EDWARD SCHILLEBEECKX AS CRITICAL THEORIST: THE IMPACT OF NEO-MARXIST SOCIAL THOUGHT ON HIS RECENT THEOLOGY 'TI HE FLEMISH DOMINICAN, Edward Schilleeeckx, published the Dutch original of his Christ the acrament of the Encounter with God in 1960. In this work, he transposed Catholic sacramental theology into the anthropocentric mode which had been pioneered by Henri de Lubac and Karl Rahner. So involved was he in the existential categories of the anthropological turn that he described " religion " as " essentially a personal relation of man to God, of person to person." 1 The English translation of this influential book appeared in 1963 while Pope John XXIII was in the process of convening the second Vatican Council. Nearly two decades later, the English translation of the second volume of Schillebeeckx's Christological trilogy appeared, bearing the title Christ the Experience of Jesus as Lord. To pass from the first of these books to the second is to traverse a period of singular turbulence in recent Catholic theology. Both books express Schillebeeckx's long standing concern that theology enhance contemporary Christians' experience of Jesus. By 1977, however, Schillebeeckx could no longer designate that experience as primarily one of " personal communing with God." 2 As he put it in his speech on September 17, 1982, accepting the Erasmus Prize for his contributions to European culture, contemporary theology involves "a historical praxis of commitment to mysticism and politics." 3 1 E. Schillebeeckx, O.P., Christ the Sacrament of the Encounter with God (New York: Sheed & Ward, 1963), p. 4. 2 Ibid. a Schillebeeckx, God Among Us, The Gospel Proclaimed, trans. by John Bowden (New York: Crossroad, 1983), p. 253. 341 342 WILLIAM L. PORTIER Over the past fifteen years Schillebeeckx has studied and made a qualified theological appropriation of the critical theory of society of the neo-Marxist Frankfurt School. In the present article I will argue that the measure of the distance from Christ me Sacrament of the Encounter with God to Christ the Experience of Jesus as Lord is the permanent impact of critical theory on his theology. The exposition of Schillebeeckx's thought which follows will have a fivefold purpose: 1) to consider in a general way why contemporary Catholic theologians are interested in Marxist social thought, 2) to examine the stakes involved in a Christian theological appropriation of ideology critique, 3) to situate the dialogue with the Frankfurt School in Schillebeeckx's intellectual biography as a whole and to delineate that dialogue's impact on his understanding of the nature of theology, 4) to show how this conception of theology is at work in Schillebeeckx's recent work on office in the church, 5) to raise some critical questions about the continuity between this latest development in his thought and its earlier phases, and to question the extent to which Schillebeeckx has succeeded in appropriating the tradition of ideology critique into contemporary Catholic theology. I. Why Marx? For some in the Catholic Church, any dialogue between Christian thought and the Marx-inspired tradition of ideology critique is doomed from the start. Marxism is a closed materialist system, inherently atheistic. For his part, Schillebeeckx views the varying currents in the Marxist stream in a more differentiated way. Marxist thought is a resilient body of ideas, its thinkers capable of self-criticism. Noting what he regards as its fruitfulness in Latin American liberation theology, Schillebeeckx feels that Marxism must "also be a constant source of inspiration tn us " in the political democracies of the industrial West. 4 He locates Marx's claim to our at4 Schillebeeckx, God ig New Each Moment, in conversation with Huub Oosterhuis and Piet Hoogeveen;trans. by David Smith (New York: Seabury, 1983)' p. 95. SCHILLEBEECKX AS CRITICAL THEORIST 343 tention in his identification with the sufferings of those who bore the physical burden of the industrial revolution. Thus Marxist thought makes a present claim on us, not as a function of some pseudo-scientific system of materialist philosophy, but as a function of the extent to which Marx, and those who have attempted to revise his thought, share in what has recently been called the " hermeneutical privilege of the oppressed." 5 Jesus preached the gospel to the poor, healed the blind and the lame, and welcomed sinners and ate with them. Schillebeeckx perceives a correlation between Jesus's characteristic concern for the outcast and marginalized of first-century Palestine and Marx's starting place in a genuine concern for the victims of industrialization in the nineteenth century. He speaks of a " convergence " between the emancipative interest by which critical theory is guided, and the liberating power which proceeds from the gospel, although they are not identical. 6 By 1971, when he wrote the essay cited above, Schillebeeckx's encounter with critical theory had convinced him that human communication in history, even the proclamation of the gospel of Jesus Christ, can be systematically distorted in the interests of maintaining unjust social structures. He therefore concluded that theological hermeneutics had to be extended systematically to include ideology critique. " Ideology" is any body of ideas whose relationship to reality has been 5 Lee Connie, "The Hermeneutical Privilege of the Oppressed: Liberation Theologies, Biblical Faith, and Marxist Sociology of Knowledge," OTSA. Proceedings, 33 ( 1978), pp. 155-81. As Monika Hellwig has noted, however, those who claim this privilege for the oppressed are rarely poor. See her eloquent case for poverty as a paradigm for the human situation before God in Whose Experience Counts in Theological Reflection? (Milwaukee: Marquette U. Press, 1982), pp. 35-40. 6 Schillebeeckx, "The New Critical Theory and Theological Hermeneutics," in The Understanding of Faith, Interpretation and Criticism, trans. by N. D. Smith (New York: Seabury, 1974), p. 139. 844 WILLIAM L. PORTIER distorted in the interests of privileged groups.7 Such groups need not be defined in terms of an easily disposed of notion of "class." They can be designated on the basis of social status, sex, race, etc. To do ideology critique is to ask who benefits from the truth of a given body of ideas. Do they embody the veiled interests of dominant peoples or do they give voice to the deep aspirations of the marginalized? Do they work toward the maintenance of things as they are or would the affirmation of their truth demand social change? Theologians could conceivably " practice " this sort of ideology critique from the comfort of their desks. But in his more recent works, Schillebeeckx has gone on to embrace the position, set out in some detail in the Christ book, that unless theologians have political commitments which set them against the social injustice which leads to the ideological distortion of the gospel, they will be unable to overcome that distortion and communicate the gospel in truth. II. What Is at Stake in the Theological Appropriation of Ideology Critique? To the extent that the church's preaching of the gospel becomes distorted in the interests of preserving unjust social structures, Christianity will appear as the palliative spoken of by Marx in his oft-quoted designation of religion as " the opium of the people." In spite of the positive role he grants to religion earlier in the same text as the veiled bearer of authentic human the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world "-Marx nevertheless retains Feuerbach's atheist premise that religion is a creation of human consciousness: " Man makes religion." 8 in ibid., p. 163, n. 90 and more recently 7 See Schillebeeckx on "ideology" in "The Magisterium and Ideology," Journal of Ecumenical Studies, 19 (1982), pp. 5-17. Cf. Gregory Baum, Religion and Alienation (New York: Paulist, 1975), pp. 34-5 and "The Impact of Sociology on Catholic Theology" in The Social Imperative (New York: Paulist, 1979), pp. 119-27. s Karl Marx, "Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right. Introduction" ( 1844) in K. M arm and I!'. Engels On Religion (5th ed.; Mos- SCHILLEBEECKX AS CRITICAL THEORIST 345 In this well-known text of Marx, we encounter the radical difficulty in any theological appropriation of ideology critique. The logic of Marxist analysis tends in a reductionist direction, i.e., it tends to treat religious ideas thematically as products of human consciousness. What then of the reality transcending human consciousness at which religious ideas aim? Even if one follows Schillebeeckx in his extension of theological hermeneutics into ideology critique, on'e must admit that an unavoidable aspect of theological activity is the acknowledgement, without apology, of an historical authority-a positive call or demand, an offer of salvation-which theologians seek to make present. His acceptance of critical theory's suspicion of hermeneutics must therefore be a qualified one. This means an inevitable conflict between theology and the complete autonomy of reason or absolute freedom abstractly conceived. This conflict involves weighty questions of fundamental theology. In an otherwise systematically reductionist frame of reference, what is the impetus which accounts for the introduction into the discussion of the reality of God? If, as Schillebeeckx argues, human freedom and divine grace are parallel realities only in our reflection, but are really two different perspectives on the same reality, what in our experience justifies the introduction and maintenance of the religious perspective? 9 These fundamental theological considerations make it important to ask if there is anything of the " personal communing with God " of 1960 in the "mediated immediacy " of 1977? In short, is there continuity between the de Petter Thomist-cumphenomenologist of Christ the Sacrament of the Encounter wi,th God and the critical theorist of Christ the Experience of cow: Progress. Publishers, 1972), p. 38, and the commentary on the text in Religion and Alienation, Ch. II, and Matthew L. Lamb, Solidarity With Victims (New York: Crossroad, 1982), pp. 52-3. theological discussion in Schillebeeckx, Jesus, An 9 See the fundamental Ewperiment in Theology, trans. by Hubert Hoskins (New York: Seabury, 1979), pp. 633-35, and the critique of sacrahsm in " The Magisterium and Ideology," pp. 7-8. 346 WILLIAM L. PORTIER Jesus as Lord? Has Schillebeeckx's performance in his appropriation of critical theory been consistent with his theological intent? Although a full treatment of these fundamental theological issues is beyond the scope of this essay, they must be kept in view as we trace the path of Schillebeeckx's encounter with the critical theorists. III. Critical Theory and its Impact on Schillebeeckx's Understanding of Theology In 1934 a group of German-Jewish scholars from the institute for Social Research in Frankfurt came to Columbia University in New York seeking a refuge from National Socialism. In Weimar Germany, they had begun a revision of Marxist theory which they called the" critical theory of society." Chief among its exponents were Max Horkheimer (1895-1973) , Theodor Adorno (1903-1969), Walter Benjamin (1892-1940), who took his own life before he reached the United States, Herbert Marcuse (1898-1979) and Erich Fromm. The critical theorists found themselves in a world which one hundred years of Marxist theory and practice had failed to transform. They perceived that the needless suffering and domination under state socialism were easily the equal of the repression of the forms of capitalism which had developed from the industrial economy criticized by Marx. In what appears as heresy to more " orthodox " Marxists, the critical theorists turned from an analysis of political economy to multidisciplinary analyses of Western culture. They sought, particularly in psychological categories, an account of what l\farx's own theory had failed to explain. 10 Access to this critical theory of the Frankfurt School is gained via two key ideas: the dialectic of enlightenment and critical negativity. Horkheimer and Adorno viewed the his10 For a history of the Frankfurt School up to 1950, see Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination (Boston: Little, Brown, & Co., 1973). Cf. the discussion of critical theory in Lamb, Solidarity with Victims, Ch. 2. Lamb's note 3 provides a bibliography of recent studies on critical theory in the U.S. SCHILLEBEECKX AS CRITICAL THEORIST 347 tory of reason, from the Greeks up through the Enlightenment to contemporary science and technology, as profoundly ambivalent. While promising liberation from the domination of irrational forces, be they nature, tradition, or religion, critical reason has succeeded instead in creating new forms of domination which " science " now studies as part of nature. This is the "dialectic of enlightenment." In One-Dimensional Man, Marcuse would apply it to the contemporary United States. Mass culture, he argued, had integrated dissent so successfully that the liberal ideals of reason, freedom, tolerance, pluralism, etc., had turned into their opposites. As he brought the book to its conclusion, he wrote: " Dialectical theory is not refuted, but it cannot offer the remedy. It cannot be positive." He closed the book with a call to the " Great Refusal," citing the words of Walter Benjamin: "It is only for the sake of those without hope that hope is given to us." 11 This is the " critical negativity " which passionately refuses to recognize the identity of reason and reality in contemporary society. For fear that they would only reflect present contradictions, critical negativity likewise refuses to propose positive alternatives. Instead it maintains hope in what Horkheimer called " the longing for the totally other " and engages in the kind of critical imaginings and rememberings we find in Marcuse's Eros and Civilization (1955) . To those who would require a theoretical account of this hope, the critical theorist might reply that such an account would be premature. Reason and reality are not in fact identical. For the philosopher to give the impression that they are by joining them in theory could only redound to the advantage of those who occupy positions of privilege in the present reality. 1·1 Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968), pp. 253, 257. For a correlation of critical theory's analysis with the theological notion of sin, see William P. Loewe, "Dialectics of Sin: Lonergan's Insight and the Critical Theory of Max Horkheimer," Anglican Theological Review, 61 (1979), pp. 224-45. 348 WILLIAM L. PORTIER If asked how he/ she knew this, the critical theorist might ask inquirers to put themselves in the place of those who suffer needlessly, including those who have died. In its negative dialectic, critical theory exhibits a characteristic concern for the liberation of human beings from needless domination, from what Marcuse called " surplus repression." This accounts for its heated opposition to the various forms of " positivism " which, according to the Frankfurt School, had invaded all of contemporary theory. "Positivism" mistakes what is in good measure a product of society for what is " natural," thus enhancing the power of this " nature " to dominate people needlessly. 12 While he is committed to carrying on the critical theory of Horkheimer and Adorno, Jurgen Habermas (b. 1929) finds that critical negativity, in its inability to make positive proposals for political transformation, has itself become ideology. He therefore devoted his efforts to seeking a " quasi-transcendental " ground from which to make such proposals. In the early 1970's, this move took the form of his theory of " communicative competence," according to which positive political proposals should aim at the enhancement of the " ideal speech situation " implied in the very structure of language itself. 13 The Frankfurt School's revision of Marx has implications for the key question of whether Marxist analysis involves an unalterably reductionist view of religion. Because they treat culture as more than simply a superstructure for economic 12 On "positivism," see Max Horkheimer, Oritical Theory, trans. by Matthew J. O'Connell et al. (New York: Herder & Herder, 1972), p. 138 and Jurgen Habermas, I1nowledge and Human Interests, trans. by Jeremy Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1972), pp. 88-9. 13 For bibliography and discussion on Habermas, see Oontinuum, 8 ( 1970) ; Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 2 (1972); Cultural Hermeneutics, 3 (1975-76); Quentin Skinner, "Habermas' Reformation," New York Review of Books, Oct. 7, 1982, and the reply by Thomas McCarthy in the Jan. 20, 1983, Review; Dennis McCann; "Habermas and the Theologians," Religious Studies Review, 7/1 (Jan., 1981), pp. 14-21. SCHILLEBEECKX AS CRITICAL THEORIST 349 reality, it could be argued that critical theorists never totally identified religion and ideology. Critical theory would then be more open to religious reality and to at least the negative task of theology than Marx himself is usually thought to be. Both Adorno and Walter Benjamin were sensitive to the prophetic and mystical strains of Judaism which gave impulse to their thought. The same can be said of Horkheimer's claim that: the traditional Jewish prohibition on naming or describing God and paradise was reproduced in critical theory's refusal to give substance to its utopian vision. 14 Schillebeeckx himself has noted the structural affinity between the prophetic tradition of Judaism and critical theory, as well as the aptness of negative dialectic as an expression of the future-oriented, eschatological faith in the God of Jesus Christ. 15 In his recent theology, particularly in the Christ book and its projected sequel, Schillebeeckx has made critical theory's characteristic concern for the alleviation of needless human suffering his own. He refuses to discuss Christology apart from thematic reference to the "' barbarous excess " of suffering and evil in human history. 16 He has thus begun the process of making his theology thematically responsive to the hermeneutic privilege of the poor. Schillebeeckx encountered the critical theory which philosophically informs his recent theology during the years between 1968 and 1973. The English-speaking reader has access to this 14 See Jay, Dialectiaal Imagination, pp. 56 and 32ff. On Horkheimer as "negative theologian," see Rudolf J. Siebert, "Max Horkheimer: Theology and Positivism I & II," Ecumenist, 14 ( 1976), pp. 19-24; 42-45. Walter Benjamin wrote his "Theses on the Philosophy of History " in response to Gershom Scholem's Major Trends of Jewish Mysticism. See Elisabeth YoungBruehl, Hannah Arendt, For Love of the World (New Haven: Yale, 1982), pp. 161-63. 15 Schillebeeckx, Understanding of Faith, p. xiii, and " Critical Theories and Christian Political Commitment," Oonoilium, 84 (New York: Herder and Herder, 1973), p. 51. 11s Schillebeeckx, Ohrist the Ewperience of Jesus as Lord, trans. by John Bowden (New York: Seabury Press, 1980), p. 725. 350 WILLIAM L. PORTIER dialogue with the Frankfurt School in the translations 0£ a series 0£ essays written during that period. I have elsewhere reviewed this dialogue and briefly indicated its impact on the conception and execution 0£ Schillebeeckx's Christological project. 11 In describing the development evident in these essays it is difficult to overlook the role his experience of the Church in the Netherlands played in this development. This is especially true 0£ what he calls the '" critical communities " or the "'basic movement" within Dutch Catholicism. He tells us that, around 1969 or 1970, he made a conscious decision to identify himself with this movement as a kind 0£ sympathetic theological critic and spokesman. He sees in this movement a promise for the Church's future. Loosely associated with these critical communities in the Dutch church at this time was a group 0£ young theologians, some students of Johann-B. Metz at Munster, all under the influence 0£ the spirit of protest animating European university li£e at the time. They included the Dutchmen Frans van den Oudenrijn and Ben van Onna and the Belgian Marcel Xhaufflaire. I have the impression that it was this group-Schillebeeckx called them theologians 0£ "contestation "-which challenged the direction 0£ his thought at this time. Although he had been introduced to the negative dialectic of Adorno and Marcuse by the time he wrote the "' Epilogue " to God the Fu11 See William L. Portier, "Schillebeeckx's Dialogue with Critical Theory," Ecumenist, 21 (Jan.-Feb., 1983), pp. 20-27. The first two of the five essays reviewed in this article are "Toward A Catholic Use of Hermeneutics" and "Epilogue: The New Image of God, Secularization and Man's Future on Earth." Both were translated from the Dutch by N. D. Smith and appeared in God the Future of Man (New York: Sheed & Ward, 1968) as Chapters I and VI. They appeared in Dutch as Chapters 1 and 7 of Geloofsverstaaen ( 1972) but not in the English translation of 197 4. "The New Critical Theory" and "The New Critical Theory and Theological Hermeneutics" originally appeared in Dutch in Tijdschrift voor Theologie, 11 ( 1971), pp. 30-50; 113-39. In English translation by N. D. Smith, both appeared in The Understanding of Faith as Chapters 6 and 7. The fifth essay, "Critical Theories and Christian Political Commitment," translated by David Smith, appeared in Ooncilium, 84, pp. 48-61 in 1973. SCHILLEBEECKX AS CRITICAL THEORIST S51 ture of Man in 1968, Schillebeeckx was still very much taken by the theology of secularization and the death of God current al this time. His trip lo the United States the previous year had perhaps fueled this interest. 18 At about the same time, Marcel Xhauffiaire was putting the finishing touches on his theology dissertation under Metz at Munster, Feuerbach et la. Theologie de la Secularisation. In Feuerbach the young Belgian found a type of modern theology's uncritical reflection of Western secularism. He denounced as " secularist ideology" the unquestioning acceptance of Western culture implied in the then current theologies of secularization. 19 Theology in a "post-Feuerbachian" context, he argued, required a revolution in the way theologians conceive the relationship between theory and practice. 20 The alternatives would be either the eager capitulation to the modern world of secularization theology or various forms of resentful rejection of the world, both of which would be content to leave the world exactly as it was. This is what Xhauffiaire and his friend Karl Derksen refer to as Le.utall interpretations the basic hidden catalyst 398 LEO SCHEFFCZYK and the standard of measure for legitimizing or denying any experiences of Jesus. It is the subjective significance for people today and for the modern self-understanding, as is shown by the final statement about Jesus's signs and miracles: "Even had Jesus historically and literally done all of this, still how could that be of meaning for us today? What does a social worker in the third world of today care about the miracles of Jesus from way back then?" (16). Here it is clear that the author is not concerned in the end with gaining access to the historical Jesus, who despite all these efforts is claimed to be inaccessible, nor is he interested in the final analysis in how the disciples experienced Jesus's power and miraculous deeds; rather, the purpose seems to be a critique carried out by a modern self-understanding which is not that of ecclesial faith. This completely selective use of the historical-critical method and the related principle of experience can be seen especially in Schillebeeck:x's attitude towards the saying of Jesus found in Mt 11, 27, a passage important for the mystery of this person and in former years often termed the " J ohannine section " of the synoptic gospels, since it seemed to stand like an isolated island in their midst. While many modern exegetes express their conviction that this saying cannot be demonstrated to have derived from the post-resurrectional community, our author himself at first admits that this saying " at its core " could be considered as genuinely coming from Jesus, only then to claim that it is saturated to the core by hellenistic, JewishChristian, late Jewish and even Hassidic influences, which are in opposition to any possible derivation from Jesus himself apart from the residue of a simple consciousness in Jesus that he had a mission (235) .9 Despite all verbal protestations to the contrary, a nonkerygmatic, historical Jesus remains the postulate and leading motif of the explanation, as is evident in the omission of those der neueren Problematik 9 Cf. L. Scheffczyk, Tendenzen und Brennpunkte un die Hellenisierung des Christentums. (Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Phil-Histor. Klasse, 1982/2) Miinchen 1982. CHRISTOLOGY IN THE CONTEXT OF EXPERIENCE 399 Pauline confessional formulae which also extend back into the earliest tradition and where the " divine " picture of Christ is characterized by preexistence and by an equality to the Father despite the acknowledgment of the lowliness of the one who became human (cf. Phil 2, 6-11; 1 Cor 15, 3-5). That center from which the religious meaning of salvation in the historical Jesus himself is said to stem and in which the " salvation from God " finally is based is his unique relationship to the Father, so that the judgment of Jesus himself is viewed again here under the aspect of religious experience. After expressing certain reservations about the theological potential of the concept and language of " Father " heard from the mouth of Jesus, it is finally admitted that this concrete, immediate " Father-experience " can be viewed ". . . as the soul, the source, and the entire manner of his self-presentation" (235f.). At this point the dilemma both of this hermeneutical startingpoint and of the systematic structure of this Christology comes to light. Regarding the immediate, concrete Father-experience of Jesus, the question is posed which would be in principle of significance for all the experiences of the disciples as well, viz., whether it might not well have been derived from a deception, whether Jesus's exceptional experience was not the result of an illusion in light of which, of course, all subsequent Christian experience of the disciples and of all Christianity would have to be termed illusory. The answer is interesting for its logical consequence, which follows stringently from the point of departure in an experience which in the end could never be objectified. According to Schillebeeckx, one could very well dismiss Jesus's Father-experience as an illusion; but what is decisive is to put one's trust in Jesus. And yet, in that case, one should draw the consequence that this trust is incapable of demonstration, that it is preceded by no plausibility or judgment of its believability whatever. It is not objectively based in Jesus himself, but rather in his reflection in human experience. It is a voluntaristic, at worst even an arbitrary, decision. This whole complicated hermeneutical manner of 400 LEO SCHEFFCZYK thought leads in the end to something very much like a merely arbitrary option. It can be understood easily enough that there is but little room for a realistic view of the salvific dimensions of Christ's death and resurrection in such a scheme of human experience, measured as it is-at least in its remote meaning-by the standards of the modern understanding of self. Although the author admits that Jesus viewed his death as a consequence of his service of love for humankind and solidarity with others, he denies that Jesus considered his death as "salvation or a propitiatory sacrifice". This death was proof of Jesus's fidelity to his mission, which implies already in the pre-resurrectional ministry a reference that the concern or " affair " of Jesus should continue. Although the author himself occasionally admits that the reconstruction of this historical picture of Jesus and his deeds is ''rather vague and weak" still, it provides the basis for the interpretation of the Easter events and the reports of appearances, which present merely an expression of the conversion experience which the disciples achieved through a reflection about the historical Jesus. These " visions " were " extrapolations of the graced character " of the divine workings in the disciples. Everything beyond is but "supra-naturalist hocuspocus" (576). The author's subjectivistic principle of experience is confirmed once again by this interpretation, in which the hypothetical nature of method comes clearly to light. According to this explanation the Easter experience does not stem from a new, transsubjective event subsequent to the death on the cross but rather begins simply as a process of recognition among the disciples, an occurrence of conversion and a reminiscence about the historical Jesus, who for his part serves only as the departure point and a point of reference for an internal, human experience. It is for this reason that the " Easter experiences " lack the significance and strength to reach (much less surpass) the validity and normativiteness of the simple picture of the pre- CI1RISTOL0GY IN TIIE CONTEXT OF EXPEJRiENCEl 401 resurrectional Jesus. The normative statement of the New Testament about the mystery of the person of Jesus remains that concerning the eschatalogical prophet: " It is from God that Jesus is present for his fellow humans; he is God's gift to all people. That is the New Testament's ultimate vision of Jesus of Nazareth and at the same time the definition of his essence" (493) . Accordingly, the statements about Christ in the Fourth Gospel are assigned a lesser rank; they are " theology of a second grade" (482) . " Logos " and " Pneuma " are to be understood only as abstract concepts which offer as little proof of Jesus's preexistence as do the contentions of preexistence in regard to the Jewish Torah (483) . Even more obvious is that only a minor significance could be attributed to the further christological development in the ancient Church, as it often expressed the one-sided influence of the view of Christ in the Fourth Gospel, which is " not to be taken in such an exaltedly christological fashion". For this reason, too, Jesus may not be interpreted from the mystery of the Trinity, since this is but "theology of the third grade" (593). In the end, the author does try to link the life of Jesus with the mystery of the Trinity, which in its turn receives a quite different interpretation. In his creatureliness and his humanity Jesus is understood as son of the Father thanks to his essential relation to the creative God. He distinguishes himself from other humans in the end only by his Abba-experience (583f.). Thus the Nicene doctrine with its divergent formulation can be said to have been unnecessary. Likewise, the doctrine of Chalcedon is disqualified as the expression of the " lofty, philosophical sophistries of these Greek minds" (500), a position which could easily be shown to stand in contrast to the results of the history of dogma. Even the title " Son of God " falls under this critique, since Jesus is not named in this way anywhere in the New Testament (487). In line with this argumentation, the church's confession of faith in the God-man is rejected, since" God-man" is an" equally conceivable and inconceivable mixture ". The " God-man " is " a divine icon ", 402 LEO SCiiEFFCZYK by which "we neutralize the critical power of God himself" (596). One can understand why the critics identified this interpretation of Jesus with liberal theology or brought it into association with A. Ritschl's model of the ethical Jesus, where the "divinity" of Jesus is understood only as an index of his ethical significance.10 And yet one need not criticize or refute our author's concept of Jesus on the basis of such extraneous comparisons. A comparison between his own early writings on the "sacramental Christ" and his final verdict against the " divine icon" Christ could offer the basis of an internal critique. The book Christ and Christians: The History of a New Praxis for Life 11 is constructed on the basis of much the same hermeneutic and systematic principles, which represent more of a "Jesusology" than a Christology, the latter being viewed as ideologically suspect. In this work the emphasis is placed more on the question as to how New Testament Christianity experienced salvation and grace and how this experience could provide us with orientation for today. Concerning positions on Christology itself and their hermeneutical justification, there are no major, essential differences from the previous work. In connection with the description of the experience of grace, Pauline theology is allowed a greater significance than before. For Paul salvation is definitely and exclusively " salvation in Christ from God" (171). The universal significance of Christ (in Colossians) and the cosmic-political understanding (in Ephesians) are expressly singled out and brought into connection with modern " political theology " and a theology of liberation . Even the majestic-authoritative statements about Christ as the " glowing reflection of the glory of God " Cor 4, 4) or as the image of God and the mediator of creation (Hebrews 1, 3) are mentioned as characterizing the New Testament's faith-consciousness and are grasped as a way of 10 Cf. R. Slenczka, in: Tkeol. Lit. Zeitung 103 ( 1978) 425. 1977. 11 Freiburg, CHRISTOLOGY IN THE CONTEXT OF EXPERIENCE 403 contemporizing what is nonnative about the faith, viz. that "salvation comes in Jesus from God" (293). This work also speaks more positively than before of the Johannine Christology, albeit with the reservation, born of personal conviction, that this Christology is merely functional and that for John Jesus merely stands" in a unique relationship to God in a way which surpasses all else " (417) . Even the splendid titles of Christ in the Apocalypse are acknowledged to have been contemporizations of the core Christian creed in light of a specific situation of persecution (422) . The apocalyptic features predominant in this sacred book are claimed as the basis of a Christian theology of liberation, the recommendation of which ends Schillebeeckx's own work (446) . Ignoring the likely objection that this is a henneneutically premature subordination of the biblical statements to modern problems and needs, one could understand these statements as building blocks for a biblical Christology which erects a bridge to the dogma of the ancient Church. But such is quite clearly not the author's intention. He measures all such statements over against what he considers to be the original Christian message of the " eschatological prophet ". Measured by this standard these statements appear to be quite secondary; this is a method which tries to justify itself by implying that the scriptures as such, taken as a whole, possess little formal but rather only a socalled existential authority, born of experience, which in the final analysis is the original experience of the disciples with the historical Jesus. All later interpretations stand under the negative index of being " second " and " third grade" theologies. The first Jesus-book, in a passage often overlooked, contrasted these with " first-order " statements, where basic Christian orthodoxy is said to be already so fully constituted (485) that everyone must be viewed as an orthodox Christian who holds to the simple Jesus of the early biblical tradition. That agrees with the clear attempt of the second Jesus-book to devalue the Pastoral Epistles for their " unaltered " and '' uncontemporized " repetition of the matter of the tradition, which is 404 LEO SCHEFFCZYK offered " in the form of cliches " (283) . These biblical statements, too, are to be criticized by the standard of measure provided by the early, concrete experience of Jesus, especially since an illegitimate, " institutional elevation " of the original experience of Jesus through the juridical, formal authority of the Church can be detected here (62). The canonization of the sacred scriptures is judged critically, and the doctrine concerning the conclusion of revelation with the death of the last apostle is dismissed; for where a legitimate contemporization of the "original history" of Jesus takes place, revelation is actually still going on. The revelation arising from an encounter with Jesus belongs to the authentic process of revelation. But, in all of that, there is one constant which controls and permeates all successive " revelations " and which must remain acknowledged as the basic experience of " salvation from God in Jesus", where Jesus is understood in terms of his merely human, pre-resurrectional, non-divine life. The various and changing interpretative experiences remain at the level of dependent variables. When this variable is experiencd concretely as corresponding to "the suffering prophet Jesus" (i.e. in the non-argumentative, subjective experience) and when the current contemporization of the original life-witness is a success, a " fifth Gospel " (2) comes into being, a claim which demonstrates how radically the temporal situation or even the individual with his or her experiences is meant to be related constitutively to" revelation". "The contemporary life-report of Christians belongs to the very core of Christology" (2). Despite all this emphasis on the contemporary and ever-new dimension of progressive, never-ended revelation, the question remains what really is so new about the result. Even in the first Jesus-book it was obvious that supposedly new interpretations of Jesus's person and works (to be a self in radical giving of self, to defend fellow humans, to be a mystic or an exegete of God, etc.) were in fact only rhetorical exaggerations of Jesus's humanity; it is at least doubtful whether these interpretations really do correspond as well to the modem mind as CHRISTOLOGY IN THE CONTEXT OF EXPERIENCE 405 is contended. That holds no less for the predicates suggested for Jesus in the second book: the mystic of God; the defender of humanity; and the fellow human, who has experienced humanity to its depths and yet gives expression to God (828). Basically, no truly, qualitatively new experiences are brought about with Christ, but old ones are clothed with new terms. Even these terms fall short of the mystery of faith in the Godman, Jesus Christ, as is clear in the Jewish conception of Jesus, which is expressed in the " first-order " statements. IV. Approaimation to the Christological Dogma? The goal of both the large Jesus-books was to bring Jesus and his concerns and "affair" in their human and natural historical dimensions nearer to modern humanity, which is supposedly incapable of belief in Christian dogma. On the basis of the alleged original form of the gospel Jesus was to be presented in the categories of everyday human experience, which need not even be expressly religious. This attempt, which only seeks to provide the "prolegomena" to a Christology, is characterized often today as "' Christo logy from below ". Our author rejects this title, probably not least because, in its valid dimension of coming from above, faith is included already in the development from below. But new problems are posed by the Catholic principle of faith and doctrine-to the extent that one still wants to hold to it. There follows a whole series of questions, hermeneutical and systematic, wihch are especially urgent in light of the unfinished task of permeating the masses of material collected in these works with clear and consistent theological thought. One question, for example, is this: What kind of faith is it which can be directed towards a prophetic human being and the history of his impact? The question becomes all the more unavoidable because in the whole context of these works the reflection on the difference between faith and experience is too abbreviated, as is the discussion of the differences' between experience on the one hand and cognition, judgment or insight on the other. The assent of faith, which 406 LEO SCHEFFCZYK refers to divine truth transcending our reason and yet made accessible by revelation, is largely equivalent to the assent of experience, where the motive is the evidentia sensibilis. The emphasis on the subjective moment in experience, where an inherent ambiguity could never be finally excluded, is exaggerated, so that in the end an arbitrary decision is made for one particular experience, while other experiences, especially those of the later Church, are minimalized in their claim to be binding. This leads ultimately to a subjectivistic reinterpretation of revelation and of the normative witnesses of revelation, as is indicated in the rhetorically bold but again ambiguous formula of the " fifth Gospel ". If the consequences of such contentions are considered closely, an understanding of revelation would have to follow in which the authority of revelation and the authority of (Christian) experience would merge (Christ, 55) . Experience belongs constitutively to the occurrence of revelation. By a sweeping condemnation of any gross opposition between revelation and experience (which in this form is maintained by no one), and despite occasional protestations to the contrary, the a.uthor moves towards a synthesis of both realities which is theologically and hermeneutically untenable. The synthesis suggested here is equivalent to misunderstanding the basic human hermeneutical situation, which is characterized not by a co-constitution of the text itself by its interpreter, or of the letter by its reader, or of the contents of a missive by those addressed, but rather by an understanding acceptance of the message, by receptivity and hearing and by attention to what is said, after which one can make what is said (or revealed) one's own or reject it. In these later works of Schillebeeckx, one often gains the impression that he is making human conditions and human receptivity, including all that is human and so all that is experienced, much more than instrumental causes of divine revelation; he is making them its efficient cause in the full sense of the word or even its formal cause. To use an extreme example, one might object that the one addressed in a letter should have to deter- CHRISTOLOGY IN THE CONTEXT OF EXPERIENCE 407 mine its content and even compose it, in order to understand and accept it. To pursue this starting-point even further, the question might be allowed why the ones addressed should need ever to open and read the letter at all, since the content was coposited and co-constituted by themselves. As a matter of fact, the question occasionally posed in these works as to why salvifically significant human experience can come to existence only with Jesus of Nazareth is never answered. H. Braun's answer was of stricter logical consequence: viz., that he simply did not have any other experience at his disposal (which, at least ideally, should call attention to the limits of experience). Schillebeeckx seeks to answer or at least to dismiss the objections of his critics in several recent, shorter works. 12 They show how, where the presentation is kept short, as is the case here, many positions emerge more sharply, if somewhat more crudely as well, whereas the explosive expansion of hermeneutical questions and preliminary inquiries can make the original movement of understanding more difficult and less clear. Christian theology is led back to two sources, viz., revelation and experience, both of which are constitutive for it. (Cf. lnterirn Report on the Books Jesus and Christ [=A], cited as with the previous works according to the pagination of the German translation, cf. here A 13). "Interpretative experience belongs essentially to revelation" (A 20 f.), although the human does not ground revelation itself (a statement which actually should eliminate the claim that experience is essentially constitutive for revelation). It is now said of Jesuswith still greater clarity than before-that he is simply " the point of departure for the concept of salvation in the New Testament" (ME 31). It is also explained that Jesus merely made an offer which people responded to with their own projections. He was simply a" stimulus, a catalyst of name-giving 12 Die Av,ferstehung Jesu als Grund aer ErUJsung (Quaest. disp. 78) Freburg 1979 (A); Mensohliohe Erfahrung und G"laube an Jesus Ohristus. ]j)ine Reoken,sohaft, Freiburg 1979 (ME). 408 LEO SCHEFFCZYK projections " (A 33) . In an interesting aside, it is said that his catalytic role lay in what " he appeared to be from his life and death" (A 33; italics mine). These projections relate thus to something uncertain and merely apparent. On the other hand it is hard to avoid the impression that the author did not remain fully unimpressed by his critics. The accepted pluralism of New Testament Christologies is qualified by the addition that in their convergence a kind of unanimity or harmony of the one faith quite well could have arisen (A 55) . In the same context, Christian tradition seems to experience in principle an increase in value, even if only as a tradition of experience. Assurance is given that " second order" statements do not mean second rate statements (111). The conception of the resurrection is clarified at various points to show that. neither the empty tomb nor the visions concerning appearances need to be denied a certain historical reality (A 89 f) , even if later (e.g. A 102) the " bodily resurrection " once again approaches being a mere model of Schillebeeckx acknowledges a Christology which includes dogma in its method from the start and seeks in its effort merely" to lead believers to a Christology" (A 114). One may perhaps thus see grounds for expecting the further step over to an acknowledgment of the vere homo, vere Deus, even though this does not yet seem to have occurred, at least if the author's appended Credo is taken seriously. A confession of faith in the "only-beloved son" is not yet identical in sense or content with the Nicene-Constantinopolitan confession of faith in unum Dominum Jesurn Christum, Filium Dei unigenitum. A good theological hermeneutics will not overlook the difference. (Translated by Richard Schenk, O.P., Munich) LEo ScHEFFCZYK University of Munich Munich, West Germany DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE NOETIC DIMENSION OF UNITY OF FAITH A UNDAMENTAL PROBLEMATIC which underlies contemporary ecumenical efforts is the question of how ecclesial unity can be attained when churches hold dogmatic traditions which collaborative efforts find impossible to reconcile on a conceptual level.1 Past approaches to ecumenism from within the Roman Catholic tradition often stressed the necessity of a unilateral conversion and adherence to Roman Catholic dogma as a condition for unity. More recently, ecumenical efforts since Vatican II have probed ways to arrive at a unity which respects the ecclesial traditions of each church and entails a conversion for all. One contemporary approach of great import focuses on the Council's affirmation of a legitimate pluralism not only in understanding but in dogmatically confessing the mysteries of faith. 2 Unquestionably, unity of faith embraces the level not only of dogmatic confession but also of lived praxis, of worship and service together. 3 One issue raised in the context of the Vatican II affirmation, 1 The Orthodox dogma of the procession of the Spirit from the Father alone and the Roman Catholic filioque are a case in point. 2 Decree on Ecumenism III, 17; in Vatican Oouncil II: The Oonciliar and Post-Oonciliar Documents, edited by Austin Flannery, O.P. (Northport, New York: Costello, 1975), p. 466. a Few would find cause to disagree with Rahner's reflections on this point: "The community and the unity which are being achieved do not exist simply or exclusively in the dimension of the word as such and at the conceptual level. ... we must express this one creed in common, celebrate the Death of the Lord in common in the physicality belonging to this, celebrate the sacraments in their physicality, serve the world in common in action, and then through all this process community of creed is achieved in the midst of all the pluralism of the theologies." Karl Rahner, S.J. "Pluralism in Theology and the Unity of the Creed in the Church," in Theological Investigations XI (New York: Seabury, 1974), pp. 21, 22. 409 410 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. however, is the question of what constitutes the specifically noetic dimension of unity of faith when the possibility of an irreducible dogmatic pluralism is recognized. The Vatican I decree Dei Filius affirms at the heart of every dogmatic formulation a core sensus which is understood and declared by the Church, 4 and which is " ever to be retained." 5 Although theologians such as Fransen, Dulles, and Chirico have distinguished between the perduring insight of a dogma and its embodiment in the thought forms of a particubr historical epoch, words like " content," " intent," " signification," and " meaning " often are used interchangeably to denote what it is that perdures within the historical relativity of a dogmatic formulation. 6 This article seeks to clarify further the nature of the noetic dimension of unity of faith in the context of differing dogmatic traditions. After some pre-notes on the notion of dogmatic pluralism, the first part of the study summarizes approaches represented by Lonergan, Fransen, Dulles, and Chirico. The second part of the study focuses on the contribution of Schillebeeckx to the discussion by examining some of his early insights on the noetic dimension of faith as it is constituted by both conceptual and non-conceptual kinds of knowing. 7 The last part of the essay utilizes Schillebeeckx's insights to clarify further the nature of unity of faith in its noetic dimension, and thus, also, the nature of legitimate dogmatic pluralism. 4 DS 3043. 3020. For a consideration of the context of this declaration see Bernard Lonergan, S.J., Doctrinal Pluralism (Milwaukee: Marquette U. Press, 1971), pp. 40 ff. 6 David Tracy in Blessed Rage for Order (New York: Seabury, 1975) stresses the importance of reflecting on what meaning in a theological context means. 7 Convinced that the thought categories employed in these past essays are foreign to a modern mentality, Schillebeeckx in recent writings has abandoned this kind of thinking in favor of an experiential-existential approach. This article calls attention to the value of his earlier argument in its own right, and its theoretical contribution to a pressing contemporary question. 5 DS DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THin UNITY OF FAITH 411 PRE-NOTE: THE CONCEPT OF DOGMATIC PLURALISM The notion of a legitimate dogmatic pluralism is related to yet distinct from the concept of theological pluralism. Faith itself unites the believer noetically to the unseen God, not in the manner of the immediacy of the life of heaven, but in a way that is mediated by concepts and symbols and yet which transcends what can be contained in these representations. Faith's impulse to understand and to express the reality to which it clings finds expression in theology. If theology is faith seeking understanding, theological pluralism is the diversity of ways to understand and articulate these mysteries. A pluralism of social-cultural settings and life experiences gives rise to different ways of experiencing and expressing the Christian mystery. This diversity includes conceptual frameworks involving divergent philosophical and theological presuppositions. Often these differences are of such proportion that they may be described, in Rahner's words, as an " insurmountable" theological pluralism. 8 A pluralism in theological opinions necessarily has implications for the dogmatic formulations of the Church. Because of their power to express a fundamental faith experience of the Church with a clarity of insight needed at a particular time of crisis, certain theological understandings have attained an authority beyond that of theological opinion. The central mysteries of the faith thus articulated in an ecclesially authoritative way are dogmas. As faith confessions, dogmas necessarily employ conceptual categories which serve the mind's and heart's confessing of God. But every dogma is expressed in the context of a specific sociological and historical setting which conditions the choice of language used and, indeed, the choice of one specific theology expressed in the formulation. As a fruit of human reflection, dogmatic formulations of necessity s Rahner, "Pluraiism in Theology," p. 12. 412 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. find expression through the use of a particular theological stance. Because they are ecclesiological proclamations addressed to a Church called to believe and confess God together, dogmas entail a communal linguistic terminology which is always historically conditioned. Dogmas thus point to the mystery but do not exhaust it. Aquinas's insight that dogmas are a perception, a glimpse of the divine truth " tending thereto," captures the truth that dogmatic formulas are meant to lead and open the believer beyond the limitedness of concepts to the presence of the saving mystery itself.9 Nevertheless, dogmas do express the central mysteries of the faith in a way that is authoritative for the believing community. Dogmatic pluralism, then, is a diversity in the ways of understanding and authoritatively confessing central mysteries of the faith. The possibility of such a pluralism is recognized by the Vatican II Decree on Eoumenism: The heritage handed down by the apostles was received differently and in different ways, so that from the very beginnings of the Church its development varied from region to region and also because of differing mentalities and ways of life. . . . What has already been said about legitimate variety we are pleased to apply to differences in theological expressions of doctrine. In the study of revealed truth East and West have used different methods and approaches in understanding (cognoscenda) and confessing (confitenda) divine things .... 10 In commenting on the decree, G. Dejaifve has argued convincingly that the technical word confitenda employed in the document applies to a valid diversity in dogmatic formulations. The decree acknowledges a legitimate pluralism involving different ways of experiencing and articulating the divine mystery in an authoritative way. References in the document to the " apostolic heritage " received and developed in diverse ways, 9 " Actus autem credentis non terminatur ad e:imntiabile, sed ad rem." Aquinas, Summa Theologia.e II-II, 1, 2, ad 2. 10 Deorw Qn Ji]cw»ienism Ill, 14; III, 17; Flannery, pp. 464, 466. DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH 413 and to the legitimacy of differences not only in understanding but in " confessing " divine things, suggest the validity of Dejaifve's conclusion: A theological pluralism, that is, an irreducible diversity of theological systems, is, in effect, possible in the framework of dogmatic assertions themselves, and this fact is verified precisely at that heart of the Catholic Church itself. 11 Thus, the question addressed in this paper is not simply that of a pluralism in theological conclusions deriving from dogmas, a pluralism which has abounded from the earliest centuries of the Church, but the more difficult question of pluralism in those relatively few theological statements of truly central aspects of the Christian mystery, articulated authoritatively in ecclesial faith confessions, and explicitly affirmed precisely as dogma by their respective churches. The Vatican II recognition of the legitimacy of precisely this kind of pluralism serves to focus the problem of this study: in the context of a legitimate dogmatic pluralism, can further clarity be brought to the question of what constitutes unity of faith in its specifi· cally noetic dimenison? A SPECTRUM OF APPROACHES Unity of Faith on a Non-Noetic Level A first approach adopted by Bernard Lonergan situates unity of faith in the non-noetic dynamism of the human spirit reaching out in unrestricted love for God. The unity of faith binding together ecclesial communities in their diverse beliefs is transcendental religious experience. This latter is the "inner word " constituting the reality of " faith." As a state of unrestricted being-in-love with God, the " content" of the experience which is " faith " is not a content given by knowledge, and its object is not reflexively known. This experience is un11 G. Dejaifve, S.J., "Diversite dogmatique Nouvelle Revue Th6ologique 89 (1967), 21. et unite de la Revelation," 414 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. interpreted, unmediated by concepts, images, or words, and belies the universal validity of the thesis that nothing can be loved unless it is first known. Through faith the believer grasps transcendent value and experiences fulfillment of the human dynamism toward unrestricted love. Faith is a judgment of transcendental value, and is the " eye of religious love" which, beyond the outer word of various religious beliefs, is the true bond uniting all religious traditions. It is on this level of transscendental consciousness that true unity of faith lies.12 What is the value, then, of specific "beliefs?" Beliefs are the fruit of value judgments, and these latter in turn come from the inner word of faith as the " eye of religious love " able to discern God's self-giving. Specific beliefs are the "outer word" of faith and the concrete expression of the "inner word " of being in love; they mediate this latter word to the levels of meaning. Deeper than the differences of various beliefs lies "faith " as the height of fulfilled consciousness surveying all with the eye of love. This fundamental distinction between faith and beliefs thus provides a foundation for an ecclesial unity which transcends all specific religious traditions. Faith as the power of unrestricted love is the bond making all traditions one.13 "Such a positive orientation and the consequent self-surrender, as long as they are operative, enable one to dispense with any intellectually apprehended object." 14 It is love which " replaces doctrine as the unum necessarium." 15 Lonergan thus situates unity of faith on the non-noetic level of the immediate, uninterpreted experience of unrestricted love. Thi:s position has evoked Pannenberg's caution that Lonergan risks identifying "meaning" with an intentionality that is volitional in kind. 16 To situate unity of faith on the level of un12 Bernard Lonergan, S.J., Method in Theology (New York: Herder and Herder, 1972), pp. 112, 115, 119. ia Ibid., p. 119. 14 Doctrinal Pluralism, p. 26. 15 Ibid., p. 27. 1s See W. Pannenberg, "History and Meaning in Bernard Lonergan's Ap· proach to Theological Method," in Looking at Lonergan's !Jfethod; edited by Patrick Corcoran (Dublin: The Talbot Press, 1975), pp. 88·100. DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH 415 interpreted transcendental experience risks clouding the specifically noetic character of faith, and obscures the intrinsic value of faith confessions. As Schillebeeckx stresses, human experience is necessarily interpreted experience, and the place of meaning is not simply the interior reaches of patterns of consciousness, but the reality of the objective world: The faith of trust and confidence (fides fiducialis) is in Scripture always accompanied by a formulated confession of faith. The personal, existential act of faith, as a fundamental choice, cannot, in other words, be separated from "dogmatic faith," in which the personal attitude is completely dominated by the objective reality of the revelation that presents itself.11 Unity of Faith on a Noetio Level A second approach to what constitutes unity of faith is represented by theologians such as Fransen and Dulles who argue for a noetic dimension of unity of faith and who acknowledge meaning as a specifically noetic reality. In an early article, Piet Fransen suggested that dogmatic pluralism can be reconciled with unity of faith by distinguishing between the conceptual and symbolic elements of faith statements, and their true "signification and intention" which "necessarily point in a dynamic way towards the fullness of the divine mystery." 18 Fransen situated unity of faith on the level of the true " signification and intention" of faith statements, but he did not distinguish between these two words. His approach raises the question of whether the signification of a faith confession is its " meaning," and whether this "meaning " is its " intention." Adopting a similar approach, Avery Dulles distinguishes between the meaning intended in a dogmatic formulation, and the always historically conditioned manner of expressing it. 19 11 Edward Schillebeeckx, O.P., "The Creed and Theology," in Rev·elation and Theology I, translated by N. D. Smith (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1967)' p. 216. 18 Piet Fransen, "Three Ways of Dogmatic Thought," Heythrop Journal 4 (1963), 21-22. 19Avery Dulles, S.J., The Survival of Dogma (Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1971), p. 160. 416 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. Critiquing the " conceptual agnosticism " of Leslie Dewart, Dulles argues for an " authentically cognitive role " of some faith concepts, for they give noetic insight into the divine mysteries and " mediate a contemplative union between the knower and the known." 20 While acknowledging the objective value of the conceptual content of faith confessions, Dulles cautions that " the truth of revelation is never known in its naked absoluteness, but is always grasped within the perspective of a sociocultural situation." 21 The " binding force " of a dogmatic confession is to be interpreted in the light of this always historically limited formulation and its specific intent in guarding an aspect of the saving mystery in the face of a specific error. The conceptual contents and terms chosen in a particular situation as a defense against an erroneous interpretation of the mystery are thus always historically conditioned. The binding force of the sta:tement is to be interpreted in the light of its intention, and there can be more than one valid way of conceptualizing and articulating that same intent. In the light of this distinction, Dulles acknowledges that logically irreconcilable dogmas can exist side by side in the same Church: The question still remains whether total unity in confession is a prerequisite for full ecclesiastical communion. From what precedes, it should be clear that simultaneous dogmatic pluralism is sometimes admissable without prejudice to church unity. If one and the same faith can be differently formulated for different historical epochs, a similar variety may be tolerated for different cultures in a single chronological period. 22 Peter Chirico adopts a position which critiques the conclusion reached by Dulles. In response to the question of how ecclesial unity can be attained when churches hold differing or contradictory dogmas, Chirico focuses on the concept of a core meaning at the heart of every dogma, and summarizes three 20 Ibid., p. 193. p. 173. 22 Ibid., p. 167. Zl Ibid., DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH 417 theological stances toward this concept. A first position either explicitly denies the notion of a universal immutable meaning of a dogma, or so stresses the historicity of dogmatic formulations that the effect is the same. Chirico rejects this first position because it implies that dogmas do not have a core meaning and that nothing can be identified as a constitutive belief for Christians of every age and culture. 23 A second approach appeals to the Vatican II Decree on Ecumenism in its recognition of a hierarchy of truths. This position distinguishes between dogmas whose meaning all would accept, and less central dogmas whose meaning need not be accepted by all. A future united church is thus envisioned in which all groups need not explicitly confess every dogma of the Roman Catholic tradition but would recognize the right of other groups to hold them. Chirico critiques this position as dismissing the inter-relation of all dogmatic meaning. Because saving reality is one, the meaning of one dogma cannot be denied without denying the meaning of all others. 24 Prescinding from a solution which would simply demand unilateral adherence to every Roman Catholic dogma, a third " developmental " approach distinguishes between historically conditioned meanings and formulations and the " core meaning " expressed by these formulations. This solution rests on the supposition that certain Roman Catholic dogmas are unacceptable to other churches only because their " core meaning " is not yet fully understood or developed. If Catholics and other Christians work together to develop and articulate the " saving meaning" of the truths held by their respective churches, there can be hope for a " moment of convergence in which the two developments meet." In this way, no church will relinquish its basic tradition. Rather, by developing what is central in each, the riches of each will become the riches of all. 25 23 Peter Chirico, " Dogmatic Definitions as Ecumenical Obstacles," Journal of 11Jcumenical Studies 16 (1979), 53. z4 Ibid., p. 54, n. 10. 2s Ibid., pp. 55-56. 418 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. Chirico refines this last position. What is to be developed in each tradition is: a) the " saving meaning" of a doctrine, that is, the reality it points to that is a constituent of salvation; and b) its " operational significance," that is, the expression of its implications in one's attitudes, feelings, thoughts, and activities. Chirico is convinced that if the Roman Catholic Church in particular develops the saving meaning and operational significance of its dogmas, it will find that other Christians had rejected them not because they rejected the saving meaning of the reality intended by the formulations, but only because the saving meaning and operational significance of these dogmas had not been clarified for them. 26 Chirico's solution rests on a three-fold assumption. a) " Dogmas represent aspects of the one reality that all must accept in order to be saved." 21 b) Thus, no dogma is more dispensable than others. 28 c) Every dogma contains a core meaning that is universal and immutable and which can be distinguished from its encasements in historically limited meanings and formulations. Going beyond these latter to develop the core-saving meaning will reveal a convergence enabling non-Catholic Christians to accept the Catholic dogmas they reject due to lack of clarity about the universal and saving meaning of these dogmas. What is to be noted is that Chirico's assumption that every Roman Catholic dogma bears a meaning that is universally compelling leads him to a solution which in effect denies the possibility of an irreducible dogmatic pluralism. THE CONTRIBUTION OF SCHILLEBEECKX Lonergan locates unity of faith on the non-conceptual volitional level of the impulse of unrestricted love for God. Fransen and Dulles acknowledge the necessity for a unity that is 26 Jbid., p. 65. 21 Jbid. 2s Ibid., p. 54. DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH 419 in some way noetic in character, while Chirico focuses on the need for achieving a unity on the level of noetic articulation of every dogma believed by Roman Catholics. But what, more precisely, is the nature of this noetic dimension of unity of faith, especially as it is investigated in the context of a recognition of legitimate dogmatic pluralism? It is this question upon which some earlier writings of Schillebeeckx can be brought to bear. The specific problem which Schillebeeckx investigated is how doctrinal development can be compatible with the absolute character of the truths of faith. Although the terms of the question are differently posed, it is nevertheless possible to find in his thought insights helpful in further clarification of the specific question at issue in this study. 29 According to Schillebeeckx, the tradition of the Church has guarded a two-fold dimension of the believer's faith knowledge. a) Explicit faith confessions employing human concepts and words are necessary and valid in conveying objective speculative intelligibility about the mystery believed. b) The believer does truly attain to the reality of God through a noetic contact mediated by the faith confession, yet in a way which transcends what human concepts can grasp or contain. 80 Thus, the Church has constantly affirmed both the objective value of its ecclesial confessions and the utter transcendence of the mystery of God. 31 This two-fold affirmation has its basis in a fundamental assumption: faith is a noetic contact with God which is impossible without concepts, and yet it is a knowledge which is more than conceptual. 82 This assumption provides the perspective in which Schillebeeckx pursues the question of how the relativity of doctrinal formulations can be reconciled with the " absolute character " of the truths of faith. 29 See note \ 7 above. 30 Edward Schillebeeckx, "What Is Theology?" in Revelation and Theology I (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1967), p. 125. of 'Truth,' " in Revelation 11;11,d, Theology · s1 Schillebeeckx, "The II, p. 22. · ·s2 ''What Is Theology?" p. 1.25. 420 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. The Conceptual Dimension of Faith Confessiori.f the ApO?!tolic Faith," p. 76. 43 Ibid., p. 83. 44 Ibid., pp. 76-77. Non-Conceptual Intellectual Dimension," p. 175. William J. Hill, O.P., presents a masterful explication of precisely this central insight on the nature of conceptual knowledge of God in I(nowing the Unknown God (New York: Philosophical Library, 1971·). See also his study, "Two Gods of Love: Aquinas and Whitehead," Listening 14 ( 1979) : 249-264. 46 Schillebeeckx, " The Non-Conceptual Intellectual Dimension,"· p. 172. · 45 "The 424 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. thus found in their character of being a " projective act in which we reach out towards God via the conceptual contents." Included within the non-conceptual awareness of faith, the concepts employed by faith " impart a direction and meaning to the transcending beyond the concepts to reality." 47 By thus distinguishing between the finite conceptual content of faith knowledge and the non-conceptual noetic awareness to which faith opens these concepts as the matrix or perspective in which they are understood in a new way, Schillebeeckx lays the foundation for his concluding thesis. The act of the knowledge of faith and of faith confessions is an act of " intending God " which exceeds the signification or conceptual content of the formulas employed. What is intended by the ecclesial faith confession transcends the conceptual meaning of the words. This excessus of the intending act does not render the conceptual content of the confession objectively without value. Rather, it is through the conceptual content that the reality of God is indeed intended: The act of signifying goes further than the ratio nominis [the conceptual content] but it exceeds this ratio in the direction indicated by its content itself, in such a way that the reality is really envisaged but not conceptually grasped. 48 That the act of signifying God can transcend the conceptual content of the words used is founded in creation's act of be-ing which in a mysterious yet objective way is an inner dynamism revelatory of and tending toward God. For it is God who, as lpsum Esse Subsistens, is Be-ing itself and the cause of creation's participated be-ing.49 Schillebeeckx draws attention to the fact that, for Aquinas, the " signification " of the faith confession is its conceptual content. 50 But the act of "signifying" exceeds the "signification" of the words. A faith confession does not" apply" the The Concept of ' Truth,' " p. 20. Non-Conceptual Intellectual Dii:nension,'' p. 171. 49 Ibid., p. 177. so Ibid., pp. 170, 171. 47 " 48 "The DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH 425 conceptual content to God, " but in the direct line of this and no other conceptual content, the divine reality is truly intended." 51 The objective value of ecclesial faith confessions thus lies in their nature as an " intending act." 52 Through the " objectively referential value " of their conceptual content, faith confessions both " intend " God and " tend to " God: intendere Deum et tendere in Deum. 53 Thus both the mystery of God and the limited though objectively noetic value of ecclesial faith confessions are guarded. Through the latter the believer does not contain yet truly contacts the inexhaustible mystery of God. 54 The value of Schillebeeckx's thesis hinges on whether faith in fact does involve a non-conceptual dimension which is properly noetic in kind. While the very nature of the thesis precludes a definitive and exclusively logical demonstration of its validity, support for its truth can be found in the writings of both medieval and modern theologians and mystics. Schillebeeckx's position is an explication of the insights of Aquinas on the instinctus fidei, the non-conceptual dimension of the act of faith. Aquinas is clear in identifying also a non-conceptual noesis which accompanies the habit of faith. For Aquinas, " to know, " precisely as an act of the intellect rather than the will, is to "judge with certitude" (Summa ThJeologiae II-II, 9, 1). In God, knowing is sure judgment of truth not through the process of conceptual reasoning, but through simple intuition (II-II, 9, 1, ad 1). In believers, created participation in this sure judgment is through the gift of wisdom, given with faith to all the baptized (II-II, 9, 2). Wisdom knows the divine realities not through concepts but through a union, with them (II-II, 9, 2, ad 1). The cause of wisdom is the charity residing properly in the will, but the essence of wisdom is in the intellect, whose proper act is right judgment. Thus the gift of 51 "What Is Theology?" p. 124. pp. 123, 124, 125. ss Ibid., p. 124; "The Non-Conceptua,l Intellectual Dimension," p. 177. 54 "What Is Theology?" p. 125. 52 Ibi4., 4Q6 MARY' ANN FATULA, O.P. wisdom involves a true knowing which is the result not of conceptual reasoning but of a " connaturality " caused by the union of charity (II-II, 45, 2; II-II, 45, 4) . The contemporary mystical theologian William Johnston has argued that William James's study in Varieties of Religious Experience concludes to the existence of this kind of intellectual knowing beyond concepts, and that the experience itself of contemplation confirms Aquinas's insight. 55 The preceding offers a beginning indication that Schillebeeckx's thesis articulates a reality to which faith experience can testify. IMPLICATIONS If Schillebeeckx's argument on the nature of conceptual and non-conceptual faith noesis illumines the reality of faith knowing, as I believe it does, his insights suggest the following summary theses: 1) The human faculties of knowing and loving are meant to be fulfilled by a union with God that is not only volitional but noetic in kind. This latter noetic union begins on earth through faith. 2) Unity of faith thus comprises not only the volitional level of love of God and one another but also a specifically noetic level 3) The noetic dimension of unity of faith is both conceptual and non-conceptual in kind. 4) The nonconceptual, experiential level of faith's knowing, given by the Holy Spirit through the supernatural grace of the light of faith, is the graced perspective which provides the " matrix " in which the created concepts used in faith confessions are understood in an entirely new way. It is the graced non-conceptual knowledge of faith which allows the believer not only to know-in a limited way-but also truly to contact and be united to the God whose oneness, for example, is not that of an isolated monad, but the unity of a God who is irreducibly Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. 5) This non-conceptual, noetic 55 See, for example, William Johnston, S,J., The EJtiZi Point (New York: Fordham University Press, 1970), pp. 126, 135, DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH perspective constitutes a faith confession as an "intending act" containing more than the conceptual content of the confession. This excessus of the intending act which is a faith confession is able to be perceived through the grace of the light of faith, and is founded in nature on the dynamism of be-ing which, as created, bears a true but inexpressible similitude to its Creator. 6) The created conceptual content of a faith confession, while it does not of itself unite the believer noetically to God, nevertheless is indispensable for this union. Within the non-conceptual noetic perspective opened by faith and through which the believer truly contacts God, the conceptual content delivers to the believer the objective reference or direction in which God is to be found. What implications of practical import for continued ecumenical discussion can be drawn from these theses? In the context of these insights, it is perhaps helpful to distinguish at least four kinds of knowledge involved in a faith confession: a) Possible non-conceptual content which is symbolic and imaginative in kind. b) Properly conceptual content which objectively directs, refers, and points the believer to the reality confessed. c) Knowledge which comes from and is praxis, or what Chirico has termed the lived expression of the implications of a faith confession in one's attitudes, feelings, thoughts, and actions. d) The non-conceptual experiential knowledge caused by the light of faith, and which not only gives the believer access to but truly unites him or her to the reality objectively pointed to by the conceptual content. Adoption of appropriate terminology to designate each of these four kinds of knowing is matter for continued discussion. But in view of the frequency with which terms like " intent," " significance," " signification," and " meaning " have been used interchangeably to denote each, any, or all of these kinds of knowledge, I would suggest the following terminology to denote respectively the four kinds of faith knowing outlined above: a) symbolic or imaginative content; b) conceptual content; c) lived significance; d) dogmatic intent. This last kind 428 MAltY ANN FATULA, O.P. of faith knowing I have termed" dogmatic intent" rather than " dogmatic meaning " in order to draw attention to the distinction between the faith knowledge which is properly conceptual and that which is noetic yet non-conceptual-the graced awareness which unites the believer to God. Because the word "meaning" can have a wide range of referents in this context, the choice has been made here to adopt terminology which attempts to convey in a clear way the distinctions involved in the kinds of faith knowing. This author's preference is to reserve the term " dogmatic meaning " for the properly conceptual content of a dogma. Dei Filius speaks of a lasting sensus at the heart of every dogmatic formulation; Dulles and others have distinguished between the perduring intention of a dogmatic formula and the historically conditioned ways of expressing it. This study suggests that what perdures in a dogmatic formulation is what properly and formally constitutes unity of faith in its noetic dimension. It further suggests that the graced non-conceptual faith knowledge which Schillebeeckx's study has illumined, and which we have termed "dogmatic intent," is precisely that locus. It is this graced non-conceptual knowing which, formally and properly speaking, noetically unites the believer to God. This study suggests, then, that what constitutes the noetic level of unity of faith, formally and properly speaking, is the nonconceptual knowing caused by the Holy Spirit through the light of faith. To say this is not to suggest that the noetic level of unity of faith is constituted by this kind of knowing alone. Two pitfalls are to be avoided. On the one hand, the noetic dimension of unity of faith is not to be reduced to agreement on the conceptual level alone (agreement which in some cases would be impossible to achieve; for example, over a thousand years of East-West dialogue witness to the conceptual irreconcilability of the Orthodox " the Spirit proceeds from the F'ather alone," and the Western filwque) . On the other hand, while the noetic dimension of unity of faith is situated most formally and prop- DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAlTH erly speaking at the level of faith's non-conceptual noetic union with God, it must of necessity embrace some fundamental level of shared conceptual content as well. The recognition by Vatican II of a hierarchy of beliefs allows one to distinguish between what might be called "fundamental" and "derived" faith confessions or dogmas: Unity of faith requires the Church's ability to confess together in a common vocabulary at least the most fundamental expressions of its belief in the reality of the God to whom it clings in faith-for example, that this God is one, and is truly and distinctly Father, Son and Spirit .... Within this unity of faith there can be a diversity of ways to understand and articulate derived mysteries, for example, how Father, Son and Spirit are distinct. 56 The distinction I make here between " fundamental " and " derived " dogmas is not simply that between " dogma " and " theological conclusions derived from dogma," where theological pluralism always has abounded. As I have stressed in the first part of this article, dogmas differ from theological conclusions precisely in the former's authoritative status: in their being articulated in an ecclesial creed, and confessed precisely as dogma by their respective churches. " Fundamental " dogmas are those few theological articulations at the very heart of the Christian mystery to which it would be necessary for churches to assent in a common language and common, faith confession, thus, for example, that there is one God, not three, and tha.t this one God is truly and distinctly Father, Son, and Spirit. What I term " derived " dogmas are theological conclusions derived from these fundamental confessions which are themselves recognized precisely as dogma in their respective communions. An example ilJustrative of these points is the Western filioque and the Orthodox dogma of the Spirit's procession from the Father alone. The two formulas are recognized as dogma 56 Mary Ann Fatula, O.P., " The Council of Florence and Pluralism Dogma," One in Christ 19 ( 1983) : 16. in 430 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. in their respective communions. 57 Years and even centuries of dialogue have proved the formulations to be conceptually irreconcilable. The formulas embody divergent Eastern and Western conceptual frameworks and theological insights on hmv the Father, Son, and Spirit are hypostatically distinct. Yet each formula is rooted in the deeper and common affirmation of the truth that the Father, Son, and Spirit are hypostatically distinct. Most importantly, both formulas bear fruit in their respective communions in worship of the one God who is Father, Son and Spirit. 58 Unity of faith thus could be compatible with a conceptual irreconcilability of formulation in some instances. The following criteria, which I have suggested elsewhere, allow for a legitimate dogmatic pluralism guarding unity of faith on both noetic levels suggested by Schillebeeckx: (a) The formulations in question are recognized in their respective ecclesial communions as bearing an authority for the community that is not simply that of theological opinion but of dogmatic confession; (b) These diverse formulations are not simply 57 On the Orthodox recognition of the Photian formula as dogma, see, for example, Serge Verkhovsky, "La Procession du Saint-Esprit d'apres la triadologie orthodoxe," R·ussie et chretiente 4 ( 1950), p. 204. On the Roman Catholic recognition of the filioque as dogma, defined at the Councils of IV Lateran (1215), II Lyons (1274), and Ferrara-Florence (1438-39), see, for example, G. de Margerie, La Trinite chretiervne dans l'histoire (Paris: Beauchesne, 1975), p. 230. There are, however, exceptions to this conviction that each formula is held as dogma in its respective church. See, for example, VBolotov, "Theses sur le filioque,' " Istina 17 ( 1972), p. 282; P. Henry, S.J., "Contre le 'Filioque,'" Irenikon 48 (1975), 170-177. 58 The Orthodox theologian Vladimir Lossk;y argued that the divergency between the eastern and western formulas on the Spirit's procession has not resulted in the same orthopraxis in East and West, and that the filioque is responsible for an ecclesiastical structure and spirituality in the West practically devoid of the Spirit. See, for example, his works The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir's Seminary Press, 1976) and In the Image and Likeness of God (St. Vladimir's Seminary Press, 1974). While it is certainly true that western ecclesiastical structure and spirituality need more awareness of the Spirit, it can be argued justifiably that the West has not been as untouched by the Spirit as Lossky seemed to think. DOGMATIC PLURALISM AND THE UNITY OF FAITH 431 verbally different expressions for one equivalent meaning but are truly and irreducibly distinct; (c) the diverse formulations are rooted in and give concrete ·expressionto a more fundamental faith confession to which both traditions can and do assent; (d) The diverse formulations both bear fruit within their respective communions in the same orthopraxis and worship of the triune God.59 The above criteria relate to the different kinds of knowing implied in adhering to a specific dogmatic formula. When churches seeking union face an impasse posed by dogmatic formulations proving irreconcilable on a conceptual level, examination of the formulations in light of the kinds of faith knowing implied could be a helpful step in reaching accord. This study suggests that unity of faith is situated most properly on the level of faith's non-conceptual yet truly noetic contact with the living God, that is, on the level we have termed "dogmatic intent." In addition, unity of faith must comprise a fundamental level of conceptual content that is held in common. Here the churches seeking union will need docility to the Holy Spirit in discerning what truly are sine qua non formulations expressing their communion's most basic beliefs and what are derived dogmas which, though perhaps irreconcilable on a conceptual level, are rooted in and give concrete expression to a more basic faith confession to which both traditions can assent. Further, churches involved in such dialogue will need to discern whether, in any symbolic or imaginative language employed in diverse formulations, there is a deeper and common level of meaning implied to which both traditions can assent. Finally, there is need for adverting together to the fact that in many instances formulations which are conceptually diverse still bear fruit in their respective communions in the same worship and orthopraxis. CONCLUSION The possibility of recognizing legitimate dogmatic pluralism as one contemporary approach to ecclesial unity gives rise to Fatula, " The Counoil of p. 16. 432 MARY ANN FATULA, O.P. the need to clarify the nature both of dogmatic pluralism and of the noetic dimension of unity of faith. Schillebeeckx's insights on the nature and proper function of two kinds of knowing invlved in professing a dogmatic formula-conceptual and non-conceptual-provide a theoretical fundament for the following clarifications: The locus of unity of faith in its noetic dimension, formally and properly speaking, is the graced nonconceptual knowing caused by the Holy Spirit through the light of faith and uniting the believer noetically to God. This non-conceptual knowing we have termed the " dogmatic intent" of a formula. This latter perspective constitutes a dogmatic confession as an " intending act " containing more than its conceptual content. Within this graced perspective, the indispensable function of conceptual content is to refer and direct the believer objectively to the mystery of God. Finally, distinguishing among various kinds of conceptual and non-conceptual knowing implied in adhering to a dogmatic formulation provides the basis for articulating criteria for a dogmatic pluralism which guards unity of faith on both noetic levels illumined by Schillebeeckx. MARY ANN FATULA, Ohio Dominican College Columbus, Ohio O.P. THEOLOGY AND NATURAL SCIENCE: BEYOND THE TRUCE? A A REVIEW DISCUSSION * UMBER OF BOOKS and conferences in recent years have given expression to a growing dissatisfaction with " the uneasy truce between science and theology "--John Habgood's label for the state of affairs that obtains if we accept the popular thesis that, if properly understood, theology and natural science can have no bearing on one another, so conflict cannot arise. 1 In the present political situation, in this country at least, that thesis has its appeal. Nonetheless, in a world in which natural science and technology affect life and thought so pervasively, generating moral problems and dangers and (a point less often stressed in this context) turning situations we previously could do nothing about into potentially tractable problems, many are convinced that the truce isn't good enough. Among recent manifestations of this conviction are an international symposium of theologians, philosophers, and scientists, held at Oxford in 1979 and now published as The Sci* A. R. Peacocke, ed., The Sciences and Theology in the Twentieth OenturyJ (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981). Thomas F. Torrance, Ohristia1i Theolog11 and Scientific Oulture (New York: Oxford University Press, 1981). Harold P. Nebelsick, Theolog11 and Science in Mutual Modifiqation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1981). I was also invited to review W. A. Whitehouse, Oreation, Science and Theolog11: Essays in Response to Karl Barth (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1981). The subtitle better reflects its contents than does the main title. Of this collection of essays and sermons by the Congregational theologian, mostly written between 1945 and 1970, only two deal to any great extent with science. Several are expositions of Barth for British readers; the rest address a wide range of topics, sensitively and thoughtfully. 1 John S. Habgood, " The Uneasy Truce between Science and Theology," in A. R. Vidler, ed., Soundings (Cambridge: at the University Press, 1962), pp. 21-41. 433 484 WILLIAM H. AUSTIN enoes and Theology in the Twentieth Century; and a series of volumes published under the sponsorship of the Templeton Foundation and the general editorship of T. F. Torrance, of which the first two are Christian Theology and Scientific Culture (by Torrance) and Theology· and Science in Mutual Modification (by Harold Nebelsick). I will be reflecting on these books in this essay. It may be helpful if I briefly indicate the perspective within which I am writing. I write as a philosopher of, roughly speaking, the "analytic" persuasion (and of the subspecies oriented toward logic and the philosophy of science), who once studied theology (in a liberal Protestant setting) but is no theologian. What is offered here, thus, is a not-completely-uninformed outsider's view of the discussion. On an overall view of the books under consideration, three general features stand out. The first is that the theology that appears in these volumes is virtually exclusively the theology of the Western religious traditions. John Bowker, as befits one who teaches in Ninian Smart's department at Lancaster, mentions the importance of considering Eastern thought, and one or two other contributors to the Oxford symposium allude to it, but none pursue the matter. This may seem quite unremarkable. The problem of the relation between science and theology, and the problem of the relations among religious traditions, are usually thought of as far removed from one another, and seldom do both capture the sustained attention of one theologian. One can't talk about everything at once, even in theology. But we will find that the plurality of religious traditions turns out to be pertinent at more than one point in our discussion. The second striking feature is the wide diversity of views of what " theology " is that informs the contributions of the various authors. Torrance and Nebelsick, along with several of the Oxford symposiasts, have confessional theology in mind. But some, notably the physicist Richard Schlegel, take " theology " more broadly, to include the work of people like Whitehead THEOLOGY AND NATURAL SCIENCE 435 and Hartshorne. And the confessional theologians differ notably among themselves in their conceptions of their task-in particular, in their ways of understanding revelation and dogma and how the.ir work is to be controlled thereby. This too is no astonishing thing. Nor is it any great novelty to suggest that the nature of the dialogue that can take place between scientists and theologians will be greatly affected by the extent to which, and ways in which, the theologians are constrained by requirements of faithfulness to dogma. But it seems to me that this is one of those points that, just because they are so familiar and obvious, tend to be insufficiently considered. The third feature is that, among the authors who deal with the substance of natural science, all concentrate almost exclusively on physics-extended in one direction as far as biochemistry, and in another to comprise astronomical cosmology. Evolutionary biology, the focus of popular concern and controversy, gets virtually no attention. (The one author who attends to it, Philip Hefner, is concerned primarily with putative moral implications, as in E. 0. Wilson's sociobiology, and devotes most of his paper to a survey of positions people have taken or might take on the is/ought relation, urging that there are questions here that can't be settled by murmuring " naturalistic fallacy.") I do not know the reasons for the neglect of evolutionary theory. Perhaps it is just an accident of the personal interests of this particular combination of authors, but I suspect there is more to it than that. Perhaps it is connected with a reaction against anthropocentrism in theology, noticeable in several of our authors, most especially Torrance. Or it may reflect an emerging consensus among theologians, and natural scientists interested in theology, that reductionism is the real issue, and evolutionary biology doesn't affect the fundamentals of that issue, merely filling in an apparent gap. One more hypothesis is suggested by an impressionistic generalization which I will now risk: in recent years physical scientists, when interested in theology at all, have been much more likely than biologists to be sympathetic to traditional 436 WILLIAM H. AUSTIN religious beliefs; the biologists (Wilson, Jacques Monod, Francis Crick, earlier Julian Huxley) have been more likely to attack them and propose radical alternatives. It may be that theologians, tired of being on the defensive (tired too perhaps of Teilhard de Chardin?) have sought discussion rather than controversy and preferred the conversational company of physicists. In any case, I do not think that discussions between scientists and theologians can bypass evolutionary biology and continue to he fruitful. In his introduction to the Oxford symposium volume, A. R. Peacocke lays out a convenient typology of familiar views concerning the relation of natural science and theology resulting from various combinations of views as to the nature and aims of each. He then suggests that the typology is probably inadequate, because it leaves out a third dimension: critique of both science and theology by practitioners of the sociology of knowledge. He suggests further that it is too soon to tell how valuable the sociologists' analyses will turn out to be, but it "is already clear that the sociological critique, however unpalatable to both scientists and theologians, can only be ignored at the peril of irrelevance of the whole exercise." 2 One of the most interesting divisions among the symposium papers is between those that take this suggestion very seriously indeed and those that ignore it. In the papers by those who take sociology seriously, two rather different lessons are drawn. One is developed most fully and systematically by Martin Rudwick, an historian of science with a primary interest in geology and paleobiology. We have long been familiar, he notes, with sociologists' and anthropologists' accounts of the social origins and functions of religious beliefs and institutions. Traditionally, however, sociologists have shied away from attempting similar explanations of natural science. More exactly, correct scientific beliefs have bee.n exempted from such treatment; their correctness has been z Peacocke (cited in note 2), p. xv. THEOLOGY AND NATURAL SCIENCE 437 thought to provide sufficient explanation of their being held; sociology comes in only when the acceptance of scientific errors is the explanandum. Recently this procedure has been challenged by proponents of the " strong programme in the sociology of science," the leading theoreticians of which are Barry Barnes and David Bloor of Edinburgh. According to the strong programme, the acceptance of beliefs we regard as correct is to be explained in just the same way as those we regard as erroneous; social-functional explanations are equally to be sought in both cases. The significance of all this for science/religion debates is that before the advent of the strong programme a kind of priority or favored status was accorded to accepted scientific theories. This situation served well the cause of what Rudwick calls " scientific triumphalism " in its treatment of past and present science/religion controversies. (He takes Jacob Bronowski as his main example of a scientific triumphalist, but no doubt he would be willing to add Wilson.) Under the strong programme, science and religion are in the same boat; neither is entitled to favored status. Rudwick goes on to argue that sociologists and historians working within the strong programme have overshot the mark by trying to make social causes the only relevant explanatory factors. They need to broaden their methods to include the psychology of individuals and (crucially) the impingement of objective reality among the determinants of theory-acceptance and fact-acceptance in science. (In the usage of the strong programmers, " knowledge " is defined not as philosophers would have it, as "justified true belief" or some variant on that formula, but simply as generally accepted belief; likewise with " 'fact.") Rudwick does not try to sort out the relations among the explanatory factors he advocates: he contents himself with insisting that objective reality should be counted among the determinants of belief. Then-the last step-he argues that since the presumption of special status for science has been destroyed, consistency requires that we give the same 438 WILLIAM H. AUSTIN sympathetic consideration to the religious believer's claim that the impingement of objective reality is among the determinants of his or her beliefs as we do to the scientist's comparable claim. Many questions arise, which I cannot go into here. 8 I will note only that this is one of the points where the diversity of religious traditions becomes relevant. Scientists, from all sorts of cultural backgrounds, are able to reach an impressive measure of agreement, and surely we must attribute this fact in very large part to the uniform impingement upon them of what is really out there. Believers of different religious traditions reach little agre,ement. It seems then that (to put the point quickly and crudely) we must either assume that Christians and Buddhists are responding to quite different objective realities, or look to social, cultural, and psychological factors to explain their differences. Mary Hesse, one of the foremost contemporary philosophers of science, draws more radical conclusions than Rudwick's. In her Retrospect of the symposium she stresses the importance, not only of sociological but also of recent epistemological critiques of the scientific and theological enterprises. Scientific theories, especially on their ontological side, are radically underdetermined by data. They achieve a certain cumulativeness and permanence of technical and instrumental results, but their ontologies are (a) to a large extent functions of social factors and (b) subject to revolutions. One conclusion Hesse draws is that theologians should not worry much about whether what they say about nature is in harmony or apparent cona I discuss some of them, in the context of a general discussion of the questions whether and when explanations of how beliefs came to be held would have any bearing on their rational credibility, in "Rational Credibility and Causal Explanation of Beliefs," forthcoming (in English) in the Neue Zeitschrift fur 8ystematische Theologie tind Religionsphilosophie. Related matters are treated, with special attention to E. 0. Wilson, in my essay "Evolutionary Explanations of Religion and Morality: Explaining Religion Away?", to appear in Evolution and Creation, ed. Ernan McMullin (University of Notre Dame Press) . THEOLOGY AND NATURAL SCIENCE 439 flict with what the scientists say. For one thing, it isn't clear that they are concerned with the same aspects or features of nature; for another thing, by the time theologians have harmonized their doctrines with the scientists', the scientists' are likely to have changed. Clearly, Hesse's line of thought could easily be developed into an argument for reinstating the mutual-irrelevance thesis, founded on instrumentalistic interpretations of both science and theology. 4 But she does not take quite that line. She suggests, rather, that both theology and theoretical science should be radically reinterpreted along Durkheimian lines as systems of social symbolism. It is on that ground, rather than common subject matter or method, that their relations should be thought out. We cannot say now what the outcome is likely to be, since the task of reinterpretation is one " in which, for our culture, almost all remains to be done." 5 (She says this specifically of theology, but presumably would say the same of science.) Not everyone would agree, of course, that the epistemological and sociological critiques force such drastic measures upon us. Certainly many philosophers of science would join Ernan McMullin in urging that scientific theories are better grounded objectively than Hesse allows. Instead of trying to encapsulate the current discussion of the status of scientific theories, I will simply raise a problem or two about the proposed reinterpretation of scientific theories. Hesse suggests that we explore " the positive symbolic function of science in expressing the cosmology of a culture." 6 In the context it is clear that by " cosmology " she means a view of the physical world as it bears on people's hopes and aspirations, not a disinterested measure of agreement with the thesis of 4 Hesse expresses a considerable Rubem Alves of Brazil (the only third-world speaker) that science belongs to the realm of contemplation, religion to that of action. According to Alves, one should ask of religious doctrines, not whether they are true, but whether they promote life and of happiness. . 5 Peacocke, p. 293. 6 Jbid., p. 291. 440 WILLIAM H. AUSTIN theoretical enterprise. But then what are all the experiments and equations for? A really determined advocate of the scienceas-ideology (or science-in-the-service-of-ideology) thesis might reply that they serve to provide an illusion of objective support, but that claim has yet to be convincingly supported. I want to suggest (a) that theoretical science is probably not a very good source for the kind of social symbolism Hesse has in mind, and (b) that to the extent that it is a good source, it is potentially universal-there is no reason to confine it to " a culture." As to the former point: many physicists would insist that you cannot really understand their theories without understanding the mathematics of their formulation and the experiments that support them. If that is so-and I admit that physicists differ among themselves as to the extent to which their subject can be popularized-then physical science is too esoteric to be a source of social symbolism (and getting more esoteric all the time, in the realm of elementary particle physics). As to point (b): since physics is now an international, trans-cultural enterprise, such symbolism as it can provide would seem to be available to all, not limited to any one culture. Here there is a contrast with theology as a source of social symbolism. While it is true that the major religious traditions have in varying degrees transcended their cultural origins, it is also true that none has any foreseeable prospect of universal acceptance. Participants were invited to respond to Hesse's Retrospect, and two theologians, Torrance and Wolfhart Pannenberg, replied sharply (in Pannenberg's case, with overt anger). Pannenberg firmly declines Hesse's proposal for reinterpretation: " Theologians can hardly be content with looking upon the Christian tradition as a symbolic expression of something else than God and his revelation." 7 The point that theological language is culturally conditioned he finds old hat: we theologians have been aware of. that for a long time. One could reply that T Ibid., p. 298. THl