible that a small quantity of life should give a greater quantity of pleasure than the greatest possible quantity of life that is only just " worth living." l!6 And judging evolutionistic ethics on its own merits, that is, not as related to hedonism, Moore points out that while it may be true that the actual evolution of the universe has favored an increase in intrinsically good things, we have no assurance that it will so continue. Darwin's law of natural selection, for instance, might, under changed conditions, favor the evolution of lower forms of life which might be better only in the sense that they were more suited to those new conditions. 27 We now tum to the refutation of hedonism, to which Moore devotes a whole chapter in Principia Ethics. 28 By hedonism, Moore understands the doctrine that pleasure is the sole good, a· " vulgar mistake " which is quite widespread because " it is the first conclusion at which any one who begins to reflect upon Ethics naturally arrives. It is very easy to notice the fact that we are pleased with things. The things we enjoy and the things we do not form two unmistakable classes, to which our attention is constantly directed. But it is comparatively difficult to distinguish the fact that we approve a thing from the fact that we are pleased with it " 29 Among the philosophers whom Moore considers to be hedonists are listed Aristippus, the disciple of Socrates, and the Cyrenaic school he founded; Epicurus and the Epicureans; the utilitarians such as Mill and Bentham; Herbert Spencer in his non-evolutionistic moments; and Moore's own predecessor in the chair of moral philosophy at Cambridge, Henry Sidgwick. We can here do not more than summarize very briefly the •• Ibid., pp. Ibid., p. S7. 21 •• Ibid., Chap. III. •• Ibid., p. 60. MOORE's CRITICISM OF SOME ETHICAL THEORIES 269 s