THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington, D. C. 20017 VoL. XXXIV JANUARY, 1970 No.1 THE RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY: THE NEW LAW I N THE RENEWAL of moral theology, in its pedagogy, but more profoundly in its epistemological aspect and the inspiration deriving from it, the relationship between law and grace is without doubt the heart of the problem. Moreover, this is no longer a matter of one-sided controversy with Lutheran theology but, beyond the necessary reaction of the defense of orthodoxy, of agreement on a radical investigation of the internal dialectic between law and grace, which Lutheran intuition has already grasped. My qualifications in this area are not those of a moral theologian but rather of a historian of theology, or, more precisely, in a sociological history, of an historian of the Gospel among the People of God, at that precise point where the Gospel is the leaven in the Church, the extent of the mystery and the place of the Spirit. I do not, therefore, offer a labora1 M.D. CHENU tory-type scientific analysis of the theoretical relationship between law and grace but, in its effect on concrete behavior (is this not where the impact of moral theology, a practical science, lies?) , the relationship of law and grace as it actually exists in the community life of the Church structured by the Spirit. My profession as historian has led me to look favorably upon these experiences, whether authentic or deviate, and thus has made me ultra-sensitive to the present problem, not so much in its theoretical articulations, urgent as they may be, but in its community contexts. It is commonly agreed that the Council directed neither its attention nor its decisions explicitly to the field of moral theology. Certainly, many of its documents, in particular the Constitution Gaudium et s-pes, furnish copious material; but today we have to elaborate upon it, drawing inferences from the many pregnant ideas beneath the texts. Having been witness to many of them, I would like to note the evangelical aspiration which impregnates them: how the freedom of the Gospel, amidst the powers of the world, emanates from the complex, sometimes turbulent, play of charisms exercised in the awakenings and movements of poverty in the heart of the People of God urged forward by its messianic hope: the poor in the Church are of themselves contesters of the structures, the moral precepts, the established order, briefly, of the Law itself. Another example with reference to current controversies: an accurate knowledge of the concrete relationships between law and grace will allow us to go beyond the contrasted positions of " situation ethics." Right at the beginning I must remark that the category "moral theology," as distinguished from "dogmatic theology," cannot be employed without reservation. Not that it is false, but in its pedagogical formalism it separates the elements of a global perception outside of which truth remains fragmented. It is well-known that this distinction is ill-suited to the ordo disciplinae of Saint Thomas. It is likewise known that in the Council where the category of pastoral, by way of distinction and often by way of opposition, was placed ahead RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY of that of doctrinal, the impact of the truth of the Gospel on Christian life--except for the abstract doctrine of apostolic pragmatism-has not been sufficiently determined. The conditions for a "pastoral" magisterium, as it is called today, that is, of an authentic teaching in which the "law of liberty" (a term used by Saint Thomas in referring to the New Law) dominates and transforms the precepts, cannot be established except through an integral theology of grace and law. Thus there is an urgent need to supplant ihe entire theology of the Counter-Reformation, using constraint when opportune, both mental and pedagogical. A wonderful hope, of which moral theologians can be both witnesses and doers. What then is my approach as an historian, observing the performance of the "new law," the Gospel in history? For it is in history, a sacred history, that the New Law finds its subject and its intelligibility. SALVATION HISTORY To begin with, let us register one very important and meaningful fact which reveals a primary law in the life of the Church: the " return to the Gospel," according to the full meaning of this expression, is the condition of a Christian's presence in his day, of a presence both in thought and in action, as regards the formulation of problems as well as pastoral insights. Return to the Gospel, presence in our day: 1 baffling dialectic when subjected to an abstract and detemporalized analysis; but, for the historian, a homogeneous knowledge of an economy whose dynamism emanates from an investment by God in history between the two comings of Christ. The "return to the Gospel," by its inspiration, its direct 1 We have here the very tenns of the Council when in the Decree on Religious Life it defines the radical principle of renewal: "Accommodata renovatio vitae religiosae simul complectitur et continuum reditum ad omnia vitae christianae fontes ... et aptationem ad mutatas temporum conditiones " (n. 2). Simul is employed intt-ntionally in its intensive meaning to signify not only a juxtaposition but an interference. This perfect formula is valid for the renewal of the whole of the Church. 4 M.D. CHENU reading, its charismatic thrust, is the very principle-pastorally and epistemologically-{)£ understanding the concrete situations of today, beyond the data of non-temporal terms and abstract precepts. This is the way of the Word of God: God speaks today,-in a community in which the apostolic ministry, continued by the episcopal ministry, functionally (rule) and sacramentally (orders) conditions the teaching of the faith and pastoral conduct. The actual life of the Church, the hierarchical community of the People of God, is the appropriated theological place, locus ultimo paratus, of theologae and theological understanding of the" New Law," another name for grace and the presence of the Spirit. Far from yielding to the counterposition of grace and law, liberty and obedience, their theoretical and practical articulation manifest their intrinsic complementarity. Unobtainable in its perfection, the organic unity of evangelical liberty and preceptive authority is, nevertheless, the permanent intention of our efforts and our researches. Today: the Christian economy is defined as a history, a " salvation history," which faith, hope and charity, the virtuous organism of grace with its equipage of gifts and charisms, guides and renders intelligible. But, while being " salvific," this history is nonetheless history, embracing secular history whose total reality is assumed by the People of God, the Body of Christ animated by the Spirit. " Spiritus Dei, qui mirabili providentia temporum cursum dirigit et faciem terrae renovat, huic evolutioni adest." 2 It is within this active presence of the Spirit that all laws play their part. THE REGIME OF THE SPmiT The most significant and most famous case in the West of this " awakening of the Gospel " in history is that manifested, stirred up and nourished by the foundation of the Mendicant Orders, under the charismatic power of Saint Francis and of Saint Dominic, the ecclesial context of the theology of Saint s Gatulium et Spes, n. 26, 4. RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY 5 Thomas, unthinkable without this spiritual disturbance. Here we can only mention this major episode,-from which expressly proceed our vocation, our life, our institution, our theology. Let us observe that it was not merely a movement of moral reform, with a better observance of laws, but, in today's terminology, a " structural reform," in which the charisms of the Spirit consubstantially play their part, and, as always, the sociological index is the call to poverty, for liberation from the established order. The episode of the Spirituals in the Order of Saint Francis, in their criticism of institutions, legalisms, moral precepts, suggests (and very much so today) that equilibrium is difficult to maintain in this evangelism. Let us remember that faith in the Spirit and sensitivity to the movement of history on the march toward the end-time have been simultaneous from the beginning. It has been something quite other than the adaptation of a moral teaching, called eternal, to accidental circumstances. It is salvation history in action in history: the " return to the Gospel " is provoked by the consciousness of a violent change of a decayed anthropology and of an out-dated society: they are being contested in the name of the Gospel. Here the established Church has been subjected to a difficult testing, which, while extremely beneficial, has not been without risk or failure, even in the area of theology. Saint Thomas's treatise on the New Law in the Summa is the scientific formulation, in the intellectus fidei, of this lofty experience of the People of God. The ultimate reason for this ecclesial and theological operation is the Incarnation, by which the Word of God becoming flesh entered into history, which is from now on innervated by the grace of Christ. Humanization, understood here as moral and social humanization, is the locus for divinization. Christ is not a divine being on a visit to the world of men to whom he would bring, in the nature of a message, the expression of the general and non-temporal divine will as a super-decalogue. In him the law is "new"; its precepts and its dogmatic formulas are but dispositions for justification. (For this reason 6 M.D. CHENU we cannot read the questions of Saint Thomas on law in the I-II without the III Pars.) . This double historicity, of man and of God, determines an economy of movement according to the eschatological dynamism of the accomplishment of God's plan. It is certain that in Christ the investment is total: all in him, past, present and future, is accomplished in being, truth and goodness. There is no longer any need for awaiting another age, an age of the Spirit, in which all laws, institutions, and even the very sacraments themselves would be dissolved. Such was the false utopia promised by the new Gospel under the odd prestige of Joachim of Flora, which seduced a whole line of "Spirituals," including some of the early Preachers. In fact, there is contestation regarding conceptual and institutional data. We know that Saint Thomas was strongly against these myths. But this absolute which is Christ does not in any way preclude distentions in time-the time of the Church-between the two comings. It is precisely this distention in time (and in space) which introduces psychological, social and political dimensions to the history of humanity without impairing its fidelity to an identical economy. The impact of the Gospel can be discerned whenever events become" signs of the times." The apostolic and doctrinal import of this evangelical category, which the Council fixed as a key position and made into a law, is recognized by all. The reading of these " signs " is the work of faith understanding history within the hierarchical Community in which presence to the world is the objective title to a discernment of these " signs." 3 Thus socialization, a typical phenomenon of the new civilization, engenders human values in which the Gospel takes on its " political " dimension in a fraternal love which takes possession of the collective structures: a newness in act in the law of the Spirit and not merely the reform of a social doctrine laboriously accommodated to a drastic evolution. Individual morals and preceptive behavior • Cf. the Constitution Gaudium et spell, n. 44; and John XXIII, Pacem in tertia, n, 1(10. RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY 7 may no longer and should not be based on anything other than this socialization of the Gospel, within the context of salvation history. A certain spiritualism of the " interior life," affected by the view of eternity, has for a long time led to grave distortions within the Church and thus become alien to the world and to history. The "New Law" is the presence of the Spirit in the evolution of humanity. 4 CREATION AND INCARNATION In this historical economy-the Gospel in time-the Christian finds himself defined by the double dimension of two mysteries, Creation and Incarnation, or, better still, of the unique mystery of the Word, realized in two operations: the Word creator and the Word incarnate. There you have, in fidelity and through fidelity to this mystery, the twofold cause of the permanent" newness." Ecce nova facio omnia. 5 This is the axiom of the "New Law." God did not create a ready-made universe upon which man would be placed like an angelic spirit upon heterogeneous matter or as the foreign spectator of a landscape at one moment fascinating and at another overwhelming. God has called man to be his cooperator in the progressive organization of a universe of which man himself, the image of God, must thus be the demiurge and conscience. He is precisely and primarily the image of God inasmuch as, being associated with his creator, he is by that very fact, in full liberty and responsibility, the master and builder of nature. Now, due to the gigantic progression of man's grasp of nature, the radical metamorphosis of the conditions of his cultural and moral growth, the massive involvement of the construction of societies, we here are becoming aware of this "continuous creation," in a permanent state of innovation, in man's creativity. This vision of a history by which man is continually formed, and in which likewise the Word continually • Cf. the text quoted from the Council. • Apoc. 21:5. 8 M.D. CHENU manifests himself, is able to renew the biblical revelation of creation and to nourish a " theology of event " under the recapitulation of all reality in Christ. Thus God's Word, once for all and completely realized in Jesus Christ, preserves riches forever new in the Church consequent upon the historical and cultural situations in which they are welcomed and assimilated. It is the same faith, but it has a history, developments, epochs. Far from fearing to be dissolved, this faith recognizes, as an essential condition of its survival, the necessity of being resolutely inscribed in the diversity and succession of cultures which form human history. Thus the "New Law" includes in its insights and in its exercise a consubstantial coefficient of prophecy in order that this permanent innovation be honored. Greek thought, which has always fallen short of the all-embracing reality of history, and Roman law, whose categories do not lend themselves to this dynamism without rupture, have not, despite their invaluable benefit, adequately responded to this evangelical demand. It is quite insufficient to say that Saint Thomas baptized Aristotle; and history is not satisfied with the affidavit Ecclesia vivit iure romano. The General Assembly of the World Council of Churches, which was held July 1968 at Upsala with the active participation of the Catholic Church, had for its theme: Ecce nova facio omnia, the verse already quoted from the Apocalypse. At the opening conference the Metropolitan of Latakia, Mgr. Hazim, presented the subject in this way: We will not adopt this phrase as simply a program of study and of action. That would lead us to the impasse of established orders and of revolutions: to moralize. No, "I make all things new" is not a program but an event, the sole Event of history. We are the prophets of the new, the visionaries of the resurrected Christ. The Eastern prelate went on to describe this creator Newnessthe newness of the law-which cannot be explained by the past but by the future, in this way: RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY 9 God comes into the world as to his own encounter; he is up front and he calls, he upsets, he sends, he causes increase, he liberates. Any other god is a false god, an idol, a dead god, and it is high time that our modern consciousness bury it. This multiform god who inhabits the former consciousness of man is in effect behind man as a cause; he commands, organizes, causes man to regress and finally alienates him. There is nothing prophetic about him; on the contrary, he always comes afterward as the ultimate reason for the inexplicable or the last recourse of irresponsible people. This false transcendent is as old as death. . . . On the contrary, the creator newness comes into the world with the world. It does not invent itself, nor does it prove itself: it reveals itself. It is either welcomed or refused but it comes as an event ... (It is the action of the Holy Spirit which makes this newness come into the world.) Without it, God is far away, Christ is in the past, the Gospel is a dead letter, the Church a mere organization, authority a domination, mission a propaganda, worship an evocation, and the Christian way of life a moral slavery. And he concluded that the Church, the place and sacrament of this mystery, is " the prophetic conscience of the drama of this hour." THE DECALOGml It is in this context of the mystery acting in history that is developed and illuminated the dialectic of grace and law according to which the conceptual and preceptive elements, transubstantiated by grace, become conditionings, "dispositions," according to the unusual expression of Saint Thomas, of the life of the Spirit. There is no longer the question of receiving grace in order to become capable of facing up to the demands of the commandments (such a notion presided over the construction of the Counter-Reformation catechisms) but to live in dependence on the interior movement of the Spirit. In the long run the ethical ideal resides in the fact that man is a law unto himself and not in the fact that he obeys God's command coming from without. Such is the root of Christian liberty which is certainly not the absence of every norm but implies the free choice of a line of conduct conformable to the inner call of grace. Man fixes for himself his own law before 10 M.D. CHENU God: I psi sibi sunt lex. Thus the" evangelical revivals" in the Church overcome moral reforms: theological intensity of faith, exaltation of hope both eschatological and terrestrial, personal and collective disturbance of fraternal charity, challenge to the outmoded apparel of society and the Church, charisms of the presence and work of the Spirit, evangelical counsels assented to in the gratuity of vocations and human relations: so many blaring indices of the permanent newness of the " New Law " in the history of the People of God. Among the many efficacies of this regime, the historian is able to observe in the facts and theologiGal analyses change of sense which is operative in the precepts of the so-called "natural law." A certain insistence upon this "natural law," its content, its personal and social constraints, strongly risks atrophying, with reference to Christ, the " law of liberty" enjoyed by the Christian. The history of the exegesis and practice of the Decalogue is very significant here. At times the Decalogue is presented as the Word that an eternally unmovable God pronounced about a people which would be taken out of history through obedience to this Word,-and not as a Word spoken in history by a God who is making history to a people inserted in this history. The Ten Commandments would explain the general and universal conditions of all morality, providing morality with a series of pronouncements more perennial and unmovable than are reputed to come from the mouth of God, who is himself eternal and unchangeable: " Thus speaks the Eternal. ... " So God says eternally the same thing. That which, in the preaching of the prophets, indicates the actuality of the Word of God, is converted into a proclamation of his eternity. There is certainly some truth in this; but there is the immediate danger of falling into an abstract deism without history, outside the Covenant of the Old Testament, beyond the evangelical impact of the " new creation " in Christ. Certainly, going along with the great scientific theology of the thirteenth century, I continue to think that, without any detriment to the Gospel and its kerygma, theological reasoning RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY 11 can very fruitfully discern, establish, and analyze the rational and universal structure of this divine law. Thus Saint Thomas and Saint Bonaventure consider that the articulations of the Ten Commandments "recte ordinata sunt." I do not agree with the Barthian criticism of the Decalogue as natural law. Under the divine law nature is brought back into its own, and reason is bolstered in its autonomy of vision and method. This is what justifies, in documents such as Pacem in terris and in the Constitution Gaudium et spes, the aforementioned analyses of natural law. It is always true that for the People of God in the world in formation, an existental consideration involves the feeling of a presence of the Gospel not only at the level of pastoral efficacies but at the level of theological and historical understanding of the Kingdom of God. Otherwise this " natural law " turns into a catalogue of abstract truths made all the more rigid in the encounter with the movement of history. Innovation, discovery, creativity, charisms, are all eliminated from it. This is what happens in certain presentations of "social doctrine," closer in their uprooted universalism to W olfian philosophy than to the evangelism of the theology of Saint Thomas. An analogous analysis could be drawn of the moralizing interpretation of the " Sermon on the Mount," which makes from that which is first of all a prophetic proclamation of love in the actual coming of the Spirit abstract principles of morality, directed to an accounting of good works. In the final analysis, such are the relations between ethics and religion, religion being understood as the "New Law" in Christ. The difference of application of categories, the very vocabulary, demonstrate that we are epistemologically confronted by two types of truth: evangelical truth as prophetic testimony, as the living message, messianic promise, and moral truth as enunciated by theological reason. " Saving" truth has in its christological and eschatological concentration a dimension specifically historical: not formally that which is, but that which happens, that which we concretely experience, the 12 M.D. CHENU truth of Saint John, pistis and dikaiosune, the power of the Church manifested in the Word. The Good News proclaimed in joy, today. Thus the "New Law": the grace of the Holy Spirit, communicated in faith, and not written law, consigned in documents and in principles. M. D. CHENU, 0. P. Couvent de Saint-Jacques Paris, France THE TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW T HE TEACHING FUNCTION has been for a long time restricted to an elite class, closely supervised by political or ecclesiastical authority, and regulated by corporate statutes. In our own times the very idea of this type of authoritarian control and corporate regulation raises objections; in fact, the teaching function has been so diluted that it can be said to be reserved to no one and is open to all. The audience reached by a journalist, or even a songwriter, is often greater, due to the multiplicity and facility of means of expression, than that reached by a professor with degrees and official approval. However, to the extent that the teaching profession still exists, the training of teachers and the establishment of philosophically-oriented programs are less assured and are subject to many variations, since they are now more greatly influenced by the movements of public opinion. Political events, unpredictable as they are, currently have repercusions on the career and choice of teachers as well as upon the duration of programs and the spirit of teaching. Teaching must meet the needs of the people as they are expressed and are capable of being solved. Hence the demand of truth, to the extent that it is expressed and wherever it is concretely accompanied by the willingness to pay the price, bears less on objective and disinterested truth than it does on an exact adjustment of the student for his future tasks, either by organizing the teaching of moral theology to meet the need of the Church for confessors, or by channelling the flow of students toward subjects which will immediately assure them of a good position and answer the needs of economic development and of social welfare. It appears, therefore, that the teacher, because of his concern 18 14 JEAN TONNEAU for effectiveness, especially in the apostolic and the pastoral area, tries to become a journalist, if not a songwriter, in order to get a great hearing. He fears that, unless he does so, he will be thought of as a mandarin. The democratization of teaching easily tends towards a " massification." 1 I do not even wish to speak of the at times troubling overtones which accompany or run the risk of accompanying this symptom: a laziness which precludes sustained and silent effort; an appeal to the tinkle of vainglory. Above all there is the objection based on principle: why, what right have I to oppose them? Even the theologian who, more than anyone else, should say to himself: " My doctrine is not my own," experiences similar scruples. These he resists to the extent that he has not fallen prey to an idealistic epistemology or to phenomenology which denies "ready-made " truths, that is, precisely those which are not for everyone to create for himself, those which constitute the object of a doctrinal tradition. We should add that the process is one which is auto-accelerating; once a striking formula hits the public ear it resonates and is amplified so that it seems to be a confirmation of its truth. It may have been proposed merely as a hypothesis by the author, but it soon succeeds too well for him to withdraw his conviction that it is firmly established, and thus it immediately passes for a conclusion of modem science (or an exigence of the modem conscience) . This is so much so that the author loses every chance of continuing and of deepening his thinking on the matter, of keeping his critical spirit on the alert. Paradoxically, success itself condemns him to psittacism. 2 Moral science, and the theory of law 8 which forms part of it, are particularly suspect. It is amusing to note that Abbe 1 Cf. G. Gottier, Le langagc de la foi. Fidelite et invention, in Table Ronde, n. 250 (Nov. 1968), p. 67. • Cf. J. De Bourbon-Bosset as quoted by P. Gache, La France catholique, July 29, 1966, p. 6. • There is nothing quite as distressing to the public as this word theory, and authors avoid it as much as possible. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 15 J. M. Aubert begins his work, Loi de Dieu, Loi des hommes, with humble oratorical precautions, as if he needed to beg forgiveness for writing on so grim a subject. 4 Not long ago the manuals showed more boldness; they did not hesitate at all to affirm as prime and incontestable truths the existence of divine and human laws, the nature of law, its inviolable power to bind, etc. We are far from this robust healthiness, which would pass today for naive triumphalism. The Abbe Aubert suggests an explanation for this change of attitude: the decadence of Christian teaching on law. In the final analysis, I believe that all explanations can be reduced to this. But it is evident that this decadence depends on many causes, and it remains to be asked especially what a good Christian teaching on law should be. We might think that the rapid and profound changes which the world has known and is still experiencing are responsible, to a large extent, for the distrust and even contempt which the idea of law arouses. Everything changes, challenge is not new, but it seems that we have a sharper awareness of universal change. Thus in this constant change it could be said that law seems to be a stumbling block, an insoluble lump in a universal fluidity; as soon as a law is established, it weighs down as a heritage from the past 5 upon a movement which pushes us forward; it is always by definition a fixed and circumscribed conception which prevents us from seeing with a clear and alert eye the perpetual flow of unrecorded situations wherein we are led to each moment by a living reality. Established laws make us react awkwardly to these ever new situations with a slowness that can never be overcome. This is presuming that change and constant novelty appeal to us. Rightly or wrongly, we project all our hopes into the future: change, novelty, fluidity, by dropping the baggage and • In the collection " Le mystere chretien," published by Desc!ee. I am happy to say that this work contains nothing grim. • To resent the heritage of the past considered as something weighing down is a recent and remarkable phenomenon. Up to now, to benefit from the treasury accumulated by the Fathers and carefully transmitted to subsequent generations had been considered as an advantage, as the mark of a noble civilization. 16 JEAN TONNEAU impedimenta of the past, appear to us as positive, I mean favorable, values, even if they involve risks and force us to abandon vested interests with legitimate regret. No matter how respectable these regrets, how justifiable our disturbance, there is no question of fighting shy of the future toward which we are heading with joyous fervor, as if we were sure that the balance sheet of every change, of every step forward, was necessarily favorable and that every tomorrow must necessarily sing out precisely and uniquely because it is a tomorrow. If this act of faith were reasonably based, there would be no point in eulogizing the law. Rather, it would be more fitting to challenge all established laws, their restraints, their barriers that slow us up on the incline down which we are rolling. The conclusion was drawn in this sense. It is a matter of paring down as much as possible, of dissolving even that which remains of the legal establishment, of rendering the present situation uncomfortable, unbearable, of aggravating its irritating aspects, and of laying down justifying bases, if we are to pave the way for the future whatever it may be. Of course, we know nothing about the future, except that it will be necessarily better; to pretend that we can impose upon it in advance a prefabricated or preconceived plan is not to follow the rules of the game. Our freedom is not only unable to choose and to prepare for what " must " come, but it would contradict itself, so to speak, if whatever " must " come could be read in advance. There remains for us only one thing to do if we wish willy-nilly to contribute to what is coming, if not to the construction of the future: demolish everything that exists, make a clean sweep with the intention of accelerating the course of events. This intention, let us note, is probably illusory, for it gratuitously presupposes that there is at least a human activity, a subversive activity, which is endowed with efficacy and which could in a certain manner affect the future; but this, contrary to the logic of the system, is to reintroduce a law. The true logic of the system is that of fate. Man is just a straw swept along powerless by the stream of becoming. Our act of faith is only a sentimental aftermath of faith in a TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 17 provident God who directs the course of history. Thus, just as economic liberalism began by being optimistic, by thinking that it could read into the fatality of laisser-faire a natural providential order but soon becoming pessimistic, so now our naive confidence in tomorrows which will sing can in the wink of an eye become transformed, with just as much or as little cause, into the most somber despair. In any case, we can observe that to raise a question on the law is to raise a fundamental question, without doubt the fundamental question, not only in the order of morality but with regard to reason, one which affects man and his place in time and in the universe. The different problems raised by the tract on law can be grouped under two headings, simply put, those from the viewpoint of doctrina sacra and those from the viewpoint of moral theology. It is clear what the first point of view entails: why speak of law in theology when we live by faith and the Gospel? On the other hand, the theologian, if he speaks of law, necessarily touches on moral considerations, 6 and if he borrows from the moralist, he must supervise the quality of these borrowings. Thus we will have occasion to control from this philosophical point of view the very definition of law in general and more particularly the notions of legislative authority and of the moral obligation of law, which is practically one and the same problem. Finally, a few remarks will be necessary touching on the relationship between the tracts on law and on grace in the Prima Secundae. These problems will be taken up in four parts: I. Law in doctrina sacra; II. The Thomist definition of law; III. The authority of the legislator and the binding force of law; IV. The relationship between the tracts on law and on grace. I. LAw IN Doctrina Sacra Not infrequently we experience a somewhat saddened surprise in seeing theologians devote so much space to law in their 6 This is the tenn employed by Saint Thomas when he laid down the plan of the Secunda Pars. 18 JEAN TONNEAU exposition of doctrina sacra; we are inclined to reproach them for introducing into the simplicity of revelation a foreign body, a technique, called for by the need or the elegance of a system. Is this not one more sad result of the treachery of dialectics? Why water down the pure wine of God's word? This kind of uneasiness betrays a certain profane, sociological and juridical idea of law. The latter seems in effect to come from a world other than that of revelation, for example, from canon or Roman law, or from Stoicism, in short, from man, and we believe ourselves authorized to prune doctrina sacra of these profane superfluities. In reality, one has but to read the Bible (this is how theology got its start) to realize that theologians could not do otherwise than to speak about law. This is not something which they have freely chosen to do, not a systematic option which they had need to justify through some technical concern for the good order of reason. The word itself is found in the sacred text and cries out for attention, first of all, by the quite large number of its meanings. 7 Once in a great while the word law is used in an absolute fashion, without any specification, as when I Mace. teaches that Antiochus gave orders asking the Jews either to abandon the law or the books of the law would be confiscated. These books can designate either the Torah in its entirety or simply the legislative books, either the Pentateuch in its entirety or only the Book of the Covenant, i. e., chapters 20-23 of Exodus. Mathathias distinguishes himself by his zeal for the law, and he mobilizes the troops crying • This observation has been made by Saint Thomas on many occasions; for example, twice in a row in his Commentary on the Epistle to the Romans. He notes first of all (in Chapter III, lect. 2, n. 292) that this word designates either the whole of the Old Testament or one of its parts: and since the Old Testament is divided into two or three parts, the word can designate either of two different sets of books, depending on whether the Bible is divided into the Law, the Psalms and the Prophets, or into the Law and the Prophets. Further on (Chapter V, lect. 6 n. 462) the enumeration is more complete: the word law can designate either the Old Testament in its entirety, or the Pentateuch, or the Decalogue only, or the totality of the ritual precepts, or finally such a ritual precept in particular; Saint Thomas gives a text in support of each of his affirmations. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 19 out: " Let everyone who has a fervor for the law come out and follow me." (I Mace. 2: 26-27) With a specification we often find the expression law of Moses. Moses in reality is not the author of the law; he transmits it to the people on the part of God, but God gives all his laws through the intermediary of Moses, even those oral laws which have been transmitted from generation to generation and which are all considered to be connected with the revelation on Sinai. We still speak of the law of God, a consecrated term now become technical, with religious resonances, and reasonably equivalent to what we call " revelation." Undoubtedly God communicated his revelation through different means, but in proportion as devotion to the Law developed after the Exile, the gift of the Law monopolized the whole of revelation; this gift sums up the best of all God's benefits to his people. In the strict sense, the word law has come to stand for any Scriptural text whatever. The case of John 15:25 is well known: "But all this was only to fulfil the words written in their law: they hated me for no reason"; now this citation refers back to Psalm 35. We should not forget that according to rabbinic usage as taught us by the Mishnah (Pirke Aboth) , "Moses received the law of Sinai and communicated it to Josuah, and Josuah communicated it to the elders, the elders to the prophets; the latter entrusted it to the men in the great synagogue," which brings us to the generation which edited the Mishnah, during the second century of our era. Torah means not only the written Mosaic legislation, the 613 mizvot, positive as well as negative, extracted from the Pentateuch by the rabbis, but also the whole doctrine which was transmitted and taught during the course of centuries regarding law under the more juridical form of Halakah or under the edifying form of the Haggadah. All of this would have been known by Moses through the revelation received on Sinai and faithfully transmitted during the course of time to be divulged gradually as needed. Some of these traditions, as we know, found their way into the New Testament, for example, that the law was 20 JEAN TONNEAU given to Moses through the intermediary of angels. (Acts 7: 58; Gal. 8: 19; Heb. 2: 2; cf. I-II, q. 98, a. 8) Next, the word law appears in the sacred text as a series of semantic developments with a firm continuity but also with an unexpected richness which it has received in the course of centuries and through various translations. This point is closely linked to the history of the theology of law itself, but it can be approached here on the level of vocabulary. It is classical to lament the fact that the Septuagint authors translated the Hebrew Torah by the Greek Nomos, which necessarily led to the Latin translation lex. Certainly, if words were once and for all univocal signs with unique meanings, we could be concerned about bringing together words which have their respective origins and a different history and which are, normally, involved in systems which are different in their signification. Etymologically the word Torah would go back, according to specialists, to a root which evokes the idea of " to cast " (as in casting lots, an oracle, etc.), the role of the priest seeming actually to have been originally that of a consultant who makes known the will of the gods rather than a sacrificer, a role which could easily have been fulfilled by the head of the family or clan. Hos. 6:6 relates the word Kahen not to sacrifices but to the Torah and the knowledge of God and his will. Since God is consulted in the case of trouble or litigation, the answers or judgments received before God in the sanctuary easily take on the sense of decisions which, from our point of view, are juridical decisions; the usage has repercussions, according to a well-known law, on the original (?) or etymological meaning of the word. Similarly, again from our own point of view, the fact that Yahweh was consulted in order to resolve problems of conduct gives to the instruction in question a practical signification, even if the people involved, ignorant of philosophy, had not even the faintest idea of the distinction between speculative reason or truth and practical reason or truth. Let us then avoid introducing into the Bible logical precisions which do not belong there. Whatever their contents, the tmot are essentially a teaching, an instruction, a doctrine TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 21 from God, and therefore every time God speaks to men in order to reveal to them his thoughts, his plans, his wishes, there is torah. In this wide fundamental sense we can clearly see evolving under the pressure of practice the meaning of a rule of conduct, of imperative practical truth. This does not diminish the fact that the Torah also contains historical accounts, particularly the recalling of God's benefits, or threats, promises, etc. And especially we must expect to see through the course of centuries the sense of the Torah becoming more complicated and enriched as the Law played an ever greater, sometimes encroaching, role in the life of the people, particularly when prophecy died out and there was no other voice than the Torah to know Yahweh's plans; even more so when there was no longer a Temple or sacrifices and when the Law became in some way identified with all religion. When the Seventy translated the Bible into Greek, the word nomos 8 was already specialized in its different usages and stood for the written law regulating the life of the city; its etymological meaning with the connotation of distribution and of allotment had been generally lost. But in the Jewish milieux of Alexandria nomos quite naturally inherited the meaning of Torah. It is not etymology but usage which modifies and gives nuances to the meaning of words under the mental context which clarifies their meaning and makes them more precise. As much must be said for the later translations into the Latin lex and the French Zoi: these words have their own origin and history, but, introduced into a Christian, thoroughly biblical language, they do not allow for the retention of the basic idea of instruction which was the meaning 8 Nomos, unknown to Homer, appears about the eighth century B. C. and invades the religious, musical, moral and political spheres; it means a melody, a musical style, a hymn. In religion, it is the order of ceremonies, the ritual, or one of the ceremonies in the ooncrete. In morality, nomos is the principle of value recognized by the entire social body and, ooncretely, it signifies good actions or the rules of conduct. In politics, it is the public order, or the laws, or a particular juridical institution. At the etymological origin of 1W1IW8 is found the idea of distribution and allotment. Cf. E. Laroche, Hutorie de la racine NEM-en grec ancien (Paris, 1949). JEAN TONNEAU of Torah. It is not surprising to see Saint Thomas, who did not know Hebrew but was nourished by the Bible, including the most apt formula to introduce the theology of law: (Deus) nos instruit per legem (I-II, q. 90, prol.) . I really believe that the misunderstandings which have arisen from the study of this tract stem from the fact that we forget or neglect the fact that the language of this theologian is a Christian language, i. e., biblical. For obvious reasons we shall dwell on the tract in the Prima Secundae." Its structure is well-known. Having treated of law 9 First of all, for a very practical reason: our teaching in fact comes from reading and commenting on this text. There is also a deeper reason: the Thomist work is the only complete exposition from the point of view of doctrina sacra. Commenting on the Sentences Saint Thomas is not the master of his plan, and he approaches the question of law in accordance with the occasions furnished him by Lombard's text: in Book II, d. 35, the Augustinian definition of sin (" ... quod fit contra legem Dei "), in Book III, d. 36, how charity contains the whole of the law; beginning with d. 37, an analysis of the Decalogue; more particularly, d. 40 on the ninth Commandment which forbids desire is the occasion for a comparison between the Old Law and the New Law; the study of the sacraments in Book IV occasions remarks on the sacraments of the Old Law, on circumcision and on marriage. But the law is never studied for its own sake, either in its general philosophical definition or in its historical realization and its role in the economy of salvation. Even more interesting are Chapters 111-146 of III Contra Gentes, a very personal construction of Saint Thomas, very much involved in a highly structured work and going into great detail. But this exposition, though certainly theological, lacks the simplicity of intention found in the Summa Theologiae; it is not solely doctrina sacra. Not that it is philosophical, but it answers to a specialized task and reflects the theologian organizing the defense of revealed truths against those who deny them, and this is done using arguments which can be accepted by the infidels. It is therefore a work of theological wisdom, but a personal and original work in the line of apologetics and not in that of symbols, of catechesis and of other kinds of expositions prepared by a believer for the use of other believers in order to proclaim in good order, as exactly and completely as possible, the totality of the truths of the faith. Because of its date (between 1261 and 1264) this part of the Contra Gentes has the additional advantage of being almost contemporary with the Prima Secundae (1269-1270). In one sense the Thomist commentaries on the Scriptures come closer to the point of view of the Summa Theol., the latter having originated precisely to prolong, organize and adapt them to pedagogical needs (" secundum quod congruit ad eruditionem incipientium " . . . " secundum ordinem disciplinae "). It is then a greater unity of intention and not only a more thorough analysis that we would like to see in the Commentary on Saint Matthew, (nearly contemporary with the Sentences), on the Epistles of Saint Paul and on Saint John (respectively contemporary with the Summa Contra Gentiles and the TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 28 in general (definition, kinds, effects), Saint Thomas in turn discusses each of the varieties of law (except lex fomitis) which he had enumerated in his general introduction. Thus we have the following chapters: the eternal law, nautral law, human law, divine law in its twofold expression of Old and New Testaments. Historians tell us that this manner of organizing a tract on law was something relatively new; it had been inaugurated by Franciscans and particularly by John de la Rochelle and was found in the work entitled Summa theologica which bears the name of Alexander of Hales (John de la Rochelle and Alexander both died in 1245) . The tertia pars of the Summa of Alexander is presented (general prologue) as a complete exposition of the Christian faith: " Tota christianae fidei disciplina pertinet ad duo: ad fidem et intelligentiam. Conditoris, ... ad fidem atque intelligentiam Salvatoris." Thus it has already been treated from the point of view of fides Conditoris; there remains the question of the Savoir: in his person (Incarnation) and in the work of salvation (sacraments and glory) . This format is followed in the first part of this third book. But, at the threshold of the second part a new distribution of material is proposed under the title: De legibus et praeceptis: Summa theologicae disciplinae in duo consistit, in fide et moribus. The author declares that he has already treated of faith (Redeemer), and he is ready to treat of morals. Now in this respect, he says, it is necessary to interpose precepts and laws, grace and the virtues, gifts, fruits and beatitudes: precepts and laws "ut ostendentia debitum boni faciendi et mali vitandi "; grace, virtues, etc., ... "ut praestantia facultatem faciendi et vitandi." Actually this second part is subdivided into two sections: De legibus et Summa Theologiae). Finally, let us acknowledge the existence of more or less elaborate reflections, scattered throughout the work of Saint Thomas, on divine law considered in its precepts (In duo praecepta caritatis et in decem praecepta legis) or as the ensemble of revelation (the two Principia de commendatione et partitione sacrae scripturae, as well as various prologues to theological works which delineate the mission of the Word as Wisdom who reveals God, enlightens our paths and brings us happiness). 24 JEAN TONNEAU praeceptis, De gratia et 'Virtutibus, which form the second and third parts of the whole of book three. The section de legibus et praeceptis embraces a fourfold investigation (inquisitio): 1. on eternal law; 2. on natural law; 8. on the Mosaic law, first in general and then in particular in three sections: moral precepts (in general and de singulis), judiciary precepts, ceremonial precepts; 4. on evangelical law in two tractatus: de latione et conditionibus legis evangelicae, de praeceptis legis evangelicae. The whole tract on law was therefore clearly drawn up before Saint Thomas. The Summa of Alexander, however, does not mention human law and omits giving a universal definition of law. On this last point Saint Albert will be the initiator. But if we go beyond the mere comparison of matters treated and prologues and heads of divisions where the author reveals his intention, we notice that, in favor of the successive modifications of the plan/ 0 matters which should be presented under the title work of salvation are henceforth entitled De legibus et praeceptis. In order to justify this title it should be kept in mind that all theological teaching comes back to that of faith and morals, and that, the doctrine of faith having been begun in the study of the Savior in his person (Incarnation), the only thing left is to take up the teaching on morals, i. e., to speak of laws and precepts, grace and virtues, gifts, fruits and beatitudes. While perfectly traditional formulas are employed, it happens that, consciously or not, their realization takes place in a perspective which is clearly moral. While expecting a study of the economy of salvation, where law and grace were placed in the context of the unfolding of sacred history, law and precepts are given the function of putting into relief the duty of doing good and avoiding evil, grace and the virtues being that which gives us the capacity to do this. These considerations are certainly not false, but they keep us on the level of moral. 10 We should not be overly astonished to see an author announce a plan which he does not in fact follow; this is not unusual. In the present case, these hesitations and new starts are probably due to the fact that the Summa of Alexander is com· piled from preexistent works. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW Once we go on to the tract in the Prima Secundae we notice that moral is not neglected, that the preceding considerations are found once more, that the same matters, the same solutions (more often than not), and the same categories are retained. But the initial prologue, at the head of q. 90, serving as the key and the framework, gives the tone to the entire piece and leaves no doubt regarding the "economic" significance of the tract. As the indication is circumspect and since the prologue is usually badly interpreted, it should be reread attentively. Let us be clear on what should be read and reread: it is the text of Saint Thomas. In the present case one must be wary of headings added on by editors, either at the head of a question or in the table of contents. For a long time theologians believed that for Saint Thomas law and grace were external principles of human activity; most of them considered this so obvious that they never bothered to explain it; some, such as Banez, raised doubts but believed that they had to base themselves on the authority of Saint Thomas. Actually the Common Doctor, precisely on the subject of human law, which could more easily be looked upon as an external principle, says the opposite; 11 the legislator in promulgating the law gives to those who receive it • quoddam interius principium actuum." Besides, if the law is not confused with its material prop support (tables of stone or of bronze, paper, the writing itself) but is the reality which is reason of which Saint Thomas speaks in the first article of the tract (with its precisions in the ad 2) , we will wonder how law ever got to be called an exterior principle. The text in the prologue is perfectly explicit: it designates by name God and the devil as the two external principles. Since the action of the devil was sufficiently treated in the Prima Pars, there is no need to return to it. There remains, therefore, toward the end of the Prima Secundae a 11 I-II, q. 98, a. 5c: "Sicut homo imprimit denuntiando, quoddam interius principium actuum homini sibi subjecto, ita etiam Deus imprimit toti naturae principia propriorum actuum." . . . The ad 1 compares the promulgation to an impreasio activi principii mtrimeci quantum ad res naturales. 26 JEAN TONNEAU single exterior principle to study, God, who instructs us by means of the law and assists us by means of grace. 12 * * * * * It could be asked at this point if it is suitable to question the fittingness, law notwithstanding, of taking God as an exterior principle. But this time we are on familiar ground. We often read in Saint Thomas that man is master of his actions because he is capable of deliberation, that this deliberation is put into motion by an anterior deliberation, and that at the source of all this movement of which man is master the initiative necessarily belongs to an exterior principle. The theme is treated ex professo in the study de motivo voluntatis (I-II, q. 9, aa. 4-6); it comes up again at the beginning of q. 109, a. 2, ad 1 and in many other places as well.13 We can see in what sense the exteriority of this principium movens ad bonum must be understood: as it often happens in the unfolding of the tract on human acts, this exteriority is treated in relation to the voluntary (quod procedit a principia intrinseco). What we are talking about then is a divine effect whose initiative does not depend on the human will; quite the contrary, it is the movement of the will towards the good which depends on this principle of divine intervention. In the spirit of the Wisdom literature, as in that of the prologue of St. John, there is no place in this respect to distinguish between the different sorts of 10 A good point for Billuart basing himself on the text of the Prologue: God and the devil without further commentary. The case of Conrad Koellin is to be noted: he faithfully takes up the text of the Prologue, but he adds: "quia tamen non determinatur de ea (namely, of law and especially of the New Law) nisi quia a Deo qui est extrinsecus, ideo tractatus ille vacatur de principiis extrinsecis." The formula was therefore already accepted in his time (his work: Exposition commentaria on the I-II carries the approval of the Master General, Cajetan, dated 1511). This does not prevent the editor (1589, Venice) from beginning the tract on law with a heading of his own invention: De principiis exterioribus actuum, scilicet de lege in communi, quantum ad essentiam, which is an awkward formula in every respect. 13 See the beautiful study of M. Seckler, lnstinkt und GlaubenswiUe, which has, among others, the merit of tracing the sources of this doctrine, in particular, for God and the devil, in Saint Hilary (p. 39). A meaningful connection between law and the gifts of the Holy Spirit. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 27 " instruction," natural or supernatural, the normal conduct of Providence or the historical event realized once and for all. This is why the prologue to question 90 is perfectly proportioned to the contents of the tract. There is no doubt that it deals with the entire Christian revelation realized through the mission of the Word. It is impossible to agree with those who suggest that Saint Thomas was principally interested in human law considered as the perfect type of all law and that he understood the consideration of the Old Law and the New Law only pe1' modum complementi, by playing more or less on the sense of the word law and " not without artifice." 14 He did not admit the concept of lex fomitis. Is it not more exact to think that he chose to speak of lex fomitis because Scripture invited him to do so and that he was interested in the Old and New Laws for the same reason? Juridicism, if juridicism there is, is there only for those who cannot read the word law without immediately thinking of Gratian or of Roman law. We are therefore led to the question of the real sources of this tract on law. At the same time we will notice that its various parts are well-balanced. Not only is it noteworthy that of the entire nineteen questions (90-108) eleven treat of the Old and New Laws (98-108), but some of them are developed to the point that there are none longer throughout the rest of the Summa. It is necessary to approach the study of this tract through the interpretations of commentators to think u This is the expression employed by J. de Finance, Etre et agir (1960), p. 171, note 80. And yet this author has the eternal law and the natural law in mind: "L'artifice est visible chez saint Thomas quand il s'efforce d'appliquer a Ia loi eternelle et a Ia loi naturelle une definition de Ia loi inspiree des Etyrrwlogies d'Isidore et du Decret de Gratien." As a reference the author quotes for us q. 90, a. 4 where in fact is found, in the sed contra, a text from Gratian: Leges instituuntur cum promulgantur; and q. 91, a. I where nothing is found, but that matters little; in the same a. 1 of q. 91 we find a reference to Prov. 8:28 which is more significant. It is strange that de Finance (Ethica generalis, 1959, p. 174) finds an exaggerated juridical flavor in the Thomist definition of law in general! If we take into consideration the quotations made by Saint Thomas as indications of the drientation of his iliought, we will be furilier edified. JEAN TONNEAU that the intention of Saint Thomas was principally applied to a philosophico-juridical study of law. Actually, it seems that these commentators steal away when question 98 comes up. There is, however, one exception of weight: in 15M3-1554 Dominic Soto wrote a work which was no longer a commentary on the Summa but an independent book whose success was immense and whose example was contagious, a De Justitia et Jure, whose first part devotes two books to law: I) law in general, the eternal law, the natural law, and human law; the Old Law, the New Law, comparison between the Old and New Laws, and the contents of the New Law; the third book treats of right, of justice in general, of judgment, of divisions of justice and in particular of distributive justice (since the latter was not to be treated later). The second part of the work, starting with the study of dominium, treats of commutative justive; it is the heart of the work. A third part (completiva), in three books, treats of vows, oaths, and the episcopate. The content of the first part has already been noted: its first two books exactly duplicate and in the same order the tract on law in the Prima Secundae. The work is obviously that of a master. The third book admirably sets forth the beginning of the tract on justice, always following the order of the questions of the Summa (II-II, qq. 57-61). By deliberate intention 15 the author modifies the order of his exposition in such a way that it clearly appears that law is the source of right and that a law which does not eventually create a right is an imperfect law, by a kind of reductive analogy. 15 " 16 " Consultius tamen duxi rationem paululum mutare scribendi" (D. Scoto, De jusitia et jure Prooemium). 16 • If there is a necessity for renewal in the teaching o£ the tract on law in its totality, the need is even more urgent for questions 106-108 in particular, relative to the New Law. While these questions have always been there for us to see whenever we study the Summa, this tract can be said to be altogether new, as if it shared in the grace of novelty which belongs to the evangelical law. Altogether new, most of all because it is practically overlooked by the great commentators, Thomist or otherwise. Those who, like Billuart or John of Saint Thomas, comment in the form of dissertation without confining themselves to the order of the articles, omit it entirely. Billuart includes a solid tract on law but leaves out the Old and TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW i9 Now it is a fact that Saint Thomas did not make his tract on law a part of the study of justice and right. This is surprising. Some regret that the Thomist definition of law is too juridical, others feel that the plan of the Summa does not stress this characteristic enough and that the study of law should show a definite connection with that of justice and right, undoubtedly forgetting that, for Saint Thomas, law "non est ipsum jus, proprie loquendo, sed aliqualis ratio New Laws; John of Saint Thomas proceeds directly from the tract on the virtues and the gifts to the tract on grace. Those who follow the text article by article obviously cannot do likewise, but even they do not give these three questions their just due. In broad terms, I find that they comment on this text I) without properly situating these three questions in the whole of the Summa and, consequently, 2) without delineating the theological significance of this small tract either as an element of the tract on law (where it figures somewhat as a rather pious and evangelical appendix), or as an element of sacra doctrina in its entirety. As for exploring the depths of this tract for its own sake, making a special monograph of it, very few theologians have ever dreamt of doing so. At first glance, without having made a methodical search of the libraries, I find very few theologians of the Counter-Reformation, Dominic Soto and Suarez, the first in his De justitia et jure (see the text) and Suarez in his De legibus; paradoxically, both of them use this tract against the Protestants, which leads them to interpret it in a sense which, to be anti-Protestant, lends itself too readily to a juridical legalism. In the eighteenth century the Italian Dominican Patuzzi (1700-1769), in the course of his anti-probabalistic polemics, ultilizes these questions in his Etkica ckristiana (published in 1781), a work remarkable on many counts and pleasant to read but still a bit forced or distorted by its preoccupation with polemics (I was going to say partisanship). More recently, the Franciscan Antonio de Monda has published an interesting work entitled: La legge nuova della libertc't secondo S. Tommaso. It is indicative of a renewal of the tract in the light of the progress made in historical and biblical studies in our own century. However, the hill is a difficult one to climb, and this doctoral thesis remains too closely attached to moral and psychological considerations (it is true that these considerations carry considerable weight in the spirit of the times and that in their own way they contribute something toward the inspiration and sustenance of research) . The work concentrates on the idea, surely correct, that the New Law is a law of liberty. But that this law has a role more profound than that normally attributed to it today, that it has an ontological character in the supernatural physics of grace, has escaped the notice of the author who has not attempted to fmd among the predecessors of Saint Thomas and especially among the Fathers a more developed doctrine on the New Law organically linked to the totality of the economy of salvation, and consequently the 80 JEAN TONNEAU juris," 16 where the term ratio needs to be clarified by the definition found in the I-II, q. 90. Then we will realize that not only can law not be identified with right, that it is not the creative source of right, except accidentally and when the legislative object coincides with an act of government modifying the play of social relationships in that which is called positive law, but, besides, that law pertains to all kinds of areas foreign to right. Before coming to this point, let us continue to draw the perspectives within which the tract on law is written, such as we find it in the text of the Prima Secundae. A first impression is given by the citations found there. Without wanting to attach to them a definitive importance, it is permissible to expect from them an approximate view of the sources consulted by the author and of his principal centers of interest. A brief outline will suffice. The quotations will be distributed in three columns: A. Citations borrowed from questions 90-97; B. Citations borrowed from questions 98-108; C. The total of the two preceding columns reflecting the entire tract. The reason for this division is to bring out strongly the special character of the questions of the Old Law and the New Law. central meeting-place of the doctrines of the Trinity, of the Incarnation, of the Holy Spirit, of the Church, of Revelation, and of justification by faith. This tract on the New Law has been renewed not by the achievement of Scholastic theologians but thanks to the lights thrown upon it by biblical and patristic studies. These lights have become so alive that they have brought about an awakening of the School through numerous articles in which Scripture scholars have tried to cast evangelical doctrines so as to be useful for the Christian life of souls. (A. Feuillet, St. Lyonnet, C. Spicq, F. M. Braun). In this they have been authentic thCQlogians. The bes• study available, not on the tract of the I-II but on the theology of law in Saint Thomas, is that of a Protestant, Ulrich Kuhn, Via caritatis, Theologie des Gesetzes bei Thomas von Aquin, Gottingen, 1965. Written in the ecumenical spirit of doctrinal rapprochement among the various confessions, it shows a deep and sympathic knowledge of Thomist thought. 18 II-II, q. 57, a. 1, ad 2. 31 TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW Bible Aristotle Augustine Biblical glosses Isidore "Jura " (Digest, juriscons. etc.) Maimonides Gratian and Gregory IX Cicero Denys Jerome Chrysostom Damascene Ambrose Gregory the Great Josephus Boethius Hilary Peter Lombard Basil Julius Caesar Ausonius Ambrosiaster Bede the Venerable Cassiodorus Hesychius Pelagius Pseudo-Chrysostom Theodore of Mopsuestia Origen Plato Valerianus Maximus -A- -B- -C- 64 48 35 5 25 12 0 8 3 0 0 0 2 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 660 48 52 28 7 0 9 0 5 5 5 4 0 2 2 2 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 724 96 87 33 32 12 9 8 8 5 5 4 2 2 2 2 2 2 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 208 841 1049 JEAN TONNEAU However unfamiliar one might be with Saint Thomas, this table speaks for itself. His thought is definitely concentrated on Scripture and relies principally on Augustine and Aristotle. If it were possible to go into greater detail, we would find that within Sacred Scripture the most frequently quoted are the books of the Pentateuch (especially Deuteronomy) and the Psalms; then come the Wisdom books, Isaiah, Ezechiel, Hoseah, Job, and Jeremiah. We find about the same thing in Saint Augustine: citations are taken from a great variety of works, but two groups dominate, namely, citations from the Contra Faustum and from the De spiritu et littera in questions 98108, from the De libero arbitrio and from the De vera religione in questions 90-97. With regard to Aristotle, cited the same number of times in both groups of questions, the references are principally to the Ethics, then to the Politics, and then sporadically to the books of the Metaphysics, Rhetoric, and the Physics. The privileged position of the Ethics and Politics is possibly more pronounced in questions 98-108 than in questions 90-97. On the basis of such evidence we are clearly invited to look for the main inspiration of this tract within Christian thought, i. e., in the Bible and in all the commentaries and reflections of the Fathers and Doctors of the Church elaborated on behalf of the faithful or to avert heresy and which they have transmitted to the theologians of the Middle Ages. In this respect Saint Augustine and the scriptural gloss condense all the essential elements of the data and the problems. With Saint Augustine and the glosses, including the anonymous ones, we know that the West received much more than what we ordinarily think has been the inheritance of Greek patristics, expecially that of Origen. 11 But Origen himself, with his genius 17 Even the influence of Philo is recognizable in Saint Ambrose. But we have far better documentation on the extent and depth of Origen's influence on the West. On this subject see Jean Chatillon's research in the Melanges bibliques rediges en l'kcmneur d'A. Robert, p. 537-547: "Isidore et Origene. Recherches sur Jes sources et !'influence des Questiones in vetus testamentum d'lsidore de seville." It contains a bibliography on the <-'Onsiderableand somehow renewed influence of Origen in the TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 33 and his extraordinary capacity for work, is not an absolute beginning; we must go back further to Saint Justin whose Dialogue with Tryphon already contains the whole theology of the two Testaments including most of the biblical types and their spiritual exegesis. We must go back further to the Apostolic Fathers, especially Saint Irenaeus and, through an unbroken continuity, to the exegesis of the rabbis and to the spiritual universe which witnessed the maturing of the revelation of the Old Testament, in the land of exile, or in Palestine, or in Egypt. It is there that we must now search for the sources of the theology of law if we wish to understand the genesis and the authentic sense of the tract in the PTima Secundae. * * * * * The glory and originality of Israel was evidently not constituted by having lived under law or even by having looked upon these laws as a gift of God; the same things can be found among nearly all primitive peoples. That which is proper to Israel, which characterizes biblical thought and which will influence the New Testament, is a certain theology of law, precisely that of the divine law. Now this theology, necessarily posterior to the very existence of the law, took form toward the end of the Old Testament under the influence of events and under divine inspiration according to a movement of thought and of reflection which is superbly represented in the twelfth century. The role of polygraphers and of compilers in the style of Isidore is particularly effective; sometimes we read without noticing it selected bits of Origen in their collections and encyclopedias (preserved by anonymity). Even more, "Isidore n'a pas seulement transmis a tous ceux qui l'ont lu ou recopie quelques themes exegetiques isoles, il a contribue aussi et surtout a introduire dans Ia pensee medievale une conception des rapports de !'ancien et du nouveau testament et de la signification typologique de l'Ecriture qui s'apparentait directement a ce que l'exegese origenienne offrait de meilleur et de plus sur." Through Isidore or through direct borrowing, Claude de Turin (under the name of Eucher) in the eighth century, Remigius of Auxerre and Rabanus Maurus in the ninth, Bruno of Asti at the turn of the eleventh to the twelfth century, Richard of Saint-Victor (Allegoriae in vetus testamentum, in his Liber Exceptionum) at the height of the twelfth century, the Ordinary Gloss which begins to take form at this time, these are so many channels through which Origen was received by the West in bulk. 34 JEAN TONNEAU Wisdom books. This trend has been studied for some years; it is not possible here to give the details, but it is necessary briefly to trace its broad outline in order to clarify the theology of law in Christian thought. There have always been, in Israel as among all peoples, reflections and discourses of wisdom which take the form of proverbs or of stories, of maxims or of parables. This current of wisdom in Israel left written witnesses from the time of the kingdom, especially of Solomon, which was an epoch of commerce and of administrative organization. Although there was no antagonism in principle between the men of wisdom and the men of the divine word, they nevertheless are distinct in principle. It is eminently evident in Moses that the man of the Word and the man of the Law go hand in hand; they transmit to the people what they have seen and heard from God's mouth; they are the men of the Covenant. The wise man, in principle and according to the rule of literary genre, communicates to his son or to his disciple the fruit of his thoughts and of his experience; he addresses the individual as such, is interested in his trials, the dangers he runs, his destiny, and in this way his message of wisdom has an international import. He takes on more importance and grows in wisdom as he makes contact with nations, either during the Exile or in the land of the diaspora. Wisdom, whose throne can only be in God, who is the worker of creation and who is pleased to dwell among men whom she loves, becomes like a grace of divine revelation and, more than the Word to which she tends to become identified, acquires a sort of personality very near to God himself, while at the same time very much mixed with that of man, of the people of Israel above all, since she has chosen Sion for her dwelling, but also, through Israel, of all nations. She is like a permanent manifestation of Providence, of God's power and goodness; through Wisdom alone does prosperity, life and happiness come to men. 18 18 H. Cazelles, "A propos d'une phrase de H. H. Rowley," in Supplement$ to Vetus Testamentum, Vol. III, Wisdom in Israel and in the Ancient Near East, 1955, pp. 26-82. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 35 But before the end of the Old Testament, notably in Eccli. and Baruch, this Wisdom which tends to become a person meets with the Law. This joining is surprising to us, but we know that rabbinic speculations had given to the Law a prestigious status with characteristics closely resembling those of Wisdom: preexistence before creation, a directive and regulative role in creation, supreme gift of God, source of life, of light, of prosperity, a pledge of God's presence, etc. As Richard Simon remarked: " since those who composed the New Testament were Jews, it cannot be explained without a reference to Judaism." 19 After having looked just about everywhere and especially to Greek thought for the alleged sources of the New Testament, it appears that today a great and profound continuity between the Old and the New Testaments is more readily recognized. Due credit must be given, however, to the considerable influence of Greek thought, especially after the dispersion of the Church in the Hellenistic world and after the penetration of the Christian faith among the educated classes of society. But the fact is that even Palestinian Judaism, and with greater reason Alexandrian Judaism in permanent contact with the Gentiles, solicitous for apologetic dialogue and proselytism, had received a great deal from Hellenistic thought, as the Wisdom books among others testify. We must also take into account the fact that Jewish milieux were far from being uniform and homogeneous. The New Testament would suffice for us to guess that, in a common fidelity to the Law and to traditional observances, there were schools of thought as different as the Pharisees and the Saducees, Baptist currents, Essenes, etc. It is evident that the young Saul, of Pharisaic upbringing from an early age at Tarsus and then at the feet of Gamaliel in Jerusalem, could not read the beautiful text of Deut. 30:11-14 without being filled with reverence and admiration for this Wisdom become internalized and identified with the all-powerful Word which is 19 Quoted by J. Steinmann, Richard Simon et les origines de l'exegese biblique, p. 72. 86 JEAN TONNEAU no other than the Law. 20 It is enough to refer back to the books of exegesis to measure the influence of the sapiential current upon the synoptic evangelists and, perhaps even more so, upon Saint Paul, Saint John, and the author of the Epistle to the Hebrews. At this point in our demonstration let us not imagine that the writers of the New Testament had the intention of developing this sapiential movement, to bring it to its term by searching, by finding in it the person of Jesus as a representation, a historical and concrete incarnation. What actually happened is the exact opposite, an historical encounter: " that we have heard, and we have seen with our own eyes; that we have watched and touched with our hands: the Word, who is life." (I Jn. 1: 1) And for Paul, everything began also with an encounter which happened to him. It is in listening to and beholding Jesus that the Apostles were led to express the mystery of his person and of his mission with the vocabulary and the biblical notions of Word and Wisdom, bringing, moreover, to term the development inaugurated under the Old Testament in such a way as to conclude definitively: The Word is God, Wisdom is God, because Jesus is God. If not, the personification of Wisdom and of the Word would remain what it was in the Old Testament, incomplete, a bold and poetic metaphor. The mystery of Christ, this is the resume of the whole of the apostolic preaching. The word " mystery " means not so much something incomprehensible as something hidden, something which is precious to know but which needs to be revealed. The mystery is in part linked to wisdom, which is also God's secret that God alone can communicate. In general, according to the New Testament, to know a mystery is to know (and at the same time to receive, to touch) the benefits promised by God, prepared for our glory (formula of I Cor. 2: 6); or •• Deut. SO: 11-15. Cf. text on p. 49 below. A note in the Jerusalem Bible says that this text is a source of the theology of the Word, such as it is expressed in I John, after having matured in the Wisdom books (cf. Prov. 8: !l'l!; Wis. 7: 'l!'l!); and Saint Paul applies this text to the word of faith in Rom. 10:6-8. TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 37 according to the more extensive formula of Eph. 1: 9: "He has let us know the mystery of his purpose, the hidden plan he so kindly made in Christ from the beginning to act upon when the times had run their course to the end: that he would bring everything together under Christ, as head, everything in the heavens and everything on earth." This mystery is nothing other than the Gospel (cf. the final doxology in Rom. 16: " Glory to him who is able to give you the strength to live according to the Good News I preach and in which I proclaim Jesus Christ, the revelation of a mystery kept secret for endless ages, but now so clear that it must be broadcast to pagans everywhere to bring them to the obedience of faith. This is only what scripture has predicted, and it is all part of the way the eternal God wants things to be." This identity between mystery and the Gospel does not efface the nuances of expression: in the language of mystery the accent falls upon the impenetrable depth of God's designs and on the absolute gratuity of their revelation; in the language of the evangelical message the point of view is that of men who, until then, were plunged into darkness and to whom the light comes, the good news of salvation, connoting the laborers of the Gospel who have been charged to proclaim this good news everywhere. But the content is the same, it is the totality of all the good things which God resolved to communicate to men in the silence of the centuries. This is a far cry from the esoterica and the syncretistic mysteries of pagans; this is the true connection with the sapiential teachings: it is especially to the little ones, to the poor, to the humble, that, according to the Gospel and as already found in the Wisdom literature, the mystery is revealed. These benefits, then, these things which have been revealed, this good news, are not solely or especially what Our Lord said; it is not so much a question of the words which he uttered. It is not that alone which was promised and shown but indeed Christ himself revealing in his person the whole essence of the mystery. As we read in the Song of Zachariah (Luke 1:6879), the Incarnation is the culmination and the last word of 88 JEAN TONNEAU all the sacred words which reverberated in the Old Testament; all those long discourses, accounts and oracles which could be written down, held in the hand, kept in cupboards or placed upon the pulpit. But the word which sums up everything and which says everything, the verbum abbreviatum, is the incarnate Word. He is the content of Wisdom's plan, the object of the Father's complacency, or, as Saint Hippolytus of Rome put it, to thelema tou Patros, the will of the Father, certainly not a faculty but the summation and the entirety of what God wants, the fullness of his loving kindness and the totality of his promises so magnificently and so superabundantly kept. 21 In other words, Christ is not only he who expresses the dictates of the Father in human language, he is not only the revealer and thereby the artisan of our salvation; he is salvation, for he is God's Word, that one which saves; he is God in person with us, he who sums up every blessing and all promises. He is not only the way but also the very truth and life. At this point in our demonstration a problem arises. No one can ignore the prestigious position of the Law in the Jewish world and in the rabbinic teaching at the time of our Lord; it is also readily conceded that sapiential thought had considerable influence on the New Testament, particularly in Saint Paul and Saint John; it is recognized that the rapprochement between the Word and Wisdom in the person of our Lord is solidly attested. But if the Jewish milieux continued more than ever to identify the Torah with the Word and with Wisdom as being the full and eternal revelation of God, such a promotion of the Law seems quite foreign to the New Testament and at the same time to the faith of the first Christians, who, however, would have been nourished by this doctrine. 22 It could be remarked as an aside, however, that the entire evangelical teaching could not be contained in the books of the New Testament: "The world itself, I suppose, would not hold all the books that would have to be written." (John 21: 25) 21 Saint Hippolytus of Rome, Adv. Noet. xiii; PG, 10, 819. •• W. D. Davies, Paul and Rabbinic Judaism, 1948 (new edition 1963), Chapter 7: The Old and the New Torah: Christ the Wisdom of God, pp. 147-176, TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 39 More precisely on what touches our problem which concerns the relationship between the new faith and the Jewish law, the New Testament teaches us through the pens of Paul and of Luke (his friend and companion who saw everything from the same point of view), writing during the crisis of the Judaizers. Certainly, at the Council of Jerusalem in 49 Paul's views in his quarrel with the Judaizers were officially approved; James and John" shook hands with Barnabas and me, as a sign 9) but this liberating decision on of partnership," (Gal. behalf of converts from paganism in no way implied that the other Christians had to break away from Judaism; it merely imposed the duty to be tolerant towards them. John, in particular, was among those "who intended to break away from authentic Judaism the least possible." 23 Confronted with the Judaizers Paul also claimed for himself an " authentic Judaism "; here the anti-Semitism depicted by Marcion is absent; Paul is just as Jewish, and even more so, then they are. (II Cor. 11: Addressing himself to the he upholds the advantages and the prerogaRomans (3: tives of the circumcized: "First the Jews are the people to whom God's message was entrusted," i.e., the law; the latter is irreproachable, for if it is powerless to forgive sin, it is because it never pretended to do so. If the Christian is once and for all set free from the Mosaic law, it is not because the latter has failed; it has simply done its time as it should have and fulfilled its task of putting sin into relief in order to bring out the gratuity of the promise and of salvation. The Judaizers did not err in observing the law (which in any case was impossible to observe) but in attributing to its observance an efficacy for salvation which it did not have and which belongs only to grace. Those whom the Apostle combats do not constitute the verus Israel which kept the "oracles" of God which were entrusted to it. In these prophecies there is law. not law as understood by the Judaizers but law at the service of the promise now realized in Jesus Christ. There was a time •• F. M. Braun, Jean le theologien, I, p. SSO. 40 JEAN TONNEAU in the life of the Chosen People when their blind fidelity to the (Mosaic) law made them unfaithful to the promise. But this official refusal must not make us forget the first conquests of the faith within the Jewish milieux. Right up to the episode of the centurion Cornelius (c. 48) there were mass conversions among the Jews of Palestine or of the diaspora, including Pharisees and " a multitude of priests." These converts from Judaism were perhaps less converts than the representatives of the verus Israel arrived at its full maturity. Their condition is truly unique, never will the Church which springs up from Gentiles ever be comparable to it, and we must await, to again witness this plenitude, the conversion of Israel announced for the end of time. The first Judea-Christian community was made up of the privileged elite which had without harm passed from the promise to its fulfillment in Christ. Such was the case of James and of John; unfortunately we know little about the details of their teaching since "after having reported in detail their exchanges of views, Luke centered his attention on the missions of Paul. The role of John from then on is passed over in silence." 24 It is conceivable that for Saint Paul at grips with the Judaizers, or for Saint John writing after the fall of Jerusalem and the complete separation between Judaism and the Church, the word Law would ordinarily have designated the Mosaic law, and even more readily, in a pejorative sense, the Law would have been viewed as a temptation or obstacle on the path of the faithful. And in the same measure that Judaism was concentrated on the Law (the Law was everything for the Jews), the opposition must have been even more marked: The Jews have the Law, we have Jesus Christ! We must not expect in this context to find the Law identified with Jesus Christ. But pushed to an extreme, the opposition can be resolved by substituting Jesus Christ for the Law, with the functions and prerogatives of the latter (truth, way, light, life, "'lfnd. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 41 food, salvation, sacrament of the presence of God, gift, grace, revelation, preexistence, role in creation, eternity, etc.) henceforth ascribed to Christ; whereas the Jew glories in the Law, the Christian glories in Christ, etc. In the eyes of the Christian, however, grace and Christ are superior to the Law, for actually the Jews were wrong in expecting salvation from the Law. Saint Paul pointed out to them that salvation comes from the promise, which is much anterior to the law; it is the promise which is constitutive of the Covenant at the service of which, consequently, the Law was given. The novelty of the New Law, or of Christ considered as our New Law, is the union which took place between the Covenant and the Law identified in the person of Jesus Christ. It is precisely because the New Law contains the fulfilment of the promise that it no longer exhibits the relativity and the powerlessness of the Old Law; in other words, because the New Law consists essentially in the grace of the Holy Spirit, i. e., in the " gift of God " which the " benefits promised to David" prefigured, the New Law or the evangelical Good News consists in the event of the death and resurrection of Jesus, the fulfillment of all the promises. And since Christ had to die, since "the death of Jesus was bound up with the institution of the New Covenant, it was normal for the Savior to have been considered not only as a mediator signing the Covenant in the name of his Father but as a testator who leaves to those near to him the goods he now disposes of." 25 •• C. Spicq, L'epitre aua; Hebreux. II, Commentaire, Excursus IX, p. !l89. Thus we see the connection between Covenant and law already outlined in the Old Testament fully realized in the Christian economy; as for the idea of testament, somewhat foreign to berith (for, covenant is broken by the death of one of its contractors, whereas a testament gets its life and strength by the death of the testator), it was foreign to Jewish thought until the penetration of Roman law, but at that time it was designated in Hebrew by the transposition of the letters of the word diatheke. This fact explains the use of diatheke for either covenant or law, even the commandments or ordinations, and finally for the dispositions of the testator as in Gal. 8:15-17 and He b. 9:16-17, a development which is related to the idea of adoption, since the institution of heirs was equivalent to the introduction of new sons into the family. See also A. Jaubert, La notion d'alliance dans le judaisme aua; abords de l'ere chretienne (Patristica Sorbonensis, 6), 1968, pp. 811815. 42 JEAN TONNEAU If then it is true that, according to the canonical writers, the law, taken absolutely, ordinarily means Mosaic law, and if the word law needs qualification as the law of Christ, or the royal law, or the law of the Spirit of life in order to mean the Gospel as a new way of life in Christ, it can also be stated that in certain Christian authors, who are no more Jewish than Paul or John but whose mentality and language further prolong, through simplicity or through archaism, the language and mentality of the synagogue, have a way of speaking about Christ as law which accurately characterizes that which we have called the Judea-Christian theology. The principal texts showing this have been assembled by J. Lebreton/ 6 completed and exploited by J. Danielou 27 and are now easily accessible. 28 There is no need for us give an account of them here; it is enough to state here with J. Danielou that " the idea of Christ introducing a new covenant and giving a definitive law was current in the New Testament. But the importance of the texts (which are considered here) is that they present a further element, which is that they identify the Son of God with the Law and the Covenant." " Christian speculation on the Bible from the categories of postbiblical Judaism," such texts have left their mark on ancient liturgical formulas. Later theology used other categories, especially after Nicea, but these archaic traces are still recognizable. They moreover draw our attention by the obstinate recurrence of certain words, certain themes and of certain biblical texts: wisdom, law, truth, principle (reshit, arche, principium with the corresponding texts Gen. 1: 1; John 1:1 and Prov. 8:22 the old warhorse of the supporters of Arianism). Considering the great freedom with which rabbis, the authors of the New Testament and the Fathers in their exegesis established their proofs, it can said that the mere appearance of these words would be enough to evoke Christ on every page of the Bible. The word Logos, with its am•• J. Lebreton, Origines du dogme de la Trinite, II, pp. 648-650. •• J. Danielou, Theologie du judeo-christianisme, pp. 216-219. •• These are passages from the Kerygma Petri recorded by Clement of Alexandria, from texts of the Shepherd of Hermas and the Dialogue with Tryphon of Justin, etc. TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 43 bivalent meaning of Reason and of Word, should certainly be added to this list; this should be remembered when embarking on the Thomist tract on law. After this review which is perhaps too long and yet perhaps too concise, what is at stake and the scope of the tract can be grasped. To tell the truth, it is not so much a tract, an element of a systematized theology; it is plainly a question of the first, and for a long time, the only article of faith; this is why the Gospels were written and to which it was sufficient to adhere to be Christian. This is the answer to the question asked by our Lord: " Who do people say the Son of Man is? " 29 That is to say, what does Jesus, the son of Mary, represent in the history of salvation? There was no need for preaching the existence or the unity of God unless the audience was Gentile. As for the preaching of the properly Christian mystery of the Trinity, it did not, at the start, have any other form than the unveiling of everything implied by the mystery of Christ. Even to the .Jews it was not necessary to prove God's fidelity to his promise; it was enough to show that these promises were finally realized and that the novelty of the present situation, so long awaited for, was nothing other than " novissime diebus istis " God has spoken through his Son. The Good News is therefore, after the prophecy "multifariam multisque modis " addressed by God to the Patriarchs and the Prophets, the advent of the plenary and definitive Word which is the Word incarnate. This dogma is not only the first historically, but it contains all the others, and the development of the faith and of theology consists in deductions from and articulations of this "revelation." Just as the word revelation has two meanings, the act of revealing and the matter revealed, in the same way theology will make progress by displaying, so to speak, and by organizing in actu exercito in the course of its tracts all revealed matters; but theology must also apply itself in actu signata to the description of the very act of revealing, the fact of revelation. It can be said that it begins •• Matt. 16: 18. 44 JEAN TONNEAU in that way, in considering Christ as the revealing Word of God. The question now is about a tract de revelatione, even though we would have some difficulty in recognizing it as such, accustomed as we are to read under this rubric theses which appear to be philosophical on the human dispositions for the act of faith, with legitimate apologetical preoccupations. In reality, before elaborating and putting in order the various revealed truths, faith and theology are first of all struck by the fact that God has spoken, that his Word has resounded, and that this Word always has the realistic efficacy of the Word of God; it produces what it utters, it transforms being by penetrating it to the core, it guarantees the Covenant, makes us sons and heirs, it accomplishes all the promises, it saves. It is this intervention of the Word of God that we must perceive in, and needless to say throughout, this tract where Saint Thomas tells us that God "instructs us through the law." 30 It might be objected that this is hardly apparent. Is a great deal of good will required to draw such a conclusion from so tenuous an indication as a short phrase taken from the Prologue? I will refrain from pretending that this objection lacks any weight; it is enough to think of the many commentators who, in effect, have never dreamed of drawing such a consequence from this little text; they have perhaps never given this text anything but a rapid and distracted attention. The answer 30 In these conditions there is no need react with undue emotion to the reproach frequently levied against the Summa Theologiae: the tract on revelation is missing! We answer this objection in the same way we have answered (see infra) the one concerning the alleged " absence " of Christ from many tracts in the Summa. In the valuable article of A. Robert, "Le sens du mot Loi dans le ps. 119," Revue biblique (1937), p. 191, I find a quotation of Grether which summarizes this conclusion well: "Ainsi dabar s'entend de Ia Ioi mosalque conc;ue non pas comme Ia somme des preceptes particuliers, mais comme !'incarnation de toute Revelation divine qui, tantot ordonnant, tantot promettant on menac;ant, vient se presenter aux hommes. L'unite de Ia Revelation est affirmee si fortement que Ia difference entre revelation legaliste et revelation prophetique, entre dabar legaliste et dabar prophetique, s'efl'ace dans cette unite" (Grether, Name und Wort Gottes im alten Testament, 1934, p. 126). It is sufficient to remember that this revelation is a progression up to the revelation in Filio, novissime diebus istis. TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 45 to this objection is complex and delicate but, we think, solid. First of all, there is always good reason to take very seriously whatever indications Saint Thomas gives in his prologues; they are always well thought-out and significant, though under a painless appearance. Sometimes they seem to be on a much higher level and very remote from what is contained in the tract which follows; but this is precisely because they dominate it and, from above, relate it to perspectives broad enough to clarify it. And this clarification is often very personal: to tell the truth, one cannot be so sure that the order of the Summa is particularly original by merely observing the sequence of the tracts considered as doctrinal blocks. It is only at junctures and articulations, at the transitions that original explanations arise, decisive not only for the logical organization of the tract but for the significance of its contents. Next, it must be admitted that, although we are enjoying a biblical renewal, Saint Thomas, nevertheless, was very familiar with the Bible. However, the evolution of modern thought, even within the Church, makes it very difficult for us to enter into the mental world of a thirteenth-century author by simply reading him. We will see later how this affects the notion of law. But let us consider for the moment the word reason which abruptly opens article 1 of q. 90. For us reason means something profane, and the idea never occurs to us (at least at first glance) that behind this word lies what an assiduous student of the Bible would almost unconsciously be aware of: the Word, the Logos. Its translations are even more obscure, for the system of words in different in each language. In a Latin Bible it takes us a while before we recognize the Word whenever the word Sermo is substituted for the word Verbum [c£. St. Thomas, Commen. in Ep. ad Hebraeos, c. IV, p. 2 (Marietti, n. 217) ]. Furthermore, account should be taken of the fact that the Summa is a summary for the use of students who in addition were listening to the normal lectures of the Master of Scripture. It is principally in the commentaries on Saint John, Saint Paul, and on the Epistle to the Hebrews (in which the contribution 46 JEAN TONNEAU of the Greek and Latin Fathers bear fruit) that we find the complementary lights which illumine the skeletal summary of the Summa. These commentaries contain more than a biblical exegesis; they preserve for us a long tradition of disputes Adversus Judaeos which go back to the origins of Christianity and which were a very live issue in St. Thomas's time and beyond it. On another front they were struggling in an antiGnostic battle in order to determine the correct path between two errors, one which persisted in denying or misunderstanding the divinity of Jesus Christ, a divinity which implied the recognition of his salvific mission, and another which consistently denied or diluted the reality of his historic humanity (" born of David ") . This polemic had been dominated above all and for centuries by the genius of Saint Augustine. Even the summary given in schematized form in the Summa bears the stamp of this tradition. We can understand at the same time how all the essential elements of the faith could, in general, be reduced to these two points: to believe in the divinity and in the humanity of Christ the Savior (De articulis fidei et eccl. sacram., n. 598 ed. Marietti) . This is exactly the echo of the words of Saint John: The Word became flesh and dwelt among us, or of Saint Paul: God all in all, through a unique and decisive intervention of God in human history. 31 Finally, without pretending to be complete, I would add that the sapiential character of the prefaces and prologues which Saint Thomas placed at the beginning of most of his theological writings leaves no room for doubt; whether we examine the prologue which opens the scriptum on the Sentences, or the dedicatory prologue of the Catena aurea, or that of the Compendium theologiae, most of the time the same sapiential texts traditionally applied to Christ are used. They 31 A unique intervention but one which continues throughout the history of humanity and which culminates in the Incarnation. Thus, with regard to the rite of Baptism, we read in 4, d. 6. q. 2, a. 2, ad I, that the catechetical summary of tl1at which is absolutely essential can be reduced to this simple expression: "in quadam summa, ut scilicet videat (the catechumen) quomodo in quolibet statu mundi Deo cura fuit de hominibus." TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 47 show that Wisdom is not only creative but that it conserves and perfects all things, especially spiritual creatures made in the image of God. This solicitude is expressed in a teaching which is light, life, happiness, and is a kind of completion of creation in that it makes men the children of God. All these words of salvation scattered throughout his writings seem to be summed up in the unique and shortened expression (verbum abbreviatum of Rom. 9: 28) which means in tum and at the same time the Incarnation and the evangelical preaching, without prejudice to the synopses and compendia which the symbols and the works of theology offer of them. 32 82 The Commentary on this passage from the Epistle to the Romans, 9:28 (Marietti, n. 803 and 804) is probably the best summary of this efficacia verbi. The Gospel has a double efficacy, following the two epithets consummans and abbrevians in aequitate employed by Saint Paul. Consummans, i. e., perfecting, since the Law has brought nothing to perfection (Heb. 7: 19), but the Lord has come, not to abolish but to perfect the law (Matt. 5: 17), 1) to the law as type he adds the reality (veritatem); 2) as for the moral precepts of the law, he has explained them as they should be, he has suppressed the occasions for transgressing it and has even added on to them counsels of perfection. The Lord could then rightly say to the rich young man: If you want to be perfect (he had already practiced the commandments of the law), there is only one more thing you must do, go and sell everything you have, etc. (Matt. 19: 21), and he could say to his disciples: " You must therefore be perfect just as your heavenly Father is perfect." (Matt. 5:49) In the second place, the Gospel has the efficacy of being terse, and this conforms well with the first type, for the more a word is perfect the more it is profound and consequently simpler and briefer. Hence the evangelical word abbreviates the words of the law, for all the figurative sacrifices of the law are in the Gospel comprised in the one, true sacrifice in which Christ offered himself up as victirn for us (Eph. 5: 2). And he has enclosed all the moral precepts of the law in the two precepts of charity (Matt. 22:40: " On these two commandments hang the whole Law and the Prophets also ") . And since in this summary nothing is lost or forgotten of the multitude of figures and precepts of the law which are all presen·ed in the brevity of the Gospel, the latter is justly said to be abbrevians in aequitate, according to Psalm ll8: 72, Omnia mandata tua aequitas. And it is remarkable that (n. 804), wanting to give the reason for this efficacy, the Apostle evokes the author of this word Dominus super terram; it is the Lord, dwelling on earth as a man, who was to be this abbreviated word, and to quote the text of Baruch: Post in terris visua est et cum hominibus conversatus est (Bar. 3: 88), in which the Latin version has translated into the masculine a common verbal form applicable to both genders but whose subject is Wisdom; the latter, moreover, is identified with the Law in the following verse 48 JEAN TONNEAU There should be no trouble over the fact that the teaching of wisdom often looks vague and hazy in the patristic literature and the biblical commentaries. In reality, thanks notably to the De Trinitate of Saint Augustine, this theology has taken a scientific form. In Saint Thomas the place for this study is found in the tract on God and in the tract on the Trinity. Its elaboration has involved a certain complexity in the heirarchy of laws. For the rabbis, the Mosaic law was at the same time qualified as divine law and eternal law. Under the influence of philosophy, especially that of Stoicism, eternal law was situated in the world of divine ideas which are the rationes of all created things; the precepts of the eternal law are the rationes agendorum. Often enough, for example, in the Contra Gentiles, the expression divine law simply designates the eternal law. So, it is only in the Summa Theologiae, at least in the tract on laws in the I-11, that Saint Thomas employs a more articulated vocabulary in which divine law designates the positive divine law and not the eternal law. Nevertheless, this properly theological elaboration maintains the reference to Christ that we have recognized in the wisdom and patristic literature. In the tract on the eternal law (1-11, q. 93, a. 4, ad 2) it is expressly stated that the Son of God was not subject to the eternal law but that, according to the doctrine of Saint Augustine in de vera religione, c. 31, the Son of God is the eternal law instead, by a kind of appropriation. To clarify this overly succinct statement, references could be made to a few passages, especially from the commentary on Saint John, where the influence of Saint Augustine is obvious. In John c. 5, lect. 4, when our Lord says that "Every judgment comes from the Father," Saint Thomas uses an interpretation of Hilary and Chysostom which he develops in this way: at the same time that the Father begets the Son and gives him life, he also gives him all judgment, he begets him precisely as judge, and that because the Son is none other than (same text in the exergue of the Principium, Mar., p. 485). This theme of verbum. abbreviatum is an ingenious way for the prologue of the Compendium theologiae to introduce the matter, but is not without precedent. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 49 the conceptus paternae sapientiae; hence it is by the fruit of wisdom that each pronounces his judgments. That the Son is the Word, i. e., the conceptus paternae sapientiae, has been established at the very beginning of the commentary in the Prologue (c. I, lect. 2) when discussing" omia per ipsum facta sunt." Further on, in John 12:49-50, we are given a more detailed explanation (lect. 8) : "For what I have spoken does not come from myself; no, what I was to say, what I had to speak was commanded by the Father who sent me, and I know that his commands mean life eternal." All the divine commands, we read, are in the mind of the Father because the commands are nothing but the rationes agendorum. Thus, just as the reasons (ideas) for all creatures produced by God are in the mind of the Father, so also the reasons for all the things which we should do are found there. And both of these derive from the Father in the Son, who is the Father's wisdom. Saint Thomas remarks that, when the Father commands the Son, it is the same thing as begetting him. And a little further on he explains that " his command is life eternal " by recalling that the Son is himself the command of the Father, ipse enim Filius est mandatum Patris, an assertion based on I John 5:21: Hie est verus Deus, et vita aeterna. One final text, taken this time from the commentary on Rom. 10:5 ff, will suffice. Speaking on the opposition between the justice born of the (old!) law and the justice born of the faith, Saint Paul recalls one of the most beautiful passages in Deuteronomy (Deut. 30:11-14 very strongly colored by sapiential influences where the " interiority of the Law " is proclaimed: For this law which I enjoin on you today is not beyond your strength or beyond your reach. It is not in heaven, so that you need not to wonder: "Who will go up to heaven for us and bring it down to us, so that we may hear it and keep it?" Nor is it beyond the seas, so that you need to wonder: " Who will cross the seas for us and bring it back to us so that we may hear and keep it?" No, the Word is very near to you, it is in your mouth and in your heart for your observance. 50 JEAN TONNEAU These vain attempts in the heavens and beyond the seas can be recognized as the sapiential style and the mode of Job 28 or of Baruch 3:29 ff. Hence Saint Paul plainly attributes to the Word of faith what Moses understood of the Law; and what must be received in the heavens and brought down, or what must be received at the bottom of the deep and brought up, is simply Christ who has in fact come down from the heavens and returned from the dead. Conclusion: the word is very near to you on your lips and in your heart. Saint Thomas explains this text from Saint Paul in this way without giving the impression that the Apostle's exegesis is the product of a heady boldness; he reassures his reader: "Nee est inconveniens si quod Moyses dixit de mandato Legis, hoc Apostolus attribuit Christo, quia Christus est Verbum Dei, in quo sunt omnia Dei mandata." All that we can permit ourselves to observe without doing injustice to formulas consecrated by an elaborate (I almost said stale) theology is that Christ or the Word of God is a much more comprehensive conceptus divinae mentis: for if he bears the ideas of the whole universe of creatures, he first of all expresses the fullness of the divine Being; it is in this fullness that he contains the ideas of all that proceeds from this creative plenitude. Furthermore, and this is the sense of the expression eternal law, he bears the reasons of all movements and created activities. Among these reasons there are some in which irrational creatures participate passively and others in which rational creatures participate actively (natural law). Positive laws, both those which men make for themselves (human laws) and those or that (according to an historical development) by which God instructs men in order to guide them on the way to happiness (Old and New Law), are derived from these reasons. Perhaps now we are better prepared to understand what the word " reason " means in the initial mention made of it in q. 90: Utrum lex sit aliquid rationis? Otherwise, we will see nothing but a scholastic refinement or elegance ( ?) in the care taken by the ad 2 of Article 1 to make a conceptus mentis of the law, purposely (by opposing it to an TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 51 operatio), an operatum, a fruit of reason, aliquid per hujusmodi actum constitutum, with the customary parallel between speculative and practical reason. What pertains to speculative reason, the proposition in relation to its conclusion, must also be said to pertain to practical reason, law in relation to its operation, i.e., law is both an universal active principle and a director of operation. On this level, of course, there is no further obstacle to the unity o£ the tract and especially the universality o£ the definition of law given at the end o£ Question 90. II. THE THO MIST DEFINITION OF LAw We think it opportune to introduce the next two sections, which are very moralizing and the product o£ philosophical analysis, by a summary discussion o£ the concept o£ moral theology. Most certainly there is no question here o£ forgetting that Saint Thomas attempted to group what he calls moral considerations (I-II, q. 6, Pro!.) in the Secunda Pars. It was this part o£ the tract on law which led moralists, at least the vast majority o£ them, to look upon law as the indispensable and ultimate reference £or discerning between good and evil actions. 33 This placed the tract on law in an unexpected perspective and light, namely, o£ moral science, by suggesting that law plays the role o£ pivot in morality. It was certainly not Saint Thomas's intention to lead us down this moralizing road; the misinterpretation occurs whenever the tract is read with a frame o£ mind characteristic o£ those sciences which are formally moral. I£ it has been believed opportune to displace the tract on law, it is because we have sought in it answers to 33 This is the reason which leads authors of manuals to treat of law before taking up the question of the morality of human acts, a strategem foreign to Saint Thomas who sees in law essentially a doctrina taking into account that which it is, a type of knowledge which plays the part of rule, since it allows acts to be measured and directed as is fitting and not as a source of morality constituting certain acts as good and others as evil. This formalistic conception, if we should carry it into the realm of technical rules, would make us think that the goodness of an omelet, for example, consists in the fact that it has been made exactly according to the directions of the cookbook. 52 JEAN TONNEAU questions which Saint Thomas never pretended to resolve. What is more serious is to approach it with prejudices which distort its understanding. Briefly, then, remember that moral sciences-whether moral philosophy or what today is called moral theology-constitute bodies of knowledge which not only serve to direct practice but which are formally and methodically organized to give this service. But this is not, basically the nature of theology; it cannot be defined as a science in the service of practical living; like the faith itself, it is somehow the environment of a living spirit; it does not dispose for an end, it contains that very end; it is Christian wisdom, knowledge of God, meaning not simply discourses on God and divine things but the receiving of God's revelation and imparting a beatifying introduction to the life of God himself. That this exercises a considerable influence upon human conduct there is no doubt at all, for this is the case for every truly speculative knowledge which is presented as a life in which the great realities of end and beatitude are assimilated; but this type of knowledge must not because of this be conceived and structured according to formally moral or practical bodies of knowledge in view of an end which is not properly its own. Not only is it inappropriate to build a moral theology to provide, as has already been pointed out, 34 an apprenticeship for the ministry of the confessional; without falling so low, the very idea of placing theology at the service of anything whatsoever, even at the service of the Christian life, cannot be maintained as such. It is true that the theologian has a certain role to play in the Church, that theology eminently educates the faithful, that it also defends the faith against errors. But theology itself, understood in its complete Christian dimension, with the faith whose rational and methodical fructification it is, is not a •• In the article Tribut of the Dictionnaire de theologie catholique, Vol. XV, c. 1588. Here is the interesting section: (If we wish to appreciate the true worth of certain critics) " il ne faut pas oublier le point de vue et Ia tache propre de Ia theologie morale: avant tout elle entend preparer le futur pretre a son ministere penitentiel et le mettre a meme de ne pas manquer a la justice vis-a-vis de ses penitents." TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 53 school, preparing for the Christian life, it is itself the exercise of the Christian life. Nothing is more dangerous here than to oppose the doctrinal and pastoral functions: with what bread will pastors nourish their flocks if not with that of the word of God which they should ruminate and contemplate so that the faithful, too, may ruminate and contemplate it. Theology is too tied up with the faith not to be, in all its parts, like the faith, essentially contemplative. Faith does not prepare us for eternal life, it communicates this life to us, as was said to us at Baptism. Of course, this does not preclude the role of a supernatural synderesis; theology has certainly played a part in the conduct of human life, and this is why moral considerations are part of its make-up; but even so, theology remains a participation in the beatifying mystery, an entrance into the possession of the end (through faith, of course). Like faith and by faith, theology (even in its moral considerations) puts us in touch (gropingly, as through a veil, while awaiting the definitive revelation or the unveiling of the vision) with the term, beatitude, the end itself, beyond the reach of any " ad finem, behaviors organized and regulated by the moral sciences Otherwise, we would be led to understand that theology and consequently faith could be put in the service of another end, of a better end, higher and worthier than that offered us here below through our knowledge of God and the mysteries revealed to us. There is a certain primacy of contemplation that we cannot fail to recognize without ceasing to be Christian. To return to the relationship between pastoral theology and sacred doctrine, the pastoral function which consists in giving just laws to the Christian people is nothing other than the current application adapted to circumstances of the doctrinal function by which the bread of divine truth is distributed. 35 35 This idea is expressed in a work where we would not expect it: " La fonction de regir le peuple de Dieu n'est done qu'un appendice de Ia fonction de l'instruire des choses divines" (L. Boyer, La decomposition du catholicisme, 1968, p. 96). The idea is quite justified, only the word " appendice " seems insufficient to me. I would say that the essential thing in pastoral theology consists in the exercise of the doctrinal function, but that it is secondarily extended to its applications and 54 JEAN TONNEAU Assume, then, without further discussion since this would take us too far afield, that moral theology remains indeed a genuine theology. It is also true that theology, when it deals with moral considerations, must be wary of the quality of notions and arguments that it borrows from moral science. The theologian must not be confused with the moralist, 36 but neither must his work be compromised by accepting the services of any moralist whatsoever. Saint Thomas is a theologian and not a moralist, but he knew what the Philosopher had said in his Ethics, he studied it, criticized it, and made use of it as a theologian "cui omnes aliae artes deserviunt." The realm of morality is particularly dangerous in view of the fact that it is of interest to everybody and that everybody, more or less, believes himself competent in it. This realm is the favorite dwelling place of ready-made ideas, accepted without criticism, on the basis of unsuspected pseudo-evidence. In what concerns his theory of law there is no need to come to the defense of Saint Thomas; his definition of law has been rightly accepted by all as excellent; it is hailed and admired on all sides and is in everybody's memory. I quote it here with the punctuation found in the Leonine edition: QUAEDAM RATIONIS ORDINATIO AD BONUM COMMUNE, AB EO QUI CURAM COMMUNITATIS HABET, PROMULGATA (q. 90, a. 4c). Since there is no solid support for this punctuation in the manuscripts, it necessarily reflects the interpretation of the editor; this particular one evidently represents an interpretation which is currently accepted in our schools as the classic one. However, we must point out that all is not clear in this formula. consequences at times remote. As for what pertains, for example, to jurisdiction and the judiciary function, let us recall what Saint Thomas says: "unusquisque per conceptum suae sapientiae judicat," and thus he sees in the fact that Christ is Wisdom the foundation of the power to judge which has been given him by the Father (In Jo., c. 5, lect. 4, Marietti, n. 768). 86 See I-ll, q. 7, a. 2, ad 8. TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 55 Should we excuse ourselves for going into such grammatical minutiae, or rather admire the translators and commentators who have intuitively resolved them without bothering to justify their reading? Since this formula is given in the last article of question 90 as the summary of the four articles of this question, it might be thought that each member of this definition corresponds to one of these articles. The number four spontaneously invites us to look for the four causes: the formal cause in Article 1, the final cause in Article the efficient cause in Article 3, while Article 4 introduces an existential or subjective consideration of promulgation, which is not without reference to the material cause, namely, the subjects" affected by" this promulgation. But this reading presents an anomaly. The phrase ab eo qui curam communitatis habet, being logically related to what precedes, leaves the promulgata isolated in apposition; the first three parts would constitute the integral definition from the essential point of view the whole being projected into existence through promulgation. There is the impression, however, that this formula is defective in that the first statement lacks a verb: quaedam rationis ordinatio ad bonum commune, ab eo qui curam communitatis habet. This is the way this definition should be read, if account is taken of the contents of the articles the formula is supposed to be summing up. In effect, the author of the promulgation is not discussed in Article 4, whereas, after speaking of the multitude which is a true cause of law, Article 3 mentions this persona publica quae cnram habet multitudinis. Nevertheless, to follow the natural drift of the grammatical construction, ab eo, etc . ... has to be referred to promulgata. Translators are inclined to believe that the author of the ordinatio rationis is the same as the one who promulgates. In order to arrive at a grammatically correct and complete sentence, they add a verb in order to sustain the logic of the ordinatio . . . ab eo; there is then a certain verbal force in the noun ordinatio; their is the idea of a putting in order by someone. This is the sense obtained in Father Laversin's translation 56 JEAN TONNEAU in which he adds the word established which doubles the promulgated, the result being this: "On ordinance of reason in view of the common good, established and promulgated by one who has charge of the community." J. Kaelin's translation is perhaps preferable for it is more literally exact: " An ordinance of reason in view of the common good, established by one who has charge of the community, and promulgated." 37 In both translations it is obvious that quaedam simply becomes the indefinite article une. In both these cases also-and it was inevitable-there is no longer any question of the one who curam habet multitudinis, the multitude itself remains in the background; it could be sustained in theory that the multitude has charge of itself because of its key position, but the fact is that in Article 3 the one who has charge of the community is a distinct person, an "official" personage, or as Laversin says, a persona publica. I do not pretend that my explanation of this text is new or altogether satisfactory. It is possible, after all, that the text itself is not perfect, either from the grammatical point of view or as a resume of the content of the articles. It is definitely to these articles that we must look for a sure and faithful understanding of the definition which pretends to be their summarization. It can be easily seen that Article 4 stands apart relative to the others; we read there that, if law is to have that virtus obligandi that is proper to it, it should be applied to men whose actions are to be regulated, and this application properly constitutes a notification. This is an interesting idea, and it agrees with the longer exposition on the study of conscience found in q. 17 of de Veritate. We will come back to this. Let us go back to Article 3. The title which we find immediately at the beginning of the articles in our printed editions is borrowed, everyone knows, from the first words of the first objection. The authentic title given to the article 81 Saint Thomas Aquinas, Des Lois, texte traduit et p7esente part Jean de la Croix Kaelin, 0. P. (Paris, 1946), p. 88. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 57 by Saint Thomas in the prologue to the question is De causa ejus (sc. legis) . But the first objection opens the battle with a lively and impressive formula: Anyone's reason can make laws. To the question thus raised it is not possible to answer otherwise than by acquiescing. Naturally it is not up to the first one who comes along to make a law at the drop of a hat. Saint Thomas does not contradict this, but it is not so certain that our thinking corresponds exactly to his. If we are men of our times, we make a distinction between the multitude, which is subject to a law imposed from above, and the one qui curam communitatis habet, namely, authority. Now Saint Thomas undoubtedly granted that it did not belong to a particular isolated individual, nor even to all individuals taken collectively, to make law, but he did categorically affirm that this legislative activity belongs to the multitude, for the decisive reason exposed in the preceding article that law has for its end the common good, the good of the multitude; for in any domain he who ordains for an end is always the one to whom this end belongs as his own. I might add that Saint Thomas does not stop here: the power to legislate, he states, belongs either to the multitude taken as a whole, or to a person whom he describes as persona publica quae totius multitudinis curam habet, or again, aliquis vice gerens totius multitudinis. In any case the principle remains: to ordain for the common good of the multitude belongs to the one for whom the common good is properly an end, namely, in the final analysis, the multitude. It is here that we risk losing the authentic sense of the Thomist formulas we repeat so often. We quite naturally, I mean spontaneously, believe that, faced with a multitude of individuals in which each must seek his own proper good, i. e., his particular good, since the particular good is the proper good of the individual as such, there must be above and beyond this multitude of individuals one who has charge of it, someone who is both qualified and authorized to legislate for the common good of this multitude. But such a schema leads us astray. Such a prince is exactly the one who in a classical sense has 58 JEAN TONNEAU been called a tyrant. For this alleged common good for which he legislates is not a common good but rather a collective good, that of a great number of individuals; even a complete assemblage of particular goods does not make up the common good; what we call a multitude of individuals does not constitute a multitude in the technical sense of social philosophy, i.e., a community. We know that within the multitude each has his own, individual subsistence; but what constitutes a multitude out of this collection of individuals in the sense of a political and social community is that, since each individual is naturally endowed with reason, his proper good is not a particular good; it constitutes the common good insofar as, independently of the subjective limits and oppositions found among individuals, there truly is a good which is common to all and which is precisely the proper good of the human multitude, being recognized and sought by every being endowed with reason and following his rational inclination. It is different in the case of a flock. The image of the shepherd king, indeed, the idea of pastoral government, cannot be held except analogously. The shepherd is authorized to rule (but not exactly to legislate) over his flock because he is endowed with reason; he thinks and ordains in view of the collective good of his sheep, and when we see the flock prosper in rich pastures, we commend such a shepherd and expect that shepherd kings or ecclesiastical pastors will follow such a beautiful example. Now, the univocal transposition from the good shepherd to the government of men is the tyrant. He is a tryant not because he might be bloodthirsty and act brutally (we assume that he is good toward his sheep and perhaps becomes exhausted in the effort), but he is a tyrant because he substitutes for the multitude in the conception and organization of a collective good falsely declared to be the common good. Classically it is said that the tyrant governs for the sake of his particular good instead of for the common good; this can be granted, providing that we take a cold view of things, of the positive conception of the shepherd, but it seems that the classical definition of tyrant no longer applies to the analogous TEACHING OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 59 conception, pious and romantic as it may be, of the shepherd king, who precisely seems to act not at all as egoist and who is all attention for his " sheep " who are his subjects. But it must be clearly stated that even in this case there is tyranny involved; for we do not claim that this particular good which is sought and commended by the tyrant is an egostic good, but it remains that the collective prosperity of individuals each seeking his particular good is still a particular good and that the conception and service of this good (even if it be the blissful satisfaction of the subjects), being reserved to the prince who makes it his business, is properly speaking the particular good of the tyrant. This is precisely the way that we imagine a good tyrant to be, not only an enlightened despot but one with a generous, even sensitive, heart. It is therefore not incorrect to say that the author of law is the multitude, understood in the sense of the community of rational beings. This is verified even in monarchical regimes whose pastoral form of representation should not necessarily be interpreted literally but rather analogically, the basis of which is the devotion the prince has for the welfare of his subjects. Conversely, it should not be imagined that a democratic form of government necessarily guarantees the success of the community and the intention of the common good; it can happen that such a regime will result, somewhat mechanically, in many particular wills which no common good can ever establish into a community, wills sufficiently informed that each is aware of the resistance of the others in order to avoid a war in which all would suffer and to benefit at least from the possibilities offered by the regime for an increase in the particular happiness of each. All that is asked of the shepherd king, then, is that he maintain a state of equilibrium, a favorable and enriching milieu conducive to the profit of each individual. This concern is therefore the work, the proper task of the tyrant, it is the end which is defined for him; but since there is no genuine community, it is clear that this proper end is the particular good of the tyrannical government. Thus, to the extent that a human collectivity fails to constitute a community (which 60 JEAN TONNEAU requires more than the external forms of mutual tolerance, discretion and politeness), it can only oscillate between anarchy and tyranny; at times, the instinct for self-preservation makes it prefer a tyranny which, if it is clever and efficacious, assures a favorable external context allowing particular wills to live side by side while avoiding conflicts and damaging infractions. However, it is clear that this is not the proper good of power, nor of individuals, nor even of the collectivity of individuals. It should be admitted that this representation of a tyrannical power, which adopts the idea and assures the promotion of welfare in the collectivity without attaining a unity of views and intentions which would constitute a common good and make of it a " multitude " in the classical sense, is the image which we spontaneously form of political power, so much so that it seems to us normal and almost desirable. The legitimacy of this power depends on a single condition: that it was instituted in some way by that which is called its base, the collectivity of individuals; nothing is more logical, since the individuals entrust to political power the task of setting up conditions for existence for all. In other words, we have here again a lex regia, by which the people invests the prince with this authority which, henceforth, as long as they continue to consent to it, will properly belong to him. The normal rule, in our estimation, is that authority should stem from the collectivity, but it should properly reside, with power, in the head of the collectivity, who will henceforth exercise it and therefore legislate. Now this representation effectively saves the empirical appearances and corresponds to the imperfection of political communities which history has described for us, but it does not satisfy Saint Thomas. 38 Saint Thomas is not ignorant of the •• To tell the truth, this is the reproach which a " realistic " spirit will make against the Thomist idea: to make the multitude the proper subject of legislative authority seems to disregard the fact that the " communities " are always more or less divided, or as we modestly say, pluralistic. And is this not to forget that every political regime which history has known has bequeathed to us an image of itself corresponding to the schema of tyranny? The answer is twofold: TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 61 practical necessities of life in society which often prevent the multitude taken as a whole from carrying on its legislative work; this is why he makes room for a vicem gerens totius multitudinis. Still it is necessary to take into account the massive fact of purely customary laws which ruled humanity for thousands of years to the exclusion of all written law; it clearly seems that the multitude was the cause of this; the first instance of written law generally consisted in codifying customs. But in any case, if there is a vicem gerens, Saint Thomas does not conceive him in the sense of intersubjective relationships according to the contractual figures of the mandate, of delegation or of representation. He is referring instead to a specific differentiation of multitude, hierarchically organized in its being, so that certain persons analogically assume the role of organs specialized for diverse functions. Whoever has charge of the multitude is referred to as a " persona publica," which we should envisage, it seems, as the personification of the community. 39 Thus, for the moment, 40 the head must not a) We concede first of all that in a large measure the multitude is made up of imperfect men who can never constitute a perfect community; it follows that, to this extent, it is resistant to a political government, that it must be directed by other processes than that of law and that there are definitely less laws worthy of the name than there are of texts so designated in the official literature. b) In the second place, it should be remarked that a political reality is only known by us through the descriptions that are made of it; as these are imperfect, more or less penetrating or complete, it is infinitely probable that in politics there are realities which are not explicitly recognized and described and which would probably be the most plain, profound and lived rather than explained; political life would then be more complex and better on the whole, more human, than the analyses and explanations of theoreticians \vould have us believe. In these conditions, we will not be too astonished at the rigorous, apparently unattainable, requirements of the political thought of Saint Thomas. Understood in depth, man is without doubt !,'Teater and more admirable than he appears to be in his superficial and empirical manifestations. 39 The idea of person in this context must obviously be understood in the analogical sense. It is clear that in the proper sense all human beings, whatever their social status, are persons. In social philosophy the term " person " is reserved for those who are active, or more precisely, for those who have voice in community assemblies and whose acts make some impact, count for something within the society. The force of the analogy is such that, on this level, some human beings who are true persons from the ontological point of view are not conceived 62 JEAN TONNEAU be thought to be a distinct person who enters into interpersonal relationships with the community in a contractual way; undeniably there are such relationships, but they envisage the " individual " who is vested with this function, an individual for whom it is necessary to find a position in relation to the community. We are now at a point which is logically anterior, and we are considering the community in its head as in one of its members who personifies it, because it is in him that it affirms itself as a person, that it speaks, that it acts; the other members are not so involved to the point that we can recognize in their words and actions the words and actions of the community. In the prince, on the contrary, the community acts in the principal way, the community affirms itself as a principle of action. 41 Certainly, it should be repeated, all the as having a personality; in return, personality is accorded (this is the artificial part or the fiction which belongs to every analogy) even to reasonable beings and institutions whose counsel or agreement is imposed on others, i.e., who act (on the social level actions are always operations which terminate in others and resound in them). The point of the analogy, regulating and justifying its application, is evidently that persons are recognized as principles of action and that reciprocally everything which is a principle of action is recognized as a person. It is on this basis that persons enter into social relationships: they oppose each other, adjust to each other, they are subjects of rights, in brief, they are the "others." We can see that the analogy was born and remains on the level of social transactions and that it owes practically nothing, except perhaps its point of origin, to metaphysical researches on the formal constitutive of personality. We must avoid ascribing to analogical personality a metaphysical reality which only belongs, according to Boethius, to the rationalis naturae individua substantia, as much as we must avoid reducing the metaphysical personality of persons properly so-called to their social personality defined in terms of others with whom they enter into relationship by their operations. 4 ° For the moment, for we must not forget that we are living in the time of social structure; it is evident, and it is even the most evident thing in our daily experience, that once society is structured, with everyone in his place and carrying out his function, persons will enter into relationships by the very play of their activities: we will see come into being, in the distinction of agents, the opposition, the equilibrium of distinct subjective rights, as well among the members of societv as among each of them and society considered as a person having rights them and intervening in their activities. 41 Tradition recognizes a record of reflections revolving around the Principium and the Caput (In principia ... In capite libri ... ) . The theme occurs often in Saint Thomas, with references to Aristotle. It follows from this that every being is essentially defined by that which is principal in it (I-II, q. 29, a. 4). Thus what TEACIDNG OF THE THO MIST TRACT ON LAW 63 members act both by reason and will, otherwise there would be only a herd and not a political community; but the other members cannot pretend to play the role of principle of activity in such a way that the community would be considered to be acting in each of their actions. We can now understand the sense of the alternative vel ... vel ... given in Article 3; it does not imply that whoever is in charge of the multitude is a transcendent subject separated from the multitude after having been invested with authority by it. There is in reality but one authority, whose proper subject is always the multitude; but it can happen that this multitude, few in number, remain relatively disorganized; all the members can assemble, deliberate, decide, or rather, i£ we remain faithful to the lesson of history, there is an implicit and tacit consensus, but well determined and very firm, which founds this form of law which is unwritten law or custom. Otherwise in larger and more developed communities the social structure will be different; certain organs will be consciously recognized as having the power to legislate/ 2 in agreement with men accomplish by reason is taken as being done absolutely and in the highest degree by themselves (In IX Ethic., lect. 9, n. 1871). The motive in this is that " unaquaeque res illud videtur esse quod in ea est potissimum, ut Philosophus dicit" (I-II, q. 106, a. 1). This is then applied to the structure of the social being: "Alio modo dicitur homo esse aliquid secundum principalitatem, sicut princeps civitatis dicitur esse civitas" (II-II, q. 'i!5, a. 7). And again: " Unumquodque maxime videtur esse illud quod invenitur in eo esse principium; omnia autem alia videntur ei quod est principium adhaerere et ab eo quodammodo assumi, inquantum id quod est principium aliis utitur secundum suam dispositionem: quod quidem patet non solum in ordinatione civili, in qua principes civitatis quasi tota civitas esse videntur, et aliis utuntur secundum suam dispositionem, ut sibi adhaerentibus membris; sed etiam in ordinatione naturali. Licet enim homo naturaliter constet ex anima et corpore, principalius tamen videtur homo esse anima quam corpus, quod animae adhaeret et quo anima utitur ad operationes animae convenientes " (De rationibus fidei, n. 980). •• It seems that, in French, words such as "legiferer," "legislation," "legislateur," etc., were very little used before the French Revolution; they have come strongly into vogue only since that date. Now, if they etymologically derive from the Latin, from a historical reality, it is not directly from the Latin that they have been borrowed but from the English language; this enrichment of language is due to the influence of the political ideas of England on the philosophers of the Continent. Cf. Sten Gagner, Studien zur ldeengeschichte der Gesetzgebung, p. 57. This 64 JEAN TONNEA l1 the multitude which gives its more or less explicit consent, and even sometimes a tacit adherence to the state of affairs. But it is not in virtue of personal authority that they do this; on the contrary, it is because they are the organs of law that they are invested with this authority, just as in a regime ruled by custom the wise men and the elders who speak the law are consulted on points of custom, and speak with the authority which is attached to custom. Thus it is clear that this reference aims at the multitude and that the authority of the multitude can be none other than that of reason. We will see what has become of this Thomist doctrine in later history. Let us tum to the second Article. We do not stop here for long, since the remarks already made regarding the multitude as author or cause of law have led us to treat sufficiently of the bonum commune of Article Q. Let us at least point out that the expression " common good " is somewhat obsolete, if not worn out, and that it lacks attraction for most people. From one aspect this falling from favor is irreparable, since we are forced to choose an absolutely universal and abstract term if the definition of law is to be applied to all that is defined in its innumerable varieties and species. If this difficulty (which stems most of all from the lack of philosophical culture on the part of our audience), were to be overcome, it could be observed that the attractive reality of the common good is a datum anterior to the law. It is not the law which forces us to adhere to a desirable common good; without this desirability there is no community, much less a law. It is desirable for the audience to possess a certain maturity, an experience of human life which will give them a sense of the different desirable objects which constitute, at all levels, the indicates, at least to us, that under the Ancien Regime, if not among the specialized authors, at least in current language, the nature of the act of legislating and its author were not hotly discussed. No one claimed to make law: the king would mete out justice according to the laws of the kingdom, the judges, would render judgment, etc. But the law was considered as a popular datum which was sometimes expedient to look into without proving the need to do so or granting the right to do it. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 65 common good in which men will share because it is good to join in anything which shares in reason. In the domain of action the end is the principle, and the principle of principles can only be the end of all ends, beatitude, i.e., God. No law, not even divine law, can prescribe for us the obligation of adhering to this ultimate end which is the principle of all law. In a profound sense the law does not create obligation, it discovers it; if we are already obligated, related to God, no law, not even divine law, can touch us or bind us. Let us state once again that God who is the universal end and the common Good of all men is the same God who is the object of love. We ordinarily think of God as the sovereign authority; this difficulty justifies a special section (III) . But the question is actually about infinite lovableness, such that in the order of integral nature all men would naturally love above all things, that which we love out of charity in the order of healing and elevating grace. Maintaining all due proportions, the same thing can be said of human laws; there is a priority of the common good over the law. Certainly the requirements of the common good become more and more contingent and complex as the communities they are applied to are more particular; 43 it can be maintained that the existence of good laws is an element which contributes to the common good of the community. But this a posteriori consideration does not obliterate the direct and fundamental consideration, which is that the end is not the law but the common good. It is the common good which is, in relation to the law, a first principle. The notion of principle serves as a transition to the first Article. Remember its title: the law is "aliquid rationis." This is a curious intrusion into what is supposed to be a theological tract. The word mtio is one of those which discourages the translator. For us, in keeping with the current use of the word in Saint Thomas, it can mean cause or motive, argument, ••" Bonum commune constat ex multis " (I-ll, q. 96, a. lc). This is precisely a question of human law. 66 JEAN TONNEAU the meaning or notion of a thing; again, it can designate a faculty of the human soul, or an act of this faculty, or a certain habitus of this faculty. The second objection points out this diversity of meanings and contests that none of them agrees with law. In his answer Saint Thomas makes a general remark on the ambiguities of ordinary language. The same word, often intentionally so, such as " construction," can designate either an activity or the result of this activity. The activity ceases when the masons leave the construction; and in this sense construction ceases. But the resulting construction happily remains. If we take the word ratio in the Latin sense of calculation it signifies an activity which is performed, and, if successful, ends in a result. The word ratio is also ascribed to this result which has a durable mode of existence independently of the activity which produced it; this kind of calculation served later on for an indefinite number of paradigms or rules for other constructions; thus, once the value of 3,1416 has been determined as the proportion between a circumference and its diameter, this calculation made once and for all serves as a tool, a rule, a measure for making other calculations. Hence, and this is the starting point for the argumentation, given what is not demonstrated but is universally accepted, law is the rule or the measure of human acts (speaking here provisionally of that which is better known, the law which rules in human societies, but the definition ought to apply to every law, eternal, natural, divine). This is what is meant when it is said (and it is said often today, so it is not very likely false) that law binds us to do this or to avoid that. 44 We are then in agree44 Curiously, authors have been stopped by this formula: (lex) obligat ad agendum, and want to see in it a valuable teaching of the article. The logical course and flow of the article clearly show that it is only a start; it is the first and uncontested datum, in no wise elaborated, of what everybody understands by the word law: it is something which obliges you to do this or to avoid that. Saint Thomas translates this into his own language: it is a rule of human activity, and he does not feel the need to push the point, since in the main this is exactly what everybody means by the term. That this beginning is illustrated by a recourse to the etymology of lex a ligando (a little further on, recourse will be had to another etymology: lex a legendo) is nothing but a recourse to first and TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 67 ment: law is essentially a rule of human conduct; there are many kinds of laws, but that matters little: the word rule covers a great number of things; a thing can be a rule in many different ways. Thus if we are speaking of regulating human acts, this, of course, is considered an appeal being made to reason; this has already been demonstrated, and it is enough to dispel all doubt to recall what man is and what a human act entails. More precisely, we speak of a rule or measure. While this may be slightly redundant, the two notions are not absolutely identical. Every rule is a measure but every measure is not a rule. To measure is basically an operation destined to give us knowledge of some object. This is valid first of all for objects which have extension, volume, weight, or number, in short, in the category of quantity; this is analogically extended, without any special problem, to every kind of knowledge, whether speculative or practical. And it is good to note that, in order to measure, we make use of a unit of measurement which plays the role of touch stone, of principle of knowledge. It is that which is known previously and whose truth will found and justify the knowledge of everything else in that order. It does not matter much whether this truth be had naturally, as in the first principles of reason, or be instituted through convention, as in the meter or the kilogram; in any case we possess knowledge (sufficiently proximate for the case of the meter or of the kilogram for which our imagination or senses have a certain appreciation) which allows us to measure, i.e., to know, all the rest, that is, all which in the same order derives from this principle of knowledge. The unit of measurement enjoys then a certain kind of perfection, first as unit and then as principle within a given order. This remark is important, as we will immediate insights common to everyone. We can therefore base our reasoning on the above. What strikes me in this case is what little attention Saint Thomas pays to the avenues opened to him by the etymology of a ligando if these avenues were in fact of interest to him. It is obvious that he does not even think about them. The important thing is ad agendum; to say that a law obliges makes no sense unless we precise it further: to do this or to avoid that. 68 JEAN TONNEAU see when discussing the notion of rule. I know very well that the unit of measurement is often chosen rather arbitrarily and that one cannot without caution attribute absolutely and in the ontological order a privileged position to this unit of measure rather than to another; there is no reason why the meter should be preferred to the kilometer, considered in itself. However, if we go beyond the realm of material mensurations and strive to measure and to appreciate spiritual dimension, the unit of measurement is the perfect; any given quality will be small or great depending on whether it is nearer to or more remote from pure perfection. But even in quantitative measurements the choice of the units of measurement is not necessarily arbitrary; a certain technique will measure in terms of feet or inches, or meters or kilometers, or light-years, or microns; the reason for this is that techniques also are aliquid rationis. But we are now dealing with measures which are also rules. Among the things which need to be measured to be known are our deeds and our operations; the measure in this case is called the rule, which means nothing else than the measure of practical intention which properly rules movements. 45 All measures in moral matters are rules, because human actions are considered as movements. Etymologically, to rule denotes the notion of rectum, and consequently a rule can be looked upon as knowledge directing us in the light of the principle which rules the whole order of human actions, namely, reason. To rule in the moral sense means, then, to introduce into those movements which are human acts the perfection proper to movements, the rectitude (whose contrary or absence is disorder) which has reason as its unit of measurement, the principle. There is no way, therefore, to escape the conclusion that if the law, as everyone claims, is the rule of human acts, then it must pertain to reason. •• I leave aside as useless for our discussion the case of measures which share in the nature of rules because, while being foreign to practical reason and belonging to a kind of speculative reason, their usage implies operations. It is to meet the exigencies of these operations and to render them, in a certain sense, more practicable, when it is not so simply by professional tradition, that different units of measurement are chosen by different techniques or sciences. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 69 Having concluded with a rapid reading of question 90, we see that the definition of law proposed in Ariticle 4 is at the same time very rigorous and very comprehensive; it leaves no types of law which merits the name of law in the proper sense [except for lex fomitis which bears the name of law only in an analogical roundabout way (indirecte); but it is not properly a law SECUNDUM QUOD (lex) est regula vel mensura. 46 ] In fact, it is only the authority of the Apostle which authorizes such talk. III. AuTHORITY OF THE LEGISLATOR AND THE BINDING FoRcE oF LAw Because the two problems originated together historically, are logically bound together, and constitute but one and the same difficulty in teaching, I have decided, for the sake of brevity, to consider in one section both the author of law and the problem whether law is the source of obligation. The commentators on Saint Thomas today have difficulty dissociating themselves from the modem idea that law expresses the will of authority. They are particularly careful to justify the existence and the vis obligandi of law, to base it on an authority transcending the multitude ruled by law. And yet, historians for some time now have already done justice to this anachronistic perspective. 47 From the historical point of I-II, q. 91, a. 1c, and reply. See, for example, the classical work of the brothers R. W. and A. J. Carlyle (whose writings date back as far as entitled A History of Medieval Political Theory in the West, especially Vol. I for its beginnings and the Fathers of the first centuries, and Vols. V-VI for the thirteenth century and the two centuries following. Also important are the works of G. de Lagarde, especially La naissance de l'esprit & 3rd ed. from 1956 on). Even more laique au declin du moyen age significant are authors who are in no way specialists in the history of political doctrins but have an interest in some author of Christian antiquity, such as Tertullian, and who end up by realizing that our notion of law is vastly different from that which was prevalent in remote times. Here are a few warnings given by the brothers Carlyle mentioned above: " We are so much and so naturally, if not very intelligently, influenced by belief in the existence of a conscious sovereign authority, of which law is the expression, that we find it difficult to understand the state of mind of these ages when the conception 46 47 70 JEAN TONNEAU view there is no room for doubt; even the theologians have begun to take account of this. 48 Let us attempt to study the problem by means of rational analysis. The idea which came to light in philosophical literature much before it found its way into the political and constitutional realm can be traced back to a legal formalism already marked in Jewish thought and even more so in Stoicism (chiefly in its distinction between kathekon and katorth6ma) , and found again later on in Kant: in order to obey the law in a perfectly virtuous way it is not enough to observe its tenets because such conduct is good, answers inclinations of nature and satisfies the reason; law must be observed, without any reference to its content, formally because the law commands it. There is a certain nobility, a bit forced but sometimes heroic, in this position; it has attracted many. What is new toward the end of the thirteenth of the sovereign, in the modern sense of the word, hardly existed " (A History ... , Vol. V, p. 42). "It is really time that historical scholars should recognise that to think of the mediaeval king as in his own individual person a legislator is really to misunderstand the whole structure of mediaeval life and society, and to read back into it conceptions which belong to a later world" (Ibid., p. 462). " The first appearance of the conception that the prince was the legislator was due to the revived study of Roman law, but it remained till the end of the thirteenth century merely academic and had no effect upon the constitutional practice of mediaeval societies, and very little en political theory" (Ibid., p. 468). And here, in what regards Tertullian, is the conviction of a specialist, E. Langstadt, Some Observations on Tertullian's Legalism, in Studia patristica, Vol. VI, Part IV (1962). I summarize: we project into the ancient texts a very particular conception of law, the modern conception. Among the concepts which have never been criticized, it is curious that the most fundamental appears in the theology of Tertullian, that of law and the idea of God as Legislator. We are speaking of "law" in general and in the abstract. But we always take this term in the specific sense of a formal law, a sovereign will imposed by a sovereign power. This is not law but the modern conception of law which, without crying " Look out! " has been received as the general notion of law, by nature and by definition, in modern thought, i.e., ours. Starting with this formal notion, all the rest follows with a strict logic, and we come to deny to the religion of law every serious consideration. Law thus conceived must necessarily rest on fear and on the hope of rewards as the only motives for obedience; what God expects of man can be reduced to the precepts of law, and thus we come to the acquisition of merit according to our good works. •• Precisely on this subject, with the " Gerson case " and the quarrel between Vasquez and Suarez, see, for example, L. Vereecke, Cl)nscience morale et loi humaine (Desclee et Cie, 1957). TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 71 and the fourteenth centuries is that this theory has, so to speak, been given its letters of Christian nobility and has become like a cyst in the tissue of nominalist theology. With a religious sense pushed to the absurd, the omnipotence of God (de potentia absoluta) was so insisted upon that this omnipotence was " liberated " from every rule other than the principle of non-contradiction. Whereas the tracts on law, as we have already seen, had been bathed until then in the atmosphere of wisdom, henceforth they were inscribed under the title of the perfectly free and omnipotent will of God. Connected with this general position, let us note a consequence which is in no way fortuitous: since liberty supposes the absence of every motive which would bind it, its perfection consists in absolute detachment and a supremely indifferent free play; up to that time the will was envisaged as an appetite which behaves with a certain passivity, an attachment or a radical attraction to the good; from then on, the perfection of this faculty consisted in not being involved with anything so as to allow for self-determination in an entirely autochical fashion; it was no longer passive, it was all realizing, effectrix, energy. The moral good is no longer defined in terms of its active attraction upon the will; this is strictly what our manuals call physical good. To be moral, no matter what its physical reality is, it is necessary and suffices that it obliges the will, and as a will can only be obliged by the precept of a superior will and ultimately of the divine will, it follows that the nerve of all moral goodness depends on God's will. Not only is all that God commands morally good (all are agreed on this) but nothing is morally good except what has this title and is done for this motive. Certainly, since God commands justice or temperance, it is right to acquire the virtues which give us a taste for them; but if it is good to acquire the taste for virtuous actions, it is to help us to do them and consequently to attain the unique moral value which consists in submission to the divine precept. The importance that the lawmaker has in this perspective is obvious. Until then it was thought that all truth was good, 72 JEAN TONNEAU no matter who uttered it. Now, at least with regard to that truth which serves as a practical principle, what counts is the authority which imposes it upon us. A moral life consists less in being good and becoming better that in doing all that is necessary in order to maintain good relations with the superior. Outside the area circumscribed by the will of the superior there is only moral liberty, i.e., the absence of moral good and evil. Here ·again that kind of detachment characteristic of nominalist liberty is encountered. We have then the germ of modern moral theology: in principle one is free (in the sense mentioned above); moral begins with the notion of obligation, when a legitimate authority imposes certain restrictions on the natural field of freedom. This is why this morality is founded on law, but on law which expresses in a clear way the quantum of obligation imposed by the sovereign. Hence the author of law cannot be the multitude, because the multitude is ourselves, and we cannot impose obligations upon ourselves; there is no voluntary limitation in the freedom of a will. The author of law should therefore be vested with an authority that raises him above the multitude, otherwise his claim would not be founded and his law would not have the power of binding the multitude in conscience. With an intrepid logic certain theologians marked by nominalism, such as P. d' Ailly and Gerson, concluded that no human law obliges in conscience, since there is no human authority that has the power to oblige in conscience. 49 They scarcely received a following, but what response could be made to them to preserve the force (in conscience) of human law? A detour was taken: certainly, the human legislator does not have the power of obliging in conscience directly, which would imply, so they say, that he had the power to send transgressors to hell; but he defines a certain positive order rendered morally good by the divine sanction, which is then imposed on the conscience, and whose infraction thus becoming a sin will be punished by •• Except, of course, when authority and human law merely restate the divine precept. TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 73 God in the hereafter. This solution made of the human legislator God's minister, a thought which is not at all strange and which is supported by many pages of the Bible; the lawmaker is charged by God to complete in their contingent application the solemn prescriptions of the divine law and of the natural law. There was no pretense that he discharged this mandate with a continuous and complete success, but, despite all his limitations, the human legislator shares in the divine authority and, through him, it is ultimately God whom we obey. Basically, if we have been led to this apotheosis of the human lawmaker, it is under the influence of an idea of law quite different from that of Saint Thomas. There is certainly no question of discussing the premise: law does oblige. Although the Thomist definition of law does not mention obligation, and although it is not even mentioned in question 9'2 (on the effects and acts of law), the manuals, even the Thomist manuals, cannot keep themselves from speaking about it. If they comment on the Thomist definition of law, they insist upon the word ordinatio in such a way as to evoke the idea of order, in opposition to counsel; if they explain question 90, they propose a theory much more subtle than the text of the Summa, in which all the acts traditionally attributed to law (command, forbid, permit, punish) are related to a unique act which they call the formal effect of law, to oblige. The nominalist definition of law, which I have taken from Gabriel Biel, is unambiguous: " Lex obligatoria " (i. e., true law as opposed to counsel) "est signum verum creaturae rationali notificativum rectae rationis dictantis ligari eam ad aliquid agendum vel non agendum." (Super 3 Sent., d. 37, q. unic., art. 1, notabile lm) . In this view it would be possible to maintain that law is an external principle, by definition in some sense, since law is only a sign (it is not a first principle of practical truth), and what it signifies necessarily is the thought of the lawmaker (who is necessarily someone else, since he obliges); finally, it is lacking nothing, what is signified is a thought whose content is formally that the subject is bound, i.e., obliged, to do this or to avoid that. In recto, what law 74 JEAN TONNEAU says is that you are obliged, more precisely, that the sovereign imposes an obligation upon you, puts you under restraint; all that remains is to inquire about the extent of this obligation and, as each one defends his own freedom, seeing that it (freedom) is "in possession," it is believed that the limits of this obligation will be duly controlled. As for the intrinsic value of those things which are rendered obligatory, this is especially the concern of the conscience of the human legislator; he will have to account for the way he has legislated, for the acts he has imposed, or for the abusive limitations which he has imposed on his subjects. But for the moral subject (I mean the one who sees things only from this point of view, no matter what the orientations of his appetite might be, no matter what are his likes or dislikes), only one point deserves consideration: to know exactly to what he is obliged. Modern moral would then be casuist and (human weakness impelling thither) probabalist, that is to say, animated by a perpetual spirit of challenge to the law. Little by little, when the religious spirit weakens, all that will remain of " traditional " moral is this frightful paradox: instead of being the sign of the grandeur of man "made to God's image," it will be the sign that man is quite inferior to God (who himself escapes moral, since he has no superior to oblige him). Law is then a shameful reminder, and man will always believe that he is being freed, coming of age, becoming God, in shaking off his moral obligations. 50 50 The accusation of alienation articulated against morality dates further back than today. In the I Sent., d. 43, q. 11, a. 2 Saint Thomas asks whether God acts de necessitate justitiae or not. The sixth objection is very interesting: God cannot be necessitated in his power by a created justice (for such a justice is not the rule of divine operations), nor by uncreated justice, for the latter does not contradict either the divine power or the divine will. This type of reasoning with its cutting logic is perfectly nominalistic; the objection supposes then that the necessity of a rule implies at least the possibility of a contradiction between the rule and the power ruled. In terms of the moralist, a rule becomes necessary only in the measure that there is at least the possibility of disagreement between it and the will. Since obligation is a kind of necessity, we can see that the rule ceases to be natural, becomes properly obligatory (or morally necessitating) when the will resists, or at least when it is presumed to be capable of resisting, the rule. This is also what Kant assumes when he sets pure will against holy will (Critique de la TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 75 The fundamental problem is what is called moral obligation. Certainly this notion does not play in the Thomist system the role that it subsequently usurped. But it would be absurd to imagine that Saint Thomas did not understand this term from daily language and misconstrued its notion. Obligation is like conscience; these notions are recognized and used, but when it is question of a scientific determination and when Saint Thomas is personally involved and speaks his own technical language, he substitutes something else for them, or rather his synthesis is built in such a way that these themes find no particular place there. It cannot be said that the notion of obligation is a false one: this would make no sense. The word obligation arouses in the spirit the idea of something everybody knows and which is quite real. To say that law does not oblige is shocking to any good man; he will justly protest. It is as if I were to say that the sun will not rise tomorrow morning. In both cases (unless I am to be taken for a fool) I am suggesting a false idea to my listener: the idea of a cosmic cataclysm which would plunge us into endless night; or this raison pratique, I, 1, § 7; I, 8). Saint Thomas gives the following answer (ad 6): "Dicitur Deus non posse injuste facere, non propter justitiae suae contrarietatem ad suam potentiam, sed propter injustitiae incompossibilitatem. Haec enim sunt incompossibilia, quod Deus aliquid faciat et illud justum non sit." There is perhaps a connection between the formalism of Kant, the trifle case he makes of goods, of theso-called materialist morality, and the Protestant attitude with regard to deeds. Cf. the Institution chretienne of Calvin (ed. Belles-Letters, Vol. I, pp. 202-208). Assuredly, Calvin has cause for reprimanding the mercantile calculation of bad Christians who rely upon their works according to the law in order to obtain justice; but this was no more the fault of the evangelical law than it was of the Mosaic law; these bad Christians correspond to the bad Jews. Calvin had been nourished by a theology which had lost contact with Saint Thomas; we will see that, properly speaking, it is not law which obliges us to accomplish certain works for the sake of reward; before the Law, there is a belonging to God through faith, and it is this which obliges us to God first of all and then to a conduct in keeping with the grace received. The practice of the Christian law is only the employment of grace, it is not the cause of grace. The study of the Christian virtues traditionally comes in theology after the study of grace, of which it is the prolongation, the explicitation and the exacting manifestation. This is somewhat like the precepts of the natural law as related to the rational natme which nature has given us. If the good tree yields good fruits, why would these works, in which grace bears fruit, not be good? 76 JEAN TONNEAU other cataclysm, not less frightful, of a law which would not be the rule of good action. But if we explain ourselves, if we raise ourselves to a sufficiently technical level, we will say without shocking anybody that tomorrow morning (or any other morning) it is not really the sun that will rise on the horizon but the portion of the earth on which we live that will begin to turn towards the sun. Quite often, with regard to obligation, Saint Thomas speaks like everybody else; he says that law should have a vis obligandi quod est proprium legis (otherwise, what good are laws?). At the beginning of Article 1 of Question 90 Saint Thomas starts off with the banal idea, not false but common and not technically elaborated, that law, for everybody, is that which obliges to do this or to avoid that, and consequently that law is indeed essentially a rule of human activities. This is enough, as a starting point, to indicate what the question is all about. But the analysis remains to be had. Here it is merely a question of knowing of what we speak, as moralists, in this atmosphere which is not that of a bank, when we talk of obligation (qualified as moral obligation when necessary). Etymology is not much help here: recalling the bonds by which the Law of the Twelve Tables kept debtors insolvent gives us the occasion to say that we do not wish to speak of a constraint or a physical limitation of liberty. However, there is indeed some analogical kinship between the two cases and ours does insinuate (especially in the modern doctrine of liberty) something like a limitation placed on liberty (we must add, here again, moral) . A friend has suggested: "The obligatory is what is imposed hie et nunc, taking into account all the circumstances, and what consequently is imposed universally whenever the exact same circumstances are present." It is obvious that this friend is a professor of philosophy and that he is not ignorant of Kant. It is true that we do not deny the quality of obligatory to universal principles which do not touch us hie et nunc; for example, a celibate is quite capable of judging and declaring that the rules proposed as obligatory in the Encyclical TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 77 Humanae vitae are indeed so; they are obligatory, and yet it is clear that they do not oblige in the precise sense of the word, for they do not touch or concern him hie et nunc. We can even say (even though negative precepts extend absoluately: sempe1· et ad semper ... ) that these rules do not oblige married persons hie et nunc at every instant but only when the question is put. And yet, I repeat, for everybody and at every moment the question is being put of knowing whether these rules are obligatory. 51 Not only can it not be maintained that a universal rule, because it is universal, possesses no vis obligandi, but if in fact it does oblige hie et nunc, it is because there is already some obligation (perhaps under a different form) attached to the univeral rules. On the contrary, there is not less obligation, quite the contrary, in universal principles than in conclusions; but this allows us to proceed a bit further in our analysis. There is more truth, more necessity in universal principles; but this necessity is not yet in contact with the act which is itself always singular, without precedent or repetition. Here we come once more to the idea proposed by Saint Thomas when he approaches the question technically with regard to obligation: it is a kind of habitudo, a contact, a position in the network of circumstances, which causes the rule to enter into contact with the act which is to be regulated; in a word, it is the position "en marche," the application of the rule hie et nunc. The fault of modern moral philosophy, when it gives obligation an explanatory value, is to think that a rule, provided that it is applied, provided that the human act has not transgressed it, i. e., remains in contact with the act from beginning to end, as does the hand of the pupil on the wooden ruler when he draws a line, necessarily guarantees the perfection of the act. Certainly, if the rule is not applied, the act is not regulated! But if the application of the rule or the obligation 51 This was Abbe Oraison's contribution to the discussion of the encyclical during a radio dialogue; and yet, neither the person of the orator, nor the place, nor the other circumstances allowed for the slightest hesitation over the non-obligation hie et nunc. 78 JEAN TONNEAU has some moral force, it is because it is a true rule. If a pencil carefully follows a crooked ruler, the line will not be straight. We find here the same formalism already denounced. It is very true that a rule is made to be applied, (quod est proprium legis); but to stick to the application of the rule to explain the morality of acts is to stick to the consideration (not the formal but the formalist and therefore material consideration) of submission or non-submission, contact or non-contact, obligation or freedom, all subjective and interesting considerations but posterior and secondary. After all, if there is any technical or moral interest in applying a rule, it is because this rule is true, with a practical truth which calls for application, but an application which would have no sense if it were not an application of truth. Men have long accepted the duty of applying rules; little by little they have begun to wonder why rules are to apply. This is the point where we are now. The situation is not at all catastrophic. It is enough to fill the substantial void which has left in moral theology a nominalist way of thinking which is careful only to adjust the exact relations of conformity and submission, relations, however, empty of all substance, of all attraction for the appetite, since they were ignoring the specific quality of the terms thus related. It is not for submission or for application of rules that the rational creature hungers. It is for truth. Having said that, the rules which instruct us in the truth will be loved and a joy given in applying them, because submission itself is based on truth. IV. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE TRACTS ON LAW AND ON GRACE We usually say that the Prima Secundae contains a tract on law and a tract on grace. And immediately two things come to our attention: first, that the most beautiful part, the very summit of the tract on law, the evangelical law, consists essentially in the grace of the Holy Spirit. Once we come to Question 109 we pride ourselves on finding a tract on grace, and we then make this second statement: this tract is really too short and incomplete. What are we to think of this? TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 79 Has not Saint Thomas given us all that he promised or are we expecting from him what he had no intention of giving us? His intention is manifested in the prologue to Question 90. He does not announce a tract on law or a tract on grace; he wants to tell us how God instructs us through law and aids us by grace. But what about the content? How is the program announced in the prologue fulfilled? The tract on law seems to be complete; it may even contain too much including, as it does, the important chapter on an evangelical law which consists essentially in the grace of the Holy Spirit. Actually, that the law is a gift, a grace from God, is a thought which goes back a long way, to the Old Testament; we are in the thread of a beautiful and solid tradition, or rather we are at the end of a long wait, and we are witnesses to the realization of ancient promises; we have seen that this is precisely what the Good News is. There is, therefore, not even for an instant, any question of dissociating the tract on this grace which is the evangelical law from the tract on law; this would be tantamount to the dethronement of the whole Christian economy, the divestment of its salvific significance. Thus, it should be admitted that questions 109-114 do not constitute a complete tract on grace; let us be logical. It is not the tract on grace, since what is lacking in it is much more than a mere accessory development or such nuances as can be found elsewhere, as, for example, in the tract on the divine missions. This tract, this so-called tract, is only interested in the manner in which grace helps man to good, or rather in which God aids man by grace. This is no discovery: for a long time it has been noticed that these questions 109-114 have been peculiarly dominated by the Augustinian perspective in its struggle against Pelagianism. There was no sparing of reproach for the poverty of this tract for ignoring an aspect so dear, as they said, to Greek theology, the aspect of grace as illumination, of adoption, and of divinization. We will be less embarrassed to recognize this if we admit that Saint Thomas's intention was not to assemble in these few questions all the elements of a doctrine on grace. 80 JEAN TONNEAU The fact that we find in questions 106-108, under the title of New Law or law of grace, an obvious part of the tract on grace, has not been sufficiently acknowledged, as if we had remained traumatized by the Pauline polemic against the " law " which opposed the law of faith. Justifiably, Saint Paul is fighting a Judaizing idea of the law, an idea which was an obstacle to the " economic " unfolding of the plan of salvation; but Saint Paul himself and Saint John after him, in meditating on Christ aE Wisdom and Christ as the Word of God, show us that this obstacle should be met and the leap taken. The progressive convergence of the notions of Word, Wisdom, and Law, their conjuncture in the person of Jesus, the need for safeguarding the theocentricity of a Christocentric faith, all invite us to consider the incarnate Word not only as the intermediary, the word-bearer who transmits God's revelation, but also as the epiphany, the theophany of God in a Word which "dwells among us " to act in us as the Word of God does. From this comes an ontological or entitative modification which makes the new man, with the Son as exemplar, with the adoption, the inheritance rights, and the communication of divine secrets; the human act of adherence to this new covenant is faith in Jesus Christ, but more than ever we should translate the word Covenant here by diatheke in order to put the absolute and gratuitous initiative of God into relief. From that time we would tend to judge the notion of law as insufficient unless care was taken of the biblical connection between ratio and word in logos. Is it deluding ourselves with empty verbal images to say, with so many ancient Doctors, that the incarnate Word, received and so to speak mystically begotten in our hearts by faith, is the key word which summarizes and brings to term the economy of salvation? One would have to be certain of knowing" what the gift of God is" to dare to contest it. Let us glean some more indications from Saint Thomas. On the one hand, he writes that what is essential, the principalitas (cf. above and note 41) of the New Law, what in it is principium, is the grace of the Holy Spirit who is given by faith (106, 1); on the other hand, he writes that the TEACHING OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW 81 principalitas legis novae consists in the grace of the Holy Spirit who " manifests himself in faith working through charity " (108, 1). Thus the principalitas which pertains to the grace of the Holy Spirit (or again the Spirit of Christ, to speak as Saint Paul does) is presented, on the one hand, as principium of the New Law, which is to say that by faith the Holy Spirit accomplishes his work in hearts by conforming them to the First-Born, by divinizing them by a kind of spiritual generation perfectly appropriated to the Holy Spirit as life-giver. But, on the other hand, the same grace of the Holy Spirit is presented as principium of the New Law insofar as it is manifest in faith working through charity: under this aspect, which is secondary and deriving from the first, grace is principium of the New Law understood precisely as law, i.e., as rule and measure of Christian activities. Grace then can be considered as a new nature (it is not a matter of Aristotelian physics, but justice must be done to the second birth announced in the Gospel, or rather to the Gospel itself) ; according to this nature the New Law is indita homini 52 by an inherence analogous to that of natural law in human nature. Parallel to nature, this grace is at once principle of life in the entitative and in the operative sense; it seems that, precisely as law, it should be understood in the second sense. It is in this sense that it is rule for the activities of the new man. Now if there is one point solidly affirmed by Christian tradition and raised again by Saint Thomas, it is that, contrary to the Old Law which announced a program of life without giving men the interior impulse necessary to fulfil it (as if the Creator had paused after having modelled in clay the figurine of the first man and omitted to breathe into him the breath of life), the New Law gives us this breath and in that brings us ""I-ll, q. 106, a. 1, ad The translation of indita by internal is a little weak; but if it were translated otherwise, it would not apply to the case of natural law pertinens ad naturam humanam but could be said of the New Law, which is aliquid inditum . ... quasi superadditum per gratiae donum. We could have said " inscribed " in the wide sense if the article precisely did not oppose the written law to the law indita: all things considered, inherent seems to me to be the least poor translation, 82 JEAN TONNEAU the indispensable help to lead effectively the kind of new life which it delineates for us. Therefore, questions 109-114 should be considered as the continuation of questions 106-109. We see there actually, in the Augustinian perspective which is dominated by the anti-Pelagian struggles, how God's help by grace is combined with the play of the human will, more precisely on the level with free will, notably in that which concerns the two crucial questions of justification and of merit. In both cases the solution comes back to always giving an absolute priority to the action of grace (which gives God the initiative in the granting of the diatheke), but insisting (and this is the key which permits us to escape contradiction) upon the interiority, the immanence, the "radicality " of this action as interior principle. The insertion of the principle is so radically profound that it does not interfere with the unfolding of human activity of which it is the source and which it embraces by strengthening it on the level of a simplex velle. Once this strengthening has taken place, the material program of acts to accomplish or to avoid is hardly different from the prescriptions of reason according to the natural law, since, once the judicial and ceremonial precepts of the Old Law have been abrogated, there remain only the moral precepts which are known to be valid in any hypothesis " quia secundum se pertinent ad rationem virtutis "; 53 in that, the New Law is already to a great extent liberating. But, it is especially liberating in that, with the limited program which remains, it makes us fulfill it more freely " in quantum ex interiori instinctu gratiae ea implemus." 54 Let us note well that this liberty should not be understood as the free play of a wheel gone wild. This liberty is too deeply rooted not to be an intense and determined voluntariety, "ex principio interiori cum cognitione finis." The libertarian error consists in thinking that the free man is one who is at his own disposal, i. e., who has not yet made up his own mind, committed himself to some end. Such •• I-ll, q. 108, a. 8, ad 8. •• Ibid., a. 1, ad 2. 83 OF THE THOMIST TRACT ON LAW a man is not even yet able to make up his own mind by a process of deliberation, because one can only deliberate in view of an end which has hold of you prior to this deliberation. In other words, one cannot hover between the world and God without belonging to one or the other. It is a delusion of the imagination that causes us to give a privileged position to this vain and unreal indifference as if it were pregnant with all the promises of the future. There is no future or promise of life except for the man who is attached to life's source: Homo quanto Deo magis conjungitur, tanto efficitur melioris conditionis.55 In this union which binds us, obliges us to God, God has the initiative and the auctoritas of principle, for it belongs to the Father who gives life. The precepts of the New Law, isolated from this principium, are nothing but an empty letter, and it is always opportune to recall this truth to keep us from judaizing. But, under this auctoritas the precepts of the New Law trace the kind of life and the condition which suits the " reborn"; it is the glorious livery of the people of God, in signum obligationis suae, not as a book of obligations but as the manifestation of his belonging, 56 for "the Law was made by the Word, old law new word, both coming forth ' from Sion and Jerusalem' (Isa. 2: 3) , and the commandment has been made grace, the figure reality, the lamb the Son, the sheep man, and man God?." 57 JEAN ToNNEAU, Paray-le-Monial Franc/J •• Ibid., q. 98, a. 5, ad 2. •• Cf. II-II, q. 111, a. 2, ad 2; q. 185, a. Sc; q. 186, a. 7, ad 2. •• Melitus of Sardis (second century), Homelie sur la Paque. 0. P. LAW AND GOSPEL LuTHER's TEACHING IN THE LIGHT OF THE DisiNTEGRATION OF NoRMATIVE MoRALITY S INCE THE REFORMATION, the accusation has been raised against Luther that with his original and peculiar definition of the relationships between faith, grace, and good works he has destroyed the foundations of Christian ethics and has paved the way for a collapse of all moral striving. Already in his " Sermon on Good Works " of a time when Luther was neither excommunicated or even threatened with excommunication 1-he had to defend himself against the insinuation that he slighted good works: " Thus it happens, when I place so much emphasis on faith and reject faithless works as I do, they lay it up to me that I forbid good works, though in fact I will gladly teach the proper good works of faith, and want to do so." 2 Even so, not until our own century has the charge been laid to rest, that Luther, if not in his 1 This little book was written between March and May, 1520, and, as we learn from a letter of Melanchthon's dated June 8, was available in print in the beginning of June. The bull "Exsurge Domine," which threatened Luther with excommunication, was issued June 15, 1520. • 6/205, 11; cf. 10 I 1/410, 14; 56/233, 20; 286, 7. These page numbers refer to the complete critical German edition of Luther's works, Weimar, 1883- (called WA, = Weimarer Ausgabe): citations are given according to volume (in given cases, one must add half-volume and section: thus, 10 I 1), page and line. In these footnotes, the line indicated will be that at which the text in question begins, and thus the reader should understand "sqq." whenever this would apply. Besides the Weimarer Ausgabe we have also 0. Clemen's practical school edition: (8 v.) Luthers Werke m AU8Wahl (Berlin, 19666 ), which contains all of Luther's more important works; and the Munich edition: Martin Luther, Ausgewiihlte Werke, ed. H. H. Borcherdt and G. Merz, 6 v. 7 suppl. v. (Munich, 19483 ), reprinted 1962/1963. This edition gives not only a German translation of Luther's Latin works but also a modern German version of his German writings. Both of these editions, moreover, indicate in the margin the corresponding pages of the WA, and thus also handy reference to the citations. + 84 LAW AND GOSPEL 85 intention, at least in his effect in the de facto order, did open up the way for the modern decay of moral norms and solid ethical convictions. 3 If we undertake to pass a moral theologian's judgment on this decay and to this end inquire what Christian tradition has to say on the theme " Law and Freedom," then an investigation of Martin Luther's theology takes on special importance. We must test out whether and to what extent Luther's theology really does occasion and justify the above accusation. And if not, then we should ask what judgment Luther's theology for its part would give concerning this modern decay of normative morality: is it the bastard child of an illegitimate union between his theology and modern secularism? Or is it the neglected, spoiled child of an authentic Christian spirit brought to life by Luther? In which case, possibly, just a little care and rehabilitation could offer this child the chance for a new Christian generation. The question we have raised would fit squarely under the above-mentioned headings " Law " and "Freedom." Luther, for his part, considered "Law " and " Freedom " as opposed, contrary, antagonistic concepts: one need only think of his programmatic document of " On the Freedom of the Christian Man," addressed in its expanded version to Pope Leo X, a document which Luther scholars and church historians count among the "classic Reformation texts." 4 Thus, among Luther scholars our theme is treated under precisely this rubric." However, "Law and Freedom" is for Luther no fixed technical formula. The way we stated the 3 Cf. K. A. Meissinger, Der katholische Luther (Munich, 1952), pp. 101-108. A large number of examples from Catholic textbooks of Dogmatics is assembled in A. Hasler, Luther in der katholischen Dogmatik. Darstellung seiner Rechtfertigungslehre in den Katholischen Dogmatikbiichern (Munich, 1968), 52 sq., 77 sq., 85 sq., 96, 98. • 7/20-28; following the Latin Yersion, 7/42-78. Also pertinent here is the "De servo arbitrio," written in 1525 against Erasmus, 18/600-787, where at great length and under many aspects the relation between law and freedom is discussed. 5 The most important study in recent years on this theme is: W. Joest, Gesetz und Freiheit. Das Problem des Tertius usus legis bei Luther und die neutestamentliche Paramese (GOttingen, 8 1961). 86 OTTO HERMANN PESCH question rather focuses our attention quite involuntarily on another formula of Luther's: " Law and Gospel." If, as may be presupposed here, the essential and typical note of Christian ethics always finds expression in the fact that law and legalistic behavior take on a pejorative overtone, as something to be overcome, to be transcended-then, the counter-concept which one sets up over against the concept "Law," and the very manner of the opposition, will necessarily show forth our understanding and evaluation of "Law," on the one hand, and the starting point of Christian morality on the other. For Luther the concept opposed to "Law" is not "Grace" (as it was, e. g., for Saint Thomas), but" Gospel." All the other counterconcepts, such as " Freedom," are of secondary importance. 6 Consequently, we can answer our question only by searching out the meaning of this formula in Luther. 1. The Meaning of the Formula" Law and Gospel" in Luther's Theology. Our undertaking is faced with a two-fold difficulty. First of all: this formula, " Law and Gospel," does not constitute a single doctrine or treatise, as, for example, we can speak of Luther's doctrine on baptism or the Last Supper. Instead, this formula leads us to the very center of his entire theological thinking. Luther himself often said as much. "Practically the whole of Scripture and the understanding of all theology depend on a correct understanding of Law and Gospel." 7 The distinction between Law and Gospel is " the highest art of Christianity." 8 " Oft have ye heard, that there is no better way of teaching, preserving pure doctrine, than that we follow the method, namely, that we divide Christian doctrine into two parts, namely, into Law and Gospel." 9 Should anyone, as, for example, Erasmus of Rotterdam, not take this distinc• For Luther, concepts synonymous with "Gospel" are "Verheissung" ise ") and " Zusage " (also " promise ") . 7 7/502,84. 8 86/9,28. • 89 I/861, I. ("prom- LAW AND GOSPEL 87 tion to heart, he understands nothing of the Sacred Scriptures, however much he might know about them. 10 We have here expressions from the early, the middle, and the last years of Luther's activity. They allow us to recognize the central place of this theme "Law and Gospel." On the one hand, Luther thinks that "Law and Gospel" fully sums up materialiter the two statement-complexes of the Christian message; on the other hand, he teaches that the distinction of "Law and Gospel" shows us f01"maliter the way in which each and every statement of Scripture and Theology is to be examined and thought through. The Protestant theologian and Luther scholar, Gerhard Ebeling, is consequently quite right in his formulation: "Law and Gospel " is for Luther the "fundamental formula of theological understanding." 11 Thus the formula, "Law and Gospel," seen as the recapitulation of Luther's theology, opens up many lines of research. Indeed the enlightenment contained therein, which our interest in the contemporary disintegration of normative morality has driven us to seek, is from Luther's point of view a problem relating to the entirety of the Christian Gospel, not merely of a "moral theology " pursued as a thing in itself. The distinction between "Law" and "Gospel" is, to begin with, a hermeneutic principle, i.e., a methodological indication for the proper interpretation of Sacred Scripture. A prime complaint of Luther against the theology of his predecessors, leveled again and again in many variations, is that their exegesis has made a law out of the Gospel, indeed a more oppressive one than was the Law of Moses. A classic expression of this view is the well-known sentence from his " great Confession "' of 1545, where Luther, looking back over his struggles as a reformer, sees his Reformation break precisely at the point of his turning 10 18/693, 5; cf. 680, 28; 40 I/207, 17; 486.26. G. Ebeling, "Luther: Theologie," in Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, v. IV (1960), pp. 495-520: p. 507. Further testimony of this is brought together in 0. H. Pesch, Theologie der Rechtfertigung bei Martin Luther und Thomas von Aquin. Versuch eines systematisch-theologischen Dialogs (Mainz, 1967), p. Sl, n. 5. 11 88 OTTO HERMANN PESCH away from that confusion of Law and Gospel of which he accuses Tradition. In effect, the aged Luther sees everything as dependent on a correct understanding of Paul's expression "the justice of God " in Rom.l: 17. He had felt himself forced by Tradition to understand "God's justice," of which the Apostle speaks, as the active, punitive justice of God. This view, however, confronts Luther with the tormenting question, " Shall it not then be enough, that the wretched sinner, eternally damned through Original Sin, should be afflicted in the Law of the Decalogue with miseries of every kind? Must God then even through the Gospel heap sorrow on sorrow and threaten us in the Gospel, too, with his justice and his wrath"? 12 As a factual account of Luther's Reformation break, such statements are to be accepted with a certain reserve, 13 but they do show where the Reformer, looking back over his theological life-work, places the accent and wishes it to be placed: the Gospel (and after all Paul does want to preach the Gospel!) is misunderstood to the point of despair when one conceives it as serving the same function as the Law, indeed as intensifying the working of the Law. The distinction between Law and Gospel, consequently, alone makes Scripture clear and shows forth its message as a saving, liberating word. 14 Secondly, the distinction between Law and Gospel takes on in this light a direct dogmatic significance. We make contact here with the doctrine on the justification of the sinner, which for Luther, as everyone knows, is the "articulus stantis et cadentis ecclesiae." 15 If the sinner is justified before God, not 54/185, 30. Not to be overlooked is the scholarly discussion focused on this text since the beginning of the century. Cf. 0. H. Pesch, "Zur Frage nach Luthers reforrnatorischer Wende. Ergebnisse und Probleme der Diskussion urn Ernst Bizer, Fides ex auditu," in Catholica 20 (1966), 216-243, 264-280. The most important contri· butions to the discussion are reprinted in B. Lohse, ed., Der Durchbruch der reformatori;when Erkenntnis bei Luther (Darmstadt, 1968). u Luther's theological impulses are detectible and have their effect even on into modern Protestant answers to actual moral problems. As a typic-al example, one might take the Protestant position on divorce and remarriage. 15 40 III/352, 3; cf. 39 I/205, 2; 40 I/33, 16; 50/199, 22. One begins to see how all hangs together; if the doctrine on justification is the " articulus stantis et 12 13 LAW AND GOSPEL 89 through the law but through its opposite, the Gospel, then the sinner is not justified through that which the law demands, namely, works, but through the very opposite of this: through his being set free from the works demanded by the law, that is, through pure grace, which man must allow himself to accept as a gift, without seeking to make any payment. Thus from "Law and Gospel" a path leads directly to those "particula exclusiva" of the Reformation: " solus Christus," " solus Deus," " sola gratia." And yet the precise point of Luther's teaching on justification is by no means adequately labled with the formula " sola gratia," unless we add thereto " sola fides ": this also follows logically from the distinction between Law and Gospel. For one thing, this is so because " faith " for Luther means precisely this: to let oneself accept a gift and to renounce self-justificatory works, the "fulfillment of the Law." We will come back to this aspect. 16 But "faith" is also man's response to the " Word." Thus, seen as a consequence of the distinction between Law and Grace, the "sola fides" implies the fundamental affirmation that salvation and forgiveness of sin are communicated to man through the Word, and still further, that the Gospel itself is in fact the promise and proclamation of forgiveness of sins and of God's grace and mercy. From this follows notable consequences for understanding the salvific effectiveness of the Sacraments: Luther bitterly defended the sacraments against the Zwinglians and those other dissident Reform groups, whom he himself calls "Schwarmer" (vision(fanatics), and against any dearies) or "Schwarmgeister" valuation of the Sacraments he appealed to the fact of their establishment by Christ. But he emphasized, against the halfmagical sacramental usages of his time (which he wrongly identified with Catholic tradition) , that salvation lay only in the relation of God's word and man's faith-response, and that cadentis ecclesiae," and yet the distinction between Law and Gospel is " the highest art in Christianity," then, if both are to hold true together, the entire teaching ou justification must be summarily included in "Law and Gospel." •• lnfm, p. 94. 90 OTTO PESCH one could rightly understand the Sacraments only by seeing in them a Christ-founded institution in which this relationship is brought about. 11 It is impossible for us to pursue all these considerations in the present article. We had to mention them, however, so as to avoid in what follows the fallacy of taking the part for the whole. If there is ever a case of the part being intelligible only in the light of the whole, this is true in the case of Luther. Consequences that initially shock us, when seen in the context of the whole, appear convincing and almost self-evident. Given a grasp of a certain few basic premises, the conclusions seem altogether simple and direct: once we concede a Christian legitimacy to these basic premises, we can no longer avoid their consequences. It is just this which makes our dialogue with Luther so fascinating and stimulating. The particular aspect of the "Law and Gospel" formula of concern to us here may be designated: Freedom and Obligation. We must recognize from the outset that one can refuse to hear Luther on this subject only if he considers any Catholic confrontation with the decisive statements of Luther's theology as fruitless and illegitimate. A second difficulty confronting us is bound up with the question: where can we find Luther's authentic conception of "Law and Gospel " ? Unlike a Thomas Aquinas, for example, Luther wrote no Summa Theologiae at the end of his life that might have systematized his thought and provided us with a standard source for his definitive teaching. Quite the contrary, the writings of Luther's last years, from 1580-1545 or thereabouts, should in no sense be seen as tying together or putting precise finishing touches to Luther's thought. The polemical writings of this period are aimed chiefly at defending positions he had reached long ago against opponents in his own camp; the disputations and class lectures of this period seek to impart to a second generation of Reformed theologians, in easy-tograsp classroom style, a theology thought out long before. The 17 Cf. Pesch, Theologie der Rechtfertigung, pp. 326 sqq. LAW AND GOSPEL 91 claims made on him by problems of church politics no longer allowed Luther the leisure he had enjoyed in early years to prepare his lectures. Add to this that on the whole the greatest part of Luther's published works represent transcriptions of his oral conferences in the pulpit or the classroom and that the reliability of the transcription varies, depending on who is responsible for the same. With all this in mind it can be appreciated easily enough how difficult it will be to give Luther's doctrine on any particular point with critical certitude and how tremendous are the methodological problems confronting historico-critical Luther scholarship. Fortunately, in the "Law and Gospel " questions we do not labor under the full weight of these difficulties. Above all, we are spared the most difficult of all the questions involved here, that of Luther's "Reformation break": in other words, that of the date after which Luther had so clearly stated his Reformed positions that the Church (at least that of the sixteenth century) would be no longer willing to recognize him as orthodox. 18 It is methodologically evident that whatever Luther had to say before this point in time cannot be regarded as evidence for his Reformed Theology but rather must be measured for their " Lutheran authenticity " against the unequivocally Reformational statements. Now if the assignment of this date in current research varies between 1512 and 1518, by the same token the source value of Luther's important earlier writings, notably the First Commentary on the Psalms (1513/15) , the Commentary on Romans (1515/16), and even the documents of the Indulgence controversy (1517/1518) , is equally controverted. In terms of the question of" Law and Gospel" we get around this difficulty in that, as the research reveals, the content of the formula appears early enough in Luther's writings, but the technical elaboration and application of this formula as the " basic formula of theological understanding " is first discernable after the latest cut-off date of the "Reformation break," namely, after 1518.19 Moreover, Luther, fortunately for us, was com18 19 Cf. n. 13 supra. On this, see G. Ebeling, " Die Anfiinge von Luthers Hermeneutik," in Zeitschr. OTTO HERMANN PESCH pelled at every stage of his teaching career to speak out on the " Law and Gospel " theme, so that in view of the theme, the audience, and the opponents of the moment, everything conspired to clarify the problem in a precise and exhaustive way. Thus we have first-class sources for Luther's " Law and Gospel " theology at our disposal, unshadowed by any literarycritical problem, namely, the two Commentaries on Galatians (the so-called "small" Galatians Commentary of 1519) and the " great" Commentary on Galatians, presented as a course in 1531 and published with alterations in 1538/ 0 the" De Servo Arbitrio " (1525) / 1 and the three disputations against the "Antinomians" (1532/38) ,22 to which we can add sermons on pertinent Scripture texts. 23 Guided by these texts, and basing ourselves on the intense research effort they have provoked, we can in the following pages develop Luther's thoughts on "Law and Gospel," or better, present a systematic sketch of them. 2. The Radicalizing of the Law. Countless texts reveal that, to begin with, Luther understands by "Law" nothing different from the theology of his own and earlier epochs, namely, God's will promulgated to men. This does not, as it were, enter into force with the Law of the Old Covenant. Rather, it is an eternal law, written fii,r Theologie und Kirche, 48 (1951), 172-230; 208-216; Ebeling, Luther: Einfiihrung in sein Denken (Tiibingen, 1964), pp. 100-122; E. Bizer, Fides ex auditu: Eine Untersuchung ilber die Entdeckung der Gerechtigkeit Gottes durch Martin Luther (Neukirchen, 3 1966), pp. 15-22; H. Bornkjamm, "Zur Frage der Iustitia Dei beim Jungen Luther," part I in Archiv filr Reformationsgeschichte, 52 (1961), 16-29; part II, ibid., 53 (1962), 1-60: II, 18-22. Further references in Pesch, Theologie der Rechtfertigung, p. 32, n. 6. 20 In epistolam Pauli ad Galatas M. Lutheri commentarius: 2/443-618; In epistolam S. Pauli ad Galatas commentarius, ex praelectione D. Jl. Lutheri collectus: 40 I/15-688; 40 II/1-184. 21 18/600-787, esp. 671-688. 29 39 L/342-584. 23 Esp. 36/8-79: "Wie das Gesetz und Evangelium recht griindlich zu unterscheiden sind ... " (iiber Gal. 3:23-29, 1532. LAW AND GOSPEL 93 in the hearts of men, which corresponds content-wise to the Law of Moses, notably the Decalogue, and would have been binding of itself had Moses never given a Law. The need for this latter Law is traced to the darkening of reason and poisoning of the will through sin. Moses, then, gave no new law, but had only recalled anew God's eternal law. Christ, too, had simply interpreted and reinforced this law and had in no sense abolished it. 24 But to speak of the Law only in this sense is, for Luther, to miss the point of the Law's meaning for concretely-given man, i.e., for man after Original Sin. In this case the Law would be an affair of the angels; for man, such talk about the Law would be "empty." 25 For, from Paul, Luther has learned that the Law accuses, visits threats and demands upon the sinner. The Law is lex accusans, reos agens, exactrix. 26 This and nothing else is for the present the function-a function necessary for salvation-of the Law. 27 The Law exercises this function in that it reveals to man that he has failed God's will and still constantly fails it. More exactly, the concrete detailed prescriptions of the Law allow man, first of all, to recognize his violation in detail, convey to him, that is, his actual sins. 28 But this is not the decisive point. For even if one were to succeed in fulfilling all the detailed prescriptions of the Law, in this case the accusatory role of the Law would by no means be exhausted. On the contrary, it would then become plain that man was able to fulfill the Law only at the price of extreme personal effort; in other words, he in no sense carries 24 39 l/374, 2; 387, 5; 413, 14; 454, 4; 478, 16; 539, 7; 540, 1; 549, 8; 17 11/102, 24; 2/580, 7-23; 56/198, 8. Here as in the rest of the article we mention only a few " loci classici." A more thorough listing and interpretation may be found in my study mentioned in n. 11 above, esp. pp. 35-76, 296-317. 25 " Whenever we speak of Law, we speak not of an empty Law, ... as the angels might speak of it, ... but of a Law which accuses, a Law which acts in us and exacts from us." (translated from the Latin) 39 l/434, I. 26 Cf. the text quoted in n. 25. 01 2/466, 3; 10 III/338, 4; 39 1/363, 19; 412, 2; 277, 1; 40 I/506, 24; 18/673,40684, 29; 766, 25 . •• 89 l/540, 8; 40 l/257, 22. 94 OTTO HERMANN PESCH out God's will with that generous devotion that his outward behavior might appear to indicate-in effect he fulfills the Law only "slavishly" (serviliter); he lacks "affectus" and "sponta.nea voluntas." 29 A final issue is that man seeks to fulfill the Law without faith. But this is directly counter to the Law's intent: the first commandment of the Decalogue, to have no strange gods besides God, demands that we let God alone be God, which is to say, to acknowledge God as all-powerful Creator and allgenerous Love. 30 If one does so, he can no longer will to stand before God other than through God's love and grace. This attitude is one of the central contents of the concept "Faith." To wish to be just before God through following the Law, and indeed through following the Law servilely and not out of total devotion, is the very opposite of this: unbelief. Herewith we have the explanation of Luther's famous thesis that every sin is at root lack of faith and that lack of faith is the sin absolutely speaking. 31 Were man only to believe, he would then fulfill the Law out of gratitude and devotion to the praise of God's glory. But, since and because of Adam's fall, man rduses to believe and would rather fulfill the Law as master of himself, in order to be justified before God through his own personal achievement. 32 However, this must fail, since this was never within the intent or possibility of the Law. Thus in the Law man encounters despair and hatred towards the God who gave us such an over-demanding Law. 33 So the Law entangles 29 6/353, 15; 56/200, 13; 253, 25; 255, 4; 274, 11; 289, 15; 242, 33; 249, 9; 1/227, 26; 376, 26; 376, 26; 2/587, 27; 7/335,6. 30 40 I/399, 18; 419, 13; 39 I/428, 14; 531, 2; 581, 9; 5/395, 6; 40 III, 343, 4. In addition see the exposition by P. Althaus (based on an earlier investigation which Die 1'heologie Martin Luthers (Glitersloh, '1963), pp. still remains important): 119-127, 230-232. 31 Besides the texts cited in n. 20, cf. those analysized in Pesch, 1'heologie der Rechtfertigung, pp. 85-88. •• 40 II/393, 25; 404, 26. •• 39 I/557-559; 2/527, 35; 5/210, 1; 557 sqq.; 10 I, 453, 2; 464, 2. Since man will never be free of this relationship to God and his Law, this is the point of departure for Luther's theory of lingering sin and ultimately for his formula " simul justus et peccator." Cf. Pesch, op. cit., pp. 78-85; 109-122. LAW AND GoSPEL 95 man even more deeply in sin; it works "anger," as Luther following Paul expresses it; it" kills." 34 The Law opens up no possibility of a way to God, it simply brings to consciousness the possibilities already forever closed off; it not only makes clear to a man his own actual sins, it also reveals to him the self-righteousness lying beneath his outward obedience. This means his irremovable, radical sinfulness, in that he thereby sees that he thus constantly violates the commandment of faith. Man not only commits sins, he is through and through a smner. Without gainsaying here the broader problematic of which Luther himself is quite conscious, 35 it must be emphasized that God so wills it. 36 The Law itself, in its literal meaning, does not so will it. The Law wills a generous fulfillment of itself. But God wills with his Law, rebus sic stantibus, to drive men into despair. He wills that man's self-assertiveness should come to grief upon the Law, even at the price of letting man sink deeper into sin. To be sure, he does not will this despair, this sinfulness for its own sake. The Law and its death-dealing effect are, as Luther likes to put it, God's" opus alienum "-his "fremdes Werk." God engages in this for the sake of his "own work by right," his " opus proprium." 37 This latter is the Gospel, as we are now to show. Let us first, however, pause for a moment and cast a glance at the results we tentatively expect to arrive at in our pursuit of this question. The Law, considered as a code of detailed prescription, IS H 39 l/557, 18; cf. 347, 29; 363, 19; 412, 2; 477, 1. •• Here we should seek further information from Luther's teaching on God: if God's Law drives us into sin, is not God then responsible for sin? Also of special importance here is the work "De servo arbitrio." Cf. Pesch, op. cit., pp. 106-109, 377-382. 86 The controversies raised by Karl Barth's little book, Gesetz und Evangelium (Munich, 2 1956), have plunged Luther scholarship these last three decades into a discussion with implications both for the history of theology and for systematic theology. Cf. Pesch, op. cit., pp. 46-51. The most important contributions to this discussion have been brought together in Gesetz und Evangelium: Beitriige zur gegenwiirtigen theologischen Diskussion, ed., E. Kinder and K. Haendler (Darmstadt, 1968) . •• 1/112, 24; 356, 39; 5/503, 26; 7/531, 30; 9/101,37. 96 O'l'TO HERMANN PESCit important for Luther in that man learns thereby just how far he falls short of the mark. Luther, indeed, in his sermon on the Judgment and in the light of Biblical texts concerning the Last Judgment, speaks quite concretely about the detailed prescriptions of God. 38 At the same time, however, the detailed prescriptions of the Law are far less important for Luther than they would be for a moral theology in the traditional sense. For, as God's "opus alienum," the Law is assuredly not supposed to indicate how we should act or answer questions about the proper behavior of Christians but rather nothing other than to reveal the fundamental sin of self-righteousness and lack of faith. It is supposed not only to make us aware of actual sins but rather, through this, to lay open the " wicked heart," the root and source of all wicked deeds. In reference to our problem this means: upon an understanding of the Law there arises, for Luther, not a moral theology problem of freedom and obligation in Christian behavior, of" freedom of conscience " and " formation of conscience " but rather-before all such questions-the theologico-anthropological problem, of a liberation of man's existence before God. The question put by Luther to the Law is not "What shall I do"? but "Who rescues one from the death-dealing word of the unfulfilled Law of God?" or, more briefly, "Who rescues one from the curse of the Law? " We are in no position here to pursue further the question, so far-reaching in its import, of Luther's justification in appealing to St. Paul for his theology of the Law. 39 One thing is sure: he did take quite seriously Pauline thoughts which, from the earliest times-out of understandable motives and interests 40had been, as it were, " domesticated " by the traditional 38 E. g., 7/207 sqq.; 6/231, 35; 242, 22. •• Cf. the work of Joest (n. 5 supra); also G. Ebeling, Wort und Glaube (Tiibingen, 1962), pp. 263-277; P. Blaser, "Gesetz und Evangelium," Catholica 14 (1960) 1-23; 7-20; on a more general level cf. B. Lohse, Lutherdeutung heute (Gottingen, 1968), pp. 19-32. •• With the Epistle to the Galatians alone it would be impossible to build up any !IOrt of orderly Church life! LAW AND GOSPEL 97 exegesis.41 On the other hand, we have an important distinction to make: the" Law" to which the Apostle ascribes the aforesaid effects represents for Paul an historical quantity, an epoch, in a word, the constitution of the Chosen People. Now that the time of grace and the Spirit has dawned, this epoch has been brought to an end and left behind. " Lawful " behavior marks a regression to this bygone age. The time of the " pedagogue" (Gal. 3: 25) is past, the Christian is the adult grown to full maturity. For Luther, on the contrary, the Law is, to use modern terminology, an existential. It qualifies human existence in an absolute way-the Law, the Decalogue is indeed written in man's heart. It is overcome not, as for Paul, once and for all, but anew each day, through belief in the Gospel. From here we can trace a direct path to Luther's much misunderstood formula: simul justus et peccator, which Paul in any case did not know in this Lutheran formulation. 42 In the two we see a shift in the historical situation of the Church. Paul's Church is a missionary church: adult baptism is quite naturally experienced as the great turning point and continuing sinfulness as the carry-over from a bygone age. Paul need only say to his Christians: "Become what you are!" But Luther's Church is a "Volkskirche," an established national church based on infant baptism; in place of that great turning point is the experience of continual sin, of a heart as rebellious as ever before. The accusatory function of the Law now accompanies the Christian throughout his whole life, and Luther must say to him: "Become each day anew that which you are not (until you die)"! Exegetically Luther has not been true to Paul: he has stretched the Apostle's text. But his interpretation of Paul is nonetheless a piece of authentic history " Thomas moves in a broad stream of exegetical tradition when in the Summa Theologiae, in reference to Rom. 5: 20, he explains that the " killing " of the Law takes place not " effective " but " occasionaliter," and that the " ut " of " ut abundaret peccatum" is to be understood consecutively, not finally; see I-11, q. 98, a. 1, ad 2; 99, a. !l, ad 3. On the difference with Luther, see Pesch, op. cit .. pp, 431-432, 459-460. •• Cf. Joest, 2., "Paulus und das Luthersche simul justus et peccator" in Kerygma uml Dogma 1 (1955), pp. 269-320. 98 OTTO of the faith, just as the "domestication" of Paul's statements in Tradition is in its turn exegeticaUy false but still an interpretation of Scripture in reference to some concrete reality of the Church's existence. 3. The Gospel as Deliverance. Who overcomes for man the curse of the Law? The answer is not straight-away " the Gospel " but rather " Christ." Every attempt (and incidentally, this represents a whole school of thought) to explain this overcoming of the Law apart from the central role of Christ may indeed have its good reasons and be perfectly intelligible in the light of its own historical context, but it cannot stand as an historically faithful interpretation of Luther. Here as elsewhere, Luther's theology is, in contradiction to current conceptions, decidedly Christocentric. 43 Christ is the only man to have fulfilled the Law whole and entire with all the generous devotion due to God. 44 He has thereby satisfied God in a twofold sense: he has made recompense before God for all man's defections; and also, by that very fact, he has delivered man from the excessive burden of bringing about his own justification before God by a personal fulfillment of the Law. 45 Of man it is now demanded only that he believe in Christ, the fulfiller of the Law; or more exactly, to believe in God who, through Christ, himself the one just man by his fulfillment of the Law, delivers us from the curse of the Law and ascribes Christ's justice to those who believe in him. 46 The proclamation of this is the Gospel, and one will seldom find in Luther a definition of the Gospel in which •• In the footsteps of the great Lutheran theologian and church historian, Karl Holl (and his " school "), the Catholic discussion with Luther likes to regard his thoughts on the "unique effectiveness of God" as the way to approach .Luther's theology. In opposition to this, the Evangelical theologians (chiefly German), whose Luther scholarship has been influenced by Karl Barth, stress the Christocentric starting point of Luther's thought, whether from the historical or from the objective-systematic viewpoint. u 56/260, 18; 2/466, 14; 497, 28; 523, 15; 10 I 1/74, 7; 17 II/240, 24; 291, 19; 31 I, 317, 7. •• 1/505, 24; 2/479,28/490, 32; 492, 17/563, 35; 39 I/357, 19. •• In addition to the texts cited in n. 45: 24/4,11/5/169, 14. LAW AND GOSPEL 99 Christ's name does not appear. 47 As a message of peace, forgiveness of sin, and grace, the Gospel frees us from the accusation, the despair, the death, into which the Law plunges man. " The Law says ' Do, what you are supposed to do! ' The Gospel says, ' Your sins are forgiven you! " 48 " The Gospel is in its essential definition the promise of Christ, who frees us from the terrors of the Law, from sin and death, and brings grace, forgiveness of sin, justice and eternal life." 49 The Law is thus for one who believes and hears the message of God's working in Christ divested of its authority: God rescues the sinner " contra legem." 5 ° For the sake of Christ, the just and sinless one, the salvation of man no longer depends on whether or not the man himself has fulfilled the prescription of the Law. Shall this be taken to mean that God's imperative "Thou shalt" is no longer meant to be taken seriously? It is meant seriously and remains so at all times, and this with all the embarrassment, not for its own sake but for the sake of Christ. As long as man has not come to doubt the possibility of becoming just before God on the basis of his own power, he cannot understand what God has done in Christ. He must therefore live out his entire life under the Law in this ineradicable quest for self-justification, even to the bitterly confused end. Only then can God's saving love fully open up to him in the Gospel, in that same moment in which the Law is overcome and God's honor as all-generous love is reestablished, in that man finally does what he had refused God from the beginning. Passively, in the "posture of pure reception " (Paul Althaus) , he lets himself receive through Christ the gift of grace and justice as the ground of his life. "So long, Christ says, must the Law terrorize and disturb your conscience, until John comes and points out the Lamb, who takes away the sins of the world. Once I learn this and accept this, then must I bid a long farewell to all these Laws that accuse and condemn me, yea, even "2/500, 11; 39 I/478, !W; 479,4 (cf. infra, nn. 53, 54) . •• 2/466,6. •• 89 I/887, 2. •• 89 I/!!19, 21. 100 OTTO HERMANN PESCH to the Decalogue." 51 Even to the Decalogue? Yes, in all seriousness even to the Decalogue: 52 " For to one justified, the Law ought not to be exposed and preached as something to fulfil but (it is to be preached to them) as fulfilled, for the justified already have in Christ what the Law demands of them." 53 " Thus the demands and accusations of the Law fade before the pious, for what shall it still demand when Christ is already there .... " 54 How seriously all this is meant is illustrated by Luther's bitter polemic against the description of Christ as " legislator," and therewith against an understanding of the Gospel as " nova lex," even if it be a " lex caritatis." Under no conditions is Christ a new Moses; he is not a "legislator," but rather a " propitiator " and a " salvator." 55 "Where Christ is, there shall Moses the old peasant give way." 56 Or as Luther puts it, short and to the point: "Lex est negatio Christi." 57 This is a point especially emphasized by Protestant Luther scholars: " Where Christ becomes a ' legislator ' and the Gospel a ' nova lex' a ... weakening is brought about: the tremendous ' But now! ' of the Gospel is reduced to a shadow of what it was and is thus robbed of its explosive force over against man's ' cramp ' of self-assertiveness." 58 To do justice, we must note here that, even as they continue Luther's own emphasis on this point, contemporary scholars have come to show more reserve in arraigning before Luther certain prominent theologians of the Catholic tradition. Recent Catholic works 59 have alerted Protestant scholars, and Luther39 1/455, 3. It is not as though only the ceremonial precepts of the Old Law had been brought to an end with the Gospel, but so also has been the Decalogue: 2/468, 32; 492, 5; 18/764, 35; 40 1/229, 34 . .. 39 1/478,20 . .. 39 1/479, 4. 6 " 40 1/232, 29; cf. 298, 13; 2/494, 9; 8/70, 20; 40 1/114, 13-20. 68 40 1/262, 9; cf. 259, 26; 56/339, 3. 67 40 11/18, 4. " 8 Joest, Geaetz, und Freiheit (cf. supra, n. 5), p. 28 sq. •• Above all, the works of G. SOhngen, Geaetz und Evangelium (Munich, 1957); "Gesetz und Evangelium," Catholica 14 (1960), 81-105; F. BOckle, Geaetz und 61 69 LAW AND GOSPEL 101 an research itself has shown, for instance, that St. Thomas's teaching on the " nova lex Evangelii " has nothing in common with what Luther is out to attack. 60 I£ for Thomas the "nova lex " is identical with the grace of the Holy Spirit won for us by Christ, if this grace comes not through works but through faith and the Sacraments, if everything other than this grace which is identified with the New Law has at most a preparatory or manifestative function, never a meritorious efficacy, with respect to grace, if all good actions stem from the inner " ought " ("lex indita "!) of the freedom of the children of God, then all that Luther seeks has been objectively realized. At most, one may quibble about the opportuneness of using the word " lex " in this context. 61 The same is true of " Christus legislator ": for Thomas, Christ is a " legislator" only in the measure that the New Law is a "lex." This means: he is a " legislator " chiefly in that he bestows on us the grace of the Holy Spirit and institutes the Sacraments, and only secondarily in that he preaches the Sermon on the Mount. Thus, the novelty in Luther is not the substance of his doctrine: what Tradition held important, Luther also holds important. The novelty is a certain crisis over the concept " lex," and a polemic arising out of this, in which Luther felt constrained to defend himself against something which Tradition as such had never taught. As we bring this section to a close, let us once more focus clearly on what we are aiming at in this discussion. I£ it be true that the above understanding of the Law in no way gives rise to the moral theologian's problem of freedom and obligaGewissen: Grundfragen theologischer Ethik in okumenischer Sicht (Luzern-Stuttgart, 1965). 60 At this point, a reference is in order to the praiseworthy achievement of U. Kiihn, Via caritatis: Theologie des Gesetzes bei Thomas von Aquin (Berlin, 1964/ Gottingen, 1965). See my review, "Thomas von Aquin in Licht evangelischer Fragen: Zu drei neuen Thomas-Monographien," Catholica QO (1966), 54-78. 65-72, 76-78. 61 If Thomas does so, this is obviously because he places more emphasis on the continuity between Old and New Covenant than does Luther, whose thought is based entirely on Saint Paul. 102 OTTO HERMANN PESCH tion, since Luther understands the Law as a radical accusation of human existence before God, it is equally impossible that the problem should arise from his understanding of the Gospel, since the Gospel abolishes every Law. The Gospel is no" nova lex " over against which some freedom might be set and then discussed in terms of its limits. On the contrary, the Gospel is itself freedom, because it is a deliverance of man from his guilt and fallenness before God. The sum-total of our considerations thus far, then, can only read: the formula " Law and Gospel " has, in its immediate meaning and in its theological function, no bearing whatever on the moral theologian's problem of freedom and obligation, of conscience and the decay of moral norms. 4. Luther on Christian Ethics. Only at first sight is this result disappointing. For it goes without saying that, for Luther, the justified sinner, the Christian in other words, does have ethical duties. 62 Luther cannot block out this question or put it in parentheses or even give it only limited attention. The contrary is assured not only by the New Testament itself, to which after all he appeals for his understanding of Law and Gospel, but also by his controversy with the old Church. For, as already mentioned, the latter had not hesitated at an early moment to accuse him of endangering moral-ethical effort. If, however, Luther holds so inexorably to his affirmation that the Gospel brings about freedom from the Law and that this is the key to an understanding of the entire Christian message, then this must surely have consequences for the foundations of Christian ethics and the guidance of Christian action. Definite foundations, definite modalities are in any case excluded in the light of this distinction between Law and Gospel. As for Luther's manner of arriving at a determination •• Lutheran theology treats this problem under the heading " Justification and Sanctification," a terminology admittedly found in Luther's own writings but never in a technical sense, and for that matter not always in the same sense. See Pesch, 'fheolopie der p. 287 sq. LAW AND GOSPEL 108 of norms for Christian action, without reversing the overcoming of the Law by the Gospel, we must bring to light what the formula "Law and Gospel " does have to say about norms and freedom of conscience. What norm is Christian behavior to follow? Lutheran theology after Luther's time, following Melanchthon, developed in this connection the formula " tertius usus legis." 63 This is intended to mean: God's Law, like any human law, has as its first function to repress sin in the outward dimension of life, to keep order in the life of society, to provide for the upbringing of the young, to secure freedom, to protect the preaching of the Gospel. This is the so-called " primus usus legis," also called " usus politicus," " usus civilis." 64 Following this we have the " secundus usus legis " through which all that we have spoken of above is effected: manifestation and multiplication of sins (thus it is called "usus elenchtius "; a negative preparation for justification (thus "usus theologicus," "usus sanctus," " usus salutaris ") and an education unto Christ (thus, "usus paedagogicus "). But what of now? Have the prescriptions of the Law no further meaning for the justified " after " 65 the " usus elenchticus " has done its work? Quite obviously they do! ea And to explain this, first Melanchthon and then Lutheran theology of the post-Luther period (including the Lutheran creedal statements themselves) developed the theory of "tertius usus legis." Meant here is a function of the Law whereby it does teach man what the will of God demands but no longer terrorizes, menaces, and " kills." For man, insofar as he believes, no longer follows the Law " serviliter," as do the self-righteous, but rather out of joyful and •• See Ebeling, Wort und Glaube (cf. n. 39 supra), pp. 50-68. ••" Usus " is difficult to translate (i. e., into German); perhaps the best possible would be " Funktion," itself a borrowed word. •• This "after" (German "nach ") is surely meant here in an altogether peculiar sense; because of continual sin (cf. supra, n. 39) man never experiences until his death a time " after " the " usus elenchticus legis." •• After elimination of all that is time-conditioned in the Law and which was valid only for the political existence of the Chosen People. See the relevant text 39 I/540, 8; and on this, Ebeling, op. cit., p. 228. 104 OTTO HERMANN PESCH thankful devotion to God. The doctrine of the " tertius usus legis " appears therefore to hold together in happy fashion not only the distinction, indeed the break, between the state of sin and that of justification but also the continuity of the one will of God, ever remaining the same. At the same time the basis of Christian ethics is explained: an obligation to the will of God as promulgated in the Law out of the free devotion of faith springing from the heart itself, this is the source and the essence of Christian behavior. Luther himself is unfamiliar with the terminological formulation "tertius usus legis." He knows only (and this in a thoroughly untechnical sense) the formula "duplex usus legis." 67 Thus our research is faced with the question: did he know the reality expressed by this "tertius usus legis"? A whole string of statements from Luther argues that he did. Christ does not do away with the Law but builds it up in the proper way, by his new interpretation of it; 68 by the same token the Law is interiorized for the believer; he seals "friendship" with the Law. 69 Luther emphasizes the permanent significance of the Biblical admonitions as directives for Christian life. 70 These observations have led a considerable number of scholars to the conclusion that the objective reality corresponding to the "tertius usus legis" was upheld by Luther. An even larger number, however, are of the very opposite opm10n: with this theory of the " tertius usus legis " the whole point of Luther's understanding not only of the Law but also (and notably) of the Christian condition would be obfuscated. 71 And this for two reasons. The first, on terminological grounds. "Law" according to the tenor of Luther's expositions is that which exercises against men this function of See Ebeling's study mentioned in n. 63 supra. 39 I/387, 5; 2/580, 7-23. 69 4/467, 7; 5/562, 31. 70 6/207, 26; 18/693, 1; 39 I/542, 16. n Cf. Lutheran positions on one side or the other collected in Pesch, op. cit., p. 73 sq. Understandably, Catholic theologians are inclined to speak out in favor of the " tertius usus legis." 67 68 LAW AND GOSPEL 105 accusation and death: for Luther, the Law is defined precisely in terms of this function. A Law that does not accuse is not a law, however much its content may happen to correspond with that of the Law which accuses. Thus the later formulation marks a departure from Luther's own way of using words. But this-and this is the second, reality-oriented reason-is more than just an argument about words! Whoever seeks to regulate the life of the Christian through the " tertius usus legis " forces him, no matter how much generous devotion of will might be involved, to look back once again to the letter of Holy Scripture to discover what he is supposed to do. It seems indeed to be no coincidence that, in reference to the Christian, Luther no longer speaks of Law but only of " admonition" (exhortatio) and" commandment" (mandatum), and indeed explains quite explicitly that this is to indicate a "weakening" of the Law for Christians. 72 Luther ought to have thoroughly dispelled all doubt, when alongside his disquisitions on the permanent positive meaning of the Biblical directives we can find his incisive remark that Christians would make for themselves " new Decalogues " even better than that of Moses. Paul himself had gone far along this very road with his long lists of virtues/ 3 Quite plainly, Luther will stick to the end by his conviction: the Gospel brings freedom, and the Law can place no man, for whom Christ has interceded before God, under any condition whatever for salvation, save that of faith. Not only must the form of Law, the "exactio," give way to freedom, the content of the Law, too, must be subordinated to this freedom, no matter what restrictions must still be made in view of unintelligent, simple men who as such will always need leadership. The " tertius usus legis" is chiefly for these objective reasons un-Lutheran. So then, where does this leave us? Are there no more norms for moral action? Licence all down along the line, even to the notorious " pecca iortiter, sed fide fortius? " 74 How does Luther approach the foundation-laying of a Christian ethics? •• 39 I/474, 8-475, 6; cf. 78 39 I/47, . ... WA, Letters, 3; 513, 8. 106 OTTO HERMANN PESCH 1. First of all, we should note that Luther, in opposition to Tradition, sees the basic and complete Christian act not in " caritas " but in faith. If I compare the contents of the two concepts, their difference falls away almost to nothing. Everything that Tradition brings together under the concept of "caritas "-the grace-filled yet spontaneous self-giving of the soul to God for his own sake which ties together and directs all the other aspects of our relationship with God such as trust, hope, fear, assent and the like--all these Luther subsumes under the concept of faith. For him, "caritas " is above all love of neighbor, not love of God. Conversely, that which Tradition conceptually understands by "faith "-the assent of the reason (assensus) to the revealed word of God-is only one element in Luther's complex concept of faith to which, if considered all alone by itself, Luther himself never did and never would ascribe the justification of the sinner. The greater part of the polemic on both sides over the matter is built on mere terminological misunderstanding. 75 And yet there does remain something that cannot be brought together, something hard really to put one's finger on, since it transcends the theoretical domain and belongs to the level of one's personal relationship with God, one's spirituality. Anyone who uses the word " caritas " in the traditional sense does not think at once of his sins, but he does think quite readily of duties: not without significance the question of the " ordo caritatis" comes to the surface immediately. 76 Anyone who speaks o:f "faith" in Luther's sense thinks right away of his sins, faith places him under God's forgiveness and releases him from the oppression of the Law. "Faith" therefore excludes this immediate thought of duties. To put it another way, •• Here we can give only a general reference to the exhaustive presentation of this problem in Pesch, op. cit., pp. 735-747. See also the important articles by J. Lortz, " Luthers ROmerbriefvorlesung: Grundanliegen," Trierer Theologische Zeitsckrift 71 129-153, 216-247, and P. Manns, "Fides absoluta-fides incarnata: Zur Rechfertigungslehre in Luthers grossem Gala.terkomentar," in R&formata Reformarula: Festschrift fiir H. Jedin (Miinster, 1965), v. 1, 265-3U, •• Cf. St. Thoma.s, Summa Tkeologiae, II-II, q. 26. LAW AND GOSPEL 107 "faith" as the fundamental Christian act in Luther's sense implies primarily, in the light of his distinction between Law and Gospel, man's total passivity, his "death" so far as his "will to achieve " is concerned, the absolute gift-character of salvation, from which nothing can be taken away by any " partnership-like" contribution on man's part. The reverse side of this is a conclusion directly relevant for ethics: radical freedom. Where God has made man's salvation entirely his own affair, man's own action is no longer in any way bound up as a condition with salvation; no particular behavior is any longer an objectively necessary precondition for receiving salvation. Faith and the " freedom " of a Christian are correlative. If one asks in a precise sense what the Christian must do to attain salvation, the answer is equally precise terms can only be: nothing. 77 He receives it as a gift, literally for nothing. Should he want to do something toward it, this would mean a denial of faith. Thus the fundamental premise of Christian ethics, for Luther, will be: man has no ethical duties whatsoever in relation to his attainment of God's justifying grace. Put more briefly: Towards God (" erga Deum ") there is no ethics. 2. So what then, no duties and norms? Naturally, of course, there are, but in relation to God only insofar as such duties are nothing more than the reverse side of faith. Luther knows and admits only one such duty: the struggle against sin, or in a word, penance. 78 A faith, which did not take up an active struggle against self-seeking, mediocrity, and pride would deny in life what it affirmed in faith-that sin is against God and that God's judgment of the sinner is a just one. The struggle against sin, together with the genuine if always fragmentary advance of real justice, is so important for Luther that he can declare 77 " Novitas nostxa est quidem necessaria, sed non ad salutem, non ad justificationem nostxam. Ad salutem seu justificationem nostram necessaria est sola 8). misericordia Dei, quae apprehenditur fide." (89 •• For more detailed treatment see Pesch, op. cit., pp. 288-295, where further references are given to the literature on this question. 108 OTTO HERMANN PESCH quite unambiguously that without this struggle-progress faith and the Gospel are in vain. 79 Thus penance and the struggle against sin are also of ethical significance, for they stand in service of that very freedom which is the gift of faith. For this reason, continued sin is the enemy of freedom, for the quintessence of sin always remains rooted in man's seeking to justify himself, through which he brings himself anew under the oppressive weight of the Law. Every inch of ground conquered from the sway of sin increases freedom, which God at once gives to man and demands of him. Paradoxically expressed: because no ethic holds before God, Christians have the ethical duty of fighting against sin, because sin ultimately consists in the desire to be justified before God by one's own ethical achievement. 3. But where does man go from here with this God-granted freedom? Naturally he becomes involved in works and deeds, and he should do so. Are there still no norms for this? Do not ethical demands somehow hold at this stage of the game? When Luther pronounces himself on " Faith and Works " his first concern, in the light of his polemical situation, is to emphasize that faith does not derive its power to justify from any works that may accompany or follow it. " When faith is not lacking in every (sort of) work, even the slightest, it does not justify, indeed it is not even faith in this case." 80 This statement from his theses of 1520 characterizes the constant accent in all his pronouncements on the theme. But the thesis we have cited reads on: "It is, however, impossible for faith to exist without zealous, numerous and great works." After the epoch of polemical line-drawing, which served to sharpen Luther's own position and make it one-sided, contemporary Luther scholarship sees clearly that, without any desertion of the "sola fide," works, i.e., ethical behavior, take on an essential place in Luther's understanding of what it means to be a Christian. And so one might arrive at the .. 80 7. LAW AND GOSPEL 109 formulation that Luther's formula should not read "sola fide " but, to be true to reality, it should read: " sola fide numquam sola." 81 But how does the relation between this faith free of works and the works necessarily bound up with it shape up? If we try to summarize in thesis form the essential viewpoints emphasized by Luther, we must eventually come up with some such thing as the following: Faith is the ground of works and is related to them as the tree to its fruits, that is, faith makes the works good, but good works do not give faith its salvific power. 82 They are necessary, therefore, not as a condition of salvation but as an expression and evidence of salvation. 83 As such they are the life-form of faith: it exercises and indeed "incarnates" itself in them. 84 Luther can express this in the optimistic words: faith hardly stops first to ask if good works are to be performed; before even asking, it is already involved in doing them. 85 Conversely, Luther draws the conclusion from all of this that, where no good works are in evidence, one may be sure that no salvific faith is present. 86 At times Luther can explain in the most beautiful traditional manner that Christian life consists in faith and works. 87 With this we have succeeded in laying a foundation for Christian ethics, though a concrete ethics itself is yet to be worked out. Faith makes our works good before God: they are no longer the fruit of the sin which still dwells in us. But faith of itself does not spell out just which works we are to perform here and now. Who can determine this, if the Law can and ought no longer do this not even in the sense of a "tertius usus legis"? Luther's answer is: only he for whorn 81 This is the title of a little article by Althaus, Una Sancta 16 (1961), 227-235; it is also the tenor of his Theologie Luthers, pp. 213 sqq., and the works of W. Joest we have mentioned. 80 2/492, 21; 39 I/46, 28; 288, 9; 39 II/188, 37; 38/646, 20. 88 39 I/114, 28; 292,8; 47/789, 29; 10 III/225, 35. 8 •14/23, 17; 6/249, 7; 40 II/158, 1. Cf. Manns' article mentioned inn. 75 supra. 8 " WA, Deutsche Bibel, 7/11, 10. 8 "10 III/287, 20; 12/289, 29; 39 I/46, 20; 92, 17; 106, 24; 114, 24; 39 Il/248, 14. 81 U/289, 29; 10 I 2/88, 2; 17 I/98, II. 110 OTTO HERMANN PESCH the works are good and who needs them. That is by definition not God who freely bestows salvation and forgiveness without works, but only man, our neighbor. Luther distinguishes between "pious" (" formmen ") and "good" (" guten ") works. The "pious" work is one that one performs "for God's sake" (a pilgrimage, for instance). Such works fall under the total condemnation of " justification through works," insofar as they are undertaken in view of some special meritoriousness before God; and Luther is unaware of any "pious" work that is not undertaken for this motive. The " good " work, on the contrary, is that which is directed toward our neighbor and his welfare. " Have you ears to hear, and a heart that can attend, well, listen and learn for God's sake, what good works are and mean. A good work is called good, because it serves and benefits and helps the one toward whom it is directed." 88 " And we call good works, not those which we do for God but those we do for our neighbor, these are good works." 89 On this fundamental position Luther bases his critique of monasticism, 90 on the one hand, and his professional ethics (" Berufsethik "),on the other. 91 Good works in this sense are a simple exigency of our gratitude toward God in Christ: as God has done for sinners, so shall the redeemed sinner do for his neighbor; freely has he received, freely ought he to give. 92 In this way the Christian becomes another Christ. 93 In full accord with the " sola fide numquam sola," we find in Luther the paradox: " A Christian man is a free master of all things and subject to no one. A Christian man is a useful servant of all things and subject to everyone." 94 88 10 I 1?/39, 3. 10 III/98, 16. For a formulation which sums everything up beautifully: "Opera gratiae sunt necessaria, ut testentur de fide, ut glorificent Deum patrem, qui in coelis est, ut serviant proximo." (39 I/225, 3). 90 On this, see Pesch, "Luthers Kritik am Monchtum in katholischer Sicht," in Strukturen christlicher Existenz, ed. A. Pereira et al. (Wiirzburg, 1968), pp. 81-96. 91 See G. vVingren, Luthers Lehre vom Beruf (Munich, 1952). •• 7/36, 3; 37, 32; 6/516, 32; 10 I 2/168, 17 . 89 •• 7/35, 34; 66, 3; 11/513, 8; 15/504, 14 . •• 7/21, 1. LAW AND GOSPEL 5. Questions posed by Luther's Theology present-day Catholic .111oral Theology. 111 of Freedom for It would be impossible for us to discuss in full all the important questions that Luther's teaching on " Law and Gospel " poses for Catholic moral theology in our time. Let us at any rate close by at least intimating these questions. Luther's theology ordinarily considers this question under a presupposition not always appreciated in Lutheran circles: Luther's concrete ethical pronouncements are no more adequate for our day than are those of St. Thomas and St. Augustine. The "neighbor " whose need Luther made the measure of good works was the man of an agricultural or at best of a small town society, the society from which Luther himself came. The direction, to serve one's neighbor in your calling with the "tool" (" Handzeug ") that God gives you, is sufficient here. But even in Luther's day, it was insufficient to cover the social, political, and economic changes that were already underway all around him. 95 And they are surely insufficient for the problems of modern industrial society and the economic ethics such a society requires, or for the problems of our " one World," the atom bomb, the total manipulability of the world and even of man himself. It is not his concrete, detailed prescription 96 which raise questions for us but rather the underlying structure of his theological ethics. For the sake of clarity and to avoid any misunderstanding, I have intentionally formulated these questions in as brief and pointed a way as possible: 1. Is Catholic moral theology ready to admit that God has granted us salvation with no reference to works whatever, but unconditionally, for the sake of Christ? Is Catholic moral theology ready to admit that God wants, not our " pious " works but only our " good " works•• Cf. a recent presentation of this by R. Friedenthal, Luther: Sein Leben un