THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICANFATHERS OF THE PROVINCE oF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington, D. C. 20017 VoL. XXXIX OCTOBER, 1975 No.4 TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE AND REALIST METAPHYSICS I. URING THE FIRST decades o£ this century Thomists, anxious lest they be charged as dogmatists before the bar o£ post-Cartesian philosophy, concentrated on the problem o£ philosophical method. 1 In the development o£ this school o£ methodologically-oriented Thomists, Pere Joseph Marechal, S. J., 1878-1944, remains a preeminent figure.2 His magnum opus, Le point de depart de la metaphysique, consists o£ five volumes," c.ahiers,"which are subtitled" D 1 See Georges van Riet, Thomistic Epistemology: Studies Concerning the Problem of Cognition in the Contemporary Thomistic School, trans. by Gabriel Franks (St. Louis: B. Herder Book Company, 1963) . • Cf. Bernard J. F. Lonergan, S. J., " Metaphysics as Horizon," in Collection: Papers by Bernard Lonergan (New York: Herder and Herder, 1967), p. HZ; Otto Muck, The Transcendental Method, trans. by William P. Seidensticker (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968), pp. 631 632 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY sur le developpement historique et theorique du probleme de la connaissance." 8 Cahiers I to IV project an historical nexus for what Marechal identified as the modern philosophical problem of knowledge. Cahier V resolves this same problem by a polemical epistemology derived from a confrontation of St. Thomas and Kant. 4 Most notably, this fifth volume displays Marechal's effort to refute the Critical Philosophy from its own principles by utilizing the Kantian transcendental method to reestablish a " Thomistic " or, as I shall emphasize, a realist metaphysics. For the specific " problem of knowledge " set forth in Cahier V is the possibility of a method that could guarantee metaphysics to be a universal and apodeictic science of Being.5 Among Thomists, Cakier V provoked a controversy in which it was argued, often sharply, that Marechal had violated not only the letter but also the spirit of orthodox Thomistic philosophical doctrine. 6 If this· particular polemic is jejune, as it is sometimes claimed/ the basic controversy, far from being a passing scholastic quibble, has been kept alive in today's 8 Cahier 1: De l'antiquite a la fon du moyen age: la critique ancienne de la ccmnaissance, 1st ed. (Paris: Alcan, Museum Lessianum, section philosophique, 1922); Cakier II: Le conjtit du raticmalisme et de l'empirisme dans la pkilosopkie modeme avant Kant, 1st ed. (Ibid., 1923); Cahier Ill: La Critique de Kant (Ibid., 1923); Cakier IV: Le systeme idealiste chez Kant et les postkantiens Desclee de Brouwer, Museum (Brussels: L'Edition Universelle, and Paris: Lessianum, section philosophique, 1947 [published posthumously]); Cahier V: Le tkomisme devant la pkilosopkie critique (Louvain: Editions du Museum Lessianum, and Paris: Alcan, 1926) . For the complete bibliography, see A. Milet, " Bibliographie du Pere J. Marechal," in Melanges Mareckal, I (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 1950), pp. 47-71. A partial English translation of the five cahiers can be found in A Mareckal Reader, trans. and ed. by Joseph Donceel (New York: Herder and Herder, 1970). All of my citations of Marechal refer to the volume and page number of the French original. • See V, 14; 84. • See V, 15; 34-43. 6 The bibliography for this controversy can be found in Milet, pp. 65-71. Cf. Muck, pp. 205-243. 7 See Bernard A. M. Nachbar, "Is It Thomism? ," Continuum, 6 (1968), pp. 282-235. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 633 discussion of the role of hermeneutics and method in determining the rational foundations of metaphysics and theology .8 Under the guise of hermeneutics, there is reincarnated the dominant issue of the earlier exchange: the proper interrelationship of metaphysics and epistemology .9 Yet, the current methodological vogue is unequivocal only in that it endows Le point de depart de la metaphysique with a contemporary significance. How this significance is to be discerned, stated, and evaluated continues to be a major dilemma if the principles of a Thomistic tradition are compared with the diverse, perhaps contrary, presuppositions of prevailing hermeneutical theories. 10 In the original debate, one can conveniently isolate two kinds of questions. Roughly speaking, there are: (1) historical questions about the Thomistic character of Marechal's metaphysics; (2) philosophical questions about the criteria that would serve to identify a genuine doctrinal development within a philosophical tradition. 11 However, it is this distinct separation of historical and philosophical questions which is now frequently labelled an uncritical assumption ignorant of the cognitive horizons that structure our inquiries. Operationally, in the actual exegesis of a text, the two kinds of questions are, to be sure, sometimes mixed together. The stronger and here principal thesis is that hermeneutical presuppositions necessarily determine the structure of all historical or exegetical questions and their corresponding answers. 12 8 See Foundations of Theology, ed. by Philip McShane, S. J. (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1971) and Language, Truth and Meaning, ed. by Philip McShane (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1972). • See Etienne Gilson, Le realisme methodique (Paris: Pierre Tequi, n. d. [1935]). 10 See Etienne Gilson, Linguistique et Philosophie; Essai sur les constantes phiques du langage (Paris: J. Vrin, 1969). 11 Cf. Jacques Maritain, The Degrees of Knowledge, ed. by Gerald B. Phelan (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1959), pp. 71-81. 12 " In view of this intention of any ' retrieving ' interpretation, it in fact appears doubtful whether it is to be refuted in detail by arguments from traditional research. . . .. It would be remiss to assume that there is for Heidegger a thing ' in itself ' which could ' from the outside ' yield a ' criterion ' which would determine whether the 'unsaid ' in what is said in a definite text has been disclosed 'correctly' or 'falsely.'" Werner Marx, Heidegger and the Tradition, trans. by 684 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY As a prophylaxis against this thesis of a constitutive hermeneutical a priori, whose radical historicism could only be cured by some form of realist metaphysics, let us assume that we all travel around the famous circle: that the meaning of a text can only be exposed from an intellectual and cultural stance, and that the stance requires a further critique to render itself explicit. So much, one readily supposes, is obligatory for every self-reflective investigation. But acknowledgement of the hermeneutical circle does not entail the additional but commonly held premise that the intentionality of any but especially of a historical text is, in itself* inaccessible to the inquiries of the reader. That is, one can abstain from or repudiate a hermeneutics in which the interpretation of the text becomes essentially an imposition or a construction of meaning, a construction whose plausibility is determined not by the intrinsic intelligibility embodied in the text but by the systematic consistency of the cognitive horizons or categories of the interpreter. 18 In opposition to a " Copernican" hermeneutics 14 or, more exactly, to its epistemological forebear, the Thomists of MareTheodore Kisiel and MurraY: Greene (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1971)' pp. 109-110. Merely to catch the Hegelian-Heideggerian resonance that can be heard among some contemporary " neo-scholastic " philosophers, the following quotation seems example enough: " There is no pure immediacy of what appears and what is to be received because every objective content which comes to us as givenness is already mediated through the performance of the subject. The way in which we see the object, against which background and in which context we understand it, which questions we direct at it, and which answer-from our perspective-we expect from it, all this helps determine the object as it discloses itself to us and becomes ' phenomenon.' "-Emerich Coreth, S. J. "I=ediacy and the Mediation of Being: An Attempt to Answer Bernard Lonergan," in Language, Truth and Meaning, ed. McShane, p. 88. 13 Cf. Joseph Owens, C.Ss. R., "Judgment and Truth in Aquinas," in Mediaeval Studies, 82 (1970), pp. 188-158; Hans Jonas, "Change and Permanence: On the Possibility of Understanding History," Ch. 12 in Philosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1974), pp. 287-260. " " On peut penser que Kant, de nos jours, aurait donne un supplement a sa Dialectique, specialement consacre a l'histoire." Victor Goldschmidt, Platonisme et pensee contemporaine (Paris: Aubier Montaigne, 1970), p. 218. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 635 chal's generation, by reason of their own noetic principles, were obliged to evaluate, historically, the Thomistic character of his metaphysics. That historical interpretation proceeded from the realist contention that meaning or intentionality is effected by but is not a construction of the human intellect. In Thomistic terms, the debate about a historically, that is, a textually verifiable interpretation of St. Thomas, is legitimated by the very possibility of metaphysical knowledge. Words and word usage are, indeed, immersed in the obfuscating changes of history, hence the need for hermeneutics, but intelligence and intelligibility transcend their historical instantiations, hence the need for a realist hermeneutics. Now the human mind ... is in itself above time, but it is subject to time accidentally, inasmuch as it understands with continuity and time, in keeping with the phantasms in which it considers the intelligible species ... (Summa Theol., I-II, q. 113, a. 7, ad 5). A text, albeit difficult to interpret, retains a potential but intrinsic intelligibility which historical exegesis partially unveils but does not create. Understanding in its own right the meaning of a text, the goal of a realist hermeneutics, is an instance analogous to the intellect grasping the natural intelligibility of a thing. 15 For hermeneutics, with all of its peculiar and sometimes intractable problems, is a derivative science governed, in its fundaments, by the principles permitting knowledge of Being. The distinction posed between historical and philosophical questions does not deny that such investigations are reciprocal. They are, however, differently ordered. Historical exegesis aims to reveal the meaning of the text in itself; philosophical reflection, methodologically subsequent, demonstrates that this intelligibility can, in principle, be revealed in itself. Therefore, in the order of discovery of meaning, historical exegesis can 15 A realist hermeneutics reflects the crucial distinction between instrumental signs (words and texts) and formal signs (concepts). For the epistemological elements of a realist hermeneutics, see Maritain, Degrees of Knowledge, pp. 119-128, 387-417. 636 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY function independently of any explicit hermeneutical theory. 16 The Thomists' response to Marechal centered on a point of order-the order to be observed between metaphysics and epistemology. Does a realist metaphysics, to be considered apodeictic, need as its proper prolegomenon a critique of knowledge? The judgment that Marechal's philosophy is not " Thomistic " depended on historical and systematic arguments that asserted the impropriety of such a critical prolegomenon for a Thomistic Realism. These arguments merit rehearsal, but, since the stated purpose of Cahier V is also to instantiate the Critical Philosophy, it is no less compelling to ascertain whether Marechal reestablished a realist metaphysics of Being by means of a Kantian transcendental method. 17 Roughly speaking, this is an investigation of the historical kind which, although it does not evoke the full Thomistic doctrine of metaphysical knowledge, at least grants that the hermeneutical circle is not " vicious " : that there is an essential distinction to be maintained between the intentions and meanings embodied in a text and the structuring features of our inquiry into the text. On this realist hermeneutical principle, which Marechal professed/ 8 is founded the central historical analogy drawn in Cahier V: between Aquinas and Aristotle, Marechal and Kant. 16 " We need, in the first place, a nonhistoricist understanding of nonhistoricist philosophy. But w.e need no less urgently a nonhistoricist understanding of historicism, that is, an understanding of the genesis of historicism that does not take for granted the soundness of historicism." Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago.: The University of Chicago Press, 1953), p. 33. " What does a philosophical understanding of the history of philosophy involve? It involves nothing less than the discovery of philosophy itself. Only he who knows philosophy can see the history of philosophy in its light. If there is a philosophical truth, then it and it alone is the real location of the meaning of the history of philosophy." Anton C. Pegis, Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, Vol. I, "Introduction" (New York: Random House, 1945), p. xliii. 17 A project suggested but not carried out by Francis P. Fiorenza in the "Introduction " to Karl Raimer, Spirit in the World, trans. by William Dych, S. J. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968), p. xxxiv. 18 Cf. V, 13-17; 29-31. The conclusion of this paper is to question whether Marechal could consistently maintain such realist principles. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 637 II. The vocabulary common to Aristotle and Aquinas has occasioned the idea that Thomism, in its internal principles and structure, is Aristotelian philosophy in the service of a Christian emendation and amplification of Aristotelian doctrine. Such was Man!chal's conviction. 19 But this interpretation, and others like it, are over-simplifications that leave unexplained how Aristotle and St. Thomas, supposedly using the same principles and method. could have reached patently different conclusions in their respective metaphysics. 20 The historian most responsible for an alternative view, Gilson, has insisted that, despite the indisputable " presence . . . of an Aristotelian level," Thomism " did not come out of Aristotelianism by way of evolution but of revolution." 21 The transformation of Aristotle occurred, in the main, because St. Thomas believed in the theological doctrine of creation, understood God as the Prima Causa, and identified actus essendi and not form as the primary actuality in a finite substance. Put succinctly, Aristotle and St. Thomas reached different conclusions because their philosophical principles were different. In the most general perspective, to correlate the methods of St. Thomas and Aristotle is to distinguish the theological Summa of a mediaeval Christian theologian from the metaphysics of his Greek predecessor, a non-Christian, pagan philosopher. This delineation of the realms of philosophical nature 19 " ••• Ia pensee philosophique, a travers ses tatonnements, ses oscillations, ses deviations, ses redressements, ses progres, recherche obscurement, a chaque epoque, et aujourd'hui autant que jamais, une position d'equilibre, qui correspond, en fait, pour l'essentiel, a celle qu'occupa l'aristotetisme thomiste." V, 34. [Italics mine.] Cf. I, 101, 104, 106, 256-257; V, 35, 39, 75. 20 See Anton C. Pegis, St. Thomas and Philosophy (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1964); "Some Reflections on Summa Contra Gentiles II, 56," An Etienne Gilson Tribute, ed. by Charles J. O'Neil (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1959), pp. 169-188. 21 Etienne Gilson, Being and Some Philosophers (Torcmto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1952), p. 158; History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages (New York: Random House, 1955), p. 365. 638 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY and theological grace touches upon theoretical and historical problems too many and too complex to be raised here. 22 Instead, it is sufficient only to note that considered that Aristotle and St. Thomas had engendered a common, metaphysical patrimony. For this heritage, Marechal essayed a transcendental justification that should have reconciled Kant's new method to old metaphysical conclusions. 28 Paradigmatic for the relationship drawn between Kantian method and realist metaphysics is the relationship that Marechal attributed to Aristotle and St. Thomas. As Aquinas had made explicit what was latent in Aristotelianism, so Marechal could make explicit and justify the realist metaphysics that he thought latent in the method of the Critical Philosophy. 24 If Marechal's project seems a quixotic or an untenable legerdemain, this suspicion is generated by one's own conception of the aim of the Critique of Pure Reason. For there have issued, from different interpretations of the Critical Philosophy, the numerous commentaries whose proliferation is mirrored in a variety of ideas about Kant's purpose in the first Critique. 25 Although Kant himself often mentioned what he hoped to accomplish, his intention is most neatly stated in the question that is asked in the " Introduction" : " How is metaphysics, as science, possible? " [B22]. This question, if we allow that it correctly poses the aim of the Critique, requires attention to Kant's deployment of the term "metaphysics." 26 22 See Anton C. Pegis, The Middle Ages and Philosophy: Some Reflections on the Ambivalence of Modern Scholasticism (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1963). •• Cf. V, 33-34, 39, 599-601. ••" Comment constater, dans le kantisme meme, la presence ou I' absence de cette metaphysique implicite .... Telle fut . . . {1'] attitude prise par les Cahiers devant le probleme de la connaissance." V, 602. •• See Nathan Rotenstreich, "Interpretations and Systems: On Approaches to the Critique of Pure Reason," in Experience and Its Systematization: Studies in Kant (The Hague: Martin us Nijhoff, 1965), pp. 132-174. •• See D. P. Dryer, Kant's Solution for Verification in Metaphysics (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1966). Cf. Nathan Rotenstreich, "Kant's Concept of Metaphysics," Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 8 (1954), pp. 392-408. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 639 In defining " metaphysics," Kant indicated that it is a knowledge of things but, mostly, he stressed that the Critique is an investigation concerned" not so much with objects as with the mode of our knowledge of objects" [AI2]. Kant's emphasis notwithstanding, the Critique is not, in the later sense of the Mar burg school, an epistemology. Kant, it is important to remember, was concerned with the mode of our knowledge of objects and not with our knowledge of knowledge. 27 Marechal can be assimilated to the group of interpreters who recognize that the purpose of the Critique of Pure Reason is to establish the possibility of metaphysics as a science.28 This assessment makes plausible, if only initially, Marechal's proposal to use the Critique to reestablish a metaphysics. That this is a realist metaphysics and that it can be derived from Kant's method is the heavy burden of proof assumed in the fifth cahier. For there, the demonstration of the "affirmation ontologique " is attempted. As itself an explicit judgment, the " affirmation ontologique " declaims the "absolu de l'etre": in Kantian terms, the existence and theoretical intelligibility of God and the noumenal order. 29 As true, the "affirmation ontologique" is the logical ground for all judgments and is the implicit condition of the possibility of any object of thought, 80 and, in that sense, resembles Kant's concept of the Transcendental Ego. 81 That it is also the ontological ground for the objectivity of knowledge precisely supersedes the possibilities of Kantian philosophy to express. Although the Critique does demonstrate the objectivity of human knowledge by explaining how the noetic object is conCf. Dryer, p. 26, footnote 2. See Heinz Heimsoeth, "Metaphysical Motives in the Development of Critical Idealism," in Kant: Disputed Questions, trans. and ed. by Moltke S. Gram (Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1967), pp. 158-199; Gerard Lebrun, Kant et la fin de la metaphysique (Paris: Armand Colin, 1970), pp. 13-41. 29 Cf. V, 318. •• Cf. V, 459. 81 Cf. Critique of Reason, B131-Bl36 = [K. r. V., B131-Bl36.]. 27 28 640 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY stituted in and for consciousness, Marechal, curiously enough, construed Kant's explanation as an answer to how the phenomenon, defined as "l'etat d'impression subjective," becomes an "object." For Marechal, the essential characteristic of a noetic object is a certain " unite independante " or self-contained permanency, whereas the defining mark of a phenomenon is its accidentality. A phenomerum.,Marechal claimed, is merely a changing, qualitative modification of consciousness.82 In this phenomenological sense, the distinguishing feature of the noetic object is that it is an" en-soi "known only" par opposition au sujet." 88 Whether there is an ontological ground for this phenomenological " opposition " both the Thomist and the Kaniian must determine. In making this determination, each philosophy confronts a comparable problem which can be located in reference to the coterminous intra-mental and extramental character of a noetic object. For St. Thomas, a noetic object is the immanent form of the intellect: " Intelligibile in actu est intellectus in actu." 84 But there is for this formula a counter-balance, the doctrine of the transcendent or intentional character of a noetic object: " Species. intelligibilis non est quod intelligitur, sed id quo intelligit intellectus." 85 From a profoundly altered slant, the Critique explains the noetic object as the product of the understanding, the " relation [which] is nothing but the necessary unity of consciousness." 86 But this revolutionary assertion must also be squared with Kant's famous remark in the "Aesthetic": "Thoughts without content are empty ... [and] it is, therefore, just as necessary to make our concepts sensible, that is to add the object to them in intuition." 87 Kant's account of the objectivity of knowledge Marechal regarded as an error originating in a self-contradictory doctrine •• Cf. III, 141-145. •• III, 145. •• Summa Theol., I, q. 14, a. 2. 86 Ibid., q. 85, a. 2 . •• K. T.v., A109 . •• K. T. v., A5l, TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 641 of phenomenality. The transcendental deduction of the" affirmation ontologique " is designed to expose this contradiction and to supply a true account of the ontological ground for the noetic object. The linchpin in Marechal's deduction is the concept of final causality, for it enabled him to appropriate the principal conclusion of traditional theory: that all agents must have some final end or terminus for their activity. And the human intellect, with its infinite potentiality, has for its final end Infinite Being. 38 The relationship of final causality is to be observed in the process that is identified as. objective knowledge. Marechal emphasized that the possession of an intelligible form, the species abstracted from the material thing, is not a static perfection or actualization of the intellect; it is "le dessin actuel d'un mouvement," 39 a provisory term or end of the intellect's tendency toward Infinite Being. As provisory, a noetic object is distinct from the knowing subject because it is only a partial realization of the intellect's potency and not the final end of the rationalis appetitus. Demonstrate that all these partial ends are necessarily in the " ordre absolu du noum{me," 40 and one thus proves that the condition which distinguishes a noetic object from the subject, the relationship of finality, is the same condition that grounds a noetic object in the ontological order. This demonstration establishes that the phenomenological affirmation of the extramental character of a noetic object also entails the ontological reality and intelligibility of the noetic object, the noumenal "en-soi " distinct from the subject. Kant restricted the affirmation of the noumenal order to postulates of practical reason that enshrine the moral necessity to ground the categorical imperative. In addition to the difficulties inherent in Kant's singularly austere concept of duty, 38 " L'infinite virtuelle de !'intelligence, comme puissance, et !'objet formel total de !'intelligence, l'etre abstrait et transcendantal, sont done des expressions correlatives, qui se peuvent indifferemment deduire l'une de l'autre." V, 375. 39 v, 443. 445. ••v, 642 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY Marechal discerned a more fundamental oversight in the argument from Practical Reason. Moral action is only secondary or derivative; practical postulates should be derived from the conditions of the fundamental human a priori, the necessity of voluntary action in genere. In opposition to Kant, Marechal insisted that the affirmation of the noumenal order is a necessity of theoretical reason because such an affirmation is the necessary logical condition for voluntary action in genere. That is, to attempt to will an end which is, under all conditions, a logical impossibility is simply to attempt to will non-being. And this notion, in reference to the primary nature of the will, is self-contradictory. 41 Consequently, the logical condition for every voluntary act or pursuit of an end, is, implicitly, the judgment that it is logically possible to realize this end. If we schematize Marechal' s prolix argumentation/ 2 his 41 Marechal claimed that the Final End, God, is logically possible for man to attain. It cannot be the case that " ... la tendance radicalle de notre nature intellectuelle devient une absurdite logique: l'appetit du neant" v, 448. In this reductio ad absurdum argument, Marechal fell back on the axiom, " Desiderium naturae non potest esse inane." Otherwise, " ... 'la volonte de nature' devrait etre con<;ue comme volonte de !'impossible: l'etre tendrait au neant; la position serait negation, le non-etre etre" V, 421. However, these assertions are not meant to compromise the gratuitous, super-natural character of the Final End. See V, 419-423. •• Marechal propounded a metaphysical and a transcendental deduction of the " affirmation ontologique." The transcendental deduction deploys the phenomenological method and is considered to be, because of Kant, an unavoidable prolegomenon for a critical metaphysics. (Cf. V, 15-16.) The phenomenological method, however, is " un artifice " yet legitimate because it terminates in " I'affirmation metaphysique sous les phenomimes" (V, 69). Thus, the two deductions are complementary since they both arrive at the same ontological conclusions. The metaphysical deduction, although it assumes the ontological reality of the noetic object, includes the transcendental subject. The transcendental deduction, although it begins only with the a priori subject, concludes to the existence and intelligibility of the ontological object. (Cf. V, 69-70.) The difference between the metaphysical and the transcendental deductions is the difference in their starting points. The starting point of the metaphysical deduction is the noetic object interpreted ontologically: the "proportion entitative" between existent things and the intellect. (Cf. V, 460, # 1.) In the Kantian sense, the metaphysical deduction is " uncritical." A critical (transcendental) de- TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 643 transcendental deduction devolves into three major steps that bridge the gap between the logical (phenomenological) possibility of volitional and noetic ends and the ontological or noumenal reality of those ends. The deduction proves that: (I) Phenomenologically, the Final End for the human intellect is Infinite Being, the Absolute, or God. 43 The logical possibility of God entails the existence of God. 44 (3) The existence duction assumes only the phenomenal object denuded of any ontological reality. Its point de depart is " ... une diversite ordonnee de 'phenomenes' contingents, presents a la pensee, et dont il s'agit precisement d'apprecier le rapport eventuel . avec un absolu ontologique" (V, 48 "Intellectus autem respicit suum obiectum secundum communem rationem entis; eo quod intellectus possibilis est quo est omnia fieri" (V, 374). For Marechal, the Thomistic argument is demonstrative but it should be put into a transcendental mode. (Cf. V, In the transcendental mode, the concept of an end is " analytically " derivable from the concept of motion as a passage from potency to act. (Cf. V, 363.) That St. Thomas did not have an " analytic" concept of final causality has been established in a detailed textual survey by George P. Klubertanz, "St. Thomas' Treatment of the Axiom 'Omne Agens Agit Propter Finem,'" in An Etienne Gilson Tribute, ed. by Charles J. O'Neil (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1959), pp. 101-117. In referring to the Final End, Marechal used expressions such as " Infinite Being," " the Absolute," and "God,'' interchangeably. (See V, 375, Cf. Edouard Dirven, S. J., De la forme a l'acte: Essai sur le thomisme, de Joseph Marechal, S. J. (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 1965), p. 149, footnote 44 " La fin subjective adequate de notre dynamisme intellectuel-la beatitude parfaite, possession du Bien parfait-consiste dans nne ' assimilation ' saturante de la forme de l'etre, en d'autres termes dans la possession de Dieu. Et cette fin, quoique surnaturelle, doit etre, en soi, possible: sinon la tendance radicale de notre nature intellectuelle devint une absurdite logique: l'appetit du neant. Or la possibilite de la fin subjective (' finis quo ') presuppose la realite de la ·fin objective, ('finis cujus ') pour que I' assimilation r:Etre absolu soit possible, il faut avant tout que cet Etre absolu existe. . . . Et, par consequent, dut-on repousser la valeur metaphysique immediate des tendances ' naturelles,' valeur admise par les Scholastiques, il resterait encore que poser un acte intellectuel quelconque, c'est affirmer implicitement, non pas seulement la possibilite mais la realite de la ' fin objective,' du ' finis qui, vel cujus,' condition logique de possibilite de la ' fin subjective.' Lorsque la 'fin objective' est un objet fini, le mode de realite de ce dernier n'est point totalement fixe par le seul fait de 'terminer' objectivement une tendance .... Mais lorsque cet objet est Dieu, lorsque la fin objective s'identifie avec l'Etre necessaire par soi (Acte pur), qui n'a pas d'autre mode de realite que I' existence absolue, l'exigence dialectique enveloppee dans le desir prend une portee nouvelle-et cela, non pas a raison du seul desir naturel, mais a raison de 1'objet du desir: a 644 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY of God as the Final End grounds the noumenal existence of all finite (partial) ends. 45 Since it embodies much traditional metaphysical vocabulary but does so under a novel doctrinal aegis, it is necessary to reiterate, with some commentary, the three steps of this deduction. First, appealed to the idea of the adequate formal object of the intellect (totius en tis universalis) and finality (rationalis appetitus). This reinstatement of traditional metaphysics, however, is made from the standpoint of a phenomenology that portrays Infinite Being, the Absolute, or God as the Final End of the human intellect. To this phenomenology is joined a logical analysis of the conditions which make possible the activity of the finite will. Secondly, Marechal stressed, it is true, the de facto dynamism of the finite intellect but the existence of the Absolute which grounds this dynamism is demonstrated by a simple and classic statement of the Ontological Argument: 46 the existence of God affirmer de Dieu qu'il est possible, c'est affirmer purement et simplement qu'il existe, puisque son existence est la condition de toute possibilite. Nous pouvions done poser, en toute rigueur, que la possibilite de notre fin derniere subjective presuppose logiquement !'existence de notre fin derniere objective, Dieu, et qu'ainsi, dans chaque acte intellectuel, est affirmee implicitement d'un Etre absolu: ' Omnia coguoscentia coguoscunt implicite Deum in quolibet coguito ' (V erit., !it!it, !it, ad I. Interpreter ceci par S. Th., I, 84, 5; 88, 3) ." V, 448-450. •• "Achevons de degager ce que la finalite de notre acte intellectuel renferme d'implicite. Nous tenons deja !'existence necessaire de la fin derniere objective. Ajoutons-y !'existence necessaire de tout ce que !'analyse revelerait etre indissolublement lie a la fin derniere; cela va de soi [viz., les fins partielles subordonnees].' v, 451. " Les formes particulieres, immanentes a notre intelligence, tiennent done leur valeur objective de leur subordination finale a une Necessite absolue .... " V, 459. •• My assertion has been called "simply wrong" by J. Michael Vertin, "The Transcendental Vindication of the First Step in Realist Metaphysics According to Joseph Marechal" (unpublished Ph. D. dissertation, University of Toronto, 1973), p. !it86. [Cf. Denis J. M. Bradley, "Transcendental Critique and the Possibility of a Realistic Metaphysics: A Study in the Philosophy of Joseph Marechal" (unpublished Ph. D. dissertation, University of Toronto, 1970), pp. 137-138.] But consider Vertin's reconstruction of Marechal's argument: ". . . (1) the intelligence's striving for an objective term implies the intelligence's affirming that TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 645 is possible, but since the Divine Existence must be conceived as the necessary ground of all logical possibility, therefore, God exists. that term is (a) at least possible, in general, and (b) actual at the time when it is achieved, (2) the intelligence inevitably strives for an ULTIMATE objective term, and (3) the notion of the ultimate objective term implies the notion of unlimited actuality and thus excludes the notion of mere possibility; and, consequently, (4) it follows that the intelligence inevitably affirms that ultimate term as actual." [Ibid.] No less than Marechal, Vertin (expressly in step 3) argues from the notion of possibility to the "notion of unlimited actuality." Dirven candidly admits: "Ce texte [V, 448-450], qui ressemble tellement a la preuve ontologique de Leibniz, est simplement deroutant " [op. cit., p. 248] but emphasizes Marechal' s reference to " l' exigence dialectique du desir " (p. 250) . Vertin also stresses "the implicit, dynamic, performative order" (p. 286) and cites Marechal's specific criticisms of the Ontological Argument (See V, 473, 339, 344-346, 472-474, etc.) to support the idea that the deduction argues from the de facto intellectual dynamism to the Final End which makes this dynamism possible. Similarly Dirven: "Ceci est prouve [i.e., the existence of God], non par I' analyse logique du contenu conceptuel, ni par un examen du pur finalisme ... mais par un enracinement dans l'etre du dynamisme . .•. " (Op. cit., p. 253, italics mine). However, on the premise that Marechal criticized the Ontological Argument one can hardly conclude that his own deduction is free from every vestige of Anselmian logic. To the contrary, the regulations which initially govern the deduction create a profound antithesis: Either (1) the de facto intellectual dynamism is merely and strictly a phenomenological dynamism void of any ontological referent, or (2) it is, actually, an existential dynamism rooted in Being. In order to refute Kant, Marechal needed to prove (2) but was constrained to begin his argument with the assertion of (1). Yet if Dirven and Vertin have correctly characterized the deduction, then Marechal, in fact, began with (2), in which case his argument does not accomplish its stated objective. Assuming that his argument begins at (1), as Marechal claimed, it seems necessary that some form of the Ontological Proof be interpolated. For if Marechal presupposed, uncritically, the ontological existence of the de facto intellectual dynamism, his deduction founders on a methodological inconsistency. The " factuality" of that dynamism must be maintained to be strictly in the phenomenological realm. But if it is consistently restricted to a phenomenological terminus a quo, the deduction can only move from a notion (a description with an existential epoche) of intellectual dynamism to that analytically implied notion of the intellect's Final End which, in this case, must necessarily be conceived to exist. Indeed, the Ontological Proof introduced at this point is highly " dialectical " and more subtle than the Anselmian and Rationalist formulations that Marechal criticized. However, merely to observe that Marechal's deduction " ... est suspendue, non a notre marche vers un terme, mais a l'objet en taut que conditionnant l'etre de la marche" (Dirven, p. 250) is to ignore the methodological problem and to 646 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY ... affirmer de Dieu qu'il est possible c'est affirmer purement et simplement qu'il existe, puisque son existence ,est la condition de toute possibilite (V, 450). The third step promulgates the significant and novel conclusion. In the case of the partial specifications of finite intellectual dynamism, the End absolutely " justifies" the means. Because God exists, any noetic object that is, phenomenologically, a subordinated end on the way to the Absolute must also be conceived to have a noumenal existence and intelligibility. Elsewhere, it should be readily acknowledged, Marechal denied the probity of Anselm's reasoning, confident, no doubt, that his own dialeotical treatment of intellectual tendency did not stray from the preserve of Thomistic orthodoxy .. But one asks how is there a way to pass from a truly Phenomenological Absolute to a truly Ontological Absolute other than by the Ontological Argument? Surely in the very necessity to make this passage, there is revealed the radical discrepancy between Cahier V and the classical, especially Thomist, procedure. The Aristotelian and Thomistic arguments begin with the existent motion in the world, establish the impossibility of an actually existent infinite series of moved movers, and conclude to the actual existence of an Unmoved Mover or Final End which is the definitive termination of the series of relative or subordinated ends. Marechal, however, could not demonstrate that the ontological existence of the Final End follows from the existence of the subordinated series of relative ends because, in his deduction, these ends are initially assumed to be only phenomenal. Indeed, it is the specific purpose of the deduction to demonstrate that this initial assumption is ultimately false but it is essential to begin only there. raise but not pursue the ontological question. How can Being be introduced into an argument which is, ex hypothesi, strictly phenomenological? Reviewing Marechal's argument, Joseph De Vries, S. J., La Pensee et L'Etre (Louvain: Editions Nauwelaerts, p. concludes: " ... une metaphysique de la connaissance qui pretend resoudre les problemes critiques fondamentaux en s'appuyant sur la connaissance de la ' nature de !'intelligence' ne peut manquer de presupposer deja ce qu'elle veut demontrer." TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 647 In a Thomistic metaphysics, no bridge can be built between a Phenomenological Absolute and its subordinated series of phenomenal ends and an Ontological Absolute which is the causa essendi of all subordinated beings. For Marechal removed from his deduction the initial affirmation of finite esse that is the cardinal principle and sole motive force of the Thomistic proof.. As a result, the transcendental deduction of the ontological affirmation reverses the order of the Thomistic proof from final causality; it argues from the existence of God to the existence of finite beings. 47 In Marechal's deduction, then, there is sufficient "ontologism " to satisfy the suspicions of Kantians and Thomists alike. On the other hand, Marechal understood the Critical Philosophy to be contradictory since it posits a phenomenal object divorced from its ontological grounds. But the doctrine of a strictly phenomenal object was Kant's personal mistake. Kant's method can be freed from that mistake. An adequate transcendental analysis, even if-for the sake of philosophical dialogue-it begins, hypothetically, with the Kantian phenomenal object, proves that the so-called strictly phenomenal object must necessarily be "sublated" into the reality of the noumenal order, indeed, into the very order of the Absolute. III. Unfortunately, terminological and logical confusions mar Marechal's ingenious attempt to refute the Kantian doctrine of cognitive objectivity. In Marechal's reading of the Critique, the " premiere opposition " of the subject and the object is engendered by the " imposition " of the categories on the phenomenon. His definition of the phenomenon as " le donne reS!u par nous" corresponds, apparently, to Kant's term "appearance" (Erscheinung) in the first edition, the sensible datum as subject to the a priori forms of space and time. 48 If "opposi•• See Joseph Owens, C. Ss. R., "The Conclusion of the Prima Via," in Modern pp. 88-58, "Actuality in the 'Prima Via' of St. Thomas," Mediaeval Studies, (1967), pp. •• Cf. ill, 145; K. r. V., A90, Schoolman, 80 648 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY tion" first arises when the phenomenon (Erscheinung) is subject to the categories, the implication is that there can be an unsynthesized manifold, that is, an Erscheinung not subject to the categories. Although problematical/ 9 there are texts to support this idea in the Critique. Kant gave one clear statement of the relationship between "appearance" (Erscheinung) and" phenomenon." Appearances, so far as they are thought as objects according to the unity of the categories, are called phenomena . This text, however, is not included in the second edition, which does not hold to the distinction first drawn. On the contrary, in the second edition, the term " Erscheinung " is used to cover both the indeterminate object of sensible intuition and the determinate object of the understanding. 50 In the case of the indeterminate object of sensible intuition, what is given, strictly speaking, is the matter of appearance. The form of the appearance pertains to the a priori forms of the sense faculty. 51 In both editions, Kant rarely used the term " phenomenon " and when it is used, it can only refer to Erscheinung in the full sense-to the determinate object of the understanding. In A248 52 Kant distinguished the different contributions to knowledge of the sense faculty and the understanding. Sensibility accounts for Erscheinung, the understanding for the phenomenal objects, although the production of the phenomenal object comes about only because the understanding is necessarily related to the sense faculty. Marechal's definition of the "phenomenon," "l'etat du donne sensible sous les formes spatiale et temporelle " 53 is confusing and confused. 49 See K. r. V., Cf. Graham Bird, Kant!s Theory of Knowledge: An Outline of One Central Argument in the Critique of Pure Reason (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, p. 58. 50 E. g., K. r. V., fl'. Cf. T. D. Weldon, Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, ed., 1958), p. 51 See K. r. V., 52 Commenting on this text, H. J. Paton, Kant!s Metaphysic of Experience, Vol. II (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1986), p. 440 complains: " ... [Kant] habitually uses the word 'appearance ' [Erscheinung] without making clear whether by that he means the whole object or only a partial and temporary aspect of it." 58 III, 144, TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 649 Kant did not use the term " phenomenon" to refer to the indeterminate object of sensible intuition and never considered the phenomenon to be merely "l'etat d'impression subjective." 54 Marechal's notion that the categories impose "conditions nouvelles " 55 on the "phenomenon" and that these new conditions are what enable one " connaitre le phenom{me objectivement" 56 is meaningless. By Kantian definition a "phenomenon" is a categorized object, so that the subjectobject opposition cannot be based on an opposition of the phenomenon to the a priori categories of the understanding. In the Critique there is not and cannot be any such opposition. Evidently, Marechal's muddled terminology indicates a more significant anomaly in the starting point of his deduction. Marechal identified the " phenomenon" in a way that could only be isomorphic with Kant's problematical idea of an unsynthesized manifold. But the idea o£ an unsynthesized manifold is never the initial premise in any of Kant's arguments. Rather, all the versions of the Transcendental Deduction presuppose an empirical unity of consciousness, a unity that is multifaceted and variously explicated by Kant. What Kant demonstrated is that the de facto empirical or psychological unity of consciousness has its necessary ground in an a pnon or transcendental unity of consciousness. 5 7 54 55 III, 141. III, 145. Ibid. Marechal noted "' L'objet dans Ia pensee,' ou la 'pensee objective,'-postulat initial de toute Ia Critique- .... " (III, but commenced with "le point de vue de !'objet, considere precisivement comme 'objet phenomenal '" (V, 589). This, supposedly, is "le minimum incontestable d'objet donne ' a titre de science ' . . . selon Kant. . . ." (ibid.) . By "precisivement," Marechal meant that one should adopt an "as if" stance: his deduction proves that "la notion d'objet exclusivement phenomenal" is intrinsically contradictory but, in the beginning, this is the assumed (false) pr.emise. (Cf. V, 517.) Robert Paul Wolff, Kant's Theory of Mental Activity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1963) , p. 105, explains that " In each of the versions of the Deduction, ... the starting point ... is a revised form of the cogito which expresses what Kant believes to be the most general fact about any consciousness: its unity." 56 57 650 DENIS .T. M. BRADLEY In the first edition, Kant distinguished between a Subjective and an Objective Deduction. 58 The text is tortuous but the key to the Subjective Deduction is the doctrine of the threefold synthesis which is the a priori generative process, the activity which is the understanding itself, that underlies and grounds the unity of consciousness. The Objective Deduction assumes this generated unity of consciousness, the " original apperception," and proceeds to the essential elaboration of the validity of our a priori concepts. In the second edition, although the distinction between the Subjective and Objective Deductions is not maintained with any consistency or clarity, the doctrine of a priori synthesis must still be presumed to be the generative source of the transcendental unity of apperception. This latter doctrine, fully developed, is the characteristic Kantian expression of the necessary unity of consciousness. For, on the level of the understanding, the transcendental unity of apperception is not only the principle governing concepts but it is also the supreme principle of the possibility of all intuitions. 59 The function of judgments, the categories of the Metaphysical Deduction, is to bring the manifold of intuition under this one, original apperception. 60 Kant did allow, perhaps inconsistently, that we can think of the concept of an unsynthesized manifold. But this is the concept of thought negating its own contribution and leaving as a remainder the uncategorized sensible data. Since Kantian knowledge is the determination of sensible intuitions according to the categories, it is impossible, in any positive sense, to know the sensible given in and by itself. The attempt to conceive this situation is only to set a limit, in reference to the mutual conMarechal thought that his own conception of the " phenomenal object " marked the most elementary level of consciousness since " ... on ne pent descendre endessous sans rendre impossible toute conscience objective" (V, 589). But Kant would have regarded Marechal's starting point as already making " conscience objective" impossible. Cf. K. r. V., BlSl-132. 58 See K. r. V., Axvi. 59 See K. r. V., Al22. •• See K. r. V., Al27, Bl35. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 651 tributions of sensibility and understanding, to " the notion of experience itself." 61 Marechal's concept of the phenomenon and Kant's idea of an unsynthesized manifold, if we have correctly coordinated them, are both Grenzbegrif]e. Yet the purpose of Marechal's deduction is to demonstrate that Kant's concept of an" objet exclusivement phenomenal" is self-contradictory. This supposed self-contradiction is puzzling. How does it arise if the phenomenal object is entirely defined by negating any determinative predicates? There can be no contradiction, it would seem, unless Marechal's concept of a phenomenon incorporates some categorial content which could be signified by predicates that are incompatible in the same subject. The discovery that the concept of the phenomenal object is self-contradictory indicates, certainly, a deviation from any isomorphic element discernible in Kant's epistemology but, principally, it reveals the equivocation latent in Marechal's definition of his own starting point. In comparison with the texts wherein Kant distinguished the phenomenal and noumenal orders, Marechal's version of the phenomenal object is truncated. Kant clearly attributed to the phenomenal object an ontological ground. 62 The definitions of appearance and thing-in-itself, or phenomenon and noumenon, are correlatives. The phenomenon is the noumenon known under the forms of sensibility and the categories of the understanding. Despite persistent criticism, Kant never doubted either the independent reality of the thing-in-itself or its unknowability. Paradoxically, because we krww only phenomena we can and must think of noumena. Without the doctrine of the ontological autonomy of the noumenon, the Transcendental Aesthetic, with its definitive affirmation of an independent, nonsubjective source of the manifold of sensible intuition, would be completely overthrown, and with it, the entire Critical Philosophy. 68 81 Bird, p. •• See K. r. V., Bxxvi-Bxxvii. •• See Bernard Rousset, La doctrine kantienne de l'objectivite: L'autonomie 652 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY The affirmation of the ontological reality of the thing-in-itself is, admittedly, problematic. "Existence" is a category which, in the Critique, can properly apply only to the data of sensible intuition. The Kantian problem becomes insurmountable if one regards the phenomenon and the noumenon as two separate entities or affirms the being of the noumenon to be diverse from the being of the phenomenon. For Kant, apart from some occasional, careless phrases, did not envisage the noumenon as an entity distinct from the phenomenon. The distinction between the two is not in the ontological order. The noumenon refers to the same ontological object as the phenomenon but from a different epistemological perspective. 64 The duality that characterizes the noumenon and the phenomenon is a duality that springs not from two diverse beings but from the fact that the known object has two different kinds of relationship to the knowing subject. These two different relationships are analytically implied by the concept of Erscheinung by which it is both possible and necessary to think of the object of experience apart from the conditions of sensibility. If that possibility is eliminated, then the Critique could no longer meaningfully pose the givenness of sensible intuition. As evidenced by the great divide between Kant and his successors, the objectivity of knowledge, ultimately, rests on the ontological reality of the unknowable thing-in-itself, the foundation that makes the Critical Philosophy an .empirical realism and not an empirical idealism. 65 In the First Critique, against the claims of dogmatic metaphysics, Kant protested that theoretical reason could neither prove nor disprove the existence of God. However, once rendered impotent, theoretical reason could permit a philosophical faith. For the God of the Second Critique is the rationally justifiable postulate of a practical reason which, in the face of nature's indifference to man, must show the "necessary concomme devoir et devenir (Paris: 162-177. •• See K. r. V., ASO. 65 See K. r. V., A370, B519a. Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1967), pp. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 658 nection between morality and proportionate happiness." 68 This divine harmony, or Summum Bonum for which men strive, is guaranteed in the Third Critique by a God whose existence is postulated as the necessary condition for the moral teleology intrinsic to free human action. 87 The Moral Law, which always commands some end to be achieved, entails the concept of freedom, of agents causing effects in the phenomenal world, and this agency, in turn, necessarily implies purposiveness. Concomitantly, there appears, between the realms of a postulated freedom and a nature bound in ineluctable causal chains, an " immeasurable gulf " 68 that theoretical reason cannot traverse. However, the First Critique, in fact, had already constructed just that bridge in the schematism which depicts judgment as the link between reason and understanding. 69 By their schematism, the Faculty of Judgment can give to itself the law of the purposiveness of nature, not as a determinative category but as a heuristic principle or reflective judgment guiding the understanding. 70 Purposiveness, not only as an exigency of the moral realm, must also be attributed to nature itself because the concept of " mechanical " causality is insufficient to explain all phenomena. Nature may be regarded as a mere mechanism but not even a Newton can explain the production of a blade of grass, or any other living thing, without relying on the concept of a design or purpose underlying the pertinent causal laws. Kant did not suggest, however, that teleological explanations, because they are necessary heuristic principles, are logically superior to causal laws. "As far as it is in our power," 71 everything in nature should be interpreted according to mechanical causality. 68 Critique of Practical Reason, trans. by Lewis White Beck (New York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1956), p. 129. •• See Critique of Judgment, trans. by J. H. Bernard (New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1951), pp. 298-804 [= C. J., pp. 298-304]. 68 c. J., p. 12. •• See K. r. V., B176-B187 . J., p. 17. 71 C. J., p. 264. •• c. 654 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY In one sense, teleological and causal explanations are on a par. The causal principle is itself constitutive of our knowledge of nature, but the maxim that "All explanations should only be causal ' as far as it is in our power' " is a regulative principle. Without generating an antinomy for theoretical reason, the two maxims, since they are reflective judgments, govern only our way of investigating nature which must be viewed from both the causal and the teleological standpoints. The concepts of the understanding, although determinative of nature in general, the horizon of possible experience, do not exhaust the manifold of nature. There remains an indefinite number of laws that cannot be deduced from the categories of the understanding but can only be educed from empirical experience.72 From the standpoint of our understanding, these empirical laws are known as contingent but because we regard them as laws of nature, we must think them as necessary. Since they cannot be derived from the categories, there must be discerned for these laws another principle of unity, " so as to make possible a system of experience." 73 Such a unified system is accomplished by reflective judgment positing the law of the purposiveness of nature. When applied to the realm of appearances, the concept of an unconditioned is not a constitutive principle of any empirical series but is a heuristic rule governing "the widest possible empirical employment of the understanding." 74 An appearance as such is always conditioned, and reason in investigating a series of appearances proceeds, by indefinite regression or infinite analysis, without a terminal point. Kant's scientific progress is the modern, never-ending search for particular causal laws. Although God is the ground for the totality of all empirical conditions, Kantian reason must think the Necessary Being" as entirely outside the series of the sensible world." 75 The concept •• K. r. V., Bl65 . •• c. J., p. 16. •• K. r. V., B545. •• K. r. V., B589. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 655 of God signifies; not the first member in a series of empirical conditions, for there is none, but the " unknown ground of the possibility of the sensible series in general." 76 In the noumenal realm, Kant allowed that reason can think that causes do not proceed in infinitum. 77 But this concept of pure reason has no application to the realm of appearances, and no speculative proof for the existence of God can be constructed on the basis of the traditional metaphysical principle, Impossibile est in finibus procedere in infinitum. This latter is not a constitutive principle of the understanding that governs any empirical series. Similarly, the corollary principle, Omne age'M agit propter finem, is not a universal and necessary condition of all possible experience but should be applied only to one class of agents. For Kant carefully argued, in the Third Critique, that some cause-effect relationships can be simply and completely explained by mechanical or efficient causality. The only causeeffect relationship that necessitates reference to the concept of end or purpose is found in a living, organized being, the relationship of the living whole to its parts. In this case too, the purposiveness attributed to the living whole is posited in a reflective judgment that embodies an analogical concept of purposiveness originally instantiated in the moral act. 78 In Cahier V, the description of noetic finality is a knowledge claim about the universal and constitutive feature of phenomenal experience. In that way, Marechal identified the heuristic and the constitutive. For the Critical Philosophy, this attempted identification could only be judged illegitimate, a dogmatic over-extension that confuses determinative and reflective judgments. In the opinion of contemporary scholars, an opinion which Marechal also held, the problem of noetic objectivity is "the K. r. V., B59Q. Cf. K. T. V., B443-B448. 78 " For we bring in a teleological ground . . .when we represent to ourselves the possibility of the object after the analogy of that causality which we experience in ourselves .... " C. J., p. Q06. 76 77 656 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY specifically critical problem," identical with the " transcendental deduction" 79 itself. In the Critique the objectivity of knowledge emerges from the oppositions of internal to external sense, from sensible intuition to the a priori categories of the understanding, and from the subject as activity distinguished from the product of its activity. The dynamic activity of the Kantian subject is displayed in the irreducible distinction between intuition and spontaneity, and, most clearly, in the ceaseless workings of the imagination whose temporal schemata mediate between the pure categories and sensible intuition. 80 From a Realist, and especially from a professed Thomist, one might anticipate the charge that the Kantian resolution of the critical problem is deranged because it establishes that the " subjective is the foundation of the objective." 81 But Marechal precisely complained that Kant ignored the proper dynamism of the knowing subject in favor of a static and formalistic epistemology .82 Kant, we know, did not advert, in the three critiques, to any teleological theory to explain the objectivity of knowledge. This, however, is neither a lacuna in the Critical Philosophy nor a sign of its excessive formalism; it is, rather, merely an indication, in this context, that the First Critique provides a unique elucidation of the subjective activity that underlies all objective knowledge. Kant explained, in a footnote in the Prolegomena, that be,.. 79 H.-J. De Vleeschauwer, The Development of Kantian Thought: The History of a Doctrine, trans. by A. R. C. Duncan (London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, Ltd., pp. 56, 75. 80 " This schematism of our understanding, in its application to appearances and their mere form, is an art concealed in the depths of the human soul. ... " K. r. V., BISO. De Vleeschauwer, p. 70. "En fait, Kant ne tire aucun parti de l'acte transcendantal d'affirmation, que pourtant il suppose. En formulant les conclusions agnostiques de la Critique de la raison pure, il se rabat sur les seules relations formelles et statiques de la connaissance. L'affirmation de la 'Chose en soi' reste un episode inexploite" (V, Rousset, however, is more judicious: "Ala racine de la correlation statique entre le sujet et !'objet, il y a done un perpetuel dynamisme constructeur, que mettent specialement en evidence laplace accordee a !'imagination, la definition de l'entendement par !a spontaneite .... " (Op. cit., p. 341). 81 82 TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 657 cause of a difference in the argument's starting point, two different methods could be employed in the development of the Transcendental Deduction. 83 The Prolegomena, for reasons of pedagogic simplicity, uses the analytic method which assumes the cognitive validity of physics and geometry, and regressively explicates the a priori conditions of possibility for these sciences. The Critique, since a truly critical argument must be presuppositionless, uses the synthetic-progressive method. It demonstrates from independently reasoned premises about the unity of consciousness, that geometry and physics, but not metaphysics, are transcendentally possible and valid. 84 The actual argument of the Critique, however, surpasses the tidy distinctions of the Prolegomena. Commentators dispute how the two methods are finally related, but usually they hold that the Critique reinstates both methods at a higher level of philosophical complexity .85 The reason for this complexity can easily be grasped. By means of the synthetic-progressive method barely outlined in the Prolegomena, Kant attempted to prove not only the possibility of an object of experience but to prove the possibility of experience in general. The nature of this task, so unique and difficult, suggests that the relationship between the two methods, as they were mutually developed in the Critique, could not have been given a simple or an exact parallel elsewhere. Between the Critique and Cahier V, however, there is no methodological parallel. Marechal's transcendental deduction is not a synthetic-progressive demonstration because it does not begin with a reasoned premise whose truth remains certain. The conclusion of his argument cancels the initial premise (the concept of a strictly phenomenal object) by exposing its inherent self-contradiction. But, alternatively, Marechal's deduction is not analytic-regressive. Its initial premise, although 83 See Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, ed. by Paul Carus (La Salle, Dlinois: The Open Court Publishing Company, 1955), p. 9!7, note. •• Cf. ibid., p. 9!4. But this text is contradicted by K. r. V., B!itO. 85 See Roger Verneaux, Le v.ocabulaire de Kant: doctrines et methodes (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1967), pp. 175-181. 658 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY hypothetically taken to be true, does not correspond, obviously, to the Prolegomena's assumption of the validity of geometry and physics. The Critique, far from undermining their assumed validity, provides for these sciences a transcendental and indubitable justification. Marechal's deduction begins with an apparently true premise that is then proved to be false by the internal movement of the argument itself. The self-contradiction hidden in the assumed starting point necessitates a passage from falsity to truth, or, one may say, from appearance to reality. This internal movement or passage provides the clue to the method actually used in Cakier V. The common purpose of all the various forms of the dialectical method is " to transcend or remove contradiction," 86 and, in the Hegelian dialectic, the removal of contradiction is accomplished by an" inward mediation ... [that] proves itself to be necessary." 87 This, exactly, is what Marechal's argument effects on its own premise: the concept of a strictly phenomenal object is shown to be self-contradictory, and, therefore, necessarily generative of a new starting point. Marechal accused Kant of propounding a theory of knowledge which was excessively "formelle et statique." 88 This remark, so indicative of a dialectical philosophy, echoes Hegel's fundamental complaint: "After all, it was only formally, that the Kantian system established the principle that thought is spontaneous." 89 Whereas Marechal accepted the basic viability of Kant's method, Hegel had decided that the Critical Philosophy needed a radical reorientation to overcome the one-sidedness of its method through a Dialectic that would restore to Reason its 86 Richard P. McKeon, "Philosophy and Method," Journal of Philosophy, 48 (1951), p. 662. 87 G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. I, trans. by E. B. Speirs (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1895), p. 65. 88 V, 592. 89 The Science of Logic: The First Part of the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline, trans. by William Wallace, 2nd ed., rev. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1892), p. 119. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 659 full scope and power. 90 Thus, Marechal's transcendental justication of a realist metaphysics, if successful, not only turns the Critique of Pure Reason on its head, but also refutes the Hegelian riposte that the partiality of the Kantian method leads necessarily to its dialectical sublation by Reason. Therein lies the central issue. In their disavowals of the Critique and in their constructive designs, a close parallel can be drawn between the criticisms and objectives of Hegel and Marechal. Are we, then, to view Cahier V in terms of its stated intentions, as an attempt, possibly valid, to reestablish "Aristotelian-Thomistic" metaphysics, or are we to conclude, through a more precise analysis of the deduction's inner structure, that Marechal's argument is, all said and done, a simulacrum of Hegel's Logic? If, in fact, Marechal did not use Kant's method, as I have argued, then the latter, Hegelian alternative may supply the correct vantage for an assessment of the metaphysics in Cahier V. IV. The transcendental deduction of the " affirmation ontologique," as a type of argument, resembles the Hegelian transformation of phenomenology into logic or ontology. 91 The Phenomenology, by means of a philosophical description of fragmentary experience, is compelled to reach at its end " science " or the " organized whole of determinate and complete knowledge." 92 The Logic, since it has been handed this " ladder," 9 °Kant's "mistake was to stop at the purely negative point of view, and to limit the uncDnditionality of Reason to an abstract self-sameness without any shade of distinction. It degrades Reason to a finite and conditioned thing, to identify it with a mere stepping beyond the finite and conditioned range of understanding. The real infinite, far from being a mere transcendence of the finite, always involves the absorptiDn of the finite into its own fuller nature." Ibid., p. 93. 91 " Consciousness is Spirit as knowing which is concrete and engrossed in externality; but the schema of movement of this concrete knowing (like the development of all physical and intellectual life) depends entirely on the nature of the pure essentialities which make up the content of Logic ... philosophy is just the exhibition of this movement." Science of Logic, trans. Johnson and Struthers, I (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 19£9), p. 37. 92 The Phenomenology of Mind, trans. by Sir James Baillie (London: George Allen and Unwin, rev. £nd ed., 1949), p. 79, [Preface]. 660 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY begins at the standpoint of the Absolute and gives, in purely conceptual terms, a circular demonstration of its own rational necessity. Within that circle, the Ontological Argument evinces that this necessity, the inseparableness of Thought and Being, is " found in an absolute form ... in the case of God " 93 and in a relativ.e form in the case of finite being. 94 In comparison with a PhenomeJWlogy that reveals the goal of history and culture, or a Logic. that thinks the thoughts of the Absolute, Cahier V may seem exceedingly modest. Nonetheless, it contains a phenomenology of the form of knowledge that internally generates an ontology of God and man. For Hegel and Marechal this dialectical transformation has as its privileged center an assertion of the necessary unity of Infinite Being and finite thought. In both dialectics, the Ontological Argument so employed entirely transcends its Anselmian formulation because it posits not only the existence of God but also the existence of all beings subordinated to God. Cahier V stipulates that finite thought is possible because it is governed by the Principle of Identity which, in traditional metaphysics, is also the first principle of Being. 95 But one should not, as Marechal chastised Kant for doing, treat the Principle of Identity solely as an analytic norm of logic and ignore, thereby, its synthetic character. 96 This synthetic character can be grasped in the necessity expressed. In any judgment of identity the predicate is affirmed as necessarily identical with the subject, and this modal necessity reveals the unity of intelligibility and Being or, as Marechal maintained, the unity of essence and existence. Marechal's conclusion though idiosyncratic follows upon " Kantian " premises: since every synthesis is a unified diversity, for which there must be a prin93 Philosophy of Religion, Vol. III, p. 358. •• " ... every 'proof' of God [for Hegel] is reducible to the ontological proof; each argues from the necessity of thinking the infinite, if we are to think the finite." Quentin Lauer, "Hegel on Proofs for God's Existence," Kant-Studien, 55 (1964), p. 452. 95 See V, 87-89. ••see V, 88. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 661 ciple of unification, the necessary unity of Being and intelligibility in every judgment of identity has a ground. 97 In the Principle of Identity, the synthesis expressed is of the most universal order," etre comme Realite et etre comme Idee." 98 One principle of unity is alone superior to this universal synthesis: the Absolute Unity of reality and thought-God. Finite thought, synthetic in nature because governed by the Principle of Identity, is unable to encompass the absolute unity of God except analogically. But once the first principle is affirmed, there is implicitly posed as its ground the necessary unity of Thought and Being in God. 99 In effect, by making explicit the necessary relationship between any finite statement of identity and the Absolute, Marechal provided the elements of a proof for the existence of God. Although rudimentary and undeveloped, this " proof " conjures up Hegel's project. The Logic begins with the statement of undifferentiated identity or Pure Being. This presuppositionless beginning, to which in its own fashion Cahier V cursorily alludes, is the " point de depart " of Hegelian science. In the full mediation of the Logic, the Principle of Identity provides the dialectical source of all the categories implicit in the absolute identity of Thought and Being.100 Unlike the Logic and Cahier V, the Critique raises no ques•• " Car aucune synthese n'est necessaire par soi: la diversite, comme diversite, ne pouvant etre principe de sa propre unification, la necessite d'une synthese doit avoir sa source dans la necessite meme d'une unite oil s'efface la diversite des termes synthetiques." V, 563. Cf. K. r. V., BIOS. •• V, 563-564. •• "Les etapes dialectiques qui nous conduisent a l'Etre absolu par la voie du premier principe, entendu en son sens metaphysique integral, sont done les suivants: a) possibilite objective du premier principe, reconnue dans son application necessaire a !'objet physique ... ; b) affirmation de l'Absolu, Acte pur, comme source necessaire de cette possibilite objective. La seconde etape est bien reellement a priori mais elle resterait hypothetique, faute de la premiere." V, 565. ' 00 " ••• it is clear that the Law of Identity, and still more the Law of Contradiction, is not merely analytic, but synthetic. For in its expression the latter contains not only empty, simple self-identity, but also the Other of identity in general, and, further, absolute non-identity or self-contradiction. And the Law of Identity itself contains ... the movement of Reflection .... " Science of Logic, Vol. II, pp. 4f.!-43. 662 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY tion of Being because Kant considered the origin of finite existence to be theoretically insoluble. 101 In that sensible intuition is simply given, Being too is simply given. Being is truly the supreme quaestio facti and the Critical Philosophy carefully confines itself to a manageable quaestio juris, how sensible intuition is possible and thinkable. This latter question transcendental method can resolve by validating the a priori concepts of the understanding, a validation which shows that the concept of God is solely a regulative idea of pure reason. 102 Cahier V, however, raises the Hegelian question but withdraws from the Hegelian answer. It demonstrates that the necessarily existent God is an a priori condition of possibility for finite thought. The Phenomenology takes the next decisive step: God is an a priori condition of possibility for finite thought because the concept of the Absolute is Thought's most universal category. 103 In his intentions ever the faithful Thomist, Marechal did not take that step. To do so is to replace the Thomistic doctrine of a formal union between the knower and the known, the adequatio rei et intellectus, with the Hegelian doctrine that Thought and Being are identical. Above all, it is to do away with a created intelligence possessed of analogical knowledge of God in favor of an Absolute unfolding itself in finite thought. 104 101 " The objects of exp.erience, then, are never given in themselves, but only in experience, and have no existence outside it .... For everything is real which stands in connection with a perception .... The non-sensible cause of these representations is completely unknown to us .... We may, however, entitle the purely intelligible cause of appearances in general the transcendental object, but merely in order to have something corresponding to sensibility viewed as a receptivity." K. r. V., B521-B522. Cf. Cornelio Fabro, "The Transcendentality of Ens-Esse and the Ground of Metaphysics," International Philosophical Quarterly, 6 (1966), pp. 389-427. 102 See K. r. V., A696/B724-A702/B730. 103 " This last embodiment of spirit-Spirit which at once gives its complete and true content the form of self, and thereby realizes its notion, and in doing so remains within its own notion-this is Absolute Knowledge. It is spirit knowing itself in the shape of spirit, it is knowledge which comprehends through notions." Phenomenology of Mind, pp. 797-798. 104 Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 84, a. 1 and Science of Logic, Vol. II, pp. 466-486; Summa Theol., I, q. 12, aa. 1-13 and Phenomenology of Mind, pp. 789-808. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 663 Thomistic metaphysics identifies Thought and Being in God/ 05 but preserves against any dialectical sublation the irreducible otherness of finite esse intentionale and esse 1UJr turale. 106 Moreover, in the Beatific Vision, in which the divine essence is seen because it is the form by which the intellect, through grace, understands, the finite intelligence does not dissolve into the divine intelligibility but remains incapable of comprehending the infinite God infinitely. 107 Guided by Sacra Doctrina, the metaphysical theology of the Summa Theologiae explains the relationship between finite thought and Being as a relationship between the creature and the Creator. Because human knowledge consists of judgments that refer to the ipsum esse rei, 108 it is related to God Who is lpsum Esse Subsistens and the universal causa essendi.109 But this ontology of knowledge, entirely derived from the creature's existential relationship to the Creator, does not negate the " epistemological" level that is maintained in Thomistic noetic theory. 110 At the epistemological level, the level at which the intrinsic principles of the cognitive act are elucidated, the Absolute does not func105 "In Deo autem non est forma quae sit aliud quam suum esse. . . . Unde, cum ipsa sua essentia sit etiam species intelligibilis . . . ex necessitate sequitur quod ipsum eius intelligere sit eius essentia et eius esse." Summa Theol., I, q.14, a. 4. 106 " ••• esse dupliciter dicitur: uno modo, significat actum essendi; alio modo, significat compositionem propositionis, quam anima adinvenit coniungens praedicatum subiecto." Ibid, q. 4, a. 4, ad 2. 107 " In tan tum enim intellectus creatus divinam essentiam perfectius vel minus perfecte cognoscit, inquantum maiori vel minori lumine gloriae perfunditur. Cum igitur lumen gloriae creatum, in quocumque intellectu creato receptum, non possit esse infinitum, impossible est quod aliquis intellectus creatus Deum infinite cognoscat. Unde impossibile est quod Deum comprehendat." Ibid., q. Hl, a. 7. 108 In Boethium de Tn'nitate, q. 5, a. 3, ed. P. Wyser, pp. 38, 11, 8-11. 109 " Cum autem Deus sit ipsum esse per suam essentiam, oportet quod esse creatum sit proprius effectus eius .... " Summa Theol., I, q. 8, a. 1. 110 " ••• in luce primae veritatis omnia intelligimus et iudicamus, inquantum ipsum lumen intellectus nostri, sive naturale sive gratuitum, nihil aliud est quam quaedam impressio veritatis primae .... Unde cum ipsum lumen intellectus nostri non se habeat ad intellectum nostrum sicut quod intelligitur, sed sicut quo intelligitur; multo minus Deus est id quod primo a nostro intellectu intelligitur." Ibid., q. 88, a. 3, ad 1. 664 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY tion as an immanent condition for finite thought.r 11 Both nature and intelligence are created and are secondary or dependent, but each, in the Thomistic scheme, sustains its own authentic and integral causal efficacy.112 Thus, the human intellect, considered as an activity, is the proper agent of its own cognition, and, considered as a receptivity, is infqrmed by its proper object, the abstracted natures of sensible things. 118 If we reflect on Aquinas's unremitting rejection of Avicenna's Dator Formarum or Averroes's Agent Intellect, 114 or, more significantly, his complete recasting of the Augustinian theory of divine illumination, 115 Cahier V, from a Thomistic perspective, seems to obfuscate metaphysical and epistemological explanations. True enough, God's existence is only implicitly affirmed in each noetic act but, in fact, a solely epistemological explanation of the validity of cognition is eliminated. 118 To explain adequately a noetic act as act, one must posit God Who, seemingly so transcendent, becomes a necessary condition within the epistemological justification of knowledge. Here, viewed 111 " ••• habitudo ad causam non intret definitionem entis quod est causa tum .... " Ibid., q. 44, a. 1, ad 1. 110 " ••• quod Deum operari in quolibet operante aliqui sic intellexerunt, quod nulla virtus creata aliquid operaretur in rebus sed solus Deus immediate omnia operaretur .... Hoc autem est impossibile. Primo quidem, quia sic subtraheretur ordo causae et causati a rebus creatis. Quod pertinet ad impotentiam creantis: ex virtute enim agentis est, quod suo effectui det virtutem agendi.--Secundo, quia virtutes operativae quae in rebus inveniuntur, frustra essent rebus attributae, 'li per eos nihil operarentur. Quinimmo omnes res creatae viderentur quodammodo esse frustra, si propria operatione destituerentur; cum omnis res sit propter suam operationem." Ibid., q.105, a. 5. 118 " Et ideo ad intelligendum non sufficeret immaterialitas intellectus possibilis, nisi adesset intellectus agens, qui faceret intelligibilia in actu per modum abstractionis." Ibid., q. 79, a. 8, ad 8. 11 ' See ibid., q. 79, aa. 4-5. 110 See Etienne Gilson, " Sur quelques difficultes de !'illumination augustinienne," Revue N eo-scholastique de philostYphie, 86 (1984), pp. 828-881. 118 "Nous croyons superflu d'insister sur Ia rencontre inevitable, dans toute connaissance intellectuelle d'objet, d'une double condition relative a Ia Realire: une condition empirique (intuitive sensible), et une condition tranacendantale (rapport implicite de toute synthese objective a Ia Realite absolue) .... " V, 565. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 665 from the Hegelian context, Marechal's argument stops short of an identification of "logic" and "ontology." 117 On Kantian principles, Cahier V must certainly be judged a mistaken effort to reestablish pre-critical metaphysics. 118 But, in this regard, Marechal's mistakes are not those of an incompetent historian but of a philosopher who, in bending a method to serve purposes which, historically and philosophically, are alien, irresistibly transformed his own principles. Since philosophical methods, principles, and conclusions are mutually constituted, it is to be expected that the observant among latterday Kantians and Thomists should reject Cahier V. On both sides, this rejection, needless to say, leaves unresolved the truth of the Hegelian Aufhebung. Respect for the integrity of individual philosophies disinclines one to read the history of post-Kantian philosophy with Hegelian spectacles. 119 It should be allowed that the method of the Critique need not lead by any Hegelian necessity to the Phenomenology and the Logic. 120 Yet the Hegelian Aufhebung one might still consider, with whatever reservation, as the pertinent historical denouement of post-Kantian philosophy. But, merely on those cautious terms, the Logic can be seen to incorporate Cahier V in the unfolding of its own Dialectic. The transcendent Reason, by means of which Hegel closed in the Absolute the hiatus between finite thought and Being, brings 117 " ••• Ia logique transcendentale est deja Ie germe de Ia logique speculative de Hegel qui ne connait plus Ia borne de Ia chose en soi. Cette logique de l'etre se substitne a l'ancienne metaphysique qui s'ouvrait sur un monde transcendant. Hegel ne revient pas au dogmatisme anterieur, il prolonge Ia logique transcendentale en logique speculative. Les categories deviennent les categories memes de l'Absolu." Jean Hyppolite, Logique et existooce: essai sur la logique de Hegel (Paris: Presses Universitaires, 1961), p. 70. 118 One recalls Kant's fulminations in the "Open Letter on Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre, August 7, 1799," in Immanuel Kant, Philosophical Correspondtmce, 1759-99, ed. and trans. by Arnulf Zweig (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1967), pp. 253-254. 119 Cf. pp. 9-17. 12 ° For a general characterization of the "school of transcendental philosophers," see Klaus Hartmann, " On Taking the Transcendental Turn," The Review of Metaphysics, 20 (1966), pp. 223-249. 666 DENIS J. M. BRADLEY to a complete realization and harmonization, so he claimed, the God of the metaphysical tradition and the insights of transcendental philosophy. 121 In making the same attempt Marechal's metaphysics seems mightily, albeit unintentionally, drawn towards the same Absolute. 122 Of course, the distance between St. Thomas and Marechal is not in direct ratio to the distance between lpsum Esse Subsistens and the Hegelian Absolute. 123 The movement of Cahier V, with all of its explicit vacillations and latent tensions, cannot be reduced to that, or to any, :fixed proportionality. Yet the Hegelian comparison can be left standing because it illumines those vacillations and tensions. 124 Although they did not excel the historical finesse of Gilson and like-minded colleagues who refused to their philosophical programs the accolade of "Thomism," the Nco-Scholastics of that generation continued to proclaim, vehemently, their allegiance to St. Thomas. Forty years later, that particular .vehemence has abated somewhat/ 25 since, for one reason, a tolerant aggiornamento has tamed doctrinaire ecclesiastical censorship. But discussions of the nature of historical Thomism are 121 See Emil Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension In Hegel's Thought (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), pp. 15-18. 122 Marechal, of course, eschewed Idealism because " ... les Idealistes post-kantiens enervent leur principe de finalite en le combinant de force avec le prejuge de la totale immanence" (IV, 454). But " ... la metaphysique thomiste trouverait sans doute dans ces systemes plus jeunes, qui renouerent la tradition metaphysique interrompue par le kantisme, des inspirations heureuses pour son propre developpement " (IV, 455). 123 "La differenza metafisica fondamentale sul problema del'.essere fra Hegel e S. Tommaso e nulla concezione della creazione, in quanto per Hegel l'elevarsi al punto di vista speculativo comporta il riportarsi in Dio al 'momento che precede la creazione.' Invece per S. Tommaso e soltanto con la creazione, come produzione libera e totale del'essere da parte di Dio .... " Cornelio Fabro, C. P. S., "L' Esse' Tomistico E II 'Sein' Hegeliano," Sapientia Aquinatis: Communicationes IV Congressus Thomistici Internationalis (Romae: Officium Libri Catholici, 1955), p. 268. 124 The opposite contention, that Marechal illumines the unresolved problems in Hegel, is made by Franz Gregoire, " Themes hegeliens et depassements thomistes," ibid .• pp. 282-291. 125 For a different opinion, see J. Donce.el, S. J., " Transcendental Thomism," The Monist, 58 (1974), pp. 67-85. TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE & REALIST METAPHYSICS 667 not, these days, altogether passe because theories abound that directly counter the principles of historic Thomistic metaphysics.126 Yet, as well as be tested, this metaphysics can also test. To wit, it might be profitable to examine the historicism planted by Hegel now flowering in the hermeneutics of secondgeneration Heideggerians. 127 However, there is place to pause for an intermediate question. If my analysis of Marechal is germane, one may wonder whether contemporary " Transcendental Thomists," as N eo-Scholastics are now called, are not themselves caught in implicitly Hegelian dilemmas, dilemmas which can be more clearly posed-and perhaps abandoned-as the consequences of Hegelian principles. 128 Explication of these dilemmas, especially as they bear on the problems of hermeneutical theory, I take to be an appropriate point de depart for further investigations. DENIS J. M. BRADLEY Georgetown University Washington, D. C. 126 Cf. Terence G. Walsh, S. J., "Assimilation and the Problem of a Contemporary Thomism," The New Scholasticism, 44 (1970), pp. 591-599. 127 See Alphonse De Waelhens, "Sur une hermeneutique de l'hermeneutique," Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 60 (1962), pp. 578-591. 12 " Cf. Georges Van Riet, "Histoire de la philosophie et verite," in Problemes d'epistemologie (Louvain: Publications Universitaires de Louvain, 1960), pp. 218-282. DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY AND MAN'S KNOWLEDGE OF BEING P HILOSOPHERS AND PSYCHOLOGISTS in the twentieth century who reflect on man's knowledge-its scope and processes-generally deny to man the kind of metaphysical knowledge St. Thomas ascribes to him. In such a situation those who share Thomas's view that man has a capacity for, and an orientation to, a metaphysical knowledge of reality as being, do well to reflect upon man's knowledge in a way that is in close touch with contemporary thought. In this article I wish to do just that, to present an account of the psychogenesis of being that makes central use of contemporary psychologies of knowledge and has in view contemporary objections against man's metaphysical knowledge-albeit only in an exploratory manner, more to suggest its significance than to develop my theme with the fullness it deserves. To introduce this study, brief though it is, we must review something of the Thomistic analysis of man's understanding of being. There is no one universally accepted interpretation of Thomas's view on the way man knows reality as being. There is however widespread agreement that the existential judgment is proportioned to the knowledge of being as understood by Thomas, since for him being is that which is. Reality as being is reducible neither to substance nor to the act of being. If one accepts this, there still remains disagreement about the principles that account for such knowledge being present in The main Thomistic view is that man's knowledge of the concretely existing sensible reality is primary in the genesis of such knowledge, and thus that both the concrete sensible reality and man's knowledge of it through sense, intellectual abstraction, and insight are the essential principles of this 668 PSYCHOLOGY AND MAN's KNOWLEDGE OF BEING 669 knowledge. But for many interpreters this cannot fully account for man's existential judgment, since sense knowledge and intellectual abstraction as such do not properly deliver esse or the act of being. In another place I have defended the view that for a full explanation of the existential judgment one has to recognize that the act of being is more properly the object of man's affective inclination and volitional act than of his intellectual insight mediated by sense knowledge and abstraction. 1 As supportive of this view we may note that we place the infinitive form of the verb in a sentence as the direct object of a word or .expression referring to our acts of love, desire, and hate; for example, we say " I want to live." We normally express the direct object of an act of knowledge by a noun or a noun clause. If esse is more properly the object of affectivity and desire than of intellectual knowledge, the existential judgment and the knowledge of being proper to metaphysics is dependent in part on the intellectual knowledge we have through participation in our affective inclination, act, and its object-our own actualization (or act of being) as the good we seek, and other realities that are related to this or to which our actualization is related. The existential judgment is not fully explained by direct intellectual knowledge of concrete sensible reality through sense and abstraction. We need not review the major modern difficulties against this view of man's knowledge of being-such as those that come from Heidegger on the one hand or from an empiricism, rationalism, or constructivism on the other-to recognize that we need something like a contemporary " phenomenology " of knowledge if we are to evaluate Thomas's view in a way that meets the problems of our time. 2 For such a contemporary analysis of man's knowledge I suggest that major attention should be paid to the developmental psychology of Jean Piaget, 1 See "Existence, the Intellect and the Will," The New Scholasticism, 29 (1955), 145-174, and "Man's Transcendence and Thomistic Resources," The Thomist, 38 (1974)' 426-484. 2 I examine these difficulties and suggest an approach to them in " Religious Reflection and Man's Transcendence," The Thomist, 37 (1973), 1-68. 670 JOHN FARRELLY and I suggest this in spite of his strictures against a philosophy of knowledge.8 His is widely recognized to be the outstanding twentieth-century psychology of knowledge he has an epistemological interest in showing how one comes to have the structures of knowledge exhibited in modern science; and his developmental approach provides a unique insight into the dynamism of man's knowledge. Moreover, his study of human knowledge has gone far beyond the reductionism of the behaviorists. By turning to Piaget we have a vast reservoir of experiments on and observations of human knowledge in its stages from infancy to adolescence that philosophers of differing traditions have to come to grips with. Yet Piaget's work, valuable as it is, needs to be supplemented by the work of some American psychologists who have a different emphasis and interpretation from Piaget's. In fact, it appears that the traditional dichotomy between empiricism and rationalism (or some form of idealism) is seen in a different way today in this divergence between some American psychologists such as Eleanor Gibson and Jerome Bruner (different as these are from one another) and Piaget and his associates. Their agreements are all the more significant for their differences, and these agreements and differences help us to grasp the present state of the question. For a full study of the relevance of their work for the psychogenesis of being one would have to analyse their questions, methods, and evidence at much greater length than we are able • These criticisms are expressed in J. Piaget, Insights and Illusions of Philosophy (New York: 1971). Lhave commented on several of them in ;