THE THOMIST A SPECULATIVE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY EDITORS: THE DoMINICAN FATHERS OF THE PROVINCE OF ST. JosEPH Publishers: VoL. 41 The Thomist Press, Washington, D. C. JANUARY, 1977 No. 1 A CHRISTIAN REFLECTION ON MARTIN HEIDEGGER* A THE ENCOMIUM S ONE who pondered Martin Heidegger's writings, who had the great privilege of studying under him in Freiburg, who was considerably influenced by his type of thinking, and who has actually written, lectured, and given courses on him, I am honored to offer this testimonial, written on the occasion of his 85th birthday, to the man and his thought. Germany has meant a great deal indeed to the world in every aspect of civilized existence-scientific, scholarly, educational, technical, industrial, artistic, musical, religious-including even Orientalism, perhaps Germany's greatest single achievement *EDITORIAL NoTEs: Martin Heidegger died at Freibnrg im Breisgau (Germany) on May 1976 at the age of 86. I was privileged to know him personally and to attend his funeral. He was buried in Messkirch, his native town (not far from Beuron), near his parents. His nephew Father Heidegger, a priest of the archdiocese of Freiburg, took care of the funeral rites as the late philosopher had wished. A member of the Faculty of Catholic Theology at the University of 1 CHARLES H. MALIK has been in the realm 0£ fundamental thought, otherwise called philosophy. A cultured German may or may not have any particular avocation, but it is impossible £or him not to be in love with ideas, not to be philosophical. It would appear that, when it comes to the deepest and most creative thought, one is either German and therefore Greek in his thinking, or one is outside the pale 0£ this particular fraternity 0£ the spirit, with all that it has concretely meant in history. I say" German and the1'efore Greek," because this original Greek flame has passed on to the Germans more than to any other people, and they have abundantly honored it. In all universities 0£ the world more philosophy is taught today that stems originally from the Greeks or from the Germans than from any other people. It is therefore fitting that we meet to honor, while he is living, a man many consider, and I certainly believe to be, the greatest German philosopher 0£ the twentieth century, and Freiburg, Monsignor Bernhard Welte, professor of Christian philosophy of religion, gave the eulogy in which he drew special attention to the never ending search for truth in Heidegger's life. JOHANNES QUASTEN Catholic University of America Honorary Professor: University of Freiburg Charles Malik delivered this critique of Heidegger's thought over a year before his death in an opening address to a symposium held at the Goethe Institute in Beirut, Lebanon, on the occasion of Heidegger's S5th birthday. That address, subsequently modified and amplified, is here printed in its entirety. The flowing style of Malik's rhetoric contrasts sharply with Heidegger's dense, hyphenated prose, to which our readers are perhaps more accustomed. We believe that Malik's critique will be of Bpecial inteI'est to them, however, first as a testimonial to Heidegger, and secondly, as offering the reflections of a devout Christian on the alternative possibilities, so much discussed by scholars in our times, either of Heideggerizing theology ur of theologizing Heidegger. Dr. Malik, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the American University of Beirut and former President of the General Assembly and of the Security Council of the United Nations, is eminently prepared to give a critique of this type. He did his doctorate in philosophy at Harvard under ·whitehead before studying intensively under Heidegger at Freiburg, and so understands well the intricacies of both process and existentialist thought, as well as what each has to offer the development of Christian theology. REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 3 one of the greatest thinkers in all German history. Such statements may appear to lack responsible reserve; often they sound romantic and sentimental; but all sentimental romanticism about the present one disappears once you subject yourself to a real Heideggerian treatment. Secondly, I want to seize this happy opportunity to express my humble gratitude to Martin Heidegger himself, my honored teacher, for all that he meant to me personally in my life. In his memorial address at the celebration in 1955 of the 175th birthday of the composer Conradin Kreutzer, Heidegger said that "the master's presence in the work is the only true presence," and that "the greater the master, the more completely his person vanishes behind his work." You will certainly find Heidegger in every sentence and every word he has written or uttered: you can as it were infer him back from his written or spoken words, because his spirit, his fundamental attitude, what is goading him, his boundless wonder at Being, he himself, marvelously animates and shines through all his articulations. His own doctrine of discourse is that it is only the articulation of an already existentially articulated Dasein. Of course his writings are difficult, very difficult. Some have held them the most difficult of all German philosophy, and that is saying something indeed if you know how difficult German philosophers are, for instance, Kant and Hegel. But after a while, if only you are patient with him and enter into his thinking with the spirit of love and expectancy, you will overcome this initially forbidding feature of his philosophy; in fact in time you will love it, seeing in it a sign-an unavoidable one-of the immensely difficult problems with which he is wrestling. What is more, you will find it a model of simplicity and clarity, because he is talking only about that "in which we live and move and have our being," which, because it is so close to us, we have been missing all the time. When I reach this stage of understanding of Heidegger I can read him faster than any newspaper. You do not prescribe ahead of time, as for instance did Descartes, conditions on Being that it should 4 CHARLES H. MALIK turn out to be simple, neat, fluent, clear, familiar, distinct, uncomplicated, undemanding, before it reveal its secrets to you; you may then be distorting the character it will reveal. You are grateful for whatever mysteries it may deign to disclose to you from its womb, regardless of any onerous demands it may rightly make upon your understanding. In Sein und Zeit Heidegger justifies his plethora of new terms and new constructions on the ground that " not even the grammar " needed for his task had been created before. Heidegger therefore is his works in the triple sense that he ventured forth on an exceedingly rough terrain to pioneer and explore, that he had to devise entirely novel modes of exploration and novel forms in which to couch his findings, and that the discoveries, or rediscoveries, he was thus granted are immensely important and valuable in themselves as well as for the confused, ungrounded and " lost " thought characteristic of this age. And on all three counts I am deeply grateful for what I learned from him. But a man really is never quite his works; this is especially true of creative thinkers. Their works, no matter how much they consume themselves in them, are at best a distant reflection-and a very distant one at that-of their personal crises and sufferings, not to say a "changing of the subject from," or a covering up of, or a fleeing away from, these crises and sufferings. For Being, especially personal existence, simply is, and can never be expressed in works of any kind. The crises could be in terms of life and destiny and being, or they could be in terms of concepts and thought alone; and even the latter are always ultimately reducible to the former. In the case of Heidegger they could never be of the latter type only. The rarefaction of life and death and destiny and being into concepts is the prerogative of the philosophers; that is why the saints and Nietzsche saw through them totally; they read back, sometimes rather rudely, their life and death and destiny and being from their rarefied concepts. When Nietzsche says there was no philosopher-psychologist before him who penetrated to the innermost depths of the philosophers and caught them red- REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 5 handed in the very act of covering up and escaping from themselves, he was quite right. But the saints were philosopherpsychologists too, who caught the philosophers red-handed exactly as Nietzsche did; yet with this difference, that whereas Nietzsche judged them in terms of a criterion-a worthy redblooded criterion-he had in his own mind, the saints came out of themselves and quite simply allowed Jesus Christ to judge them himself. Because they came out of themselves and allowed Christ to do the judging, it would seem that the saints are more capable of judging Nietzsche, the judge, himself than he was of judging them, eternally wrapped up in himself as he was to the very end. So the saints and Nietzsche would tell you that no man is really quite his works, least of all perhaps the philosophers, whose powers of covering up are simply fantastic. Thus a glimpse of the existing man Heidegger can better be acquired from his seminars and lectures than from his writings. Although perhaps better than his writings, this access to the man is still woefully inadequate; we need prolonged intimate acquaintance, we need friendship, with all its informality and playfulness and fun, before we can know-before we can discover-one another. I was not privileged with such closeness to be able to say that I know the personal being of the man or to verify my reading back of this being from his writings, or even from his seminars and lectures. But my experience in his seminars and at his lectures was singularly rewarding. The seminars dealt, one with Leibniz's Monadology and one with Schelling's philosophy of freedom; and one set of lectures treated Kant's Critique of Judgment and another tried to answer the question: _Was ist ein Ding, What is a Thing? Limited and inadequate as these two modes of nearness to the man were, I was nevertheless privileged to behold in them something that I have never forgotten and will never forget. In the lectures there was absolute preparedness; nothing was left to chance or to improvisation. Always at the beginning of each lecture we were reminded of the gist of the argument up to that point, so as to establish the connectedness of the thought of the lee- 6 CHARLES H. MALIK turer; and the body of what was delivered was articulated in such a novel and striking manner, and the voice (and this stands out most in my memory) had .such a tone and ring about it, that I felt I was in the presence of the highest integrity and seriousness. In the midst of the lecture certain statements would often fall from Heidegger's lips which I took to mean something very personal to me. Not that he was thinking in the slightest of me or of anybody in particular, or even was aware of my existence in the lecture hall, but the statements themselves were of such nature that I felt they applied to me directly, and always, alas, unfavorably. I recall distinctly one such incident. One morning I happened to read the account in the Gospel in which Christ tells the Syro-Phoenician woman, in the coasts of Tyre and Sidon, who was desperately appealing to him for help for her daughter who had an unclean spirit, that he was not to squander away his powers on strangers, but "let the children first be filled: for it is not meet to take the children's bread, and cast it unto the dogs." The woman, wholly overcome by the tragedy in her family, would not take no £or an answer; so she exclaimed: "Yes, Lord: yet the dogs under the table eat of the children's crumbs." Whereupon this quality of faith so amazed Jesus that he granted her forthwith the crumb she was asking for, the cure of her daughter. Wholly in the mood 0£ this story I then went and entered the hall in which Heidegger was to lecture. In the midst of the lecture one sentence, which I do not now remember at all, suddenly hit me. I found myself exactly in the position of the Syro-Phoenician woman. Although Heidegger was talking solid existential stuff, he was talking in general. Yet I interpreted the message to mean: Who am I to understand what is being expounded, indeed to be worthy of understanding it? Who am I to have claim for the wonderful spiritual fare that was being dealt us, with such amazing lavishness and profundity? I picked up a crumb here and a crumb there. Crumbs are like seeds which take a lifetime to germinate and bloom. I thank the seed and the sower, and I thank all who REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 7 had before helped in preparing my soil for the reception of the seed, as well as all who later watered it in my life. But above all I thank him who was behind me, behind the sower and seed, and behind the waterers, and who gave the increase. I took a sort of voluptuous pleasure in this feeling, because there is nothing I hate more than fraud and falsehood and sham, and it is this that I loved most in Heidegger's philosophy of Eigentlichkeit and Uneigentlichkeit. Therefore to have whatever fraud there may have been in me uncovered gave me a triple satisfaction: firstly, because it was uncovered; secondly, because the uncovering was effected by Heidegger; and thirdly, because it was effected philosophically, that is, at a distance, without knowing me. The fact that I interpreted these statements as convicting me personally, while knowing that Heidegger knew nothing about me and could not possibly have been thinking of me as he made them, I kept a close secret to myself; and such guarded secrets whereby one's possible shams are exposed to him without anybody knowing it always produce a genuine catharsis in the human soul. At the end of the lecture Heidegger would gather up his papers and quietly leave the room, invariably to the spontaneous applause of the audience; he had said his word and would not loiter for involvement in any public discussion, for any silly questioning after he had squeezed dry his soul bordered on sacrilege. This I admired immensely, and ever since I have always coveted leaving the room in which I lecture or speak by the back door, literally without seeing or talking to anybody, including those closest to me, for three hours. But alas this fervent prayer of mine has never been granted, to my infinite sorrow. And even the suffering of this ungratified wish, unmurmuringly suffered, purifies. The seminars were a much more intimate affair. There were 37 of us in them from all over the world. We were all handpicked by Heidegger himself. I was coming at the time from my discipleship under Whitehead at Harvard and so he was kind enough to include me. Heidegger would ask the more ad- 8 CHARLES H. MALIK vanced students to prepare and read at the beginning of each session what he called " protocols," that is, brief condensed treatments, lasting for about 15 minutes, on some theme we were studying, which would then be thoroughly questioned by him and by us. The scrutiny to which the protocol-readers were then subjected was most searching. Heidegger himself in the exposition of some text would focus sometimes for hours on a single proposition, a focusing onto which we the students would be thoroughly drawn at every step. He would bring to bear on that proposition the entire history of philosophy and much besides of the experience of other facets of Western civilization. He would show how the matter before us had its genetic roots way back in the Greeks, what transmutation, if any, it underwent in the Middle Ages, and how it received its :final formulation, say, by Leibniz. Those moments of prolonged dwelling on a single sentence and bringing to bear on it all that went before constituted the most valuable experience I had under Heidegger. They were moments of sheer joy. In them time simply stopped and we were ushered into the presence of eternal essences; or, much better, time appeared in the guise of epochs and cultures and essential positions and decisive turning points, and had nothing to do with the day-by-day linear succession of events-so that Heraclitus, for instance, far from " being" " before " and " behind " Descartes, would in this sense " be " considerably " after" and " ahead of " him. The infinite care and respect for his students, the infinite attention to detail, the quiet and grace of his gestures and movements, the depth and extent of his knowledge of the history of philosophy, his mastery of Greek and Latin and of the living European languages, his passion for what was being considered, his power of telescoping almost everything into that single sentence, all this was absolutely extraordinary. It was total love for men and subject matter that possessed Heidegger, love wholly unaffected and unconscious. And the fruit of this prolonged, leisurely concentration, of this loving dwelling, was always the self-releasement of truth. In the seminars I felt I was not just picking up REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 9 a few crumbs here and there from under the table. I felt I was participating in the banquet itself. For all this that I owe Martin Heidegger, as well as for the lasting profit I got from reading and entering deeply into his writings, I am deeply and eternally grateful. He has already been blessed in his lifetime with the knowledge that he is universally recognized as the most important thinker of our day. I pray that God grant him many, many more years of peace, vigor and happiness, to the end that he continue creating in thought what God still wants him to create. HEIDEGGER I Sein und Zeit is Heidegger's masterpiece. I have spent more time in the study of this book than of any other, with four exceptions: the New Testament, the Book of Psalms, the principal works of Whitehead, and the principal dialogues of Plato. This book made a lasting impression on my mind. The phenomenological method, with its imperative " zu den Sachen selbst," to the things themselves, and therefore with its own infinite tender care in "handling" these "Sachen," with its interpretation of the phenomena this " handling " yields, contrary to Husserl's interpretation, as states or modes of being and not-being and nothing less, opened my philosophical eyes as no other method had done. I became existentially transparent to myself. I saw these 70 or 80 .structures fully constituting every other Dasein: The fundamental distinction between man, on the one hand, and tools which one uses and adjusts to one another as well as things on which one just stares, on the other. The fact that man's essence is his existence, so that man is precisely that being whose being itself is its very problem. The radical difference between categories and existential modes of being. The fact that we are always in-theworld. The fact that we are always concerned with this or that thing, including above all and behind all our very being and notbeing. The notion of encountering (begegnen). The hiddenness or concealedness or covered-up-ness of truth. Discourse as grounded in existential self-articulation. The fact that Dasein has always 10 CHARLES H. MALIK made some sort of decision. The fact that Dasein is its possibilities and nothing more or less or else. The fact that we are always ahead of ourselves in our plans and projects, so that we never catch up with ourselves until death catches up with us once and for all. The fact that Dasein exists either authentically or unauthentically, and that we exist authentically only when we concern ourselves with our ownmost possibilities, and every other mode of being is dreaming and escaping and silly talk. Our happy-go-lucky everyday mode of existence in which all distinctions are averaged up or leveled down or blurred, and in which we take no firm stand. The existential spatiality of man, so that far from man being in space in the sense of being contained in space, space itself is contained in man and man himself is spatial. The concrete notion of the environment (Umwelt). The fact that there is a primordial existential knowing in which all perception, scientific knowledge, determination of nature, etc., are grounded. The fact that we are always living with others (Mitsein). The pregnant phenomenon of" das Man," " the ' they '," which to Heidegger is, if I may say so, the very devil himself, to which however we are always subject. The notion of solicitude (Fursorge). The fact that we are always" there," always outside ourselves and always outside others. Being there as mood and being there as understanding, so that we are always in some mood or other and we always understand something or other. The fact that we gossip no end. The fact that our idle curiosity knows no limits. The fact that we are usually undecided and therefore ambiguous, so that if, as we said, we have always already made some decision, the decision we have made here is to be undecided and vague. The fact that our essence is care (Sorge), so that we are really full of cares all the time. The difference between anxiety and fear. Death and how we are essentially towards death all the time, although this is also all the time covered up by our everyday mode of existence. What it means existentially to be towards death (Sein zum Tode). The being of death in our life being our living it in our limitations and anxieties. How we are our true selves only in resoluteness (Entschlossenheit), only when, facing our death, we put aside all childish distractions and dreams and throw ourselves wholly upon our ownmost possibilities, no matter how humble and unpretentious. Conscience as the call from unauthenticity to authenticity of being, a call which our own care-ful existence makes upon us: a gnawing or sudden "pulling ourselves together" into decisiveness and being. The sense of guilt as the being of the what- REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 11 might-have-been, especially if the call is from our silly distractions to our real possibilities of being which we have neglected. The fact that, since by deciding we always destroy possibilities, we are always essentially guilty by the being of these destroyed possibilities in our being. How time-past, present, future-is grounded in our essence as care, and as mood and understanding. How thus a temporal character adheres to every existential structure of Dasein, to everything we have exhibited so far-mood, for instance, being somehow mixed up with the past, understanding with the future, gossip and "das 'Man'" with the present. A critique of the traditional notion of time, especially with Aristotle and Hegel. How we are essentially historical, and how the possibility of writing history, historiology, is grounded in the historicality of the historian. Exactly what this existential historicality consists of, an.d a critique of the notion of world-history. I know I have barbarized Heidegger, and I apologize for that. It is impossible to appreciate the full impact of Heidegger without personally going through Sein und Zeit from beginning to end several times. But these and countless other existential phenomena are carefuly worked out and articulated with and into each other in this great work. This is man, this is Dasein, this is you and I. When one thus gets thoroughly Heideggerized one refuses thereafter ever to admit any theory or doctrine without an authentic certification as to how it is integrally grounded in human existence. Man is the measure of all things not accidentally, not capriciously, not individualistically, but essentially and in a structurally existential sense. HEIDEGGER II The later Heidegger, or Heidegger II as he is sometimes called (and there are some who detect even a Heidegger III), tried to go beyond Dasein and to come to grips with Being in general, but without departing-so far as I can judge, and despite the turning, the Kehre-from the fundamental existential analytic of Dasein in Sein und Zeit. Both at the beginning and at the very end of this book he emphasizes that the existential analytic was only "preparatory " for this task CHARLES H. MALIK of going beyond, inasmuch as " philosophy is universal phenomenological ontology, and takes its departure from the hermeneutic of Dasein." He therefore considers Sein und Zeit as only " enkindling" the problematic of ontology and therefore as being only "on the way." One may therefore say that the Kehre, far from being a departure from or reversal of Sein und Zeit, is already presaged in that work. The fundamental distinction between Being and beings is of course retained throughout. The quest is for the meaning of Being-nach dem Sinn von Sein. But Existenz in the sense of Dasein gives way to Being, and we hear more of thinking, Denken, than of phenomenology. Indeed phenomenology would appear to be only one way of thinking, and thinking now becomes the way to Being. And yet we must keep in mind the statement I have just quoted that after all "philosophy is universal phenomenological ontology." According to this position, then, when thinking-meditative, besinnliches Denken, I mean-puts us in touch with Being, be it the Being of poetry or art or philosophy or science or the world situation, we are then also in the immediate presence of phenomena, namely, of what ultimately grounds all these things ontologically. The themes which now fascinate Heidegger include, among others: The concrete historical situation. Such disclosure of Being as destiny-laden great poetry, for example that of Holderlin and Rilke, vouchsafes. The tremendous historical phenomenon of Nietzsche as completing or closing the chapter of modern metaphysics: namely, in Nietzsche, through Nietzsche, and since Nietzsche modern metaphysics beginning with Descartes and reaching its full bloom in Kant and Hegel is finished. The possibility of the opening up of a new age in philosophy based on Heidegger himself, with his emphasis on man, Existenz, Being and meditative thinking. The radical disturbance, if not perversion, which modern ruthless technology creates and promotes in Being, and the grounding of this whole disturbance in something that happened to the human soul way back in the beginning of the modern era, an event which found REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER its philosophical expression in the misfortune that was Descartes, whereby reality is reduced to objects, and our attitude to it is dominated by calculative thinking (rechnendes Denken) with a view to self-assertion, control, prediction, use and exploitation, rather than by love and adoration with a view to dwelling respectfully and hopefully beside it. A deep lamentation over the fate of modern man, who no longer has any sense for the holy and divine, to whom God is dead or has defaulted, from whom the gods have departed, leaving behind them no trace or track leading back to them, with the poor poets the only people left in this destitute time to try desperately, perhaps with the aid of the ether which the wine-god still affords, to unearth a trace here and sniff out a track there. All this with a profusion of terminology every bit as arresting and rich and evocative as that of Sein und Zeit, a terminology designed solely to put us in the presence of Being, including the Being behind such terms as: Ground and origin. Nature and world. Life and fullness. The slow growth or maturation of nature. Appropriate and inappropriate. Mortals and immortals. Heavenly and earthly. Beast, man, angel. The quadruple manifold of earth, sky, divinities, mortals, mirroring each other. Forces all around us, drawing us. The draft of this drawing. The unheard-of center of these drawings. This unheard-of center being " the eternal playmate " in the world-game of Being-so there is a game going on. Venture and daring. Flinging beings loose. Flinging into danger. Hazarding oneself. Hanging in the balance. Unprotectedness, unshieldedness. Destiny and fate. Man the merchant. Absence, abyss, Nothing. This destitute time. The world's night and the mid-night of this night. The dying world era. The coming world era. Calculative thinking (rechnendes Denken). Meditative thinking (besinnliches Denken). The self-assertive will, the will to will. Noblemindedness (Edelmut). The poets, the sayers. The song. Dwelling, building, thinking. Thinking, meditating, suspending judgment, asking questions. Persistently questioning because one suspects a hidden meaning beyond and underneath. Stepping back, keeping a distance. Lingering at, stopping at, loitering by, dwelling, being near to. Listening, waiting-not waiting for but waiting upon. Silence, stillness. The Open. Openness to the mystery (Off enheit fur das Geheimnis). Releasement (Gelassenheit). The clearing of truth. Regioning and that which regions. Uncanny (unheimlich). Direct encountering, encountering without mediation. Presence and presencing. 14 CHARLES H. MALIK Turning, conversion. The already, the beforehand, the apriori, the "schon," the condition of the possibility of. Art heralds history, starts history, but only after the artist has undergone a transformation in his own being. Language the precinct, the house, the temple of Being. The road, the path, the way, various stations on the way. This is only a random sampling from Heidegger's later terminology. The expressions are all basic and technical. The germs of most of them can be detected in Heidegger I, though not in the context of the sweep here manifested. Also some of them he owes to Holderlin and Rilke, and when he meditates on them he loads them with meanings of his own which one is not quite sure were in the minds of the poets. In fact this is his doctrine of great poetry-to sense out Being and invest it with words which the philosopher can then meditatively think through and adopt as his own. This random listing only serves here to point to the domain or "region" of Heidegger's later concern, and here and there it suggests perhaps something of the flavor of that concern and of its findings. It is a separate task to show how Heidegger's thought throughout, especially in the later phase of his thought, is essentially determined by a species of pantheistic-monistic-theosophical mysticism, deriving originally from Meister Eckhart and the coincidentia contradictorum of medieval German mysticism, which so fully impregnates all German thought. In this connection I only wish to remark that if you remove this basic dialectical strain from German thought, which harkens back to German mysticism and beyond it to Pseudo-Dionysius of the sixth century (that strange, obscure and most important figure, who was probably a Syrian) , very little will be left, at least as to the distinctive flavor and cast of this thought. The characteristic unity and essential continuity of German thoughtwhat one might denote as the typical Germanness of that thought-is integrally grounded in the peculiar genius of medieval German mysticism. It is like a gigantic creative bud, gigantic not in the sense of size but in the sense of potency, fully self-enclosed, all its own, that took centuries to unfold and REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 15 bloom. Bloom indeed, into a thousand different blossoms; and just as Aristotle keeps on affirming that although all beings are, being is not a genus, so there is no genus comprising these thousand blossoms, save only the fact, which is not a generic characterization, that they all somehow stem from the original mystical bent of mind of the coincidentia contradictorum. This is all a separate task. But the more typically Heideggerian of Heidegger's passages sound very much like the language of the great sufis and mystics, such as Jalalud-Din al-Rumi and Joa'l of the Cross. In many of his more passionate moods one clearly senses a " flight of the alone to the Alone " a la Plotinus. The "ineffable One" mysteriously hovers all over. I know I have here again barbarized Heidegger, and I apologize for that. To compensate a little for this barbarization I wish to insert here a few short lines of poetry by him. The world's darkening never reaches to the light of Being. We are too late for the gods and too early for Being. Being's poem, just begun, is man. We never come to thoughts. They come to us. Three dangers threaten thinking. The good and thus wholesome danger is the nighness of the singing poet. The evil and thus keenest danger is thinking itself. It must think against itself, which it can only seldom do. The bad and thus muddled danger is philosophizing. He who thinks greatly must err greatly. We may venture the step back out of philosophy into the thinking of Being as soon as we have grown familiar with the provenance of thinking. Thinking's saying would be stilled in its being only by becoming unable to say that which must remain unspoken. 16 CHARLES H. MALIK Such inability would bring thinking face to face with its matter. What is spoken is never, and in no language, what is said. That a thinking is, ever and suddenlywhose amazement could fathom it? Forests spread Brooks plunge Rocks persist Mist diffuses Meadows wait Springs well Winds dwell Blessing muses APOLOGIA FOR A CRITIQUE I passionately share Heidegger's passions and convictions: his love for nature and his fascination by its moods; the recreation of his being through walks in the fields and forests-to me they are walks in these wonderful valleys and hills or along these great historic shores; his emphasis on roots and rootedness; his doctrine of dwelling, abiding, resting, being near, stepping back, being at a distance; his insistence on openness to the mystery; his doctrine of releasement toward things; his trust in the lighting of thought; his sensitivity to the prophetic power of great poetry; his faith that truth is there waiting only to be unconcealed; his patient waiting on Being; his teaching that Being ventures forth man, flings him out, into danger and unshieldedness; his doctrine that we are always in the balance; his horror of the debasing and dehumanizing of man by modern technological civilization; his groaning at the midnight of this night; his critique of the Cartesian aberration; how a single thought at times perhaps after long waiting and suffering in the twinkling of an eye flashes in our being with such overpowering force and conviction as to take us a day, a month, a year, sometimes a lifetime, and in the case of our unutterable recurrent longing for Being more than a lifetime, to develop and make fully our own; his conviction that there have been peaks REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 17 in history, including Aristotle and Plato and Kant and Nietzsche, in which truth cried forth more truthfully than in history's fallow plains; his fundamental historical-personal question: Whither man at all, and especially whither man today? My gratitude to Heidegger in confirming and deepening me in these and many, many other positions knows no bounds. But all this bespeaks to me Jesus Christ. Heidegger's themes almost wholly coincide with those of religion and theology. In attending carefully to Heidegger, religion and theology spontaneously spring forth in one's mind. One says to oneself, the man is discussing religious-theological subjects in his own way. Heidegger's fundamental topics-man, the human condition, the historical situation, destiny, death, Being, truth, existential distortion and falsehood-what are these but very topics of theology itself? One can thus establish two columns, one containing the 100 or 200 basic terms of Heidegger, and the other their equivalents in theology. This would be a separate undertaking. The two realms almost overlap, but there are notable exceptions, the most important of which are: Jesus Christ, the Holy Spirit and the Church. There are no equivalents for these beings in Heidegger's thought, nor for the others, such as grace, faith, communion, resurrection, which flow from them; and if equivalents were pointed out or devised, it would be in a strained and farfetched and wholly unauthentic way. But I doubt that there is any topic in Heidegger that is not originally considered in theology. A profound decision appears to have been taken in the mind of Heidegger to reduce theology to immanent human thinking. He boldly takes over and treats the themes of theology, but he steers strictly away from any entanglement in or contamination by Biblical, theological, Christian meanings. He transforms all these meanings into human existence and self-revealing Being. In his plenary maturity which man has now attained, man can dispense with all the Christianly intended meanings. Thus when Heidegger refers to Augustine and Pascal, for instance, he is most careful to select the Christianly neutral elements of 18 CHARLES H. MALIK their thought, passing by on the other side of what they would consider the essence and source and ground of their thoughtthe discovery of Jesus Christ in their own lives and in the world. And when he gives an example in Sein und Zeit of what he calls Dasein's pre-ontological way of interpreting itself existentially as Sorge (care), he chooses an ancient fable on cura (care) attributed to one Gaius Julius Hyginus who flourished ,at the end of the first century B. C. While the fable is very interesting and suggestive, Heidegger could have chosen another " £able " from the Old Testament which, I think, suits his purposes perfectly, I mean the account in Genesis 8 of the consequences of man's disobedience and fall; there is here as much Sorge as Heidegger can possibly want (perhaps there is too much!) , but he would not choose it because it comes from the JudaeoChristian tradition, and it seems he wants to have nothing to do with this tradition. It is a sort of fundamental existential oath which Heidegger has sworn to himself ahead of time, way deep down in his being. In many places you ask yourself, if only Heidegger would come out with what he wants to say in plain theological language, with all the concrete personal commitment that this would involve, it would be much better; but in vain do you wait upon that" coming out." There is a built-in fundamental inhibition which prevents him from doing so. Phenomenological description and meditative thinking and their findings completely replace theology and religion. Just as Kant affirmed the autonomy of the kingdom of reason from all experience, so Heidegger wishes to affirm the full autonomy of man (meaning always the thinker) from all Biblical or theological or ecclesial conceptions. The problematic of religion is indeed very real, but as the Bible and the Church hold an archaic, that is, pre-ontological or ontologically ungrounded, view of man, being and time, what they were talking aboutthe most serious matters indeed, Heidegger would aver-need not be cast in terms of their own conceptions at all. Even their experience on which they base their conceptions is something now over and finished, and in any case it admits of another REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 19 interpretation. A new conceptual language based on strict ontology and thought can be devised, fully comprehensible by our understanding and fully adequate to all the themes of the human condition. We may therefore say that Heidegger is the detheologizing of theology-not the destruction of it, but the detheologizing of it-, that is, the secularizing, the humanizing, the intellectualizing, the ontologizing, the immanentizing, of it. For, I repeat, the same themes so dear to theology proper are frontally attacked by him, but in the attack they are denuded of any traditional theological content. That is the significance of the two columns to which I referred. Heidegger is theology, but without God, and certainly without the revelation of God in Jesus Christ. God and revelation can be dispensed with-and that in the interest of the truth of God and revelation themselves. What is left is the truth about man and Being in its ontological purity. Since Heidegger's thought is thus thoroughly theological without owning it, or by owning it in the guise of covering it up, or attempting to salvage the truth of theology without theology, a theological critique is fully justified. One does not write "a theological critique " of Marx or Russell or Dewey or Bergson or Wittgenstein, because these thinkers had nothing to do nwterially with theology, and that despite the Deux Sources in the case of Bergson. But one does write " a theological critique" of Heidegger because the subject matter of Heidegger is the very subject matter of theology, though camouflaged in a non-theological dress. Heidegger of course would presumably say that the subject matter of theology is itself the very subject matter of fundamental ontology, though camouflaged in mythological, pre-ontological terms. The difference however between the two claims is obvious: theology proper deals with the existing God of faith in his historical dealings with specific existing individuals and groups-Abraham, Moses, David, Jeremiah, Christ, Paul, Augustine, Chrysostom, Aquinas, and others, and the children of Israel and the Church of J e.sus Christ, the two most historically continuous communities with distinct ex- 20 CHARLES H. MALIK elusive universal claims, as existing historical communities, in the world, so unbroken and continuous in fact that mankind today dates all its history in terms of their own historical reckoning. Whereas the claim of Heideggerian ontology that theology is only camouflaged or mythologized ontology is the claim of a single philosopher or school of thought (a very important philosopher and school) having no relation, so far as this claim is concerned, to an existing, historically continuous community with exclusive universal claims. Heidegger's presumable claim about theology moves in the sphere of concepts or what Heidegger would call thought; theology's actual claim about Heideggerian ontology grounds itself in the sphere of historically continuous existing communities. I am not interested here in showing that this or that Heideggerian equivalent of this or that theological concept is not as rich or " true " as its equivalent, or is a distortion of this equivalent. This, of course, can be done. Nor am I concerned with pointing out this or that saying or perhaps lapse in Heideggerand there are many such sayings and lapses-which leaves room for positive traditional theology; for if he intended the filling out of such room he would have done so himself. Nor indeed is it my job here to "complete" or replace Heidegger's untheological theology with the authentic Christian way of looking at things. I believe this Christian way is the true way, and will long survive Heidegger's way or any" new era" of metaphysics built on Heidegger or Nietzsche. A man is ultimately himself; he is what and who he is; this is his fate, his Schicksal, on which Heidegger keeps harping; and I happen to love Heidegger for what and who he is, and to find in him, and in Nietzsche, the greatest untheological reminders of true theology-most welcome reminders indeed, considering who the reminders are and the fact that they come, at least on the surface, from outside theology proper. I only wish to make a few general observations which I trust will go to the heart of the matter, especially to the fundamental existential oath to which I adverted. I speak from the strict Church-Biblical-Christian point of view, REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER which I know and which I existentially hold. We are facing in Heidegger a non-Semitic, non-monotheistic, non-Abrahamic "theology"; Islam and Judaism therefore would just as much take exception to this "theology," especially in the matter of transcendence, as would Christianity; we are facing a form of heathenism by way of an atavistic reversion to medieval German mysticism and pre-Socratic cosmologism-fully brought up to date, to be sure, through phenomenology and the distinctive genius of Heidegger. I make my observations in a tentative and preliminary manner; I make them with fear and trembling, and with the deepest respect and love for Heidegger. THEOLOGICAL QUESTIONING First I wish to repeat what I stressed above that Heidegger is essentially theological in intent and content. Any fundamental interest in existence and being is theological. The entire problematic of his philosophizing would have been impossible as to its content without the basic theological data which he received from his own tradition and culture, regardless of how he purged them in the process. He owes this tradition, thoroughly Judaeo-Christian (in its ontological-transcendental reference) no less than Graeco-Roman-German (in its intellectual-mystical reference), more than he acknowledged, at least so far as the Judaeo-Christian component is concerned. Secondly I wish to stress what I called above the fundamental existential oath that Heidegger took upon himself. Why he should have taken this oath, never, in the elucidation of man, Being and destiny, to implicate himself thematically and explicitly in Christian subject matter, is a mystery to me. Was it really necessary to hold so tenaciously to this position? Is it " truth " that he is thus serving, and what kind of " truth " ? Is he not unnecessarily depriving and therefore impoverishing himself of material that would have added infinitely to the richness and concreteness of his thinking and description, perhaps a hundredfold more than he could possibly get from even such great poets as Holderlin and Rilke? Openness to the mystery CHARLES H. MALIK should mean openness even, or perhaps especially, to the mystery of Christ, the Church and the Bible. Why should it exclude these? His answer presumably would be that the ChurchBiblical-Christian subject matter does not belong to his historicality. This answer may be true personally, but certainly not so far as it may apply to his Germany or to this age in general, no matter how destitute and forlorn this age may be. The Church, the Bible, Christ, are living and active in Germany and Europe, and on every theme he touches upon they have something to say, and something very decisive. But even personally the answer is questionable if we keep in mind Heidegger's background, culture, concrete spiritual rootedness, and immense learning. Therefore a decision somewhere in the dark recesses of Being must have been taken. Nor would I dare explain this decision, though explanations can be thought. I would not attempt an explanation partly because all explanations of such great mysteries are more questionable than the matter to be " explained " ; partly because the explainer in this instance would have to be explained himself, or to explain himself; but principally because of my deep respect for Heidegger. But I note here only the existential oath as a striking fact, and raise the ultimate anguished" why?, why?" about it. Only Heidegger himself can " explain " the mystery of this oath being taken "in the dark recesses of Being." Heidegger's transformation of Christian theology into strict untheological ontology is wholly incapable of achieving three things, even if it achieved everything else perfectly. The first is meeting the question of creation and origins. The Christian view is that God created the world, meaning man and Being and thought and everything, " visible and invisible," from nothing. This is a firm and straightforward position, without the slightest equivocation, to be understood only from within the context of the theological affirmation of God's existence and nature. But to the sophisticated and self-confident philosopher it may appear naive, dogmatic, hollow, empty, even superstitious, certainly unphilosophical, at best "pre-ontological." REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER Heidegger touches upon " God " and " nothing " in this Christian position (in Was ist M etaphysik?) and makes of God the question itself (which with him must always mean the questioner), and of "nothing," "something" as "Nothing," that is, as " Something " which is God himself. This is equivalent either to breaking up God (whether as man or Being or something else) into two, and that is the ancient question of the coeternity of matter and the world with God, or, on the supposition that God is only the question, to making everything in the end come literally from nothing (" nothing " this time in the most absolute and literal sense; i. e. precisely not " something" in any sense of the term) . This latter possibility is either a species of magic or the well-known modern doctrine (cf. Whitehead and Sartre, noting at the same time the essential differences between the two) of everything being its own creator. Karl Barth analyzes and comments on Heidegger's treatment of Nothing in Was ist M etaphysik? (Church Dogmatics, Vol. III, Part 3, Chap. XI, Art. 50, Sec. 3) . He concludes that " in Heidegger nothing is actually the pseudonym which conceals the Godhead." Barth continues: We have already seen that [according to Heidegger] the basic question of metaphysics as wrested from nothing is why there is anything at all and not nothing. We have seen the underived and comprehensive dynamism and activity of this nothing: how it actually compels, obtrudes, repels and nihilates; how it can never be discovered by us, yet reveals itself in dread as the basic mood of existence; how our existence itself is a projection into nothing and is constituted by our enquiry into it; how to be open to nothing is the fundamental virtue of existence, and " distortion " of nothing its fundamental sin; and finally how even that which is, is only as nothing pervades and is present with it, and discloses itself to existence only as it becomes elusive and evanescent. We have seen that it is nothing that exhibits the nature and mode of that which is, and the fact that it is. We have seen that it is the whence and whither of transcendence, the basis and pure content of human science. We have seen that "pure being and pure nothing are one and the same " [Hegel's formula]. Must we not say that just as it is irrelevant that Sartre explicitly denies the existence of God, His place being taken and filled by man, so it is irrelevant that CHARLES H. MALIK Heidegger does not explicitly deny it, His place being fully and finally taken and filled by the all-dominant and dynamic depth of nothing? We might easily say that if Sartre were not to deny God, and Heidegger to deny Him, it would not modify in either the essential fact that God is not dead, but that a substitute is provided and therefore He is suppressed, and put as it were " on the retired list." Heidegger differs from Sartre only in choosing a different substitute for God: " My cause on nothing is founded." But in his teaching this substitute has actually arrogated the place and function of deity. Thus his doctrine, too, is really a mythological theogony .... In Heidegger's thought, nothing seems lacking in none of the essential features of the conventional figure of God (aseity, uniqueness, omnipotence, omniscience, infinity, etc.), but nothing has of course no relation to the biblical concept of God, which is not taken into account by either Heidegger or Sartre in their respective mythologies. It might well be said, then, that the God of the Bible, the living God, is entirely unaffected by the suppression and pensioning off of " God " in terms of these two mythologies. In the " God " whom Heidegger and Sartre suppress by providing a substitute for Him, the Church cannot possibly recognize the One whom it calls God. . . . From the standpoint of the biblical conception of God these alternative postulates ... are only mythological fabrications ... This quotation from Barth calls for five observations: (I) For a variety of reasons Sartre cannot be compared with Heidegger; this Barth is quite cognizant of. " Sartre contrasts with the ponderously reflective German Martin Heidegger as a type of the perennial French debrouillard." Again, Heidegger "has not mastered this factor, scil. nothingness, [as Sartre thinks he has] neither does he trifle with it. He handles it with religious solemnity. The effect which he produces is therefore immeasurably more serious than that of Sartre." (2) Barth's real point, regardless of whether or not his comparison of these philosophers is legitimate and the extent to which it is legitimate, is to prove (and he does so at some length) that neither the Frenchman nor the German has really faced, let alone understood, the nothingness which the Bible calls " the depths of Satan " and " the deceitfulness of sin." Real nothingness is the lie and deceit of Satan and sin, and of this the two REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 25 philosophers have no knowledge, or if they have, then it is sup· pressed knowledge. Thus the nothing or nothingness of either philosopher has nothing to do with, is indeed (in Sartre) a child's play or (in Heidegger) heaven itself compared to, the awful nothingness recognized in the Bible from which Christ has once and for all delivered us. (3) The Hegelian identification of being and nothing, which Heidegger adopts but reinterprets, is simply another indication of the gnostic-mystical coincidentia contradictorum which lies at the deepest base, which indeed constitutes the characteristic genius, of all German thought, including especially that of Hegel and Heidegger. (4) Heidegger's mythological theogony, whether based on being or on nothing, or on the identity of the two, cannot serve as an adequate doctrine for creation and origins. Independent external existence, of things (yonder snake) an dof others (that man-you, he), which is more primordially given and far more certain than any phenomenological disclosure of anything, including the disclosure of nothing by dread, cries to high heaven for the independent cause, source, ground, origin of its being and its order, beyond every conceptualization and every idealistic (e.g., Kantian) doctrine of causation. One can theogonize or mythologize or indeed phenomenologize no end, but it will be a strange kind of heart which will then think that it has thereby explained or understood the mystery of independent external being and independent external order. (5) I come now to the fifth observation. No man, certainly no philosopher, is without some god whom he ultimately worships. Worship is a fundamental phenomenon; worshiping is an original mode of being of man, every bit equiprimordial with understanding or gossip or being-with-others or dread or dying or any other fundamental existential structure; and someone should develop the phenomenology of worship in the strictest phenomenological manner-a manner that only a Heidegger can prove equal to. No man is without something which he trusts more than anything else. To Sartre it is he himself, to Heideg- 26 CHARLEs H. MALIK ger it is nothing; to the materialist it is matter (or so he says), to the dialectical materialist the class struggle, to the revolutionary revolution, to the naturalist nature, to the hedonist pleasure, to the idealist the idea or reason, to Aristotle substantial individual existence. It appears then that one of the deepest characteristics of man is to search and to keep on searching for something to which he can finally cling. In this respect men do not differ in that some cling to something and others to nothing; all cling to something; and even when they call it nothing; as here in the case of Heidegger, they invest this nothing with the attributes of deity. In other words, they worship it. In this sense no man is an atheist: the atheist himself believes in and worships something. The only question is whether the ultimate thing people worship is true or falsetrue or false in the sense of being the true God or a sham, an idol. Whatever and whoever be the god of Sartre or of Heidegger, certainly he is not the God of the Church or the Bible. You do not get rid of God by simply rejecting him or remaining silent about him-you only succeed then in replacing him by another god, a false one. You can no more evade God than you can evade being; for if you exist at all, you are necessarily worshiping something or somebody, whether true or false; and of course your heart's deepest desire is that it be true. In the case of Heidegger it is of course an oversimplification to say that the God whom he invests with the attributes of deity and therefore whom he worships is the Nothing of Was ist Metaphysik?. Throughout the range of his writings one is struck with the fact that his god changes from one writing to another and from one period of his life to another. Sometimes you feel it is Being, sometimes Dasein, sometimes the future, sometimes death, sometimes authentic existence, sometimes phenomenology itself, sometimes metaphysics, sometimes philosophy, sometimes thinking (rather the meditative type), sometimes sheer mystery, sometimes a certain ineffable harmony, sometimes the allpregnant Nothing. Aristotle would probably say these are Heidegger's gods in differing senses, for God, like being, is not REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 27 a genus. This polytheism of Heidegger, if I may so call it, is of a piece with his principle of equiprimordiality which he stresses so much in Sein und Zeit. His metaphysical situation is pluralist; the ultimate principles, to which would perhaps correspond the ground phenomena, are many-none subordinate to any of the others, all on the same footing metaphysically. There is in Heidegger a deep-seated heathensm which is simply another term for searching and groping, whether before finding or after having found. The Kehre only typifies it. Sincere as he is, the only question is whether he will land, or land again, where he ought, or whether his fate in this regard is already sealed. However, with God-I mean the true one-nothing is impossible. Heidegger lacks a metaphysical doctrine of causation, and to say that his rejection of Aristotelian time carries with it the necessity of rejecting Aristotle's concept of causation is no answer; for the why?, why? persists. No man has asked questions, and especially the why?, more insistently than Heidegger, with the possible exception perhaps of Socrates. His pages are strewn with questions. Sein und Zeit begins with a question and ends with one, and in between perhaps a thousand questions are thrown in. To say that after the self-revelation of Being, whatever that may be, any further questioning is silly, is no answer. Why Being at all and not rather nothing?, as he exclaims in Was ist Metaphysik? Nothing, nothing ("nothing" here with no dialectical-substantive connotation whatever) can quench the wonder of man at Being-not even Being itself. Hence always, always, whence and whither Being?. You do not rest after you know the human situation in its fullness; you do not rest in the knowledge of this situation: you become even more restless. In fact your real restlesness begins just then. Why?, why?, why? keeps on maddeningly knocking on your soul-why? both ontologically and personally. Ontologically, in the sense of Why Being at all and not rather nothing? (Being always in the Leibnizian sense of the independent external existence of the monads and the independent external order or harmony reigning fl8 CHARLES H, MALIK in them and among them), and personally, in the sense of why these sufferings and disappointments, why these frustrations and trials?-including the hatred and envy of men, including ageing and death. A doctrine of creation and causation is lacking in Heidegger. When one strains his powers here, one usually speaks of the abyss (Abgrund) as somehow relieving one of the necessity of providing such a doctrine; but such a mode of speaking is either to repeat the question itself, thinking that in the mere repetition of it an answer is given, or to lapse into some kind of dark mysticism, unsupported and unillumined by the living concrete, independent, personal God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, the Father of Jesus Christ. * * * * * This is the problem of the ultimate why? But secondly there is the problem of the ultimate which? Man is his possibilities, and the Being of his possibilities is understanding: this is certainly true. But I am always before a range of alternatives to choose from; which of these possibilities must I throw myself upon, what is the principle of my choice? The only hint at an answer I find in Sein und Zeit is the related doctrines of authentic existence, Dasein's ownmost possibilities, resoluteness, and the voice of conscience. But suggestive and helpful as these doctrines are, they are nevertheless largely formal and subjective. I certainly know only too well in my own life how, when I fritter away my energies in softness of living, in idle curiosity and petty talk, in stupid and sterile seductions, conscience calls me back resolutely to my real, authentic possibilities of existence; and when I then throw myself wholeheartedly and undistractedly on my ownmost task, no matter how humble and unglamorous, I am in the fullest sense of the term. But usually we are presented (apart from death, which we hardly ever think of choosing) with more than one ownmost possibility; thus there is freedom of choice not only between authentic and unauthentic existence, but between modes of authentic existence itself; in such a situation we lack a criterion of choice. The conflict of duties is a perennial feature of existence. Moreover, what is the REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 29 ownmost possibility of, say, a gambler or a degenerate person? The gambler will tell you his owmnost possibility, the thing he can do best, is to gamble, and the degenerate person to wallow in degeneracy. Thus to avoid radical subjectivist relativism, which I am sure Heidegger would never allow, a criterion of choice from outside man altogether is required. Heidegger affords no such criterion from outside, or for that matter," from inside." At times it looks as though I just close my eye.s and toss a coin. There is in Heidegger no doctrine of preferential valuation, no doctrine of better and worse, except the formal injunction about resolute, authentic existence. To say that this is a matter of cultural determination, of upbringing, of environment and society, of family background, either lapses back into relativism or leaves unanswered what determines the better and worse in all these situations. Heidegger owes his Christian culture in this matter of the valuational determination of conscience more than he explicitly admits. The Christian answer is that the better is what accords with the will and spirit of Christ. The Christian answer goes farther: it holds that all decisions are ultimately judged by the standard of Christ, whether or not the decider knows it; and when he hesitates and weighs, saying to himself, this is better, this is worse, it is the immanent Christ in him which is weighing thus, whether or not he knows Christ or whether he has ever heard of him. All mankind in every decision it takes is implicitly or explicitly under the judgment of Christ. Those who were groping for the right decision before his actual appearance in history, as well as those who are groping for the right decision outside him today, are nevertheless all groping for him; and, after the decision is taken and it turns out to be right it can always be .shown that it is right because it conforms to the standard of Christ. The criterion " from outside " is always Christ. The Christian holds all this in the simplicity of his heart, and that is why it appears so questionable and absurd to the outsider. Christian theology, certainly based on faith, can answer the question of the which? Heidegger cannot. 30 CHARLES H. MALIK The ultimate why?, the decisive which?-these Heidegger cannot answer. Neither can he answer the question of the how? or the what? I may call this the problem of realization, but since reality as commonly understood is rejected by Heidegger-and I accept both his criticism here and his rejection! shall call it the problem of "bringing about" or the problem of "becoming." How do I become existentially what I want to be even .supposing I possess a perfect criterion which enables me to know unerringly what it is? To raise the famed question of old: Is knowledge virtue? Can the idea by itself bring about itself? I am fed up with my wishy-washy being; I cannot stand my softness and flabbiness and ungenuineness any longer; I am disgusted with my being given to gossip and idle curiosity, and with my lostness in " das Man " ; I am unbearably weighed under by such and such a bad habit which I have contracted, and often I shed tears because of my bondage to it; I cannot sleep at night because my conscience keeps calling me to resoluteness and authentic existence; I can decide perfectly and correctly, but I canot bring about what I decide. Heidegger's powers of presencing Being and beings-almost stealthily, as it were, without Being and beings noticing it (for instance all these modes of being of myself which I have just enumerated) is simply uncanny; but he is powerless to suggest how I may bring about my heart's innermost yearning. He has no idea, nor in the nature of the case can he possibly have an idea, as to Paul's anguished cry: "0 wretched man that I am! " This is an observation that applies indeed to all philosophy and to all thought, but in the case of Heidegger, as of no other philosopher, the question of becoming and bringing about cries to high heaven, because his primary interest is in Being. An interest in Being, no matter how genuine (and Heidegger's is not only most genuine but most fruitful) , that is yet satisfied only with description, no matter how perfect, but that does not bring about the deepest personal Being we crave, has something profoundly the matter with it. It raises itself as a problem unto itself. Most certainly knowledge i.s not virtue; most certainly REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 81 the devil all of a sudden intervenes and spoils everything, even the most perfect knowledge. The Christian's answer is again Paul's: " thank God through Jesus Christ our Lord." That is, Christ, prayer to him, participation in his worship, the wonderful sacred music of the Church, the Bible, the lives of the saints, living my ordinary Christian life, helping to carry the burden of the Church, getting out of myself to help others at any cost for the sake of Christ alone, letting his grace and spirit dwell in me despite my unworthiness, performing all sorts of little or big acts of sacrifice " in secret " so that my " Father which seeth in secret" might "reward me openly," the living fellowship of those who love me in Christ, their forgiveness, their faith in me despite my failings, their going out of their way to help me for Christ's sake, the actual existence of the Christian community, the actual love of Christ manifesting itself in a thousand different ways around me and in every phase of civilized existence in the world and throughout history-all these things help me mightly to bring about what I want. This is the Christian how? of the becoming or the bringing about of the what? IMPLIED CONSEQUENCES These are the questions of the why?, the which?, and the how? or what? that Heidegger cannot answer. Now to some consequences. Heidegger is really loading philosophy with much more than it can bear. Calculative thinking which he deplores and condemns when it tyrannizes over man can never by itself, nor even by philosophy, give rise to meditative thinking. Heidegger can call attention to both types of thinking, he can describe them superbly, he can yearn for the conversion of calculative to meditative thinking, or at least for both to be kept in their right place without either usurping the province of the other, but neither he nor all philosophy put together can bring about this conversion or prevent this usurpation. This is a gift from outside man altogether. Man is helpless here. To put it this way is of course to wound the pride of self-sufficient CHARLES H. MALIK man, especially the pride of the philosopher, to the quick. "The fear of the Lord is the beginning of wisdom "-and not meditative thinking. This thinking itself is impossible without that "fear." Does self-sufficient Western man today understand that? " Except the Lord build the house, they labor in vain that build it; except the Lord keep the city, the watchman waketh but in vain." Western self-contained immanentist thought has no idea what this means. Truly it comes to it from outside itself altogether, like a strange unintelligible voice from another world. It " speaks in an unknown tongue." That is why it took the love and suffering and patience of countless believers for hundreds of years to convert pagan Europe to begin to understand what this voice is saying, what this tongue means. And now Europe, on the word of some of its greatest thinkers, wants to return to its paganism and to turn a deaf ear to this voice. The problem of calculative versus meditative thinking is nothing compared to the problem of the calamitous divorce between faith and the intellect which has been afflicting the very soul of Europe and the West for centuries, and the latter problem is certainly at the base of the former. If death is Dasein's ownmost possibility (eigenste Moglichkeit) , and of course it is, then despite the fact that the voice of conscience would, as resolute anticipation of death, call us back to our authentic possibilities from lostness in the world of " das Man," we are never totally whole except in death. There is a possibility here of opening up suicide as a way outI say only a possibility, because I know Heidegger's answer to this possibility. But the mere possibility disturbs the Christian. For it is written, thou shalt not kill, and suicide is killing. Nay more, thou shalt not kill is superseded by Christ's law, thou shalt not even be angry with thy brother without a cause. This anger which is a form of hatred is itself killing. The point is that there is a rule from outside Dasein in Christianity, a rule which, as coming from outside, ontology would of course hate or be angry with; and in the radical ontological aloneness of Dasein according to Heidegger one is reminded of the proud REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 88 self-sufficient aloneness of the Stoics, and therefore of their recommending suicide. On the plane of concrete existence there is the saddest aloneness in Heidegger-I do not mean in his life, I mean in his thought. Love would perhaps mean to him the tranquillization of " das Man." But we are only by love, which is much more than and radically other than simply to state the matter in these words. No man has ever been or will ever be except insofar as love, at least the love of his parents or of somebody, has touched him. In Christianity the essence of everything about man is society, company, fellowship, friendship, interaction, belonging together, the ecclesia, koinonia, community, love, the Holy Spirit. These are all absent from Heidegger and his treatment of Mitsein is the poorest substitute for them, even ontologically speaking. One moment of genuine openness and trust and peace and communion in love is worth all the certitude and all the discoveries of the most authentic thought. This is a phenomenon and not an obfuscation by "das Man." May it not be, from the existential point of view, that because for whatever reason we are denied the Being of communion and love we fall back upon the Being of thought and get stuck in it? The certitude of thought, even the most authentic and creative thought, is a poor substitute for the peace and joy and " understanding " of the fellowship of love. This is the Gospel's reaction to philosophy, this is Jesus Christ's challenge to Plato and Aristotle aml all philosophy and thought. I cannot possibly read Heidegger without all the time inwardly suspecting that he knows all this as well as anybody. And yet there is something that holds him back, that inhibits him, from openly coming out with what he knows and feels. It is as though he is ashamed of it. Consider those gems of poetical insight which Heidegger embodied in his " The Thinker as Poet" from which I quoted above. We are told the inspiration came upon him When the early morning light quietly grows above the mountains, When the little windwheel outside the cabin window sings in the gathering thunderstorm, 34 CHARLES H. MALIK When through a rent in the rain-clouded sky a ray of the sun suddenly glides over the gloom of the meadows, When in early summer lonely narcissi bloom hidden in the meadow and the rock-rose gleams under the maple, When the wind, shifting quickly, grumbles in the rafters of the cabin, and the weather threatens to become nasty, When on a summer's day the butterfly settles on the flower and, wings closed, sways with it in the meadow-breeze, When the mountain brook in night's stillness tells of its plunging over the boulders, When in the winter nights snowstorms tear at the cabin and one morning the landscape is hushed in its blanket of snow, etc. There is beauty here, there is peace, there is quiet, there is nature, there is the pensive mood, there is the joy of inspiration, there is the sweetest nostalgia. But there is the saddest and deepest solitude. I see no trace of inspiration coming from having looked another person in the eye; from will that has been tried and tested by another will in act; from having quarreled and argued with another face to face; from the living trials of loving friendship; from having shared with others; from having personally participated in some responsible social or political decision in which more than the fate of one's thought was at stake, in which perhaps the fate of a whole people, a whole culture, a whole movement, a certain turn in history, was in the balance; from having stood in awe at the mystery of independent external personal existence in communion. I feel in Heidegger at times a most heart-rending loneliness, whatever its causes and attendant sufferings, a loneliness painfully reminiscent of that of Holderlin, Nietzsche and Zarathustra. I need hardly add that this loneliness in no way invalidates the profound truths it has yielded. But the heart cannot rest in solitude; it craves company, communion, love. Communion is indeed in every respect prior to solitude. Now certainly there " abideth thought, solitude, communion, these three; but the greatest of these is communion." H there is heaven in this life or beyond, it does not consist in musing on the early morning light, or the gathering thunderstorm, or the little windwheel REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 85 outside the cabin, or the wind grumbling in the rafters of the cabin, or the lonely narcissi, or the butterfly of the mountain brook, nor in the reflections which these musings evoke in us, but in the fullest active communion of soul with soul in total transparency, trust and love. Nor may we forget that Christian theology had to break up God into three Persons so as to relieve His otherwise unsupportable loneliness with the possibility of inner communion and love, not within an absolutely undifferentiated One, but between three Persons. I certainly am passing judgment on thought and philosophy as such, and not only on Heidegger, when I say that I cannot help contrasting the thinker's lonely responsibility for his thinking alone with the responsibility of, say, a Socrates or a Paul, or Christ himself, who articulated their thoughts in the midst of (or at least as a result of) concrete personal life-anddeath confrontation and suffering, in the midst of giving themselves in face-to-face encounter to others, in the midst of uttering nothing except to save others from the powers of darkness, " the sorrows of hell and the snares of death." A similar contrast exists, although on quite a different plane, between the lonely thinker and the politician or statesman or administrator, no matter how purely or impurely motivated, who finds himself caught in the midst of concrete historical responsibility and decision, affecting, perhaps fatefully, the whole course of events. Thought is not everything, and what it is not may well be the more important thing. With all the wonders of Kierkegaard and Nietzsche-personal wonders, existential wonders, spiritual wonders, intellectual wonders, especially the incredible wonders of Nietzsche-what finally judges these two men is their utter loneliness. From the sufferings of their loneliness lonely beings can discover and be many wonderful things, but the whole point is that there is ;something wrong in being utterly lonely without lovers and without friends, and that man is not to shatter himself to pieces-to be sure, very delectable pieces-in the sufferings of his loneliness, but to consume, and therefore to restore and find 36 CHARLES H. MALIK himself, in the joy and peace of actual fellowship and love. The very writing these lonely men pour themselves into in their melancholic loneliness is intended by them to be read and appreciated by somebody; no man has ever written just into the air; therefore their writing is itself a mode of fellowship, though not actual fellowship but fellowship in the mode of hope. They are denied actual face-to-face fellowship and love and therefore they write, in the hope that somebody will read and recognize them in absentia, at a distance, whether in space or in time. Would a fully happy person fully absorbed in the act of fellowship and love ever write? He has no time to write! This is all very well, but a residual problem abides here: there are lonely people, there are people who after every effort at fellowship remain lonely, there are people who do express the unutterable sufferings of their loneliness in writing; and my sermonizing here cannot get them out of their loneliness. The problem of election (what Heidegger would call fate or destiny) is most real. It is true, of course, that Jesus spent whole nights praying, and once for forty days and forty nights he was alone in the wilderness without food and without drink; but he was never alone; he was always communing with the Father, even when he was wrestling with the devil. Furthermore, after every retreat into prayer Jesus did not bur.st out into fits of writing: he always returned to fellowship in the Holy Spirit with his disciples. He as it were replenished himself spiritually in order to pour himself in active fellowship upon the world. "And when he had sent them away, he departed into a mountain to pray." The prayer life of Jesus was in the midst of intense social activity, in the midst of his ministry; and to understand this one should keep in mind in the most complete and concrete detail what kind of ministry it was. So different from the thinking-the "prayer" ?-of the philosophers! Nor can we say that the saints were lonely-St. Anthony, St. Francis, St. John of the Cross, St. John of Damascus-although some of them did write wonderful things; for in their loneliest loneliness they were all the time in communion with Christ: he was ever their com- REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 87 panion and friend. For this is the point of faith which God was gracious euough to grant these men in full: to believe that Jesus Christ of Nazareth rose from the dead, that God "hath highly exalted him, and given him a name which is above every name," that he is there, is living, is beside them, is, as the Psalmist would say," on their right hand" and therefore they " shall not be moved." DETHEOLOGIZING THEOLOGY In a footnote in Sein und Zeit Heidegger says Kierkegaard elaborated the phenomenon of anxiety or dread " in the theological context of a ' psychological ' exposition of the problem of original sin," implying that his elaboration of this phenomenon, being purely existential-ontological, is completely independent of this context. The truth as it appears to me is that without the traditional theological perspective neither Kierkegaard nor Heidegger could have dwelt on this phenomenon, but that whereas Kierkegaard maintained this context within his discussion both from acknowledgment of his existential sources and perhaps from faith, Heidegger, in conformity with his fundamental existential oath, weaned himself from it, perhaps from lack of faith, without acknowledging his existential-personal indebtedness to it. Without the living Christ in the living tradition neither Kierkegaard nor Heidegger would be possible, and I believe both of them know that. But in the case of Heidegger blame the fundamental existential oath for his not acknowledging this fact and for his accepting to bear the necessary existential-personal-moral consequences. Christianity is always uneasy in the world. In vain can it fully adapt itself to the world and in vain can the world fully adopt it. This is the significance of the two cities of Augustine, commingling and living constantly side by side. This is the significance of the Scriptural doctrine of " the world " in the half dozen or more senses of this term. There is simply a radical opposition between the righteousness of God and the sinfulness of man, between the truth of God and the falsehood and fallen- 38 CHARLES H. MALIK ness of the world; and only Jesus Christ of Nazareth can reconcile the two. Christianity has all along been uneasy in Germany and many Germans repeatedly appear to be uncomfortable with it. For good or for ill it has implanted itself in Germany-I believe irrevocably, both in Germany and in Russia-and according to a superficial interpretation of Nietzsche (which is not my interpretation) he regrets this fact and wishes it did not happen and that now it be wholly undone, not only in Germany but throughout the whole world. Despite the fact that he is militantly explicit on this regretting and wishing, I read him differently. Thus there is always a harking back among .some of the finest German thinkers to pre-Christian or non-Christian pagan sources, whether German or Nordic or Greek or Roman, or whether Indian or theosophical, or revolutionary as in the case of Marx, a harking back which aims not at appropriating these sources by correcting and purifying them under Christ, but at adopting and developing them as substitutes for Christ. These German thinkers feel more at home with them. But this is the whole point, for it belongs to Christ to make people-all people and not the Germans alone-not feel at home in their home. Because he ever reminds them, as all saints in every time and clime have experienced and affirmed, including the great German saints, he ever reminds them of their true home, namely the heavenly Jerusalem, of their desperate need for being near, not only their soil and their earth and their roots and their forests and their hearth and their folk and their gods, but for being near him, which is the surest way-indeed the only way-of enabling them to be truly near all these other things. Heidegger secularizes the ultimate theological categories; he denudes them of their theological significance; he detheologizes them. They are not a matter of the Bible, of the Church, of the living Christian tradition, of what the saints, not as philosophers, but as saints, were talking about, of Jesus Christ and God as understood by the Church. He couches them in human, conceptual terms, invents entirely unheard-of terms for them, REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 89 and therefore demonstrates the dispensability of the ontology of the Bible and the possibility of putting the whole thing in immanentist-human, transcendental-subjectivist terms. He thus affects to prove either that there is no inherent necessity for the Biblical-theological-ontological categories or that these categories are only one possibility and another his own achievement, or that they were only crude, primitive, unrefined, preontological formulations by the .somewhat uncouth JudaeoChristian-Near-Eastern mind. Since he is not an avowed atheist, like, for example, Sartre, he will not deny, I think, the possibility of the Biblical-Church interpretation of man and Being, but he will hold either that it is one possibility and his interpretation another, or, in the moments of absolute self-confidence, he might say his interpretation is deeper, i.e., more original (ursprunglich), i.e., again, necessarily presupposed by the Biblical interpretation, if only this interpretation would understand what it was saying. In effect, then, since he disrupts the over-all " unity " (I am using the term " unity " here in a very broad sense) of the Graeco-Roman-Judaeo-ChristianEuropean tradition, by recognizing, in his conception of the autonomy of philosophy, only the purely intellectual (or, in his own terms, conceptual or meditative or thoughtful) elements appertaining to the Graeco-Roman-European tradition (by European here I mean Eckhart, Boehme, Cusanus, Leibniz, German philosophy since Leibniz, especially Kant, Schelling, Hegel, Nietzsche, phenomenology, and his own personal genius, all thoroughly denuded of any strictly Christian reference or content), he is separating the Graeco-Roman-European element from the Judaeo-Christian element. He is pitting the two elements against each other, and saying, in effect, that the union of the two was a misfortune, that at any rate it was accidental and unnecessary, that if the Judaeo-Christian element has reference to mystery, the Graeco-Roman-European element has such reference too, and it is his duty to unearth it ( or, to use his own terms, to release it, or let it reveal or release itself, or to be open to it), and wherever he does not find it in the 40 CHARLES li. MALIK European secular tradition, he will provide it for that tradition independently himself. There is no need for the Judaeo-Christian revelation; Europe and the West can dispense with it. Europe and the West can fold back upon themselves in total self-sufficiency and independence from any such alien contamination. If this view of mine is wrong, then I ask the very simple question: Why does Heidegger not make full use of the immense ontological-existential material, so full of mystery, so full of depth and content, so directly relevant to all the themes he discusses, so full of food for thought, so thought-provoking, to use his own term, in the Psalms, the Gospels, the Epistles, the liturgy of the Church, the writings, and especially the prayers, of the saints, sacred music, including the great Protestant hymns, sacred art, the incredible iconography of the Orthodox Church? Faith is a matter of believing others. Believing only your thought, even the most sublime thought, leaves you entirely within yourself. If there is a devil, this is exactly what he is, "to be left entirely within yourself." This is why the devil has been enjoying a marvelous field day in modern subjectivist thought, including the German transcendental subjectivist thought of Kant and Hegel. In this state of being, sooner or later you either get bored or you degenerate. There are many others who may induce faith in us. Of all the others Jesus Christ of Nazareth is the most other. He is the wholly other. The problem of thought is not what it thinks, nor to be faithful to Being by bringing it to conceptual clarity or by letting it simply unconceal itself. The problem of thought is what it makes of the wholly other, of Jesus Christ. The problem of thought is the decision it takes when it encounters Jesus Christ, not only in the Bible, but in the face and life and thought of the living human beings who, now and in history, believed in Jesus Christ and remained faithful to him. What do you think of Jesus Christ?-this is the most important question facing every human being. Since it is a question of "What do you think? " it faces especially the thinker. It is easy to put the REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 41 matter so simply, but let the thinker really and concretely ponder what the Bible says, how the saints were and what they said, what the Church says and teaches, how it worships in the Divine Liturgy, let him moreover meet a few humble Christians just around the corner from his house-and then he will ask himself: What must I make out of all this? No other question then will appear to him more relevant or more pres.sing, or more ontological. The trouble with thought and thinkers is that they worship themselves, they do not know Christ. Until thinkers have met the wholly other they have not thought: they have only hugged themselves. Jesus Christ, in all that he meant to the world in history, and precisely in what he meant to Germany, meant the revelation of the hidden truth of the human heart as well as man's most authentic possibilities; and all this precisely as Heidegger is most concerned with it. He calls every man to be true-true precisely in the sense which Heidegger so wonderfully describes in his doctrine of authenticity. Of course Christ does much more than that, but he certainly does that. Who told the Western world today that this existential truth can either be revealed or conjured up or brought about autonomously by man? When Christ calls man to be true he tells him, I am the way, the truth and the life. All this is very well known in Germany, very well known to Heidegger himself. Can Germany, therefore, with all the great truths it has revealed and realized in history, truths which overflowed upon the entire world, can Germany now, penetrated and blessed so abundantly by Christ for 1500 years, deny its ownmost heritage? Can it now, on the deepest plane of its existence, and on the tongue of its greatest thinker, concerning the most momentous issues (man, being, existence, truth, destiny, death) , afford to throw off the " yoke of Christ " and revert to pre-Christian, indeed pre-Socratic, paganism? On the western front of the main building of the University of Freiburg in which I attended those unforgettable lectures and seminars by Heidegger one could read in bold letters at the very top of the wall: " Die Wahrheit 42 CHARLES H. MALIK wird euch freimachen." We know who said this, we know what he meant by it, and we know the piety of those who carved this saying on this 518-year-old great institution of higher learning. Are we now to turn our gaze away from this saying and from him who said it and the specific personal meaning he attached to it, toward another inscription on the southern wall of the same building, an inscription imposed on the University in the thirties, which reads " Zum ewigen Deutschtum " -and if not Deutschtum then Menschheit, and if not Menschheit then simply and purely Dasein? Is the warm, personal, inner, universal, Christian content, pointing to the beyond, to the transcendent, to the ground-as Heidegger perhaps would love to call it-now to be replaced by something vague, general, particular, subjectivist, idealistic, mystical, pointing indeed to some ground, but a ground absorbed in the immanence of total darkness, a ground that is no ground at all, because it has lost its own independent autonomy and freedom by being simply subservient to the autonomy and freedom of Dasein? For the real ground, the real Transzendenz (and Heidegger will pardon me for using the word "real" here), is that in terms of which Dasein is to be conceived rather than one itself conceived in terms of Dasein and in order to serve and cushion him up. And such a real ground, such a real Transzendenz, will not wait until man discovers it, not even until the philosopher makes it speak; it will have spoken before man makes it speak, certainly before philosophy discovers it. The discovery of it by philosophy is made possible only by a prior free uncovering of itself, so that philosophy then will have to accommodate itself to it rather than accommodate it to itself. This is the real prior, the real" schon," the real beforehand, the real Transzendenz. And this means a real honest search for and a real humble recognition of that voice coming from the real beyond-altogether beyond and other than not only Deutschtum but M enschheit and Daseinand of him who uttered it and what it actually .said. The wlw? and the what? here are decisive. And there is no equivocation whatever abnnt the identity of the who? and the what? For REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 43 I hear the voice saying, there is truth indeed, and the truth shall make you free, but I am the way, the truth and the life. And I happen to hear the voice really, truthfully coming altogether from outside me-from outside all thought, all culture and all philosophy-and I believe it. Any Transzendenz other than this Transzendenz is not serious; it is self-abuse; it is immanence all over again; it is a joke. How much I wish Heidegger would ponder and comment on, say, Isaiah 40, Psalm 139 and First Corinthians 13, in the manner in which he pondered and commented, say, on Holderlin and Rilke, or in the manner in which, say, Augustine or Chrysostom pondered and commented on these texts! It would be a good exercise, I think. These three chapters are only preliminary; they afford only a foretaste of the real meat-in the Gospels, in the Epistles, in the Psalms, in Job. Is there anything in all human literature, including Greek and German and even Christian literature, comparable to this material? Why should a Westerner of the caliber of Heidegger pass by this infinite wealth on the other side? Why divorce ourselves so studiedly from the Judaeo-Christian tradition, which has certainly formed and transformed us and our whole history and culture? Why revert to heathenism alone? Why? And I use the term heathenism here, not pejoratively, but with the fullest appreciation and gratitude for the solid values it embodied, in law, in art and in philosophy. But to live and think and act under the hidden existential oath of having nothing to do with the Judaeo-Christian tradition without which Western existence is unthinkable, to appear to feel that any constitutive contact with this tradition only pollutes and contaminates, is what I do not understand. Not even Nietzsche, not even the heathen doctrine of destiny and personal fate can make me understand it. Take, for example, a great psalm of David. Can Heidegger say it and mean it as David said it and meant it-as innumerable believers today say it and probably mean it, if it happens to be incorporated into the prayer life of the Church? 44 CHARLES H. MALIK Certainly he cannot. But the psalm is not therefore dead and :finished. The psalm arose within the personal historicality of David when he was addressing " the Lord "as he poured out his heart to him. David was not only bewailing his lot, he was not only poetizing as Holderlin and Rilke were, although of course their poetizing too sprang from their own immediate world situation. Nor was David only philosophizing or meditatively thinking on the human condition and on Being, as Heidegger is. David was addressing a distinct personal being wholly other than himself, whom he called " the Lord." This addressing of his was not just a literary trick, a literary vehicle for the conveyance of his own thoughts. It was most serious: " the Lord " whom he was addressing was there, wholly other than himself or his ideas and concepts. And today many serious people, some good philosophers, read David every morning, antl find him more relevant to their immediate personal situation, and to the general situation of the world, than almost all contemporary philosophy and poetry; and with him and in his own words they address " the Lord " who is there and who is wholly other than themselves. This Holderlin and Rilke were not doing. Whom then were they addressing? Whom does Heidegger address? "The universe," "nature," "the world," "Being," "some other poet or philosopher," " a student of his," " his closest friend," " a colleague of his," " the general philosophical audience," " the present age at large," " the future ages," " his own feelings," "himself," "nobody," "Nothing" ? Thus the psalm arose from the authentic historicality of David, and David was able to say and sing it authentically, regardless of whether it belonged to the historicality of Heidegger or Holderlin or Rilke. But if it does not belong to their existential historicity, is it therefore a pure relic to them? When they read it-if they read it-what does it mean to them? Is it nothing, does it mean nothing? It happens to belong to the existential historicity of innumerable people, both by reason of their personal sufferings and joys, and by reason of the fact that the Church has kept it alive. Since it was living and not dead in the days REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 45 of Augustine and Chrysostom and Luther, who, through their meditative thinking, commented on it in a most marvelous manner; since it is still living today in the lives of innumerable people, some of whom, through their meditative thinking (better, through their prayerful meditation), are commenting on it in their own way; the fact that it does not belong to the existential historicity of Heidegger, for Heidegger to be able to meditate and comment on it, is of course a problem that has to be faced. Why is the matter so? Is it fate or destiny or luck, good or bad? Must we starkly note the matter and leave it at that? Must we not wonder at it? Is it enough to say that God is dead? Does the matter end with this statement, which, it must be noted, when made by Heidegger and Nietzsche, is made with an unmistakable undertone of sadness? Is it enough to say, the gods have defaulted, the gods have forsaken us? They may indeed have defaulted, they may have forsaken Heidegger and Nietzsche and innumerable other people in this brave new age. But the fact that they have not forsaken innumerable other people, and they have not forsaken the Church, which is not exactly nothing in the world today, ought to force Heidegger and Nietzsche to stop and think. They cannot impose their position on others, and I doubt that they want or care to, much as they may wish it to embrace all, so as not to feel uncomfortable in the presence of those who continue believing. May it not be that the defaulted God is only a psychological (a la Nietzsche) reflection on man and his mysterious freedomon this or that man, or this or that epoch or culture? Far from God Himself forsaking us, may it not be that in the mystery of our freedom we have forsaken God ourselves? This is all food for thought even if God does not exist. Firstly, because Nietzsche and Heidegger really do not know that God does not exist, although Nietzsche may will Him not to exist; and secondly, because to dismiss the matter by saying, this is my fate, I cannot help myself, I cannot be other than I, is not enough, especially when I find myself in the presence of many others who, in this respect, are other than I. 46 ClIARLES H. MALIK THEOLOGIZING HEIDEGGER The dethinging of things, the denaturing of nature, the dehumanizing of man-these afflictions of our age Heidegger superbly describes and laments. He also traces them to their origin in certain perversions of the human heart. But then to detheologize theology is to compound the affliction. Never without the real living God Who has revealed Himself and Who is not waiting to be revealed from some "unheard-of center of Being" can man save himself from the countless devils who are now possessing him. And many theologians-Bultmann, for example-are Heideggerizing theology instead of theologizing Heidegger. Nietzsche and Heidegger appear to be more upset by the demise or absence of God than believers appear to rejoice in his presence. The philosophers are quite uneasy at this situation. They are haunted by a terrible lack. They bemoan it all the time, Nietzsche by attacking Christianity and doing everything he can to confirm the death of God, thereby only succeeding in confirming his state of being haunted by a lack, and Heidegger by assuring everybody either that God is really finished, or that if He still exists He must, if He should return (because Heidegger doubts not that He has departed) , take full cognizance of his, Heidegger's, ontological-existential analytic of man; namely, if God returned, He would have to return only as a guest of whom the host will be the being of man as Heidegphenomena in Sein und ger characterized it by his 100 or Zeit. God the guest must accommodate Himself to man the host. At least, if God exists, He and man are coeternal, not of course in the Aristotelian or Hegelian or Christian sense of eternity, but in the Heideggerian ontological sense of equiprimordiality. One is not quite sure whether Nietzsche and Heidegger in their concern about God really miss His presence (I suspect they could not be so agitated if they did not), or are really scared lest they should wake up one morning to find that He has suddenly returned, or are doing everything they can to " prove " His non-existence or at least irrelevance. Since God did play an REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 47 important role-and is still playing an important role in certain quarters-they appear to be occupied with devising substitutes for that lost role. It appears that something that would function as God is necessary. To Nietzsche this substitute (Ersatz) is man-not of course this awful man, you and I and every man including certainly Nietzsche himself, but the tJbermensch, who can only be reached by somebody resolutely overcoming in himself all that has been man hitherto and straining after the full measure of the tJbermensch as delineated by Nietzsche. As the substitute God thus turns out to be a figment of Nietzsche's own imagination, the ultimate consolation Nietzsche finally lands in is the Idea; not a given, independent, existing, whole human being. To Heidegger the substitute appears to be philosophy itself, otherwise called thinking or meditative thinking; and if philosophy is considered only a way, then the substitute, the end of the way, is Being or Nothing. "We are too late for the gods and too early for Being. Being's poem, just begun, is man." But even when thinking does not rest except in phenomena (the self-revelation of Being), still these phenomena, being the end of the way, are themselves in a sense ideas. They cannot be Being itself. German thinkers are incurable idealists no matter how much they appear to be rebelling against their own idealism. You do not substitute for God something less than God-less than God both in being and in idea. It is clear why the substitute as idea is false, because God is not an idea. Nor in being, because the old dead God (missed or unmissed) did not function as idea to be sought and realized, but supreme being, both in the life of the simple peasant woman and in the life of Paul or Augustine. They submitted themselves to Him, but here we are asked to create Him ourselves. Thus the brave new substitutes for God will simply not do. The dead old God will keep on haunting man until man repents himself of his rebellion or until He, God, returns in power and glory despite this rebellion and in the face of it. For presumably He is used to such rebellion and sees through the present one and is not much disturbed by it. 48 CHARLES H. MALIK In his What Is Called Thinking? Heidegger calls Nietzsche's The Antichrist" the terrible book" (p. 80). He does so, however, in the context of commenting on the first sentence and the last sentence of Nietzsche's" autobiography," which Nietzsche wrote at the age of 19 and whose manuscript was first discovered in 1935 and published the following year. In the last sentence Nietzsche says: "Thus man grows out of everything that once embraced him; he has no need to break the shacklesthey fall away unforeseen, when a god bids them; and where is the ring that in the end still encircles him? Is it the world? Is it God? " Heidegger then immediately observes: Even the later Nietzsche, the man who, in the last year of his creativity and after losing balance more than once, wrote the terrible book The Antichrist, was still asking the same question-if only we can and will read it. However-to hear this questioning, to come close to his ways of thought, one requires here to respect and to acknowledge. Respecting and acknowledging are not yet agreement; but it is the necessary precondition for any confrontation. For my part, I respect and acknowledge Nietzsche even innay, especially in-The Antichrist, though I do not agree with him; and I respect, acknowledge and wholly agree with Heidegger on these observations of his. I feel absolutely sure Nietzsche " was still asking the same question " at the end of his life; his real self-tormenting lure was throughout God-not any god, but Christ himself. No man knows what St. John calls in the Book of Revelation " the depths of Satan " and at the same time the superabounding grace of Christ (on " where sin abounded, grace did much more abound," see Karl Barth's Christ and Adam, Scottish Journal of Theology Occasional Papers No. 5, London, Oliver and Boyd, 1963) except after he has been shaken to his deepest depths, politically-socially-morally, bytheutterrottenness of the world, morally-personally-existentially, by the utter rottenness of his own nature, and, culturally-intellectuallymorally-existentially, by honestly " confronting" Nietzsche in all his works (especially in Thus Spake Zarathustra, The Will to Power and The Antichrist) in an "acknowledging" and REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 49 " respecting " spirit, and then, despite this overpowering experience, remaining unshaken in his faithfulness to Christ, or, more exactly, Christ remaining unshaken in his faithfulness to him. * * * * * The genuineness, the seriousness, the directness, the power, the sureness, the freedom, the total abandon of Jesus in the account of the Gospels! And yet one must have the power of multiplying what he thinks he senses in the Gospels by a factor of one hundred or more to capture something of the original fullness of the reality of Jesus. That is what we mean when we sometimes say: would that we were there with Jesus in the company of Peter and John and Andrew and James and Philip and the others! Jesus was so absolutely full of certainty and power, and that with respect to the most serious matters, that he never hesitated to say what he said and to act in the manner he acted. Where in all history is there anything even remotely comparable to this? And that not just in phenomenological description and ontological analysis, but in actual living and being, which included, among other things, training the disciples, establishing the Church, curing the sick, raising the dead, forgiving sins, teaching truths, imparting his spirit, resolutely carrying his cross and dying. Nietzsche asks on several occasions: Who before him saw what he saw and said what he said? So does Heidegger: such and such a doctrine or interpretation or position or exposition he was the first to grasp and formulate. And both are right: there are things that these two men have seen and said that are, of their kind, unique in history. But the question is not about what they saw and said about being and existence; the question is being and existence themselves. The phenomenon of the being and existence of the total living Person Jesus Christ of Nazareth is itself, of its kind, unique in history, and not some phenomenological-ontological writing of his. This phenomenon ought to interest the unprejudiced, that is, the open, philosopher, especially if he happens to be dealing with human existence, and doubly so 50 CHARLES H. MALIK if he grasps authentic existence as masterfully as does Heidegger. For there is no "instance" of authentic existence that even compares with Jesus Christ of Nazareth; I do not mean the "idea" and "description" of authentic existence, but the very act and being of authentic existence itself; Jesus Christ is authentic existence par excellence. And if the philosopher does not interest himself in this unique instance of authentic existence, then, it seems to me, there must be a contingent reason for that, and not an essential one. Of course Nietzsche interested himself in Jesus Christ no end, but in his own prejudiced, unopen way. Despite the perverse and totally unworthy manner of his interest, still Nietzsche unerringly felt that an existential philosopher of his kind cannot not notice Jesus Christ; and that is to his eternal credit. Why should the philosopher be so wary of going out of himself (this is the real ecstasis, and not what Heidegger describes in relation to past, pre.sent and future in the second part of Sein und Zeit) , out of his subjectivity, out of his ideas, out so to speak of his reason, out of his era, out of the Weltgeist which so numbs and stifles him, to encounter someone altogether strange and different, altogether other, altogether outside the whole tradition of Graeco-German philosophy, and yet someone speaking with such power and force, someone actually living around him and in his tradition in a thousand different ways? Perhaps he is afraid of being then judged, of falling then under his spell and control, and the philosopher wants to be himself the judge, himself the one who would control and cast spells on others. Jesus deeply disturbs the philosopher, and yet this disturbance is nothing yet compared to the depths of disturbing of which Jesus is capable; let the philosopher only cling to Jesus for twenty or thirty years of his life, and let Jesus be gracious enough not to forsake him but to keep on chastening him all these years, and then he will be treated to dimensions of disturbance that he cannot now dream of. Who ever cried on reading philosophy, even the deepest philosophy? But innumerable people have cried on reading the REFLEdTiON ON HE'.IDEGGER 51 Bible or hearing the Bible read in church, and really attending to what is being said and who said it, and to the concrete circumstances under which it was said. People too have cried on reading Dostoyevsky or other great literature; but a responsible consideration of why they cried here will always lead you to the Bible and to Christ and the Church as the ultimate ground. Plato and Aristotle wrote very great literature; so did Heidegger and Nietzsche; but we never cry when we read them, nor do I think people cried in the sense I mean here in the Academy or the Lyceum. I believe when we thus cry we are closer to Being-in any and every sense of the termthan when we only wonder, ask questions, analyze and reflect, and think meditatively. After I receive the gift of tears-and it is a gift-and I accept it without gloating over it or hardening my heart (and this non-hardening of the heart and this nongloating are themselves also gifts), I can do anything better: I think better, I write better, I work in the garden better, I discuss things with my friends better, I attend to my duties better, I laugh better, I see better, I hear better, I eat better, I sleep better, I walk better, I listen better, I understand better, I love better, and, I think, if I am then called upon to die, I die gracefully and in peace; at least I talk much less, or I do not talk at all. Then I really am, then Being really presences itself to me. This is not to be explained psychologically or physiologically: this is a fact that ought to disturb the self-satisfied explaining psychologist or philosopher at his deepest. "Now all these things happened unto them as warnings: and they are written for our admonition, upon whom the ends of the world are come." (First Corinthians 10: 11) The world ended, it was simply finished, in Jesus Christ. Henceforth we have only a new creature or death, or what in a sense is even worse than death, dying. Everything is simply dying outside Jesus Christ, no matter how exuberant and self-sufficient it may seem. Henceforth we have either those who were touched by Jesus Christ or the dead who have ended. To expect salvation from within the world after the world has ended in Jesus Christ is 52 CHARLES H. MALIK hopeless. This means every world has ended in Jesus Christ, including this very world in which we live today-and not only the world of Paul. This means all our worldly standards and hopes today are hopeless because they have all ended in Jesus Christ. This means the only possibly new thing left is this or that person or culture which is saved, adopted, chosen by Jesus Christ, born anew in him. There is nothing new any more except the experience of Jesus Christ, except the Holy Spirit falling upon this or that person in fellowship with those upon whom He has already fallen. Everything else is boringly, disgustingly, monotonously meaningless repetition. Nietzsche's "eternal recurrence," hailed by him as his greatest affirmation, is itself the psychological and subjectivist expression of the total meaningless sameness of existence apart from Jesus Christ. (I say" psychological and subjectivist" because Nietzsche does not really know that " eternal recurrence " is true, but only " wills" it to be, as to him the will, indeed his will, creates both being and truth; thus " eternal recurrence " is the pure fantasy of Nietzsche's effervescent imagination; it is, to speak a la Nietzsche, a sort of psychological relief-he would call it, of course, selfovercoming-from his terrific subjectivist resentment, and profound sense of revenge, against the world, including above all the rottenness of man.) Now that the world has ended, now that there is nothing new any more, the only thing that can stand is the Church, because it is held together by the resurrected Lord who sitteth now and forever on the right hand of God. I know perfectly the answer of existential ontology to all this " nonsense," and I can elaborate it, though of course not as well as Heidegger, but, thanks to my discipleship under him, somewhat as he can. But in the living knowledge of Jesus Christ and his grace and strength and power and certainty and victory and peace, in the fellowship of the Church, this answer leaves me completely cold, even when made by Heidegger. It shakes me, it tests me, but still it is nothing in the actual presence of Jesus Christ. I am talking from outside existential subjectivism and humanism, outside Heideggerian philosophical REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 53 anthropology, outside the quietism of medieval German mysticism, outside the pseudo-transcendentalism of phenomenological-ontological-conceptual immanentism. I am talking from the side of the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, the Father of our Lord Jesus Christ, and not, as Pascal would protest, the God of the philosophers. I am talking from the knowledge of Jesus Christ in my own living-dying life, in the living-dying life of countless persons I know, in the living-dying life of the great saints-Paul, Ephrem, Chrysostom, Damascene, Augustine, Teresa of Avila, John of the Cross. I am talking from what Jesus Christ has meant in art (the great cathedrals, the great sacred music, the great iconography), in poetry (Ephrem, Dante, John Donne), in the law systems of civilized humanity, in the amazing endurance of whole communities that withstood over the centuries the most unbelievable trials and odds. How did they stand? Only by their love for Je-sus Christ, nay by his love for them. I am talking about the l ring-suffering, though appropriately concealed, life of the lhurch today in our very midst-in Europe, in Russia, in America, in the Middle East, everywhere in the world. This living-suffering being is impressive, and not only to " the ' they '," to " das Man." "Upon whom the ends of the world are come "-faith cries that if Heidegger is waiting (and to wait is a fundamental Heideggerian structure of being) until something turns up from the womb of Being to save the world-I mean, to save Germany, Western civilization, technological-calculative-objectifying-dethinging civilization, which has seduced and gotten hold of the entire world-Heidegger is waiting in vain. He is waiting in vain because he need not wait. For something has long since turned up from the womb of Being precisely to perform this function, even Jesus Christ of Nazareth, who continues to dwell in our midst, whose glory is the glory of the only begotten of the Father, and who, as he dwells among us, is "full of grace and truth." "Upon whom the ends of the world are come "-faith cries that if Heidegger thinks that meditative thinking (besinnliches 54 CHARLES H. MALJK Denken), when it turns up in this or that thinker, or when it entrenches itself in high places (a la Plato who dreamt that when the philosophers or the authentic meditative thinkers rule, all will be well with this or that city or state or the world) , is going to save us from the curse of calculative thinking and the degeneracy it engenders in concrete personal and cultural existence, he is mistaken. He is mistaken for four reasons. First, because it is not a matter of thought at all, but of fundamental attitude, of total personal orientation, of " the spirit " of the thinker which is wholly distinct ±:Porn his thought, of his will (in this sense certainly the will is decisive), of being-and it is this that creates the thought, and not the other way round; and therefore the question is how to bring about this original being which will itself create the meditative thinking. (Heidegger of course fully agrees with all this.) Secondly, because the dark, rebellious, destructive, dehumanizing pitfalls to which human existence is heir, if they do not cling to calculative-objectifying thought, as they do today with such fateful devastation, will cling to something elsedespotism, dictatorship, falsehood, radical hatred of personal human existence and its inalienable freedom, self-will, degeneracy, totalitarianism, whole systems based on hatred, rejection and force. Therefore Augustine was right in holding that we shall always have the corrupt city of man side by side with and around and interpenetrating the city of God, which itself too is subject to all sorts of infirmities. Thus the city of God will always be .struggling, suffering, getting crucified at the hands of the city of man and of human corruption in general, but penetrating and convicting and leavening it all the same; and thus the worry about the world even as swept and dominated by calculative thinking is a misplaced worry. The real worry is about the integrity of the existing city of God, and about saving one's own integrity in the midst of the universal collapse, as Socrates says in the Republic, by taking refuge in a genuine lee while the storm rages. But unlike Socrates, who knew nothing about it, the believer knows that, now that " the REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 55 ends of the world are come upon us" in Jesus Christ, this shelter, this lee can only be Jesus Christ in the Church. Thirdly, because, if Christ created the best in Germany and the West, including the preservation and appropriation of a purged, i.e., Christened, Graeco-Roman heritage, as well as meditative thinking itself, then for Germany and the West now to seek salvation outside this their creator, namely, "to go awhoring after other gods," is demonically rebellious ingratitude, and therefore they will be denied the salvation they seek. Fourthly, because, while meditative thinking can rightly bewail its lot in the world today, it is intellectual pride, it is a form of the will to power, nay it is willful usurpation of power, for meditative thinking to suppose that it can ever save itself, let alone the world. Without grace and tenderness from above and from outside, meditative thinking is as doomed as calculative thinking and as the rest of us. Thus meditative thinking should either fall on its knees and smite its breast confessing the sin of arrogance and false self-sufficiency and repenting itself of it-and I do not expect ever to be treated to the spectacle of a philosopher, as philosopher, falling on his knees and smiting his breast and repenting of the sin of intellectual pride-or stoically and without the slightest hope accept its inevitable doom. In What ls Called Thinking? Heidegger suggests an original relationship (in Part II, Lecture III) between thanking and thinking. He relates the Old English thencan, to think, to thancian, to thank. The discussion is ontological and suggestive. In giving thanks, the heart gives thought to what it has and what it is. Original thanking is the thanks owed for being. We give thanks for something by giving thanks to him whom we have to thank for it. The things for which we owe thanks are not things we have from ourselves. They are given to us. We receive many gifts, of many kinds. But the highest and really most lasting gift given to us is always our essential nature, with which we are gifted in such a way that we are what we are only through it. That is why we owe thanks for this endowment, first and un- 56 CHARLES H. MALIK ceasingly.... But the thing given to us, in the sense of this dowry, is thinking. . . . How can we give thanks for this endowment, the gift of being able to think what is most thought-provoking, more fittingly than by giving thought to the most thought-provoking? The supreme thanks, then, would be thinking? And the profoundest thanklessness, thoughtlessness? Real thanks, then, never consists in that we ourselves come bearing gifts, and merely repay gift with gift. Pure thanks is rather that we simply think ... These are indeed thought-provoking admonitions, so true and fundamental, especially as addressed to students. Heidegger is saying that the best thanks you can give me is to learn to think yourselves. The discussion thus stops at the gift for which we ought to be thankful: our essential nature which is to think. Apart from whether Heidegger thinks that our essential nature is to think, rather than, in conformity with Leibniz, Schelling, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, to will (and he discusses or implies this position in many places), in the phenomenology of thanking the " to " is at least as primary as the "for": we always owe thanks to somebody for .something. Heidegger does not move on to the to whom? Are we thankful to Being for articulating itself through us? This is clearly in the end a mode of thanking ourselves. This vagueness or .silence on the question of the to whom?, this leaving the matter freischwebend, reveals Heidegger's mystical, Eckhartian monismexactly the same type of outlook one finds in Hammarskjold's Markings. The personal and interpersonal element fuses or merges or dissolves into impersonal, mystical cosmologism or ontologism. Man is alone-he has nobody to whom to give thanks; therefore he thanks himself, or Being. It would be unfair to Heidegger to belabor this point, but the danger of radical solitude, radical individualism, radical subjectivism, radical hesitation to express gratitude to a person, exists: one misses the warmth of the interpersonal element, within which all thankfulness moves. Love is more fundamental than thinking or thanking, and something is inhibiting us when we merely equate thinking with thanking. It is not for nothing that in the Christian tradition God is equated with love, and not with thought, REFLECTlON ON HEIDEGGER as with Aristotle-not even with thought as thanks. Whoever thanked thanking itself? Whoever thanked Being or the universe or nature or the unheard-of center or Nothing for his ability to think or to thank? To thank is to thank somebody, and ultimately to thank Somebody who is really worthy of being thanked, and that can only be God. For every human being we thank is not exactly worthy, and even the quality in him for which we thank him (his compassion, generosity, hospitality, love, consideration, sympathy, helpfulness) he owes to somebody beyond himself, and in the end to God. "I thank God through Jesus Christ our Lord," cried Paul. The commonest phrase on the mouth of everybody in the Middle East is" thank God"; every thanks is ultimately "thank God." It is easy for secularized, technologized, progressive, modern, immanentized, Western society to make fun of this and to call it at times " a relic " of an old superstition. I am sure, regardless of how much it has in fact become a relic, and regardless of his own position on God, Heidegger would appreciate and respect the purity and mystery of the original intention of this phrase. One of my many phenomenological-existential proofs for the existence of God is that we thank each other all the time, and we never really mean this thanking to stop at the other person we thank, knowing man's essential mortality and corruption. An absolutely lonely person cannot thank nor can he be thanked. The ratio, just as the thanking, is always social, always interpersonal. The " danke," the "thank you," fully understood, proves the existence of God, or else we are in the end thanking nobody and nothing. Danke, thank you, therefore God exists. Presumably when we speak of " gift " and " giver " and " the things for which we owe thanks are not things we have from ourselves," we are not only speaking metaphorically; we are not speaking " as it were " and " as if." Presumably we mean something solid, no matter how possibly vague and undetermined. The question then is inevitable: what (not to say " who") is the giver? What (not to say "whom") should we thank for 58 CHARLES 11. MALIK the gift? Did the gift "come" from nowhere and nothing? Presumably it" came" from somewhere and something. What is this source of the gift? Must I just thank Being for it, must I thank nature, must I thank the " unknown God " of the Athenians we read about in Acts 17? I know the gift, be it thinking or willing, but I do not the giver. I know "for what" I should be thankful, but I do not know " to whom or to what " I should tender my thanks. And this lands me in the end precisely in the impersonal, cosmological, monistic mysticism of the naturalists-a mysticism, to be sure, much more refined and sophisticated than the mysticism of a Spinoza or a Bertrand Russell. The Christian thanks the living, personal, given God for the gift. He knows this source of the gift from faith; but faith here is not something dark and magical and private. Faith here includes a thousand different living evidences, especially of the order of " trust and love " among the members of a living community, the Church, held together by living traditions of "trust and love " constituted and sustained by the Holy Spirit of Jesus Christ. Without the to in the act of thanking, the for remains wholly unsupported, hanging in mid-air. * * * * * Heidegger has a profound nostalgia for God. " Die Frage nach dem Sinn des Seins," is probably the fittest motto of his whole life. Nietzsche had a similar nostalgia. The two men simply miss God. On every page of Heidegger I sense this longing for mystery, this nostalgia for God. He desperately wants faith, but he does not seem to be able to get it. One who has eyes to see and ears to hear the hidden melody of his thought will find Heidegger sharpening, in his own way, almost to the breaking point, the tension between thought and faith; he will find him struggling to show that without ground and mystery and transcendence, without " the beyond," thought is dead and forlorn. Being is there, Being is independent-you only let it speak. The difficulty, the impediment, is not in Being, but in you. Nietzsche too sharpens this tension, not "almost" to the breaking point but " precisely " to the breaking point, REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 59 and beyond. One interpretation of Heidegger-of the service he has rendered-is that he is profoundly nostalgic for a reinterpretation of the profane-pagan tradition in terms of some religious faith. H this is so then he is £aced with the inexorable double disjunction: either go back to the faith of your fathers, absorbing and making foll use of the profane tradition without losing any of faith's most distinctive elements viz., God, Christ, the Holy Spirit, the Church, the Resurrection of Christ, the resurrection of the body, etc.; (Schelling at the end of his life was distinctly groping in that direction); or seek another faith (there are plenty of them around!) and wholly identify yourself with it; or, if you cannot return to the faith of your fathers, and you are not satisfied with any other available faith (and this is part of the greatness of Heidegger, that he knows that all the faiths that are being peddled about are not the real thing) , then create yourself a faith of your own. To what degree this third alternative is possible, is of course the greatest problem for Heidegger. But one cannot go on indefinitely affirming the profane tradition and completely extruding faith, leaving only a vague nostalgia for something. One cannot straddle indefinitely between faith and reason, in any sense of the term reason, without profound personal tragedy; neither can reason, in any sense of the term, ever lead one to faith; but faith, originally given, can, without compromising its integrity in the slightest, folly appropriate reason, with whatever mystery reason may point to. Christ is the target of a whole world-wide movement that takes many forms, sometimes wholly unknown one to the other, sometimes enemies of one another for different reasons. It is like the many-headed hydra of Plato. Anti-Christian atheistic thought, whether of the militant or of the subtle kind, is only one tributary of this movement. Other tributaries swelling the torrent are the return to pre-Christian heathenism and the quest of the thought and life of the non-Christian paganism of Asia and Africa. How much this heathenism and this paganism are adulated today! There are many other tendencies con- 60 CHARLES H. MALIK spiring to the same end. The world simply hates Jesus Christ because he judges it. How well he knew this from the beginning! "If the world hate you, ye know that it hated me before it hated you." " The world cannot hate you; but me it hateth, because I testify of it, that the works thereof are evil." (The " you " in the two quotations refers to two different audiences.) How much Christ sees through the philosophers, of all peoples " in the world " ! Especially the philosophers of Being, who, sincere as they are in their quest, yet, instead of recognizing, in humility and adoration, the only Being worthy of the name, namely, the Being which is wholly other than themselves, usually end up with seeing only their thought, that is, with identifying thought and Being, and indeed, their thought and Being! And so, if the world and the philosophers cannot crucify Christ again, they will at least banish him, as the Grand Inquisitor of Dostoyevsky did when he intimated to him that he should please go away! While one may see in Nietzsche either ignorance of the plenitude of grace and certainty which those who know Jesus Christ experience in their own lives, or a certain perverse will in relation to Paul and the New Testament, and to Christianity in general, one cannot suspect either ignorance or perversion of will in the case of Heidegger. Heidegger cannot possibly be ignorant or superficial when it comes to Christ, the Church, the saints, and the Bible. So, while Nietzsche is either ignorant or, so to speak, possessed, Heidegger is neither the one nor the other. This is a very strange situation. What is Heidegger's state of being then from the Christian point of view? It can only be being on the way back to faith-full-blooded faith, not intellectualized faith, not conceptualized faith, not thought-out faith; but the direct faith of Mary and Peter and Paul and Augustine and Teresa; faith based on personal knowledge of Jesus Christ; certainly not the faith of a Bultmann or a Tillich or even a Kierkegaard, or any of the men now trying to Heideggerize theology instead of theologizing Heidegger. I do not see any of these men in my mind falling on his knees and smiting REFLECTION ON HEIDEGGER 61 his breast and shedding tears of love and gratitude for and to Jesus Christ of Nazareth, as Augustine did in the garden, and innumerable times afterwards. This is my interpretation of Heidegger's constant questioning, his never resting in any position, although the illumination of any position he assumes or thinks through for the time being is simply extraordinary. This is my interpretation of his perpetual insistence on "the way," "the path," "the movement," "the stations of the way." Heidegger is on the way back to the faith of his fathers. If only die Kehre, the turn, of Heidegger's way should turn into die Umkehr, the return, in the simple childlike sense of the termin the sense of the great conversions, or, better, great" returns" of history-and this despite all doctrines of fate and helplessness, despite Holderlin's soothing words about "the enduring measure common to all " whereby " each of us goes toward and reaches the place that he can" (What Are Poets for?) . If in God's providence this should happen, then we would have one of the greatest events of the twentieth century, perhaps even more important than the event of Solzhenitsyn! This is all in God's hands. CHARLES HABIB MALIK American University of Beirut Beirut, Lebanon THE PROBLEM OF BEING IN HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS I N HIS RECENTLY PUBLISHED lecture course at Marburg (1927) entitled The Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology, Martin Heidegger makes the following observation: 1 They have said that my philosophical work is a Catholic phenomenology. Presumably because I am of the opinion that thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus have understood some(GPdP, 28) thing about philosophy. Heidegger goes on to say that there is no such thing as a Catholic phenomenology, no more than there is a "Protestant mathematics." 2 Yet it is remarkable nonetheless to us today that Heidegger would have been popularly thought of as a Catholic. He was afterwards taken to be an atheist and nowadays we are not sure what to think of the place of God in his thought. The importance of Heidegger's observation is that it underlines for us the Catholic scholastic origins of his thought. Consider these remarkable facts. He was born and educated 1 I will use the following abbreviations for the works of Heidegger: GPdP: Gesamtausgabe, B. 24: Die Grundprobleme der Phiinomenologie (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1975). (This work is referred to in the body of the article under the English translation of its title.) SZ: Sein und Zeit, 10. Aull (Tiibingen: Niemeyer, 1963). English translation Being and Time, translated Macquarrie and Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962). N. II: Nietzsche, B. 2 (Pfullingen: Neske, 1961). English translation in The End of Philosophy, translated Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1973). ID: Identity and Difference. Translated with the German text by Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1969). We will cite the German pagination followed by a slash and the English pagination. 2 Cf. the remark in An Introduction to Metaphysics, translated R. Mannheim (Garden City, Doubleday, 1961), p. 6, that a Christian philosophy is a square circle. This is apparently an Husserlian attitude, for whom philosophy is strenge Wissenschaft. HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTlCS in Catholicism and had studied for a while for the Catholic priesthood. He was presented for the Ph.D. at Freiburg in 1914, not by Rickert, under whom he did his major work, but by Schneider, because the latter was also Catholic. 3 He wrote his Habilitationsschrift in 1916 on Duns Scotus (on the pseudoScotistic de modis significandi) .4 His thought was inspired by the work of an ex-priest-Brentano-on Aristotle's Metaphysics-a figure who had also introduced the scholastic idea of intentionality into modern thought. Brentano's book had been given to him by Conrad Grober, who was to become Archbishop of Freiburg. From 1919-1927 Heidegger lectured on such topics as: the philosophical foundations of medieval mysticism (he would have a life-long interest in Meister Eckhart), the philosophy of religion, Augustine and Neoplatonism, Aristotle's De Anima, Physics, Nicomachean Ethics and Rhetoric, Aristotle and the High Scholastics, and medieval ontology. 5 Heidegger's beginnings are steeped in the Catholic-Aristotelian-scholastic tradition, and any understanding of his thought must take into account his relationship with the scholastics. The purpose of the present study is to discuss the relation between Heidegger's understanding of Being and scholastic metaphysics. This task will be carried out by studying the critique which Heidegger makes of the scholastic theory of essence and existence. This critique is contained in a lengthy section of The Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology (GPdP, §§ 10-12), a discussion which greatly expands and facilitates our understanding of the somewhat more 3 Paul Hiihnerfeld, In Sachen Heidegger (Miinchen: Paul List Verlag, 1962), p. 42. •For a study of Heidegger's Duns Scotus book see my "Phenomenology, Mysticism and the Grammatica Speculativa: A Study of Heidegger's Habilitationsschrift," The Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 5, no. 2 (May, 1974), 101-17. 5 For Heidegger's lectures from 1915 to 1958 see W. Richardson, Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague: M. Nijhofl', 1962), pp. 663 ff. For a study of Heidegger and Eckhart see my " Meister Eckhart and the Later Heidegger" in two parts in The Journal of the History of Philosophy XII, 4 (October. 1974), 479-94 and xxiii, 1 (January, 1975), 61-80. 64 jQHN D. CAPUTO cryptic presentation which Heidegger makes of the .same subject in his 1941 Nietzsche lectures (NII, The focus of the present study lies in the fact that both Heidegger and the scholastics, particularly the students of St. Thomas Aquinas, claim to be the philosophers of Being par excellence, and each claims that the history of philosophy (in which each includes the other) is a history in which Being has been " forgotten" or distorted into something which it is not. What I am interested in more than anything else in these pages is these conflicting counter-claims. For Heidegger has insisted that it is only in recognizing the " ontological di:fference " between Being and beings that the " truth of Being" can be attained. And the Thomists maintain that only in St. Thomas's metaphysics of esse-of the primacy within being (ens) of the existential act of being-is there a genuine recognition of Being as Being. For Heidegger, St. Thomas's distinction between essence and existence lies on "one side" of the ontological difference and lie.s therefore in the oblivion of Being. Yet Bernard Rioux rejoins that St. Thomas has grasped the being (ens) in its Being (esse) ,-sand therefore that he is acutely sensitive to the ontological difference. We must however proceed very carefully in attempting this confrontation. We must not naively assume that when Heidegger .says that the distinction between Being and beings supersedes the distinction between essence and existence, he is speaking in the same terms as the scholastics and from the same standpoint. We must be on guard against thinking that he is merely arguing that we replace one set of metaphysical categories with another. As Father Richardson writes: 7 ... one must be extremely cautious in seeing any correlation between what Heidegger means by Being and any sense that the scholastics, such as St. Thomas Aquinas, gave to the term. 6 Bertrand Rioux, I:Etre et la verite chez Heidegger et Saint Thomas d'Aquin (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1968) , p. 188. 7 Richardson, p. 8!'l0, n. !'l7. HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 65 Because Heidegger's work is through and through affected by his phenomenological standpoint, the word "Sein " has for him a radically altered-because phenomenological-meaning. We are not therefore dealing with a different metaphysical distinction, but a radically different kind of philosophy of Being. The overall plan of this study is quite .straightforward. In the first half we will, in an expository way, follow Heidegger's critique of scholastic metaphysics. A good deal of this section will be devoted to his discussion of essence and existence in the 1927 lecture course, The Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology. It will conclude with an examination of the 1941 Nietzsche lectures on the same theme. In the second half of the study we will make a critical assessment of Heidegger's charge against the scholastics. There we will take up explicitly the question of whether the Thomistic notion of esse lies, as Heidegger claims, in the forgetfulness of Being. PART I. HEIDEGGER'S CRITIQUE OF THE SCHOLASTIC THEORY OF BEING For reasons that cannot be fully developed here, Heidegger always maintained that " the fundamental problem of phenomenology" is the problem of Being. The 1927 lectures are devoted to a discussion of four main " theses " that have been put forward concerning Being: (1) Kant's thesis that Being is is not a real predicate; (2) the scholastic thesis that Being is composed of essence and existence; (3) the thesis of modem ontology that Being divides into res cogitans and res extensa; (4) the thesis of the logician that Being is the copula. Kant's thesis is related to that of the scholastics; this is evidenced by the rejection by both Kant and Aquinas of the ontological argument. For neither philosopher can real Being be attained merely by knowing the definition of a thing. Both require a "there is" (Kant's "position") or a "judgment" (Aquinas) in order to attain real being, even the Being of God, though both philosophers held that God's essence includes existence. Kant's ontology thus is an extension of medieval ontology (GPdP, 108-110) . 66 JOHN D. CAPUTO Heidegger entitles his treatment of the second thesis " The Thesis of Medieval Ontology, which Goes Back to Aristotle: Being-what (essentia) and Being-present (existentia) Belong to the Structure of Being of the being." Two things are of interest in this title. (1) The thesis is said to go back to Aristotle. That is a provocative statement. For there has been a vast literature issuing from the Thomists and the medievalists which argues that this particular ontological thesis does not go back to Aristotle or to any Greek philosopher. It cannot, it is claimed, because this thesis was introduced to explain creation, viz., the contingency in being of the creature. But the Greeks had no idea of creation and held to the eternity and necessity of the world. Heidegger does not discuss this point, although he does mention in passing that Aristotle does not have much to say about existence. Nonetheless he does have his reasons for taking this thesis back to Aristotle (and also Plato), which we shall have occasion to examine below. (2) Secondly, the title of the thesis gives us a preliminary idea of how Heidegger sees the scholastic distinction between essence and existence in relation to his own "ontological difference." Essence and existence belong to " the Structure of Being of the being " (die Seinsverf assung eines Seienden) . Accordingly essence and existence belong on the " Being " side of the Being-being distinction. Thus they represent an " articulation " of Being, or what the scholastics would call the " composition" of Being (GPdP, 109). We might graphically represent the two distinctions as follows: Heidegger I scholastics 111 111 essence Sein I existence II Seiendes I Let us now turn to the body of Heidegger's 1927 text to see how Heidegger works out his interpretation of scholastic metaphysics in detail. HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 67 Aquinas, Scotus and Suarez. Heidegger begins his discussion by differentiating three different positions concerning essence and existence that have been historically taken by the scholastics. For while all the scholastics agree that in God (ens a se) essence and existence are identical, there is a longstanding controversy among them as to how this distinction applies to creatures (ens ab alio) . Here there are three major schools of thought: (1) Aquinas (Dominicans): "real distinction"; (2) Scotus (Franciscans): "formal distinction"; (3) Suarez (Jesuits) : "distinction of reason." What is interesting about this discussion is the slight tilt which Heidegger shows-within the parameters of the scholastic debate-towards Suarez's position. He rightly says, citing in this connection Giles of Rome, that the core of the Thomistic position is that, if the real distinction between essence and existence is not maintained, it would be impossible to explain the being of creatures and how their being differs from God's (GPdP, 28-31). Concerning Scotus, Heidegger expounds his theory that essence and existence represent different aspects-truly different but not separable aspects-of the selfsame concrete being, these aspects being called by Scotus " modalities " or " formalities " (distinctio formalis a parte rei) (GPdP, 131-2) .8 But Suarez is afforded the most attention by Heidegger (GPdP, 132-9). One can of course only speculate as to how much Heidegger's preference for Suarez is affected by his own brief excursion with the Jesuits. Heidegger credits Suarez with having a decisive influence on modern philosophy, as having communicated the main tenets of medieval ontology to the modern period (GPdP, 112; SZ, 22/43-4; N II, 418/17). In particular Suarez first made the distinction between metaphysica generalis (ontologia) and metaphysica specialis which exercised such a decisive influence on Wolff and Baumgarten, and through them on Kant and Hegel. General metaphysics 8 I am assuming in these pages that the reader is already familiar with the scholastic tradition and I am concentrating my attention on what is distinctive about Heidegger's interpretation of the scholastics, 68 JOHN D. CAPUTO deals with the concept of being in general, and special metaphysics with particular beings. Indeed I do not believe we would be too far astray in finding traces of this distinction in Heidegger's own" ontological difference." For this is a distinction between Being-which is to be met with only in Dasein's "understanding of Being "-and beings. Being is not any existing, particular being and must never be confused with such; Being is rather that upon which beings are projected in order to be understood in their Being. Being must be understood before beings, even as general metaphysics precedes special metaphysics. Thus "fundamental ontology "-the inquiry into Dasein's understanding of Being-precedes the metaphysics which is to be built up upon it and which will deal with particular, existing beings (the regional ontologies) .9 Suarez's position on essence and existence, Heidegger says, " is the most suited for carrying out a phenomenological exposition of the problem" (GPdP, 135) because Suarez approaches the problem on the level of experience. Suarez, we will recall, argued that one could only make a conceptual distinction between essence and existence in created beings. If one considers the actual, existing concrete being then it is clear that the two principles are identical. For a thing is not real by something other than itself. Because Suarez's views are inspired by considering what concretely exists, his standpoint is closer to the phenomenological one, to first-hand seeing, to an "intuitive look" at the created being. Aquinas, on the other hand, proceeds " conceptually " from the idea of what a created being must be if it is to be intelligible. From Heidegger's phenomenological standpoint, Aquinas's view represents more of a ' theory ' which attempts a conceptual interpretation of the "idea" of a created being.10 9 See Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, translated J. Churchill (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1962), § 2, on Heidegger's interpretation of the distinction between general and special metaphysics in terms of his own " ontological difference." 10 Heidegger's attribution of a more existential approach to Suarez against a more conceptual-abstract approach in Aquinas must be particularly painful to HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 69 The Genetic Origins of the Scholastic Distinction. Scholastic metaphysics is a good example of what the phenomenologists call "objectivism," viz., a theory in which all reference to the thinking subject is excluded in order to bring a pure object into view. Objectivism is the theory of the objective thing in itself. Theoretical physics-for the scientific realist at least-is another example. Thus scholasticism and mathematical physics originate for the phenomenologist in a similar frame of mind. (We recall Pascal's complaint about the God of the philosophers versus the God of Abraham) . Phenomenologists reject objectivism on the basis of their theory of intentionality, according to which every object is an object for consciousnes; every objective property is a clue to a subjective activity in which it is constituted. Now both Heidegger and Husserl in his later works argued for a " genetic phenomenology," viz., a phenomenological analysis which would trace every theoretical object back to the foundational activities (Urstiftungen) in the life of the subject from which these objects first originated and received their meaning. Thus Husserl traced the origin of pure geometry back to the lifeworld of the first geometers, to their need to measure (metros) the earth (geos) in order to build, farm, travel, etc. 11 Heidegger undertakes here just such an analysis of the origin of the scholastic distinction between essence and existence. In his Habilitati-Onsschrift, under the influence of Dilthey's Weltanschauung philosophy, Heidegger traced the medieval doctrine of the analogy of being back to the amplitude of experience of medieval man, i.e., to the presence in his experience of the super.sensible realm of beings-of the soul, angels and God. 12 In The Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology Heidegger Gilson and his followers who contrast Suarez's philosophy of essence with Aquinas's philosophy of existence. 11 Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, translated David Carr (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970), "The Origin of Geometry," pp. 858 ff. 12 Martin Heidegger, Friihe Schriften (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1972), 850-1. 70 JOHN D. CAPUTO situates the origin of essence and existence in human productivity and making (Herstellen). This is carried out as follows. For the scholastics existence is actualitas, but actualitas is related to agere, the act in which something actual is brought forth. In German existentia is translated as "Wirklichkeit ., which is related back to the verb "wirken" (to effect or produce). Thus Giles says that esse is impressed upon essence in order to bring it forth as a being. Now a being is constituted as an actuality for the scholastic inasmuch as it is created, brought forth, produced (hergestellt). Existence refers back to the divine act of making (GPdP, 143-8). Essence too operates within the same conceptual framework. For the essence of a thing is that which gives a thing its ' look' (eidos). For the Greeks eidos is the exemplar (Vorbild) for the formation (bilden) of what is patterned after it (Gebilde) . The exemplar is how what is produced looks before it is produced. Hence the definition of essence as quad quid erat esse, that which a thing was to be (GPdP, 151). Again, the word morphe, which belongs to the order of essence, sounds the motif of that which is stamped or formed according to a certain pattern (GPdP, 149-151) . Both essence and existence refer back to the idea of what is produced: essence is the look which the thing to be produced has; existence is actually being brought forth. But the conceptual framework of producing and making leads back to Dasein's own concrete Being-in-the-world. For Dasein lives its everyday life within the horizon of a world of tools and instruments, of things which Dasein makes and uses (Zeuge, Gebrauchsdinge) , whether these things be actual products of his (farm tools, e.g.) or that which, being "already there," he uses (the farmer's field itself) (GPdP, 152-3). This conception of Being within which Dasein lives his daily life is what Heidegger calls "being ready to hand" (Zuhandensein), i.e., Being which is accessible to Dasein's use.13 Dasein itself, in its pre13 Notice how Heidegger's idea of "Zuhandensein" tinction between " nature " and "art." overlaps the traditional dis- HEIDEGGER AND THE SCIIOLASTICS 11 ontological understanding of Being, supplies the horizon within which beings can be conceived or made (or used) . Accordingly Dasein itself supplies the horizon within which Being is interpreted in scholastic metaphysics, in which the Being of God is determined as the creator (H ersteller) and the beings around us are determined as "created" (hergestellt) . Thus the ideas of essence and existence take their origin from the subjective-existential sphere; they have their "birth certificate," to use Kant's expression (GPdP, 140), in Dasein's concrete life. But this genetic origin was forgotten by the scholastics, and that is what makes scholastic " objectivism " possible. Like every objectivism it is naivete, forgetfulness (GPdP, 155). Producing (Herstellen) is that by which something is brought forth so that it may stand there by itself (fur sfoh steht: GPdP, 152). But once it is set forth we tend to forget that and how it was put there. We stand back and behold it. On the side of the subject, the practical life which produces is replaced by the theoretical look of the observer. On the side of the object the being takes on the look of the readymade, the finished, the in-itself (GPdP, 159-60) . Being-in-itself is really Being which has been " released " and " set free " from its subjective origin. Thus even as the origins of geometry were forgotten, and the structures of geometry were taken over as ready-made by Galileo and the practitioners of the new science, even so the life-world origin of the ideas of essence and existence dropped out of sight. Essence and existence are then taken to mean objective structures of Being which have nothing to do with the conscious subject out of whose concrete life they are first born. In Heidegger's view, ancient ontology was "tailor made" (GPdP, 168) to the needs of medieval Christian philosophy and theology. All its basic concepts-morphe,. hyle, eidos, energeia, ousia-move within the horizon of Herstellen. To be sure the ancients lacked the idea of creation ex nihilo. But the fundamental horizon of its ontology, the pre-ontological framework within which its basic concepts were framed, was JOHN D. CAPUTO that of making. Thus, even though the concepts of ancient ontology were modified by the medievals, the scholastics still remained within the fundamental " understanding of Being " which existed in antiquity. The changes made by the scholastics were ontic. They made new assertions about beings: the demiurge and prime mover were replaced by a creator-God; the psyche of Plato and Aristotle became the medieval anima, the bearer of immortal life; they added the whole economy of sin and redemption and the angelic order. But what Being itself meant derived from antiquity: that which, being made according to a pattern, stands forth finished and-to the observer-ready-made. Heidegger's interpretation must indeed appear most provocative to the medievalists, and Thomists in particular, for whom the idea of esse represents a distinctive and original principle in Thomistic metaphysics, a principle which sets Thomas off once and for all from Greek ontology. For Heidegger, the notion of esse is but an extension of Greek ontology which leaves the basic framework of Greek ontology untouched. We shall have occasion to return to this idea below in our critical evaluation of Heidegger's interpretation (Part II). But for the moment we should point out that in his later writings Heidegger modifies this view. In the Nietzsche lectures he will still regard the doctrines of essence and existence as belonging to the metaphysics of making, but he will then say this metaphysics was distinctively medieval, not Greek. This too will be discussed below. The Articulation of Being and the Ontological Difference. Heidegger next raises the question of the relationship of this distinction to his own " ontological difference." He approaches this problem by criticizing the applicability of these categories to Dasein. Dasein, he says, does not answer to the question of ' what ' (quid) is it, but to the question of ' who ' is it. It is inappropriate to speak of the "whatness" or "quiddity" of Dasein. Nor is Dasein's existence mere existentia (Vorhandenheit) , having-been-brought-forth. On the contrary, Dasein is HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 78 the thrown and " factical " being whose Being is an issue for itself. Neither category befits Dasein. In place of essentia one must speak of Dasein's being-a-self (Selbstsein); Dasein is always 'I myself' (Jemeinigkeit), whether in the mode of being faithful to itself (Eigentlichkeit) or not (Uneigentlichkeit) . And in place of existentia one must speak of Dasein's " facticity ." 14 Essence and existence are categories of things and fit under a more general distinction between ' how ' a thing is and 'that' it is. We may diagram this as follows: How That I I I Dasein Selfhood (W erheit) Facticity Non-Dasein I I Essence (W asheit) Existence I In Being and Time Heidegger says that the" essence" of Dasein lies in its "existence" (SZ, 42/67). But he puts the word essence in quotes, to differentiate it from the traditional idea, and he uses "Existenz " in the Kierkegaardian sense, which is sharply differentiated from existentia. Thus he uses the language of the tradition to say something quite untraditional. I think the sentence-the traditional definition of God-is meant to have something of a shock value and, in its paradoxicality, to draw attention to Heidegger's new concept of Dasein. ' How ' and ' that' thus constitute the basic " articulation ·• of Being. This distinction is itself differentiated according to the various kinds or regions of beings to be considered. We may diagram this as follows: Being (Sein) I beings (Seiendes) I that I how I I Selfhood I individual Dasein Dasein I Facticity V orhandensein I existentia I essentia I individual things J "Despite what Heidegger says here this two-fold articulation of Dasein's Being is a Procrustean bed into which Dasein does not suitably fit. Dasein has a three-- fold temporal structure. 74 JOHN D. CAPUTO Thus the categories of essence and existence have a two-fold shortcoming. In the first place, they are the categories of things. They do not apply to man. Nor do they apply to God, Who is not a" thing" either. That is why Pascal raised his complaint about the God of the philosophers, and why Heidegger later on would speak of the necessity to find a God to Whom one could bend one's knee (ID, 140/71-fl). These are categories which have been drawn from the sphere of Dasein's everyday Being-in-the-world and from the sphere of its commerce with things. They befit neither man nor God. Hence one gets no closer to the Being of God or men when one settles the question of whether essence and existence are the same or different in each. For one's understanding of the Being of each is radically defective.15 This brings us to the second fault of this distinction. In remaining wholly on one side of the ontological difference, it fails to raise in a radical way the question of the meaning of Being. It does not rise above the conception of Being as V orhandensein to question Being itself in its manifold sense. It has not ascended to Being itself but remains confined within a certain regional category of beings, a limited kind of Being. Were it truly a radical metaphysics, scholasticism would have conceptualized the ontological difference. It would have recognized the radical difference between Being and beings, that Being is never a being or region of beings, flnd that it can never be confined within a single kind of Being. But instead the scholastics contented themselves with the understanding of Being which had been passed down to them from antiquity. They devoted their energies to debates about the structures or articulation of Being-as-V orhandensein without ever stepping out of the circle of this understanding of Being to question it as such, and that means without ever truly raising the question of Being. That is the criticism which Heidegger has in mind 15 We can see here why Heidegger does not identify God with Being but locates Him within the sphere of beings. Heidegger does not mean that God is an individuum limited by some principium individuationis. He means that the Being of God is always approached from some prior understanding of Being which lays down the basic framework in terms of which we determine God's Being. HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 75 when he says that the scholastic distinction remained on one side of the ontological difference. Essence and Existence According to the Later Heidegger. It is not possible to adequately address ourselves to the question of Heidegger's interpretation of the scholastic doctrine of essence and existence without including a discussion of the later Heidegger's treatment of this theory in 1941, some 14 years after the Marburg lectures (N II, 899-420/1-19). Heidegger's standpoint has been altered considerably in the intervening years, so much so that the whole project of transcendentalhermeneutical phenomenology, such as we find it in 1927-and .so of a regress to the 'subject' (Dasein) (GPdP, 108) as the explanatory basis for what Being means-has been overcome in favor of a thinking in terms of the history and mission of Being (Seinsgeschick). Speaking of the second part of Being and Time (a destruction of the history of metaphysics), Heidegger says: But this destruction, like phenomenology and all hermeneuticaltranscendental questions, has not yet been thought in terms of the history of Being. (N II, 415/15) What Being means in the middle ages is now understood to be the way Being reveals itself to medieval man, rather than the way Being was projected in the medieval understanding of Being. As in 1927 Heidegger traces the distinction between essence and existence back to Plato and Aristotle. But the difference is this. For the later Heidegger the original essence of Being is expressed in the Greek words aletheia and physis. That is to say, Being is the process of emerging into presence and abiding there; it is the process of self-showing by which the being shows itself from itself. Rather than being the light projected by Dasein's understanding of Being (1927), it is the light of Being itself in which beings are made visible to Dasein. Now this original essence of Being is found in its pristine form 76 JOHN D. CAPUTO in the Presocratics, after whom it is progressively covered over. Plato and Aristotle are the first figures in the history of " metaphysics," and that means they are already fallen out of the experience of Being. But being .so close to the Presocratics they have retained something of the power and meaning of their original experience. For Plato Being is the presence which abides (ousia) not in individual beings but in the eidos,. which is the true and abiding look of a thing. Essence (eidos) is prior to individual things (existence). Aristotle, with his distinction between ousia in the primary and secondary sense (Cat. V, 2a 11 ff.) reverses this order. For him, Being is the presence which abides in the form of the singular individual. What exists is prior to its pure look. Thus Plato and Aristotle open up the distinction between essence and existence, and in .so doing inaugurate the history of metaphysics. But in both cases Being is determined as ousia, and that means that something of the original experience of Being as presence and as that which lies forth in unconcealment is retained (N. II, 399-410/1-10). But with progression from energeia and eidos in the Greeks to the medieval aotualitas and essentia an essential change sets in. These are not innocent translations (Ubersetzungen) but an essential modification of the tradition (Uberlieferung). For now Being is determined in accordance with the metaphysics of making. Despite the fact that the word "existence" at first holds some promise, the medieval is soon recognized to be further fallen out of the original experience of Being: Ex-sistere specu means for Cicero to step out of the cave. One might suspect here a deeper relation of existentia as stepping out and forward to coming forward to presence and unconcealment. Then the Latin word would preserve an essential Greek content. That is not the case. Similarly, actualitas no longer preserves the essence of energeia. The literal translation is misleading. In truth it brings precisely another transposition or misplacement to the word of Being. (N. II, Instead of meaning what stands out (ex-sists) in concealment, existence now means that which stands outside of its causes and HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 77 so outside of non-being (res extra causas et nihilum sistens) . This medieval sending of Being occurs in terms of making and producing. Thus essentia is the "possibility" of what is to be made, existentia the " actuality " of what has been posited outside of its potency. God is then conceived as the purely actual being who stands outside of any need to be made and for whom there is no possibility preceding his actuality. The ChristianRoman experience of Being is cut off from the original Greek experience. It is one step further removed from "Being" as unconcealment and " thought " as that which lets the being lie forth (Vorliegenlassen). Instead we find in the middle ages a metaphysics of "reality" (Wirklichkeit), of the work which is brought forth, and of thinking as causal thinking. The outlines of modern technology (Technik) are already to be found here. The world is treated as the product of a making (Herstand) and thought is contracted to demonstrative argumentation. The similarity of the attitudes of scholasticism and mathematical physics turns out to be no mere accident. The forgottenness of Being is beginning to take over. The middle ages represent a decisive step in the "de-volution" of thought (N II, Heidegger's attitude towards the medievals has in the years and 1941 become considerably more critical. Inbetween stead of seeing the unity of Greek and medieval ontology he now points to the rift between the Greek and the ChristianRoman experience of Being-between Greek and Latin. Now only medieval ontology belongs within the metaphysics of " making " and this represents a corruption of Plato and Aristotle. What then has become of the extensive argument in The Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology about morphe and hyle, energeia and eidos? In part Heidegger has become considerably more .sensitive to language. Because it is separated from the Greeks by a different language, the medieval experience of Being has taken a radically different shape. I think too that Heidegger's sympathy for the middle ages has waned somewhat over the years; he is now no longer in danger of being 78 JOHN D. CAPUTO taken as a " Catholic phenomenologist." Hand in hand with this, his appreciation for the Greeks has been intensified and his interpretation of the Greek experience of Being as aJ,etheia has been sharpened. Finally, Heidegger has, as he himself says, adopted a more radically historical point of view than is to be found in Being and Time-historical not in the sense of giving an historical report (ein historischer Bericht NII, 399/1) about the history of metaphysics, but in the sense of following the history and mission of Being in each epoch. He thus came in his later works to agree in his own way with the medievalists who see a sharp difference between the Greek and medieval doctrines of Being. Like them he would see the doctrine of creation to be the focal point of this difference; but this difference would represent for Heidegger a devolution, not an advance. In either period, early or late, Heidegger saw the distinction between essence and existence to be a failure to attain Being itself. In both cases he considers the scholastics to have determined Being in terms of the categories of a particular kind of being. They attain not to Being but to the " Beingness of beings" (die Seiendheit des Seienden, NII, 414/14) and their efforts are bent only on " articulating " the latter; as such scholasticism arises from the forgottenness of Being. That is the central claim of Heidegger's critique, and one to which we must now address ourselves. PART II. A CRITICAL EVALUATION OF HEIDEGGER'S INTERPRETATION OF SCHOLASTIC METAPHYSICS. The first difficulty which faces any attempt to assess Heidegger's critique of scholastic metaphysics is to decide which critique to assess. For the early Heidegger criticized the scholastics, from the standpoint of a transcendental-hermeneutical phenomenology, for a naive objectivism which failed to recognize the genetic origin of its ideas in Dasein's own Being-in-the-world. But in the late Heidegger this standpoint and the criticism arising from it are dropped, and the critique shifts to a new standpoint, viz., that of Being as aletheia. I will therefore dis- HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 79 cuss three questions. (1) The first concerns the early Heidegger's "genetic phenomenology" of essence and existence. For even if Heidegger later on saw fit to drop the transcendental standpoint, the argument retains an interest in its own right which will repay consideration. (2) Secondly, I wish to discuss Heidegger's notion that the principles of essence and existence belong within the framework of a metaphysics of HersteUen. This position is a constant in Heidegger's thought: in the early period, " making " is the transcendental horizon upon which beings are projected by medieval Dasein; in the later period " making " is the face which Being turns to medieval man. (3) Thirdly, I wish to discuss Heidegger's charge that the doctrine of essence and existence represents a form of the oblivion of Being. In particular this will involve discussing the relationship between esse in Thomas Aquinas and Heidegger's aletheia. Heidegger's Genetw Phenomenology of Essence and &dstence. Scholastic theory is naive, according to Heidegger, because it believes it attains an objective being-in-itself whereas in fact every objective structure is a projection of subjective life. This is a transcendental criticism of scholasticism which stems from a Cartesian standpoint that is radically at odds with scholastic realism. The scholastic philosopher who reads Heidegger's critique might want to direct our attention to the doctrine of analogy. For there scholastic philosophy achieves a criticalreflective awareness of the origin and applicability of the terms which it uses. It would be pointed out that the scholastic philosopher is aware that his determination of God as a maker must ultimately be based upon a direct knowledge of human making, which is what we know directly and properly about making. But, it would be argued, human making is then subjected to an analogical transfer by which it is predicated of God only " eminentiore modo." The scholastic philosopher is not naive because he knows that whatever is affirmed of God is also denied of Him, inasmuch as everything predicated of God has its epistemological origin in the sensible world. 80 JOHN D. CAPUTO But Heidegger's argument cuts deeper than any theory of analogical predication. For one thing, his argument is that every theoretical object comes back to the existential subject from which it derives its meaning. It asserts therefore the primacy of the practical and the derivative character of all theoretical objects, a thesis which is incompatible with the primacy of the speculative among medieval intellectualists. But more importantly Heidegger's (and Husserl's) "genetic phenomenology " denies the whole idea of objective being-in-itself and so of realism-scholastic, scientific or whatever. 16 Being for Heidegger is always Being as it enters into Dasein's understanding of Being. There is Being, Heidegger says, only insofar as it is understood by Dasein (SZ, 212/255). Being is always thought in terms of a horizon which is projected by Dasein. The ultimate conclusion to which Being and Time builds up is that the meaning of Being is time, that is, Being is projected upon time inasmuch as temporality constitutes the Being of Dasein. Thus Heidegger's claim is far more radical than any theory of analogy. The theory of analogical predication does not escape Heidegger's charge of naivete, for this theory allows us to believe that we attain being-in-itself, even if such being is only imperfectly grasped. But it is only because the genetic origins of such beingin-itself have been forgotten, in Heidegger's view, that we entertain such an illusion. The scholastic who wishes to respond to Heidegger's critique has to come to grips with the whole premise of transcendental philosophy. This is not to say that scholasticism is incompatible with every form of transcendental philosophy, as is testified to by the emergence of " transcendental Thomism " in the 20th century in the writings of Marechal and his followers. Here the attempt is made to relate St. Thomas's metaphysics to "the regress to the subject," i. e., to relate the Thomistic doctrine of Being to the Being of the subject which understands Being. Thus Emerich Coreth looks with favor upon Heidegger's project 11 Cf. Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, translated W. R. Boyce Gibson (New York: Collier Books, §§ 48 and HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 81 of a "fundamental ontology." 17 He attempts in his Metaphymcs an exposition of Thomistic metaphysics which thematizes the idea of the " question of Being " and of the Being of the questioner. He makes use of Heidegger's idea of a preontological understanding of Being which Dasein " always already" (immer schon) possesses. The task of metaphysics, says Coreth, is to make this implicit understanding of Being explicit. Such a metaphysics must in the end depart in a fundamental way from Husserl and Heidegger, but it belongs to the circle of problems raised by the early Heidegger's critique of scholasticism and it represents, I believe, a fruitful line of interpretation of St. Thomas. Being and the Metaphysics of Making (Herstellen). Heidegger has persistently maintained that scholastic metaphysics takes place within the horizon of " making," that it does not grasp Being as such but Being within the determinate horizon of a particular region of beings, the things which are to be made. In this section and the one that follows I would like to limit my considerations to Thomas Aquinas, because his conception of esse represents the important contribution of scholastic metaphysics and, I believe, the most fruitful basis of comparison and contrast with Heidegger's "thought of Being " within the scholastic tradition. Heidegger claims that the Thomistic idea of existence is to be conceived as the actualitas which gives reality to a posmbilitas which awaits making. This is, I believe, an oversimplification of St. Thomas. To begin with, essence is not a free-floating possihilitas which awaits actualization, although that is how Heidegger tends to portray it, particularly when he is speaking of Aquinas in reference to Suarez. On the contrary essence is a real principle in an actual being, but it is a principle of limitation, while esse is what is limited. Moreover 17 Emerich Coreth, Metaphysics, translated and edited J. Donceel (New York: Seabury Press, 1973), pp. 27-9. 82 JOHN D. CAPUTO Heidegger puts no particular stock in the fact that Thomas does not use the word e-:dstentia but rather esse. But is not the whole thrust of this verbal noun to avoid contracting Being to any of its modes which would be less than the pure act of being itself? I think that Heidegger underestimate.s Aquinas's notion of esse by trying to confine it within the horizon of making. It is perfectly true that the doctrine of creation was the principal "motive" for Aquinas's philosophy of esse. But his notion of esse is not reducible to the framework of making. The Thomistic commentators are right to defend the originality of St. Thomas on this point. Aquinas's conceptual framework is not confined by the Greek idea of what is made according to a pattern, although the same cannot be said for other medieval philosophers who remained more thoroughly under the influence of Plato and Aristotle. Thomas conceived of an order of actuality beyond the sphere of matter and form, which are the original" regions" in which Aristotle spoke of act and potency. As it has been repeatedly pointed out, Aquinas discovered an act which is not a form but the .simple act of being itself. He has achieved an insight into the simple act by which a thing is rather than is not, by which it rises up into being and abides there. The being is conceived by him not as ex-sisting in the sense of standing outside its cause-for esse applies both to what is caused and uncaused-but rather in its very actuality as a being, in its very be-ing. It is indeed true enough that Aquinas does not remain within this sphere of the simple insight into the emerging into Being of the being. On the contrary-just as Heidegger says-this esse is divided into the esse which has been received from another-esse causatum-and the esse which subsists of itselfipsum esse subsistens. In other words this insight into esse takes place in the sphere of causal thought, and it is for all practical purposes lost to the sight of Heidegger and his followers. It is developed into a causal-demonstrative scientia which establishes causal lines between God and creatures, which charts the struc- HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 83 tures of the various created orders of beings and which seeks to determine the Being of God as the uncaused cause. In other words this insight into Being passes over into what Heidegger calls "onto-theo-logic": a demonstrative science (logic) of being as such (ontology) which has recourse to God as the cause of beings (theology) . It is occupied in giving an " account" (Rec.hnen) of the relationship between beings instead of savoring and unfolding its original insight into the simple act-of-be-ing-itself. The Forgetfulness of Being and Aquinas's Notion of Esse. In what sense then does Heidegger think that Aquinas is guilty of a forgetfulness of Being? 18 Has not Heidegger rather unfairly represented the best insights of Thomas's metaphysics? Has he not missed precisely what is meant by esse when he says that scholasticism attains only to the being as a being (das Seiende als Seiende), the being in its Being-ness (das Seiende in seiner Seiendheit)? That is indeed what the students of St. Thomas who are familar with Heidegger maintain. Bernard Rioux writes: 19 The interest of a confrontation of St. Thomas with the thought of the philosopher from Freiburg is that the former is perhaps the only representative of that tradition, which is accused of having forgotten Being, who has made Being the central theme of all his reflections in regard to truth. and again: ... St. Thomas has developed an ontology of truth which reposes in the unveiling of every being (em) in its Being (ipsum esse). Emerich Coreth says: 20 1 • Of course Heidegger is not speaking of any personal fault on Aquinas's part; Aquinas is simply the victim of the withdrawal of Being in the Middle Ages. 1 • Rioux, pp. 254, 183. 2 ° Coreth, p. 29. See also: Max Millier, Existenzphilosophie im Geistigen Leben der Gegenwart 3. Aull. (Heidelberg: Kerle, 1964), 241 ff; Gustav Siewerth, Das Schicksal, der Metaphysik von Thomas zu Heidegger (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1959); Cornelio Fabro, "The Transcendentality of "Ens-esse" and the Ground 84 JOHN D. CAPUTO No thinker of the past has been more clearly aware of the ontological difference than Thomas Aquinas, nobody has more clearly distinguished between being (ens) and being (esse), or interpreted beings more consistently in the light of being. As a matter of fact, it is precisely with the forgetfulness of Being that the Thomists charge other philosophers. It is precisely this that Gilson has attributed to the history of metaphysics.21 Plato and Plotinus think Being not as Being but as the one, Aristotle as substance (ousia), Augustine as eternity, and so on with Descartes, Kant and positivism. Each of these metaphysical systems, each in its own way, is a victim of what Gilson calls " essentialism," of an attempt to reduce Being to some" whatness," some particular kind of Being. The glory of Aquinas, it is held, is that he does not emphasize any "predicate "-unity, permanence, extension--over the purity of Being itself. Instead St. Thomas thinks Being as such, in terms of the pure " act-of-being." Should we conclude then that Heidegger simply has not followed closely enough the modem interpretations of Thomas Aquinas? I have no idea of what Hiedegger knew about these developments, but I have a healthy fear of saying that he does not know about this or that interpretation of a major historical figure such as Aquinas. His historical erudition is quite extraordinary; his unorthodox interpretations stem not from mis'Understanding what Aristotle or Kant mean, but from a deeper philosophical dialogue with them. We will, I think, clarify nothing simply by charging that Heidegger does not understand Aquinas. The better path consists in thinking Heidegger's critique through. To do this I propose we turn our attention to Heidegger's treatment of the Greek words physis and aletheia, around of Metaphysics," International Philosophical Quarterly VI, 8 (September, 1966), 21 Etienne Gilson, Being and Some Philosophers (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1949); The Christian Philosophy of St. Augustine, translated L. Lynch (London: Gollancz, 1961); The Unity af Philosophical Experience (New York: Scribners, 1987). HEIDEGGER AND TBE SCHOLASTICS 85 which his whole understanding of Being turns, and then relate this back to Aquinas's understanding of esse. Physis for Heidegger refers to Being as emergent. 22 He emphasizes the connection of the word with life and growth, a sense which has completely dropped out of our " physical " ; indeed we contrast the physical with the living (physics vs. biology). This original meaning is also contained in the Latin natura (nascor, nasci, natus sum), but this is again hardly retained by our" nature." Physis means the process by which the being emerges into presence, irrupts; it signifies a certain upsurge into being. Now on the basis of what we have said above in connection with esse as the pure act of be-ing, I believe that a good case can be made that both Aquinas and Heidegger think Being as an emergent power, as an active upsurge into being. Esse for St. Thomas is not a mere status, not a static factum, but an agere, an upsurge which rises up and overcomes nothingness. Aquinas's esse and Heidegger's " Wesen understood verbally" are close kin. Indeed the verbal wesen is a Middle High German translation of esse--e. g., in Meister Eckhart. The difference sets in when we turn to the word aletheia. The process of emergence for Heidegger is an emergence into " manifestness," emergence from concealment (lethe) into unconcealment (a-letheia). Thus Being is inseparable from "truth" for Heidegger, not propositional truth, but a "manifestness " proper to Being itself. It is here that the " phenomenological" (taken in a wide enough sense to cover both the early and late Heidegger) character of Heidegger's work must be accorded its due. In his early writings Heidegger insisted Being is to be met with only in Dasein's "understanding of Being " in which the " meaning " of Being is constituted. Being is that in reference to which beings must be understood in order to be manifest as beings. In the late work Heidegger retains this relatedness between Being and Dasein's understanding, but now he reverses the direction of the relationship. ••Cf. An Introduction to Metaphysics, 11-4; Der Satz vom Grund (Pfullingen: Neske, 1957), pp. 86 JOHN D. CAPUTO In Being and Time the being is projected in terms of a certain understanding of Being; Being is " unconcealment " because it is what is uncovered in and through Dasein's disclosive activity. But in the late works Being rises up and discloses itself to Dasein, addresses Dasein, reveals itself; the task of Dasein is not to "project" Being but to "release" it, to let it be (Gelassenheit) . Yet it would be a mistake to think that in the later work, where the transcendental attitude is overcome, Being becomes thereby something "in itself," detached from Dasein. Rather it is essentially a process of rising up and disclosing itself to Dasein. Instead of being projected or uncovered by Dasein, it reveals and discloses itself to Dasein. The relationship to Dasein, while modified, remains unbroken. Thus Being is truth for Heidegger, i.e., a process of emerging (physis) into "presence" (Anwesen), unconcealment (aletheia). Now if a case can be made for a kinship between esse and physis, as I believe it can, no comparable case can be made for esse and aletheia. Aquinas's esse is not emergence into unconcealment, a process of "revealing" itself to the intellect. At least it is not essentially and primarily that. Rather the relationship to the intellect is something subsequent to or consequent upon esse in St. Thomas. One need only read De veritate, I, I, to see that Being is not grasped primarily and essentially as unconcealment. On the contrary, St. Thomas argues there that truth, "ontological" truth (as opposed to propositional truth) , is some kind of addition to Being (ex additione ad ens), which is consequent upon being (consequens omne ens). To the first objection, that Augustine .says that truth means "that which is," St. Thomas responds that this is a definition of truth not in the formal sense but in terms of its foundation in reality. Augustine's definition of truth refers to " that which precedes the formal notion of truth, and in which truth is founded." And again: " ... the entity of a thing precedes the notion of truth." 23 Truth does not, as in Heideg23 " ••• id quod praecedit rationem veritatis, et in quo verum fundatur." " ... entitas rei praecedit rationem veritatis ... " Thomas Aquinas, Q. D. de veritate, I, 1, c; cf. ad I um. HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS 87 ger, enter into the definition of Being; rather verum is a transcendental property of Being which arises insofar as Being enters into a relationship with the intellect. That being is "precedes" (ontologically, not chronologically) its entering into a relationship with intellect and so being determined as truth. But for Heidegger this conception of Being and truth is a victim of the naivete of" Being-in-itself," Being prior to its revelation to Dasein. It is a naivete which forgets that Being is "always and already" something understood by Dasein. We are now in a position to understand why Heidegger charges the scholastics with the forgetfulnes of Being. He means that Being has ceased to mean that which shows itself, that which emerges into manifestness. Eidos (the pure look of that which shows itself) becomes essentia (the form in accordance with which a thing is made). Being as pure selfshowing passes over into Being as caused and uncaused. The pristine simplicity of Being as that which steps forth into the light, that which shines and appears (scheint und erscheint) recedes in favor of a contraction of that appearing into cause and effect, act and potency, essence and existence-all of which are determinate structures, specific ways of appearing. Appearing as such (Sein als Scheinen) is lost and its place is taken by a particular kind of appearance. Appearing as such gives way to appearances, to what is in appearance. Manifesting gives way to what is manifest. The simplicity of pure selfpresenting, the purity of mere showing itself as such, recedes behind the clamor of the things which are seen. We see the things that the sun illumines but we never look up to the sun, to luminosity itself. More fundamental for Heidegger than every determination of Being is the self-manifesting of Being itself. Manifestness is not a predicate which-along with four or five others-is convertible with Being, but that which Being properly and primarily means. For Aquinas self-showing is something "consequent" upon Being, not its very meaning. If it is true, as I believe it is, that Aquinas had a real insight into the physis-character of Being, 88 JOHN D. CAPUTO into Being as simple emergence into presence, still this insi,ght took place in the sphere of objective thinking. Even if Aquinas grasped Being as the act-of-be-ing, as emerging-into-presence, Heidegger would still want to say that he has conceived this whole process non-phenomenologically, as taking place in the sphere of things-in-themselves and this is a form of naivete. For Aquinas esse is the act by which a thing comes to be and to .stand in itself; for Heidegger it is a process of emerging into sight, appearing, self-showing. When Heidegger's charge of a forgetfulness of Being against the Thomistic doctrine of esse is carefully scrutinized, it amounts to a charge that Thomas has forgotten Being-as aletheia. I do not think it can be maintained, as Heidegger would have us think, that esse is something " ontic," that it attains to " befagness" not Being. But it remains true that Being is not for St. Thomas what Father Richardson calls a "lighting process." Aquinas thinks Being "objectively," independent of its relationship to the subject (intellectus). It is not Being but the manifestness of Being which is primary for Heidegger, for Being is manifestness, self-revelation. Against Husserl, Heidegger was compelled to argue for the ontological character of phenomenology, for the fact that a phenomenon's "appearing" is its "Being": to appear is to be. Against Aquinas, he would argue the other side of this position, viz., the phenomenological character of ontology, that is, that Being is the principle of self-manifestness: to be is to appear. 25 For Heidegger it is possible to speak of Being as esse only if Being is already manifest (aletheia). For Aquinas truth (aletheia) is possible only if there is first of all Being (esse). For Aquinas truth (aletheia) is "founded" on being (esse) . ••Richardson refers to Being as a-letheia as a " lighting process " ; cf. pp. 6-8 et passim. 25 It is interesting that when one tries to differentiate Heidegger from Husserl, Heidegger appears as something of a realist; but when one tries to differentiate him from Aquinas he appears to be more of an idealist. Of course the truth is that he is neither. Phenomenology represents the mediation of these two positions; cf. SZ, HEIDEGGER ANb THE SCHOLASTICS 89 For Heidegger to be " founded " is itself a certain conceptual determination, a certain mode of being manifest which presupposes Being as manifestness; to be " founded " is a meaning which appears out against the background of a whole system of self-revelation on the part of Being. For Aquinas it is Heidegger who is forgetful of Being itself and who has contracted it to one of its modes-viz., to truth. For it is only in a metaphysics of esse that Being is grasped as such; truth-and goodness and beauty-are convertible terms with being, consequentia of Being, things defined in terms of Being. For Heidegger, it is Aquinas who has forgotten Being because he has forgotten that before it is anything else-before it is essence or esse, act or potency-Being is simple emergence into unconcealment. " Objective " Being-in-itself, and the articulation of it into essence and esse, is a naivete, a construction derived by taking Being, as it were," before" it is manifest (esse praecedit rationem veritatis) , cutting off its relationship to Dasein, and treating it as if it were "merely present" (Vorhandensein). Essence and esse are modes of being manifest which presuppose the process of manifestness itself. For Heidegger, " objective Being" (esse) is a derivative mode of truth (aletheia); for Aquinas truth (verum, ontological truth) is a mode of Being (ens). What one discovers when one attempts a confrontation of Aquinas and Heidegger is that the two positions arise from radically different standpoints, radically different approaches to the question of Being. St. Thomas proceeds intellectualistically and objectivistically. I do not mean to say that St. Thomas is a " rationalist " in the 17th and 18th century sense, or to deny his starting point in sense experience. I mean to say that his method is 1) detached," objective," purely" scientific," and that, given its original point of departure in the senses, it proceeds along the route of rational argumentation. St. Thomas speaks " about" Being in propositions for which there can be proofs and refutations (disputatio). But Heidegger's approach is radically different: he speaks from within Being, " out of 90 JOHN D. CAPUTO the experience" (aus der Erfahrung) of Being. His words are not " propositions "·or assertions about Being but the words in which Being itself is given birth in language. Heidegger's whole approach is to listen, to hear, to be touched by Being. It does not in the end depend on concepts (Vorstellungen) but on a deeper experience of Being. Now it is in this respectively differing approach to Being that the different understanding of Being which Aquinas and Heidegger offer to us is rooted. Because Aquinas's approach is objectivistic and scientific he conceives Being as the objective act-of-be-ing. But because Heidegger's approach was at the outset "phenomenological," and because this was then later transmuted into a Seinserfahrung, an experience of Being, Heidegger's understanding of Being was quite different. For him Being is experientially encountered and it is from this standpoint that he speaks of it as a rising up into presence, an emergence into the light (phos, phainomenon), a surging up into the "clear" (Lichtung). From Heidegger's standpoint Being is truth; from Aquinas's, truth is a predicate of Being. It is a question of methoddisputatio vs. Denken. I do not mean to imply that this confrontation dissolves into an arbitrary difference of standpoint, that it comes down to an initial groundless act of the will in which one adopts one's basic approach. I mean rather that the real debate between Aquinas and Heidegger must be seen to take place on the level of method, that it is really a question of how Being is to be made accessible to us. Can Being be the object of a scientia,indeed even the early Heidegger thought of the phenomenology of Being as strenge Wissenschaft-or is it only "given" in an " address " which can best be " heard " in the depths of our experience? Can there be proofs in metaphysics or only "experiences"? Is Being the "object" of a science? Or is it more objective than any object and more subjective than any subject? It is with such questions that one must deal if one wishes to relate Heidegger's thought of Being to scholastic metaphysics. * * * 91 HEIDEGGER AND THE SCHOLASTICS Aquinas and Heidegger are two of the great philosophers of Being in Western thought, neither of whom, I believe, can be properly accused of the forgetfulness of Being. We cannot, however, pretend to have adequately dealt with the whole of this subject matter. We have not so much as mentioned the important, indeed central, theme of time and history in Heideg.ger.26 But we can pretend to have made a contribution towards the understanding of the interplay between their thought. In the confrontation of these radically different yet mysteriously akin interpretations of Being there lies a great opportunity for us to awaken in ourselves a renewed sense of the question of Being. For as Heidegger says in the course of the lectures (GPdP, it is not Aristotle or Kant-and we can add Aquinas or Heidegger-that we wish to renew, but we ourselves. JOHN D. CAPUTO Villanova University Villanova, Pa. 26 An essential part of the scholastic's naivete for Heidegger would consist in his unmindfulness that the aletheia process is essentially historical. The scholastic is taken in (eingenommen) by the pull (Zug) of his age which is really Being's withdrawal (Entzug). Thus the scholastic treats Being in terms of a scientia which uses the categories of cause and effect, act and potency, etc. It is the same in our age, only nowadays the scientia goes under the name of Technik. The task of thought is to get loose from this epochal manifestation in order to experience the epochal sending itself, the "it" which "gives." Cf. "Time and Being" in Martin Heidegger, On Time and Being, translated Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1972), pp. 1 ff. HUMAN DESTINY AND WORLD POPULATION: THE INDIVIDUAL AS HORIZON AND FRONTIER Adam was therefore established in the perfection befitting the founder of the whole human race. And so it was necessary that he should reproduce in order to multiply the human race and hence that he should take food. But the perfection of the risen will consist in a human nature coming totally into its perfection once the number of the elect is complete. And consequently there will be no place for reproduction nor for the taking of nourishment. 1 (Thomas Aquinas: Summa contra Gentiles, IV, 83) E STIMATES OF THE TOTAL number of human beings who already have lived on the planet Earth are, of course, highly problematic. In any case, whether or not the number is approximately 85 billion, as indicated by several responsible calculations, there have been a finite number of human beings during the course of the aeons since the human race first appeared. Recent attention, furthermore, has concentrated not .so much upon the men and women who have already lived, nor even upon the roughly four billion now alive, as upon the supposedly vast numbers who will yet live: the "futurables," the objects of "futurology." We now know, moreover, that there is a vast difference between the number of people who, severally if not collectively, could emanate from any one human couple-several hundreds on the part of the female if all ova were fertilized during one lifetime, billions on the part of the male-and the number who actually will exist. The decision as to which, if any, of the potential combinations 1 Institutus ergo £uit Adam in tali perfectione quae competebat principio totius humani generis. Et ideo oportuit quod generaret ad multiplicationem humani generis; et per consequens quod cibis uteretur. Sed perfectio resurgentium erit natura humana totaliter ad suam perfectionem perveniente, numero electorum jam completo. Et ideo generatio locum non habebit, nee alimenti usus. HUMAN DESTINY AND WORLD POPULATION 93 should be realized becomes a serious social and moral question once men recognize that the reproductive process can be controlled by will, by force, or by scientific techniques. This has become a crucial contemporary issue because the earth is popularly believed to be reaching its " finite limits " or carrying capacity. Indeed, morality, what it is to be a good man, is currently being interpreted more and more in terms of population density, so that the control of this human population becomes the prima lex for the salus, the wellbeing, of a republic, or of the world. Our primary enemy is coming to be seen as the very existence of additional men, against whom a kind of " incipient " warfare is to be waged by eliminating human conceptions or terminating them before, by birth, they can break into the light of day and gain rights of life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. In this manifoldly questionable view, moreover, men conceive their " function," that is, the justification for the whole collectivity of men to exist at all, as the transformation of the earth in such a manner that there will exist only a steady limited number-say, three to five billion-on Earth at any given time. The purpose of the human race on the planet, seen in its temporal sequence, is held to be the preservation and wellbeing of this privileged collection for as many centuries or ages as possible until the sun finally burns out or some other cosmic event terminates life on Earth. Ultimately, those who do not fall within this planning have no right to exist, since they threaten the collectivity that the Earth allegedly can support. And, even when the Earth can no longer support life, as Wernher von Braun remarked when men first walked on the moon, the earthly race of men may now be " immortal " precisely because it may be able to send its own kind to populate the myriads of Earth-like planets that are thought to dot the cosmos. This new ethico-political goal proposed to the human race, it should be noted, deserves more critical attention than it has been receiving, especially from Christians, who have not been quick to recognize how this thinking often diverges from essential religious views. 94 JAMES V. SCHALL, S. J. At first sight, too, such contemporary issues do not appear to have much connection with the kind of thinking Aquinas engaged in some seven centuries ago. Yet, especially in the Summa Contra Gentiles, there are several remarkable discussions of issues that have now been secularized or politicized. Indeed, it might well be argued that the form in which these notions of ultimate human numbers and purposes appears today is the direct result of rejecting basic values and positions underlying the system of Aquinas. The rise of so-called political theology, so strikingly absent in Aquinas, flows moreover almost directly from deemphasizing the human soul and the final locus of its beatitude. Aquinas never doubted that the number of human beings to be created was itself limited (Summa Theol., I, q. 23, a.7). But the notion that social ethics could be reduced (or nearly reduced) to a proposition of keeping alive a fixed number of men down through the ages would have seemed to belittle less than a revival of Greek biology and its application to man: the immortality of the .species is seen as the purpose of reproduction, and the individual exists only for the species and is not willed except in collective terms. It is surely of some moment that this can be proposed as an alternative morality to that envisioned by Aquinas, which was based upon the free creation, election, and personal destiny of each human being. The Summa Contra Gentiles was written .specifically for a non-Christian and non-Jewish audience so that it might appeal directly to men who had only their humanity in common (I, 2) . The structure of the Contra Gentiles is global. It seeks to establish the nature of God, man, and the universe, and especially to locate and define man's ultimate happiness. This involves Aquinas in the famous position that each man contains within himself all the intellectual powers needed for knowing, so that the destiny of man is open to all knowable things and therefore to God (II, 59; III, 84) . The end of any intellectual creature can only be to know God, and this is the purpose for which men were created (III, 25) . In all of creation there is freedom since the world need not have been at all; nor was it from eternity HUMAN DESTINY AND WORLD POPULATION 95 (III, 23; I, 81). The plan of the universe, then, is achieved when, through Christ, men-body and soul-are able actually to attain to a complete life with God (Bk. IV) . Undoubtedly, at least for modem ears, the part of Aquinas's teaching which is hardest to accept is that each member of the human race existing historically can in his very individuality achieve full beatitude. This is what constitutes ultimately the dignity of the person. But this accomplishment is not something that arises out of mere human activity, nor is it merited by the individual or the race . . . . That predestination and election are not caused by any human merits can be shown not only from the fact that the grace of God, which is the efiect of predestination, does not comes from merits but precedes all human merits ... but also from the fact that the divine will and providence is the first cause of whatever happens, while nothing can be the cause of the divine will and providence .... (III, 168) 2 This, of course, is not to deny that men really have something to do in the universe-secondary causes are real causesbut to confront directly any proposition that would locate human happiness and destiny outside what is ultimately possible only through God's graciousness. We are warned, in other words, against defining man solely in terms of his worldly condition and its temporal succession. The last chapter of the Contra Gentiles-On the State of the World after the Judgment (IV, 97)-is at first sight a curious mixture of medieval astronomy and theological speculation which seeks to justify the continuance of man in the universe after he is no longer subject to those celestial motions that supposedly caused or influenced his begetting on Earth. The import of the considerations, in other words, is how men in a resur• . . . Praedestinatio et electio causam non habet ex aliquibus humanis meritis, potest fieri manifestum, non solum ex hoc quod gratia Dei, quae est praedestinationis efiectus, meritis non praevenitur, sed omnia merita praecedit humana . . . sed etiam manifestare potest ex hoc quod divina voluntas et providentia est prima causa eorum quae fiunt, nil autem potest esse causa voluntatis et providentiae divinae .... (III, q. 163) 96 JAMES V. SCHALL, S. J. rected state can survive when the present conditions of the cosmos no longer obtain. For Aquinas there are indeed things made ad perpetuitatem, made forever though with a beginning; among these are the souls of men by which they transcend the universe itself. And in the Christian dispensation the body shares this destiny also, even though God must supply what is lacking to it-Deo supplente sua virtute quod eis ex propria infirmitate deest. This is the result, furthermore, not of some natural self-transcendence but of the concrete history of salvation to which this race of men is subject. 3 This leads into two observations which are especially relevant to the way in which the contemporary problem seems to be working itself out. The first is that Aquinas regards the number of human beings as finally limited. The goal, however, cannot be the multiplying of souls ad infinitum, since the infinite is contrary to the nature of a goal. So nothing unfitting follows if we posit that, when mankind has reached a cer- tain number, the motions of the heavens will cease.4 •Battista Mondin's comment on W. Pannenherg's theology, and on the importance of this historical race of men and the kind of salvation that is promised them, is worth quoting (in our English translation) : "As is apparent (and the words of Pannenberg allow no doubt), the incarnation of the Son of God in the perspective of transcendental anthropology is not the result of a historical decision on the part of God to rescue man from the condition of sin and to restore the lost grace of adoptive sonship, but is rather the consequence of a natural development of the transcendental openness which belongs to the being of man. Accordingly Pannenberg quite logically interprets the history of salvation as the history of the transcendental openness of man. The incapacity of man by his own power to open himself to God constitutes sin, while salvation takes place when openness to God and union with Him are realized. In this way, however, the effectively historical character of revelation is inevitably sacrificed to the Hegelian dialectic of contraries and the historical facts are systematically transformed into gnostic speculation. " In the anthropological scheme of transcendental openness sin as personal fault can never find adequate expression. Moreover, the very concept of sin appears to be contradictory. For, if one affirms with Pannenberg that transcendental openness constitutes the essence of man, does not the hypothesis of a closing of man to God become absurd? " Battista Mondin, "L'antropologia teologica di W. Pannenberg," L'Osservatore Romano, Rome: April 1976, p. 3. •Non autem potest esse finis multiplicatio animarum in infinitum: quia infinitum contrariatur rationi finis. Nihil igitur inconveniens sequitur si, certo numero hominum completv, ponamus motum coeli desistere (IV, 97) . HUMAN DESTINY AND WORLD POPULATION 97 Just what should determine this completed number is, as Aquinas notes in the Summa Theologiae (I, q. 23, a. 7), disputed. God knows the number both materially and formally; that is, he knows the total number and each individual comprised in it. Physical creation is ordained to achieve man's purpose, and more particularly, the purpose of those who in fact choose God within the confines of history. Aquinas seems to suggest that God does not directly choose the number of damned-who, of course, also make up part of the universe's total-since that would imply that God chose their fallen lot directly. And what is this total number? Aquinas cites various speculations-that it is equal to the number of fallen angels, or to the number who did not fall, or to the number of angels created. 5 But he is sceptical about all this. "But it would be better to say that God alone knows the number of those chosen for supernal happiness." 6 What should be emphasized-this is our second observation-is that the ultimate number of human beings is limited because men are in fact to reach their end, which is seen to be the personal vision of the triune God and nothing less. This relativizes any ethic which conceives man's corporate function on Earth as that of preserving himself as long as possible so that standards and values which define man's dignity and destiny become subject to this continuation ethic. For Aquinas it is the other way about; preserving and developing the natural and Christian ethic is that according to which we should order the world. Yet the goal of knowing all things, all earthly things, is precisely the normal function of the human intellect with respect to its immediate object. The ideal often proposed for Earth, its preservation as a natural place of beauty and abundance-the Garden of Eden myth modernized, so to speak-is also present in Aquinas, but again posed as a problem that concerns the ultimate status of physical creation. 5 Summa Theol., I, q. !lS, a. 7. • Sed melius dicitur quod soli Deo est cognitus numerus electorum in supema felicitate locandus. 98 JAMES V. SCHALL, S. J. Since, then, corporeal creatures will ultimately be disposed so as to fit the condition of man, not only will the condition of man be freed from corruption but it is also necessary that even corporeal creatures in their way participate in the glory of the (divine) refulgence.7 These are, in fact, the last words of the Contra Gentiles, except for the brief citations from Apocalypse (Chapter and Isaiah (Chapter 65) about the new heavens and the new earth. What is here noteworthy is that the kind of thinking which Aquinas applies to the state of things after the general resurrection and judgment is now more and more directed to a thisworldly project. The pertinence of what we have been saying can be seen very clearly if we recall Aquinas's views about sexual activity after the Parousia. This is of .special interest because recent proposals tend either to eliminate sex as a means of procreation or at least to restrict reproduction so severely that it has little to do with actual human lives. Indeed, cloning proposals eliminate the connection between birth and sex altogether, as do those which propose refashioning the human body on the model of existing genetic structures so that no really new human persons will be created, contrary to the present order of things, in which new persons are created in the succession of unique human births. Aquinas held firmly that there would be no reproduction of new human beings after the resurection. If we allow for differences of milieu, his views are not dissimilar to those of contemporaries who insist that no more children ought to be produced than are needed to maintain the desirable total number of human beings. But for Aquinas the reason for excluding further human births was that all men are at the same moment to be resurrected and to experience the Parousia. Any children born after that time would escape the condition of the (finite) historical race of 7 Quia igitur creatura corporalis finaliter disponetur per congruentiam ad hominis statum; hominis statum non solum a corruptione liberabitur, sed etiam gloriam induetur ... oportebit quod etiam creatura corporalis quandam claritatis gloriam suo modo consequatur. HUMAN DESTINY AND WORLD POPULATION 99 men to whom salvation is promised and for whom it is achieved (IV, 83, 88) . Sexual characteristics, however, were to remain after the resurrection, as these are essential to the person. Women were even to understand better why they were created! Similarly, also, the weakness of the feminine sex is not excluded by the perfection of the risen. For this weakness is not a departure from nature but intended by nature. And this very distinction of nature in the human race will manifest the perfection of nature and the wisdom of God, disposing all things in a certain order. 8 For the risen, Aquinas calmly rejected the notion-practically de rigueur today-that personal relationship or enjoyment apart from reproduction would justify sexual relationships. His reason is that each person on reaching his final goal when the universe reaches its final goal, would not need to experience a lesser pleasure, especially one without its own natural purpose. Aquinas is very much of the opinion that men are made for ultimate happiness and that they do achieve it. Aquinas also held that it was the purpose of the intellect to know all things. Our intellect then is in potency to know all the forms of things, and this potency is actualized when it knows some one of them. Therefore it will not be totally in act nor achieve its ultimate end until it knows all things, or at least all material things. But man cannot accomplish this through the speculative sciences by means of which we know the truth in this life. Hence the ultimate happiness of man cannot be found in this life (III, 48) .9 • Similiter etiam nee infirmitas feminei sexus perfeetioni resurgentium obviat. Non enim est infirmitas per reeessum a natura, sed a natura intenta. Et ipsa etiam naturae distinetio in hominibus perfeetionem naturae demonstrabit et divinam sapientiam, omnia cum quodam ordine disponentem (IV, 88). • Intellectus autem noster est in potentia ad omnes formas rerum cognoscendas: reducitur autem in actum cum aliquam earum cognoscit. Ergo non erit ex toto in actu, nee in ultimo suo fine, nisi quando omnia, saltem ista materialia, cognoscit. Sed hoc non potest homo assequi per scientias speculativas, quibus in hac vita veritatem cognoscimus. Non est igitur possibile quod ultima felicitas hominis sit in hac vita (III, 48) . 100 JAMES V. SCHALL, S. J. From a contemporary point of view this is also a significant passage for another reason. The current secular argument for severely limiting human numbers is based largely upon statistics of available resources. These are believed to be in very short supply in comparison with population. Rapid population growth, it is held, will soon exhaust such resources so that men will reach the secular apocalypse precisely by " increasing and multiplying." Most such dire predictions, however, are themselves products of the philosophy that defines man's purpose as a continuance of the species down through the ages. The level of scientific development upon which calculations are based, furthermore, is very narrow and does not allow for even the pre.sent powers of the human intellect. As the more perceptive scholars are beginnng to point out, there is really only one natural resource in the universe. This is the human mind-as is already implicit in Aquinas's definition of the intellect as that faculty open to all being. In a very real sense it is ultimately possible to transform anything-except the human person-into anything else, so that resources are not limited in any meaningful sense compared to human population (or at least they need not be, for men can always refuse to do what they are able to do) . This would suggest that the Earth is adequate for its purpose, which is to minister to men achieving their transworldly destiny. Aquinas again places the ultimate realization of all knowledge beyond this life, suggesting perhaps that the race of men is not in fact likely to achieve in history all that it could achieve. Aquinas never doubted that the number of human beings to be created was itself limited. Moreover, the fact that he speaks of the number of the elect suggests that this number is determined rather by the personal drama of each created person in selecting his own destiny-and this within whatever social order he might find himself in. The Contm Gentiles does not deal with the destiny of nations or other collectivities. What divides men ultimately and even in this world is their moral and spiritual character. Indeed, under the rubric in the Contra Gentiles HUMAN DESTINY AND WORLD POPULATION 101 that seems to bear most directly on the subject-" That happiness does not consist in worldly power" (III, 31)-Aquinas is mainly concerned with showing that because of its intrinsic instability earthly power cannot be that which men ultimately seek. If some power is the highest good, it must be the most perfect. But human power is the most imperfect, for it is rooted in the wills and opinions of men, in which there is the greatest inconstancy. And the greater we think a power to be, the more things it depends upon. This belongs to its weakness, since what depends upon many things can be destroyed in many ways. The highest good for man therefore cannot be worldly power.10 The import of this is that the norms of human destiny govern what man does with his temporal existence and not vice versa. It is really the rejection of the proposition that we must change our morality and our life to conform to earthly exigencies rather than try to be the kind of persons God created us to be. Modern thought, as Karl Rahner has pointed out, strives to give meaning to the earthly enterprise as such, its meaning in the whole temporal sweep. But it consistently ignores the fate of persons, individuals, very easily subordinating them to the collectivity and its supposed higher mission. 11 Precisely because • 0 Si aliqua potestas est summnm bonum, oportet illam esse perfectissimam. Potestas autem humana est imperfectissima: radicatur enim in hominum voluntatibus et opinionibus, in quibus est maxima inconstantia. Et quanto maior reputatur potestas, tanto a pluribus dependet: quod etiam ad eius debilitatem pertinet; cum quod a multis dependet, destrui multipliciter possit. Non est igitur in potestate mundana summum hominis bonum. 11 " But if it is the will of modem man to exist not only, as his ancestors did, as the same man, although under somewhat different conditions, but also to create really new futures in creative freedom (individually and collectively in the limitations of both these dimensions , then this will of contemporary man is ever and again rebuffed and thwarted by death, which takes on a new unique and radical quality precisely on account of its contradiction to this rather new will of man. This fatal contradiction between man's radical will to unlimited freedom and his being condemned to death, although this is suppressed in all the ideologies of our contemporary history, is obviously not reconciled for the existing individual by the fact that the succession of generations of such individuals ordained for death is thought of as going on into an indeterminate future. This fatal contradiction 102 JAMES V. SCHALL, S. J. Aquinas does not seek human meaning ultimately in some form of worldly state of human society, however defined, he can concentrate his attention upon the meaning of each person as such-" If then the body of the risen man will not be composed of this flesh and these bones of which it is now composed, he will not be numerically the same (IV, 84) .12 The destiny of mankind, its numbers and completion, are seen from the viewpoint of what does happen-men, persons, do die-of what is permanent, of God, the soul, and, as related to them, the body and the universe. Modern theorizing about the implications of population often paradoxically treats, in relation to the present, questions that Aquinas saw must be treated in relation to the Par011'Sia: the ultimate destiny of sex and reproduction, the relation of the human intellect to knowing all corporeal things, the number of human beings, the purpose of human creation. In the Prologue to his Commentary on Book III of the Sentences is the famous pasage: "For man is a sort of horizon and is not made legitimate by the fact that it is understood to be going on eternally, and each generation is only the platform upon which the victory monument of the next generation is erected, which generation with its victory likewise perishes in turn. " Every man has a responsibility not only for those who follow him but also for the dead who lived before him, and not only for his own life but also for his own death. The modern mentality of an unconditional will-to-the-future, if it is not to be deceptive, must acknowledge itself to be frustrated by death." K. Rahner, "The Death of Jesus and the C1osing of Revelation," Theology Digest, Winter, 1975, pp. "Adhuc. Homo naturaliter refugit mortem, et tristatur de ipsa: non solum ut nunc, cum earn sentit, earn refugiens, sed etiam cum earn recogitat. Hoc autem quod non moriatur, homo non potest assequi in hac vita. Non est igitur possibile quod homo in hac vita sit felix." (Contra Gentiles, III, 48.) 12 Si igitur corpus hominis resurgentis non erit ex his carnibus et ex his ossibus ex quibus nunc componitur, non erit homo resurgens idem numero. It is interesting that the current movements and proposals to deepfreeze human bodies instead of burying them (the Christian tradition in view of the resurrection) is based on hope of eventual resurgence and cure so that the same individual could continue in a cycle of ages without facing death. But it is the same instinct to preserve the same individual person which Aquinas also recognizes when he asserts that we shall rise as the same individuals. The one is based on natural science, the other on Christ. HUMAN Dl!lSTlNY AND WORLD POPULATtON 108 frontier of the spiritual and the corporeal, a sort of medium between them, participating in bt:}th corporeal and spiritual good things." 10 This means, of course, that the authentic values and destiny of Earth are indeed man's to accomplish. Man is the horizon and the frontier. The completion of human numbers is a definite project. Yet we must recognize that men's relation to what they themselves are created to be is itself the primary determinative factor as to how many there can and will be. Furthermore, human numbers in Aquinas are never seen to be a question of numbers as such but as the universitas of persons who achieve the goal for which the universe was created-that is, the free choice to respond to God's invitation to share his inner life. The immanent meaning of the world-the rise and fall of nations, the " hominization " of nature, even the peaceable kingdom-by themselves are not the essential drama. The " horizon " of man, in all his numbers, in all his accomplishments, is always God. "The end of the divine law is that man adhere to God. . . . Human laws, however, are ordered to certain earthly goods" (Summa Theol., II-II, q. 140, a. 1) .14 Even by the best of earthly organizations men may not really be achieving the goal to which they as persons are called. Reflection on these doctrines of Aquinas on human numbers reminds us today that when questions which ultimately pertain to the Parousia and its condition reappear in essentially secular, political terms, it means that we are losing contact with the radical destiny to which the individual person is called. Christianity's validity as a religion, as the Contra Gentiles seems to argue even from natural reason, is precisely its refusal to allow men a lesser destiny than the highest, which must include the happiness of the singular, individual person or else it is merely an abstraction and not a hope. Contemporary speculation on 13 Homo enim est quasi horizon et confinium spiritualis et corporalis naturae, ut quasi medium inter utrasque, utrasque bonitates participet et corporales et spirituales . . . "Finis autem legis divinae est ut homo inhaeret Deo .... Leges autem humanae ordinantur ad aliqua mundana bona. 104 JAMES V. SCHALL, s . .t. human population and sexuality should not be .seen for less than what is is-an effort to provide answers to ultimate questions in a this-worldly context. It is not enough to maintain that the answer cannot be found here, in this world, no matter how long it lasts or in what conditions. We must also recognize that the effort itself to subsume these questions into a manageable technological or ecological perspective is resulting in a refusal to accept the kind of men that in fact were created-and their destiny post judicium. And it is this choice to accept the human condition as such that defines this particular human race's hope to escape nothingness (but not by itself, of course). We live in an age which seeks to exalt the human enterprise, yet fears to accept its conditions. The new original sin, ironically, has almost become-what it was not for Aquinas-sex activity that increases population. Perhaps the last words should be those of Aquinas " ... Humility is essentially located in the appetite inasmuch as by it one restrains the impetus of his soul from inordinately seeking great things, but it has its rule in knowledge, namely, that one should not esteem himself above what he really is" (Summa Theol., II-II, q. 161, a. 6) .15 We are told not to esteem ourselves as more than we are, yet we are ultimately given everything. This is the mystery that will be worked out in history-and beyond it, when the prescribed number of men will be complete, certo numero hominum completo. JAMES v. SCHALL, S.J. Gregorian University Rome, Italy 15 Humilitas essentialiter in appetitu consistit, secundum quod aliquis refrenat impetum animi sui, ne inordinate tendat in magna, sed regulam habet in cognitione, ut scilicet aliquis non se existimet supra id quod est. FRIENDSHIP AND THE PROBLEM OF EGOISM A SURVEY OF RECENT philosophical literature indicates continuing interesit in the problem of egoism. Ethical theory traditionally has had to grapple with this issue, if only because in every generation the question recurs, " Why not pursue the selfish course of action? " Recent attempts to resolve that question have focused on a logical problem, that of challenging the consistency of an egoist's claims, or the contradictions at least latent in the directives issued by the egoist. Whether such an analysis defeats the egoist has been a matter of dispute, and it is likely that refutations grounded in logic will continue to be advanced and counter-attacked. My paper proposes to move on a different front. For too long philosophers, fearful of committing a " naturalistic follacy," have neglected consideration of empirical evidence, for example, that of psychology, which would have a bearing on this question. The supposed gap between facts and values has led to such claims as " It is now pretty generally accepted by professional philosophers that ultimate ethical principles must be arbitrary. One cannot derive conclusions about what should be merely from accounts of what is the case ... " 1 I believe it is incorrect to assume that one's ethical premisses can only be " baldly asserted " because " here there is no room for reason even to go wrong." 2 Rather, it seems to me that facts about the human situation are relevant to decisions about how humans ought to act, and that reason can here go wrong precisely in not attending to those sources of action which empirical enquiry lays bare. It shall be my contention that egoism is vulnerable to considerations " capable of determining 1 Brian Medlin, "Ultimate Principles and Ethical Egoism," AU8tralattian of Philosophy, Vol. 85 (1957), p. 118. •Ibid. 105 106 ROBERT B. ASHMORE, JR. the intellect either to give or withhold its assent to the doctrine; and this is equivalent to proof." 3 Analogous to the argument in Mill's Utilitarianism, the evidence which will be appealed to concerns what people do in fact seek in view of their needs and interesrts as social beings. The distinctive way in which this approach to egoism may be distinguished from other recent efforts is perhaps illustrated by the two kinds of test for universalizability which Kant employed. 4 One test argues from the impossibility of one's maxim becoming a universal law, and the other argues from the undesirability of universalization. The desirability of acting on an egoist principle, it shall be argued here, is incompatible with what experience manifests to be its consequences. For this sort of evidence one clearly must leave the closet of philosophical speculation. A point that requires clarification at the outset concerns definition of terms. It is especially true regarding egoism that it derives some initial plausibility, as C. D. Broad has noted, from " verbal ambiguities and misunderstandings." 5 A case in point is Ayn Rand. In her introduction to The Virtue of Selfishness Rand states that " the exact meaning and dictionary definition of the word 'selfishness' is: concern with one's own interests." 6 Dictionaries do not support her claim. For example, Webster's Third International Dictionary defines "selfishness " as "concern for one's own welfare or advantage at the expense of or in disregard of others." Similarly," selfish" means "seeking or concentrating on one's own advantage, pleasure or well-being without regard for others." 7 The danger in permitting Rand's stipulative definition to pass for an ordinary •John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (Indianapolis. New York: Liberal Arts Press, Inc., 1957), p. 7. "Immanuel Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (New York: Liberal Arts Press, Inc., 1959), pp. 40-42. • C. D. Broad, "Egoism as a Theory of Human Motives," Ethics and the History of Philosophy (New York: The Humanities Press, 1952), p. 229. •Ayn Rand, The Virtue of Selfishness (New York: The New American Library, Inc., 1964), p. vii. •Webster's Third New International Dictionary (Springfield, Mass.: G. & C. Merriam Co., 1967). FRIENDSHIP AND EGOISM 107 language meaning is that it confuses what is really at issue. The question does not concern the acceptability of a self-realization theory, but whether the integral fulfillment of human needs and interests entails the exclusion of regard for others. Sidgwick was correct when he observed, " Egoism, if we merely understand by it a method that aims at Self-realization, seems to be a form into which almost any ethical system may be thrown without modifying its essential characteristics." 8 Common sense discriminates between those who devote their lives to caring for lepers and those whose career is loan-sharking. The ordinary man perceives a difference between sharing one's books with others as opposed to pilfering a book from the public library. Few people confuse the motive of a mother assiduously attending to her sick child with the motive of one who beats a child that disturbs her sleep. Customary use of the terms "selfish" and "unselfish" is intended to mark the real difference between these sorts of actions, motives and states of character. Were we to abandon that vocabulary, reducing everything to selfishness, it would be necesary to invent new language to reflect our everyday experience of these differences. H it were the case, as Hume has argued, that " even unknown to ourselves, we seek only our own gratification while we appear the most deeply engaged in schemes for the liberty and happiness of mankind," this would not establish the egoist's position. "As the same turn of imagination prevails not in every man, nor gives the same direction to the original passion, this is sufficient, even according to the selfish system, to make the widest difference in human character and denominate one man virtuous and humane, another vicious and meanly interested." 9 In other words, even granting ... that in all cases self-interest were the only motive, we must still admit that in some men a certain association of ideas or trick of the imagination or mistaken reasoning causes them to do actions 8 Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1966)' p. 95. •David Hume, An Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (New York: Liberal Arts Press, Inc., 1957), p. 114. 108 ROBERT B. ASHMORE, JR. which benefit others rather than themselves. Such men and such actions would be called ' unselfish ', and it would be a fact that we approve men who habitually deceive themselves in this way, and disapprove those who do not. 10 That anyone should adopt such a monistic interpretation of human behavior and motivation, and then " devote endless labour and ingenuity to explaining away plain facts which obviously conflict with it " 11 challenges us for an explanation. The possibilities are various. One is the very simplicity of the theory. A reduction of all impulses to forms of self-love is attractive when priority is given to economy of explanation. A veritable longing for simplicity can override the most compelling evidence that motivation is complex, that constituents of the self are diverse, and that a plurality of objects motivate our impulses. Another possibility derives from the influence which a social' environment can have upon the individual's values. John Dewey has written at length to establish the point that our moral judgments, our habits and, hence, our conduct are socially conditioned. "Of what avail is it to preach unassuming simplicity and contentment of life when communal admiration goes to the man who 'succeeds '-who makes himself conspicuous and envied because of command of money and other forms of power?" 12 At a time when thought is decidedly individualistic, and social arrangements are judged to be secondary and artificial, it is little to be wondered that egoistic justifications should occur to individuals presumed to be naturally isolated. Moreover, when this prevailing individualism is expressed in an economic theory which maintains that each person is, or can only survive if he is, a rugged individual seeking his own profit in competition with others, social approval will erect egoism into a virtue. 13 1 ° C. D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical TheMy (Paterson, N. J.: Littlefield, Adams & Co., 1959), p. IOI. 11 C. D. Broad, " Egoism as a Theory of Human Motives," p. 12 John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (New York: The Modern Library, 1957). p. 819. 13 Cf. John Dewey, TheMy of the Moral Life (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1967), pp. 168-4. FRIENDSHIP AND EGOISM 109 Relatedly, Peter Marin in a recent article has called attention to a current " trend in therapy towards a deification of the isolated self." 14 The "new narcissism," as he terms it, arises from a desire to defend ourselves against a sense of shame and guilt occasioned by routine inequities of consumption and distribution which benefit us and condemn others to misery. "So we struggle mightily to convince ourselves that our privilege is earned and deserved." 15 The ground of community disappears in the face of growing solipsism, and the hunger for relation is suppressed in the name of selfishness posing as enlightenment. A third factor which encourages egoistic theory is the type of dynamic psychology which assumes inflexibility in basic motives and drives. Psychoanalysis and other genetic accounts assume that every motive of personality traces back to infancy. Against this Gordon Allport has argued that one cannot assume motives operative in the infant or the small child to be isomorphic with those of an adult. It may be granted that the child starts life as a completely selfish being, thoughtless, grabby, demanding immediacy of gratification. However, these egocentric beginnings are not consciously referred to self and, as the self matures and becomes socialized, a genuine transformation of motivation occurs. 16 With extension of the ego, an individual can come to find it intolerable to seek happiness at the expense of others. What Allport terms the " functional autonomy of "Peter Marin, "The New Narcissism," Harper's Vol. 251., No. 1505 (October, 1975)' p. 45. 15 Ibid., p. 47. 16 Gordon W. Allport, Becoming (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1955), pp. 28-30. This view might at first blush appear to be in conflict with Dewey's claim that "our native impulses and acts are iwither egoistic nor altruistic ... " Theory of the Moral Life, p. 156. Cf. Democracy and Education (New York: The Free Press, 1966), pp. 43-44, where Dewey rejects the " alleged pure egoism of children." However, Allport is making another point. Granted that no choice is even possible at the infant stage, and conscious reference to self or others is nonexistent, nevertheless the behavior in question is in fact egocentric. In the course of early training we teach the child to approve or disapprove of acts according as they are or are not considerate of others. On this question, cf. also Gordon Allport, "A Basic Psychology of Love and Hate," Personality and Social Encounter (Boston: Beacon Press, 1964), pp. 205 and 210. 110 ROBERT B. ASHMORE, JR. motives " provides the necessary antidote to " the faulty logic of bellum omnium contra omnes ... Motives being completely alterable, the dogma of Egoism turns out to be a callow and superficial philosophy of behavior, or else a useless redundancy." 11 A fourth and perhaps most significant encouragement to egoism rests upon two commonplace confusions, each often intertwined with the other. The first maintains that whenever I act, I am simply doing what I most want to do. That is to say, it is my wants, desires and interests which prompt me to act. Allegedly, the crucial fact is that, whether I am helping an elderly person cross the street, or I am stealing coins from a blind beggar's cup, it is my interest that determines the act. In the final analysis, all my acts are selfish because what motivates me is the interest or desire which I happen to have and which I want satisfied. The problem with this argument is that " we confuse the ownership of an impulse with its object." 18 It was Joseph Butler who pointed out that " although every particular affection is a man's own," we require language to express" the difference between the principle of an action proceeding from cool consideration that it will be to my own advantage, and an action ... by which a man runs upon certain ruin to do evil or good to another." 19 The appetite or the passion is in each case distinct, and the object of the one is not the same as the object of the other. The fact that both acts proceed from inclinations in the self cannot be denied. The relevant point is that in the one case my inclination is to assist the elderly pedestrian, and in the other my inclination is to obtain money at the expense of the blind beggar's own needs. Selfishness and unselfishness are terms which mark this real difference in the kinds of character traits which produce acts of the one sort or the other. Gordon W. Allport, Personality (New York: Henry Holt & Co., 1937), p. !'l06. C. D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical Theory, p. 65. 10 Joseph Butler, Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel (London: G. Bell & Sons, Ltd., 1914), pp. 168-9. 17 18 FRIENDSHIP AND EGOISM 111 Indiscriminately to label all my acts as selfish merely because they are my own accounts for nothing that is of interest either psychologically or morally. What we find it important to distinguish is behavior which is considerate of the needs of others and that which is not. Undoubtedly it is my desire which is satisfied when I assist the elderly pedestrian, and it is my desire which is satisfied when I steal the beggar's coins. The egoist's contention reduces to the trivial truth that it is I who am acting whenever I am acting. What is morally .significant, however, is the kind of person who is acting, whether that person is sensitive to the interests of others, or whether he is obtuse to those interests. Either disposition is obviously a constituent of the self, and in action springing from that disposition the interest of the self is involved. But, as Dewey has pointed out, " the different selves have different values. A self changes it.s structure and its value according to the kind of object which it desires and seeks; according, that is, to the different kinds of objects in which active interest is taken." 20 A .second confusion closely related to the first has it that everything we do has pleasure as its goal. All agents act to attain what they expect will give them the most pleasure. Since we all are pleasure-seekers, apparently altruistic acts are as much a manifestation of underlying egocentrism as any other act. That some derive their pleasure from tending lepers and others derive pleasure from stealing beggar's coins, it is said, should not obscure the fact that seeking one's own pleasure is the common denominator. In response, it is once again necessary to point out how little is asserted in a claim of this sort. It goes without saying that performance of an act for which one has some appetite is attended with pleasure. Indeed, pleasure just is the satisfaction experienced in fulfilling an appetite. One would hardly expect a person not to experience pleasure in the performance of an act towards which he is disposed. But what is of moment here is 80 Dewey, Theory of the Moral Life, p. 159. 112 ROBERT B. ASHMORE, JR, the sorts of things which give one pleasure. It has been on the record at least as far back as Aristotle that what distinguishes the good man from the evil man is not that one or the other finds pleasure in what he does, since both do. Rather, the distinction derives from the activities which characteristically are a source of pleasure to each. The just man will experience pleasure in doing just deeds. The unjust man will experience pleasure in doing unjust deeds. And each would experience pain were he to perform the act pleasurable to the other. What one finds pleasurable or painful, then, will depend on the dispositions he has formed. Consequently, it is the prior suitability of an object to an interest that determines its pleasurableness. What objects are suitable to given individuals are contingent upon the interests of those individuals. As those interests obviously can vary, the thrust of moral education is to discourage formation of interests which disregard the welfare of others, i. e., which are selfish, and to encourage formation of interests which are considerate of others, i.e., which are unselfish. In sum, an " unselfish interest in another is one of a man's oum interests but not one of his selfish interests ... it is not made less moral by the fact that it gives satisfaction to the doer." 21 It should also be noted that pleasure is not itself the object of our act, whether selfish or unselfish. The cup of tea, the relief of a child's distress, the publication of an article, may each of them be the object of one or another act. It is because I desire the object that I will have a pleasant experience in the attainment of the object. But the pleasure presupposes the existence of the appetite, and the appetite is specified by its object. Were pleasure itself the object of desire, what would differentiate our desires? To cite Butler once again, That all particular appetites and passions are towards external, things themselves distinct from the pleasure arising from them, is manifested from hence-that there could not be this pleasure were it not for that prior suitableness between the object and the passion; 01 Michael Scriven, Primary Philosophy (New York: McGraw-Hill Book Co. 1966), p. ft35. FRIENDSHIP AND EGOISM 118 there could be no enjoyment or delight from one thing more than another, from eating food more than from swallowing a stone, if there were not an affection or appetite to one thing more than another. 22 My earlier example should illustrate this point. When I assist the elderly person across the street, what I seek is not pleasure, but the safe passage of the elderly person. That is my object. That I experience pleasure in the fulfillment of that purpose is to say little more than that my purpose is accomplished. There is nothing but confusion in the egoist's claim that I did the act in order to receive the satisfaction, since I would give up doing it if that act gave me no satisfaction. Satisfaction is not the object of my act, but is a sign that the object is appropriate to my disposition. The ethical problem is not that a self is satisfied, but what kind of self is satisfied. It is on this issue that the egoist's view is impoverished. In morals, the concrete differences between a Jesus, a Peter, a John and a Judas are covered up by the wise remark that after all they are all selves and all act as selves ... The fallacy consists in transforming the (truistic) fact of acting a,s a self into the fiction of action always for self. Every act, truistically again, tends to a certain fulfillment or satisfaction of some habit which is an undoubted element in the structure of character ... But theory comes in and blankets the tremendous diversity in the quality of the satisfactions which are experienced by pointing out that they are all satisfactions. The harm done is then completed by transforming this artificial unity of result into an original love of satisfaction as the force that generates all acts alike . . . In reality the more we concretely dwell upon the common fact of fulfillment, the more we realize the difference in the kind of selves fulfilled.23 The fact that the self is fulfilled when acts of an unselfish nature are performed indicates the error which underlies the bifurcation of self from others. Historically the egoism problem has sprung in part from the false assumption that a strong disjunctive choice is necessary in determining the course of one's ••Butler, op. cit., pp. 167-8. ••Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct, pp. 136-7. 114 ROBERT B. ASHMORE, JR. life. Either I act to realize my own interests and potentialities or I act self-sacrificingly to satisfy the interests of others. Not only have philosophers such as Aristotle and Dewey attacked this misconception, but contemporary humanistic psychologists have as well. Personality theory, which seeks to explain the development of the individual from infant beginnings toward full maturity, supports the philosophical thesis that man is a social being, and that egoism fails precisely because it is unfaithful to this ego-transcending dimension of the self which is constitutive of our human nature. Philosophers today can neglect the evidence of psychology and the other social sciences only at the risk of rendering a prioristic their own reflections on the human condition. It is the case that some philosophers recognize the relevance of psychological and other empirical data. 24 Nevertheless, the predominant tendency is to shy away from such " naturalistic " orientations and, in the process, ensure the sterility of philosophical deliverances. This consequence follows, I am persuaded, from the fact that philosophers have no privileged access to reality. The study of man advances most fruitfully when somewhat pridefully erected barriers between the disciplines are dismantled in the interest of restoring unity to the complex object of investigation. 25 Abraham Maslow is one of many contemporary psychologists studying personality development who deplore the false dichotomizing which pathologizes the human situation. Maslow insists that experimental and clinical evidence compels us to think holistically rather than atomistically. "Dichotomizing seems ••Cf., for example, Richard B. Brandt, Ethir;al Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1959). Brandt acknowledges that, concerning "the strategy for maximizing happiness " we must not confine ourselves to a study of the history of philosophy. "But in a complex modern world, and after the rise of psychology and the social sciences, we can and should look for something more sophisticated and better founded in observation. The sciences of psychology and psychiatry certainly bear on this ... " p. 39l9. 25 I have argued this point at length elsewhere. See my " Deriving the Desirable from the Desired," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, Vol. XL (1970), pp. 15il-60. Also, "Aquinas and Ethical Naturalism," The New S()holasticism, Vol. XLIX (Winter, 1975), pp. 76-86. FRIENDSHIP AND EGOISM 115 now to be characteristic 0£ a lower level 0£ personality development and 0£ psychological functioning; it is both a cause and an effect 0£ psychopathology." 28 Direct study 0£ psychologically healthy individuals reveals that in them the satisfaction 0£ basic needs is propaedeutic to movement toward a higher level termed "self-actualization." At this level there is integration 0£ motivations and inclinations which at a lower level are viewed as, and also £unction as, opposites. Relevant to our purposes is Maslow's finding that in self-actualizing people the dichotomy 0£ selfishness and unselfishness is resolved into a higher, superordinate unity. Such growth emerges only from safety so that, i£ deficiency-needs are not gratified, the individual will not evidence ego-transcendance. The growth pattern 0£ a healthy child indicates an initial movement outwards to the environment. l£ not crippled by £ear and frustration the child will continue to dare. Egocentricity, at first only a pre-reflective appetite for immediate gratification 0£ impulses, will emerge as the dominant, conscious tendency only when the environment confronts the developing personality with a conflict between safety and growth. Study 0£ free choices in both healthy and sick individuals leads to the conclusion that, in those whose capacities are developed and fully functioning, there is egoless or selftranscending object-centeredness. Self-love and altruism are not opposites. Rather, love in self-actualizing people involves a free giving 0£ oneself, without reserve, wholly and with abandon. 21 The needs 0£ the other become one's own needs, so that for psychological purposes one is no longer observing separate egos, but a single unit. Psychology 0£ personality suggests that " this need to go out beyond the limits 0£ the ego may be a need in the same sense that we have needs for vitamins and minerals, i. e., that i£ the need is not satisfied, the person becomes sick in one way or another." 28 26 Abraham Maslow, Towards a Psychology of Being (New York: D. Van Nostrand Co., 1968), p. "'Abraham Maslow, Motivation and Personality (second edition; New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1970), ch. rn. 28 Ibid., p. 194. 116 ROBERT B. ASHMORE, JR. The social parallel of this holistic psychological theory is the perception of culture as itself instrumental to need-gratification when appropriately constituted. The interests of the individual and of society are not necessarily exclusive and antagonistic. The challenge is to create social conditions which foster universal self-actualization. 29 The age-old problem of reconciling personal good and common good is attacked at its root when the person is revealed as an organism whose needs in quasi-instinctive fashion draw him forward to seek others, and in the further reaches of that growth to an identification with others. If the culture is itself "healthy," the good pursued through collective effort will be synonymous with the requirements for psychological maturation. These claims of Maslow find support in the research of another psychologist, Andras Angyal. Life may itself be defined as " a process of self-expansion." 30 This life process embraces both organism and environment, and there is a tendency toward increase of autonomy, i.e., toward self-assertiveness, freedom and mastery. However, equally basic to human existence is what Angyal calls the" trend to homonomy." Humans strive for a place in larger units of which they wish to be a part. Th0 search for integration into superindividual units indicates that life is not contained within the individual self. Homonomous tending satisfies that level of human existence in which the need is to mean something to someone else. We want to have existence in the thoughts and feelings of others, so that our own life is reflected in an understanding and affectionate way. Theories which presume an egocentric organization of the individual conflict with evidence that we not only have needs, but we also want to be needed. Homonomous integration can be toward another person, toward a group or toward a cause. In any case, the need to belong forms a community or a unit towards which one's attitude is quite unlike the self-assertive tendency toward ••Maslow, Towards a Psychology of Being, pp. 159 and 221. 80 Andras Angyal, Neurosis and Treatment (New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1965), p. 5. FRIENDSHIP AND EGOISM 117 autonomy. "While the trend toward increased autonomy aims at the domination of the surroundings, the characteristic attitude toward superindividual wholes is rather a kind of submerging or subordination of one's individuality in the service of superindividual goals. In this latter trend a person seeks union with larger units and wishes to .share and participate in something which he regards as being greater than his individual self." 31 Personality development requires integration of the individual into the social group, and psychological theory cannot neglect this powerful source of human motivation. Homonomous expression is essential for normal adjustment. "Self-centeredness, being wrapped up in oneself, inability to ' loosen up,' to get out of oneself, is a well-recognized characteristic of many forms of personality disorder . . . The merging into superindividual wholes, the sharing and participation in larger units, is a powerful .support of mental health." 32 Although the autonomous and homonomous trends are distinguished and can be opposed to one another, " in a wellintegrated person the two orientations are complementary rather than conflicting." 33 An attempt to master the environment uncovers the need for a homonomous attitude in understanding and respecting the laws of that environment. By the same token, a loving relationship lacks quality when the individual is deficient in resourcefulness and self-reliance. For Angy al as for Maslow, then, at a higher level of personality development the apparent opposition of egoism and altruism dissolves in the perception of the self as one whose essential nature is expressed in tendencies to incorporation. 31 Andras Angyal, Foundations for a Science of Personality (New York: Viking Press, 1972), p. 172. •• Ibid., pp. 179-80. •• Angyal, Neurosis and Treatment, p. 29. Cf. F