The JANUARY '83 THOMIST begins with a reexamination of the attempt to reconcile God's existence with the phenomenon of evil and suffering that is all pervasive in the world. Is such evil inevitable in the light of finite freedom (as Alan Plantinga argues)? Or could God preclude all evil without doing violence to created freedom? Theodore Kondoleon argues, against Plantinga, for the latter, insisting that to admit the principle as a logical possibility not in fact actually realized, need not be interpreted as telling against the existence of God. Following this is a somewhat original reflection on the focal Thomistic notion of analogy which, when seen as a phenomenon of language rather than as anal,ogia entis, more closely approximates the preference for dialectical speech about God operative in Reformed Theology. Colman O'Neill draws out the ecumenical implications of this by suggesting a development of analogical method into a general hermeneutic for all interpretations of the Judaeo-Christian tradition, one wherein analogy is concerned with knowledge already acquired rather than with knowing the unknown. Next is a stimulating essay by George A. Kendall suggesting that mankind's contemporary sense of alienation is rooted in a refusal of creaturehood. This amounts in fact to an ideology, in sharp contrast to the biblical view of the struggle for existence as due to the creature's living in a wrong relationship to their Creator. Subsequent to this is a piece of historical scholarship from Francis E. Kelley on an early (late thirteenth century) Thomistic thinker, Robert Orford, discerning in his writings influences from Giles of Rome, an Augustinian against whom Orford ordinarily reacted in polemical fashion. Kees de Kuyer then offers a reflecton on Heidegger's search for the meaning of ground, by way of Leibniz's principle: Nihil est sine ratione. The implications of this enable Heidegger to maintain that every being has its source in Being, shedding some light on his constant contention that " the thoughtworthy is the unthought discovered as the depth dimension of the already thought". Lastly is a" Review Discussion" of Alan Donagan's Theory of Moral,ity in which Stephen Theron expresses strong reservations on Donagan's contention that law in morals does not require a divine lawgiver. Rounding out the issue are reviews of nine recent books of significance, featuring a lengthy reflection on Jurgen Moltmann's innovative reconcep. tualization of the doctrine of the Trinity, and reactions to Edward Schillebeeckx's two provocative studies of Christian ministry. W.J.H. THE FREE WILL DEFENSE: NEW AND OLD O RIGINATING WITH Augustine (See On the Free Chmce of the Will, particularly Book III) , the Free Will Defense (hereafter FWD) is the strategy most Christian apologists have relied upon to meet the atheologian's challenge that the existence of evil, acy evil, but particularly the amount and quality of actual evil, is incompatible with the existence of God. 1 In its most general or widely accepted form this defense amounts to the following argument: (1) A universe containing moral free agents who can choose or reject God as their ultimate good (and i.n which there is also, presumably, a greater balance of moral good over moral evil 2) is a universe that surpasses in value any universe lacking such While God, in creating free agents, makes moral creatures; evil possible, the free agent is itself, by its own act of choice, directly responsible for this evil of action which He, God, nonetheless permits for the sake of certain goods to which it is logically presupposed; and, finally, (3) Aside from moral evil, 1 For some recent discuussions of this subject see Alvin Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1974), Chapter 9 and God, Freedom and Evil (New York): Harper Torchbooks, 1974). For the atheologian's side see II. J. McCloskey, God and Evil (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974). Also see J. L. Mackie, "Evil and Omnipotence," Mind, LXIV (1955), pp. 200-!?12 and "Theism and Utopia," Philosophy, XXXVII (1962), pp. 153-158; and Antony Flew, "Divine Omnipotence and Human Freedom," New Essays in Philosophical Theology, ed. A. Flew and A. Macintyre (Nfilw York: The Macmillan Company, 1964). 2 In his FWD, at least as he presents it in On the Free Choice of the Will, Augustine neglects to include this proviso as an essential part of such a defense. Aquinas, 011 the other hand, seems to have been a little more sensitive to this point since he, at least, contends that given the existence of angela and their existence in great multitude the amount of moral good in the universe resulting from the exercise of free will exceeds the amount of moral evil. On this point see Summa Theologiae, I. Q. 63, a. 9, c. and ad I. 1 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON other evils befalling man in this life (as well as in the next) come under the heading of evil of punishment. 3 At first glance the FWD would appear to reconcile God's existence with what, from the human standpoint, are the major forms of evil in the world, and even one contemporary atheologian has felt compelled to remark how "it is a powerful defense, which has satisfied many believers and routed or at least rattled many sceptics." 4 Nonetheless, the more undaunted of their number (Flew included) , rather than withdraw from the attack, have scanned it for possible weaknesses and claim to have found it vulnerable, even fatally so, in the following two areas. (I) Granted a universe containing moral free agents (and in which moral good outweighs moral evil) is superior in goodness to any universe which would lack such creatures, still God could have created a universe which would include free agents but one in which all these agents would always choose rightly. God could have done this because it is evidently something logically possible and, therefore, God as all-powerful could have brought it about. 5 Clearly, or so it would seem, Christian teaching evil of punishment includes not 3 According to traditional only the punishment inflicted because of one's own personal sins but also the punishment inflicted on all men because of original sin. However, in Plantinga's FWD (as we shall see) one possible explanation of natural evil, considered evil because it causes human suffering, is that it is due to the evil actions of Satan and his cohorts. Plantinga claims to find this explanation of natural evil in Augustine (I do not, but more on this later). Yet to be consistent with Augustine if not nlso with traditional Christian belief, he would have to allow that such evils that " natural evil " c>auses would not have befallen man if Adam had not sinned. 4 A. Flew, op. cit., p. 146. 5 As Mackie puts this point: "If God has made men such that in their free choice they sometimes prefer what is good and sometime' what is evil, why could he not have made men such that they always freely cho:Joe the good? If there is no logical impossibility in a man's freely choosing the good on one, or on several occasions, there cannot be a logical impossibility of his freely choosing the good on every occasion. God was not, then, faced with a choice between making innocent automata and making beings who,- in acting freely, would sometimes go wrong; there was open to him the obviously better possibility of making beings who would act freely but always go right. Clearly, his failure to avail himself of this possibility is inconsistent with his being both omnipotent and wholly good." "Evil and Omnipotence," p. 209. The two versons of the FWD that I will ex- THE FREE WILL DEFENSE: NEW AND OLD s such a universe would give greater testimony to His wisdom and goodness than a universe in which some (even one) are permitted to sin and to remain attached to an undue end thereby forfeiting happiness. Therefore, as infinitely good and wise, God would be expected to do what is better here and create a sinless world. Since, obviously, He has not done so, He must not exist. (Q) The amoun.t of moral evil in the actual world, to say nothing of the great pain and suffering consequent upon such evil, some of which is visited upon the innocent but which has also to include the stern punishment a divine justice would be expected to mete out to the wicked, precludes any possible justification for its divine permission. Therefore, even if this world were the best God could create (as some have argued, in one form or other, it is), He should still have refrained from creating it. 6 However, prim.a facie, it would certainly appear that God could, and therefore should, have done better. Evidently, then, He must not exist. A relatively recent and somewhat ingenious version of the FWD, that proposed by Alvin Plantinga, has been designed to meet this renewed attack by contemporary atheologians. It consists chiefly of arguing (1) possibly God could not have created a world containing moral agents without also permitting sm and amine above have two quite different replies to Mackie's objection. One, Plantinga's, will contend that possibly it was not within God's power to create beings who would act freely but always go right; the other, Saint Thomas's, will concede that God could have done this but that it would not necessarily have been the better thing to do. 6 On this point see McCloskey, op. cit., p. 80. To quote him in part on this matter: " A wholly good, omnipotent God would refrain from creating a world in which evil predominated even were this the best possible world he could create. I suggest therefore that the underlying suggestion that evil is justified if this is the best of all possible worlds is mistaken." Here McCloskey is obviously addressing himself to the problem of actual evil and it is his considered view that, in light of the enormity of human suffering and the amount and kinds of moral evil, this world is not a world that an all-perfect being would have created. But more on this later. ' 4 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON (Q) possibly God could not have created a world containing ,a greater balance of moral good over " broadly " moral evil than the actual world contains. 7 Since (1) contradicts (3) (necessarily) God could have created a universe containing moral agents none of whom would ever sin and (Q) contradicts (4) (necessarily) God could have created a universe containing a greater balance of moral good over broadly moral evil than the actual world contains, if both are demonstrably true, then the whole of the atheologian's renewed attack would have been met and soundly defeated. Moreover, since the traditional version of the FWD (e.g. that to be found in Augustine and Aquinas) would allow that God could have created a universe containing free agents and willed (or caused it to be) that none of them would ever sin, Plantinga's version seems less vulnerable to attack and thus, if true, would seem to provide a stronger defense if not also a definitive solution to the problem of evil. 8 In what follows I propose to examine Plantinga's FWD primarily from the standpoint of its philosophical acceptability. In this connection I shall argue that, aside from certain theological objections to which, perhaps, it lies even more exposed, it involves a philosophical mistake with respect to God's knowledge, one that adversely affects its understanding of His power, and must, therefore, be rejected as false. I will then co)lsider the case made against God's existence, based upon evil, by one contemporary atheologian, namely, McCloskey, and attempt a solution along traditional, principally Thomistic, lines. I. Plantinga's FWD 1. A note on free will. Basic to Piantinga's FWD, as well as to its other versions, are the following two assumptions. (1) 7 Plantinga includes under " broadly " moral evil any evil resulting from the morally evil acts of free agents. See The Nature of Necessity, pp. 192-193. s See, for example, Saint Augustine, The City of God, Book XIV, ch. 27. THE FREE WILL DEFENSE: NEW AND OLD 5 Certain created beings are free agents, i.e. they are not necessitated (or determined) to this or that particular good (real or apparent) but have it within their power to determine for themselves, a;t the very moment of choice, which of two opposing goods they will have to use or enjoy. (2) The most significant choice a created free agent can make (one which, generally speaking, they all must make) is the choice between a· real and an apparent good, or the choice between moral good and evil. While neither of these two assumptions entails the inevitability of moral evil in a God-created universe containing free agents, they do imply the genuine possibility of such evil in such a universe. However, some contemporary atheologians, in attacking the FWD, have argued that God could have created man (or any other free agent) so, or of such a nature, that he would always choose rightly and therefore need not have risked even so much as the possibility of moral evil in His universe. 9 One, Flew, actually argues this position from the standpoint of compatibilism (something which McCloskey apparently rejects) .10 However, his argument to support this theory is a curious one and completely fails to prove its point. 11 9 See Mackie, " Theism and Utopia," p. 155. Also see Flew, op. cit., pp. 149157 and McCloskey, op. cit., 118-119. In these references Mackie contends that " it was logically possible for God to make men such that they would always freely choose to do good," and McCloskey inquires " Why, then, given the love a man may have for God and his fellow man, could not men be so made as never to incline to evil but to incline to acts of love which are good?" However, Flew argues his position from the standpoint of compatibilism. 10 See ibid., p. 117. To quote him on this point: "It is not possible here to enter into a discussion of whether we do or do not possess free will. Instead I simply note what follows if we lack freedom, namely that there would be no problem of moral evil but a more perplexing problem of physical evil. I shall assume that free will is incompatible with complete determinism." 11 To give Flew's argument here: " to say that a person could have helped doing something is not to say what he did was in principle unpredictable nor that there were no causes anywhere which determined that he would as a matter of fact act in this way. It is to say that if he had chosen to do otherwise he would have been able to do so, that there were alternatives within the capacities of one of his physical strength, of his I. Q., with his knowledge and open to a person in his situation." P. 150. In other words, according to Flew an action can be said to be free, even though antecedently determined by causes over which the 6 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON Moreover, if Flew is right about compatibilism, then one may well wonder how men can be morally faulted for acting the way they do and God for creating man the way he is. I would think, then, that the problem of moral evil depends upon a non-deterministic conception of free will and, therefore, that an attempt at its solution can equally proceed on the same premise. However, I am quite willing to concede to the atheologian that freedom of choice need not entail the possibility of moral evil. One has only to mention in this connection God and the angels in heaven. 12 Moreover, unlike Plantinga, I am also willing to allow that God could have created free agents yet so ordered things that no one would ever sin. But I will return to this point later in the discussion. Let me for the moment proceed on the assumption (I believe a correct one) that, given the actual order of things, for those of us who do not possess the absolute good or a special privilege of grace, the possibility of making a morally wrong choice (i.e. a choice opposed to the divine rule) can always arise. 13 However, the atheologian could still pursue the present line of attack by asking, Could not God have created a universe containing moral free agents each one of whom always, and this purely contingently, chooses rightly? Since there would appear to be nothing logically contradictory in this latter state of affairs, it can be argued that God should have created such a universe. It is this particular challenge that Plantinga's FWD principally intends to meet. 2. Plantinga's FWD and Universal Transworld Depravity. As I have already noted, Plantinga's version of the FWD argues that it may not be within God's power to create a world containing free agents no one of whom would ever make a morally wrong choice. If this is true, then possibly God should agent had no control, if the agent, it to- decide to do the opposite, would be able to do so. But this is like arguing that a perfectly normal and healthy person even though bound hands and feet is free to walk because if he were unbound he could do just that! 12 See Summa Theoi., I, Q. 19, a. 9, ad 2, and Q. 62, a. 8, c. and ad 2 and ad S. 1a See ibid., Q. 62, a. 8 and Q. 100, a. 2. THE FREE WILL DEFENSE: NEW AND OLD 7 not be faulted for not having done so, or for creating the world He (supposedly) did create, since, possibly, this was the only option open to Him consistent with His goodness and His decision to create. We have now to determine how correct Plantinga is in arguing this defense. To begin with, Plantinga willingly allows that a world containing free agents in which no one ever sins is a possible one for, evidently, there is nothing contradictory in the notion of a multitude of free agents all of whom always choose rightly. What is more, he also upholds the view of God's power which asserts that it can effect, or bring about, any possible state of affairs so long as its being brought about does not involve a contradiction. How then, one might ask, can Plantinga possibly oppose the view that God could have created a world containing free agents but one without moral evil ? But this would be to overlook the most important weapon in his whole FWD, namely, free will. For, according to Plantinga, what free choices free creatures will make in any universe God should decide to create containing them is something determined by them, not by God.14 Moreover, and this is his major point, it is entirely possible that each and every possible free creature would, if created and allowed to act freely, at least once choose to do something morally wrong. In Plantinga's somewhat quaint terminology, they would all suffer from " Transworld Depravity." Finally, and this point is also important, God, as omniscient, would presumably know this. 15 Consequently, it is demonstrably possible that God, even though omnipotent, cannot create a world which contains free agents but no moral evil. It would be well to note here how Plantinga's hypothesis of universal "Transworld Depravity" disposes of the objection, sometimes heard, that God, if He willed to create a universe containing free agents (as His wisdom and goodness would (seemingly) require Him to do if He willed to create at 14 See The Nature of Necessity, pp. 184, 190. See also God, Freedom and Evil, pp. 42-44. 15 See ibid., pp. 42-43 and also The Nature of Necessity, p. 180. 8 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON all) could at least have willed to create only those free agents who He foreknew would never sin; for, according to Plantinga, th'ere may be no such agents. Let us now see how Plantinga works out his defense in terms of " possible worlds." 16 Among possible worlds Plantinga invites us to consider a possible world, W, in which a particular free agent, P, in a given situation, S, is free with respect to a certain action, A. Now assume that in WP does A. Consider also another possible world, W1 , which in its time segment up to S is alike in every respect to W (in other words, let S entail everything that has occurred in W and W1 up to and including S) ; however, in W1 P does not do A but the opposite. Which of these two possible worlds, Plantinga might now ask us, do you think God can actualize? Our initial impulse would be to answer," Either one, since God is omnipotent and therefore can actualize just any possible world." Not so, says Plantinga, and here is why. Suppose that if S were actual P would do A (and God, as omniscient, knows this); then, clearly, God cannot actualize W1. Suppose, on the other hand, that if S were actual, P would not do A but the opposite (and God knows this); then, clearly again, God cannot actualize W. In either case there is a possible world that God cannot actualize. Since examples here are easy to multiply, one would have to conclude that there are many possible worlds God, despite His omnipotence, simply cannot actualize, namely, those worlds which contain free agents but whose actualizations would entail a contradiction. Thus, according to Plantinga, God, in deciding to create a world containing free agents, must be guided by HiEI knowledge of what choices each and every po8sible free creature would make i1' created and plar·e INTER-CONFESSIONAL THEOtOG1' 55 The role of judgment in faith: Existence, concepts and judgments. Current debate about ways of knowing God takes it largely for granted that what theology must do, if it is to measure up to modern man, is to elaborate existential ways of approaching God. Here is a salutary corrective to exaggerated forms of intellectualism that are little more than disguised rationalism, even though one suspects that what many authors are reacting against is their own imperfect grasp of what an objective approach to God really is. What arouses suspicion is the fact that, if a discussion of the question is even considered necessary, the whole argument turns on concepts, on their inadequacy when it comes to speaking about God, and on their historical conditioning. Here there is a fundamental misunderstanding of what is at stake. To pose the problem in terms of whether or not our concepts are adequate for expressing the mystery of God is already to have answered it, because they are not; and anyone who has ever considered the question admits this; so this is not the point that needs to be argued about. This means that there is something wrong with the way the question is being posed when a contrast is set up between the analogical and the dialectical methods because the problem then being set has to do with the concepts used by theologians. It certainly seems, at any rate, that the dialectical method is concerned with a. dialectic of concepts or of symbols, even though the claim would probably be made that this corresponds to a dialectic in the process of reality. It would also appear to be true-and this may be the source of the confusion-that anyone who claims to defend "analogical concepts" is placing himself on the same terrain and is, presumably, ready to do battle with the dialecticians on the terms chosen by them. Both sides would then miss the point because of a failure to grasp the fundamental intuition of the theory of analogy. Analogy, we have insisted, is a form of predication. This means that the basic unit that it considers is a complete state- COLMAN E. o'NEILL, O.P. ment which expresses a judgment. Statements certainly incorporate references to those concepts which the theologian attributes to God, but they do so only in so far as the concepts are taken up into what we may call the dynamism of a judgment, that is, into a living movement of the human spirit towards the reality of God. The concepts used are always drawn exclusively from experience of this world but they acquire a new relevance when they are given that explicit reference to existence-in this case the divine existence itself-which a judgment, as distinct from a concept, always achieves. Created reality's participation in God, on which the analogical method relies, is not the result of our projecting onto reality the logical structure of our conceptualization. If that were the case, it would be high time the proponents of analogy adopted one or other of the much more sophisticated forms of idealism now at hand. But in fact participation is realized in the innumerable individual acts of existing which impose themselves on our consciousness; the way we conceptualize the inner richness of those acts of existing is secondary from this point of view and it may be more or less successful. The theory of analogy claims that it is possible, whether by reason or by the power of the Spirit, to prolong the movement of our judgment beyond created acts of existing to the existence of God himself. Unhappily, this is something that the professional thinker's training causes him to miss, perhaps because it is so simple. People can be trained to manipulate concepts; existence they have already found for themselves. The act of existing, the obviously real, as soon as it is conceptualized (as we are doing now), is falsified or, at best, only faintly shadowed. We can certainly grasp it, as we do a butterfly in flight, and hold it living in our own existential act of judgment; but once we begin to t_alk about it we have transformed it into a pathetic object of study, subject to whatever measurements our ingenuity can devise. It is attained, that is to say, not in a concept but in an intellectual act of judgment rooted in an immediate sense experience; when we put it into ANALOGY, DIALECTIC AND INTER-CONFESSIONAL THEOLOGY 57 words we use some part of the verb" to be". Obviously, every existential judgment we make also uses universal concepts which serve, more or less adequately, to thematize for ourselves what we perceive to be the concrete content of an individual act of existing. But such concepts are always abstract, an idealizing of what exists; in this lies their power of generalization but also their weakness in the face of reality. The judgment, on the contrary, because it affirms the act of existing of the individual, constitutes the knowing subject's acknowledgment of the inexhaustible richness of the other. It is the other who leads the way, who imposes itself on our knowing; and it always transcends, simply because it exists, whatever conceptualization we may form of it. The created act of existing, in particular the individual personal existence, is for us a mystery. It is the irony of the human condition that, when we undertake the highest task of reflective reason, the elaboration of an ontology, we necessarily conceptualize and render abstract that very reality which, because of its utter originality, will not permit itself to be grasped in such a fashion. The theologian (or, for that matter, the philosopher) who claims to speak of the divine mystery should not be unaware of this mystery of created existence which eludes his grasp even before he attempts to raise his thoughts to God. The theological theory of proper analogical predication deals with the very complex phenomenon of complete statements which express judgments inspired by faith about the reality of God. It naturally offers an evaluation of the concepts used in such judgments; but it is principally concerned with the believer's claim that he is really talking about God, which is to say that his judgment of faith attains God's own act of existing. This is why it is false to place this theory on the same footing as those which deal only with concepts. From created existence to the divine act of existing The fundamental relation between the creature and God is affirmed when we say that the Creator is the principle of all 58 COLMAN E. O'NEILL, O.P. created acts of existing. What we are in fact affirming of God is a two-fold transcendence: we say that he transcends, as principle, that which, even in the created order transcends our concepts; and this we must maintain even as we confess that he gives himself in his own reality to our act of knowing. All this is expressed in the apparently simple affirmation of faith that God exists. However natural it may be for the believer, its epistemological status is extraordinarily complex. First of all, it is an analogical judgment, for we have transferred the word " exists " from its natural context where it signifies an act of existence seized in our inner-worldly experience, with its reference to sense data, and have placed it in a proposition whose subject does not belong to that experience. The procedure is a daring one and all the more pregnant with mystery when we advert to the fact that the normal signification of the word escapes our conceptual grasp. If we were considering only concepts we would have to admit that our grasp of God would be precarious in the extreme. But this is not the case because, secondly, "God exists" is a judgment and, as such, it would be meaningless unless in it we are able to open ourselves to the reality of God of whom we are speaking. Now, it is quite evident that we cannot open ourselves to the reality of God in the same way that we attain the acts of existence encountered in daily experience. But there are other ways. The philosopher who is convinced that he has proved the existence of God will affirm his conclusion in virtue of the rational force of the argument he has constructed; the judgment affirmed in the conclusion acquires its realism, its openness to the reality of God, from the conviction which the argument carries. The believer, on the contrary, makes his affirmation in the power of the Holy Spirit; the judgment that he forms as he opens himself to the reality of God is borne up in its realism by the intervention of the Spirit. The inner mystery of God and his plan of salvation are simply not realities for us unless in this way God himself imparts to our subjective judgments that dynamism towards his own reality which is characteristic of any existential judgment. ANALOGY, DIALECTIC AND INTER-CONFESSIONAL THEOLOGY 59 It is now possible to formulate more precisely the general hermeneutic implicit in the theory of analogy. It is expressed in the judgment, " God exists '', understood, not as a simple preliminary axiom of theology, but as a fundamental judgment which situates the transcendent existence of God with respect to created existence. As such it exercises a constant dialectical function with respect to every statement of faith, for no interpretation of such a statement will do justice to the transcendence of God if it is not consciously related to the two-fold transcendence affirmed in the fundamental judgment. The theologian must remind himself constantly that the concepts which are applied to God are realized in him, not simply at the level of existence (which is why any real thing transcends our concepts) , but at that summit of reality which is the act of existing without restriction. The point has been made most tellingly in the field of philosophy by Etienne Gilson 2 ; it remains valid in theology, where the realism of faith depends on the Spirit. The moments of negation and eminence invoked by the theory of analogy are intended to draw attention back to the act of divine existing in all its transcendence. A whole series of judgments is called for, each one correcting the imprecision of the others, without the possibility of arriving at a definitive statement. Here there is an evident dialectic but it is not confined to one that is set up between concepts thought of as mutually contrary or complementary; it is not, in its most crucial stage, a dialectic of ideas at all. It is the dialectic which affects the human person when faced with the mystery of the divine reality, a dialectic between all conceptualization as such and the irreducible reality of God, to which the Spirit opens the believer and which the theologian can only hold in awe. Once this dialectic is recognized as the fundamental intuition of the analogical method, it becomes possible to give a theological 2 E. Gilson, L'etre et l'essence, Paris, Vrin, 1948; a summary reference in The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas (=Le Thommne, 5° ed., 1948), New York, Random House, 1956, pp. 108-110. 60 COLMAN E. O'NEILL, O.P. evaluation of another form of dialectic, that which is found particularly in symbols and in the concepts derived from them. It still remains true that analogy implies a more positive evaluation of the capacity of certain concepts to direct our thematized judgments towards the being of God than seems to be recognized in systems which appeal exclusively or primarily to a dialectic of concepts. It implies also a more confident acceptance of the truth-value that is given through the complex mediation not only of concepts but also of metaphors and symbols, functioning within the judgment of faith. This is because the idea of participation takes into account both the transcendence of God and his immanence in creation, in the Incarnation and in the sending of the Spirit. Creation, reaffirmed in the Incarnation, can supply concepts which direct towards God the mind of the person who is brought to God by the Spirit. Faith judgments of identity The dynamism of the judgment as it opens the knowing subject to reality is expressed in language by the copula, some form of the verb " to be"; in the judgment of faith this word can be pronounced only as a gift of the Spirit. Here there is something that merits the special attention of the theologian. Whether he is involved in textual and historical research or in a project of systematization, the theologian is concerned almost exclusively with the meaning of concepts, images and metaphors; and this preoccupation becomes particularly evident at a time when the community is asking for new ways of expressing the faith. It is for this reason that so much is heard today of " models," which are conceptual constructs put forward as possible thematizations of the mysteries. The creative thought that goes into all of this can only too easily overlook the fact that the verb " to be " constitutes a special case when statements of the tradition are being examined. It can be treated as though it expressed just another concept, just another perspective on reality which could quite easily be put in another way. The ANALOGY, DIALECTIC AND INTER-CONFESSIONAL THEOLOGY 61 analytic method largely used by the theologian, which works reasonably well for concepts, has a way of asserting itself like this even when the statements being considered move out of the irealm of conceptualization into that of the unique relationship with reality given in the judgment. In its strongly existential sense (it may have other senses but these need not detain us) the verb "to be" indicates that the speaker is affirming that the referents of both subject and predicate of his statement are united, not simply by logical juxtaposition, but also, and primarily, in one reality which exercises its own unique act of existing. The speaker, if he is being serious, has some reason for making such an affirmation even though he may be quite unable to say how it is that what he is talking about is the way he affirms it to be. Now, it is clear that the Christian tradition makes statements having this strong existential character. In such cases the theologian is guilty of an elementary fault of logic, but one with devastating consequences, if he fails to advert to the unique significance of the verb " to be " as understood by the tradition he claims to be speaking for. It might be difficult to draw up a full list of such " limit propositions " where " to be " has this sense and where the Christian faith is immediately engaged. Evidently the Scriptures cannot supply an answer since they themselves pose part of the problem. The believer will be led to assume that the Holy Spirit makes other provision at the appropriate times for indicating which propositions are of this kind; the Christian communities do in fact make such an assumption in more or less explicit fashion. The central example for all traditions could hardly be other ·than: "You m·e the Christ, the son of the living God". As far as concepts and images go, it is evidently true that both subject and predicates provide an inexhaustible field of enquiry and meditation. Equally, the fact that they are brought together has a limitless existential significance in terms of Christian life. But the broad signification of the terms, as understood in the Christian tradition, can be made clear to anyone and so can the claim being made by means of the " are ". We can COLMAN E. dNEILL, O.P. make the confession our own only in the power of the Spirit. If we do, we know that we are talking about one and the same person possessing both kinds of characteristics; and arguments that profess to demonstrate that this is not the case or even that it is the case will not make any essential difference to our confession because they will be conceptual while it is more. As far as the assent of faith is concerned we can only surrender ourselves to the mystery of the divine reality showing itself in Jesus Christ. Within the Catholic tradition a similar mysterious simplicity attaches to the words" This is my body". Conceptual analysis, if left to itself, is going to miss the point of statements of this kind. The tradition-or the teaching office of the church-fulfils its function if it simply reiterates the judgment of faith. Analogy, dialectic and theological style It is not analogy as such which is characteristic of a certain theological tradition, for it is difficult to envisage any theology conscious of its epistemological status which could ignore the need to justify the believer's unusual use of ordinary language; and to pose this problem is to recognize that the believer uses language analogically, even if this term is not adopted. Where the real difficulty lies is revealed in the expression analogia entis, the analogy of being, a misnomer usually employed unreflectively by those who do not accept the method or, if they do, have not quite grasped it. This shows that what is at stake is a particular justification for analogical predication in statements of faith, namely, the metaphysical doctrine of participation. It is in virtue of the participation of created beings in the creative act of divine existing that a theology may lay claim, with all due reserves, to justify proper predication of God. The participation on which analogy rests is a two-way street. It can permit the formulation of a general hermeneutic for interpreting statements of faith in such wise that the divine ANALOGY, DIALEC'l'IC AND INTER-CONFESSIONAL THEOLOGY 68 transcendence is not compromised; but it also points the way to a reaffirmation of the values of creation and so to an authentic humanism. The immanence of the divine Son is seen to imply a restoration by the Spirit of what was given by God in his act of creation but was refused by sin. The whole mystery is precisely that of the immanence of God in mankind. A theology that acknowledges participation will therefore present its own special way of looking at the Christian life for it will be a theology whose principal thrust is concerned with the Spirit who can progressively transform the sinner in the measure that one who is justified by grace acknowledges the divine goodness, with all that that implies, as the dominant inspiration of his life. It is within these perspectives that a St . .Thomas could build his anthropology round the doctrine of the image of God which finds its future fulfilment in the vision and love of God. This is the context too of his moral theology which is structured by the articulation of the theological and moral virtues and the gifts of the Holy Spirit. Here, vocation to the beatific vision is seen as taking on its present ethical obligations according to the terms of the gospel beatitudes; sin and the negative commandments appear only as the negative side of grace. A theology of this kind is, in principle, capable of opening itself to any genuine insights of Christian experience. This is because its fundamental intuition points to the most universal and the most concrete phenomenon of reality-the act of existing itself. It is totally subordinated to the mystery and the revelation in Christ, for this is the way in which God has chosen to exist in the world. For this reason, too, it is open to the intuitions of a theology of the cross with the dialectic that that implies. For St. Thomas, the cross of Christ, though he speaks of it with all the pathos of medieval spirituality, finds theological significance only when interpreted in the light of the goodness of God who chooses this way of communicating himself historically to sinful man. Still, the place for a dialectic remains; but it is significant that St. Thomas finds it in the COµµN JD• p'NEIµ, O.P. treatise on the sacraments in which those who believe the word of the gospel are united with Christ precisely in their existential condition where sin and suffering still exercise their power. The dialectic is an only too real fact of the Christian community's existence; but when it is projected onto the incarnate Son it can no longer retain the same significance, for he was without sin. Indeed, so far as his loving commitment to the Father and to us is concerned, all is positive. The negativity of his sufferings cannot be accounted for in terms of his individual person unless perhaps we were prepared to say that he was, like so many other human beings, a victim of historical circumstances. It is only when those who believe in him are brought into actual union with him that a true element of negativity makes itself felt, for then the influence of sin becomes an active agent in a dialectic which is the developing mystery of Christ among us. His sufferings are drawn into the dialectic only when we, who are both justified and sinners, add our own sufferings to them, making up what is wanting to them in our own persons. If he is artificially seen as an isolated individual, then it will be said that he suffered simply because that was the way his message was received by the political and religious interests of his time. But if he is seen, as he ought to be, as one whose significance depends on his being actually received and acknowledged in faith, then his sufferings will not be isolated from those of believers or, indeed, from those of the world; and then the suffering can become an integral part of the development of the image of God in mankind as it seeks to overcome sin and its consequences, for this cannot be done without suffering. The true dimensions of the kenosis of the Son are to be discovered only when he, the original image of the Father, is seen as here and now drawing all men to himself, within the complexities of our human existence, marked as it is by the reality of sin, This very summary interpretation of the scholastic teaching on Christ's "satisfaction" is intended to indicate how an approach based on analogy, which stresses love as the key to Christ's saving activity, can be opened out to a dialectical ap- .ANALOGY, DIALECTIC AND INTER-CONFESSIONAL THEOLOGY 65 proach. 8 But this is possible only if the dialectic is confined to the existence of believers and is not permitted to touch the person of Christ himself. The interpretation is evidently based on a development of Col., UM. It could be further developed in terms of the Eucharist where Christ's saving activity is at work and where his members unite their sacrifice with his; in the Eucharist the dialectic is more real than it could have been on Calvary since grace is here found in direct confrontation with sin and its consequences. No theology conscious of its pastoral function can ignore the dialectic of the Christian life. But it should turn to it only because it has already received a message which speaks positively of the grace of God and one which, if words mean anything, presents an objective statement about the divine plan of salvation. A purely existential message would not be existential since, lacking all objectivity, it would not present a valid possibility of life. A purely dialectic approach to the message, though it claims to be existential, appears to be obliged to place in brackets, as unattainable, the whole ontology which is implicit in the claim to objective knowledge about God. It seems that it does this because its proponents are concerned to maintain a dialogue with European agnostic philosophy. The Reformed tradition, it would appear, has resources which cannot be confined in so narrow a compass; the New Testament certainly has. Its totally uninhibited openness to God can be maintained in theology only if the theologian is prepared to open himself again to being, to the living butterfly, full of existence but so easy to crush. The alternative is to think about thinking about God and that discovers reality only when the one who is doing the thinking is God himself. COLMAN E. O'NEILL, O.P. University of Fribourg Fribourg, Switzerland s The theme is developed by R. Cessario, O.P., Christian Satisfaction in Aquinas. Towards a Personalist Understanding, Washington, D.C., University Press of America, 1982 (a doctoral dissertation presented at the University of Fribourg). ALIENATION AND THE STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE: BIBLICAL AND IDEOLOGICAL VIEWS IN CONTRAST E VERY SERIOUS effort to understand the human condition has led to the formation of a myth of the Fall, a myth which expresses the understanding that the actual condition we find ourselves in is not that of our genuine, normative human reality but is rather a condition of separation or alienation from that reality, a flawed mode of existence in which existence is a struggle, in which existents are set in conflict with one another in consequence of their separation from true being. Thus emerge two concepts which play key roles in our understanding of ourselves: 1) the struggle for existence. The reflection on the human condition will therefore attempt to ask and to answer three questions: 1) What is the nature of alienation ? That is, from what are we alienated ? What is the nature of the genuine reality of our existence and how does our actual existence differ from it ? 2) Concretely, how does our actual existence as struggling existents derive from this primary alienation ? 3) Given the etiology of the struggle, how can we hope to overcome or transcend it ? The present discussion will attempt to contrast two radically divergent answers to these questions: 1) that found in the Jewish and Christian scriptures and in the view of the world grounded in these scriptures and the revelation they attest; 2) that provided by characteristically modern ideologies, such as Marxism, contemporary radical libertarianism, etc. 1 The 1 For a more complete exposition of the concept of ideology presupposed here, see my article "Ideology: An Essay in Definition" in Philosophy Today, Vol. XXV, Number S/4, Fall, 1981, pp. 66 ALIENATION AND THE STRUGGL'I\) FOR EXISTENCE 67 fundamental inadequacy of these ideologies for dealing with the problem will be a central theme of the present essay. I The Bible is quite clear both on the source of alienation and on the primary human reality preceding alienation. The account of creation given in Genesis tells us that God created the world in six days and that at the end of each day he looked upon his work and saw that it was good. When he had reached the end of the six days, culminating in the creation of man, he looked at all his creatures and saw that they were very good. Thus it is overwhelmingly clear from the account that the fault does not lie in man's creaturely state as such, that is, in his condition as a distinct and separate existent who is in no way identical with God, the absolute, the Ground, or whatever, but who receives his distinct individual existence as a gift from the Creator. This status of creatureliness is in fact his true and genuine reality, a reality which the Creator can pronounce to be very good. It is in fact the effort of the creature to abolish his creatureliness which the Bible sees as the source of the Fall. In the Genesis account, man is persuaded to eat the forbidden fruit by the argument that in so doing he will become as God, i.e., as the Creator, that he will no longer be in the position of receiving his existence as a free gift from God but will acquire the ability to confer existence on himself. Thus, in his genuine, creaturely human existence, in his primary right relationship to God, man receives his existence from God as a wholly free gift, a gift in which he takes joy, enabling him to live eucharistically, in thanksgiving. When this right relationship is lost, when man seeks to transcend his creaturehood, existence becomes, no longer a gift to rejoice in, but rather something which one must try to bestow on oneself, and thus something we must struggle for in competition with other creatures. Hence man must earn his bread by the sweat of his brow, woman must bring forth in sorrow, etc., all existence becomes something one must fight for, even against other crea- 68 GEORGE A, KENDALL tures who become one's enemies because they too are struggling for existence. One notes the change immediately in the passage (Genesis 8: 12-18) in which Adam and Eve present their excuses for their sin. Adam blames it on the woman, the woman in turn blames it on the serpent. We see already the breakdown of solidarity among creatures, the end of mutual support, etc. It is every creature for himself. Thus man's attempt to abolish his creaturehood leads directly to the struggle for existence. Because it is not creaturehood but man's negation of his creaturehood which eventuates in his alienation and in the conversion of his life into a struggle for existence, the Biblical images of the overcoming of the struggle (classically found in the Sermon on the Mount) involve a reaffirmation of creaturehood, not its negation. For example, the following passage is central: Therefore I tell you, do not be anxious about your life, what you shall eat or what you shall drink, nor about your body, what you shall put on. Is not life more than food, and the body more than clothing? Look at the birds of the air: they neither sow nor reap nor gather into barns, and yet your heavenly Father feeds them. Are you not of more value than they? And which of you by being anxious can add one cubit to his span of lifer And why are you anxious about clothing? Consider the lilies of the field, how they grow; they neither toil nor spin; yet I tell you, even Solomon in all his glory was not arrayed like one of these. But if God so clothes the grass of the fields, which today is alive and tomorrow is thrown into the oven, will he not much more clothe you, 0 men of little faith? Therefore, do not be anxious, saying, "What shall we eat?" or "What shall we drink?" or "What shall we wear?" For the Gentiles seek all these things; and your heavenly Father knows that you need them all. But seek first his Kingdom and his righteousness, and all these things shall be yours as well. Therefore, do not be anxious about tomorrow, for tomorrow will be anxious for itself. Let the day's own trouble be sufficient for the day. (Matthew 6: 25-34, RSV) · Here we are told, not that the needs which we struggle to satisfy are wrong or illusory, but that, in a right relationship to God, these needs will be satisfied by the Creator's free gift. .ALIENATION AND THE STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE 69 Anxiety is to be overcome by accepting existence as a gift, i.e., by returning to full creaturely status. Similarly, in the passages exhorting us not to resist evil, we are told, in effect, that if we exist in a right relation to God, our existence can no longer be something we struggle to defend against the various forces which would seek to take it away from us, but is rather something to be accepted from the Creator without anxiety or defensiveness. For the Christian, therefore, overcoming his alienation and terminating the struggle for existence is a matter of the slow progress in the life of grace by which he becomes increasingly able to die to himself (i.e., to his pretensions to be more than a creature) and thus to give up the struggle for existence so that he can receive his existence as a gift from God. " For whoever would save his life will lose it, and whoever loses his life for my sake and the gospel's will save it (Mark 8: 35) ." For the Christian, therefore, the end of the struggle for existence comes when he can give up the struggle, not when he can can give up existence understood as a gift from the Creator. (It must be understood, however, that for the Christian this giving up is the work of grace and cannot be realized as a social and political project to be somehow forced on the earthly city, as, e.g., pacifists try to do, thus engaging in their own kind of struggle for existence.) In summary, for the Biblical perspective, alienation and the struggle for existence emerge from the negation of creaturehood and are to be overcome, through grace, by the reaffirmation of creaturehood. II The ideological understanding of alienation, in contrast, can best be understood in terms of the idea of a kind of fall from potentiality into actuality. To exist as an actual, particular creature, embedded in a network of relations, commitments, responsibilities, etc., is seen as alienation from one's true being, which is universal and unlimited (e.g., for Marx, man's 70 GEORGE A. KENDALL " species-being") . To be an actual existent distinct from some sort of "All" or "One" is to be alienated, cut off from one's true being. A couple of representative passages from the writings of ideologues may help to illustrate this. Marcuse, commenting on Freud, makes the following remarks: .... Phantasy (imagination) retains the structure and the tendency of the psyche prior to its organization by the reality, prior to its becoming an " individual " set off against other individuals. And by the same token, like the id to which it remains committed, imagination preserves the memory of the subhistorical past when the life of the individual was the life of the genus, the image of the immediate unity between the universal and the particular under the rule of the pleasure principle. In contrast, the entire subsequent history of man is characterized by the destruction of this original unity: the position of the ego " in its capacity of independent individual organism " comes into conflict with " itself in its other capacity as a member of a series of generations." The genus now lives in the conscious and ever renewed conflict among the individuals and between them and their world. Progress under the performance principle proceeds through these conflicts.2 Similar passages can be cited from the young Marx: In estranging from man (I) nature, and (fl) himself, his own active functions, his life-activity, estranged labour estranges the species from man. It turns for him the Zife of the species into a means of individual life. First it estranges the life of the species and individual life, and secondly it makes individual life in its abstract form the purpose of the life of the species, likewise in its abstract and estranged form. 3 Estranged labour turns thus: (3) Man's species being, both nature and his spiritual species property, into a being alien to him, into a means to his individual existence:' ... The proposition that man's species nature is estranged from him means that one man is estranged from the other, as each of them is from man's essential nature. 5 Now it is obvious that such passages offer monumental difficulties to interpretation, but what -one clearly senses, with the 2 Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilization (New York, 1962), p. 129. a Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (Moscow, 1961), pp. 74-75. 4 Ibid., p. 76. s Ibid .. p. 77. ALIENATION AND. THE STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE 71 aid of a little spiritual discernment, as underlying them is an animus against individual existence as such insofar as the latter is seen as implying, in some sense, a loss of universal substance. What such writers struggle against is the simple, obvious reality of common sense that to be a particular existent is not to be any other existent. Ohe detects, in these writings, not merely a reaction against the extremes of atomistic individualism in advanced industrial society, but a generalized opposition to particularity as such, to the fact that, e.g., to be a particular human being precludes being universal humanity. Now what needs to be clarified here is precisely what it means to be a particular, individual human being. First of all, to be a particular human being means to be an actual human being, i.e., to have given up being merely a potential human being. But one becomes an actual human being in the encounter with others in the course of which one makes commitments, takes on responsibilities, becomes embedded in a network of relations which define, that is, delimit, what one is. Thus to be an actual, particular being is to be defined and limited, to have given up the unlimited realm of the potential for the limited realm of the actual. But selfhood in this sense, as a limited structure emerging out of the limiting encounter with others and with an order of existence of which one is a part and no more, is an object of bitter hatred for characteristically modern ideologies. Nowhere is this more clear than in the rash of " liberationist" ideologies which have grown up like weeds in the past generation, of which feminism is a typical example. Such ideologies again and again repudiate actual selfhood in favor of a potential selfhood which they see as true selfhood. Ideologues committed to such views spend their lives fantasizing about the infinite potentialities which would be open to them if only a repressive society had not forced them into this or that role, e.g., forced them to be women, or to be men, etc. Now actual selfhood is the selfhood acquired when one is actualized by the encounter with objects, and its opposite is a kind of potential " selfhood" which is in reality pure subjectivity. A pure subject is open 72 GEORGE A. KENDALL to infinite possibilities-an actual self is not, it is limited by the possibilities it has actualized in the process of becoming a self. The essential subjectivism implicit in the " liberationist" movements is well illustrated by the insistence, on their part, that everyone be referred to and treated solely as a " person," that is, that all charaderistics which differentiate people (cultural, sexual, ethnic, etc.) be simply ignored (in other wnrds, that "humanity" or" personhood" be made a univocal term, an issue to be discussed later) . But since it is precisely by virtue of such attributes that one is an actual human being rather than merely a potential one, what the liberationists are really insisting on is that everyone be thought of purely as a potential, not an actual, human being. But a purely potential human being is a pure subject, so that what we are really being asked to do is to see and treat everyone solely as a pure subject. But the pure subject is a negation of selfhood, since to be a self is to be an "impure" subject, a subject actualized in various ways, e.g., by culture, by social roles which culture assigns in various ways to various individuals, in general, by commitment and responsible action emerging from the actualizing encounter with others. Where for the Christian freedom or wholeness implies the ability to act and exist as a particular, actual creature limited and bound by a network of relations rooted in the created order of being, for the " liberationist " freedom or wholeness means openness to infinite possibilities, it means the total absence of any closure or limitation of the personality, it means spending one's life confronting limitless possibilities without ever acting so as to limit them. For the Christian this is not freedom but paralysis of the will and hence slavery. It is clear, then, that for ideologues creaturely existence as such is the root of alienation and consequently the struggle for existence occurs solely because there are existents, because there are creatures, not because creatures live in a wrong relation to their Creator. The distinction between the two understandings becomes clear enough when we compare their respective visions of how the struggle for existence is to come to an end. For the ALIENATION AND THE STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE 78 Christian, it is the struggle, not existence, which is to end, when creatures learn to accept their existence as a gift and, in this joyful acceptance, affirm, not negate, their existence. In contrast, for the ideologue, the struggle for existence will end with the abolition of creaturely existence, with the swallowing up of the particular, individual self in the infinite sea of pure potentiality, pure subjectivity, which, in the last analysis, is a form of nothingness. III But the contrast presented above in outline is in need of more technical clarification. At the center of the ideologue's rejection of particular, creaturely existence is the belief that such a creaturely existence involves the loss of universal existence. Hence at the center of the problem of alienation is the ancient problem of universals, and just how one understands universals and their meaning will be determinative of how one understands the relation between universal and particular existence so central to the problem of alienation. Now it is clear that universals can be looked at in three ways: I) As univocal, i.e., as applying in an identical way to a multitude of particulars; 2) As equivocal, i.e., as merely homonymous; 3) As analogous. The equivocal or homonymous notion of the universal term need not concern us here. What is crucial is the contrast between the univocal and analogous understanding of the universal. Clearly, for ideological thought, the universal is always univocal and thus it can only be imperialistic in its pretensions, tolerating nothing which would limit it. The univocal universal must subsume all particulars under some -common something which is identical for all. But the only thing we can find which is truly identical for all members of a class is some potentiality shared by all. As soon as we introduce actuality, we introduce diversity, because actuality comes into being when universal 74 GEORGE A. KENDALL potentiality is actualized and limited. Thus to get at what all existents in a species share identically we must remove all actuality and hence reduce all the particulars to pure potentiality in which there can be no particular. Thus universal humanity must assume the form of a kind of universal human potentiality because it can only be found when we remove from it everything which is particular and hence actual. Thus particular existents within the species must be abolished, e.g., there can be no men and women but only " persons." If humanity is to be univocal, it must swallow up all diversity, since the latter can be understood only as the loss of universality and hence as alienation, as illusion. In contrast, for the analogous concept of the universal which is always central to the Christian vision of the creation whether or not it is theoretically articulated, this type of conflict between universal and particular is not inherent in the very structure of things. The concept of the analogia entis 6 does not require the presence of any one something which all particulars share in common in an identical way. Rather, what holds particulars together, what makes them part of a class of some kind, whether that class is the human species or the creation as a whole, is the diversity of relations which all have to a common term, i.e., to God, who is the prime analogate. Ultimately, a particular creature has its particular form by virtue of a relation it has to its Creator which we may call imaging. Each particular creature images the Creator in a unique way built up out of the network of relations, limits, etc., in which that creature has its roots and out of the tension to image the Creator which is in a sense the creature's essence qua creature. An example may help to illustrate this. If we were to take the 6 The problem of the analogia entis cannot, of course, be treated in any depth in the present context. Of particular value as a source for this issue is James F. Anderson's work, The Bond of Being: An Essay on Analogy and Existence (New York, 1949). Etienne Gilson's The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy is also an invaluable source on this problem. The present discussion attempts to point only to certain elemental concepts which the author sees as central to the present issue, and should not be read as if it were an attempt to deal adequately or completely with the problem of the analogy of being. ALIENATION AND THE STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE 75 variety of images of Christ which we find in churches, we would find almost no limit to their diversity and we would be hard put to find any one something which all had in common. But the relation which each has to the one term, Christ, draws them into the same class, however diverse the relations are. Thus the creation could be thought of as the universal community of images of the Creator. Universality is not, in this context, some univocal something which swallows up all particulars in identity, but is rather understood as community, which draws together all the particulars by virtue of their shared but diversified relation to the Creator. Universality, understood as community, in no way militates against particularity but rather requires it. In the community, each particular has its own unique and distinct existence but belongs to all the others by virtue of its imaging the same Creator. Thus, for Christians, universal humanity can be understood as the community of human icons of Christ. In a right creaturely relationship to God, individuation implies no loss of universal existence but rather is a condition for it. IV Ideology thus emerges, in the context of this problem, as a hatred of creaturely existence as such. In summing up this theme, it seems somehow appropriate to follow Plato's practice of presenting a myth. It has been suggested by theologians that Satan's sin was not a rejection of God as such, but an insistence on having God on his own terms, not on God's. One suspects that the key to Satan's rebellion, thus understood, may lie in his attitude to the creation. One might speculate that Satan's zeal for God was such that he willed that God should be God wholly in and for Himself, without creatures who are other than God and who, in Satan's view, in some way lessen or limit God's glory. But in fact, God freely chose, not to be God in and for himself only, but to be God with and for the creation. This understanding of the matter is summed up with particular clarity by Karl Barth: 76 GEORGE A. :KENDALL God's deity is thus no prison in which He can exist only in and for Himself. It is rather His freedom to be in and for Himself but also with and for us, to assert but also to sacrifice Himself, to be wholly exalted but also completely humble, not only almighty but also almighty mercy, not only Lord but also servant, not only Judge but also Himself the judged, not only man's eternal king but also his brother in time. All that, rather, is the highest proof and proclamation of His deity. He who does and manifestly can do all that, He and no other is the living God. 7 To will that God be God wholly in and for himself is to will that God be God otherwise than as he has freely chosen to be God, and is thus to rebel against God in the name of God. And with this rebellion goes a hatred of the creation, a hatred of the splendid multiplicity of creatures each imaging God in its own unique way and deriving its form from this imaging. Since the imaging is the source of all form, the rebellion involves a hatred of all form, a desire to unform all creatures and thus to reduce them to the closest possible approximation to nothingness. And thus ideologues, in their endless efforts to abolish all form, to abolish all creaturely existence, to draw all things back into pure potentiality, manifest only too clearly whose servants they are. And there is no inconsistency in the fact that they are themselves creatures, because their efforts to abolish form extend even, perhaps especially, to themselves; they ceaselessly work, and with considerable success, to unform and deform themselves, seeking the nothingness before all creation as their telos. Indeed, it seems to be precisely with themselves that they are most successful, reducing themselves to distorted shadows of the God-imaging creatures they were meant to be. The ideological understanding of alienation and its transcendence is thus fundamentally destructive. It negates existence, warring against the joy in existence which holds the creation together. GEORGE Lansing, Michigan T Karl Barth, The Humanity of God (Atlanta, 1978), p. 49. A. KENDALL THE EGIDEAN INFLUENCE IN ROBERT ORFORD'S DOCTRINE ON FORM S OMETIME BETWEEN the years 1277 and 1279, the English Franciscan William de la Mare wrote a polemical work entitled: Correctivwni fratris Thomae. 1 The purpose of this treatise was to safeguard the orthodoxy of those young Franciscans who might have been reading the writings of Thomas Aquinas. The Franciscan Chapter of Strasbourg held in 1282 ordered that the friars have this book before them while reading Aquinas. We know of three Dominican responses to William's Correctivum which were written at Oxford, each being identified by its opening word, viz., Quare, Sciendum and Quaestione.2 The second of these, whose full title is: Correctorium Corruptorii Sciendum is ascribed in MS. Madrid Bibl. Real. VII, H. 5 (now University Salamanca 1887) to a certain Guillelmus Torto Callo Anglici. On fol. 89v is the explicit statement: Here ends the correction of the corruptor by brother William of Torto Collo, an Englishman, Master of Theology, of the Order of Friars, Preachers. This same man, Torto Collo, also wrote a work against Henry of Ghent which is found in MS. Vat. lat. 987, fol. lr-128v, but in this work against Henry his name is written Colletorto. On fol. 128 in a contemporary hand are the words: 1 For a discussion of this work, its dates and the events surrounding its appearance, see my The Quaestio Disputata de Unitate Frirmae by Richard Knapwell, (Paris, 1982), pp. 165. 2 All these works are available in editions. Le Oorrectorium Corruptorii ' Qucire ', ed. Palemon Glorieux (Kain, 1927); Le Correctorium Oorruptorii 'Sciendum ', ed. Palemon Glorieux (Paris, 1956); Le Correctorium Oorruptorii ' Quaestione ', ed. Jean-Pierre Muller (Rome, 1954) . 77 78 FRANCIS E. KELLEY and here are notations in the margins of these titles or articles by Master Robert of Colletorto, so that one might see how he (i.e., Henry) contradicts himself. Despite the difference in the way the name appears, i.e., Torto Collo and Colletorto, internal evidence makes it clear that one and the same man wrote both works. We might note also that the author of contra dicta H enrici, viz., Robert Colletorto, made several references to a responsorium ad corruptorium, and in one of these references he said it was his own responsorium: but because Henry does not oppose what I have written concerning this matter in my response to the corruptor, I do not care to deal with what he says here.3 Colletorto or Torto Collo also wrote another treatise, against Giles of Rome, entitled Reprobationes dictorum a fratre Egidio in primum Sententiarum which is extant in one manuscript, viz., MS. Merton Q76.4 Although the latter work is anonymous in the Merton manuscript, a comparative examination of Reprobationes fratris Egidii, contra dicta Henrici and Sciendum shows that one man wrote the three works. A comparison of what we read in the three treatises in connection with the relationship of the intellect to the will makes it clear that Torto Collo is the author. Is the intellect the su., perior faculty in man; or is the will? If the question be set in these precise terms, it might have seemed an odd or perhaps trivial thing to he asking. But the implications of the question for the scholastic were far-reaching. The way he discussed the point depended largely on how he stood regarding the broader question of that time concerning the role of philosophy in the Christian scheme. The excessive rationalism of the so-called a " Sed quia Henricus non opponit se ad ea quae ego scripsi circa materiam istam in responsorio ad corruptorium, ideo non _curavi tractare quae sic recitat ", MS. Vat. lat. 987, fol. 122rb. P. Bayerschmidt shows that the respomcmum in question is Sciendum, Robert von Colletorto, Verfasser des Correctoriums • Bciendum' ", Divus Thomas (Freiburg im Breis.) 17 (1939), pp. Sll-S!!6. 4 RobeTt d'Orford Reprobationes dictorum a fratre Egidio in Primum Sententiarum, ed. A. Vella (Paris, 1968). THE EGIDEAN INFLUENCE .IN ORFORD 79 radical Aristotelians brought on the strong counter-measures of the Church and University authorities. The debate over the. relative superiority of intellect and will did not reflect this conflict in its entirety, but it formed an important element in the dispute. The opposition to those who stressed unduly the excellence of the rational element in man is reflected in some of the propositions condemned at Paris in 1277: 40. That there exists no higher calling than to give oneself to philosophy. That the intellect, man's highest perfection, is entirely abstract. 144. That every good possible to man consists in the intellectual virtues. 145. That there is no question subject to rational inquiry which the philosopher should refrain from disputing and deciding, for arguments are derived from external reality. But Philosophy in its several areas deals with all external reality.5 121. Aquinas, in his efforts to remain consistent with Aristotelian principles as he understood them, insisted that the rational and true and therefore the intellect enjoyed an ontological priority over the good and the will.6 Of St. Thomas's view William de la Mare said: To us this seems to be false and to pave the way for many other false things even if it does not appear to be directly contrary to the Faith or to upright living.7 For support William relied heavily on the authority of St. Augustine and St. Anselm, without however neglecting to cite and interpret Aristotle and the Commentator in accord with what he took as the Augustinian position. In Sciendum, Torto Collo arranged his main response under three headings. In 5 Chart. Univ. Paris, I, pp. 545-552. For St. Thomas's position see Summa Theol., I, 82, 8; 11-11, 28, 6, ad lum; Contra Gent., III, c. 26; Quaest. Disp. de Veritate, q. !l!!, a. 11. R. Macken discusses the ' intellectualism ' of St. Thomas in relation to the ' voluntarism ' of Henry of Ghent in " La volonte humaine, faculte plus elevee que l'intelligence selon Henri de Gant", Recherches de TMologie ancienne et medievale, 4!! (1975), pp. 5-51; see especially pp. 41-51. 1 In Quare, p. 161. 6 80 FRANCIS E. Di.LEY fact he started out as if we were going to hear two lines of argument: but a faculty can be considered in two ways: either as a kind of power, and this would be in comparison to its activity, for a power is what it is from its relation to activity; or, these faculties can be considered in relation to their terminating objects. 8 In following out his scheme, however, which is taken from Aquinas, he added a third argument: Again, the same thing is clear if [the faculty] be compared with the essence of the soul. The first and third arguments follow closely what St. Thomas had written in the Summa Theologiae 0 ; the second argument, which appears to be original, is verbally identical with what is found in the oontra Egidium: For since the essence of the soul is one and the faculties are several, and there is progress from one to many according to a certain order, of necessity there exists an order among the faculties of the soul. According to the order of nature perfect things are prior to the imperfect, but according to the order of generation it is the other way round. But by the order of nature the intellect comes before the will . . . Therefore, simply speaking, in this way the intellect is the higher faculty .10 In the later oontra Egidium Torto Collo referred to this place in Soiendum and quoted from it verbatim. 11 In Quodlibet 1, 14, Henry of Ghent said that if we had to compare the two faculties then we ought to say that the will enjoys a pre-eminence over the intellect. His conclusion was: Therefore it must be said without qualification that in the entire kingdom of the soul the will is the superior power; and thus [it is superior] to the intellect. 12 s Sciendum, p. 148. Them., I, 8!e, S. 10 Sciendum, pp. 148-149. 11 Reprobationes contra Egidium, p. 51. 12 "Absolute ergo dicendum quod voluntas superior vis est in toto regno animae; et ita ipso intellectu ", Quodlibeta Magistri Goethals a Gandavo, I (Paris, 1518, vol. 1), fol. llr. 0 Summa THE EGIDEAN INFLUENCE IN ORFORD 81 In the main response to Henry found in contra H enricum Torto Callo directed the reader to what he had already written m Sciendum: The solution as to how the intellect is a higher faculty than the will is sufficiently set forth in Responsorio contra Corruptorem, question 34, and it is found in super II Sent., distinction 33. There also are found the solutions to all the arguments repeated here. Therefore I shall pass over them briefly. For in that place it was shown how the intellect is a higher and nobler faculty than the will be comparing them to the activity, habit and object. 13 As we have seen, in Sciendum Torto Callo compared the faculties "to the act, to the essence and to the object". The slight discrepancy between " to the essence " and " to the habit " does not disturb the parallel. The next words in contra Henricum, viz., " in that place also the answer to the authority of Anselm when he calls the will ' mistress ' " 14 is a reference to the first objection in Sciendum: " To the first opposing argument, it must be said that when Anselm says ... " 15 And his following words against Henry, viz., "It is also clear there how the intellect moves the will and vice versa [how] the will [moves] the intellect " 16 are again a reference to what he had already said in Sciendum. The four remaining points in contra Henricum have their counterparts in Sciendum as well: is There also is the answer to the argument concerning Charity. 17 There also is answered the last argument placed here. 18 To the 13 " Solutio qualiter intellectus sit altior potentia quam voluntas satis declaratum est responsorio contra corruptorem, quaestione 34, et ponitur super 2 Sent., distinctione 33. Ibi etiam ostensum est solutiones ad omnia argumenta quae hie replicantur. Ideo brevius est pertranseundum. Ibi enim ostensum est quomodo intellectus est altior et nobilior potentia quam voluntas comparando eas ad actum et ad habitum et ad obiectum ", MS. Peterhouse 129, fol. 6va; MS. Vat. lat. 987, fol. 7vb. 14 "Ibi etiam responsum est ad auctoritatem Anselmi cum vocat voluntatem dominam '', ibid. 15 Sciendum, p. 149. 1 6 " Patet etiam ibidem quomodo intellectus movet voluntatem, et econverso voluntaa intellectum '', MS. Peterhouse 129, fol. 6va; MS. Vat. lat. 987, fol. 7vb. 17 In Sciendum the reply to the fourth objection dealt with the question of charity: "To the argument relating to charity ... ", p. 150. 18 The reference here is to Henry's argument that the will's object (bonum) is FRANCIS E. KELLEY argument: it is more noble to love God than to know Him, the response is found in article 89.19 How reason commands the will is explained in Responsorio ad Corruptorem, question 55,2° and it is found in super II Sent., distinction 88.21 After this reference he elaborated on what appeared in contra Egidium: Therefore I say it is true, the will moves the intellect to its activity. But it should be recognized when we say this that we do not mean the will moves the intellect to its act of understanding pure and simple, for were we to take the latter meaning then the act of will would come before the very first act of understanding, and this is not true, for we will only what we know, as the blessed Augustine says: nothing is loved unless it is known. [When we say the will moves the intellect] this must be taken as referring to a special act of understanding. Taken in this special sense, there are two aspects requiring our consideration, namely, the activity itself and the determination of the activity, or to say it another way, 'to understand ' and ' to understand this particular thing '. In a similar way, in the special act of willing [there are two aspects], viz., ' to will ' and ' to will this particular thing '. Therefore, in the special act of understanding the activity itself is the result of willing, for the activity comes about by virtue of a mediating habit, and a habit is something we put to use when we will to do so. However the determination of this activity does not come from the will, but from the species l or idea] which is the form in the intellect of the thing being understood. For through the mediation of the idea of man I understand what a man is, and through the idea of better or 'higher' than the intellect's object (verum). The point here is that verum is not bonUJn. In Sciendum the reply to the last argument took this point under consideration: " it must be recognized that since the true is a kind of good ... ", p. 150. 19 In Sciendum see article 50: "To the other argument, when it is said ... to love God is more noble than to know Him, it must be said ... ", pp. 20 See Sciendum, article 55: " Whether to command is an activity of the reason ", pp. 21 " Ibi etiam responsum est ad argumentum de Caritate. !bi etiam soluta est ultima ratio quae hie ponitur. Ad illud: diligere Deum est nobilius quam cognoscere, responsum est articulo 89. Quomodo autem ratio imperat voluntatem, patet in resp0118orio ad corruptorem, quaestione 55, et habetur super II Sententiarum, distinctione SS.", MS. Peterhouse. 129, fol. 6va; MS. Vat. lat. 987, fol. 7vb. THE EGIDEAN INFLUENCE IN ORFORD 88 horse, what a horse is. With the will the reverse is true. For since the will is the seat of liberty, though not its cause-as will be made clear in the next question-and since action flows from this seat, therefore the will acts freely. But even though it can only will after what is known determines it to will this or that, in the sense that reason proposes this or that to the will, the will itself is not however forced to will this or that-this will become clear. 22 The cross references and parallels here are sufficient for us to say that one man, Torto Collo, wrote the three works. Although the different spellings of the second name is of no significance, the author's first name is William in one manuscript ascription and Robert in the other, and this is most significant. Palemon Glorieux, in the introduction to his edition of Sciendum prefers William as the correct given name and dismisses the ' Robert' found in the Vatican manuscript as an error. 23 His reasoning for this choice places great emphasis on the fact that the Stam.-; Catalogue has a correctorium under William Macclesfield's name and not under Robert Orford's. 22 " Dico igitur quod ' voluntas movet intellectum ' verum est quantum ad exercitium actus. Hie tamen sciendum est quod cum dicitur voluntas movet intellectum quantum ad exercitium actus, hoc non dicitur intelligere quantum ad exercitium intelligendi simpliciter, quia secundum hoc, primum intelligere praecederet actus voluntatis, quod falsum est; cum nihil volumus nisi quod cognoscimus, secundum beatum Augustinum: nihil amatur nisi cognitum. Sed hoc debet intelligi de actu intelligendi speciali. In hoc enim speciali actu intelligendi vel intelligere sunt duo considerare, scilicet exercitum actus et determinationem actus, ut in intelligere et intelligere hoc. Similiter, in speciali actu voluntatis sunt velle et velle hoc. In hoc ergo speciali intelligere, exercitium actus est a voluntate, quia actus elicitur mediante habitu. Habitus autem est quo utimur cum volumus; determinatio autem actus non est a voluntate, sed a specie quae est forma rei intellectae in intellectu. Mediante enim specie hominis intelligo hominem, et mediante specie equi, equum. Econverso est de voluntate. Cum enim voluntas sit subiectum libertatis, quamvis non sit causa, ut patebit in quaestione sequenti, et subiecti est agere, voluntatis est libere agere. Sed quia nihil potest velle nisi per cognitum determinetur ad volendum hoc vel illud, ex hoc quod hoc vel illud a ratione sibi proponitur, non tamen necessitatur ad volendum hoc vel illud, ut ibi patebit ", MS. Peterhouse IQ9, fol. 6va; MS. Vat. lat. 987, fol. Sra. 23 " Tout inviterait ainsi a abandonner la candidature de Robert d'Erfort et, dans ces conditions a considerer cornrne errone sans doute le prenorn que la notice du Vatican a attribue au Tortocollo, auteur du traite contre Henri de Gand ", p. 17. 84 FRANCIS E. KELLEY Two observations are in order here. First, we must remember that the absence of a certain work under one's name in an early catalogue might mean nothing more than that it is incomplete in the given instance. There s reason to think this is the case with Robert Orford and a correctorium, for the later chronicler John Bale assigns to him a Protectorium Thomae Aquinatis. 24 Second, one must bear in mind also that all we are sure of from Stams is that William Macclesfield wrote one of the correctoria; which particular one he wrote is in no way hinted. The same Stams Catalogue which Glorieux cites as an argument against Robert Orford having done Sciendum attributes to him the other two works: contra dicta HIN [RICI] de Gaude [GANDAVO], quibus impugnat Thomam, contra primum Egidii, ubi impugnat Thomam. 25 But what of the ' William ' written in the Madrid manuscript? D.A. Callus gives an interesting explanation for this. 26 The name William might not in fact designate the author but rather the author's adversary, viz., William de la Mare. The three line colophon in MS. Madrid, fol. 89va is: Explicit [in mag. correctorium] corruptorii fratris Guillermi de Torto Collo anglici magistri in theologia ordinis fratrum predicatorum, According to Callus, this might very well have been a four-line colophon in the copy the scribe used, so that reconstructed it would read: Explicit [ correctorium] corruptorii fratris Guillermi [de Mara anglici magistri in theologia, Robertil de Torto Collo anglici magistri in theologia ordinis fratrum predicatorum, The scribe's significant mistake in omitting and then correcting later his omission by including the important word correctorium 24 Scriptorum lllustrium Maiori.s Brythannie Catalogus (Basel, 1557), p. 824. Denifle (Archiv fiir Literatur-und Kirchengeschichte des Mittelalters, 2, 1886), p. 60. 26 Bulletin Thomiste, 9 (1954-1956), p. 658. 25 Catalogus Stamsensis, ed. THE EGIDEAN INFLUENCE iN ORFORD 85 in conjunction with the easily possible homography suggested by Callus, is an inviting supposition. While an element of doubt remains, we are safe in saying that these three works, one of them being the correctorium corruptorii Sciendum, very probably belong to Robert Orford. Emden puts Orford down as a Franciscan. 27 This is a slip,28 for there can be no doubt he was a Dominican. His name is in the Stams Catalogue which lists only Dominicans and he is identified as a Preacher in MS. New Coll. 92 and MS. Worcester 46. 29 From .MS. Assissi we know he acted as respondens in two disputations: one, with a certain ' Clif ', and on another occasion with Alan Waker:field who was the 17th Franciscan regent Master at Oxford. 80 He also preached a sermon there on February 22, 1293, whether as a Master or not we do not know. 81 From Stams we know he became a Master at some point, but the date of his inception is not known. In vi·ew of his writings against Giles of Rome and Henry of Ghent, Vella suggests Orford may have spent some time studying at Paris. 32 The Dictionary of National Biography states it as a fact: Afterwards he was at Paris where he wrote in support of Thomas Aquinas against Henry of Ghent and Giles of Rome. 33 If he did so, then his departure from Oxford and later return would have paralleled the moves of his confrere, William Mac127 A Biographical Register of the University of Oxford to A.D. 1500, ii (Oxford, 1958), p. 1401; Biographical Register of the University of Cambridge to 1500 (Cambridge, 1963), p. 435. 2s The source of the slip could be the ambiguous sentence in Oxford Theology and Theologians ca. A.D. 1282-1302, Little-Pelster (Oxford, 1934), p. 12, where, in speaking of Orford a reference is made to the Franciscans lists. 29 Oxford Theology and Theologians, p. 163. so Ibid., pp. 105; 112. See also Thomas Eccleston, Fratris Thomae vulgo dicto de Eccleston Tractatus de Adventu Fratrum Minomm in Angliam ed. Little (Manchester 1951), p. 53. 31 Oxford Theology and Theologians, pp. 168; 181. 3 2 Reprobationes contra Egidium, pp. 12-18. as DNB, 42, p. 252. 86 FRANCIS E. KELLEY clesfield.84 It is easy to understand a decision of the Dominican superiors to have arranged such a trip for these two enthusiasts in the interest of peace as well as for their own welfare. Orford's concern with these two Paris masters, however, in and of itself is not enough to suggest a sojourn in Paris. There was plenty of interest in Giles and Henry at Oxford, at least among these early Thomists, making the Paris trip for Orford a superfluous conjecture. 35 Indeed, in the earliest work we have from him, viz., Sciendum, Orford reveals his familiarity with Giles.86 While the Paris sojourn lacks sufficient evidence, there is a clue that Orford might have spent some time at Cambridge. If, as Pelster says, the first 15 quires (with the exception of 11 and rn) of MS. Assissi 158 originated in Cambridge, since in the fifth quire Orford's name appears as reS'pondens,81 it follows that he was there at that time. At any rate, he is back at Oxford, if he ever left, by ca. 1285 responding under Alan Wakerfield. In article 31 of Sciendum entitled: "Whether in man there exists only one substantial form", Robert Orford presents his basic argument in defense of the unity thesis. 38 The core of his argument appeals to a distinction drawn between the ' form of the part ' and the ' form of the whole ' in the way they give ' substantial existence ' to a substance. It is possible, he says, to view substantial existence in two ways: in part, or in its entirety. For example, we can speak of ' man ' as a single complete entity, and corresponding to this is substantial existence in its entirety. Or we can speak of the' arm' or' toe', each of which is a part of the composed substance 'man', enjoying an existence in a sense its own. It is perfectly acceptable to say there are several substantial forms in the one composed sub84 See F. Kelley, The Thomists and their opponents at Oxford in the last part of the thirteenth century (unpublished D.Phil.- thesis Oxford Univ., 1977), MS. Bodleian D.Phil. d. 6!!58, p. 58. 85 Ibid., p. 168. 36 See infra, pp. 88sqq. 37 Oxford Theology and Theologians, p. l!l. sap, 187. THE EGIDEAN INFLUENCE IN ORFORD 87 stance, if by so saying we refer to the ' forms of the parts ' which give partial substantial existence.39 But if one were to hold that there is more than one form of the whole substance giving total substantial existence to the composite, then he would be wrong. Indeed, to say such a thing implies a contradiction, for it amounts to saying that one thing is many things.4° Orford's argument here is most unusual, at least for a Thomist. Throughout the discussion he is referring to existence, and emphasizing the way form gives existence. The most remarkable thing of all is the way he draws the distinction between total substantial existence and partial substantial existence which, he says, corresponds to and is ' given by ' the form of the part and the form of the whole. One looks in vain for anything resembling this in the writings of St. Thomas. F. Roensch says that Orford here " bases his rebuttal of the pluralist view on St. Thomas' Commentary on the Metaphysics",4 1 but what Orford says in the argument just considered is not at all what St. Thomas has in the place Roensch cites. It is true, Aquinas uses the terms ' form of the whole ' and ' form of the part ', but he uses them in an entirely different meaning from Orford's. By ' form of the whole ' St. Thomas means the nature taken in abstraction from the individual, as for instance when one speaks of ' man ' in general. This usage corresponds exactly to what he elsewhere calls total abstraction. 42 By ' form of the 89" Dare autem esse simpliciter, scilicet esse substantiale, contingit dupliciter, vel partiale vel totale. Esse autem plures formas in re aliqua quae dant esse substantiale partiale non est inconveniens, immo necessarium est; cum enim ex non substantiis non fiat substantia, partes substantiae sunt substantiae; unde Philosophus in Pra.edicamentisvult quod manus et pes quae sunt primae substantiae non sunt accidentia, quia non sunt sicut accidens in subiecto, sed sunt substantiae quae sunt sicut partes in toto ", Sciendum, p. 138. 40 " Si loquamur de esse substantiali totali et de forma quae