TRIUNE SELF-GIVING: ONE KEY TO THE PROBLEM OF SUFFERING S OME YEARS AGO a witty friend of mine used to make a pretense of defending the view that this is the worst of all possible worlds. Though undoubtedly far from the worst possible, this world plainly falls short of some conceivably better, if not best, scheme of things finite. Discerning savants of the next century or two may look with pity, mixed with a good bit of anger and contempt, on the atrocities committed or officially condoned by that curiously arrogant and morally obtuse creature that some glorify as twentieth-century man. But whatever the judgment from whatever vantage point passed on our period, the current rising tide of troubles raises anew, perhaps more poignantly, the problem of evil in a universe traditionally held to be cradled in the everlasting arms of an allloving Father. As men, all of us at one time or another must struggle with pain and injustice. As thinkers (at least in some modest sense) , we must come to grips with one of the murkiest of puzzles, that, even where it may not afflict the heart, perplexes the mind: how are we to square the dreadful fact of evil with the sweet face of an all-good and all-powerful God? In recent years the problem has been somewhat recast: how can an all-loving God remain unaffected by the suffering of the men he has created? It is to this narrower formulation of the question that this essay addresses itself. The God of classical theism is totally other and unchangeable; as wholly other, he has no need of human love; as unchangeable, he cannot be touched by whatever transpires for the weal or woe of his rational creatures. No matter what evils agonize man in or outside time, God remains self-subsistent, holily self-loving, serene in boundless beatitude. The chasm infinitely dividing God and 173 174 JOHN M. QUINN, o.s.A. man apparently annuls any humanly meaningful sense we might assign to. his being all-loving and all-caring. From one angle such a God evokes, along with trembling awe, a certain moral and aesthetic repugnance. He seems to be mysterium tremendum et repellens. Affective disenchantment intimates that an infinitely distant God may he an irrationality, a vestigial idol of an outmoded theology. In place of an Absolute, process-thinkers, notably A. N. Whitehead and Charles Hartshorne, have vigorously argued for a supreme but limited God. Finitist theism has also proved alluring to minds not ordinarily catalogued under process-thought, and of these we have chosen to take a quick look at Nicholas Berdyaev, a legatee in part of Boehme, and Peter Bertocci, an avowed disciple of the American personalist, Edgar Brightman. First, we shall sketch the main lines of these four finitist approaches. While initially prepossessing, the finite-God case is saddled with a number of difficulties, some of which appear mortal. For all the obscurity that clings to any conceptualization of the strictly divine, the God of classical theism turns out to be incontestably loving and caring not in spite of but because of his immutability and infinity. Nothing inferior to a being of limitless wisdom and power can explain the otherwise paradoxical harvesting of good and harmony out of the evil and poisonous discord in the universe. Secondly, for further light on the still enigmatic features of a loving but nonsuffering God's tie-in with creation, the rational theist who is a Christian can cross the border into theology. In Jesus God suffered and died in some reasonable sense. The suffering of the God-man, however, leaves God impassible. Yet because Jesus is the incarnate revelation of divine life, his death out of love signalizes the selfgiving within Godness itself. A nonsufiering but self-giving trinity of persons in God serves as a model for making each man a god. One key to analytical and existential mastery of suffering lies in the renovation of finite spirit in the image of the triune self-giving of infinite spirit. TRIUNE SELF-GIVING 175 I Whitehead and Hartshorne present apparently compelling briefs for a limited God enriched by as well as enriching the world he oversees. Their fundamental position receives, outside a processive perspective, broad substantiation and corroboration from Berdyaev and Bertocci. But any gains accreditable to a more understandable finite status seem outbalanced by losses in the depth and width of divine power and love. In becoming finite, God forfeits Godness: he is nothing but a superhuman, but less than supreme, spirit. Though the precise mode of eternal operation always lies beyond human ken, only an infinite being can bestow his love on finites so as to transmute the devastation spewed by evil into per se goods for the upbuilding of the whole universe. 1. (i) According to Whitehead, the God of classical theism, that is rooted in the power-oriented Semitic idea of the one creator, "is a concept which is clear, terrifying, and unprovable." 1 The only available route to his existence seems to he the misnamed ontological proof originating with Anselm, today by and large dismissed as invalid. 2 Too, an infinite transcendence puts him " completely outside metaphysical rationalization." Thus both the existence and the nature of an infinite God are undisclosable by rational analysis. Moreover, in patterning God after an absolute imperial ruler, the Church has rendered unto God the things that are Caesar's. Enthroned in the sanctuary of classical theism is a Caesar stripped of all human attributes save a naked power, now bafflingly infinitized. In place of this absolutized Power Whitehead conceives of a God that blends reinterpreted features of Aristotle's sel£thinking thought and the virtues of Jesus Christ. Like Aris1 Alfred North Whitehead, Religion in the Making (New York: World, 1960; first published in p. 72. 2 Ibid., pp. 68-69. From the vantage point of the twenties Whitehead was unable to foresee the upsurge of a surprising interest in and a more surprising support for the Anselmian proof, some of which was stimulated by Hartshome's persuasive elaboration of the argument (especially in The Logic of Pmjection [La Salle: Open Court, 1962] and Anselm's DiscO'Very [La Salle: Open Court, 1965]). 176 JOHN M. QUINN, O.S.A. totle's God, Whitehead's highest entity is not utterly outside the world but is the topmost part within the universe, so grounding and possessing forms that in some sense he thinks them. Unlike Aristotle's God, the supreme actual entity is not only of the world but in the world as well, for, Whitehead maintains, it is more blessed for God to receive as well as give: the world God forms and finalizes, in turn, fashions him. God is dipolar, manifesting two natures or sides, the primordial and the consequent. When we think God abstractively, simply as the repository of the forms and aims that determine and attract entities, we are focusing on his primordial nature, in virtue of which he is an unmoved mover unlimited and dissociated from the world. But in his consequent nature God is a moved mover profiting from the reciprocal causation of the entities whose subjective aims he ordained; in this respect he grows with the development of the world. Through the consequent nature all the tragedy born of contingency is overcome in final harmony; God tenderly gathers up all the fragments of the good and beautiful of perished actual occasions lest they be lost. Poet of the world, he molds its welter into an intellectual beauty and joy to last forever. Further, God not only immortalizes the data of perishing entities but, on his superjective side, capitalizes on them so as continually to endow ever-fresh entities with their income. Making the kingdom of heaven come, superjective action evidences divine love for each individual; God so loves the world that he ceaselessly gives it of himself-a generosity that brings with it divine providence, supreme solicitude for each of his creatures. Indeed not only is he father but brother of us all: " God is the great companion-the fellow-sufferer who understands." In these real-relational dealings with the world God reflects, with due measure of metaphysical refinement, the virtues of Jesus Christ. "The world lives by its incarnation of God in itself." Here the stock theological term does not mean that God clothes himself in nature as the Word incarnates himself in human nature. However, its use is not whimsy but an indicator that elsewhere the God of and in process metaphysically TRIUNE SELF-GIVING 177 idealizes lineaments Christians believe to be unique in their incarnate God. Jesus enfleshes the revelation of the love of God; Whitehead's God is primarily a God of love, tenderly holding all to his bosom. So in the image of the Good Shepherd, he does not drive but persuades his flock. Again, Jesus is sent, as his name signifies, to be savior; in his consequent nature God saves all perished occasions. As Jesus salvifically abandoned himself to suffer with and for his fellowmen, God suffers with and for all creation, compassionating with every least occasion. A God-with-us is no Absolute steelily sequestered in infinite changelessness. His very suffering tempers and helps overcome variegated creaturely sufferings as his sympathy enfolds in divine harmony all that looks fragmentary and dissipated. 3 (ii) While not strictly classifiable as a disciple, Hartshorne has developed many of Whitehead's insights into a more systematic natural theology that resembles, with the intention of superseding, the scholastic version of God. He trains his guns on two incongruities of traditional theism: an Absolute divorced from creation and an inaccessible Autocrat that is unloving and therefore unlovable. First, asymmetry in the relation between God and the world is indefensible. Divine infallible cognition is necessarily relative: from " God knows there are men " we are bound to infer" There are men." Again, God's knowledge must be actually different if this actual world differs from some hypothetical other world. 4 Just as a world without a creator is unthinkable, so a creator without a real relation to his crea•Ibid., p. 68. Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality (New York: Macmillan, 1929), pp. 520-26, 532; Religion in the Making, p. 149. •Charles Hartshorne, The Divine Rdativity (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1948), pp. 9, 11, 14. In Two Process Philosophers (Tallahassee, Fla.: American Academy of Religion, 1973, ed. Lewis S. Ford), David Griffin, " Hartshorne's Differences from Whitehead," pp. 35-57, and Lewis S. Ford, "Whitehead's Differences from Hartshorne," pp. 58-83, call attention to points of divergence between two major process thinkers not uncommonly taken to be related as master and disciple. However, whether or not we accept Hartshorne's estimate that his relationship with Whitehead might be better designated " pre-established harmony " rather than " intellectual descent," the general and particular lines of affinity between the two seem more numerous and much more significant than several marked dissimilarities. 178 JOHN M. QUINN, O.S.A. tion is unintelligible. Secondly, in one respect the God of tradition bears a disquieting likeness to a transcendent tyrant supreme in jealousy of his prerogatives and in infinite £rigidity toward his subjects. In another respect he seems monstrously cruel. A father utterly unconcerned about the well-being or unhappiness of his children would be shunned as shockingly inhuman. Yet a wholly changeless God, perched infinitely high above the flux, has to be literally unmoved by the sorrows and joys, miseries and glories of his creatures. Enwrapped and enrapt in himself alone, he remains totally unruffled by and uninterested in the incalculable suffering of the human realm. In preference to this internally incoherent monopolar God Hartshorne proposes a highest being that seems consistently both absolute and relative. Absolutely taken, God is metaphysically unique; no other being can be divine. But devoid of all relation to other entities, God reduces to an absolute that is absolutely empty. Hence God is relative, sovereignly so, responsive to the feeblest pulse of actuality. A similar strategy of qualified relativization refurbishes the divine attributes. God cannot not be perfect, all-knowing, all-powerful, and all-loving, but the all of knowledge, power, and love is delimited by rational possibility. He is perfect but only as far as possible, only as thinkable in reference to lower-order beings, only as modifiable through the impact of other actual entities. His allembracing cognition does not descend to every particular, and his grasp of the future is only vague. Again, God's power is without question the greatest possible, but its exercise must make room for and be fenced .in by spontaneous causal activities. Similarly, divine love, which is not cloistered apart from the causal influx of creation, does not chillingly turn its back on the hurly-burly of events. A loving father, God makes the joys and sorrows of creatures his own, sympathetically resonating with their songs and groans. From this standpoint the curious gap between Jesus and the heavenly Father is bridged. Jesus truly reveals the inner suffering of God himself. The life and death of Jesus prove that " God really is love-just that without equivocation." The · TRlUNE SELF-GIVING 179 cross symbolizes the outgoing care of and generosity of God in His divine nature. God is inexpressibly co-suffering, taking our cross upon himself, ultimately bringing light and consolation out of humanly uncontrollable evil with its potency for destruction that would otherwise stun the mind and shatter the heart. 5 Thus a concrete God dissolves paradoxes ramifying from an immutable (unrelatable to creation) yet creating (related) God and supplies literal backing for the Christian claim that Jesus as friend and savior is the sign and image of the Father. Yet the relativity of God, we must not forget, does not derogate from genuine supremacy. Not only in but above process, God remains perfect, all-knowing, all-loving, and allpowerful within the limits of intelligibility. (iii) Though bursting into flower from different soil under another sky, the concept of God in Berdyaev seems remarkably similar to the notion constructed by Whitehead and Hartshorne. The primordial factor is not God but the Ungrund, a pre-divine Nothing out of which course God and a freedom uncreatable by God. The creative act betrays a limited creator rather than a stonily immobile Absolute: " Creation of the world implies movement in God, it is a dramatic event in the divine life." 6 God has to be finitized also because man is the offspring of freedom or nonbeing as well as the child of God. The myth of the Fall dramatizes the powerlessness of God vis-a-vis beings able to rebel. In response to the fact of evil, God incarnationalIy plunges into the cauldron of human living. The death of the Son lifts the veil from tragedy within God himself. A God of sacrificial love, he confronts evil and winces under its blows, •Ibid., pp. 83, 26, 86, 20, 123-24, 54. Man's Vision of God and the Logic of Theism (Chicago: Willett, Clark, 1941), p. 165; quoted in Ralph E. James, The Concrete God (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1967), p. 133. •Nicholas Berdyaev, The Destiny of Man, trans. Natalie Duddington (New York: Harper, 1960; first published in 1935), p. 29. See Hartshorne's remarks on Berdyaev in Philosophers Speak of God, ed. Charles Hartshorne and William L. Reese (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), pp. 285-87 and 293-94, and the comments and strictures on this self-styled philosopher of freedom in Charles Journet, The Meaning of Evil; trans. Michael Barry (New York: Kenedy, 1968). pp. 97-102. . 180 JOHN M. QUINN, O.S.A. undergoing the tragedy of the cross to triumph over the tragedy of freedom. The extraverted propensity of God arises from his trinitarian personality. The loving give-and-take between God and creatures reflects the personal communion at the heart of his inner life. An inwardly personalistic God has to be outwardly communicative, sharing with creatures even to the point of drinking the cup of sorrow to its dregs. 7 (iv) The finitist conception of Bertocci also takes its rise from a critical restructuring of traditional Christian experience, this in an American setting. 8 The Mind necessarily superintending and directing agencies to their ends is first and foremost a Person, a cosmic Knower and a cosmic Loving Agent. Though God creates ex nihilo, two facts, the one natural, the other personal, block any ascription of infinity. A co-eternal Impediment, a brute given akin to the Receptacle of the Timaeus, resists God's efforts to maximize the harmony in the universe. The very creation of free co-creators, moreover, fixes boundaries to his power. Because free, persons map and work out their cosmic careers in partial independence of God. The maturitycreating insecurity that co-creators endure is felt in and by God. His control over future particulars subjected to the checks of freedom, God experiences a certain tension, a suffering through which he grows along with companions he elects to help shape the moral universe. Jesus stands out as the unparalleled example of the fruits of the cosmic Lover in man. Jesus's total openness to divine love releases the re-creation on which God spends his energies to effect in each man and in the whole history of man. 9 •Ibid., pp. 80, 81, 82, 57. Under the influence of Brightman, Whitehead, Bergson, and Hartshorne he was converted, Bertocci confesses, to a conception of " change in God in ways similar to Hartshome's view." Peter A. Bertocci, The Person God ls (London: Allen and Unwin, 1970), p. 25, n. I. •Ibid., pp. 22-80, 85-87, 290, 814-15; "Theistic Temporalistic Personalism and the Problem of Good-and-Evil," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philo• sophical Association (Washington: Office of National Secretary, 1977), 51, pp. 61-65. The notion of a co-eternal obstacle derives from Brightman, Bertocci's first major and probably most influential teacher; see Edgar A. Brightman, A Philoflophy of Religion (New York: Prentice-Hall, 1940), pp. 286-87, 887-89. 8 TRIUNE SELF-GIVING 181 2. The advantages of a finite-God concept are undoubtedly numerous. He is not exasperatingly inaccessible and not ineffably transcendent to nor imperturbably walled off from the petty round of creaturely comings and goings. Depths within depths of divine knowledge that classical theism declares impenetrable by rational understanding become in principle available to our minds. While present knowledge may be slim, the human spirit can legitimately aspire to lay hold of the inner workings of a kindred finite spirit, albeit the highest possible, that we call God. But these benefits are purchased at a price that many may judge exorbitant, indeed impossible, to pay. First, qua finite, such a top entity cannot strictly qualify as God. Second, only by being transcendent can God be omnipresently immanent. Third, infinite power is not the antithesis but the executive vehicle of infinite love. Fourth, an anthropomorphism partially undermines the finitist case. Fifth, not irrationality but a certain ineliminable dimension of mystery due to the eternal mode of operation envelops an infinite God. (i) Only in a Pickwickian sense can a finite God be equated with a supreme being. A nontranscendent part of the universe has to fall short of being its ultimate ground. No matter how superior his metaphysical endowments, a so-called God that functions as a component of the universe has to be reciprocally dependent on lower agencies and, as dependent, must himself be caused. The dependence of a process-imbued God on inferior executive and final causes demands a further explanatory factor. What is ultimately responsible for the ordination of the world to a finite God and a finite God to the world? Surely not God; surely not the world; surely not God and the world taken jointly; for these are precisely the things ordered that need explanation. A cause locked within the system ordered is not the explanation but an explanandum. Compelling a caused cause to act as first cause traps the mind in a vicious circle or an infinite regress. The source of a finite-God-world interlinkage must lie in a cause dwelling outside the factors ordered. In short, to account for agency and order among dependent things, we are bound to conclude to an uncaused or 182 JOHN M. QUINN, O.S.A. absolutely first cause usually synonymous with the God of classical theism. 10 (ii) The finitist thesis posits a false contrast between the transcendence and immanence of God. The super-eminence of God, it is implied, puts him outside the reach of and makes him void of concern for creatures. But transcendence and immanence are not contradictorily but only relatively opposed. Indeed so closely do they comport with one another that in the line of causation God is most immanent in things because he is absolutely transcendent. Immanence does not cancel out but depends on transcendence. The higher the entity, the farther its causality extends. Since an infinite God is pure act or subsisting existence, he causes as his proper effect the existence of each and every actual entity. Since God properly causes the existence that we may take as the most radical, the most formal determination or principle in a thing, he is most intimately present, most formally immanent, in the being and operation of all created things. Lack of absolute transcendence, however, may shorten the entitative gulf of essence between God and man but it also constricts the ambit of divine causality. The nearer the divine nature comes to ours, the more distant becomes his influence on creatures. The closer God is en10 Summa theologiae (Madrid: Biblioteca de Autores Cristianos, 1961), I, 2, 8 (henceforth referred to by numerals alone). Though specifically different because of distinct middle terms, all of the five. ways terminate in a supreme being variously viewed as an unmoved mover, first cause, and per se necessary being. The second obj.ection argues in terms of what is today called Ockham's razor that nature and reason (plus will) can account for all events without resort to the God-hypothesis. If in the answer to the difficulty we alter nature to read primordial stuff or undifferentiated creativity and substitute a superhuman intellect for reason (and will), the response becomes a repudia:tion of the finitisttheistic case. Pared down to essentials, a finite God is ordinarily equivalent to an angel or super-angel (see n. 16 below), a mighty finite spirit fashioning the universe with the cooperation, or sometimes in the teeth of the opposition, of a co-eternal stuff or creativity. But no matter how towering the spirit, finite intellect and will fail to qualify as primary " because these are mutable and defectible; we have to reduce all mobiles and defectib1es to some primary principle that is immobile or per se necessary." Limitation bespeaks mutability, and mutability bespeaks limitation; this reciprocal implication dooms every brief, however brilliantly presented, for a finite God. TRIUNE SELF-GIVING 188 titatively brought to our level, the more he is causally withdrawn and uninvolved. Only the entitatively highest can be causally closest. Only an infinite God can be roost intimately present in every fiber and most sensitively attuned to every pulse of finite things. 11 (iii) Proponents of a finite God also tend to dichotomize divine power and love. The upshot of the arbitrary splitting of these two attributes is nothing short of a grotesque caricature. A God of unchecked power, process thinkers tell us, tramples on pitiable creatures; super-power makes God a supertyrant ever inclined to hurl thunderbolts down on cringing subjects. So this quasi-Moloch must be toppled and his place ceded to a God of love exquisitely persuading creatures to ideal ends. But transmogrification of an omnipotent God into a neardevil rests on a misconception of the relation between divine power and love. Infinite power does not operate in resplendent and sinister isolation. The zeal with which finitists repudiate infinite power as irrational stems from selective disregard of the overarching wisdom and love that direct and impel divine power. Not classical theists but finitists, in attaching the label "God" to irresponsible power, fabricate the bizarre apotheosis that leaves the intelligent God-seeker disenchanted. For the power of God operates within the constraints, so to speak, of a divine nature untainted by the slightest proclivity for the irrational. The action of God cannot violate a nature one with infinite intelligence. The power of God is the outflow of the 11 III, 6, 1 ad 1: ". . . creatures are caused by God and depend on him as the principle of their existence. And then because of the infinity of his power, God immediately attains any one thing by his causation and conservation." As I, 8, le and ad 1 and ad S make clear, God entitatively transcends all things but fa causally immanent in every created entity. Sinoe he is essentially existence, he is immediately present in all things as the cause of their existence. While immediately causing existence, God mediately or instrumentally applies causes secundum fieri (which cause this dog to exist) and causes s.ecundum esse (which cause dog, the form of species); I, 104, 1. Unfortunately, this precision is blurred in one widely circulated translation that throughout infelicitously renders ease, the act of being, as being (which seems as analytically and linguistically misguided as translating anima, the act of a living body, as living being). 184 JOHN M. QUINN, O.S.A. divine nature or, more specifically, the executive expression of his wisdom and love.12 From the side of the per se good, God is first of all love that, with reference to the misery of men, becomes mercy. It is through the exercise of his power that his mercy is effectively broadcast over all his works. God applies infinite power to procure all the goodness possible within a lovingly designed finite frame. 13 In short, divine power at work in the world is an ordered omnipotence. It is limitless power operative within limits, it is power ordered to the delimited goodness appointed by infinite wisdom.14 Moreover, the refusal of infinite power tends, contrary to the finitist averral, to assure the obstruction rather than the release of God's love. A finite God is a crippled God. He is therefore not more but less loving than an infinite counterpart. The shrinkage of his power drastically curtails the energy and variety of his love. A :finitized God bears a likeness to a gifted brain surgeon whose vision has been blurred and hands made wooden by a stroke. Visual distortion and loss of manual flexibility reduce to nearzero efficiency the dexterity that prior to paralysis skilfully canalized his medical wisdom and humane concern. Boxing divine power within finitude also hamstrings the persuasiveness so prized in a nonabsolute God. Persuasion cut off from the resources of omnipotence has to be notably enfeebled, and a good number of the plans to which it is tied have to prove abortive. But infinite power in the ministry of infinite love, infinite power serving as an organ of goodness without stint, guarantees an unrestricted sweep of persuasion that is nothing else than the free play of infinite wisdom and love toward the optimum sowing and reaping of shared divine values in the universe. Only a God of infinite power can be maximally persuasive. His wisdom disposes all things sweetly according to his love and all things firmly according to his power. The sweetness is firmly 12 I, 25, I. Power is differentiated from knowledge and will in God not "secundum rem but merely secundum rationem insofar as power conveys the import of a principle executing what the will commands and knowledge directs." 1 • I, 21, 4 and I, 25, S ad s. "I, 25, 5c and ad I. TRIUNE SELF-GIVING 185 applied and the firmness sweetly applied, for his power is, to repeat, nothing but the executive expression of a loving command articulated with infinite discernment. In an infinite God alone is power maximally loving and love maximally powerful. (iv) An anthropomorphism lies behind the misrepresentation of God as heartless and despotic. Finitists misuse an otherwise indispensable analogical cognition when they compress God into a rigidly human mold and render a verdict on the good or evil implications of his attributes by measures appropriate only to the human situation. God, because he is God, can be commendably and nonegoistically self-sufficient and allpowerful. To put an infinite God down as cosmically powerdrunk seems to be as illogical as upbraiding a father for dictatorial behavior because he sanely thinks himself wiser than his three-year-old son and accordingly directs the child in a nondemocratic fashion that makes only small provision for the exercise of his son's freedom. Apart from its image-ridden character, this anthropomorphic misconstrual springs from a partially univocistic concept of God. In a blunt, arbitrary manner Whitehead lays down the stipulation that the ultimate reason for the world cannot be " wholly transcendent " but must be in and of " the actuality of this world." 15 Like other finites, God is potential, temporalized, growing along with his world that stamps him exclusively as its own. Simple fiat probably canonized by Kant's self-denying anti-metaphysics of God determines a priori that only a finite God can meet the requirements of divine attributes scaled down to a finitist framework. Even an infinite God rationally accessible by causal analysis and proper analogy is doomed to fail any test drawn up in accord with finitist standards. Furthermore, as mentioned earlier, unbending insistence on the finite in God erases his Godness. However humanly consoling and pictorially appealing, a finite God is an incoherent admixture of attributes. He is eternal and temporal, perfect and always growing, all-knowing and partially ignorant. Univocally conceived, he possesses 18 Religion in the Making p. 59. 186 JOHN M. QUINN, O.S.A. strengths and deficiencies that, while tolerable in a sublimated human spirit, seem inadmissible in God.16 (v). It would be naive and pretentious to think that these few brief remarks have let the daylight in on every aspect of the problem of the one and the many. 11 Indeed if we fully 16 I, 3, 7. A finite God would seem to be self-stultifying: as finite, he has to be composed of diverse facts it is with Kant, for the perfective attainment integral to happiness includes the moral capacity as well as the others. Priorities In this final section I want to ask whether human nature, or rather this human-nature-based value theory, has any relevance for settling certain questions about priorities among values. We are asking this question, remember, not from the moral point of view, which would obviously be central here, but indirectly from the point of view of human nature. Is there any indirect light to be gained from this quarter? First, we confront the question of whether there is any inherent precedence in the claims of some values over others. Are some values more valuable than others? All depends here on the perspective of such precedence, for there are different sorts of priority. Let us consider three of these in which the essential traits do seem to suggest some precedences. These may be called etiological priority, generic priority, and ontological priority. Etiological priority refers to any characteristics that are causally prerequisite, at least in the sense of necessary conditions, for the emergence of other values. From this perspective it seems obvious that the elementary psycho-physical characteristics-body, life, consciousness-are causally prior. If we do not have bodily maintenance and conscious awareness, the other values, dependent on these, cannot come to fruition. Generic priority refers to any characteristics that may be so pervasive in human life that they are qualitatively ingredient in, and required for, the flourishing of other values. And here there seems good reason, rooted in an understanding of human nature, for the traditional prominence given to moral and intel- 294 DONALD WALHOUT lectual virtues. It seems that other values cannot flourish without, or at least are greatly enhanced by, the moral ordering of life conducted by wise practical intelligence. And if moral and intellectual " virtues " does not exhaust what we mean by moral and intellectual " values," since the latter include dimensions and satisfactions beyond the former, it can still be the case that moral and intellectual characteristics have a generic priority among values. Ontological priority refers to man's relation to the reality that transcends him. This is the characteristic we have spoken of as cosmic dependence, and if this is the natural origin of religious value, then religious value could be thought of as having ontological priority. That is, the effective attunement with that which is ultimately and veridically transcendent would have the greatest ontological claim. This point is different from an analogous point, often made by theological writers, that one's ultimate commitment to what is ultimate determines all other commitments. The latter contention seems to be a point about obligations, or perhaps determinism, rather than about values. Concerning values, the question is simply whether there is a kind of culminating satisfaction-in-fulfillment through relation to the ultimately transcendent. And on this point there is no lack of historical tradition affirming this to be the case. Thus Plato focuses on the Forms and the Form of the Good as the culmination; Aristotle on emulation of the supreme mover; Biblical tradition on personal communion with God; Spinoza on intellectual love of God; and so on. One difficulty is that the nature of reality, or of the transcendent, is the thing most in dispute in philosophy, dividing theists and materialists, etc. Many would deny that religious value is veridical, let alone prior. Another difficulty is that ontological priority is confused with moral priority, leading to other-worldliness; with esthetic priority, leading to pietistic art; and so forth. But the existence of these difficulties would not be incompatible with saying that, from a normative point of view, if a maximum satisfaction-infulfillment were obtained through a veridically understood at- HUMAN NATURE AND VALUE THEORY 295 tunement with transcendent reality, that would have a certain claim of priority from the ontological perspective. A related question concerning priorities is that of the serial ordering or ranking of values. Is it possible to take all the intrinsic values and rank them all qualitatively from maximum to minimum, highest to lowest? I know of no attempt to do this literally with all possible values and subvalues. But it might ·seem feasible to make some broad groupings of families of values and endeavor to rank these. The principle of classification here would presumably be the degree of value, that is, the degree of fulfilling satisfaction in perfective attainment. Suppose, then, for example, that someone proposed a ranking like the following: (1) religious values (14 from the above lists) (2) freedom and morality (7, 8) (3) intellectual values (6) (4) existential values (11) (5) esthetic and creative values (9, 10) (6) social and cultural values (12, 13) (7) affective values (3, 4, 5) (8) psycho-physical conditions (1, 2, 3) . Would such a ranking he plausible? More exactly, is there anything about human nature that would justify it? This seems very doubtful. For one thing, such a ranking is controversial, would hardly be accepted by all, and yet there seems nothing about the fact that certain capacities are essential to man that places them in such a ranking. Essentiality by itself does not settle hierarchy. For another thing, much depends on the context in which values are experienced. To a person threatened with paralysis, the relearned ability to walk may be a more rewarding satisfaction, intrinsically, than confronting a Picasso or a work in mathematics. Finally, there is the inevitable matter of individual differences. People simply differ in their capability for intellectual work, for moral leadership, for esthetic taste, and so on. It seems incongruous to specify a ranking of 296 DONALD WALHOUT values to consist of a fixed list of abstractions apart from the personal centers who are to experience those values. It follows that if individuality is an essential property in human nature, its presence will be a deciding factor in the composition of the total human good. That is, the pattern or ranking of value emphases will show some variability depending on the individuality, the haecceitas, of each person. But if this is so, does it mean that the experience of the good is entirely r·elative in content to individual preference, taste, or declaration? Is this a valuational relativism of a privatistic sort? The answer must be no, for there are several governing conditions to the contrary that are drawn from other aspects of human nature. First, since every individual has a common human nature, the types of fulfillment possible, i.e., the intrinsic values, must be the same for all. We are talking, presumably, merely about patterns in Paradiso, or at least Purgatorio, not arrangements in Inferno. One man's food here is not another man's poison; rather, one man's food emphases may differ from another's but have similar nutrition. Intrinsic values may be variably displayed but cannot be replaced by disvalues. Second, the moral capacity of man is perfected in similar ways, namely, by the execution of obligations and the cultivation of virtues. Among these obligations and virtues are duties to oneself and virtues of proper self-regard. Thus the moral factor would require some ordering of values with a view to maximum personal good. Not any old pattern of value ordering could be acceptable from a moral point of view. Third, it is certainly possible to look upon ranking statements as hypotheses or generalizations about how most human beings, sine impedirnentis, would find maximum value satisfaction. For instance, one might propose that, if etiological priorities are met, rational contemplation, given a fair chance, will be found by most people to be one of the most satisfying values in life. One might identify a small group of topmost intrinsic values, meaning by this that on the whole most people would find these HUMAN NATURE AND VALUE THEORY values most rewarding to their individualized human nature. This is what Mill was worried about in trying to establish qualities 0£ goodness to avoid quantitative hedonism, and there is no reason to think he is not right in his generalizations, though his proof and his hedonism need not be accepted. Plato wants to go further and give a fixed ranking of different types of life, presumably based on their proximity to knowledge. Such proposals too can be considered as hypotheses about degrees of actual human perfective satisfaction, and there may be much truth in some of them. But from the standpoint of human nature, as well as actual experience, it seems that people can derive comparable levels of value experience whether their primary source be that of a thinker, a moral activist, a religious, an artist, or something else. Of course any life would be enhanced by including as much as possible of all the intrinsic values, provided there were no disproportionate loss in the primary source. And no doubt there are vast differences in the levels of value £ulfilhnent possible to different people due to given capacities and deficiencies. But if different individuals have realized their individual human nature, which might also be called their ideal self or destiny, it does not appear that they must necessarily be inferior to some, or superior to others, in the satisfaction that comes from perfective attainment. Perhaps it might be so in fact; but human nature does not suggest that it must be so. Finally, for any who believe that human nature has a perfective destiny beyond the natural order, speculation about a more settled ranking of capacities might seem in place in reference to that further realm. The speculation might seem in place since "it does not yet appear what we shall be." But such speculation should probably not count any longer as philosophy. DONALD WALHOUT Roclcford College Roclcford, Illinois BOOK REVIEWS Two Views of a Recent Book on Cajetan's Role in the Reformation. Cajetan Responds: A Reader in Reformation Controversy. Translated and Edited by JARED W1cKs, S. J. Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1978. Pp. ii + 292. $19.95. A FIRST VIEW-The principal part of this work is a translation into English of the lesser works of Cajetan which are related to the Reformation of the 16th century (pp. 47-244). While Fr. Wicks did not judge it necessary to provide a complete version of the writings (he gives only a summary of the less important passages), his book gives us a view, well conceived and put together, of all the writings of the " Cardinal of St. Sixtus " on the Reformation. This is an advantage not furnished to the reader of the original text. This central part of the work is preceded by an introduction divided into two sections of unequal length. The first is a biographical essay on Cajetan, followed by a brief evaluation of the Cardinal in relation to the Reformation (pp. 1-46) . A bibliography (pp. 244-253) and the notes for the introduction and the text of the translation (pp. 255-292) terminate the work. Clearly, the principal aim of the introduction is to furnish the background against which the twenty-five short works were produced. In fact, we are treated to a presentation of Cajetan's entire life, although some parts of it are analysed with a very special care, as, for example, the years surrounding the trial of Luther. The work of A. Cossio, Il Cardinale Gaetano e la Riforrna (Cividale, 1902), despite its uncontested merits, has been surpassed by the works of P. Kalkoff. Influenced, however, by certain theses and prejudices, the German scholar, in more than one place, arrived at conclusions which have to be called too precipitate (cf. Baumer, Der Lutherpro:zess in Lutherpro:zess und Lutherbann, KLK 32, Munster, L972, pp. 18 ff.) Fr. Wicks, bringing together the fruits of contemporary research, presents a more objective summary, well-balanced and precise, of the events into which Cajetan was plunged at the beginning of the Lutheran Reform. In passing, it seems well to underline some of the suggestions and attitudes of Father Wicks. He is not taken in by the hoary and tiresome accusations frequently hurled against Cajetan on the condemnation of Reuchlin (p. 8), nor does he trifle with the idea that the Legate was author of the letter sent by Maximilian to Leo X (p. 259, n.41) . Fascinating are the reflections based on the information furnished by W. Link after the meeting at Augsburg: "Cajetan told Luther that the second point (faith in the Sacrament) could remain open for the present, since, with some refinement, BOOK REVIEWS 299 or a slight re-definition Luther's view might well stand " (pp. 24 ff., cf. pp. 260 ff., n. 53) . To understand better the attitude of Cajetan, if Link's information is correct, it is necessary to take into account what Cajetan will write in his article on the faith (cf. p. 222 ff.). In preparing for the meeting at Augsburg (Oct. 1518), Cajetan had before him two writings of Luther. The notes made by the Cardinal, in themselves, constitute the first series of articles, which revolve around two points: the relationship between faith and the sacrament, and the doctrine of indulgences. A note, which is implicitly an answer to Luther's pamphlet on the excommunication, completes the Cardinal's series (pp. 47-98). Wicks notes that a passage of Sacred Scripture cited by Cajetan in favor of Luther, in one of the Cardinal's works, is not found in the writings which antedate his meeting with the Augustinian. Also, he thinks, and with good reason, that the addition was made by Cajetan after reading the written defence presented by Luther, October 14, 1518 (cf. p. 267, n.9). From 1519 to 1521 date his writings on the use of Sacred Scripture, on the institution of the Roman Pontificate and on the propositions of Luther which were condemned by the bull Exurge Domine: the 7th, 10th, 15th, 17th, and 28th (pp. 99-153). Some years later, at the request of Clement VII, Cajetan drew up a memorandum for use by an envoy who was to discuss Zwingli's doctrine on the Eucharist (pp. 154-173) . In 1530, and again in 1534, the Cardinal was asked for his views on the marriage of Henry VIII and Catherine of Aragon, a decisive question in the religious future of England (pp. 175-188; 241244) . In relation to the Diet of Augsburg, the Roman Curia envisaged the possibility of an agreement with the Lutherans, based on some concessions. The Pope and a group of his councillors were reluctant to summon a Council, in spite of the urging of Charles V. From another point of view, because of the constant threat from the Turks, the Pope needed to be careful not to alienate the princes who were favorable to the " innovators." He sought from Cajetan, then, advice on possible advances to the Lutherans. Clement VII was interested in at least three of Cajetan's suggestions. It is worthy of note that the idea of dispensing priests of the Latin Rite from celibacy was fiercely fought, for very different reasons, by two laymen: the King of France and the Emperor of Germany (pp. 201-203) . At this time, constantly concerned about Lutheran doctrine, Cajetan composed a series of small works, entitled " Against the Lutherans." The first, written May 3, 1531, is well-known and it has been much used by Catholic theologians. It involves an enigma not yet resolved. Father Wicks indicates its principal elements (p. 287, nn.1-7). The Cardinal knew very well the line to take in answering a work which taught a strictly Lutheran view on the real presence but which rejected the sacrificial value of the Mass and its application to the dead. While, in identifying the sources of the Lutheran pamphlet, it is quite legitimate to appeal to the soo :SOOK REVIEWS Confession of Augsburg or to the Judicium de Missa of Melanchthon, it is another thing to try to find in the works of Luther a passage which assembles the texts from the Epistle to the Hebrews on which the principal argument of the Lutherans depends. Indeed, any true argumentation on the subject seems to be lacking in the writings of both Luther and Melanchthon. The book which Cajetan had before him at the time remains unknown until the present day. It should also be noted that the passages of Sacred Scripture to which the Cardinal refers, as well as the form of his argumentation, are much like his way of writing about Zwingli (De Canone Missae Epicheresis, in Siimtliche Werke, I, Leipzig, 1906, pp. 288 ff.). The other writings in this series are concerned with communion under both species, the complete accusation of sins, satisfaction, and the invocation of the saints (all themes brought up in the Confession of Augsburg) and, finally, faith and works, one of the principal objects of disagreement between Cajetan and Luther. The subjects treated by Cajetan are highly varied. Father Wicks relates them both to the events of the period and to the life of the Cardinal. In addition, he makes reference to other outstanding facts of Cajetan's life: the dispute on Averroes and his doctrines at Padua, the reform in the Dominican Order, the Fifth Lateran Council (in which he gave a discourse on the Reform of the Church) . In this area, it is of importance to note that all the editions of the Acts of the Councils from the time of Cajetan (15U) to modern times contain texts that are mutilated. Much to be preferred is the edition of Rome, of 1512, which contains the lesser works of Cajetan. Father Wicks does not pass over the exegetical works of the Cardinal. It has often been said that Cajetan's interest in Sacred Scripture was the result of his meeting with Luther at Augsburg, but Father Wicks shows that this contact had only a secondary influence on the Cardinal's scriptural studies. This seems a truer assessment of the facts of history (cf. A. F. von Gunten, " La contribution des Hebreux a !'oeuvre exegetique de Cajetan," in Histoire de l'exegese au XVIe siecle: Etudes de philosophie et d'histoire, 84; Geneve, 1978, pp. 57-60). It is well to be on one's guard, not to be deceived by the brevity of Father Wicks's work, or by the title of the Introduction, " A Biographical Essay." This author has a complete acquaintance with all the recent studies on the subject which he treats. The bibliography itself is an indication of this fact (pp. 286-258) . Every work of any importance is cited. The number and choice of the citations, the questions raised, or even suggested, in these pages show that Father Wicks absorbed and judged intelligently the entire problematic, and that he has given space only to the points which are related to his chosen theme. His presentation is well-balanced and free from polemical spirit. From my own knowledge, I conclude that this biography, in spite of its succinctness, is one of the very best. With some addi- BOOK REVIEWS 301 tions, it merits a separate publication, and it should be translated into other languages. To present an exposition of the doctrine of Cajetan, to defend it, or merely to judge its value, to say that Thomas de Vio (Cajetan) resolves all the questions which he raises-all these are far from the intent of Father Wicks. His aim is simply to provide those who are interested in the problems of the Reformation with a tool for studying the theological works of one who was a witness of this movement of the 16th century. The choice of Cajetan was a happy one. Grasping the actual climate of the times, without the passions which affected many generations of historians and having a profound understanding of Cajetan's encounter with Luther, the author penetrates to the heart of the teachings of the Legate of Leo X in the innovative movement of the 16th century. Elsewhere, in the present day, one looks in vain, among Protestants as among Catholics, for such a precise delineation of the Cardinal of St. Sixtus, free from superficial or preconceived theses-for example, in G. Henning, K. V. Selge, or 0. H. Pesch. Even so, this is not to say that the author has succeeded in describing perfectly the theological and spiritual viewpoint of Cajetan, nor in portraying exactly its relation to the attitude of Luther. That question remains partially open. A. F. VON GuNTEN, O.P. Univei·sity of St. Thomas Aquinas Rome, Jtal,y AN ALTERNATE VIEW-Jared Wicks has made available for the first time in full English translation, or in synopsis, the eleven controversial treatises of Thomas Cardinal de Vio Cajetan, spanning the years 1518-1534. Excellent notes accompany the translations. A brief biography of Cajetan serves as an introduction. Of special interest is Wicks's account of the background and circumstances surrounding Cajetan's meeting with Luther at Augsburg in October, 1518. He provides us with the chronology of the meetings and a summary of the matters discussed. His research does much to put Cajetan's role at Augsburg, and his later involvement in the Reformation controversy, in a new perspective, one most favorable to the Dominican Cardinal. Eight of the eleven treatises deal with his response to Luther and his movement, two with the Marriage Question of Henry VIII, and one is a critique of the Eucharistic doctrine of Ulrich Zwingli. Readers familiar with the controversial writings of Cajetan's contemporaries, both Catholic and Protestant, will discover in his works a marked difference in style, methodology, and argumentation. They are devoid of all polemics against person- 302 BOOK REVIEWS alities, reveal a conscientious use of sources available to him, are brief and clear. He did not attempt, as did his Catholic colleagues, a line by line response, but rather isolated major dogmatic issues, clarified his opponents' objections, and responded with his own concise arguments. The treatises dealing with the Lutheran question cover two periods: 1518-1521, the early years of controversy, and 1531-1532 when Cajetan commented on the Augsburg Confession and the Apology of Melanchthon. The Augsburg Treatises of 1518 are in reality a collection of thirteen position papers written by Cajetan for his own benefit in preparation for his meeting with Luther. They reveal his careful analysis of Luther's Explanation of the Ninety-five Theses, the Sermon on Penance, and the Sermon on Excommunication. In these writings Cajetan discerned two major issues at divergence from Catholic teaching. The first involved a new understanding and description of the nature of justifying faith, which Luther claimed rested solidly on the authority of Scripture. The traditional Catholic formulation of justifying faith as fides caritate formata had become in Luther fides certitudine remissionis peccatorum f ormata. Cajetan quickly perceived the far-reaching doctrinal consequences of such a position. The second point of difference concerned Luther's rejection, on the grounds of the lack of clear scriptural evidence, of the authoritative teaching of Clement VI on the nature, extension, and efficacy of indulgences. Thus in the Augsburg Treatises Cajetan responded to various aspects of Luther's doctrine bearing on these two issues. It is significant that at this early date he perceived in germ what will later become the central theses of the Reformation controversy: sola fides and sola scriptura. Two treatises of significance followed in 1521. The Divine Institution of the Pontifical Office was occasioned by Luther's published Resolutio of the thirteenth thesis of the Leipzig debate of 1519, wherein he denied the unique role of the Pope in defining matters of faith. Cajetan's disciplined response, based on carefully selected scriptural and patristic sources, was highly praised by Erasmus. The ambivalent reaction to Luther's condemnation in Exurge Domine of Leo X prompted Cajetan to write The Five Articles of Luther-A Justi,.. fication for Their Condemnation. This was a concise statement of formal theological reasons for the condemnation of certain key Lutheran theses, some of which he previously dealt with in the Augsburg Treatises. These works reveal Cajetan's growing conviction that Luther before all else had to be answered by argumentation from Scripture. His experience in Germany had made him aware of the distrust and deep antipathy felt by the German Humanist and early Lutherans toward arguments from Scholastic Theology and Canon Law. To meet the challenge he assiduously dedicated himself from this period on to the study of Scripture, and by the BOOK REVIEWS 303 end of the decade had produced several commentaries of note on the Old and New Testaments. As Wicks observes, Cajetan's exegetical approach sets him apart from most of his Catholic contemporaries. For example, he insisted, like his master Aquinas, that only the literal sense of the text provides a valid basis for theological argumentation. He also had for his day the rare perception that the Latin Vulgate was a quite fallible translation and needed to be checked frequently against the original. To insure for himself the accuracy of the biblical text he employed Hebrew scholars as assistants, and made consistent use of the New Testament studies of Lefevre d'Etaples and Erasmus. At this time he also advanced a Catholic understanding of the formula sola scriptura, the principles for which he had already enunciated in his commentary on the Summa of St. Thomas. It was unfortunate for the Catholic cause that Cajetan's scholarly creativity met vehement opposition and only the Pope's intervention saved him from condemnation by the theological Faculty of Paris. But this study did bear fruit in his treatises of which are a high point of excellence in the controversial literature of the pre-Tridentine period. In response to the Augsburg Confession of 1530 he published in May of 1531 The Sacrifice of the Mass and its Rite-Against the Lutherans. With arguments drawn exclusively from the New Testament, notably the Epistle to the Hebrews, he offered a solution to the Lutheran objection concerning the sacrificial nature of the Eucharist by showing the unity of Christ's unique sacrifice with the Church's sacrifice, the Mass. Again he earned the enthusiastic praise of Erasmus. In August of the same year came his treatise on the Four Lutheran Errors in which he defended the Catholic position on the question of Communion under both forms, integral confession, satisfaction for sins, and the invocation of the saints. The treatise Faith and Works of addressed questions raised by the Apology of Melanchthon concerning the human response in faith to God's gracious action in the human heart. Cajetan's argument included an insightful description of what it means to live in the love of mutual friendship with God, an analysis clearly based on his own exposition of Paul's Epistles and I John. Another point of Faith and Works concerns the meritorious character of the works of the man reborn by God's grace. In this regard Cajetan utilized as the basis of his response the Pauline theme of the believer's incorporation into Christ. Works are meritorious because they are performed in Christo et per Christum. It would be a serious mistake, however, to limit Cajetan's involvement in the Reformation crisis to a mere defensive and apologetic role. The reform of abuses within the Church, even before the events of 1518, was his passionate concern. Nor was he intransigent and inflexible in his attitude to- 304 BOOK REVIEWS ward the Reformers. His Guidelines for Concessions to the Lutherans of 1581 is perhaps the most significant of his Reformation treatises. Written as a memorandum to Pope Clement VII, Cajetan with courage and wisdom outlined a plan for the restoration of the unity of the Church which in his judgment would preserve the essentials of the Catholic faith and, at the same time, make possible an honorable and painless reconciliation for the Lutheran teachers. Based on topics suggested by Melanchthon in the summer of 1530, he proposed, among other things, that clerical marriage in accord with the custom of the Greek Church be permitted for the Germans, that Communion under both forms be allowed in the German liturgy, and that all laws of purely ecclesiastical origin be declared for the whole Church as not binding under serious sin. The Guidelines met overwhelming opposition at the Roman Curia. Wicks gives a probing analysis of why Cajetan had no appreciable influence in changing the course of events in the early Reformation period. His genius itself is in large measure the reason. Two different levels of discourse characterize the dialogue with Luther, especially as regards the 1518-1521 period. Always confining himself to the scientific and formally theological, he failed to perceive and take into account the pastoral and at times deeply religious intent of Luther. In the Reformation war of words Cajetan's disciplined responses had nothing of Luther's passionate appeal to the religious aspiration of the German people. Even his late treatises, with their profound biblical insights, had no impact on the Reformers. They had come too late, but perhaps more significantly, they too were on a different level of discourse. For much of Luther's biblical exegesis rested upon a Christological or tropological interpretation of the sacred text. His writings did bolster Catholic confidence and self-identity. But he failed to communicate his vision for the renewal of Catholic biblical studies, and to convice his contemporaries that the use of the best of the humanist methods of textual criticism would at the same time effect the revitalization of Scholasticism, especially Thomism. His genius stood alone. It goes without saying that Jared Wicks has made another major contribution to Reformation studies. Cajetan Responds will be welcomed by Roman Catholic and Lutheran scholars who are once more engaged in the task of the reconciliation of the Churches. WILLIAM Dominican House of Studies Washington, D.C. A. NEWMAN, O.P. BOOK REVIEWS sos Meister Eckhart, Mystic and Phuosopher. By REINER ScHUID>i£ANN. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978. Pp. 9l69. $17.50. Have there been five books published in English on Meister Eckhart in this century? The past eighteen months alone have brought us three: C. F. Kelley, Meister Eckhart on Divine Knowledge (Yale, 1977); a symposium on Eckhart printed in The Thornist (April, 1978); and finally this volume by the professor of philosophy at the New School for Social Research. Although this book is a translation of a French edition, it owns a fine English style, bright and succinct. Schlirmann recently published in France a book of autobiographical reflections, Origines, which attracted wide attention as a first view of life after World War II by a young German. So the author's literary talents enhance this study of Eckhart, for it is aesthetically as well as intellectually captivating. Schlirmann wants not to explain everything about Eckhart but to unlock the central spark of the mystic: the unavoidably and permanently dynamic Eckhart. "As long as Eckhart's readers attempt to grasp his thought in relations among entities, isolating different philosophical currents like musical motifs, the simple source from which everything springs remains hidden. Eckhart's thinking is such that probably any list of 'theses' drawn from his works will provoke objections and rejectien for diverse reasons " (p. 164). The format of this book is novel and avoids the labored structure, inspired by dissertations, of a superfluity of quotations and references culled from all the great man's writings. Instead, Schlirmann has carefully chosen three sermons which through exposition and hermeneutic allow the Meister's word to emerge and to impress. Each of the sermons contains central motifs of Eckhart's philosophico-theological view of the world and the self: detachment and birth; the quaternity of dissimilarity, similarity, identity and dehiscence; the concluding juxaposition of ontic nothingness opening to the nothingness of the Godhead; and being-born in the being of the Son of God. Schlirmann points out that these moments are " intensities " for every or for any moment of a person's life; they are not stages in a methodology of prayer or interior ascent. For each of the three chapters exegeting one sermon newly translated, the author provides a second sermon: an expansion upon, an illustration of the teaching in that particular chapter. The professor at the New School expresses lucidly an approach which has been on the tip of the tongue of other, European scholars. He observes that to remain with a metaphysics of substances is inevitably to be incapable of expressing what Eckhart, as mystic and writer, wants to say. Eckhart, no more than any other speculative mystic, thinks of God and the mind as united by some kind of fusion of entities into a common substance; rather, 306 BOOK REVIEWS Got entwird: in the disappearance of the God-Person and of the man-person, in detachment and the great forgetfulness of self, being accomplishes itself. Only this process "is." Breakthrough, on the one hand, birth on the other, are reconciled in the itinerancy of the detached man. (p. 164) The critical apparatus of the book is sparse, but this should not delude readers and scholars into the opinion that the volume ignores the intellectual sources and milieu of Eckhart. Schilrmann knows medieval thought very well, and his uncovering of Eckhart's words and ideas in Albert or Aquinas is thorough. He unravels and intertwines in a sophisticated way the interplay of Neoplatonism and Aristotelianism in Eckhart. He makes a good case in the final sections for showing that Eckhart finds the different kinds of theories of analogy inadequate for his thought. Schilrmann explains how Eckhart saw true prayer and mystical insight attaining the Godhead beyond God. This "breakthrough" (the word is Eckhart's own creation) to the Godhead-through radical detachment and Zen-like focus upon the present existent-must mean that the philosophical categories which were at hand for the Thuringian Dominican appeared inadequate: not false but inadequate. "The authentic core of Meister Eckhart's thinking is releasement. In the history of ideas, each epoch has its own language, and perhaps releasement precedes its own epoch. Our experience is that it reveals the framework of established metaphysics as too narrow, for releasement is as inexhaustible as being itself .... (There is) an interval in the itinerary of Eckhart into which the theory of analogy cannot reach." (p. 191 f) No reader will wish that the final pages on Eckhart and Martin Heidegger were absent from this book, but it is not clear why Heidegger enters at this point with such a prominent position. Not that Heidegger has no extensive relationship to Eckhart: as John Caputo's writings also show, he does. Nevertheless, there is a certain aesthetic intrusion as one thinker, among the many influenced by Eckhart, assumes such a major role. Schilrmann's style, not as an author but as a philosopher, resembles Heidegger's. For the reader will find this book to be not only a study of Eckhart but an exposition so lucid and original that it crosses the line from exposition to philosophy. The final appendix on Eckhart and Zen will lead readers, I hope, to Schilrmann's longer article on this topic in the Eckhart symposium published in The Thomist recently. The book is most controversial and inevitably limited as it reaches its denouement in the question of the Godhead. A valuable discussion of the Neoplatonic influence upon Eckhart's understanding of analogy is interspersed within a slow crescendo leading to the Godhead beyond God. A perfectly released man literally represents nothing. Being as present and as nothingness arises on the path which Eckhart describes as that of solitude, of the desert and of forgetfulness. Both the philosopher of analogical identity and the BOOK REVIEWS 307 thinker of peregrine identity articulate some kind of presence ... , Releasement knows that things are there for nothing. Hence nothingness is as valid a title (for God), in Eckhart's ontology, as being." (p. 189) One can understand that, from the horizon of created beings, God is nonbeing. Are not, however, some nuances left undeveloped as the pleroma of nothingness in the Godhead is mentioned along with the ontic nothingness of a created, contingent being? How does the nothingness of sin and of grace-enabled apophatic spirituality enter here? It is rare to find a book on a complicated thinker which is creatively conceived, at times inspiringly written, and always intellectually challenging. A lasting question which the book raises---one which is both superficial and profound-is that of a point of translation. Is " releasement " a satisfactory English word for Gelassenheit? Overtones in English from the prefix " re- " unsettle the reader. Is not this German form of letting with a syllable of abstraction at either end best reworded as " letting-be? " The author seems to agree, for in the section on Heidegger this English translation is employed. THOMAS F. O'MEARA, 0.P. Washington, D.C. Meister Eckhart on Divine Knowledge. By C. F. KELLEY. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977. $18.50. As readers of this journal know, in recent years there has been a quantum leap in Eckhart scholarship in English. Meister Eckhart has always been a controversial and enigmatic figure, whose works have yielded an astonishing variety of interpretations. It is therefore not surprising to find him once again the subject of intense scrutiny and discussion. Several recent studies have modified our understanding of the fourteenth-century Dominican. Among these, C. F. Kelley's Meister Eckhart on Divine Knowledge attempts a sympathetic reconstruction of Eckhart's vision in terms of divine or " principial " knowledge. With this theme as his focus, Kelley uses the full range of Latin and German works to develop a systematic interpretation of Eckhart. He also lays claim to a more than historical inquiry, when he states that the book's purpose is " to introduce the reader not only to the insights of Meister Eckhart, but primarily to the doctrine of Divine Knowledge which, as expounded by him, is to be found in the Word" (p. 16). Kelley thus takes the standpoint of a believer who thinks with Eckhart on the theme of divine knowledge. Kelley claims that the Thomistic influence is decisive for Eckhart, and that Aquinas in tum must be viewed in light of the Pseudo-Dionysius's 308 BOOK REVIEWS negative theology (p. 108). Kelley therefore takes the Neoplatonic strain in Thomas as normative for Eckhart. In particular, Thomas's affirmation of " the isness of Divine Knowledge as supreme Principle " (p. 88) is central to Eckhart, and becomes the focal point for Kelley's interpretation. The foundation of being in divine knowledge is a major theme in the Parisian Questions, where Eckhart states that " God does not know because he is; rather he is because he knows, in the sense that God is unrestricted knowledge and understanding, and knowledge is the foundation of his isness" (p. 174). With this presupposition, Eckhart attempts to preach and write from within the divine intellect and its unity, prior to differentiated, individual being; he speaks not as one on the way to divine knowledge, but as one who has already arrived. Kelley thus defines " principial knowledge " as " the consideration of all things and all manifestations as it were from within the Godhead, the unconditioned principle, or tamquam in p1'incipio infinito" (p. 250). Meister Eckhart on Divine Knowledge is a sustained, well-documented argument for this principal mode of knowing. We may distinguish the following themes in Kelley's presentation of principial knowledge: the role of knowledge in Eckhart's anthropology; the birth of the Word in the soul; inversion and detachment. First, Eckhart distinguishes between God and the human self primarily in terms of knowledge. God's being consists in unrestricted knowledge, while man's being qua individual and creature consists in an unrestricted will to know (pp. 56-58) . Second, only the divine Word satisfies the human will to know. As the believing soul receives the Word's revelation, a radical shift of perspective occurs. :For the Word's "birth" in the soul restores it to its primal identity within the Godhead, where the soul becomes one with God himself. Eckhart writes that the Father " begets me as his Son and the same Son ... not only does he beget me as his Son, but he begets me as himself, and himself as me, and me as his being and nature" (p. 129). Kelley notes that this identity is not substantial, but principial; that is, it represents not a fusion of discrete substances, but the original and fecund unity of all things in God, since "that which is in God is God" (p. 100). More precisely, God's unrestricted knowledge embraces all things in its unified act. Further, dwelling within God, the soul comprehends all things in their original unity. As Kelley states, " The end of the intellect is the realization of oneness with the Word, and when this realization is actualized in the ground [of the soul] then all is known principially-' gleichwie in the Word.' It is there and only there that the transposition to principial knowledge is effected " (pp. 125-126). The revelation, birth, and reception of the Word thus constitutes the condition and essential content of principial knowledge. The unity of the Word and the soul requires inversion and detachment. Eckhart distinguishes " a double isness of the creature-in God and in itself" (p. 161). In itself created being remains finite and BOOK REVIEWS 309 and qua creature man's knowledge of God proceeds from this individual, subjective standpoint. Principial knowledge, however, inverts this perspective, as it "starts within God and then proceeds to understand all things from the standpoint of divine insta.sis" (p. 142). Eckhart's identification of being and intellect leads to a full coordination of the noetic, ontological, and logical dimensions of inversion: the intellect's inversion into the Word as its principle; the ontological inversion of manifest being into the unmanifest Godhead; and in logical terms, the " negation of the negation," that is, the turn to infinite affirmation through negating its restricted-and therefore negative-forms. If we cling to our finite standpoint, this inversion and principial knowledge are inconceivable. Hence, Eckhart insists that only a radical detachment can effect this inversion. Detachment involves " utter dispossession of the self" (p. 217) , and acknowledges created being's total dependence on God and nothingness in itself. More precisely, the detached self becomes "poor in spirit": wanting, knowing, and having nothing in itself, the self becomes pure receptivity and "lets God be God" (pp. QQ2-2Q7). In this way, detachment yields inversion and principial knowledge. Kelley has written a challenging and difficult book. Indeed, Meister Eckhart on Divine Knowledge may be a little more difficult than it need be. Its style is somewhat stiff, and Kelley's translations occasionally seem forced. In general, the book's argument could be more clearly delineated. Another problem is a recurring polemic, which interrupts basically sound analyses and makes Eckhart appear more remote from the reader than necessary. On this point, John Caputo's and Reiner Schiirmann's comparisons of Eckhart and Heidegger provide a corrective to Kelley's denial of contemporary analogues to Eckhart's thought. These minor reservations aside, Meister Eckhai·t remains a very useful study. It has been painstakingly researched, with extensive notes and a helpful index. From a speculative point of view, the book compels interest not as a definitive study but as suggesting directions for further research. For instance, Kelley's heavily Neoplatonic reading of Thomas is controversial, but may accurately reflect Eckhart's own interpretation of Thomas. Here we see the need for further inquiry into Eckhart's use of Thomas and Albert, and into the Dominican milieu of Cologne. More significantly, Kelley's analysis of principial knowledge provides a powerful, organizing focus that clarifies many of Eckhart's ambiguities. Yet Kelley gives insufficient attention to Eckhart's oscillation between the principial and the distinctively human perspectives. Eckhart himself emphasizes the contrast and tension between the " here " of the human subject and the " there " of its being in God. While detachment and the Word's birth in the soul unify these perspectives, their difference and tension remain in Eckhart's language. In part, the achievement of Eckhart lies in his style, whose vigor, symbolic richness, and 810 BOOK REVIEWS paradoxes enable him to speak from "here" as though from "there." By focusing on prineipial knowledge, Kelley has disclosed one pole of this contrast, and surely for us the more fundamental pole. By minimizing the human standpoint, however, Kelley overlooks both Eckhart's dialectical play between perspectives and his uncanny knack for expressing divine knowledge in human language. A more comprehensive interpretation would attend precisely to those " edges of language " (Van Buren) where the inversion of perspectives occurs. Such an explicitly hermeneutical approach would also involve thinking with Eckhart, and would owe a great deal to M ei.ster Eckhart on Divine Knowledge. DoNALD F. Ducww Gwynedd-Mercy CoUege Gwynedd VaUey, Pennsylvania Just and Unjust Wars. By MICHAEL WALZER. New York: Basic Books, 1977. Pp. 861. Cloth. $Q5.00. Modern weaponry, ideology, and disregard for the moral rules dictated by the right to life have combined to made modern warfare savage beyond compare. An important attempt to reestablish the authority of moral rules in warfare has been made in Michael Walzer's ]itSt and Unjust Wars. This book is a much-needed study of the judgments of contemporary international lawyers and moral philosophers of the justice and morality of modern forms of warfare. Most of the evaluations he presents in this work are correct and accurate, but the moral reasons he gives for many of these evaluations are superficial and obscure because of his apparently positivist view of moral rules and principles (p. 13). Walzer refuses to state explicitly the relevant moral principles that govern the conduct of war, and this must be counted against him. His study would have been more cogent and coherent if he had developed the notions of the community of nations, threat, reconciliation, the right to life and of discrimination in action, and related these more directly to the specific cases he reviewed. I wish to do this and show how an elaboration of these concepts would enhance our understanding of the moral character of some aspects of modern warfare. He states that the community of nations has rights, and that the violation of these rights constitutes a necessary and sufficient ground for organized political violence (p. 61). He does not state what these rights are, or why their violation is so grave, and what needs to be asserted here is that the community of nations is an interdependent community in which individual member nations can only survive and flourish when their interdependent relationships are just, fair, and equitable. When these qualities BOOK REVIEWS 311 are extracted from these relationships, then interdependent relationships are destroyed, nations cannot flourish, and in some instances, they cannot survive (p. 110). War is a crime when it destroys these interdependent relationships without warrant, and directly threatens the survival of individual member states. No individual state has the right to employ organized political violence to jeopardize these relationships in the absence of a sufficient warrant or due cause. Because the very vitality of individual states depends on the maintenance of these relationships, it is then the positive duty of all states to promote justice, fairness, and equity in these relationships, and their negative duty to refrain from acts that destroy these values and relations. This negative duty entails the necessity of all states acting so that these values are reasserted if intentional acts of organized political violence have destroyed them. The only moral purpose for the prosecution of war is the actualization of conditions in the power relationship among adversaries which will permit a process of reconciliation to be initiated upon the termination of hostilities which will end in a state of reconciliation and not just " a better state of peace " (pp. 115-6) . This is the only morally permissible purpose for the prosecution of war because it alone will reassert the conditions of justice, fairness, and equity in the relationships of interdependency required for the vitality and flourishing of the community of nations. Winning a war will not guarantee the reestablishment of these relationships, but prosecuting it so that a state of reconciliation is realized will achieve this end. War is not morally prosecuted for the purpose of totally destroying the capabilities of self-defense of an adversary, but only so that power relationships may be reasserted that will permit the initiation and successful completion of a process of reconciliation. And soldiers who die in war for anything more than this have died for a morally impermissible objective (p. 110). The principle which grounds all calculations concerning the morality of war is the principle of the unconditional and absolute claim of persons to the right to life. The rule of war which cannot ever be permissibly overridden is that which prohibits the imposition of threats on those who pose no direct or indirect threat to others. Individual persons, and persons in the associations of nation-states or ethnic groupings, have an absolute and unconditional right to life, existence, and survival. The capability of persons, individually and collectively, to assert radically superior orders of logic, value, and meaning into existence in all domains of human existence is the basis for possession of this right. Claims to this right may be permissibly waived only when heroic, saintly, or conspicuously virtuous deeds are entailed by this forfeiture. Moral agents invalidate their claims to the right to life only when they freely, voluntarily, intentionally, and directly pose a threat to another valid claimant of the right to life. A certainly 312 BOOK REVIEWS permissible condition under which organized political violence may be undertaken is when a threat of this type is proximately and actually present, for this makes the initiation of war identical in morally relevant terms to acts of self-defense by individual persons (p. 12Q) . 1£ violence is threatened which is capable of certainly endangering the existence of a state or ethnic group, then the prosecution of war is permissible. Those who have posed a free, intentional, direct, positive, and proximate threat cannot claim the freedoms and protections offered by the right to life because this threatening act directly entails the destruction of higher orders of logic, meaning, and value. Consequently, any act that entails protection for valid claimants is permissible if it does not in turn threaten those who have a valid claim to this right. These acts of defense, however, must be discriminating to the point where they only inflict violence on those agents who pose the threats. It is never permissible to perform acts or deploy weapons, tactics, and strategies that cannot discriminate between those who pose threat of this nature and those who do not. In war any act that intentionally and indiscriminately kills is a murderous act. And it must be recalled that the intention of the agent does not constitute the moral value of the act, but only contributes to or detracts from its moral value. I wish to relate these principles to some of the problems Walzer confronts to show why they provide stronger moral reasons for prohibiting certain acts in war. He faces the issue of the conditions necessary for a permissible intervention by a state on the behalf of an adversary in a conflict, and rightly notes that the legalist paradigm is inadequate for determining these conditions (p. 86) . In the case of an officially sanctioned governmental act of massacre or massive violation of human rights, it is certainly permissible for other states to intervene to protect those whose right to life is being violated, but it is not obligatory for them to do this. Intervention such as this to protect another's right to life is a conspicuously virtuous deed, and, like all deeds of this type, is non-obligatory. Intervention in this situation is permissible, not because of the manner in which certain acts shock the conscience of humanity, for this is not a moral reason but only a reference to moral psychology. It is permissible when this is the only means available of stopping a massive, positive, and proximate direct threat to those who validly claim the right to life. However, a failure to perform acts of this nature on account of fear is often morally reprehensible. Violent intervention by a state is only permissible when the threat is actual and present, and when it is actualized on account of a governmental policy. If the threat posed is less serious than this, it is permissible to refrain from intervening, and if it is only remote or potential, or if it is the result of the action of a private citizen, then intervention is impermissible. Walzer objects that the killing of occupation troops by disguised par- BOOK REVIEWS 313 tisans after a formal surrender is an impermissible act of assassination. Because partisans have supposedly abandoned the right to kill after the surrender, Walzer contends that this act of political resistance is murderous. I do not believe that this is as clearly certain as he thinks. For if the partisans' nation was unjustly attacked, then it is not certain that the victors retain a valid claim to the right to life on account of their successful aggression. And the surrender of the defeated nation to an unjust aggressor does not entail an acknowledgment of the validity of the aggressor's claim to the right to life. Hence, killing after the surrender to an unjust attack is not necessarily murder because it is not clear that a valid claim to the right to life has been violated. A valid claim to the right to life does not necessarily attach to victorious but unjust aggressors simply on account of their victory. If this form of disguise is impermissible, then the use of enemy uniforms by commando units should also be prohibited. Any killing done while using this disguise would also be assassination according to Walzer's principles, because of the identity between this and the act of the partisans. I doubt that Professor Walzer would wish to prohibit this form of commando action, but the principle which prohibits partisans from killing occupation troops would prohibit commandos from killing their enemy while under disguise. The indiscriminate use of organized political violence is correctly condemned by Walzer, but the moral reasons he gives for this are rather weak. The direct, intentional, positive, and voluntary killing of those who surrender, civilians, or neutrals is impermissible because their valid claim to the right to life is violated. And the unintentional killing of these individuals for the purpose of military expediency is either negligent homicide or murder. Weapons that cannot be deployed discriminately, or whose deployment strongly implies the deaths of those with valid claims to the right to life, are also prohibited in these instances. And tactics, strategies, and weapons deployments that pose free, voluntary, positive, and proximate threats to those who pose neither direct nor indirect threats are impermissible violations of the right to life. Reprisals are condemned according to this principle on the grounds that they are unwarranted threats to individuals who are not direct or indirect threats to those making the reprisals. It cannot be assumed, as Walzer does, that wounded combatants have reacquired a valid claim to the right to life on account of their injuries, for they can still conceivably pose a direct or indirect threat if they remain under military command. And those who are directly engaged in the production of weapons or munitions that can only be rationally deployed in a threatening manner may be indirectly and unintentionally killed by attempts to destroy the means· by which these are produced. This is the case on account of the fact that the labor of these individuals poses a free, intentional, and proximate, but indirect threat. And because this threat is only indirect, 314 BOOK REVIEWS these noncombatants may not be directly killed, but only indirectly threatened by attacks on the facilities that produce their weapons. Siege warfare is a particularly difficult form of violence to evaluate because it poses an indirect, but positive, proximate, intentional, and voluntary threat to noncombatants who themselves are neither directly or indirectly threatening. This strategy has the purpose of forcing the surrender of the besieged army by starving it, but it also entails the same threat to noncombatants who are not in any way threatening, and is therefore impermissible. The only type of siege that is permissible is that which allows noncombatants to be released and interred in the prison camps of the besieging army, for this does not violate their right to life, even though it does expedite military victory. This limitation is permissible because it is never permissible to obtain military advantages by directly threatening those who have a valid claim to the right to life. Military expediency alone is not sufficient to warrant the violation of the right to life of those who have not invalidated their claim to the right to life. Walzer's study of the moral character of nuclear deterrence and weapons is faulted by his failure to understand the inherently immoral character of strategic nuclear weapons. This is seen in his analysis of Truman's use of the atomic bomb. Truman justified his use of the bomb against Japan on the grounds that the force it demonstrated saved many Japanese and American lives by making further resistance out of the question. But if he had wanted to demonstrate American power, he could easily called a halt to military operations, and summoned Japanese observers to witness the dropping of the bomb in the uninhabited regions of the Pacific ocean. This would have demonstrated the fearsome power of one plane and one bomb without violating the right to life of thousands of non-threatening noncombatants. In spite of his contentions, the traditional categories of moral discourse apply to nuclear weapons, and they unconditionally condemn their strategic deployment (p. . These weapons are absolutely prohibited on account of the fact that they cannot possibly be deployed in a discriminating manner. Nuclear deterrence is immoral, not because it holds noncombatants hostage, but because it uses weapons that cannot be deployed in a discriminating manner. It is impossible to use these weapons without indirectly and unintentionally posing a threat to those who have a valid claim to the right to life. For not only do the blast and fallout from these weapons threaten presently existing claimants to the right to life, but the effects of radiation threaten those born after the conflict. Nuclear deterrence is an inherently immoral form of deterrence, for it repels threats by means of reprisals rather than by prohibiting military forces from reaching their designated targets. And the reprisals threatened by the use of nuclear weapons are identical in morally relevant terms to any other form of reprisal or retaliation. 315 BOOK REVIEWS The study of the moral dimensions of military command by Walzer is quite valuable, and his point that the moral responsibility of commanders is directly proportionate to their freedom is correct. This principle is an application of the moral rule which holds that the non-possible is the nonobligatory. Walzer notes that commanders must exercise their authority with moral responsibility, but he fails to note that it is exercised on behalf of those who have a valid claim to the right to life. Commanders must assume that orders will be misunderstood, poorly executed, and sometimes disobeyed, and this prohibits them from issuing vague or imprecise orders that do not positively prohibit violations of the right to life of valid claimants. Deaths of these individuals that result from imprecise, vague, and ill-defined orders must be considered as negligent homicide. Much of Just and Unjust Wars is devoted to studying the notion that some actions that violate valid claims to the right to life are permissible when they are required by military necessity. Walzer rightly contends that most often the principle of military necessity is invoked for the purpose of reducing risks to military personnel or to expedite swift victory. While combatants and noncombatants may use any means available against those who pose unwarranted threats, these means must not threaten those who pose no threat. In conditions of extreme emergency, those who do not pose threats may not be attacked directly or indirectly, intentionally or unintentionally, for they still retain a valid claim to the right to life. Military necessity cannot warrant direct attacks on those who pose no threat, and if these noncombatants are caught in combat zones, discriminating weapons, strategies, and tactics must be used to protect their valid claim to the right to life. For it is never permissible to pose proximate threats to those with a valid claim to the right to life if discriminating but costlier tactics, strategies, and weapons may be deployed. Walzer's work is flawed by an inadequate theory of the structure of the international community and by the absence of explicit elaborations of the moral rules and principles that govern the evaluation of organized political violence. This is not entirely his fault in that the explicit purpose of his work is that of analyzing contemporary positivist theories of international law. The defective character of these theories is seen most clearly in situations of military necessity and extremity where its rules and principles collapse into act-utilitarianism. W alzer's work remains, however, the most complete and comprehensive study of the morality of war to appear in this decade. ROBERT BARRY, Dominican House of Studies Washington, D.C. 0. P. 316 BOOK REVIEWS Thinking About Religion: A Philosophical Introduction to Religion. By R1cHARD PURTILL. Englewood Cliffs, N. Y.: Prentice-Hall, 1978. Pp. 175. Richard Purtill's Thinking About Religion leaves the reader without the slightest doubt concerning its thrust. He attempts to defend, with the strongest arguments and best methods of justification, the crucial beliefs of Christian religion. Reacting to a current climate of everyday religious opinion which he perceives as" ... a generally more emotional and less intellectual approach to religion in recent generations .. ," (p. xi) , his book is a challenge not only to skeptics but to believers who would hold that religious beliefs are not subject to rational scrutiny and who are wary of entertaining arguments offered by the agnostic or atheist. The book is especially directed towards students whose perplexity leads to the position that religious belief is, finally, an irrational " leap of faith." Purtill indicates that these students "need to understand why anyone holds any religious belief and to consider whether there are grounds for holding one set of religious beliefs rather than another" (p. xii). Therefore, I believe the central question which implicitly unifies his entire book is the following: "Is it 1·easonableto believe in God and an afterlife?", where "reasonable" suggests an appeal to proof, justification, reasoning, and evidence. His answer is an unqualified "yes." But the reader should not conclude that Purtill's text is merely an exercise in proselytizing. The structure of discussion in each chapter is always dialectical. Positions are met with objections; objections are met with counter-objections. Purtill attempts to be as fair as possible to each aspect of a dispute. Although Purtill indicates that his book covers " a somewhat different range of material than the usual introductory book " (p. xi) in either "Philosophy of Religion" or "Introduction to Religion," the range of topics is, for the most part, still rather standard. After an introductory chapter which describes " Religion Today " and " Why don't we believe anymore ... ?," there are chapters on the problem of evil, arguments for the existence of God, miracles, the historical nature of the Bible, and life after death. Those topics discussed which Purtill conceives of as " different " from the normal range of material are, I suppose, those considered in chapters on eastern religion and " mysticism and drugs," chapters which, '.I might add, are the weakest parts of the book. There is little discussion of such standard topics as the nature of religious langauge and the relationship between faith and reason. As with Purtill's former book, Thinking About Ethics, each chapter begins with a story or parable " designed to arouse student interest and to raise questions which lead into the discussion of the topic of the chapter " BOOK REVIEWS 817 (p. xii) . I found these introductory parables for the most part satisfactory, and I do think that they might provide a helpful teaching instrument; but at least two of these stories reflected a lack of balance which would conflict with the pedagogical intentions of the author. The story introducing the chapter entitled " Knowledge of God: ls God Really Dead? " presents the " Death of God " theologian as a modish immature young man who could not stand up to a devastating attack authored by a more experienced critic, leaving the student with little doubt about who " won " the intellectual skirmish, while the story introducing the chapter on eastern religion is almost a parody of helpless young souls who mindlessly embrace a foreign tradition. While I cannot discuss the entire range of topics treated by Purtill, I will consider the two topics examined at greatest length by Purtill (he spends two chapters apiece on each) : the existence of God and life after death. He indicates that " Historically this describes the central core of belief in the two major Western religions, Judaism and Christianity, and in the Near Eastern religion which most resembles them, Islam" {p. 12-18). Additionally, I found Purtill's discussion of each topic to be the most interesting parts of his book. The introductory chapter provides a solid foundation for the later discussions. In a clear and nontechnical style (which is characteristic of the entire book) , Purtill wonders "Why Don't We Believe Anymore ... ? " and offers three typical reasons often cited: the failure of the arguments for God's existence, the problem of evil, and the incompatibility of the scientific perspective and the religious W eltanschauung. It is the supposed incompatibility of science and religion which dominates the discussion in Chapter l, and it is Purtill's response to this problematic which provides not only the core of that argument for God's existence which Purtill defends but also an underlying motif throughout the book. Purtill suggests that many people are hesitant to embrace religious beliefs because " ... questions about the existence of God or about life after death cannot be settled by methods like those of science ... " (p. 4). But, he responds, there is no reason to think that only scientific methods can settle any question, and an appeal to scientific method to support such a claim obviously would be questionbegging (p. 4). In fact, Purtill argues, it is the success of science and the universe itself which is properly explained by God's existence. The existence of science as embodying successful techniques for dealing with the universe and apparently successful techniques for understanding the universe can be taken as a piece of data: a fact which itself needs to be explained. The religious believer has an explanation for the success of science; in his view the universe orderly and understandable because it has been made by an intelligent Being and made in such a way that we can understand it and learn from it about its maker. (p. 7) 318 BOOK REVIEWS Not only are science and religion compatible, but the metaphysical hypothesis of God's existence is, according to Purtill, the only satisfactory ultimate explanation for the success of science. Purtill comes back again and again to this same theme. In chapter 4, he presents a combination of the traditional " cosmological " and " teleological " arguments as the " strongest possible argument " (p. 57) for God's existence. Arguing that there must be a necessary being which "always exists whether [or not] anything else exists" (p. 54), he says that the necessary being could not simply be the material universe itself. In so far as the material universe is not just a random collection of things, only the supposition that an intelligent Being brought it about explains the order of the universe. I'lence, Purtill argues that " ... the view that the universe was created by God seems to be the only view that accounts for all the facts, that gives reason a place, that leads us to expect continued regularity and understandability in the universe " (p. 57) . Unless we admit the existence of God, we fall into hopeless skepticism: "Arguments of this kind try to show that unless God exists the universe is not finally understandable" (p. 57). Or, we are" trying to convince the critic that he must choose a view which admits ultimate explanations, or else give way to skepticism " (p. 59). Finally, even in his discussion of miracles, he comes back to the same point: " If we really accept the idea that our minds were the accidental result of the workings of mindless forces, we should be haunted by doubts as to whether our apparent understanding of the universe is illusory " (p. 69). Positively, his defense of a "cosmological-teleological" argument is a forceful and compelling discussion in which the student will clearly see that the order and intelligibility of the universe provides at least some rational support to the metaphysical necessity of positing the existence of God. Negatively, although certain objections are offered, Purtill does not discuss some of the more obvious replies to his argument, e.g., Hume's criticism of the teleological argument. Purtill's discussion of "Life after Death" (Chapters 9 and 10) is a curious blend of philosophical argumentation and unabashed speculation. First, he attempts to show that the notion of disembodied survival is intelligible by responding to some current objections to this notion. For example, critics claim " ... that there is no criterion or standard of personal identity which does not depend on bodily continuity" (p. 129), and mental criteria are also inadequate. Therefore, since the believer cannot properly explain what constitutes the uniqueness of the individual soul, the notion of disembodied survival is unintelligible. Purtill responds by defending two criteria for personal identity: the "personality pattern" criterion and the "body animation capacity" criterion (p. 129-80). He sums up his argument by saying the following: Though these two criteria are not the ones we use now, it is plainly reasonable to identify as me a future disembodied person with memories identical, with mine, BOOK REVIEWS 319 with my unique personality pattern, and with the capacity to re-animate a body recognizably mine, which began to be conscious at the very instant of my death. While it might be logically possible that this individual is not me,_ it would be irrational to hold that it is not me. (p. 132) Purtill ends his discussion of " Life after Death " with a chapter which attempts to " make real " for the believer what life after death would be like. He thinks that a major barrier preventing some people from believing in life after death is their inability imaginatively or reflectively to conceive of this as a real possibility. He speculates that" ... our perception of time and the operation of our memory in life after death might be different from anything we can experience now ... " (p. 138), because our relation to time would be fundamentally changed, seeing or experiencing our past "by somehow participating in God's ' eternal now ' where past events are still present" (p. 141). As I have already noted, I found two chapters the weakest parts of the book: that on mysticism and drugs and that on eastern religion. First, in the chapter on " Mysticism and Drugs," Purtill argues that " ... the kind of experiences which could in principle be induced by drugs would differ in important ways from what are understood to be mystical experiences within the religious tradition" (p. HW). Certainly a discussion of mystical experience is appropriate in a book like Purtill's, but one wonders whether relating this to " drug experiences " warrants an entire chapter and whether this is a capitulation to a false canon of relevancy. Second, the chapter on" Eastern Religion " is extremely weak. While attempting to compare and contrast western religious beliefs with " eastern " beliefs, the generalizations are so large concerning " Eastern Religion " that Purtill ends by saying things that either require qualification or are plainly inaccurate. I will give two examples. 'Vhile criticizing eastern notions (God, soul, Karma, reincarnation, which are never adequately explained), he says" ... we run up against the Hindu and Buddhistic idea of the identity of atman and Brahman " (p. 104, emphasis mine). Of course, one of the most important ideas concerning even an elementary understanding of Buddhism is the Buddha's initial rejection of pre-Buddhistic (especially Hindu) notions of soul and God and his outright rejection of the Hindu notion of atman with his doctrine of anatta or no-self. In addition, Purtill indicates that" ... defenders of Eastern religion have shown little tendency to give rational arguments of any kind in support of their beliefs " (p. 107) . I think this is plainly false, and ·indicates that little, if any, attention has been given by the author to the vast tradition of eastern philosophy and religion. There are many other examples of misleading or inaccurate statements in this chapter, especially when his statements do not accord Buddhism its unique stance. Overall, Purtill has written a clear, interesting, and challenging book in the philosophy of religion. I predict a substantial classroom success for the 820 BOOK REVIEWS text, although I would hope that he will correct the numerous inaccuracies in the chapter on " Eastern Religion." RANDOLPH M. FEEZELL Creighton Omaha, N The Ideas of Newman: Christianity and Human Religiosity. By LEE H. YEARLEY. Pennsylvania State University Press, 1978. Pp. xii + 188. $rn.5o. Interpreting Newman is no easy task. He is such an original and personal thinker that commentators all too frequently find themselves with inadequate categories for analysis. His fate at the hands of the late 19th- and early 20th-century scholastic writers is well documented. The sectarian nature of his conversion from Anglo- to Roman Catholicism often puts many critics in clearly opposing camps. Finally, the very power of his rhetoric and the clarity and candor of his spirit beg some kind of engagement that often enough clouds scholarly objectivity. By setting his study of Newman in the larger context of comparative religious studies, and by applying the methodologies of that discipline, Lee Y earley provides a fresh and provocative reading of one of the most important thinkers in the history of Christianity. At first blush, the title, " The Ideas of Newman," might seem either naive or presumptuous. Quite the contrary. The author's purpose and focus are sharply set. He addresses himself to an understanding of Newman's life-long foe: religious liberalism. By moving away from traditional theological methods and applying those drawn from the comparative study of religion, Yearley is able to sort out Newman's key ideas, to eliminate or explain apparent contradictions in his thought, and to pull together under the name" Liberal Religion " many of his disparate statements on liberalism. Most importantly, this study highlights Newman's stunning relevance to the religious predicament of our own time. This is one of the most valuable studies of Newman to appear during the past twenty years. In Chapter 1, "Natural Religion," Yearley examines what he calls "human religiosity," the basic human potential for religion. Key to all of Newman's thought is his belief that human nature is naturally religious. This approach clarifies what might seem a contradiction in Newman's use of the term " natural." Sometimes he opposes " natural " to supernatural. At other times " natural " refers to that which is characteristic of human nature. Thus when he writes of Natural Religion in the Grammar of Assent he speaks of our natural capacity for fulfillment through a religious experience of God. At other times he insists that this natural capacity BOOK REVIEWS is merely nature, i. e., impotent without supernatural grace. The characteristics of this religious type (Natural Religion) are: providence, prayer, revelation, sacrifice, and the mediatorial power of a holy person. In showing how Newman formulates these characteristics Yearley suggests how closely he anticipates the thought of writers like Eliade and Van der Leeuw. The chapter is an admirable summary of all Newman says on religion in general and contains a superb study of his tenet that conscience is central to the religious experience. Chapters and 3 examine Christianity according to two further types of religious ideas one finds in Newman: the fulfillment model and the authority model. These are both types of revealed religion as opposed to natural religion {needing the supernatural) . The fulfillment model is more irenic and stresses the continuity of religious growth. The authority model is more divisive and stresses or at least implies the discontinuity inasmuch as revelation "intrudes" into the human process. Here Newman develops his idea of the economic communication of revelation and the process of "assimilation" which is one of the characteristics of true doctrinal development. Yearley finds one major difficulty in Newman's use of the fulfillment model: his unawareness, not to say ignorance, of other world religions than Judaism and the classical Graeco-Roman religions. He thus feels that, if Newman had made a distinction between phenomenological and historical preparation for the fulfillment of human religious potential by Christianity, he would have been on safer and more consistent ground in facing the problems posed by the claims to truth by other religions and by the difficulty of tracing the historical connections in the gradual " economic " unfolding of revelation to mankind through the ages. In using this fulfillment model Newman thus stresses Christianity's completion and perfection of human religiosity (natural religion) but would have been unable to face, methodologically, the claims of other religions to do the same. The second religious model Y earley finds in Newman is the authority model. In this model human religiosity is completed not only by the revelation of a revealing deity but by the eventual investing of that revelation in one absolute religious authority. It is in Newman's espousal of this type that Y earley finds the greatest conflict and contrariness in his thought. First of all, it is hard to reconcile this with the fulfillment model. Secondly, even Newman in his insistence on submission to absolute religious authority was increasingly riled by the actual situation within the Roman Catholic community. To remedy this Newman began, largely in correspondence and unpublished writings, to make a distinction between an ideal church authority and the reality of 19th-century Roman Catholicism. Yearley admits, however, that Newman's genius consisted in survival during a period of profound cultural transition between the old and the new and that his temperamental affinity was to a religion that allowed a dynamic tension of opposites rather than one that moved toward total resolution. Thus, BOOK REVIEWS along with liis stress on conscience, Newman always felt quite comfortable with the ultimate mysteriousness on which true religion focused. In the next chapter, on" Liberal Religion," Yearley pulls together Newman's many diverse statements made over a period of forty to fifty years. In doing this he constructs a composite picture which he sets up as still one more religious "type," Liberal Religion, which has six "principles: (1) human nature is good; private judgment is obligatory; (3) deity is a principle discoverable through examination of evidence; (4) revelation is a manifestation not a mystery; (5) useful goods are primary; and (6) education is salvatory." He then applies Newman's views, positively outlined in the first three chapters, to this religious type and shows quite convincingly how even when rejecting aspects of liberalism Newman was sensitive to its sincere efforts to make religion acceptable to the modern age and did himself lean toward certain valid "half truths" it contained. The conflicts pointed out between the fulfillment and authority models again surface when dealing with these six principles of Liberal Religion. A final chapter evaluates two aspects of Newman's analysis: "the relation of Christianity to other religions and the view that Liberal religion deforms humanity's religious potential." In dealing with these points Yearley uses further religious models: "(1) one religion is true and all others are a single essence underlies all religions; (3) one religion is the fulfillfalse; ment of all others; and (4) a plurality of true religions exists and a person just affirms one." Yearley suggests that these theoretical models be looked at in this way: the first two models ate poles of a problem that the second two models try to solve. In the final analysis Yearley sees Newman reflecting the fulfillment model and moving toward the plurality model. This conclusion is persuasive when one considers the great stress Newman put on the centrality of conscience and the validity of internal perception. While Yearley cannot accept totally Newman's attempt" to affirm both the sacral quest and the sacral foundation," he does agree with his assessment of liberal religion's inability to fulfill human potential and states that he pevhaps more than any other religious thinker has moved toward a validation of the sacral quest and sacral foundation type of religion for moderns. Lastly, the book provides a healthy antidote for Harold L. Weatherby's Cardinal Newman in His Age (1973), which wrongly argues that Newman relinquished traditional Christian theology for modernist ways. And it deals in a more structural way with matter covered by Stephen Prickett in his recent admirable study, Romanticism and Religion (1976). No student of Newman can afford to miss this excellent analysis of the key ideas that underlie all of his writings. PHILIP The University of Detroit ·Detroit, Michigan c. RULE, s. BOOKS RECEIVED Beauchesne: Theologie de l'agonie du Christ by F-M Uthel. Pp. rn4; 24.Fr. Blackwell: Cognitive Systematization and Leibniz: An Introduction by Nicholas Rescher. Pp. 2H!; £ 4.95. Cornell University Press: Paradox and Identity in Theology by R. T. Herbert. Pp. 197; $H!.50. Editorial San Esteban: La essencia de la caridad and Los dones del Espiritu Santo by Santiago M. Ramirez, 0.P. Pp. 384, 318; no price given. Eerdmans: The Holy Spirit by C. F. D. Moule. Pp. mo; $3.95. Fortress Press: Studies in Lutheran Hermenetltics edited by J. Reumann. Pp. 370; $14.95. Franciscan Herald Press: Bonaventure and the Coincidence of Opposites by Ewert H. Cousins. Pp. 316; $rn.95. Gill and Macmillan: Doing the Truth: the Quest for Moral Theology by Enda McDonagh. Pp. 217; £ 7.50. Humanities Press: Radical Phenomenology: Essays in Memory of Martin Heidegger edited by John Sallis. Pp. 318; $15.00. Kaiser: Gotteserfahrungen: Hoffnung, Angst, Mystik by Jurgen Moltmann. Pp. 71; DM 8.80. l,oyola University Press: Doing Evil to Achieve Good: Moral Choice in Confiict Situations edited by Richard McCormick and Paul Ramsey. Pp. 267; $11.95. Martinus Nijhoff: The Changing Profile of Naf1tral Law by Michael B. Crowe. Pp. 321; DM. 29.80. Pustet: Gott der Eine und Dreieine by Joseph Ratzinger and Johann Auer. Pp. 600; DM. 29.80. Routledge and Kegan Paul: Meaning and the Moral Sciences by Hilary Putnam. Pp. 145; £ 4.95. Tyrolia: Verantwortung und Gehorsam: A.spekte der heutigen Autoritas und Gehorsamsproblematik by R. Toon. Pp. 155; DM 28. University of Nebraska Press: Heidegger and the Language of Poetry by David A. White. Pp. 246; $18.00. Uppsala University Press: Christus Redemptor et Consummator: A Study in the Theology of B. F. Westcott by Victor Waranch. Pp. 340; Sw.Kr. 107.50. 323