THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DOMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: The Thomist Press, Washington, D. C. 20017 VoL. XL JANUARY, 1976 No. 1 -A BICENTENNIAL ARTICLE - PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF THE FOUNDING FATHERS: MYTH AND REALITY 1 ULIAN BOYD has suggested that the era of the Founding Fathers was to government what the Age of Pericles was to art, the Age of Elizabeth to exploration and discovery. 1 On the threshold of the nation's bicentennial, it would be advisable to separate this myth from the reality that is the great experiment that is America. For so much myth surrounds the Founding Fathers that the reality often disturbs the placid conviction that our heroes were unmoved by the base passions and the turbulence characteristic of contemporary life. The word, myth, of course need not be used pejoratively. Mircea Eliade has revealed how pre-scientific mythic visions of reality did at least give the ancient world a cohesive world 1 Fundamental, Testaments Washington: 1973, p. 3. of the American Revolution, intr. Julian Boyd. 1 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN view, even if the deeds of the gods were somewhat capriciously invoked, and the vision itself destined to yield to more precise scientific explanation. The mytho-poetic vision of Homer and Hesiod bore little resemblance to consequent Platonic or Aristotelian visions of the universe, but the power of myth seems less determined by inner structure than by the extent to which it is given credence. For instance, it has been comforting to us to see Puritan forefathers, harassed by the motherland, blazing new trails in an exciting new world, seeking freedom above all else. It has been said more accurately perhaps that they wanted to worship God in their own way and to force everybody else to do the same. The Puritan mind was as sternly conservative in the new world as it was in the old. In the 17th century it was theocentric and family oriented, paradoxically committed to the establishment of a theocracy and suspicious of the political realm. Faith, not reason, was to be man's guide, and the Convenant of Grace was more important than rational arrogance-especially since reason was and is an integral part of a nature vitiated by primal sin. The Puritans indeed rejected the formalism of establishment Anglicanism and Catholicism, were suspicious of an Anglican religious establishment allied to an inevitably unholy state, and they chose simplicity over what they considered a quasi-popish ritual. Although James Madison was later to see a vital link between liberty and learning, the 17th century Puritan of the "Holy Commonwealth " was not tolerant theologically, not democratic politically, nor inquisitive intellectually. 2 A native toughness of mind did pose questions that Puritan mysticism was to avoid. 3 The attempt to understand the world of the 2 Cf. Perry Miller, Errand into the Wilderness, New York: 1956, Ch. V, "The Puritan State and Puritan Society," pp. 141-153. Alan Hemert has best described the complexity of the eighteenth century religious mind in his book, Religion and the American Mind, Cambridge, Mass.: 1966. 8 John Bentley disagrees. He sees "democratic ideals embedded deeply in Puritan hearts," and "with matchless wisdom they joined liberty and learning in a holy alliance." Outline of American Philosophy, Patterson: 1963. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 3 Founding Fathers will not be satisfied as much by a study of their political institutions, social conditions, and economic situation as by a study of their manner of thinking. Gordon Wood, in his monumental work, The Creation of the American Republic, cites Joel Barlow's observation that the mind of man is the only foundation for any system of politics. If this be so, it becomes increasingly necessary to study the .evolution of a mentality, rather than limit oneself to empirical data. This is but another way of expressing the primacy of the logos over the deed, if we really want to understand the deed. 4 It is also probable that we see here the power of myth and the limitation of fact. If men think that they are unequal in an Aristotelian political sense, they will not be disturbed by their consequent inequality of status; but if the colonists were convinced that all men were equal in their rights, then the Revolution was indeed made and sustained by the basic conviction. It is another question to ask what the basic convictions of the colonists were. Were they egalitarian in the first place? Are they the transplanted ideas of the philosophes of the French Enlightenment, 17th century English jurists, Puritan theologians, or of Locke and the Commonwealthmen? Were the young Americans stimulated by the indigenous pamphleteering in the colonies, or were they reacting by way of " brute pragmatism" to the American scene? In accepting Barlow's thesis, one can still see something valuably formative in the colonial experience itself that possibly led to a habit of thinking discernibly different from the original thinking that produced the experience. There is indeed an emerging pattern of belief in 18th century America, complex in structure, and sometimes imprecise in terminology, dependent to a degree upon classical and medieval sources, but growing out of all of them to express a new • One thinks here of Goethe's line in Faust: "In the beginning was the deed," as contrasted with the opening words of St. John's gospel, "In the beginning was the logos." 4 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN political outlook that will find only partial expression in the Constitution. The American Revolution was one of the least revolutionary of revolutions, if we would calibrate revolutions by the violence they exhibit. But however articulated, the conviction was there. Camus, in The Rebel, says "Rebellion is born of the spectre of irrationality, confronted with an unjust and incomprehensible condition .... Man is the only creature who refuses to be what he is." 5 The colonists perhaps were not always capable of defining injustice, but they eventually saw themselves as unjustly treated victims, and they indeed refused to be what they were. The loyalists, who possibly numbered about one-fourth of the population, on the contrary, saw the Revolution as madness and fury beyond comprehension. 6 However sympathetic we may be to the much neglected Tory point of view, the scope of which has been examined by that knowledgeable scholar of the period, Bernard Bailyn, the American Revolution was primarily a revolution of the mind rather than a series of convulsive acts of passion committed by a desperate and tyrannized people. The colonists seem to have been more exercised by the idea of being dictated to than they were to de facto dictation. When Edmund Burke had thf' colonists sniffing tyranny in every tainted breeze, he was aware that the colonists were intellectually concerned with the problems of equality, right and justice, long before they had been to any great degree deprived of them. 7 Albert Camus, The Rebel,, New York: 1956, pp. 10-11. Cf. William N. Nelson, The American Tory, Oxford: 1961; Wallace Brown, The King's Friends, Providence: 1966; Bernard Bailyn, The Ordeal of Thomas Hutchinson, Cambridge: 1974; Pauline Maier, From Resistance to Revolution, New York: and Mary Beth Norton, The British Americans: The Loyalist Exiles in England, 1774-1789. The war, of course, was, in a real sense, a civil war whose combatants were not divided by geographical borders. 7 Samuel Eliot Morrison calls them " the freest people in the world," not to obtain freedom, but to confirm it. The Oxford History of the American People, New York: 1965, p. 5 6 PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 5 The historian often laments the poverty of his sources. But when one consults the writing of the period, especially the sermons and pamphlets, one wonders if the colonists ever had an unexpressed thought. As Gordon Wood observes: It seemed to be a peculiar moment in history when all knowledge coincided, when classical antiquity, Christian theology, English empiricism, and European rationalism could all be linked .... To most of the Revolutionaries there was no sense of incompatibility in their blending of history, rationalism and scripture. 8 But perhaps most theoreticians of the Revolution found the inconsistencies of eclectic politics easier to bear, both because of the casualness of their exposure to the contradictory traditions, and because of the adaptiveness that became so much a part of the American character after more than a century of struggle in an unrelenting primitive environment. And perhaps the comparative absence of violence in the struggle could be found, not in the moral superiority of the colonists themselves, but in the colonists' sympathy for the Constitution of the British they were fighting. As late as January 1776, John Adams expressed himself against independence from Britain. The colonists seemed to feel in some vague way that divine ordinance, nature, and rational legal refinement were felicitously combined in the Constitution of Great Britain. From Montesquieu to the Adamses, no praise was too great for the " perfect " Constitution, although hostility could simultaneously be directed against an insensitive Parliament and a remote monarchy which were thought to be perverting that very Constitution. THE EARLY YEARS It is customary to begin our colonial philosophical history with a consideration of Jonathan Edwards (1703-1758), but 8 Gordon Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787, Chapel Hill: 1969, pp. 7-8. 6 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN despite the curious blendings of Calvinistic theology and Lockean empiricism, it would seem that dissenting theologians in general rather than Edwards in particular were of more importance. It has been suggested that the philosophical origins of Congregrational Puritanism go back to the Platonic humanism of Peter Ramus (1515-1586) whose anti-scholasticism and anti-Aristotelianism would be compatible with the Founding Fathers' humanistic deism-although Jefferson was no admirer of Plato either. Almost a century before the Declaration of Independence, Platonism had a base in Cambridge, and one of the Cambridge Puritans, William Ames, provided the philosophy texts of early New England. 9 Thomas Hooker is another name that was to be famous in the convenant theology of New England, and his influence was to become both religious and philosophical. Schneider sees convenant theology as a secular variant of social contract theory, directed against religious formalism as the compact is directed against excesses of the Crown. Although it is questionable that the Puritan Platonists were more philosophical than Biblical, the transition to deism and r.eligious naturalism does seem to have been a gradual and almost inevitable development. Not only were Locke's Treatises widely read in the colonies, but Locke was a hero to Edwards all of his life. Quite simply, the greatest ideological influence on the Founding Fathers of our nation-before and after the revisionist theory of the past fifteen years-is the towering figure of John Locke . There is considerable interest in philosophical influences to which Locke was subjected, and the odd way in which his libertarian theory weaves in and out of the thought of the Commonwealthmen and pro-American Parliamentarians. Those influences would he the classical study of his Westminister years, the Scholastic philosophy which, like Descartes, 9 Cf. Herbert W. Schneider, History of American Philosophy, New York: p. 6. 1963, PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 7 he knew and disliked; the libertarian ethics and theology of Ralph Cudworth, the Cambridge Platonist; the Christian humanism of Richard Hooker; the rationalism of the great Descartes; and the cautious scepticism and empiricism of Gassendi, which he probably knew best through his discussions with Gassendi's disciple, Bernier. Caroline Robbins sees Locke as a "determined Whig," but exposed to many friends of varying beliefs at home and abroad. 10 At least in his earlier years before the return to Oxford in 1666, he does seem to be more the involved politician than philosopher, although he began to write his philosophical ideas down as early as 1660. His long association with Lord Ashley, later Earl of Shaftesbury (for whom he was both secretary and physician) was to sharpen his taste for political theory. Especially pertinent was his association with Shaftesbury in the 1669 writing of a constitution for the colony of Carolina, and his developing distaste for political and religious intolerance. Although involved almost all 0£ his life in practical affairs, he nursed at times a Cartesian aloofness, and a caution possibly born of his successful fight against extradition before the Glorious Revolution. Not only was the work of Locke known to the more literate colonists, but his 1690 Essay Concerning Human Understanding provided much 0£ the basis for the French philosophes' faith in Reason. His Second Treatise of Government, written between 1679 and 1681, was perhaps a more direct influence on social contract theory among the Founding Fathers. 11 1 ° Caroline Robbins, The Eighteenth Century Commonwealthman, Studies in the Transmission, Development and Circumstance of English Liberal Thought from the Restoration of Charles II until the War with the Thirteen Colonies, Cambridge: 1961, p. 58. 11 The best available version of the Essay is edited by Peter H. Nidditch. It is the first volume of the Clarendon Edition published at Oxford. Peter Laslett's Two Treatises published by Cambridge in 1960 is the best edited version of that important source. In 1960, Mr. Paul Mellon purchased the Lovelace collection of Locke's works and presented them to the Bodleian Library at Oxford. Cf. R. I. Aaron, John Locke, Oxford: 1955; Maurice Cranston, John Locke, A Biography, London: 1957; and J. W. Gough, John Locke's Political Philosophy, Oxford: 8 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN Scholarship has, within recent years, challenged the view that Locke was, in Merle Curti's words, America's philosopher, or in Morton White's, the father of American Philosophyor indeed, one of the Founding Fathers by adoption. Although these claims cannot be lightly dismissed, the case for Locke as the greatest single philosophical influence can be sustained. First of all, what does Locke actually say in the Two Trea.tises of Government? Because of the comparative recency of Peter Laslett's critical edition (1960), one can determine better what Locke actually believed. The lesser First Treatise, as is well known, is simply a disdainful evaluation and critique of Sir Robert Filmer's Patriarcha, the celebrated defense of the divine right of kings. The ridicule Locke heaps on the unfortunate Filmer would, of course, be most sympathetically received by the colonists, especially by the more literate, who were less than ardent admirers of George III. The more important Second Treatise begins with a treatment of the common state of nature into which all men are born. The state of nature is not meant to be an actually existing primitive historical condition, but the pre-state situation of men, who, though not involved in Hobbesian warfare, live according to reason " without a common superior on earth with authority to judge between them." In short, it is the absence of civil society. Pre-state man, guided by reason, is destined to endure in benevolence and good will; but because of the regrettable tendency of some to seek power and violate the rights of others, civil government by the consent of the governed comes into being. There is no compact here between ruler and ruled, but between individuals of equal status. And if any become tyrants, they are enemies who may be punished by the community at large. 1950. John Dunn emphasizes the influence of Locke's religious commitments in the formation of his political theory and minimizes the influence of Locke on American political theory in the eighteenth century. The Political Thought of John Locke, Cambridge: 1969. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 9 It is interesting to note that Locke here .espouses an optimistic rationalism which recognizes tyranny to be a behavioral aberration from normative appropriate behavior. And yet his odd and indefensible def.ense of slavery is not seen in this context of aberrant behavior. H is doubtful, however, that Locke's espousal of slavery contributed greatly to that institution's prospering in the new world. The concern of the slave owners was more financial and practical than ideological. It will be remembered that the status of the slave and prohibition of the slave trade were discussed but consciously omitted before the American Constitution was drawn up, and Congress was specifically prohibited from abolishing the slave trade for twenty years. 12 The colonists certainly realized that slavery was a painfully obvious denial of liberty, but they realized too that its abolition would spell financial ruin. Few even of the most enlightened Virginians were willing to declare, as Jefferson did in the instructions he wrote for his colony's delegation to the First Continental Congress, that ' the rights of human nature (are) deeply wounded by this infamous practice.' 13 In general, it may be said that the colonists had a qualified interest in equality (except for those cited occasions when equality would entail a significant financial loss). But they were aware, as was Locke almost a century before, that those free men of superior gifts and industry would inevitably acquire preferential status. And as Charles Lee was to observe, the honors would be obtained " without court favor or the rascally talents of servility." 12 The colonists were certainly aware of the Lockean justification of slavery, and the literature of the period reveals that they thought themselves victims of a British effort to reduce them to the position of slaves. Cf. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, Cambridge: 1967, pp. 282-246. 13 Ibid., p. 286. Patrick Henry too agonized over this inconsistency, and hoped for a future opportunity to get rid of this " lamentable evil." This does not appear, however, to be a widely shared sentiment among 18th century Americ1m plantation owners, 10 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN The question of property was of considerable concern to Locke, Although no one had natural and exclusive rights to the goods of the earth, man was represented as having a right to seek and acquire the goods of the earth for his own well being. It is by the labor of man that the goods of nature are transformed into property, and the state is obliged to safeguard property in its acquisition, maintenance and transference. Locke rather interestingly articipates the labor theory of value, and suggests that man's acquisitive powers be limited to that which can be transformed by his personal labor. He takes for granted the" just precedency" of some over others. Power is to be employed by the people for " the mutual preservation of their lives, liberties, and estates." Sovereignty remains with the people, although they may designate one, the few, or the many to represent their interests. It is significant to remember in this context that Jefferson objected to being ruled by Parliament, not because its rulings were unjust, but because Parliament had no right to make the rules in the first place. The colonists' suspicion of the metastasis of power was not limited to the excesses of Great Britain. In later years it would be directed against their own representatives. The pervasive Whig mistrust of power had in the years since Independence been increasingly directed not only against the traditional rulers, but also against the supposed representatives of the people, who now seemed to many to be often as distant and unrepresentative of the people's interests as Parliament once had been. 14 Locke himself seemed to prefer an executive constitutional monarch, and an elected parliament, and there would seem to be considerable pro-monarchy sentiment even among those who would refuse George Ill's claim to this position. Professor Wood suggests that the hostility of the colonists was not "Gordon S. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787, Chapel Hill: 1969, p. 598. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 11 directed against aristocracy as much as against a crownappointed aristocracy. But of interest to the colonists particularly would be Locke's justification of rebellion under extraordinary circumstances. He was not interested in hobbling the executive power, but he did recognize the necessity of rebellion when lesser means of redress failed. It is human reason that judges the gravity of governmental injustice, and it is that same human reason that prompts man to refrain from hasty precipitate action when less drastic measures suffice. Rebellion is aimed, not at anarchy nor at a return to the individualism characteristic of the state of nature, but toward the just government of the many. And when the prince rules arbitrarily and unjustly, ignoring constitutional or legal restraints; when he dissolves the legislature or impedes its work, sovereignty returns to the people. 15 In general, Locke's philosophy is open, liberal, sympathetic and forward-looking. He is the believing rationalist, who accepts Revelation as a supplement to reason, repudiates the right of the state to intrude in matters of the spirit, and who speaks, for the most part, eloquently in the defense of religious freedom. It is perhaps this sympathy to religion, a quality not found ordinarily in the philosophesoftheEnlightenment, that made a felicitous combination of the political and spiritual for the religious colonists. It is perhaps surprising that he was so wrong in the matter of slavery and in his unwillingness to extend toleration to Catholics and atheists, but for the time in which he wrote, he was quite liberal. 15 It is here that Locke invokes his " appeal to heaven " argument, by which tyrannized people, " by a law antecedent and paramount to all positive laws of men", have the right to rebel. Ultimately, this is the Hobbesian argument of self-preservation. Cf. Treatise, Ch. xiv; Bailyn, op. cit., pp. 198-229; Wood, op. cit., Ch. x, " The Sovereignty of the people," pp. 344-390. ROBERT PAUL MOHAN ENTER THE REVISIONISTS It has been customary to consider Locke's influence as indirectly exercised on the colonists by means of the philosophes of the Enlightnment, but the revisionst work of scholars in the past decade has given us new insights into intermediary influences only partly Lockean in inspiration. Of particular importance in any study of the philosophical pre-suppositions of the Founding Fathers has been the work of Caroline Robbins and Bernard Bailyn. 16 Bailyn has summarized what he calls the myth of the American colonial experience, citing first the supposed fact that, previous to the American Revolution, the political experience of Colonial America was roughly analogous to Great Britain; secondly, that an alliance of planters and merchants, constituting an aristocracy embodying religious orthodoxy, economic privilege and social hierarchy, were attacked by native, frontierbred democrats through the medium of many provincial assemblies, especially in the decade previous to 1776. The traditional picture is completed with the American Revolution destroying the oppressive power of this aristocracy and giving power to freedom-loving Whig colonists. By the imposition of these radical ideas on a traditional society, a social revolution was effected that destroyed all but the remnants of an old aristocracy-but remnants which survived to regain power in a counter-revolution of the 1780s and impose conservative views on the new Federal constitution. By its light, politics in America, from the very beginning could be seen to have been a dialectical process in which an aristocracy of wealth and power struggled with the people, who, ordinarily ill-organized and inarticulate, rose upon provocation, armed with powerful institutional and ideological weapons to reform a periodically corrupt polity .17 16 Caroline Robbins, op. cit.; Bernard Bailyn, "Political Experience and Enlightenment Ideas in Eighteenth Century America," in The American Historical Review, Vol. 67, January, 1962, pp. 339-351. The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, Cambridge: 1967. 17 Bailyn, American Historical Review, Vol. 67, p. 841. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 18 The assumption involved was that an Enlightenmentinspired group 0£ American radicals had turned a dispute in imperial relations into a sweeping reformation 0£ public institutions and land, and that what evolved, evolved from a necessity 0£ time and place. The revisionists, writing against the theory 0£ such texts as Carl Becker's History of Political Parties in the Province of New York, 1760-1776, and Charles Beard's Eoonomio Interpretation of the Corn.stitution, tell a different story. To some 0£ them, it was not the Enlightenment that provoked American radicals during the Revolution, nor any other ideological source, but the brute pragmatism 0£ American li£e.18 Daniel Boorstin in The Amerioans: The Colonial Experience (1958) emphasizes experience, the "given", as the secret 0£ American li£e rather than old world wisdom 0£ any class 0£ knowers. So two sets 0£ £acts are in evidence. The first, the conscious seriousness with which Revolutionary leaders took ideas 0£ social and political theory that they certainly knew; and colonial practicality, which spawned an ad hoo ideology that the uniqueness 0£ their situation suggested. Moreover, Robbins sees a continuous fresh flow 0£ information into the colonies (already strong in the 17th century, but increasing in the 18th) coming principally by way 0£ English dissenters and their American co-religionists. This means that a neglected source 0£ colonial thought was the commonwealth radicalism 0£ the 17th and 18th centuries, involving not only the obvious figures 0£ Beccaria, Montesquieu, Voltaire, and Locke, whose works were known to the colonists, but a whole group 0£ lesser known foes 0£ traditional authority like Trenchard, Gordon, Neville, Harrington, Watts, Neal, Sidney, Priestley, and Price. Moreover Diderot, Montesquieu, and Voltaire, liberal as they were, had doubts about the 18 Cf. Frederick B. Tolles, " The American Revolution Considered as a Social Movement: A Re-evaluation," in The American Historical Review, Vol. 60, October, 1954, pp. 1-12. 14 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN possibility of republican government succeeding m a great country. Most interestingly, It IS to be noted that in the pamphlet literature-and Bailyn discovered more than 400 available in wide circulation in 1776-the work most often cited in the colonies was not that of Montesquieu or Locke, but Ca.to's Letters, radically libertarian essays written in London between 1720 and 1723 by two dissenters, John Trenchard and Thomas Gordon, 19 who later were to write commentaries on Sallust and Tacitus that evoked the praise of Franklin, Adams, and Jefferson. The controversy over the validity of imperial government in the colonies is seen as providing a common vocabulary, common thought, and later, common principles. But the revisionists see the colonists not only aware of being innovators, but effecting reforms in the name of reason. They also see franchise not being exercised by colonists who could vote, and dissent well tolerated and not penalized. 20 In short, dissent is seen as a well-established phenomenon before the Revolution. And Enlightenment theory is seen as having little to do with these developments, which are occasioned by the exigencies of the situation. Bailyn says simply: "Nowhere in the 18th century was there democracy-middle class or otherwise-as we use the term." 21 The Commonwealthmen of whom Caroline Robbins speaks were an extraordinary group. Their names are not well known and no great achievements are attributed to them, but they were a group of Whigs who preserved the evolutionary tradition for service in the American Revolution. They worked from the older libertarian tradition of Harrington, N edham, and Milton 19 Books, newspapers, travel, correspondence are also cited as sources of transmission of Whig radicalism. Cf. Pauline Maier, From Resistance to Revolution, New York: 1979!. • 0 It has been said that mobs in 18th-century America functioned as a part of the political structure rather than as an attack upon it. "Bailyn, Ibid., p. 346. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 15 in Cromwell's time; through Sidney, Neville, and Locke at the time of Charles II; and a later group including Burgh, Price, and Priestley were the latest of the series. The Commonwealthmen themselves produced, soon after 1689, accounts, arguments, essays, and histories which might be dubbed the apocryphal books of the Whig Bible as it was to be read by revolutionaries and reformers all around the Atlantic world. 22 Robbins goes on to describe the Commonwealthmen of three generations, seeing Priestly and Price early radicals of the last period whose work was roughly contemporaneous with the Revolution. Their thought, of course, was not a matter of unanimity, but they argued for personal freedoms, a system of checks and balances, resistance to tyranny, and constitutional government. Adams and Franklin both had direct contact with the Trenchard-Hutchinson Whigs and were probably influenced by the preoccupation of this group with religious and political liberty, extension of the franchise, freedom of thought, although oddly enough, not with egalitarianism. The London tavern rather than the academic hall was the favored meeting place, and many a tract or pamphlet seems to have been born of these "club " discussions. It is, of course, impossible to cite all of the figures involved, but one man stands out among the early Commonwealthmen both for the violence of his convictions and for the fact that his Discourses were "more of a Bible to the revolutionaries than any of the works of his century, Milton alone excepted." 23 Algernon Sidney the aristocratic self-proclaimed foe of tyranny, was executed by the government of Charles II. His Discourses, abusive to the Crown, though not egalitarian, placed power in Parliament and in the people; justified rebellion when necessary; condoned the slaying of tyrants and the freeing of slaves; and advocated a militarily strong state. ••Robbins, op. cit., p. 5. 23 Robbins, op. cit., p. 46. 16 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN A ringing message from a violent man, it not only appealed to the revolutionary mind in England and in America, but expressed the hopeful conviction that popular government is self-corrective. And his was an appeal that lasted for over a century. It is somewhat odd that the more temperate Locke does not seem to have read the Discourses.24 The fame of the great Milton and the equally great Newton is in the fields of literature and science. Though Newton, like Descartes, sought a low profile, his socio-political theorizing and theological speculations seems to have influenced his own century as much as his science did a later one. Richard Cumberland (1631-1718), Anglican bishop and anti-Hobbes political philosopher, in De Legibus N aturae emphasized the role of reason operative in a teleological universe, and he appears to have been widely read. Robert Molesworth (1656-1725), one of the most important Whigs of his time, was admired by Locke and wrote in his famous Account of the blessings of health and liberty. He was erroneously supposed to have contributed to the immensely popular Cato's Letters of the independent Whigs, Gordon and Trenchard. Another work that had eleven printings and was well known in the colonies was The Case of Ireland of William Molyneux (1656-1698), basically because of its anti-colonial sentiment. Another Englishman of this period was Thomas Hollis, whose interest and benefactions to the colonists .elicited Dr. Johnson's exaggerated but flattering charge that he was partially responsible for the American Revolution. FRANKLIN AND FRIENDS The Enlightenment in the American experience is first associated with the name of Benjamin Franklin (1706-1790). "Curiously, Locke recommends Sidney, but claims he never read him. Madison, in a letter to Jefferson on February 8, concerning textbooks, expresses reservations about both Sidney and Locke, though conceding that they both are basic sources for English republican theory. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 17 Thirty-seven years older than Jefferson, he had spent sixteen years in England, where he made the acquaintance of David Hume. And in his seventy-first year, he began a nine-year sojourn in France, where he enjoyed the friendship of Condorcet, Voltaire, Madame Helvetius, and other figures prominent in the French Enlightenment. 25 Exposure to the critical thought of Hume and Voltaire, and the rationalism of the philosophe.'!, while encouraging a political stance that showed a marked development from a Conservative loyalty to British institutions to a political liberalism based on self-determination, did little to disturb his rather serene deism, and the relatively conservative work ethic reflected in the aphorisms of Poor Richard and in the Autobiography .26 He certainly believed in the service character of government, had a rationalistic confidence in the ability of well-intentioned men to form viable political structures, and saw man as destined to an eternity with the God who created him. Yet Franklin, though he has been called with Jefferson the fullest embodiment of the Enlightenment spirit in America, is For him, more the experimentalist than the theoretician. philosophy lets light into the nature of things, and while he is interested in theoretical understanding, the practical skills take precedence. This same "pragmatic wisdom" is found in Franklin's 26 Cf. Ralph Ketcham, Benjamin Franldin, New York: 1965; Frank Mott and Chester Jorgenson, eds., " Introduction," in Benjamin Franldin: Representative Selections, New York: 1936; The Autobiography of Benjamin Franldin, New Haven: 1964; The Papers of Benjamin Franklin, 8 vols., New Haven: 1959; C. L. Sanford, Benjamin Franldin and the American Character, Boston: 1955. Condorcet and Turgot, who considered Americans " the hope of the world," were to figure importantly in the philosophy of progress, one of rationalism's most powerful dynamics. 26 His acceptance of a Providential God, mentioned in a 1790 letter to Jefferson's friend, Yale president, Ezra Stiles, would suggest a rather unorthodox deism. The classic exposition of deism is probably J. Toland's Christianity Not Mysterious (1696), which rejects Revelation and Providence. Cf. also S. Clarke, Demonstrations of Being and the Attributes of God (1704-06) . 18 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN approach to morality and politics. 27 It is the empirical intelligence of a Bacon and Locke that he brings to domestic and foreign politics and ethics. Like Jefferson, he esteems good works over good words. Socrates and Christ were not for Franklin the rather blasphemous association they would be for a Jonathan Edwards. A particular influence on Franklin was the Welsh dissenter and moral philosopher, Richard Price (l His well known pamphleteering in behalf of the American cause possibly lessened Franklin's aversion to breaking "that fine and noble vase, the British Empire," although the latter did propose separation as early as 1767. 28 The Philadelphian, as has been noted, had been in England almost uninterruptedly from 1757 to 1775, and had become friendly with Price, to whom the Continental Congress with Washington's blessing wanted to extend citizenship. The Congress was interested in his skills as a government financial consultant. He is also remembered for his philosophical discussion with Hume and Priestley. 29 His association with Franklin took place chiefly at the fortnightly meetings at the London Tavern of the Honest Whigs, a group of dissenters that included Priestly and Boswell. His Obser- vations on the Nature of Civil Lib'erty, The Principles of Government and the Justice and Policy of the War with 27 The term is Adrienne Koch's, used in her description of the American She sees hers as a mediating theory between the Carl Becker Enlightenment. thesis (that the 18th century colonial mind accepted a divinely designed nature that could be discovered by reason and articulated in normative laws) and the Boorstin view that the given and the experienced took precedence over theory in the American experience. Boorstin sees the colonists uncongenial to any class of knowers and sensitive to the unique and "unpredicted whisperings " of environment. Cf. Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence, New York: 1945, and The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth Century Philosophers, New York. Daniel Boorstin's work is The Colonial Experience, New York: 1958. 28 Jefferson too, writing as late as August 25, 1775, to his loyalist relative, John Randolph, hoped for an end to an " unnatural contest," and wished for a reunion with the parent country. 29 Carl B. Cone, Torchbearer of Freedom; The Influence of Richard Price on Eighteenth Century Thought, Lexington, Kentucky: 1952. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 19 America (1776) was his most significant work, and his Discourse on the Love of Our Country (1789), written in defense of the French Revolution, was to provoke Burke's famous Reflections on the Revolution in. France. Price saw in his Observations an America being deprived of the natural and inalienable right of liberty. He described the various species of civil liberty involved in the principle of self-direction, and eventually proposed for the peace of the world a league of independent states. Government power should be forever suspect; structures should be representative; people should not be arbitrarily taxed; and the people should be the ultimate arbiters of the rule under which they live. He mocks the enemies of the colonists who sneer that America's defenders are Mr. Locke's disciples-and glories in the title. 30 Joseph Priestley (1733-1804), "a dissenter by training and disposition," ten years younger than Price, was minister, scientist, and philosopher. In his work, An Essay on the First Principles of Government (1768) he displayed his Lockean sympathies in behalf of political and religious pluralism and civil liberty in general. His work is an odd combination of unitarianism, determinism, and that kind of materialism espoused by Jefferson that is compatible with spiritual values. He continued to write on theological and political questions after emigrating to Pennsylvania on 1794, angering some Americans by his criticism of their intolerance, but enjoying Jefferson's friendship and protection. 31 Passmore credits Priestley's Socrates and Jesus Compared (1803) with provoking Jefferson's Syllabus of religious beliefs; and another of the former's works, The Doctrines of Heathen Religion Compared with Those of Revelation (1804) evoking in John Adams an interest in comparative religion. The greatest of the political pamphlets of the American Revolution is Common Sense of Thomas Paine (1737-1809). Published early in 1776 by the erratic corsetmaker, grocer, 8 °Caroline Robbins, op. cit., p. 344. 81 Cf. John Passmore, Joseph Priestley, New York: 1965. 20 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN teacher, and preacher-perhaps best remembered by the colorful but inaccurate description of Theodore Roosevelt as " that filthy little atheist,"-it touched, as Bernard Bailyn has suggested, " some extraordinarily sensitive nerve in American political awareness," although the author had been in the country less than three years prior to its publication. 32 What is most notable is that, at the time of its writing, independence from England was neither a political nor a popular cause of great significance. As late as January, 1776, John Adams was to assert that he did not wish America to break away from Britain. The picture of an American nation almost universally desirous of independence from Britain in 1776 is a popular myth. The American nation was a scattered group of individualistic colonies possessed of neither ideological nor political unity, and Great Britain, despite her rather short-sighted ruling clique, had a much better record on constitutional liberties than her contemporaries, who would have been quite willing to further their own interests at America's expense. 33 It has been said that Paine considers government, like clothes, a badge of lost innocence. And despite its emotional intensity which would suggest that this first widely disseminated plea for independence was more reflective of heart than mind, the pamphlet has some philosophical pre-suppositions, chief among which are the pessimistic convictions that a just monarchy is even theoretically impossible, and the optimistic conviction that corporate good sense and a rational capacity for perceiving the orderly universe resides in the masses. Quite simply, Paine was writing to a people who did not as a group want independence from Great Britain. He saw an umbilical cord that was not a conv.eyor of life but a rope of 32 Bernard Bailyn, "Common Sense," in Fundamental Tenets of the American Revolution, Washington, 1973, p. 7. John Adams despised Paine in particular, and New Yorkers in general. 33 Professor John Alden, however, argues for "the essential solidity of the English colonies," A History of the American Revolution, New York: 1969, p. 5. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 21 strangulation-and he wanted it severed. He saw Europenot England-as the mother country, and he lamented the narcotic effect of any phrase or thought that would deaden the political aspirations of the colonists. Paine is not speaking in a formal Enlightenment idiom, although he is eventually to arrive by sheer wrath at Enlightenment conclusions in favor of the individual versus the iniquitous tyranny of a " sullentempered Pharoah " like George III. In short, his is the short-cut of rage through the lucubrations of reason. Logic and reason will later support his plea for independence and freedom-although he specifically denies having even read Locke. His heart quite clearly had its own reasons and he expressed those reasons with incredible intensity .34 The message of Common Sense spread like wildfire through the colonies after its publication in January of 1776.35 JEFFERSON In any discussion of the philosophy of the Founding Fathers, the name of Thomas Jefferson (1743-1826) inevitably assumes the pre-eminent place. Although it is not a matter of unanimity that Jefferson was a philosopher at all in the strict sense of the term, the many-sided genius was much more than the chief representative of Enlightenment thought in the colonies. 36 84 Cf. Alfred Owen Aldridge, Man of Reason: The Life of Thomas Paine, New York: 1959. 85 John Adams, however, cited Jonathan Mayhew's A Discourse Concerning Unlimited Submission and Non-Resistance to the Higher Powers (1750) as the opening gun of the Revolution. It combined libertarian thought of Sidney, Milton and Locke. 86 Adrienne Koch, for instance, cites the reluctance of the Jefferson scholar, Gilbert Chinard, to consider Jefferson as a philosopher in the formal sense of the word. She insists, however, that while Jefferson scorned school metaphysics, and was not a system-builder like Aquinas, Spinoza, Kant and Hegel, he was a man of considerable intellectual curiosity and talent, with a capacity for methodical rational analysis of the human situation and environment. Cf. The Philosophy of Thomas Jefferson, Chicago: 1964, pp. xi-xiv. Cf. also The Papers of Thomas Jefferson, Julian Boyd, ed., 16 vols., Princeton: 1950; Paul Ford, ROBERT PAUL MOHAN Our knowledge of the first four decades of Jefferson's life is not helpfully revealing, but we do know that from his study of the classics in James Maury's private school, he was exposed to the thought of Homer, Euripides, Herodotus, Virgil, Ovid, Seneca, and Cicero. 37 Stoicism and Epicureanism were also to figure in his early formation, but neither tradition could be said in any sense to have claimed his allegiance as a system. He was a practical man whose thought was frequently speculative. He was the great American libertarian, swearing eternal hostility to every attempt to constrain the mind of man; yet at various times, as Michael Kammen has pointed out, " ... he could embrace loyalty oaths, consider internment camps for political suspects, draft a bill of attainder, urge prosecution for seditious libel, ignore the Fourth Amendment's protection against unreasonable searches and seizures, condone military despotism, use the army to enforce laws in peacetime, choose professors for their political opinions, and endorse the doctrine that means, however odious, could be justified by the ends." 38 Jefferson is not simply categorized in any philosophic or religious system, for the simple reason that he never submitted his opinions to any party or system in politics, religion, philosophy, or anything else, and considered such submission as servility and as a degrading addiction for a free moral agent. "If I could not go to heaven but with a party, I would not go there at all." 39 The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, 10 vols., New York: 1892-1899; Daniel Boorstin, The Lost World of Thomas Jefferson, New York: 1948; Merrill Peterson, The Jefferson Image in the Virginian, Vol. I, Jefferson and the Rights of Man, Vol. II, Jefferson and the Ordeal of Liberty, Vol. III, Jefferson, the President, Vol. IV. Two additional volumes are to complete this definitive biography begun in 1948. Norman Cousins, In God We Trust, New York: 1958. 37 The Literary Bible of Thomas Jefferson: His Commonplace Book of Philosophers and Poets, Gilbert Chinard, ed., Baltimore: 1928. 88 Michael Kammen in Book World, The Washington Post, July 7, 1974, pp. 1-2. 39 Letter to Francis Hopkinson, March 13, 1789, Memorial Edition, Writings, Vol. 7, p. soo. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS Like Franklin, whom he admiringly referred to as the Father of American Philosophy, Jefferson had, in his Paris period (1785-1790), acquired a personal knowledge of the figures and principles of the French Enlightenment, which is suggested as a major philosophical influence in his life. The common sense realism of his contemporary, Dugald Stewart, was to influence him and colonial college curricula considerably .40 The Enlightenment, of course, is frequently cited as one of the great sources of Revolutionary thought. In general, the Enlightenment refers to the 18th century Age of Reason when popularizers such as Voltaire, Holbach, Diderot, La Mettrie, Condorcet, Helvetius, D'Alembert, and Beccaria developed a distinctively rationalistic point of view conditioned by the empiricism of Bacon and Descartes, and social theory derived from the thought of Hobbes, Rousseau, and Locke. Fundamentally, the philosophes were not professional philosophers, but they were concerned with rationally ascertained knowledge of man and nature that hopefully would lead man to the good life. Implicit in Enlightenment thought was an optimistic philosophy of progress which would see the good life as possible by the unaided natural powers of enlightened man. 41 Jefferson not only knew the philosophy of Locke, but he was also influenced by Bolingbroke's scepticism which is structured along the lines of Book Four of The Essay Concerning Hurrwn Understanding. Henry St. John Bolingbroke (1678-1751), the colorful Tory statesman and man of letters, the object of Hume's contempt and and Dr. Johnson's wrath, was not an important philosopher, but his deism and rather inconsistent 4 ° Cf. Jefferson to Madison, November 15, 1817, The Writings of James Madison, Vol. 4, p. 213. Jefferson was interested in Stewart, the friend of his Paris days, on the faculty of his " new " university. 41 Peter Gay, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation: The Rise of Modern Paganism, New York: 1966; Ernst Cassirer, The Phuosophy of the Enlightenment, Koelln-Pettegrove trans., Boston: 1955; Carl Becker, The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Phuosophers, New Haven: 1932; and J. B. Bury, The Idea of Progress, London: 1920. ROBERT PAUL MOHAN scepticism, coupled with a humanistic concern, appealed to Jefferson. 42 In Bolingbroke authority and surmise is to yield to reason; principles, far from being absolute, are relative to a time and place; materialism is the philosophy reason dictates, but reason must find a way to justify spiritual values. Jefferson was perhaps sensitive to the inconsistencies of his position. He seems to have been uncomfortable with any form of philosophic idealism, yet he had, as his voluminous correspondence reveals, a profound interest in and respect for ethical and spiritual values, even attempting to use the materialist idiom to define the human soul, fashioned, like the universe, by an orderly and intelligent "Superintending Power." 43 The man who has such a natural sympathy for the empirical idiom tries with only partial success to articulate a belie£ in an intelligent and benevolent Creator, who is at one time identified as being akin to Mind, yet who cannot really be known or described. 44 A life well lived is, for Jefferson, the ultimate test for religion's value. The good man, who reflects the sublime doctrines of Jesus of Nazareth in his life, is more important than sectarian affiliation. Yet it can be seen that even this qualified personal faith is far removed from the strident atheism of a Holbach or a Diderot, whose extraordinary versatility his own skills resemble. 45 It will be remembered that the Encyclopedie, ou Dictionnaire 42 Cf. Sir Douglas Harkness, Bolingbroke: The Man and His Career, London: 1957; Walter McMerrill, From Statesman to Philosopher: A Study in Bolingbroke's Deism, New York: 1949. 43 Letter to John Adams, April 11, 1823, Memorial Edition, Vol. 15, p. 427. ••Ibid. ••Jefferson's quasi-intuitionist ethic would, of course, differ sharply from Diderot's rejection of free will in the deterministic D'Alembert's Dream. Yet they share an ethical naturalism. In searching for a teacher of ethics for the University of Virginia, Jefferson, in a letter to Madison on November 30, 1824, suggests a layman to teach in a philosophical tradition of Locke, Stewart, Brown, or Tracy, rather than a clergyman, who, he felt, would slant philosophy in the favor of a specific religious traditio!l, PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 25 ra-isonnedes scwnces, des arts, et des metiers, edited by Diderot and finished just four years before the Declaration of Independence, was to become not only the bible of rationalists, but the greatest cultural ev.ent of its time. But it was not a formally philosophic work any more than its famous contributors were formal philosophers. Jefferson was particularly impressed with D'Alembert's famous introduction to the Encyclopedic. D' Alembert knew English empiricism, and the D-iscours preliminaire reveals not only a debt to Cartesian rationalism, but more specifically to the empiricism of Bacon, Newton, and Locke. He also shared Jefferson's acute distaste for school metaphysics, and saw the human mind as capable of ferreting out the One Great Truth that is the universe. Jefferson did not accept John Adams' vigorous denunciation of the Encyclopedists as men " totally destitute " of common sense, but he did not accept either their mechanism or belief that religions were merely illusory " visions judaiques." 46 But even given Jefferson's general philosophic orientationand it must be remembered that he used the word philosophy in a generalized sense that would include systematic investigation on the natural sciences-he is in no sense an American edition of the French Encyclopedists. Even the term American Enlightenment which implies similarity to the French movement is perhaps an unfortunate one. Adrienne Koch identifies the Franklin-Jefferson synthesis as Pragmatic Wisdom, a blend of empiricism, rationalism, and a humanistic concern for the whole man. 47 Its message is the confident Jeffersonian conviction that the fruits of pragmatic wisdom were more evident in America than in England. Jefferson, like many of the prominent theorists of the American Revolution, had his misgivings at times about the success of the great experiment; but he did feel 46 Letter to Adams, April 8, 1816, Memorial Edition, Vol. 14, pp. 468-71. "Adrienne Koch, " Pragmatic Wisdom and the American Enlightenment," in The William and Mary Quarterly, Vol. 18, July, 1961, pp. 813-829; and The American Enlightenment, ed., Adrienne Koch, New York: 1965. ROBERT PAUL MOHAN that the three greatest men who ever lived, Bacon, Newton, and Locke, philosophers and Englishmen all, found their crowning achievement in the new world rather than in the old. 48 To pursue the investigation of the source of the ethical convictions of Jefferson, one must cite the man credited by the Sage himself as the author of the greatest moral philosophy ever written, Pierre Charron (1541-1603). Charron's De la sagesse espoused an optimistic and naturalistic humanism which was not only to influence Jefferson's moral theory, but which was to have a direct influence on his political stance. The liberal Whig or conservative Tory, in Jefferson's mind, is not the product of an independent rational investigation. The parties are determined by the nature of men, and dichotomized by good and bad psychological traits respectively. 49 Oddly enough, Adrienne Koch, in her classic study of Jefferson's philosophy, takes little note of Charron as a formative influence. Pierre Charron was an ordained priest and lawyer. His important De la sagesse (1601), highly controversial and widely read, was admired by Pierre Gassendi, among others. Sceptical and fideistic in tone, it proposed both the inadequacy of human knowing powers and the legitimacy of the faith affirmation. From a sceptical methodology, Cartesian in nature, man develops a natural ethic as best he can, even though the human predicament precludes certainty based on the resources of nature. 50 THE SLAVERY QUESTION Perhaps the most perceptive study of slavery and the Founding Fathers has been provided by William W. Freehling, 48 Letter to John Trumbull, February 15, 1789. This is a recurrent theme in Jefferson. ••Letter to Joel Barlow, May 3, 1802, Memorial Edition, Vol. IO, p. 319; letter to Lafayette, November 24, 1823, Memorial Edition, Vol. 15, p. 490. "° Cf. Richard Popkin, The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes, Assen, The Netherlands: 1963. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS fl7 who examines the impact of revisionist history on one of our less glorious institutions. 51 The original roseate vision of our Founding Fathers sounding the death knell to an iniquitous institution has yielded to a more cynical view that sees both privilege and slavery fortified by an elitist Constitution. At first glance, Jefferson's eventual freeing of nine of his slaves strikes one as a rather pallid liberalism, somewhat reminiscent of Dick Gregory's remark that a liberal lynches a victim from a low tree. There is an agonizing ambivalence in Jefferson's approach to the problem dictated by the internal conflict of idealist and pragmatist. He sees the utopian goal rendered impractical by the world that was, and his own suspicion of black sexual prowess and intellectual inferiority must be admitted to be a part of the world that was. By conviction Jefferson, like Washington and Randolph, would have freed all of his slaves. But property value and ethnic theory were both involved. The financial cost of abolition, heavy enough by itself, was made too staggering to bear by the Founding Fathers' racism, an ideological hindrance to anti-slavery, no less important than their sense of priorities and their commitment to property. 52 At any rate, though slavery was not dying in Jefferson's Virginia, he must be credited with localizing the .evil and looking 51 William W. Freehling, "The Founding Fathers and Slavery," The American Historical Review, 77 (1972), 81-91. Cf. also Robert McColley, Slavery and Jeffersonian Virginia, Urbana: 1964; Staughton Lynd, Class Conflict, Slavery and the United States Constitution; William Cohen, "Thomas Jefferson and the Problem of Slavery," Journal of American History, 56 (1969), 503-26; Merrill D. Peterson, Thomas Jefferson and the New Nation: A Biography, New York: 1970. David Brian Davis' works are classic: The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture, Ithaca: 1966, and The Problem of Slavery in the Age of Revolution, Ithaca: 1975. 52 William W. Freehling, op. cit., p. 83. Thomas Hutchinson, the most famous loyalist in exile, wrote in his anti-Declaration pamphlet of November, 1776, his mystification as to the unalienable character of life and liberty if more than a hundred thousand Africans were denied those rights. Cf. Bailyn, The Ordeal. .. , p. 358. 28 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN forward to its ultimate strangulation. We Northerners conveniently forget that fourteen percent of New York's population at the outbreak of the war were slaves. And though the battle was carried on by Edward Coles, the friend of both Madison and Jefferson, Jefferson's initiatives are recognized in his drafting of the anti-slavery ordinance of 1784, his message to Congress on December 2, 1806, on the eve of the deferred abolition of the slave trade, and in public and privately expressed opinions on the evil of slavery as an institution. Jefferson and his friends indeed, in Freehling' s words, left to posterity a crippled and restricted institution. l£ one believes that the American Revolution did not end in 1790, then one can see the virtue of a policy, which though too compromising by our standards, was realistically farsighted by his. James Madison (1751-1836), the great Virginia constitutionalist, reflects both the political liberalism and the pragmatism of the Founding Fathers. 53 He was particularly impressed by Hume's anti-faction Ideas of a Perfect Commonwealth (175'2). As a follower of Jefferson, the Father of the Constitution was a longtime advocate of religious and political freedom, a foe of Hamilton and the conservatives of the Washington administration, yet pragmatist enough like Jefferson to accept a constitution that more recent scholarship has revealed to be a basically conservative document. Herbert W. Schneider sees the period as a time when philosophical thinking and social action were most intimately joined. America " gathered into action the reflections and passions of several generations of European thinkers, and it also led the way toward the bold political, religious, and moral experiments in which the whole world has ever since participated." 54 Not only were Adams, Franklin, Jefferson and Madison not 53 Cf. Adrienne Koch, Jefferson and Madison, the Great Collaboratiou, New York: 1950. 54 Herbert W. Schneider, A History of American Philosophy, New York: 1963, p. 35. The coordination factor is illustrated by John Adams' arresting figure of thirteen clocks striking together. PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 29 philosophic system builders, but even their great themes of religious liberty, natural rights, equality before law, freedom of thought and expression were shortly to be assailed, and often repudiated. Democratic thought in the colonies was neither unanimous nor continuous after 1776, as has been noted. And a change was taking place in the religious formulations of the period that would influence its philosophical assumptions. It was the dissenters' progressive movement from a vertical supernaturalist theology to a deistic horizontalist humanitarian ethic. In short, much more was involved in the evolving mentality than the rejection of the mediatorial office of the priesthood, the sacramental system and Anglican formalism. THE SUMMING UP In the final analysis, what were the philosophical presuppositions of the Founding Fathers? The author has perhaps reprehensibly minimized the classical influence that Richard M. Gummere has so ably described. But despite the erudite character of the late Jefferson-Adams correspondence, it is questionable that either Jefferson or Adams ever really understood Plato; nor is it probable that many American farmers could read Homer. 55 Certainly themes in Aristotle, Cicero, and Polybius are discernible in the political patterns for the new republic, and the classical tradition did figure in the education of Adams, Jefferson, and Madison; but it is difficult to see these influences as proximate or significantly specific. The first and foremost philosophical influence (although this influence is perhaps more indirect than formerly thought) would still be John Locke-and the political and empirical synthesis of Locke, Bacon, and Newton. Enlightenment rationalism with its progressivist social theory 55 Richard M. Gummere, The American Colonial Mind and the Classical, Tradition: Essays in Comparative Culture: Cambridge: 1963. The correspondence, despite the modesty of the writers, is much more than " senectutal loquacity" or "senile Garrulity." 30 ROBERT PAUL MOHAN and libertarian religious and political ideas would seem to be a strong second influence. Next would be the tradition of English common law, with its repudiation of tyranny, its advocacy of inteUectual and religious freedom and representative government. Fourth, the tradition of dissent through correspondence, tract, pamphlet, newspaper, and pulpit of the English Commonwealthmen of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries is a much neglected source of colonial theory. As Jack P. Greene has observed, these elements of dissent were long a part of colonial political tradition before the outbreak of overt hostilities. J. G. A. Pocock would go as far back as Florentine Renaissance humanism to see the origins of these eighteenth century eruptions. Giambattista Vico once suggested that one of the greatest faults of the historian was what he called the conceit of the learned, that is, the habit of assuming that the people about whom one is writing were as reflective as the historian himself, whereas the world-historical individuals were among the least academically minded. Thus it is that when the above sources are cited, it is with the realization that much of the inspiration for the Revolution was not the result of a priori philosophical principles as much as an ad hoc ideology based primarily on pragmatic considerations. Genuine equality would appear to be largely a myth both before, during, and after the Revolution, despite the Declaration of Independence. It is not strongly affirmed by the otherwise liberal Commonwealth (at least before the time of Price), nor is it satisfactorily contained in the American Constitution which was their memorial. Their anti-Catholicism can be partially explained, not by an endemic narrowness of mind, but by the involved character of Stuart politics and religion. Colonial ideological unanimity is another myth. Tory sentiment was not only strong, as the studies of Maier, Bailyn, Nelson, and Norton remind us, but the supposed tyranny of PHILOSOPHICAL PRE-SUPPOSITIONS OF FOUNDING FATHERS 31 Britain was not as widely felt in the scattered colonies as traditionally represented; and the Revolution was felt to be the embodiment rather than the rejection of English constitutional government. Perhaps the colonies were far removed from the profound tranquillity that General Gage spoke of in 1772, but they were hardly seething with rebellion. The principal works influencing the colonists, directly or indirectly, would seem to be Algernon Sidney's Discourses (c. 1683), Cato's Letters of Gordon and Trenchard (17201723), Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) and Second Treatise of Government (c. 1680), and Paine's Common Sense (1791-1792). Yet one can readily admit that thousands of colonists never heard of the above works of their authors. Staughton Lynd once noted that observations about national character are usually extrapolated from the documents of the articulate wealthy. They tend to reflect a point of view and a valuable one, but one realizes that a Carolina farmer was probably more interested in crops than in constitutions. Our gratitude to the Founding Fathers needs neither apotheosis nor cynical reappraisal. Our Founding Fathers could be as choleric as Adams, as inconsistent as Jefferson, as promiscuous as Franklin. We need not be shocked that they often exhibit the less admirable qualities of us, their descendants; they also exhibited that idealism and tough practicality that add up to greatness. The men and the hour met, and it is not their fault if we choose to interpret their heritage as events to be commemorated rather than work to be finished. RoBERT Catholic University of America Washington, D. C. PAUL MoHAN TALK OF GOD AND THE DOCTRINE OF ANALOGY If then we take the divine attributes one by one and and ask whether each of them is to be found in God, we must reply that it is not there, at least as such and as a distinct reality, and since we can in no way conceive an essence which is nothing but an act of existing, we cannot in any way conceive what God is, even with the help of such attributes. E. Gilson The world requires as its cause a being totally transcending it in every respect; but how can we even affirm the existence of such a being, if our experience of the world gives us no words by which to define him? E. L. Mascall I T HE CLASSICAL DOCTRINE of analogy has been used to try to show how terms involved in God-talk have an appropriate meaning even if the key statements involving God-talk are not verifiable even in principle. Someone who 1) accepted the verifiability principle as a criterion for what is to count as factually meaningful and Q) who took the intent of the normal use of most indicative God-talk sentences to be to make factual statements, would assert that for ' God loves His creatures ' to be properly meaningful, we must show what implications for our experience would or at least in principle could count for or against its truth. Some defenders of the doctrine of analogy present an alternative account of the meaning of such utterances, an account, which, if correct, would, for much of God-talk at least, supply an answer to the challenge that non-anthropomorphic God-talk is devoid of factual significance. I shall consider the merits of such views. ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 33 Father F. Copleston and Professor James F. Ross provide us with distinguished contemporary statements of such a position. 1 They both claim that where we are speaking of a transcendent and infinite being-the object of a religiously adequate Godtalk-the terms predicated of this being must be used analogically if they are to have any meaning at all. We need such an analogical account to escape the following dilemma. If, on the one hand, the terms are used with the same meaning, say in respect to God and to man, then God becomes an anthropomorphic being. That is to say, if God's intelligence or love is like man's intelligence or love, then God becomes simply a kind of superman, a being that is a part of nature, and not an infinite, non-spatio-temporal being, transcendent to the world. Yet, on the other hand, if ' intelligence ' and ' love ' are said to have a completely different sense when applied to God, they lose all meaning for us. The meaning-content of terms such as ' intelligence ' and ' loving ' is determined by our experience of human beings, by our experience of human intelligence and love, "and if they are used in an entirely and completely different sense when predicated of God, they can have no meaning for us when they are used in this way." 2 'Intelligence' as applied to dogs and men could have (I don't say it does have) a completely different sense and still 'intelligence' could be intelligibly predicated of a dog's behaviour as well as a man's because we could ostensively teach how we 1 F. C. Copleston, Contemporary Philosophy (London: Burns and Oates, 1956) and James F. Ross, "Analogy as a Rule of Meaning for Religious Language," International Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. I (1961), pp. 468-502. In his later "A New Theory of Analogy," in Logical Analysis and Contemporary Theism, ed. by John Donnelly (New York: Fordham University Press, 1972), Ross uses work in structural linguistics to give the outline of a new theory of analogy which he believes to be compatible with the classical theory. His account there (where it applies to analogy of proper proportionality) is vulnerable to most of the criticisms I level at his earlier and more detailed account. I shall concentrate my discussion most extensively on his earlier and more detailed account, but I shall in the final section say something which applies particularly to the later account. 2 Copleston, op. cit., p. 93. 34 KAI NIELSEN used the term. But the case is different with God for we have not observed and cannot observe God-anything that could be observed, ipso facto, would not be God. 8 Since this is so we cannot discover by ostensive definition or ostensive teaching what it means to say God has intelligence or is loving. Thus if' intelligence' and 'love' have a completely different meaning when applied to God, we can have no understanding at all of these predicates. If such key utterances as ' God loves human beings ' or 'God's intelligence is manifest in his creation' are to have meaning, then 'love' and 'intelligence' must be used analogically: "that is to say, a term which is predicated of God and finite things must, when it is predicated of God, be used in a sense which is neither precisely the same as nor completely different from the sense in which it is predicated of finite things." 4 Terms like ' love ' and ' intelligence ' must be used in a " sense which is similar and dissimilar at the same time to the sense in which it is used when predicated of finite things." " To put the matter in a slightly different way. For Aquinas and for other late medieval writers, who, as thoroughly as most contemporary writers, rejected any claim that there could be a logically necessary being or a purely conceptual identification of God, the problem of meaning was an acute one. 6 Our ordinary language with its pervasive empirical anchorage was accepted by these thinkers as being applicable to God. We must start from the language of common experience if we are to have any understanding of anything at all. But, as Ross puts it, Aquinas' problem then was this: How could he show that this language (all of the terms, expressions and employments of which are learned from human experience) can be applied, without such equivocation as would render invalid all argument, to God, an entity which is so different from the • Ibid., p. 91. • Ibid., p. 94. 5 Ibid. 6 See here Terence Penelhum, Religion and Rationality House, 1971), pp. 77-87, and 365-79. (New York: Random ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 85 objects of experience as to be ' inexperience-able ' in any of the ways common to ordinary human experience. 7 It is claimed that it is just here-if our God-talk is to be shown to have an intelligible factual content-that we must develop a viable theory of analogical predication. Again, as Ross puts it, in a more technical rendering of Copleston's point: If the predicate terms in G-statements (statements with 'God' or a synonym as the subject) are totally equivocal with respect to the occurrences of the same predicate terms in E-statements (with any object of ordinary, direct or indirect experience as subject), then all arguments with an E-statement in the premises and a G-statement as the conclusion will be invalid, committing the fallacy of equivocation; and all G-statements will be meaningless because none of the human experience will count either as evidence for or as explications of those statements. 8 But if our common terms here have a univocal meaning, we (Ross agrees with Copleston) fall into a gross anthropomorphism in which our statements about such an anthropomorphic deity are certainly literal enough but false or, as Copleston puts it, at least they commit their user to a concept of God that no one (presumably no ' contemporary man ') " would be seriously concerned to argue" for. 9 As Ross puts it" if the G-statement predicates are univocal with a representative set of instances of those predicates in E-statements, then our statements about God will be, in most cases, obviously false and, in the remainder, misleading." 10 We are back with the old problem: God-talk seems to be either without a proper meaning or, where it has an evident factual content, our fir.st-order God-statements are simply false and embody religious concepts which are plainly religiously inadequate. 11 The analogy theory on such conRoss, op. cit., p. 470. •Ibid., pp. 487-88. 9 Copleston, op. cit., p. 89. 10 Ross, op. cit., p. 498. 11 See here my " On Fixing the Reference Range of 'God'," Religious Studies, Vol. II (October, 1966), Contemporary Critiques of Religion (London: Mac7 86 KAI NIELSEN temporary readings as Copleston's and Ross's is designed to bail us out here. II I shall begin by examining Copleston's account, for it is relatively straightforward and yet it attempts, taking into account the analytical or linguistic turn in philosophy, to break new ground. I shall then in section III examine Ross's "Analogy as a Rule of Meaning for Religious Language." Ross's essay is a complicated piece, full of stipulative definitions and a formidable jargon, but it does, though in an unnecessarily cumbersome way, attempt to come to grips with these crucial problems of meaning. I shall not examine E. L. Mascall's Existence and Analogy for two reasons: (1) it has already been extensively criticized and (2) , as Ross points out, it does not really come to grips with the problems of meaning, for it treats analogy as a theory of inference rather than as a theory purporting to .show how God-talk can have factual intelligibility. 12 To say (1) 'God is intelligent,' (2) 'God made men out of nothing,' and (8) ' God loves all human beings' is, according to Copleston, to use-when (1), (2) and or (8) are vehicles for religiously adequate assertions-'intelligent,' 'made,' and 'loves' analogically. As we have noted, where our God-talk is not grossly anthropomorphic, all predications of God must be analogical. Where we have analogical predication as in (4) 'James is intelligent,' and (5) 'Fido is intelligent,' we must say that the terms predicated of the different subjects, e.g. James and Fido, are used in a sense which is neither precisely the .same nor completely different. Yet this general remark, Macmillan Ltd., 1972). For millan Ltd., 1971) and Scepticism (London: F. C. Copleston's account of this situation see his "Man, Transcendence and the Absence of God," Thought, Vol. XLIII (1968), pp. 24-38, "The Special Features of Contemporary Atheism," Twentieth Century: An Australian Quarterly Review, Vol. 25 (Spring, 1970), pp. 5-15 and his reviews of Axel Hagerstrom's Philosophy and Religion and Richard Robinson's An Atheist's Values in the Heythrop Journal, Vol. 7 (1966) and Vol. 5 (1964), respectively. 12 Ross, op. cit., p. 469. ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 37 Copleston stresses, tells us very little. Moreover, to be told that ' intelligent ' is used analogically when applied to God is not yet to be told what meaning it does have or even how to determine what meaning it has. 13 To say that 'intelligent' in (5) is used analogously to the way it is used in (4) is most certainly not to tell us how it is used. We still do not know what it means to say that Fido is intelligent. What behaviour traits are we referring to? What would Fido have to do not to be regarded as intelligent? As we have indicated with Fido and his canine brethren, we can resort to ostensive definition but with God no such thing is possible. How then do we know how 'intelligence ' is used when applied to God? The negative way, though it is a natural way to proceed, will not do with (6), 'God is intelligent,' for we cannot intelligibly go on saying that God's intelligence is not like this or like that, if we cannot .say what God's intelligence is. Every time I say that God's intelligence is unlike a characteristic of human intelligence, I whittle away more of its meaning. To intelligibly apply ' intelligence ' to God I must make, or be able to make, some positive affirmation such as ' God is intelligent in an infinitely higher sense than human beings are.' But this, Cople.ston is well aware, is still to say very little. Moreover, when asked to give " a positive account of this higher sense," I find myself, full circle, back to the way of negation. Furthermore, if I continue in the affirmative way I end in anthropomorphism.14 A successful theory of analogical predication must combine those methods without falling into the pitfalls of either. As Copleston puts it, "to avoid anthropomorphism of a gross sort the mind takes the way of negation, departing from its starting point, namely human intelligence, while to avoid agnosticism it returns to its starting-point." 15 We try here, in oscillating back and forth between anthropomorphism Copleston, Contemporary Philosophy, p. 94. Copleston, Contemporary Philosophy, pp. 94-95. See also his "Man, Transcendence and the Absence of God," Thought, Vol. XLIII (1968), pp. 24-38. 15 Copleston, Contemporary Philosophy, pp. 96-97. 13 14 38 KAI NIELSEN and agnosticism, in our predications concerning God, to hold together similarity and dissimilarity at the same time. 16 This is indeed perplexing, but we must not forget that we are speaking, or trying to speak, of a mysterious being transcendent to the universe. We have, Copleston tells us, no direct apprehension of God.17 God transcends our experience and thus He " cannot be positively and adequately described." This, he believes, should not lead to a rejection of God-talk as incoherent but simply to a recognition that our understanding of God-who after all is mysterious-is of necessity inadequate. Without the possibility of an adequate understanding of God, we must use analogy to have any understanding of God at all. This is simply one of the features " of our understanding of descriptive statements about God." 18 But, Copleston continues, that our concept of God is imperfect and can never be thoroughly purified of anthropomorphism does not mean that the very idea or concept of God is anthropomorphic; it only means that what Copleston calls the "subjective meaning" of ' God is intelligent ' or ' God loves his creation ' is inadequate and in part anthropomorphic. It does not mean that the objective meaning of these statements is inadequate. Copleston's use of that tricky word 'meaning' is rather unusual. By ' subjective meaning' he means " the meaning-content which the term has or can have for the human mind." 19 By 'objective meaning' he means "that which is actually referred to by the term in question (that is, the objective reality referred to ) . . ." 20 In the case of such key God-statements what is objectively referred to isn't at all anthropomorphic, but what our subjective meaning signifies is. It is this meaning that is inadequate, but not ' necessarily false.' The distinction Copleston draws between 'subjective meanIbid., p. 97. Ibid., pp. 96-97. 1 • Ibid., p. 97. 1 • Ibid., p. 96. 20 Ibid. 1• 17 ANALOGY TALK OF GOD-A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 39 ing ' and ' objective meaning ' most certainly seems to be crucial in his attempt to rehabilitate the appeal to analogy, but it unfortunately is not a coherent claim. We might intelligibly speak of the distinction between ' subjective meaning ' and ' objective meaning,' where the former referred to the meaning-content of a term as used on a given occasion or set of occasions by an individual or some group of people. This would make a nonvacuous contrast with 'objective meaning, ' since the latter could be taken to refer to the meaning-content the terms would have if people were fully informed and took to heart the implications of the terms in question. But for Copleston ' subjective meaning' includes any meaning-content the term or terms" can have for the human mind," the 'objective meaning' of terms predicated of God is said to transcend our experience. 21 "It cannot be positively and adequately described." 22 But >if the ' can ' and ' cannot ' here have a logical force, viz. if it is logically impossible to adequately grasp the objective meaning of these terms or even if it is some sort of ' ontological impossibility,' then there is no genuine contrast between 'objective meaning' and 'subjective meaning.' We can have no understanding of this 'objective meaning;' we can have no understanding of whether the ' subjective meaning ' adequately or inadequately characterizes that 'objective reality' that the objective meaning adequately signifies. Any understanding at all of such matters that we humans can have-no matter how purified of anthropomorphic elements-is still subjective; the meaning we apply to predications of God is still necessarily and irredeemably ' subjective meaning.' Having no grasp of the ' objective meaning,' we can have no idea at all of whether our attempts to purify our ' subjective meaning ' succeed or fail. Indeed ' purifying ' actually has no use here, for we cannot know what would count as ' purifying' the meaning of a term unless we had some grasp of the standard of perfection aimed at. How, in short, does subjective meaning A fall shorter of 21 2• Jbid. Ibid., p. 97. 40 KAI NIELSEN perfection than subjective meaning B? To know this we must have some understanding of the meaning-content of that which they fall short of, but if we have such a knowledge, then by definition it will not involve 'objective meaning' but ' subjective meaning.' But again we do not know and cannot know how this stands in relation to A and B. There is a further quite unrelated difficulty in Copleston's account. In trying to avoid agnosticism about our predications of God we try to " hold together similarity and dissimilarity at the same time.'' 23 To be an analogical predication of God and man, the terms in question must be used in a sense which is neither precisely the same nor completely different. But this characterization is ambiguous. Taken in one way it makes analogy the same as univocity; taken in another it makes analogy the same as equivocity. If, on the one hand, 'James is intelligent' and' God is intelligent' have even one similarity, then it is the case (or so at least it would seem) that one property (characteristic) of intelligence when referred to man and God is the same. But this means (or so at least it would seem) that the term by which this property (characteristic) is signified is a univocal predication of man and God and that, after all, not all God-predicates are analogical. If this is true, then analogical predication is neither essential nor complete in our talk about God. Indeed even for analogical predications to be possible, there must be some univocal predications as well. Suppose, on the other hand, the 'not precisely the same ' rules out their having any common property or relation, then there can be no similarity since we cannot assert in what respect they are similar. If this is so, analogical predication really becomes the use of equivocal terms. Yet there seems at least to be no other way of intelligibly taking the terms being used so that in the different contexts they are used in a way which is neither precisely the same nor completely different. Thus Copleston has not been able to give us an intelligible account 2• Ibid. ANALOGY TALK OF GOD-A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 41 of analogical predication that would distinguish it from a univocal or equivocal use of predicates when applied to God and the world. There is a further problem that Copleston .should face which is directly related to the falsification issue. l£ his claim that' intelligent' (for example) is in a definite sense similar, when used of both God and man, then (given the correctness of the above argument) in both employments of' intelligent' the term must signify at lea.st one common property or, if you will, a relation. But then, aside from being committed to claiming-inconsistently with his general thesis about analogical predication-that at least one predication of God is univocal, he also in effect commits himself to treating ' God is intelligent ' as a statement which can, at lea.st in principle, be confirmed or disconfirmed, for if to be intelligent is to have property X and if property X is never manifested by God or if God does something inconsistent with ascribing X to Him, then we have grounds-though surely nothing like conclusive grounds-for denying that God is intelligent and if He does manifest X we have grounds for asserting that 'God is intelligent' is true. We have (if this is so) shown how such God-talk is verifiable by showing how evidence is relevant to the truth or falsity of 'God is intelligent.' The same, of course, applies to ' God loves all human beings.' But now these theological-metaphysical statements become what Copleston elsewhere has denied that they can be if they are to count as metaphysical .statements, namely empirical assertions. 24 This unintended implication of his account of analogical predication is surely unwelcome, for Copleston is committed to the view that such God-talk does not at central points consist ••This is very evident in his debate with A. J. Ayer. See A. J. Ayer and F. C. Copleston, "Logical Positivism: A Debate," in A Modern Introduction to ed. by A. Pap and P. Edwards edition, New York: Macmillan, 1967). In a later essay "Man, Transcendence and the Absence of God," Thought, Vol. XLIII (1968), Copleston contends that while believers and non-believers have the same expectations in regard to events in the world, their interpretations of the world are different. (See p. 37 of his text.) 42 KAI NIELSEN in statements of empirical fact open to the usual precedures of confirmation and disconfirmation. Indeed Copleston seems anxious to meet, in some way, Flew's challenge about falsifiability. God-statements are taken by him to be factual statements, but they are alleged to be ' factual metaphysical statements.' Of these Copleston remarks: " I can hardly be said to know what is meant by a factual statement unless I am able to recognize that something at least is not asserted " and " unless I am able to recognize that something is excluded I do not know what is asserted." 25 But in his actual arguments concerning this, Copleston does not give us straightforward factual statements which could be used to confirm or disconfirm our theological statements. Rather, reasoning like what has been called a theological non-naturalist, his statements, used in confirmation and disconfirmation, hav:e the same equivocal and controversial logical status as the statements to be confirmed or disconfirmed. He never breaks out of the religious network of statements; that is to say, in Ross's terminology, he gives us no E-statements to confirm his A-statements and so does not in reality meet Flew's challenge or give our A-statements their needed empirical anchorage. That this is so can be seen from Copleston' s own analysis of 'God is intelligent' and' God loves all human beings.' He asks us, in asking for the meaning of these statements, to consider why a person would make such statements. Consider ' God is intelligent.' A man who has the idea of an ' existentially dependent world ' naturally ascribes the order or system in the world to a creator. My' subjective meaning '-the only meaning I can have for' God is intelligent,' on Copleston's accountis ' There is a creator of the world who orders the world.' But if one is puzzled over what (if anything) it could mean to assert or deny that God is intelligent, one is going to be equally puzzled about the statement, given as the' subjective meaning• or part of the' subjective meaning' of that statement. We •• Copll)ston, Contemporary Philosophy, p. 99, ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 43 do not have a .statement that is plainly an empirical statement to give empirical anchorage to our G-Statement. The same applies to ' God loves all human beings.' 26 Copleston remarks 'that if this statement or rather putative statement " is compatible with all other statements that one can mention and does not exclude even one of them," then it is devoid of factual significance. But it appears at least that it is so compatible, for no matter how many millions are put in the gas chambers, it is still said by the faithful that God loves his children. No matter what wars, plagues, sufferings of little children are brought up a la Dostoevski, they are still taken, by the faithful, to be compatible with the truth of the .statement ' God loves all human beings.' Given such linguistic behaviour, one is tempted to think that nothing is excluded in the statement and thus it appears to be devoid of factual content. But, Copleson avers, this impression is mistaken. Something is incompatible with it, only we have been looking for that something in the wrong direction, namely in the experiences of men. But the Christian theologian knows a factual statement with which it is incompatible, namely' God wills the eternal damnation and misery of all human beings.' The truth of ' God loves all men ' is confirmed by ' God offers all men through Christ the grace to attain eternal salvation.' Knowing this latter statement to be true, we are justified in asserting ' God loves all men.' But here again Copleston is lifting himself up by his own bootstraps, for he is verifying religious statements by appealing to further religious statements without any of them getting the necessary empirical anchorage. The verifying statements are as problematic as the statements they are supposed to verify. In short, Flew's challenge concerning falsifiability is not met, for we have not been given any empirically identifiable state of affairs that is excluded by these statements. We do not have the anchorage in experience that Copleston so stresses as necessary for an understanding of God-talk. •• Ibid., p. 100. 44 KAI NIELSEN In short, Copleston has not provided us with an answer to Flew's challenge: he has not shown us how experiential statements either verify or falsify' God loves all mankind' or' God is intelligent ' or any G-statement at all and he has not given an intelligible account of analogy that would enable us to overcome the anthropomorphism of univocal predication or the impossibility of understanding what is meant by the predicates in God-talk if they are used equivocally when applied to God and the world. He has not shown us how it is that ' we see through a glass darkly,' for given Copleston's approach to the incomprehensible Godhead, we can never know whether, by self-consciously and sensitively using our analogical concepts, we purify or fail to purify our understanding of God, because we can have no idea at all of the ' objective meaning' of such a concept. III Ross tries to state in contemporary terms what he takes to be the vital heart of Aquinas' theory of analogical predication. But while his .statement is far more complicated than Copleston's, it is no more successful. As has frequently been pointed out, ' analogy ' is itself au analogical term, that is to say, it has several meanings which are not unrelated: that is, they are partly similar and partly different. Moreover, 'analogy' is a term of art for the scholastics. In speaking of analogy we speak of analogy of attribution, metaphor and analogy of proper proportionality. But, as Ross and others have argued, it is analogy of proper proportionality that is most crucial in considering the analogical relation between terms predicated of God and terms predicated of man and other' contingent natures.' It is then to analogy of proper proportionality that we shall tum. Ross escapes some of Copleston's confusions by arguing that " analogy of proper proportionality is the general form of language about God " and that it is improper to call this language inadequate " for no other language is possible given the Christian assumption that God is transcendent and different in kind ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 45 from all other things." 27 ' God,' on this account, is " a shorthand for the definite description which would result from a combination of all the properties shown to be attributable to one unique being with some (psychologically prior) property such as' First Cause' or' Creator.'" 28 But the terms signifying these properties are all " analogous by proper proportionality with respect to psychologically prior instances of the same terms in ordinary experience describing statements." 29 In order to make sense of religious discourse, in order to explain how we have any understanding of the concept of God at all, we must give an intelligible account of analogy of proper proportionality and then show how it applies to God-talk. What then are we talking about when we speak of analogy of proper proportionality? A proportion is the equality of two ratios, i.e. a is to b as c is to d. Ross gives several paradigms the least unfortunate of which is (a) Fido caused the barking and (b) Plato caused the murderous act. 30 Here 'caused' is supposed to be such an analogical term. And in (a) and (b) we have an analogy of proper proportionality. Fido's causing the barking is as Plato's causing the murderous act. Where we have analogy of proper proportionality, we have statements of the form: 1. (a) A is (or has) T (b) B is (or has) T or: Where ' T ' is a term, namely a word capable of naming or applying to a thing or things, A and B are things, and x and y are properties, actions or events. No. I above, Ross argues, is reducible to no. 2. We are asked initially to assume that in our paradigm op. cit., p. 501-02. Ibid., p. 500. •• Ibid., p. 501. " 0 Ibid., p. 487. 27 Ross, 2• 46 KAI NIELSEN 'caused' is not being used univocally. Later Ross will attempt to show that this assumption is justified. Secondly, to have such an analogy there must be at least two instances of the property signified by' T.' As Ross puts it, "the second condition states, briefly, that the two things denoted by the term 'T' must have the property signified by' T' and that the first condition must still be preserved: that the term is equivocal." 31 There is, as Ross recognizes, quite obviously a problem here. If ' T ' is equivocal, the properties would not be the same. But if the term' T' in its instances signified the same property, has the same meaning as or is equivalent in its instances, then, in its instances, it has the same intention (connotation). But if this is so, then either the term is, after all, univocal or the second condition is unsatisfiable. 32 The first and second characteristics of such analogical terms appear at least to clash and this casts doubt on the coherence of analogy by proper proportionality. To make sense out of this conception of analogy, we must show how both characteristics of this type of analogy are jointly satisfiable. This is exactly what Aquinas, Ross tells us, sets out to do and in Ross's opinion he is successful. To do this Aquinas must show how a term can be " univocal in signification ... while being equivocal in not conforming to the rule for univocity of intention.'' 33 That is in (a) 'Fido caused the barking ' and (b) ' Plato caused the murderous act ' we must show how 'caused' in both cases signifies the same property, yet does not have exactly the same intention: does not in each case have the same conjunction of terms applicable to that to which each instance of 'caused' is applicable. There must be some term which is applicable to that to which 'caused' in (a) is applicable which is not applicable to that to which ' caused ' in (b) is applicable and yet ' caused ' in both occurrences must still signify the same property or set of properties. Bl Ibid. ""Ibid. ••Ibid., p. 487. ANALOGY TALK OF GOD-A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 47 We must examine whether such a notion makes sense. It most certainly appears to be nonsensical. But, as Ross argues, appearances are not to be trusted here. To understand how this might be done, we must attend to a distinction Aquinas makes and Ross stresses between the res signifi0ata and the modus signific,andi of a term. A necessary condition for having an analogy of proper proportionality is to have a ratio in which the modus signific,andi differs and the res signifi0ata is the same. In such a situation we have the requisite .similarity in difference. We have a situation in which we have a univocal signification together with an equivocal intention of the terms in question. To make anything of this we must understand Aquinas' distinctions here. The intention of a term specifies not only the property or properties signified by the term but the way it is signified. The former is the res signific,ata of the term and the latter-the way it is signified-is the modus signifi0andi of the term. 84 In considering our paradigms (a) and (b), if we take our allegedly analogical term ' caused,' we can speak of two instances of the term ' caused ' differing in their modus signifi0andi in the sense that ' caused' refers to different kinds of causality. (Ross also works out the same point for' knowledge.') The intention of 'caused' is proportionally the same in (a) and (b) "but the mode in which the property is possessed makes entirely different the kinds of action which can be performed." 85 We have the foundation of analogy of proper proportionality in " the unequal and different in kind participation of different natures in the same property according to differing modes of being determined by their nature.'' 86 The terms ' knowing ' and ' causality ' are indeed univocal or equivocal depending on their use in sentences. In (a) and (b) ' caused ' is not uni vocal even though we may form a metalanguage term ' caused ' or ' causality ' which is neutral with •• Ibid., p. 488. 36 Ibid., p. 489. 36 Ibid., p. 490. 48 KAI NIELSEN respect to all the object-language senses of 'caused.' The object-language senses of 'caused' are themselves equivocal. Given that the meta-language term' caused' is about language and is neutral in the respect mentioned, then it need not be univocal with respect to any object-language sense of 'caused.' 37 In the different kinds of causality, distinguishable in the different object-language uses of 'caused,' we have the basis for the difference (the analogues are partly different) and in the meta-language use of the term 'caused' we have the basis for similarity (the analogues are partly similar). The neutral sense of ' caused ' is not on the same level as the different kinds of causality exhibited, in the different uses that ' caused ' has in different .sentences in the object-language. The former is a meta-linguistic notion which includes the other uses and signies them all equally and alternatively. 88 It, as a meta-linguistic term, is a predicate in sentences about predicates of sentences. This meta-linguistic use of the term is univocal. But this does not make the object-language terms univocal. They are, in contrast, equivocal. It is here that we have an intelligible rationale for analogy of proper proportionality. There is, however, a fundamental confusion in Ross's argument. Where 'knowing' or' caused' (the analogous predicate in question) is a predicate about predicates, where it is a metalinguistic term, it is no longer ' knowing' we are talking about but '"knowing".' Where we are actually talking about knowing or causing something-the object-language terms-we are not talking about linguistic expressions but about their meaning or use in object-language sentences. But where we are talking about the expression ' knowing ' or ' causing ' we are talking about language. ' She is bald ' makes sense; ' She has three letters does not.' ' " She " is bald ' is nonsense while ' " She " has three letters ' is not. 'Knowledge is difficult to obtain and Jane caused him to give up the quest' make sense but ' Knowledge has nine letters and caused has six letters ' is Ibid. ••Ibid., p. 491. 37 ANALOGY TALK OF GOD-A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 49 nonsense. Again'" Knowledge" is difficult to obtain and Jane "caused" him to give up the quest ' is nonsense while ' "Knowledge " has nine letters and " caused " has six letters ' is an intelligible meta-linguistic sentence. Ross thinks that he has found a univocal sense of 'knowledge' and' caused' and a equivocal sense of 'knowledge' and ' caused ' and that he has thus escaped a crucial difficulty about analogy of proper proportionality. But he has not at all, for he is not really talking about the same verbal symbol, for, even on his own definition, we can only say that two marks or sounds are the same verbal symbol when they have the" same recognizable pattern." But ' knowledge ' and ' " knowledge " ' are clearly distinct. It is apparent we do not have the same verbal symbol or the same expression, so we have no basis for univocity and thus none for analogy of proper proportionality. Let us assume, however, that somehow this difficulty has been surmounted. Being analogous is a semantical property of a term and-someone might possibly argue-I have mistakenly treated it as if it were a syntactical property. This does not seem at all plausible to me, but let us assume that my criticism can thus be put aside or that it can somehow be gone around. (After all, Ross in his later "A New Theory of Analogy " has formulated a doctrine of analogy which is not vulnerable on this score.) Still, even with these assumptions granted, is everything in order with Ross's account? When we apply this analysis to the concept of God, Ross's position gives rise to exactly the same difficulty as Copleston's. In the res significata, if analogous terms signify a common property or set of properties, as they do, then the terms specifying that property or set of properties will be univocal and thus some univocal predications of God are possible. As Ross shows, if there is to be an intelligible account of analogical predication, the analogical terms have, through their res significata, a property or set of properties in common. Thus there must be some univocal predication possible concerning God if there is to be any analogical predication at all. But the crucial point 50 KAI NIELSEN of Aquinas and the N eo-Thomists is that all predications of God are analogous. The fact that they are used in different modes or in different contexts or with differing intentions will not alter the fact that, since they have a common term signifying (standing for) a common property, it is the case that some univocal predication is possible. The terms signifying those common properties must have been used univocally. In neither of his essays has Ross escaped this difficulty. That Ross (and, on his interpretation, Aquinas) is committed to such a position can be seen from what he says about (c) 'Fido knows his dog house' and (d) 'Plato knows philosophy.' 'Knows' in (c) and (d) is supposed to be used analogously. But if we accept Aquinas' partial definition of 'knowing,' we have accepted a generic common feature of knowing, a property that is common to and distinctive of all knowing. This feature is, according to Aquinas, "the possession of the form of another as belonging to another." 39 This is indeed but a partial and very obscure definition; to fill out his definition Aquinas adds to the above quotation " according to one's natural mode of possession." This last qualification presumably gives us the difference which keeps the predication from actually being univocal. But it remains the case that, on the assumption (questionable in itself) that Aquinas' account of knowing is intelligible, it is true that on all uses of 'knowing' there is a property that remains common to and distinctive of all these uses. That is to say, we could construct a predicate signifying the res mgnificata of ' knowing ' that would be predicated of all cases of knowing. This would be a univocal predication. Exactly the same thing would be true of the res mgnificata of 'God', if the predicates of 'God' are to meet Ross's conditions for analogical predication. But to meet these conditions they must violate another supposed characteristic of predications of ' God,' namely that all such predications be analogical. •• Jbid, ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 51 In short, for there to be analogical predication of a subject ·term some univocal predications must be possible. Yet Aquinas and the Neo-Thomists will not allow that there can be any univocal predications of ' God ' ; but then it is impossible for there to be any analogical predications either. As a kind of postscript to this argument, it should be noted that Ross's account here clashes radically with Yves Simon'<:i account of analogical predication. Ross is committed to the claim that in analogical predication the res significata picks out generic features common to all instances of a given analogical term. But Yves Simon's fundamental point is that such abstraction is impossible for analogical predication. Two important Thomistic accounts are in plain conflict with each other. Even if my above arguments are mistaken and Ross has given an intelligible account of analogical predication, it will not work for what it is really crucial for, namely for' God.' We, if it were correct, would never be in a position to understand the modus significandi of ' God.' As Aquinas, Copleston, Ross, Simon, and Thomists generally all stress, we can have no direct apprehension of God. We are limited to our own human ways of apprehending things. But the modus sign.ifioandi of predicates applied to ' God ' is supposed to be distinguished by being according to God's distinctive mode of possession. But we finite creatures can have no understanding of that, so we can have no understanding of the modus signifioandi of the predicates applied to God. When Aquinas tells us that the nature of the thing denoted by the logical subject determines the modal elements of the intention of predicates which are applied to the subject, he cannot apply this to ' God,' for no direct apprehension of God is possible and if no direct apprehension is possible-if no use has even been given to ' a direct apprehension ' of God-then no indirect apprehension is possible either. If it is replied that ' knows ' in ' Fido knows his dog house ' has the same logical features as ' love' in ' God loves all man- 52 KAI NIELSEN kind,' yet it is plainly meaningful, it simply must be pointed out, against Ross, that ' Fido knows his dog house ' does not have all these logical features. It is not the case that there is " within the intention of the terms applied to animals ... no term which specifies how the dog knows." 40 We can speak of conditioning, of memory, of seeing a familiar object, of smelling and a host of other things. If we are prepared to use ' know' with respect to animals, we can bring in these definite characteristics, for this ' mode of possession.' Let us again assume that all my previous criticisms of Ross's reconstruction of Aquinas have been in some way mistaken. Yet there are still further difficulties in his account. Aquinas is claiming that a necessary condition for two terms being analogous by proper proportionality is that they differ in their modus significandi but have the same in res significatia. But this is but a necessary condition, for the terms could still be equivocal. 41 So far we have at best explained (1) "why certain terms cannot be used of God and creatures univocally " and (2) "how a term can in two instances signify the same property and yet be equivocal.'' 42 In short, we have at best shown how the first two conditions for analogy of proper proportionality are compatible. But there is a third condition, namely that there must be a proportional similarity between what is denoted by the two putatively analogous terms. We must scrutinize this notion of 'proportional similarity.' There is a similarity in what the terms in question stand for " if they are in some respect identical but never numerically identical.'' 43 The respects, of course, must be specifiable. 'Proportion ' for Aquinas, is a synonym for ' relation.' ' Relation,' e.g.' to the left of,' is a two or more place predicate in objectlanguage sentences. By 'proportionality between A and B,' Aquinas means, according to Ross, that "there is a similarity ' 0 Ibid., p. 492. " Ibid., p. 494. '"Ibid. ••Ibid., p. 495. ANALOGY TALK OF GOD--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 53 in the proportions (or relations) of A and B." Thus there is a "proportional similarity ... between any two things, A and B, which have similar relations to some property, event, or thing." 44 Thus for' caused' in (a) 'Fido caused the barking' and (b) 'Plato caused the murderous act ' to be analogous by proper proportionality, they must have some common properties or relations. 45 Ross then significantly mentions that if we are to be able adequately to establish a doctrine of analogy by proper proportionality, we need some criterion to determine when in fact two things are proportionally similar. 46 We need in short "a criterion of similarity of relations" and this in turn means that we must be able to say in what respect they are similar and this, as Ross points out, means that they are in some respects identical, though never numerically identical.47 Recall that for Ross, as for most followers of Aquinas, 'God' is a short hand substitute "for the definite description which would result from a combination of all the properties shown to be attributable to one unique being with some 'psychologically prior ' property such as ' First Cause ' or ' Creator'." 48 This means (gives to understand) that there is at least a partial identity between God and the world. But this most certainly seems to be a denial of God's transcendence. It seems, at least, to make it impossible to say what Thomists and all orthodox Christians and Jews want very much to say, namely that God is transcendent to the world. (Note the initial quotations from Gilson and Mascall.) However, following Bochenski here, Ross .sets out a criterion for similarity of relations that might, if workable, mitigate somewhat this anthropomorphism by making it innocuous. We can say that ' Relation R is similar to relation R'' if (1) both are relations and (2) if they" have common formal properties with respect to either a formal or merely linguistic set of axioms, "Ibid. ••Ibid. •• Ibid., p. 496. "Ibid., p. 495. ••Ibid., p. 470. 54 KAI NIELSEN the latter not being explicitly formulated in ordinary language, or, they have a common property." 49 Yet, as Ross is quick to point out himself, there are plainly difficulties here. If we consider first whether there are common " formal properties, i. e. common syntactical and semantical properties," we face the difficulty that such an ideal language has not yet been worked out and that it ".supposes a more extensive formalized language than seems practicable." 50 But, it seems to me, that there is a far more crucial objection to this first alternative in setting out a criterion for similarity of relations, namely that in so talking about purely formal properties we are, in effect, talking about an ideal language or an uninterpreted calculus. To give it an interpretation so it would have .some application to reality, including the putative reality of God, we would need to be able to specify some non-formal properties. Thus, the first alternative in effect reduces to the second and to specify non-formal properties would, in the case of talk of God, require the unwanted partial identification of God and the world. Indeed, we would have a univocal predication bobbing back up at us again, for we can, as Ross puts it, have a proportional similarity only if the terms are in some respect identical. 51 Ross operates (quite properly I believe) on the assumption that if x is similar to y, then there must be some respect in which xis similar to y. But this, given his reconstructions of Aquinas' account, in effect lays the foundation for the inescapability of some univocal predications of God. But it is exactly this conclusion that he and Thomists generally wish to avoid. There is a further related difficulty in Ros.s's account similar to a difficulty we found in Copleston. His account would make a statement such as 'God loves all men' open to Flew's challenge. That is, such statements would be empirically verifiable (confirmable or disconfirmable), for it is a question of ••Ibid., pp. 496-97. " 0 Ibid., p. 497. " 1 Ibid., p. 495. ANALOGY TALK OF GOD-A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 55 empirical fact whether ' loves ' in ' Nixon loves all Americans ' and' loves' in' God loves all men' have a property in common. (That this is so, is even more evident in Ross's "A New Theory of Analogy.") But, as Thomists argue in other contexts, such God-statements are not so verifiable. 52 But, if they accept this last criterion, of similarity of relations, they must treat such God-talk as open to empirical confirmation and disconfirmation. They want it both ways but they cannot consistently have it both ways. Finally, even if we accept, as I argued we could not, common purely formal properties as an adequate criterion for similarity, we still in a way are caught by Flew's challenge, for it is a fact whether there· are or are not such formal properties. If we have no reason to say that there are, then we should say that it is probably false that ' God loves all men ' and the like are intelligible, i.e., do have their intended factual significance. At the very least, we should say that we had evidence that counted against the intelligibility of that claim. But the faithful are not at all willing to put their claims to such a test. In short, even if such a theory of analogy can be worked out for terms like 'caused' and 'knows,' it does not work for God-talk. If no other language is possible, as Ross claims, if we are to talk literally and intelligibly about God, then it must certainly appear that we cannot talk literally and intelligibly about a nonanthropomorphic God, for such an account of analogical predication is thoroughly broken-backed. IV I have not claimed that generally speaking all theories of analogy have been shown to be unsatisfactory. I do not even 52 See here M. J. Charlesworth, "Linguistic Analysis and Language About God," International Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 1 (1961), pp. 139-67, Thomas Corbishley S. J., "Theology and Falsification," The University No. 1 (1950-51), C. B. Daly, "The Knowableness of God," Philosophical Studies (Maynooth, Ireland), Vol. IX (1959), pp. 90-137. I have critically examined their views in my "God, Necessity and Falsifiability," in Traces of God in a Secular Culture, ed. by George F. McLean. (Alba House: Staten Island, New York, 1973). 56 KAI NIELSEN claim that for the conception of analogy of proper proportionality. What I have shown, if at least most of my arguments are sound, is that two distinguished and influential accounts of analogical predication have crippling defects. Perhaps some account could, or even does, escape these difficulties; perhaps there is or could be a perspicuous account of analogical predication. I do not know of one, but it is well to remain agnostic on this score. Finally, I should say something about a later and parallel effort by Ross, namely his "A New Theory of Analogy." There he deploys some of the technique of structural linguistics and appeals to some of their findings. But, I shall argue, not with the result that he has .shown how there is a formulation of the doctrine of analogy of proper proportionality that obviates the key difficulties I have found in his earlier and more extended account. In his "A New Theory of Analogy," Ross shows what I have not been concerned to deny, that analogy is a pervasive feature of natural languages, that any predicative term can be used analogously and that analogy is a crucial "part of the expansion structure of ... language." 58 Indeed it is the case that "many terms have varying meanings in different contexts and that the meanings of some pairs of the .same-terms may be regarded as being derivative either from one another (unius ad alterum) or from some ' prior ' use (or set of uses) of the same term (multorum ad unum) ... " 54 Furthermore, I agree that competent native speakers can and do recognize, in practice at least, that "there are sets of same-term-occurrences which are, taken pair by pair, equivocal but which can be ordered as meaning derivatives ... " 55 There are sets of same-term-occurrences which are in pairs equivocal which are regularity conRoss, "A New Theory of Analogy," in Logical Analysis and Contemporary Fordham University Press, 1972), p. 126. ••Ibid., p. 125. 58 Theism, ed. by John Donnellly (New York: ""Ibid. ANALOGY TALK OF GOI>--A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 57 trolled and there are pairs which are not. Ross's example of the last for ' fast ' .seems well taken. (Compare ' He ran fast,' ' He observed the fast,' ' He stood fast ' and ' He considered her fast.') The various uses of ' fast ' here vis-a-vis each other seem at least to be regularity controlled, though it is difficult to be confident about this. (Is not ' fast' in 'He considered her fast' derivative from' fast' in' He ran fast')? Now compare these uses of 'fast' with the uses of 'count' and 'calculated ' in the following: ' Children count when taught to ' and ' Computors count when programmed to ' and ' In oppressing the dissidents the use of physical force was calculated ' and in ' In building the bridge the physical force of the spring floods was calculated.' ' Count' and ' calculated ' here are equivocal when just the same term pairs are considered, but it is also the case that they differ from ' fast ' in being regularity controlled vis-a-vis each other. ' Count' in ' Computors count when programmed to ' is derivative from ' count ' in ' Children count when taught to ' in a way that the different instances of ' fast' cited above seem at least not to be derived. Similarly the first instance of ' calculated ' above is derivable from the second instance. What Ross rightly stresses is that there are such analogy regularities built into the structure of our language. People with a grasp of the language readily understand derivative uses of terms; there are, legitimatizing them, meaning regularities within the corpus of our actual discourse and in mastering our language (English, Spanish, Swedish, etc.) , we come to have an understanding of them. However, the acceptance of all this is quite compatible with making the criticisms I have made of Copleston's and Ross's accounts of analogy, for they were giving a certain reading or account of 'analogy' which would have a certain import for theology. They were not just establishing that there are analogical uses of language. My criticisms have been directed against their readings and against their attempted theological employment. 58 KAI NIELSEN In his ' new theory ' Ross uses ' count ' and ' calculated ' to exhibit how analogy of proper proportionality works and is indeed something which can quite naturally be extrapolated from semantic regularities in our natural languages. Consider the following: (1) Children count when taught to. (2) Computors count when programmed to. (3) The use of force by the police was calculated. ( 4) The force of the wind was calculated. Here, with (1) and (2) and again with (3) and (4), we have relationships which are meant to exhibit analogies of proper proportionality. In (2) 'count' is derivative from 'count' in (1) and it differs in meaning from ' count ' in (1) in exactly the ways in which 'computors' in (2) differs in semantic category from' children' in (1). That is to say, the meaning of ' count ' in (2) is derivative from its meaning in (1) and is altered " with respect to ' computors' in just the way the semantic categories of that term differ from those of ' children'." 56 It is "the difference-of-meaning by combinatorial contraction which corresponds to proportionality." 57 This enables us to understand the shift of meaning, while still carrying similarities, which sometimes obtain when there is a shift from one discourse environment to another. 58 The same considerations hold for' calculated' in (3) and (4). In (1) and (2) and in (3) and (4) both pairs of terms differ in their respective pairings in their discourse environments and this is what in modern terms could be called their differences in modus signific,andi. But in both cases there is still a sameness in res significata for each. In simpler terms (or at least in a more familiar jargon) Ross's point could be put as follows: in both pairs respectively the property (set of properties) which the term signifies is present and indeed is the same property; i.e. both times 'count' signifies the same property (set of Ibid., p. 189. Ibid. 58 Ibid. 66 57 ANALOGY TALK OF GOD-A NEGATIVE CRITIQUE 59 properties), and both time.s 'calculated' signifies the same property (set of properties), but in both cases respectively " the conditions of use of the term in two contexts ... prohibit us from making all the same inferences of each occasion." b 9 ' Calculated ' on both occasions of its use signifies the same property and 'count ' on both occasions of its use signifies the same property, but the entailments of 'calculated' and 'counts' differ, showing that in each case the property is present in each subject in a different way. However, as in his first account, there is in this very sameness in the res significata an implicit appeal to univocity. In (1) and (2) and (3) and (4) this can be seen. In spite of all the difference in discourse environment' count' in (1) and 'count' in (2) both signify a reckoning up to find a sum or total. When we assert-talking about either or both what the computors did or the children did-' There was a reckoning up to find a sum,' we can in that proposition say something which is significant and indeed sometimes even true. And there is also a predication here, but the predication ' reckoning up to find a sum here' is univocaL 00 The use of 'calculated' in (3) and (4) might seem more helpful for Ross. In (3) 'calculated' could be replaced by 'deliberate' with little, if any, change in meaning. But no such substitution could be made in (4) , yet 'calculated' in (3) is derivative from 'calculated' in (4). We move from ' computed by figures ' to ' ascertained beforehand by exact reckoning' to 'planned deliberately.' And here 'calculated' seems to have a family-resemblance rather than its being the case that there is any respect in which what they signify is similar. What, it is well to ask, is the characteristic in common 59 Terence Penelhum, op. cit., p. 81. Penelhum generally in his discussion of analogy acknowledges his indebtedness to Ross. 60 I simply use 'predication' here in the standard way, characterized by Michael Durrant as follows: "An expression that gives us a proposition about something if we attach it to another expression that identifyingly refers to something which we are making the proposition about." See Michael Durrant, The Logical Status of 'God' (London: Macmillan Ltd .• 1973), pp. Xiii-Xiv. 60 KAI NIELSEN signified by 'calculated' in (3) and (4)? In both cases we are talking about something reckoned up according to plan. But do ' reckoned up ' and ' according to plan ' signify common properties or are they themselves family-resemblance terms? Even allowing that the elusive conception of family-resemblance is well-enough fixed so as to exclude common characteristics between paired terms, both (3) and (4) would be false, if no expected result was ascertained. And it is implausible to claim that ' result was ascertained ' is so different in the two environments that there is no respect in which what they signify is similar. Moreover, as Ross acknowledges himself, where there is a similarity between two terms we must, for ' similar ' to be intelligible, be able to say in what respect they are similar. But then again we can see how univocal predication underlies analogical predication such that the very possibility of two terms being in an analogical relation of proper proportionality requires that we can make some univocal predications of what is referred to by these terms. And this brings with it the host of problems I discussed in the previous section. In sum, Ross in two essays, one detailed and utilizing some of the techniques of modern logic and one more sketchy and using some of the techniques of structura1 linguistics, has sought to articulate a sound theory of analogy which will serve as a crucial philosophical underpinning in making sense of our talk of God. I have argued that he has failed in both attempts, though in the latter he has made it quite evident that there are analogical uses of language and he has shown us something about these uses. But neither he nor Father Copleston have given us an account of analogy which will enable us to make sense of non-anthropomorphic God-talk. KAI NIELSEN University of Calgary and University of Ottawa ANALOGY AND THE MEANINGFULNESS OF LANGUAGE ABOUT GOD: A REPLY TO KAI NIELSEN I MUST SAY that I feel considerable sympathy with Professor Nielsen in his difficulties in making sense out of the Thomistic doctrine of analogy as a device for rendering language about God meaningful. In fact, for many years now I have been struck by the constantly recurring phenomenon of philosophers outside the Thomistic tradition trying to understand the doctrine of analogy as applied to God and being quite sincerely baffled in their attempts to see how it can do the job assigned to it. When this occurs so often, there is a good chance that the fault is not all on the one side. And, to be honest, I do not think Professor Nielsen gets adequate help from either Father Copleston or Professor Ross. He may not get adequate help from me either, but I would still like to try, since I consider the issue such an important one. The main reasons for the obscurity surrounding the Thomistic theory of analogy seem to be three. First, historically, St. Thomas himself, ordinarily such a systematic thinker, for some unexplained reason was never willing to pin himself down to any one consistent terminology or structural analysis of the logical form of analogy. He simply used it, very sensitively, but without any full dress explanation of what he was doing. When Thomistic commentators after him have tried to pin down the theory more precisely and technically, they too often have fallen into the straight jacket of Cajetan's oversimplified and restrictive systematization, in which the structure of proper proportionality is understood as a four-term proportion, a structure that St. Thomas himself quietly abandons as not adequate by itself after his early work, De Veritate. 1 1 For a summary of these developments, see David Burrell, Analogy and Philosophical Language (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973), Chap. 6 61 62 W. NORRIS CLARKE Secondly, doctrinally speaking, Thomists tend too often to omit in their formal analyses of analogy the indispensable metaphysical underpinning that alone justifies the application of analogy when one of the terms is not known directly in itself. No purely logical or semantic analysis of the structure of analogous concepts can supply this extra-logical component. In addition, Thomistic commentators for the most part do not bring out clearly enough-if indeed they accept the point at all-the fact that analogy does not lie so much in any formal structure of concepts themselves as in the actual lived usage of meaningful analogous language, found only when the so-called analogous concepts are used in judgments. 2 In the light of the above comments I would like to see if I can shed some light of my own on Professor Nielsen's difficulties, so that at least the authentic and essential points of disagreement may be brought more clearly into focus and allow more fruitful dialogue thereon than usually seems to be the case in this elusive question of analogy. Objections of Professor Nielsen The three most crucial objections of Professor Nielsen against the explanations of Copleston and Ross seems to me to be the following. (1) The first concerns the distinction made by Copleston between the " subjective meaning" of an analogous term, i. e., our understanding of the meaning as drawn from instances in our experience, which he admits is anthropomorphic, and the "objective meaning," i. e., the objective reality referred to by the concept as found in God and affirmed of him, even though we do not know just what this is like, but only point to it in the dark, so to speak, and for good reasons, since it is an infinitely higher mode beyond the direct grasp of our experience and concepts. But the on Aquinas, and G. Klubertanz, St. Thomas Aquinas on Anafogy (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1960). 2 Although I had come to this conclusion some time ago myself, I am deeply indebted to Fr. Burrell for his fine elucidation of this point, one of the main ones in his fine book cited in n. I. ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN Al!'FIRMATIVE REJOINDER 68 trouble here, as Professor Nielsen points out, is that, since we have no access to this objective meaning as it is verified in God, which is quite different from the subjective meaning drawn from our experience, this so-called objective meaning is vacuous, empty of meaningful content for us who are using the term. And the gap between the two meaning-contents indicates that the concepts predicated in each case are not the same, though the same word is used; hence there is equivocation. (2) The second concerns the very meaning of an analogous concept in itself. At the heart of every analogous concept, Professor Nielsen insists, there must be " a common core of meaning," which in tum necessarily implies that this core of meaning must be univocal. " Common core of meaning " and " univocal " are co-existensive and convertible terms. No merely formal structure of isomorphic relations can supply such a common core. (3) Third, Professor Nielsen points out that there is no way of confirming or verifying the meaningfulness or truth of what is analogously predicated of God, since there is no way of verifying or falsifying it from experience or by any kind of testing for consequences. Most of my reply will be directly concerned with the objections to Copleston, since the objections to Ross seem to me merely a more technical application of the same basic difficulties. And, besides, I agree with much of Professor Nielsen's dissatisfaction with any attempt to lay out analogy in some formal logical structure. No isomorphism of formal relations can supply for intrinsic similarity in content between the sets of relations compared. Since I do not think it feasible to separate out the answers to the three objections, for they all involve the same roots, I shall give my own account of how analogy works and pick up the objections along the way at appropriate points. I will not give any distinct answer to the third objection. Many have handled this already. And there is simply no testing from experience or from consequences of predications when one is discoursing about the attributes of God. The only testing is the metaphysical exigency of 64 W. NORRIS CLARKE intelligibility itself: predications about God must have both meaning and truth if our own world is not to fall into unintelligibility. They are all metaphysical musts flowing from the primary must of the causal bond itself. Hence I will divide my exposition into three main sections: I. Must Analogy Be Rooted in Univocity? IL The Extension of Analogy Beyond the Range of Our Experience. III. The Application of Analogy to God and Its Metaphysical Underpinning. I. Must Analogy Be Rooted in Univocity? As we read through Professor Nielsen's criticism of both Copleston and Ross, we notice one crucial assumption functioning over and over again, at first more or less implicitly, then finally surfacing with full explicitness. It is this: if there is to be any genuine similarity within difference in the various predications of an analogous term, then this similarity necessarily involves some " common property" or attribute, even if only a relation, which holds in all applications; now the presence of such a common property necessarily involves a "univocal core of meaning." Analyzing one of St. Thomas's descriptions of knowing (it should be noted, however, that this does not apply to all knowing but only to the knowing of another than oneself) , which runs, " the possession of the form of another as another, according to one's natural mode of possession," Professor Nielsen comments: This last qualification presumably gives us the difference which keeps the predication from actually being univocal. But it remains the case that on the assumption (questionable in itself) that Aquinas' account of knowing is intelligible, it is true that in all cases of ' knowing ' there is a property that remains common to and distinctive of all these uses. That is to say, we could construct a predicate signifying the res significata of 'knowing' that would be predicated of all cases of knowing. This would be a univocal predication. (p. 50) In other words, whenever there is a common property predicated, there must be a univocal core of meaning. Hence even ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 65 the qualifying phrase added by St. Thomas, "according to one's natural mode of possession," must leave intact the univocal core of meaning, " possession of the form of another as another." Here is the central and clear-cut point of contention between Professor Nielsen and the Thomistic tradition in the very meaning of analogy itself. Thomists would admit-though a,few, like David Burrell, seem unduly squeamish about doing so-that in some significant sense there must be some common core of meaning in all analogous predications of the same term, for otherwise it could not function as one term and concept. But they insist, on the other hand, that this common core of meaning is not therefore univocal, but remains analogous, similar-in-difference, or diversely similar. If it is any consolation to Professor Nielsen, his objection is exactly the same as that brought against Thomistic analogy by Duns Scotus and William of Ockham shortly after the time of Thomas himself. For them the sufficient requirement that a term be univocal is that it be able to function as a middle term retaining the same meaning in both premises of a syllogism, enough to avoid equivocation. An analogous term was for them really a verbal unity of two distinct, though related, concepts, and if used in both senses in the same argument would introduce a fourth term and invalidate the argument. 3 Yet this is definitely not the Thomistic understanding of univocity and analogy. The difference in approach between the two positions might be summed up thus: The Scotus-Ockham analysis is geared primarily to the demands of deductive reasoning and the logical functioning of concepts. It also takes the word and concept as the fundamental unit of meaning, 8 Cf., on Scotus, Burrell, op. cit., Chap. 5 and 7; C. Shircel, Univocity of the Concept of Being according to Duns Scotus (Washington: Catholic University of America, 1942); on Ockham, Burrell, op. cit., Chap. 7; M. Menges, The Concept of the Univacity of Being regarding the Predication of God and Creatures according to William Ockham (St. Bonaventure, N. Y.: Franciscan Institute, 1958). 66 W. NORRIS CLARKE which remams intact in its own self-contained meamng no matter how it is moved around as a counter in combination with other concepts, including its use in a judgment, which is interpreted simply as a composition of two concepts, subject and predicate, without change in either. The Thomistic analysis is geared much more to the actual lived usage of the concept in a judgment, interpreted as an intentional act of referring its synthesis of subject-predicate to the real order, as it is in reality. Hence it tends to look right through the abstract meaning of the concept to what it signifies, or intends to signify (intendit significare), in the concrete, and so adjusts the content of the concept to what it knows about its realization in the concrete. The difference in perspective-and in theories of the relation of concept to judgment-leads to quite different conclusions, which I think are considerably more than a merely verbal dispute over different terminologies for the same thing, though there is some of that hanging like a cloud over the scene too, causing the opponents to pass each other in the fog without meeting. Let me explain now how I think Thomistic analogy actually works, building it up genetically from its actual origin and use in living language. I take it as understood that from now on when I speak of analogous terms and concepts I am referring only to what Thomists identify as properly and intrinsically analogous terms, i. e., those that are intended to express a proportionate intrinsic similarity found in all the analogates (hence not analogies of the so-called " extrinsic attribution," such as " healthy " applied to man and to food, which is not designed to express similarity but some relation of causality, belonging to, etc.). Such intrinsic analogies are found in terms like "knowledge," " love," " activity," " unity," "goodness," "being." We construct and use analogous concepts in our languagelif e to fit occasions wherein we cannot help but use them. This occurs when we notice some basic similarity-in-difference, or proportional similarity, across a range of different kinds ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 67 of subjects (or on different levels of being, of qualitative perfection), such that the similarity we notice does not occur in the same qualitative way in each case but is noticed to be found in a qualitatfoely different way in each case. When we form a univocal concept, on the other hand, we pick out some similarity, usually some form or structure or quantitative relation, which we judge or notice to be found with significant qualitative variation in each case, usually falling within the same species or a genus with closely related properties. In such a case we notice that, even though a few examples are needed to get started, the meaning content, what the term objectively signifies, once grasped, remains neutral, indifferent, unchanged with respect to any further instances. Such a content is thus quite well defined, determinate, and fixed. Not so with an analogous concept. The similarity we notice here is not some one thing or characteristic that remains exactly the same in all cases, except for some new additional note being added on each time from the outside. It is rather that the similar property itself is more or less profoundly and intrinsically modified in a qualitatively different way each time, so that through and through the whole property is recognized as at once similar yet different (not just found in some new instance that in other ways is different). An analogous concept is not a composition of one part exactly identical and another part different, as Scotus, Ockham, and Nielsen seem to imply; rather it is an indissoluble unity where the similarity itself is through and through diversified in each case. As a result there is quite a bit of " give," flexibility, indeterminacy, or vagueness right within the concept itself, with the result that the meaning remains essentially incomplete, so underdetermined that it cannot be clearly understood until further reference is made to some mode or modes of realization. This leads us to discover one of the most remarkable and distinctive features of analogous concepts, especially the ones of broadest range: it is in fact impossible to define what we 68 W. NORRIS CLARKE mean by an analogous concept, to grasp the similarity involved, except by actually running up and down the known range of cases to which it applies, by actually calling up the spectrum of different exemplifications, and then catching the point. The similarity involved cannot be isolated from its qualitatively diversifying modes and expressed by itself clearly, as it can be in the case of a univocal concept. It can indeed be caught or recognized by an act of intellectual insight as we run up and down the scale of examples. It can be seen., and shown forth by our meaningful linguistic behavior, as Wittgenstein would say, but it cannot be said or expressed clearly by itself. Or, if you wish, it can be said by framing one linguistic term for use in all cases, but the meaning of the term cannot be grasped at all clearly without actually calling up a diversified range of cases. The meaning of the term, therefore, must be completed and made determinate in each case by reference to some concrete qualitative mode. That is why the notion always contains within it, at least in an implicit way-which can easily be made explicit, as St. Thomas does in the example of knowledge-the parenthetical indication (like a kind of metalinguistic instruction or warning) that the property in question will be present in each case " according to the mode proportionate to the nature of each." Yet the concept itself, as an abstract predicate by itself, fit to be used in many different predications as somehow the same one concept, does not mention or contain within its expressed content any of these particular modes in any of its predications, but is understood as transcending them all. Otherwise, it is clear, it could not be used to refer to any other instance with a different mode. However, when this indeterminate abstract concept, unified as such, is actually used in a concrete judgment, its meaning, as understood in the whole concrete act of knowing that is the judgment, then molds itself or shifts to take on the particular determination of the case in hand, while at the same time continuing to recognize the intrinsic proportional similarity-in-difference of this instance with all the others in ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 69 the range outlined by the concept. This is the point of the very astute remark made by Gilson long ago, that "'analogy' for Aquinas refers to our ability to make the kind of judgments we do," that it is to be explicated " on the level of judgment " and "not of concept " alone. 4 Analogy is to found and understood on the level of the lived use of concepts and terms, not in any formalizable logical structure of the concept in itself. Thus when I understand in an analogous way a proposition like " x is intelligent," what I mean is, " x exhibits or realizes in this different but still sufficiently similar way the same similarity-in-difference which I have already noticed running through a certain range of cases, so much so that I feel justified in expressing this case by the same analogous term as the others." I have laid special stress in the above on the importance of the lived use of concepts in judgment, because it is not always brought out sufficiently by Thomists, and is one of the distinguished marks of the approach of St. Thomas when compared to that of Scotus and Ockham. A Thomistic analogous term does indeed contain a certain genuine unity, though heavily laced with indeterminacy at its core, enough unity to function logically quite like a univocal term. And, of course, if one considers an analogous concept from a comparative or negative point of view with respect to other concepts, it is quite determinate in what it excludes from consideration, in how it delimits its whole rang•e from that of other concepts. But the point remains that when looked at in what it positively includes within its range it cannot express clearly by itself the similarity in isolation from the differences. When it tries to do so through so-called definitions it can only call up as paraphrases other equally analogous and indeterminate terms, which themselves require reference to a range of diverse examples in order to be meaningful. And whenever it 'E. Gilson, The Christian Phil,osophy of St. Thomas Aquinas Random House, 1956), pp. 105-107. (New York: 70 W. NORRIS CLARKE tries to become too precise, it contracts to become identical with just one of its modes and loses its analogical function. Let me illustrate what I have been saying above by taking the same example used by Professor Nielsen, that of knowledge, defined by St. Thomas as " the possession of the form of another as another, according to one's natural mode of possession." Let us say that we have already recognized as included within its range of proper instances the dim knowledge through touch of the environment around it by an oyster or snail; the more complicated integration of visual, tactile, and audible sense images by a dog or other higher animal; the intellectual insight of man into justice or the inner law of operation of a typewriter or Einstein's Theory of Relativity; the Zen master's empty, imageless, supra-conceptual awareness of reality; the mystic's awareness of God in the "fine point of the soul " beyond all concepts and faculties. All are judged to be genuine though highly different instances of knowing. Now suppose we try to say or describe just what is the similarity amongst all of them, in itself. And suppose the person to whom we are trying to describe it says "I don't want you to do it by examples; just tell me what it is in itself." What could we possibly tell him that could capture the commonness by itself? We can only run through the spectrum of examples on different levels and then appeal to the person's own experience. "Do you know what I mean? Do you get the point? " Professor Nielsen, it seems, would like to insist: " But there is a common univocal core: possession of the form of another as another ... " Yet suppose we try to apply this even to only two cases, such as a dog's "possession" of the "form" of a typewriter in the mode of a visual image of its external shape and color, compared with a man's" possession" of the" form" as intellectual insight into the inner law of operation of the machine. What in the world does "possession" mean here? How can we describe it in itself? Is it like the possession of a marble in one's pocket? No. Or having a ca;st in one's eye? ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 71 No. Is it possessing a visual image in consciousness? Aside from the problem of defining "consciousness," this is one example, but not one that adequately circumscribes the meaning, since having an intellectual insight into the intelligible form or law is vastly different, even though somehow similar-it is impossible to specify just how. The same difficulty would occur in trying to explain " form." The only thing one can finally do is call up the whole range of examples and ask, "Don't you catch the point? Do you see what I mean? " This is not an evasion; it is precisely the intelligent (in fact, the only effective) way to do it. The same with other analogous concepts, such as unity, activity, love, goodness, power, perfection (imagine trying to describe precisely what is similar in all instances of activity or perfection) . In a word, although one can indeed say that in some true sense (analogous) there is a common core of meaning in an analogous concept, it is nonetheless clear that the concept functions quite differently-if we look at it from within as used, not just from without a,s a logical counter in an argument-from a univocal concept with its common core. This leads me to one more distinctive characteristic of the analogous concept which I think it most important to mention, since it too is frequently not made explicit by Thomist commentators. What kinds of things, or aspects of reality, or properties are thus amenable to, even necessarily require, expression through analogous terms? As I see it-and I am willing to defend this, even though it is not commonly mentioned-there is only one " dimension " of reality or " kind " of property that is capable of truly analogous expression: this is the realm of activities or dynamic functions, what we might call " activity properties " understood in the widest possible sense (plus, 0£ course, the opposite correlative properties of receiving, being acted on, etc.: loving and being loved, causing and being caused are equally analogous). All such properties are expressed originally and primarily by verbs, not nouns, or are in some way reducible to verbs. Analogous W. NORRIS CLARKE terms can of course be nouns, but then the noun presupposes the verb-e. g., it signifies a subject, but as the doer of such and such an action, which aspect alone is made explicit (knower, lover ... ) . The reason why activity properties are such fit candidates for analogous expression is that the same general " kind " of activity can be performed quite differently by different kinds of agents or subjects without destroying the similarityin-difference of the activity aspect itself. This is not true of forms, structures, quantitative relations, and the like, which are not thus elastic in their realizations. Different kinds of things in the universe, different levels of being, are not like each other in their essential specific forms or essences considered statically. But they are proportionally alike in their modes of activity, in their dynamic functions. Different forms themselves can only be compared as alike insofar as they are forms or structures for similar actions. If there is any formal structure to analogous concepts, it is not a strictly logical or formal structure, but the structure of an activity situation: an analogous term expresses this general kind of activity x, recognized as carried on in one distinctive proportionate way by subject a, in another distinctively different proportionate way by subject b, etc. The subjects and modes of acting are quite different in each case; the activities themselves are recognized as proportionately similar, similar-in-difference, although it remains impossible to state just what this similarity is apart from its range of varied modes. Let me add that if the term " activity" itself here is allowed to expand to its full analogous breadth of illuminative meaning, existence itself then not only can be described but is uniquely appropriate to be described as the most radical kind of activity or act, the act of "presencing." This is the Thomistic analogous notion of being itself: "that which has, or exercises, the act of existing." ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD--AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 73 II. The Extension. of Analogous Terms beyond thJe Range of Our Experience So far we have been analyzing how analogy functions within a range where all the main levels of exemplification lie within our experience, hence where the different modes can be directly known to us. The next phase of our investigation, crucial for the application to God, concerns the extension of analogous concepts beyond our present range of known examples, i. e., the formation of "open-ended" concepts whose range extends indefinitely beyond our present experience, at least in an upward direction. The ranges of analogous concepts can be roughly classified as follows: (1) those having a ceiling but no floor (no lower limit) in their application: terms like physico-chemical activity, whose upper limit is biological activity, or perhaps consciousness, but that extend downward to unknown depths of matter still hidden from us and perhaps very strange indeed compared with what we know; (2) those having both a floor and a ceiling, say, biological activity, or sense knowledge, limited by the non-living or unconscious below and intellectual knowledge above; (3) those having a, floor but no ceiling: intellectual knowing, love, life, joy, etc.; (4) those having neither ceiling nor floor: the all-pervasive "transcendental properties" applicable across all levels of being, such as being, activity, unity, power, intelligibility, goodness (in the widest sense). Our special concern will be with numbers (3) and (4) , as alone applicable to God. How in general do we go about opening up an analogous concept beyond its presently known range of examples? Let us take the example of knowing. Suppose we reflect on how remarkably diverse are the modes we already know, and how impossible it is to deduce from a lower level what a higher level will be like; it then appears to us, when reflecting on the ttnalogous meaning of knowing, that we have no good or decisive reasons for closing off its possible range at the level i$ $Orne plausible suspicioµ that we knqw; in. 74 W. NORRIS CLARKE may be higher kinds of intelligence on other planets or perhaps even beyond all corporeal entities (not yet God) . We decide we should remain prudently open to the possibility of higher intelligence trying to communicate with us through some kind of signal. We have no idea what kind of communication or signals-they would not even have to be through material signs but might be by direct telepathy or thought-communication-or what the mode of intelligence involved might be like or how it might function in itself, even when not attached to a body. Yet it makes perfect sense, and in the concrete it is quite easy-we are actually doing it already-to open up the range of meaning of what we now experience and understand as intelligence to include in expectancy some possible level at present quite unknown and uncharacterizable by us. The new extension of the term, though empty of any precise content describable by us now, is not simply empty. It gets its new and very useful content of meaning from its place on an ascending (it might also be descending) scale, which serves as guide for evaluation assessment (respect, awe, fear, caution, etc.). Such a role as guide to evaluation procedures, and their practical consequences, is an indispensable one for our concrete life of the mind in the midst of a reality that is always partly known, partly concealed in relation to us. Another example arises from the new scientific interest in para-psychology and psychic phenomena of various kinds. There is widespread talk of some new kind (s) of force that produces effects in the material world, yet seems to operate in ways thus far unknown to us and is quite different from the other physical forces we know-" psi-forces," some caU them. They may be a new kind of physical radiation, or more probably psychic energy fields, or what have you. The point is that we quite readily enlarge the notion of force to make room for the possible discovery of a new mode, concerning which we can say nothing clear as yet, not even that it really exists. It may be objected that there is a univocal core in all description of such forces, in that they produce observable ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 75 effects in the material world. There may, it is true, be one element of their definitions that has a univocal cast: the material effects produced. But the notion of force does not mean the effects produced. It means the power producing such effects, and as long as this central part of the meaning is variable in its mode the meaning must remain analogous. In both of the above, and many other possible examples, in order to extend the range of an analogous concept we must " purify " its meaning-content, what it explicitly signifies, making it indeterminate enough so that its range of application will not be restricted within present limits. l£ we judge that this cannot be done without a violent and arbitrary wrench in the meaning that renders the term no longer comfortably serviceable enough, we judge the proposed extension inviable, too confusing, and devise an entirely new term to express the additional range of cases presumed to exist. This is a matter of good judgment, of a sense for successful living language, not a matter of the logical structure of concepts. It is within the context of this extension of an analogous concept to a new application whose mode of realization is unknown to us that the traditional distinctions arise between "objective meaning" and" subjective meaning" (Copleston), the res signific,ata, or the objective property signified by the term, and the modus signific,amdi, or the modes by which we express to ourselves this property (St. Thomas), and other similar semantic devices. There is unfortunately much confusion in terminology here (and not infrequently in thought too, I fear), and I am not happy with either of the above ways of trying to spell out the same general point. St. Thomas' way is clear enough in itself-though often misunderstood, as it clearly is here by Professor Nielsen-but is so narrow in scope as he uses it that it does not do the entire job that has to be done. Copleston's way is, I fear, open to serious misunderstanding and seems to me to be inadequate to its task. So let me first state the job to be done, and how I think it best to express it, and then return to assessing the two sets of distinctions mentioned above. 76 W. NORRIS CLARKE In such a context of using analogous language, we must separate out the following: (1) the res significata, i. e., the " thing " or common property signified, which is what is actually predicated in each case, whether previously known or not. Its meaning-content as expressed in the analogous concept is deliberately or systematically vague and indeterminate, not restricted to any of its modes so as to be truly predicable of all cases. (It does not mean, by the way, the actual concrete referent of this predicate in a given judgment, although the terminology of " thing "-res-has misled some into thinking so.) (2) The real modes, or modes of being, in which this common objective property or attribute is understood to be realized in given applications, as we apply the term in concrete complete acts of knowing in the judgment. These modes may already be known to us, as the animal and human modes of knowing, or they may as yet be unknown to us, in which case we intend to signify what is there in the concrete but through a vague and incomplete act of knowing. Or, if you wish, we intend to refer to what is really there, but through a vague and incomplete mental sign, recognized as such, although we do recognize clearly that we are referring to a mode different from the others we know. These modes, however, are not part of what is actually predicated by the abstract analogous predicate itself, as is (1) above, although we understand the indeterminate content to take them on in the concrete, as we actually use the term. 5 (8) The modes of 5 St. Thomas himself is quite clear about this. Cf. his sensitive basic treatment in Summa Theol., I, quest. 13 entire, esp. art. 3: " Some words that signify what has come forth from God to creatures do so in such a way that part of the meaning of the word is the imperfect way in which the creature shares in the divine perfection. Thus it is part of the meaning of " rock " that it has its being in a purely material way. Such words can be used of God only metaphorically. There are other words, however, that simply mean certain perfections without any indication of how these perfections are possessed-words, for example, like 'being', 'good', 'living', and so on. These words can be used literally of God" (the translation is the new English one edited by Thomas Gilby, Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. I, Garden City, Doubleday Image Book, 1969). ANALOGlCAL TALK OF G01>--AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 77 our understanding of the res mgn.ificata, which are the best known modes of concrete realization of the common property, considered as ways or media through which we first come to lay hold of the meaning of the property and upon which we fall back as the clearest examples when we wish to evoke its meaning for ourselves anew-since, as we noted above, it is always necessary to call up some examples across a range in order to grasp or recall the meaning of an analogous comcept. Among these there is usually-not necessarily always, it seems-one or more that stand out as prime analogates for us, i. e., as focal meanings or privileged examplars closest to us by which we most easily and immediately grasp the meaning experientially, and out from which as from a center we extend it in lessening degrees of clarity. This usually means the properties as experienced and lived in our own selves, whether in body, psyche, or spirit. But it should be clearly understood that these ways of our coming to understand most vividly the common property do not themselves enter into the object meaning of the term when it is predicated analogously, in any of its predications. They are modes of revealing the analogous meaning of the term; they do not constitute its objective meaning itself-otherwise they would restrict it and destroy its analogical spread. Its objective analogical meaning as predicated is deliberately expanded, enlarged, made more vague and indeterminate than these modes of discovery, so that it will be able to transcend them in scope of applioation. Thus at the same time that we call up these privileged modes in order to evoke the meaning of the concept for ourselves, we understand (at least implicitly, but in a way that effectively controls our use of the term) that the meaning of the analogous term is being left open for further application, that it is not tied down to these modes of discovery. Thus if we were asked, in the example of speaking of hypothetical higher forms of " intelligence " that might communicate with us from outer space, what we mean by "intelligence," we would say something like this: " You know, 78 W. NORRIS CLARKE the kind of thing we do, being self-conscious, comprehending the natures and properties of things, making signs or communicating in some way, in a word, understanding, but probably in quite different ways from ours." We do not confuse the modes of understanding with the reality understood, or signified. We could add another aspect (4) which would correspond exactly to St. Thomas' modus significandi, or modes of signifying the res sign.ificata. These are often misunderstood as signifying aspect (2), the actual modes of concrete realization of the common property in particular cases, as Professor Nielsen seems to understand them. This is quite incorrect. They are also sometimes extended to coincide with our (3), man's modes of understanding the res significa,ta. There is no great harm in deliberately using modus significandi with this meaning, and one does need some appropriate term to express these. But it is still not what the expression itself means as Aquinas uses it. It refers only to our human modes of expressing the res significa,ta, i. e., conceptual-linguistic modes. It was originally intended to take care of the obvious difference between the way God's perfections are found in him and our way of expressing the perfections of God through multiple verbal predicates, each distinct from the other, which are predicated of a subject as though they were accidents inhering in a distinct substance: " God is wise, and loving, and powerful." This is the way they are found in us, where wisdom can come and go and where a man can be wise but not powerful or vice versa. But what they signify as found in God himself is that God is identically all the positive perfections signified by these terms but united together in a single simple plenitude of perfection. Similarly we speak of God, who is beyond time, through verbal forms with tenses. Yet St. Thomas is quite clear that, although our modes of expressing these attributes bear the mark of their origin in our experience, these modes are not what is express'ed and predicated by the concept itself, ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIBMATIVE REJOINDER 79 in any of its predications. 6 To say that John is wise and powerful does not mean, though it may indeed be understood to be also true, that wisdom in John is an accidental attribute really distinct from his power and his own essence. It is simply stating that it is true that he is wise and it is true that he is powerful, without stating how these are related. Hence our modes of expression do not corrupt with anthropomorphism our predications about God, or about anything, for that matter. This is as far as St. Thomas's modes of expressing take us, though he also speaks of the " modes in which a perfection is found " or realized in its subject, which are not quite the same thing, but correspond rather to our modes of rea.lizatU:min (2) above. Where do Copleston's "objective meaning" and" subjective meaning" fit in here? 7 It is not entirely clear to me from his text how they do, and it is no wonder to me that Professor Nielsen had serious-and to my mind quite justified-difficulties with his explanation. For Copleston, the "objective meaning" means" the objective reality itself referred to by the term in question," which in his example, " God is intelligent," he maintains is "the divine intelligence itself,'J as it is in itself. The "subjective meaning" is" the meaning-content in my own mind ... primarily determined for me by own experience ... of human See his text in note 5. The main part of the text Professor Nielsen is quoting (Contemporary Philosophy, Westminister, Md.: Newman Press, 1956, p. 96) runs as follows: " By 'objective meaning' I understand that which is actually referred to by the term in question (that is, the objective reality referred to), and by 'subjective meaning' I understand the meaning-content which the term has or can have for the human mind ... i. e., my understanding or conception of what is referred to .... If this distinction is applied to the proposition 'God is intelligent', the 'objective meaning' of the term 'intelligence' is the divine intellect or intellect itself .... And of this I can certainly give no positive account .... The 'subjective meaning' is the meaning-content in my own mind. Of necessity this is primarily determined for me by my own experience, that is, by my experience of human intelligence. But seeing that human intelligence as such cannot be predicated of God, I attempt to purify the 'subjective meaning' . . . . And in doing so we are caught inextricably in that interplay of affirmation and negation of which I have spoken." 6 7 80 W. NORRIS CLARKE intelligence." But here it seems that "intelligence" means in this predication " divine intelligence " and yet the only meaning-content in my mind in all predications is " human intelligence." This opens up a yawning gap between the two which Prof. Nielsen has very astutely seen, and it is not at all clear from this text alone just how one crosses the gap. What Copleston fails to explain is that what he calls the " subjective meaning " is not really the meaning-content in my mind at all which I mean to signify by the analogous concept. It is my way of discovering the meaning, but not the purified more indeterminate analogous meaning itself. He needs another intermediate term in his discussion to indicate this. He comes close to it, in fact, when he adds at the end of his text, not quoted by Nielsen, " But seeing that human intelligence as such cannot be predicated of God, I attempt to purify the 'subjective meaning' .... And in so doing we are caught inextricably in that interplay of affirmation and negation of which I have spoken." It is this "purified meaning," purified by being made more indeterminate and open, that is the one actually predicated of God, which is not Copleston's objective meaning either, since that is already determined to fit God only. He does not make this clear enough in his text. (I fear there is some confusion too in Fr. Copleston's text between meaning and reference, when he speaks of the meaning as " the reality referred to.") Thus it should be clear that I dissociate myself from Fr. Copleston's explanation and consider it an inaccurate rendering of St. Thomas's teaching, or at least an easily misleading one. Professor Nielsen has good reasons for finding it unsatisfactory. There is in fact no gap between the meaning of "intelligence " as predicated of God and its meaning as predicated of man. But there is a gap between the modes of realization which I understand this attribute will take on in the concrete in each case, as well as between my mode of coming to understand this meaning and the mode I affirm in God. ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 81 III. Application to God Let us now take brief stock of what we have accomplished. We have tried to explain what the structure of analogous predication is in general, how it works, and what it means to extend the range of an analogous concept beyond its ordinary range in our experience. But the actual extension of our analogous language to some new entity, such as God, that is beyond the range of our experience requires three further steps: (I) we must have good grounds for affirming that there actually is (or at least might be) such a new candidate for the application of our language; (2) we must have good grounds for affirming that this new candidate is actually objectively si,milar in some way or ways to the presently known beings in our experience-in other words, that there are good grounds for applying our concepts and language at all; (3) once we are in possession of these grounds we must then proceed to figure out just which of the attributes in our store of knowledge are apt to be extended meaningfully and legitimately to such an entity. But the first two suppositions cannot be provided by a theory of analogy itself. They must come from outside, to build a bridge across which our analogical language can walk. It is especially the lack of any awareness of the second point above, the establishment of a bond of similarity between God and creatures, that renders Professor Nielsen's exposition of Thomistic analogy so cripplingly incomplete. Let us now turn to each of these three points. The first two will be handled together under Section 1. I. Causality as the Bond of Similarity between God and World The first step is establishing the existence of God. This is done through a causal argument, which postulates that, under pain of our world of experience falling into unintelligibility, there must exist, as experience's ultimate condition of intelligibility, or adequate sufficient reason, one ultimate Source of all being, whose only intelligible mode of being must be W. NORRIS CLARKE infinite perfection-for otherwise it could not be the ultimate condition of intelligibility. I would not carry on this argument through the Five Ways of St. Thomas, since they are too incomplete by themselves and defective in structure to do the job for us today. I would use rather the simpler and more basic metaphysical resources of St. Thomas, not drawn on clearly enough in the Five Ways, to show that no being that begins to exist, or is finite in perfection, or composed in its radical being, or member of a system of dynamically interrelated elements-to sum it up most simply, no finite being or group of finite beings-can supply the sufficient reason or ground of its own existence, and that such an ultimate condition of intelligibility is not reached until we posit an infinite being, a being infinite in perfection. It is not my purpose to work out this argument here, since it would take another whole article, and our main aim here is explaining the function of analogy within such a framework. Let us therefore suppose that this step has been carried out successfully. If it cannot be, there is no point in discussing Thomistic analogy any further as applied to God. But as soon as we have established the argument, without paying any explicit attention to analogy in the process, we discover that a strange thing has happened. Analogy is already being used in the very formulation of the conclusion: there is an ultimate Source or condition of intelligibility for the existenee of . .. , or cause. (This by the way is all we mean by " cause " here in its widest metaphysical sense: that which fulfills a need for intelligibility, which answers the question, "What is effectively responsible for the existence of this datum x, which has turned out to be non-self-explanatory? "-not some meaning drawn from the sciences.) 8 For to be intelligible to us, these terms 8 For this whole question of the meaning of "cause " in the context of the mind's quest for intelligibility and its necessarily analogous character as a correlate of the enquiring mind at work, see my own fuller development in "How the Philosopher Gives Meaning to Language about God," in The Idea of God, ed. by E. Madden, R. Handy, M. Farber (Springfield, Ill.: Charles Thomas, 1968), ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 88 themselves must all be analogous when applied to a being outside our experience. Does this mean that a vicious circle is here involved, that analogy presupposes causality and causality itself presupposes analogy? This is an excellent and crucial question, which Professor Nielsen himself has certainly seen, when he speaks of a circle where one religious statement backs up another. There is indeed a circle of mutual involvement, but it is not a vicious circle; it is a vital one. For it is the very thrust of the mind's search for intelligibility, reaching out into the unknown to postulate a sufficient reason somewhere in being, that both sets up a new beachhead in being for our knowledge to explore further and at the same time carries with it its own enveloping field of analogy. Immanent in the entire innate drive of the mind toward intelligibility is an unrestricted commitment to intelligibility, wherever it may lead, and simultaneously to its objective correlate, being itself, as the source of all answers to this quest. To this range of intelligibility and its correlate being it is impossible to set any limits, since the mind, as soon as it becomes aware of these limits as limits, immediately transcends them by this very awareness. Our own inner experience of this quest for intelligibility that defines the very life of the mind reveals to us that both the quest itself and the answers to it are infinitely Protean, taking on endlessly different forms and modes. In a word, we experience the field of intelligibility, enveloping our own minds and reaching out beyond into its correlate, being, as intrinsfoally analogical, open-ended but somehow all bound together in some vague unspecifiable unity. The first and allembracing analogous field which we discover-not by constructing it deliberately but by waking up within it, so to speak-is the correlation intelligibility-being. Hence it is that when, as in the case of the affirmation of pp. 1-28; about God," in Christian (Washington: Catholic of America Press, 1966), pp. 39-73, esp. pp. 46-51, 61-71. and "Analytic Philosophy and Language Philosophy and Religious Renewal, ed. by G. McLean University 84 W. NORRIS CLARnl God, the mind is convinced-for what it believes are good reasons-that it can save the intelligibility of the world of our experience only by positing or postulating as existent outside this world (i. e., transcending its limitations) an ultimate infinitely perfect source of all being, it necessarily envelops this term that it posits with its own pre-existent and potentially all-embracing field of analogy, at once positing it as a real condition of intelligibility and as necessarily analogous in the same movement of thought. This initial analogy is extremely vague, not yet extending beyond the immediate correlates of the intelligibility-being field itself, together with the index of location within this field at the supreme apex of perfection, whatever that may be. For all the terms used to describe God in this initial stage, "ultimate condition of intelligibility for the existence of the world = cause," are nothing but reaffirmations of the general principle of the intelligbility of all being in principle, tailored to the particular situation where the beings we start with do not contain their own sufficient ground of intelligibility within themselves, hence force us to look beyond them. 9 9 It is very important to make the point here that according to St. Thomas's metaphysical method-and any sound metaphysical method, it seems to me, which seeks to achieve knowledge of some being beyond our experience-it is a fatal error to accept the demand so habitually made by analytic philosophers and others that one must define what he means by " God " before undertaking to establish His existence. This stand is not an evasion; it is a question of proper method. It is impossible philosophically to give any definition of God that can be shown to make sense before actually discovering Him as an exigency of the quest for intelligibility. The meaning of " God " emerges only in function of the argument that concludes to the need of a being to which we then can appropriat-ely give the name " God" or not, according to our culture and religious tradition. The philosophical meaning of God should be exclusively a function of the way by which He is discovered. Hence a properly philosophical approach to the existence of God should not ask, " Can I prove that God exists? " but rather, " What does the world of my experience demand in order to be intelligible? " Following out this exigency rationally, we " bump into " God, so to speak, as a being all of whose properties are defined exclusively by its needs to fulfill its job of satisfying the exigencies of the quest for intelligibility. Hence any philosophical " proof for the existence of God " has already taken the statement of the question from some non-philosophical source, usually religion. ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFffiMATIVE REJOlNDER 85 Thus the very initial positing of God as cause of the world situates him within the primary a priori (a dynamic and existential, not a logical, a priori) analogous field of both intelligibility and being-of being precisely because this is demanded by intelligibility. From the very beginning of our intellectual life there is a necessary mutual co-involvement of intelligibility, being, and analogy. This very vague initial analogous beachhead of knowledge about God is now ready to be expanded by further judicious search for more determinate valid analogies. It is at this point that a second crucial corollary of the causal bond comes into play, one that is too often neglected in expositions of analogy, and of which there is likewise no hint in Professor Nielsen's discussion. This is the principle, handed down to St. Thomas by both the N eoplatonic and the Aristotelian traditions, that every effect must in some way resemble its cause. In a word, every causal bond sets up at the same time a bond of intrinsic similarity in being. In the Platonic-Neoplatonic tradition this took the form of the principle that every higher cause communicated something of its own perfection to its effect beneath it, which participated in the latter as much as its own limited nature allowed. In the Aristotelian tradition it took the form of the principle that no being can cause any perfection in another unless it already possesses in act (in some equivalent way) this same perfection. These two strands were joined together in a single synthesis of causal participation by St. Thomas and other medieval thinkers; and the same general principle of causal similitude has been accepted by most realistic metaphysicians ever since, in one form or another. The philosophical reason why every effect must in some way resemble its cause, at least analogously, is this: since all the positive perfection of the effect, as effect, derives precisely from its cause (s), the latter cannot give what it does not have; the effect must in some way participate or share in the perfection of the cause that is its source. If the cause does not possesss 86 W. NORRIS CLARKE in an equal, or some higher equivalent manner, the perfection it communicates to its effects, then the perfection of the latter would have to come from nowhere, have no relation to its cause. Where there is no bond of similarity whatever between an effect and its cause, there can be no bond of causality either. The similarity in question, however, could be of two main kinds. If both cause and effect were of the same species the similarity would be on the same level and kind, that is, univocal. If the cause were a higher level of being than the effect, then the similarity could not be strictly univocal but would have to be at least analogous. In this perspective, the very fact of establishing a causal link between a lower effect and a higher cause at once ipso facto generates an analogous similarity, a spectrum of objective similarity extending from the known effect at least as far as the cause, whether the latter is directly known or only postulated as a necessary condition of intelligibility for an already known effect. Whether both terms of the relation are known or only one, every effect has to be similar in some way to its cause, or it could not be a real effect, and the same holds for the cause. As St. Thomas sums it up: Effects which fall short of their causes do not agree with them [i. e., are not exactly like them] in name and nature. Yet some likeness must be found between them, since it belongs to the nature of action that an agent produce its like, since each thing acts according as it is in act. The form of an effect, therefore, is certainly found in some measure in a transcending cause, but according to another mode and another way [i. e., analogously]. For this reason the cause is called an equivocal came [a term that is " equivocal by design " in Aristotelian terminology is the same as what was later called "analogous "-opposed to "equivocal by chance"] ..... So God gave all things their perfections and thereby is both like and unlike all of them. 10 An effect that does not receive a form specifically the same as that through which the agent acts cannot receive according to a 10 a. 5. Summa Contra Gentes, Bk. I, chap. 29, n. 2. Cf. also Summa Theol., I, q. 13, ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD--AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 87 univocal predication the name arising from that form .... Now the forms of the things God has made do not measure up to a specific likeness of that divine power; for the things which God has made receive in a divided and particular limited way that which in Hirn is found in a simple and universal unlimited way. It is evident, then, that nothing can be said univocally of God and other things .... For all attributes are predicated of God essentially ... But in other beings these predications are made by participation.11 It is because of this metaphysical context of causality and causal participation undergirding the Thomistic theory of analogy that the most recent and authoritative-in the sense of being almost universally accepted among Thomistscommentaries on St. Thomas's theory of analogy now all agree that despite his many changes in terminology he fairly early drops the structure of proper proportionality, taken by itself alone, for a richer structure involving both immanent proportionality among the analogates of a term and a reference to the causal source from which the analogous perfection in question is communicated to all the participating analogates. structure of analogy as This fuller metaphysical-semantic applied to the relation of God and creatures is most aptly called " the analogy of causal participation." The previously long accepted "orthodox" explanation of Cajetan in terms purely of proper proportionality without reference to a source is now recognized as inadequate to handle the application of analogy to a being not accessible to our experience, as is the case with God. A purely formal isomorphism of relations can supply no positive content of knowledge about the term of comparison otherwise unknown to us unless some positive intrinsic bond of similarity has already been established between both ends of the comparison. Cajetan presumed this had been done elsewhere, but his omission of this step from his 11 Ibid., chap. 82, nn. 2 and 7. He goes on to say in chap. 88, n. 2: " For in equivocals by chance there is no order or reference of one to another, but it is entirely accidental that one name is applied to diverse things .... But this is not the situation with names said of God and creatures, since we note in the community of such names the order of cause and effect .... " 88 W. NORRIS CLARKE formal and explicit analyses of analogy leaves a very serious gap in his formal theory of analogy when taken by· itself, as most non-Thomistic thinkers, if not forewarned, would naturally tend to do. St. Thomas himself appears to have come to recognize this, since after his early work De Veritate-the main source for Cajetan's systematization of all Thomistic texts-he never again uses the formal structure of proper proportionality by itself to express his own thought. Thus it is not surprising that when non-Thomistic thinkers like Professor Nielsen come to the theory of Thomistic analogy through older traditional expositions in the mode of Cajetan, which omit the context of causal participation as part of the doctrine itself as applied to God (or to any unknown cause), they find the structure of the analogy of proper proportionality by itself quite inadequate to perform the role claimed for it. Their critical insight is quite accurate. 12 2. Which Attributes Can Be Applied to God? Once we have set up this basic framework of causal similitude between all creatures and God, from which it follows that there must be some appropriate analogous predicates that can be extended properly and legitimately to God, the next step consists in determining just which attributes can, in addition to the initial most indeterminate attributes of being and perfection, allow for open-ended extension all the way up the scale of being, even to the mode of infinite plenitude, without 12 It is because of this basic similitude between all creatures and God that the phrase applied so often to God by theologians, philosophers of religion, and spiritual writers, describing His transcendence over creatures, namely, that God is " totally Other," is really, if taken in unqualified literalness as a metaphysical statement, quite unacceptable as sound philosophy, theology, or spirituality. For if God were literally totally other, with no similitude at all with us, there could be no bond whatsoever between us, no affinity drawing toward union as our true Good, no image of God deep in the soul, etc. He might be totally other in His essence or mode of being, since He is beyond all form, but not totally other in His being itself or the activity properties that flow directly from its fullness of perfection. ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD--AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 89 losing their unity of meaning. This is the search for the " simple or pure perfections," as St. Thomas calls them, which are purely positive qualitative terms that do not contain as part of their meaning any implication of limit or imperfection. Once we have located one of these, even though we enter into its meaning in first discovering it or in re-evoking it through the limited and imperfect modes (i. e., our privileged modes of exemplifying it to ourselves) belonging to the things we find in our experience, what we intend or mean directly by the concept, once we have purified or enlarged it for good reasons into an analogous concept, is a flexible, broadly but not totally indeterminate core of purely positive meaning that transcends all its particular possible modes, both those we know and those we do not know. We can recognize that we have effected this purification when we can meaningfully affirm, as we certainly do, that all the experienced modes of these open-ended perfections, such as unity, knowledge, love, and power, are limited, not yet perfect modes. For to affix the qualification "limited or imperfect " to any attribute is already to imply that our understanding of this attribute transcends all the limiting qualifiers we have just added to it. Any attribute that cannot survive this process of purification, or negation of all imperfection and limitation in its meaning (and of comse in its actual mode of realization when applied to an infinite being) without some part of its very meaning being cancelled out, does not possess enough analogical " stretch " to allow its predication of God. The judgment as to when this does or does not happen is of course a delicate one that requires careful critical reflection, along with sensitivity to the existential connotations of the use of the term in a given historical culture. 13 Two types of attributes have been sifted out as meeting the above requirements by the reflective traditions of metaphysics, religion, and theology: (l) those attributes whose meaning 13 Cf. for a fuller development my articles cited in note 8. 90 W. NORRIS CLARKE is so closely linked with the meaning and intelligibility of being itself that no real being is conceivable which could lack them and still remain intelligible, i.e., the so-called absolutely transcendental properties of being, such as unity, activity, goodness and power; and (;2) the relatively transcendental properties of being, which are so purely positive in meaning and so demanding of our unqualified value-approval that, even though they are not co-extensive with all being, any being higher than the level at which they first appear must be judged to possess them-hence a fortiori the highest beingunder pain of being less perfect than the beings we already know, particularly ourselves; such are knowledge (particularly intellectual knnwledge), love, joy, freedom, and personality, at least as understood in western cultures. a) The Absolutely Transdendental Properties Once established that God exists as supreme infinitely perfect source of all being, it follows that every attribute that can be shown to be necessarily attached to, or flow from, the very intelligibility of the primary attribute of being itself must necessarily be possessed in principle, without any further argument, by this supreme Being, under pain of its not being at all, let alone not being the supreme instance. Thus it is inconceivable that there should exist any being that is not in its own proportionate way one, its parts, if any, cohering into one and not dispersed into unrelated multiplicity. Hence God must be supremely one. Such all-pervasive properties of being are few, but charged with value significance: e. g., unity, intelligibility, activity, power, goodness (in the broadest ontological sense as having some perfection in itself and being good for something, if only itself), and probably beauty too. Since these properties are so general and vague or indeterminate in their content-deliberately so to allow for their completely open-ended spectrum of application-we derive from this inference no precise idea or representation at all as to what this mode of unity, etc., will be like in itself. But we do ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD--AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 91 definitely know this much: that this positive qualitative attribute or perfection (in St. Thomas's general metaphysical sense of the term as any positive quality) is really present in God and in the supreme degree possible. Such knowledge, though vague, is richly value-laden and is therefore a guide for value assessment and for value responses of reverence, esteem, etc. I am puzzled as to why Professor Nielsen would consider such value-laden and value-guiding concepts simply empty and hence apparently able to serve no cognitive purpose at all. b) The Relatively Transcendental Properties There is a second genre of transcendental attributes of being that are richer in content and of more immediate interest and relevance in speaking about God. These are terms that express positive qualitative attributes having a floor (or lower limit) but no ceiling (or upper limit), and hence are understood to be properties belonging necessarily to any and all beings above a certain level of perfection. Their range is transcendental indefinitely upward but not downward. Such are knowledge (consciousness, especially self-consciousness and intellectual knowledge), love, lovableness, joy (bliss, happiness, i. e., the conscious enjoyment of good possessed), and similar derivative properties of personality in the widest purely positive sense (not the restrictive sense it has in many oriental traditions). All such attributes appear to us as purely and totally positive values in themselves, not matter how imperfectly we happen to possess them here and now. As such, they demand our unqualified approval as unconditionally better to have than not to have. Hence we cannot affirm that any being that exists higher than ourselves, a fortiori the supremely perfect being that God must be, does not have these perfections in its own appropriate mode. To conceive of some higher being as, for example, lacking sel£consciousness in some appropriate way, i. e., being simply blacked out in unconsciousness, would be for us necessarily to conceive this being as lower in perfection than ourselves. 92 W. NORRIS CLARKE Nor is there any escape in the well-known ploy that this might merely mean inconceivable for us but in reality might actually be the case for all we know. The reason is that to affirm that some state of affairs might really be the case is to declare it in some way conceivable, at least with nothing militating against its possibility. This we simply cannot do with such purely positive perfection-concepts. What happens in our use of these concepts, as soon as we know or suspect for good reasons that there exists some being higher than ourselves, is that, even though our discovery of their meaning has been from our experience of them in limited degree, we immediately detach them from restricting links with our own level, make them more purified and indeterminate in content, and project them upward along an open-ended ascending scale of value aPJYl'eoiation. This is not a logical but an existential move, hooking up the inner understanding of the conceptual tools we use with the radical open-ended dynamism of the intellect itself. One way we can experience this power of projection of perfections or value attributes beyond our own level is by experiencing reflectively our own poignant awareness of the limitations and imperfection of these attributes as we possess them now, even though we have not yet experienced the existence of higher beings. We all experience keenly the constricting dissatisfaction and restlessness we feel over the slowness, the fuzzy, piecemeal character of our knowing and our intense longing, the further we advance in wisdom .. for an ideal mode of knowledge beyond our present reach. The very fact that we can judge our present achievement as limited, imperfect, implies that we have reached beyond it by the implicit dynamism of our minds and wills. To know a limit as limit is already in principle to have reached beyond it in dynamic intention, though not yet in conceptual representation. This point has for long been abundantly stressed by the whole Transcendental Thomist school, not to mention Hegel and others, who bring out that the radical dynamism of the spirit indefinitely transcends all finite determinate conceptual expressions or temporary stopping places. ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 93 The knowledge given by such projective or pointing concepts, expressing analogous attributes open-ended at the top, is again very vague and indeterminate, but yet charged with far richer determination and value content than the more universal transcendental attributes applying to all being, high or low. By grafting the affirmation of these attributes, as necessarily present in their appropriate proportionate mode in God, on to the lived inner dynamism of our spirits longing for ever fuller consciousness, knowledge, love (loving and being loved) , joy, etc., these open-ended concepts, affirmed in the highest degree possible of God, can serve as very richly charged value-assessment guides for our value-responses of adoration, reverence, love, longing for union, etc. But note here again that the problem of the extension of analogous concepts beyond the range of our experience cannot be solved by logical or conceptual analysis alone, but only by inserting these concepts into the context of their actual living use within the unlimitedly open-ended, supra-conceptual dynamism of the human spirit (intellect and will) , existentially longing for a fullness of realization beyond the reach of all determinate conceptual grasp or representation. Thomistic analogy makes full sense only within such a total notion of the life of the spirit as knowing-loving dynamism. The knowledge given by these analogous concepts applied to God, therefore, though extremely indeterminate, is by no means empty. It is filled in by a powerful cognitive-affective dynamism involving the whole human psyche and spirit, which starts from the highest point we can reach in our own knowing, loving, joy, etc., from the best in us, and then proceeds to project upwards along the line of progressive ascent from lower levels towards an apex hidden from our vision at the line's end. We give significant meaning to this invisible apex precisely by situating it as apex of a line of unmistakeable direction upward. This delivers to us, through the mediation (not representation) of the open-ended analogous concept, an obscure, vector-like, indirect, non-conceptual, but recognizably positive knowledge- 94 W. NORRIS CLARKE through-love, through the very upward movement of the dynamic longing of the spirit towards its own intuitively felt connatural good-a knowledge " through the heart," as Pascal puts it, or through " connatural inclination," as St. Thomas would have it. 14 Such an affective knowledge-through-connatural-inclination is a thoroughly human kind of knowing, quite within the range of our own deeper levels. of experience, as all lovers and artists (not to mention religious people) know. Yet it is a mode of knowing that has hitherto been much neglected in our contemporary logically and scientifically oriented epistemology. Conclusion It is time to conclude this already too lengthy response. To sum up, analogous knowledge of God, as understood in its whole supporting metaphysical context of (1) the dynamism of the human spirit, transcending by its intentional thrust all its own limited conceptual products along the way, and (2) the structure of causal participation or causal similitude between God and creatures, delivers a knowledge that is intrinsically and deliberately vague and indeterminate, but at the same time richly positive in content; for such concepts serve as positive signposts, pointing vector-like along an ascending spectrum of ever higher and more fully realized perfection, and can thus fulfill their main role as guides for significant value responses, both contemplative and practical. Such knowledge, with the analogous terms expressing it, is, and by the nature of the case is supposed to be, a chiaroscuro of light and shadow, of revelation and concealment (as Heidegger would say), that alone is appropriate to the luminous Mystery which is its ultimately object-a Mystery which we at the same time judge 14 Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 1, a. 6 ad 3; I-II, 9-45, a. 2. Also J. Maritain, "On Knowledge through Connaturality," Review of Metaphysics, IV (1950-51), 483-94; V. White, "Thomism and Affective Knowledge," Blackfriars, XXV (1944), 321-28; A. Moreno, "The Nature of St. Thomas' Knowledge per connaturalitatem," Angelicum, XLVII (1970), 44-62. ANALOGICAL TALK OF GOD-AN AFFIRMATIVE REJOINDER 95 that we must reasonably affirm, yet whose precise mode of being remains always beyond the reach of our determinate representational images and concepts, but not beyond the dynamic thrust of our spirit which can express this intentional reach only through the open-ended flexible concepts and language we call analogous. Such concepts cannot be considered" empty" save in an inhumanly narrow epistemology. w. NORRIS CLARKE, s. J. Fordham University, New York, N. Y. ECCLES/A DOCENS: STRUCTURES OF DOCTRINAL AUTHORITY INTERTULLIAN AND VINCENT I N THE CONTROVERSY following the publication of the encyclical Humanae Vitae, the discussion concerning ecclesiastical doctrinal authority occupied much more time than the arguments over the moral issues more directly involved. The prohibition and condemnation of contraception had to be upheld, it was maintained, because to do otherwise would mean introducing an element of serious discontinuity with previous Catholic teaching. 1 It has been claimed that this preoccupation with continuity is a trait of the modern Church, especially of the modern Papacy. It is intriguing to consider whether the remark of Tertullian in Adversus Praxean referred to similar concern for continuity c. 200 A. D. The bishop of Rome, according to Tertullian, was on the verge of granting some sort of recognition and approval to the Montanist movement in Asia Minor, when the Modalist heretic, Praxeas, dissuaded him with lies and" ... by (his) insistence on the decisions of the bishop's predecessors." 2 Continuity, in one form or another, has been a constant concern of the Church. In earlier centuries, this concern could be summed up in the word" apostolicity." As the first generation of Christian gentile converts began to pass from the scene and increasingly discordant versions of the Christian message were preached, the need for verification of the link with the past became evident. Irenaeus could speak proudly of his direct connection with the Apostle John through Polycarp of Smyrna. Yet Florinus had had the same experience and Irenaeus con1 2 H. Kling, Infallible? An Inquiry. (Trans. E. Quinn, Garden City, 1971) 54. Adversus Praxean. 1 (CC Kroymann & Evans). 96 " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 97 sidered him a heretic.a Papias could proclaim his preference for the living voice of tradition. Yet his own beliefs, e.g. millenarianism, demonstrated the unreliability of this approach. Eusebius deemed Papias " a man of exceedingly small intelligence." 4' The growing dilemma led to increasing pressure for a practical solution. This practical solution was found in combining the argument from succession, formulated succinctly in Clement of Rome, with the ever more important officeof the monarchical episcopate. 5 Gnostics also claimed that their teaching took its origin from the teaching of the Apostles. As Ptolemy wrote to Flora: "For with God's help you will learn ... if you are deemed worthy of knowing the apostolic tradition which we too have received from a succession ... " 6 The answer to the Gnostic challenge was formulated by Irenaeus and Tertullian. 7 The basic argument has not changed greatly since that day. Immutability is the hallmark of Catholic doctrine; variation, the characteristic of heresy. Bossuet in the 17th century, like Tertullian in the third, could still pursue this reasoning. 8 As historical knowledge increased and, more important, the historical mentality took deeper root in the 18th and 19th centuries, this view became untenable. Evolutionary and developmental theories became the fashion of the time. Yet, when it was a question of Catholic doctrine, only a homogeneous development was acceptable. Catholic doctrine did change, it was recognized, but always in the sense of progress, always in the direction of greater clarity and explicitation. As Jossua has observed, homogeneity came to play in historically aware • Eus. H. E. V. 20. 4-8. (GCS text (E. Schwartz) in K. Lake, Loeb edition. Vol. 1 496-8.) • Eusebius H. E. III. 39.13 (LCL 1.296). 5 Clement of Rome. 42. 1-2 (K. Lake, Loeb edition 78-80.). The Letters of Ignatius of Antioch (LCL 172 ff) . 6 Letter of Ptolemy to Flora (SC 24.68 Quispe!) (Paris, 1949). • Irenaeus Adversus Haereses III. 3 (SC 211. 30£ Rousseau & Doutreleau) (Paris, 1974). Tertullian De Praescriptione Haereticorum 36 (CC 1.216-7 Refoule). 8 0. Chadwick From Bossuet to Newman Ch. 1 "Semper Eadem" (Cambridge 1957). 98 ROBERT B. ENO circles the role that fixity and perenniality had for more conservative minds. 9 Today's problematic is considerably more complex than this. Even a recent Roman document like Mysterium Ecclesiae (sect. 5) admits the problem of the historicity of doctrines but then gives it short shrift. One's view of the ancient solution of apostolic succession seems highly colored by one's basic ecclesial presuppositions. Van den Eynde, writing in 1933, found: " In sum, the supreme norm in doctrinal maters is none other than the Church herself. It is her teaching, a legacy received from the hands of the Apostles, which serves as a measure for every other doctrinal source. It is her chiefs, successors of the Apostles, who guard the tradition and who alone teach the faithful with authority." 10 In other words, van den Eynde found the modern Catholic idea of an episcopal magisterium in command in the and 3d centuries. Swedish Lutheran B. Hagglund, writing in 1958, came to a different conclusion. " For Irenaeus, the true tradition is nothing else than prophetic and apostolic tradition. It is false, therefore, to understand this as an explanation of the content of the Faith by bishops or Church teachers. Its content coincides rather with Holy Scripture ... The correct traditw of the Church therefore is a traditw of Holy Scripture." 11 For some Protestant critics, the rise of the notion of Apostolic tradition, while meant to guarantee unbroken continuity with the teaching of Christ and the preaching of his disciples, only succeeded in betraying the lack of such continuity, "The early Catholic concept of tradition is based upon a dual error. First of all, there was an historical error, because the tradition which was claimed to be apostolic did not stem from primitive •Jean Pierre Jossua "Immutabilite, Progres ou Structurations multiples des RevScPhTh (1968) 175. Doctrines chretiennes?" 10 D. van den Eynde Les Normes de l'Enseignement chretien dans la litterature patristique des trois premiers siecles (Paris, 1933) , 103. 11 B. Hagglund " Die Bedeutung der 'Regula Fidei' als Grundlage theologischer Aussagen" Studia Theologica rn (1958) 15-16. " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 99 Christianity alone. Furthermore, there was an error in principle, for the Church could not exist historically simply by clinging to a tradition which was understood as a completed law." 12 The modern evaluation of the ancient idea of apostolicity is itself thoroughly conditioned by the critic's view of what constitutes the Gospel. The modern critic, whatever his persuasion, finds a number of questionable presuppositions behind the ideas of the Fathers: that the content of Christian faith constitutes a unity and a totality from the beginning; that this content is definite and determined from the beginning and, despite the best efforts of heretics, is destined to remain so forever. How were the ancient Christians so certain of these presuppositions? How did they recognize and accept one doctrine as apostolic and reject another as false and heretical? They accepted what they had been taught, of course. But what happened if two regions of the world Church claimed apostolic authority for divergent customs? This did happen in the Quartodeciman controversy and the predictable result was conf:lict.13 The solution to the wider question, however, is not so easily apparent. In their own minds, they just knew what was apostolic, suggests Greenslade. 14 In their view, there could not have been such divergencies in the age of the Apostles. Such evils could arise only later. One gets the impression that the belief and practice of the Church of any given time and place were simply presumed to be in fact apostolic. Certainly, in the realm of praxis it is not surprising (to us!) that divergences could arise in time, slowly and imperceptibly, and these would, locally at lea.st, be presumed, with the passage of a generation or two, to be of apostolic origin. 15 12 C. Andresen Die Kirche:n der alten Christe:nheit (Stuttgart, 1971) 688.; G. Ebeling, The Problem of Historicity (Trans. G. Foley, Phila. 1967) 53. 13 Eus H. E. V. 23-4. (LCL l.502-512). 14 S. Greenslade "Scripture and other doctrinal Norms in early Theories of the Ministry" Journal of Theological Studies 44 (1943) 164. 15 N. Brox, "Altkirchliche Formen des Anspruchs auf Apostolische Kirchenverfassung " Kairos rn (1970) 123, 129, 116. 100 ROBERT B. ENO What Norbert Brox calls the Church's perennial "Urspr141glichkeitsbediirfnis " led it to look backward to its origins, seeking especially to justify its present belief and practice by reference to those foundation stones of the Church, the Apostles. The argument from Apostolic succession furnished the basic instrument for this justification. 16 As the centuries passed and the time of the Apostles became more distant, problems became more complex. Correspondingly, the Church's instruments, its mechanisms, for dealing with these problems, especially doctrinal problems, within the framework of apostolicity, became more sophisticated. This process of growing complexity and the initial development of some mechanisms of defence and decision can be traced in two early Western documents dealing explicitly with questions of innovation and continuity. These are the De Praescriptione llaereticorum of Tertullian (c. 203 A. D.) and the Commonitorium of Vincent of Lerins (c. 434 A. D.). II Faced not only by the teachings of the Gnostics and their threat to the coherence of the Christian Church, but especially by the Gnostic claim to be passing on to its adepts the real teachings of Jesus, albeit esoteric ones fit only for the illuminati, Christian thinkers developed a line of argumentation which has become standard throughout the later history of the Church's resistance to heresy. The elements of authority and succession in ministers of the local Church are found variously in earlier strata. It was left to Irenaeus and then Tertullian to combine these elements and weld them into a theory of authority for the future as well as a weapon against the troubles of the present. Although Tertullian authored several treatises against a 16 Reference to the past, as later times would show, could be used as an instrument for innovation under the banner of reform. See J. Preus " Theological Legitimation for Innovation in the Middle Ages" Viator. Medieval and Renaissance Studies Vol. 3 (1972) 1-26. Also K. Morrison, Tradition and Authority in the Western Church, 300-1140. (Chicago, 1969) 7. " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 101 variety of enemies, both individual and collective, he hoped in his treatise on prescription to forge a weapon that would serve as a " short way with heretics," a general historical proof of the truth of Catholic doctrines rather than a detailed refutation of the tenets of any particular heretic. The object of interest here is not the question of the prescription or prescriptions in this work,17 but the question of whether or not Tertullian sees in any Church office or structure a mechanism empowered to distinguish between doctrinal error and truth. Does Tertullian see in the Church of his own time .someone or something that has the authority to decide whether a given doctrine or practice is compatible with the teaching of Christ? The offices or structures, the " mechanisms " of doctrinal authority of which the modern Catholic immediately thinks, namely, the Papacy and/or councils of bishops are clearly not within Tertullian'.s view when he discusses questions of doctrinal import. In two late works, from his Montanist period, he mentions councils. In one instance, he remarks that the Pastor Hermae has been rejected by numerous councils from the accepted Scriptures. Moreover, he distinguishes between Catholic and Montanist councils.18 In the De leiunio he speaks of councils being held throughout Greece. The subjects of their discussions are not .specified. Although Tertullian says that they treated " certain deep issues," the whole fleeting reference comes in the context of a discussion of obligatory fasts, specifically the Montanist Xerophagies. 19 There are also a few clear or problematical references to the Church of Rome in Tertulliam's later works. In the well-known attack on the bishop who proclaimed his authority to forgive sins of adultery and fornication, Tertullian sarcastically refers to his opponent as a " bishop of bishops " and a " Pontifex 11 On the prescriptions, see D. Michaelides, Foi, Ecritures et Tradition. Les Praescriptiones chez Tertullien. (Paris, 1969), and J. Stirnimann, Die Praescriptio Tertullians im Lichte des romischen Rechts und der Theologie. (Fribourg, 1949). 18 De Pudicitia 10.12 (CC 2: 1301. Dekkers.). 19 De leiunio 13.6 (CC 2: 1272. Reifl'erscheid & Wissowa). 102 ROBERT B. ENO maximus." 20 Many scholars have seen in this adversary not only a bishop of Rome but specifically, Callistus (217-22) . In 1914, Adhemar D' Ales even wrote a book on this "Edict of Callistus." In fact, of course, no one has proved definitively that the target of Tertullian's righteous indignation was really a Roman bishop. A sizable number of scholars opt rather for a bishop of Carthage, probably Agrippinus. The other incident involving Rome is that referred to in passing at the beginning. Praxeas is accused of having turned the Roman bishop against the prophecies of Montanus, Prisca and Maximilla just as he was on the verge of " recognizing " them and offering peace to the Churches of Asia and Phrygia. 21 The exact meaning of what Tertullian is describing is not clear; less clear still, in view of his Montanist bias, is the relation between what he describes and what actually happened. What does emerge is the very general conclusion that, in Tertullian's mind, Roman approval of the New Prophecy would have been a prestigious gain for it. The incidents mentioned in which the Roman bishop or Greek councils were involved are concerned basically with problems of discipline. To be sure, many disciplinary issues have doctrinal implications or repercussions. Moreover, Tertullian's own notion of disciplina has been shown to include elements we would now classify as doctrinal. 22 Yet, at least it can be said that the issues in question are not to be found in the regula fidei. Here it should be pointed out that the regula fidei is the faith itself (fides quae). The rule is not an external criterion or an outside measuring device whereby individual tenets of the faith are either tested and approved or found wanting and rejected. 23 De Pudicitia 1.6 (CC 2: 1281-2). Adversus Praxean 1 (CC 2.1159) " ... agnosccntem iam prophetias ... et ex ea agnitione pacem ecclesiis Asiae et Phrygiae inferentem .. ," 22 V. Morel, "Le Developpement de la 'Disciplina' sous !'Action du Saint-Esprit chez Tcrtullien" RevHisEccl 35 (1939) 263. 23 F. Refoule, Introduction to: Tertullien: Traite de "la Prescription contre les Heretiques, (SC 46, 51-2) (Paris, 1957). 20 21 " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 103 This regula is of the greatest significance for Tertullian. For him there can be no question that it has been handed down whole and entire from Jesus himself as a simple, unified, definite and determined corpus of doctrine. 24 Christ taught these things to his Apostles and they are the key figures for the transmission of this faith, not only to their own age but to all subsequent ages as well. All centuries of the time of the Church receive the teaching of Christ as handed on from Christ to the Apostles and from them to the Churches they founded. " This is my basic principle: that a single and definite doctrine has been taught by Christ which the world must believe absolutely ... " 20 We come into contact with the teaching of Christ always mediately, through the Apostles. They are our auctores.26 If, as Tertullian believed, the teaching of Christ is a single, unified, definite and determined corpus of doctrine, it was the prime task of the Apostles to pass it on unchanged to those whom they converted. In the course of developing this line of thought, Tertullian answers various objections. Christ did not have a secret doctrine he communicated to some while giving another teaching to the masses. If there were such a secret doctrine, who would have received it but these same disciples? On the contrary, they were fully instructed in the very schola Chnsti. 21 Similarly, it is incredible that the Apostles themselves would have taught an esoteric doctrine different from their public preaching. Again, if such a special teaching existed, who would have been its recipients but the leaders of the Churches founded by the Apostles? The deposit of faith committed to the Apostles is not a secret one. 28 Thus all heresies are proved to be that worst of evils, innovations, attempts at twisting or distorting one or another teaching handed down by the Apostles. By its very nature, the •• B. Hagglund, Art. Cit. 85. De Praescriptione Haereticorum. 9.8 (CC 1.195 Refou!e.). •• Prae. 6.4 (CC 1.191). 27 Prae. 22.8-5 (CC 1.208) Scorpiace 12.l (CC 2.1092 Reifferscheid & Wissowa), •• Prae. 26.Sf. (CC 1.208); Prae. 25.8 (CC 1.206). 25 104 ROBERT B. ENO divine truth has priority over falsehood. The original must come before the imitation. 29 It does no good to argue that the entire Church around the world has strayed from the truth. If such errors had crept in, variations inevitably would be the result. Yet, as all can see, the Churches in different parts of the world all teach the same doctrine. Heresies are developments of the times after Christ, although their coming was predicted. 30 This truth handed on faithfully by the Apostles and their successors is found in the regula fidei. The regula is the doctrina and the Scriptures are the instrumenta doctrinae. 31 Unfortunately for the apologist, the heretics also make use of the same Scriptures. They, however, interpret them in an incorrect and perverse way, through either mutilating them (Marcion) or simply twisting the meaning to their own purposes. Hence the need to emphasize the regula as the traditional teaching of the Church found throughout the earth. "Where true Christian discipline and faith are found, there will be the true Scriptures, the true interpretations and all the true Christian traditions." 32 Even in the late work, De Pudicitia, when his own earlier arguments were being turned against him, he was still able to write: "From the beginning they have fashioned the very substance of their doctrine to agree with the details of the parables. Of course, since they are not bound by the rule of faith, they are free to hunt up and piece together things which seem to be typified by the parable. We, however, do not fashion doctrines using the parables as raw materials, but rather, we interpret the parables on the basis of our doctrines." 33 Tertullian has already arrived at a well-known dilemma. What is to be taught as Christian doctrine is to be found in Prae. 35.3 (CC 1.216); Adversus Marcionem 4.5.1 (CC 1.550-1. Kroymatnn), Prae. 28 (CC 1.209); Prae. 30.4 (CC 1.210-11). 31 Prae. 38.2-3 (CC 1.218). 32 Prae. 19.3 (CC 1.201). 33 De Pud. 8.12-9.1 (CC 2.1296). 29 30 " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 105 Sacred Scripture, yet these Scriptures do not explain themselves. Thus the traditional teaching of the Church is to be taken as the correct and orthodox interpretation of what the teaching of Christ was as the Apostles handed it down. He mentions the Holy Spirit as the " vicaria vis . . . qui credentes agat" and the "Christi vicarius" who could not have allowed the Churches to believe otherwise than he preached through the Apostles. Yet he never develops this thought very much. 34 Tertullian does not yet have any mechanism or structure in the earthly Church which is itself a God-given authority enabled to judge between truth and falsehood in doctrine. Offices and structures like the Roman primacy or the council are barely seen in Tertullian. The monarchical episcopate has moved much beyond the embryonic stage although it does not occupy a very large amount of space in Tertullian's thoughts as mirrored in his writings. One possible exception to this statement is to be found in the De Praesoriptione. My contention is that Tertullian's use of the episcopate in this work does not involve an appeal to an authoritative office as such but an appeal to historical verification. It is the capstone of Tertullian's argument that the teaching of Christ as transmitted by the Apostles has been handed down faithfully and unaltered by the succession of bishops of the local communities which make up the world Church. He places special but not exclusive emphasis on the local Churches founded by the Apostles themselves. Yet all the Churches founded later by missionaries from these primordial Churches are apostolic by " consanguinitas doctrinae." 85 To sustain his claim of complete doctrinal continuity and consistency, Tertullian appeals to the evidence of the universal Church, especially as seen in the local Churches founded by •• Prae. 13.5 (CC 1.198); Prae. 28.1. (CC 1.209). To be sure, in his later works, the Paraclete takes on ever increasing importance. Even here, Tertullian is careful to insist that there is no change in doctrine, only a greater progress in disciplina (in the direction of ever greater rigorism) . 85 Prae. 32.6 (CC 1.213) . 106 ROBERT B. ENO Apostles. The basis of argumentation is still to be found in the idea of succession, a notion which Tertullian describes in almost the exact words of Clement of Rome. The Apostles in their missionary preaching founded local Churches. They, who had received the integral teaching from Christ, passed this on to these same Churches with the exhortation and warning not to adulterate or distort this work of the Lord. 86 The lesson is that one who is seriously seeking the true teaching of Christ and his Apostles must go to these same Churches. Such Churches are conveniently scattered about the Roman world so that they may be consulted with relative ease wherever the sincere seeker may be located. Rome is the apostolic church of record for Carthage as well as the whole West. It is outstanding for its association with not just one but three Apostles and these, the leaders of the Apostolic band. 87 The uniformity of this apostolic teaching found the world over in these ancient Churches as well as their offshoots is proof that they have preserved the Lord's teaching undefiled. These Churches are the matrices et originales fidei.88 Yet in all this, there is no hint of automatic acceptance of a doctrine because it is proposed by an authoritative person or structure. Doctrines taught by Christ and handed on by the Apostles are to be accepted, of course. But this is precisely the question: What are these doctrines? Tertullian does not appeal to an authoritative individual or body which is viewed as having the power to decide what the teaching of the apostles is in the contemporary world. Neither the bishop of an apostolically founded Church nor his community is to decide what that teaching is. They are simply to pass on what they have received intact to the next generation and to other newly 86 Clement of Rome 4!U-2 (LCL 78-80); Prae. 37.1 (CC 1.217); Prae. 21.4 (CC 1.203); Prae. 20.5 (CC 1.202). 87 Prae. 32, 36 (CC 1.212-3; 216-7). Peter, Paul and John. Tertullian is the earliest instance of the apocryphal tradition in which John was thrown into boiling oil in Rome in an unsuccessful attempt at execution. •• Prae. 21.4 (CC 1.202) . " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 107 founded Churches. The apostolicity of persons or offices is totally subordinated to the apostolicity of what it is they are commissioned to transmit. 39 The structures of the local Churches are not the masters of this doctrine but its servants. They are not its makers, but its witnesses and purveyors. 40 In fine, Tertullian's arguments are not an appeal to structures of authority, but an historical appeal to the preservation of the apostolic preaching in the public teaching of the Churches founded directly or indirectly by the Apostles. The basic structure of doctrinal authority, the episcopate, was already in place. Papal and conciliar structures developed from it. Yet the episcopate is still viewed as subordinate to and controlled by the teaching it has received from the past. III. In the approximately 230 years separating the two related works of Tertullian and Vincent of Lerins, the whole world was transformed and turned upside down. The Western empire, for Tertullian the bulwark holding off the end, 41 now was in disarray, divided up among barbarian invaders. Christianity, the once suspect and hounded sect, had become the official religion of the empire. Wracked by dissension in the Arian and Donati.st controversies as well as by a host of lesser contentions, it nevertheless could boast of having enjoyed the devoted service of most of the leading minds of late antiquity. Throughout the trials of the fourth century, the Church had envisaged its task in exactly the same way as always: to preserve and hand on intact the deposit of faith. But at the same time, there had been considerable developmental growth in the structures and offices of doctrinal authority, notably the monarchical episcopate in its divergent forms as manifested in the Roman primacy and the ecumenical council. By the time of the Council of Ephesus (431), the conciliar structure had become the prin•• F. Refoule, Traite (SC 46, Prae. 6.3-4 (CC 1.191). 41 Apologeticum (CC 40 Dekkers). 108 ROBERT B. ENO cipal means of confronting serious and widespread doctrinal disagreements. Augustine, who died in Hippo as preparations for the Council of Ephesus were being made in the East, apparently attributed supreme authority to this organ of the Church and the bishops. In his lengthy debates with the Donatists, Augustine was faced with the embarrassing task of admitting that Cyprian had been wrong in his views on the re baptism of heretics. Yet he attempted to exculpate the great African hero-martyr, at least partially, by recalling that the question in his day was still basically an open one. Since Cyprian's time, a plenary council had spoken and the consensus of the Church had been made clear, thus depriving the Donatists of any excuse or of any further justification for carrying on the old practices. 42 Individual authors may err, local councils may be wrong. All must give way to the authority of plenary councils. 43 Augustine wrote in the context of trying to show that, however exalted Cyprian's position in the African Church, his opinion could not be considered infallible against the decision of the Church as a whole expressed in later plenary councils. While Augustine's statement about later councils correcting (improving?) earlier ones is much disputed, his views of the plenary council as having a final authority are clear. What is not clear is what he means by a plenary council. He states that earlier plenary councils have "often" been corrected by later ones but when Augustine wrote (c. 400-1), only Nicaea was commonly accepted in the West as an ecumenical council in the modern sense. Obviously what we mean by an ecumenical council cannot simply be equated with Augustine's "plenary" council. Some thirty-three years after Augustine's De Baptismo and Augustine De Baptismo 1.18.28 (BibAug 29.116-120. Paris, 1964). Augustine De Baptismo 2.3.4. (BibAug 29.132-4). On Augustine's views on councils, see: F. Hofmann, "Die Bedeutung der Konzilien fiir die kirchliche Lehrentwicklung nach dem heiligen Augustinus" 81-89. (in) J. Betz and H. Fries, hrsg. Kirche und Uberlieferung, Freiburg, 1960.; more recently, H. J. Sieben, "Zur Entwicklung der Konzilsidee" Part 4: Augustine and (for what follows) Part 5: Vincent. Theologie und Philosophie 46 (1971) 364-386; 496-528. 42 43 " ECCLESIA DOCENS " 109 in the wake of the council of Ephesus, Vincent, a monk of Lerins, an island off the coast of S. Gaul, wrote the second work of interest to us as one of the few ancient treatments dealing explicitly with the questions of doctrine, orthodoxy and authority. Not without a certain irony, it has been suggested that the work was discreetly but pointedly aimed at Augustine and his supporters. Feeling that Augustine in his declining years had gone too far in his writings on grace and predestination, Vincent, the argument goes, brought up the cases of Origen and Tertullian to assert that however great any individual author, he is not guaranteed immunity from error. Yet so great was Augustine's reputation after his death that this polemic had to be carried on without so much as a mention of his name. 44 In any event, the solution to the question of Vincent's view of Augustine is no part of this essay. Depite the more than two centuries separating them and the developments of these two centuries, there is a surprising continuity between Tertullian and Vincent. Like Tertullian, Vincent is aware of the difficulties of relying on Scripture alone for settling doctrinal disputes. The same text is interpreted in quite diverse fashions by different people. In fact, heretics are very zealous in their insistence on Scripture. The heretic will scour the Scriptures to present thousands of examples and testimonies to support his own ideas. They are well aware that this is the surest way to ensnare the innocent and the gullible. 45 Like Tertullian, Vincent knows that something more is needed beyond the authority of Scripture. This something extra is basically the Scriptures as interpreted by the tradition of the Church. 46 44 For a negative view on this question, see: W. O'Connor. "St. Vincent of Lerins and St. Augustine" Doctor Communis 16 (1963) rn3-257. 45 Vincent of Lerins. Commonitorium (ed. by Adolf Jiilicher, Tiibingen, 1925) 2, 26, 25 (Jiilicher 3, 42, 39). 46 Comm. 29 (Jiilicher 46); "Non quia canon solus non sibi ad universa sufficiat, sed quia verba divina pro suo plerique arbitratu interpretantes varias opiniones erroresque concipiant, atque ideo necesse sit, ut ad unam ecclesiastici sensus regulam scripturae caelestis intelligentia dirigatur." 110 ROBERT B. ENO Vincent had much more history to look back over than did Tertullian. It is not surprising then that there is less direct and obvious reference to the Apostles in Vincent. Yet, once again, the basic argument of both Vincent and Tertullian is the same, though expressed differently. Tertullian had taken, as a basic axiom, the temporal priority of truth over truth's counterfeit. The original must predate its imitation. Vincent's more sophisticated appeal to antiquity, universality and consent rests on the presumption that the authentic tradition is ancient and error is novel. In Vincent, too, the apostolic is there as the basic datum but because the time of the Apostles is so much more distant, the reaching back is that much more tortuous, the dangers that much more numerous and subtle. With the usual presupposition that the Apostles have handed down the teaching of Christ whole and entire and that it is the task of each Christian generation to do exactly the same, Vincent outlines his solution of how this is to be accomplished. Scripture does not interpret itself. Such interpretation must be directed " according to the norm of the ecclesiastical and catholic sense." 47 In short, one must cling to that which has been taught ubique, semper and has been accepted ab omnibus. This alone can be considered truly and properly Catholic. New and questionable developments are ruled out by the requirement for antiquity. False teachings which may give the impression of antiquity will be eliminated from consideration in a restricted area. The Christian must eschew the craving for novelty and cling to the " tradita et recepta semel antiquitus credendi regula." 48 Vincent begins his work by speaking of the doctrines handed down by the ancestors and deposited with us. These doctrines, however, are not simply entrusted to individuals. The Church is to be " the loyal and careful guardian of what has been entrusted to her." 49 Is this any different from Tertullian? Basi"Comm. 2 (Jiilicher 8). ' 8 Comm. 21 (Jiilicher 81). • 9 Comm. 28 (Jiilicher 86). " ECCLESIA DOCE'NS " 111 cally, no. The Catholic of Tertullian's time, after all, was not left on his own. Specifically he was directed to consult the Churches founded by the Apostles. For Tertullian, what the Apostolic Churches taught was traced back to the Apostles. There was a de facto consensus among all these local Churches at any given time although they did not through their representatives come together to express it formally. For Vincent, this appeal has been replaced by a more formal mechanism. Instead of the simple appeal to antiquity and universality, there was an historically more verifiable appeal to consent as expressed in the councils. If there arises some question about error in antiquity, the inquirer will .seek out the decrees of a previous ecumenical council to solve his doubt. These councils have not decreed anything new; rather they have made more clear or explicit what had been believed before confusion was introduced by the wiles of heretics. The authoritative decrees of such councils, basing themselves on the faith of the Fathers, fix and make more definite the regula fidei. It is not lawful to scorn such conciliar decisions. 50 Vincent's vocabulary demonstrates the development and importance of these structures of doctrinal authority. In times of heretical attack, the teachings of the past are in danger: " superiorum instituta violantur . . . rescinduntur scita patrum ... " 51 In contrast to these rather vague terms, Vincent with growing frequency speaks of the translated as "a piece 0£ grammatical knowledge" (Cooke), " a certain point 0£ grammatical knowledge " (Edghill) ) is in a subject, the soul, but is not said of any subject; and the individual white (To 'l"t A.evKov "a particular whiteness" (Cooke), "a certain whiteness" (Edghill)) "is in a subject, the body (for all colour is in a body) but is not said 0£ any subject" (la26-9). Precisely what is intended to be marked out by this definition and the examples given is controversial, and several recent journal articles have been devoted to this question. We shall consider the point in a moment, but will be content now merely to agree with Ackrill (p. 74) that Aristotle refers here to "individuals in categories other than substance." The remaining two classes are concerned with species and genera. (a): "Some [things] are said of a subject but are not in any subject. For example, man is said 0£ a subject, the individual man, but is not in any subject" (la20-3). And (c): • Whether these two expressions are equivalent in meaning is controversial. Hamlyn, "Aristotle on Predication" Phronesis, VI (1961), p. 113, and Ackrill, see a Aristotle's Categories and De lnterpretatione (Oxford, 1963), pp. 76, difference; J. M. E. Moravcsik, "Aristotle on Predication" The Philosophical Review, LXXVI (1967), p. 85, n. 11, holds that Aristotle does not keep a two expressions, distinction by use of 138 EDWARD REGIS, JR, "Some are both said of a subject and in a subject. For example, knowledge is in a subject, the soul, and is also said of a subject, knowledge-of-grammar (Tfjs ypaµ,µ,anKf}s)" (la29-b2). To simplify matters, we will hereafter substitute for " species and genera " the term " universal." 4 Summarizing, then, the results so far, we have the following fourfold division of reality: Individuals ( d) primary substances (b) qualities, quantities, etc., Universals (a) universals said of, but not present in, subjects ( c) universals both said of and present in subjects Two problems are evident at this point. One is the ascription to Aristotle of the doctrine of individuals in categories other than substance, that is, members of class· (b) , for this doctrine has recently been branded a " dogma," and dismissed. The other is that class (c) appears to be in flat contradiction to the conception of universals that we impute to Aristotle in this paper. For we hold it to be his view that universals exist only in the mind and not in things, whereas class (c) is said quite explicitly to be made up of universals which are " in a subject." We can attack these problems together, for they are very much intertwined. The thesis that class (b) is not composed of individuals in non-substance categories has been propounded by G. E. L. • The substitution is clearly legitimate. It is a matter for discussion only because Ka06"11.ov, the term translated by " universal," does not appear in the lines we have been discussing, nor, indeed, anywhere in the Categories. The term does not have a history prior to its being used by Aristotle, and is a crasis of Karil. 5"11.ov (lit., ' in respect of a whole,' or perhaps as a whole,' or 'taken generally'), which is used by Plato in this sense at Meno 77a, and Republic 392de. The term coined by Aristotle is defined by him and used characteristically to mean 'that which is predicable of many,' cf. Metaph. 1023b29-32, lOOOal; De Int. l 7a38-b2. It is likely that it was used first by Aristotle in the logical works where it is employed regularly in the sense of universal proposition. In any case it is clear that inasmuch as a species and genus denote kinds or types of things, and hence are predicated of many, it will be appropriate to subsume them under the more general term " universal." ARISTOTLE ON UNIVERSALS 139 Owen,5 in a paper which has elicited much criticism. 6 We will not attempt to catalogue here the arguments which have already been given for and against Owen's thesis; rather, we limit ourselves to seeing whether the texts which Owen himself advances against the traditional interpretation of class (b) can be made consistent with that interpretation. In the process we hope to show in what sense it is true that universals can be spoken of by Aristotle as being in a subject when in fact all that is in a subject is particular. Against the traditional view of class (b) Owen offers the following texts: I: "knowledge is in a subject, the soul" (lbl-2) II: "colour is in body and therefore also in an individual body; for were it not in some individual body it would not be in body 'at all" (2b2-3) These texts, Owen thinks, " settle the issue " ; that is, they show that members of class (b) are not individual. For ready reference we quote again Aristotle's formulation of this class: III: "the individual-knowledge-of-grammar is in a subject, the soul, but is not said of any subject; and the individual white is in a subject, the body (for all color is in a body), but is not said of any subject" (la26-9) If I and II can be made consistent with III when III is understood in the traditional way, then Owen's argument will collapse. Assume, then, that III is to be taken in the traditional way. What meaning can then be attached to the phrase in parentheses: a'Tl'av yap xpwµa f.v cr Koiv6v) of all our subjects of investigation-if e.g. they are animals, we lay down what the properties are which inhere in every animal 7To/,a 7Tavrl 'iii'P 1Yrrapxn An. Po., 98al-5, Mure tr. some [characteristics] which are common to all things that have a share in life [are] waking and sleep, youth and age, inhalation and exhalation, life and death, De Sensu, 436al2-16, Hett tr. The common characteristics are observed, not necessarily inferred, to be in things: "We must collect any other common character which we observe (a),J...o 'n oavracria is neither sense-perception (428a5-16), nor scientific knowledge nor intuitive reason (a16-18) ... and that it may be either true or false" (ibid.). But imagery may play the role we assign to it here quite in spite of these facts. For even though imagination is not scientific knowledge or intuition, it may nevertheless be operative in the formation of these. For sense-perception itself is not scientific knowledge or intuition but the account in An.. Po. is very definite that senseperception is nonetheless a requirement of scientific and of intuitive knowledge as well. As for the possible falsity of images, it is surely difficult to see how a process which issues in infallible knowledge can make use of other processes which are themselves fallible, but the fact is that memory is explicitly said (at An. Po. 100a3-6, cf. Metaph. 980a27-8lal) to be involved in the genesis of the primary axioms, and it is fallible also. (This is implied by the distinction between good and bad memories (De Mem. 449b5-8, 453a32-b8), and by its dependence upon images (ibid., 450a10-11); further, it is said to belong" to that part of the soul to which imagination belongs" (ibid. 445a24) .) According to Ross the imagination is a disability because it is " due ... to the eclipse of reason by passion, disease or sleep in man," (op. cit., p. 39) . But in the sole pas.sage to which Ross appeals for support of this view, De An. 429a6-8, Aristotle does not say that the faculty is " due " to these phenomena, but only that men "frequently act in accordance" with images as a result of these causes. This does not mean that imagination may not be valuable in the genesis of knowledge. 15 Returning to An. Po. we find that frequent repetition of such persistence, which we now take to mean: frequent repetition of images, gives rise to memory. 16 This interpretation is at least 15 Contrast Ross himself in Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford, V. I, p. 116 on Lesher, pp. denies that Aristotle holds awareness of first principles to be " infallible." 16 lOOal-4, cf. Metaph. 146 EDWARD REGIS, JR. partially confirmed by De Mem.: "Memorizing preserves the memory of something by constant reminding. This is nothing but the repeated contemplation of an object as a likeness, and not as a thing in itself." 17 The dependence of memory upon imagination is stressed: "memory, even of the objects of thought, implies an image." 18 Aristotle makes an even stronger claim: " it is impossible even to think without an image." 19 We may pause at this point to ask what is the relation, if any, between images and memory on the one hand, and common properties inhering in individuals on the other. The answer is that it is just those individual properties common to many individuals which are the objects of perception and remembered in the form of images. Sensation puts us in contact with qualities of individuals, 20 and these qualities will be individual in any given instance of perception. Inasmuch as images resemble sensations, it follows that they would have to be as individual as the qualities of which they are ' mental pictures.' Universality does not exist at the level of sensation, 21 nor, therefore, on the level of images. Where, then, does universality first exist? On the level of memory? It seems that the universal does not exist yet on this level. 22 For at 100a4-7 the universal is described as being "in the soul," but that is already the level of experience (eµ,7TEtp£a). Further, since memory is simply " the retention of an image as a likeness of that of which it is an image" (De Mem. 451a14-16), it would follow that since images and what they resemble are individual qualities, that this is all that is remembered as well. The universal, then, is not yet present at the level of memory. From memory arises experience: " repeated memories of the 45la13-14. 450aU-13. 19 449b31-50al, cf. De An. 432a7-10. 20 De An. 418al3-14. 21 An. Po. 88a2, 87b30-33. 22 This is in contrast to Ross' account, Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1949), pp. 677-8. 17 18 ARISTOTLE ON UNIVERSALS 147 same thing give rise to experience; because memories, though numerically many, constitute a single experience " (An. Po. 100a46, Tredennick tr). This is the level at which it is definite that the universal exists in the soul, £or in experience there is " the whole universal come to rest in the soul, the one alongside the many, which is one and the same in them all." 23 When Aristotle speaks of " repeated memories of the same thing" does he mean the numerically same thing? 24 In view of the fact that induction is regularly described as dealing with particulars rather than with a particular, and is usually illustrated by many particulars which have some feature in common, 25 it .seems unlikely that Aristotle means to restrict " the same thing " to one and the same individual. Indeed, it would be difficult to extract a universal, which is common to many, from a single individual. How then does the universal arise in experience? Perhaps in this way: The several memories, each of which is composed of an image representing some individual attribute of a previous perception, are all memories of some common characteristic. When one object, image, or memory is perceived alone and by itself, all that is perceived is individual. But when the many memories, representing common attributes are perceived, as it were ' together,' and the fact of their commonality is apprehended, this is experience, and the specific form in which the commonality is realized is the universal. The universal, then, is an intellectual apprehension, realization, or experience as a whole of the common attributes which exist apart in many individuals. This is the meaning of lOOal 7-bl: "though the act of sense-perception is of the particular, its content is universal." Is this interpretation consistent with the ' rout in battle ' 23 100 A 6-8: 7ravT0s 1,peµ-l}uavTosToV Ka86Aov Ev Tfi lf!vxfi, ToD €v0s TrapO. re\ 7roi\A&, Ev'fi EKelvois rb aVr6. a Clv Ev ChraUlV 24 As thought by Apostle, Aristotle's Metaphysics 1966), p. £55, comm. 6. 25 Top. 105al3-17, 108bl0-11. (Bloomington and London, 148 EDWARD REGIS, JR. metaphor and the ' clearer ' account of the whole process given at 100a15-b4? The battle metaphor is intended to provide an analogy to the way in which ai €gcii;, the ' states of knowledge' just described, viz. memory, experience, and the universal, develop out of sense-perception, yiyvovmi d:iro alafJ'ljaewi;, lOOall. The analogy is this: there is a military formation which is broken by a retreat; but then one man stops retreating, then another, and another, until the original formation has been taken up once again. This is picturesque, but not very informative. Aristotle explains it at 100a15-b4: ..ov. This can only refer to the level of experience: what stops is a universal, which exists first at this stage. 26 Perhaps the universal corresponds to the common attributes in individuals as the formation before the rout corresponds to the one after it. Or perhaps' the intended parallel is with the common attributes as represented by images in the memory. The analogy is not close and cannot be pressed closely with complete success. It is possible that the ov aacpwi; at 100a15 is intended to warn us of this. The parenthetical remark at 100a16-bl is disturbing. The assertion there that " perception is of the universal " (Ti 8' ataOT)at<; roil Ka86Aov eariv) is contradicted earlier (88a2) : " there is no perception of the universal " (ov yap roil Ka86Aov ataOTJaii;), and the reason for the latter is clearly given: granting that perception is of the object as qualified, and not of a mere particular, still what we perceive must be a particular thing at a particular place and time. A universal which applies to all cannot be perceived by the senses, because it is not a particular thing or at a given time ... (87b30-33, cf. 34). Indeed, Aristotle insists again and again that only repeated perceptions of individuals can give rise to a universal, for example Top. 108b10-ll: "it is by induction of particulars on the basis 26 Ross, Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytic, p. 677, holds that the ' standing still ' is " of an individual before the memory" ; Lesher, p. 61, holds that an infimae species is meant. ARISTOTLE ON UNIVERSALS 149 of similarities (e1Tt TWV oµofow) that we infer (atwvµev) the universal" (cf. An. Po. lOOal-6) .27 Lesher, for these reasons, holds that " it is simply false to say that the universal is present in the soul from the first perception of the individual." 28 But perhaps this problematical assertion (as well as the similar claim at 100b4-5) is to be understood in the light of the earlier (lOOal0-11) explanation (which is in fact the clearer account, in spite of the ov