ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIBVAL CULTURE 'TI HIS YEAR marks the seven hundredth anniversary f the death of St. Albert the Great. He died on Novemer 15, IQ80, at the age of "eighty and more." His life thus spans the first eighty years of the thirteenth century, aperiod of great vitality, development, and achievement. Throughout the world this year, and particularly in Germany, there are numerous celebrations going on to commemorate the life and works of this remarkable German Dominican, who was known as "the Great" even in his own lifetime. When we think of Alexander the Great, St. Gregory the Great, Charles the Great (Charlemagne), or even Catherine the Great of Russia, we all think immediately of the person in question and we have some idea, however vague, of why they are called "the Great ". Unfortunately this is not the case with St. Albert the Gre,at. Outside of Germany, he is known only as the teacher of St. Thomas Aquinas, if at all. In Germany legends of Albert abound, usually those that lack all substance or verisimilitude. The German philosopher Hegel could speak in his history of philosophy of Albertus Magnus as " the most celebrated German schoolman, of the noble race of Bollstadt." 1 And he could recount the legend of Albert's learning as a special gift of the Blessed Virgin Mary to a very dull and stupid youth who changed quickly from an ass into a philosopher. The Virgin ]\fary is supposed to have promised him that he would enlighten the Church, and, in spite of his science, would still die in the faith. Hegel commented that " five years before his death Albert forgot his philosophy as quickly as he learned it, and then actually died in the dulness (sic) and orthodoxy of his earlier years." 2 Hegel the philosopher could also say that Albert's 1 Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philo1;ophy, trans. by E. S. Haldane and F. H. Simson (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1955), 3: 75. 2 Ibid. p. 76. 481 482 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. learning was generally understood to consist largely of magic. For," he says, " although natural objects have nothing to do with scholasticism proper, which was really perfectly blind to nature, he occupied himself much therewith; and amongst other devices he manufactured a talking machine which alarmed his pupil Thomas of Aquino, who even aimed a blow at it, thinking he saw therein a work of the devil." 3 Without understanding either Albert or the culture of his time, Hegel could select outlandish interpretations and anecdotes concerning Albert to give us, as he says, a picture of the conditions of culture in these times. Hegel was not a medievalist and he could not be expected to be sympathetic to medieval Christian culture, and his selection of quaint examples can hardly be called an accurate picture of the condition of culture in the Middle Ages . .The " eighty and more" years of St. Albert's life are intertwined with three major movements that characterize the High Middle Ages: (1) urbanization of European society, especially in Germany and Eastern Europe; (2) reevangelization of Christian Europe, mainly through the mendicant orders founded by St. Dominic de Guzman in 1215 and St. Francis of Assisi in 1223; and (3) intensive growth and formulation of" scholastic" philosophy and theology in the university centers of Christendom, especially at the University of Paris and its spin-offs, such as Oxford, Cologne, Cambridge, Toulouse, and Montpellier. Although the urbanization of France, Italy, and parts of England had begun vigorously early in the twelfth century, Germany, apart from the Rhine Valley, was a backward country in 1200 even by medieval standards. "The thirteenth century," as John B. Freed has amply shown," was the high point in the urbanization of medieval Germany," 4 and the history of Germany in that century is in large part the history of the Dominican and Franciscan Orders beyond the Rhine, the Elbe, the Oder, and even the Vistula. The same can be said of Bohemia, Poland, and Hungary. •Ibid. •John B. Freed, The Friars and German Society in the Thirteenth Century (Cambridge, Mass.: Mediaeval Academy of America, 1977), p. ii4. ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 483 When Albert joined the Dominican Order as a young man of there was no German Dominican twenty-four at Padua in Province, and only two small priories had been established in the territory. But when he died in 1280, there were sixty-two flourishing priories in the Dominican Province of T eutonia, which stretched from Vienna, Austria, to Bern, Switzerland, in the south, and from Stralsund on the Baltic to Utrecht, Holland, in the north. The German Dominicans even established a missionary house in Riga, Latvia, in 1234, which was incorporated into the Province of Teutonia in 1244, well before Albert himself became Prior Provincial of this vast territory. Finally, Friar Albert was the first German Dominican to become a master in theology (1245) from the University of Paris; and he himself established the first center of higher studies (a studium generate) in Germany at Cologne in 1248. This studium generale was the predecessor of the University of Cologne, which was not organized until 1388.5 By this late date the Franciscans, Carmelites, and Augustinians also had general studia in Cologne. Although Albert was already a mature lector of theology in his home province of Germany and weH-trained in the" scholastic method " before he went to Paris and encountered the seductive " new learning " that inundated Paris from Greek and Arabic sources translated in the south, he eventually "rewrote" the whole of Aristotelian philosophy in the Latin language, restating, expounding, correcting, expanding, and even adding whole new areas of scientific thought, as we shall see. His younger contemporary Roger Bacon enviously complained in 1267 /68 that philosophy was now considered by the bulk of students (a vulgo studentium) and some men of repute (sapientes) "to be already transmitted to the Latins, and completed, and composed in the Latin language " (quod phi"losophia iam data sit Latinis, et completa,. et composita in lingua Latina). Bacon goes on to complain that all of this was done during his own days (in tempore meo) at Paris, roughly between 1237 and • Willehad Eckert, Kleine Geschichte. der Universitiit Koln (Cologne: Universitiit .zu. Koln, 1961).. 484 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. 1257, and that the author of this philosophy is considered an authority (an auctoritas) in the schools on the same level as Aristotle, Avicenna, and Averroes, even though this author is still alive-an unheard of precedent. 6 Albert's reputation as "the Great", even while he was still living, 7 became not only legendary, but was grossly exaggerated, so much so that in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries it was utterly fantastic. The task of the modern historian is to separate and eliminate the myth from the real man of learning, who sought only the discovery of truth in nature and the vision of the Triune Creator in the whole range of Christian culture. This is no easy task, even in our own age of sophisticated historical methods and techniques. Despite the admirable scholarship of recent French and German historians concentrating on Albert's life and works, there remain many uncertainties and contradictions. Certainly there is nothing written in English that can serve as a reliable guide. Albert's Youth and Entry into the Dominican Order Albert, a Swabian by birth, was commonly known to his European contemporaries as Friar Albert the German (Frater Albertus Tentonicus) or Albert of Cologne (Frater Albertus de Colonia). But to his countrymen and confreres in the German Province, he was more properly and accurately known as Friar Albert of Lauingen, as is indicated on the signet ring ( sigillum) he received on becoming a master in theology at the University of Paris in 1245. Lauingen is a sma11 town in Schwabia situated on the Danube between Ulm a few miles above and Dillingen a few miles below, in the diocese of Augsburg. At that time Schwabia, the home of the Hohenstauffen dynasty, was part of Bavaria, and Austria was " lower Bavaria." It is certain that Albert came from a military family (ex militaribus) of lesser nobility (knights) in the service of the counts 6 Rogeri Bacon, Opus tertium, c.9, ed J. S. Brewer, Opera quaedam hactenus inedita (London: RS 15, 1859), p. 30. • Annales Basileenses, anno 1277, "Albertus Magnus, lector Coloniae," Monumenta Germaniae llistorica, Scriptores, 17: 202, 10-11 ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 485 of Bollstadt, whose castle, now in ruins, was less than 19 miles from Lauingen. But it would seem that the whole of Albert's family, including his younger brother Friar Henry of Lauingen, was in no way related to those who eventually took Bollestat or some variant as a family name. Albert's knightly family, like all German soldiers, had long been in the service of Frederick Barbarosa of Schwabia, who had been king of Germany since 1152 and Holy Roman Emperor from 1155 until his death in 1190. It is uncertain how many brothers and sisters Albert had; but it seems likely, considering the opposition to his becoming a Dominican, that a military career had been expected of him. Notwithstanding the contradictory dates always given for Albert's birth, all that can really be said is that he was born around moo or a year before. Certainly the date 1206/07 insisted on by Mandonnet, Glorieux, Van Steenberghen, and all modern historians is too late. Mandonnet's disputable evidence is based on the statement of Henry of Herford's Chronica (ca. 1355) that Albert was "a boy of sixteen years" 8 when he entered the Order in 1223. This age of sixteen is below the eighteen year minimum insisted upon since the time of St. Dominic himself and contrary to the invariable practice of the Dominican Order at that time. Sixteen was the minimum age for the Premonstratensians, which Dominic deliberately altered in the original rule. At the same time, the date 1193 given by Irranz Pelster, H. C. Scheeben, and most older authors is much too early; it is based on the statement of Luis of Valladolid (Paris, 1414) that Albert died in 1280 "having completed about (Girciter) 87 years of his life." 9 Surprisingly, one of the first authors to give both dates without apparently seeing their impossibility was Peter of Prussia, Albert's first really critical 8 Henrici de Herford, Chronica seu Liber de i·ebus memorabilibus, ed. A. Potthash (Gottingen, 1859), p. 201. See Mandonnet, "La date de naissance d'Albert le Grand," Revue Thomiste 36 (1931), 233-56. •Luis of Valladolid, Brevis historia de vita et doctrina Alberti Magni, c. 1, ed. in CataloJUB Codicum llagiographicorum Bibl. Regiae Bruxellensis (Bruxellis, 1889), £: 96; for the history of this work and a better text of the catalogue of writings, see H. C. Seheeben, "Die Tabulae Ludwigs von Valladolid im Chor der Praedigerbriider von St. Jakob in Paris," Archivum FFr. Praed. 1 (1930), 223-63. 486 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, 0 .P. biographer, writing in 1486-87 with a view to Albert's canonization.10 Peter rightly eliminated many of the myths accumulated by his predecessors, especially by Thomas of Cantimpre and Luis of Valladolid, preserved in the Legenda Coloniensis. But somehow he failed to see that Albert could not have been " a boy of sixteen years " in rn2s and a man "having completed about 87 years of his life " in rn8o, as maintained by Luis of Valladolid and his successors. The only contemporary evidence of Albert's age when he died on 15 November rn80 is that of Tolomeo of Lucca, who says Albert was "more than eighty" in one passage and "eighty and more" in another. 11 Tolomeo was a retired bishop and an octogenarian himself when he inserted the brief lives of Albert and Thomas into his monumental Historia ecdesiastica sometime after he had completed it in September 1817. His contemporary Bernard Gui merely copied Tolomeo's phrase in his chronicle: "Hie obiit in conventu Coloniensi anno Domini MCCLXXX, octogenarius et amplius." 12 Whatever may be said about the meaning of et amplius is sheer guesswork. The only reasonable birthdate consistent with the rest of Albert's chronology is moo or one year before. Albert showed early in life his interest in nature. As a boy he was taught to train falcons and ha.wks in his home town of Lauingen. In later writings he showed considerable knowledge of many species of falcons and hawks, their instincts, and their training. As a young man, Albert was sent to Padua under the care of his uncle to study the liberal arts at the incipient university. Many years later, he himself described "Pata via, which is now called Padua, in which a studium litterarum flourished for many years," 13 and he recalled two memorable natural 10 Petrus de Prussia, Legenda Alberti Magni (Coloniae: Johannes Guldenschaifl', after 11 Jan. 1483, ca. 1487). 11 Ptolomaei Lucensis, HisttYlia Ecclesiastica, xxii, c. 19, and xxiii, c. 36, ed in L. A. Mura tori, Rerum ltalicarum Scriptores (Milan, 1724), 11: 1151 and 1184. 12 Bernard Gui, additions to Stephen of Salanhac's De Quatuor in Quibus Deus Praedicatorum Ordinem lnsignivit, ed. T. Kaeppeli, MOPH (Rome: S. Sabina, 1949), p. rn5. 13 Alberti Magni, De natura locorum, tr. 3, c. (ed. Borgnet 9: 570b-71a). I ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 487 phenomena he had witnessed when he was a youth in Padua and in Venice.14 Albert's interests at that time were certainly in natural phenomena, and it is likely that he was exposed to some of Aristotle's philosophy, translated by James of Venice ca. 1150-70, still forbidden at Paris. But it is unlikely that he absorbed much of Aristotle at that date. That was to come later. Early in the summer of H!23, Jordan of Saxony, the immediate successor to St. Dominic (d.rn21) as master general of the Order of Preachers, came to Padua in the hope of bringing young students and masters into the order by his preaching. There seems to have been a house of Dominicans already in the city, and Jordan was on his way to Bologna for the annual General Chapter of the order opening on Pentecost. At first he found " the students of Padua extremely cold, " but ten of them soon sought admission, " among them two sons of two great German lords; one was a provost-marshal, loaded with many honors and possessed of great riches; the other has resigned rich benefices: and is truly noble in mind and body.'' 15 The latter of these two has always been identified as Albert of Lauingen; the other may very well have been John of Wildeshausen, later General of the Order. In the Vitae fratrum, compiled by Gerard of Frachet between H!54 and rn58 from stories sent to him by brethren throughout the order, the story of Albert's "conversion" to the order by Jordan while he was a student at Padua is narrated at some length, supposedly in Albert's own words. In it Albert tells of his uncertainty about entering and his great fear of not persevering in the order once having entered. Jordan is supposed to have assured him of persevering once he had made up his mind. 16 It is a simple story, but Mandonnet completely misunderstood the story of "Alberti Magni, Metheor. III, tr. 2, c.12 (ed. Borgn.et 4: 629a); De mineral. II, tr. 3, c. 1 (ed. Borgnet 5: 4Sb-49a). 15 Beati Jordani de Saxonia Epistulae, Ep. 20, ed. A. Walz, MOPH 23 (Rome: S. Sabina, 1951), p. 24. 16 Vitae Fratrum Ord. Praed. P. IV, c. 13, § 9, ed. B. Reichert, MOPH 1 (Louvain, 1896), p. 188. 488 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. Albert's conversion to bolster his thesis that Albert was sixteen years old when he entered the Dominican Order in H223. In fact, Albert was about twenty-four when he entered, a youth for those early days of a mendicant preaching order. Albert was certainly a "young man" (iuvencmus or adolescens) when he entered the Order, but he was not a "boy" (puer) in the canonical sense, nor even a "youth" (iuvenis) in the strict sense of being under twenty-one. Relatively speaking, Albert at the age of sixty could refer to his "youth" at Padua; and Roger Bacon, who joined the Franciscans when he was around forty, could speak with an air of disdain of Albert and Thomas as pucri when they entered their order. In any case, it is certain that Albert joined the Dominican Order when he was a student at Padua, receiving the habit from Jordan of Saxony around Easter of 1223, despite many personal and domestic difficulties as narrated with embellishments in the l'itae fratrum. Young Friar Albert in Germany (1223-ca. 1242) Albert would have been received into the order for some specific province. But when he joined in 1223 there was no Province of Germany (Teutonia). There were only two priories: Friesach (1219) in Austria, which was in a critical state, and Cologne (ca. 1220) on the lower Rhine, where Friar Henry, Jordan's classmate and companion at Paris, was then prior. It is most probable that Albert was sent to Cologne to make his novitiate and study theology under the local lector. Cologne, then, would henceforth be considered his native priory, even though he could be sent by his superiors anywhere in the known world. At Cologne, in the Dominican Priory of Heilige Kreuz on the Stolkgasse, Albert would not only have completed his oneyear novitiate, but would also have attended all the theological lectures of the official leetor of that priory. No Dominican priory could be established by the General Chapter unless there were twelve friars, a prior, and a lector of theology. The task of the lector, whose importance in the house was second ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 489 only to that of the prior, was to give theological lectures on some book of the Bible to the entire community, including the prior. According to the primitive constitutions of 1228, no one could be appointed lector unless he had studied theology at least four years. By Albert himself had become a lector. According to Henry of Herford, Albert " was first lector in Hildesheim [in Saxony, founded in 1233], then Freiberg [in Saxony, founded in 1236], then Regensburg [in Bavaria] for two years, then Strassburg [in Alsace], then he went to Paris. " 11 Albert certainly was in Saxony when he and many others observed the comet of 1240 passing near, as it were, the north pole of the ecliptic 18 ; and he travelled great distances to examine various metals in mining districts (loca metallica), among which he mentions as particularly important Freiberg and Gosslar in the Harz :!\fountains in Lower Saxony. 111 Albert's description of melting iron suggests that high temperature blast furnaces existed earlier than previously known. 20 He also described surface mining of gold, which he observed in the Elbe and Rhine rivers. 21 In his earliest known treatise, De natura boni, a primarily devotional work written in Germany before he went to Paris, he cites explicitly ten works of Aristotle, including six of the libri naturales in their older versions, still proscribed in Paris. But in Germany he was completely out of touch with the novelties, excitement, vibrant problems, and stimulus of the " new learning" that made Paris the foremost intellectual center of Christendom. The point is that, although Albert knew much Henrici de Herford, Chronica, ed. cit., p. 201. Alberti Magni, Metheor. I, tr. 8, c. 5: "Ego autem cum multis aliis ab incarnatione Domini MCCXL in Saxonia vidi cometem quMi iuxta polum septentrionalem, et proiecit radios suos inter Orientem et Meridiem, magis dirigendo eos ad Orientem; et constat quod ibi non fuit via alicuius planetae" (ed. Borguet 4: 504a). 19 See D. Wyckoff, "Albertus Magnus on Ore Deposits," 49 (1958), 109-122. 20 See N. F. George, "Albertus Magnus and Chemical Technology in a Time of Transition," Albertus Magnus and the Sciences, ed. J.A. Weisheipl (Toronto: PIMS, 1980), pp. 236-240. 21 Alberti Magni, Mineral. ill, tr. 1, c. l and c. 10 (ed. Borgnet 5: and 72a-b). 17 18 490 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. about Aristotle and Aristotelian science before he went to Paris, he still had a great deal to learn about the forefront of Christian thought when he got to Paris. Outstanding in his own province, he was the first German Dominican selected by the fourth master general of the order, John "Teutonicus" of Wildeshausen, when John became general in 1241. The idea of sending Albert to Paris most certainly orginated with John of Wildeshausen, but it would have been with the support of Hugh of Saint-Cher, who himself was Dominican Regent Master in Theology at Paris, Provincial of France, and later cardinal. Although John of Wildeshausen was himself a German, he spent most of his Dominican life outside Germany and was fluent in French, Italian, and Latin, as well as his native German. At that time the master general of the order alone had the authority to send individuals to the only studium generale in the order where Dominicans held two chairs of theology, the University of Paris, one for members of the Province of France, the other for all foreigners. Consequently when Albert was in his early forties, he was sent to the center of Christian culture to absorb the " new learning " and eventually to rewrite it. Albert at Paris (ca. 1242-1248) Albert was sent to Paris to lecture on the Sentences of Peter Lombard and to prepare himself for the mastership in the chair for foreigners as its third Dominican master, succeeding Gueric of Saint-Quentin. The difference between Germany and Paris was like the difference between night and day. While teaching the Sentences for about three years, he was busily absorbing the " new learning '', even after he became a master in 1245. As Regent Master, Albert had clearly defined duties to perform: to lecture as master on some approved text (legere), to preside at public disputations and to resolve questions he himself had posed { disputare), and to preach to the academic community on certain days (praedicare). But Albert's main efforts, it would ·seem, were devoted to writing two massive theological works, ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 491 namely a Swrnma Parisiensis in six parts, of which the wellknown Summa de creaturis constitutes only two parts, and a seven-volume commentary (in the Borgnet edition) on the four Books of Sentences, completed after he returned to Cologne. These were written while he was lecturing on all the books of pseudo-Dionysius, and 3Jbsorbingthe" new learning". It was when Albert was a new master in his mid-forties at Paris that he first met Thomas Aquinas, a young man of twenty, who had just arrived in Paris in the company of John of Wildeshausen to complete his novitiate. Thomas had been received into the Dominican Order at Naples the preceding year and was on his way to Bologna when he was abducted by his soldier brother and companions north of Rome and was taken to the family castle of Montesangiovanni for the night. It was there that the soldiers tried to get a prostitute to seduce Thomas, but without avail. The next day the company of soldiers took Thomas to his mother, the formidable Donna Theodora, waiting at the family estate of Roccasicca in the territory of Emperor Frederick II. The Aquino family was convinced that their security required Thomas to be abbot of Monte Cassino. The real problem was that the future of the family lay with the Emperor Frederick II, who was then at odds with the pope. But when Frederick was excommunicated and deposed by the Council of Lyons in 1245, the Aquino family switched allegiance and temporarily gave up trying to make young Thomas abbot of Monte Cassino. After about a year's confinement at the family estate, Thomas was allowed to return to his Dominican confreres and his earlier plans, which now involved going to Paris for his novitiate and studies. It was at Paris that Thomas first heard Master Albert lecture to the university students. William of Tocco, Thomas's first biographer, reports that Thomas " had no sooner heard [Master Albert] expound every science with such wondrous depth of wisdom, that he rejoiced .exceedingly at having so quickly found that which he had come to. seek, one who offered him so unsparingly the fulfiH- JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. ment of his heart's desire." 22 Tocco goes on to say that in order to profit from this exceptional opportunity, Thomas "began to be more than ever silent, more than ever assiduous in study and devout in prayer." After three years at Paris, Thomas accompanied Albert to Cologne for another four years of study. Albert at Cologne (1248-1254) In the summer of 1248, Albert, accompanied by Friar Thomas d' Aquino and other Dominican friars, travelled on foot to Cologne to establish the first studium generale in Germany. The Dominican Order was anxious to increase its centers of learning. For three years the general legislative body of the order planned to open four more studia outside of Paris, namely at Montpellier, Bologna, Cologne, and Oxford. Since the proposed establishment of the four new houses of study had successfully passed the two preceding chapters, preparations had been underway in all four places for the expected decision of 1248. Around the time of Albert's arrival in Cologne, the cornerstone of the new cathedral was laid, and Albert characteristically took a keen interest in the excavations involved in laying the foundations of the new edi:fice.23 The Dominican priory on the Stolkgasse (where the main postoffice now stands) extended as far as An den Dominikanern. By 1250, the Palatial residence of Duke Walram IV of Limburg adjoining the Dominican property on the Stolkgasse was purchased by the Dominicans for the comparatively low price of 150 marks. The total complex was quite ample for the new studium open to all Dominicans of the world and to the local clergy. At Cologne Albert was free of Parisian regulations and could conduct the studium as he thought best. He not only continued his lectures on pseudo-Dionysius, completing the entire corpus including the Letters, but he had the audacity to lecture on the 22 Gulielmo di Tocco, Hystoria beati Thomae de Aquino, c. 12, Vitae Fontes Praecipuae, ed. A. Ferrua (Alba: Ed. Domenicane, 1968), n. IS, p. 44; see Bernardi Gui, Legenda, c. 9, ibid. n. 80, p. 139. ••Alberti Magni, De prop. element. I, tr. 2, c. 8 (ed. Borgnet 9: 605a-b). ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 493 Ethics of Aristotle with questions on the text. This is a most remarkable series of lectures by a most remarkable man, and Rene Antoine Gauthier rightly waxes eloquent when comparing them to Thomas's own inferior commentary. All that had been known of Aristotle's Ethics previously were Books II-III (Ethica vetus) and Book I with fragments of the others (Ethica nova). But around 1246/47, Robert Grosseteste, bishop of Lincoln (1235-53), translated for the first time all ten books of the Ethics from the Greek. The temptation to lecture on this treasure was too much for Albert, and he did so at Cologne around 1250-52, despite the fact that he was a master theologian charged with directing a theological studium open to all clerics. Although this commentary-with-questions was taken down by Thomas in his own unintelligible hand, Thomas's copy is no longer extant; but nine other manuscripts of this text still exist, and the first part of this work is now published for the first time. 24 Albert's audacity in lecturing on Aristotle's philosophy in a theological studium is another example not only of his independence but also of his conviction that philosophy and science are indispensable for theological studies . It was this same conviction and audacity that prompted Albert to "rewrite" the whole of Peripatetic philosophy. This conviction he would also embody in the first ratio studiorum for the Dominicans in 1259 together with Thomas and three other inasters. 25 It was at this time that Albert must have begun his huge paraphrase of all the Aristotelian and pseudo-Aristotelian books, beginning with the Physics. In the Physics, Albert explains that his Dominican confreres had implored him for a good number of years to compose a work on physical science in such a way that they could attain the whole of natural knowledge and thereby understand the works of Aristotle. 26 This plea of 24 S1iper Ethica: Commentum et quaestiones (ed. Colon. 14/1, 1968). See ibid. Proleg. § 1. 25 26 Chartularium Univ. Paris. ed. H. Denifle (Paris, 1899), 1: 885-86, n. 335. Alberti Magni, Physica I, tr. 1, c. 1 (ed. Borgnet 3: la). 494 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. the brethren was made in Hl48 when he returned to Cologne, if not long before that. Finally, by the end of 1249, he acceded to their wishes, but his plan was far more ambitious than his brethren could have imagined. Not only would he explain the fundamentals of natural science with all the aids at his disposal, but he hoped to explain systematically the whole range of human learning embracing all the natural sciences (inanimate and animate), logic, rhetoric, mathematics, astronomy, ethics, economics, politics, and metaphysics, including the Liber de causis. "Our intention," he said, "is to make all the aforesaid parts of knowledge intelligible to the Latins (Latinis intelligibiles) ." 21 That the plan was deliberate, systematic, and consecutive with the Aristotelian corpus can be seen from the extant autograph copy in Vienna, Oesterreichische Nationalbibliothek, cod. misc. Latin. 273, which contains the last five lines of the Physics on folio 72v and continues from the same folio to De caelo, De natura locorum, and De causis proprietatum elementorum. The chronological order of the rest of the Albertinian corpus of philosophy seems to be the following: De generatione et corruptione, M eteora, De mineralibus et lapidibus, De vegetabilibus, De anima, Parva naturalia (eleven distinct works), De animalibus, Metaphysica, Ethica, Politica, and Liber de causis. Albert completed all of these paraphrases (occupying 20 of the 40 volumes of complete works) certainly by April, 1271, more likely by 1269, when Thomas was just begining his Aristotelian commentaries . Thus it took Albert twenty years of a busy life to rewrite the whole of peripatetic philosophy. No one can say, as some have said, that Albert did not take these works seriously or that they do not express his own mind. In his Aristotelian paraphrases he made frequent digressions, clarified difficulties, supplemented what was lacking, and at times added whole books of new sciences that Aristotle had not discussed. To Aristotle's De mineralibus, Albert added a whole medieval lapidary; to pseudo-Aristotle's De plantis, he 27 Ibid. (ed. Borgnet 3: ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 495 added a verified herbal, and to the large De animalibus, he added a five-book bestiary. The doctrine Albert presented was systematically and deliberately " Peripatetic," that is, Aristotelian, although he never failed to correct Aristotle when he was in error regarding facts of experience or the teaching of faith. To those integralists who insisted on agreeing with Aristotle on the eternity of the world, he said, " Whoever believes that Aristotle was a man, then doubtless he was liable to error, just as we are. " 28 On countless occasions, Albert rejected a supposed observation of the Stagirite, saying that it is contrary to his own observations, as when he said that ostriches do not eat iron, because he tried to feed them iron and they would not eat. In practice as well as in theory, Albert recognized that " the aim of natural science is not simply to accept the statements of others, but to investigate the causes that are at work in nature. " 29 In March, 1252, Albert had his first experience of a role that he would be called upon to play throughout his long career: the role of arbiter and peacemaker. This first experience involved a dispute between Conrad von Hochstaden, archbishop of Cologne, and the burgers of the city. On 25 March, Cardinal Hugh of Saint-Cher, legate of the Holy See, and Friar Albert, lector of the Dominikanerkloster in Cologne, were called upon to arbitrate the litigation; they gave their decision in April, and it was confirmed by Pope Innocent IV in December. The list of Albert's arbitrations is long and varied, lasting up to fifteen months before his death. The last document is dated 18 August 1279. Albert as Provincial of Teutonia (1254-1257) At the Provincial Chapter held at Worms in June, 1254, Friar Albert was elected prior provincial of the Province of Teutonia. By 1254 the Province of T eutonia numbered thirty-six priories for men and more than twenty cloisters of nuns. It was a vast 28 29 Alberti Magni, Physica VIII, tr. 1, c. 14 (ed. Borgnet 8: 558b). Alberti Magni, De mineral. IT, tr. 2, c. 1 (ed. Borgnet 5: SOa). 496 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. area and the priories were increasing. During his three full years as provincial, Albert made formal visitations on foot for all the houses 0£ his Province, including the mission house in Riga. It was on his long journeys by foot that he collected material for his scientific works. He also established three new priories in the north and at least two cloisters of nuns, the more famous being the Paradisus near Soest in Westfalia. As provincial he participated in the General Chapters of Milan, Paris, and Ii'lorence, always walking to them on foot. He strictly forbad the brethren to travel by horseback or carriage, except under the gravest necessity. It was Albert's custom while traveling-always on footfirst to visit the chapel of the religious house where he intended to stay the night, to thank God for the safe journey, then immediately to visit the library to see whether there were any books there that he had not yet seen. Often his candle burned late into the night as he copied long passages of interest to him that could be used later. Hence, Albert frequently cites titles of books and gives direct quotations from works now lost. The most significant event of Albert's provincialate was his summons to the papal curia at Anagni, where he represented the Dominican Order with Humbert of Romans, the master general, in its struggle against the attacks of William of SaintAmour and his colleagues from Paris. St. Bonaventure, minister general of the Franciscans, played a most decisive role in this issue both in his writings and in his public debates, and the bitter controversy was temporarily resolved in favor of the mendicants with the condemnation of William's De periculis novissimorum ternporum on 5 October 1256. Albert himself states that at the papal curia he publicly debated against the Averroist doctrine of one intellect for all men; the material for this debate was later (1263) turned into a little book called De unitate intellectus contra Averroistas. Albert, it would seem, was the first to attack the Averroist doctrine that was later to grip the academic community at Paris. During his years as provincial Albert was working on his paraphrase of Aristotle's De aninw, a paraphrase he himself considered im1 ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 497 portant, and eleven works of the Parva naturalia, including works on nutrition, dreams, aging, and death. After the chapter of }i'lorence in June 1257, Albert was allowed to resign as provincial and return to his home priory of Cologne, where he held disputed questions on Aristotle's De animalibus. He was continually called upon to arbitrate difficult cases and to serve as peacemaker between rival family claims. Bishop of Regensburg and Preacher of the Crusades (1260-64) Then, out of a clear blue sky, in January, 1260, Albert received Pope Alexander IV's letter, appointing him bishop of Regensburg in the ecclesiastical province of Salzburg, which happened to be in a deplorable state financially and spiritually. At the same time, Alexander IV also wrote to the dean and chapter of Regensburg to receive Albert as their bishop and to obey him in all things. Humbert of Romans immediately penned a most fervent plea to Albert, begging him not to accept the dignity, for it would set a lamentable precedent in the Order, and would be a dishonor to his well-known nobility of mind and religious fervor. But apparently Albert had no choice. He was consecrated in the cathedral at Cologne during March and was invested as a secular prince by a delegate of the Holy Roman Emperor. It is said that he entered Regensburg unobtrusively after sunset on March and stayed with the Dominican friars at St. Blasius, where as a younger man he had been lector. On the following morning, Tuesday of Holy Week, he entered the unfinished cathedral for his enthronement and Solemn Mass, during which all the clergy present promised obedience. It is also said that he found the cupboards of the adjoining episcopal castle bare of all food, the wine cellars completely empty, and the diocese bankrupt. Albert, known to the local Bavarians as " Boots the Bishop " because of his walking shoes, devoted a full year to covering the whole of his large diocese on foot, reforming everywhere. Many of his reforms were reenforced by synodal decrees from Salzburg. 498 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. During his episcopate, Albert was undoubtedly writing his commentary on De animalibus. The phrase "in my villa above the Danube " in Book VII can refer only to the episcopal castle of Donaustauff, about three miles from the city, on the Danube. The entire work must have been completed not much after 1261,30 after he left Regensburg. Already by the end of 1260, Albert was ready to seek release from his unwanted burden. By the end of December, Albert, having set the diocese in order, left Regensburg for Viterbo to submit his resignation to Alexander IV. He placed the diocese in charge of Henry as vicar, Leo Torndorf as dean of the chapter, and Ulrich as pastor of the cathedral church. He arrived at the papal curia at Viterbo in July, 1261, only to find that Alexander had died at the end of the preceding May. A new pope was elected in August and consecrated at Viterbo on September 4, taking the name of Urban IV. Albert's resignation was finally accepted around November; elections were ordered at Regensburg, and Leo Torndorf, dean of the chapter, was elected. But it was not until May of 126£ that Leo's election as successor to Albert was confirmed by Urban. All during this time, Urban kept Albert in the illustrious circle gathered around him at Viterbo and Orvieto. The poet Master Heinrich of Wiirzburg wrote an encomium of the papal curia at Orvieto at that time, entitled De statu curiae Romanae. In a few lines he describes the illustrious court and the presence of a great philosopher of considerable eloquence who had become the wonder of the scholarly world: Whoever comes will find whatever he thirsts for; That house is equipped with all the arts. There is someone there,. 0 Philosophy, who, if the House burned to the ground, would design a new one. The new builder would erect it in finer fashion and; By his art, would prove superior to men of old. 31 See Alberti, Metaphysica, Proleg. § I (ed. Colon. 16/1, 1960), p. viii. 19 ff. De statu curiae Romanae, vv. 877-82, ed. H. von Grauert, Abh. d. Bay. Akad. d. Wiss., philos-philolog. u. hist. Klasse, 27/1-2 (Munich, 1912), 80 31 ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 499 The editor of the poem, Hermann von Grauert, considered this philosopher to be Thomas Aquinas, who was also in Orvieto, lecturing at the Dominican priory. However, as Martin Grabmann soon pointed out, the philosopher alluded to can be none other than Heinrich's countryman, Albert the Great. 82 Citing numerous contemporary sources, mainly German, that referred to Albert as " a great philosopher " and " the wonder of the world, " Grabmann showed that Albert was best known to his countrymen as a philosopher, rather than a theologian, even though he was a master in theology of Paris and bishop of Regensburg. In fact, he was far more famous than Thomas ever was during his short lifetime. Urban kept Albert at the curia for a year and a half with the scholars, diplomats, bishops, and missionaries from all Christendom who had passed through his court. Although Urban was engaged in a losing war with Manfred, son of Frederick II, he " was a great friend and promoter of philosophical studies, " 33 and he was deeply concerned with reconciling the schismatic Greek Churches with Rome. It was in this atmosphere that Albert finished his monumental De animalibus, his paraphrase of Ethics, the Posterior Analytics, and possibly the unusual commentary on the Politics. In February, 1263, however, Pope Urban IV ordered Bishop Albert to preach the crusade in Germany, Bohemia, and all lands that spoke the German language, and he conferred extraordinary powers on him for the successful prosecution of his new mission. Albert's movements between March of 1!263 and the death of Urban IV in October of 1!264 can be traced easily as he traveled on foot throughout German-speaking countries, preaching a new crusade to the Holy Land. Last Years of Albert (1264-1280) With Urban's death, Albert's commission to preach the crusade came to an end. For the next three years he lived in the 82 M. Grabmann, " Ist das ' philosophische Universalgenie ' bei Magister Heinrich dem Poeten Thomas von Aquin?" Historisches Jahrbuch 88 (1917), 815-00. 83 M. Grabmann, Guglielmo di Moerbeke, O.P., il traduttore delle opere di Aristotele (Rome: Gregorianum, 1946), p. 48. 500 JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. Dominican Kloster in Wilrzburg with his brother Henry, writing the Metaphysios, 34 arbitrating difficult cases, and performing numerous para-episcopal duties, such as consecrating churches, altars, choir stalls, and nunneries, and presiding at ecclesiastical functions. He complained that such duties kept him from his primary desires of study and prayer. Finally, around 1269, John of Vercelli, then master of the order (1264-83) , asked Albert to reside in Cologne as leotor emeritus. For the next eleven years until his death he resided in Cologne with frequent journeys out of the city to arbitrate litigations, consecrate churches, and preside at functions. For example, on 12 September, 1276, four years before his death, he consecrated the Dominican church of St. Paulus in Antwerp, which he had caused to be built in 1265 when he was provincial. News of Thomas d'Aquino's unexpected death in 1274 caused profound grief and frequent tears in Albert's later years. Albert was not at the Council of Lyons, but news reached him very quickly and moved him to such torrents of tears that the brethren thought they stemmed " from a weakness of mind." We have only one moving account that details his sad but heroic journey to Paris in 1277 to defend the writings of Thomas, then being attacked in the city of philosophers. 35 But his efforts came to naught, and Tempier's condemnation of 219 scattered propositions came out on 7 March, 1277. Up to fifteen months before his death, Albert was clearly competent to negotiate various delicate transactions, including intricate arbitrations, as is evident from six documents dating from 26 September, 1277 to 18 August, 1279. When Albert made out his last will and testament in January, 1279, making his brother Friar Henry of Lauingen, prior of Wilrzburg, executor of the will, he stated that he was of sound mind and body (sanus et inoolumis). 3fl ••See Alberti, Metaphysica, Proleg. § 1 (ed. Colon. 16/1, 1960), pp. vii-viii. ••Bartholomew of Capua's testimony in Proc. Canoniz. S. Thomae, n. 82 in Thomae Aquinatis Vitae Fontes Praecipuae, ed. cit., pp. 824-25. •• H. C. Scheeben, Albert der Grosse: Zur Chronologie seines Lebens, Quellen und Forschungen zur Geschichte des Dominikanerordens in Deutschland (Vechta: Albertus-Magnus-Verlag, 1981), pp. 128-27. ALBERT THE GREAT AND MEDIEVAL CULTURE 501 That Albert was getting senile toward the end of 1279, at the age of eighty, can hardly be gainsaid. It is quite possible, considering his age and the incredible energy he had put into everything he did, that Albert's memory did begin to fail and that at times he might have been completely befuddled. Henry of Herford gives three explicit indications of Albert's growing senility, all of which seem to have taken place during the last fifteen months of his life. For example, once a certain Archbishop Sigfried wanted to visit the aging bishop, but when he was announced, Albert replied, " Albert is now here. " 37 All that can be said is that neither Albert nor his confreres were unprepared when death came for the saintly bishop on Friday, the feast of St. Geltrud, 15 November 1280. He was then octogenarius et ampliiis. No one knows how much amplius, but he could not have been more than eighty-one when he died. In his own day he was with good reason known as Doctor universalis and Doctor expertus, for his knowledge was truly " universal " and he knew much from personal " experience ". Late in his own lifetime he was even known as Lord and Friar Albert " the Great. " In the words of Ulrich of Strasburg, a Cologne disciple and intimate friend, Albert was " a man so superior in every science, that he can fittingly be called the wonder and miracle of our time. " 38 Today he is not only a saint and Doctor of the Church, but also the heavenly patron of those who cultivate the natural sciences. He is seen as the much-needed intercessor in our new age of atomic power and its consequent uncertainties. May his wisdom guide us now in our scientific and moral dilemmas. JAMES A. WEISHEIPL, O.P. Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies Toronto, Ontario Canada Henrici de Herford, Chronica, ed. cit., p. !W2. ••Summa de bona IV, tr. 3, c. 9. See J. Daguillon, Ulrich de Strasbourg, La "Summa de bono." Livre I (Paris: Vrin, 1930), p. 189. 87 THE KINGDOM OF GOD IN ALBERT THE GREAT AND THOMAS AQUINAS HE CALL TO REPENTANCE and conversion on ccount of the imminent corning of the kingdom of God the central theme of the proclamation of Jesus. 1 It seems moreover that Jesus was the only teacher of Judaism or early Christianity to make the kingdom the center of his message. Not that the formula was original to him. The idea that God is king is present in early strata of the Old Testament as well as in the religions of Israel's neighbors. 2 The formula ' kingdom of God ' derives from the thoughtworld of Jewish apocalyptic and of the Aramaic targummim that were read in the synagogues of Palestine in Jesus's day. 3 The kingdom is never precisely defined in the gospels and this is not the place to defend a reconstruction of its meaning. It must suffice here to summarize a view which is common in modern biblical scholarship and which is presupposed in what follows. Interpretations of the Kingdom The kingdom then is a future reign of God upon earth which brings with it peace, justice, joy. It occurs in time, in history; it embraces the political, social, and personalistic dimensions of life and is intended to include all human beings and the entire cosmos.4 Thus from the viewpoint of the Synoptic Gospels the 1 J. Weiss, Jesus' Proclamation of the Kingdom of God (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1971; Germ. orig., 189Q); R. Schnackenburg, God's Rule and Kingdom (New York: Herder & Herder, 1963; Germ. orig. 1959). • K. L. Schmidt, s.v. basileus, etc., in Kittel, Theological Dictionary of the Ne:w Testament (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1965), vol. 1, pp. 573-595; Kleinknecht, Quell, Stauffer, Kuhn, s.v. theos, ibid., vol. 3, pp. 65-123. 8 Schnackenburg, God's Rule, pp. 41-75. •Matt. 6: 33; Rom. 14: 17; P. Tillich, Systematic Theology (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1963), vol. 3, pp. Q97-4Q3, esp. the four defining characteristics, p. 358; 502 THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 503 believer has two hopes: the individual expectation of death, resurrection, judgment, heaven, and the enjoyment of the blissmaking vision of God on the one hand, and an expectation of a future intervention of God through the Son of Man come to earth, in a word, the kingdom of God, on the other hand. This double expectation of the synoptics, that is, of Jesus, quickly began to break up after his death. The kingdom is less central in Paul, and in the gospel according to John it has nearly disappeared (five times only, in 3: 3,5; 18: 36, as contrasted with 121 times in the Synoptics) , to be largely displaced hy the promise of ' eternal life ' begun here on earth and completed in the resurrection. 5 As Christianity moved ever further into the Hellenistic world and left behind its Jewish Palestinian roots the apocalyptic kingdom hope faded further and further into the background. This becomes clear from a brief survey of patristic views.6 As a representative of Alexandrian neo-Platonic philosophical Christianity, Origen held that the kingdom was identical with Jesus himself. To express this he coined the term autobasileia, self-kingdom, by which he meant that Jesus was himself the kingdom. Origen went on to interpret the kingdom pietistically as the soul of the believer divinized or transformed by grace. Thus the kingdom came to mean for him the immortality of the soul, eternal life, heaven itself, the goal of the soul. For Eusebius of Caesarea, who had become a kind of court chaplain to Constantine, the first ruler of the Christian empire, the kingdom was obviously the Christian empire itself. Thereby he expressed the hitherto persecuted Christians' astonishment J. Moltmann, Theology of Hope (New York: Harper, 1967); W. Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God (Philadelphia: Westminster, 1969). 5 J. Blank, Krisis (Freiburg: Lambertus, 1964); P. Ricca, Die Esckatologie des vierten Evangeliums (Zurich: Gotthelf, 1966); M.-E. Boismard, "L'evolution du theme eschatologique dans les traditions johanniques," Revue Biblique 68 (1961): 507-24. 6 R. Frick, Die Geschichte des Reich-Gottes-Gedankens in der alten Kirche bit zu Origenes und Augustin (Giessen: Tiipelmann, 1928); G. W. H. Lampe, "Some notes on the significance of basileia tou theou, basileia christou, in the Greek Fathers," Journal of Theological Studies 49 (1948): 58-73. 504 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. at their sudden reversal of fortune. It was only natural that in the first flush of their enthusiasm for the new arrangement the fourth-century Christians like Eusebius overestimated its significance and future potential theologically. It did not take them long to be disillusioned. In the thought of Augustine a few generations later such a nai:ve identification of kingdom and empire has been tempered by experience. Augustine, in his great work The City of God (Book 20,9) , moves in a different direction. He comes close to identifying the kingdom with the church, as he says: " The Church even now is the kingdom of Christ, and the kingdom of heaven," although he realizes that it is not so perfectly or as it will be in the future. For his refined thought it is really the elect who are the kingdom, but, as his view became the common one in the Western Church for a long time, some of the fine points were gradually lost. In medieval Augustinianism there were occasional temptations to identify the kingdom with the Holy Roman Empire but these tendencies were resisted by Pope Gregory VII (Hildebrand) and his successors. For them the church was the kingdom on earth. Even Dante, who fiercely fought for the view that the authority of the Roman Empire came directly from God and not from the church, did not go so far as to assert that the Empire was the Kingdom of God on earth, although he does argue that it is typified by " the earthly Paradise " and he goes on to say that the emperor is responsible for guiding mankind to whatever temporal happiness there is.7 One could argue that Dante comes very close to making the identification between Kingdom of God and Empire for all practical purposes. But in fact there is a gap between the New Testament view and his, because the New Testament expects a new divine intervention in history and Dante does not. 7 Dante, On World-Government 01' De Monarchia (New York: Liberal Arts, 1957; 1310-.13 or 1317), especially III, 16. For views on the Christian Empire through the ages, see Alois Dempf, Sacrum lmperium (Munich-Berlin: R. Oldenbourg, 199l9 repr. 1978). THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 505 Summarizing then we may say that the Middle Ages on the whole did not well understand the this-worldly future dimension of the kingdom because of three factors: a widespread ignorance of the apocalyptic Jewish background of this expectation, together with an acute Platonic longing for the eternal, for a place outside of time and history. This is the first factor. To it we must add the Augustinian transformation of the kingdom into the church militant and triumphant, and lastly the imperial ideology of the Christian empire as the kingdom of God on earth. Joachim of Fiore and Eschatology This unclarity about a this-worldly future divine kingdom characterizes three of the giants of high scholasticism: Bonaventure, Thomas and Albert. But before turning to their thought we should notice the one striking exception to this general state of affairs, the prophetic movement associated with the name of the Calabrian abbot, Joachim of Fiore (c. 1135rno2). Although Joachim, so far as I can tell, did not directly reflect on the kingdom theme of the gospels, he did renew a this-worldly hope of a new period of salvation history, which he called a third status of the world, in which the works of the Holy Spirit would be brought to perfection and in which there would be no need for clergy since all the people would be living as pure contemplatives. It seems that Joachim himself presumed a continuity between the church of the second stat.us and that of the third status, a continuity which would be firmly maintained by a perduring Petrine papal office.8 This simple threefold scheme of history sufficed to fire the 8 On Joachim and his influence see M. Reeves, The Influence of PTophecy in the Later Middle Ages (Oxford: Clarendon, 1969); idem, Joachim of Fiore and the Prophetic Future (New York: Harper, 1976); B. McGinn, Apocalyptic Spirituality (New York: Paulist, 1979), pp. 97-181; idem, Visions of the End (New York: Columbia, 1979), pp. rn6-141, 158-167; H. deLubac, Exegeae Medievale, vol. s (Paris: Aubier, 1961), pp. 437-558; ibid., vol. 4 (Paris: Aubier, 1964), pp. 825-344; E. Staehelin, Die Verkilndigung du Reiches. Gottes in der Kirche Juu Christi, vol. 3 (Basel: Reinhardt, 1955), pp. 119-171, 251-269. 506 BENEDICT T. TIVIANO, O.P. imaginations and to raise the hopes of many for a better future in this world. As such it had revolutionary and socially disruptive potential. While we cannot pursue all the tangled trails of Joachimism through the Middle Ages, we must mention briefly the scandal created by the eternal gospel promulgated by the Franciscan Gerard of Borgo San Donnino (the modern Fidenza) in 1254. In that year Gerard circulated a collection of three of Joachim's main works together with an introduction in which he drew the most damaging conclusions. Seven errors extracted from that libellus introductorius were condemned by Pope Alexander IV on 23 October 1255. These errors are: (I) that the eternal gospel which is identical with Joachim's teachings surpasses the teaching of Christ and thus the whole Old and New Testaments; (2) that the gospel of Christ is not the gospel of the kingdom and therefore does not build up the church; (3) that the New Testament must be as invalid as the Old Testament; (4) that the New Testament will only remain in force for the next six years that is, until the year A.D. 1260; (5) that those who live beyond this time are no longer held to accept the New Testament; (6) that to the gospel of Christ another gospel follows, and another priesthood in place of the priesthood of Christ; (7) that no one is able in himself to instruct people about spiritual and eternal matters except he go about barefoot. 9 At the University of Paris this affair was blown up to huge proportions by the animosity of the secular masters, and particularly William of St. Amour, against the Mendicants. Gerard had made matters worse by identifying the three angels of the fourteenth chapter of the Apocalypse with Joachim, Dominic and Francis and explaining them as heralds of the third status. At the provincial Council of Arles in 1263 the whole " pernicious doctrine" of the three status, as preached by the Joachites, was condemned, together with the writings of Joachim which were 9 Original Latin in H. Denifle and E. Chatelain, Ohartularium Universitatia Parisiensis, vol. 1 (Paris, 1889), p. 272. Cf. E. Benz, " Die exzerptsiitze der Pariser Professoren aus dem Evangelium Aetemum," Zeitschrift fur Kirchengeschichte 51 (1932) : 415ff. THE KINGDOl\f IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 507 its foundation. In spite of these condemnations and of the failure of Gerard's hopes to materialize in 1260, his doctrine spread like wildfire among many friars, affecting even the generals of the two major new orders. This situation provided a real threat to the leadership of the church and a challenge to the greatest theologians of the Franciscans and Dominicans, Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas respectively. This crisis also helps to explain the relative blindness of these great men to the centrality of the gospel theme of the kingdom of God. To be sure it is only a partial explanation, but it did leave its mark. The response of the two doctors varied as vary it must given the different situation of the two orders. Bonaventure had to try to meet the Joachites within his order halfway, to attempt a compromise, because the number of extremists was larger among the Franciscans and the danger of their going into schism was greater, and because the eschatological evaluation of their founder Francis was nearly universal among them and was shared by Bonaventure himself. This solution Bonaventure attempted in his great Collationes in Hexaemeron which he gave at the University of Paris in the summer of 1273 and which had to be left incomplete and unrevised because of his elevation to the cardinalate. In this work Bonaventure undertakes a fundamental treatment of the theology of history. It is the only work in which a leading scholastic theologian attempts a synthesis of historical symbolic thought (such as characterized Joachim's interpretation of biblical prophecy) with the conceptual-abstract thought of Scholasticism. 10 Abbreviating Bonaventure's careful and complicated schemes drastically we can say that he did attempt to discern a pattern of salvation history, including an expectation of an ultimate flowering of the Church within history. He follows Joachim exactly in the expression of this hope by placing the seventh age between the destruction of Antichrist and the Last Judg10 Bonaventure, Opera omnia, 10 vol. (Quaracchi, 1882-1902), vol. 5, pp. 829449. Reeves, Prophecy, pp. 179-181. The fundamental analysis is by J. Ratzinger, The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure (Germ. orig. 1959; Chicago: Franciscan Herald, 1971). 508 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. ment and by distinguishing it from the eighth age.11 He also lists Francis as a member of the ultimate order, the ordo contemplantium, the ordo seraphicus, and gives him eschatological status as Sixth Angel of the Apocalypse (Rev. 7: 2) and as Elijah in his second coming. But he does not hold that the concrete, historical Franciscan order is this ultimate, seraphic order. It is only cherubicus and not seraphicus. This means that the present Order of Franciscans is not yet the true Order of Francis. Thus Bonaventure makes a distinction between Francis and Franciscanism. 12 By means of these distinctions Bonaventure tried to link events of his own day with an imminent eschatological future while at the same time preserving continuity with the existing church. He inherits from Joachim a thisworldly hope but firmly connects it with the return of the Son and the abiding validity of the New Testament. In this he was perhaps being faithful to the true meaning of Joachim himself but not to his radical successors.18 Thoma.s Aquinas and the Kingdom of God The attitude of Thomas Aquinas to the radical expectations of a third age of the church aroused by the Joachite movement is more abruptly negative. But before we look at Thomas's relation to Joachimism we should first consider his position in regard to our central theme of the kingdom of God, in order to see why the Joachite conflict is relevant. If one consults the standard index to the two Summae of Thomas 14 under the Collationes, Delorme ed., p. 185. Ratzinger, Theology of History, pp. 31-51. 13 Reeves, Prophecy, p. 180f. 14 Indices . . . in Summa theologiae et in Summa contra Gentiles . . . , ed. C. S. Suermondt (Rome: Leonine, 1948); the older index to the complete works of Thomas, called the Tabula aurea, of Peter Bergamo (Rome: Paulinae, 1960), p. 822, adds a few minor ref.erences whnich do not substantially alter the picture: In Sent. 4, d. 49, q. 1, art. 2, q. 5, c.; 1-2, q. 108, a. 1, ad 1 um; In Sent. 4, d. 15, q. 3, a.I, q. 4, ad 1 um; In Rom. 10, lect. l; 11, lect. 1; 14, lect. !?. The picture which emerges from the new massive Index Thomisticus, ed. R. Busa (Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 1975), Sectio II, vol. 19, entry no. 69107-a, -b, pp. 290-293, is certainly much vaster and more complex, but not significantly different from that already drawn. 11 12 THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 509 word regnum one will find almost nothing. While this disconcerting result is not entirely justified, as we shall see, it contains an important lesson. The fact is that Thomas Aquinas does not devote any significant portion of his principal theological enterprise to the kingdom of God, the central theme of the preaching of Jesus. This may be considered a serious weakness in the greatest doctor of the medieval Church. Our task is not to praise or to blame but to understand. Of course Thomas has a vast moral construction built around the theme of justice in his great Summa theologiae. And as a matter of fact Thomas does treat of the kingdom in his commentary on Matthew as well as in his Summa theologiae, in his commentary on the Sentences, in the Quctestiones quodlibetales as well as in the theological opusculum, Expositio super secundam decretalem ad Archidiaconum Tudertinum. But in all of these instances except for the first it is in a context of polemical interaction with the theology of history of Joachim of Fiore. Thus in his day the subject was a theological live-wire which Thomas handled with reserve. We will now consider some of the kingdom texts from Thomas and then suggest some reasons why he remained so cool toward the theme and toward Joachimism. In his commentary on Matthew where he cannot bypass this theme we get the impression of a certain amount of confusion. This confusion may of course be due to his secretary since this commentary is a reportatio, that is, unrevised lecture notes taken down by a student secretary, as opposed to a dictatus. His view (on Matthew 8: 2) runs: The Kingdom of Heaven in the scripture may be understood in four ways. For sometimes it means Christ himself dwelling in us through grace; The Kingdom of God is within you. Here the Kingdom of Heaven is spoken of because by means of the indwelling grace the way of the heavenly kingdom is begun in us. -Secondly the Kingdom can mean Sacred Scripture itself; thus Matthew says: The Kingdom of God will be taken away from you, that is, Sacred Scripture. It is called a Kingdom because its law leads to the kingdom. -Third, it refers to the present Church militant; Matthew 13:47: The Kingdom of Heaven is like a net cast into the sea and gathering all manner of fish, etc. 510 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. Here it is called a Kingdom because it is founded and set up in the manner of the heavenly Church. -Fourth, the Kingdom of Heaven can mean the heavenly court: Matthew 8: 11: They shall come from the east and from the west, and they shall recline with Abraham and Isaac and Jacob in the Kingdom of Heaven. 15 Of these four senses the first is the familiar false start based on Luke 17: 21, which becomes the basis for an individualist, private interior definition. The third and fourth, the kingdom is the church on earth and heaven after death, follow the usual Augustinian line. The second, which defines the kingdom as Scripture itself, can only be characterized as a rather remote, arbitrary equivocation. A second, more familiar passage on the kingdom comes in the Summa theologiae, in one of its finest patches of biblical theology, the tractate on biblical law (I-II, qq. 98-108). In the subsection on the New Law of the gospel (qq. 106-108), in q. 106, article 4, is found the question whether the new law will last till the end of the world. Here the objections are all derived from Joachite or radical Joachite teaching and the fourth explicitly mentions the kingdom (of God) . In the body of the article Thomas makes a distinction in terms of the status mundi, Joachite terminology: The state of the world may change in two ways. In one way, according to a change of law, and thus no other state will succeed this state of the New Law. For the state of the New Law succeeded the state of the Old Law, as a more perfect law a less perfect one. Now no state of the present life can be more perfect than the state of the New Law .... In another way,. the state of mankind may change according as man stands in relation to one and the same law more or less perfectly .... Thus, too, the state of the New Law is subject to change with regard to various places, times and persons, according as the grace of the Holy Spirit dwells in man more or less perfectly. Nevertheless, we are not to look forward to a state wherein man is to possess the grace of the Holy Spirit more perfectly than he has possessed it hitherto .... 15 Thomas Aquinas, Super EvangeUum S. Matthaei lectura, ed. R. Cai (Turin: Mar.ietti, 1951), on ch. 3, verse !'.!, par. 250. Cf. Maximino Arias Reyero, Thomas von Aquin als Exeget (Einsiedeln: Johannes, 1971). THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 511 With respect to a promised age of the Holy Spirit advanced in the third objection, he scores an effective point: The Old Law corresponded not only to the Father, but also to the Son, because Christ was foreshadowed in the Old Law .... In like manner, the New Law corresponds not only to Christ, but also to the Holy Spirit, according to Romans 8: 2: The law of the Spirit of life in Christ JesWJ, etc. Hence we are not to look forward to another law corresponding to the Holy Spirit. In other words, the whole Trinity is always present to its creation, is always active in history. To the mission of the Son succeeded that of the Spirit, but that occurred already at Pentecost. Whatever is to come in the future will involve the Son as well. With respect to the kingdom he simply says in the reply to the fourth objection: " Since Christ said at the very outset of the preaching of the Gospel: The kingdom of heaven is at hand (Matt. 4: 17) , it is most absurd to say that the Gospel of Christ is not the Gospel of the kingdom. And so with harsh words like vanitas and stultissimum he rejects the Eternal Gospel of Gerard's distorted Joachimism, as well as Joachim's Trinitarian scheme of history. In a Quodlibetal Question (q. 13, a. 1) on the possibility of a massive defection in the church from the ideal of Gospel poverty, a difficulty is raised that nowadays the church has armies (castra) at her disposal. In his reply, based on Augustine, he does admit different temporal states of the church but not a fundamental discontinuity. Augustine replies in a letter Against the Donatists, based on Psalm 2: I: "Why do the nations rage?" He distinguishes different times of the Church. There was a time when kings resisted Christ, and at that time they did not give support to the faithful but killed them. But now is another time when kings understand and the learned serve the Lord Jesus Christ in fear, etc., and so in this time kings are vassals of the Church. And so there is another state of the Church then and now, but there is not another Church. 16 16 Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones Quodlibetales., ed. R. Spiazzi (Turin: Marietti, 1956), pp. 23lf., no. 244 (19). BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. This is an indication of considerable social optimism, as well as a high evaluation of the Christian empire, but makes the empire still subordinate to the church. Finally, dealing with speculation on the millenium, Thomas expresses scepticism about foretelling the future by the concords of the Old and New Testaments: I do not think that these persecutions were prophetically signified by those deeds done in Egypt, although, by those who think this, individual events from both periods exquisitely and ingeniously seem to be compared: This is done not by a prophetic spirit but by the conjecture of the human mind which sometimes arrives at the truth and sometimes fails. And the same should be said about the sayings of the Abbot Joachim who by such conjectures sometimes predicted truly about future events and in some matters was deceived. Thomas's critique of Joachim's method of finding harmonies between the Testaments is trenchant and reasonable, but there is an alternative danger of spiritualizing, ahistorical exegesis of a kind dependent on the Pseudo-Denis. Thomas himself is not always immune from this danger, and Albert, as we will see, is even more prey to it. The value of Joachim's method is as a corrective counterweight which takes the events of history with full religious seriousness.17 Before turning to Albert, let us summarize some of the factors which inhibited Thomas in his appreciation of a theology of history which is implied in a this-worldly coming of the kingdom and which was represented in his own day in a somewhat deformed way by Joachite speculations and expectations. First of all he probably realized the socially disruptive potential of this theology and, since he had family connections with the Hohenstaufen emperors, was on friendly terms with the saintly French king Louis IX, and from time to time served as a theologian at the papal court, he wanted to help them to maintain 17 Cf. DeLubac's balanced judgment, Exegese Medievale, vol. 8, p. 556f. Joachim's own contrast of allegoria and concordia, both of which he accepts, may be found in McGinn, Apocalyptic, pp. 12!'l-124, from Concordia, Book 2, Part 1, Chapters 8 and 4. THE KINGDOM IN ALB'ERT AND AQUINAS 518 the fragile social fabric as it then was. Secondly, the antimendicant controversy and the excesses of Gerard of Borgo San Donnino threatened the very existence of the friars. Under these circumstances it would have been unwise to encourage apocalyptic expectations. Third, Thomas's chief claim to social boldness and apostolic heroism was his effort to meet the intellectual and spiritual needs of the new class of urban lay intellectuals and merchants by the integration of Aristotelian science and Christian faith. To do this he had to emphasize sober theological restraint and timeless necessary truths, rather than the caprice of historical change. 18 Fourth, Thomas's secular learning is predominantly philosophical rather than historical and his approach to Scripture and theology is predominantly sapiential rather than polemical or prophetic or historical. 10 He also had a strong conviction about the absolute finality and sole sufficiency of Jesus Christ as well as about the present work of the Holy Spirit and those were at least compromised by Joachimism. The great works of Greek, Roman and Jewish historiography were simply not available to him, nor were the pseudoepigraphical works of Jewish apocalyptic. 2° Finally, we may note that he did not complete his great Summa, so that we do not have his last word on eschatology, but if we judge from the sketch at the end of the Summa contra Gentiles this would not have altered the picture significantly. Albert the Great and the Kingdom of God With Albert (1206-1280) we are in a different world. Although he has much to say about the kingdom, he nowhere, so far as I can see, discusses it in terms of Joachim's theology of 18 Cf. B. Smalley, The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages, 2nd rev. ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1952), p. 292. 19 But his great tract on prophecy in the Summa theol., II-II, qq. 171-174, contained enough power to ignite a Savonarola. See McGinn, Apocalyptic, p. 804, n. 10. 2 ° For a fuller and more balanced presentation of Thomas's relation to history, see Max Seckler, Das Heil in der Geschichte. Ges.chichtstheologischesDenken bei Thomas van Aquin (Munich: Kosel, 1964). 514 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. history. We are back in the world of Plato, the Pseudo-Denis, and Augustine, but with the addition of Aristotle. We can treat him last because he lived longer than Thomas and Bonaventure, and because his great commentaries on the four canonical gospels 21 were given their final form toward the end of his life, between 1270 and 1276.22 These commentaries are the only certainly authentic works among the various commentaries on New Testament books attributed to him. 23 They have not yet been critically edited, unfortunately. They are masterpieces of medieval university exegesis, always striving for the literal truth, the veritas litterae. Perhaps Spicq does not exaggerate when he says that " a ce titre, ... il est le createur de l'exegese scientifique." 24 For our purposeS' we have checked every reference to the kingdom of God in his commentary on the synoptics and found the richest material in his commentary on Matthew, to which he refers back in the rest of his references. Albert gives a preliminary definition of the kingdom of God at its first occurrence, in Matthew 3: 2. His fullest treatment is found when he comes to the Lord's Prayer, at 6: 10. This runs to eight quarto pages. All the other comments are comparatively brief. Our procedure then will be first to present a translation and analysis of the first definition, then to summarize his shorter, scattered remarks, and then thirdly to concentrate on his full dress treatment. We will conclude with an overall evaluation in light of contemporary theology and exegesis. The kingdom of the heavens is threefold: (I) one, which is within " The Kingdom of God is within you." And this us, Luke 17: 21 These four commentaries are found in the Borgnet edition (Paris: Vives 1898), in volumes 20-!M. 22 Cf. J. M. Voste, "Sanctus Albertus Magnus Evangeliorum interpres," Angelicum 9 (1932): 242-246. Also published in book form, S. Albertus. Magnus sacrae paginae magister (Rome: Angelico, 1982), vol. 1, pp. 3-62. 23 C. Spicq, Esquisse d'une historie de l'exegese latine au moyen age (Paris: Vrin, 1944), p. 296. 24 Spicq, Esquisse, p. 298. Other treatments of Albert's exegesis may be found in Smalley, Study, pp. 298-302 and passim, and H. de Lubac, Exegese medievale, vol. 4. pp. 302-307. See also the brief noticeR in G. G. Meerseman, Introductio in opera omnia B. Alberti Magni 0. P. (Brugge: Beyaert, 1981), pp. 93-96. THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 515 is that concerning which it is said in Romans 14:17: "The Kingdom of God is not eating and drinking, but righteousness, and peace and joy in the Holy Spirit." And through this Kingdom God reigns in us. For this is, as Dionysius says,. " distribution of laws, and precepts, and offices, and classes (gradus) and goods which pertain to the civilization (civilitas) of the saints." And this is the kingdom of God through which God reigns in us. And as the first kingdom is the soul of the true (or: first) king, whose insights (illuminationes) and orders and laws and acts as they take effect among the people themselves constitute the kingdom, so this kingdom is first of all in the mind of God, and then, when it is promulgated among the saints, makes up the kingdom of the heavens. And that which in heaven is external to ourselves (extra nos) is like to this; but it is even more like the kingdom/reign of the mind of God, which is third, and exemplar,. and object, and cause of the two other kingdoms. And it consists in three things: (a) in the enlightening of those who belong to the kingdom, and (b) in the powers of the kingdom, and (c) in the duties actually (ad actum) exercised. (2) The second kingdom is the kingdom of the heavens outside of ourselves, which is the place and the honor and the joy (jucunditas) of those reigning in heaven. And this is acquired by the first kingdom (the one within us). (3) The third kingdom is the one which is the object and cause of these: and this is God descending into both the kingdom within us and the kingdom in heaven. Wisdom 3: 8: "They will rule over peoples, and the Lord will reign over them for ever." Isaiah 33: 22: "The Lord is our king." 25 Albert's understanding of the Kingdom of God may be summarized as follows: the kingdom consists of three realities, the life of virtues within the soul of the believer, the life of the saints in heaven, and thirdly God himself. But as Albert understands the third aspect there is really an underlying unity which binds all three aspects together and that is the divine reality present to itself, to the soul and to the blessed. In a word, for Albert the kingdom of God is God himself. This is a relatively original concept in the history of interpretation of this biblical theme. Before Albert the kingdom had been interpreted either as virtue or the resurrection or as the Christian empire or as ••Albert Magnus, Enarrationes in Evangelium (Paris: Vives, 1893), vol. 20, p. 94. Matthaei, 3:2, Borgnet ed. 516 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, 0.P. the church, either the present church or the future church of the Spirit, even as Christ but not, in any major witness, as God. Let us take a closer look at the text to see what might have led Albert to his peculiar view. His starting point is unpromising enough, because he begins with the least representative text in the Gospels, Luke 17: 21: " the kingdom of God is within you." This much abused text has usually misled readers to the conclusion that the kingdom is an inner spiritual reality in the soul of the believer without any future social reference except resurrection to eternal life with the saints in heaven. But if translated as "the kingdom of God is among you, i.e., in your midst," and read in context, viz., as addressed to unbelieving Pharisees, as following upon a healing miracle (Luke 17: 11-19) and as introducing an entire discourse on future eschatology (Luke: 17: 22-18: 8), then the verse yields a view which fits better with the predominantly future sense of the kingdom present throughout Luke and the entire synoptic tradition. The verse would then mean that, while the fullness of the kingdom is yet to come, it is already sufficiently discernible in the healing deeds of Jesus to lead eyewitnesses to a decision of faith in Jesus as the divinely accredited agent of the kingdom. It has nothing to do with a kind of private, individualistic pietism. 25 But all of this was not apparent to Albert, who depended upon the Vulgate's intra vos. After this false start, Albert unwittingly veers toward the best and truest definition of the kingdom to be found in the New Testament: Romans 14: 17: "the kingdom of God is not in food and drink but justice and peace and joy in the Holy Spirit." Had he understood these values as a promise for an earthly future and as social goods he would have been quite on Augustin Goorges, Etudes sur l'oeuvre de Luc (Paris: Gabalda, 1978), pp. When Albert himself comes to comment on this verse, he will recognize this. After discussing other meanings, he then concludes: " Nevertheless according to the letter here [Jesus] means that a material kingdom is already present among the Pharisees: because the king of the righteous, and the first ordering of powers, and of the princes of the Apostles and disciples was in their midst, and they did not recogni11e him. ' 26 THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 517 target. But his understanding of these realities is dominated by his privatized view of the kingdom which he derived from Luke 17: 21, so he takes them to be purely inner magnitudes, and thereby strips them of their innate social, transformative power. For Albert God reigns in our hearts but not directly in the world. (Perhaps such a low view of God's power to influence and to direct the turn of historical events may be attributed to Albert's depressing episcopal experiences at close range with the workings of the Christian church and empire, and especially to his bitter experiences at having preached the crusade (ca. 1263) which went down to defeat at the Horns of Hattin (1287) and finally lost even the miserable little toehold of St. Jean d'Acre (1291). With the fall of Acre went an archbishopric and a Dominican province.) Perhaps this line of interpretation which we have been pursuing is misdirected. Perhaps Albert is not so unsocial after all. A judgment in this matter depends in part on our interpretations of the next sentences in which Albert is drawing upon a phrase of the Pseudo-Denis: " [The kingdom of God is] the distribution of laws, and precepts, and offices, and classes (gradus) and goods which pertain to the civilization of the saints." 27 From his comments on this passage it appears that Albert is not an unpolitical theologian. Rather he works out of the Platonic mode of political theory which is psychologizing and idealistic. For Plato the ideal ruler is a philosopher, and his principal means of directing his citizens is educational and rhetorical, winning their hearts and minds through persuasion. The Christian neo-Platonism of the Pseudo-Denis which Albert follows transports this model of political theory into the mind of God. It too is concerned with laws, offices, social classes and civilization in general. For Albert the divine mind works through persuasion, order, and actions. Thus there is an unmistakably social dimension to this thought. Albert thinks of 27 So far as I can tell, this is a loose quotation from Dionysius the treatise On the Divine Names, ch. U (P. G. S, 969 A; Dionysiaca, 1, p. translation into Latin is that of John Sarracenus). the 518 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. the kingdom as the divine rule, not in specifically territorial terms. This is possible for him because the Latin term in question, regnum, can mean both kingdom, in the sense of a territory under royal government, and the actual governing activity, rule (Herrschaft) . This interpretation is supported by much contemporary biblical scholarship which prefers to translate basileia toit theoit as rule or reign of God. This translation however fails to catch the earthly, territorial reference of the biblical concept, so that many exegetes, the present writer included, still prefer the translation" kingdom ". 28 But there can be no doubt that Albert is catching an aspect of the biblical meaning. And as Plato's Republic can be interpreted both psychologically and politically, so for Albert God's rule of hearts is also a rule of the state and sovereignty called the kingdom of God. Concluding our analysis of this key passage we note simply that for Albert the second phase of the kingdom is the heaven of the saints, and that the third, which holds the other two together, is God himself. What is most striking in all of this is Albert's Platonic way of grasping and failing to grasp the social dimension of the biblical concept. Turning now to the second part of our study of Albert, we will simply present without comment some of his more striking and original remarks on the kingdom. On Matthew 6: 33, noting that Chrysostom says that the kingdom of God is here eternal retribution, Albert comments: " This is true with respect to the ultimate goal intended. But the kingdom which we are here enjoined to seek is that by which God reigns among men. The meaning is ' First,' by struggling, preaching, working well (militando, praedicando, bene operando), constantly' seek the kingdom of God,' i.e., that he reign by a strengthened kingdom-rule over men. 'And its righteousness,' i.e., the justice by which this reign is strengthened, and which leads to an everlasting reign. " 28 S. Aalen, "Reign and House in the Kingdom of God in the Gospels," New Testament Studies 8 (1961-2), 215-240. THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 519 On Matthew 13: 31 he observes: "The kingdom of heaven is not like the kingdoms of other powers. For these rule by coercive force (virtute ooactiva) . But the heavenly kingdoms attract us by the force of love (virtute ... amativa) ." Commenting on Matthew 25: 1, the parable of the wise and foolish virgins, he says: "The kingdom of heaven is here understood as the pursuit of beauty which is set before man according to the laws which lead to heaven." On Luke 17: 2la he teaches the universality of the kingdom which he contrasts with the provincialism of the Donatists in Africa and of the Arians elsewhere: "regnum enim gratiae Dei, in potestate saeculari non erit: neque in una parte mundi, sed in toto mundo, quia totum orbem obtinebit." Finally we come to Albert's fullest treatment of the theme, his commentary on the phrase of the Lord's Prayer, Adveniat Regnum Tuum, Thy Kingdom Come. 29 His extensive observations fall into three parts. (1) What is a kingdom, and what is this kingdom? (2) In what way is this kingdom the kingdom of God the Father? (3) Why do we pray that it come? Thus each of the terms Regnum Tuum Adveniat is analyzed separately. Of these three sections the longest, giving the definition of the kingdom, is the first. It contains a remarkable compendium of political philosophy, drawing upon Plato, Democratica (?), Timaeus, Aristotle, Ethics, Politics, and De Regimine Dominorum (?), Cicero, Rhetorica prima, Ambrose, Augustine, and the Pseudo- Denis. In this section Albert first attempts a definition and characterization of a kingdom or state in general and then (pp. 269-271) applies this data to the religious concept of the kingdom of God. At a high point in the discussion of the second section, Albert spontaneously bursts into a prayer which will provide our own last words here (p. 272). The third, brief section represents a sound and balanced theology of grace in which God's initiative is primary, but includes and invites our human, free response. Leaning on Plato, Albert defines a kingdom as: nothing other than complete power and dominion in a single person, animate ••In Evang. Matthaei, Borgnet ed., 20, pp. 265-272. 520 BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. justice, ordered by laws, concretized by urban communities as its parts, strengthened by the force of arms, governing according to the best principles of civilization, superabounding in external goods and supplied with sufficient organic resources.... And if this power were not in a single person, but were a divided power, then division and schism could arise, and thence desolation. . .. A body with many heads is a monstrous thing. Albert then proceeds further to define each element in this definition and his definitions are amplified and supported both by classical and patristic authors and by frequent quotations from the Bible, particularly from the historical books of the Old Testament, as well as from the prophets and wisdom literature. This section is characterized by practical common sense, as well as by some bizarre military ideas derived from the Timaeus, but the whole discussion is conducted in terms of classical antiquity with no reference to specifically contemporary events or conditions, although, when Albert reports a class of unmarried soldiers in Plato's ideal scheme, he might be thinking of the military religious orders of his own day. His definition of justice is the standard Aristotelian suum cuique tribuere, rather than the more Christian definition of Peter Lombard: iustitia est in subveniendis miseris. Albert then turns his attention to how all this applies to the kingdom of God. His approach is highly spiritual and moral. Taking all these matters into our spiritual lives (in spiritualibus), then the divine processions [of the Trinity] create the dominion of the kingdom in us, elevating, enriching and strengthening us. These processions are rays of divine grace, which lift the heart up from anything which would depress it into servitude, so that now we should disdain to look at such things, but be powerfully lifted beyond them, and crush them, and be filled with beautiful and good things as by a fountain (fontaliter). By this means we are sublimated above the vile (vilia) and never fall into them. Albert then takes most of the elements of the Platonic definition and interprets them in terms of the spiritual life of the believer. Thus "justice must be our everlasting life." "The divine laws are engraved on our hearts to be kept inviolably." I THE KINGDOM IN ALBERT AND AQUINAS 521 Urban structures are interpreted as the duties of the virtues. The seven women who embrace one man in Isaiah 4: 1 become the seven virtues (theological and cardinal) . The weapons in this kingdom are " studies, alertness and Scripture, by which the enemy devil is kept out." We also share in the legions of the angelic hosts, grouped in the nine choirs of the PseudoDenis. And so on. Thus God the Father confirms his kingdom in us, by giving us a share in his lordship through grace, by which he raises us up and assimilates us to his Son the king, who sits at his right hand. Colossians 3: If. In the second section Albert explains why this kingdom belongs to the Father. "In it he reigns, he gives it to the Son, through the Son he leads believers to adoptive sonship, and at the end of time the kingdom will be turned over to him by the Son with all who are in it and it in them." Each of these four aspects is then supported by Scripture quotations. The most dynamically eschatological among these four aspects is the last, which looks forward to a definitive divine resolution of history, based on I Corinthians 15: 24. This verse presupposes a Jewish apocalyptic world view for its full understanding, but Albert did not have such a world view at his disposal and the implications of the verse remain undeveloped in his commentary. When Albert turns to the third and final term in the clause Thy Kingdom come, (Adveniat) , his commentary becomes a little treatise on the theology of grace, in which the accent falls on the primacy of the divine initiative and yet we are called to a response. Thus he stands in the same line as Augustine and Thomas. It does not say that we should come to the kingdom [but that the kingdom come to us]. This is because we do not of ourselves have the power to do so. But if it should first come to us, then we can finally by its force come to it .... Since the kingdom of God is the power of perfect righteousness, the kingdom comes to us when it goes ahead of us (nos praeveniens) and lays claim to us [and liberates us, vindicat sibi], and then associates us in a common work, that we might cooperate with it toward the establishment of the BENEDICT T. VIVIANO, O.P. kingdom .... No one arrives at the honor of the kingdom, until the kingdom has first come to him through the keeping of the laws and virtues and righteousness and power in the aforesaid manner. (p. 272) It is time for a concluding evaluation of Albert's teaching on the kingdom. This may be quickly accomplished by two observations, one laudatory, one deprecatory. Albert passes the test of Tillich's four-point definition of the kingdom: it is political, social, personalistic and universal. But for Albert the kingdom of God is only political in the Platonic psychologico-political sense. In general we may speak of an emphatic spiritualizing tendency in Albert's thought on this point, which makes his doctrine unsuitable as a theological basis for radical social doctrines today. This is confirmed by our second observation. Albert fails the test of comprehending the Jewish this-worldly inner-historical eschatological divine intervention which was the specific content of Jesus's own preaching. Let us nevertheless conclude with Albert's prayer: Igitur, 0 Pater, est hoc hoc regnum decoris: in tuo diademate fulget tota pulchritudo coelestis per circuitum orbis: in cuius manu sceptrum est rectitudinis, eaque omnis rectitudo est, certius verbis et sententiis: in cuius conscientia sacramenta consiliorum sunt abscondita: in cuius conversatione fulgens et regalis praefulget conversatio virtutis. Hoc igitur regnum tuum adveniat! BENEDICT Aquinas Institute of Theology Dubuque, Iowa T. VIVIANO, O.P. ALBERT THE GREAT AND THOMAS AQUINAS ON THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION B OTH PRE-CHALCEDONIAN and post-Chalcedonian Christology focused on the relationship between humanity and divinity in the Christ, Jesus of Nazareth. Roman Catholic Christology has always devoted attention to the " person " of Christ, to his ontological " make-up " which is the ultimate source of his activity. If we look at the development of Christology in the Middle Ages, it becomes clear that intense study was given to this issue.1 One of the significant contributions of Thomas Aquinas to Christology touches on this same topic. 2 There is, however, another issue which was important for medieval Christology: not the nature of the Incarnation or the mode of union, but the purpose or motive of the Incarnation. This question may not have been the primary Christological concern of the Middle Ages, but it was a question which medieval theologians pondered 3 and which was significant both in 1 A valuable study in this regard is Walter Principe's four volumes on the theology of the hypo&tatic union in the early thirteenth century: William of Auxerre?s Theology of the Hypostatic Union (1963); Alexander of Halea's Theology of the Hypoatatie Union (1967); Hugh of Saint-Cher's Theology of the Hypostatic Union (1970); Philip the Chancellor's Theology of the Hypostatic Union (1975) ; all published by the Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, Toronto. 2 ST, III, qq. lil-6, written toward the end of Thomas's second Parisian regency, and especially q. 17, written after De unione V erbi lnearnati, constitute Thomas's contribution to and discussion of the mode of the Incarnation, See James Weisheipl, Friar Thomas d' Aquino (Garden City: Doubleday, 1974), pp. 307-815. 8 For further discussion of the history of this question, see Rudolf Haubst, (' Das hoch-und- spiitmittelalterliche 'Cur Deus homo?'" Miinchener Theologische Zeitschrift (1955), 302-303. Also Robert North, Teilhard and the Creation of the Soul (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1967), pp. 139-161. Whether there would have been an Incarnation if man had not sinned is a question primarily discussed within Latin theology during the high and late 524 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. late medieval thought and in the Christology of the Reformation and Counter-Reformation. The issue was expressed as follows: would God have become incarnate if man had not sinned? Would there be any ' reason ' for the Incarnation if there had been no need of redemption? Was the intention of God in becoming man to redeem humankind from sin, so that there would have been no Incarnation if there had not been sin? But, if there is ' more ' to the Incarnation than the goal of redemption, in what does this 'more' consist? Of course, in one sense, there is no way to answer such a question. Any response can easily become a faulty, speculative tendency to ' read the mind of God.' Can we know what God had in mind in becoming incarnate? Man can know that God became incarnate and that the Incarnation was redemptive, but can we know anything more than that? As Thomas Aquinas rightly points out, we can only know through what God has chosen to reveal to us. Does his revelation then tell us anything concerning this question? In the end, it is a question of what the Scriptures say, and it is in the interpretation of Scripture that different opinions emerge. Middle Ages. An exception seems to have been Isaac of Nineveh, 700 A.D. As North points out, Rupert of Deutz, c. 1100, raises the question, and Alexander of Hales, c. moo, does so as well. Albert the Great gives his opinion in the early thirteenth century. Robert Grosseteste agrees with Albert. Bonaventure, however, takes the opinion contrary to that of Albert, as does Thomas Aquinas. Alexander, Albert, Robert Grosseteste, generally represent the opinion later attributed to Duns Scotus. Bonaventure and Thomas maintain the opinion associated with Thomas. Theologians of the half century after Thomas accepted the opinion of Albert, e.g., Matthew of Aquasparta, Raymond Lull, Peter of Auvergne, William of Ware, Duns Scotus. John of St. Thomas and Cajetan later defended the view of Thomas. But Ambrose Catharinus and Giacomo Nacchianti, both Dominicans, did not follow Thomas on this issue. For a discussion of the view of Duns Scotus, see: Johannes Bissen, " De Motivo lncarnationis," Antonianum 7 (1932), 314-336; Robert North, Teilhard and the Creation of the Soul (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1967), 139-161; Edwin Rabbitte, "The 'Motive' of the Incarnation: Was Scotus a Scotist?" Irish Ecclesiastical Record 65 (1945), 117-125; Dominic Unger, "Franciscan Christology: Absolute and Universal Primacy of Christ, " Franciscan Studies 2 (1942), 428-475; Dominic Unger, "Robert Grosseteste, Bishop of Lincoln (1235-1253) on the Reasons for the Incarnation, " Franciscan Studies 16 (1956), 1-86. THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION 525 Setting aside the question of whether Scotus himself was a "scotist" on this particular question, what we have come to label the "scotist-thomist" controversy had little to do originally with the views of Thomas and Duns Scotus themselves, for the so-called " scotist " or Franciscan position had already been the opinion of the famous teacher of Thomas Aquinas, one of the greatest Dominican intellectuals of the Middle Ages, namely Albert. 4 On the other hand, Bonaventure,5 the great Franciscan, and Thomas both held the same opinion. The issue becomes something more than various theological opinions, however, with the Protestant Reform. For now" creation-centered" theology and " salvation-centered" theology are opposed to each other. For Luther, the Incarnation takes place for justification. The centrality of Scripture, of Paul, of justification, was emphasized and became a norm for Protestantism. Yet, to the Catholics, the Protestant Reform seemed to be a reaction which cut off rich theological traditions. To Catholic eyes, it appeared as if it were Luther alone who interpreted justification, and justification alone which was the norm for interpreting Paul; and, finally, Paul alone the norm for understanding Scripture. The issue of the relationship between creation, Incarnation, and redemption is not simply academic; it has ecumenical implications. In the days of Albert and Thomas we find both opinions peacefully held, more compatibly entertained than in the late medieval or post-Reformation theology. Other issues have complicated and intensified this one. It is too great a simplification to say that Greek theology and Franciscan theo4 Alexander of Hales, a Franciscan, prior to Albert, is also generally considered to have held this 'scotist' view. See Alexander of Hales, Summa theologica, III, pars 1, tractatus 1, quaestio 2, titulus 2 (Quaracchi edition, 1948, vol. 4, text, pp. 41-42) (Cologne edition, 1622, III, q. 2, m. 13). Haubst, p. 304, however, concludes it is difficult to know the precise opini-on of Alexander of Hales. 5 Bonaventure, Commentaria in libros sententiarum, III, distinctio 1, articulus 2, quaestio 2 (Quaracchi edition, 1887, vol. 3, pp. 21-28). Also see Alexander Schaefer, "The Position and Function of Man in the Created World According t-o St. Bonaventure," Franciscan Studies, 20 (1960), 261-316, and 21 (1961), 233-382. 526 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. logy tend to be creation-centered and cosmic, and that Latin theology and Thomas Aquinas tend to be salvation-centered. Thomas, arguing from Scripture, holds that salvation from sin is the motive of the Incarnation, but he also suggests that another motive is possible. It is also too simple to say that Catholicism is creation-centered and Protestantism salvation-centered. This question is also important because it has pastoral implications for morality, spirituality, politics and liturgy as well as ecumenism. Most contemporary Catholic christologies, such as that of Karl Rahner, are 'scotist.' 'Scotism' is found in contemporary Protestantism as well, as we see in the theology of Herbert Richardson and Wolfhart Pannenberg. The philosopher, Charles Sanders Peirce, was influenced by Scotus. Let us turn, then, to Albert and Thomas to see what we can learn from their theologies composed when the issue was less polemical. Albert on the Motive of the Incarnation 6 Three central ideas form the core of Albert's opinion and can be found in his solutio to the question. First, Albert manifests an awareness of the tenuous character of any opinion on this question. In the end, we simply do not know whether God would have become man if man had not sinned. The' motive' for the Incarnation involves the freedom of God and hence the incomprehensibility of that decisive choice. Thus Albert is modest about offering an opinion. His own view is not to be asserted strongly (nihil de hoc asserendo dico) ; it is uncertain (in hac 6 The chronology of Albert's life poses many difficulties. Sometime after 1!?40 he came to Paris, where he lectured on the Sentences of Peter Lombard for at least two years, c. H!43-1245, and possibly for four years, 1241-H!45. During the summer of 1248 Albert went to Cologne to organize the first Dominican studium generale in Germany. The final revision of Book IV of the was completed in Cologne in 1249. He was elected provincial of the German province in 1254. He died in 1280, about 80 years old. See Weisheipl, Friar Thomas, pp. 32-51; also Weisheipl, "The Life and Works of St. Albert the Great," Albertus Magnus and the Sciences-Commemorative Essays 1980, edited by James Weisheipl, Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, Toronto, 1980). THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION 527 quaestione solutio incerta est) ; and it is expressed reservedlyinsofar as an opinion can he formed (quantum possum opinari) .7 Second, Albert's opinion is that" the son of God would have become man even if there had never been sin." Albert's opinion is not the same as that of Thomas; nor, however, is it as far removed from Thomas's as it first appears to be. Third, Albert offers his opinion hesitantly but still sees it as more probable (probabilius) because, as he says, it is more in accord with the piety of faith (credo hoo quad dixi, magis concordare pietati fidei) . His reason, given the uncertainty of either opinion, for being inclined more to one side of the question than to the other is based on what seems to him to agree with the life of the faithful. 8 Let us look at Albert's discussion a little more closely. If man had not sinned, he asks, would the Son of God have become incarnate? Albert first gives four reasons why God would not have become incarnate if man had not sinned, and to each of these he subsequently replies. Then Albert presents the other side and states six reasons why God would have become incarnate even if man had not sinned. These " sed contra " arguments cannot be identified with Albert's opinion itself, for he also replies to all six of these and disagrees with all six. In accord with the style of the Schools, Albert is giving the arguments for both sides, but he does not then simply accept one side. None of the arguments on either side stands; hence both opinions are uncertain. This uncertainty is Albert's most fundamental assertion. The basis 7 Albert's discussion and direct quotations from him are from his commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Book III, distinction 20, article 4. For secondary sources, see Haubst, p. 305, and North, p. 141. See V. M. Pollet, "Le Christ d'apres saint Albert le Grand," La Vie spirituelle, 34-35 (1933), 78-108. 8 I have translated "pietas fidei" as " the piety of faith. " It is not immediately clear how Albert understands the expression. Pietas can mean piety, devoutness, the devotional life, the practice of the faith. Fides refers to the faith, the life of faith. Perhaps pietas fidei can be seen as the life of the faithful, the practice of the faith. I use " the piety of faith " as a translation in order to avoid interpretation, but " the life of faith " or simply " the Christian life " might render it better. 528 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. on which he then expresses a preference is his understanding of the piety of faith. Let us look briefly at some of these pros and cons. He offers the following arguments in favor of the opinion that God would not have become incarnate if man had not sinned. The first two arguments are the liturgical use of the Exultet sequence of Easter, and its felix culpa theology. With this approach, however, Albert disagrees. He writes, "Such ways of speaking as calling a fault ' blessed ' or ' happy ' are most improper, for it is not called blessed or happy in itself but from what follows upon it. . .. The Incarnation of Christ is not a consequence of the fault; nevertheless, the great works of redemption ... did come after the fault." Hence the poetic felix culpa argument does not prove that, if there had been no sin, there would have been no Incarnation. Properly speaking the fault is not " blessed " in itself, but only incidentally, since the works of redemption do follow it and are grace. The third argument is based on Romans 8: 28, that all things work unto good for those who love God. A gloss includes, "even sins." So good can come even from original sin and this good is the incarnate Christ; if there had been no sin, there would have been no need for Incarnation. The fault in this argument is the gloss. For Albert, sin does not work unto good except incidentally, e.g., by making someone more vigilant. Hence one cannot link the Incarnation only to original sin. Redemption does follow upon sin, but one does not know whether there would have been an Incarnation or not if there had been no sin. To assume that the Incarnation is tied only to redemption would be begging the question. The fourth argument is that without sin there would be no need for liberation or redemption. 1£ man had not sinned, God would not have manifested so great a love as he did after sin had been committed. To this Albert replies that Christ might still have become incarnate to demonstrate his infinite love and to prepare multiple delights for us since he regards us as brothers and sisters. THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION Albert therefore does not accept the above arguments; in one form or other they all beg the question. Incarnation and redemption are in fact related, but would they have to be so in such a way that there could not be one without the need for the other? Albert is unconvinced that they are 'necessarily' tied together. God could have become incarnate in any case. Whether he would have is another question, and Albert's response is-we do not know. Does Albert accept the other opinion: that God would have become incarnate even if man had not sinned? This position is also flawed. The first opinion is false because it states that God would not have become incarnate apart from sin; the second is false because it states that God would have become incarnate apart from sin. Albert's opinion is that God could have (hence the first opinion is false) , but that we do not know whether he would have (hence the second opinion is false). Albert's own opinion is that probably God would have become incarnate but we cannot conclude that with certainty. The freedom of God underlies Albert's opinion. The first opinion is false because it denies the freedom of God to become incarnate and the second because it denies God's freedom not to. These stated opinions do not sufficiently esteem the freedom of God. Albert offers six reasons as to why God would have become incarnate even if man had not sinned, all six of which he also rejects. The first one is the axiom, Goodness is diffusive of itself. God cannot better diffuse himself than by becoming incarnate. Albert replies: Goodness diffuses itself according to the capacity of those who receive it. The union of the divine and human is not something merited by human nature itself. Hence it was not necessary for God to share Himself in this way. Again Albert presumes God's freedom. The next is similar to the first. " The greatest love shares itself in the greatest way. But there can be no greater love than when someone joins himself to another. Therefore since God's love for man was so great, he would unite himself to him. There- 530 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. fore it seems that God would unite himself to man even if man had not sinned." Albert replies, " The manifestation of his love in glorification was enough, for it was not necessary that God manifest every manner of love," Again Albert appeals to God's freedom. There is no need to look at all of the six statements along with Albert's objections to them. One further example is sufficient, the third argument: " An angel is not capable of being united to the divine nature, but man is capable of being united. Since no aptitude is created by God in vain, therefore it was necessary that God become incarnate." But, for Albert, "this aptitude is not from nature but from the grace of election .... It is not necessary that God do anything whatsoever in the best way in which he could have done it if he had so willed, but it is enough that he does things as he wills, as long as he does not deny to them anything concerning their nature." Albert, then, is hesitant and uncertain about any opinion which involves the divine will and freedom; hence his position is that we do not know whether God would have become incarnate or not if man had not sinned. But the opinion that God would have become incarnate is probable for Albert simply because it is congruent with the piety of faith. It certainly would be fitting for God to do so. The Early Thomas: The Commentary on the Sentences In his commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Thomas's view appears closer to his master and teacher, Albert, than the thomist opinion might lead one to believe.9 He is 9 Thomas studied under Albert shortly after Albert was preparing his own lectures on the Sentences. It is not certain whether he had already studied under Albert in Paris. If he did, he would have been with him from l!M5-1252. Nevertheless, he studied under him in Cologne from 1248-1252. In 1252, Thomas went back to Paris and lectured on the Sentences from l!M2-Hl56, at the age of 27. Undoubtedly at this time Albert's influence on Thomas is strong. Thomas's Summa comes later. He worked on the first questions of the tertia pars, the christological section, in 1272. He stopped writing toward the end of 1273, and he died in 1274. Albert was still alive. (Cf. Weisheipl, Friar Thomas, pp. 67-80, 289-320), THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION 531 aware of the soundness of both positions with respect to this question and also the tenuousness of each. The arguments for neither side are necessary. In fact, in the commentary, Thomas does not adhere strongly to either opinion. Thomas gives seven reasons in favor of the opinion that God would have become incarnate even if man had not sinned. 10 He then gives four reasons for the contrary opinion. His own response is that either view can be sustained. He is aware of the "probable" character of both views, and maintains that both views can be held-held as probable. He expresses no direct preference for either. Thomas begins his response with a theological and methodological principle. Only he who willed the Incarnation could know its motive. That which depends on the will of God alone cannot be known by us, or rather can be known only insofar as it has been revealed, hence insofar as it is in the Scriptures and the holy exposition of Scripture. In Scripture, however, the only cause assigned to the Incarnation is the redemption of man from the slavery of sin. Hence some say that" probably" the Son of God would not have become man if man had not sinned. As a support for this opinion, Thomas quotes Pope Leo and St. Augustine. It is interesting-given the principles, and given Thomas's apparent conviction that this is the 'reason' most consistent with Scripture-that he still speaks only of the probability of the opinion, not its conclusiveness. The major support for this opinion, however, is its basis in revelation itself. Thomas then considers the opinion of others who would maintain that, in fact, the Incarnation accomplished not only a liberation from sin but also the exaltation of human nature and the consummation of the whole universe. Hence, even if there were no sin, these other causes would have motivated an Incarnation. And Thomas writes of this opinion: " This can also probably be upheld." Thomas recognizes that those who uphold the first opinion speak of it as probable, and those who maintain the other opin1 ° For this discussion and the references, see Thomas Aquinas, Scriptum super libros. Sententiarum, III, distinction 1, question 1, article 3. l:>ONALf> GOERGEN, 6.P. ion can also sustain their view as probable. It appears as if Thomas does not hold to either opinion himself, and is, then, not so far from the stance of Albert. All seven arguments in favor of the proposition that God would have become incarnate even apart from the need for redemption are quite speculative. To each of these, Thomas replies that the argument is not conclusive. For example, the fourth argument favors the opinion that God would have become incarnate even apart from sin because human nature is not expanded or enhanced as a result of sin. Yet human nature was found in the Incarnation to be capable of assumption into union with a divine person. Therefore it must have been capable of being so assumed even prior to or without sin. Moreover, God does not deny to the creature any good which it is capable of receiving, and so he would have assumed human nature even if man had not sinned. To this Thomas replies by distinguishing the capabilities of a creature as natural potencies from those which belong to our fundamental nature, to our obediential potencies which are not part of our nature but which point to what God can still choose or will. The capacity of human nature to he assumed into unity with a divine person is not a natural but an obediential potency. God does not deny any good which is in the order of a natural potency, but the fulfillment of an obediential potency is different. God is not bound to fulfill obediential potencies, simply because he is not bound to do everything that he can in fact do. One notes here the emphasis on divine freedom so central to Albert's theology. Aquinas's four statements, however, which express the view that God would not have become man apart from the need for redemption are either biblical or patristic. The arguments rest on Luke 19: 10, 1Tim.1: 15; and upon a union of Hebrews 2: 14 and Romans 5: 12; comments of Augustine as well as Gregory the Great are used. 11 In the article's conclusion, Aquinas responds to these four statements, to all who maintain that there 11 Thomas's text in the Sentences links the Augustine's gloss to Matthew 18: 11, but Luke 19: 10 (so identified in the Summa theol.) is meant. ' THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION 588 would have been no Incarnation if there had been no sin; he briefly states that these maintain that Christ came for ransom or redemption (ad redimendum) and not simply, i.e., without qualification (non simpliciter) . We are led to conclude that Thomas has some sympathy for the opinion that God became man £or the sake of redemption. He does not express at this point an explicit preference for one opinion or the other, and he is aware that either opinion can be sustained as probable. Like Albert, he shows an awareness of the tenuousness of the discussion. He is sensitive to theological method, to the limits within which a theologian can speak, to the theologian's dependency on Scripture in this issue. He is not quick to eliminate a contrary opinion as simply unacceptable, even when there are some biblical or patristic grounds for doing so. Yet Thomas is inclined in the direction of saying that, if there had been no sin, there would have been no need for redemption, and thus no Incarnation: (I) the very basis of his own responsio is that we can only speak on this question from what has been revealed in Scripture; (2) the supports for this particular opinion are scriptural, whereas the supports for the other opinion are speculative; (8) this opinion forms the bulk of his response and comes first, whereas the other opinion is listed second and described as also or likewise (etiam) probable; and (4) he makes no effort to contradict this opinion, whereas he replies to each of the seven arguments in favor of the opinion that there still would have been an Incarnation. Yet, although Thomas preferred one opinion, he acknowledges the limits of either opinion, refrains from taking sides explicitly, and allows the other to stand with almost equal probability. Thomas was certainly aware that the direction his own inclination takes would lead to an opinion different from that of Albert. The Late Thomas: The Summa Theologiae As we move from Thomas's Commentary on the Sentences to his Summa theologiae, the opinion of Thomas becomes explicit 534 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. but no less careful. 12 The tertia pars of the Summa contains Thomas's theology of the person of Christ. The very first ques'" tion inquires 'de conV'enientia incarnationis.' Thomas recognizes, at least, a pedagogical importance attached to the question of the " suitability " or " appropriateness " of the Incarnation. This question is a prologue to the tertia pars, an introductory preface before Thomas discusses the nature of the union itself. Of the six articles in the first question, only the third article concerns us, asking whether, if the human race had not sinned, there would have been nonetheless an Incarnation. Thomas begins his response by acknowledging that " there is a difference of opinion on this matter." "Some say that even if man had not sinned, the Son of God would have become incarnate. Others assert the contrary; and agreement with them seems preferable." Here Thomas makes his preference explicit; it is a preference, however, not a conclusive argument. His language does not reject the probable character of his earlier discussion. That the Son would not have become incarnate apart from sin seems more likely, more probable. But why? That which comes forth from the divine will is a mystery the reasons for which cannot be known in and of themselves; they can only be known if God chooses to reveal them, if they are contained in Scripture. It is Thomas's opinion (and was already so in his commentary on the Sentences) that in Scripture the sin of the first man is given as the reason for the Incarnation. Thus " it is preferable (convenientius dicitur) to hold that the work of the Incarnation is ordered by God as a remedy for sin, in such a way that, if there had been no sin, there would have been no Incarnation." Aquinas adds the qualification: " Divine power, of course, is not limited to this, for God could have become incarnate even if there had been no sin." Again, as with Albert, it is important to distinguish what God could have done, would have done, and what in fact he did do. For Thomas, God in fact did become incarnate in order to save us from the effects of sin. He could have, however, become in12 See ST, III, q. 1, a. 8. THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION 535 carnate even if there had been no sin. The question then is whether God would have become incarnate apart from sin. Here Thomas maintains that we can only inquire into this question on the basis of what Scripture says since there is no other way of knowing. Disagreement with Thomas would have to be on the basis of Thomas's interpretation of Scripture or on his methodological presuppositions (e.g., the divine will cannot be known unless revealed; revelation is contained in Scripture). One might disagree with Thomas by arguing either (1) that Scripture itself in other texts does not limit the effects of the Incarnation to redemption, the removal of the effects of sin, or that Scripture is speaking only about what God in fact did choose to do, and not about what he might have chosen or would have done if there had been no sin. Scripture would not in fact seem to address the specific question of what God would have done. Given the existential, historical, non-speculative character of the Scriptures, one might well argue in this vein and conclude with the early Aquinas that the other opinion is also probable and fitting. Thomas Aquinas, however, understood Scripture to say that God became man for salvation. In the Summa he does not cite all the biblical references that he used in the Sentences. The sed contra includes approvingly a comment of Augustine on Luke 19: 10 and the Gloss on I Tim. I: 15. The Scriptures, Augustine, and the Gloss 18 help make his final opinion " more probable." The weight Thomas grants Augustine and the Gloss cannot be underestimated. There are two other places where Thomas makes his preferred opinion clear: in his Commentary on the First Epistle to Timothy and in his disputation, On Truth. 14 13 The Gloss is the Glossa ordinaria of Anselm of Laon and his assistants, working about 1100-1130, the standard medieval commentary on the Bible. B. Smalley identifies Anselm himself as responsible for the Gloss on Paul, Gilbert de Ia Porree, Anselm's pupil, and Peter Lombard were responsible for Anselm's glosses becoming the standard, the Gloss; The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages (Notre Dame: University Press, pp. 46-66, pp. 60-66). 14 The writings on the date from rn52-rn56. The first questions of the tertia pars of the Summa are from 1272. The commentary on 1 Timothy 536 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. 1 Timothy 1: 15 states, "The saying is sure and worthy of full acceptance, that Christ Jesus came into the world to save sinners." Thomas writes in his commentary on this epistle: But if there had been no sinner, would he have become incarnate? It seems not, because he came to save sinners. Therefore the Incarnation was not necessary. Thus the Gloss: take away the illness and there will be no need of medicine. I respond. From the words of the saints, this is clear enough. But this question is not of great authority because God ordained that things come about according as they are to come about. And we do not know what he would have ordained if he had not had foreknowledge of sin. Nevertheless authorities seem to say explicitly that he would not have become incarnate if man had not sinned, toward which opinion I am more inclined. 15 As in the Summa, Thomas also makes his opinion explicit but points out that this opinion is not authoritative. Thomas also writes in the De V'eritate, "Christ's humanity is related differently to angels than to men ... with respect to the end of the Incarnation, which was carried out principally for the sake of man's liberation from sin; and so Christ's humanity is ordained to the influence which he exercises upon men as the end intended, whereas his influence upon the angels is not the end of the Incarnation but a consequence of the Incarnation." 16 A Final Perspective Both Albert and Thomas are aware of the uncertain character of both opinions. Both are aware of the theological and methodological issues involved. Their "opinions" are less far apart than they seem to be when taken out of the context of discussion and theological method. Each would acknowledge his own dates from the second Parisian regency,, 1269-1272. De veritate, question 29, is dated during the third year of the first Parisian regency, 1258-1259. Thus Thomas's opinion becomes explicit between 1256 and 1258. For the above datings, see Weisheipl, Friar Thomas. 16 In Epistolam 1 ad Timotheum, lectio 4. 16 De veritate, q. 2:1, a. 4, ad 5. THE MOTIVE OF THE INCARNATION 537 opinion as being more of a preference than a certain conclusion; each would be open to the other opinion as probable. In Albert's approach three points stand out. First, God could have become incarnate even if there were no need for redemption from sin; supporting this is a theology of the freedom and power of God. Second, we do not know whether God would have become incarnate or not. Any opinion on this question will be uncertain, for God's freedom is central to Albert's Christology. Third, his own opinion on the second point above is that the Son of God probably would have become incarnate if there had been no sin, even though we cannot be certain of this. Here he refers to the piety of faith. Thomas represents an equally careful approach to the issue. In his Commentary on the Sentences Thomas would agree with the possibility apart from sin. With respect to the third point, he does not make explicit an opinion one way or the other. He is developing the methodological issues which lie underneath Albert's second point mentioned above. As Thomas insists that either opinion can be maintained (and both are only probable) he draws out the implication of Albert's emphasis on the freedom of God. That which depends on the will of God cannot be known by us as to whether it would have taken place or not, except through what has been revealed through Scripture. Thomas implies that the reason for the Incarnation as found in Scripture is that of redemption. The Summa theologiae does not develop any new directions; Thomas makes his implicit preference explicit. The still uncertain, but now expressed as more probable because of Scripture-is sin as the reason for the Incarnation. There could have been an Incarnation, but, more probably, there would not have been as far as we can judge from Scripture. Does Aquinas go too far in the Summa? Do the Sentences represent a view more consistent with his method? We can recall that Scripture only gives the primary reason why God did become incarnate and does not discuss other motives apart 538 DONALD GOERGEN, O.P. from sin. His method leaves us between divine freedom and historical fact. The difference between Thomas and Albert is that Thomas tends to see Scripture as more congruent with the opinion that, if there had been no sin, there would not have been an Incarnation. Albert sees the piety of faith as a support for a creation-centered theology of the Incarnation, a view of incarnation in humanity and history with or without sin. DONALD GOERGEN, Aquinas Institute of Theology Dubuque, Iowa O.P. ALBERT THE GREAT AND MARTIN LUTHER ON JUSTIFICATION O NE RESULT of the ecumenical revolution which occurred in that remarkable decade, the 1960s, was the appearance of a number of studies comparing Thomas Aquinas and Martin Luther. Stephen Pfiirtner uncovered similarities between Luther's understanding of faith and Aquinas's theology of hope. Harry McSorley displayed in Augustine, Aquinas and Luther a triad of interpretations of free will, sinful bondage and grace. H. Vorster's book on freedom in Aquinas and Luther represented a Protestant contribution to this conversation between two of the great Western theologians. The final position of consummate achievement belongs to Otto Pesch's one thousand page study of justification in Aquinas and Luther. 1 Some German reviewers of these books, sensitive to history and historicity, pointed out the cultural and intellectual distance between Aquinas and Luther. As if in support of this gap, McSorley and Pesch had shown that Luther had little if any direct knowledge of Aquinas's writings. 2 Nonetheless, cultural history and the question of comparing one thinker and his 1 S. Pfiirtner, Luther and Thomas on Sol,vation (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1965); H. McSorley, Luther, Right or Wrong (New York: Paulist, 1969); H. Vorster, Das Freheitsverstiindnis bei Thomas von Aquin und Martin Luther (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1965); O. Pesch, Die Theologie der Rechtfertigung bei Martin Luther und Thomas. von Aquin (Mainz: Griinewald, 1967); C. Hennig, Cajetan und Luther (Stuttgart: Calwer, 1966). This enterprise began with Y. Congar, "Luther," Vraie et fausse reforme dans l'eglise (Paris: Cerf, 1950), pp. 377ff. On the changing view of Luther in Catholic scholarship in general, cf. R. Stauffer, Luther as Seen by Cavholics (Richmond: John Knox, 1967). 2 Cf. McSorley, pp. 139f., and Pesch, "Existential and Sapiential Theology. The Theological Confrontation between Luther and Thomas Aquinas," Catholic Scholars Diol,ogue with Luther (Chicago: Loyola, 1970), pp. 6lfl'. 539 540 THOMAS F. O'MEARA, O.P. Zeit.geist with another cannot be quickly dismissed. To select thinkers from different ages and to claim that they easily or clearly agree, or that they participate in some single, eternal, transcendental truth is to deserve the critique of scholars and the burial ·Of history itself. Weltgeschichte will be the Weltgericht of such an enterprise. If, however, we wish to understand why two thinkers from admittedly different cultural worlds (such as the Parisian thirteenth and the German sixteenth centuries) do disagree, then our enterprise is legitimate. For to compare two thinkers adequately and fairly is at the same time to compare their cultural worlds and to see both the similarities and differences therein. The following essay does indeed abstract from the thought-forms of Luther and Albert, which are quite different. We will look at the issue of justification, especially of justification within or apart from the activity of the human personality of the one justified. Although truth is not easily timeless, it is possible to examine how an Albert and a Luther, an Augustine and a Biel maneuver within the dialectic of the grace of an omnipotent God and the fallen freedom of a creature. In counterposing Aquinas and Luther, scholars in the 1960s were doing more than comparing two of the great figures in Western Christian theology. They were doing more than composing the counterpoint of an ecumenical fugue. For Aquinas and Luther are not only individuals: they formed the collective consciousness of parts of Christianity. And this primal role belongs also to Aquinas's teacher, for not only is he a medieval thinker of import but before Aquinas he gave the momentum to the great thirteenth century. The Roman Catholic has until recently thought almost exclusively out of an Aristotelian-Thomist framework; the catechisms of Catholicism since Trent are, in the main, simplified scholasticism. The Lutheran family of the Reformation, however, thinks out of the framework of Paul and Augustine which Luther vivified anew. For instance, for the Roman Catholic, sin is a free, disoriented action contrary to the natural and ALBERT AND LUTHER ON JUSTIFICATION 541 eschatological plan of God; for the Lutheran, sin is the human condition, the prior and present ecology of our world before God's wrath and word. Despite the recent decades of a theology of grace which is more biblical and more personal, the Roman Catholic tends to imagine grace to be an intermediary, dynamic entity with which God moves my will to do good; for the Lutheran, grace is God's attitude towards me, merciful, forgiving, just but loving. So, to compare Luther with Aquinas was and remains worthwhile, for it has been the contrast not only of men, but of churches, of theologies, of world-views. U. Kuhn begins his comparison of Aquinas and Luther on law by suggesting that not only is Aquinas typical of the Roman Catholic mentality, but that Baroque scholasticism must be passed through so that in the real contributions and limits of medieval theologians Lutherans as well as Catholics can find teachers. 3 This anniversary year of Albertus MUo