THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PROVINCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington, D. C. 20017 VoL. XXXII CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, I. EXISTENCE No.2 APRIL, 1968 CRISIS OF FAITH? OF THE CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM 1. Testimony of the Supreme Pontiff Paul VI to the Synod P of Bishops AUL VI, having frequently deplored the existence o£ the crisis concerning the Magisterium o£ the Church, especially on the occasion o£ the Wednesday general audiences, deemed it his duty to manifest anew his preoccupations in his inaugural Allocution to the Synod o£ Bishops, Sept. 29, 1967, in these words: The earnest concern for the faithful preservation of doctrine, which was voiced so solemnly at the start of Vatican II, must guide our post-conciliar period. Indeed, it must now be displayed with even greater vigor by those in the Church who have received Christ's mandate to teach and spread the Gospel message and to preserve the " deposit " of faith; for today the dangers threatening the deposit of faith are more numerous and more serious, enormous dangers connected with the irreligious outlook of the modern mentality and insidious dangers cropping up within the Church 147 148 LUIGI CIAPPI itself. Some teachers and writers are trying to give expression to Catholic doctrine, but they often seem to be more concerned about adapting the dogmas of faith to secular forms of thought and expression than about following the norm of the Church's Magisterium. They thus give free run to the view that, disregarding the requisites of sound doctrine, one may select only those truths of faith that are admissible in the judgment of one's personal instinctive preference and reject the rest. As this erroneous opinion would have it, conscience is free and responsible for its own actions; it may claim its rights even in preference to the rights of truth, foremost among which are the rights of divine Revelation (cf. Gal. 1:6-9). Moreover, the doctrinal patrimony of the Church may be subjected to review in order to give Christianity new ideological dimensions quite at variance with the theological ones which genuine tradition, with its immense reverence for God's word, has traced ouU 2. Awareness of the crisis on the part of the Synodal Fathers Among the subjects presented to the First Synod of Bishops celebrated in Rome in October of 1967 figured the following: Some dangerous modern opinions. A theism. Among these opinions there was singled out, in the field of ecclesiology, a certain crisis of the divine authority of the Magisterium of the Church. In fact, the synodal presentation document spoke of the opinion of those who reduce the office of the Magisterium to the task of registering the religious conscience of the community, gathering together and sanctioning with its own authority those truths which flourish and are developed in such a collective conscience. Harkening back, then, to the condemnation which emanated from the Holy Office, with the decree Lamentabili of July 3, 1907, against the Modernists who upheld the emancipation of exegesis from the Magisterium of the Church and reduced the task of the Church to that of approving the opinions prevalent in the learning Church, 2 the same presentation document insinuated that the modern crisis could well be held as a symptom of neo-modernism. Another, although less serious, indication of the cnsts was L'Osservatore Romano, Sept. 30, 1967. Enchiridion Symbolorum, Denziger-Schonmetzer, ed. XXXIII n. 3406. 1 2 (Herder, 1964), CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 149 pointed out both in the presentation document offered to the Fathers and in the report made to them by His Eminence, Michael Cardinal Browne. After calling to mind that the Magisterium, even when it does not define, remains an organ divinely instituted for the teaching of the faithful to which is due a religious submission, even though this is not to be identified with theological faith, the two documents lamented that among Catholics not all profess due submission to the authentic ordinary Magisterium of the Church. But, notwithstanding the fact that the report had been made with moderation in judgment and without any indication of the seriousness and extension of this crisis, and in a more moderate tone than that used by the Supreme Pontiff in his inaugural Allocution, it did not draw unanimity of consent. Nor does this cause any surprise. In fact, the chronicle of the Synod has informed us that a great number of the Fathers judged the presentation document on the actual doctrinal and disciplinary situation of the Church to be negative, ignorant of the advances achieved after the Council, not completely responsive to the reality of the facts, which have many encouraging features, and, therefore, that the presentation document was alarmist and should be set aside. The history of Vatican II is, in part, repeated. Not all the synodal Fathers, as was expected, shared the optimism of the protesters; opposition, then, was inevitable and it exploded with particular vigor in regard to the lamented crisis of the Magisterium. Without giving the names of the authors of the various interventions and of the Conferences represented by them (in order not to violate secrecy and to give rise to unpleasant reactions), we limit ourselves to reference to the essential content of the opposing judgments. A. Prevalent agreement of judgments on the existence of the crisis a. Crisis of the M agisterium in the conscience of the faithful The synodal Fathers who, in the name of the Episcopal Conferences of the more diverse and distant countries of the 150 LUIGI ClAPP! Catholic world, expressed their agreement with what was deplored in the presentation document, brought to light various aspects of it, more or less serious and widespread. The spreading of an attitude of diffidence and of neglect with regard to the ordinary Magisterium of the Supreme Pontiffs and of the Bishops was lamented by many of them. Others expressed the judgment that, among the opinions singled out in the presentation paper, there were some that were not only dangerous but also false. Someone brought up the existence of signs of doubt and uncertainty, too, in matters of faith and morals, even among priests and religious. There was one, moreover, who deplored the lack of full assent shown by some toward the solemn documents themselves of the Magisterium. The fact was likewise brought up that some claim for themselves the unlimited faculty to discuss even in public the more difficult and delicate problems of dogma and moral. The crisis of the Magisterium, another Father observed, is institutional, because some claim to submit the Teaching Authority to the judgment of the charismatics, keeping open for discussion all the things which have not been defined and limiting the normative value of the documents, even conciliar documents, to the times in which they emanated. However, while deploring the obfuscation of faith and of obedience in the conscience of many of the faithful in their views concerning the Magisterium, the Fathers reaffirmed with the Council the right to freedom in scientific research, the duty, on the other hand, of the Hierarchy to promote studies and dialogue, in the firm conviction that the Magisterium is not an obstacle to dogmatic and scientific progress but rather a light and a salutary guide. b. Crisis of the M agisterium in the conscience of Pastors There was no lack of synodal Fathers who humbly and frankly held that one of the principal causes underlying the lamented crisis in the Christian people can be found among many Pastors, namely, in the diminished awareness of their own responsibilities. Indeed, not all the Masters of the faith CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 151 by divine right seem to have a clear awareness that the grace of the theologian is one thing, that of the bishop another; that the bishop is, at it were, the sign of the true rule of faith. Some of them, not fulfilling with zeal and firmness their proper office, namely, that of proposing with clarity and authority the certain and indisputable truths of faith and morals, have permitted surprise and scandal to arise among the faithful by the dissensions made evident to them among exegetes and theologians on points of Catholic doctrine which have been held up until today to be fundamental and definitive. The Bishops, observed one distinguished prelate with a certain wry humor, must not be dumb dogs. 3 B. Prevalent disagreement of judgments on the existence of the crisis Although not daring to contest the existence of a certain crisis of the Magisterium, both in the conscience of the faithful and in that of some Pastors, many Fathers believed it their duty and right to attentuate the seriousness and the dimensions of the crisis. Wherefore, not a few were in agreement in saying that, as with other aspects of the life of the Church, so also in the functioning of the Magisterium and of the respect due to it there is a crisis of development rather than one of decay and serious weakness. In our time, then, both Pastors and faithful would act substantially in a way more worthy of persons conscious of their own rights and duties, of the legitimate autonomy which belongs also to the faithful. Rather, the crisis must be imputed, at least in part, to the repeated impediments placed by Authority to scientific research and to the manifestations of personal opinions. Other Fathers singled out the danger of deeming erroneous what in reality are attempts at progress, at the conquest of old ideologies, at the purification and strengthening of the faith. One other made the observation that the way of Authority does not favor advancement. What is more important, today, is adaptation to modern thought 3 Cf. "II Sinodo dei Vescovi," La Civilta Cattolica (Nov. 4, 1967), pp. 289-290. 152 LUIGI CIAPPI and manner of speaking. As was expected, none of the Fathers defending the actual situation thought it opportune to promote attentiveness to the Magisterium crisis in the conscience and activity of the holy Pastors. II. REMEDIES FOR THE CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM I. Remedies indicated and offered by the Holy Father Paul VI In his inaugural Allocution to the Synod the Pope constantly indicated as the first and principal remedy for the crisis of faith, which is extended also to the Magisterium, the revival of the exact notion of faith, reminding all believers that: Faith is not the fruit of an arbitrary or purely naturalistic interpretation of God's word, just as it is not the religious expression which springs from the collective opinion, deprived of authorized guidance, of those who say they believe; and much less is it acquiescence in the philosophical or sociological currents of the fleeting historical moment. Faith is the adhesion of our whole spiritual nature to the wondrous, merciful message of salvation that has come down to us through the luminous and secret ways of Revelation. Faith is more than a process of inquiry; it is above all a certainty. It is not the fruit of our inquiring search; it is a mysterious gift, summoning us to take part docilely, promptly and trustingly in the dialogue which God initiates with our souls.4 And in the conviction that faith is not the fruit of our investigations and discussions but the gift of God (Eph. 2: 8) , Paul VI indicates that the arm of defense and the rising increase of faith lie above all in and through prayer and he goes on to say: For this reason we considered the safeguarding of the faith so imperative after the close of the Council that we invited the whole Church to celebrate a " year of faith " in honor of the two Apostles the chief teachers and witnesses of Christ's Gospel. The of this year is to meditate on the very faith handed down to us and to assess in the modern context the decisive function this fundamental virtue has for the stability of our religion and the vitality of • L'Osservatore Romano, Sept. 30, 1967. CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 153 the Church, for building up God's kingdom in souls, for ecumenical dialogue and for the genuine contact for renewal that Christ's followers intend to make with the world of today. We wish in this way to strengthen our own faith as teachers, witnesses and pastors in God's Church, so that Christ, living and invisible, her sole and supreme Head, may find it humble, sincere and strong. We wish also to strengthen the faith of all our children, especially those who pursue the study of theology and religion, so that with a renewed and watchful awareness of the Church's unalterable and certain teaching they may give wise collaboration to the furtherance of the sacred sciences and to the maintenance, in light and in fruitfulness, of the inviolable aim of Catholic teaching. 5 Q. Remedies suggested by some synodal Fathers There were those among the Fathers who, with the aim of surmounting the actual crisis of faith in the Magisterium, asked that the Synod reaffirm the duty of submission to the Supreme Pontiff. Another Father underlined the necessity of a clear episcopal magisterium, a necessity advised especially by Seminary professors; another, then, insisted on the duty of an authoritative concordant teaching, on the collegial level or at least the fruit of a continuous communion among the Bishops of individual nations, so as to avoid the situation that one Pastor would approve opinions that another shortly afterwards would declare to be false, temerarious or dangerous. It is not allowed, one Father energetically entreated, that another authority than that of the authentic Magisterium prevail in the Church. 3. Remedies proposed by the synodal Commission and approved by the majority of the Fathers The members of the Synod-144 out of ISS-demonstrated that they were without doubt in agreement in maintaining that the exercise of the authentic Magisterium, singly or collegially, is the medicine or tonic more adapted to giving vigor and firmness back to the faith and to the submission due to the representatives of Jesus Christ, the author and perfecte1· of our faith (Heb. IQ: 2) . "Ibid. 154 LUIGI CIAPPI The dogmatic and theological motives that induced the Fathers to approve also the second principle, expressed above, as a secure antidote to the " dangerous modern opinions," were those which had been expressed by the authors of various interventions and which the text of the Report summed up in this brief synthesis: According to the doctrine of the Church the office of teaching matters regarding faith and morals authentically, that is, with the authority of Christ, has been confided to all the successors of the Apostles. It is the task, moreover, of the Roman Pontiff, teaching personally, and of the Episcopal College united in Ecumenical Council, to meet the spiritual needs of the Christian people with the assiduous exercise of such a magisterium. But this is not enough, because the individual Pastors in their respective dioceses or regions are abliged, according to their proper office, to the same most grave duty. In our day the sacred ministry is exercized more fittingly in collegial form, that is, through Episcopal Conferences. But it must be executed by each one of them in communion with the teaching imparted by the bishops of the whole world and principally by the Apostolic See. It will then happen that, with a regard for the needs of the whole Church, reciprocal help will be offered to us, disturbances avoided and unity reinforced. On a subordinate but related level, remedies were indicated which the Pastors ought to suggest to their subjects. All the faithful, then, must be clearly taught, in ways corresponding more to today's spiritual needs, about the duty which they have to offer filial obedience and sincere adherence to the declarations of the Church, although in various degrees, in keeping with the distinct character of each of these decrees, as was stated in the Acts of Vatican Council II. 6 III. RECALL TO THE DIVINE AuTHORITY oF THE MAGISTERIUM IN THE YEAR OF FAITH Given the diagnosis and the therapy that the Synod of Bishops formulated to surmount the actual crisis of the Magis6 Cf. Dogmatic Constitution Lumen gentium, c. III, n. ft5. CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 155 terium of the Church, one must logically conclude that this crisis has its true origin in a diminished " sensus fidei " in the supernatural value of the office of masters that the divine Savior communicated to His legitimate representatives. Indeed, if we look at the teaching Church, one has the impression that not all the Bishops are fully aware of their proper and incommunicable charism of teaching in the name of Jesus Christ, and thus with divine authority, to which is due the assent of faith or at least religious, internal assent even on the part of men of science, notwithstanding the human gifts and charisms which these men can boast of or believe they possess. On the part, then, of the learning Church, it must be evident that many, both priests and laypersons, claim that they have the right to interpret and formulate anew the same dogmatic definitions, with the optimum intention of rendering them more intelligible and acceptable to Christians or non-Christians of our times. Moreover, they claim that they can pass judgment on the declarations or prescriptions of the authentic, ordinary Magisterium, because they maintain that it is no longer definitive, infallible and irreformable, and therefore it is to be accepted, rejected or interpreted in accordance with the value of the theological or philosophical reasons brought forward by it to reconcile the assent of the faithful. In the expectation that the Supreme Pontiff, accepting the petition made to him by the Synod of Bishops, will issue a positive document on the truths " of faith and morals " which seem today to be more opportune to profess, defend and investigate, it will be useful for all good Catholics to reflect in some degree on their own faith in the divine Magisterium of the Church in this "Year of Faith " in the light of the documents that the Supreme Pontiffs and the Ecumenical Councils Vatican I and Vatican II have issued precisely with the intent of illuminating our path as believers and thus of leading us to the glorious goal of eternal salvation. 156 LUIGI CIAPPI l. The divine institution of the M agisterium and its object: the truth to be believed and to be practised The existence in the Church of a power, not only of vigilance and of direction but also of full and supreme right of teaching, in the name of Christ the Redeemer, all the members of the Church, and, indeed, all men, " the faith they must believe and put into practice " (" fidem credendam et moribus applicandam ") ,1 is a dogma of faith. It is equally a truth of faith, even though not defined, that the responsible subject of such power is the College of Bishops, in communion with the Roman Pontiff, to whom such power belongs also by personal title, without any restriction as to its exercise.8 On the other hand, the subject of authentic but not infallible power, one limited to determined territories or subjects, is every individual residential bishop. 9 As to object, that is, doctrinal extension, it is a certain and incontestable truth that the power of the Magisterium is not restricted to things of a strictly religious character, but it embraces the whole domain of the natural law, determining, interpreting, applying it, under its moral aspect, that is, with reference to man's actions ordainable and to be ordained to the highest good and the ultimate end. In other words, the Magisterium does not exhaust its task only within the ambit of man's relations with God, but it has the right and the duty to interest itself, to teach and to pass laws also in the very broad field of the " reality of life." Therefore, numerous and very serious matrimonial, social, political, cultural questions, by reason of their intimate and inseparable connection with ethics, with conscience, with eternal salvation, fall under the authority and the pastoral care of holy Mother Church. 10 Ibid., n. 25 A. Cf. ibid .• n. 22 B. 9 Cf. ibid., n. 25 A. 1 ° Cf. St. Pius X, Encyclical Singulari quadam, Sept. 24, 1912; AAS, (1912), pp. 658-659; Pius Xll, Alloc. "Magnificate Dominum," Nov. 2, 1954, AAS (1954), pp. 672-673; Cone. Vat. II, Const. dogm. Lumen gentium, c. III, nn. 21-25; Const. past. Gaudium et spes; F. Hurth, S. J., "Episcoporum triplex munus, Observationes 7 8 CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 157 2. The divine assistance promised to the Magisterium of the Church a. The infallibility of the solemn, definitive M agi."terium It is a dogma of faith, that is, a truth of divine, defined and Catholic faith, that the Roman Pontiff: " when he speaks ex cathedra, in virtue of the assistance promised to him in the person of blessed Peter, enjoys that infallibility with which the divine Redeemer willed His Church to be endowed in defining doctrine concerning faith and morals." 11 The Bishops possess the same prerogative " when gathered together in an ecumenical council they are teachers and judges of faith and morals"; therefore, " their definitions must then be adhered to with the submission of faith." 12 b. The infallibility of the ordinary universal M agisterium Of the greatest importance, in the face of the crisis of faith or of religious submission which torments the conscience of many Catholics, is a firm adherence to the three following declarations: Pius IX: The submission which is proper to the act of divine faith must not be limited to those things which have been defined by expressed decrees of the Ecumenical Councils or of the Roman Pontiffs or of this See, but it must be extended also to those things which are transmitted (" traduntur ") by the ordinary Magisterium of the whole Church dispersed throughout the world as divinely revealed and thus by universal and constant consent are maintained by Catholic theologians as belonging to the deposit of the faithP ad respectivas Allocutiones Pontificias mense maio et novembri 1954," Periodica de re morali, tom. XLIII, fasc. III-IV (Rome, Pont. Univ. Gregoriana, 1954), pp. 281-251. 11 Cone. Vat. I, Const. dogm. Pastor aeternus, c. 4, Denz.-Sch., nn. 8074-8075; Cone. Vat. II, Const. dogm. Lumen gentium, c. III, n. 25 C. 12 Lumen gentium, n. B; cf. Msgr. Philips, L'Eglise et son mystere au deuxieme Concile du Vatican. Historie, texte et commentaire de la Constitution "Lumen gentium," tom. I (Desclee, 1967), pp. 13 Ep. Quas libenter to the Archbishop of Miinich, Dec. 21, 1868, Denz.-Sch. n. 158 LUIGI CIAPPI Vatican Council I: By divine and Catholic faith everything must be believed that is contained in the written word of God or in tradition (" tradita "), and that is proposed (" proponuntur ") by the Church as a divinely revealed object of belief either in a solemn decree or in her ordinary universal teaching. 14 Vatican Council II: The Bishops ... even when they are dispersed around the world, provided that, while maintaining the bond of unity among themselves and with Peter's successor and while teaching authentically on a matter of faith or morals, they concur in a single viewpoint as the one which must be held conclusively, pronounce infallibly the doctrine of the Church. 15 c. The infallibility of the M agisterium, both solemn and ordinary-universal, even in things not revealed but connected with them Examining the tenor and the import of the declarations referred to above, it follows that: 1° the primary object of the infallible Magisterium, both solemn and ordinary-universal, is those things (deeds and words, truths to be believed and to be put into practice) which are formally revealed, either in a clear and explicit manner or at least obscurely and implicitly; and which, as such, have been "transmitted" (" traduntur ") or "proposed " (" proponuntur ") ; 2° the secondary object, on the other hand, is the things which have not been formally revealed, not even in an obscure and implicit way, but whose connection with the revealed truths is so intimate that their denial would imply the danger of failing even as regards the primary object. 16 This is why Vatican Council II, seeking to include the primary and secondary objects, does not restrict the ambit of infallibility to the revealed doctrine of Christ to be believed with divine faith, but extends it to every matter of "Const. dogm. Dei Filius, c. 3, Denz.-Sch., n. 30ll. Lumen gentium, n. 25 B. 16 Cf. F. Hiirth, "Annotationes in Pii XII Nuntium Rad. 23 martii 1952 et in Alloc. 18 apr. 1952," Periodica XLI (1952), p. 248. 15 CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 159 faith and morals taught unanimously by the Bishops as something that is to be retained as definitive (" tamquam definitive tenendam ") and therefore irreformable. Indeed, even in this case, the ordinary universal Magisterium " proclaims infallibly the doctrine of Christ." "This authority (the Council adds) is even more clearly verified when, gathered together in an ecumenical council, they are teachers and judges of faith and morals for the universal Church." 17 One must extend "the submission of faith " as much to the " definitive interpretation " of the Episcopate dispersed throughout the world, but unanimous in proclaiming it, as to the " definitions " of the Ecumenical Councils and to the personal " definitive act " of the Roman Pontiff. 18 Vatican II does not add divina, in order not to restrict the submission of faith only to the truths contained in the deposit of Revelation. d. The infallibility of the ordinary Magisterium of the Roman Pontiff It is certain that the Supreme Pontiff is infallible when he speaks ex oathedra (e. g., dogmatic Bulls), that is, when Lumen gentium, n. 25 B. Ibid., n. 25 A, B, C. Msgr. Philips, commenting on n. 25 C of Lumen gentium, writes: "Here we are, once more, before a very compact text which touches on a great number of problems. I. First of all, it clearly circumscribes the object of infallibility, a question which Vatican Council I treated only tangentially without furnishing a complete answer to it. The Constitution Pastor aeternus, c. 4 (Denz. 3070), simply affirms that the assistance of the Holy Spirit is assured to the successor of Peter ' to guard jealously and explain faithfully ' the revealed doctrine. The Fathers of Vatican II specify today that the privilege of infallibility extends as far as is required by the preservation and explanation of the deposit of faith confided to the Church. That far inclusively, but no farther. Once traced, this frontier encomposes a certain number of fundamental truths fixed by philosophy inasmuch as it is the expression of universal human experience. If someone, for instance, claimed that human reason is forever incapable of grasping any certain truth, he could no longer admit, logically, an article of faith. But total relativism and agnosticism are not found condemned by name by revelation, for the simple reason that neither Scripture nor the ancient Church encountered such error all along their path. Theologians bring together under the same rubric of ' indirect object ' of infallibility a whole series of other elements, among which are those they call dogmatic facts. All that belongs to the domain of professional theology; the Council, itself, is content to establioh the basic principle and leave the rest to the care of technical treatises." Op. cit., pp. 327-328. 17 18 160 LUIGI CIAPPI " he proclaims by a definitive act some doctrine of faith or morals." 19 But one cannot argue from this that he is never infallible in his ordinary Magisterium, although he would not be by force of a solemn, definitive sentence (" infallibilis effatio ") but inasmuch as he proclaims an infallible truth (" effatum infallibile ") which is such for other reasons. Thus, for example, the Supreme Pontiff is to be held to be infallible when he declares his intention to propose, in his ordinary teaching (radio messages, allocutions, and especially encyclical letters), that which the whole Church has certainly and universally maintained and maintains even today as the doctrine of faith. Now, the universal Church cannot err about that which is intimately connected with eternal salvation. 20 It seems to us that the Fathers of Vatican Council I wanted to include also the infallibility of the ordinary Magisterium of the Popes (in the aforementioned delineated sense) in this statement: " For we are fully cognizant of the fact that this See of St. Peter always remains untainted by any error, according to the divine promise of Our Lord and Savior made to the prince of His disciples, ' I have prayed for you, that your faith may not fail; and once you have recovered, you in your turn must, sterengthen your brethern'" (Lk. .21 It is a question, then, of preservation from error, guaranteed to the constant Magisterium of the Roman Pontiffs, because they are successors of Peter, with regard to the guardianship of the faith of the whole Church. In this case the constant teaching of the Supreme Pontiffs is free from error, not only because it is in agreement with the constant and universal doctrine of the Church and of the Ecumenical Councils but also because it is unthinkable that the Popes would have repeatedly confirmed their Brethren in the faith and the entire Church in doctrine and morals contrary to divine revelation and harmful to their eternal salvation. It must indeed be kept in mind that, given the rarity of Ecumenical Councils in about two 19 2 Lumen gentium, n. 25 A, C. ° Cf. F. Hiirth, "Episcoporum 21 triplex munus ... , pp. 244-245. Pastor aeternus, c. 4, Denz.-Sch., n. 3070. CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 161 thousand years of the Church's history) and of solemn or ex cathedra definitions (Benedict XII on the beatific vision: Denz.-Sch. 1000; Pius IX on the Immaculate Conception of Mary: Denz.-Sch. 2803; Pius XII on the bodily Assumption of Mary: Denz.-Sch. 3903), the guardianship of divine truth, the progress of Christians in faith and morals, the very diffusion and authentic interpretation of the thought of the Councils, has depended principally on the ordinary Magisterium of the Supreme Pontiffs. Finally, there seems to be no exclusion of the case of an infallible act (" infallibilis effatio ") based upon a definitive interpretation (not defining, that is, not pronounced with the customary formula and solemnity) obliging the whole Church to the submission of faith. 22 This would be verified (according to some theologians), for instance, in the condemnation uttered by Pius XI in his Encyclical, Casti connubii, against the abuse of marriage. 23 e. The authenticity or divine value of the ordinary Magisterium of the Bishops and of the Supreme Pontiff There is the pertinent twofold declaration of the Constitution Lumen gentium: Bishops are preachers of the faith who lead new disciples to Christ. They are authentic teachers, that is, teachers endowed with the authority of Christ, who preach to the people committed to them the faith they must believe and put into practice. By the light of the Holy Spirit(" sub lumine Sancti Spiritus ") , they make that faith clear . . . vigilantly warding off any errors which threaten their flock. Bishops, teaching in communion with the Roman Pontiff, are to be respected by all as witnesses to divine and Catholic truth. In matters of faith and morals, the Bishops speak in the name of Christ and the faithful are to accept their teaching and adhere to it with a religious submission. This religious sub22 I. Salaverri, S. J., "From the certain and manifest intention of obliging all the faithful to absolute assent, the infallible exercise of the ordinary Magisterium can be inferred, no matter whether it is the Pope or the Church " (De Ecclema Christi, n. 468 in Sacrae Theologiae Summa, 5 ed., [BAC, 195!l], vol. I). 23 AAS, (1930), p. 560, Denz.-Sch., n. 3717. 162 LUIGI ClAPP! mission of will and mind must be shown in a special way to the authentic teaching of the Roman Pontiff, even when he is not speaking ' ex cathedra.' That is, it must be shown in such a way that his supreme magisterium is acknowledged with reverence, the judgments made by him are sincerely adhered to, according to his manifest mind and will. His mind and will in the matter may be known chiefly either from the character of the documents, or from his frequent repetition of the same doctrine, or from his manner of speaking. 24 To understand well, and not to undervaluate, the sense and the burden of these declarations, it is useful to observe, with the Council itself, that the supernatural value of the Magisterium of the Church does not proceed only from its divine institution-now remote in time-but from the continual assistance of the Holy Spirit promised to it: usque ad consummationem saeculi: " And know that I am with you always; yes, to the end of time " (Mt. 28: 20) . In short, it is said of the ordinary Magisterium of the individual Bishops that they make clear " sub lumine Spiritus Sancti " the truths of faith and morals; for the acts of the extraordinary Magisterium of the Ecumenical Councils and of the Roman Pontiff there IS mention made of the "assistentia Spiritus Sancti" or, as is stated, " praelucente Spiritu veritatis." 25 3. The submission of the faithful to the M agisterium of the Church a. Submission of divine and Catholic faith. This is due to acts of the infallible Magisterium. It is thus a question of divine truths, regarding faith and morals, proposed as revealed by God or as intimately connected with them. These are the proper object of such assent of faith, that is, of the act of theological faith. The formal motive, therefore, that is, the one truly determining and internally operating, is the authority of God revealing, because this alone is proportioned in an absolute manner with the divine truths which are believed, through the perfect identity existing between God in Himself •• Lumen gentium, n. 25 A. 25 Ibid., n. 25 A, C, D. CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 163 and God knowing Himself (Veritas Prima in essendo and V eritas perfecta in cognoscendo) . The proposition of the Church (in virtue of the divine assistance, that is, of the charism of truth) is only the indispensable condition (conditio sine qua non) so that our assent of faith might, even from the psychological and moral point of view, be perfectly tranquil. 26 However, the living Magisterium of the Church is the proximate and universal norm of faith, whose supreme rule will always remain divine revelation contained in the Sacred Books and in Tradition. 27 b. Submission of ecclesiastical faith to defined but not revealed truths It does not seem that the Constitution Lumen gentium authorizes the distinction of a twofold faith: one divine and Catholic, the act of the theological virtue by which one adheres to formally revealed truths; the other ecclesiastical, which would be an act of non-theological faith by which one adheres to truths which are proposed infallibily by the Church as connected with revealed truths. The Constitution speaks only of the submission of faith (" fidei obsequium ") 28 due to the 26 Cf. C. Journet, L'Eglise du Verbe Incarne, Essai de theologie speculative. I. Hierarchie apostolique, ed. (Desclee de Brouwer, 1955), p. fl04. 27 D. Mongillo, 0. P. rightly observes: "The infallible proposition of the truth on the part of the Church, even if normally required, is not an essential condition of the act of faith. Before the dogmatic definition or outside the Church personal certainty that a truth is revealed by God or connected with revealed datum obliges to belief. In such a case the truth will be believed with an act of divine faith which, however, cannot yet be said to be of divine-Catholic faith. Only public certainty (that guaranteed by a definition of the teaching Church) represents for all believers the obligatory and infallible norm of the faith " (S. Tommaso d'Aquino, La Somma teologica, Traduzione e commento a cura dei Domenicani italiani, XIV, La Fede e la Speranza [Firenze, 1966], p. 19). 28 Msgr. Philips comments: "Theologians, who are infatuated with exactness, can devote their attention in this case to a first-class challenge. The Constitution, a few lines farther on, stipulates that the object of infallibility extends to all assertions, even not formally revealed, but which prove themselves absolutely necessary to preserve intact the deposit of faith. These necessary affirmations would not be called into question without revelation itself being shaken by it. Indirectly, therefore, these truths also enjoy the guarantee of faith. A certain number of 164 LUIGI ClAPP! c. Religious submission of the will and the mind to the ordinary M agisterium It is a matter of that submission which the Constitution Lumen gentium mentions, especially in regard to the authentic ordinary Magisterium of the Supreme Pontiff, even when he does not speak ex cathedra. 29 There is thus required on the part of the faithful (not excepting theologians with respect to the Bishops and the latter with respect to the Pope) , not a simple " respectful silence " (silentium obsequiosum) but a" positive assent" (" adhaerere debent ") ,30 that is to say, an act of the mind; religious, that is, to be given through a religious motive, such as submission to the ecclesiastical authority to which the assistance of the Holy Spirit is promised; internal, inasmuch as it is an act of the intellect moved by the free will under the impulse of grace; morally certain, that is, not purely opiniative or dubitative but such as is required by motives which prudently exclude doubt. The motives, therefore, for the sincere internal submission are not the reasons cited by the Magisterium, according to the principle: " the strength of the authority is no more than the strength of the arguments." This is true on the plane of theologians apply here their theory (of rather recent date) of 'ecclesiastical faith.' Submission to the revealed truth commands, in the case that we are examining, an assent which excludes all hesitation, but is it opportune to speak of ' eccesiastical faith?' The term does not seem to us very happy. Certainly, if one reduces faith to intellectual assent pure and simple, the aforesaid expression incurs no reproach: the Church demands that our reason be inclined to this assent. But faith is even more than a mere knowing: it implies a homage to the living and true God, a free act caused by the grace that the Father accords us by sending us the Son and the Spirit. We cannot transfer this homage to any other subject in directing it to the Church. The latter, indeed, is only the sacrament or the means of salvation. The origin, the term, and the motive of true faith, its formal object, if you will, is found only in God alone. But God guarantees the declaration of the Church by affixing His seal to it so that we can ' believe ' what it preaches, not because of her authority but having Him in mind. These last remarks, it is true, go beyond the strict commentary on the Constitution Lume:n ge:ntium" (op. cit., p. 326). conciliar definitions. •• Cf. Lume:n ge;ntium, n. 25 A. 80 Ibid. CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 165 rational conscience, not on the plane of faith. 31 No, the true motive of assent (even when there is question of the interpretation of the natural law) to the proposition of the Magisterium is " the secure charism of truth (carisma veritatis certum) which exists, has existed, and will exist always in the Bishops the successors of the Apostles" (St. Irenaeus, Advers. haer. IV, PG 7, 1058 C). Therefore, that which seems better and more in conformity with personal thought or with that of the age in which one lives must not be upheld; on the contrary, the absolute and immutable truth preached from the beginning by the Apostles should never be believed, never be interpreted in PL 40) .32 another sense (Tertullian, De praescript., c. However, while the charisms, the gifts and the reasonings of the theologians cannot be convincing, both as to their existence and as to their probative value, the apostolic and episcopal charism is indisputable both as to its persistence in the Church and as to its genuine divine value. The reasons adduced by the Magisterium are not the true motive either of the assent to the truths of faith or of the assent to the proposition of the Church, but they render the one and the other easier, prompter and psychologically more satisfying. 33 d. Is it permissible, in the name of religious freedom and the freedom of science, to suspend assent and to discuss the doctrine of the M agisterium? The Decree Dignitatis humanae, on religious freedom, after having declared the right of man to freedom from every external coercion in seeking, embracing and professing divine truth, declares that the Catholic has the religious duty to adhere to the certain doctrine proposed by the Magisterium of the Church. In the formation of their consciences, the Christian faithful ought carefully to attend to the sacred and certain doctrine of the Cf. Pius XII, Alloc. Magnificate Dominum, AAS, 46 (1954), p. St. Pius X, Motu proprio Sacrorum antistitum, Sept. 1, 1910; Denz.-Sch., n. 2147. 33 Cf. F. Hi.irth, "Episcoporum triplex munus ... ," p. 31 32 166 LUIGI CIAPPI Church. 34 The Church is, by the will of Christ, the teacher of the truth. It is her duty to give utterance to, and authoritatively to teach, that truth which is Christ Himself, and also to declare and confirm by her authority those principles of the moral order which have their origin in human nature itself. 35 The obligation just noted is of its nature grave, because required by the duty of submitting oneself to the legitimate authority o£ the Church within the limits of its competence. Besides, it is a matter of avoiding a serious danger in the field of faith and morals. But, if in an exceptional case someone had clear arguments for doubting that the doctrine of the Church, not definitive and irreformable, is true, or that its decisions are just, he would not be held to internal assent, and yet the obligation of " silent submission" would remain. However, he cannot claim to find himself in such a situation by the sole fact that he is in the process of presenting some difficulties but not of adducing new and convincing arguments in favor of the contrary opinion, or of producing some new and relevant element in regard to the extension and the weight of the arguments already known. One can even admit that in some case there is a subjective good faith, based on the judgment of a mistaken conscience, for not adhering to the teaching of the Church; but no objective justification exists for a like negative attitude. 36 On the other hand, one cannot admit good faith in one who discusses in public, especially if it is in books or reviews destined for the general public, the teaching or the decisions o£ the ordinary Magisterium. 37 •• Cf. Pius XII, Radio message, May 23, 1952, AAS, 44 (1952), pp. 270-278. •• Declar. Dignitatis humanae, n. 14. 36 Cf. F. Hiirth, " Tuto doceri non potest," Divinitas V (1961), p. 842. 37 Pius XII: " But if the Supreme Pontiffs in their official documents purposely pass judgment on a matter up to that time under dispute, it is obvious that that matter, according to the mind and will of the same Pontiffs, cannot be any longer considered a question open to discussion among theologians." (Enc. Humani generis, AAS, 42 [1950], p. 568) . Msgr. Philips has observed, commenting on Lumen gentium: " But we cannot pass over in silence the case of a competent Christian who would have serious motives for preferring a divergent manner of thinking to CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 167 e. Living M agisterium and dead M agisterium? Pius XII recognized that theologians have the task of indicating in what way are contained in Sacred Scripture and in divine Tradition, explicitly or implicitly, those truths which are taught by the living Magisterium of the Church; and he adds: Together with those two sources [Sacred Scripture and Tradition] God has given to His Church a living Magisterium to elucidate and explain what is contained in the deposit of faith only obscurely and implicitly. This deposit of faith our divine Redeemer has given for authentic intepretation not to each of the faithful, not even to theologians, but only to the Magisterium of the Church. 38 From the context of the Encyclical Humani generis it appears to be clear that Pius XII, speaking of the living Magisterium, intends above all to signify the teaching of the Church of today, that is, of the Roman Pontiff and living Bishops, that is, of men of our time: it is to this Magisterium, the sole authentic intepreter of Scripture, of Tradition, of the Ecumenical Councils and of the pontifical documents of the past that the duty and right of being the proximate and universal norm " in matters of faith and morals" belong. The authentic judge, therefore, of dogmatic and theological progress in the Church remains alone the Magisterium of the Sacred Hierarchy, just as it is the one only authentic author of dogmatic definitions, which guarantee a secure and irreversible grasp of the truth, opening at the same time the way to new investigations and new grasps. Although innumerable masters of the faith are dead, as Peter himself is dead, the gates of hell (Mt. 16 : 18) , that is, the forces of error and of death, the official directives, or who could cause founded motives to be produced for leaving the question in doubt. He would not, with the best will in the world, be forced to an interior assent. Besides, no one forbids him to continue his investigations as long as he avoids throwing discredit, through spite or intellectual pride, on the declarations of the Magisterium. In practice, this man would have to observe a great prudence in order to prevent a public debate in which sentence would be pronounced by a tribunal of incompetents. This attitude is commanded of him by the respect due not only to the Magisterium but also to his brethren in the faith, whom it is not lawful to cast temererally and without any profit into inextricable conflicts of conscience" (op. cit., p. 323). 88 Enc. Humani generis, loc. cit., p. 569. 168 LUIGI CIAPPI have not prevailed, nor will they ever prevail against the indefectible and infallible Magisterium. From what has been said to this point, one will have to conclude logically that new dogmatic formulas, although activating a true conceptual progress over and above terminology, cannot render vain, surpassed and useless, or have held to be false or adapted only to the philosophical mentality of other times, the formulas with which the Magisterium has expressed divine truths in its documents. In fact, the definitions formulated by the Ecumenical Councils of antiquity, of the Middle Ages, of Trent, of Vatican I, and those pronounced personally by the Roman Pontiffs, have been the true, proper and exact expression of divine revelation and of the truths intimately connected with it, even though in a human and conceptual, and thus analogical and imperfect form. Under this aspect one can speak of only " approximate " truth, compared, that is, to the divine reality, infinite, not possibly contained within the limitations of concepts and words, ineffable. But the absolute transcendence of divine truth is not synonymous with total diversity, even though there is a greater diverity than similarity between uncreated and created truth. 39 IV. OVERCOMING THE CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM IN THE YEAR OF FAITH The Synod of Bishops, in which a widespread and preoccupying crisis of faith even in the authentic Magisterium of the Church was deplored, has been celebrated, providentially, during the " Year of Faith." Paul VI, although he lamented such a crisis also in his Apostolic Exhortation Petrum et Paulum, sent to all the Bishops of the Catholic Church on the 19th centenary of the glorious martyrdom of Saints Peter and Paul, has expressed the confidence that in this very year such a crisis will be overcome. •• Lateran Council IV: "Between the Creator and the creature so great a likeness cannot be without the necessity of noting a greater dissimilarity between them " (Denz.-Sch. 806). CRISIS OF THE MAGISTERIUM, CRISIS OF FAITH? 169 But here now we have this anniversary of the Apostles, come round again on the wheel of time, to strengthen our faith in the true meaning of that term, to encourage study of the teachings of the recent ecumenical council, to sustain the energies of Catholic thought in its search for fresh and original expressions while remaining faithful to the doctrinal " deposit " of the Church, eodem sensu eademque sententia. This anniversary offers to every child of holy Church the happy opportunity of giving to Jesus Christ, the Son of God, the mediator and accomplisher of revelation, a humble and exalting " I believe," the full assent of intellect and will to His word, His person and His mission of salvation; it thus offers an opportunity of giving honor to those distinguished witnesses to Christ, Peter and Paul, by renewing the Christian commitment of a sincere and effective profession of faith, theirs and ours, and by continuing to pray and work for the reestablishment of all Christians in the unity of the same faith. 40 The "Year of Faith " will thus have to revive in all Catholics the persuasion that " on the faith of Peter reposes the whole edifice of the holy Church" (c£. Mt. 16: 16-19) and that, consequently, on the faith and on the Magisterium of his successors the whole dynamism of our spiritual, supernatural life, which thus irradiates its influence in apostolic action by contact with the modern world, must find conscious and tranquil solidity. In other words, the sensus fidei of the learning Church must be in accord with the sensus fidei of the teaching Church because, although there is only one Spirit of truth who illumines directly the minds of believers by leading them to the sweet assent to divine truth and inciting them to develop the seed of the faith received in Baptism, the full certainty of following the illuminations of the Spirit is not had except in adhering to the objective, authentic teaching of the Bishops, and, above all, of the Roman Pontif£.41 If the Fathers of Vatican Council II have required such submission of all true disciples of Christ, they have done so, not from ambition to dominate or from a spirit of paternalism but because they are convinced of having received with episcopal consecration itself 40 41 L'Osservatore Romano, Feb. 23, 1967. Cf. Lumen gentium, n. 25. 170 LUIGI ClAPP! the certain charism of the authentic M agisterium in the service of divine truth and of the whole People of God, according to the words of Jesus Christ to His apostles: "Anyone who listens to you listens to me; anyone who rejects you rejects me, and those who reject me reject the one who sent me " (Lk. 10: 16) ; " Go out to the whole world; proclaim the Good News to all creation. He who believes ... will be saved; he who does not believe will be condemned." (Mk. 16: 15-16). The Magisterium, therefore, has full awareness of being above the People of God, not as though it were not, even its Pastors, the sheep of Christ, members of His Mystical Body; but the Bishops know that they are over others inasmuch as they are true representatives of Christ the Head of the People of God, although they also are equal to others by communion in the same faith and by the bond of the same ecclesial charity. The Holy Father has nobly expressed this awareness, proper to the Hierarchy, on the day sacred to the Purification of the Blessed Virgin and the Presentation of the Child Jesus, "Light of the Gentiles," in the Temple: Illumined obedience seeks the divine design which beholds in the People of God the presence and action of Christ's representatives as a cause which we well understand is instrumental but genetic and natural. These representatives are endowed with Christ's pastoral authority and the charisms of magisterium, of leadership and of sanctification for the service and the salvation of the community of the faithful. The Church is hierarchical, not inorganic, and not even democratic in the sense that the community itself should have a priority of faith and authority over those whom the Holy Spirit has placed at the head of Church of God (cf. Acts 20: 28); that is to say, that the Lord wanted some of the brethren to have the unquestionable mandate (cf. I Cor. 4 :4) of giving to other brethren the service of authority. of leadership as a principle of unity, of order, of solidarity, of efficiency, always so as to form that economy of truth and of charity which is called " His Church." 42 LUIGI CrAPPI, 0. P. Master of the Sacred Apostolic Palace Vatican City •• L'Osservatwe Romano, Feb. 3, 1968. TO KNOW THE MYSTERY: THE THEOLOGIAN IN THE PRESENCE OF THE REVEALED GOD (Concluded) PART IV. THE NoN-CONCEPTUAL LOGICAL W II IN THE DYNAMISM OF OuR THEO- THOUGHT E HAVE elaborated a certain dynamism present in our theological knowledge of the divine Reality. In so doing we showed the possibility of by-passing certain problems in theology (e. g., in reference to Malet) by realizing i) that our concepts, though expressing something that was formally in God, looked for their verification in an order of infinite simplicity, where God is indeed the "Ineffable One," and ii) that these concepts were affirmed of the divine Reality as concretely given in salvation history. Of itself, this would indicate a certain necessary dynamism in our knowledge before the transcendent Reality of the revealed God. It indicates, too, the direction in which we should look for a non-conceptual depth in our theological knowledge, in that the Reality that is presented to our intelligences can be apprehended only in and through faith, with its firm, dark, personal " Yes " to all that God is and has done. Accordingly, insofar as faith has a non-conceptual element, and because theology is a reflection-in-the-faith, we may look for a nonconceptual element in our theological thought. In this way we shall be able to see the realism of the theological noetic, in its attainment of its object, in that the conceptual element lives from a non-conceptual element which grounds it and gives it a depth of realism that any purely notional knowledge would not have. In other words, here is a chance to see how the " objective orientation" of our concepts occurs, to use the phrase of 171 ANTHONY J. KELLY E. Schillebeeckx.Ho He has drawn our attention to the fact of the non-conceptual in our knowledge, but in so doing he has lessened the formal role of the concept in our knowledge of God who was known merely in a non-conceptual way. In this process of knowing, the whole knowing subject is involved; to this extent there must be not only an objective signification in our knowing but also a depth of personal significance. 141 This aspect of significance surrounding and enveloping our notional knowledge calls for close consideration. And an increasing number of theologians have become interested in the question. 142 On the philosophical level the problem of our non-conceptual knowledge has been one of the great preoccupations of the modern post-Kantian era. 143 This contribution will be made from the " Thomistic standpoint " (in the sense explained, with the necessary speculative flexibility in the face of more modern insights) and with a necessary limitation, for here we must be content with sketching merely the basic principles. Implied in the notion of faith is the assent to the divine Reality through a conceptual determination. 144 Our study uo Revelation et theol., 108 ff. Cf. also 343: "a proprement parler nous n'appliquons pas le concept lui-meme a Dieu, mais le contenu conceptuel tend vers Dieu." Here we take up the question of how does the concept " tend towards " the divine Reality, having shown the fact that the concept is, in a sense, properly applied to God, not as representing Him but as formally directing our affirmation of the divine Reality. " 1 " Signification " I here define as the abstract conceptual, expressable content of our concepts. " Significance" is the non-fully conceptualizable "plus " in our consciousness, in that our whole personal life is axiologically orientated toward a given reality and implicitly recognized as such. " 2 E. Schillebeeckx, op. cit., 106-110; ff., etc. J. Mouroux, "Presence de Ia raison dans la foi," loc. cit., C. Cirne-Lima, Der Personale Glaube (Innsbruck, 1959), engl. Personal Faith (New York, 1965); L. Melevez, "Theologie contemplative et theologie discursive," Nouvelle Revue Theologique, 86 (1964), M. Dupuy, "Experience spirituelle et theologie comme science," ibid. (1964)' 1137-1162. 148 Cf. J. Girardi, "Les facteurs extra-intellectuels de la connaissance," Revue Philosophique de Louvain, (1964), 477-500; G. Klubertanz, "Where is the evidence for Thomistic Metaphysics," ibid., 56 (1958), 144 " Ad fidem duo requiruntur: quorum unum est cordis inclinatio ad credendum; et hoc non est ex auditu sed ex dono gratiae. Aliud autem est determinatio de credibili, et istud est ex auditu." Ad Rom., c. 10, lect. TO KNOW THE MYSTERY 178 must concentrate on the connection between these two; thus by examining the dynamism of faith we can arrive at some further conclusions regarding the unique noetic of theology, which is the prolongation of faith into reflection. E. Brunner has well characterized the position of the theologian as being a wandering between two worlds, for in theological thought there is a doubleness: the theologian is at once a scientific thinker comprehending objectively and a believer darkly affirming the revealed God: " this is the particular burden and difficulty of theology." 145 The burden enters in when the theologian, in accord with the scientific exigencies of thought, is forced to elaborate and analyze the realities of Revelation on a purely conceptual level, which of its nature seems a long way from that personal encounter with truth experienced in faith and Revelation. This sense of doubleness and burden would be mitigated, were it realized that theology, in its vital connection with the affirmation of faith, has a unique non-conceptual depth springing from a special dynamism which is at work. I. A philosophical note on the dynamism of personal knowledge There is a great deal of literature available to help us in this note. As was remarked before, it has been one of the great preoccupations of post-Kantian philosophy to ground our conceptual knowledge, to have not merely a notional affirmation of reality but a " real " affirmation of it. This distinction originated in the writings of J. H. Newman and has been much popularized by Blondel, Olle-Laprune, and other modern philosophers.146 " 5 E. Brunner, Wahrheit als Begegnung (Ziirich, 1963), engl. Truth as Encounter (London, 1964), 113. " 6 J. Girardi, op. cit.; G. Klubertanz, op. cit.; C. Cirne-Lama, op. cit.; W. Kern, " Das verhiiltniss von Erkenntnis und Liebe als Philosophisches Grundproblem bei Hegel und Thomas von Aquin," Scholastik 34 (1959), 394-427; A. Forest, "Connaissance et Amour," Revue Thomiste 48 (1948), 113-122; M. Roland-Gosselin, "de Ia connaissance affective," Revue des sciences Philosophiques et Theologiques 27 (1938) 5-27; J. de Finance, Etre et Agir dans la philosophie de S. Thomas (Rome, 1960), J. Lebacz, Certitude et volonte (Paris, 1962), an excellent bibliography for modern work. 174 ANTHONY J. KELLY Our concern here is to stress, not so much the " real " content of our knowledge in general but the special depth of our notional knowledge regarding another person, and this again, not in general but insofar as this person is the object of our love. The first observation that can be made is that our knowledge is situated in a larger noetic process than that represented by the formally and statically signifying role of the concept. The whole knowing subject is involved. There is, indeed, a notional element, that is, various intelligible aspects of the reality are disengaged by the intellect; these can be formally expressed in their precise meaning and validly analyzed; they can be correlated and finally synthesized into one intuition of the known object whether it be personal or not; in the evidence of this intuition, the reality in question can be affirmed to be such and such. This is the necessary objective and formal aspect of our knowledge. As such, it is the interior necessary component of any objective appreciation of extra-mental reality; for the reality is signified, represented to us through our concepts in its essential meaning, in its formal intelligibility; we could call this type of knowledge the knowledge of " signification." But there is another element, subjective where the other is objective, "real " or " existential " when the other is notional or essential, dynamic where the other is more statically representative. The reality in question is present to our consciousness, not merely as a thing objectively expressed but as a reality which is " lived." In this way, it is not apprehended as objected to us, exterior to our personal life, but as something or someone which intimately pertains to us. The reality is not thrown up to our minds as to an analytical faculty for speculative appraisal and notional assent, but as a reality which is part of our life, part of our " self consciousness," part of ourselves; it is " significant." 147 This appreciation of reality as something significant as well as signified is based on what has been traditionally called 147 J. Girardi, op. cit., 802 ff. TO KNOW THE MYSTERY 175 " connatural " knowledge. This type of knowledge enables us to put the cognitive process into a more existential and personal context. Along with the conceptual attainment of the reality in itself, in its ontological essence, the knowledge of connaturality implies an axiological attainment of the reality; this axiological "touching" of the reality takes place in the object's livedreference to the person, in its functional role toward the knowing subject, as "quid intime suum." As J. de Finance has remarked, man is by no means "pure thought"; there is, and must be, an " au-dela " to our concepts. 148 Whatever spiritual activity we talk about, whether it be cognitive or volitional, it must not be forgotten that it is the person who is acting; knowing and loving are the two dimensions of personal life. Not only are these two operations to be considered as springing from the one spiritual subject but lived in the one consciousness: the person is present to himself in these operations, conscious of himself as the one who is, in this double way, opened out to the infinite expanse of being. Consequently, knowledge and love, despite their inverse orientations, do not exist, as it were, in two parallel and independent lines of personal life but as two aspects of the one personal openness to the unlimited horizon of being and perfection. There is in this double fecundity of personal life, on the one hand, an expression of the perfection of reality to oneself in knowing; and, on the other, through this interior expression of the other-ness of reality to oneself, within oneself, there results an inclination toward the reality as it exists, a love of reality in its actual present existence. Knowledge is terminated within the spirit; love finds its term in the real order of things, in their full existential actuality. Hence, reality has a double relationship to the person, in his openness towards the Infinite and the Absolute: Now a thing is found to have a twofold relationship to the soul: one by which the thing itself is in the soul in the soul's manner and not in its own, the other by which the soul is referred to the thing 148 Etre et Agir, 337. 176 ANTHONY J. KELLY in its own existence. Thus something is an object of the soul in two ways. I) It is so inasmuch as it is capable of being in the soul, not according to its own act of being, but according to the manner of the soul, i.e., spiritually. And this is the essential constituent of the knowable insofar as it is knowable. Something is the object of the soul according as the soul is inclined and oriented to it after the manner of the thing itself as it is in itself. This is the essential constituent of the appetible insofar as it is appetible. 149 Here we have a clear expression of the inverse orientation of spiritual life of the person, fruitful in the sense of " owning," according to the spiritual manner of being of the knowing subject, reality, in an objective interior expression of it. Together there is a complementary tendency of the knowing subject toward the reality in its real existence, affecting the spiritual subject toward the real in itself, attracting it to a good outside itself. * * * * * Since then it is the one reality attained under two aspects and the one person open spiritually to the totality of the existent, the life of the spirit can be expressed as a circular movement, as the person in his spiritual consciousness expresses the perfection of the reality outside of himself, within himself, and through that expression tends to the full attainment of that reality in its actual existence. 150 This circular movement in the spiritual life of the person results in a mutual interpenetration of the two spiritual faculties: the mind understands the good as the good of the whole person and in this understanding presents it to the will to be sought for and attained; the will desires truth for the mind, so that the personal life will be based on objective reality and so that the person, through the knowing faculty, will express the perfections of reality within himself and thus be established in communion with the totality of the existent order. In other words, in the spiritual life of the person there 149 150 a. 1. De Verit., q. 22, a. 10. Ibid., q. 1, a. 2; de Divinis Nominibus, c. 4, lect. 10; Summa Theol., I, q. 16, TO KNOW THE MYSTERY 177 is union and communion in that double fecundity of knowing and loving which is proper to the person as a spiritual being. 151 The spiritual presence of the objective reality within the mind of the persons enables the will to be determined, specified; thus informed by the intellect it attains or tends toward the existent reality in its full axiological and existential dimensions, as this reality is concretely referred to the person. On its part, the faculty of love adds a depth of real content to the knowledge of the intellect, especially to the purely intellectual or conceptual knowledge that it enjoys: in the one personal knowing consciousness the will, in its actual tendency toward the existent reality as it exists in its concrete existence, aligns our conceptual knowledge with the actual existent thing; our conceptual knowledge is " clothed over " with the tendencytoward-the-real under the influence of the love in the will. It is only by mutual envelopment that each faculty develops in the line of its own attainment; the will being enveloped by the knowing faculty attains the true good, and the intellect, enveloped in the movement of the will; is conscious of the whole reality. Thus the possibility of dynamism in our knowledge becomes apparent; there is in the knowing consciousness a conceptual and non-conceptual element. The conceptual element is indeed a valid, formal expression of reality, but it is completed by a non-conceptual affective knowledge which gives it an existential depth, which the concept taken abstractly, in itself, does not have. As has been said, the reason for this mutual interpenetration of the faculties in the full dynamism of knowledge is because both faculties are pertaining to the one conscious personal life. The person, in the presence of some meaningful reality, is conscious not only of the meaning of the reality in itself but also of an existential content of that reality in reference to him. He knows it as his reality, as a thing not merely "known" but "lived": he knows it as something that belongs to him, pertains to his life. And this is all the more the case when it is 151 On this interpretation of intelligence and will cf. W. Kern, "das Verhiiltnis von Erkenntnis und Liebe ... ," Scholastik 34 (1959), 415-421. 178 ANTHONY J, KELLY considered that through an act of "free-will," of self-commitment, he has invited this reality, whatever it be, into his conscious personallife. 152 Obviously this has the utmost pertinence when we speak of interpersonal knowledge; there is not only the conceptual knowledge of the person as an object, but in the consciousness there is the presence of this person as a " thou " because of the love experienced toward this person as part of oneself. This consciousness is heightened the more the person is affirmed as a " thou " by the supremely conscious and personal act of free commitment with regard to that person, so that the whole personal consciousness of the " I " is " affected " by the living presence of the " thou." In such a case our intellectual conceptual knowledge would be immensely enriched by an" au-dela" which, while remaining inexpressible, would give a personal and existential depth to the whole process of conceptual knowledge. The presence of the beloved person to the consciousness of the loving-knowing subject is partially based on what he has already apprehended about the object of love; but the knowing power of the mind does not rest in the consciousness that it has exhausted the full mystery of the beloved. Impelled by love the intelligence continues to seek a deeper insight into the object of love by the contemplation of every aspect that is accessible regarding the life and personality of the " thou ": As to the apprehensive power, the beloved is said to be in the lover, inasmuch as the beloved abides in the apprehension of the lover ... the lover is said to be in the beloved, inasmuch as the lover is not satisfied with a superficial apprehension of the beloved, but strives to gain an intimate knowledge of everything pertaining to the beloved, so as to penetrate into his very soul,153 Thus the knowing life of the lover is dominated and concentrated in a striving to understand more intimately the reality of the beloved. However, it is not only the conscious orientation of the 152 For a good analysis of this aspect, see C. Cirne-Lima, op. cit., 415-421, and J. Girardi, loc. cit., 62 (1965), 336-346. 153 Summa Theol., I-II, q. 28, a. 2. TO KNOW THE MYSTERY 179 knowing powers that is a constituting factor of the presence of the "thou" but also that consciousness of the attraction that the loved object exerts over the heart of the lover; this increases the mutual inherence of the beloved and the lover that makes the knowledge of the " thou " more and more real to the consciousness. The lover is conscious of his axiological affection toward the beloved which is mysteriously grasped as present in this tendency: " the object loved is said to be in the lover, inasmuch as it is in his affections by a kind of complacency. • • ." 154 This consciousnes of the beloved as a presence is completed by a sense of being" in the other," in a sympathy, in an affective oneness of life and love " ... the lover ... seeks to possess the beloved perfectly, by penetrating into his heart, as it were ... as though he were become one with him." 155 The beloved person is not merely esteemed as a good for oneself but esteemed as oneself, as another " I," a presence in one's consciousness that cannot be expressed in merely conceptual terms, even though these conceptual elements are necessary ones for initial knowledge, objective appraisal and communication. Nonetheless the knowing-loving subject is conscious of the inadequacy of conceptual expression to express this mystery of the " thou " which he lives. Thus conceptual knowledge may have a depth of non-conceptual knowledge, an axiological and affective element creating the dynamism of connatural knowledge by which the mind is borne beyond its notional and conceptual grasp of reality to a more intimate yet inexpressible knowledge of this reality. There is always the objective signification of the known reality, but, through the influence of affective knowledge, there is also the factor of subjective significance. * * * * * This total, dynamic view of human knowing allows for attentional and intentional aspects 156 which do not pertain to the conceptual level of knowledge, as such. 15 A.6yo> and p.w6r7J>• of right reason and the virtuous mean, which does not consist in a mathematical point but may be attained and realized with more or less exactitude, in a greater or lesser degree of perfection. The term itself is found for the first time, it would appear, in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas. He uses it, however, principally in the domain of the virtue of justice; there the medium rationis is precisely the medium rei (cf. p. 388). That is by and large true; but, I think it should be pointed out, too, that St. Thomas does apply it also to the vice or the sin of envy (cf. de Malo, q. 10, a. 2 in fine corp.), which is in the domain not of justice but of charity. And that, it seems, is of vital importance. The term and concept were of very secondary importance for St. Thomas, and continued to be so right up to the 16th century. The all-important thing for him was the greater or lesser disorder caused in the order of charity (the subiectio hominis ad Deum and the foedus humanae societatis [see II Sent., d. 42, q. 1, a. 4; also Summa Theol., I-11, q. 88, a. 2; de Malo, q. 7, a. 1; q. 10, a. 2l), together with the intensity and depth of personal involvement. I think Meier's penetrating expose would have gained much in clarity and precision had he gone to the trouble of explaining in a special section the very important notion of a moral object. St. Thomas, then, was ever conscious of the immense complexity of human action and ever avoided the pitfall of over-simplification. For that reason, I cannot altogether agree with Meier when he maintains that St. Thomas understands the term exclusively of the material object of an act of justice (nur sachbezogen, p. 350) and proceeds to see in that a discrepancy between the mind of Aquinas and that of Cajetan (p. 353-354) . St. Thomas always sees human activity in its totality, in its objective or essential determinedness and in its subjective, intersubjective and existential relatedness. Meier very rightly sees in that the special genius of Aquinas (p. 391). From the 16th century on there appears a complete shifting of emphasis that utlimately leads to the heated discussions caused by the teaching of Sanchez that delectatio venerea admits of levity of matter (p. 360-361). St. Thomas's comprehensiveness of view was gradually and definitively lost sight of and all human activity was reduced to legal and lifeless categories. It is in this theological climate that the peccatum mortale ex toto genere suo first makes its appearance in the Theologia moralis (Cologne, 1707-1714) of CLAUDIUS LACROIX. The expression is the crowning product of a depersonalized and devitalized moral theology. It was not immediately accepted by moral theologians, as its absence from the works of Billuart and Alphonsus de Liguori witnesses. However, it was taken up again over a century later by Scavini in his Theologia moralis universa ad mentem S. Alphonsi de Ligorio (Novara, 1847) and put forward as an Alphonsian category! Thence in passed into the manuals of today. BOOK REVIEWS 251 It is impossible to do justice to Meier's work in a short review. It is a piece of historico-speculative research competently and even brilliantly done. Strange as it may seem for such a technical and scientific work, it pulsates with life and must certainly be regarded as one of the major contributions towards an authentic renewal in moral theology produced in recent times. Meier is convinced that no true advance and no true renewal can be realized in the field of theology unless it be built upon tradition. Through study and pastoral experience he is fully aware of the modem Problematik and of the pressing need for new answers to new problems and questions. And with that in view he sets about attempting to point up the authentic theological tradition in one single, but very important, corner of the immense field of Christian moral theology. His historical investigation is fully documented, meticulous and, according to the demands of the problems under examination, complete. His speculative and scientific presentation and understanding of an extremely complex and delicate problem -the mystery, namely, of sin-is subtle, profound and satisfying. Meier is careful to point out that right along the line of the authentic tradition in Christian moral theology sin was always and ever understood in the context of the history of salvation, of the Heilsgeschichte; it was always understood with reference not so much to a law of some kind or other but to a person, to the person of God and of Christ the Savior, and then and only then in reference to a law, when that law is understood as the law of charity which implies, of necessity, the subiectio et reverentia hominis ad Deum and the convictus societatis humanae (cf. de Malo, q. 7, a. 1, in fine). In that sense moral theology, and in a special way its approach to sin in the life of Christ's followers, may be considered not only theocentric and christocentric but also nomocentric.-The only important critical remark with regard to Meier's work as a whole has been made above, namely, with reference to the absence of any special treatment of the meaning of moral object. The notion, technical as it may appear, is of the utmost importance in both the sphere of speculative and scientific investigation and in that of practical life. Meier does touch on the question frequently in passing. But in the end one is left wondering what a "moral object" really is. As the present reviewer sees things, it is only through a very precise notion of what a moral object is that one can attain to an understanding of the full meaning of parvity of matter with all its implications. That St. Thomas's concept of the object (and end) of vice or virtue, of sin or merit or of the whole moral life as such, was not exclusively matter-centered or object-centered (as Meier would seem to imply on p. 350) is clearly shown by this word of Thomas: "bonum illud ad quod virtus ordinatur non est accipiendum quasi aliquod obiectum alicuius actus; sed illud bonum est ipse actus perfectus, quem virtus elicit " (de Verit., q. 14, a. 3, ad 3: this text is to be found verbatim in BOOK REVIEWS the commentary of St. Thomas's favourite student, the later Cardinal Annibaldo degli Annibaldeschi, on the third book of Lombard's sentences, dist. art. ad a work that was often attributed to St. Thomas himself and is found is the complete edition of his works by Vives, t. 30, p. 539b). For St. Thomas the whole of moral theology, and the whole of moral life a fortiori, is at one and same time both object and subject centered. That is why he insists so strongly on the fact that human actions are specified by the end (cf. Summa Theol., I-II, q. 1, a. 3; q. 18, aa. 4 & 6) and receive their moral structural specification, their ratio boni et mali, not from the matter or object alone of the act, but also from the subjective disposition of the moral agent, ex aliqua dispositione agentis (ibid., I-II, q. 88, in fine corp.). That is why, too, one may be allowed to think that St. Thomas would have answered Lacroix and the rest: there can be no such thing as a peccatum mortale ex TOTO genere suo! On one other point-and it is not unconnected with what has just ben said--one ventures to express a certain disagreement with Meier: St. Thomas's teaching on the parvitas materiae, as far as it goes, is seen to be an application, on the theological level and in the context of the life of those striving to attain to the full stature of the grace of Christ, of Aristotle's teaching on the virtuous mean: as "the man of practical wisdom would determine it" (Aristotle, Eth. Nich., ch. 6, 1107 a 1), that is, as the man enlightened by attachment to Christ in a faith shot through with love for and devotedness to the person and example of the Savior would determine it. Meier's book is so important that one dares to hope that the translator and publisher will be found to bring out an English version of it. CoRNELIUS WILLIAMS, 0. P. 895 Kaufbeuren Germany The Pilgrim Church. By GEORGE TAVARD. New York: Herder & Herder, 1967. Pp. 176. $4.95. Today in the American Catholic Church we are witnessing a widening gap between a relatively small but sophisticated group of people who are already moving well beyond the newer insights of Vatican II and the vast majority of Catholics who lag behind and whose ideas about the Church have undergone little change since the Council. What is needed, at least in part, is a greater abundance of solid, yet popularized theological literature. Many a Catholic, layman or priest, is lost between the superficialities of Time magazine on the one hand and the obscurities of Rahner and Schillebeeckx on the other. George Tavard's new book, " The Pilgrim BOOK REVIEWS 253 Church," is admirably suited to this large section of the Catholic population that has yet to assimilate fully the teaching of the Council. What we have here, then, is not another theological specialist writing for his fellowspecialists but a knowledgeable theologian who succeeds in elaborating the main themes of the Council Constitution on the Church in a simple, yet not over-simplified language. " The Pilgrim Church " is, in the main, a collection of lectures given by Tavard on various occasions since the Council on the principal themes of the Vatican II document on the Church. When he does touch on other declarations of the Council, it is only insofar as they relate to the central topics of the Constitution on the Church. Tavard's book is not, however, a chapter by chapter commentary on the Council document. Thus, while he has separate chapters on chapters I (the Mystery of the Church), II (the People of God), III (the Hierarchy) and VI (Religious), he combines his treatment of chapters V (the Universal Call to Holiness) and VII (the Eschatological Nature of the Pilgrim Church) of the Constitution in one chapter. Tavard has no separate consideration of the chapters on the Blessed Virgin Mary and the Laity, although the latter theme is necessarily included when he speaks of the people of God in general. The professional theologian will perhaps be most interested in his opening chapter where he writes of the theological setting of Vatican II. The author gives a brief but balanced over-view of the theological context of the Council, particularly the post-war period leading up to the opening of the Council. It is Tavard's judgment that the theologians who usually got the major share of publicity during the Council were not " the true pioneers without whose prophetic work the Council could not have taken place." (35) On the whole this reviewer agrees, but it is difficult to understand how Tavard can exclude Rahner from the ranks of the true pioneers of the Council. Throughout these essays Tavard is at pains to emphasize the continuities between the teaching of Vatican II and past Church teaching. Any Catholic whose theological knowledge has remained on the level of superficial slogans will be surprised to read: "I would tend to rehabilitate the Counter-Reformation as a providential link between the great theology of the Middle Ages and that which may characterize, let us hope, the dawning 21st century." (36) Tavard himself has already begun this rehabilitation process in the area of scripture and tradition in his worthwhile " Holy Writ or Holy Church." At this point, however, it is good to keep in mind the distinction between the Counter-Reformation and the post- Tridentine period. Oftentimes the latter period did little more than parrot the answers of the previous age. Tavard's stress on continuities is evident at many other points. Thus " the common priesthood has ever been an essential point of Catholic 254 BOOK REVIEWS teaching." (75) He also sees nothing new in the Council's statements on the collegiality of the bishops, " except, to some extent, the word." (95) Tavard certainly has historical evidence on his side. Such doctrines as the universal priesthood and the collegiality of the bishops have been propounded in some way down through Christian history. However, we must be less sanguine when we refer to popular preaching, especially in the period between Vatican I and II. The average layman was completely unaware of his share in the priesthood of Christ. Indeed, the Council debates showed that many bishops had a very poor realization of their own collegiality. Now the primary exercise of the Church's teaching office is in and through the liturgy. Therefore we can find small consolation that such doctrines were taught in some past age or on some higher level when they were neglected in ordinary preaching. The only place in the book where Tavard develops his own thought beyond the Council documents in a significant way is in his chapter on religious. He finds the specific characteristic of religious life in community rather than in the three traditional counsels. PETER DEMAN, 0. P. Berkeley Priory Berkeley, California A New Catechism: Catholic Faith for Adults. New York: Herder, 1967. Pp. 510. $6.00. Herder and This generally excellent translation presents to English-speaking peoples the effort of many Dutch Catholics-bishops and theologians, priests and lay folk-to express Catholic doctrine in contemporaneously meaningful terminology and in a style judged suited to present Western culture. The prevailing "mood" of this book is existentialism and Teilhardism ecumenically oriented. Consequently, it will appeal very strongly to a rather welldefined segment of Western society. The sustained, vigorous effort to present the faith to that segment, and to all twentieth-century men, is completely admirable. The work qualifies as a true catechism for it is a highly systematic, even lengthy, presentation of Christian doctrine and morality. Unlike most catechisms, it is written in continuous narrative form; its approach is more historical than dogmatic; its discussion of the meaning of doctrine usually begins from human experience rather than from the implications of the terms in which God's revelation is communicated to us. But the Catechism's most striking single characteristic is its embrace and extensive use of the existentialist- Teilhardian categories and rhetoric. BOOK REVIEWS By a familiar paradox this outstanding strength is closely related to the book's most remarkable vulnerability. The near-total embrace of the favored outlook and terminology (other factors may be involved) often works to hide full Catholic doctrine rather than to communicate it, to suppress rather than to express. To discuss, even to cite, all instances of this would be undesirable, perhaps impossible, in a brief review. Instead, in two areas, namely, Catholic dogma and morality, this review will suggest a few " samples " illustrative of tendencies characteristic of the work as a whole. 1. In the field of Catholic dogma. a) Catholic faith holds that Christ " was born of the Virgin Mary" and that Mary is " ever-virgin." Discussing what this dogma says or means, the author writes that the evangelists Matthew and Luke " proclaim that this birth does not depend on what men can do of themselves ... This is the deepest meaning of the article of faith ' born of the Virgin Mary ' ... The gospels do not say that she (Mary) had other children after him (Jesus)." (pp. 75-77) Both the statement that the mystery's "deepest meaning " is mystical and the statement about the silence of the gospels are patently true. But do the two statements adequately communicate the Church's understanding of this mystery? Never denying a "deepest" mystical sense to the mystery, the entire Catholic community has always affirmed that the dogma has an obvious, physical sense also, namely, that "the Mother of God, the holy and ever-virgin Mary ... conceived God the Word without seed ... and without corruption brought him forth" (Council of the Lateran, a. 649, can. 3; Denz.-Schon. 503), so that "the unspotted virginity (of Mary) did not know (experience) ... coitus" (Council of Toledo XI, Symbolum fidei, Denz.-Schon. 533). The Catholic tradition understands this physical meaning to be the basis of the deeper, mystical interpretations of the mystery; and this first meaning the Catechism leaves simply unmentioned. In the question of the perpetuity of Mary's virginity is Catholic belief communicated by stating only that the gospels are silent on the point? Conceding evangelical silence, the Catholic community nevertheless asserts that Mary's perpetual virginity is divinely revealed, so that "if anyone shall not confess (that the Word of God) was incarnate of the holy ... and ever-vigin Mary . . . " he is in heresy (II Constantinople, can. Denz.-Schon. . Catholic liturgy expresses the same truth in the way appropriate to liturgy. One is aware that some persons today and in the past find all this " a hard saying," but an open exposition of Catholic faith cannot successfully evade the fact that the Church has said, and does say, that Mary is evervirgin in the realest sense. BOOK REVIEWS b) Catholic faith asserts that Christ "descended into hell "-again an unwelcome affirmation, perhaps, in our culture and in many cultures. The Catechism discusses the mystery: "The expression 'descended into hell ' is obviously composed of elements which are no longer part of our world of thought . . . By saying ' he descended into hell ' Christians affirm that he was really dead. It means the humiliation of being dead ... Jesus was imagined as announcing the redemption, immediately after his death, to the souls in hell." (pp. 176-177) But the Catholic community understands this article of faith to mean more than the Catechism states. Scripture teaches that when Christ "had died . . . in the spirit he went to preach to the spirits in prison " (I Peter 3 : 18-19). An event is here described; an event subsequent to Christ's death, therefore distinct from it; an event in which a certain mysterious activity is ascribed to Christ in his " spirit " or soul. If this is Petrine " imagining," if no corresponding event or activity occurred, Scripture would be deceptive. The Fourth Lateran Council defined that Christ " suffered and died, descended into hell, arose from the dead, and ascended into heaven; but he descended in his soul, arose in his body, and ascended in both." (Cap. 1; Denz.-Schon. 801). Each of the four is a distinct article, as signified by identifying (inadequately) distinct subjects for each. In particular, the descent into hell, manifested according to Scripture in his preaching " to the spirits in prison "-an activity other than the condition of being deadis more than a restatement of the Lord's death, as well as more than the work of imagination, granted, of course, that imagination is at work in every human statement. c) The Catechism's account of the holy Eucharist, especially of Christ's Real Presence therein, is, as an account of Catholic faith, troublesome. The dogma of transsubstantiation (defined by the Mystical Body as divinely revealed, cf. Trent, sess. XIII, can. 12; Denz.-Schon. 16512) receives a one-sentence mention after being identified as a medieval way of" expressing the mystery." Then we read: "when we consider the matter in terms of present-day thought we should say that the reality, the nature of material things is what they are . . . for man. Hence it is the nature of bread to be earthly food for man . . . at Mass, however . . . the bread is essentially withdrawn from its normal human meaning or definition and has become the bread which the Father has given us, Jesus himself." (p. 343) To the revealed doctrine which the Catholic community expresses in terms of transsubstantiation, the Cathechism's theory of transsignification (or transfinalization) need not involve opposition. The two are not at all answers to the same question. Transsubstantiation answers the question: in the Eucharist, what existing reality underlies the sense-perceptible BOOK REVIEWS appearances of bread and wine; whereas transfinalization, directly concerned only with " meanings for man " and not with reality in itself, seeks to answer the question: what meaning should man see in the Eucharist? Each question and each answer has validity in its own way. The Catechism's presumptions that the two are different answers to the same question, that they are opposed as medieval and present-day answers, that the value of the dogma of transsubstantiation was restricted to the Middle Ages (one wonders at the reckoning which places the Council of Trent, which defined this dogma, in the Middle Ages) do make one pause. All are aware that in his encyclical on the Eucharist Pope Paul VI writes: "These formulas (Tridentine formulas proposing the eucharistic mystery) express concepts that are not tied to a certain specific form of human culture, or to a certain level of scientific progress, . . . Instead they set forth what the human mind grasps of reality through necessary and universal experience, and what it expresses in apt and exact words . . . these formulas are adapted to all men of all times and all places . . . it is the teaching of the First Vatican Council that ' the meaning that ... the Church has once declared is to be retained forever and no pretext of deeper understanding ever justifies any deviation from that meaning . . . ,' " so that no one may " take doctrine that has already been defined by the Church and consign it to oblivion, or else interpret it in such a way as to weaken the genuine meaning of the words or the recognized form of the concepts involved" (Ency. Mysterium Fidei, Sept. 3, 1965). Catholic faith in the holy Eucharist does not describe transsubstantiation as a medieval "way of expressing the mystery," a way to be now supplanted by transsignification. The Catechism here misrepresents authentic Catholic understanding and Catholic teaching. d) Of the Catechism's treatment of original sin many aspects, quite predictably, invite discussion. The following observations merely suggest the tenor of some of them. " The sin which stains others was committed by . . . every man ... It includes my sins . . . Original sin is the sin of mankind as a whole (including myself) insofar as it affects every man ... It may be said that it only takes on concrete form in our personal sins," (p. 267) even in the ultimate sense that " no one is condemned for original sin alone," (p. 267) which implies, of course, that "there must be a way by which unbaptized infants are saved." (p. 252) Neither the views expressed nor the manner of expression lacks appeal. But how do these views relate to the Catholic faith which the Catechism sets out to present? The inspired Scripture teaches that " by one man sin entered the world," (Rom. 5: 12) so the Catholic community holds as revealed bv God that "when the first man Adam had transgressed God's comm;ndment he immediately lost sanctity and justice ... for himself and his offspring, and 258 BOOK REVIEWS transmitted . sin . to the entire human race" (Trent, Sess. V, can. 1, 2; Denz.-Schon. 1511, 1512). In Catholic doctrine " original sin is contracted without consent " !Innocent III, Ep. "Majores ecclesiae causas "; Denz.-Schon. 780), so that it was the act of " the first man Adam " alone, and not a sin committed by "every man," (though it infects mankind). Again, in us, prior to any personal sin, or any personal act at all, this sin has " form " in the sense that it is the real deprivation of " holiness and justice"; it is a true modification of our nature, consequently, the statement that it " only takes on concrete form in our personal lives " distorts more than reports Catholic thinking. And the outlook that "no one is condemned for original sin alone " hardly expresses the Catholic teaching that " the punishment for original sin (as distinct from personal sin) is lack of the vision of God" (Innocent III, loc. cit.) . e) Discussing life-after-death, that is, the condition of the dead prior to the general resurrection, the Catechism in unsatisfactory, incomplete. It reads: " we should keep to the words of Scripture ' they have fallen asleep' ... They wait-they are about to rise." (p. 474) Are such men (or souls) beatified? Even the question is not raised; no activity except "waiting" is assigned to the dead. Yet the Church holds as divinely revealed that " the souls of all the saints . . . even before the resumption of their bodies . . . see . . . the divine essence . . . the souls of those who die in actual mortal sin descend to hell immediately after death . . ." (Benedict XII, Const. Benedictus Deus; Denz.-SchOn. 1000-1002) . " They wait "but not for ecstatic fulness of life which is already theirs. " They are asleep "-in the body, not asleep to infinite fulfillment. What the Catechism teaches is truth, a partial truth and obvious in one sense. The awesome, God-revealed truth goes undisclosed. The Catechism's teaching on who are members of, or belong to, the Church (p. 235 and elsewhere) is different from the Magisterium's teaching and simply does not report the Church's position on the point. The existence of angels and of the devil the Catechism treats as an open question. (cf. p. 482) Yet an ecumenical council has defined that " from nothingness " God created " the spiritual and the bodily creature, namely, the angelic and the earthly, then the human creature" (IV Lateran, cap. 1; Denz.-Schon. 800; I Vatican, cap. 1; Denz.-Schon. 3002). These two positions, that angelic existence is a question and that God created "the spiritual ... namely, the angelic creature" seem not to be identical. As to Satan, the ordinary Magisterium teaches that he was " a good angel, made by God" (and not the substance of evil). (cf. Council of Braga, can. 7; Denz.-Schon. 457) . In Catholic doctrine the question left unanswered by the Catechism has an answer. On the doctrinal points mentioned (and on some others) it seems clear BOOK REVIEWS 259 that the Dutch Catechism is less than a straight-forward, frank report of Catholic teaching. In the field of morals. The moral sections of the Catechism, which have often struck reviewers as ideally addressed to teenagers, present some related difficulties, which can be more briefly suggested in very few "samples." Predictably, given the book's characteristic "mood," the general problem of sin is treated most subjectively. "Is it (sin) not folly and blindness? Is it really done knowingly? Is the will really free? Sin is . . . so impenetrable. We recognize nevertheless that it exists. Something in our Christian experience tells us that it is more than things taking an unfortunate turn ... The good is comprehensible ... Evil is a breach of good order . . . Hence one cannot do evil with as full knowledge as one does good." (p. 451) Beyond " something in our Christian experience " as giving awareness of sin (which in a given instance may be real enough) is the objective revelation of God and the instruction of that apostolic college to which Christ said: " He who hears you hears me ... whatsoever you shall bind on earth shall be bound also in heaven " (Luke 16 : 16, Matt. 18 : 18) . Sinful unease within " Christian experience " is neither alone nor ultimate in the Christian's moral judgment, for this latter is instructed, gnided by God's explicit law and by the directives of Christ's authority within the community. These give objective, reliable norms of moral good, and evil; they are truly directive even of Christian moral experience. The statement that " one cannot do evil with as full knowledge as one does good " is pregnant with metaphysico-psychological implications, but these are not directly moral, for the most part, nor much concerned with Catholic truth. But to any reader of the book whose own philosophy is one of realism, the outlook succinctly expressed in the statement would be intriguing, if perhaps also questionable. More in particular, the Catechism's discussion of birth control practices is summed up in the simple statement, " The last word lies with the conscience." (p. 403) This is no doubt true in the pragmatic sense that each person makes his own decision and for his own reasons. But as a statement of the Catholic position on birth control, it is not adequate. Catholic discussion cannot simply ignore (as does the Catechism) that the authority of Christ in the person of Pope Paul VI has reaffirmed as binding the directives of Pius XI and Pius XII in this matter. Even if one considers that the natural reasons to which these directives appealed are questionable (as many honest Christians seem to consider), it remains true that to ignore the Papal moral teaching is to ignore Christ's authority here speaking. The Catechism's teaching about cases in which Christian persons freely, 260 BOOK REVIEWS knowingly, and validly married, divorce and marry other persons (outside the Church, necessarily) is subject to similar criticism. (cf. pp. 396-397) It again ignores Catholic belief and conviction that Christ's authority is found, dynamic, within the Christian community. It should be noted that Christian exegetes who accept the Church's Magisterium would have special problems with this Dutch Catechism. One illustration suffices. In Christ's miracles of exorcism, the possessed, we are told, are to be understood as " men who give ... signs of insanity." (p. 109) The interpretation is hardly new; but as a statement of Catholic faith it is new, together with its inevitable implication that the Lord was indeed a giant in the practice of "instant" psycho-therapy. In general, the Catechism's account of miracles simply as events in which men see the power of God at work, although men cannot know whether in fact purely natural forces are at work, (cf. p. 107) is less than a restatement of the Catholic understanding expressed by Vatican Council I, namely, that miracles a) are divine deeds (facta) which clearly indicate God's omnipotence and infinite knowledge, b) are most certain signs (of divine revelation) , c) are proportionate to all men's understanding, and d) can be known with certainty (in some instances, at least) (cf. Sess. III, Const. De Fide Catholica, cap. 3; Denz.-Schon. 3009; and can. 4 de fide; Denz.Schon. 3034) . It seems to the reviewer that this work must appeal to many intelligent, vocal, zealous Christian men and women, keenly alive to outlooks and convictions current in contemporary Western society. But it also seems that the work needs important revisions. What divides, and will divide, is faith's attitude readers into "revisionists" and "non-revisionists" toward the Magisterium of the Church. The Dutch Catechism at times obscures the teaching of the solemn Magisterium, at time departs from the ordinary Magisterium. Is the resulting work truly a Catholic catechism as it stands? Or is it, in part, some person's private reinterpretation of Catholic teaching? Pope Paul VI declared: " ... There are limits which cannot and must not be imprudently exceeded by the exegete, the theologian .... These limits are marked by the living Magisterium which is the proximate norm of truth for the faithful " (Allocution, Siamo particolarmente lieti, July 11, 1966) , and Vatican II declared that " sacred tradition, sacred scripture, and the teaching authority of the Church . . . are so linked and joined together one cannot stand without the other " (Const. De Revelatione, Chap. fl, n. 10). To those who accept the papal and the conciliar teaching there is no sure way of grasping the word of God except through the voice of Christ. His voice speaks within the Church, through her Magisterium. It is this voice of Christ's body, this voice of the Magisterium, which is so often muted in the Dutch Catechism. BOOK REVIEWS 261 Each reader of this work is faced perhaps by the important question: shall he or shall he not believe in action as in theory that he who hears the Magisterium hears Christ? THOMAS u. MULLANEY, 0. P. Providence College Providence, R. I. Divine Science and the Science of God. A Reformulation of Thomas Aquinas. By VICTOR PRELLER. Princeton University Press, 1967. Pp. 281 $8.50. The ruthless honesty with which a number of basic questions relating to our knowledge of God are treated makes this book a work of importance. The intention of the author is a worthy one: he is attempting to rethink the problem of the meaningfulness of religious language " in the context of the explicit rejection of the epistemological presuppositions of traditional empiricism " (p. vii) . The problematic in which the matter is treated is the linguistic discussions of the past decade in the Anglo-Saxon world. Though the author is not a " Thomist " of any recognizable school, his constant reference point is the work of St. Thomas, whose positions he revises and corrects when necessary in terms provided by the philosophy of Wilfred F. Sellars (with particular reference to his book, Science, Perception and Reality [London, 1963]) . It would be unjust in this short space to attempt to give even the main lines of the author's argument. However, the general movement of the book is as follows: first, we are introduced into the real problem of referring to God in language. This is developed further in a special note on the use of philosophy in theology, especially as performed by St. Thomas. (Ch. 1) The next chapter is no less than an attempt to reform basic positions in Thomistic epistemology. Thus, the way is opened for a direct consideration of special problems in our linguistic reference to God. Through an analysis of the relation of experience to the conceptual system that informs it, and by showing that the intelligibility of what is known is derived from the logic of the syntax of the system, which in turn originates from the "radical intentionality" of the intellect itself (p. 74), what results is an extremely negative qualification of our knowledge of God. God can never be understood in an affirmative judgment by appealing to the intelligible content of our particular conceptual system. Consequently, Chapter Three shows that the " Five Ways " are significant in that the existence of an unknown entity is posited, whose relationship with the world remains also unknown. A more positive interpretation of these proofs would mean an unjustifiable extrapolation from our own conceptual system. The final BOOK REVIEWS chapter treats on the role of faith in our discourse on God. The " material moves " of theological language are rendered intelligibile only in the light of faith, interpreted as a radical conformity to the divine intentionality. Whereas Professor Preller's aim is laudable and the performance suggestive, it will be surprising if there is not much stringent comment from even the more flexible of Thomists. There is so much that is not quite clear, e. g., the key notion of concept and conceptual system. Furthermore, it seems that many Thomistic positions on analogy, even if influenced by Cajetan, are not as "horrendously naive" (p. 19) as the author suggests. It is hard to see how the author could hope for a convincing performance without a more ample viewpoint. One feels that at least some cognizance of modern theories on analogy is demanded {e. g., that of Schillebeeckx and de Petter in their clear rejection of Cajetan). Likewise, the distinctly Kantian slant of the author's position might have been remedied by an incorporation of some elements of the transcendental method as favored by so many modern Thomists. However, that is to anticipate the dialogue that must result. Though this book may suffer {and merit) quite drastic refutation, honest questions have been asked and a highly intelligent attempt has been made to reinterpret the best of St. Thomas in the light of the best in modern linguistic philosophy. A. J. KELLY, c. ss. R. St. Mary's Mrmastery Wendouree, Victoria, Australia Infallibility of the Laity. By SAMUEL D. FEMIANO, C. S. B. New York: Herder and Herder, 1967. Pp. 155. $4.95. The growing interest in the thought of John Henry Newman has produced several recent studies which have attempted to trace the historic development of Newman's thought in particular areas. The present work carries the catchy title of "Infallibility of the Laity." The author's own phrase which designates the purpose of his undertaking, viz., "Newman's thought on the voice of the laity in the Church " (p. 3) , more accurately reflects the major portion of the book. Newman's prevailing interest was focused on the continuity and witness, especially doctrinal, of the Church with her beginnings, as evidenced by his researches on tradition and the development of doctrine. It is in this sense that "the gradual evolution of Newman's thought on the laity was linked to his studies on the Church and on tradition." (ibid.) The "legacy of Newman" has exerted its influence upon the periti of this century and found echoes in the teaching of Vatican II and more recently and explicitly BOOK REVIEWS 263 in the collective pastoral of the American hierarchy, The Church in our Day. One of the contributions of this legacy regards the infallibility of the laity. The " infallibility which the Roman Pontiff, the head of the college of bishops, enjoys in virtue of his office " is that " infallibility with which the divine Redeemer willed His Church to be endowed in defining a doctrine of faith and morals " (Vatican II, Lumen Gentium, n. Q5; Vatican I, Pastor Aeternus, ch. 4) . Thus the Church as a whole, " the holy People of God, . . . spreads abroad a living witness to Him. . . . The body of the faithful as a whole ... cannot err in matters of belief ... it manifests this unerring quality when ' from the bishops down to the last member of the laity,' it shows universal agreement in matters of faith and morals" (Luman Gentium, n. IQ) . In what does the infallibility of the laity consist? Father Femiano traces the thought of Newman on this point by the current method of formative years, Anglican years, Catholic years, and special problems, in this case Newman's controversy in the Rambler on "consulting the faithful." For Newman the laity's role in the communication of the truth of the faith is one of bearer of tradition and of witness to the church's doctrine; witnessing, not judging or defining, is the laity's function. From his earliest years Newman had regard for the position of the laity in the Church. Here, as with the broader topics of his reflections, his thought had fundamentally crystallized by the time of his entrance into the Catholic Church. He had always been impressed by the doctrinal steadfastness of the faithful in the Arian crisis. The statements of Pius IX that he had sought the opinion of the faithful regarding the Immaculate Conception weighed heavily with him as an argument in his later writings on the sensus fidelium and in his controversy in the Rambler. This book brings together in a short survey one area of Newman's investigations in which he was in advance of his time, misunderstood and suspected, but which today is the subject of considerable theological and pastoral inquiry. NICHOLAS HALLIGAN, 0. P. Dominican House of Studies Washington, D. C. The Commentary of Peter of Auvergne on Aristotle's "Politics" (The Inedited Part: Book III, less. I-VI). Introduction and critical text by GuNDISALvus M. GRECH, 0. P. Rome: Desclee (Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas), 1967. Pp. 137. The value of a commentary on Aristotle's Politics should be gauged on a twofold basis, namely, a finn grasp of the science of politics as the 264 BOOK REVIEWS Stagirite presents it in this work and as much pertinent erudition as possible. This erudition is indispensable, inasmuch as politics demands far more experience than that required for simple ethics, whether this experience is the investigator's own experience or information gleaned from other observers, past or present. In his paraphrase, St. Albert expresses considerable doubt anent many portions of the Politics, probably because he could not get the pertinent information. Thomas Aquinas has penned the most outstanding commentary on the first three books (up to about half of the fifth chapter of Book III [lesson 6]) . The Peter of Auvergne who, a native of Crocq (Auvergne), became a student and master in the Faculty of Arts, and for some time Rector, of the University of Paris, and eventually Bishop of Clermont, has produced what presently seems to be the most fruitful work on the latter portion of the Politics by way of a continuation of the Aquinas commentary. "The [printed] texts, however, of the commentaries of Peter and Thomas are far from reliable. They were produced by humanists who not only removed from them the inelegant, non-classical Latin elements, but also made regrettable changes-interpolations, modifications, additions and omissions-which affected the technical aspect of the text and also betrayed the author's thought." (pp. 10-11) This editorial note suggests the urgency of a critical edition of Peter's Continuation, notably as regards his explanation of Aristotle's teaching about education under its civic aspect (Book VIII) . " Out of twenty-seven extant manuscripts containing St. Thomas's commentary, sixteen also give Peter's Continuation, and twelve of these include the six parallel lessons on the Third Book." (p. 11) The editor's report on his evaluation of these twelve manuscripts (pp. 63-66) is a model of clarity through consciseness and serves as a guide for those who may be encouraged to edit at least portions of the Continuation. Grech's presentation of the established history concerning Peter, the authenticity of Peter's commentary on the Politics, the relation of the inedited part of this commentary to the six parallel lessons of St. Thomas, the critical apparatus relevant to the reconstructed text, and his indices of manuscripts and names make this book a necessary reference for future studies concerning this most famous Auvergnian. FRANCIS Dominican House of Studies Washington, D. C. c. LEHNER, 0. P. BOOK REVIEWS 265 The Chinese Mind, Essentials of Chinese Philosophy and Culture. Edited by CHARLES A. MooRE with the assistance of ALDYTH V. MoRRIS. Honolulu: East-West Center Press, University of Hawaii Press, 1967. Pp. 402 with index. $9.50. This book, together with The Japanese Mind and The Indian Mind, comprises a series of three studies of the Oriental mind. All articles selected for this anthology were given at the East-West Philosophers' Conferences at the University of Hawaii and published subsequently in its Proceedings of 1939, 1949, 1959 and 1964. The purpose of this anthology is to give Western readers a comprehensive picture of the Chinese mind from the philosophical perspective. There are fifteen articles in all, not counting the Introduction by C. A. Moore. The last six papers deal with the same topic: the individual in Chinese philosophy. Each article is reviewed in the order as it appears in the book. 1. Chinese Theory and Practice, with Special Reference to Humanism. By Wing-Tsit Chan. (pp. 11-28) The author presents, first, the Chinese notion of truth and, second, its relation to practice. The Chinese conceived truth to be the discoverable and demonstrable principles in human affairs. Thus all truths have a moral quality. Since truth has to do with human events, human history at once becomes the test as well as the deposit of truth .. While Wang Yang-ming (1472-1529) is of the opinion that truths exist primarily in the mind, Chu-Hsi (1130-1200) thinks that truths are inherent in things and human events. Because of the Chinese unique conception of the relation between truth and history, all historical events are considered as the unfolding and functioning of eternal principles. Consequently, Chinese classical history exercises supreme authority as a natural law over government, religion, society and other spheres of Chinese life. If truth is moral, then it implies an ethical ought. Confucius was the first to advocate the unity of knowledge and action. This doctrine was accepted by all Chinese thinkers and expressed in the Chinese maxim: " knowledge is the beginning of action and action is the completion of knowledge." The consequence of this theory is the practical orientation of all sciences, including philosophy, which has been considered not a science of pure speculation but also of doing. The discussion on truth is too brief, and the major portion of the article is devoted to practices in poetry, art and drama. The author also fails to observe the distinction between truth and knowledge and used the two terms interchangeably. 2. The Story of Chinese Philosophy. By Wing-Tsit Chan. (pp. 29-76) The history of Chinese philosophy is divided into three symphony-like movements: from 600 to 200 B. C. a period of three major themes of 266 BOOK REVIEWS Confucianism, Taoism and Moism, plus four minor ones of the Logicians, Neo-Moism, the Legalists and Yin-Yang Interactionism. The second movement from B. C. to 1100 A. D. is that of synthesis of Chinese philosophy with a counternote of Buddhism introduced from India. The third movement from 1100 to the present unfolds the melody of Nco-Confucianism. This article is neither profound nor original. It seems futile to recount in a brief article the whole history of Chinese philosophy. 3. Epistemological Method in Chinese Philosophy. By E. R. Hughes. (pp. 77-103) The author aims to prove two things: that there is an epistemology in Chinese tradition and that this epistemology is primarily linguistic, as shown in their linguistic experiments and their use of abstract categories. He believes that the Chinese consider philosophy a critique of language and a checking of this critique by a critique of history. Therefore, Northrop's theory that Chinese thinking is intuitive and not postulational is questionable, since linguistic method is postulational, not intuitive. He concludes that, in comparative philosophy, linguistic method is the most useful. I agree with the author that, unless we have an adequate understanding of the nature of Chinese language, we would never fully appreciate Chinese philosophy. However, many of his suppositions are by no means correct. For example, he says that Chinese philosophy is a critique of language or communicated meaning. This opinion is totally unwarranted. On the contrary, the Chinese consider language a poor vehicle for philosophy. Oftentimes silence is preferred over dialogue. Zen Buddhism is a perfect example of this development. When the author claims that the Chinese thought in terms of abstract categories, he again makes an unverified supposition. It is a common teaching that the Chinese think modo concreto not modo abstracto. There is a Chinese term for this man and a term for man as all men, a generic term, but no term for manhood. What the author considers to be abstract categories, such as Yin, Yang, the five Hsings, are generic terms. The only possible abstract terms are Tao in Taoism and Fa (Dharma) in Buddhism. . 4. The Scientific Spirit and Method in Chinese Philosophy. By Hu Shih. (pp. 104-131) F. S. C. Northrop has expressed the opinion that the East's failure to develop natural sciences was due to the fact that " the method of intuition and contemplation became the sole trustworthy modes of inquiry." This Dr. Hu considers to be historically untrue. He says that no race or culture " ... admits only concepts by intuition." Man, being a thinking animal, is compelled by his daily needs to make inferences. That sciences were neglected in the East was due to historical reasons. The author points out that the Chinese had a scientific spirit and method which were first embodied in Confucius's teachings, such as his agnosticism and naturalism. By rejecting ancient myths Confucius was truly . the BOOK REVIEWS 267 Socrates of China. During the Nco-Confucian renaissance this scientific spirit and method were further developed by Chu-Hsi, whose school singled out the The Great Learning from the Book of Rites for special study because it contained a new logical method as a Novum Organum. Chu-Hsi writes: "Investigate with an open mind. Try to see the reason with an open mind. And with an open mind follow reason wherever it leads you." Chang Tsai has said: "The student must first learn to be able to doubt. If he can find doubt where no doubt was found before, then he is making progress." To this Chu-Hsi adds: " but should also learn to resolve the doubt after it has arisen. Then he is making real progress." This the author considers to be Chu-Hsi's scientific method of hypothesis and verification by evidence. He further points out Wu Yii's literary investigation of phonetics in the Book of the Odes as a shining example of the Chinese scientific spirit. There are some flaws in the author's argument. First, Confucius never developed a Socratic method. Second, Chu-Hsi's method was nothing but a method of literary criticism. All the doubting, searching and verifying were concerned with commentaries on the classics. 5. Synthesis in Chinese Metaphysics. By Wing-Tsit Chan. (pp. 148) The author lists four periods in the history of Chinese philosophy when metaphysical syntheses were supposed to have taken place. The first synthesis took place in the classical times when the Yin-Tang Interactionism was absorbed into the Great unity of Taoism and the Confucian doctrine of the Mean. The second synthesis was found in the meeting of Buddhism and Taoism; the third in the synthesis of Buddhism and Taoism into Nco-Confucianism. The last synthesis is now taking place between Western and Chinese thought. However, the main article is concerned with the following topics of synthesis: being and non-being; Li (reason) and Ch'i (ether, matter); the one and many; man and the universe; good and evil and knowledge and conduct. This article leaves something to be desired. To equate Yang with being and Yin with non-being is grossly misleading. Some of the topics in no way represent a process of synthesis but a quest for unity in thought which is the life of all philosophies. 6. The Basis of Social, Ethical and Spiritual Values in Chinese Philosophy. By Y. P. Mei. (pp. 149-166) First of all, the author believes that all classical Chinese philosophers were religious thinkers and that their teachings truly established the foundation of all values. Confucius was a religious man who affirmed life in his doctrine of Jen (love). Mencius was not only religious but in fact a mystic. Mo-Tzu believed in a personal God and preached universal love for all men. Though Lao-Tzu and Chuang- Tzu rejected God, they both insisted upon Good and Tao as the highest reality. Historically, however, many of these assertions are BOOK REVIEWS debatable. Mei displays certain theistic bias. His exposition is good, but it is too broad to provide any deep insight. 7. Filial Piety and Chinese Society. By Hsieh Yu-Wei. (pp. 167-187) The Chinese as a race is best known as a family people. This is not without a long historical tradition and a philosophical foundation, which this article eloquently explains. In the Confucian scheme of things, filial piety is the root of all virtues and of social and cosmic harmony. The Confucian len (love) is the cardinal virtue, and its germination and development depend upon the cultivation of filial piety. As Mencius says: "The substantiation of len begins with service to one's parents." The Confucian notion of man is primarily relational, i. e., man has five dimensions in society, the principal of which is that between children and parents. Once this primary relation is made harmonious, then the others would follow. It is said in the Classic of Filial Piety: "Filial piety at the outset consists in service to one's parents; in the middle of one's path in service to his sovereign; and in the end, in establishing oneself as an authentic man." Unfortunately, the exaltation of filial piety was not without some ill effects. It hindered the development of individuality and freedom and perpetuated the subjugation of women and paternalism in politics. 8. The Development of Ideas of Spiritual Values in Chinese Philosophy. By T'ang Chlin-I. (pp. A value is considered spiritual if: 1) presented or revealed to the spirit, that created or realized by the spirit; is, " for the spirit "; 3) self-consciously recognized as such in 1 and The author believes that the history of Chinese philosophy is a history of the development of such values. The author's assertions seem to be nonsequiturs, since he has not first established (I don't think he can) that the Chinese have looked upon the spirit in the same way as the West. What others call humanistic values, he terms spiritual. 9. Chinese Legal and Political Philosophy. By John C. H. Wu. (pp. The foundations of Chinese political authority, according to the author, are three: the mandate of heaven, the people's will and the ruler's virtue. The government has a double function: to enforce laws and promote morality. This is because the Chinese consider law and morality to be identical. This identity is based on the notion of law as a system of duties rather than of rights. As Lao- Tzu says: "The man of virtue attends to his duties; while a man of no virtue attends to his rights." This emphasis on duty has rendered all laws subject to ethics. Only a virtuous ruler can be a good ruler and only a virtuous citizen is a loyal citizen. The purpose of both government and law is to achieve harmony in human affairs. The author's arguments are cogent and his documentation relevant. However, he omitted the discussion of Li (propriety) and music, which are considered integral parts of the whole legal system. BOOK REVIEWS 269 10. The World and the Individual in Chinese Metaphysics. By Thome H. Fang. (pp. This article covers all three major Chinese schools: Confucianism, Taoism and Buddhism. The Confucian metaphysics takes the Tao of Heaven as the creative power whereby the dynamic world of all beings comes into existence and considers man as a participating nature in congruence with the cosmic order. Individual dignity and finality consist in man's cooperation and reciprocation with nature for the harmonious completion of the total order. With Taoism the emphasis was shifted from man to Tao-in-itself. It is anti-social in that man's total concern is not with his fellow men or society but with union with Tao. They are extreme individualists. With the advent of Buddhism a metaphysical synthesis took place and resulted in Chinese Buddhism, which teaches the search for the Ultimate through self-annihilation. The author's thought is often obscured by his style, which is at times terse and at times pedantic. 11. The Individual and the World in Chinese Methodology. By T'ang Chiin-I. (pp. This is an epistemological study of the principles of individuation. The most important discussion is found in the first part. For the Moist, there is only species and no individual. Universal love is fostered at the expense of individuality. Mo Pin, a later Moist, holds that all names are class-names, whether of a species or genus. There is no proper name, since every such name is universalizable. Logicians concede that individuals can be known and pointed to but not conceptually determined. Hiin- Tzu teaches that an individual is spatia-temporally determined. Attributes and properties do not determine an individual, because they are universal terms. Therefore, things are determined by the ways in which they variously relate to each other. Yin-Yang School considers the individual to be a ultirelational system. An individual is one of the reciprocal relations with others. It is unfortunate that the author does not mention whether or not the Chinese philosophers ever discussed the intrinsic principles of individuation. To my knowledge, the Classic of History and the Book of Changes contain some pertinent passages on this subject. The Individual in Chinese Religion. By Wing-Tsit Chan. (pp. 306) No native Chinese religion was ever institutionalized, and this, the author believes, was due to their religious convictions: 1) purpose of Chinese religions is self-realization; this is achieved through natural and self-oriented means; 3) ultimate salvation is union with Heaven in Confucianism, identification with Nature in Taoism and Nirvana in Buddhism. The author fails to distinguish between Chinese religions and the philosophical schools, even though the public has often confused the two. Confucianism never has been a religion nor has the Taoist religion followed faithfully the Taoist philosophy. A religious Taoist believes in earthly BOOK REVIEWS immortality, not identification with Nature, which is a philosophical doctrine. 13. The Status of the Individual in Chinese Ethics. By Hsieh Yu-Wei. This article reads like an apologetics. The author tries to (pp. prove that the status of the individual in Confucian ethics is that of equality and freedom. However, he fails to add that equality is an equality of duties, not of rights, and freedom is that of doing the necessary, not a freedom of autonomy. In the Confucian family system and social structure equality and freedom were indeed very limited, if they existed at all. 14. Tke Status of the Individual in Chinese Social Thought and Practice. By Y. P. Mei. (pp. This is another apologetic. To determine the exact status of the individual, all facts, whether favorable or unfavorable, must be submitted for judgment. The author discusses only what favors the individual status and omits all the social practices which had subjugated millions of Chinese under the benign tyranny of Chinese tradition. 15. The Status of the Individual in the Political and Legal Traditions of Old and New China. By John C. H. Wu. (pp. 340-364) This article is by far the most objective discussion on the individual status in Chinese tradition. The discussion on the old legal system is fascinating. All laws in China were penal laws. There was no civil law. Any immoral act constituted a crime. The principle was: "whoever does what ought not to be done shall be punished." All persons, including the Emperor, were equal under the law, but the law itself was discriminating. Eight categories of people were exempted from punishment unless imposed personally by the Emperor. The law decreed that members in a family be unequal according to their status. The law also discriminated against women, who were made totally dependent upon men. Man was allowed to divorce his wife, but a woman was never permitted to divorce her husband. These inequalities were remedied only after the promulgation of the new law under the Republic. The book as a whole shows a total lack of editorial control. Being an anthology, it is not expected to have a uniform theme and style, but some of the repetitions and even contradictions in the various articles could be eliminated. However, these flaws do not alter the fact that it is a rich source bf Chinese philosophy in the English language. Though the Chinese mind is not made totally scrutable, it has been unveiled. PAUL Catholic University of America Washington, D. C. K. K. ToNG BOOK REVIEWS 271 The Indian Mind: Essentials of Indian Philosophy and Culture. Ed. by CHARLES A. MooRE. Honolulu: East-West Center Press, 1967. Pp. 458. $9.50. The East-West Center at the University of Hawaii provides a bridge oi communication between philosophers from both sides of the world. Its East-West Philosophers' Conferences were held in 1939, 1949, 1959, and 1964. The Indian Mind is a selection of papers from those conferences brought together and edited by the late Professor Charles A. Moore. All but one of the essays were re-edited by the authors themselves especially for this publication. This reviewer is strongly convinced that Western thinkers, and especially " Thomists," should become broadly acquainted with Eastern thought, since much is to be found there that blends with and leads to a better understanding of Western thought. The Indian Mind will serve well those who seek a starting-point for extended reading in this area. Raju's "Metaphysical Theories in Indian Philosophy" is a distinctive contribution as a general introduction to Hindu thought. Raju presents a comprehensive view of many Hindu schools and gives special place to Vedanta as " the essence of Indian Philosophy " and to Samkara's Advaita [meaning non-duality] as" the most popular expression of Vedanta thought." This reviewer does not disagree with Raju's evaluation of Samkara, but he does feel that thomistically orientated thinkers will find the later Vedantist Ramanuja's doctrine of non-duality-with-differences more compatible with their doctrine of analogy and their moderate realism. Even though it is difficult to pick and choose among the essays, this reviewer found " Buddhism as a Philosophy of ' Thusness ' " by Takakusu to be a most informative presentation of the Buddhist doctrine of causality and some of its allied principles. Despite the technical language, this essay brings into rather clear focus some of the basic elements of Buddhism and gives Western thinkers specific grounds for comparison and judgment. Some may find the Buddhist notion of causality too polaristic, but they can also see in it some of the implications of finite causality. In view of contemporary Western concern with the relations between the religious and the secular dimensions of human life, there should be much interest in Radhakrishnan's "The Indian Approach to the Religious Problem," Nikhilananda's "The Realistic Aspect of Indian Spirituality," and Raju's " Religion and Spiritual Values in Indian Thought." Mahadevan in " Social, Ethical, and Spiritual Values in Indian Philosophy " brings into value structure his discussion of the metaphysical basis of the the same prayerful fragments from the as were quoted by Pope Paul during his visit to India. 272 BOOK REVIEWS Five of the authors discuss the individual from different aspects: Bhattacharyya, the metaphysical; Murti, the religious; Desgupta, the ethical; Saksena, the social; and Chand, the institutional aspect. These present a well-rounded approach to the problem of individualism so prominent in the West today. In the limits of so brief a review, all essays could not be treated individually. All are informative and important. The book is highly recommended as a doorway to more extensive reading in Indian thought. E. RussELL NAuGHTON La Salle CoUege Philadelphia, Pa. The Making of Men. By PAUL WEISS. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967. Pp. 152 with index. $4.95. In this book, which is a series of reflective glances at the educative process in the twentieth century in the United States, the author, a philosopher, offers philosophical evaluations of the various ingredients which comprise the present-day system of schooling young men from early grades to college. The book is more evaluative than descriptive. Moreover, it is not argumentative nor even insistently persuasive; the style is simple didactic and the content represents the matured judgments of the long-trained philosopher and educator, expressing with a certain finality the wisdoms which years of thoughtful experience have refined. Therefore, the book's impact does not derive from the power of its syllogisms but from the character and authority of the man who is presenting in it the best results of his years of involvement. As must be expected, the man whose making interests Paul Weiss is the civilized, cultivated, perceptive, virtuous man; he is concerned with the educational process insofar as it is ordained to the formation of wise, urbane, creative, humane and sensitive human beings. Several touchstones are consistently applied to gauge the worth of all the educational ingredients at each stage of the process. To be truly educative, the materials offered to the developing skills, talents and mind of the growing person must be challenging enough to stir interest but not so difficult that they frustrate, nourishing in a way which satisfies the appetite and still whets it for more. At every stage, the growing individual must be treated as he is at that stage, the child as child, the youth as youth, the young man as young man, each with his proper needs and aspirations, which are different from those of an adult and not merely those of an adult-scaled-down-tosize, but each qualitatively appropriate. While the mind is taught, the spirit BOOK REVIEWS 273 must also be formed, in the childhood by stories, in teen-age by heroes, in youth by the records of great men and events in history. Techniques and procedures are not part of the properly educative process; they are appropriately taught in vocational institutions. True education prepares the mind to grasp and assimilate final goods, the goods which make life worth living, and men truly men. These materials are the materials which embody universal principles and values, as opposed to those which are particular and technical: philosophy, for example, as opposed to forestry, chemistry and physics as opposed to engineering, biology as opposed to medicine, art as opposed to craft. Inevitably the author is designing his criteria with an eye to his key evaluation, his ultimate evaluation of the genuine good life and the genuinely fulfilled man. This is, of course, not only the heart question of the book but one of the heart questions of the whole history of philosophy. Whoever in any compelling way answers this question, which is also a great question in theology, religion and politics, will be called greatest of the great, and therefore it cannot be expected that Paul Weiss, although he is wise, will have finally located the key to the mystery. He examines the claims of pleasure, knowledge, wealth, power, fame and security; he estimates the contributions of engineers and other producing people, politicians and other organizing people, humanitarians and other serving people, scholars and other thinking people; he beautifully balances the values of each and the limitations inherent in each and acknowledges that none of them is the answer to the ultimate good life and happy man. But then he must provide his own answer. He frames first a subjective answer: the good life must be correlative to man, must fulfill the promises of mind, body and emotions in a harmonious way and enable good men to live in harmony with each other. Hardly anyone will argue with this, but the crucial question remains: what is objectively correlative to man in this way? What objects respond thus to his needs and promises? The author's answer is a kind of weighted blend of things permeated with reflectiveness: a happy man is primarily involved in the dedicated use of one power while all his other powers have some play; he is vitally concerned in one great area of endeavor while appreciative of all the others. He will find a center in himself which will leave him open to the clustering riches around him. This is all true and good and broad enough to include almost any good life, even a life which finds its center in some way outside itself. But it is not a definite answer and not truly an objective answer. The blend of all good things adapted to the individual's individual wants truly describes what will make life good, but the defining process seems to be a subtle projection of the subjective criteria to the objects proposed rather than a recognition of a goal as ultimate in its own right. Moreover, attractive as it is, it does not seem to be for all men-only men capable of deep thought 274 BOOK REVIEWS and enjoying considerable leisure can achieve it. It is a philosopher's answer for the philosophically oriented. Nevertheless, within these bounds, important things are being said about man's ultimate goods and his happiness, which education, as an institutionalized, civilized procedure, should take into account. It must be acknowledged that even the finest educational process will not by itself produce the good man; other factors enter into the mixture even at the level of essential constitutives, e. g., sexual and familial love. And at the level of actual constitutives, still other elements must be considered; how is suffering integrated into the full life's plan, and how are men to achieve the maximum possible of the good life in view of the myriad compromises and compensation they are obliged to make because of personal deficiencies and unyielding circumstances? These questions are outside the scope of this book, but they must be recognized and answered before the whole design of the good life is clear. In the meantime, Dr. Weiss has written an illuminating and even moving account of the part that schooling should handle. MICHAEL STOCK, 0. P. St. Stephen's Priory Dover, Massachusetts St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, vol. 10 (1a. 65-74) (Cosmogony), ed. WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967. $U5. Volume 10 of the new English translation of the Summa theologiae contains St. Thomas's cosmogony or hexaemeron. The editor, William A. Wallace, 0. P., makes no exaggerated claims for this section of the Summa. He notes that " the fact that St. Thomas's treatment of the Hexaemeron is so immersed in patristic exegesis and in the science of the Middle Ages has long made it an antiquarian piece even for Thomistic scholars " (p. xxi), and he refers to this as one of St. Thomas's "weakest expositions" (p. xxiii). And yet it is Father Wallace's contention that "the marks of his genius are still discernible. . . . On the difficult topic of the Hexaemeron he could not offer a correct and definitive solution. Even in error, however, his efforts compare so favourably with those of others that they deserve careful analysis and thoughtful appreciation" (p. xxiii). The section in question is, of course, a commentary on the Genesis account of the six days of creation. Here St. Thomas is forced to deal with such traditional problems as the creation of light on the first day and of the luminous celestial bodies (the principal sources of light) three days later, the perplexing claim that there are waters above the firmament, and the BOOK REVIEWS fl75 suitability of the various terms employed in the Scriptures to describe God's creative work. Other problems appear to have acquired new urgency for St. Thomas through the recovery of the whole corpus of Greek and Islamic science in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. Thus he inquires into the possibility that God employed intermediaries in producing the material world; he asks if the celestial bodies are animate; he questions whether matter was formless for a time before diversification. St. Thomas reveals his ample knowledge of science and natural philosophy as he faces the exegetical problems associated with Genesis I and 2; contemporary astronomy, physics, optics, biology, and metaphysics are all brought to bear on the text. This fact reflects St. Thomas's relatively strict "scientific concordism ": the Scriptures are to be interpreted literally, and the Scriptural and scientific accounts of the world must agree in detail. But as Father Wallace points out, in spite of St. Thomas's concordist views and his command of scientific knowledge, this particular section of the Summa is predominantly Biblical and patristic-it was so determined by the great abundance of patristic literature on the subject of the Hexaemeron. Thus on each question St. Thomas faithfully records the views of the various Fathers of the Church and attempts to mediate between their differing viewpoints; and his solution to a problem is more often drawn from a Scriptural text than from a scientific argument. As editor of this volume, Father Wallace has brought to bear on the text of St. Thomas's Hexaemeron not only the" careful analysis and thoughtful appreciation " which are its due but also a vast amount of erudition. His explanatory notes will surely be helpful to those not versed in medieval natural philosophy. Similarly, appendices 3-6, although sometimes going beyond the minimum required to understand St. Thomas, present a succinct and nearly impeccable summary of ancient and medieval astronomy, Aristotelian physics, medieval optics, and medieval biology. Appendices 7-10 provide a most illuminating introduction to literature on the Hexaemeron from the patristic period to the present, thus enabling the reader to view St. Thomas in historical context. The translation is always lucid and usually faithful, though occasionally the attempt to be modern and colloquial strains the meaning of the text ever so slightly. Inevitably there are quibbles. One wonders why, in this entire edition, references in the text to particular treatises are always left untranslated (is it really advantageous, for example, to render "ut habetur Matt." as " as Scripture records "? [pp. 138-9]) and why punctuation is omitted at the end of footnotes. Minor errors appear occasionally in the notes and appendices: a Newtonian view of inertia was not held by Kepler, as Father Wallace suggests (p. 123). The great circle in which the sun moves is more properly referred to as the ecliptic than as the zodiac (pp. 185, 219) . An epicycle is not the path traced out by a point moving about a small circle, 276 BOOK REVIEWS the center of which is moving about a larger deferent circle; rather, the epicycle is the small circle itself (p. 186). The commonly accepted date of Roger Bacon's death is not 1!294 but 1292 (p. 194) . But surely these objections are of a most trivial sort, and they in no way detract from the high standard of scholarship displayed throughout the book. Father Wallace has performed a most valuable service for both Thomistic scholars and historians of medieval natural philosophy. DAVID c. LINDBERG University of Wisconsm Madison, Wisconsin Reflections on the Analogy of Being. By JAMES F. ANDERSON. The Hague: Mattinus Nijhoff, 1967. Pp. 88. Imagine that twenty years ago you wrote a book which (along with brilliant chapters on the history of analogy) set down Thomistic analogy according to the schema of Cajetan. Subsequently a vast literature on the subject appeared through which runs an anti-Cajetanian thread: by and large, people argue that Cajetan's views on analogy are not those of Aquinas, make not much sense considered in themselves and ought to be discarded. Knowing this literature, having the opportunity to write another book, what would you do? If you are Professor Anderson, what you do is offer substantially the same book minus the historical chapters. The book is divided into discussions of analogy of inequality, analogy of attribution, metaphor and analogy of proper proportionality. I would like to report that, in his restatement of his position, Professor Anderson has achieved a tightness and clarity which surpass the measure of clarity reached in The Bond of Being. I would like to say that Professor Anderson, recognizing as he does the difference between establishing a position as being that of Aquinas and arguing for it convincingly in propria persona, has done one or the other or both. Professor Anderson makes no effort to show that his views are those of Aquinas, though he seems certain of the coincidence. He makes nothing like a convincing case for his own views. In order to convince his reader, Professor Anderson needs more precision in his statement. His book begins with the promising reminder that " analogy " has first of all a mathematical meaning, but he immediately rejects the significance of this. We are then told that there are many kinds of analogies which are analogously analogies because they participate in various ways in what is truly analogy, analogy of proper proportionality. The latter has never before been so firmly equated with being. Analogy of proper proportionality involves proportional-that is, analogous-unity. Being is explained in terms of proper proportionality and proper proportion- '277 BOOK REVIEWS ality is explained in terms of being. One cannot help wondering what would have happened if Professor Anderson had asked himself what kind of analogy is operative in his claim that his three (or four) kinds of analogy are analogously analogies. From the very outset of the book, what is to be explained is invoked to explain itself. This reviewer hopes that the present book represents a warm-up exercise and that Professor Anderson will soon turn his genial and cultivated mind to some, at least, of the difficulties that have been advanced against his Cajetanian views during the past several decades. As an echo of his past work, this book is disappointingly anachronistic; as possible fanfare for further and more persuasive stuff, it whets the intellectual appetite. RALPH MciNERNY University fY/ Notre Dame South Bend, Indiana A Short Account of Greek Philosophy. By G. F. PARKER. New York: Barnes & Noble, Inc., 1967. Pp. 194. $5.00. Plato and His Contemporaries. By G. C. FIELD. New York: Barnes & Noble, Inc. Pp. 242, University Paperback Edition, 1967, $2.25. Deny to the life of mankind any semblance of continuity, deny any value to history and the role of the historian amounts to little more than a collector of facts, interesting perhaps but unrelated to modern life. Affirm a community to life, accept the experience of living as a fact which, while ancient with years, has maintained its identity through the passage of time, the appearance and disappearance of cultures, of social and political institutions, then the search into the past of life must be viewed as a labor capable of yielding authentic values for life in the twentieth century. The authors of these two works share the conviction that life is an experience of both the past and the present. They also share a commitment to the thesis that history, the recorder of the experiences in living from the past, can be profitable for life in the present. It is this double assent which explains the two studies of Greek Philosophy. G. F. Parker's A Short Account of Greek Philosophy draws its incentive from an awareness of the gulf that separates the " two cultures." And its purpose is to provide a bulwark against the possible tragedy of " Science, adrift from its moorings in humanism and history, (becoming) a ravening monster, while the Arts, oblivious of new areas of reality revealed by Science, (become) as arid as the deserts of the moon" (p. 4). For the author, the study of Greek Philosophy is one "of a number of common platforms on which those who wish to be both literate and numerate can 278 BOOK REVIEWS meet " (p. 5) , since " Greek civilisation is the common source from which the divergent streams of art and science flow down to us" (ibid)· G. C. Field is more modest in his appeal to history. He addresses his study on Plato and His Contemporaries primarily to those whose interest in philosophy is already assured. Describing the book as a " preliminary or supplementary essay to a study of the philosophy of Plato " (preface, p. v), Field directs his major effort to the task of bringing into proper focus the circumstances of history in which that philosophy emerged and developed. Only in a minor way does the platonic system itself occupy the author's attention. In the pursuit after his purpose Field achieves an admirable success. His study of the platonic historical milieu offers the initiated valuable insights into the genesis of the problems to which Plato addressed himself. It gives that philosophy a sense of being involved in the cross currents of the life of those days. For those who have yet to encounter Plato through a systematic study of his philosophy the work makes that philosopher and the problems with which he wrestled something more than academic incidents far removed from life. And Parker, too, achieves a goodly measure of success in his effort to construct a bulwark against the tragedy of mutually distrustful science and art. His invitation to today's men of science to spend time in the company of the philosophers of the 7th to the 4th centuries B. C. is cleverly couched in terms that should elicit something more positive than a hasty, unthinking refusal. His portrayal of the thinkers and searchers of those times as men made restless by the challengers offered them by the universe cannot impress the modern man of science as a sort of self-portrait. The invitation is attractive and its benefit, if accepted, makes available history's story of intellectual life which is not without consequence to living today. There is, however, a phase of the portrait of the thinkers of Greece which, to my mind, merited more care in its delineation than the author actually gave it. It seems to me that, in his effort to woo the scientist to cultivate an acquaintance with the era of Greek philosophy, Parker fails to present with sufficient vibrancy the figures of those philosophers whose forte was located outside and beyond the limits of the Philosophy of Nature. These are indeed mentioned and their thought presented with commendable fullness. But their relevancy is not adequately emphasized. And they are relevant. The paths traversed by Socrates in his ethical philosophy, of Plato and Aristotle in their search for a First Philosophy were the result of the demands of the spirit of man who found himself threatened with being engulfed almost to the point of insignificance by the world of the naturalists. Modern man is experiencing a like feeling. JosEPH Dominican H01U1e of Studit!$ Waskinvton1 D. (}, C. TAYLOR, 0. P. 279 BOOK REVIEWS The Moral Philosophy of Mo-Tze. By AuGUSTINUS $6.00. China Printing LTD, 1965. Pp. A. TsEU. Taiwan: This book (originally a doctoral dissertation) is published under the auspice of Fu-Jen Catholic University on Taiwan. Since the philosopher Mo-Tze is so little known in the West, this study of his moral philosophy is a welcome addition to the English sources of Chinese philosophy. A contemporary of Mencius, Mo-Tze was a unique Chinese philosopher, because he, unlike Lao-Tze or Confucius, was not of scholarly or aristocratic stock but a common man. Furthermore, he reacted against the naturalistic tradition of Taoism and Confucianism and replaced it with a religious philosophy of Heaven. The basic tenets of his system are: Heaven is loving and intelligent, provident and just; and the will of Heaven is the moral law for man. This will of Heaven as discovered by the ancient sages and Mo himself is universal love for all men. Good or evil, rewards or punishments, prosperity or misfortune, all hinge on whether or not the will of Heaven is realized in one's life. Being of poor origin, MoTze shunned luxury and extravagant rituals. He advocated absolute equality among men and a pacifistic policy among nations. He instituted a tightly organized fraternity with numerous loyal followers. However, Mo-Tze's teachings declined immediately after his death, partly because the Han dynasty adopted Confucianism as the orthodox teaching of the Empire, and partly because Mo-Tze's philosophical spirit was at variance with the tradition and temperament of the Chinese people. Universal love without distinction and absolute equality of all men were considered lofty doctrines but too impractical if the social and family structures of that time were taken into consideration. Therefore, Mo-Tze remained almost unknown until the Nationalist Revolution in this century. Since that Revolution, as every revolution, initiated a strong anti-traditional sentiment, Mo-Tze as the antagonist of Confucius again captured the imagination of the modern Chinese. Many works on Mo-Tze's philosophy have come off the press in recent times. The author's study is detailed and cogent; however, his scholastic background has prejudiced his judgments on controversial issues, and also his exposition is too argumentative. His digression in Chapter two, section one, is cumbersome, and typographical errors abound in the book. Nevertheless, I feel that sinologists may find the book valuable. PAUL Catholic University of America WC18hington, D. C. K. K. ToNG BOOKS RECEIVED Alba House: Restructuring Religious Life, by Patrick J. Berkery, S.M. M. (Pp. 19f.l, $3.95); Catechism of Vatican II, by Franco Pierini, S. S. P. (Pp. f.l60, $4.95); Personality Types and Holiness, by Alexander Roldan, S. J. (Pp. 384, $6.50); Newman on Justification, by Thomas L. Sheridan, S. J. (Pp. f.l65, $6.50); The Literary Genre Midrash, by Addison G. Wright, S. S. (Pp. 164, $f.l.95). Barnes & Noble, Inc.: Elementary Formal Logic, by C. L. Hamblin (Pp. 18f.l, $f.l.f.l5 paperback, $f.l.75 hardback); Plato and His Contemporaries, by G. C. Field (Pp. f.l4f.l, $f.l.f.l5 paperback, $4.00 hardcover). Desclee de Brouwer: Thomisme Ou Pluralisme?, by Jean Racette (Pp. 1f.l7, 111 FB); Temps, Dieu, Liberte, by Simon Decloux, S. J. (Pp. f.l6f.l). East-West Center Press: The Japanese Mind, by Charles A. Moore (ed.) (Pp. 357, $9.50). Free Press: The Concept of the Primitive, ed. by Ashley Montagu (Pp. f.l67, $6.95); Modes of Thought, by Alfred North Whitehead (Pp. 179, $1.95). Harper & Row, Publishers: America's Forgotten Priests, by Joseph H. Fichter, S. J. (Pp. f.l54, $6.95) . Herder and Herder: The Relevance of the New Testament, by Heinrich Schlier (Pp. f.l58, $6.50). Holt, Rinehart & Winston, Inc.: The Peasant of the Garonne, by Jacques Maritain (Pp. f.l77, $6.95). Inst. d'Etudes Medievales: Le Retour a Saint Thomas, A-T-Il Encore Un Sens Aujourd'hui?, by Fernand van Steenberghen (Pp. 60). MacMillan Company: Structures of Christian Priesthood, by Jean-Paul Audet (Pp. llf.l, $4.95) . Martinus Nijhoff: Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. XVI (Pp. 161, $f.l.50). Miniverse Services: Divination & Historical Sources of I Ching, by Joe Everett McCaffree (Pp. 64, $4.00). Ohio University Press: Reason and Virtue, by Antonio S. Cua (Pp. 196, $5.00). Oxford University Press: The Second Vatican Council, ed. by Barnard C. Pawley (Pp. f.l6f.l, $3.75). Presses de L'Universite Gregorienne: Ethique Generale, by Joseph De Finance, S. J. (Pp. 448, 3000 lires). Philosophical Library, Inc.: The War Against the Jew, by Dagobert D. Runes (Pp. 19f.l, $6.00). Sheed and Ward: Redeeming the Time, by James V. Schall, S. J. (Pp. f.!44, fl80 BOOKS RECEIVED 281 $5.50); The Spiritual Journey of St. Paul, by Lucien Cerfaux (Pp. 236, $5.00); Life in the Spirit (Theological Meditations, Vol. IV), ed. by Hans Kling (Pp. 157, $3.95); The Church, by Hans Kling (Pp. 515, $6.95) . Twayne Publishers, Inc.: J. F. Powers, by John V. Hagopian (Pp. 174, $3.95). University of New Mexico Press: Directory of American Philosophers, Vol. IV, ed. by Archie J. Bahm (Pp. 439, $13.95). University of Notre Dame Press: Integration of Man and Society in Latin America, ed. by Samuel Shapiro (Pp. 356, $6.50); Cluny under Saint Hugh-1049-1109, by Noreen Hunt (Pp. 228, $6.95); Trilogy on Wisdom and Celibacy, by J. Massingberd Ford (Pp. 298, $7.95). Wayne State University Press: Prophetic Faith in Isaiah, by Sheldon H. Blank (Pp. 241, $2.50). Whittemore Associates, Inc.: Art Studies in the Life of Christ, by C. Fraser Keirstead, D. D. (Pp. 64, $.65) .