THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS oF THE PROVINCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington, D. C. VoL. XXXVII JULY, 1973 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL CONSIDERATIONS BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION T No.3 ON HE PROBLEM of biological evolution, as we understand it now, appeared in the 19th century as a consequence of scientific data totally unknown to philosophers and theologians before Darwin. It makes little sense, therefore, to search for this problem in the writings of St. Thomas. Sharing the opinion common to his time, he believed the universe to be no more than 6,000 years old. The ancient theologians did, however, discuss a type of evolution; that is, that the universe was created in six days. St. Augustine, for example, maintained that all six days were one since God created all things simultaneously: the inorganic in act, that is, in their present state; and the organic in potency, namely, in their quasi-seminal state. Plants and animals were implanted in the world "after the manner of seed (tamquam seminaliter mundo indita) by virtue of the Word of God when he created all things simultaneously, and from which all things, 417 418 ANTONIO MORENO each in its proper time, would be drawn in the course of the ages." 1 According to other saints the six days of Genesis denoted the order of time and succession in creation. There was an order not only of nature but also of time and duration in the work of the six days. This latter opinion held that various creatures were produced successively, whereas St. Augustine believed that all was created instantly. Whereas the latter interpretation emphasized the creative power of God through the passage of time, St. Augustine taught that God created the whole world instantaneously-if not entirely in act at least in potency. For St. Augustine, the world, bit by bit, was transformed into actuality. 2 It is most significant that St. Thomas simultaneously accepted both interpretations: The first explanation of these things, namely, that held by St. Augustine, is the more subtle and is a better defense of Scripture against the ridicule of unbelievers; but the second which is maintained by the other saints is easier to grasp and more in keeping with the surface meaning of the text. Seeing, however, that neither is in contradiction with the truth of faith and that the context 1 St. Augustine De Gen. ad litt. 6. 5, 8; ML 34, 342. Cf. ibid., 4, 33, 52; ML 34, 318: "God created all things simultaneously." Ibid., 5, 4, 11; ML 34, 325: " Therefore, it has been said that then the earth produced the herb and the plant in their causes, that they received the power to produce. For in it were already, as it were in their roots of times, those things that were to come about in future times ... " Ibid., 5, 5, 14; ML 34, 326: In reference to animals St. Augustine says: " ... all the swimming creatures and the flying creatures and these also potentially in numbers, which would come forth in their proper cycles in time. Similarly the animals of earth, as if the last from the last element of the world; nevertheless potentially, whose numbers time would manifest visibly." • St. Thomas, On the Power of God, q. 4, a. 2. Cf. ibid., ad 28: " ... the plants were brought forth then, not into actual existence but only in certain seed-forms, inasmuch as the earth enabled to produce them. . . . Hence the plants were not actually produced on the third day but only in their causes: and after the six days they were brought into actual existence in their respective species and natures by the work of government. Consequently, before the plants were produced causally nothing was produced, but they were produced together with the heaven and the earth. In like manner the fishes, birds, and animals were produced in those days causally and not actually. " CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 419 admits of either intepretation, in order that neither may be unduly favored, we now proceed to deal with the arguments of either side.3 A gradual appearance in time of the different genera and species was acceptable to St. Thomas, the concept of evolution was plausible. We must be cautious, however, not to color the process of St. Augustine's evolution with our modern views. Nevertheless, it is most interesting to explore the philosophical principles of St. Thomas in the light of modern scientific evolution. Evolution and Philosophy In St. Thomas there does exist the possibility of a science of evolution. A philosophy of evolution, however, is not easy to formulate since so complex and intricate a matter needs a whole philosophical system to account for it. Evolution is definable in general terms as a one-way, irreversible process in time, which during its course generates novelty, diversity and higher levels of organization. It operates in all sectors of the phenomenal universe, but has been fully described and analyzed in the biological sector.4 Evolution, first of all, is intimately connected with change and must depend on the process of generation and corruption at work in the cosmos. The Greek philosophers were the first to ascribe to motion or change the importance it deserves and to attribute to the whole cosmos the property of motion. Everything existing in nature moves and changes; new beings come into existence and in their turn disappear. This ever-recurring cycle of generation and corruption is also integral to evolution, yet biological evolution adds a specifically new dimension to the problem as conceived by the Greeks. The particular dilemma of biological evolution is this: Is the transformation of one species into another possible? And if this transformation is possible, what are the philosophical principles involved in this 3 Ibid., q. 4, a. 2 c. Cf.Summa Theologiae vol. 10, Cosmogony (Ia. 65-74), William A. Wallace, 0. P. (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967). • Evolution After Darwin (ed., by Sol Tax, Chicago, 1960) Vol. 8, p. 107. 420 ANTONIO MORENO transformation? In other words, since evolution presupposes the gradual transformation of one species into another, it poses three philosophical and scientific problems: (i) the nature of the species; (ii) the philosophical and scientific explanation of the transformation of one species into another; and (iii) the causes that produce this transformation. I. THE NATURE OF SPECIES Nature of Species in Philosophy In theory, the determination of the nature of species is relatively simple. In his Metaphysics Aristotle says that the order of species is analogous to the series of integral numbers: " Substance is a complete reality and a definite nature. And as a number does not admit of the more and the less, neither does substance, in the sense of forms, but if any substance does, it is only the substance which involves matter." 5 This criterion is obviously true in the case of the generic hierarchy of beings in which the higher being possesses a perfection which the inferior one lacks. For example, animals are endowed with the property of knowledge which is lacking in plants, and man possesses rationality which is not found in animals. For this reason Aristotle says that " it is certainly difficult to find a state intermediate between life and the absence of life." 6 This criterion per se, however, is sometimes difficult to apply to concrete cases. Aristotle himself admits in the History of Animals that "nature proceeds little by little from things lifeless to animal life in such a way that it is impossible to determine the exact line of demarcation, nor on which side thereof an intermediate form would lie." 7 In particular instances it is often difficult to pinpoint whether or not a living being is a plant or an animal, and primitive manifestations of life can barely be distinguished from inorganic objects. In • Aristotle, Met., VIII 3, 1044b9-13. Cf. St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I, q. 47. a. 3. 6 Aristotle, On Plants, 815b36. 7 Aristotle, History of Animals, VIII, CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 421 theory, however, the criterion is applicable, in spite of its concrete difficulties. The distinction of species in comparison to that of generic kingdoms is less clear-cut. The easy dichotomy of degrees of perfection which locate the different genera in the Porphyrian tree cannot be applied to various species. That classification may be useful in logic but not in natural philosophy. Here the criterion of " like numbers " cannot be interpreted as different degrees of essential perfections but rather as irreducible characteristics which cannot belong to other species. In Aristotelian philosophy each species is different from any other species because its substantial form is irreducible to any other substantial form. Since the substantial form gives the species its unique determination, there are as many species as there are substantial forms. The form itself is signified by the species; for everything is placed in its species by its form. Hence the number is said to give the species, for definitions signifying species are like numbers, according to the Philosopher; for as a unit added to, or taken from, a number changes its species, so a difference added to, or taken from a definition, changes its species .... 8 We shall see later how this criterion is applied to physics and biology. The individual, however, cannot be identified with the species because individuals do not result from the formal distinction of beings but rather from the material multiplication o£ any one species by means of the division o£ matter. One and the same species is shared by many individuals which are numerically different because o£ the division of matter. These individuals participate in the perfection o£ the species to a greater or lesser degree, although all o£ them participate in the same essential perfection: "When we have the whole, such and such a form in the flesh and in the bones, this is Callias or Socrates; and they are different in virtue of their matter (for this is different), but the same form; for their form is indivisible." 9 All men are 8 St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I, q. 5, a 5. • Aristotle, Met., VI, 8, 1088b22. ANTONIO MORENO men, and we cannot say that some are more " man " than others. Though some are more perfect than others, the degree of perfection depends upon the different individual dispositions of the matter to which the individual form is proportioned. That from which a thing receives its species must remain indivisible, fixed and constant in something indivisible ... And for this reason no substantial form is participated of more or less. Wherefore the Philosopher says that as a number cannot be more or less, so neither can that which is in the species of substance; that is, in respect to its participation in the specific form; but in so far as substance may be with matter; i. e., in respect to material dis10 positions, more or less are found in substance. Nature of Species in Biology In the light of scientific discoveries is species a necessary concept for evolution? Do species exist? The majority of biologists take for granted the usefulness of the term, since they refer to it continually and tell us that every species of living things usually has its own characteristic genetic code. The fundamental discrete steps in evolution are the " species " because they are independent evolutionary units. Thus, the existence of species is crucial and affects the whole idea of evolution. The evolutionary significance of species is now quite clear. . . . The species are the real units of evolution, as the temporary incarnation of harmonious, well-integrated gene-complexes. And speciation, the production of new gene-complexes capable of ecological shifts, is the method by which evolution advances. Without speciation there would be no diversification of the organic world, no adaptive radiation, and very little evolutionary progress. The species, then, is the keystone of evolution.U Naturalists such as Darwin, however, sometimes call natural species merely artificial devices. 10 St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I-II, q. 52, a. 1 c. Cf. ibid., I, q. 65, a. 7 ad 8: " The difference of form, which is due to the different disposition of matter, causes not a specific but only a numerical difference: for different individuals have different forms, diversified according to the difference of matter." 11 E. Mayr, Animal Species and Evolution, (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard, 1968), p. 621. CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 423 I look at the term species as one arbitrarily given, for the sake of convenience, to a set of individuals closely resembling each other, and ... it does not essentially differ from the term variety, which is given to less distinct and more fluctuating forms. The term variety, again, in comparison with mere individual differences, is also applied arbitrarily, for convenience's sakeP This is equivalent to the denial of their objective reality and would seriously jeopardize the whole concept of evolution since, then, the evolution would exist only in our mind. Consequently, " whoever, like Darwin, denies that species are non-arbitrarily defined units of nature not only evades the issue but fails to find and solve the most interesting problems of biology." 13 Dobzhansky observes that species is both an artificial and a natural reality by illustrating his reasoning with an example: Any two cats are individually distinguishable, and this is equally true of any two lions. And yet no individual has ever been seen about which there could be a doubt as to whether it belongs to the species of cats (Felis domestica) or to the species of lions (Felis leo) . The two species are discrete because of absence of intermediates. There, one may safely affirm that any cat is different from any lion. Any difficulty which may arise in defining the species Felis domestica and Felis leo, respectively, is due not to the fact that in common as well as in scientific parlance the words " cat " and "lion " frequently refer neither to individual animals nor to all existent individuals of these species, but to a certain modal, or average cat and lion. These modes and averages are statistical abstractions which have no existence apart from the mind of the observer. The species Felis domestica and Felis leo are evidently independent of any abstract modal point which we may contrive to make. No matter how great may be the difficulties encountered in finding the modal " cats " and " lions " the discreteness of these species is not thereby impaired. 14 Here Dobzhansky clearly points out the difference between the multiplicity of individuals within the species as well as the 12 Ch. Darwin, The Origin of Species (New York: Modern Library Giant G27, n. d.) p. 46. 13 E. Mayr, Animal Species and Evolution, p. 29. Cf. Th. Dobzhansky. Genetics and the Origin of Species (New York, 1951), p. 5: "It must be stressed that this discontinuity exists whether it is or is not used by the systematists for their purposes, and for that matter whether it is studied at all. " "Th. Dobzhansky, op. cit., pp. 4-11. ANTONIO MORENO distinguishability of the two. They are discrete, because of the absence of intermediates. Although he notes the difficulty entailed in the discovery of the true concept which corresponds to these species, he does not doubt their objective reality. If species do exist, then what is the nature of this important concept? Philosophers and biologists are usually looking for different things, but even among biologists the concept does not always mean the same thing. The first modem classification of living organisms is Linnaeus's Systema Naturae published in the mid-19th century which is classical in taxonomy. This essentialist conception of reality pleases the philosopher but has been rejected by many biologists. Mayr says that "more important for the development of the synthetic theory of evolution than the rejection of ill-founded theories of it was the rejection of two basic philosophical concepts that were formerly widespread i£ not universally held: preformism and typological thinking." 15 For the geneticist focusing on the science of heredity, the concept of species is naturally connected with the reproductive process. For Dobzhansky "evolution is change in the heredity, in the genetic endowment of succeeding generations. No understanding of evolution is possible except with the foundation o£ a knowledge of heredity." 16 For Mayr, Simpson, and Beck evolutionary taxonomy replaces the idea of an essence identical in each species, with the notion of a collection of physical characteristics inherited by all the members of the same group. Species is then defined as a " population of procreation " made up of individuals capable, at least in potency, of having common offspring. The totality of genes of all individuals of a species characterizes the species and inasmuch as they are 15 E. Mayr, Animal Species and Evolution, p. 4 Cf. John Deely "The Philosophical Dimension of the Origin of Species" The Thomist, Vol. 33, 1 and fl (Jan. and April 1969), pp. 75c149, 251-335. 16 Th. Dobzhansky, The Biological Basis of Human Freedom (New York, Columbia, 1956), pp. 10-11. Cf. Julian Huxley, Evolution in Action (New York, Mentor, 11)53), p. 35: "The discovery of the principle of natural selection made evolution_ comprehensible; together with the discovery of modern genetics, it has made all other explanations. of evolution untenable. " CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 425 communities of reproduction, the species are biological realities. " The species can thus be succinctly defined as follows: it is a community of individuals possessing common essential sets of genes, and actually or potentially related (proximally) through interbreeding." 17 In this sense species are dynamic realities undergoing continuous change in space and time. The frequency of genes varies from one population to another of the same species, giving rise to different races. Therefore, the criterion of community of procreation serves to identify the individuals of the same species and to distinguish different species from each other. The man and the gorilla belong to different species because they cannot have common offspring. Species are discrete and independent units of evolution. 18 The Greek concept of essences, of species, as something eternal and immutable is often misunderstood. Species are immutable and eternal in the sense that every species is characterized by a series of fixed and permanent traits that make every species what it is and not another. If a man is a man he will be a rational animal. If such an essential characteristic is not fulfilled, then that being is not a man but something else. The essence of beings are necessary, immutable, and eternal with an eternity which is called "negative "-in the sense that it is not limited to a particular place and time. Their existential realization, however, is temporal and contingent. In other words, the essential traits of species are immutable but not 17 E. Mayr, op. cit., pp. Cf. Th. Dobzhansky, op. cit., p. 5: "In organisms which reproduce sexually and by cross fertilization, the reality of species as biological units can also be demonstrated by a quite different method .... These communities consist of individuals united by the bonds of sexual unions, as well as of common descent and common parenthood .... A species is, consequently, not merely a group and a category of classification. It is also a supraindividual biological entity, which, in principle, can be arrived at regardless of the possession o£ common morphological characteristics. " 18 F. Ayala, "Evolucion, Tiempo y Filosofia" ARBOR, Madrid, 1967, n. pp. Cf. Th. Dobzhansky, Evolution, Genetics, and Man, p. 182: "It is, then, not a paradox to say that if some one should succeed in inventing a universally applicable, static definition of species, he would cast serious doubts on the validity of the theory of evolution. " ANTONIO MORENO their existential realization in nature, which inasmuch as they are individuals are generated and corrupted in time and space without affecting their essential traits. 19 Science conclusively states that species, like individuals, have a certain span of life and sooner or later disappear. Simpson gives a species 50,000 years for transmutation and says that the fossil record which manifests the history of life is involved in four grand processes: expansion, progression, equilibrium, and extinction. 20 Species often survive for a longer period of time, for " paleontologists have described many lines that remain unchanged, completely stabilized for IQO to 140 million years, and then suddenly broke out during a new evolutionary outburst. Just what can cause such loosening up of tightly knit systems is something I think we should work out, if we can." 21 The long-lasting constancy of biological species, which is realized by the identical replication of genes, is a primary law of evolution. Yet, although one form of natural selection tends to conserve the species as its primary goal, in the long run the species is corrupted and disappears either through extinction or transformation into another species. Extinction occurs when the species is unable to adapt to an adverse environment and it disappears, as individuals do. The data of science shows species to reflect the dual tendency in nature: the primary tendency to remain constant and the secondary tendency to change. St. Thomas says: Nothing prevents a thing being against nature as to the first intention of nature and yet not against nature as to its second intention. Thus, as stated in De Coelo, all corruption, defect, and old age are contrary to nature because nature intends being and perfection, and yet they are not contrary to the second intention of nature because nature, though being unable to preserve being in one thing, E. Mayr, Evolution After Darwin, Vol. III, p. 141. ff. Also in "Rates of •• G. Simpson, Evolution After Darwin, Vol. I, pp. Evolution in Animals " in Genetics, Paleontology and Evolution, Ed. by Jepsen, Mayr, and Simpson, (Princeton, New Jersey, 1949), p. 21 E. Mayr, op. cit., Vol. III, p. 141. 19 CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 427 preserves it in another which is engendered of the other's corruption .... 22 Now it is necessary to consider the idea of species as numbers in the light of modern scientific data and the dynamic concept of species. (i) In physics, the Aristotelian criterion for the distinction of species agrees completely with quantum theory and with Pauli's exclusion principle. The principle says that "the quantum numbers of two or more electrons can never entirely agree. Two systems of quantum numbers which are deducible from each other by interchange of two electrons, represent one state." 28 As a result of this principle every chemical being is characterized by different quantum numbers. It is absolutely impossible to find two different chemical compounds, two elements of the periodic table, or two elementary particles having the same quantum numbers, to which Aristotle would agree. (ii) In regard to living organisms, it also appears to be possible to classify all living organisms according to the structure and composition of their DNA and amount of chromosomes in a way similar to the classification of chemical elements according to quantum numbers. " Biologists now know that every species of living things has its own characteristic number of chromosomes. Man has 46, white rats 42, pea plants 14, etc." 24 This does not mean that any given number of chromosomes belongs to only one species, but to every biological species corresponds a unique structure and shape. Even more, geneticists are now reducing different species to different quantum numbers. If every species is unique and discrete, then the discreteness is like the discreteness of numbers, and biology, like physics, can in a sense be quantified. 25 This •• St. Thomas, Summa Theol., Suppl., q. a. 1 ad Cf. On Truth, q. c. •• M. Born, Atomic Physics, (New York, 1954), p. 173. Cf. Wolfgang Pauli, Exclusion Principle and Quantum Mechanics, (Neuchatel, Zurich, 1947). •• The Cell (New York: Life Science Library, 1964), p. 57. •• I owe this oral information to F. Ayala. 428 ANTONIO MORENO discreteness, however, should not be confused with the different degrees of perfection which correspond to different generic beings. As a lion and a cat are members of two irreducible species, so all species of living beings are irreducible to each other. II. THE PRocEss oF GENERATION AND CoRRuPTION General Ideas The evolution of one species into another must be intimately connected with the general process of generation and corruption of corporeal beings. The generation of the new being necessarily presupposes the corruption of the old. By way of simple analysis, it is easy to determine the existence of two incomplete principles which complement each other and constitute the essence of all corporeal beings. The first principle is passive and totally potential: prime matter; the second principle is active and determines the being to be what it is: substantial form. Naturally, it would be pointless here to delve into all the subtleties involved in the hylemorphic theory. With regard to evolution, however, we must emphasize one subtlety: that which is generated and corrupted is not the form as such but the concrete individual. " For as the brazen sphere comes to be, but not the sphere nor the brass, and so too in the case of the brass itself, it comes to be, it is its concrete unity that comes to be (for the matter and form must always exist before)." 26 Or in St. Thomas's words in his commentary on Aristotle: "For it is not a form that comes to be but the composite. For a form is said to exist in matter, although a form does not (properly) exist but the composite by its form." 27 Thus, the Aristotelian distinction between the species •• Aristotle, Met., VI, 9, 1084b10. Cf. ibid., 1088b17-20: "It is obvious, then, from what have been said, that that which is spoken of as a form or substanee is not produced, but the concrete thing which gets its name from this is produced, and that in everything which is generated matter is present, and one part of the thing is matter and the other form. " 27 St. Thomas, In Met., VII, lect. 7, n. 1428. Cf. ibid., n. 1422: "The of CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 4!!9 and the individual. That which is generated essentially, namely, the concrete individual, and that which comes into being accidentally, the form, is of primary importance in causality, as we will see later, and affects the whole theory of evolution. Prime matter in the abstract is indifferent to all substantial forms. In concrete cases, however, there must always exist a proportion between matter and form which is both specific and individual because there always ·exists a proportion between potency and act. No species can be generated unless matter is endowed with the disposition required for that species; and in like manner a form cannot inform concrete matter unless that form is proportioned to its individual conditions. 28 Insofar as evolution is concerned, this means that the required disposition of matter is an absolutely necessary condition for the eduction of new form and, consequently, of a new species. The more perfect a species, the better a disposition is required in the matter to which it corresponds. Corruption results from the lack of this disposition: " As the form is not educed unless matter is endowed with the right disposition, if the proper disposition no longer exists the form cannot inform that matter." 29 Changes Required in the Disposition of Matter to Generate New Species In the process of substantial generation the individual being which belongs to one species is corrupted and replaced by another individual being which belongs to another species, as a thing refers properly to its form. Hence individual conditions, which pertain to a form accidentally, are excluded from it. And species and other individuals are generated only accidentally, when singular things are generated." 28 Aristotle, Met. Vlll, 4, 1044a15; St. Thomas, II Contra Gentes, c. 81: " Thus, form and matter must always be mutually proportioned and, as it were, naturally adapted, because the proper act is produced in its proper matter. That is why matter and form must always agree with one another in re9pect to multiplicity and unity." Ibid., Vlll MetapkyB., lect. 4, n. 1780: "From the things which are said here then it is evident that there is one first matter for all generable and corruptible things, but different proper matters for different things. " •• St. Thomas, Quut. de Anima, q. 1, a. 9 ad 16. 430 ANTONIO MORENO occurs, for example, in chemical reactions. This disposition of the matter gradually becomes less proportioned to the existing form until the moment when the original being is corrupted and a new being is generated. This transformation takes place instantaneously, for there is no possibility of two forms simultaneously informing the same prime matter. In chemistry this process offers no difficulty; in biology, however, when one takes into account the experimental data, the problem is much more complex. According to many geneticists, the process of transformation of one species into another seems to be opposed to the hylemorphic theory, for the species changes so gradually it seems impossible to determine the instant the new species is generated. " The distinction of species is in a sense arbitary. The transition of morphological traits occurs more or less gradually and irregularly. It is impossible to establish a precise temporal level which may constitute the division between species. . . ." 30 Hence, for geneticists, any philosophical system which claims to be meaningful needs to integrate the creative dimension of time and the essential trait of change in reality, especially in organic reality. From the philosophical viewpoint, if by species we mean the " community of procreation," then the gradual transformation of one species into another offers no difficulty, for the philosopher considers the gradual transition of one species into another, e. g., of different species of cats, as accidental changes within one species. For the philosopher, the species of cat undergoes accidental transformation without thereby changing the species. Here, we face a semantic problem, for philosophers and geneticists do not share the same concept of species. This consideration, however, is one part of the problem, for experimental data seems to prove that the transformation of one species into another in the Aristotelian sense of the word takes place in nature, which requires a new substantial form. In this case it is difficult to explain how the change can occur at an instant, and not gradually, as geneticists contend. Charge of form •• F. Ayala, art. cit., p. 61. CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 481 must take place instantaneously: if the form F 2 of the new species replaces the form F1 of the corrupted one, there is not room for intermediate states. The riddle does not seem insurmountable, however, if we recall how generation and corruption occur. The disposition of matter changes gradually, without the loss of the first form, F1, until the precise instant when this form is corrupted and the new form, F2, is generated. Though we may be ignorant of the precise instant that it takes place, this could be a valid description of the transformation of species. Through mutation and natural selection, the disposition and the structure of the DNA gradually changes, until the instant when the new disposition and new structure corresponds to a new substantial form and, consequently, to a new species. Geneticists tell us that many mutations are required to produce new species. " One thing no single mutation has done is to produce a new species, genus, or family. This is because species and supraspecific categories differ always in many genes, and hence arise by the summation of many mutational steps." 31 Time and the Evolution of Species How does time influence the generation and corruption of individuals and species? It is evident that time favors the corruption of things: A thing, then, will be affected by time, just as we are accustomed to say that time wastes things away, and that all things grow old through time, and that there is oblivion owing to the lapse of time, but we do not say the same of getting to know or becoming young or fair. For time is by its nature the cause rather of decay, smce it is the number of change, and change removed what is.32 Since time is the measure of motion and motion is the cause of corruption of things, time does by its nature tend to corrupt things. St. Thomas notes that corruption can be ascribed to time and generation and existence to the agent which causes the generation. 33 It is also true, however, that time indirectly Th. Dobzhansky, Genetics and the Origin of Species, p. 81. •• Aristotle, Physics. IV, 12, 2lla28-84. •• St.Thomas, IV Phys., lect. 22, n. 621. 31 432 ANTONIO MORENO causes the generation of new being inasmuch as it favors the corruption of the previous one which is new life's necessary pre-condition. Time is also related to the second law of thermodynamics, the law of entropy. Entropy indicates a gradual diminution of the process of generation along the millennia, which eventually leads to the "heat death" of the universe. The law of entropy does not violate the principle of conservation of energy, but it indicates that the total energy gradually loses the possibility of being used. Consequently, the whole process of generation is gradually slowing down. Time and entropy could be said to operate in opposite directions, for time by its nature tends to favor corruption and entropy to slow down that process. Time cannot be a creative factor in evolution except indirectly, in the sense that it favors corruption, which is the prerequisite for generation. Schrodinger believed that the entropy of a living organism did not increase but decreased. It is obvious, however, that in the organic as well as in the inorganic world entropy increases in closed systems. It does not necessarily, and in fact it often does not, increase in every element of the system. Palacios demonstrated experimentally that, if an organism is placed in a closed system, the entropy of the system increases as the organism develops. Although the biological organism evolves over time-and needs a long time-time by its nature is only in an indirect way the cause of a new species. The positive element of biological evolution lies in the agent, which is the creative factor in producing a new species, not in time per se.84 Another philosophical problem regarding time presents itself. We are often told that the theory of relativity unifies time and space and that, consequently, time influences the categories of human thought. Such a view is misleading since the theory of relativity does not consider, as does philosophy, the ontological reality of time but merely its measure; and this not in direct relation to space, for time without motion does not exist: •• E. Schrodinger, "Heredity and Quantum Theory," in The World of Mathematics (New York, 1856), Vol. I, pp. 975-1001.; Julio Palacios, De la Fisica a la Biologia (Madrid, 1947). CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 433 " Hence, since motion in respect to place is motion from something in respect to magnitude, and since every magnitude is continuous, then it is necessary that motion is consequent upon magnitude and continuity. That is, since magnitude is continuous, motion is continuous. And, consequently, time is continuous. . . ." 35 In Aristotle, as well as in Newton, there exists a necessary connection between time and space, that is, the motion which takes place in that space. The theory of relativity, it is true, changes this relation somewhat, as Einstein himself observes: First, a remark concerning the relation of the theory to the " four dimensional space." It is a widespread error that the special theory of relativity is supposed to have, to a certain extent, first discovered, or .at any rate, newly introduced, the four dimensionality of the physical continuum. This, of course, is not the case. Classical mechanics, too, is based on the four dimensional continuum of space and time. But in the four dimensional continuum of classical physics the subspaces with constant time value have an absolute reality, independent of the choice of the reference system. Because of this (fact) the four dimensional continuum falls naturally into a three-dimensional and one-dimensional (time), so that the four dimensional point of view does not force itself upon one as necessary. The special theory of relativity, on the other hand, creates a formal dependence between the way in which the special coordinates on the one hand, and the temporal coordinates, on the other, have to enter into the natural laws. 36 It is the quantitative relation between space and time through motion that relativity has changed in physics as a consequence of the invariance of the velocity of light. The theory of relativity, however, does not essentially change the ontology of time as a category of thought. III. CAUSALITY Disposition of Matter After an analysis of the process of generation and corruption we must now investigate the causes of this phenomenon. •• St. Thomas, IV Physic., IV, Iect. 17, n. 576. 86 A. Einstein, Albert Einstein: 57-58. Philosopher Scientist (New York, 191i7), pp. 434 ANTONIO MORENO First of all, since matter and form are proportioned, the generation of any being requires the right disposition of matter as a necessary condition for its becoming. What kind of cause produces this disposition? This question offers no difficulty, for natural agents change the disposition of matter until that matter is no longer well disposed to the existing form. Accordingly, that being is corrupted and a new being simultaneously generated. These natural agents operate by transmuting matter, and this causality as with all corporeal agents is exercised by motion. Since local motion is the first motion, any transmutation of matter depends initially upon that motion, which is a way of saying that the right disposition of matter depends on its structure, the spatial disposition of its parts. Changes in this disposition affect the structure of the being and, accordingly, the nature of the being as such. 37 Is the disposition of matter merely a necessary condition, or is this disposition a necessary and sufficient condition for the eduction of the new form? Does the eduction of the new form necessarily follow the right disposition of matter? According to St. Thomas, such is the case. He holds the principle that the individual form depends upon the disposition of the individual matter, and the specific form upon the disposition of the specific matter. The disposition of matter, then, conditions the nature of the individual and specific form. Naturally, this disposition is not the direct cause of the generation of the new form, but since the new form must be in proportion to the matter, its disposition conditions the nature of that form. To a new disposition of matter automatically follows the education of the form which corresponds to that disposition. 87 St. Thomas. On the Power of God, q. 5, a. 1 ad 5: "Inasmuch as corporeal agents do not act except by transmuting, and as nothing is transmuted except by by reason of matter, the causality of corporeal agents cannot extend beyond things that in some way are in matter." Ibid., III Cont. Gent., c. "Nor can alteration be accomplished unless there be a preceding local change. . . ." CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 435 Causes of the Becoming of the Individual Being The causality which accounts for the generation of forms leads us to the heart of philosophical speculation. Plato was the first to realize the difficulties in the concept of forms existing in matter as something permanent and universal, since these forms as they exist in individuals are eventually corrupted. Hence, for Plato the generation of forms can only be explained by transcending the material realm. Consequently, he postulated the existence of Ideas, of separated forms, which were the cause of everything that is made. The natural agent merely disposes the matter, but the generation of forms demands a spiritual cause: the forms existing in matter are forms by participation, wherefore the physical world is merely receptive. Man (essentially) is the cause of the participation of" humanity " in man. Plato held that there exists an immaterial man, and an immaterial horse, and so forth, and that from such the individual sensible things that we see are constituted, insofar as in corporeal matter there abides the impression received from these separated forms, by a kind of assimilation, or as he called it, participation .... 38 For Aristotle, however, the starting point is nature which manifests the general property of mobility, and local motion as the first motion. The eduction of forms is also a natural process, for the artist makes or the father begets, a " such " of " this." And when it has been begotten, it is a " this such." And the whole, " this " Callias or Socrates, is analogous to " this brazen sphere," but man and animal to "brazen sphere" in general. Obviously, then, the cause which consists of the Forms (taken in the sense in which some maintain the existence of the Forms, i. e., if they are something apart from the individuals) is useless, at least with regard to coming to be and to substances .... 39 For St. Thomas, the realm of Ideas is not necessary for the explanation of generation of forms, because Plato sought a St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I, q. 65, a. 4. •• Aristotle, Met., VI, 8, 1088b22 ff. 38 436 ANTONIO MORENO cause of forms as though the forms were of themselves brought into being whereas what is made, properly speaking, is the composite: Such are the forms of corruptible things that at one time they exist and at another exist not, without being themselves generated and corrupted, but by reason of the generation and corruption of the composite, since ev.en forms have no being, but composites have being through them: for according to a thing's mode of being is the mode in which it is brought into being. Since, then, like is produced from like we must not look for the causes of corporeal forms in any immaterial form but in something that is composite. . . . Corporeal forms, therefore, are caused, not as emanation from some immaterial form but by matter being brought from potentiality into act by some composite agent. 40 For Aristotle and St. Thomas, the only subsisting being is not the form but the composite, the individual: Callias and Socrates are the individuals that come into being. And since individuals are material, there is no need for the realm of Ideas as the cause of these concrete individuals. The cause of the generation of individuals is another individual, although the individual is not the cause of the species: This individual man is the cause, properly speaking, of that individual man. Now, this man exists because human nature is present in this matter, which is the principle of individuation. So this man is not the cause of man, except in the sense that he is the cause of human form coming to be in this matter. This is the principle of an individual man. 41 Plato's error was to consider the forms as subsisting, whereas it is the composite which actually comeS! into being and subsists. •• St. Thomas, Summa Theol., loc. cit.; cf. ibid., q. 45, a. 8: "But his opinion arose from ignorance concerning form. For they failed to consider that the form of the natural body is not subsistent, but is that by which a thing is. And therefore, since to be made and to be created belong properly to a subsisting thing 'llone, ... it does not belong to forms to be made or to be created, but to concreated. What indeed is properly made by the natural agent is the composite, which is made from matter. " 41 St. Thomas, III Cont. Gent., c. 65 . . Cf. Summa Theol. I, q. 91, a. 2: "A form which is in matter can only be the cause of another form that is in matter, according as composite is made by composite. " CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 437 For St. Thomas, the corporeal agent is the cause not only of the disposition of matter, but also of the generation of the form. 42 The Causality which Corresponds to the Species The causality which corresponds to the process of generation appears to be solved by consideration of the causality which accounts for the disposition of matter and the eduction of form. The problem is deeper, however, because these causalities are responsible merely for the becoming of things, not their being. Motion is apart from the being of the thing. Now nothing corporeal, unless it be moved, is the cause of anything, for no body acts unless by motion as Aristotle proves. Therefore, no body is the cause of the being of anything, insofar as it is being, but it is the cause of its being moved towards being, that is, of the thing's becoming. 48 This is equivalent to saying that the agent is the cause of the generation of the individual but not of the species: No particular univocal agent can be the unqualified cause of its species; for instance, this individual man cannot be the cause of the human species, for he would then be the cause of every individual man, and, consequently, of himself-which is impossible. But this individual man is the cause, properly speaking, of that individual man. Now, this man exists because human nature is present in this matter, which is the principle of individuation. So this man is not the cause of a man except in the sense that he is the cause of a human form coming to be in this matter. This is the principle of generation of an individual man. So, it is apparent that neither this man, nor any other univocal agent in nature, is the cause of anything except the generation of this or that individual thing. 44 .. Ibid., On the Power of God, q. 5, a. I ad 5. •• Ibid., Ill Cont. Gent., c. 65. u Ibid., III, c. 65, Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 45, a. 5 ad 1: "A perfect thing participating any nature, makes a likeness to itself, not by absolutely producing that nature, but by applying it to something else. For an individual man cannot be the cause of human nature absolutely, because he would then be the cause of himself; but he is the cause of human nature being in the man begotten; and thus he presupposes in his action a determinate matter whereby he is an individual man ... " 488 ANTONIO MORENO Naturally, this is incomprehensible unless we admit the distinction between individuals and species. Aristotle summarizes the problem by saying that the same form is shared by many individuals, but the form remains the same. Although Callias and Socrates differ in their matter, they share the same form. 45 The form of a species by its nature is indivisible and immobile. Hence, the multiplication of the form by individuals is not a consequence of the division of the form but of the division of matter, which is divisible. The form is divisible only indirectly, accidentally (per accidens), inasmuch as the matter which informs is divisible. Hence, the distinctions between the becoming and the being, the individual and the species, motion and immobility, are grounded at the same point. This justifies the causality of becoming as different from that of being. St. Thomas illustrates this distinction by an analogy noting that with artificial beings the builder of the house is merely the cause of its becoming not its being. Its being, on the contrary, depends upon the brick, steel, stone, wood, etc., and not on the builder. And he continues: The same principle applies to natural things. For if an agent is not the cause of form as such, neither will it be directly the cause of being which results from that form: but it will be the cause of the effect, in its becoming only. Now it is clear that of two things in the same species one cannot directly cause the other's form as such, since it would then be the cause of its own form, which is essentially the same as the form of the others; but it can be the cause of this form for as much as it is in matter-in other words, it may be the cause that this matter receives this form. And this is the cause of the becoming, as when man begets man. 46 And in like manner, since the becoming depends on the being, the cause of becoming is subordinated to that of being, as an instrument to the higher cause. 47 •• Aristotle, Met., VI, 8, 1033b32. •• St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I, q. 104, a. 1. Cf. II Sent., d. 9, q. 2, a. 2 obj. 1!. 47 II Cont. Gent., c. 21: "Whatever is caused as regards some particular nature cannot be the first cause of that nature but only the second and instrumental cause; for example, since the human nature of Socrates has a cause, he cannot CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 439 We must ask now the nature of the cause of the form or species. The first efficient cause of the form transcends the causality of corporeal agents which operate exclusively by motion; and motion is apart from the being of the thing. Accordingly, the causality of the form requires a non-corporeal cause, which St. Thomas explains thus: The existence of a thing made depends on its efficient cause inasmuch as it depends on the form of the thing made. Now there can be an efficient cause on which the form of the thing made does not depend directly and considered as a form but only indirectly: thus the form of a generated dog depends on the generating dog directly and by reason of its species, and the form of dog is in the same way in both the generated and in the generating dog, and is distinguished therefrom only by a material distinction, though being seated in another matter. Hence, since the generated dog has its form from some cause, this same form must depend on some higher principle that is the cause of that form directly and in respect of its very species. Now, seeing that properly speaking the existence of a form in matter implies no movement or change except accidentally, and since no bodies act unless moved, as the Philosopher shows, it follows of necessity that the principle of which the form depends directly must be something incorporeal, for the effect depends on its active cause through the action of a principle. And if a corporeal principle be in some way the cause of a form, this is due to its acting by virtue of an incorporeal principle and as its instrument. . . . Now this incorporeal agent by whom all things are created is God from whom things derive not only their form but also their matter. And it makes no difference whether they were all made by him immediately, or in a certain order as certain philosophers have maintained. 48 In summary: (i) The material cause produces not only the disposition of matter as proportioned to the form but also the eduction of the new form; man generates man and dog be the first of human nature; if so, since his human nature is caused by someone, it would follow that he was the cause of himself, since he is what he is by virtue of human nature. Thus a univocal generator must have the status of an instrumental agent in respect of that which is the primary cause of the whole species. Accordingly, all lower efficient causes must be referred to higher ones, as instrumental to principle agents .... " •• On the Power of God, q. 5, a. lc. 440 ANTONIO MORENO generates dog. This generation, however, is exclusively reduced to the becoming, not to the being, to the new individual which exists in " that" particular matter, and this causality is exercised by transmuting the matter through motion. (ii) The generation of the form as such, however, transcends motion, and since motion is the exclusive property of material beings, then the cause of the form has to be incorporeal. The consequences which follow St. Thomas's ideas on causality are of great significance to the theory of evolution, for according to these ideas the causality of natural agents in the evolution of species is reduced to the preparation of matter and the eduction of form. But the cause of the being, of forms as such, is ascribed to spiritual causes. The Final Cause and the Process of Generation and Corruption Is the process of generation and corruption a consequence of blind laws and pure chance or does it proceed by following a purpose, a design? According to St. Thomas, the process of generation tends towards superior beings and, ultimately, to man as the most perfect being. Although prime matter is by its nature indifferent to all forms, the concrete actualization of forms is the result of the subordination of external agents, which by acting upon one another, tend towards superior forms. What is more perfect acts upon that which is less, what is actual upon potency, thus producing through billions of years higher and higher beings. Ultimately, the whole process of generation is ordered to man's generation: Since any moved thing, inasmuch as it is moved tends to the divine likeness so that it may be perfected in itself, and since a thing is perfect as it is actualized, the intention of everything existing in potency must be to tend through motion towards actuality. And so, the more posterior and more perfect an act is, the more fundamentally is the inclination of matter directed towards it. Hence, in regard to the last and more perfect act that matter can attain, the inclination of matter whereby it desires form must be inclined as towards the ultimate end of generation. Now, among the acts pertaining to forms, certain graduations are found. Thus, prime matter is in potency, first of all, to the form of an element ... and a CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 441 sensitive one to an intellectual one. . . . After this last type of form, no later and more noble form is found in the order of generable and corruptible things. Therefore, the ultimate end of the whole process of generation is the human soul, and matter tends towards it as the ultimate form. So, elements exist for the sake of mixed bodies; these latter exist for the sake of living bodies, among which plants exist for animals, and animals for men. Therefore, man is the end of the whole order of generation. 49 The tendency of nature towards superior forms is realized through evolution, as we now understand this term. Another teleological trait exists in nature: the individual exists for the sake of the species. According to St. Thomas, the reason there are many individuals in a single species is that the specific nature, which cannot be perpetuated in one individual, may be preserved in several. 5° "Furthermore, in each individual that which belongs to the species is superior to the individuating principle, which lies outside the essence of the species. Therefore, the universe is ennobled more by the multiplication of species than by the multiplication of individuals of one species." 51 Hence, the process of generation teaches us that the individual exists for the sake of the species and that the ultimate goal of the whole process of evolution Is the generation of man. The last teleological feature of the universe is due to the absolute dependence of the universe upon God who directs the motion of all beings towards their goals. It is necessary to attribute providence to God. For all the good that is in created things has been created by God. In created things good is found also as regards order towards an end. The good of order existing in things created, is itself created by God . . . and the type of things ordered towards an end is, properly speaking, providence. 52 If the dynamic orientation of created things towards their goals constitutes providence, then how great is its extension? •• III Cont. Gent., c. 22. Cf. ibid., 9: " ... The whole of generation is ordered to man, as to an ultimate end in the genus of generable and mobile beings. " 50 II Cont. Gent., e. 98. 51 Ibid. Cf. Summa Theol., I, 47, a. 2.; II Sent .. d. 8, 1, 4 ad 8. •• Summa Theol., I, q. 22. a. 1. 442 ANTONIO MORENO If this dynamic orientation does not consider the individual, then it is possible and logical to introduce chance in evolution. Divine providence, however, subjects all beings and all actions to itself: We must say that all things are subject to divine providence, not only in general but even in their own individual selves. This is made evident thus. For since every agent acts for an end, the ordering of effects towards that end extends as far as the causality of the first agent extends .... But the causality of God, who is the first ag.ent, extends to all beings, not only as to the constituent principles of species but also as to the individualizing principles. Hence, all things that exist in whatever manner are necessarily directed by God towards some end .... 53 Since all particular causes are included under the universal cause, no effect could take place outside the range of that universal cause. According to Thomistic philosophy, then, evolution is completely directed and planned by the Creator to the last detail. Nothing escapes divine providence, certainly not the appearance of man through evolution. IV. SciENTIFIC EvoLuTION AND CAUSALITY The Genetic Code In general, heredity consists in a self-replication of the genetic material, or DNA, which with slight modifications is always similar to the DNA of the parents. Evolution, however, "appears to depend on self-replicating and self-varying (mutation) strings of DNA, and this self-replicating and selfvarying inevitably lead to natural selection. 54 Geneticists contend that, although sexual reproduction reshuffles the DNA deck of cards, no new genes can be created. Only various new combinations of existing genes come into play. Evolution, however, presupposes changes in the gene pool of a population, and there are four known processes which change this pool: (i) mutation; (ii) random fluctuation of genetic frequencies •• Ibid., q. 2 ad I. "'In Evolution, p. 95. CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 443 known as "sampling errors"; (iii) migration of individuals in and out of the population; and (iv) natural selection. 55 Mutation and natural selection, however, are the two primary factors in the process of evolution. In order to understand the change of one species into another it is necessary to keep in mind that in every chromosome, in every cell, of every individual there exists a molecule that makes a mouse a mouse and a man a man-DNA. The secret of its creative diversity is not in its composition but in its structure. The way in which DNA is built accounts for the billions of forms it can command. 56 Geneticists now think that it is the order of the steps of the DNA molecule which gives every gene its special character. The amount of DNA in a living organism and the complexity of the organism also seem to be somewhat correlated. The Change of Species Through the Code and Causality The distinction of species depends upon the amount of chromosomes and the structure of the DNA, for every species is materially determined by these traits. A change in species, then, must be the result of a change in the structure of its particular DNA molecule. Are the four factors mentioned previously capable of changing this structure and producing a completely new one? According to geneticists, mutation plus natural selection gradually change the structure and shape of the DNA until a new species is generated. 55 F. Ayala, "Teleological Explanations in Evolutionary Biology," Philosophy of Science, Vol. 37, n. 1, p. 3. 56 Evolution, pp. 100-103; ibid., p. 96: "In greatly simplified terms ;t is the line up of the DNA, whether normal or mutated, that dictates the order of amino acids in the protein. This in terms dictates the " shape " and hence the specific activity of the proteins; and protein activity dictates the form of all living things. Or to put into numbers, the 4 bases of DNA arrange 20 universal amino acids in patterns forming the thousands of proteins that control life's infinite variety." The Cell, p. 61: "Geneticists now think that it is the order of these steps, the arrangement of TA's etc. that gives every gene its special character. The amount of DNA in a living organism, and the complexity of the organism seems to be correlated. " 444 ANTONIO MORENO In general, the philosopher has no difficulty in simultaneously accepting the general theory of causality and the role of the DNA molecule in evolution. According to causality, the evolution of species first requires a new disposition of matter. A new structure of the DNA molecule corresponds to the concept we have characterized as the disposition of matter. To a profound change in the structure of the DNA, then, corresponds a new species, inasmuch as the form of the species must be in proportion to the new structure of the DNA. "One thing no single mutation has done is to produce a new species, genus, or family," Dobzhansky says. "This is because species and supraspecific categories differ always in many genes, and hence arise by summation of many mutational steps." 57 This leads us to a crucial issue: How is it possible to dispose the genetic material for a superior form? Where is the cause which produces this disposition? Here natural selection appears to be the primary factor. Natural selection is not merely a negative force in evolution but an element which creates new and superior structures in the DNA molecule that demand the emergence of new forms and new species. Natural selection is comparable not to a sieve but to a regulatory mechanism in a cybernetic system. The genetic endowment of a living species receives and accumulates information about the challenges of the environment in which the species lives. The evolutionary changes are creative responses to the challenges of the environment. They are not alterations imposed by the environment as Lamarckists mistakenly thought. 58 It is possible then, to dispose a new a.nd superior matter through natural selection which also demands a superior form and species. Evolution has achieved more than to preserve life on earth from destruction. It has created progressively more complex and adaptively more secure organizations. The human species has achieved the peak of biological security. 59 •• Th. Dobzhansky, Genetics and the Origin of Species, p. 81. •• Th. Dobzhansky, The Biology of Ultimate Concern (New York, 1967), p. li!!t. •• Ibid., p. 129. CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 445 From the philosophical viewpoint, this is perfectly acceptable because natural agents act as instruments of superior agents which are the principal causes of that disposition. 60 Natural Selection This schematic explanation of the causality corresponding to evolution depends, even philosophically speaking, on natural selection which was Darwin's greatest contribution to the science of evolution. The adaptation and diversity of life and the appearance of new highly organized forms can be explained by the orderly process of change which Darwin called natural selection. We feel sure that any variation in the least injurious could be rigidly destroyed. This preservation of favorable variations and the rejection of injurious variations I call natural selection.61 Of course, natural selection is not exactly as Darwin conceived it, for ... the selectively fit, or if you will, the fittest, is not necessarily a fellow with big muscles, or a lusty fighter, or a conqueror of all his competitors. He is rather a paterfamilias who has raised a large number of children who in turn become paterfamilias. 62 National selection is basically differential reproduction; it enhances the development of the life of the individual and ultimately of the species. Instead of being purely a process of statistical chance, natural selection, on the contrary, is an orderly process of change governed by natural laws. As a directive force in evolution, natural selection is not predictable as are physical laws which are based on the repetition of similar circumstances. Although 60 St. Thomas, On the Power of God. q. 5, a. 1 c. "This corporeal agent acts by virtue of the incorporeal principle, and its action terminates in this or that form . . . Accordingly, these corporeal agents are not the cause of the forms in things made, except they do not act except by transmuting, and this is by transmuting matter and educing the form from the potentiality of matter." 61 Ch. Darwin, The Origin of Species. Quoted by Ayala in "A biologist's view of nature," A New Ethic for a New Earth, p. 30. •• Th. Dobzhansky, Heredity and the Nature of Man (New York, 1966), pp. 153-154. 446 ANTONIO MORENO such repetition does not occur in biological evolution, natural selection is certainly not haphazard. 63 As the geneticists say, causal relations, not caprice, prevail in nature. 64 For the philosopher interested in evolution the significance of natural selection is best summarized by Dobzhansky, that natural selection tends to maximize the probability of the preservation and expansion of life. The adaptation of plant life to a desert climate, for example, is a consequence of natural selection: The fundamental adaptation is the condition of dryness which carries the danger of desiccation. During a major part of the year, sometimes for several years in succession, there is no rain. Plants have satisfied the urgent necessity of saving water in different ways. Cacti have transformed their leaves into spines, having made their stems into barrels containing a reserve of water. Photosynthesis is performed on the surface of the stem instead of on the leaves. Other plants have no leaves during the dry season, but after it rains they burst into leaves and flowers and produce seedsall within the space of the few weeks while water is available. The rest of the year the seeds lie quiescent in the soil.65 Nat ural selection can also generate new organs by increasing the probability of otherwise extremely improbable genetic combinations. For instance, geneticists regard the formation of the vertebrate eye as an example of natural selection: ... the combination of genetic units which carries the hereditary information responsible for the formation of the vertebrate eye have never been produced by a random process like mutationnot even if we allow for the three billion years plus during which life has existed on earth. The complicated anatomy of the eye like the exact functioning of the kidney are the result of a nonrandom process-natural selection. 66 The Finality which Corresponds to Evolution Some geneticists explain evolution in terms of teleology. In general, teleological explanations imply the existence of means63 See Evolution After Darwin, Vol. 8, p. 107. "'Th. Dobzhansky, The Biology of Ultimate Concern, pp. 126, 122. C. G. Simpson, Evolution After Darwin, Vol. I, p. 166. 65 F. Ayala. "Teleological Explanations in Evolutionary Biology," loc. cit., p. 7 •• F. Ayala, "A biologist's view of nature," loc. cit., p. 35. CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 447 to-end relationship in the system under consideration, thereby suggesting that the system is directly organized and intelligible. " Teleological explanations imply that such contribution is the explanatory reason for the presence of the process or object in the system." 67 For example, it is appropriate to give a teleological explanation of the operation of the kidney in regulating the concentration of salt in the blood; we have a kidney because the regulation of the concentration of salt in the organism is a necessity. The philosopher accepts this concept of teleology, for he defines finality as " that for the sake of which something is done." " That for the sake of which something is done" is the justification of the existence of a means-to-end relationship. In Darwin's theory purpose is absolutely indispensable to his reasoning. As Cassirer points out: it is safe to assert that no earlier biological theory ascribed quite as much significance to the idea of purpose, or advocated it so emphatically, since not only individual but absolutely all the phenomena of life are regarded from the standpoint of their survival value. All other questions retreat into the background before this one.68 The survival value is the ultimate purpose in Darwin's theory. Teleology also corresponds to contemporary natural selection, for the adaptation of organisms is an observed fact which enhances the conservation and development of individuals, and as its ultimate goal, the conservation and improvement of species. In general terms, natural selection is teleologically oriented in that it produces and maintains end-directed organs and mechanisms when the functions they serve contribute to the reproductive efficiency of the organism. 69 More difficult to explain teleologically is the operation of the genes and their mutation. It is clear that mutation alone would produce chaos, 67 F. Ayala, "Biology as an autonomous science" in American Scientist, Vol. 56, n. 3, p. 214. Cf. ibid., p. 214. 68 E. Cassirer, The Problem of Knowledge (Tr. by W. H. Woglom and C. W. Hendel, New Haven, Conn., 1950), p. 166. •• F. Ayala, "Biology as an autonomous science," loc. cit., p. 217. 448 ANTONIO MORENO not evolution. But natural selection redresses the balance; harmful genes are reduced in frequency, and useful ones perpetuated and multiplied. 70 Dobzhansky observes that the history of life is comparable to human history since both proceed by trial and error, with false starts, yet achieving progress on the whole. The paradoxical feature of, biological evolution, however, is that design and chance appear simultaneously. Adherents of finalism and orthogenesis contend that, since it is quite incredible that evolution could all be due to " chance," one must assume that it has had a design which it has followed. The reality is, however, more complex and more interesting than the chance vs. design dichotomy suggest. 71 It is more complex, because in the evolutionary process life had innumerable other potentialities which remained unrealized since only a tiny fraction of possible gene combinations can be actualized. Certainly, there is an element of chance in mutations, yet chance is directed by an anti-chance agent in evolution-natural selection responding to environmental challenges. Together with natural selection, especially in the evolution of higher organisms, there are discernible elements of creativity and freedom. For example, all desert plants must cope with dryness; but different plants do so by a variety of means. Animals must have some organs for respiration; yet these may be gills, tracheae, lungs, and so forth. As Dobzhansky concludes, the multiplicity of ways of becoming adapted to similar environments is not in accord with hypotheses of design and orthogenesis in evolution; these hypotheses would lead one rather to expect that a single and presumably most perfect method, will be used everywhere. On the contrary, natural selection is more permissible .... Only a minuscule fraction of the potentially possible gene combinations are ever actualized. 72 Th. Dobzhansky, The Biology of Ultimate Concern, p. 122. Ibid., p. 125. •• Ibid., p. 127. 70 71 CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 449 Yet, we must not personalize natural selection, Dobzhansky warns, for it is not some kind of spirit or demon who' directs evolution to accomplish some set purpose. " Groping in the dark " is the only way natural selection can proceed, and this "groping " is " opportunistic and shortsighted." Lacking a preview of the future, natural selection adapts the living species to the environments which exist " here and now." 73 Dobzhansky's brilliant interpretation of natural selection must be examined carefully. Rejecting the hypothesis of design in evolution he sees natural selection as opportunistic and short·sighted and often culminating in failure. 74 He notes the danger of natural selection being personalized as if it directed evolution to accomplish some set purpose. Dobzhansky is followed with some difficulty here since the philosophical concept of purpose and design, when applied to genetics, must necessarily be shortsighted, for nature can only work with " here and now " circumstances. Dobzhansky rightly points out that the transmittal of particular maternal and paternal genes is a matter of chance. 75 But natural selection directs these genes by "shortsightedly " adapting them to the immediate environment. It is true that natural selection is opportunistic; it cannot be otherwise. Sometimes natural selection fails-it cannot always cope with an adverse environment, but even in these cases it does not cease to struggle. The same purpose is manifested in •• Ibid., p. 128. Cf. ibid., p. 128. "Evolution has achieved more than to preserve life on earth from destruction. It has created progressively more complex and adaptively more secure organizations. The human species has attained the peak of biological security. It is unlikely to become extinct because of any conflicts with its physical or biological environments. " "' Th. Dobzhansky writes this on Teihard de Chardin, ibid., p. 128: " Groping in the dark is, indeed, the only way natural selection can proceed. Now, groping may lead to discovery of openings toward new opportunities for living. It may also end in a fall from a precipice. It may preserve and enchance life, or it may lead to extinction. Teilhard was a paleoneologist, and he was quite familar with extinction of evolutionary lines. Yet he devoted strangely little attention to this phenomenon in his writings. It would have caused him no difficulty had he realized that natural selection is necessarily opportunistic and shortsighted in its groupings. " •• Ibid., p. 126. 450 ANTONIO MORENO failure as well as in the instances of success. In both cases, individuals and species struggle for survival and for adaptation to the environment. Among human beings there are many individuals who cannot cope with the " here and now " circumstances and die. There are tribes in the Amazon River on the verge of extinction, in spite of their life-and-death struggle for existence. Many species of animals are now disappearing, not because they do not strive for survival but because their opportunistic and shortsighted reaction to the " here and now '' situation is insufficient to overcome adverse conditions created by man. In all these cases natural selection is at work, and certainly has its effect on the species continuing struggle for survival, though it fails. The concept of finality and design does not necessarily presuppose success but rather a certain orientation or intention. Dobzhansky's main thesis, again, must only be accepted with reluctance, if at all: " The multiplicity of ways of becoming adapted to similar environment is not in accord with hypotheses of design and orthogenesis in evolution, for these hypotheses would lead one rather to expect that a single and presumably most perfect method will be used everywhere." 76 Is it not questionable that this conclusion is contained in the premises? Certainly physical bodies always follow the single and most perfect method in motion, according to relativity, the geodesic, and the law of minimum energy. 77 But this is not the way evolution proceeds, because biological evolution is not deterministic in the way physics is. Natural selection depends upon mutation and chance and, as such, the genetic code possesses an almost infinite number of possibilities. Yet the actualization of these potentialities is restricted by the laws of statistical probability to one at a time. In other words, the Ibid., p. 127. Although the uncertainty principle seems to reject the deterministic pattern of physical laws, the interpretation of this principle is far from easy. Einstein still believes in the absolute determinism of physical laws, contrary to Bohr and Heisenberg. In addition, we should bear in mind that the laws of physics are idealizations, and, consequently, no more than approximations. 76 77 CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 451 nature of living beings necessarily presuppposes the impossibility of the simultaneous actualization of these possibilities. It also presupposes-due to the variety of genes and " here and now " circumstances-that " a single and presumably most perfect method " can hardly ever be achieved. It should be emphasized that the design for survival in genetics always implies a means-to-end relationship which by its nature must be opportunistic and shortsighted. The well-known failures do not invalidate the existence of design; even extinct species witness to the finality and design that is realized through natural selection. In man, too, there exists purpose and design which is realized in free actions. There are many potentialities in a single individual which will never be actualized, although this does not destroy purpose or design. It only tells us that design is realized in a particular way and not always by following the most perfect method. Philosophical Teleology and Scientific Teleology in Evolution The philosopher benefits from the discoveries of contemporary biology. Natural selection explains concretely how St. Thomas's idea of the gradual actualization of prime matter towards superior forms takes place: this gradual actualization is realized through evolution. In addition, natural selection fined as differential reproduction presupposes the preservation and development of species, as St. Thomas believed. The philosopher observes the existence of two basic instincts in living beings: the instinct of self-preservation and of the preservation of the species. The former is subordinated to the latter, as natural selection most conclusively indicates. Rejecting Freud's death instinct, or death drive, as highly irnprobable/8 Dobzhansky attests to the instinct of self-preservation, for " all organisms, from the lowest to the highest, react to stimuli that commonly occur in their habitual environment in ways that tend to maximize the chances of their survival." 79 Placed in novel conditions, however, the body loses its wisdom, 78 Th. Dobzhansky, The Biology of Ultimate Concern, p. 75. •• Ibid., p. 74. ANTONIO MORENO "in short, there is no instinct of self-preservation, if by such an ' instinct ' one means an ability to react to all environmental stimuli always in such a manner as to preserve the individual's life." 80 Here Dobzhansky is in complete agreement with the philosophical concept of self-preservation. There is no such thing as universal wisdom, for the living being reacts in ways which subordinate everything to the preservation of its life in a limited way. A creature is naturally not always aware of everything that may endanger its life, so the instinct of selfpreservation necessarily operates within the limits of concrete knowledge. But this knowledge is, of course, subject to further development. Even dogs, for example, can learn through experience that crossing a busy street can be dangerous. :Man is physically unaware of atomic radiation, but as soon as he learns of its existence, he takes measures to avoid that danger. As a final question it is important for the philosopher to consider how living organisms adapt themselves to the environment since they do not do so consciously. If natural selection presupposes a means-to-end relationship in the system, who determines the end, who decides the means, and who knows the relation between ends and means? Plants in the desert, for example, store water since otherwise they would perish. The storage of water is the means by which these plants preserve themselves and their species. But how do plants know they have to store water? It is remarkable to observe the following hierarchical subordination of means tn ends: the preservation of the species is the ultimate end, which requires the preservation of the individual plant; but this is impossible unless the plant stores water, which in turn requires a change of the normal process of photosynthesis. The ultimate goal, the preservation of the species, subordinates everything to itself and is the reason and explanation for the whole process, which then becomes more intelligible. If natural selection is truly teleological, in other words, then the process of evolution follows a scheme, a design. The kidney exists, for example, because the living organism requires a •• Ibid., p. 74. CONSIDERATIONS ON BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION 453 certain concentration of salt in the blood and not vice versa, that is, there is a certain concentration of salt in the blood because we have a kidney. The phenomena occurs because it is intended; if it happens without being intended then the process is not teleological, but merely a consequence of chance. The biologist is not interested in this speculation, which belongs properly to philosophy. Yet in the last analysis, it is the problem of intention and knowledge that gives full intelligibility to evolution. St. Thomas summarizes the need for knowledge of a teleological process thus: " The right ordering of a thing to a due end requires knowledge of the end, and the means to it, and of the due proportion between both: and this knowledge is found only in an agent with intelligence." 81 The full explanation of the biological process of evolution and of natural selection demands an intelligence. The old aphorism that " the work of nature is the work of an intelligence-Opus naturae est optts intelli-. gentiae," seems apropos here. The concrete realization of St. Thomas's three main ideas on finality makes evolution more intelligible: 82 (i) man as the culmination of the whole process of generation; (ii) the individual for the sake of the species; and (iii) a supreme being directing the dynamic process of the universe. Even Darwin in his early writings did not rule out the possibility of a supreme being hidden behind the process of nature. He declared at the very end of his Origin: There is a grandeur in this view of life, with its several powers, having been originally breathed by the Creator into a few .forms or into one; and that, whilst this planet has gone cycling on according to the fixed law of gravity, from so simple a beginning endless forms most beautiful and most wonderful have been, and are being evolved. 83 St. Thomas, II Cont. Gent., c. When we postulate a supreme being as directing the dynamic process of the universe, we do not mean that he directs the cosmos as we drive a car. He probably directs the biological and cosmic process by using as instruments the very physical and biological laws he created. A thermostat works without the actual direction of those who constructed it who simply used physical and chemical laws to produce the desired effect, namely, the regulation of temperature. In like manner God intervenes in nature by using natural laws in order to produce the desired efft-ct. 88 Ch. Darwin, The Origin of Species, end. 81 82 454 ANTONIO MORENO The explanation of St. Augustine of the creation of the universe in six days accounts for the gradual appearance of the species along the millennia. St. Augustine, however, does not pose the problem of evolution as it is formulated in contemporary terms, namely, as a gradual transformation of one species into another: The elements of this corporeal world have as a definite power and as their proper quality that which each one can or cannot do, that which can or cannot be made from each one. From these, as it were, the beginnings of things, all that is produced receives in its proper time its birth and its growth, the limits and the separations of its own nature. Thence it is that a bean does not grow from a grain of wheat, nor wheat from a bean, nor a man from an animal, nor an animal from a man. 84 For St. Augustine, species are in potency, after the manner of seed, which are actualized in due time. For every seminal ratio, there will exist a species at the right time, but that new species is not the result of the transformation of another species, which is what modem evolution tells us. Whether such a transformation is possible or not according to St. Augustine's philosophical principles, it is impossible to say. But the principles of a Thomistic philosophy can indeed be applied to our modem view of biological evolution. In Teilhard de Chardin's words: "Aristotelian hylemorphism represents the projection, upon a world without duration, of modem evolutionism. Rethought within a universe in which duration adds a further dimension, the theory of matter and form becomes almost indistinguishable from our contemporary speculations on the development of matter." 85 We heartily agree with the French paleontologist. ANTONIO MoRENo, 0. P. Graduate Theological Union Berkeley, California •• St. Augustine, De Gen. ad litt., 9, 17, ML 34, 406. •• Teilhard de Chardin, Oeuvres, Vol. 3, p. 181. Cf. Raymond J. Nogar, 0. P. The Wisdom of Evolution (New York, 1963). Raymond Nogar shows that evolution is not at variance with Christian thought. RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER: BEING, HEARING, AND GOD TI IMMEDIATE GOAL of this essay is to delimit e essential difference between Rahner's philosophy religion and Heidegger's philosophy of Being. Why is it necessary to establish the ground of disagreement between these thinkers? For one thing, it has been claimed by some that Heidegger's philosophy has had a profound effect on Rahner's thought. Louis Roberts, for example, has maintained "that Heidegger's influence on Rahner is nearly as great as Marechal's." 1 Rahner himself suggests that "perhaps Dr. Roberts overestimates this . . . influence somewhat." 2 In any case, it will be maintained here that any valid interpretation of the influence of Heidegger on Rahner must take into account the fundamental difference between them. It will be maintained that this difference is at the level of the most basic questions which each poses and therefore has ramifications which go beyond mere methodological differences. This is not intended to be a refutation to the claim that Heidegger has influenced Rahner, for he certainly has. It is merely hoped that the delimitation of the fundamental difference between their thought will make it possible to assess most accurately how the one has influenced the other. This essay, however, will not attempt such an assessment, nor will it attempt a point by point comparison of Rahner's philosophy with Heidegger's. A second reason for delimiting the difference between their philosophies has to do with the relation of Heidegger's thought to Thomistic philosophy, and more generally to metaphysics. It is hoped that the investigation will clarify quite emphatically Louis Roberts, The Achievement of Karl Rahner (New York, 1967), p. 17. • Karl Rahner, "Forward" to The Achievement of Karl Rahner, p. viii. 1 455 456 ROBERT MASSON the fundamental differences which underlie any apparent similarities between Heidegger's perspective on the question of being and the metaphysician's perspective. The alleged influence of Heidegger on Rahner is evident, in part, in the notion of "hearing" or "attending" (horen) which plays a central role in the thought of both. In Hearers of the Word Rahner definies man as essentially a potential hearer of a word from God. The philosophy of religion must prepare for this hearing by demonstrating metaphysically that man has this potentiality. Consequently, Rahner defines theology (theology in the "positive" and fundamental sense as the reception of Revelation and not in the sense of its elaboration) as a "hearing." Theology is fundamentally the " hearing " either of an historical word from God or of his silence. 3 Similarly, Heidegger's philosophy of Being could be defined as a type of thinking which is essentially a " hearing," or better an " attending," but as will be shown, a very different kind of hearing than is developed in Rahner's thought. More fundamental for both thinkers than the notion of hearing, however, is the notion of " being." Rahner argues metaphysically to the notion of man as " hearer of the word " from man's Vorgriff (pre-comprehension) of being. Similarly, Heidegger's notion of man as a hearer is developed in his attempt to think the meaning of Sein (Being) .4 The difference between the notion of hearing in these two philosophies is ultimately grounded in the difference in the question of being posed by each. Fundamentally, therefore, this essay is concerned with the issue of being as it is developed in Rahner's transcendental Thomism and Heidegger's philosophy of Being. It is necessary to make explicit several further restrictions of our topic. Since the essay is concerned with the point of difference between Rahner and Heidegger, and since the volume "Karl Rahner, Hearers of the Word, trans. Michael Richards (New Ym-k, 1968), pp. 10-11. Hereafter: HW. • For reasons which will become apparent Heidegger's Sein is translated here as Being (capital B). Rahner's Sein which for him is equivalent to esse is translated as being (small b). RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 451 and complexity of Heidegger's reflection on Being are so extensive, no attempt will be made here to give a balanced or comprehensive presentation of Heidegger's thought in itself. The primary focus of attention will be determined by the presentation of Rahner's thesis. Nor will it be possible to consider comprehensively the system of transcendental Thomism, as it has come to be called, except insofar as it is involved in the definition of man as a potential hearer of God's word. Finally, although it is hoped that this essay will help to indicate how one would proceed to investigate the relation of Heidegger's philosophy to theology, such an investigationvery involved in itself-will not be pursued. Since Rahner has published a reflection on Heidegger's thought-although not an extensive one, and based only on the early works-it seems quite natural to consider it first. 5 Hopefully the consideration of that article will enable us to take an initial stance with regard to Rahner's evaluation of Heidegger, and will also serve as a general introduction to Heidegger's thought. An examination of Rahner's philosophy of religion as developed in Hearers of the Word will follow, with attention focused on those elements which subsequently will be shown as the fundamental bone of contention between Heidegger and Rahner. Having done this it will be necessary to re-evaluate Rahner's critique of Heidegger's thought in the light of what will be maintained is a more faithful reading of Heidegger's question about Being. It will then be shown what sense "hearing" comes to have in regard to such a question. It will not be possible to limit the consideration of Heidegger to one or two statements of his position and so indications will have to be gleaned from a number of his works. The essay concludes, contrary to the general consensus, that the philosophies of Rahner and Heidegger differ at the very level of the question asked. * * * Karl Rahner, "The Concept of Existential Philosophy in Heidegger," trans. Andrew Tallon, Philosophy Today, 13 (1969), pp. 126-37. Originally published in French in 1940. Hereafter: CE. 5 458 ROBERT MASSON Rahner's essay on Heidegger is brief and attempts merely to introduce its readers to the broad outlines of his philosophy. It does not attempt either a comprehensive evaluation of his thought or a comparison of it to other systems of thought. Since Rahner does restrict the scope of his article, it would be unfair to evaluate it as an extensive and nuanced interpretation, much less as necessarily representing Rahner's current evaluation of Heideggerian philosophy. Nevertheless, the essay does situate Heidegger's question within a specific context, and it does project and evaluate the possible development of Heidegger's thought from that context. Although Rahner's conjectures are only provisory, they nevertheless firmly establish the ground on which Rahner's thought confronts Heidegger's. It will be shown in the discussion of Hearers of the Word how Rahner moves from this ground himself. In our own re-evaluation of this essay, however, it will be shown that the ground upon which Rahner bases his interpretation of Heidegger is indeed very shaky ground. Although few of Heidegger's later works were available in 1940, Rahner's interpretation misunderstands the most essential points made even in the works which he did consider, sc. SZ, KM, WM, and WG. 6 This is, of course, not meant as a criticism of Rahner but as a preparation for the delimitation of the difference between his philosophy and Heidegger's. Rahner considers Heidegger a metaphysician. As a meta6 The following abbreviations will be used to refer to the translations of Heidegger's works: EM-An Introduction to Metaphysics trans. Ralph Manheim (New York, 1961). KM-Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics trans. James S. Churchhill (Bloomington, Indiana, 1968) . SZ-Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York, 1966). The pagination of the German edition is given in this translation and used also in this paper. WG-The Essence of Reason, trans. Terrence Malick (Evanston, 1969). WM-" What is Metaphysics? " trans. R. F. C. Hull and Alan Crick, in Existence and Being, ed. Werner Brock (Chicago, 1970), pp. 325-61. Intro to WM-" The Way Back into the Ground of Metaphysics," trans. and ed. Walter Kaufmann, Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre (New York, 1969), pp. 206-21. RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 459 physician Heidegger, according to Rahner, asks about being as such, in its totality, as that which is most general. Rahner understands this concern with being as that which is most general, as a concern about the act of being, the esse characteristic of all beings (ens). Likewise, he understands Heidegger's concern with being in its totality as a concern with esse as the unifying aspect under which all possible objects are able to be comprehended and summed up, and as the ultimate cause to which they can be related. Metaphysics insofar as it asks this question about being is called "ontology," and insofar as it looks for the universal basis of all being it is " theology." All philosophy since Plato and Aristotle is at its base, therefore, "onto-theological." According to Rahner, Heidegger accepts this heritage-this concern about being as such-and makes it his own. (CE, 128) What is distinctive, according to Rahner's interpretation, about Heidegger's approach to metaphysics is that he seeks to put it on a new foundation. The whole tradition of philosophy from Plato to Hegel has conceived being in terms of logos and thus as correlative to thought or reason. J\ian was defined as the animal rationalis and the question of being was " interpreted from the logical grasp of being by thought." (CE, 130) Rahner maintains that Heidegger's originality lies in the fact that he asks the " question about being without conceiving it beforehand as onto-logy." (CE, 130) Thus Heidegger situates the question about being on a new plane which does not presuppose the definition of man or being in terms of logos, but which sees man as the place where being is "comprehended " in a more fundamental way. According to Rahner, this is why Heidegger defines his task as the establishing of a more "fundamental ontology." It is also for this reason that Heidegger wants to go back beyond the traditional starting point of metaphysics to the point of its origin with the Pre-Socratics when being was not conceived beforehand in terms of logic. (CE, 130) Rahner maintains that this more fundamental investigation of the being question assumes the form of a transcendental 460 ROBERT MASSON analysis. For this reason Rahner situates Heidegger within the tradition of modem philosophy which according to Rahner is essentially transcendental philosophy. As Rahner sees it, "a question is posed on the transcendental plane when it asks for the a priori conditions that make knowledge of an object possible," that is to say, when the investigator himself becomes the object of investigation. (CE, Since being as such is not accessible as this or that being, and since it cannot be obtained in its pure state, the only access which one has to being is through man who must already possess some knowledge of being to raise the question in the first place. In other words, Rahner tells us, in order to ask about the a priori conditions which render possible the knowledge of being, the investigator must become the object of investigation. (CE, Rahner notes that it is important to keep in mind that Heidegger's sole concern is always with the question about being. The transcendental analytic of man, therefore, aims at resolving the question about being. It is not in any sense aimed at establishing an anthropology. The question of man is always subordinate to the question about being. (CE, 129) Accordingly, Rahner maintains that we are able to define Heidegger's philosophy as: the transcendental investigation of what man is insofar as he raises the question of being, an investigation that rejects the initial traditional stance in this matter-exclusively intellectual-and undertaken with the intention of providing an answer to the question of being in general. (CE, 131; printed entirely in italics) Rahner tells us that Heidegger's transcendental investigation of man is an analysis of man as " Dasein." What does Heidegger mean by this term? According to Rahner, "Dasein" does not designate simply being-present-there (etrela-present) in the sense in which one could affirm anything whatever, but rather "Dasein" is being-human itself-each of us. It is characterized inherently by the transcendence which orients man towards being, and from which derives the ability to understand oneself in a definite way, to take an HAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 461 attitude towards oneself. As a conquence "existence" in Heidegger's special terminology denotes not the fact that a being is, but rather it denotes ". . . man, insofar as he is in some way the object of this free self-disposition." (CE, 131) The existential analytic of Dasein, therefore, consists in the determination of the general and formal structures which are proper to Dasein as a mode of being-human, in other words as "existence," as a state of "openness" (transcendence) to being. These structures are called "existentials." SZ is almost entirely devoted to an explication of these structures. The analysis displays itself, Rahner maintains, in two stages. The first consists in a phenomenological description of Dasein as " being-in-the-world." The second reduces this being-in-theworld to its ultimate sense as "being-in-time." (CE, Rahner explains that being-in-the-world describes Dasein's " existence " as Heidegger conceives it. Man is, only insofar as he is in the world. This being-in-the-world is not a secondary process by which Dasein as a closed subject in some way comes into contact with an exterior world. Rather, from the very start Dasein is already outside of itself in the world and in the things of the world. Being in the world according to Rahner, therefore, consists in the a priori possibility of Dasein to be related to the things of the world and the world itself. Man is from the very start open to the totality of the world, and the totality of the world is, albeit under an empty form, given him right from the outset. (CE, 132) Rahner explains that this being-in-the-world has a triple aspect which is described by Heidegger as V erstehen, Geworfenheit, and Verfallenh!eit. The first term refers to Heidegger's contention that Dasein is not present to itself by a static knowledge of properties but rather is present to itself by a This "tension-astretching-ahead-of-self-toward-the-future. head-of-self-toward-the-future" is "understanding, man's way of comprehending and grasping himself, of grasping and restructuring his own power-to-be." (CE, 133) Through this V erstehen Dasein finds itself always brought into question and ROBERT MASSON is thus present to itself. Rahner notes that according to Heidegger this stretching of Dasein towards its "subjective possibilities" must always begin from Dasein's past-a past which has been imposed upon Dasein and of which it has no hold. This "state-of-being-thrown into this or that condition" (etat-de-jete-dans-teUes et telles conditions) Heidegger calls " thrownness " (Geworfenheit) . Furthermore, the tension-ahead-of-self-toward-the-future from the past-into-which-it-hasbeen-thrown necessarily involves Dasein with the things of the world to such an extent that Dasein becomes prey to them and enslaved. This enslavement Heidegger calls "Verfallenheit." Being-in-the-world as Verstehn, Geworfenheit, and Verfallenheit is summed up by the term " Care " (in German " Sorge," in French " Sollicitude ") . (CE, 132-33) The second stage of the analysis of SZ-the reduction of Dasein to its ultimate sense-becomes evident, Rahner observes, when, on the one hand, it is noted that the proper and strict possibility towards which Dasein carries itself is the certain possibility of its own impossibility, of its death, and when, on the other hand, it is noted that to the three aspects of Care correspond the elements of human duration (la "duree" humaine): future, present, and past. Duration, here, does not refer to the " time " we calculate, but rather to the foundation of such time in the temporal structure of Dasein as: the stretching-ahead-of -self-towards-its-ownmost-possibility or future (sc. death), from its depenedence on a past into which it has been thrown, realized in the present as a response to the attraction of the future, and the compulsion and constraint of the past. Rahner concludes, then, that for Heidegger Dasein as Care and as a being essentially towards death, is by its very structure temporal. Dasein is intrinsically finite. (CE, 133-34) Having outlined the general structure of Heidegger's existential analytic of Desein, Rahner returns to the original question-what is being as such?-and discovers that SZ never directly addresses itself to this question, leaving its answer to a proposed second volume. But although Rahner is unable to HAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 463 extract the kernel of Heideggerian metaphysics from SZ, he does attempt to draw from it and from indications in WM and WG some" conjectures" about Heidegger's answer to the being question. proDasein, Rahner observes, is a being-towards-death-a jection out of past and present towards Dasein's future. This projection is not a property of Dasein, but rather is the very act of being-human. The original mode of the projection or anticipatory grasp is not a theoretical knowledge in terms of logic, but rather it is an experience or state-of-disposition (Tallon translates " etat d' ame " as " state of soul ") which Heidegger defines as "anxiety." This dispositional state reveals "nothingness" (neant) as the ultimate "virtuality" of Dasein, and as that in which Dasein is already engaged. Dasein's transcendence, his passing beyond beings, is a passing to nothingness. Rahner maintains, therefore, that Heidegger appears to identify pure being and pure nothingness. Consequently, all beings as participants in nothingness are necessarily finite. Rahner observes that this view does not seem to allow even the possibility of raising a question about the existence of God. As far as Rahner can tell, Heidegger's ontology offers no support for a pure Being positively superior as such to all finitude. (CE, 134-35) Although it seems like Heidegger's thought allows no room for the idea of God, Rahner notes that Heidegger, himself, denies that his analysis says anything either for or against the possibility of God. Thus Rahner maintains it is impossible until the completion of his ontology to tell for sure if it will give to metaphysics " a meaning that is either the most radically atheist or the most profoundly religious." (CE, 137) All we can do, Rahner insists, is note that up till now the existential analytic of Dasein logically seems to be not an ontology but an Ontochronic (an expression Rahner attributes to Heidegger himself) -" a science which showing that the meaning of all being as such, and, absolutely, the meaning of Being, is nothingness." (CE, 136) Rahner does not attempt to analyze Heidegger's thought 464 ROBERT MASSON from the point of view of Christianity, but he does explain a little more fully what he means when he suggests that the ultimate resolution of Heidegger's philosophy will be either most radically atheistic or most profoundly religious. Heidegger's eventual ontology will lay the foundation for atheism if, as Rahner seems to think it is to be feared, the last word of its anthropology is nothingness, for then the last word of the ontology still to come must also be nothingness. On the other hand, Rahner claims that Heidegger's philosophy could lay the groundwork for a profoundly religious view if the analysis of Dasein in its ultimate stage discovers the infinity of the absolute as the first a priori of human transcendence, and if it discovers the true destiny of man in the choice between eternal nothingness and eternal life before God. In this case Heidegger's analysis of man as an historical being, as an essentially " finite creature," and as a temporal being renders possible an attentiveness to Revelation. In this case, to jar man loose from the pure idea and cast him into his own existence and history, as Heidegger is doing, would be to prepare him, to make him attentive to the fact-existential, historical-of a divine revelation, would be to open him to "the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob," to the "Word of Life, seen, heard, touched" by human hands, "Jesus of Nazareth .... " (CE, 137) This description is striking because it serves as a nearly perfect introduction to and crystalization of the philosophy of religion developed in Hearers of the Word. 1 Rahner's aim in Hearers of the Word is to lay the foundation for a philosophy of religion faithful to the principles of the Thomistic tradition yet unique in that it raises a question never explicitly posed by St. Thomas. (cf. HW, 33) He suggests that the nature of this philosophy of religion could be most clearly defined by comparing it with theology. It is necessary, therefore, to ask the question about the relationship 7 This similarity of Rahner's philosophy of religion and his projection of the possible developments of Heidegger's philosophy of Being suggest the value of following the argument of HW in this preliminary delimitation of the essential difference between their philosophies. RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 465 o£ these two sciences. The question o£ the relationship between sciences, however, is ultimately a question about their common foundation, and that science which serves as foundation £or all other sciences and grants them their a priori attitudes and principles-whether or not these principles are self-consciousis called metaphysics. The question o£ the relationship between the philosophy o£ religion and theology is consequently a metaphysical question. Science of any kind, however, is a human activity. Thus, the question of the relationship between the philosophy of religion and theology is ultimately a metaphysical question about the nature of man. It is what, in the previous article, Rahner called a transcendental question. (HW, 3-7) If the question presented so far is probed deeper, Rahner maintains that a series difficulty will be discovered. "For classical Christian philosophy of religion . . . knowledge of God ... is no static, self-contained science, but a profound element o£ ontology in general." (HW, 7) But if this is true, then the philosophy of religion as ontology (or the metaphysics o£ being) is the same as the science in which it finds its ground. The question o£ the philosophy of religion is thus a question about the "self-establishment of metaphysics." Ultimately, therefore, " the question about the philosophy of religion becomes the question as to why man pursues metaphysics and being, and how human metaphysics can reach up to God." (HW, 8) If this philosophy of religion is to be truly a " philosophy " and not a" theology" there can be no question of its justifying or explicating a revelation from God. On the other hand, if theology is to be truly "theology" and not "philosophy," then the philosophy of religion cannot a priori reduce revelation to merely what is discovered by reason. To establish itself the philosophy of religion must ask if there is any " reason " to suppose that man is a potential hearer of a divine revelation. The asking o£ such a question is a purely philosophical venture, but as such it lays the foundation for theology-the actual hearing o£ the revealed word-by pointing out to man whether or not he should seek such a revealed word in history. Rahner 466 ROBERT MASSON proposes that, in fact, it can be shown that man by his very nature is a potential hearer of a possible revelation from God in history. (HW, 7-27) Rahner describes the method which he chooses to achieve this end in terms very similar to those with which he described Heidegger's existential analytic of Dasein. Rahner proposes: to sketch the outlines of a metaphysical analytic of man with reference to the capacity to hear the word of God which is addressed to man as the revelation of the unknown God allowing the history of man to appear. To put a question metaphysically, however, is to put a question about being. (HW, 32) Rahner's pursuit of this question about the being of man establishes the three propositions of metaphysical anthropology that constitute the essence of his philosophy of religion: 1) that "man is a spirit (a characterization which stamps his whole being as man) and thus has an ear that is open to any word whatsoever that may proceed from the mouth of the Eternal" (HW, 67); 2) "that man is that existent thing who stands in free love before the God of a possible revelation ... (and who) is attentive to the speech or silence of God in the measure in which he opens himself in free love to this message of the speech or silence of the God of revelation" (HW, 108); and 3) that " man is that existent thing who must listen for an historical revelation of God, given in history and possibly in human speech." (HW, 161) These three propositions and the philosophy of religion which they constitute are based on Rahner's notion of being as that which is revealed to man through a preconceptual, nonthematic grasp, but which at the same time is hidden from man because of his finitude. It is at this level where the essential difference between Rahner and Heidegger emerges, so this is where the present essay will find its focus. * * * Rahner begins his analytic for the being of man in a manner that appears to be similar to Heidegger's posing of the ques- RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 467 tion about being. Metaphysics asks about the being of tha.t which is. It " enquires into the ultimate reasons, into the final cause of reality .... " (HW, 33) This questioning is unavoidable. "We are compelled to ask: What is the' being' of that which is?" (HW, 34); and it is precisely as men that we are compelled to do so. Rahner develops this notion more fully in Spirit in the W orld. 8 There he observes that man questions, and that this questioning is irreducible because every question presupposes a placing in question. Rahner maintains that man necessarily questions because being in its totality is given to him only as something questionable. For Rahner the ontological implication of the fact that man necessarily questions is the conclusion that man exists as the question about being in its totality. Thus, the question about being as posed by man is the point of departure for metaphysics. Since nothing can be asked about the totally unknown, Rahner observes that the fact that man poses the question about being attests to an a priori grasp of being in general. Thus Rahner believes that he is able to deduce from man's existence, as " the question about existence," the familiar Thomistic teaching that "human thinking is always accompanied by an unexpressed knowledge of being [esse] as the condition of all knowledge of the existing individual." (HW, 36) Rahner proceeds further to note that being can obviously be questioned only insofar as it is known. From this Rahner deduces the Thomistic position that knowability is the most fundamental note of being. "A thing which is, and the possible object of a cognition, are one and the same, for the being of that which is, is knowability." (HW, 38-39) This implies, Rahner argues, the Thomistic position that "being is knowing and being known in their original unity." (HW, 44) The sense of knowing here is not that of reaching from something inside to something outside but is rather conceived as a presence-to-self. "Cf. Karl Rahner, Spirit in the World, trans. William Dych (New York, 1968), pp. 57-78. Hereafter SW. 468 ROBERT MASSON For Rahner, therefore, "the essence of being is the beingpresent-to-itself of being or the luminosity of being to itself as "subjectivity." (HW, 37-44) Rahner argues, furthermore, that although man can deduce the unity of being and knowing from the fact of his existence as the question about being, the questionability of being as such-that is to say, the fact that man has to raise the question, the fact that he is not absolute self-presence-rules out any form of pantheism or "debased idealism." Man "has being," but is not pure absolute being itself. Man is finite. From this fact Rahner argues to the Thomistic notion that being is " analogous." By this term Rahner means to suggest that the "attribution of being itself is an interiorly variable quantity." (HW, 47) In other words, the degree of self-presence or selfluminosity varies from being to being. A finite being is, therefore, only to the degree that it "has being," only to the degree that it has a potentiality for self presence. (HW, 45-52) But what is this being as such which Rahner conceives as self-luminosity and as analogically attributable to all beings? Furthermore, what is man's relation to being? Rahner suggests that the answers to these question can be discovered by an analysis of the act of judgment. In every judgment a predicate is affirmed of a subject. Furthermore, insofar as the judgment is true, it is itself affirmed of something that is in itself independent of the passing of judgment. By this process man establishes the object of his judgment as something different from and independent of his judgment, and therefore as different from and independent of himself. In this way man constitutes himself as a subject opposed to an object. As subject he is able to return to himself by turning out towards (that is to say, by objectifying) the objects with which he is initially one. It is only through this process that man is able to comprehend himself as a subject who subsists-in-himself and who is free (i.e., of that which stands against him) . Now the question which Rahner poses is this: what is "the ultimate cause of the possibility of man, in his subsisting-inhimself, taking a position distinct from the things he handles RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 469 in conscious thought-judgment"? (HW, 56) He argues that in essence this question is only another side of a more familiar problem in Scholastic philosophy. In every judgment a thing is affirmed as a " this " or a " that." This is also true of human activity considered more generally. Man always deals with this particular thing or that. The ability to take hold of this or that particular thing presupposes the ability to comprehend it under a general concept, that is to say, the ability to elevate the perceptions of the senses to the level of the concept. This is what in Thomistic epistemology is called " abstraction." To ask about the condition of possibility of human subsisting-in-self, therefore, is to ask about the possibility of abstraction. (HW, 53-57) Rahner describes absraction as the ability to " loosen away from " or to detach the " thisness " (in Scholastic terminology the form or quiddity) from any example of a particular " this." " Abstraction is thus the recognition of the nonrestriction of the ' thisness ' that is given in the particular sense." (HW, 58) Now in order to elevate the sense impression of a particular "this" to a recognition of a non-restricted "this," the intellect must grasp the particular as "limited." But to recognize this "limit," it must already have grasped it in reference to a " something more." This " something more " is what Rahner means by " being in general." The grasping in terms of this more is what he means by the preconcept (V orgrifj). In each particular cognition it [the intellect] always reaches out beyond the particular object, and thus grasps it, not just as its unrelated, dead "thisness," but in its limitation and reference to the totality of all possible objects. . . . The pre-concept is the condition for the possibility of the universal concept, of the abstraction which in turn is what makes possible the objectification of the datum of sense perception and so of conscious subsistingin-oneself. (HW, 59) Rahner argues that the object of this V orgrifj cannot be an object like those which are made known through the V orgrifj itself. Thus it would appear that to an extent Rahner's position 470 ROBERT MASSON is similar to Heidegger's who, as was shown, holds that " Being " is not like beings. It is in the further elaboration of this a priori grasp that Rahner seems to consciously distinguish his position from Heidegger's. As was seen previously, Rahner believed that Heidegger's Dasein as a transcendence to being is essentially a transcendence to nothingness. This alleged notion, as it was elaborated in WM, was based on the argument that negation can only be grounded in a prior comprehension of" nothingness." Here Rahner argues that just the opposite is the case-that the notion of negation is derived through man's Vorgriff of an absolute "having being" and that the concept of non-being is derived from the notion of negation. 9 Why? Rahner argues that human cognition is related to that which is, and not what is-not-at least insofar as all knowledge begins in sense perception. He maintains that, if the knowledge of the limitation of the objects of knowledge can be explained in terms of a Vorgriff of being as positive, there is no need to posit a transcendence to nothingness. But, Rahner continues, it has already been shown that beings are to the extent that they "have being." They are grasped not in terms of nothing but in terms of a V orgriff of the perfection of pure "having being." Rahner maintains that this can be deduced from the fact of the question of being, from the judgment, and from the freedom of human activity. "To the extent that judgment and free action are necessarily part of man's existence, the pre-concept of being pure and simple in its own intrinsically proper infinitude is part of the fundamental constitution of human existence." (HW, 63) Since Rahner has already ruled out the possibility of pantheism, that being which has being absolutely must be God himself. Thus Rahner claims that: God is posited, too, with the same necessity as this pre-concept. He is the thing of which is affirmed absolute "having existence." I do not mean to suggest that the arguments we considered in Hearers of the Rahner appears to be speaking much more generally. But it also seems that Heidegger's position, as Rahner understands it, is among those which he believes his arguments refute. 0 Word were intended as a direct answer to Heidegger's analysis. HAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 471 It is true that the pre-concept does not present any object at all along with itself. But in this pre-concept (as the necessary and ever already actualized condition for every human cognition and every human action) the existence of an existent thing of absolute "having being" (that is, of God) has already been affirmed if not presented. In the pre-concept the cause of his specific possibility is unknowningly affirmed. (HW, 63-64) Thus Rahner claims that from the very movement of the human intellect we are able to establish the existence of God. Granting this, it is not difficult to see why Rahner rejects any metaphysics which claims that negation must be grounded in a transcendence towards nothingness. Because of the V orgrijj of absolute being, the subject is able to perceive finite beings as limited. Negation is thus derived from the comprehension of a " less " or " limit " in terms of a " more " or " full," The concept of non-being is thus also derived from the Vorgriff of esse absolutum. Non-being does not precede negation, but the pre-concept relative to the unlimited is in itself already the negation of the finite, to the extent that, as condition for the possibility of its cognition, and through its rising above the finite, it reveals, eo ipso, its finitude. The affirmation of the thing that is in itself unlimited is therefore the possibility for negation, and not the other way around. Thus we are not required to assume a transcendence relation to nonbeing, which, preceding all negation and providing its foundation, would have to disclose the finitude of an existent thing for the first time. Positive unlimitation of the transcendental horizon of human knowledge automatically displays the finitude of all that does not fill up this horizon. (HW, 62) These analyses lead Rahner to the conclusion that man by nature is a spirit who is able to affirm the existence of God, and furthermore, because of the analogy of being, he has the potentiality for a more extensive knowledge of God. " Man is the absolute receptivity for being pure and simple." It is not possible to pursue Rahner's existential analysis further. In the discussion which follows, he argues that although being is luminous, man's grasp of it is necessarily limited because of his own finitude. He argues, furthermore, that God as absolute ROBERT MASSON being must be conceived as a free spirit who could reveal more about himself to man if it was his divine will to do so. Because of the very nature of man's receptivity as a composite of body and spirit, the place of such a free revelation would have to be human history and the mode would have to be the sensible word (understood in its broadest meaning as either word or act) . Man, therefore, has a potentiality for "hearing" such an historical word if God speaks. Furthermore, the philosophy of religion can show man his need to look for such a word in history. Perhaps at this point it would be helpful to summarize. Rahner maintains that Heidegger is essentially a metaphysician concerned with establishing a new, more fundamental ontology through a transcendental analysis of man as the one who necessarily poses the question about being. As far as Rahner can tell, however, Heidegger's analysis seems to lead to the conclusion that man transcends towards nothingness. In Hearers of the Word Rahner is also concerned with carrying out an existential analytic of man as the one who necessarily poses the question about being. Like Heidegger he appears to maintain that man is able to raise the question about being because man already has a comprehension of being as such. Like Heidegger he appears to maintain that the being of which man has a pre-comprehension is distinct from all other beings. But unlike Heidegger (as Rahner understands him) , he maintains that the ultimate sense of being is not nothingness but rather God, grasped in the movement of all human affirmation, whether in act or deed, towards pure and absolute "havingbeing." As such, God constitutes not only the object of human activity, but also more significantly, the condition of its possibility. As a composite of body and spirit man possesses the potentiality to receive a further revelation from God if one is given. Man is thus a potential " hearer " of a divine word. * * * Rahner's evaluation of Heidegger's ontology in the article discussed and his implicit refutation of Heidegger's alleged HAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 473 "nihilism" in Hearers of the Word presupposes that Heidegger, like Rahner, is asking about "being as such, under its most general and total aspect." It presupposes that "by most general is meant, ultimately the simple fact of being, esse, characteristic of every ens,'' and that " by most total is meant esse again as the unifying aspect under which every possible object can be grasped, summed up, and related to its ultimate and unique explanation." (CF, 128) Rahner, therefore, is asking about" beings as beings" or" being as being" (ens qua ens) , just as Aristotle and St. Thomas. The difference is that he founds his metaphysics on a transcendental analysis. What is more significant to our discussion is that he presupposes that Heidegger's problematic is, and must be, the same. As Heidegger's thought has developed, however, it has become increasingly clear that his understanding has emerged out of what he believes is a very different question. In the" Introduction" to WM (written in 1949), Heidegger notes that the science which traditionally has been called metaphysics has always asked about being as beings, or about being (the totality of beings) as being. The asking of this question, as Rahner noted, has led according to Heidegger's analysis to two distinct pursuits. The one seeks to understand, that is to say, to represent, that which is common to all beings-their beingness, or in Thomistic terminology esse. This study is called "ontology." The other seeks to understand the beingness of being in terms of their cause or sufficient reason-which for Rahner is esse absolutum (God) -and it is called "theology." 10 Both questions ask about beings, or in terms which Heidegger would insist are misleading, about finite being. Heidegger argues that he is asking a very different question. He is not asking about being but about Being itself as distinct from beings. Thus it will be maintained here that Heidegger's question about Being (it will be helpful to use a capital" B "to designate Heidegger's "Sein ") is different from Rahner's question about being. 10 Here " theology " refers to a branch of metaphysics, not to the Church's explication of Revelation. 474 ROBERT MASSON In An Introduction to Metaphysics Heidegger attempts to introduce the question of Being as he understands it. He maintains there that because metaphysics, in the ordinary sense of the term, is concerned only with questioning beings as beings (ta physika), it can be called a "physics." If philosophic thought is to have a solid foundation, however, it is necessary to go beyond questions about being to the question about Being itself (meta ta physica) . As he saw it in 1935, "even in the doctrines of being as pure act (Thomas Aquinas), as absolute concept (Hegel), as eternal recurrence of the identical will to power (Nietzsche) , metaphysics has remained unalterably 'physics.'" (EM, 14) Heidegger believes that the question of Being which he asks is not at all the same as the question which metaphysicians through the ages have asked. Although this position is more obvious in these later works, it has been the direction of his thought from the very beginning. As his problematic has developed it has become clear that it is not a question of Heidegger giving up metaphysics or gradually disengaging himself from the metaphysical understanding of being. Rather, it is a question of a difference, there from the beginning, between his problematic and that of the tradition, gradually becoming more explicit. 11 It is at the level of the very question asked where the difference begins to emerge between Rahner's question about esse and Heidegger's question about Being itself. It is just this difference, however, which is overlooked if the existential analytic of Dasein proposed in SZ is interpreted, as Rahner interprets it, as an attempt like those of Kant, Descartes, or any modern metaphysician to put metaphysics on a new foundation. It is true, of course, that in the introduction to SZ Heidegger describes his task as the establishing of a " fundamental ontology" through the "existential analytic of Dasein." (SZ, 13) 12 He also suggests, however, that " funda11 The analysis here does not wish to deny that there has been a " tum " in Heidegger's thought; but the fact that there has been a "tum " does not mean that his problem has essentially changed. The fundamental question remains the same even though the questions asked have changed. 12 Italics here and in all following quotes are Heidegger's unless otherwise stated. RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 475 mental ontology " is fundamental not because, as Rahner suggests, it bases the knowledge of being on a new foundation or because it asks the question about beings in a new way but because it asks a question which is more original than any such question about beings. The aim of SZ is not to lay the basis for an answer to the question about being, nor to ask the same question in a new way, but rather " ... to work out the question of Being ... " itself. (SZ, I) Thus, when he says further that " our provisional aim is the interpretation of time as the possible horizon for any understanding whatsoever of Being," (SZ, I) this should be understood to suggest not only that " time " will help to answer the question of Being but primarily and more significantly that time will indicate the very sense of the question itself. It is easy to assume that Heidegger is only polemicizing against Neo-Kantains when he says that it is necessary " to raise anew the question of the meaning of Being." (SZ, I) It becomes clear as he progresses, however, that he is speaking to the whole metaphysical tradition. What are the indications of this thesis in SZ-the principal work that Rahner considered in his essay? In the first place, Heidegger speaks of the need for a " destruction of ontology " and the "history of ontology." (SZ, I9-27) He explains that the need for destruction " is essentially bound up with the way the question of Being is formulated .... " (SZ, 23) Is it to be supposed that Heidegger intends a complete denial of the philosophic past? No, for he insists that the aim of the destruction is positive, as well as negative, and that it can achieve this aim only if it starts within the history of thought. But how begin from a destruction? What is the aim of the destruction? He seems to hint-and seen from the perspective of Heidegger's later works it is a hint difficult to miss-that fundamental ontology will begin from a rediscovery of an original beginning though a destruction of what has followed from it . . . . taking the question of Being as our clue, we are to destroy the traditional content of ancient ontology until we arrive at 476 ROBERT MASSON those primordial experiences in which we achieved our first ways of determining the nature of Being-the ways which have guided us ever since. (SZ, 22) In the pages which follow Heidegger states that this forgottenness of Being applies alike to the Greeks, the Scholastics, Decartes, Kant, and Hegel. Now Rahner had maintained that Heidegger wanted to go beyond the traditional starting point of Metaphysics because he sought a foundation for ontology which did not conceive " being " beforehand in terms of logic. This is true, but only half true. Heidegger is seeking not merely a new foundation but is seeking a new foundation in the asking of a new question. It is because a new question is asked that his ontology is more fundamental. But how precisely is the question of Being as Heidegger understands it different from the metaphysician's notion of being? What is the meaning of the word "Being" in the phrase" the question of Being"? The problem which the metaphysician confronts with SZ, as Rahner noted, is that Heidegger never gets to the task of defining the sense of Being-at least from a metaphysical point of view. What then can be discerned about the question of Being from the SZ analysis? For one thing, it has already been noted that to ask for a metaphysical definition, or even the grounds for one, from SZ is apparently contrary to Heidegger's intention. It seems that what ought to be sought is Heidegger's understanding of how the question should be asked. How? He maintains that the clue to how will be discovered, as Rahner observed, by examining Dasein, the place where the question is asked, and seeing in this examination that " time " is the ultimate transcendental horizon for the question of Being. The existential analytic of Dasein could, then, be called " transcendental " but not in the sense that Rahner gives to the term. In seeking an understanding of Dasein's comprehension of Being Heidegger is proposing to lay the basis for a question which he maintains that Kant never posed. Heidegger wants it to be understood that the question which guides him has been ignored and forgotten in metaphysics and ontology. The term of that question-Being RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 471 -should not be understood in terms o£ the history o£ philosophy and so not as a " transcendental philosophy " in the traditional sense. Rahner's contention that Heidegger is essentially a transcendental philosopher is thus very misleading i£ not altogether incorrect. What, then, does Heidegger reveal about the term o£ his inquiry in SZ? First, he tells us that Being is "that which determines beings as beings, that on the basis o£ which beings are already understood .... " (SZ, 6) Although-or perhaps because-Being is that which determines beings and is common to them all, Heidegger insists that Being is not a being or in any way like beings. The Being of beings "is" not itself a being. If we are to undersand the problem of Being, our first philosophic step consists in not p:u86v nva in not "telling a story "-that is to say, in not defining beings as beings by tracing them back in their origin to some other beings, as if Being had the character of some possible being. (SZ, 6) Heidegger makes the same point when he says: Being as the basic theme of philosophy is no class or genus of beings, yet it pertains to every being. Its " universality" is to be sought higher up. Being and the structure of Being lie beyond every being and every character which a being may possess. Being is the transcendens pure and simple. (SZ, 38) This transcending, however, is not an abstraction, nor does Heidegger propose to seek it through abstraction. Rather, he intends to " work out the question o£ the meaning o£ Being and to do so concretely." (SZ, I) A further indication o£ what Heidegger intends to interrogate in the question about Being can be found in his analysis o£ the word " phenomenology." The term originates £rom two Heidegger maintains that Greek words: cf>avvofLEvov and cf>avvOfLEVov signifies that which shows itself in itself or manifests itself as itself. "Accordingly the c/>atvofLEVa or 'phenomena' are the totality o£ what lies in the light o£ day or can be brought to light-what the Greeks sometimes identified simply with Ttl. oVTa (beings)." (SZ, 28) For Heidegger, however, this 478 ROBERT MASSON "showing-itself-in-itself, signifies a distinctive way in which something can be encountered." (SZ, 31) Heidegger maintains that the real meaning of the second term, A.Oyos-, has been covered up by later interpretations of it as reason, judgment, concept, definition, ground or relationship. He argues that the word originally meant to make manifest what one is talking about. It is a " letting something be seen." Phenomenology thus means to let be manifest or un-hidden that which manifests itself. What then does phenomenology let be seen? Heidegger argues that: Manifestly, it is something that proximally and for the most part does not show itself at all: it is something that lies hidden, in contrast to that which proximally and for the most part does show itself; but at the same time it is something that belongs to it so essentially as to constitute its meaning and its ground. (SZ, 35) What can this something be? Heidegger argues that it is Being. Yet that which remains hidden in an egregious sense, or which relapses and gets covered up again, or which shows itself only "in disguise," is not just this or that, but rather the Being of beings, as our previous observations have shown. This Being can be cove.red up so extensively that it becomes forgotten and no questions arise about it or about its meaning. (SZ, 60) This analysis of the meaning of " phenomenology " is not meant merely as a digression into the nature of Heidegger's methodology. Rather it intends to reveal a basic characteristic of Heidegger's understanding of Being which gets developed already in his conception of phenomenology as the only adequate way to do fundamental ontology. That which shows itself is the Being of beings. Being as a "showing-itself is not just any showing itself." It is not just something like appearing. Being is the foundation of any kind of appearing at all. It underlies all beings. Behind this showing-itself (Being), there is nothing else. Yet it is the character of this showing-itself, that it can be hidden and forgotten while one gazes on the beings it lets be manifest. (SZ, 36-37) Heidegger is thus seeking the meaning of the Being of beings. RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 479 Although Being appears to be correlative with the beings which it manifests., it is also distinct from them. It is not in any sense a being, or like beings. For this reason one cannot speak about Being in any way like one would speak about beings. Nor can Being be thought of as proceeding from a being. It is a " pure transcending " which is beyond beings. But note, Heidegger does not say Being is a transcendent (noun), for example, a transcendent Being. He rejects as missing the issue any question which like the one posed by Rahner seeks to trace beings to a cause (i.e., God). This is why Heidegger insists that his thought does not speak either for or against the existence of God. From the perspective of his question the problem of God does not arise. Since Rahner, however does not note the difference between his question (the metaphysical question) and Heidegger's, he is not able to see how Heidegger can claim that the analysis has not prejudged the God issue. Heidegger, however, is not seeking to determine the source of beings, but the meaning of Being itself. Being is that manifesting by which beings are " present " to Dasein. Although Being manifests itself in its manifesting of beings, in the coming-topresence of beings, it remains itself concealed. It remains itself a manifesting, not a manifested. Being needs therefore, to be brought from concealment to non-concealment. The analysis of Dasein as the place where Being is revealed, and also forgotten, shows that this comprehension takes place through the temporal structure of Dasein and thus suggests that " time " is the clue or horizon through which the meaning of Being can be questioned. SZ has not thought Being, however, merely by giving this clue or discovering this horizon. Heidegger concludes his analysis insisting that " the dispute in regard to the interpretation of Being cannot be straightened out, because it has not even been begun." (SZ, 437) It can be surmised from this that Heidegger would argue that the trouble with Rahner's evaluation of SZ is that it has not even recognized the question. It completely misses the point. Rahner's principle criticism of Heidegger, however, is not based on the analyses of SZ so much as on the arguments of 480 ROBERT MASSON · WM. According to Rahner the conclusion of these arguments seems to be that the ultimate sense of being is " nothingness." This criticism again misses the real issue. It is true that in WM Heidegger proposes to understand Being in terms of the: problem of" Nothing" (Nichts). Heidegger's use of this term, however, is carefully nuanced and should not be equated with some sort of metaphysical " nothingness." WM was originally written as a lecture for an audience composed mostly of scientists. It proposed to introduce a question which the sciences as such do not consider, namely, the metaphysical question. It must be noted from the start, however, that Heidegger is defining metaphysics as he conceives it, not as it has been conceived historically. Heidegger maintains that the sciences consider that which-is and nothing more. He claims that the " and nothing more " is intrinsic to the sciences' conception of their subject matter. But how conceive this Nothing without representing it as some thing? The question, "What is Nothing?" seems to demand the illogical reply that, "Nothing is this or that thing," when it is known perfectly well that Nothing is not any thing. To avoid this" logical" problem Heidegger suggest an examination of the off-the-cuff definition of Nothing as the negation of the totality-of-what-is. This could perhaps be reasonably maintained if the totality-of-what-is could be known or conceived in itself, but it cannot. Thus another impass has been reached. It is not an inescapable impass. Even though the whole of whatis in its totality is not accessible in itself, " it is equally certain that we find ourselves placed in the midst of what-is and that this is somehow revealed in totality." (WM,333) How is it revealed? Recalling the analysis of SZ, Heidegger maintains that the totality is grasped on the level of " disposition," and that this grasp is revealed in moods such as boredom or the joy felt in the presence of a loved one. This dispositional awareness constitutes an essential mode of Dasein's being-inthe-world. As Rahner noted, it is not just a matter of feeling but the ground for the possibility of any knowledge of beings. Unfortunately this awareness of the totality-of-what-is still does RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 481 not tell anything about Nothing, for it is a revelation of and absorption in the totality-of-what-is. It appears to exclude any revelation of the opposite, that which absolutely is not, namely, Nothing. Heidegger maintains, however, that there are moods, although perhaps rare, which reveal Nothing itself. Such is the mood of profound dread (Angst). Heidegger's description of this mood is classic. In dread, as we say, "one feels something uncanny." ·what is this "something" (es) and this "one"? We are unable to say what gives " one " the, uncanny feeling. One just feels it generally (im Ganzen). All things and we with them, sink into a sort of indifference. But not in the sense that everything simply disappears; rather, in the very act of drawing away from us everything turns towards us. This withdrawal of what-is-in-totality, which the,n crowds round us in dread, this is what oppresses us. There is nothing to hold on to. The only thing that remains and overwhelms us whilst what-is slips away, is this "nothing." Dread reveals Nothing . . . . Dread hold us in suspense because it makes what-is-intotality slip away from us. (WM, 336) The experience of dread witnesses, then, what Heidegger describes most evocatively as the failure of all " ' Is '-saying (' Ist'-Sagen) ." (WM, 336) Heidegger concludes from this analysis that negation does not precede or ground the grasp of Nothing, but on the contrary, the grasp of Nothing precedes and grounds negation. Nothing is revealed but not as any thing, and not as the negation of any or even all things. This grasp of Nothing is not just an interesting but irrelevant fact. Science, our knowledge of what-is, knows what-is only in distinction from what-isnot (i.e., Non-being or No-thing). Similarly, SZ and KM argued that knowledge of beings (what-is) is possible only because Dasein can pass beyond that which-is. What is the term of this passing beyond? It is not any thing, not what-is-intotality, but rather Nothing-that is to say, no thing. Nothing turns out to be one with Being as such. It is to Being as not any thing that Dasein transcends, and it is Being as Nothing which makes the revelation of what-is possible. ROBERT MASSON Nothing is neither an object nor anything that" is" at all. Nothing occurs neithe.r by itself nor "apart from" what-is, as a sort of adjunct. Nothing is that which makes the revelation of what-is as such possible for our human existence. (WM, 340) Here is the essential difference between Rahner's notion of Being and Heidegger's. Rahner maintains that the subject can know beings only because it sees them within the horizon of a " more." This seeing within the horizon of a more is possible because the subject already grasps (though non-thematically) absolute being in the direction of all human thought and activity. He claims, therefore, that negation and the concept of non-being are derived from this grasp of the limited as limited (i.e., partially negated) in terms of absolute being. What is most important is that he claims that these observations constitute the basis for a proof of God's existence. Heidegger, on the other hand, does not maintain as Rahner suggests that Dasein transcends toward nothingness. Rather, he argues that Dasein transcends (the term is misleading) to Being as no thing. Heidegger claims that a metaphysical analysis such as Rahner's leaves unasked the question about the meaning of Being as different from beings and as that " different " which makes the revelation of beings possible. Rahner had argued that the knowledge of beings demands as its condition of possibility a V orgriff of an absolute being. Heidegger maintains to the contrary, not that knowledge of beings must be explained by nothingness but that it can be explained sufficiently only by the recognition that Dasein grasps Being as different from beings. In the later works Heidegger comes to the realization (the famous "tum") that it is not just that Dasein grasps Being as different from beings but rather that Dasein itself is grasped-grasped in the " event " of the ontological difference. Still it is the ontological difference which opens up the world of beings and Being to Dasein. Rahner uses the term "ontological difference" in Hearers of the Word, and in The Thomist Spectrum Helen John claims HAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 483 that Rahner is aware of the ontological difference. 13 It appears from what has been seen here, however, that in a metaphysical context that term must have a very different meaning than Heidegger gives it. Heidegger would argue that to think the meaning of this difference in terms of being-even in terms of a supreme absolute having-being-is an extrapolation which has avoided the real question that needs asking. Such thinking represents Being as a being instead of probing the meaning of Being as such. It assumes an answer to the question which Heidegger wants to pose. WM, therefore, does not propose that man transcends toward nothingness. Rather it suggests that before we ask about the possibility of Dasein transcending to something, we ought first to ask what is Being as such, as different from beings. The reflection on Non-being or Nothing was intended, like the analysis of Dasein in SZ, to serve as an introduction to the question about Being as Heidegger understands it. How, then, phrase the ground question of metaphsics? Heidegger suggests the formula: "Why is there any being at all-why not far rather nothing? " (WM, 345) The implications of this formula are developed in An Introducticm to Metaphysics. It should be clear by now that for Heidegger the phrase "rather than nothing" is not a mere explication of the question, "Why are there beings?" Rather, it indicates that the question asked is not a question about beings. It is a question about Being as such, for it " remains unclear what is to be thought under the name' Being.'" (EM, 26) Heidegger claims that " here we are asking about something which we barely grasp, which is scarcely more than the sound of a word for us .... " (EM, 27) Intrinsic, then, to the question "Why are there beings rather than nothing?" is the question "How does it stand with Being? " It is "indispensable that we make it clear from the very outset how it stands at present with Being and with our understanding of Being." (EM, 27) In asking this question Heidegger does not propose to define Being, for, as he insisted even in SZ, Being 18 Helen James John, The Thomist Spectrum (New York, 1966), p. 168. 484 ROBERT MASSON is not a thing and therefore cannot be defined. Rather, he claims that the question "How does it stand with Being?" seeks to rediscover for its own what the word "Being" says. It does not seek meaning in a statement but in a question and in a questioning attitude, through which Heidegger hopes to recapture or retrieve the beginning of our "historical-spiritual existence." (EM, 32) Heidegger insists again that "fundamental ontology " in SZ did not designate a branch of philosophy which deals only with a doctrine about beings (i.e., their cause and nature) but rather signified "the endeavor to make Being manifest itself, and to do so by the question ' how does it stand with Being?' (and not with beings as such)." (EM, 34) Heidegger maintains that the very asking of this question is the only way to experience the sense of Being. In asking it Being is manifested even though in a way which is at once both totally indeterminate and highly determinate. (cf. EM, 60) The question of Being, therefore, does not seek something which we know, or can know-except by questionmg. The true problem is what we do not know and what, insofar as we know it authentically, namely as a problem, we know only questioningly. To know how to que,stion means to know how to wait, even a whole lifetime. But an age which regards only what goes fast and can be clutched with both hands looks on questioning as " remote from reality" and as something that does not pay, whose benefits cannot be numbere,d. But the essential is not number. . . . (EM, 172) This last statement perhaps raises more questions than it answers. How does one know Being questioningly? How does one think Being as such, that is to say, as different from beings? It is just this question that focuses Heidegger's reflection in his later work, and it is in reference to this question that the sense of " hearing " or " attending " is developed. A thorough and adequate examination of this problem would demand more attention than it is possible to give it here, but some idea of what sense "hearing" can have in regard to Heidegger's RAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 485 question of Being can be indicated by pursuing the analysis of EM a little further. In Rahner's summary of Heidegger's thought it was observed that Heidegger opposes any consideration of the Being question in terms of logic. In our analysis of WM it was shown that the reason Heidegger opposes the domination of the question of Being by logic is that logic as understood today is a science which deals with the consideration o£ beings. In the third section of the fourth chapter of EM Heidegger considers the relation of Being and thought. In that discussion it becomes clear that Heidegger opposes logic because there is a more primary sense of which is the ground of what we now understand by the term. This more primary sense of logos is what ought to determine our thought. In the development of this notion the sense of " hearing " is presented. Heidegger maintains that logic as the science of thought is today understood as the science of statements. Thinking, in this view therefore, is determined by the statement. Logos means " word " or " discourse " and legein means " to speak," as in dialogue or monologue. Heidegger argues, however, that for the Greeks logos originally meant " to gather" or " to collect." Heidegger cites examples from Homer and Heraclitus to illustrate his point and claims that the sense of these passages can be understood only if we understand logos as originally denoting the collecting collectedness of Being as that which manifests beings. Logos characterizes Being in a new and yet old respect: that which is, which stands straight and distinct in itself, is at the same time gathered togetherness in itself and by itse,lf, and maintains itself in such togetherness. (EM, 110) Logos is thus, according to Heidegger, originally understood as Being itself insofar as it is the gathering together of all that is. "Logos here signifies neither meaning nor word nor doctrine, and surely not' meaning of a doctrine'; it means: the original collecting collectedness which is in itself permanently dominant." (EM, 108) 486 ROBERT MASSON Heidegger notes that there is one text, however, which seems to contradict his theory. In Fragment 50 a connection is made between logos and " hearing " which seems to suggest that logos is something " audible" (i.e., a word or speech) : "If you have heard not me but the logos, then it is wise to say accordingly: all is one." (EM, 108) Heidegger argues that Heraclitus is not referring here to a hearing of " words " but to a hearing or attending to that which makes words possible, namely, an attending to Being itself. Only in this way can it be explained why men are described by Heraclitus as uncomprehending when they confront the logos. Heidegger maintains that properly understood Fragment 50 says "do not attach importance to words but heed the logos." For Heidegger, then, " True hearing has nothing to do with ear and mouth, but means to follow the logos and what it is, namely, the collectedness of beings itself." (EM, 109) Thus by " hearing " Heidegger once again refers us to the Being question. There can be true speaking and hearing only in an attending to Being itself. As Heidegger sees it, this attending is in fact the origin of the definition of man in terms of logos. The definition is not accomplished by "seizing upon any attributes in the living creature called ' man ' as opposed to other living creatures." Rather " being-human is logos, the gathering and apprehending of the Being of beings: it is the happening of that strangest of all, in whom through violence, through acts of power ... , the overpowering is made manifest and made to stand." (EM, 143) "Hearing" for Heidegger, therefore, defines the essence of man as " existence," as the place where Being is manifested and is thus quite different from Rahner's notion of man as a "hearer." * * * It is unfortunate that Heidegger's notion of the type of thought proper to Being cannot be pursued further. 14 This uSee William J. Richardson's Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague, 1963), to which the thesis presented here is much indebted. HAHNER AND HEIDEGGER 487 essay, however, was meant only as a preliminary delimitation of the essential difference between Rahner's thought and Heidegger's, and this aim has been reached. It is at the very level of the question asked that their philosophies confront each other. It seems necessary to stress that this difference is prior to, although not separate from, the question of methodology. I say this because Thomists who attempt to evaluate Heidegger's philosophy often seem to suggest that the real difference between their metaphysics and Heidegger's phenomenology is that the latter, because of the limitations of his method, cannot pursue the question of being as far as the metaphysician can. This interpretation seems to imply that the limitations of this methodology are due primarily to epistemological presuppositions. Rahner, for example, does not seem to feel that there is any reason why, if he wanted, Heidegger could not advance his thought beyond fundamental ontology to the question of God-which, of course, is vvhat Rahner does as a follower of Aquinas. But this interpretation presupposes that, although Heidegger's method is different, his question is the same. It has been shown here, however, that the question is not the same-or at least Heidegger does not believe it is the same. The question of Being as Heidegger experiences it is a question about Being as such. It is a question about that " manifesting " by which beings are manifest. It is not a question of representing the "beingness" of beings either in terms of what is common to them or in terms of the being (absolute or otherwise) that is their cause. In fact, the question of Being is not a question of representing any thing. It is a question about that which is not a being, which cannot be thought (represented) as a being, but which nevertheless is manifested as the manifesting of beings. It is a question, which as far as we have followed it here, finds its resolution in the questioning itseifman attending to Being. If this is true, Heidegger's notion of Being is not so much determined by his method, as his method is determined by the question itself. Heidegger does not make the metaphysical move beyond Being to God, because he 488 ROBERT MASSON believes that such a move originates from a radical misunderstanding of Being. Does this mean that, if one accepts Heidegger's analysis, one must forsake the problem of God and consequently the philosophy of religion? Although it seems clear that one would have to forsake the metaphysical " God " and the philosophy of religion as Rahner understands it, it is not at all clear to me that one would have to forsake either God or theology, although both would have to be thought through at a much more fundamental level. RoBERT Loyola College Baltimore, Maryland MAssoN WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE O NE OF THE CENTRAL criticisms of the empirical tradition is that it cuts the heart and spirit out of man and sorrowfully limits him to the starkly cold realm of facticity. Empiricism, say its critics, radically limits man to the world of objective facts and dogmatically asserts that the only things which exist are those things of a material and immediately knowable nature. Those things that are not knowable to science or to some form of objective analysis or measurement simply do not exist. Within such a perspective such questions as God, the reality of the soul, and the concept of infinity are immediately denied as being de facto impossible. While this criticism may be true of a number of empiricists, there are highly influential exceptions, among whom is William James. Although James was an avowed spokesmen of pragmatism and radical empiricism, he was never willing to absolutely limit man's perspective of reality to the immediate facts of experience. James contended that facts are simply not enough and that man can out-strip the bald facts of experience through the actualization of his willing nature or personal commitments of faith. Early in his career James discovered what he felt to be the proper vehicle for escaping the limitations of a radically empirical world view through his readings of the French philosopher Charles Renouvier. "I think that yesterday (April 29, 1870) was a crisis in my life. I finished the first part of Renouvier's second 'Essais' and see no reason why his definition of Free Will-' the sustaining of a thought because I choose to when I might have other thoughts '-need be the definition of an illusion. At any rate, I will assume for the present-until next year-that it is no illusion. My first acl: 489 490 A. R. GINI of free will shall be to believe in free will." 1 By accepting the reality of faith, belief, and/or free will James freed himself from the " Bayblonian Captivity " of " brute facts " and opened himself to the possibility of fulfilling his existential desires and religious needs. It is my contention that, for James, the fiat of faith became the main ingredient for all adjudications that man makes in the fields of philosophy, science, daily living, and, most importantly, religion. The burden of this study shall be an attempt to show how faith pervades the various sectors of James's over-all thought, especially in regard to religion. I shall attempt to specify all those factors which go into each personal act of faith in regard to the various circumstances in which faith acts are necessitated. By so doing I hope to free James from the usual pejoratives associated with the empirical tradition. I also hope to show that Professor James was not merely a spokesman for " popular pragmatism" who was only interested in the "cash value" of men's individual and immediate actions but that James was a highly refined philosopher whose sensitivities also included the ultimate goals and morals needs of all men. * * * * Let us begin our investigation of the doctrine of "free will" or the " gospel of belief or faith" by defining the terms " will," "belief," and "faith." First of all, by the term "will" James does not wish to indicate a specifically definable organ of the body or a section of the brain. The will is a generic term which expresses the volitional, active, or selective nature of man. The will is man's natural ability to choose or select between two or more alternatives. Thus, " to will " means to " act " or " choose " between a this or a that. In a very real sense, then, "to will" is to "act" on a singular "commitment" between a plurality of possible options; or another way of expressing it would be to say that the will is man's power or faculty of de1 Wm. James, The Letters of William James, ed. by Henry James, III (Boston: Little, Brown and Co., pp. 147, 148. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 491 liberate choice and action. By the term " belief " James meant an individual's consent or assent to the existence, reality, or truth of a specific something, somewhere, rather than something-else. Belief is an aspect of our active nature, which like will is interested in the acceptance or rejection of a this or a that. 2 For James, belief in a particular subject matter, hypothesis, or situation means a man's willingness to act irrevocably upon it to the exclusion of its contradictory ideas, hypotheses, or situations. 3 In The Principles of Psychology James accepts the Scottish psychologist, Alexander Bain' s statement that "in its essential character, belief is a phase of our active nature-otherwise called the will." 4 In other words, James felt that the concepts of brief and will are so closely tied together that in actuality belief served as the trigger to man's will and powers of active choice; that action, itself, and the will to act are the end results of a man's belief. James later goes one step beyond this by stating that will and belief are not merely closely allied but that they are, in fact, "two names for one and the same psychological phenomenon." 5 In short, both operations are acts of specific and deliberate choice in conjunction with the alternatives available; therefore, to believe is to act or to believe is to will to act: all deliberate actions are guided by our beliefs. Building on the insights he gathered from Renouvier and Bain James went on to develop his own understanding of the term "faith." " Faith means belief in something concerning which doubt is still theoretically possible; as the test of belief is the willingness to act, one may say that faith is the readiness to act in a cause the prosperous issue of which is not certified to us in advance. It is, in fact, the same moral quality which we call courage in practical affairs .... " 6 What is important 2 Cf., Wm. James, The Principles of Psychology (New York: Dover Publications, Inc.), Vol. II, p. 283. 8 Cf., Wm. James, The Will to Believe (New York: Dover Publications, Inc.), p. 3, (Hereafter: WTB). • The Principles of Psychology, Vol. II, p. 296. 6 Ibid., Vol. II, p. 321. "WTB, p. 90. A. R. GINI to notice in this definition of faith is James's commitment to action. That is to say, faith does not merely mean intellectual acceptance or just saying that one has faith in this or that; faith means active engagement or a willingness to act, especially under conditions of risk in ways dictated by the meaning of the particular act of faith in question. At its face value James's definition of faith in using the term "belief" seems clumsy. However, I believe that this clumsiness can be resolved if we are willing to accept the following interpretation. The notions of faith and belief are so interrelated and intertwined that they not only serve as synonyms for each other but are, in fact, one and the same thing. I base this statement on James's own pragmatic theory of truth which states that, if no practical differences can be found between two alternative positions or terms before us, then the alternatives mean practically the same thing. That is, if each term's respective consequences are the same, then the terms mean literally the same thing. 7 Is this not the case between the terms faith and belief? Both terms refer to a specific and deliberate choice between a this or a that; both terms suggest that one's choice should then be implemented by specific actions in regards to that choice. If this is the case, then, the dispute or problematics of the situation is idle and meaningless. Moreover, since faith and belief mean pragmatically the same thing and since belief and will are essentially the same psychological acts, I submit that all three terms refer to one and the same happening or occurence and, therefore, can be used in a synonymous fashion. Furthermore, these three terms are also synonymous with the expression free will. Again this identification is well warranted because, pragmatically speaking, one cannot identify any essential difference between an act of free will, a commitment of faith, or an act of belief. In other words, an act of free will is the actual manifestation of a faith commitment or an act of belief which chooses to accept as true one particular statement, thought, or thing when others are possible. Another more Jamesian way of ex7 Cf., Wm. James, Pragmatism (Clevland and New York: Meridian Books, 1968), pp. 4ft-48. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 493 pressing this same point would be: Free Will-is the specific acceptance or belief in a thought because I deliberately choose to when I might have accepted or chosen other thoughts or alternatives. Taking all of this into consideration, I do not believe I am bastardizing the spirit or the letter of James's own words by suggesting that what James means by a man's will, free will, faith and/or belief ultimately and only refers to each man's ability and right to accept as true any aspect of reality, which does not immediately confute reality, on the strength of his own personal desires or needs. * * * * In all of Professor James's work and writings on the question of faith or free will his purpose was always and only to establish the reality of the act of faith and not the reality of the particular facts of faith. Professor R. B. Perry helps to substantiate this thesis when he pointed out that James wrote The Will to Believe in an attempt to justify belief and not for the purpose of trying to convince us that God exists. 9 James stated that faith is an essential ingredient of our mental make-up. 10 In fact, he stated that faith is one of mankind's inalienable birth-rights 11 and that the only escape from the powers of faith is mental nullity. 12 He suggested that we cannot live or think at all without some degree of faith; that in the total game of life we stake our persons often and regularly on commitments of faith. James accepted the proposition that faith is one of man's basic abilities; that man's freedom to choose the attitude he takes toward his own fate may not change the fate but it will greatly change the man! Certainly, we are all born of woman, struggle through various stages of growth and ulti8 Cf., George Santayana, Character and Opinion in the United States (New York: George Braziller, 1955), pp. 45, 46. 9 Cf., Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William JamefS (Briefer Version), (New York and Evanston: Harper Torch Books), p. 215. 1 ° Cf., WTB, p. 91. 11 Cf., Wm. James, Some ProblemB of Philosophy (New York: Longmons, Green and Co., 1940), p. 225. 12 Cf., WTB, p. 93. 494 A. R. GINI mately die; what we think about and believe in will not change these brute facts. However, our thoughts and beliefs will vastly change how we negotiate these three-score and ten. Clearly, James was convinced that it was not only pragmatically efficient but clinically sound for a man to ultilize his powers of belief; he was totally committed to the proposition that each individual at his own risk has a right to believe in any hypothesis that is alive enough to tempt his wilU 3 For him, faith, like life, is a gamble. Therefore, he felt that each man can either doubt, believe, or deny as he sees fit because he runs his own risk, and he has the natural right to choose which one it shall be. 14 Each man must act as he thinks best and if he is wrong, so much the worse for him. 15 For many people, The Will to Believe has been taken to mean that you not only can, but that you should, believe anything you care to believe and that, with regard to anything you desire to be true, you can force yourself to believe it to be true against all incoming evidence if only your will is strong enough. This is simply not the case at all. James placed clear limitations on our right to believe. It is only under certain well-defined conditions that the will or right to believe becomes operative at all. James never intended this doctrine to serve as a blanket policy covering all occasions, and he never suggested that it gives us an unlimited license which entitles us to determine truth as we so see fit even in the face of evidence to the contrary. In other words, James's formal and intended definition of faith should not be confused with the negativity and pure subjectivism of the age-old school boy dictum: " Faith is when you believe something that you know ain't true." 16 James maintained that the definition of faith is a positive assertion based not on mere blind trust but on warranted or at least hypothetical possibility: i. e., " Faith means belief in something concerning which doubt is still theoretically possible." The key term in this phrase is the word " possible." In fact, the basic premise underlying James's assertion that 18 10 Cf., ibid., p. Cf., ibid., pp. 94, 95, (Note) . 15 16 Cf., ibid., pp. 30, 31. Ibid., p. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 495 man has the right to choose or believe is the brute reality that the world continuously offers each man the possibility of acting in many diverse ways. In other words, in a world where possibilities exist, belief is not only justified but necessary. Professor James suggested that every student of philosophy is all too painfully aware of the myriad of possibilities and choices that the actual world and the academic community are constantly placing before him. A quick look at the contradictory opinions which exist about the same topics helps to give a picture of the range of the problem and leads one to believe that we can find no proposition ever regarded by anyone as evidently certain, that has not either been called a falsehood or at least had its truth sincerely questioned by someone else: the world is rational through and through -vs- its existence is one ultimate brute fact; there is a personal God -vs- a personal God is inconceivable; there is an extra-mental physical world immediately known to the mind -vs- the mind only knows its own ideas; a moral imperative exists -vs- obligation is only the resultant of desires; there is an endless chain of causes -vs- there is only an absolute first cause; there is this -vs- there is that; etc. 17 All of this serves to indicate James's belief that the actual facts of experience, pure reason, and logic are sometimes insufficient in themselves to mitigate and explain the occurrences and happenings of reality. Reason or facts may be lacking on three separate accounts: 1) the given evidence whetherrational or factual is insufficient, i.e., it does not take us far enough to warrant a decision; 2) the evidence as presented is incomplete, i.e., all the facts are not in yet; 3) finally, it is also possible that the mind simply cannot grasp the evidence presented to it, i.e., the intellect even with truth directly in its grasp may have no infallible signal for knowing whether it be true or not! 18 In concreto what James was saying is that because of natural limitations of reason and fact very often the actions and activities of men's lives are triggered or inaugurated by something other than our intellectual nature. James called 17 Cf., ibid., p. 16. 18 Cf., ibid., p. 16. 496 A. R. GINI the non-rational aspect of the human character man's passional nature, and he stated that " our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must decide on options between propositions, whenever it is a genuine option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds; for to say, under such circumstances ' do not decide, but leave the question open,' is itself a passional decision,-just like deciding yes or no,-and is attended with the same risk of losing the truth." 19 In lieu of this, what James is implying is that man does not merely have a " will to believe," which is in effect a " right to believe," but in a very real existential sense, taking into consideration the laws of the mind and the laws of experimental science, man has a "need to believe." For James, man cannot live or think at all without some faith in the various hypotheses concerning reality. 20 Without the powers of belief, based on at least warranted assertability, man is led to the edge of the slope, at the bottom of which lies pyrrhonistic skepticism, absolute pessimism, and intellectual suicide. 21 In the final analysis, said James, not all things are available to the laws of logic, nor are they knowable to the laws of science. It is true that in the last three hundred years science has mushroomed, but what we know now is but the minutest glimpse of what the universe will prove to be when adequately understood. In other words, our knowledge and our science is but a drop and our ignorance is a sea, therefore, man must oftentimes base his decisions on the subjective propensities of his personal feelings and desires. 22 When reason and facts break down, a man's temperament is the tyrannical and controlling force which determines all faith options and belief commitments.23 Human passions, he said, are often stronger than technical rules, 24 and when all else fails, pretend what we may, the whole man within us is at work when we form our opinions, philosophical and otherwise. 25 James suggests that no matter 19 2 Ibid., p. 11. ° Cf., ibid., p. 95. 21 22 Cf., ibid., p. 39. Cf., ibid., p. 54. Cf., ibid., pp. Cf., ibid., p. 25 Cf., ibid., p. 23 2• WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 497 how undignified and unacademic it might sound, the whole history of man's opinions and ideas are to a great extent passional decisions and judgments based on a certain clash of human temperaments. Each man's temperament loads the evidence for him one way or the other, making for a more sentimental or a more hard-hearted view of the universe. Men trust their temperaments, and they seek a representation of reality that suits them. Each man feels that men of the opposite temper are out of key with the real character of the world. 26 The diversity in man's active impulses, said James, can be easily examplified by suggesting that a philosophy fit for Bismarck obviously will not be fit for acceptance by a valetudinarian poet. 27 By reason of Bismarck's postulates of faith or rationality (i.e., choices or active decisions) he perceives the world to belong to the strong, and a world in which cold steel and strength determines all. On the other hand, the poet, by his postulates of rationality, perceives reality to be quiet, weak, and in poor health. 28 In the introduction to The Will to Believe James adamantly denies that he can be accused of preaching the use of blind or reckless faith. His intended purpose from the very beginning was to preach the right of man to indulge his personal faith when he felt it was warranted. He agreed that at best this was a risky business and that there was no sure or definite method of always attaining truth by this means. However, he said, we must expose ourselves to the dangers and try to steer the middle ground between believing too much and believing too •• Cf., Pragmatism, p. 19. •• Cf., WTB, pp. 88, 89. •• James's argument concerning the tyrannical character of our temperament is based on two fundamental suppositions: " first, when we make theories about the world and discuss them one with another, we do so in order to attain a conception of things which shall give us subjective satisfaction; and second, if there be two conceptions, and the one seems to us, on the whole, more rational (i.e., more suited to our needs) than the other, we are entitled to suppose that the more rational one is the truer of the two." (WTB, p. 146) In other words, each individual accepts as true oniy those theories, ideas, or philosophies which not only account satisfactorily for his sensible needs and experiences but which also appeal most urgently to his aesthetic, emotional, and active needs. 498 A. R. GIN! little. It simply does not follow, said James, that because faith can be reckless that faith commitments should never be trusted or never be indulged in. He believed that there are certain safeguards, which if followed closely, help to minimize the irresponsibility of faith and help to give it real credibility and import in our lives. 29 First of all, he suggests that we give the name of hypothesis to anything that may be proposed to our belief; furthermore, he stated, that, just as electricians speak of live and dead wires, let us refer to any hypothesis as either live or dead. Very simply, a live hypothesis is one which appears as a real possibility to whom it is proposed. James maintained that the aliveness or deadness of any given hypothesis is not an intrinsic property of the hypothesis but exists only in relationship to the individual thinker. That is to say, the acceptance of every hypothesis is a purely subjective affair. Secondly, he suggested that we call the decision between two hypotheses an option. He stated that options may be of several kinds: living or dead; forced or avoidable; momentous or trivial. In regard to a faith commitment we may call an option genuine when it is forced, living, and momentous. A living option is one in which the both alternatives are real possibilities or choices for the individual involved; e. g., "Are you going to go to college or are you going to work instead? " A forced option is one in which there is no possibility of not choosing; e. g., "Either accept this particular truth or go without it, you have no other alternative! " A momentous option is a unique opportunity that happens usually but once in a lifetime: e. g., "Would you like to be a crew member on one of the forthcoming space flights?" Finally, James pointed out that faith cannot be so independent that it can contradict at its own pleasure matters of fact which are either immediate or remote. In other words, just by willing it we cannot believe that Abraham Lincoln's existence was a myth, nor can we by any effort of our will believe ourselves well and about when we are roaring with rheumatism in bed; •• Cf., WTB, pp. X,XI, (Preface). WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 499 or feel certain that the sum of the two one-dollar bills in our pocket must be a hundred dollars. It is true, said James, that we can" say" any of these things, but that will not change the reality of their objective existence. Whether I like them or not, certain facts are given irrespective of my wishes, and in all that concerns truths such as these subjective preferences do not and should not play a part. 30 In effect, Professor James is saying that all living options are judgments and, since every specific judgment requires a specific act of faith. Faith is that active and necessary element which pervades every situation in which man is required to make a judgment concerning the world of objective reality. Moreover, besides all of man's volitional actions, James felt that most of man's habitual actions are dependent on the operation of his will and the powers of faith and selectivity. In a broad sense, said James, the faith act designates our entire capacity for an impulsive and active life, including our instinctive reactions and those forms of behavior that have become secondarily automatic and semi-unconscious through frequent repetition. In the narrower and more usual sense acts of faith and will are such acts which cannot be inattentively performed. In all vital decisions or judgments a distinct idea of what is involved and a deliberate fiat on the mind's part must precede their execution. 31 Thus, in every instance where a judgment is necessary, the individual's choice is all important; this choice is determined by the amount of faith one has in a particular alternative before him. To be more precise, we choose a particular alternative because we believe that the results of our choice will be the most beneficial for us. 32 In this manner faith verifies itself by virtue of its own actions. In other words, every faith commitment must be judged by its fruits and not by its roots, for in the last analysis faith is measured by the action it produces. If its actions prove beneficial and useful, one can assert so Ibid., pp. 3, 4, 5. Cf., Wm. James, Talks to Teachers on Psychology: of Life's Ideals (New York: Dover Press), p. 83. •• Cf., WTB, pp. 96, 97. 81 and to Students on Some 500 A. R. GINI that a particularfaith commitment in an object or in an idea has justified itself and proven itself real and true. The conclusion to be drawn from all of this is that, for James, every preference we make, whether it be in philosophy, science, psychology, theology, ethics, or the everyday questions of living is dependent on an explicit personal act of faith; faith, then, is an element of our active nature which, in effect, completely determines all of our decisions. Every branch of science and every aspect of life must make some assumptions. After all, said James, all men are but fallible mortals, and we must sometimes begin somewhere with something which we at least titularly accept as true. 33 James found it interesting that the necessity of faith as an ingredient in our mental attitude was strongly insisted on by the scientific philosophers of his day; yet, he thought it indeed strange that they maintained that it is only legitimate when used in the interests of one particular proposition, namely, the proposition that the course of nature is uniform. That nature will follow tomorrow the same laws that she follows today is, they all admit, a truth which no man can know; but in the interest of cognition as well as of action we must postulate or assume it is true. However, with regard to all other possible truths most of these scientific philosophers think that an attitude of faith is1 not only illogical but shameful. 34 James considered all those philosophers who denied the importance of faith in our lives guilty of a grave misculculation and misinterpretation of human nature. It is almost incredible that men who are themselves working philosophers should pretend that any philosophy can be, or ever has been, constructed without the help of personal preference, belief or divination. How have they succeeded in so stultifying their sense or the living facts of human nature as not to perceive that every philosopher, or man of science either, whose initiative accounts for anything in the evolution of thought, has taken his stand on a sort •• Cf., Wm. James, "The Function of Cognition," from: The Meaning of Truth, in The Writings of William James, ed. by, John J. McDermott (New York: Random House), 1967, p. 139, (hereafter: McDermott). •• Cf., WTB, pp. 91, 92. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 501 of dumb conviction that the truth must lie in one direction rather than another, and a sort of preliminary assurance that this noting can be made to work; and has borne his best fruit in trying to make it work? 35 Although James maintained that specific acts of faith are involved in all our assertions concerning reality, he warns us that faith cannot create something out of nothing. That is, faith does not and cannot create a solipistic dream world, or a situation in reality, by the force of sheer wish-power or willpower.36 According to James faith is but a. tool to help explain and substantiate reality only in reference to our experiencing of it. Faith is not totally subjective for it cannot create new reality a.s such nor can it perpetuate itself beyond its ability to generate some sort of supporting da.ta..37 Every faith commitment must have some warranted assertability behind it, and there must be some sort of positive feedback of facts for a. faith commitment to continue in a specific direction. Thus, for James, although faith is all-important in directing and guiding men's lives, viable faith cannot be completely detached from or contradict reality: " Woe to him whose beliefs play fast and loose with the order which realities follow in his experience; they will lead him nowhere or else make false connection." 38 However, James did maintain that there is a. whole class of truths whose reality depends on our faith or the vigor of our own will power and our active implementation of their possibilities. That is, James believed that there are times when man can rise above the merely given and, by having faith in a fact, can actually help to create a fact. James fully explicated this point by the use of a.n example which speaks for itself. Suppose, for example, that I am climbing in the Alps, and have the ill-luck to work myself into a position from which the only escape is by a terrible leap. Being without similar experience, I have no evidence of my ability to perform it successfully; but hope •• Ibid., p. 98. •• Cf., ibid., p. 146. 87 Cf., McDermott, p. XXIV, 88 Pragmatism, p. 186. (Introduction). 502 A. R. GIN! and confidence in myself make me sure I shall not miss my aim, and nerve my feet to execute what without those subjective emotions would perhaps have been impossible. But suppose that, on the contrary, the emotions of fear and mistrust preponderate ... why, then I shall hesitate so long that at last exhausted and trembling, and launching myself, in a moment of despair, I miss my foothold and roll into the abvss. In this case . . . the part of wisdom clearly is to believe what one desires; for the belief is one of the indispensable preliminary conditions of the realization of its object. There are then cases where faith creates its own verification. Believe, and you shall be right, for you shall save yourself; doubt, and you shaH be right, for you shall perish. The only difference is that to believe is greatly to our advantage. 89 This example typifies James's conviction that "again and again success depends on the energy of act; energy again depends on (the) faith that we shall not fail; and that faith in turn on the faith that we are right-which faith thus verifies itself." 40 In other words, desire for a certain kind of truth can bring about that truth's existence, if we apply ourselves to the task and do not sit around merely wishing or hoping that this or that were true. 41 Before concluding this section, I think that it is important to point out that, although James maintained that each specific act of faith must fulfill its intended practical purpose, it was never James's intention to suggest that in so doing one's faith commitment had the right to over-throw or openly clash with the individual's backlog of accumulated beliefs and interests. Furthermore, each act of faith must look to the future with an eye toward the attainment of the greatest possible good. That is to say, acts of faith cannot occur in vacuo, many factors must be taken into consideration. Consequently, acts of faith or will, for James, are good, practical, and true only insofar as they serve the immediate need but without distorting or destroying one's previous fund or experience, truths, and beliefs and as long as each action is open ""WTB, pp. 96, 97. •• Ibid., p. 100. 41 Cf., ibid., p. 24. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 503 to and geared toward the greatest possible good which the future may contain. * * * * The next and obvious question concerns the role of faith commitments in regards to the religious hypothesis. James called the question of whether this world is at bottom a moral or immoral universe the most radical question of life. 42 In no uncertain terms James insisted that " man needs a rule for his will, and he will invent one if one be not given to him." 43 Specifically, he maintained that this need is a need for "an eternal moral order " which gives direction and purpose to man's life. This search, he said," is one of the deepest needs of our breast " 44 and it is a search that man is not easily distracted from. For James, man has an intrinsic "need" to be subjugated to a higher power which we commonly refer to as God. In a very real sense, said James, man seemingly has a psychic want to believe that" all is not vanity in the Universe, whatever the appearances may suggest." 45 Man wants to accept the existence of God, because an acceptance of God guarantees to man an ideal order which shall be permanently preserved no matter what happens to the world as we now know it. In other words, belief in God is a belief in the presence of promise in the world. In effect, God is the ultimate mitigator of the harshness of reality because a belief in God gives man a feeling of security, banishes man's cosmic fear, and gives him hope that tomorrow may prove more sanative than today. 46 Accordingly, each man has a vital stake in the unknown! 47 The question now arises, just how do we come to know of God? The sa.cred texts of organized religion, said James, tell us of a loving God, yet immediate experience is full of contra•• Cf., ibid., p. 103. •• Ibid., p. 88. "Pragmatism, p. 77. 45 Wm. James, "Circumscription of the (Religious) Topic," from: Variaties of Religious Experience, in McDermott, p. 748. 46 Cf., Wm. James, "Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism," from: The 1Ueaning of Truth, in McDermott, p. 313. •• Cf., WTB, p. 54. 504 A. R. GINI diction, i.e., beauty and hideousness, love and cruelty, and life and death. It is, therefore, difficult at the level of plain facts to perceive a "Good God." 48 Moreover, said James, the physical order of nature, taken simply as science nows it, also cannot be held to reveal any one harmonious spiritual intent. It is a mere " weather," as Chauncey Wright called it, doing and undoing without end but with no specific order or purpose in sight. 49 Yet, man cannot live by facts alone, and therefore when facts are not enough and when reason is insufficient man has the right to assert his will when the possibility that something might be true does not openly confute given experience. In the question of God, said James, man has a right to believe that the physical order is but a partial order and that we can supplement it by an unseen spiritual order which we assume on trust. 50 In other words, since real possibility is the key to all faith commitments, the very possibility that God exists is enough to warrant belief. Quoting his friend William Salter, James suggests that" as the essence of courage is to stake one's life on a possibility, so the essence of faith is to believe that the possibility exists." 51 After all, said James, what really has the authority to debar us from our religious demands? Science, as such, certainly has no authority, for she can only say what is, not what is not; that is, science can only tell us of what is known, not of what is not known. Surely, said James, no one will contest the statement that it is a fact of human nature that men can live and die by the help of a sort of faith that does not have a single dogma or definition. This being the case, the bare assurance that this natural order is not ultimate but a mere sign or vision; (the external staging of a many-storied universe in which spiritual forces have the last word and are eternal) , this bare assurance is to most men enough to make life seem worth living in spite of every contrary presumption suggested by its circumstances on the natural plane. 52 That the world of physics is probably not absolute, and that our whole physical life may lie soaking in a spiritual atmosphere •• Cf., ibid., pp. 41, 42, 43, 44. •• Ibid., p. 52. •• Cf., ibid., p. 52. 51 Ibid., p. 62. •• Cf., ibid., p. 56, 57. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 505 or dimension of being that we, at present, have no organ for apprehending is vividly suggested to us, said James, by the analogy of the life of our domestic animals. For example, our dogs are in our human life but not of it. They witness hourly the outward body of events the inner meaning of which cannot, by any possible operation, be revealed to their intelligence,events in which they, themselves, often play a cardinal part. Let us suppose, said James, that my pet terrier bites a teasing boy, and the father demands damages. The dog may be present at every step of the negotiations and even see the money paid, and yet be without an inkling of what it all means, without a suspicion that it has anything to do with him. The dog quite simply does not have the ability to know what is going on around him. Now, said James, let us turn from this to the life of man. In the dog's life we see the world invisible to him because we ourselves live in both worlds. In human life is it not possible that, although we see only our world and the dog's within it, there yet exists a still wider world encompassing both of these worlds which is as unseen to us as our world is to the dog? And is it not also possible that to believe in this world may be the most essential and important function of our lives? But "may be! may be! " one now hears the agnostic positivist contemptuously exclaim; " what use can a scientific life have for maybes? " Well, said James, is not the scientific life, itself, based on " maybes? " James maintained that, so far as man stands for anything and is productive or imaginative at all, his entire vital function may be said to deal with " maybes." For not a victory is gained, not a deed of faithfulness or courage is done, except upon a" maybe." Nor is there a service or a single act of generosity, or a scientific exploration or experiment or textbook that may not be a mistake, for in everything there is an element of risk or chance. Yet, said James, it is only by risking our persons from one hour to another that we live at all. Therefore, he said, if this is the state of matters, then why not risk, why not believe, for if we win we win all and if we lose we lose absolutely nothing! 58 •• Cf., ibid., pp. 57, 58, 59. 506 A. R. GIN! James maintained that the religious question is a burning one in the hearts of all men of every generation. He believed that each man must make a commitment on this topic one way or another, because he felt that there can be no neutral position in regard to God. Man cannot escape the issue by assuming a position of skepticism and sit back and wait for more evidence, because although we do avoid error in this way if religion be untrue, we lose the good, if it be true just as certainly as if we positively chose to disbelieve. 54 In such instances, said James, skepticism and immovable doubt are themselves decisions of the widest practical reach, and it is often pragmatically impossible to distinguish doubt from dogmatic negation. Moreover, skepticism in moral matters is an active ally of immorality: who is not for is against! In theory as well as in practice, dodge, or hedge, or talk as we like about a " wise skepticism," we are in the end really doing volunteer military service fol" one side or the other. 55 James pointed out that the skeptic's supposed position is like the man who hesitates indefinitely to ask a certain women to marry him because he is not perfectly sure that she will prove an angel after he has brought her home. Would he not, said James, cut himself off from that particular angel-possibility just as decisively if he went out and married someone else? Skepticism, then, is not avoidance of an option; it is an option of a certain particular line of risk: it is better to risk loss of truth than take a chance on error. The faith-vetoer is actively playing his stake as much as the believer is; he is backing the field against the religious hypothesis, just as the believer is backing the religious hypothesis against the field. Therefore, said James, to preach skepticism to us as a duty until " sufficient evidence " for religion is found is tantamount to telling us, when in the presence of the religious hypothesis, that to yield to our fear of its being an error is wiser and better than to yield to our hope that it may be true. I, for one, said James, simply refuse obedience to the skeptic's demand to imitate his kind of option. If •• Cf., ibid., p. •• Cf., ibid., p. 109. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 507 religion be true and the evidence for it is still insufficient, James will not put an extinguisher on his willing nature and by so doing forfeit his only chance in life of getting on the winning side. 56 James exclaimed that he and all men have the right to run the risk of acting on their passional need,-because in the present such a commitment gives man a "peace that passeth understanding," and more importantly, this belie£ may in the future prove itself not only prophetic and right but also eternally rewarding. In essence James is saying that given the limitations of the world of objective facts, science and logical reasoning, religion is a living, forced, and momentous option which can neither be escaped or avoided and must be resolved by each individual. 57 In other words, the religious option, like all moral questions, immediately presents itself as a question whose solution cannot wait for sensible proof, because all moral questions are questions not of what sensibly exists but of what is, or would be good if it did exist. Science can tell us of what exists; but to compare the worth of what exists and of what does not exist, we must consult not science, but what Pascal calls the heart. 58 James stated that Pascal's wager theory is possibly the most decisive argument ever presented on the question of the existence of God. Following Pascal's lead, James stated that the acceptance of the reality of God is a " leap of faith " which transcends the natural inadequacies of the human mind. 59 In the final analysis, said James, the factual proof for God's existence will remain unsolved and insoluble forever; therefore, acceptance of God is an emotional and practical thing based on faith. Man, he said, must recognize the opaque limits of his speculative insight; 60 he must realize that, if his heart does not want a world of moral reality, his head will assuredly never let him believe in one! 61 * * * * When all is said and done, the pragmatic significance of Professor James's acceptance of the free will is that this decision Cf., ibid., p. 101. Cf., ibid., p. 58 Cf., ibid., p. Cf., ibid., p. n. °Cf., ibid., pp. 185, 186, 187. 56 59 57 6 61 Cf., ibid., p. 508 A. R. GINI allows for a " cosmological theory of promise." That is, in a world where conclusive evidence is not always readily available for making definite judgments concerning the make-up, structure, and meaning of reality, the activity of man's passional nature at least affords him the "possibility" that he might be true or correct in regards to his decisions concerning reality. James contended that there is no more crippling source of deception in the investigation of reality in general which can compare with a fixed belief that certain kinds of phenomena are de facto impossible. 62 The real strength and power of free will, said James, is that it releases man from the captivity of" brute facts." Acording to James, the concept of freedom holds out to man the real possibility of hope and expectation but never the assurance of absolute certitude. Opting for free will, allows man to cast aside scientific reasoning or logic as the only acceptable vehicles for the formulation of everyday judgment and for the development of a viable Weltanschauung. That is to say, once armed with the knowledge of the power of faith and with full consciousness of the responsiblities and risks involved, man is now free to give himself over to anything strong enough to catch his eye. James suggested that one's faith-tendencies usually proceed along the lines of a seven-point procedural method which he called the " faith-ladder:" 1) There is nothing absurd in a certain view of the world being true, nothing self-contradictory; 2) It might have been true under certain conditions; 3) It may be true, even now; 4) It is fit to be true; 5) It ought to be true; 6) It must be true; 7) It shall be true, at any rate true for me. "Obviously," said James," this is no intellectual chain of inferences, like the sorites of the logic books. Yet it is a slope of good-will on which in the larger questions of life men habitually live." 63 62 63 Cf., The Letters of William James, Vol. I., p. 248. Some Problems of Philosophy, p. 224. WILLIAM JAMES: FACTS, FAITH, AND PROMISE 509 James found in man a will to believe, and he put this at the base of all of man's thinking concerning reality. Moreover, he argued that every system of philosophy depends, in the last analysis, upon the will to believe. Man wants to believe in a certain way, because the belief seems to satisfy him most completely; therefore, said James, man has the right to chose as he sees fit-but always at his own peril. According to Professor James, then, for each thinker the ultimate authority must be his own understanding o£ reality as he sees it. For James," the fons et origo o£ all reality, whether from the absolute or the practical point of view is thus subjective, is ourselves." 64 In other words, we are the sum total of our own choices within the limits of our given world. 65 Furthermore, since each man is captain of his own ship and master of his own fate, no one has the right to issue vetoes to others with whom we do not agree. James felt that we must "tolerate, respect and indulge those whom we see harmlessly interested and happy in their own ways, however unintelligible these may be to us." Moreover, he believed that " the first thing to learn in intercourse with others is non-interference with their own particular ways of being happy, provided those ways do not assume to interfere by violence with ours. No one has insight into all the ideals. No one should presume to judge off-hand. The pretention to dogmatize about them in each other is the root of most human injustices and cruelties, and the trait in human character most likely to make angels weep." 66 A. R. GIN! Loyola University Chicago, Illinois The Principles of Psychology, Vol. II, pp. 296, 297. Cf., Rollo May, "The Emergence of Existential Psychology," from: Existential Psychology, ed. by Rollo May, p. 13. 66 Talks to Teachers on Psychology: and to Students on Some of Life's Ideals, pp. 129, 130. 6• 65 WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY T !E QUESTION whether Whitehead's speculative phiosophy can be adequately applied to the fact of personal identity has long been a thorn in the sides of Whiteheadians. Personal identity seems to be a fundamental aspect of experience to which any comprehensive and systematic philosophy simply must do justice. Yet the distinctive features of Whitehead's thought, particularly its atomism, appear to militate against, if not indeed preclude, any such adequacy. In his A Christian Natural Theology, John Cobb considered this problem and attempted to provide a solution. 1 The purpose of this article is to examine that solution, to raise some questions about it, and to present some alternative suggestions. Although it has been several years since Cobb's book was published, it seems appropriate to review his contribution because of the fundamental importance of the issue. For the success of Whitehead's speculative philosophy can be viewed as resting upon the cogency of its claim to be a " one-substance cosmology." 2 The one categoreal scheme is to provide one conceptuality applicable to God, man, and the natural world alike. The cogency of this claim is reduced, however, if the scheme is really inapplicable to man's experience of personal identity. In this context Cobb's proposal becomes fairly important. If it cannot bear the weight he places upon it-and 1 John B. Cobb, Jr., A Christian Natural Theology (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1965), pp. 47-91. Subsequent references to this work are abbreviated as CNT and incorporated within the text. 2 Process and Reality (New York: Harper & Row, 1960), p. 1'!9, see p. 168. references to this work are abbreviated as PR and incorporated within text. 510 WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 511 he admits to some dissatisfaction with his own solution-an alternative must be sought. 3 I Cobb locates the problem of personal identity as resting with Whitehead's account of the soul, that center of consciousness and experience which we otherwise, and more usually, identify as the self. In more technical terms, the soul is that living person which is the series of dominant occasions within a body. Cobb does not think that questions about the role of the body in personal identity are really to the point, for in the last analysis "it is the soul that is truly personal, the true subject." (CNT 66) 4 The body is rather the environment for personal existence and is itself " ontologically distinct " from the soul. (CNT 66) Thus it is apparent that by personal identity Cobb has in mind the identity of the person construed as a centered self or soul rather than a mind-body unity of which the soul is only a part. Now it is quite clear that Whitehead's categories repudiate any notion of a numerical or absolute self-identity through time. Such self-identity belongs only to individual actual entities. The fact of personal identity through time cannot then be construed in Whitehead's system in any absolute sense. The question is whether it can be clearly construed in terms of the soul. Cobb argues that Whitehead presents two categoreal or systematic resources for this task. Both pertain to the relationship between successive actual entities in a personally ordered society. The first resource which might explicate 3 Cobb himself points out the seriousness of the issue (CNT 74, 76). • I think Cobb is incorrect in this position, but I am unable to argue the point here. Whitehead does observe that if " human occasions of experience e«sentially inherit in one-dimensional personal order, there is a gap between human occasions and the physical occasions of nature," Adventures of Ideas (New Yol'k: The Macmillan Company, 1933), p. 243. (Subsequently references to this work are abbreviated as AI and incorporated within the text.) The whole thrust of Whitehead's endeavor is directed against such a gap. Cobb's position only widens it. 512 JOHN B. BENNETT personal identity is the inheritance of a common pattern or character. The second is some special mode in which the past is inherited. Cobb's solution involves the complete rejection of the first resource and a development of the second beyond the few enigmatic statements in which Whitehead announced it. The rejected resource is that " the identity of the person through time points to the inheritance of a common character through the successive occasions." (CNT 73) Cobb regards this explanation as inappropriate for two reasons. His first argument is that we do not in practice ascribe personal identity on these grounds. Neither a common character nor the transmission of this character from moment to moment " causes us to judge personal identity." (CNT 73) Twins share commonness of character, Cobb says, but we clearly do not regard them as the same person. And commonness in what is inherited explicates only the personality which can change, he claims, without the loss of identity. His second argument is that a common character suggests repetition, whereas the problem to be accounted for is novelty. The identity of a person is the identity of a living thing, and "the decisive feature of life is novelty and not the repetition of past patterns." (CNT 74) Indeed, Cobb regards it a "perplexing fact" and perhaps a sign of "desperation" that Whitehead would attempt to account for personal identity in these terms. (CNT 74) Accordingly, Cobb contends that the case for the adequacy of Whitehead's categories can be made only in a development of the second resource, the notion of a special mode of inheritance. This is " the only satisfactory approach to personal identity allowed by his system." (CNT 75) It is here that the "whole burden" of explanation must rest. (CNT 74) This special mode emphasizes a " peculiar completeness " with which occasions of one's own past are objectified and summed up in the immediate present. (PR 244, 531) Cobb interprets this notion of a peculiar completeness, left undeveloped by Whitehead, in terms of unmediated hybrid prehensions of earlier members of the enduring object. Unmedi- WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 513 ated prehensions are those not restricted to the immediate, or contiguous, predecessor occasion. Such prehensions, he claims, are unmediated because they are objectifications of the mental rather than the physical poles. It is precisely such direct prehensions, Cobb thinks, that can explain the peculiar completeness to which Whitehead referred. Through them successive occasions of the living person have direct, unmediated access to earlier moments of experience. Likewise, the events of yesterday, or of months or even years ago, have in this way a direct, unmediated influence in one's self-experiencing and self-understanding of today. Thus the merit of this proposal, Cobb claims, is that it permits a Whiteheadian interpretation of memory. And by memory in this context Cobb means remembering one's past experiences from within rather than from without. He means remembering them as such rather than remembering something about them. It is this notion of memory which Cobb regards as the basic and indeed sufficient factor in one's sense of personal identity with his past. "Only memory can serve in my selfunderstanding to determine self-identity through time." (CNT 76) Accordingly, only the second systematic resource, the special mode of inheritance which hybrid feelings effect, can account for personal identity. Cobb completes his argument by extending the scope of memory to those experiences which can be recalled under hypnosis or through the expertise of a psychoanalyst. With this extension he contends that " personal identity obtains whenever there is a serially ordered society of primarily mental occasions (a soul) in which each occasion actually or potentially prehends unmediatedly the mental poles of all its predecessors." (CNT 79) II Cobb presents this account as faithful " both to Whitehead and to normal human intuitions." (CNT 78) Unfortunately some problems remain. One of these is raised by Cobb himself 514 JOHN B. BENNETT and leads me in this section to an immanent criticism of the specific way he employs the resources he identifies. The other problem rests with the general way Cobb appropriates the Whiteheadian resources and leads me in the next section to more methodological comments. Cobb calls attention to telepathy as illustrating the concept of unmediated feeling. The problem is that telepathy suggests that just this notion of unmediated prehension is really working against a viable understanding of personal identity as constituted solely by memory. For any such genuine experience of telepathy would require interpretation as an unmediated prehension, or a remembering from within, of experiences in that series constituting another's personal identity. But since Cobb has defined personal identity solely in terms of memory, those experiences of others which I directly intuit would, by definition, become part of my own identity too. If it is my Aunt Agatha whom I am immediately prehending, then by Cobb's account she and I are-for however briefly-the same. As an account of personal identity this is clearly unsatisfactory. Cobb notes that the problem can be solved " definitionally by appealing to the fact that the living person is serially ordered .... " (CNT 78) But it does not appear that he has understood the full requirements of this solution. For it involves the reintroduction of the rejected resource, the notion of the common character. There must be a reason why in the special mode of inheritance the objectification of past occasions is as complete as it is. Objectification is selective. If this mode is not arbitrary, and thus a matter of incoherence, there must be a reason why there is such a minimum of abstraction from the full content of the past. And the best available reason can only be that the subjective aims of the occasions in the series share a common underlying character. Indeed Whitehead himself calls attention to this when he states that " the defining characteristic of a living person is some definite type of hybrid prehension transmitted from occasion to occasion of its existence." (CNT 163) We can say that the defining characteristic emerges, and is derivative from, WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 515 the constituent occasions of the series. Indeed the ontological principle requires this. One's individuality is thereby rooted in the constituent actual occasions of his existence. But the common character thus established requires conformal inheritance, thereby limiting the sorts of full objectification which can also occur in that series. It follows that the second resource, unmediated prehension, cannot function without the first, inheritance of a common character. And this suggests that as a ground of personal identity, memory does not stand alone. Now is it true, as Cobb claims, that the inheritance of a common character suggests a kind of repetition inappropriate to personal identity? Need repetition result in trivializing of novelity or of mentality? Contrary to Cobb, I believe that the transmission of this common character does not inappropriately restrict the freedom of each member of the soul. In the first place, even with respect to this defining characteristic, there is no predictably determinate content to any specific occasion. There is no predictably determinate content because the defining characteristic, as a complex eternal object, enjoys a sort of neutrality with regard to alternative possibilities which can express this form. There is often a wide variety of ways that I can be myself in a certain situation, although there may be one way more so than others. The point is that the specific actuality, the concrete content, of the members of that society is not prescribed by the defining characteristic. In the second place, each occasion in the series remains living in its capacity for conceptual initiative. The inheritance of a common form does not take away the occasion's own autonomy in self-creation. There is conformation to the defining characteristic, for it is genetically inherited. But such conformation is also characterized by originality of response. Each occasion contributes from its own being to the special definition of its subjective forms, even those giving the series as a whole its special characteristics. We ratify who we are with various degrees of completeness and of enlargement in 516 JOHN B. BENNETT each successive moment of our existence. Inheritance of a common character does not require sacrifice of originality. 5 What about Cobb's other argument? Do twins really share commonness of character, in the sense in which character has here been defined? Doubtless some, perhaps many, common characteristics are shared. But if they are twins, and not one person, then they do not share a common defining characteristic. In the senses that we differentiate them, we ascribe differentiated defining characteristics. Nor is it any clearer that in every case the personality can change without loss of identity. For some purposes we do draw the line. The callous rapist is not the same as the selfless choir boy he once was. There has been a tragic loss of identity. That we still connect the two is a function of other criteria we are applying. Thus it appears that it is simply not correct to say, as Cobb does, that " the whole burden of Whitehead's case must fail on the fact of inheritance." (CNT 74) There are at least two resources: a character transmitted and a special mode of inheriting. As Whitehead asserts, the "concrete moments" of a living person "are bound together into one society by a partial identity of form, and by the peculiarly full summation of its predecessors which each moment of the life-history gathers into itself." 6 III The example of the choir-boy-turned-rapist suggests that personal identity is something we ascribe on the basis of various criteria. Some of these may well be in conflict with others. Arguments to adjudicate them are then in order. At this point 5 A complete response to Cobb on this issue would involve consideration of the body. The condition for spontaneity is intense physical experience. "But such an experience is derivate from the complex order of the material animal body, and not from the simple 'personal order ' of past occasions with analogous experience." (PR 161) • Symbolism, Its Meaning and Effect (New York: Capricorn Books, 1959), p. 27, my italics. Subsequent references to this work are abbreviated as S and incorporated within the text. WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 517 I feel some uneasiness about the way Cobb is appropriating Whitehead's thought. It is as though he understands that the categories constructed in Process and Reality release us from arguments. Attractive though such a possibility is, I find it unpersuasive. Some illustrations may help expose and focus the difficulty I sense in Cobb's procedure. One illustration has to do with the " normal human intuitions" to which Cobb refers in speaking of personal identity. Surely any statement of these is important and as such demands careful analysis. But Cobb, after noting that the body changes-though not enough to give us difficulty in identifying it-is content to assert that "it is highly questionable that we would correlate closely the identity of the person and the actual identity of the body." (CNT 72) Now certainly the body figures very heavily in most criteria to which we would appeal in judging personal identity. Why should it be otherwise when we are using Whitehead's categories? A second illustration of the weakness of Cobb's procedure is to be found in the unacknowledged shift in his study from the grounds on which I ascribe or refuse to ascribe personal identity to others, to those I use in speaking of my own personal identity. The first person singular pronoun has a logically different referent and use from the second person singular pronoun. This logical difference is not obviated by the categoreal scheme. It requires the recognition and appreciation of logically different criteria. However, with the rejection of common character as a resource, Cobb's whole treatment of personal identity involves the assumption that it rests only upon memory. Accordingly his analysis culminates in a definition in which it is asserted that " personal identity obtains whenever there is a serially ordered society .... " (CNT 79, my italics) Although Cobb's procedure suggests otherwise, Whitehead's categories do not release us from arguments about criteria and context. To attempt to establish personal identity qna personal identity, with no further specifications, is a fruitless effort. As Whitehead noted, the proper question is, Identity is respect 518 JOHN B. BENNETT to what? " The baby in the cradle and the grown man in middle age, are in some sense identical and in other senses diverse." 1 What we intend when we speak of personal identity shifts from context to context. Our requirements are richly textured and variegated. Whiteheadian accounts ought to recognize this. IV In issues of this sort Whitehead's system of categories can provide a context of theory in which we can express without contradiction the many facts we acknowledge in practice. We acknowledge the fact of personal identity in different ways. In practice the fact appears in different perspectives. These different ways and perspectives are reflected in the various criteria to which we appeal in declaring that some person, ourself or another, is in relevant respects the same today as he was earlier. For instance, we may appeal to bodily characteristics, skills, or mannerisms, or to memory, dispositions, or intentions, or to still other criteria. No one of these would seem to be by itself all that we use to ascribe personal identity or to indicate its meaning. Whitehead's system is adequate to the fact of personal identity to the degree that it permits interpretations of these perspectives, relating them to each other and to other facts of our experience. The scheme of categories is adequate if it is rich and fertile enough to provide the necessary resources. Corresponding to the variety of ways in which we speak of personal identity, there should be a variety of different systematic explanations that can be brought to bear. In the remainder of this essay let us look briefly at what this sort of interpretation might involve. We shall consider dispositions, memory, and intentional action as ways in which we speak of personal identity. To this end we need to return to the two resources mentioned earlier. We need also to recall what Whitehead said of Descartes' cogito argument: " the 'he' which is common to the ... egos is an eternal object 7 Modes of Thought (New York: Capricorn Books, 1958), p. 146. WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 519 or, alternatively, the nexus of successive occasions." (PR 116) Sometimes by a personal pronoun we mean a character sustained over a stretch of time, or, in Whitehead's terms, a complex eternal object ingredient in a succession of events. At other times we may have in mind the history of the person, the succession of occasions in which that eternal object is ingredient. The two resources reflect these two perspectives. With the one resource, the common character, we emphasize the complex eternal object definitive of the series. When speaking of the special completeness of transmission, we are drawing attention to the soul as a nexus. Now the soul has as its defining characteristic " some definite type of hybrid prehension transmitted from occasion to occasion of its existence." (PR 163) Each hybrid prehension characterizing the living person has a distinctive datum and a distinctive subjective form. Because it is a hybrid prehension, the datum is a form of definiteness prehended as a possibility rather than as a physically illustrated pattern. Because the datum is a possibility, the subjective form is a valuation. By categoreal obligation there will be reproduction of the data. Since it is a physical feeling, there will be conformation of subjective forms. Antecedent occasions impose upon successive ones these common elements of definiteness to be conformally inherited. In a living person these possibilities and valuations, derived from the past, are structured, thereby gaining intensity and efficacy through reinforcement. Together they come to constitute the defining characteristic of the living person. This common character enters integrally into each of the successive occasions, determining what is and what is not compatible for objectification. If we emphasize the valuations as definitive of the series, then we are urging that personal identity is a function of the continuity of the purposes, appetitions, or, more generally, dispositions which characterize the person. Quite often we do speak of personal identity in this fashion. There are patterns of behavior which identify us as the persons we are. There are JOHN B. BENNETT fundamental valuations which distinguish us and thereby separate us from others. To return to more systematic terms, there is empowerment of the present by the immanence of the past. The various appetitions and valuations of the living person are all informed by, and are particular specifications of, that complex eternal object giving the series as a whole its stability of direction and identification with the past. This specific complex can be actualized in a variety of ways in a variety of situations. But as it floods into each concrescing occasion in the series, it determines that present as in some way a continuation of itself. " The man-at-one-moment concentrates in himself the colour of his own past, and he is the issue of it." (S To be sure, this factor of " colour " is not all to which we would point in accounting for personal identity. "The how of our present experience must conform to the what of the past in us." (S 58) This " what " is not simply valuation. The " he " which is common to the occasions in the series can also refer to the nexus of successive occasions. Here the element of identity appears as the connectedness of occasions with their reiterated content. In addition to disposition there is also memory. The scheme of categories can interpret both. As a third ground of personal identity there is that special sense of identity we invoke when we speak of intention and its execution. It is to this notion that Stuart Hampshire, for instance, appeals in speaking of personal identity. "·we carry our intentions with us, and this carrying forward of intentions, together with the perception of movement, provides the natural and necessary continuity of our experience." 8 Vve are who we are, we may say, because we intend some of the things we do, as well as because we do some of the things we intend. This awareness is not simply of past experiences. That would be mere memory. It is rather the awareness of the present realization of past intention. Whitehead's account of this reason for claiming identity 8 Thought and Action (New York: The Viking Press, 1959), p. 72 .. WHITEHEAD AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 521 would involve the eighth categoreal obligation and the aim at intensity of feeling in the relevant future as well as in the immediate subject. In the later phases of the concrescence of the immediate subject, anticipatory propositional feelings emerge, functioning as lures for feeling. Part of this " anticipation of kinship with the future assumes the form of purpose to transform concept into fact." (AI 250) The future will prehend the past as having intended some factor in it. In this way there will be present awareness of past intentions as Jealized or not. Either way there is some explanation of the notion of identity involved. 9 In ways such as these, Whitehead's scheme can be used to present interpretations of personal identity. There is more than one ground for ascribing personal identity. And there is more than one systematic resource for interpreting the personal identity thus ascribed. His categories are not to supplant the various modes of discourse in which these senses of identity are presented. They are rather to render systematic interpretations of the features of experience these other modes disclose. In interpretations of personal identity, Whitehead's categories should be able to provide clear, systematic senses to the notion that a person is present in and through his experiences and so enjoys personal identity. JoHN B. BENNETT Northland College Ashland, Wisconsin 9 For an application of this notion of the soul to the problem of agency, see my "Process or Agent: A Response" in Philosophy of Religion and Theology: 1972, ed. David Griffin (Chambersburg, Pennsylvania: American Academy of Religion, 1972), pp. 146-159. ARISTOTLE'S DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER O NE OF THE PERENNIAL problems in Aristotelian studies is the difficulty of reconciling Aristotle's the account of the unmoved mover-particularly number of unmoved movers-presented variously in the Physics and in book lambda of the Metaphysics. Numerous explanations have been offered, most of which either explain too little or too much. The result is that Aristotle is either left enmeshed in hopeless contradiction, or his unmoved mover is something less than was understood by his medieval interpreters. The thesis of this study is that the distinctions made in the Physics, particularly Book VIII, must be applied to Aristotle's discussion of the unmoved mover in Metaphysics lambda. In making this claim I am aware that any successful attempt at exegesis must take into account both the textual problems in the Physics and Metaphysics and recent attempts to interpret the unmoved mover as a principle of intelligibility analogous to scientific " laws." ARISTOTLE's ARGUMENT The argument for the existence of the unmoved mover is found in chapter 1 of Book VIII of the Physics and is based on Aristotle's proofs, for the eternality of motion. Here is how the argument goes: Motion is the fulfillment of the movable qua movable. Motion presupposes the existence of things capable of motion. Furthermore, these movable things must have a beginning, or else they are eternal. To say that movable things had a beginning is to say that there was a motion, or change, before there was anything capable of being moved, which is absurd. Therefore, motion did not have a beginning. The same kind of argument is used to prove the imperish- ARISTOTLE'S DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER ability of motion. To posit a motion that destroys motion would involve one in an infinite series of destroyers, for the destructive agent will have to be destroyed, after what it destroys has been destroyed, and then that which had the capacity of destroying it will have to be destroyed afterwards, (so that there will. be a process of change subsequent to the last,) for being destroyed also is a kind of change. 1 Eternal motion must be continuous motion, for motion that is merely successive is not eternal. There are three kinds of motion: (1) rectilinear, (9l) rotary, and (3) a combination of the two. Rectilinear motion cannot be continuous, for a straight line has a beginning and an end; a rectilinear motion would involve a turning back at its terminal points. 2 Infinite rectilinear motion is impossible because the universe is finite, and an actually infinite body cannot exist. 3 Since rectilinear motion cannot be continuous, neither can " mixed " motion be continuous, for the latter is continuous only if both elements are continuous. Rotary motion, however, is not subject to the limits of rectilinear motion, for in circular motion there is no beginning point and no terminal point. Rotary motion, therefore, is primary and continuous. 4 From the eternality of motion Aristotle argues for the existence of the unmoved first mover. A good Platonic principle that Aristotle applies here is that " all things that are in motion must be moved by something." 5 This is possible in either of two ways: either the movent moves itself, or else it is moved by another. If the former is true, we have already reached the eternal, self-moving principle. If the latter is true, we likewise arrive at an eternal self-mover, for an infinite regress is impossible. 1 Physics Iff. Cf. Metaphysics 107Ib 5-10. All quototions from the Physics are from the translation by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gay•e; citations from the Metaphysics are from the translation by W. D. Ross. Both translations (tre included in The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Random House, 1941). • Physics 259• 15-20. • Ibid., 206• 1-7. • Ibid., 265• 14ff. • Ibid., 256• 524 DAVID STEW ART If then everything that is in motion must be moved by something, and the movent must either itself be moved by something else or not, and in the former case there must be some first movent that is not itself moved by anything else, while in the case of the immediate movent being of this kind there is no need of an intermediate movent that is also moved (for it is impossible that there should be an infinite series of movents, each of which is itself moved by something else, since in an infinite series there is no first term)if then everything that is in motion is moved by something, and the first movent is moved but not by anything else, it must be moved by itself. 6 A similar argument is repeated in chapter 6 of Metaphysics lambda, based on the priority of act over potency. Thus far, both the Physics and Metaphysics are in agreement. In both treatises Aristotle recognizes the eternality of motion. From this he argues for the existence of an eternal, incorruptible unmoved mover. His remaining problem is to discover the number of such movers. Is there only one, or a plurality? TEXTUAL CoNSIDERATIONS That the text of both the Physics and the Metaphysics has suffered emendations and interpolations is beyond doubt. In his monumental study, Aristoteles, Grundlegung einer Geschichte seiner Entwicklung, Werner Jaeger isolated several passages in both the Physics and Metaphysics that were not part of the original works. Since these passages are central to an understanding of Aristotle's doctrine of the unmoved mover, it is important to look briefly at them. 7 Interpolations in the "Physics" The first addition in the Physics that is significant for this study is in Book VIII, Ch. 6 (258b 10). Aristotle here states the conclusion of a proof for the existence of an unmoved mover. "Since there must always be motion without inter• Ibid., 256• 18-20. • The English translation of this work will hereafter be cited. Werner Jaeger, Aristotle, Trans. Richard Robinson, second edition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1948). ARISTOTLE's DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 525 mission, there must necessarily be something, one thing or it may be a plurality, that first imparts motion, and this first movent must be unmoved." Jaeger insists that grammatical considerations prove that the phrase, " one thing or it may be a plurality," is a later addition. 8 The second addition is found at 259a 7-13. "Motion, then, being eternal, the first movent, if there is but one, will be eternal also: if there are more than one, there will be a plurality of such eternal movents." Jaeger notes that not only is this statement tautological, it is also stylistically distinct, and the succeedings lines (159a 15 ff.) do not presuppose the disputed passage. 9 The third interpolation is at 259b 28-31. We must distinguish, however, between accidental motion of a thing by itself and such motion by something else, the former being confined to perishable things, whereas the latter belongs also to certain first principles of heavenly bodies, of all those, that is to say, that experience more than one locomotion. The implicit assumption here seems to be that each planetary sphere requires a mover, and each sphere is moved accidentally. Jaeger argues that the passage is an addition, basing his conclusion partially on linguistic grounds and partially on contextual considerations. 10 These three additions in chapter 6 of book VIII are the only relevant passages under question. 11 Interpolations in the "Metaphysics" Basing his arguments on the earlier conclusions of Bonitz, Jaeger insists that book lambda is not the intended conclusion 8 Jaeger, Aristotle, p. 362. • Ibid., p. 363. 10 Ibid., pp. 364ff. 11 G. Verbeke, in the Revue philosophique de Louvain 46 (1948), p. 151, argues that chapter 1 of book VIII of the Physics (dealing with the eternality of motion) was originally an independent treatise that was added later. That this is far from conclusive is shown by Professor Fredrich Solmsen, Aristotle's System of the Physical World (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1960), p. 224, n. 8. "It is correct that ch. 3 does not make use of the conclusions reached in ch. 1. Yet are not the opinions combated in ch. 3 sufficiently different from those opposed in eh. I? The question of ch. 3 is no longer whether movement had a beginning." 526 DAVID STEW ART of the Metaphysics. 12 He argues that originally the Metaphysics was only a ten-book collection which omitted books alpha minor, delta, kappa, and lambda. Jaeger further argues that book lambda was originally an independent workpossibly a lecture on metaphysics which was composed for some special occasion, a " complete system of metaphysics in nuce " 13 -basing these conclusions not only on an analysis of the argument of book lambda but also upon its stylistic characteristics. He observes that book lambda is unusually brief, even for Aristotle, and employs a style foreign to the rest of the Metaphysics: " It contains only the main points, sketchily put together, sometimes merely jotted down one after the other with a recurring 'Note, next, that ... ,' and bare of all stylistic polish in detail." 14 There is one exception to this, however. In chapter 8 Aristotle considers the problem of whether there is only one unmoved mover or a plurality. The chapter is fully out, unlike the rest of book lambda which is a marvel of what Jaeger calls "Aristotelian brevity." 15 Not only is chapter 8 stylistically incongruous with the rest of the book, it also interrupts the train of thought in chapters 7 and 9. Chapter 7 considers the divine characteristics of the unmoved mover; chapter 9 begins with the words, " the nature of the divine thought involves certain problems .... " Jaeger is right when he observes that "chapter 9 interrupts this continuous train of thought and breaks it into two parts. Remove it, and chapters 7 and 9 fit smoothly together." 16 These difficulties are further compounded by the fact that within chapter 8 there is a passage which is assumed to be a later addition. It is found at 1074a 31-38. Evidently there is but one heaven. For if there are many heavens as there are many men, the moving principles, of which each heaven will have one, will be one in form but in number many. But all things that are many in number have matter; for one and the same definition, e. g., that of a man, applies to many Jaeger, Amtotle, Ibid., p. 219. H Ibid., p. 344. 10 18 p. 194. 15 16 Ibid., p. 345. Ibid., p. 346. ARISTOTLE's DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 527 things, while Socrates is one. But the primary essence has not matter; for it is complete reality. So the unmovable first mover is one both in definition and in number; so too, therefore, is that which is moved always and continuously; therefore there is one heaven alone. Jaeger argues, on linguistic grounds, that this passage is an addition, noting that " with its first words, ' evidently there is but one heaven,' another style begins, and with the last word of the insertion, ' therefore there is one heaven alone,' it ceases again." 17 The style of this passage, Jaeger states, "is the same shorthand style as obtains in the rest of Book A, and contrasts sharply with the impeccable language of chapter 8." 18 Jaeger also points out that the grammatical connection of the preceding and succeeding sections is disturbed by the addition of lines 31-38. Furthermore, it seems explicitly to contradict Aristotle's earlier contention that there is but one unmoved mover. Jaeger's conclusion is that this passage was originally a marginal comment, a piece of self-criticism, which Aristotle's "faithful editors " introduced into the text. 19 The upshot of all this is that the passages most relevant to a study of the Aristotelian doctrine of the unmoved mover are questionable, to say the least. There is good evidence, on linguistic grounds alone, to assume that the three previously discussed passages in Physics VIII were not part of the original work. There also is good evidence, both on contextual and linguistic grounds, for believing that book lambda, perhaps originally a separate treatise, was not included in the earliest formulation of the Metaphysics. The evidence, however, for insisting that chapter 8 is a later insert is not conclusive. The Dutch scholar, Augustine Nolte, suggests that at this point Aristotle was on unfamiliar ground and that the more fluent style of the chapter simply indicates that he was here following material previously worked out by astronomers. 20 Whether or not lines 1074a 31-38 of Ibid., p. 353. Ibid. 19 Ibid. 20 Augustinus Nolte, Het Godsbegrip bij Aristoteles (Nijmegen-Utrecht: 17 18 Dekker 5Q8 DAVID STEW ART chapter 8 disrupt the unity of the chapter is likewise subject to dispute. Jaeger feels that this passage involved Aristotle in contradictions. 21 Joseph Owens, on the other hand, insists that this passage, which proves the unity of the universe, is vital to the arguments of the chapter. If the change in style must mark it as a later addition, it could have been added subsequently by Aristotle to take care of an actual or possible challenge to the basis of his reasoning. That would explain the abrupt and precise style. In any case, the literary connection with the preceding sentence is quite smooth. 22 These conflicting interpretations indicate emphatically that the textual evidence is far from certain, even though Jaeger makes a strong case for his textual analysis. The significant factor in all this is that, even given Jaeger's textual analysis, it can be scarcely doubted that all the passages in question are from the pen of Aristotle. Jaeger's thesis is that Aristotle originally began with the theory of one, primal unmoved mover, which is reflected in the earliest versions of the Physics and Metaphysics. Astronomy, however, convinced him that " the hypothesis of a single uniform ultimate motion was too primitive to account for the complications of the actual heavenly motions .... " 23 So Aristotle turned to astronomy for an explication of the actual number of first principles. A further implication of Jaeger's view is that the emended & Van de Vegt V. N., 1940), pp. 147-48. cited by Joseph Owens in The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1951), p. 415, n. 36. Owens adds that Nolte holds that this chaper is nol a later addition and accounts for the difference in style by Aristotle's need to have before him the exact statements of the astronomers. 21 Jaeger, Aristotle, p. 353. •• Owens, op. cit., pp. 282-83. Concerning this passage, Owens continues: " So if it is a later insert, it is more likely something written expressly for this place, as Jaeger thinks, rather than a previously composed remnant as in v. Arnim's theory." [Hans von Arnim held that this passage had no connection whatsoever with the surrounding text.] I think here that Owens slightly misunderstands Jaeger. Jaeger did not argue that this addition was expressly prepared for this section but was rather a piece of " self-criticism " which Aristotle jotted in the margin and did not intend to be included in the text itself. •• Jaeger, Aristotle, pp. 350-51. ARISTOTLE's DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 529 sections in Physics VIII come from a period of doubt "when Aristotle, though seriously considering the possibility of extending the principle of the prime mover to the planetary spheres, still hesitates to draw this consequence." 24 Jaeger concludes that the addition of book lambda to the Metaphysics was only a "makeshift" arrangement which indicated Aristotle's dissatisfaction with his earlier formulation. At this point Aristotle "was wrestling with these problems anew and failing to solve them .... " 25 Chapter 8 of book lambda must then be seen as an earlier version of Aristotle's attempt to solve the perplexing problem of the first principles, and even if it was an editorial addition to book lambda, it was doubtless from the pen of Aristotle himself. The disputed comments at 1074a 31 ff. were marginalia -Aristotle's own "self-criticism "-which were later incorporated into the text by subsequent editors. Such are the conclusions of Jaeger. The willingness of Aristotle to adapt his earlier theory of one prime mover to the demands of astronomy for a plurality of planetary movers indicates Aristotle's devotion to what Jaeger calls his "unbending sense of fact." 26 But Jaeger argues that this revision led Aristotle into hopeless contradiction. This is really the point at issue. Assuming the text to be genuinely Aristotelian, though agreeing with Jaeger that it probably underwent several redactions, must one conclude as Jaeger does that Aristotle contradicted himself? Is there no way to reconcile the apparent conflict between Physics VIII and Metaphysics lambda? Or must one say that in his old age Aristotle suffered a period of intellectual senility which allowed him blandly to overlook a manifest contradiction in his revision of earlier positions? THE NuMBER OF UNMOVED MovERS If Jaeger is right, and there is no good reason to contest him on this point, Aristotle began with his theory of one eternal •• Ibid., p. 357. 25 Ibid., p. 354. •• Ibid., p. 351. 530 DAVID STEW ART unmoved mover and later made additions to the text in order to accommodate the findings and demands of astronomy. The perennial question is whether Aristotle contradicted himself in so doing. In the Phyf!ics, Book VIII, chapter 6, the first two interpolations merely suggest the possibility of more than one unmoved mover. In the third interpolation Aristotle introduces the self-movers of the heavenly bodies and remarks that there is a self-mover for each planetary sphere. Then in chapter 8 of M etaphyf!ics lambda, which originally did not include the passage at 1074a 31-38, Aristotle assumes the probable existence of a plurality of unmoved movers-one for each planetary sphere. In Jaeger's account, Aristotle, having advanced his theory of the plurality of movers, jotted down in the margin a note in favor of the uniqueness of the prime mover which Aristotle's " faithful editors" later introduced into the text where it remains as a contradiction to the arguments in the rest of the chapter. 27 I£ this addition does contradict the rest of the chapter, as Jaeger insists, perhaps one would agree with Professor Guthrie that it was added by a " not too intelligent editor." 28 On the face of it, Jaeger's theory accounts for the interpolated passages; but there is still something unsatisfying about accusing Aristotle of being so clumsy in his revision of these portions of the Phyf!ics and M etaphyf!ics. Does it not seem strange that Aristotle would have allowed one interpolation three lines long (Phyf!ics 259b 28-30) to suffice as a revision of his entire theory of the unity of the unmoved mover? I£ Aristotle were revising his theory to include the existence of a plurality of prime unmoved movers, does it not seem as though this would have called for a more drastic revision of the eighth book of the Phyf!ics? Does it not likewise seem strange that Aristotle would have left chapter 8 of Metaphyf!ics lambda in such a condition that •• Ibid., p. 353. W. K. C. Guthrie, "The Development of Aristotle's Theology- II" The Classical Quarterly (New York and London: The Classical Association) XXVIII 28 (1934), p. 97. ARISTOTLE's DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 531 a "self-critical" note in the margin would contradict the arguments of the entire chapter? And is it not equally difficult to believe that Aristotle's "faithful editors" understood him so imperfectly that they introduced a glaring contradiction into the body of the text? If one accepts Jaeger's interpretation, viz., that Aristotle is changing from a belief in only one prime unmoved mover to a plurality of prime unmoved movers, he is left with no choice but to insist that Aristotle is enmeshed in flagrant contradiction. If, on the other hand, one can find an interpretation that does justice to the text but avoids the alleged contradiction, so much the better for Aristotle. RANDALL's SoLUTION One fairly recent, and obviously attractive, solution to this difficulty is offered by Professor Randall in his book on Aristotle/ 9 in which he argues that the unmoved movers are really principles of intelligibility analogous to Newton's laws of motion. By this interpretation he attempts to extricate Aristotle from the difficulties in which traditional interpretations have entangled him by insisting that much of Aristotle's language is metaphorical and even mythical. Randall argues that Aristotle's First Philosophy, i.e., the science of any existent as existent, sustained a relation to Aristotle's physics analogous to the relation of mathematics and mathematical logic to modern physics. He characterizes mathematics and logic as the " metaphysics " of modern science in the Aristotelian sense of" first philosophy." Contemporary mathematics sets forth the formal structure or order which makes natural processes intelligible. " In very much the same sense," Randall argues, "Aristotle's First Philosophy is the 'metaphysics' growing out of his logic and biology .... " 30 Given this view of Aristotle's metaphysics, it is a small step Aristotle (New York: Columbia University Press, •• John Herman Randall. 1960). For an excellent critical review of Randall's book, see Troy Organ, "Randall's lnterpretation of Aristotle's Unmov•ed Mover," The Philosophical Quarterly 12 (October, 1962), pp. 3-11. 80 Randall, Aristotle, p. 110. 582 DAVID STEW ART to conclude that the first mover of Metaphysics lambda is only a principle of intelligibility. Randall correctly points out that for Aristotle motion has no efficient cause, but it must have a "reason why," a Oto r£; and to discover this "reason why " is not to attempt to find a cause of motion but rather to discover its function. Randall asks: How are we to understand the fact that it is motion, and only motion, that " causes" motion, world without end? The answer to this question will be a principle of intelligibility: it will be the arche of motion. In our own physics, motion is understood in terms of the "laws of motion," Newtonian or Einsteinian. Aristotle's answer, the Unmoved Mover, is just such an answer to just such a question: it is the Aristotelian counterpart of Newton's principia mathematica of motion, the laws of motion, the laws of motion of the science of dynamics. 31 One fact that Randall uses to support his view is that the unmoved mover is not a creator either of motion or of anything else. From this Randall concludes that " it is a logical explanation, not a physical cause, a natural law, not a force .... It is an arche, a principle of intelligibility, a ' reason why.' " 32 Because Randall views the unmoved mover as a principle of intelligibility rather than a physical cause, he insists that it is a principle of physics rather than a principle of metaphysics. " Book Lambda," he says, " thus has no real place in Aristotle's metaphysics, taken as his mature First Philosophy." Randall goes on to assert that it has no place in theology either and "is not to be identified with' God,' in any Moslem, Jewish, or Christian sense." 33 The reasons Randall gives for this are that the unmoved mover does not create anything; it does not sustain the world; in fact, it does not even know the world and does not have the power of intelligence in the' sense in which man is intelligent. Randall concludes that since Aristotle's unmoved mover has no power, no knowledge, and no moral or religious relevance; inasmuch as there are really fifty-five unmoved movers corresponding to the fifty-five heavenly motions to be explained; 11 Ibid., p. 184. 82 Ibid., p. 135. 88 Ibid., p. 136. ARISTOTLE'S DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 533 and since the unmoved mover is a purely intellectual idea and " the mature Aristotle did not understand and apparently had no interest in investigating " religion, it is a " colossal irony " that the medieval tradition made use of Aristotle's thought. 34 Obviously Randall interprets book lambda in purely naturalistic terms, a task which he must reconcile with the language of the book. For there can be little doubt that the terminology of book lambda is not the language of a scientist-a fact to which Randall agrees. He observes that Aristotle was in general a poor writer, and his language is usually technical. There are, however, a few passages which exhibit what Randall calls " artistic form," among which is " One swallow does not make a summer," the eloquent passages in the Ethics on friendship, and the description of the unmoved mover in book lambda. Randall argues that, although Aristotle's thought is thol'oughly naturalistic, his feelings and em(otions in book lambda clearly are not. He admits that the language and metaphors-even the " religious exaltation "-are all theistic; but they are to be compared to statements such as Dante's line, "'Tis Love that makes the world go round!" 35 Randall retreats somewhat from his earlier contention that the unmoved mover is comparable to Newton's laws of motion, for to Aristotle it would be unintelligible to talk in terms of blind forces of nature, such as Newtonian inertia. For rationalists like Aristotle (and Whitehead), "there must be a force like 'love '-desire, aspiration, the striving toward perfection. That is what makes men go round; and if men are a fair sampling of nature, that may be what makes nature go round too." 36 Randall argues that there are two " logics " interacting here-the "logic of perfection," the logic of the lover's discourse and the " logic of existence," the logic of physics and natural science. Randall's conclusion is that Aristotle unites the two " logics " in the language of myth, analogous to the "likely language" of Plato's Timaeus. "The Unmoved l\1over may well be called a Platonic myth, like the ' Active Intellect ' •• Ibid. 85 Ibid., p. 188. 86 Ibid., pp. 188-89. 534 DAVID STEW ART of the De Anima." 87 The mythical element is not the positing of fifty-five separate unmoved movers-this is to be taken literally-but rather the unification of them into a single cosmic unmoved mover. But if God is the highest activity in the world, what must he be? Aristotle himself answers that this activity must be pure understanding, pure nous. Randall adds: "For Aristotle, indeed for any Greek, the perfected functioning of nou.),"but, when from the fact that the eternal spatial motion of the universe requires a first immovable mover he raises the question whether the eternal spatial motions of the planets similarly require immovable movers, he drops the terms "accidentally" and argues only from the existence of a " first mover " who must be "immovable essentially " to the existence of a " substance " as the mover of each planetary sphere which is also "immovable essentially." 54 The crucial point is that Aristotle never describes the planetary movers as first movers; he reserves this term for the mover he describes as the first principle which is not movable either in itself or accidentally. 55 The planetary movers are described as only " first and another second according to the same order as the movements of the stars .... " "6 In light of Physics VIII, 6, it seems obvious that Aristotle applies the distinctions concerning accidental motion in book lambda of the Metaphysics. As Wolfson notes, "Aristotle assumes that the mover of the planetary spheres are movable accidentally, with the qualification, of course, as stated in the third passage in Physics VIII, 6, that they are movable accidentally, not by themselves, but by something else." 57 This "something else" is the first immovable mover, which is neither moved essentially nor accidentally. Seen from the vantage point of this interpretation of Metaphysics XII, 8, the interpolation at 1074a 32 ff. becomes less of a problem. Aristotle is simply arguing that the first unmoved mover is one both in species and number. Without going •• Jaeger, op. cit., p. 861. "'Wolfson, op. cit., p. 288, citing Metaphysics XII, 8 1078• 28-27. 55 Metaphysics XII, 8, 1078• 25. •• Ibid., 1074b 1. 57 Wolfson, op. cit., p. 289. ARISTOTLE's DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 541 into the details of Aristotle's argument at this point it can be noted that his proof applies only to the first unmoved mover. His conclusion is: "So the unmovable first is one both in definition and in number; so too, therefore, is that which is moved always and continuously; therefore there is one heaven alone." 58 The important thing to note in this passage, Wolfson points out, is that " the unity in both species and number is established only with regard to the first immovable mover, that first immovable mover which previously in the same chapter he has described as being ' immovable both essentially and accidentally.' " 59 But how can there be a plurality of planetary movers? Unfortunately, Aristotle does not tell us explicitly, and we are forced to reconstruct-as accurately as possible-a good Aristotelian answer. The genus of all the planetary movers is the same, viz., they are immaterial, immovabable movers. Since matter is the principle of individuation, and since the planetary movers are immaterial, they can be many in number only if each is a pure form comprising a separate species by virtue of the fact that each planetary mover moves a different planetary sphere. This is the interpretation favored by both Wolfson and Ross. 60 It should be noted, however, that at best this and all other similar interpretations of the problem are reconstructions and as such may not have been the answer that Aristotle himself would have given. The interpretation suggested above does offer a viable solution to the question of the number of unmoved movers without violating any Aristotelian principle and makes Aristotle consistent without reading into the text points of view which Aristotle did not share. This rapprochment between the Physics and the Meta-; physics is based on the assumption, for which I have argued above, that book lambda of the Metaphysics assumes the distinctions of the Physics. But not all interpreters agree on this point. Joseph Owens, for one, objects to any solution •• Metaphysics XII, 8, 1074• 36ff. •• Wolfson, op. cit., p. 240. •• Ibid., p. 241, and W. D. Ross, Aristotle's Metaphysics Press, 1924), pp. cxxxiv-cxl. (Oxford: Clarendon DAVID STEW ART which considers the first unmoved mover to be immobile both essentially and accidentally while considering the planetary movers to be unmoved essentially but not accidentally. He states: "This distinction applies to the Movers of the Physics The Movers of the Metaphysics, (Ph., VIII 6, however, have absolutely no matter, nor are they forms of matter. So they cannot be mobile in any way whatsoever. ." 61 Owens seems to be assuming two Cf. A 6, 107lb things here: (1) the unmoved movers of the Physics and the unmoved movers of the Metaphysics are two different classes the unmoved movers of the Physics are of entity; and material substances, whereas the unmoved movers of the Metaphysics are not. The thrust of the preceding sections of this essay has been to argue against the first assumption by showing that the unmoved movers of the Physics and Metaphysics are identical. The second assumption is completely without foundation in the Physics. Nowhere in the Physics does Aristotle state that the planetary movers are material substances. Moreover, Aristotle devotes the last chapter of Physics VIII to the task of proving that the first unmoved mover is without magnitude. A similar argument with regard to the planetary movers would have been fairly straightforward for Aristotle, but it has already been shown that Aristotle's concern in the Physics was initially the first unmoved mover and references to the planetary movers were added later. This would explain why Aristotle did not offer such a proof. Owens' reference to Metaphysics 1071 b 17 is really irrelevant to his argument. Aristotle is here arguing against those who identify the planetary movers with Platonic forms. His point is that the planetary movers are pure act and of necessity can have no admixture of potentiality. Although it is true that the planetary movers are not forms of matter, as Owens points out, they nonetheless can be conceived as pure forms. Even Owens admits that this is the only way they can be .a plurality. 62 61 62 Owens, op. cit., p. 415, n. 41. Joseph Owens, "The Reality of the Aristotelian Separate Movers," The ARISTOTLE's DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 543 Further light is shed on the subject at M etaphymcs 1073!l U-23. The first principle or primary being is not movable either in itself or accidentally, but produces the primary eternal and single movement. But . . . since we see that besides the simple spatial movements of the universe, which we say the first and unmovable substance produces, there are other spatial movements-those of the planets-which are eternal . . . each of these movements also must be caused by a substance both unmovable in itself and eternal. The view being defended in this article is that Aristotle here assumes the distinctions of Physics VIII, exemplified by the fact that he reserves for the first unmoved mover the description "not movable either in itself or accidentally." But when referring to the planetary movers he only says that they are unmovable per se and eternal. Why does Aristotle not say of them that they too are unmoved accidentally? Precisely because they receive their accidental motion from the first unmoved mover; yet they are unmoved essentially (per se) and are therefore eternal. Owens, however, objects to this interpretation of Metaphysics 1073a 24-34. The difficulty in drawing this interpretation out of the text, however, is that in the latter sentence Aristotle refers to the First Mover and the other ]\lovers in exactly the same terms-" per se immoble and eternal" (a27; 33-34). If he had meant any contrast, he should in this sentence, have characterized the First Mover as per accidens immobile, and not in the preceding sentence where only the First Mover was in question. 63 It is difficult to understand why Owens says that Aristotle refers. to the First Mover and the other Movers in " exactly the same terms," for the subject under discussion in the latter Review of Metaphysics, III (March, 1950), 333-34. Owens denies that there is a distinction here between the first unmoved mo¥er and the planetary movers, but he does state that " They are all forms without matter, distinct only by the fact of being different forms; and even this distinction is known to men only through the order of the heavenly motions." •• Owens, The Doctrine of Being, p. 415, n. 41. 544 DAVID STEW ART part of the text at Metaphysics 1073a is not the first mover at all but only the planetary movers. Evidence for this is the fact that the demonstrative pronoun rovrwv in line 33 a present active participle, refers back to TClS row which is in apposition to aAAa<; cf>opas OV(Ja<;. In other words, the first unmoved mover is in no sense the subject of the last part of the citation. It is also precarious to state with assurance what Aristotle should have written. And it does not follow that Aristotle should have made the distinction between the two kinds of motion in the last sentence, as Owens claims. For if one accepts the view that the distinctions of the Physics are assumed in the Metaphysics, there would be no particular reason for Aristotle to repeat them. Note, too, that in lines 31 and (at 1073a) Aristotle states: "for a body which moves in a circle is eternal and unresting; we have proved these points in the physical treatises." This is a reference to Physics VIII-the same book in which Aristotle introduced the distinctions between essential immobility (per se) and accidental immobility (per accidens). What further evidence is needed to justify the claim that Aristotle is assuming throughout the the prior treatment of the subject in the Physics? If the view argued for in this article is accepted, any difficulty in reconciling Aristotle's treatment of the unmoved mover in the Physics and Metaphysics disappears. By applying the distinction of Physics VIII to the discussion of the unmoved mover in Metaphysics lambda, one can make Aristotle consistent without doing violence to the Aristotelian texts. In the Physics Aristotle distinguishes between essential immobility and accidental immobility. The first unmoved mover is imThe planetary mobile both essentially and accidentally. movers, in contrast, are unmoved essentially but not accidentally. The implication is that the planetary movers receive their accidental motion from the first unmoved mover, which moves the outer sphere. Although Aristotle does not explicitly state in the Metaphysics that the planetary movers are not unmoved accidentally, this poses no problem if one agrees (as ARISTOTLE'S DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 545 there is good reason to) that he is assuming the distinctions of Physics VIII. But it is worthy of note that Aristotle does 1eserve for the first unmoved mover alone the designation of being unmoved both essentially and accidentally. The upshot of this is that there seems to be in Aristotle a hierarchy of being implicit in the doctrine of the unmoved mover. The first unmoved mover is prior in that it is unmoved both essentially and accidentally, whereas the planetary movers are only unmoved essentially. The first unmoved mover is also prior in the sense that the planetary movers receive additional motion from the movement of the outer heaven, which is moved by the first unmoved mover. A MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE It adds weight to the interpretation being defended in this study to discover that it is consistent with the Thomistic understanding of the Aristotelian doctrine of the unmoved mover. One would perhaps have to admit that St. Thomas was a little too anxious to identify Aristotle's unmoved mover with the father of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, but this is beside the point. Many modern commentators on St. Thomas and his Aristotelianism candidly point out that the Prime Mover of Aristotle is not the Christian's God. But Owens, and other interpreters of Thomas, are left in somewhat of a quandry if they insist, as Owens does, that all fifty-five planetary movers are ontologically equal with the first unmoved mover. It leaves Aristotle in a hopeless inconsistency and causes interpreters to puzzle themselves as to the reason Aristotle left the text of the Physics and the Metaphysics in such terrible shape. I have argued that there is a hierarchy among the unmoved movers. The planetary movers are immobile only per se, whereas the first unmoved mover is unmoved both per se and per accidens. This is exactly the way in which Thomas Aquinas interpreted Aristotle. In Surnrna Contra Gentiles, Book One, Thomas basically followed the same line of argument used by Aristotle in Metaphysics XII, while at the same time assuming the distinctions made in the Physics. The following citation verifies this. 546 DAVID STEW ART Again, we see that among beings that move themselves some initiate a new motion as a result of some motion. This new motion is other than the motion by which an animal moves itself, for example, digested food or altered air. By such a motion the selfmoving mover is moved by accident. From this we may infer that no self-moved being is moved everlasting whose mover is moved either by itself or by accident. But the first self-mover is everlastingly in motion; otherwise, motion could not be everlasting, since every other motion is caused by the motion of the self-moving first mover. The first self-moving being, therefore, is moved by a mover who is himself moved neither through himself nor by accident. 64 This is practically a paraphrase from Physics VIII. In reference to the planetary spheres, Thomas comments: Nor is it against this argument that the movers of the lower spheres produce an everlasting motion and yet are said to be moved by accident. For they are said to be moved by accident, not on their own account, but on account of their movable subjects, which follow the motion of the higher sphere. 65 That Thomas goes on to refer continually to the Physics in the same context is proof enough that in interpreting the Metaphysics he assumes the distinctions of the Physics. In Book II of the Summa Contra Gentiles, chapter 95, Thomas offers a solution to the problem of how genus and species are to be taken in separate substances. His conclusion is that each separate substance comprises a separate species and that there is a hierarchy of "diverse grades." This is the same conclusion reached in the disputed question On Spiritu.al Creatures, Article 8. The ways in which St. Thomas departed from Aristotle so as to identify the Aristotelian separate substances with angels is sketched out in his Treatise On Separate Substances, Chapter 2. It is not the purpose of this essay to go into detail at this point. But the important thing to note is that St. Thomas did not naively identify God with the first mover of Aristotle, nor did he glibly identify the planetary 64 Summa Contra Gentiles, trans. Antoo C. Pegis (New York: Books, 1955), Book I, 13, fl6. •• Ibid., Book I, 13, 27. Doubleday Image ARISTOTLE'S DOCTRINE OF THE UNMOVED MOVER 547 movers with angels. Rather, these items are to be considered within the context of Thomas's total philosophical system. CONCLUSION One can certainly accept the textual criticism of Jaeger without involving Aristotle in hopeless contradictions, but one is by no means forced to Randall's position which brings a degree of consistency to Aristotle's Metaphysics by impugning the substantial reality of the unmoved movers. It has been shown in this article that the argument of the Metaphysics flows smoothly without contradiction if one applies the distinctions of Physics VIII. This was doubtless Aristotle's intention, and the interpretation of the Metaphysics by Thomas Aquinas likewise proceeds along these lines. It is also significant to observe that nowhere in his commentary on the Metaphysics does Thomas find the hopeless contradictions that have plagued modern interpreters. DAVID STEWART Ohio University Athenlt, Ohio DEELY AND GEACH ON ABSTRACTIONISM THOMISTIC EPISTEMOLOGY IN I N THE JANUARY, 1971 issue o£ The Thomist, there appeared a quite long and involved article by John N. Deely entitled "Animal Intelligence and Concept Formation." Deely admits that the provocation of the article was his reading o£ Peter Geach's Mental Acts. 1 As Deely notes/ Mortimer Adler, in his The Difference in Man and the Difference It remarks that Professor Geach had adequately treated the theory of abstractionism and had found it to be epistemologically wanting. Adler appeared convinced by Geach's arguments. Furthermore, Geach purported to find support for his anti-abstractionist position in the writings of St. Thomas. In Mental Acts, Geach both explicitly quotes and makes allusions to the Summa Theologiae on numerous occasions. Moreover, Geach includes an appendix exclusively devoted to a " Historical Note " on " Aquinas and Abstractionism." Throughout his text Geach affirms that St. Thomas would structurally agree with his own remarks on the epistemological errors latent in the theory o£ abstractionism. Deely is very much concerned about Geach's negative critique o£ abstractionism and its relation to St. Thomas's epistemology. He explicitly proclaims that he has a two-fold goal in his article; he intends to show the "utter absurdity " of: a. Geach's historical claim-" that the 'mature Aquinas' was not an abstractionist "; 1 Peter Geach, Mental Acts: Their Content and Their Objects (London: Routledge and Keegan Paul, Ltd.). 2 John Deely, "Animal Intelligence and Concept-Formation," The Thomist, XXXV (January, 1971), pp. 43-93. 548 DEELY AND GEACH ON ABSTRACTIONISM 549 b. Geach's personal claim-" that the ' whole idea ' of abstraction is completely incoherent." 3 In this article I intend to argue that Deely has conceptually blurred two aspects of Geach's treatment of abstractionism. First of all, I believe that Geach's comments are intricately connected with the "use theory of meaning." Although Deely notes that Geach begins from a linguistic basis-and Deely finds fault with this beginning point for a philosophical analysis 4 -he seems unaware of the great significance played in Geach's critique by the "use theory of meaning." Secondly, I believe that Deely has misunderstood the structural account of abstractionism as used by Geach and a fortimi of abstractionism as found in the epistemological treatises written in the analytic tradition of British Philosophy since 1900. Accordingly, I believe that if Geach is to be understood in his critique of abstractionism, a necessary condition for such an understanding is both an awareness of the connection of the "use theory of meaning " to Geach' s analysis as well as a thorough elucidation of the concept of " abstractionism " as utilized by the early twentieth-century analytic philosophers. Furthermore, I believe that only in this light can Geach's claims about St. Thomas's epistemology and abstractionism be critically evaluated. In order to understand Geach's position on abstractionism, it would be well to begin with Geach's own description of this purported epistemological process: I shall use "abstractionism" as a name for the doctrine that a concept is acquired by a process of singling out in attention some one feature given in direct experience-abstracting it-and ignorfrom ing the other .features simultaneously given-abstracting them. 5 Geach is arguing that a process of singling out discriminative data in direct experience-what has been referred to as " direct acquaintance "-is not a sufficient condition for an analysis of the acquisition of concepts. Furthermore, it must be re• Ibid., p. 56. • Ibid., p. 89 ff. 'Geach, p. 18. 550 ANTHONY J. LISSKA membered that Geach is concerned over how we acqmre a meaningful command of language. 6 A prima facie consideration of these remarks by Geach would indicate that St. Thomas could hardly be used in support of Geach's anti-abstractionist position. It is obvious to any reader even vaguely familiar with the Thomistic epistemological texts that the term " abstractio" and its various derivatives appear quite frequently when St. Thomas considers both concept-formation through the workings of the intellectus agens and the actual understanding of a concept by means of the intellectus possibilis. Nevertheless, I will argue that Geach's remarks must not be immediately dismissed. First of all, one must discuss the structure of the concept of " abstractionism " as criticized by Geach in Mental Acts. It is only after this elucidation has been accomplished that one can justifiably make a judgment as to whether or not St. Thomas would agree with Geach's critique of abstractionism. A consideration of Mental Acts might best begin with a brief discussion of the philosophical milieu in which this epistemology text first appeared. Mental Acts was published in 1957. Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations was posthumously published in Ryle's Concept of Mind was in its first edition in 1949. The philosophical insights and discussions of both Wittgenstein and Ryle, I believe, must be considered as contextual material for an enlightened understanding of Mental Acts. Both books are an example of what has come to be called "Ordinary Language Philosophy." Geach himself follows this philosophical methodology in some of his analytical work. This methodology is characterized by the systematic attempt to provide " conceptual elucidations " of puzzling philosophical 6 Geach analyzes a concept as an acquired mental disposition. A concept is defined by Geach as a " mental capacity belonging to a particular person. " (Mental Acts, p. 13) This is connected with a theory of language in that Geach argues that " ... the central and typical applications of the term 'having a concept' are those in which a man is master of a bit of linguistic usage. " (/bid.) That St. Thomas used a dispositional view in analyzing both the formation and the exercise of concepts is apparent in his remarks in his Commentary on Aristotle's On the Soul, Nos. 359-361. DEELY AND GEACH ON ABSTRACTIONISM 551 concepts. Another way of describing this methodology is that ordinary language philosophers attempt to discover the" logic" of various concepts and expressions found in philosophical discourse. Understanding the" logic" of a concept is analogous to what scholastic philosophers have called "understanding the nature of a thing." That Geach places his allegiance with ordinary language philosophy is explicitly stated in Mental Acts when Geach describes his philosophical task as one of providing an elucidation of the " logical role " of " mental language ": Such and such object expressions are used in describing these mental acts; what is the logical role of these expressions.7 Not only is Geach to be associated with ordinary language During the philosophy, but he is also a Wittgensteinian. 1950's the Philosophical Investigations was serving as a philosophical spring-board for much creative and useful analysis. It is no understatement to affirm that the Investigations revolutionized analytic philosophy. I believe Mental Acts is the result of Geach's reflections on both the methodology and the insights of Wittgenstein's philosophical remarks. Some philosophers, however, were claiming that Wittgenstein himself was arguing against the existence and meaningfulness of mental activity. That Ryle's "Descartes' Myth" chapter in The Concept of Mind 8 strongly attacked mental activity associated with the " ghost in the machine " is quite obvious. Accordingly, in light of Wittgenstein's remarks in the Inve,