THE NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACIDNG OF THE CHURCH T: HE CHURCH has always claimed the authority to each in the name of Christ. This authority is given to he Pope and to the Bishops in union with him. It is their duty to hand on the Christian message and keep it intact. The duty of the rest of the faithful is to follow this teaching. The Latin term used to express this following is obsequium religiosum. 1 This is not an easy term to translate into English but in general it has been taken to mean religious assent. The use of the word assent implies that it is the human intellect that is engaged. Following Church teaching is not just a matter of obedience to a superior or observance of law, that is, of acting in a manner in accord with some precept or legislation. Obedience and observance are basically a matter of the will and external execution of a command but do not necessarily imply intellectual engagement, at least on the level of assent. It is quite true that if obedience or observance are to be human acts at all, there must be an understanding of what is commanded. But it is possible to observe a law or command without agreeing with it. And it is execution primarily that obedience and observance of law call for. If one does what is commanded either by an authority or by law, he is fulfilling his basic obligation. He may or may not agree with the command given. In other words intellectual assent is not in itself the response called for by this kind of authority. In fact, intellectual assent as such is not and cannot be required by law. When it is given, it is the magis. 2 1 Vatican II, The Church, n. 25. Documents of Vatican II, Austin Flannery, O.P. (New York: Costello, 1975) 379. obedience see the letter on the virtue 2 For a full treatment of intellectual of obedience of St. Ignatius Loyola, especially n. 9 ff. Rules of the Society of Jesus, (Woodstock: Woodstock Press, 1956) 65 ff. I 2 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. We do not mean to imply that agreement with a law or command is irrelevant. There is good reason to believe that continued observance or obedience is intimately related to agreement with a law or precept. Where there is conflict, observance may be very difficult, and may not survive at all. What we are saying is that a precept or a law aims primarily at performance, not at assent. Agreement will indeed be desirable, but as a guarantee of performance. In itself it is not a requirement of obedience or observance. But assent is the proper response to teaching. So teaching differs from a precept or a law in this respect. Obedience or observance is the response to the latter, and these may be given with or without intellectual assent. But when one is dealing with teaching, assent is called for. From the above it is clear that in claiming the authority to teach, the Church is claiming a power which even civil governments do not claim. Civil government has ruling or governing power; it makes no claim to teaching authority. So it cannot require intellectual assent to its demands. And the same is true of other human organizations, even those of a religious nature. Authorities in them may have ruling or governing power of some kind, but this is the limit of their authority. There are, of course, many teachers in our world. Anyone who imparts information or knowledge to another is a teacher. Ordinarily, however, the title is reserved to those who have a certain competence in the field in which they teach and are teachers by profession. The claim of the Church goes beyond this kind of teaching, even when the teaching is in the area of theology. It is the claim to teach in the name of Christ. 3 This makes the teaching of the Church different from other teaching. It must be admitted that when one is dealing with teaching, especially moral teaching, more than an intellectual response is called for. Assent to teaching must have an impact on conduct. In fact a precept may be connected with teaching or a Vatican II, The Church, n. 25. Loe. cit. NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACHING OF THE CHURCH 3 implied in it. Thus, the Church may teach that adultery is wrong. The commandment Thou shalt not commit adultery stems from this teaching. Assent will be without its full meaning if it is not reflected in one's conduct. In the area of Church moral teaching what is called for is not only acceptance of Christian teaching, but also following the Christian way of life. Two points must be made in reference to Church moral teaching. Simple implementation of a teaching is not enough. If one does not accept the truth of the teaching, he is not responding properly. On the other hand, failing to carry out a teaching, that is, a precept based on some teaching, does not necessarily mean a lack of assent. So conduct failure does not necessarily imply dissent to Church teaching. In this regard one must be careful not to overinterpret conduct polls regarding a particular teaching, concluding that conduct failure implies dissent. Such a judgment would frequently be unwarranted. Ordinarily any teaching calls for assent. A teacher, of course, may present opinions purely for purposes of discussion, but when he or she is imparting knowledge, either factual knowledge or truths based on such knowledge, assent is usually expected. The assent given to a teacher who communicates some knowledge may be based on evidence or it may be based on the reasons given, or it may be based on authority. Often, at least in the beginning of one's intellectual life, authority may be more operative than reason, and sometimes even when minds are more mature, although reasons may be offered, they are accepted because of the authority of the teacher. To what extent we are ever free from authority in this sense may be quite debatable. Even when we think we are being most rational, our motivation may be considerably influenced by authority. That authority or motivating force may be the reputation for competence of the teacher, or it may even be the kind of authority that other influences exercise, e.g., peer pressure, media or cultural influence, etc. 4 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. When we are dealing with the teaching authority of the Catholic Church, the assent called for is a religious assent. The reason for this is not only that we are dealing with religious (or moral) truth, but especially the fact that the basis for the underlying authority and assent is the guidance of the Holy Spirit. The authority of hierarchical teaching is not based solely on the competence of that authority in any particular field. Neither is it based on the religious expertise the hierarchy may enjoy. The reason for this authority is the guidance of the Holy Spirit. It is the claim to this guidance that makes Church teaching unique. This claim is founded on Christ's promise of assistance to His Church. This basis for the teaching authority of the Church was reiterated clearly in Vatican 11.4 A key reason for its uniqueness is the reliability which the guidance of the Holy Spirit gives Church teaching. With conspicuous guidance of this kind Church teaching enjoys a reliability which no human teacher can have. This is true not only of infallible teaching but also of teaching which cannot claim this prerogative. Since such teaching (non-infallible) may constitute the bulk of Church teaching, this reliability is of the greatest importance. It gives the faithful an assurance they cannot have even from the most reliable human authority. To gauge the level of Church teaching one must study the circumstances surrounding its exercise. The top level of any Church teaching, moral or otherwise, is indeed infallible teaching, whether this is done by the Pope himself, or by the Bishops in union with him either in council or scattered throughout the world. This teaching is clearly free from error. It is relatively easy to identify teaching as infallible when one is dealing with defined doctrine. Apart from definitions, however, it may not always be easy. The next level of teaching is non-infallible teaching, and this in turn may have different levels of authority behind it. Perhaps the highest level of this kind of teaching is that which the Church considers morally 4 The Church, n. 2i'i. Loe. cit. NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACHING OF '.1'HE CHURCH 5 certain and which carries with it an obligation on the part of the faithful not only to assent but also practice. In speaking of Papal teaching Vatican II advises that one can judge the mind and will of the Pontiff regarding a particular teaching from the character of the documents, the frequent repetition of the same doctrine and from the manner of speaking. 5 And this would be true of Conciliar teaching as well as the ordinary teaching of Pope and Bishops. One can grant that not all non-infallible teaching will carry the same weight. Our concern here is with the moral teaching of the Church. I do not think anyone would rule out the possibility that Church moral teaching might be infallible. And I think a strong case may be made for the infallibility of some moral teaching. On the other hand, it is conceded that much moral teaching is non-infallible. Since it is with the status of this kind of teaching that we are concerned, we will not deal with infallible teaching or try to decide which moral teaching is infallible and which is non-infallible. We will simply accept noninfallible moral teaching as a given. The teaching authority of the Church extends to faith and morals. The source or object of this teaching is revelation and whatever is necessary " to religiously safeguard or faithfully expound it." It is generally admitted that this includes moral norms derived ultimately from natural law. The Church claims authority to teach in this area because even though it is not revelation, it is necessary for the Christian way of life. So even in this teaching the Church claims the guidance of the Holy Spirit. One may ask why a special religious teacher is needed in regard to precepts of the natural law which presumably are accessible to reason. If one were speaking only of very general principles of the natural law, a special teacher might well be superfluous. These may be available to reason. But when one is dealing with more specific and more remote conclusions, it 5 The Church, n. 25. Loe. cit. 6 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. is not as easy for reason alone to acquire accurate knowledge. Thomas Aquinas told us long ago that these may not be known by all with accuracy. 6 So if we are to know them, we may need help. Vatican I assigned as a reason for revelation the fact that some truths which are theoretically accessible to reason cannot easily be known with certainty and accurately by all men. 7 It is easy to see how some moral truths would fall into this category. And since traditional norms are frequently under attack and new moral problems are constantly arising, the continued guidance of Church teaching is needed for the same reason. One of the encyclicals of Pius XII pointed to the atmosphere of sin in which we live as a reason for the difficulty in arriving at moral truth in certain areas. 8 This atmosphere not only makes it difficult to implement certain moral norms but even to arrive at them or apply them objectively to concrete cases. So Church teaching must play a role in the moral life even though many moral truths may be theoretically accessible to human reason. It should be added that the basic function of such teaching may be to add authority to a norm rather than provide further natural reasons. One cannot expect then that such a teaching will be more patent to reason after teaching than it was before. Nor can one conclude that when a truth does not become obvious and compelling after Church teaching, the teaching itself is erroneous, or at least less likely to be true. Rather one has the assurance that the guidance of the Holy Spirit is behind it. We have already pointed out that there may be different levels of non-infallible teaching. Certainly one of the indications of the authority of a particular teaching is the fact that it is made obligatory. While this may not be a clear sign that a teaching is infallible, it is a sign that the Church is morally a Summa Theologiae, I-II, q. 94, a. 4. 7 Dei Filius, Cap. 2, De revelatione. Enchiridion symbolorum, DenzingerSchoenmetzer, n. 1786. s Humani generis, n. 2. Papal Encyclicals, 1939-58, Claudia Carlen, 175-85. NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACHING OF THE CHURCH 7 certain about the teaching. 9 Otherwise an obligation would not be justified. It may be true that the obligation looks to the execution of the teaching as well as to assent, but as pointed out, teaching is aimed basically at assent. The Church could not impose an obligation on the faithful to follow a teaching unless it was certain of the truth it expressed. In discussing moral norms which are of obligation, then, one is dealing with Church teaching which is certain. We are confining discussion to this kind of teaching. We are not directly concerned with anything the Church might propose as an ideal. The Church can, of course, impose an obligation on the faithful apart from teaching. This would be an exercise of its power of governing or ruling. 10 The faithful could fulfill such an obligation even though they might not agree with the wisdom behind the precept. But we are dealing here with obligations that stem from teaching, and as pointed out above, imply prior assent to the teaching. The question that might naturally come to mind is whether the Church can legitimately demand assent to and implementation of teaching which is not infallible. More explicitly, does the possibility of error, which is not excluded in this teaching, make this teaching so unreliable that it could not be a legitimate source of obligation? I do not think anyone would explicitly take the position that reliability is limited to infallible teaching. If this were true, since no claim of infallibility is made for any other kind of communication of knowledge, there would be no security in human intercourse. The fact is that everyone accepts as reliable information and teaching which is not considered infallible but in which error is a possibility. Thus we trust the judgment 9Magisterium, Francis A. Sullivan, S.J., (New York: Paulist Press, 1983) 146. 10 In imposing obligations on the basis of ruling power an authority must also be morally certain of the need. The difference between ruling authority and teaching authority in imposing obligations is not in the requirement of certainty. As pointed out, the difference is that teaching authority requires assent as well as implementation. 8 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. of physicians, lawyers, and people who have other competences even though we do not attribute to them infallibility in any sense. We do this because we realize that there is a wide gap between the possibility of error and actual error, and that there are ways in which the occurrence of error can be reduced to a rarity and even to non-existence. We realize, for instance, that the more competent a person is in particular area, the less likely is error to be present in his judgments. In fact, fallibility does not imply actual error. At least theoretically, a person who is fallible can be free from error. All fallibility says is that one can make a mistake; it does not say that he actually does. And we consider a person who is fallible reliable precisely for this reason, that, a.Ithough error is possible, it will occur rarely, if at all. And we know that we will be better off and our chances of avoiding error will be much better if we follow the judgment of such people than if we rely on our own relatively uninformed judgments. 11 So it is reasonable to put our trust in those who have competence in certain areas, at least when we do this freely. Thus we prudently rely on doctors and lawyers, even though they make no claim to infallibility. It is reasonable to do the same with Church teaching even when it is not infallible. And the Church can make assent to and implementation of this teaching obligatory. Teaching does not have to be infallible to be a basis for obligation. It is sufficient that it be certain. If more were required, there would be no way to justify civil legislation. So when the Church is certain of the moral norms it teaches, it may impose an obligation to assent to and observe them. Although the possibility of error is not ruled out in this teaching, error, at least for the most part, will not actually occur because of the guidance of the Holy Spirit. This gives the one who follows Church moral teaching a security which no purely human competence or authority can give. 11 Cf. Bruno Schuler, S.J., "Bemerken zur authentischen Verkundigung kirchlichen Lehramtes," Theologie und Philosophie, 42 ( 1967) 534-51. des NON-INFALLIBLE MOH.AL 'l'EACHING OF 'l'HE CHUH.CH !J If indeed the Church is not certain of some norm, it could not impose an obligation to follow it. The Church cannot impose an obligation on the faithful to follow probable opinions as such. And where there has been question only of such opinions, the Church has traditionally allowed freedom. What about the possibility of dissent from non-infallible moral teaching? 12 If error is possible in this kind of teaching, it must also be admitted that dissent is possible. But just as there is a wide gap between the possibility of error and actual error, there must be a similar gap between the possibility of dissent and legitimate actual assent. And certainly since error does not necessarily occur in non-infallible teaching, neither will dissent be necessary. Non-infallible teaching can be just as free of error as infallible teaching. The difference between the two is not in the actual presence of error but only in the possibility. It is conceivable that the body of non-infallible teaching in the Church would actually be free from error. There would be no place for dissent in this happy situation even though it would still be possible. A very false impression regarding dissent might arise from the atmosphere in which we are living today. There is so much talk about the right to dissent and even actual dissent that one easily gets the impression that dissent can be as common and as legitimate as assent. From what we have already said, this can hardly be true. It should be stated clearly that the right to dissent does not make actual dissent legitimate. In fact, rights language may not be very useful in this issue. It may indeed be misleading. 12 Since this article is focused on the reliability of non-infallible teaching, our interest in dissent is limited to it as a response to this teaching. Promoting dissent publicly and protesting Church teaching go beyond the parameters we have set for the article. Suffice it to say that since they are even more problematic than simple dissent, they could not be handled adequately in a brief space. Dissent in itself involves only the good of the dissenter. Promoting dissent and protesting teaching involves the good of other faithful as well as the good of the teaching Church herself. The Church cannot be complacent about these activities. 10 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. If I own a house, I may have a right to burn it down, but ordinarily it would be a very stupid thing to do. It can be rather simplistic to attempt to justify some act merely by appealing to a right. One can do wrong without violating rights. As we have already pointed out, the right to dissent does not automatically make actual dissent legitimate. The legitimacy of actual dissent depends on the existence of actual error more than on the right to dissent. So whatever one may want to say about a right to dissent, the legitimacy of dissent is tied to the existence of error. If there is no error, there can be no legitimate dissent, even though a teaching is non-infallible and the theoretical possibility of error is not ruled out. Another curious aspect of the current atmosphere of dissent regarding moral teaching is that it is all in the direction of more liberal norms. Looking objectively at the whole issue of noninfallible teaching and its vulnerability to error, one would tend to expect that error might occur just as readily on the side of teaching being less strict than it should be as well as of being too strict. Yet the bulk of the dissent is against teaching which is on the strict side. This makes one wonder to what extent dissent may be related more to a desire for freedom than a desire for truth. In commenting on the frequency of dissent it will be important to determine how one legitimately concludes to error in non-infallible Church teaching? If the Church herself either expressly or implicitly accepts a dissenting opinion, one can clearly conclude that the contrary opinion was erroneous. Some point to the Declaration on Religious Liberty vis-a-vis the state as an instance of an express change in Church teaching. 13 Acceptance might also be implicit if the Church over a long period of time failed to respond to dissent. But in the absence of such acceptance, it is not so easy to conclude legitimately to erroneous teaching. In other words, even though the dissent may bring to light aspects of the problem 13 Vatican II. Flannery, 799-812. NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACHING OF THE CHURCH 11 that were not previously considered, if the Church continues to teach what it has taught it is more difficult to be sure that the teaching is erroneous. Sometimes the sensus fidelium is appealed to in support of dissenting opinion. It is indeed a fact that the Council credited infallibility in believing (not in teaching) to the faithful where in union with their Bishops all believe in some truth of faith or morals. 14 And even where a lesser consensus might be involved, although it would not warrant the above conclusion, it is something that would have to be reckoned with. If dissent is frequent in the sense that many do not agree with a particular teaching, the dissent should certainly be taken into consideration. But what Familiaris consortio says about the sensus fidelium should be attended to here. 15 One must be sure that it reflects the faith before one can confide in it. The faithful may be subject to other influences, and their opinion in a particular area may reflect these influences rather than a sensus fidei. Numbers will be significant only if they reflect a sensus fidei. If they reflect some other influence, they tell us nothing about the truth of Church teaching, and may even lead us astray So. while the sensus fidelium can be a legitimate source of religious truth, it will be so only when it reflects a sensus fidei. Ultimately, the one who is empowered to teach must decide this. Indeed, when the Church teaches something as certain and binding, there is an initial presumption of truth in favor of this teaching since it has the guidance of the Holy Spirit. As pointed out, this guidance gives it a reliability which no purely human agent can claim, no matter how competent. So the teaching enjoys a presumption of truth which no other kind of teaching can claim. The burden of proof would rest on the shoulders of the person or persons who would deny some Church teaching or propose some substitute. Their judgment 14 The Church, 15 The 440. n. 12. Flannery, 363. Apostolic Exhortation on the Family, n. 5. Origins, 11, 28-29 ( 1981) 12 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. or norm would have to be certain to overturn the presumption in favor of Church teaching. The unique reliability of Church teaching derived from the guidance of the Holy Spirit, besides offering a guarantee against the error of a particular teaching, will also make legitimate dissent a rare, if ever, phenomenon. Frequent dissent is simply incompatible with the guidance of the Holy Spirit and the reliability of Church teaching which depends on this guidance. Even in purely secular matters we would not trust the kind of guidance we would get from a teacher who was frequently wrong. It would be much more imprudent to rely on such an incompetent guide in spiritual matters. Legitimate dissent must consequently be rare. It follows that if one dissents frequently from Church teaching, even noninfallible teaching, he is questioning not only the truth of a particular teaching. He is throwing doubt on the reliability of this kind of teaching. Already pointed out, frequent error is incompatible with the reliability of the teacher. And in the case of Church teaching, where this reliability is believed to depend on the guidance of the Holy Spirit, it raises questions about the validity of this belief. I think one would also have to conclude that a person who dissents frequently from non-infallible teaching on the basis of natural reason no longer makes this teaching his regula fidei. He accepts it only when he agrees with it. His criterion of truth in this area is not Church teaching but his own reason. The dissent one hears of today does not ordinarily involve total denial of a particular teaching. Thus no one will simply maintain that there is nothing wrong with adultery, or that t'here is nothing wrong with abortion. The dissent, with perhaps some exceptions, is aimed largely at hard cases. Those who dissent are not satisfied with a solution of such cases which allows for mitigated guilt. They would like to argue that such cases are morally permissible. So they dissent from Church teaching to the extent that it includes such hard cases. Yet it is precisely because of the hard cases that the guidance NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACHING OF THE CHURCH 13 of the Church is needed and helpful. It is in these areas particularly that the ability of the individual to make objective judgments may be subject to the greatest interference, and therefore less reliable. One might well dispute the need for Church teaching in cases where the application of the norm is easy. So if one simply restricts the reliability of Church teaching to such cases, he would have great difficulty justifying it at all. One who teaches dissent to Church teaching in difficult cases is questioning it precisely in those areas in which it is most useful and needed. He is really questioning the usefulness of this kind of teaching. In this context the problem of exceptions to Church teaching arises. Does one who makes an exception to Church teaching violate this teaching? Or is this consistent with assent? Here we are not dealing, at least directly, with the possibility of error but with the possibility that moral norms are limited in their extension. Obviously, if a teaching is open to exceptions, assent to it will be limited to this extent. This is not an issue into which we can go thoroughly, but it is safe to say, I believe, that although some moral norms are open to exceptions, the Church has traditionally taught that such things as adultery, premarital sex, deliberate killing of the innocent, are absolutely wrong. In other words, they are not open to exceptions. There are some today who take the position that all moral norms are open to exception. 16 They argue that this is true even of moral norms taught by the Church under the guidance of the Holy Spirit. They contend that it is impossible for moral norms to cover all possible cases, since it is impossible to foresee all possible circumstances in which a particular norm might be applied. So every norm must be open at least to this ex16 Those who subscribe to this position are frequently called proportionalists, since their general principle is that material moral norms will yield to a proportionate reason. They deny that there are moral absolutes e111 objecto. At the most these objects constitute ontic evil. A moral judgment can be made only when all the elements of the act are considered. An act will be considered morally evil only when all the ontic evil in the act outweighs the good. 14 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. tent. It must allow at least for some possible though unforeseen exception of the future. On the theoretical level one might well dispute the need to consider all possible circumstances before establishing an absolute norm. But even if one were to admit this position, I do not think this admission would affect the absoluteness of some Church moral teaching. Even those who hold that all norms must be theoretically open to exception admit that some moral norms are practically absolute. In other words, even though theoretically these norms must be open to exceptions for socalled proportionate reasons, in practice no such reasons appear. So these norms are practically absolute. I think that one would at least have to admit that the moral norms which the Church teaches as absolute fall into this category. One who would allow an exception to such a norm would be denying that the norm itself was practically absolute. He would be saying then that this norm was erroneous to the extent that it claimed to include this case. Practically speaking, he would be dissenting from the norm to this extent. In other words, the acceptance of absolute norms in Church teaching is not inconsistent with a metaethics which maintains that all norms are open theoretically to exceptions. So no one can deny the absoluteness of Church teaching on this basis. If it is claimed that the Church is in error, it is done on the basis of the person's own estimate of the existence of a proportionate reason, not on the basis of the method itself. To argue against some absolute teaching, one would have to assume that his reason is one which the Church had never considered in the past. So it would have to be something entirely new. It would also have to be new in the sense that it is totally unlike anything the Church might have considered and rejected in the past. Nor would it be sufficient for the difference to be one of degree. It would have to be such that one would be dealing with a specifically different act. In discussing the issue of dissent some attention should be ·given to the relation between non-infallible teaching and con- NON-INFALLIBLE MORAL TEACHING OF THE CHURCH 15 science. What is the role of conscience in dealing with noninfallible teaching? In general, there would seem to be no difference between the role conscience plays in non-infallible teaching and the one it plays in infallible teaching. It is the function of conscience to discern whether a particular act in prospect falls under a moral prohibition or not. It is not the role of conscience to determine whether a particular norm is true or not. This must be done on a different level. If the person dissents from a particular teaching, the role of his conscience will then be to use the norm he accepts to determine whether the act is permitted or not. There is no strict conflict between conscience and norm. The conflict is rather between Church teaching and the norm the person considers true. It is not the role of conscience to make exceptions to norms. To be valid and legitimate, an exception must be built into the norm itself. The function of conscience is merely to determine whether the conditions for making the exception are verified in an act under consideration. It is not empowered to make an exception to a norm. If a norm is absolute, conscience must follow it. ... or else adopt a norm which allows the exception the person wants to make. Sometimes a plea is made that a person cannot in conscience observe a particular teaching. The person may be involved in what appears as a conflict between the duty reflected in the teaching and another duty, and may decide that he should follow the latter. This should not be confused with exceptionmaking. The norm he uses does not make what the person does good; it simply removes guilt when in good faith he does something wrong. To summarize, then, we tried to show that the non-infallible moral teaching of the Church which we have been discussing (morally certain and binding) , although not immune from the possibility of error, may be free from actual error, and is a reliable source of truth. Indeed, due to the guidance of the Holy Spirit, it is, apart from infallible teaching, the most reliable source of religious and moral truth we have. Since it is 16 JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. morally certain, this teaching enjoys a presumption of truth. It thus puts the burden of proof on one who would deny some Church teaching, and it will be overturned only by certainty of error. If it occurs at all, error must be rare. Frequent error is incompatible with the reliability of such teaching and with the guidance of the Holy Spirit which accounts for it. Dissent, if it is to be legitimate, must be based on proof of error, and must be rare. Frequent dissent is incompatible both with the reliability of Church teaching and the guidance of the Holy Spirit behind it. If one dissents frequently, he undermines both and makes his own reason rather than Church teaching his regula fidei. JOHN R. CONNERY, S.J. Loyola University Chicago, Illinois AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY AND THE APPROXIMATING RELATION HERE IS, IT CAN BE SAID, at least one troubleome premise (to some, unacceptable) in each of the Five Ways recorded by Aquinas in the Summa Theologiae (S.T., I, q.2, a.3, c.). Three of the W·ays, i.e., the First and the Second and the Fifth, have a premise which describes God-Prime Mover (Primum Movens, quod a nullo movetur) , First Efficient Cause (Causa Efficiens Prima), Intelligent Orderer (Aliquid Intelligens, a quo omnes res naturales ordinantur in finem), respectively-in a way which falls short of a proper or adequate (unmistakable, unquestionable, unique) identification of God. That is, it is not necessary that the Prime Mover be God, or that the First Efficient Cause be God, or that the Intelligent Orderer be God. For, whatever else God is, God is the Creator, and the Prime Mover is not. And neither is the First Efficient Cause; nor is the Intelligent Orderer. This happens because the empirical point of departure of each of these three Ways gives the causality of the Prime Mover, of the First Efficient Cause, and of the Intelligent Orderer an effect and a scope which make it impossible to identify them with the effect and the scope of the causality of the Creator. The two remaining ways, though providing a description of God which quite properly or adequately identifies God-SelfNecessary Being (Ens per se necessarium), Most a Being (Maxime Ens), respectively-make an analytic claim which is troublesome (to some unacceptable), in any case difficult to understand. In the Third Way, it is the analytic claim that " ... si ... omnia sunt possibilia non esse, aliquando nihil fuit in rebus;" and in the Fourth Way, it is the analytic claim that 17 18 JOSEPH BOBIK " . [si] ... magis et minus dicuntur de diversis secundum quod appropinquant diversimode ad aliquid quod maxime est ... , ... est ... aliquid quod est verissimum et optimum et nobilissimum ... et ... maxime ens." There are three parts in the argument of the Fourth Way ,1 and it is the first of these which is difficult to understand. The first part moves from the observed existence of the more and the less good, true, noble, etc. to the concluded existence of the most good, true, noble, etc.-the simpliciter good, true, noble, etc., as it is called in the Contra Gentiles formul,ation of an argument (S.G., I, cap. 13) which is similar to (though also quite different from) the Fourth Way of the Summa Theologiae.2 The second part argues that the most true or verissimum 1 It will be of help to the reader to have the text of the Fourth Way in hand, and to have its three parts explicitly distinguished. Quarta via sumitur ex gradibus qui in rebus inveniuntur. First part: Invenitur enim in rebus a liquid magis et minus bonum, et verum, et nobile: et sic de aliis huiusmodi. Sed magis et minus dicuntur de diversis secundum quod appropinquant diversimode ad aliquid quod maxime est: sicut magis calidum est, quod magis appropinquat maxime calido. Est igitur aliquid quod est verissimum et optimum et nobilissimum, Second part: et per consequens maxime ens: nam quae sunt maxime vera, sunt maxime entia, ut dicitur II Metaphys. Third part: Quod autem dicitur maxime tale in aliquo genere, est causa omnium quae sunt illius generis: sicut ignis, qui est maxime calidus, est causa omnium calidorum, ut in eodem libro dicitur. Ergo est aliquid quod omnibus entibus est causa esse, et bonitatis, et cuiuslibet perfectionis: et hoc dicimus Deum. relation to move to the 2 Whereas the Fourth Way uses the approximating existence of the Maxime Ens from the fact that there are real things which are more and less, the way of the G.G. uses the approximating relation to move to the existence of the Maxime Ens from the fact that there are propositions such that one is more false than the other (and so, less true than the other) more puzzling still than the Fourth Way. Here is the text of the G.G. argument: Potest etiam alia ratio colligi ex verbis Aristotelis. In II enim Metaphys. ostendit quod ea quae sunt maxime vera, sunt et maxime entia. In IV autem Metaphys. ostendit esse aliquid maxime verum, ex hoc quod videmus duorum falsorum unum altero esse magis falsum, AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 19 (already concluded to exist in the first part) is most a being or maxime ens. The third part argues that the most a being or maxime ens (concluded to exist in the second part) is the cause of the being, the goodness, the truth, the nobility, and the like, in all else, including the more and the less which constitute the point of departure of the Fourth Way in the first part of the argument. And so, the Fourth Way argues that the existence of the more and the less true requires the existence of the most true, which (qua most true) is also most a being, and which (qua most a being) is the cause of the existence, the goodness, and the like, of all else, i.e., of the more and the less. The existence of the thing called the most, it is to be noted, is established before it is argued that the most is a cause. This is troublesome; and, if not troublesome, then certainly difficult to understand. For it is not clear how the existence of the most is established; since, as it appears, it is not established by an appeal to causality. What is there about the more and the less (one is led to ask), other than its being the effect of the most (argued in the last part), which enables Aquinas to conclude to the existence of the most (in the first part) ? It is our intention, in this brief paper, to try to render the first part of the Fourth Way a bit less troublesome, a bit less difficult to understand. Let us look more closely at the first part of the Fourth Way. " Magis et minus," writes Aquinas, " dicuntur de diversis secundum quod appropinquant diversimode ad aliquid quod maxime est." What exactly is he doing here? He is pointing out that different things are said (dicuntur) -notice " are said "-to be such that some of them are more and others less good, true, noble, and the like, according as they approximate, or approach, in different ways something which is the most (or simpliciter) good, true, noble, etc. But, since Aquinas imunde oportet ut alterum sit etiam altero verius; hoc autem est secundum approximationem ad id quod est simpliciter et maxime verum. Ex quibus concludi potest ulterius esse aliquid quod est maxime ens. Et hoc dicimus Deum. !W JOSEPH BOBIK mediately concludes: " Est igitur aliquid quod est verissimum et optimum et nobilissimum," i.e., since he immediately concludes that there e:cists something which is truest and best and noblest, he is also pointing out that I) different things are said to be such that some are more and others less, because they are-notice "are "-such that some are more and others less, and 2) that these things could not be such that some are more and others less, unless there exists something which is the most, in relation to which the more and the less are precisely the more and the less they are, according as they approximate that most in different ways. He is saying that things which exist, and which are more and less, are more and less precisely according as they approximate a most; and could not exist as approximating a most unless the most they approximate is an existing most. Or, more briefly, things which approximate a most cannot approximate a most unless there is a most which they approximate. And indeed, Aquinas himself makes this point explicitly, though in another place-in his commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle: ". . . non esset aliquid affinius vero vel propinquius, nisi esset aliquid simpliciter verum." (In IV Metaph., lect. 9, n.659): " ... there would not be anything which is closer to the true, i.e., more true, than something else, unless there e:cisted something which is simply true." 3 What is there about the approximating relation which enables Aquinas to draw the conclusion that what is approximated-and what is approximated is what is a But here, Metaphysics, Bk. IV, 1008 b 31-1009 a 5, Aristotle presents his seventh argument against those who claim that contradictory statements are simultaneously true; or, as Aquinas puts it, against those qui dicun t contradiotoria simul esse vera (In IV M etaph., lect. 7, n. 611). And so, the statement of Aquinas just quoted (from In IV Metaph., lect. 9, n. 659) is about the truth of propositions (as is the argument of the 0.G. quoted in footnote 2), not about the truth of things. The Fourth Way, on the other hand, is talking precisely about the truth of things. It is to be noted that the reference made to Aristotle Metaphysics, Bk. IV, in the O.G. argument quoted in footnote 2 is to Aristotle's seventh argument against those who claim that contradictory statements are simultaneously true. AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 21 maxime or simpliciter-must exist, if there exist things which are more and less, and which (qua more and less) approximate it? This is the troublesome question, the difficult question, to which the analytic claim of the first part of the argument of the Fourth Way gives rise. * * * What, if anything, has been suggested by way of trying to clarify what goes on in the first part of the Fourth Way? 1. There is the suggestion of Harvanek (A.C.P.A. Proceedings, 1954, pp. 207-212) that t:he Fourth Way moves from the more and the less to demonstrate the existence of a most, and "prior to any appeal to causality" (p. 211) ,4 " by a kind of natural dialectic of the mind" (p. 210). In this natural dialectic, it is explained, the mind " in its recognition of grades ... implicitly asserts the existence of a maximum at the end of an ascending scale" (p. 210) maximum, one wants to clarify, in the sense of a simpliciter or an absolute, beyond which there cannot be a more. What this is saying appears to be the following. To recognize tha:t there are things such that some are more and otheTs less is to recognize that these things (i.e., the some more and others less) are such that something more perfect than any of them is in principle possible. And to recognize this entails recognizing as in principle possible, though implicitly, something so perfect that a more perfect is in principle impossible. That is, "the mind naturally judges greater and less according to some standard or norm" (p. 211)-i.e., a most, or a simpliciter, or an absolute. But then, continues Harvanek, the mind moves on beyond that to judge that the standard or norm (the most, the absolute) must actually exist, and just because the mind has judged greater and less in relation to the standard it has recognized as in principle possible.5 But, one can ask, Harvanek reflects: " ... does it follow the norm then necessarily 4 It is important, it is to be noted, to keep this priority in mind. This is saying that, if there is something than which a greater is possible, then there must be something than which a greater is impossible. And this, it appears to be saying, is demanded by the approroimating relation. 5 22 JOSEPH BOBIK exists?" (p. 211), just because the natural dialectic of the mind has judged it to exist; and precisely for the reason given?, i.e., because the mind has judged greater and less in relation to (i.e., as approximating) a most (an absolute, a standard, a norm) recognized as in principle possible? If Aquinas actually argues in this way, one will still have to make clear, Harvanek suggests-without himself attempting to make it clear--exactly how the natural dialectic which takes place in the mind actually demonstrates the real existence of an absolute, and prior to any appeal to causality (p. 211) . Here, by noting that the existence of an absolute is demonstrated prior to any appeal to causality, Harvanek puts his finger on the troublesomeness of the approximating relation which figures in the first part of the Fourth Way. And he attempts to resolve this troublesomeness in terms of the natural dialectic of the mind which he describes. But, this resolution adds a problem-that of showing how one can pass to the conclusion of the real existence of that most or absolute from one's understanding of more and less in relation to one's understanding of a most. 2. There is, secondly, the suggestion of Maritain in Approaches to God, 6 that what is operative in Aquinas's argument from the more and less to the existence of a most, and prior to any appeal to causality, is a self-evident principle which " expresses in an entirely general way the logical requirements of the concept of comparative relation " (p. 53) , namely the proposition: " Every series composed of a more and a less connotes a most " (p. 53) , a proposition with " supra-empirical and unconditional universality and necessity" (p. 53) . To say that the more and less connote a most means that " wherever there exist degrees (wherever there is a more and a less) it is necessary that there exist, somewhere, a supreme degree or a maxmium (a most)" (p. 50). The connoting is a connoting with respect to the existence of a most. But, one must ask, exactly what sort of connoting is this connoting? That is, in a Maritain, Jacques. Approaches to God, translated from the French by Peter O'Reilly. New York: Harper & Brothers Publishers, 1954. AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION Q3 virtue of what in the more and the less do they (the more and the less) connote the existence of a most, and precisely what is it in the most which gets picked out by the connoting? The most cannot be picked out as the cause of the more and the less, since causality is not operative until the third part of the argument. How then does the most get picked out? Simply as what the more and the less approximate. And, in virtue of what in the more and the less do they (the more and the less) connote the existence of a most? Simply in virtue of the fact that, as more and less, they approximate. The most emerges not as the cause of the more and the less, but simply as what is approximated by the more and the less. What is it that the most does (if "does" is the word?) for the more and the less, in being that which they approximate? Nothing-if "doing" means acting as an efficient cause. All that the most "does" is to be there as what is approximated by the more and the less. 7 A comparison may be helpful. (This comparison was suggested by Maritain's noting that the proposition" Every series composed of a more and a less connotes a most " is a necessary and self-evident proposition of the same logical type as the principle of causality-which Maritain formulates as follows: Everything which is contingent is caused-Le., known of itself per se secundo modo. Seep. 53; and p. Ql, note 1). To be contingent is to be caused. And so, if there is something contingent, there must exist a cause or causes on which the contingent thing depends. Moreover, if there is something contingent, there must exist a cause which is an uncaused (and uncausable) cause. Similarly, to be more and less is to approximate something-not just anything at all, i.e., not just something which is a more, but a most. And so, if there are more and less, there must exist a most which the more and the less approximate. That is, there must exist an approximated 7 That is, the more and less, qua more and less, approximate. qua most, is approximated. The most, JOSEPH BOBIK which does not (and cannot) approximate. 8 A contingently existing thing cannot exist unless there exists an uncaused cause on which it depends. Similarly, it seems, what exists as approximating (i.e., the more and the less) cannot exist unless there exists an unapproximating approximated (i.e., a most) which it approximates. This, it appears, is what is required by the concept of " comparative relation," i.e., by the concept of the approximating relation, at least as Maritain seems to understand it. Moreover, Maritain's understanding of the comparative or approximating relation makes it sound very much as if the most emerges, in the first part of the Fourth Way, as an exemplary cause (vs. an agent cause). 3. There is, thirdly, the suggestion of Brady (The New Scholasticism, 1974, pp. 291-232) that t:he Fourth Way moves from the existence of the more and the less to the existence of a most precisely by appealing to causality. Not to agent causality, but to exemplary causality. Brady notes that "the purpose of the first part of the text [of the Fourth Way] is to ascend from the affirmation of the degrees of existing to the affirmation of the maximal being, the exemplary cause [my italics] of aJl graded beings" (p. 229) . Agent causality does function in the Fourth Way, but in its last part, i.e., in the part in which Aquinas argues that the most a being (maxime ens), precisely qua most a being, is the cause (agent cause) of the existence, and of the goodness, and the like, of the more and the less. Writes Brady, agreeing with L. Charlier: " ... the second part [what I have called the third, or last, part; see above p. 2] of t:he text ... [of the Fourth Way] ... deals with the procession [my italics] of creatures from God, the first efficient cause [my italics] ... " (p. 229) . In order to make Brady's suggestion clearer, let us ask the question: What exactly is it that the first part of the Fourth Way tries to explain-in tJhe sense in which t:he First Way tries to explain the fact of motion; or the Third Way tries to s That is, an unapproximating absolute. approximated; a most, a simpliciter, an AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 25 explain the fact of the existence of things for which it is possible to be and not to be? And let us ask further: How would Brady answer this question? As follows, it seems: The first part of the Fourth Way tries to explain the fact that the existing things which we experience are like one another, while being unlike one another-like one another in being good, in being true, in being noble, in being in existence, etc.; unlike one another in that some are better than others, truer than others, more noble than others, etc. And in proposing what he takes to be the Fourth Way's explanation of this fact, Brady makes it quite clear that the explanation is not in terms of the agent cause (as it is in the other four Ways), for graded beings are not being seen, in the first part of the Fourth Way, as proceeding from something, but simply as imitating something, simply as being more or less like something. And so, the explanation is in terms of the exemplary cause. What proceeds from something cannot proceed, unless that from which it proceeds exists. Similarly, things that are more or less like something cannot be more or less like something, unless that which they are more or less like exists.-Or, if there are two things, one of which is less good, the other of which is better, they are such that the less good is less like the best; and the better, more like the best. But, this cannot be, unless there exists something which is best, which the better and the less good are more and less like.-Or, the better and the less good cannot be the better and the less good, unless each, in its own way, is a copy of the best. And so, if there exist a better and a less good, there must exist a best, as that which they copy, i.e., as that which is their exemplary cause. 4. There is, fourthly, the suggestion of Sister M. Annice (The Thomist, 1956, pp. 22-58) that the first part of the Fourth Way is an implicit demonstration, moving from the observed existence of an " ascending scale of perfection " (p. 26) , i.e., from the observed existence of the more and the less, to the concluded existence of a maximum, a most, which is seen as both efficient cause and exemplary cause, but primarily and 26 JOSEPH BOBIK especially as efficient cause (p. 58) . The perfections in the things characterized as the more and the less are transcendental rather than univocal, i.e., they are features which belong to the things we experience because they exist and have an essence, rather than being the features contained within their essences (p. 27) . In this implicit demonstration, there are two steps. In the first, the mind sees the ascending scale of perfections, i.e., the more and the less, as pointing to a maximum, viewed as the ultimate measure of the more and the less. The mind sees that the more and the less, or the better and the less good, entail somehow the existence of a best, not just any sort of best, but a best such that none better is in principle possible, the Maxime Ens (p. 25; pp. 27-37; p. 57). In the second step, the mind penetrates more deeply, and sees the more and the less as limited and participating; then sees the limited and participating as necessarily dependent, not on just any sort of cause, but on an unlimited and unparticipating cause, the M axime Ens (p. 25; pp. 37-44; p. 57). Moreover, it is to be emphasized, according to Sister M. Annice, that the explicit goal of this implicit demonstration is to provide a concept, that of the M axime Ens, which is to be used in the explicit demonstration which Aquinas offers in the closing lines of the Fourth Way, i.e., when he argues that the M axime Ens, precisely because M axime Ens, is the cause of the being, the goodness, the truth, the nobility, and the like, of the more and the less. Here, too, in the explicit demonstration, as in the implicit demonstration which has preceded, the M axime Ens emerges as both efficient cause and exemplary cause, but primarily as efficient cause. Writes Sister M. Annice as she brings her study to a close: The quarta via does not seem to be strictly completed until we have shown that the transcendental perfection of being and its properties found in essentially varied degrees in creatures, are unexplainable apart from an absolute Maximum, Subsistent Perfection as their proper (per se) efficient Cause [my italics]. The consideration of the exemplary Case [my italics], while not necessary to the primary proof [my italics], is helpful in understanding better the whole theory of participated perfection (p. 58) . AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 27 5. There is, fifthly, the suggestion of Van Steenberghen (Rivista di Filosofia Neo-scolastica, 1978, pp. 99-112) that the Fourth Way is inspired, quite clearly, by the Neoplatonic metaphyics of participation, i.e., by t:he view that all things not God participate in the subsistent Being of one God (exemplary causality) , the one God who is also the Creator of them all (efficient causality), in spite of the Fourth Way's explicit reference to Aristotle alone. This is by way of contrast to the Platonic view that things participate in a number of different subsistent Exemplars, in a plurality of different subsistent Ideas, no one (or group) of which has creative power. The difficulties in interpretation to which the Fourth Way may give rise are due, according to Van Steenberghen, to the excessively concise way in which it is formulated, leaving its point to a great extent implicit and imprecise and incomplete. And this, not only with respect to its point of departure, i.e., the existence of the more and the less (magis et minus), but also with respect to both of its basic principles: I) " Magis et minus dicuntur de . diversis secundum quod appropinquant diversimode ad aliquid quod maxime est" (in which exemplary causality is at work) , and 2) "Quod dicitur maxime tale in aliquo genere est causa omnium quae sunt illius generis " (in which efficient causality is at work) . Accordingly, notes Van Steenberghen, the concise formulation of the Fourth Way ought to be provided with a background, with the details, which will help make its point more explicitly, more precisely, more completely. To this end, Van Steenberg hen undertakes a study of St. '11homas's commentaries on the Liber de Divinis Nominibus and the Liber de Causis, both of which are clearly N eoplatonic works . Though neither of these two commentaries treats the problem of the existence of God in an express way, notes Van Steenberghen, both contain details which are extremely valuable for a proper exegesis of the Fourth Way (hence the title of Van Steenberghen's article, "Prolegomenes a la' Quarta Via '.") . With respect to the point of departure of the Fourth Way, !28 JOSEPH BOBIK the Neoplatonic metaphysics of participation helps make clear, notes Van Steenberghen, what kind of perfections Aquinas has in mind in speaking of goodness, truth, nobility, and the like. These are perfections which, like the perfection of being, can be possessed in diverse degrees, so that the participants form an ascending scale or hierarchy. This excludes the so-called " univocal " perfections which are not capable of more and less; a thing cannot be more or less a man, more or less a triangle. But a thing can be more or less good, true, noble, and the like. These are transcendental perfections, perfections which belong to all things, just because they exist and have an essence, essence being the measure of their being, their goodness, their truth, their nobility, and the like. This is a point stressed by Sister M. Annice as well (see ;above p. With respect to the first basic principle, i.e., " Magis et minus dicuntur de diversis secundum quod appropinquant diversimode ad aliquid quod maxime est," the Neoplatonic metaphysics of participation helps make clear that " quod maxime est " is an absolute maximum, and not a r:elative one; that is, something so great in goodness, in truth, in nobility, in being, etc., that none greater is in principle possible. The maximum, here, is a perfection in a pure, and therefore unlimited, state; a perfection which is received by its participants, and limited in them, according to the measure of their essences. Such a maximum must be either a transcendental perfection (i.e., one found in all things, just because they exist and have an essence), e.g., goodness, truth, nobility, beauty; or a simple perfection (i.e., one not tied of itself to the finite realm or to the realm of material things, though not found in all things). e.g., wisdom, knowledge, life. With respect to the second basic principle, i.e., " Quod dicitur maxime tale in aliquo genere est causa omnium quae sunt illius generis," the N eoplatonic metaphysics of participation helps make clear that the absolute maximum is the one and total agent cause, the one creative cause, of all the things which are magis et minus, i.e., of all the participants. AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION Q9 As Van Steenberghen brings his article to a close, he notes the following: In the light of the doctrine of participation abundantly developed in the Expositio super Librum de causis, the sense of the Fourth Way cannot be in doubt. Among the perfections which we discern in the world, there are some which are possessed in diverse degrees, all limited. These degrees of limited perfections imply a reference to absolute perfections, to absolute maxima: this is the principle of participation. Moreover, the maximum (absolute) in a determined order is the cause of all the participants: this is the form of the principle of causality which we have encountered most often in the Expositio of St. Thomas as well as in the De causis itself. 9 And though Van Steenberghen writes the immediately preceding with respect to Aquinas' commentary on the Liber de Causi,s, it is quite clear that it applies to Aquinas' commentary on the Liber de Divinis N ominibus as well. Among the perfections as we discern in the world we experience, there are some which are had by things in diverse degrees, all limited. These are the transcendental and the simple perfections. This ascending scale of limited perfections implies a reference (an approximating reference, to use an expression Van Steenberghen does not use) to perfections which are absolutes, to maxima which are absolutes. That is, if there are magis et minus of the transcendental and simple sort, there must be an absolute of the same sort. This is the principle of participation, focussing on a cause in the sense of an exemplar. abondamment developpee 9 "A la lumiere de la doctrine de la participation dans l'Eropositio super Librum de causis, le sens de la quarta via ne saurait etre douteux. Parmi les perfections que nous discernons dans l'univers, il en est qui sont possedees a des degres divers, tous limites. Cet etagement de perfections limitees implique reference a des perfections absolues, a des maxima absolus: c'est le principe de participation. D'autre part, le maximum (absolu) dans un ordre determine est la cause de tousles participants: c'est la forme du prinoipe de oausalite que nous avons rencontree le plus souvent dans l'Eropositio de S. Thomas comme dans le De oausis lui-meme." (Van Steenberghen, Fernand. "Prolegomenes a la 'Quarta Via'," Rivista di Filosofia Neo-soolastica, Vol. 70 (1978), p. 112). 30 JOSEPH BOBIK Moreover, the absolute maximum in a given order is the cause of all the participants in that order. This is the principle of causality, focussing on a cause in the sense of an agent. More briefly, the more and the less require the existence of an absolute most, of one absolute most, as their exemplary cause, and this one absolute most is also their one agent cause. 6. We have five suggestions 10 with respect to clarifying what goes on in the first part of the Fourth Way, i.e., in that part which moves from the observed existence of the more and the less to the concluded existence of a most. The first, that of Harvanek, describes this movement as a movement of the mind" prior to any appeal to causality," as a kind of natural dialectic of the mind moving from the less good to the better, and then from the better to the best possible, i.e., the best beyond which there can be none better; then judging that this best must actually exist, just because the mind has understood the less good and the better in relation to the best. Though this suggestion describes the movement as prior to an appeal to causality, it seems to mean prior to an appeal to agent (efficient) causality. For the natural dialectic of the mind which this suggestion describes, along with the judgment that the best possible actually exists, seems to point (though not explicitly) to an appeal to exemplary causality, inasmuch as the best possible is called a standard or a norm in reference to which the less good and the better both are, and are understood to be, the less good and the better. The second suggestion, that of Maritain, like the first, makes it quite clear, though not explicitly, that the movement from the existence of the more and the less to the existence of a most does not appeal to agent causality. And though Maritain does 10 We could perhaps have considered suggestions other than these five, even in addition to these five. But, it is not our intention here to do a history of the commentaries on the first part of the Fourth Way. Our intention in considering these five-and they serve our purpose extraordinarily well-is simply to put ourselves into a position in which we can render the first part of the Fourth Way just a bit less troublesome, just a bit less difficult to understand. AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 31 not explicitly mention exemplary causality, his suggestion that this part of the Fourth Way is based on the self-evident principle that "Every series composed of a more and a less connotes a most," along with his explanation of the workings of this connoting, principle, seem to be saying that, in his view, this part of the Fourth Way makes an appeal to exemplary causality. For, no one of these things, notes Maritain, which are more or less good, true, etc. is unto itself the reason for its goodness, truth, etc., simply because each is more or less. Only that which is a most in such a way that there can be none better, none truer, etc. is unto itself the reason for its goodness, its truth, etc. (p. 51). Which seems to be indicating that the goodness, truth, etc. of the more and the less has its reason, in some way, in the goodness, truth, etc. of the best possible, truest possible, etc., inasmuch as it connotes that most by imitating it, by approximating it. And so, the best possible seems to be functioning as an exemplary cause. The third suggestion, that of Brady, states explicitly that the movement from the existence of the more and the less to the existence of a most appeals to exemplary causality. The "plenitude of being," i.e., the Maxime Ens of the Fourth Way, is the exemplar, Brady states; the Maxime Ens is "imitated differently by all the degrees of existing," and it completely satisfies the tendency of the intellect to affirm a most, as what is imitated, simply because being is intelligible (p. 232; p. 228) . It is the intrinsic intelligibility of being, according to Bradyi.e., the resistance of being (in any attempt to explain the grades of things ) to all contradictions, which contradictions he notes on pp. 221-222-that requires the existence of the M axime Ens as the " ultimate reason " explaining the fact that the existing things we experience are graded things. And this ultimate reason emerges not as an efficient (agent) cause, since the graded things we experience are not being viewed, in the first part of the Fourth Way, as proceeding from their cause (things proceed from an efficient cause), but rather as imitating, as being measured by, their cause (things imitate, are JOSEPH BOBlK measured by, an exemplary cause) , as being more and less in approximative reference to a most. The fourth suggestion, that of Sister M. Annice, states explicitly that the movement from the existence of the more and the less to the existence of a most appeals both to efficient (agent) causality and to exemplary causality, though primarily to efficient causality; and that the Fourth Way makes this appeal twice, first only implicitly, then explicitly-implicitly, as it argues: " ... est igitur aliquid quod est verissimum et optimum et nobilissimum ... et ... maxime ens [ quia magis et minus dicuntur de diversis secundum quod appropinquant diversimode ad aliquid quod maxime est]. . .;" explicitly, as it argues: " ... ergo est aliquid quod omnibus entibus est causa esse et bonitatis et cuiuslibet perfectionis [ quia quod dicitur maxime tale in aliquo genere est causa omnium quae sunt illius gen eris] ... ". The fifth suggestion, that of Van Steenberghen, argues that the movement from the existence of the more and the less to the existence of a most is to be understood by an appeal to certain details of the Neoplatonic metaphysics of participation which Aquinas develops in his commentary on the Liber de Divinis Nominibus and in that on the Liber de Causis.-The things that are more and less are to be understood with respect to their transcendental perfections (and their simple perfections too, if they have any; though these are not explicitly mentioned by Aquinas in his point of departure) .-The transcendental (and simple) most (or maximum) is to be understood as an absolute maximum, rather than as a relative one. An absolute maximum is one so great that none greater is in principle possible. Things that are more are closer to the absolute maximum; things that are less, further removed from it. Approximation, here, is in terms of participation; the more and less are copies of one subsistent Exemplar. The more and the less form an ascending scale in which the higher the member, the closer the approach to the maximum.-In quantitative contexts, by contrast, in which there can be no absolute maxi- AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 33 mum, e.g., in the context of numbers, things are more and less in approximative reference to a unit, which is always less than any of the more and the less; indeed, there is nothing less than this measuring unit by which the measuring unit itself is to be measured. The greater (or more) is further removed from the unit; the smaller (or less), closer to the unit. Approximation, here, is not in terms of participation; the more and the less are not copies of a measuring unit which is an exemplar; they are rather constituted out of addition of the unit to itself. The more and the less form an ascending scale in which the higher the member, the further the remove from the measuring unit. Notes Van Steenberghen: •.. the more and the less in the context of numbers, for example, are not said in relation to the greatest number, which neither is nor can be, but rather in relation to the unit; the size of a man is not measured in relation to the largest man, but in relation to the unit of largeness, which is for us the meter.11 The five suggestions just summarized confirm, and make clearer, " diligenter intuenti," what was in some way clear at the outset, namely, that both exemplary causality and agent causality find a place in the Fourth Way. And a return to the text of the Fourth Way, in the light of these five suggestions, will confirm " diligenter intuenti " that it is exemplary causality which functions (though without explicit mention) in the Fourth Way as it argues to the existence of a most, i.e., the M axime Ens; and that it is agent causality which functions (though without explicit mention) in the Fourth Way as it argues that the M axime Ens, already shown to exist, is the cause of the being, goodness, and the like, in all else, i.e., in the more and the less. 7. One thing remains to be done in this brief consideration n " ... le plus et le moins dans les nombres, par exemple, ne se disent pas par rapport au plus grand nombre, qui n'existe pas et ne peut exister, mais par rapport a l'unite; la taille d'un homme ne se mesure pas par rapport a l'homme le plus grand, mais par rapport a l'unite de grandeur, qui est our nous le metre." (Van Steenberghen, art. cit., p. 106). 34 JOSEPH BOBIK of the first part of the Fourth Way, with the hope that it will become less troublesome, less difficult to understand. It remains to make clear, at least briefly, what exemplary causality is, in order to help make clear, if possible, what it is about (what there is in the nature of) the more and the less of the Fourth Way, which reveals them to be effects requiring the existence of God, the M axime Ens, as their only possible exemplary cause. This is perhaps a good way to pursue the question put above (p. 3) : What is there about the approximating relation which enables Aquinas to draw the conclusion that what is approximated-and what is approximated is what is maxime or simpliciter-must exist, if there exist things which are more and less, and which (qua more and less) approximate it? What, then, is an exemplary cause? An exemplary cause is a pattern (a design, a blueprint, a standard). A cause, generally, is that on which something else, the effect, depends in some way or other. An exemplary cause is that on which something else, the effect, depends in a special way, i.e., in the way in which a copy or an instance depends on a pattern (design, blueprint, standard. Decio Hall, for example, is a copy or instance of the blueprint conceived by one or more architects. Without the blueprint of which Decio Hall is a copy there could not be a Decio Hall. Of course, other things are required as well, such as bricks and mortar and glass, as the materials; and such as workmen, to put the materials together (using the blueprint as a guide). An exemplary cause is one of several kinds of cause on which an effect depends. What, now, is it in the more and the less of the Fourth Way which reveals them to be effects in need of God as their only possible exemplary cause? Or, what is there in the more and the less which reveals them to be copies or instances of a standard, a standard which must be, cannot be anything but, the M axime Ens of the Fourth Way? Let us begin by considering an example. We are examining two model airplanes, and we notice that one of them is a con- AQUINAS'S FOURTH WAY & APPROXIMATING RELATION 35 siderably better model than the other. What does this imply? Quite clearly, that the model which is the better one is a more faithful copy of something which is a standard or a pattern for these things. And, of course, if the better one is a more faithful copy, the other is a less faithful copy. And so, both are copies. This is saying, quite clearly, that if there are two things, one of which is a better something (whatever) than the other, then there must be some third thing, the standard or the pattern, which is better than the first two, and of which the first two must be copies. Apply this, now, to the first part of the Fourth Way. We observe the things we experience, and we notice that men, for example, are better, truer, more noble things than trees. And so, men are more faithful copies of something which is a standard or a pattern for these things. Of course, if men are more faithful copies, then trees are less faithful copies. And so, both are copies. Thus, if men are better things than trees, there must be some third thing, the standard or the pattern, which is a better thing than men and trees, and of which both men and trees must be copies. What, now, is to be said about this third and better thing, the standard? Since it is the standard, can it also be a copy of some prior standard? But, if there are standards for standards, then, it seems, there can be no standard at all. Moreover, if there cannot be a standard for a standard, then the standard cannot be better or worse. The conclusion seems to be that if there are things which are better and worse (more and less), then there must be a best (a most) such that there can be none better. For the better and the worse (the more and the less must be copies, and copies are copies of a standard, and a standard must be the best (the most), in the sense that none better is possible. The Fourth Way is concerned with the transcendental perfections of the things we experience, i.e., with features which the things we experience have in common with all existing things, just because they exist, and as existing, have an essence. 86 JOSEPH BOBIK Though goodness (value), truth (knowability) and nobility (independence) -the perfections explicitly mentioned in the first part of the :Fourth Way-belong to all existing things, just because they exist, and as existing, have an essence; not all existing things have the same grade of goodness, truth and nobility, because not all of them have the same grade of essence. This is why men, for example, are better, truer, more noble than horses; horses than trees; and trees than stones. The gTaded diversity of their goodness and truth and nobility is rooted in the graded diversity of their essences. But, each essence determines for the thing which has that essence the same grade of goodness, truth and nobility, all three. For example, the goodness, truth and nobility, all three, of a man are of the same grade, i.e., of the human grade, because all three are rooted in the same essence, i.e., human essence. Since there are things which are more and less good, true and noble, all three; there must be something which is most good, most true, most noble, all three, such that there can be nothing better, nothing truer, nothing more noble. For the more and the less must be copies, and copies are copies of a standard. Moreover, since a standard cannot have a standard, a standard must be the most possible, cannot be anything but the most possible. The most possible is the only possible standard-with respect to transcendental (and simple) perfections. This, it appears, is the 1VJaxime Ens of the Fourth Way. This, it appears, is how the approximating relation enables Aquinas to conclude that the M axime Ens exists, as the only possible exemplary cause of the more and the less. JosEPH BoBIK University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana THE DIVINE ATTRIBUTES IN AQUINAS I N THIS PAPER I discuss principally the claim of Aquinas that the divine attribute which is the formal constituent of the divine nature is es.'!e. I also discuss the consequent attribute of simplicity, with some reflections on this relation of consequence. I conclude with some remarks on philosophical realism in general, which I take to be the necessary background to this theory or, as I argue, discovery. * * * In St. Thomas's Summa Theologiae we are confronted first, not with a study of the attributes of God, but with Five Ways of knowing that God exists. Strictly consequent upon this, there are then two basic movements of thought upon which, to mix the metaphor, the next structure after the Five Ways, that of the attributes, is laid. The first step is to find just one attribute which can be put forward as the formal constituent of the divine natura, its essentia (this will be the so-called metaphysical essence, since the real divine essence is one with the simple and hence constituentless divine nature) . This is come upon through an immanent logic arising strictly out of conclusions reached through the Five Ways, and is in fact subsisting existence, ipsum esse subsistens, often called Being, confusingly, since this translates ens as well as esse. If it were not this there would be unexplained composition in God, at least between His nature and His act of existing. The second step is then to derive whatever attributes can be strictly deduced from this conception of God as subsistent esse, while a subsidiary step is to divide these into what commentators later called entitative and operative attributes. The first step identifies the nature of God with His aot of existing, 37 38 liTEPHEN THERON actus essendi, stressing that as pure ad He is not in any genus, not to be grasped in an abstract idea, even though the theory of the attributes must go on to say He is truth, is goodness and so on. The saving grace of these attributions, however, is that they do not imply limitation, even though it is a general principle of the Thomistic interpretation of things that form is what places a limitation on being, so that in being a man I cannot be an elephant. Of course the necessary infinity of these absolutely simple perfections entails that each of them is really identical with the divine nature, itself identical with His esse, His actus essendi. There can only be one reality in God, understood as the infinite. But my intention here is not to run through all the well-known arguments yet again. Thus that God, any God, must be subsisting Existence, I take to be well established. We can't have a divine essence capable of receiving existence, and for God to be love, say, He has first to be. I can make no sense of saying that this is merely chosen as appropriate to our way of thinking. I would rather say it thinks itself, once we 'let being be' (Heidegger's inspired definition of thinking) . Of course God is not being identified with ens in commune, that almost cynical error of pantheism. God is identified with His own act of existing, proper to Him alone. Since this is, as divine, an act without limitation, we then go on to say that this cannot be an existence shared with any other existing, that God must exist in a uniquely eminent way, that that act of existing which He himself is, is transcendent. In the sense in which God exists, nothing else does, as the doctrine of analogy should bring out rather than obscure. 1 Nonetheless, we need to enquire into the significance and implications of it being just existence which is the formal attribute 1 Cf. Leo J. Elders, Die Metaphysik de Thomas von Aquin, I, Salzburg 1985, p. 133: 'Das ens commune ist das geschaffene Seiende ... Gott fallt nicht unter das ens commune: Er ist das ganz Andere, von dem wir wohl wissen konnen, daB Er ist, nicht aber, was Er ist.' THE DIVINE ATTRIBUTES IN AQUINAS 39 of the divine nature, something to which both Kant and Aristotle seemed to deny the status of a formal property. The reason, after all, that it is not a formal or delimiting property is that it comes into everything. For to classify is to exclude, as even Russell's class of all classes excludes the individuals which are members of the particular classes. But something which comes into everything is just what we would expect to be the formal characteristic of God. ' Non aliquo modo est, sed est, est '. 2 This is why God gives existence to all things, in every moment; God is that being our thought requires as doing characteristically this, in very truth. Existence is His proper effect, bringing it about that there are beings. Why does God uniquely bring things into existence, create, unless because He stands in a uniquely close relation to His own infinite existence, that of an identity? This means, though, that it is in their various acts of existence that things resemble Him, if they do at all. These acts however differ supremely from His own, though, in that they are all effects, which He, first and infinite cause, in no sense is. But it is then that actual being which is the link with or trace of God in our world. 'There can, it seems to me, be no feature of the universe which indicates it is God-made. What God accounts for is that the universe is there instead of nothing '. 3 I would merely qualify this by saying it is what God accounts for most formally or properly. The Fourth Way of Aquinas indicates, to my mind validly, how infinite Beauty must account for beauty. 4 From the first St. Thomas distinguished a thing's actus essendi from the truth of the mere statement that that thing exists, though he was of course clear that it does have to be true that a thing exists if it is to have esse in rerum natura. 5 If he had not made this distinction, he would have concluded 2 St. Augustine, Confessiones XIII, 31, 46. New Blackfriars, Oxford. I would want to see beauty as a distinguishing trait of any possible being, a lack of beauty as a lack of being. s Cf. De Ente et ]i}ssentia, V. a Herbert McCabe, O.P., 'God: I-Creation', 4 Nonetheless 40 STEPHEN THERON from his identification of God's essence with His actus essendi that it is true that God exists, substantially the move of the ontological argument he consistently rejected. To appreciate what it means for God to be that act of existence which is the cause of all other acts of existence we need to appreciate just where this rather philosophical notion, actus essendi, fits and does not fit into ordinary experience and discourse. Or, rather, in the light of what we have said, for God to be God, transcendent and immanent, the actus essendi of things will have to be their central, profoundest aspect, not some rather abstruse metaphysical property. If, for example, we were to divorce the actus essendi sense of being, to be, from more ordinary uses of that verb as it comes, at least implicitly, into every predication, we would lose that connection of the divine actuality with our commonest assertions which we have said is just the sort of general connection a fundamental divine attribute needs to have. Such a divorce, that is, would rob the theory of the corroboration we would expect to find if, on other grounds, we have found that theory to be true. It would prevent us from apprecia.ting its significance. Unfortunately, whereas St. Thomas's theory of esse, the dynamism of the universe, reaches into his account of the judgment, that distinctive activity of all our thinking, and hence into his account of the copula ' is ', modern logic, in its routinely formalistic post-Fregeau autonomy, takes a different path, one which precludes appreciation of these things. But if existence is ignored at the lowest level, it does not appear in its true light at the highest, but becomes remote. When I wrote just now that ' it has to be true that a thing exists if it is to have esse ' I implicitly put on a comparable level having esse, i.e. existing or being, and something's being true. Now of course these are the two senses of est St. Thomas distinguished, actus essendi and veritas propositionis.6 But 6 De Ente et Essentia, I: ' Ens per se dicitur dupliciter . . .' Summa Theologiae Ia, 3, 4 ad 2um. Cf. Theron, 'Esse ', The New Soholasticism, Spring 1979. 'l'HE DIVINE ATTRIBU'l'ES JN AQUINAS 41 there is no reason to think that in making a distinction one wishes to declare a term hopelessly equivocal. In that case we would be left wondering why just the verb ' to be ', esse, is used for the copula in predication generally. No weight need be given to the fact that it is omitted in certain languages, since a request for elucidation would almost certainly bring it into play. Why do we say God is love and not, unless with totally different sense, God loves love, i.e. why can't ' loves ' function as copula? Of course it is true of the copula or what Geach calls the ' there is ' sense 7 that we can use it to say there is blindness in a given eye (a given eye is blind) where no actu. Stevenson, Facts and Values, New Haven, 1963, p. 3. 11 Hare, Language of Morals, OUP, 1952, pp. 80-1, 130-1. For all three criticisms of Moore see Warnock, Contemporary Moral Philosophy, London, Macmillan, 1967, pp. 15-17. ST. THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY 55 This last feature of good was called ' supervenience ' and it is in terms of it that one can understand better the point that Moore was getting at in his argument about definitions. Good is supervenient in the way indicated because it always follows or is tied to (' supervenes ' upon) other properties, but it is nevertheless not the case that it just signifies these properties or just means these properties. A certain strawberry S is good because, say, it is red and juicy. But if 'good' just means here 'red and juicy', then this assertion would collapse to 'S is red and juicy because it is red and juicy', and that is not what was originally meant. In other words good always signifies something more than the properties because of which it is predicated; it is never reducible to these properties alone. 12 The question that, of course, then arises is how to explain the ' something more' of good. Moore's answer was rejected because, as was said, it appealed to an unexplained kind of knowing, did not account for the moving force of good, and did not explain how good could be a property necessarily tied to other properties. The solution that was adopted by emotivists and prescriptivists (the two main schools that followed Moore) was that good was not a property at all, or not an object of cognition, but served to express attitudes or volitions or prescriptions. To say something was good was not a way of asserting something about it; it was a way of expressing one's approval of it, or of commending it. Good was more properly a volitional than a cognitive term. 13 According to this theory, therefore, the naturalistic fallacy is committed when one tries to analyse value-judgments in factual or cognitive terms. The advantage of this solution was that it met at once all the objections raised against Moore. The 'something more' was now explained, not as an independent property, but as an op. cit., pp. 85-6. Stevenson's 'emotive' meaning, see Ethics and Language, Yale University Press, 1944, p. 37ff; for Hare's 'prescriptive ' or 'evaluative ' meaning, see Freedom and Reason, Oxford University Press, 1963, pp. 22ff., 198. 12 Hare, 13 For 56 PETER SIMPSON attitude to or a commendation of certain other properties; the connection with; action was immediate because good already expressed a volitional commitment; the unexplained kind of knowing was avoided because there was nothing to knowmaking predications of goodness was all a question of willing, not knowing. This solution also had the advantage of leaving intact the claim that the natural and real are the province of value-free science. 14 The facts of a thing never include goodness, because goodness is an attitude towards or a commendation of facts, not itself a fact. This then is an account of the naturalistic fallacy as it appears in the principal protagonists, and it can be seen that it breaks down into a number of separate claims: the claims about supervenience, about the value-free character of facts or the natural, about knowledge, and finally about the connection between good and action. These claims may all be summed together under the headings of the two distinctions by which the naturalistic fallacy is also and usually characterized: the fact/value distinction and the is/ought distinction. According to the first it is said that values are not facts or knowable properties of things, but something over and above them; and according to the second it is said that statements of what is the case are not injunctions about how one should behave, and hence, since value-judgments involve such injunctions, that they are not statements of what is the case. The first distinction may be taken to embrace the first three claims just listed and the second to embrace the last. Of the theories to explain these features, the prescriptivist and emotivist seem the most powerful and the most attractive, for they explain them all through one basic contention, namely that ' good ' expresses something volitional, not cognitive. This element of volition becomes the something more of supervenience, explains by its absence the value-free character of sci14 Stevenson guage, p. 2ff. was particularly keen on stressing this claim, Ethics and Lan· ST. THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY 57 ence, removes the need to appeal to some special kind of knowing, and is the connection between good and action. In these theories the fact/value and the is/ought distinctions turn out to be just different ways of expressing one and the same distinction. St. Thomas was not a prescriptivist or an emotivist. He gave a cognitive analysis of good. This means that either he has some other way of accounting for the features of the naturalistic fallacy just listed; or his theory does not stand. It also means that for him the fact/value and is/ought distinctions are not the same distinction, and that one explanation will not solve both together. For granted that his analysis of good will account for supervenience and so on, it will not yet account for how knowledge of this good will lead to action. The examination of his theory must therefore fall into at least two parts. St. Thomas on Facts and Values Perhaps the key to understanding St. Thomas on this question is what he says about knowledge. Those who say naturalism is a fallacy tend to limit knowledge to the directly observable or the scientifically verifiable. St. Thomas extends knowledge to being, the whole of being or being as such. This, he says, is the proper object of mind. What we know when we know or reflect upon some sensible object is not just the sensible or quantifiable properties, but the reality or existence of the thing and and its properties. The fact that things are, this is what impresses itself on the mind; and what the mind knows in knowing anything about a given reality is some aspect or way of its being. Even scientists in observing and knowing facts, or quantifiable data, are knowing some dimension of being-some real actuality. 15 To understand the scope of the objects of knowledge, therefore, it is necessary to consider being and its divisions. Ac15 De Veritate, q.l, a.I. 58 PETER SIMPSON cording to St. Thomas there are two basic ways of being, or ways of considering being: the way of the categories and the way of the transcendentals (St. Thomas did not use this term, but it expresses his meaning well enough) . The categories are specific ways in which things are, ways that are distinct and separate from each other, while the transcendentals are general ways in which things are, ways that, so to say, overlap and include each other. 16 Let us take tlhe categories first. There are several of these because it can be seen on reflection that a thing's being must be viewed according to several quite separate differentiations. It is clear, for instance, that a horse exists or has being first of all when viewed as a self-subsistent reality, that is, as an entity that exists in and by itself and not as the modification of another thing. Then, equally clearly, the horse exists as modified in certain ways, as being so colored or so shaped or so big or as occupying such a place. It is evident that these ways of being are different and distinct from each other. A horse does not cease to be a horse when it changes its color or its position. Nor does it change its color when it changes its place. Yet it would have to if these kinds of being were the same. Classically there are ten such categories (those listed by Aristotle) . St. Thomas accepts Aristotle's listing but it is not necessary for my purpose to go into the details. It is sufficient to recognize that there are some such categories or special ways of being, not how many or what they are. The so-called transcendentals are understood by contrast with the categories. They are not specific or distinct ways but rather general ways of being, ways of being that belong to, or are common to, all the other ways of being. They are, as is said, coterminous with the whole of being, not confined to one special sort as with the categories. For just as being is itself common to all the categories (each category is a way of being of the thing) so are these others. St. Thomas numbers six trans16 Ibid., q.l, a.I; q.21, a.I. My remarks in the following elaborations from the thought of these articles. paragraphs are ST, THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY 59 cendentals in all, starting with being as the first of them. The others are thing, one, something, true and good. Just as each category is, as such, a being, so it is, also as such, each of these others as well. It is not necessary to expound St. Thomas on each of these transcendentals. It is enough to expound what he says about good. However, to get a grip on what is meant by a transcendental, and how a term that expresses a transcendental functions, it will be preferable to begin with 'one'. ' One ' is perhaps the easiest of the transcendentals to understand, and seeing how it behaves will enable us better to see how' good 'behaves. That ' one ' is a transcendental means that it serves to express an aspect of being that is common to all being everywhere, and is not confined to some one category. For instance, whiteness expresses the being white of a thing and this being white is a special mode of being; it belongs to what is called the category of quality. But oneness is not like that. Being one is something that every being and mode of being is just as such-whether substance or quality or any of the others. So a horse is one in being a substance or self-subsistent reality, for it is one substance; its color is one in being a colour for it is one colour, its shape is one in being a shape for it is one shape. But a horse is not white in being a substance; it is white by the addition to it of the being white. The oneness of something, therefore, since it cannot be some addition to its being, must just be the very being of the thing itself. A horse is one just as and just because it is a horse, while it is white not just as and just because it is a horse but by the addition to it of the further determination or category of whiteness. It is this that explains why the particular oneness of each thing differs according to the thing in question. The oneness of a horse is not the oneness of a color, or the oneness of a thought, because the being of a horse is not the being of a color or of a thought. If all this is so then there is a crucial difference between what happens when 'one ' is predicated of a horse and when ' white' 60 PETER SIMPSON is. 'White' expresses a distinct sort of being over and above the being of the horse, and it is this additional being that is understood when ' white ' is predicated. But ' one ' expresses just the being itself of the horse; it does not express any further being whatever. This, however, cannot entail that 'one' just means what ' horse ' means. To say a horse is a horse is not to say a horse is one. ' One' evidently says something more than ' horse ' says. Since this something more cannot be some additional being (as it is in the case of white), it must just be a consideration or aspect of the very being of the horse, but a consideration or aspect that is not expressed by the term ' horse ' itself. This consideration or aspect is, according to St. Thomas, the aspect of undividedness. To say a horse is one is to advert to the fact that the horse is, in its being, undivided. The horse is this just by and in itself, but this is not expressed by the term ' horse ' on its own; it is expressed by the term 'one '. Since every being and mode of being, substance, quality, and so on, is undivided in its being in the same way,' one', when predicated of them, indicates this undividedness, which the subject terms themselves do not indicate. To put it in other words, ' one ' expresses the same being as the subject term of which it is predicated-because it takes its being from the subject term-but not the same idea-because it expresses the idea of the undividedness of this being. 17 In this sense' one' is supervenient to the subject term, because it follows its being, and yet expresses a something more, the something more, not of an additional property, but of a certain consideration or respect of that being. Thus 'one', as analysed by St. Thomas, has the features that are characteristic of supervenience. It is evident from this that as St. Thomas held good to be a transcendental he held it to be supervenient in the way discussed in the previous section. Consequently his theory of good cannot be accused of committing the naturalistic fallacy in the sense that it ignores supervenience. This is important 11 Aristotle, Metaphysica, 1003b22-5. ST. THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY {)l because St. Thomas, unlike prescriptivists and others, explained this supervenience cognitively, not volitionally. The example of ' one ' shows that this is possible, for ' one ' despite its supervenience is a cognitive term. So it is, according to St. Thomas, with good. This now needs to be investigated. St. Thomas groups good along with true because, he says, the sort of something more these terms express arises not when one considers a being with respect to itself (as in the case of undividedness), but when one considers it in connection with something else. The something else in the case of true is mind, and in the case of good it is desire. Truth expresses the being of a thing with respect to the cognizing and judging mind. What the mind judges in a judgment is not something other than the being that is judged (for that would be to fail to judge it) ; it judges just that being as such, and declares that it is as it is. Truth, says St. Thomas, expresses the being of a thing along with the idea of ' this is how being is ', that is to say along with the idea of a judgment that so it is. This consideration arises from the being of a thing itself, not from some addition of being to it, and it is a consideration that involves reference to the judging mind. Good is similar to true. It involves reference to desire. Good expresses the idea that the being of a thing, just as such, responds to or fulfills desire for that being. It expresses how that being, just as such a being, is a fulfilment and completion of whatever is directed to it as to an object of desire. Good expresses being along with the idea of end, goal or fulfilment. This is perhaps most obvious in the case of our own conscious desires. When we desire something, a strawberry say, what is it that we desire in it, or what is it that makes us call it good or desirable? Nothing other than the fact of its being a strawberry, and a strawberry of a certain sort-red, juicy, etc. The strawberry is not good by the addition of some further property to it; it is good just by being what it is, because just by being what it is it is the fulfilment of our desire of it. Thus PETER SIMPSON the goodness of a red juicy strawberry is just its being red, juicy and a strawberry, though considered along with the idea of a reference to desire, namely that just in being what it is the strawberry is such as to satisfy a desire for it as what it is. This account of good explains quite neatly the supervenience of good. According to St. Thomas's category /transcendental distinction good is a term that follows or is tied to (' supervenes' upon) the being of a thing (with its properties) and yet expresses the something more of a reference to desire. So the predication of good is not a tautology nor is it the predication of some special property of its own. It is the predication of a certain consideration of the being of the thing, not a further addition of being to it. This explanation of the supervenience of goodness is evidently a cognitive explanation. To say good is being considered along with a reference to desire is to say that good is, as such, an object of knowledge or cognition. This leaves one to ask, therefore, how this allows for the value-free character of science and what kind of knowing it requires (the other two parts of the naturalistic fallacy to consider here) . That it is possible to consider how things are without considering their goodness is an implication of the above analysis of good. If good is being taken under a certain consideration, then to set that consideration aside is to set goodness aside. According to St. Thomas this is typical of mathematics for mathematics does not consider things in their moving, that is with respect to the ends or goals towards which they are as such beings tending. 18 Modern science is heavily indebted to mathematics in its method since it aims to be quantitative. It is not surprising, therefore, if it ignores the goal-directedness of things, or the teleology of nature. Of course it may be protested that nature is not teleological. To this one may say two things in reply. First, teleology for St. Thomas does not imply consciousness, which is usually what is most objected to 18 Summa Theologiae ( S.T.), Ia, q.5, a.3, ad 4. ST. THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY t.i3 in teleology. It expresses the idea that things in a state of motion or change are things on the way to becoming something (or ceasing to be something if they are decaying) , and the something they are becoming is the goal or end of that becoming. This is not contrary to the evidence of nature, since nature is precisely an organised whole of moving or changing things. Second, if one wishes to deny teleology to nature and on this ground to accuse St. Thomas of committing the naturalistic fallacy, then the ground of one's criticism has shifted. It is no longer a criticism based on logic, but one based on physics or one's view of nature. If naturalism is a fallacy it will only be because it is first an error about the nature of nature. But whether this view of nature is an error or not is a question that belongs to another sphere that cannot be dealt with here. It is enough to state what St. Thomas's position is, for that shows how his theory relates to the problems and how they do or do not constitute problems for him. The question of knowledge is more easily dealt with. The way we know good is the way we know any other being or reality, tha.t is, by the mind. Just as we recognize that things are through reflection on the evidence of the senses, so we recognise that the being of things so recognised has the aspect of goodness when viewed as the object of appetition or as a goal. There is nothing peculiar about this sort of knowing, or if there is it is something that attaches to our knowing of being and things in general, including the knowing one finds in science. Thus difficulties on this score cannot be supposed to be exclusive to cognitive accounts of good. St. Thomas on the Is and the Ought If St. Thomas' theory of good can answer the other elements of the naturalistic fallacy, it would seem not to be able to answer the question about good and action or the Is and the Ought. This is because it is a cognitivist theory and the is/ ought distinction seems fatal to all cognitivist theories. The claim is that value-judgments are action-guiding and hence en- 64 PETER SIMPSON tail or inwlve ought-judgments or judgments that indicate what one should do. But ought-judgments are not statements of what is the case, nor can they follow from statements of what is the case. Consequently value-judgments cannot be statements of what is the case. The puzzle that is being got at here might be put, not just in terms of the relations between certain judgments, but also in terms of the relations between thinking and willing, and the question becomes how can thinking move one to desire or will something. The implication of the is/ought distinction is that this cannot happen. Thinking and willing belong to different spheres. If thinking did affect one's choices it could only be because one was already committed or engaged towards what one was thinking about. For instance if seeing that x is y makes one choose x, this could only be because one was already committed in favor of y; thinking by itself cannot create a commitment or desire de novo. The is/ought distinction thus directs one to the question of the inter-relationships between thinking and willing or desire. There are thus two angles to the Is/Ought problem: the angle of judgments and the angle of the relationship between different faculties. St. Thomas's answer embraces both. In St. Thomas' theory the key to understanding this puzzle, as to understanding the previous ones, is a correct understanding of goodness. This is the' bridging' concept between thinking and desire. For, according to St. Thomas, good is in both spheres, and not just in one as prescriptivists and emotivists assume. This is because good is the sort of cognitive concept it is. Understood cognitively good is being as object of desire, and hence this one and the same consideration of being is an object for both thought and desire at once. But if the object is the same, the approach to it is not. Thought takes good as something to consider and know, desire takes it as something to pursue and get, and the move from thought to desire turns on this fact: the object is one, but the orientations towards it are different. According to St. Thomas the mind moves desire ST. THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY 65 by presenting it with its objects, namely goods. The mind conceives some good and this conception of good then becomes a focus for desire. So just by the fact that thought and desire are what they are, and that they share a common object, the move from thinking a good to desiring it becomes readily intelligible. What the one conceives and knows, the other comes to desire. This is a natural process that arises just because thought is what it is and desire is what it is.19 One must note, however, that this move from thought to desire finds its explanation in desire, not in thought. Unless desire were as such ordered to the good no amount of thinking about good would move one to desire. To make this clearer one may consider the analogy of sight, for the visible is to sight as the good is to desire. No amount of visible things would make the eye see if the eye were not already in itself ordered towards the visible as its object. 20 In this sense one may concede a certain truth to the claim that thinking does not move desire unless one is already committed to what one is thinking about. This is because the commitment to good on the part of desire has to be presupposed to any act of desiring (as the commitment to truth on the part of the mind has to be presupposed to any act of knowing) . But this commitment is not an explicit act of desire; it is the structure of desire as such which belongs to it whether one is desiring anything or not (as it is the structure of the eye to be ordered to the visible whether an act of seeing is taking place or not). Moreover nothing about this commitment requires one to deny that good is something cognitive; it is just that this commitment is a commitment of desire. This then is the way St. Thomas explains how (theoretical) thought can move to desire. It answers the objection of Grisez and Finnis that no theoretical truth can move to desire. Theory can do this by presenting desire with its objects. But 19 Ibid., Ia Hae, q.9, a.I. 2. 20 Ibid., q.10, a.I, 66 PETER SIMPSON Grisez and Finnis, along with most non-naturalists, are right to hold that it is not theory as such that explains this fact; they are just wrong to suppose that therefore theory cannot move desire at all. This is because they forget the fact of desire and its natural orderedness to good; 21 and hence that what theory naturally grasps as a truth, desire naturally grasps as an object of pursuit. Given this account it is possible to see how the move from thought to desire begins with an Is, namely the Is of goodness. And here one can see how St. Thomas's position relates to the other angle of the Is/Ought problem, the angle of judgments. The question is how to get from an Is-judgment to an Ought-judgment. The first part of the answer has already been given, namely how one gets a desire of good from a theoretical statement that x is good. The rest of the answer lies in noting how desire, once focussed on some good presented to it by thought, turns back on thought and moves it to a different kind of thinking, namely practical thinking. Practical differs from theoretical thinking in its end, that is to say in its orientation. The end of theory is truth and of practice it is action, for in practical thinking one thinks in order to discover what to do. Action, however, proceeds not just from thought by itself but only from thought with desire (or possibly desire alone in the case of passions) , since we act because we desire to act. Hence practical thinking is thinking informed by desire, or thinking set in the service of desire. 22 It is of some importance to understand the structure of this thinking. It is thinking that takes good as its starting point, since action is for the sake of some good. But it approaches this good not from the angle of theory but from that of desire; its orientation to good is that of desire. Thus the starting point of practical thinking is not so much good as the desire of good; or in other words it begins with desire and its func21 Schultz, op. cit., pp. 13-14. 22 S.T., Ia, q.79, a.11. ST. THOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY 67 tion is to reason out how to act to satisfy desire. The first principle of practical thinking must therefore reflect this priority of desire, and according to St. Thomas it does so in the form of an ought or a gerundive. The first principle is ' Good is to be pursued or done'. This 'to be' is a sort of 'ought', so one may say that for St. Thomas practical thinking begins not with an Is but with an Ought. It does not derive this Ought from some prior theoretical Is; it does not derive it at all, but rather begins with it, for it is what first constitutes it as practical thinking. This does not mean that the Ought springs up from nowhere; rather it comes from desire, for Ought just expresses at the level of reason the orientation to good of desire. 23 This does not mean either that an ought-judgment is not a judgment of reason but something volitional. On the contrary it is a judgment of reason for it is a judgment about what to do in order to attain some good. Ought just expresses the order of action to some good, and says that the action is due in view of that good (there is no categorical Ought for St. Thomas as there is for Kant; for St. Thomas Ought is always subordinate to some good) .24 The only thing to note in the case of practical oughts is that they are made from the point of view of desire. It is this that gives to these truths about the order of action to good the element of prescription or their imperative force. 25 Practical thinking may therefore be called Ought-thinking, and the point of this thinking is to discover by reasoning what to do here and now in order to satisfy the desire which set practical thinking going in the first place. In this sense it proceeds from a first or fundamental Ought about good to particular Oughts in the here and now. Here there may indeed be a process of logical deduction but it is a deduction from Ia Hae, q.94, a.2; q.3, a.4, ad 3; q.9, a.I; q.17, a.I. q.90, a.2. 25 [bid., q.17, a.I. I think that the view I express here about Ought is not too different from that expressed by Schultz, op. cit., pp. 21-3. 23 fbid., 24 Ibid., 68 PETER SIMPSON Ought to Ought (not from Is to Ought) . There is for St. Thomas no logically valid move from Is to Ought. There is nevertheless a move from Is to Ought but it is understood not in terms of logic but in terms of theory of mind. What one has to understand is how t!he first Is-thinking about what things are good (made at the level of theory) gives rise to desire of good and how this desire of good in turn gives rise to another kind of thinking, practical or Ought-thinking. And understanding this is understanding the interrelationships between thinking and desiring, not points of logic. The gap between Is and Ought is for St. Thomas both there and not there. It is there in the sense that there is no move of logic from one to the other, and it is not there in the sense that there is a move from one to the other, but it is a move that involves a to-ing and fro-ing between the faculties of thought and desire. This is how for St. Thomas an assertion of value, as that x is good, can both be a theoretical or descriptive truth and yet be a guide to action or give rise to prescriptions about what to do. For the recognition of good moves desire and desire then moves thought to think about how to get this good. Prescriptive or practical judgments thus begin in a fundamental Ought and in an act of volition, but this Ought and volition are themselves founded on a more fundamental grasp of good by theoretical mind as an aspect of the being of things. This is how St. Thomas can be a naturalist about value, that is deny the fact/value distinction, and a sort of non-naturalist about prescription, that is maintain the Is/Ought distinction. The subtlety of this position relies on the way he relates the Ought back to the Is via an analysis of thinking and desiring. Conclusion This concludes my account of the thinking of St. Thomas as it relates to the problems of the naturalistic fallacy. It can be seen how this account copes with the puzzles while still remaining fundamentally naturalistic. Predications of value are genume predications, or are genuine descriptive judgements, ST. 'rHOMAS ON THE NATURALISTIC l<'ALLACY ()9 and yet are supervenient and allow a place for a value-free science. Also these predications, without being themselves prescriptions or imperatives, allow for prescriptions and imperatives because of the input of desire. This keeps the Is/Ought distinction while drawing its non-naturalist sting. No contemporary account keeps such a balance between the conflicting positions over the Naturalistic Fallacy. One can also see from all this how this position difiers from the Grisez/Finnis position. They lack the analysis of the relations between thought and desire and that is why they deny predications of good can be theoretical and why they assert that mind is practical or prescriptive of its own nature rather than because of the input of desire. But these claims are not necessary to make sense of good and Ought, nor do they reflect the genuine thought of St. Thomas. I hope that much is clear from what has been argued above. PETER SIMPSON 'l'he Catholic University of America Washington, DC ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME I N TWO PREVIOUS ARTICLES, I tried to demonstrate how Robert Orford drew upon the thought of Giles of Rome in order to formulate his own explanation of hylomorphism and the so-called real distinction between essence and existence. 1 Orford, it will be remembered, was one of the earliest disciples of his colleague St. Thomas Aquinas, and-more important- is the first 'llhomist we know of who turned to Giles in order to gain an understanding of these basic philosophic problems, and who wove Giles's ideas into his own elaboration of what he took to be St. Thomas's position regarding them. In view of this recognition of Giles as an appropriate guide to a Thomist grasp of these issues, it is surprising to find among Orford's works the Reprobationes dfotorUJn a fratre Egidio in primum Sententiarum. 2 The Reprobationes is a strange document. In it, as I shall show later, Orford seeks every opportunity to find fault with Giles. Indeed, his criticisms, hardly ever of any substance, are at times so "picky" they cause the reader to wonder as to his real purpose in writing them down in the first place. In this article, I shall review the historical context of the Reprobationes and try to show what it was about Giles of Rome that so irritated the Dominican Orford. The early catalogues contain no more than two entries for "The Egidean influence in Robert Orford's doctrine on 1 See F. Kelley, Form", Thomist, 47, 1, January, 1983, pp. 77-99, and "Two early English Thomists: Thomas Sutton and Robert Orford vs. Henry of Ghent", Thomist, 45, 3, July, 1981, pp. 345-387. viz. MS. Merton 276, fol. 20ra2 This work is extant in one manuscript, 50ra. It has been edited by A. Vella: Robert d'Orford Reprobationes dictorum a fratre Egidio in primum Sententiarum, Paris, 1968. 70 ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 71 Orford. 3 However, from references he made in his extant writings, viz., Sciendum, Contra dicta Henrici and Reprobationes, we know the titles at least of some of his other writings. As one might have expected, Orford wrote commentaries on the books of the Sentences. In addition to the references to these commentaries he mentions also a De unitate formae, Super 2 de sommo et vigilia, Super 6 de M etaphysica and De generatione. We know of Orford's part in certain disputed questions and of his sermon in rn93. Finally, we have offered our reasons elsewhere for attributing to him the opuscule entitled De natura materiae et dimensionibus interminatis. 4 From the mere fact that Orford saw the necessity of writing against Giles of Rome in defense of St. Thomas Aquinas, one might have thought that in Giles one had found an antagonist of the Angelic Doctor. For a long time Giles was taken to have been not an adversary but rather a stout defender of his teacher, St. Thomas. 5 The picture of Giles of Rome as the loyal Thomist, the legend as it has more recently been labelled, derived in no small measure from the erroneous ascription to him of the work which is in fact Richard Knapwell's, viz. Correctivum corruptorii 'Quare '. 6 Once this mistaken ascription had been corrected and further study was done, mainly by E. Hocedez, Giles no longer appeared as having been the staunch and loyal Thomist of the legend. On the contrary, Hocedez says of him: Gilles decidement n'est pas le thomiste, clans le sens profond du mot, qui s'est donne Thomas pour Maitre et guide de sa pensee: a For a full account of what the catalogues have under Orford's name, see A. Vella, "Robert of Orford and his place in the scholastic controversies at Oxford in the late xiiith century" (Oxford Univ. B.Litt. thesis 1946), MS. B.Litt., c. 30, vol. 1, Bodleian Library, pp. 12-27. 4 See F. Kelley," The Egidean influence", pp. 90-96. "Gilles de Rome", Histoire litteraire de la France, 30 5 See F. Lajard, ( 1888), pp. 421-566. 6 "Nous croyons que ce qui a le plus contribue a faire de Gilles le disciple 'devoue du docteur Angelique, c'est la fausse attribution qu'on lui a faite du Defensorium ", E. Hocedez, "Gilles de Rome et Saint Thomas", Melanges Mandonnet, vol. 1 (Paris, 1930), p. 402. 72 FRANCIS E. KELLEY peut-on meme lui donner le titre de disciple? II parait plutot comme un eleve jaloux de sa liberte et qui veut affirmer sa personnalite. 7 However, while loyalist is no longer the right epithet, adversary is hardly appropriate either. That is to say, an 'adversary ', in a strict sense at least, would be the fitting decription for one whose main if not sole purpose in writing a given treatise would be to discredit the ideas of another. If the term be taken in this stricter meaning, one would not be called an adversary of another on the grounds that he found occasion to disagree, even often, with another. Thus, while Robert Orford was an adversary of Giles of Rome in his Reprobationes, Giles was not in the strict sense an adversary of Aquinas in his commentary on the first book of the Sentences. The title of Giles's work was not Contra Thomam in primum Sententiarum, nor would any such equivalent have been the appropriate one. It is important for our purposes to place emphasis on this point, for when Robert Orford took up his pen against Giles of Rome, it was not the case that he was doing quite the same thing as he had done previously in his Correctorium corruptorii Sciendum 8 against William de la Mare. The latter, by anyone's measure, was indeed an adversary of Aquinas. The sole aim of William's work, as its title implied, was to set right what he took to be the serious mistakes running throughout Aquinas's chief writings. Giles of Rome on the other hand, in the work Orford attacked, was simply delivering his lectures on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, in accord with University custom. After having studied under the direction of St. Thomas during his second Paris regency in the years 1269-1272, Giles continued his studies under another master whose name we do not know. He was a bachelor in theology in 1276-1277, and it was r Ibid., p. 389. s This work was edited by Glorieux: endum' (Paris, 1956). L'3 Oorreotorium Oorruptorii ' Soi- ROBERT ORFORD's ATTACK ON GIJ,ES OF ROMI<: 7j at that time Giles produced his commentary on the first hook of Sentences. 9 When he gave these lectures, the young Giles was in the words of Hocedez, ' jaloux de sa liberte ', and felt free to disagree with anyone, including his illustrious teacher, whenever he deemed it suitable. In fact, Giles's belief in the right of freedom he enjoyed in holding and expressing philosophical and theological opinions was so strong that it caused him a temporary exile. Sometime between Stephen Tempier's condemnation of the 219 propositions and his death, which is to say between 7 March 1277 and 3 September 1279, certain of Giles's teachings were officially examined and judged to have been erroneous. Rather than repudiate these errors, as ordered to do by the Paris authorities, he sought out new arguments in their defense. The young scholar's refusal to submit to Tempier's demand resulted in his having to leave Paris. The record of all this is preserved in a letter dated 1 June 1285 from Pope Honorius IV to Randulf, Tempier's successor. As we know, although our beloved brother Giles of Rome, a member of the Order of the Hermits of St. Augustine, some time ago while he was studying at Paris, said or wrote down certain things which your predecessor the late bishop of Paris Stephen upon his own scrutiny and that carried out at his request by other masters of the theology faculty, demanded that he (Giles) recant, he (Giles) did not do so, but rather tried to defend these things with various arguments ... 10 Even after a few years had passed, Giles looked back on Tempier's repressive measures (in this case against Aquinas) as a sorry chapter in the history of the young University. . . . many may well judge that all those articles were not condemned in a proper manner. For I was at Paris myself, and I can testify without any fear of error that many of those articles re9 See Mandonnet, "La Carriere scolaire de Gilles de Rome ", RSPT, 4 (1919), pp. 480-499, and Hocede7., "La condamnation de Gilles de Rome ", RTAM, 4 (1932), pp. 43-58. 10 (]hart. Univ. Paris., i. p. 633. 74 FRANCIS E. KELLEY suited not from the advice of the masters, but from the captiousness of a few.11 It is not clear what precisely were the doctrines which caused Giles his trouble with the Paris authorities. It is possible, even inviting, to think it may have had something to do with his defense of the unity of form. 12 His treatise Contra gradus formarum, written probably just before his condemnation, could well have accounted for the move against him, especially in view of its excessive denunciation of the plurality thesis as a heresy. 13 Against this hypothesis, however, is the fact that Godfrey of Fontaines was able to say in Quodlibet III, q. 5 (IQ86) that in Paris it was safe to uphold the unity of form. But I say only this: the thesis that in man there exists only a single substantial form can be upheld as probable.14 In MS. Vat. lat. 853, which contains the Quodlibet questions of Henry of Ghent, there are notations on the bottom of certain folios which refer to points of doctrine for which Giles was reproved. The first note, on fol. 3r, in connection with Henry's position in Quodlibet 1, q. 8, that the world could not have been created ab aeterno, says: This opinion is strengthened by the judgment of the masters determining in the seventeenth and final article (secundo) against Brother E. on book one of the Sentences. Hocedez interprets the note to mean that this point, i.e., the possibility of creation ab aeterno, was the subject of two articles in the list against Giles, viz., the 17th and the final one. 15 11 Aegidius Romanus In II Librum Sententiarum (Venice, 1482), d. 32, q.2, a. 3. 12 See Mandonnet, "La Carriere scolaire '',pp. 484-491. to posit several forms appears repugnant to the Catholic Faith ... ; the thesis of a plurality of forms, as we have shown, seems to stand contrary to the Faith rather than in its favor, and this we have endeavored to show", P. 1, cap. 2 (Venice, 1502), fol. 20lv (conclusion). 14 Les quatre premiers Quodlibets de G. de Fontaines, ed. De Wulf-Pelzer (Louvain, 1904), p. 197. 15 See Hocedez, "La condamnation de Gilles de Rome", pp. 42ff. 13 "Therefore ROBERT ORFORD's A'I"l'ACK ON GILES OF ROME 75 The word secundo means this was the second of two such lists, the first having been drawn up by Tempier and the second by his successor which served as the basis for Giles's recantation. Another note on the bottom of fol. Sr says that the next to last article against Giles concerned his doctrine on the will: ... that proposition, for which brother E. was censured, viz. that there is no malice in the will unless there is error or some lack of understanding in the reason-and it is the next to last article levelled against him. These are the only clues we have thus far as to what were the complaints against Giles which led to his condemnation. There was very likely a list of articles and the doctrines contained in them related to Giles's commentary on the first Sentences. 16 Five years or so after his courageous stand of conscience, if that is what it was, Giles came to think differently about the overriding importance of freedom of thought. From the letter of Pope Honorius IV we know that Giles eventually saw that the humble thing to do, and the wise thing as well, was to tender his recantation of past obstinacies: Recently however, while in residence at the Holy See, he (Giles) humbly presented himself ready to take back, in accord with our recommendation, those things he said or wrote which should be taken back. 17 The Pope, with compassion for such a humble gesture, determined it to be only fitting that the act of repudiation be made in the same place where the errors had been advanced, viz., Paris: We however, in accepting his humble offer and moved by a spirit of sympathy for him, have thought it more fitting and useful that the aforesaid items be more appropriately recanted in the same 16' On dressa une liste, assez longue, des pretendues erreurs relevees dans l'enseignement de Gilles de Rome, particulierement dans son Commentaire sur le premier livre des Sentences", ibid., p. 57. 11 Chart. Unw. Paris., p. 633. 76 FRANCIS E. KELLEY place where they were inappropriately put forward in words and writing. 18 Honorius then ordered the Paris authorities to convene for the special purpose of accepting Giles's recantation, and urged Nicholas, the chancellor, to expedite Giles's promotion to master of theology: ... we have ordered him (Giles) sent back to you, mandating by apostolic letter your fraternity, as well as our beloved brother master Nicholas chancellor of Paris along with all the other masters of the theology faculty both regent and non-regent abiding in Paris, called together for this special purpose and moving forward with their counsel regarding the aforesaid-the brother named (Giles) revoking these things in the presence of all, and especially those things your previously mentioned predecessor commanded him to revoke-to see to his prompt achievement of the licence, by our authority, inasmuch as following divine guidance you, with the agreement of the majority of these masters, will see that this profits the catholic faith and is useful for studies at Paris. 19 Giles recommenced his lecturing a.t Paris in the autumn of 1285 shortly after having agreed to the terms laid down by the authorities regarding the abjuration of his youthful mistakes of doctrine. Two years later, in 1287, he became master. 20 The foregoing sequence of events helps us to understand Robert Orford's Reprobationes contra Eguidium. There can be no doubt that this Oxford Thomist appreciated the significance of Giles's 'process of growth ' at least as well as Mandonnet or any other later observer could do. At roughly the same time that Knapwell and the other first generation Thomists at Oxford were feeling the increased ecclesiastical repressive measures, Giles of Rome was beginning to redeem the voucher he had earned as a reward for his recantation. Failure to take this 1s Ibid. 19 Ibid. 20 Mandonnet probably echoes the thoughts of many when he says: "Je ne sais s'il faut appeler une victoire ou une defaite !'accession de Gilles de Rome a la maitrise parisienne, dans les conjonctures que nous avons signalees," op. cit., p. 493. ROBERT ORFORD's ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 77 parallel of events into account makes it much more difficult to understand why it was Orford attacked Giles's early work in the way that he did as an anti-Thomist piece. Indeed, the record shows that Giles held Aquinas in the highest regard as a profound thinker. William of Tocco relates Giles's sentiments through the testimony of his close friend, James of Viterbo: The same brother James also told the witness that brother Giles of Rome, doctor of sacred theology, of the order of Augustinians, often said to him in conversation at Paris: brother James, if the friars Preachers had wished, they could have been the wise and intelligent ones and we the idiots-(i.e.) had they not handed over to us the writings of brother Thomas. 21 Of those who made bold to criticize Aquinas's writings, Giles is reported to have said: And those who scrutinize writings, failing to grasp the meaning of what they judge, carry out their work stimulated only by envyflies, leaping at the light, while they argue about things they do not understand, they are blinded by the do not appreciate the truth unknown to them. 22 In addition to this testimony, we know that Giles was one of the first to write a treatise in defense of a thesis as typically Thomist as the unity of form. 23 If it be said that, although Giles defended the thesis, his explanation varied from what Aquinas had actually taught on the subject, one might recollect that Richard Knapwell, hardly a critic of Aquinas, thought enough of Giles's work to have drawn upon it in putting together his own defense of the unity of form. 24 Indeed, Knapwell would not go as far as Giles did in the defense of this Thomistic thesis. For whereas Giles had said in his Contra 21 Acta Sanotorum, Martii, i, p. 714 (n. 83). p. 672 ( n. 41). 23 Giles wrote the Contra gradus et pluralitates formarum in 1278; see supra, p. ( 3). He was very likely motivated to write the work by the events of 1277; see Mandonnet, "La Carriere scolaire ",pp. 488-489. 24 See Callus, "The Problem of the unity of form and Richard Knapwell, O.P.", Melanges offerts a Etienne Gilson (Toronto-Paris, 1959), p. 144. 22 Ibid., 78 FRANCIS E. KELLEY gradus formarum that the opponents 0£ the unity thesis were upholding heresy as well as philosophical error, 25 Knapwell said he himself would not go to these extremes because 0£ those great thinkers who had supported the plurality 0£ forms. 26 Mandonnet found it possible to describe Giles as a Thomist, despite the £act that he disagreed with him on many points: Giles est un disciple de Thomas d'Aquin et I'on doit, sans forcer Ia note, le ranger parmi les thomistes, non pas en ce sens qu'il faille passer par lui pour aller au fond de la pensee de Thomas d'Aquin, mais en ce sens qu'il a adopte toutes les grandes theses du docteur dominicain, et qu'il suit, meme clans des details tres precis. 21 Although Hocedez emphasizes more how Giles's thought marked a departure from that 0£ Aquinas, still he is able to say of Mandonnet's description 0£ the Augustinian that it is tres juste. 28 It would be fruitless to argue over what label Giles most suitably wears: disciple of St. Thomas, Thomist, Thomist sans forcer la note, or eclectic or independent-minded Thomist, etc. The important point for our purposes is to note that of all the labels one might have selected for Giles, adversary 0£ St. Thomas would certainly not fit him when he wrote his commentary on the first book of the Sentences. From what has been said, one can understand that Giles of Rome was a somewhat ambivalent figure in the eyes of Robert Orford. On the one hand, the Giles of the first Sentences must have seemed more a comrade in arms than one to be attacked. Though he had departed from and criticized Aquinas often in this commentary, the criticism sprang not from any premeditated and carefully worked out design to discredit his former teacher wherever possible but from that same youthful and intellectually energetic spirit which had inspired him to resist p. ( 3 ) . n.24. 21 "La Carriere scolaire ", p. 497. 2s " Gilles de Rome et Saint Thomas ", p. 385. 25 See supra, 20 See supra, ROBERT ORFORD's ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 79 the threats of the bishop of Paris. At that time, Giles like Knapwell, 29 had shown himself prepared to suffer exile and to jeopardize his academic career rather than sacrifice his independence of mind. Though the criticisms of Aquinas were there, they were overshadowed by the deeper sense in which Giles followed the thought of St. Thomas. On the other hand, there was Giles the opportunist, whose recantation in 1285 could well have encouraged John Pecham to carry through with his design against Knapwell at Oxford. 30 If Mandonnet is not right when he suggests this possibility, it can at the very least be said that Giles's action could not have helped Knapwell or anyone else at that time who might have had thoughts about resisting ecclesiastical pressure where theological and philosophical doctrines were concerned. It would have been only natural for Orford, the friend and colleague of Knapwell, to have seen in Giles the opportunist, an adversary; if not in doctrine, surely in other and perhaps more real terms. This ambivalence in Orford's attitude towards Giles has left its mairk on his Reprobationes contra Eguidium. In the work Orford is" picky." He chases down what appear to be the most trivial points in order to discredit Giles. In one case, at least, it is hard not to see some dissimulation. 31 ORFORD'S CRITIQUE Orford's very first criticism of Giles's commentary on the first book of the Sentences deals with what the theologian ought to consider as the subject, taken in its most proper and technical meaning, of the science of theology. In treating this question, Giles reveals at one and the same time his dependence on 29 For the events relating to Knapwell's exile, see my Richard Knapwell Quaestio disputata de unitate formae (Paris-New York, 1982), Introd. (passim). ao" Quand nous voyons Jean Packham, de Cantorbery, condamner, le 30 avril la theorie de l'unite des formes, on peut croire que la retraction de Gilles de Rome devant l'universite de Paris avait du l'encourager dans sa demarche ", Mandonnet, "La Carriere scolaire ", p. 493. a1 See infra, p. ( 13). 80 FRANCIS E. KELLEY St. Thomas in the way he orders his material and the freedom he deemed appropriate in going beyond his teacher. As Aquinas had done, Giles cites and rejects the views of Peter Lombard, Hugh of St. Victor, and Robert of Melun. 32 Of St. Thomas's own view, viz., that Deus est subiectum huius scientiae, he says that it is true as far as it goes but that more ought to be said. The arguments proving God to be the subject in this discipline are correct, but they do not express the whole truth. For God is the subject in this discipline, but from a special aspect. 88 If one merely said God is the subject of theology and let it go at that, Giles felt one would not have adequately distinguished theology from the natural knowledge achieved by the philosopher in metaphysics. In order to underscore this distinction, Giles says that in theology God is the subject sub aliqua tamen speciali ratione, i.e., precisely insofar as God is restaurator and glorificator. . . . it is clear why God is not, without qualification, the subject in metaphysics. He is, however, the subject in theology, but from a special aspect. This is already clear. 'The special aspect' is explained in the following way: when we call something the subject of a discipline from a ' special aspect ' what we mean is that we try to understand that subject mainly from that particular point of view. But in theology our main concern is to learn about God as our Redeemer and glorifier. Therefore, etc. 34 Orford's reaction to Giles's discussion is illuminating, for it provides a good example of the kind of opportunity he searches out in order to find fault. 35 First of all there is a difference, albeit delicate, between what Giles said and what Orford says he said. Giles claimed that St. Thomas's statement was true, but did not express the whole truth of the matter: verum 32 St. Thomas, In I Sententiarum, 7. Giles of Rome, In I Sententiarum, 33 In I Sent., fol. 3vb N. 34 Ibid. 35 .Reprobationes, pp. 31-38. Prologue, q. 1, a. 4; Summa Theol., 1, I, Prologue, q. 3 (Venice, 1521), fol. 3ra-vb. ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES 01!' ROME 81 dicunt sed totam veritatem non exprimunt. Orford has Giles saying that St. Thomas's position came closer than the other opinions to the right understanding but remained insufficient: He says that the fourth position comes closer to the correct notion of the subject (of theology); but it does not adequately describe the subject, for it fails to say (God) is the subject from a certain aspect. And this is necessary as we have pointed out. 36 To come close to being correct is not quite the same thing as being correct but incomplete. And whether one does or does not like what Giles added to St. Thomas's account, it is surely not the case that the latter needed any defense against someone whose only complaint was that he did not express the whole truth. One would have thought it quite sufficient for Orford or any other Thomist to have simply dismissed Giles's additional ratio specialis as superfluous. Aquinas had very carefully drawn the distinction between theology and metaphysics in his own comment on the Sentences when he stressed: But this discipline differs from all others in that it flows from faith. 37 Orford knew this just as well as Giles. The significant point is, however, that Giles did not take exception to anything Aquinas had said in this article. His words describing what was there were: dicendum quod verum dicunt. It was therefore little more than otiose for Orford to have repeated as he did the thought found in Aquinas concerning the subject of theology: The subject of theology, however, is a matter of belief. For the articles of faith are the starting points of this discipline, and this makes it different from all other disciplines in that it flows from faith. And this, in the more basic sense, is the subject of the entire discipline, since taken in its entirety, the discipline is contained in its starting points as in a seed; that is to say, in what is believed or the object of faith. 38 p. 33. sr In I Sent., q. 1, a. 4. as Reprobatwnes, p. 34. 86 [bid., 82 FRANCIS E. KELLEY Still in the Prologue of the Sentences, Giles asks the customary question: Utrum ista scientia si,t practica vel speculativa. His reply to the question is that, properly speaking, it should be described as affectiva rather than as either practica or speculativa. However, if pressed with the question: ' but is it practica vel speculativa ', he said it is more aptly thought of as speculative than as practical: The intellect is either speculative or practical. Theology (however), properly speaking, is neither speculative nor practical, but affective. For in the main it leads to desire. Thus it is well said that (theology) is wisdom since it leads to savoring divine things rather than because it makes us understand divine things. But if the question be raised: is it more practical than speculative, or vice versa, the answer has to be, it is more speculative than practical. For godly understanding which all our knowledge, and most especially theology aims at, has more to do with blessedness than with any of our practical deeds. 39 When St. Thomas dealt with the same question, his answer was that theology includes within itself elements justifying both descriptions, viz., speculative and practical. His final word on the matter is almost identical with what Giles had. But it is more speculative than practical, for its leading interest is with divine not human things. It concerns itself with the latter only insofar as they lead man to the perfect knowledge of God, in which eternal happiness is found. 40 Admittedly, there is some difference to be noted in the way these two theologians expressed themselves in this question, but the resemblance in the way their thought advanced appears to be more striking than the difference. The two men find that both of the conventional scholastic categories speculativa and practica are inadequate to describe that system of knowledge known as theology or sacra doctrina or sacra pagina. Giles's choice of the label affectiva was not St. Thomas's own choice, fol. Sra B. Theol., 1, 1, 4. 39 In I Sent., 40 Summa ROBERT ORFORD's A'I'TACK ON GILES OF ROME 83 true enough. 41 But one should indeed be surprised to find anyone, even the most devoted follower of Aquinas, regarding such a departure from the latter's wording to be tantamount to an impugnatio. Robert Orford does, however, find it necessary to devote no less than seven different arguments to showing the impropriety of Giles's use of the word affectiva. 42 In his reply to the question in the first distinction entitled: Utrum frui sit actus intellectus, Giles's conclusion is exactly the same as St. Thomas's. 43 Even Orford cannot find anything objectionable in Giles's response, for he says: Later he answers the qunestion, showing that fruition pertains to the will, and in this case his explanation is correct. 44 But despite his approval of the main response, Orford takes time out to correct the way Giles responded to three of the objections he had raised. In his critique of the reply to the second of these objections, Orford goes beyond what Giles wrote down. Giles'sobjeetion was: Rest, and therefore enjoyment, must pertain to the dominating faculty; but it is the reason which rules over the will; hence it would follow from this that enjoyment belongs to the reason and not to the will. Furthermore, fruition bespeaks a kind of rest. But reason rules over the will, as is clear from the Philosopher in the first book of the Politics, and from the Master (Lombard) in the Prologue (to the Sentences) when he rebukes those who do not make the will subject to reason, and we do not say that inferior agents rest, since they move only when moved by superior (agents). Therefore reason, which must rule, is said to rest and therefore to enjoy. 45 41 St. Bonaventure had said that theology was affeotiva; see his In I Librum Sententiarum, Proemium, q. 3. ( Quaracchi, 1882), p. 13. 42 Reprobationes, pp. 46-48. 43 St. Thomas's conclusion is: "And thus we say it is an act of will, in accord with the habit of charity, although other habits and powers precede it". In I Sent., d. 1, a. 1. Giles has simply: "we say only the will, strictly and properly' enjoys'", In I Sent., d. 1, q. 1, a. 1, fol. llvb 0. 44 Reprobationes, p. 49. 45 Jn I Sent., fol. llrb G. 84 F'RANCI8 E. KELLEY In answer to this argument Giles said that there exists a kind of mutual pre-eminence between the reason and will. In one sense, reason has first place, i.e., as directive; in another sense the will comes first, i.e., as imperans. But if we ask which is simply speaking (si,mpliciter) first (altior), this question does not concern us at the moment: To the second argument it must be said that if the intellect is higher because it is the guide, the will is higher because it commands. And rest has more to do with commanding than with guiding. We are not, however, concerned at present with the question: which faculty is higher, all things considered. 46 Orford's remark on the solution Giles gave amounts to chiding him for not having said more than he did. He begins by simply restating what Giles did say: What he says in reply to the second argument, viz. that the will is a higher faculty than the intellect, since the will and not the reason commands: it must be pointed out that there are two things to consider in 'command'. First, that which issues the command to carry something out, and this is the will. Second, that which determines and guides the other to carry out what has been commanded, and this is the work of reason. 47 It must be noted first that Orford's restatement of what Giles had said does not read as if it were that, viz., a restatement. The words running from' he says' (dicit) down to and excluding' it must be pointed out' (dicendum) one would normally take as referring to what Giles had said. The dicendum would normally mark the beginning of Orford's own observations. Orford should have said something like et dicit praeterea instead of dicendum. As it stands, with the wrong word dicendum, the impression is given that here Giles had said nothing more than" the will is a higher faculty than the intellect." We cannot know for sure whether or not the confusion here was deliberate, but we can say that the result tends to insert an opposition between Giles and Aquinas where it did not exist. 46 Jbid. 47 .Reproba,tiones, p. 50. ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 85 Orford then goes on to point out that Giles's response ought to have gone further by showing that the intellect is, simply speaking, superior to the will. His argument for saying the intellect is higher than the will goes as follows: But in order to answer the second (argument) one should add that the intellect, all things considered, is superior since the essence of the soul is one and the faculties several. Now as the transition from one to many is according to some sort of ordering, then there must exist an ordering among the faculties of the soul; and in any natural ordering the more perfect are prior to the less perfect, even if by the sequence of generation the ordering is reversed. Since therefore, according to the natural ordering, the intellect takes precedence over the will, it follows of necessity that the intellect is the higher faculty, all things considered. In support of this idea there are other arguments in the Response to the Corruptor. 48 The reading of this argument makes one think that perhaps Orford ought to have imitated Giles and said nothing more than' this question does not concern us at the moment'. From his concluding remark: ' In support of this idea there are other arguments in the Response to the Corruptor ', we see that Orford was thinking about other opponents of Aquinas as he attacked Giles of Rome. In the fourth distinction a question arises concerning the propriety of language when speaking about the Trinity. Is it the proper thing to say ' God generates another God ' (Deus genuit alium Deum) At the end of his response, Giles says there are some who distinguish meanings which might be assigned to the word aliurn. Some, however, distinguish the word ' other '. If it be taken substantively, then the statement is true. And the sense is: 'He generates another Who is God'. If it be taken adjectivally, then it is false, for in this case the sense is: 'He generates another God, that is, He generates a different God'. But since we ought to use words the way most people do, and as this distinction is not ens48 Ibid., p. 51. This statement is verbally identical with what we read in Soiendum, p. 149; another indication of identity of authorship. 86 FRANCIS E. KELLEY tomary, in agreement with the Master (Lombard) should be rejected. 49 (I say) both In his comment on the same question, Aquinas had virtually the identical thought: But there are others who distinguish this (proposition) : 'He generates another God', for the word 'other' can be taken substantively or adjectivally. If it be taken adjectivally then the statement will be false, because it will introduce a diversity in the term 'God'. If substantively, then the construction is one of apposition, and the sentence will be true. Here the sense is: 'He generates another (God) Who is God'. But since we do not find adjectives in the masculine gender as substantives, and especially when they have annexed substantives, thus it is that the aforementioned distinction appears not altogether valid-unless perhaps, the participle 'being' is taken as implied, so that the sense is: 'another (being) God'. But this is indeed stretching matters. Thus, in company with the Master (Lombard), it should be said that both are false. 50 Indeed we should have to say that in this question Giles of Rome was doing nothing other than repeating almost to the word what his teacher had written. If one's purpose were to discredit Giles by showing how he departed from St. Thomas, this would appear to be the last place one would have cited. One can only wonder, therefore, why it was that even here Orford finds it necessary to caution Giles's reader that the aliqui he mentioned in his commentary on this question, who had ineptly drawn the distinction between the substantive and adjectival meanings of ' other', did not include St. Thomas. Be careful to note here, when (Giles) says: 'some make a distinction', this cannot apply to brother Thomas. For in part one, q. 209, in the reply to argument four, afterwards he (Thomas) shows that the (proposition) 'He generates another God' is false when the word ' other ' is a substantive and the word ' God ' is taken in apposition with it. And he (Thomas) goes on to say: but this is an improper way of speaking and should be avoided lest there be given the occasion of error. 51 49 In I Sent., d. 4, q. 2, a. unic., fol. 32vb P. d. 4, q. 1, a. 3. 51 Reprobationes, p. 79. 50 In I Sent., ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 87 To show this he need not have directed the reader to Aquinas's Summa Theologiae; 52 his commentary on the Sentences, which we have just cited, would have sufficed. At all events, it could not be clearer that both Aquinas and Giles were referring to the same source when they used the term aliqui, and it is no less clear that Giles of Rome in agreement with St. Thomas rejected the suitability of distinguishing between the two meanings of ' other '. Either Robert Orford did not understand this, which is hard to imagine, or else he deliberately tried to interpret Giles as having insinuated something, which insinuation is not at all evident. In distinction III, part ii, q. 3, a. 9l, Giles asked the question: Utrum anima sit suae potentiae. 53 His answer to the question was that the powers of the soul cannot be thought of as identical with the soul itself: And thus it is clear that the soul is not identical with its faculties, so that the faculties are the very substance of the soul. 54 The reason for his conclusion is that only in God do perfections exist with no admixture of potentiality. In the creature, all perfections including the powers of the soul must be thought of as having some measure of potentiality. Indeed, it was by so saying that the scholastic theologian insisted on the profound distinction standing between God and His creation. It must be said that all perfections found in the creature are shared perfections. And thus they are not purely actual, but have about them a degree of incompleteness. Because of this incompleteness we can speak of their generic aspect; because of the degree of actuality (or completeness) we speak of their specific aspect. For in every case the 'species '-which adds the completing element to the 'genus '-has the aspect of actuality. Thus it is that nothing is created as 'species' without at the same time taking on an aspect of 'genus'. In the first (i.e., God) alone, where perfections exist in an infinite degree, do the ' species ' exist under the aspect 52 See Summa Theol., 1, 39, a. 4, ad lum. Sent., fol. 27vb. 54 Ibid., fol. 28ra. 53 [n I 88 FRANCIS E. KELLEY of pure actuality without having the aspect of 'genus', since they lack all incompleteness. 55 But the required imperfection in the powers of the soul has the effect of placing them in the category of accident, and excludes them from the category of substance. Therefore, Giles concluded: the powe1's of the soul are not to be identified with the substance of the soul, nor is it possible for us to predicate the soul of its powers ' except in a certain way '. Since, therefore, the faculties of the soul are a species of 'quality', for they are 'natural faculties', of necessity, they remain in their generic classification, i.e. 'quality'. But if they were identical with the soul itself, they would be 'substance', for the soul is substance, as is shown in the second book of De anima. It is not therefore possible for the soul to be predicated in every way of its faculties essentially and directly, except in a certain manner. 56 The last words of Giles here: ' except in a certain manner ', were a necessary addition for him, and for any other scholastic of that time, because of the awkward fact that St. Augustine had said something which seemed to them to warrant the contrary conclusion, viz., the powers of the soul are indeed identical with the very essence of the soul: 'the mind, knowledge, and love are in the soul substantially, or to say the same thing, essentially '. 57 Giles referred to this idea of Augustine in his first objection: And it seems they are. For Augustine (says) in his sermon De imagine: the soul is the intellect; the soul is the will; the soul is memory. But this could not be so unless it were identical with its faculties. Therefore, etc. 58 The weight of authority accruing to Augustine's words is indicated by the fact that, whereas Giles had spent a mere eighteen lines of text to reach his basic conclusion to the question, 55 Ibid. 56 Ibid. 57 IX De trinitate, c. 4 (PL 42, 963). Another formulation is found in book X of the same work: "memory, understanding, one life, one mind, one essence", c. 11 (col. 983). 58 In I Sent., fol. 27vb. of this idea and will are ROBERT ORFORD's ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 89 he needed no less than eighty-three additional lines to practice his exegesis on these words which appeared to contradict that conclusion. Thomas Aquinas had dealt with the same general question, viz.: Utrum anima sit suae potentiae, in very nearly the same way as Giles did. 59 There are some differences to be noted in their main responses, but these differences are of such minor import that even Robert Orford could find nothing worth mentioning. As he had done previously, Orford turned his attention to what Giles had in his response to the first objection in order to find fault. The objection itself, as we have just seen, was a reference to the statement of St. Augustine. In his reply to the objection, Giles simply referred back to his lengthy exposition in the main response to the question: ' ... it must observed that the soul is called these three, or these three are called the soul, in the way mentioned. 60 After having noted briefly how he had dealt with the words of St. Augustine, Giles summarized what Thomas Aquinas had said in his commentary in tJhis manner: We perhaps could say, as some do, in their explanation of predication, that in the first instance there are three distinct types of totalities, viz., universal, integral, and potential. 61 The first, i.e., the ' universal whole ', is predicated of its parts according to a full and complete sense, in the way, e.g., that 'man' is predicated of Socrates or Plato. The second type of 'whole', viz., integral, cannot be predicated of any of its parts in any way whatever. We do not, e.g., say the' paint is house', or the ' nails are house '. The third type, the ' potential whole ', is a more subtle concept which the scholastic used when thinking about entities endowed with an array of diverse operations. For example, the single entity ' dog' has multiple 'powers '; that of walking, that of eating, that of seeing, etc. Thus whilst the predication 'the dog is a seer' might be appropriate as far In I Sent., d. 3, q. 4, a. 2. ao In I Sen.t., fol. 28rb. 59 61 IbiAl. 90 FRANCIS E. KELLEY as it goes, it does not express all that a dog is, or more properly 'can do' (non secundum totam virtutem). However, such a predication, in the scholastic's view, did capture and carry the essence of dog, smuggled across as it were, by virtue of the particular 'power', in this case 'seeing'. Thus the potential whole (dog) is contained in its parts secundum essentiam sed non secundum totam virtutem. Or we might say as some do that the ' whole' is threefold: universal, integral, and potential. The universal 'whole' is present in each of its parts by its essence and power, and thus it is predicated of them in every way. But the integral 'whole' is present in its parts neither by its power nor by its essence, and thus in no way can it be predicated of them. The potential 'whole' lies between these other two, for it is present in its parts by its full essence but not by its full power. And thus we can say that the soul is predicated of its faculties in a certain manner, since it is a potential 'whole' with respect to them. 62 Aquinas chose this subtle understanding of predication in order to justify St. Augustine's statement: 'the soul is intellect, will, and memory'. When Augustine said the soul is understanding, or the soul is love, we should not interpret him to have meant that the soul is intellectus or amor by way of complete equivalence (ut totum universale de partibus suis), but rather in the sense that the soul has among its powers those of understanding and willing. Giles thought that, if one followed Aquinas's mode of exegesis here, one would have to allow for such statements as: ' the soul is corporeal seeing, or hearing, or touching', and these sorts of statements are not acceptable. Thus, concluded Giles, his own way of saving Augustine is safer (magis tuta) than the way Aquinas chose. 63 The extent of Giles's departure from Aquinas in all this is anything but substantive. He even granted that one might explain the matter as Aquinas had done (vel possumus dicere, ut 62 Ibid. In addition to the place noted in his commentary on the Sentences, St. Thomas also treated this matter in the Summa Theol., 1, 77, a. 1, ad lum. ea In I Sent. fol. 28rb. ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 91 quaedam distinguunt, ... ) , but he feels his own path is magistuta. To charge Giles with having refuted Aquinas here (illud improbatQ, as Orfol'd did, 64 is to have used the word 'refute' in an unusually broad meaning. The slightest expression of hesitancy regarding the formulation adopted by St. Thomas, even though this hesitancy be couched in terms suggesting that, although the formulation is not preferred it nonetheless retained its acceptability, is taken by Orford to be tantamount to a refutation. The improbatio, Orford says, is easily resolved. For, whereas Giles had said non conceditur to making statements like ' the soul is corporeal vision ' or ' the soul is hearing', Orford counters with a flat concedo, insisting that such statements are in good order. But this is easily answered. For I grant that the visual and hearing faculties are identical with the soul. Indeed, all the faculties, both sensitive and intellective, are one with the soul, as in their cause and essence--for all of them flow from one and the same root. 65 Once having assured his reader that Giles had no reason to hesitate over our making such statements, Orford continues, explaining why it is that these statements are, in fact, minus propria: Memory, understanding, and will exist in the soul as in a subject, and not merely as in a root or cause-however, this is not true of the sense faculties, (for the latter exist as in a subject) in the toto coniuncto (i.e., in the substance composed of body and soul). And thus it is that when the soul is separated from the body in death, (the sense faculties) continue to exist (in the soul) only virtually, not actually. Hence, to say: 'the soul is vision, hearing, and touch' is less fitting than to say: 'the soul is memory, understanding, and will '. 66 64" But he refutes (him) claiming that in this way it would be proper to say things like: the soul is vision, hearing, and touch, since with respect to all of these (the soul) is also a potential whole. But we cannot allow for this", Reprobationes, p. 75. 65 Ibid. 60 Ibid. 92 FRANCIS E. KELLEY Orford's quibble here amounts to this: Giles had said that such statements are improper; they are not improper, they are merely minus propria. This sort of discussion, one feels, could hardly qualify as a high water mark in scholastic theology. There is one instance wherein Robert Orford uses William de la Mare in order to correct Giles. In article III, of his Correctivum fratris Thomae, William objected to what St. Thomas had said in his commentary on Ium Sententiarum, d. VIII, q. 3, a. 1. The text of Aquinas in question is: The claim that whatever is moveable by another calls for something moveable by itself is true when we are speaking of a chain (of moveables) found in one and the same class. For according to the Philosopher: all mobile things are traced back to a first, which he describes as moved in and of itself, for it is made up of two parts-one moving and the other moved. But this series (comprising the moveables and such a ' first ') requires in addition an original source which is utterly immobile. As Knapwell and Orford pointed out in their correctoria, 67 St. Thomas did, in fact, later deny that heavenly bodies have souls. But in the place just quoted from St. Thomas's commentary on the Sentences, William de la Mare's reading appears to be a justifiable one. In that place, William charged, Aquinas had fallen into the error of so many of the philosophers by saying that the heavenly bodies have souls. For one thing, William observed, the idea of animated heavenly bodies is contrary to the teaching of St. John Damascene and Dionysius. For another, were we to accept such an idea, we should have to confess that the souls of these bodies ranked higher in God's scheme of things than the souls of men. But Holy Writ teaches us that the opposite is true. 68 Therefore, St. Thomas, along with all those philosophers who proposed the doctrine of animated heavenly bodies, was saying something contrary to Christian belief. In his defense of Aquinas against this criticism by William s1 See Le Oorreotorium Oorruptorii 'Quare ', ed. Glorieux (Kain, 1927), p. 371, and Sciendum, pp. 312-313. ss See William de Ia Mare, Oorrectorium fratris Thomae (published in Quare, p. 370). ROBERT ORFORD'S ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 93 de la Mare, Orford points out that the Angelic Doctor, in the place referred to in the first Sentences, was not presenting his own view; on the contrary, he was merely reporting what Aristotle had said: . . . in saying this he is merely recording an opinion. Thus, in presenting this matter, he does not say the first in the chain of moveables is made up of moving and moved parts, as if he were giving us his own view. Rather, his words are: according to the Philosopher, all mobile things are traced back to a first, which he describes as moved in and of itself, for it is made up of two partsone moving and the other moved. 69 Giles of Rome, in the course of his comment on the same distinction in the Sentences, also advanced the notion of animated heavenly bodies: The primary heavenly bodies have life as a result of their inherent moving principles, which are called their souls-for though they do not derive their very existence (from these souls), they are, however, moved by them. 70 In his critique of Giles, Orford shows none of the benignity of interpretation evidenced earlier in his Sciendum when he explained how St. Thomas ought to be understood when he spoke of animated heavenly bodies. And it must be said in all fairness to Giles, that the occasion for interpreting him kindly was there, for he had taken the trouble to point out that, although the heavenly body did, in fact, draw its motus from the motor, it did not take its esse from the same motor. Therefore, if the term anima be used of this motor with respect to the heavenly body, it would have to be an extended meaning of the term. For in the mind of every scholastic of this time, the anima was considered to be an intrinsic and substantial principle which conferred esse on the entity of which it was said to be the anima. Consequently, at the very least, it might have been said of Giles's statement: 'the heavenly bodies are animated ', that the animation was quite different from any other kind of animation. 69 8ciendum, p. 338. I Bent., fol. 48vb. 10 In 94 FRANCIS E. KELLEY Orford, of course, was not looking for ways to excuse Giles. On the contrary, just as William de la Mare had done to Aquinas, Orford looked for things to say against the idea expressed by Giles. And it is interesting to note that in order to discredit him Orford could do no better than bring forward the very arguments used by William against Aquinas . Thus, when the corruptor fashioned these arguments against St. Thomas, Orford's reply had been: the arguments miss the mark, for he did not mean what some may have thought him to have meant, and this of course is clear to anyone reading his words closely (patet igitur intuenti verba sua) .71 The corruptor's arguments must have made a deep impression on Orford, however, for he paraded them later almost to the word when Giles of Rome dallied with the idea of corpora caelestia animata. 72 Finally, it is significant to note that, whatever else might have been said about Giles here, he wa;S surely not attacking St. Thomas, and therefore we can say that Robert Orford had more in mind when he wrote the Reprobationes than merely to defend his model, St. Thomas. Robert might have been the first but he was certainly not the last man who tried to indicate where and how Giles of Rome differed in his doctrine from Aquinas. 73 As recently as 1950, P. W. Nash has given us his thoughts on the subject. 74 While Nash's study does not bear the title Egidius Romanus, ubi impugnat St. Thomam, it could easily have done so. It is interesting to compare Nash's attempt with Orford's. Whereas Orford went through Giles's work page by page in search of trouble spots, Nash works out from a single leading concept which he thinks he has found at the ' heart of Giles' metaphysics ', i.e., 71 Sciendum, p. 338. 72 See Reprobationes, p. 91. says that Orford's Reprobationes was the "erste Schrift gegen das erste Buch des Aegidius von Rom", "Thomistische Streitschriften gegen Aegidius Romanus ", p. 166. 74 See "Giles of Rome, Auditor and Critic of St. Thomas", Modern Schoolman, 28 ( 1950-1), pp. 1-20, and "Giles of Rome on Boethius' 'Diversum est esse et id quod est"', Medieval Studies, 12 (1950), pp. 57-91. 73 Pelster ROBERT ORFORD's ATTACK ON GILES OF ROME 95 'his doctrine of esse in the constitution of the individual '. 75 To the degree that Nash's critique of Giles has merit, to that same degree does it suggest a failure on Orford's part to have grasped the deeper sense in which Giles disagreed with St. Thomas. Nash's very first choice of Egidian texts to support his thesis is in the commentary on the !um Sententiarum, d. VIII, q. 1, a. 2. 76 Here the question under discussion is: Utrum in Deo sit compositio esse et essentiae, and, as he points out, Giles here cited Aquinas at some length from De potentia, q. VII, a. 2, and took him to task for his manner of argument and for the way he had wrongly ' rested his case on the Liber de causi.'J'. Nash finds much significance in Giles's criticism of St. Thomas in this place, using Giles's text as an important building block in order to discover ' the heart of Giles's metaphysics,' which marked the deepest level of Giles's opposition to Aquinas. An evaluation of Nash's thesis would carry us away from our present purpose, but we can say that Giles did, in fact, make a far more serious challenge to Aquinas here than in any of the places noted so far where Orford had seen fit to take up and refute Giles's attack on Aquinas. As it happens, Orford also made note of Giles's remarks on St. Thomas's doctrine in the question entitled Utrum in Deo sit compositio esse et essentiae.11 But he did nothing more than merely note it. After having quoted Giles's critique of St. Thomas at some length, Orford had only this to say: We should note here that the position he refutes is brother Thomas's in the Quaestio De potentia, chapter 7, 2.78 Orford's failure to say anything here by way of objection to Giles's understanding of esse is not surprising, for as I have shown elsewhere Robert had found merit in Giles's doctrine. 79 of Rome, .Auditor", p. 3. "Giles of Rome on Boethius ", pp. 63-91. Virtually the whole of Nash's study is an extended analysis of the implications of Giles on d. 8. See also, "Giles of Rome, .Auditor", for a short summary of the same, pp. 3-9. 11 Reprobationes, pp. 96-97. 78 Ibid., p. 97. 19 See my "Two early English Thomists ", pp. 355-360. 75 "Giles 76 See 96 FRANCIS E. KELLEY It is surprising, however, to find Orford quoting Giles at such length in Reprobationes without any word of comment. One might have expected him, in the light of his approval of Giles on the matter, to have simply ignored the discussion, especially in a work designed to impugn the Augustinian. CONCLUSION From what we have seen of the Reprobationes, we can say that Robert Orford showed himself to have been most loyal to the cause of Thomism. There appears to be little evidence, however, of his having worked his way into the center of any substantive questions with personal and independent analysis. This appraisal of Orford's work against Giles is not unlike what Vella says in the concluding remarks of his study: The doctrinal teaching ... reveals Robert as a keen controversialist and a loyal follower of Aquinas. Orford did not aim at originality. His own intention in criticizing the opponents of St. Thomas was to restore the genuine thought of his Dominican Master distorted by critics, who were urged, in Robert's opinion, more by jealousy than by love of truth. 80 But Vella's review of Orford's criticisms is kind to the point that he fails to take note of how " picky " they often were. There were differences, to be sure, between the thought of Giles of Rome and Aquinas which Orford identified, and Vella explains some of these quite well. But there was more behind Orford's criticism of Giles than these differences. In any case, the Reprobationes was not an important piece of scholastic theology. More striking to the reader than the quality of theological and philosophical argument in the work is the author's understandable ill feeling toward's Giles of Rome, and his zeal in the cause of Thomism. FRANCIS E. KELLEY Franciscan Institute St. Bonaventure University St. Bonaventure, New Yo1·k so Vella," Robert Orford and his Place", p. 194. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN THE THEOLOGY OF EDWARD SCHILLEBEECKX A GNIFICANT UNDERLYING issue in recent .discussions of the writings of Edward Schillebeeckx, whether in academy or church, is the fundamental question of theological method. In his contemporary work, Schillebeeckx has shifted clearly from dogma to human experience a:s the starting point for theological investigation, a move in which he is certainly not unique. The growing " consensus in theology " 1 which views the theological task as a critical correlation between the Christian tradition and contemporary experience takes a unique shape, however, in each theologian's work. How is Schillebeeckx's developing theological method to be characterized and evaluated? Is his new approach to theology hermeneutical or political or both? 2 Has Schillebeeckx abandoned the earlier metaphysical and phenomenological foundations of his thought or is Thomas Aquinas still the secret mentor of his contemporary writings? 3 Does Schillebeeckx ed. Leonard Swidler (Philadelphia: West1 See Consensus im Theology?, minster, 1980). 2 David Tracy's distinction of hermeneutical from political theologies is inadequate in describing Schillebeeckx's " hermeneutics of history " since Schillebeeckx's designation of the theological task a.s hermeneutical includes an explicit political-critical dimension. See Schillebeeckx, The Understanding of Faith (New York: Seabury, 1974), esp. ch. 6-7. See also "Theologisch Geloofsverstaan Anno 1983 " ( Baa.rn: H. N el is sen, 1983). For Tracy's distinction see The Analogical Imagination (New York: Crossroad, 1981), pp. 74-75. Ghrist, Leo O'Donovan observed that a In his review of Schillebeeckx's " Schillebeeckx's real master here is still probably Thomas Aquinas, whose theological realism he is transposing into a critical and practical historical language." (" Salvation as the Center of Theology," Interpretation 36 ( 1982), p. 196). The transportation from metaphysical to historical categories does involve, however, a major philosophical shift as Schillebeeckx notes in Jesus: 97 98 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. implement the narrative-practical theology he applauds or does he remain a theoretician? 4 How does dogma fit into his present theological method, if at all? That last question has been of particular interest to Schillebeeckx's critics. More than one author has contrasted his contemporary writings with his earlier dogmatic works. Jean Galot, an outspoken critic of Schillebeeckx's recent theological writings, acclaimed Christ the Sacrament of the Encounter with God as an outstanding work of sacramental theology in accord with the traditional doctrine of the church. 5 Similarly, Leo Scheffczyck praised a "pre-critical phase of Schillebeeckx's theology " prior to his hermeneutical writings while describing the latter as " critically turned against the dogma of the church." 6 An Experiment in Christology, trans. Hubert Hoskins (New York: Seabury, 1979), p. 619. The question remains whether a theological realism grounded in creation faith and eschatological hope does not ultimately require some sort of philosophical explanation of "the idea of anticipation of a total meaning amid a history still in the making" (Jesus, pp. 618-619). William L. Portier suggests that even in order to negotiate his theological appropriation of ideology critique successfully, Schillebeeckx must retain at least a minimal, fundamentally negative, realist metaphysics from his Thomist past. ("Edward Schillebeeckx as Critical Theorist: The Impact of Neo-Marxist Social Thought on his Recent Theology," The Thomist 48 (July 1984), pp. 361-63). 4 The critique of Johann Baptist Metz, Faith in History and Society (New York: Seabury, 1980), p. 79, n.5: "None of the important modern Christologies take this practical structure of Christology as their point of departure. In this sense, they are all idealistic and characterized by a non-dialectical relationship between theory and praxis." Metz includes Rahner, Kiing, and Schillebeeckx specifically in his charge. 5 Jean Galot, "Schillebeeckx: What's He Really Saying About Jesus' Ministry?" The Catholic Register, October 1983, p. 1. in the Context of Experience: On the Inter6 Leo Scheffczyk, "Christology pretation of Christ by E. Schillebeeckx," The Thomist 48 (July, 1984), p. 389. See also The Schillebeeckm Case, ed. Ted Schoof (New York: Paulist, 1984). While the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith drew no definitive conclusions regarding Schillebeeckx's theological method in their investigation of his Jesus book and granted that his Christology could be interpreted as compatible with the doctrine of Nicea and Chalcedon, Schillebeeckx was admonished nonetheless to " make your own once again the Christology which the Church teaches its faithful" (Schillebeeckm Case, p. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 99 There is no doubt that a crucial shift took place in Schillebeeckx's theological methodology in the mid-1960s; Schillebeeckx himself was the first to identify the move in a 1967 essay. 7 To understand the hermeneutical and critical shifts in his theology as turns against the traditional doctrine/dogma of the Church and as moves which are inconsistent with his earlieT writings, however, is to misunderstand both Schillebeeckx's earlier understanding of revelation and dogma and his more recent theological method. The purpose of this essay is to trace the development in Schillebeeckx's theological method. The thesis set forth here is that the shift in theological method is undergirded by a more fundamental continuity in Schillebeeckx's understanding of revelation as the encounter between God and humanity which occurs in human history. In the context of historical consciousness, the shift from a dogmatic to a hermeneutical and critical perspective is a methodological corollary of the conviction that revelation occurs in history. The final section of the essay will address limitations and unfinished dimensions in Schillebeeckx's contemporary theological method. I. A Dogmatic Method Prior to the mid-1960s the starting point for Schillebeeckx's theological reflection was the dogma of the Church. In his book The Eucharist, for example, Schillebeeckx criticized what he perceived as a basic methodological fault in many modern Catholic approaches to the Eucharist which began from a modern phenomenological standpoint without making clear what the dogma of the Church " demands of one as a believing Catholic." In contrast to those positions Schillebeeckx as28). Schoof's analysis of the proceedings shows that the methodological differences between Schillebeeckx and the CDF are central to the dispute. Cf. T. J. van Bavel, "Hermeneutische Knelpunten in een theologisch dispunt," Tijdschrift voor Theologie 20 ( 1980), pp. 340-359. "The New Image of God, Secularization and Man's Future 1 Schillebeeckx, on Earth," God the Fut1rre o.f Mnn (New York: Sheed and Ward, Hl68), pp. 169-171. 100 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. serted, "But this seems to me to be the first question that should be asked: ' What does God's word of revelation in the Church's authoritative interpretation, tell me about the Eucharistic event? ". 8 Even in this dogmatic phase of his writings, however, Schillebeeckx never identified revelation with dogma. Dogma necessarily remained "relativized" in relation to " revelation-inreality "-no conceptual expression could ever exhaust the mystery of God's self-communicating love. Further, Schillebeeckx's fundamental hermeneutical concern for the adequate communication of the Christian mystery in every age and culture emerged already in this phase of his writings in discussions of revelation, the development of dogma, and the task of the dogmatic theologian. A. Revelation-in-Reality and Revelation-in-Word Schillebeeckx probed the meaning of revelation and theology and the relationship between the two extensively in a number of essays written in the 1950s and 1960s which were later collected as the first two volumes of the series Theological Soundings under the title Revelation and Theology. The Thomistic grounding of Schillebeeckx's approach to revelation and the theological task is clear in those essays. Like Aquinas, Schillebeeckx throughout the various phases of his writings insists that God's revelation grounds the human response of faith. 9 s Schillebeeckx, 1'he Eucharist, trans. N. D. Smith (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1968), p. 19. q At this stage in Schillebeeckx's writings, clear metaphysical and epistemological positions undergirded that theological stance. Adopting the com· bination of Thomism and phenomenology proposed by his Louvain mentor, Dominic de Petter, Schillebeeckx argued that it was possible for the human mind to know truth (reach reality) precisely because being gives itself to the human mind through an objective but non-conceptual intellectual dy· namism. See Schillebeeckx, "The Concept of Truth," Revela,tion and The· nlogy, Vol. II (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1968), pp. 5-29. Cf. "The Non· Conceptual Intellectual Dimension in Our Knowledge of God According to Aquinas," Revelation and 'l.'heolo,qy II, pp. 157-206. See also William Joseph Hill, ,Knowing tlie U11knnw11 (Jod (New York: Philosophical Library, 1971), pp. 88-97. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 101 For Aquinas, revelation necessarily included both an objective dimension (the action of God in creation and history as recorded and handed on in " the articles of faith ") and subjective dimension (the inner illumination of the mind [lumen fidei] by which the Holy Spirit enabled the believer to assent to what the intellect could never grasp fully as intelligible) . While the assent to the articles of faith provided a necessary mediation of faith, Aquinas clearly taught that the ultimate term of faith was a spiritual union between the believer and God: "The mind of the believer terminates not in a proposition, but in a reality." 10 Transposing Aquinas's understanding of revelation and faith into the phenomenological key of encounter between God and humanity, Schillebeeckx emphasized the dialogic character of the revelatory process. 11 The divine initiative and human response constitute two sides of a relationship of mutual self-disclosure and response (revelation-in-reality) . Precisely because the human partner in this dialogue is body-spirit who comes to self-awareness through the concrete mediation of the material world and the "other," the offer of encounter with God (pure Spirit) must necessarily be mediated by concrete, visible human history if human beings are to be able to hear and respond to that offer. While all of creation and human history are revelatory of God's love for humanity, that history reaches its clearest expression in the Jewish-Christian history of salvation culminating in God's very self-expression in Jesus Christ. The whole of history, and even salvation history, remain, however, fundamentaUy a.n ambiguous offer of relationship with God unless revelation is named explicitly in the words of the prophets, Jesus Christ, and the church. For human beings, words and concepts are necessary to mediate a true personal Summa Theologiae, 11-11, q. 4, a.I, reply. "Revelation-in-Reality and Revelation-in-Word," Revelation and Theology, Vol. I (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1967), pp. 36-62. cf. Schillebeeckx, "Faith Functioning in Human Self-Understanding," in The Word in Hi.story, ed. T. Patrick Burke (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1966), pp. 41-59. 10 11 Schillebeeckx, 102 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. encounter. While the body and actions reveal a great deal about the inner person, only the free choice to unveil one's deepest self through words (which clarify one's intentions and disclose the true meaning behind external manifestations) really " reveals " the person and allows true communication between dialogue partners as " centers of freedom." Thus Schillebeeckx concluded that relevation-in-reality and revelation-inword are inseparable aspects of the one offer of encounter with. God. Revelation-in-reality (the mystery of encounter with God) is necessarily mediated through revelation-in-word; yet revelation-in-word never captures or exhausts the fullness of the experience of revelation-in-reality. B. The Closing of Revelation: Scripture, Tradition, and the Development of Dogma While maintaining that revelation as encounter between God and humanity is offered in some way to all, Schillebeeckx in his early writings granted the Roman Catholic doctrinal claim that revelation closed with the end of the apostolic church. 12 The " constitutive " phase of revelation was complete with the Christ-event. In Jesus, God's self-revelation was final and definitive. Again, however, revelation-in-reality needed to be interpreted by revelation-in-word. Since the apostles were at the same time those who were immediate witnesses to the risen Christ and those who knew the earthly Jesus, their testimony established the continuity in the Christian confession that Jesus of Nazareth is the Risen Lord. The constitutive phase of revelation (as distinguished from the later interpretative or explicative phase) included the preparation for Christ recorded in the Old Testament, the saving mysteries of Christ's life, death, and resurrection, and the definitive statement of the mystery of redemption as found in the New Testament. 12 In 1952 Schillebeeckx wrote that, while not solemnly defined as dogma, the doctrine was universally accepted by the normal teaching authority of the church. ("The Development of the Apostolic Faith into the Dogma of the Church," Revelation and Theology I, pp. 63-64.) HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 103 Although the post-apostolic church continues to live in the power of the spirit of the risen Christ, there is a unique and non-recurrent character to the personal experience and testimony of the apostles. Hence later claims to an experience of the Spirit must be measured by their fidelity to the original apostolic experience. The living tradition of the church finds its norma non normanda of authenticity in the apostolic church and its written tradition, the scriptures. As revelation-in-word, the scriptures function as a necessary, but incomplete, mediation of the faith consciousness of the apostolic church. As Schillebeeckx explained: The living reality is always richer than the written expression of this reality, at least as far as its literal and explicit meaning is concerned. But this written expression in itself contains a dynamism which embraces an inner reference to the fullness of saving truth. 18 The fullness of the apostolic tradition can never be recorded adequately in the written word. Tradition is not some second oral source of revelation-in-word, but rather the process by which the church hands on the mystery of Christ (revelationin-reality). Because the church passes on this deeper consciousness of faith, later generations are able to perceive the fuller meaning (sensus plenior) in the scriptures. They can find the " word of God " in the human words of scriptures; i.e., they dis: cover revelation-in-reality through the mediation of the necessary, though inadequate, revelation-in-word. The objective dynamism inherent in the mystery of revelation-in-reality which always surpasses its expression in word was also the grounds for Schillebeeckx' s discussion of the development of dogma. The doctrine of revelation as closed in the period of the apostolic church would seem to preclude the possibility of later church statements introducing new formulations of the faith of the church as authentic, and even norma13 Schillebeeckx, "Revelation, Scripture, ity," Revelation and Theology I, p. 15. Tradition, and Teaching Author- 104 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. tive, expressions of revelation (especially formulations which find little explicit grounds in the church's scriptures, e.g., the Marian doctrines). Yet dogma is precisely that: a new official formulation of the living faith of the church which arises in a new historical-cultural situation in response to new questions or challenges to the faith tradition. 14 Hence the dilemma: How can the development of dogma (what Schillebeeckx calls "the graduail maturing of tradition") be reconciled with the church's doctrine of the closed nature of revelation and the unchangeable character of dogma? Again Schillebeeckx distinguished revelation-in-word from revelation-in-reality. It is the "the one dogma of salvation", the unchanging mystery of God's love for humanity, which must be handed on faithfully in changing expressions and forms. In the tradition of the Eucharist, for example, the church hands on the reality of the celebration of the Eucharist, not only the doctrine which attempts to express the meaning of that reality in conceptual form. No concept, no dogma, not even the church's scriptures, can capture the richness of revelation-in-reality. Still conceptual formulations of the church's faith (revelation-in-word) are necessary to mediate the deeper reality of the encounter between God and humanity-" the one dogma of salvation." C. Theological Task Even in his early dogmatic writings, Schillebeeckx emphasized that the task of the theologian is to reformulate the faith consciousness of the Christian community. In the context of his dogmatic writings this meant that the theologian was to make explicit that which was implicit in the apostolic consciousness, to draw out the sensus plenior from the Scriptures, to show the connections between the doctrines of the church and the " one dogma of salvation." The theological task was H Schillebeeckx, " The Concept of Truth," Revelation and Theology II, pp. 23-29. Cf. "Exegesis, Dogmatics and The Department of Dogma," in Dogmatic vs. Biblical Theology, ed. H. Vorgrimler (Baltimore: Helicon, 1964), pp. 115-45. HERMENEUTICS OJ<' HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 1OD not to draw theological conclusions from scripture and dogmatic statements, but to rediscover and rearticulate the "living dogma" (revelation-in-reality /the encounter between God and humanity) which was the source of the church's faith, yet which could never be fully expressed in any statement of faith. Hence the dogmatic theologian was called to become a sacred contemplative whose attention is given, so to speak, to trying to hear in a new way, with every intrinsic relationship it can possess, the self-same word of God and so to formulate it for his own times.15 The theological task arises spontaneously within the dynamics of the revelation-faith encounter. While the faith consciousness of the Christian community can never be captured in conceptual form, the dynamism of the human mind prompts the theological quest for understanding. In Thomistic terms, the mind seeks to discover the intelligibility of its assent to a mystery beyond comprehension. In his early writings, Schillebeeckx emphasized that theological reflection involves more than the hermeneutical search for meaning, more than the contemporary reinterpretation of a confessional tradition accepted in faith. Rather, the very possibility of discovering-or constructing-meaning derives from an underlying ontological basis. Reality (the inexhaustible source of meaning) gives itself to the human mind through an objective, but nonconceptual, intellectual dynamism. Human beings construct meaning only in response to the initiative of reality itself. Theology as "faith seeking understanding" seeks to move beyond the level of existential meaning to reach the underlying reality or truth (revelation-in-reality /the encounter between God and humanity). While the theologian seeks truth and not only existential meaning, and while an implicit ontological basis grounds that quest, human knowledge nevertheless remains perspectival. Human historicity means that human beings are necessarily 1fi "ExegesiR, Dogmatics, and the Development of Dogma," p. 12!!. 106 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. limited by their concrete historical and cultural circumstances in their perception/interpretation of reality. Hence the human "possession of truth" grows and evolves. The objective dynamism of being (known in faith as the Holy Spirit) provides the metaphysical foundation guaranteeing that human beings can know truth. Because of the finitude of human historicity, on the other hand, any concrete expression of this orientation toward truth provides only a perspective on the inexhaustible mystery of reality. Precisely because human language and concepts are culturally conditioned, while the mystery of the Christian faith is an offer of universal salvation meant for all times and cultures, Schillebeeckx understood the theological task, even in this dogmatic phase of his writings, as a hermeneutical task. The self-same word of God needs to be reinterpreted in every age. As he remarked later in his explicitly hermeneutical writings, Catholic discussions of the development of dogma were in reality grappling with the hermeneutical question which is grounded in the problem of human historicity. Already in 1962 Schillebeeckx argued that the awareness that God speaks to concrete human beings in diverse and cultural contexts does not reduce the word of God to something merely ' relative ', valid for one age but not for another: No matter how absolute and unchangeable is the supernatural truth, it-like every other truth-still shares, in the form it reaches in our minds, the qualities of all human things. It has the imperfection, the relativity, the possibility of development, the historical conditioning which goes with all truth as possessed by human beings. 16 The mystery at the heart of reality can and must be approached from different perspectives, none of which is exhaustive or complete. Hence mutually complementary, but correct, insights into the same truth are both possible and necessary. 1s Ibid., p. 131. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 107 II. The Shift to an Explicitly H ermeneutical Method of Doing Theology Schillebeeckx marked the year 1967 as a significant turning point in the course of his theological method. Previously he had grappled with the problem of the historical-cultural conditioning of all expressions of faith in terms of the development of dogma and the limitations of conceptual language. In the mid-1960s, however, his dialogue with United States death of God theologians and French university chaplains led Schillebeeckx to perceive a deeper theological problem: a fundamental skepticism with regard to the very possibility of revelation. No longer could the theologian presume the starting point of belief (as expressed in dogma or revelation-in-word) and merely search for new ways to express the deeper underlying reality (the "one dogma of salvation" /revelation-in-reality). Rather, Schillebeeckx concluded, the theologian must begin by listening to contemporary experience and probing the depths of contemporary culture until concrete human history itself yielded " an echo of the gospel." The revelation of God was to be found not only in the history of the Christian tradition, but also in the "foreign prophecy " coming from the experience of the contemporary world. A. Locating Revelation: Negative Dialectics Granting that the pluralism of contemporary philosophical viewpoints precluded a universal "natural theology," Schillebeeckx turned to " negative dialectics " to ground the theological task, suggesting that resistance to whatever threatens humanity presumes an implicit and initial grasp of what is truly human (tJhe humanum). While theologians and philosophers cannot agree on what constitutes the mystery of the human and thus establish a common anthropological foundation for theology, there are certain life experiences which are so profoundly inhuman that human beings instinctively real- 108 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. ize the absence of what human life is meant to be. They cry out in protest and hope: " No, it can't go on like this; we won't stand for it any longer." 17 Through the mediation of this negative dialectic, " what should be here and now " is perceived in some vague and incipient way. It is precisely the element of positive hope in the real possibility of a better future which is the source of protest and resistance on behalf of humanity. If revelation is to be found in human experience, the task of the theologian is to plumb the depths of that experience and name the ultimate source of the hope within humanity. It is at the depths or the limits of human experience that the Creator God is to be found sustaining and empowering humanity. The fundamental mystery which Schillebeeckx earlier named as can now be named more specifically as revelation-in-reality revelation-in-history or even revelation-in-human-experience. B. The Theological Task: A Hermeneutics of History If Schillebeeckx' s ea.rlier methodology ha.id been to probe the meaning of dogma in order to point towards the deeper mystery of the human encounter with God (revelation-in-reality) , now the theological task was to probe concrete human experience in order to locate that same mystery there. Theology thus becomes a form of hermeneutics. That which is to be interpreted, however, is not only a sacred text or a specific tradition of faith, but the very reality of history itself. Schillebeeckx's insistence that it is concrete human experience which must be the starting point of theology identifies his theological method as not only anthropocentric, but also political. 18 17 Schillebeeckx, "The Church as the Sacrament of Dialogue," God the Future of Man, p. 136. For Schillebeeckx's discussion of negative dialectics see The Understanding of Faith, pp. 91-101. 1s To the extent that human existence is understood in its political, social, and cultural concreteness, and not as some abstract concept of universal human experience, the anthropocentric turn in theology can be identified as a political turn. See Joseph A. Komonchak, " Clergy, Laity, and the Church's Mission in the World," in Official Ministry in a New Age, ed. James H. Provost (Washington, D.C.: Canon Law Society of America, 1981, pp. 18590, for a brief discussion of the political turn in theological method. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 109 In a key methodological essay written in 1967, Schillebeeckx explored a variety of hermeneutical theories in search of an adequate hermeneutics of history. He noted that all hermeneutical approaches to theology held a two-fold fidelity to the Christian tradition and to contemporary culture. For Schillebeeckx, however, the fundamental issue remained the involvement of theology with reality-a hermeneutical approach which remained confessional was insufficient. Distinguishing himself from both an existential hermeneutic (which deeschatologized history and dissociated nature from history) as well as from the Pannenberg circle's hermeneutic of universal history (which in Schillebeeckx's estimation failed to recognize faith as a trans-historical element in the process of history), Schillebeeckx proposed his own version of theology as a "hermeneutics of history." Here faithfulness to the biblical tradition of faith is to be found precisely in the concrete, practical actualization of faith in a new moment of the living tradition. Because it is precisely Schillebeeckx's hermeneutical method which has come under attack, and because he gradually expanded this method to include an explicitly critical dimension, it is important in order to understand Schillebeeckx's method to clarify his understanding of the hermeneutical problem and to distinguish his approach from that of existential theology and the theology of history of the Pannenberg circle. 1. Tradition and the H ermeneutical Problem The fundamental hermeneutical problem which Schillebeeckx identified earlier in his dogmatic writings is the problem of human historicity. All human experience and understanding occur within a specific historical and cultural context. The hermeneutical problem arises when one tries to understand a text or an event which arose in a different historical or cultural context. What is the meaning of the Scriptures for the life of the contemporary chmch? How can a fifth-century statement of Christological orthodoxy be normative for contemporary 110 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. faith? How can contemporary women and men experience salvation in and through Jesus of Nazareth? The Question of Identity in Reinterpretation: Dogma and Orthodoxy The hermeneutical problem is precisely that of distancethe inevitable communication gap created by two very different fields of reference. Rejecting the historicist claim that distance from the past is an obstacle to the objective interpretation of texts of history, Schillebeeckx (influenced by HansGeorg Gadamer and Paul Ricoeur) argued that there is a positive value to distanciation. The hermeneutical distance is spanned by the continuity of a living tradition which extends into the present. Historical objectivity is to be found in the truth of the past in light of the present because the past is available to us only via its "effective history." 19 Since historicity is one great evolving process (we live in the present from the past toward the future), we can understand past moments in the tradition only through what Gadamer named " a fusion of horizons." Since the past is different from the present, what emerges from such a historical frame of reference is not historical reconstruction, nor return to the original context of the " text," but rather the " application " 20 of the text in the present. The historical survival of tradition requires the new appropriation of past meaning in new historical-culture circumstances. On the other hand, the past text or tradition, in its "given-ness," limits and critiques the present understanding of the interpreter. Productive creativity and a bond with the tradition interact in forming a present understanding of a text or past event. The fundamental question which emerges in this hermeneu19 Schillebeeckx, "Towards a Catholic Use of Hermeneutics," God the Future of Man, pp. 1-49. Cf. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd ed., trans. Garrett Barden and John Cumming (New York: Crossroad, 1982), pp. 267-74. 20 See Gadamer, Truth and Method, pp. 274-278. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 111 tical approach to the understanding of a historical text or tradition is the question of identity within reinterpretation. What guarantees that the new historical appropriation of the text or tradition is indeed a faithful, as opposed to a distorted, transmission of the tradition? At this point Schillebeeckx rejected the distinction of an unchangeable " essential element " or " kernel " from its changeable " historical husk." While in his earlier writings he spoke of the " essential dogmatic affirmation " (the id quod) as distinct from its " mode of expression " t:he modus cU1n quo) ,21 Schillebeeckx now rejected that distinction precisely because it functions only retrospectively. Only after a newer interpretation of faith has been accepted by the Christian community can the historical and cultural conditioning of earlier statements be recognized. Such a distinction fails, however, precisely in the contemporary reinterpretation of authentic faith, particularly in periods of major cultural change when a real linguistic " paradigm shift " is underway. Earlier, Schillebeeckx had maintained that the identity of faith in its limited conceptual expressions was provided by a more fundamental non-conceptual dynamism, the noetic perspective of faith, which is an objective orientation toward saving reality. Now, however, he attended to the implications of his constant claim that revelation occurs in human history. A practical and concrete, rather than a purely theoretical or abstract, continuity is required by a historical tradition of faith. The promise of salvation as a universal offer in history must be made available concretely in every time and culture. As a claim about the future and the God who empowers that future, the Christian faith must be " proved true " in the course of human history. Only Christian orthopraxis (discipleship or the " doing of the truth") can provide the necessary contin( 1 21 Schillebeeckx, "Dogma," Theologisoh Woordenboek, Roermond, 1952, pt. 1, col. 1079-80, and Die euoharistisohe Gegenwart, Dusseldorf, 1967, pp. 1518. See "Towards a Catholic Use of Hermeneutics," pp. 11-13 for Schillebeeck's later rejection of this distinction. 112 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. uity in the concrete history of the Christian tradition. Schillebeeckx wrote in 1967, As It is not interpretation which has the last word, but orthopraxis, making everything new by virtue of God's promise. It is a question of being orientated towards the grace of the future, remembering God's promise and being active in faith and in so doing, making dogma true ... ultimately it is only in and through this historical realization that dogma is interpreted authentically and that the identity of faith is, thanks to God's promise, guaranteed in continuing history. 22 Further the universal offer of salvation must be expressed, both practically and linguistically, in the uniqueness of very different times and cultures precisely because it is a universal historical offer. Taking the historicity of human understanding seriously means that one can speak only in the language and interpretative framework of one's own culture and moment in history. We have no access to future ways of speaking. Neither are there universal ways of speaking. But does this relativize all expressions of faith? No more than Schillebeeckx's earlier contention that no conceptual expression of faith ever adequately names or expresses the mystery of God in history. It is precisely because Jesus is the universal Savior that christianity needs to be enculturated in every different cultural reality. The living tradition of faith needs to be reappropriated in new interpretative frameworks precisely because it is true. 23 At the same time Schillebeeckx maintained that the historically and culturally formulations of the past were the necessary mediations of the truth of the stated Christian faith at that time: Those Christians of the past could present the faith only in the way they did present it-for them the dogma stood or fell with the form in which they expressed it. 24 22 "Towards a Catholic Use of Hermeneutics," p. 38. Rahner has made the same point in a number of essays. With regard to the doctrine of Chalcedon, see, e.g., " Current Problems in Christology," Theological Investigations, Vol. I, trans. (New York: Seabury, 1961), pp. 149-200. 24 The Fluahari8t, p. 26. 23 Karl HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 11:J The universal mystery of revelation-in-reality is available and handed on only through limited historical-cultural expressions. Those expressions can be named as normative within their own context since in that particular historical period, cultural context, or polemic situation, that concrete expression may be the only way to preserve the fullness of mystery of faith. As the historical-cultural context shifts, however, so too do language and meaning shift. Expressions from another cultural context need to be reinterpreted precisely in order to communicate the same truth. 25 3. Schillebeeckx's Hermeneutical Approach to Theology Schillebeeckx's own hermeneutical approach to theology becomes more clear when contrasted with the existential approach of the " new hermeneutic " theologians 26 and the hermeneutic of universal history of Wolfhart Pannenberg. 21 Fundamentally the three differ in their theologies of revelation. For Schillebeeckx, revelation does not occur as a word event in which existential possibilities are disclosed in the encounter with the text. Rather, classic texts such as the Scriptures qr dogma preserve the expression of the living tradition of faith in one particular historical-cultural context. The biblical texts 25 Cf. Avery Dulles, "The Hermeneutics of Dogmatic Statements," in 'l'he Survival of Dogma (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday "Image Books", 1973), pp. 176-91; and Thomas B. Ommen, "The Hermeneutic of Dogma," Theolo,qical Studies 35 ( 197 4), pp. 605-631. 26 A term commonly used to refer to the post-Bultmannian efforts of Gerhard Ebeling, Enrst Fuchs, et. al., who relying heavily on the later writings of Heidegger and Gadamer's works, have developed an original theology of the proclamation of the word of God as revelatory word-event. See J. :M. Robinson, "Hermeneutic since Barth," The New Hermeneutic, ed. J. M. Robinson and J. B. Cobb, Jr. (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), pp. 1-77, cf. Robert W. Funk, Language, Hermeneutic, and the Word of God (N.Y.: Harper and Row, 1966). 21 See Wolfhart Pannenberg, "Hermeneutic and Universal History," Basic Fortress, 1970), pp. 96-136; Questions in Theology, Vol. I (Philadelphia: "On Historical and Theological Hermeneutic," Basic Questions in Theology I, pp. 137-81; and Theology and the Philosophy of Science (Philadelphia: Westminster, 1976), pp. 156-224. 114 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. are 0£ unique significance because they preserve the originating moment in the tradition. Revelation does not occur primarily in the proclamation 0£ the text nor in the event 0£ encounter with the word, but rather in the historical experience to which the text points. Grounded in a theology of creation, Schillebeeckx maintains that grace comes to expression in historical visible form. God is active in and through human history. It is this "mystery in history " (revelation-in-reality) to which the classic texts and statements of the tradition (revelation-inward) point. While claiming that revelation occurs in history, Schillebeeckx does not adopt the Pannenberg circle's approach to revelation as history. According to Pannenberg, since God is the power 0£ the future (Macht uber alles) who will be fully revealed only at the end of history, revelation can be discovered only through a hermeneutic of universal history. Schillebeeckx, on the other hand, insists that faith functions as an " almost " trans-historical element in human consciousness by which one can transcend human historicity. The promise in history is indeed an eschatological one which will be revealed fully only at the end 0£ history. That promise is made concretely available in human history, however, through "interpreting and doing in faith, in an act of surrender in which our progress through time may really become a gradual realization of the eschaton." 28 The revealing God is the Creator who is active in history precisely in and through the faith praxis of the Christian community. Theology becomes then reflection on the faith praxis of the community since it is precisely there that the revelation of God is to be found. In this second hermeneutical stage of his writings, Schillebeeckx shifted the terms of the discussions from "revelation-in-reality" to "revelation-in-history" 29 and from 28" Towards a Catholic Use of Hermeneutics," p. 42. there is continuity here, and A. R. van de Walle is correct in describing Schillebeeckx's theological project as a "theology of reality," the shift to history requires a break with classical metaphysics and even with 29 While HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 115 "revelation-in-word" to "the historically and culturally conditioned expressions of tradition." A living tradition of faith is preserved not by identifying and preserving some unchangeable essence within historically and culturally conditioned formulations, but by the practical and concrete actualization of the mystery of faith here and now. Hence the theological task shifts as well. Instead of seeking new theoretical formulations for unchanging kernels of meaning (the "essence" of the tradition) , theology becomes reflection on, and articulation of, the mystery of faith as lived and experienced within concrete human history. III. The Critical and Political Broadening of the I-Iermeneutical Task of Theology Schillebeeckx shifted from a dogmatic to a hermeneutical method of doing theology precisely in order to preserve the meaning of the living Christian tradition through the effective actualization of the past tradition in a present "new moment." Both a dogmatic and a hermeneutical approach to the transmission of tradition, however, can remain purely theoretical while failing to grasp the implications of the conflict involved in the concrete human mediation of a historical tradition. A meaning-seeking hermeneutic which does not analyze critically the process and structures of communication through which the tradition has been transmitted will overlook the distortions the phenomenological stance of de Petter, since both identified an implicit intuition of meaning-totality in every particular experience of meaning. Concrete human history remains fundamentally ambiguous: " logos and facticity stand in irresolvable tension." (Jesus, p. 619.). No universal total meaning is available before history has reached its conclusion both because of the utter non-intelligibility of evil and excessive human suffering, and because individual events and periods of history take on their full significance only in light of history's final outcome. Faith indeed wagers the eschatological hypothesis that human history will find its total meaning in Jesus Christ, but that hypothesis must be verified in the arena of concrete human history. On the other hand, Schillebeeckx continues to maintain that faith provides an "almost trans-historical element" in the historical process, and that faith is grounded in revelation. 116 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. which inevitably develop within a living tradition. Influenced by critical theorists,3° particularly Jurgen Habermas, Schillebeeckx came to realize that theology's hermeneutical retrieval of the tradition must be critical as well as creative; it must include ideology critique 31 as well as effective actualization of the past in the present towards the future. Underlying his developing understanding of theology as both hermeneutical and critical are corresponding developments in Schillebeeckx's understanding of revelation and tradition. A. Revelation In the mid-1960s Schillebeeckx realized that concrete human history must become the starting point, not just the backdrop, for locating the encounter between God and humanity. By 1977 with the publication of Christ: The Experience of Jesus as Lord, he had located the revelatory encounter more precisely in human experience, developing his earlier conviction that faith and revelation cannot be separated neatly into objective offer (in history) and subjective response (in human consciousness) . Rather, "revelation is an action of God as experienced by believers and interpreted in religious language and therefore expressed in human terms in the dimension of our utterly human history." 32 so See Understanding of Faith, pp. 102-155. See also William L. Portier, "Schillebeeckx's Dialogue with Critical Theory," The Ecumenist 21 (Jan. Feb. 1983), pp. 20-27; and "Edward Schillebeeckx as Critical Theorist,'' The Thomist 48(July1984), pp. 341-67. s1 Although Schillebeeckx grants that the term "ideology" can have the positive meaning of a symbol system which a society creates to identify and safeguard its proper identity, he uses the term primarily with its pathological derivative meaning: "a false consciousness or a speculative assertion for which no empirical or historical basis can be provided and which therefore has a broken relationship with reality" (Understanding of Faith, p. 166, n. 90.) Because the relationship of the body of ideas with reality has been distorted in the interest of privileged groups, ·wmiam Portier states that "to do ideology critique. is to ask who benefits from the truth of a given body of ideas" ("Edward Schillebeeckx as Critical Theorist,'' The Thomist 48, p. 344). a2 Schillebeeckx, Christ: The Experience of Jesus as Lord, trans. John Bowden (New York: Seabury, l!l80), p. 78. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 117 The paradox that revelation is totally free gift of the Wholly Other God which occurs nonetheless as a disclosure experience within the depths of human experience means that the authority of revelation will be manifest in a dialectical, not a direct, appeal to experience. Granting that there are some positive human experiences which ' break open ' in their very fullness disclosing the divine depths at the heart of reality, 33 Schillebeeckx remarks that in the contemporary world with its extreme and global excess of human suffering the mystery of God is revealed far more often in a dialectical way through " contrast experiences." It is precisely in those experiences in which human beings have reached their limits, in experiences of failure and finitude and even oppression, that the Creator God is revealed " on the underside of the experience " as the source of human hope, protest, and resistance. In the contrast experiences of believers, God is manifest as the power grounding and sustaining humanity in the face of all that is inhuman. The correlation between revelation and human experience is indirect. It is precisely where reality offers resistance to human expectations and categories that "something more" can be disclosed. The collapse of former patterns allows a new horizon of meaning to emerge in the struggle with the " pain of contrast." 34 The realization that revelation is experienced, interpreted, p. 34. p. 48. In the Jesus book the crucifixion of Jesus is presented as the ultimate and paradigmatic contrast experience. Precisely in the experience of abandonment and ultimate finitude, Jesus is able to "cling to God" in a radical hope which is vindicated in the resurrection. For Schillebeeckx's most extensive and clear discussion of experience and revelation and the privileged role of contrast experience see "Erfahrung und Glaube," Ohristlicher Glaube in Moderner Gesellschaft, Teilband 25, pp. 73-116. Freiburg: Herder, 1980. In God is New Each Moment Schillebeeckx is quoted as saying that "Those who suffer and are rejected are both the object of revelation and the subject of revelation ... they are the only ones who can speak with authority about revelation." God is New Each Moment; Edward Schillebeeckx in Conversation with Huub Oosterhuis and Piet Hoogeven (New York: Seabury, 1983), p. 51. 33 Ibid., 34 Ibid., 118 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. and expressed by human beings in " utterly human history " led Schillebeeckx to explore further the critical dimension of the hermeneutics of a living tradition of faith. From his earliest writings he had maintained that no concept can fully describe the reality it intends. In his shift to history and hermeneutics, he emphasized that no historical or cultural actualization of faith can fully realize the eschatological promise of the God of the Future. The insights of critical theorists were to take him further: language and structures of the living tradition are not only inadequate; they may also be repressive distortions of the true mystery. B. The Development of Tradition In his earlier writings, Schillebeeckx preferred the term " development of tradition" to "development of dogma" since what was unfolding in history was the mystery of God's encounter with humanity, not merely the implications of conceptual formulations. The " deposit of faith " entrusted to the church and handed down from apostolic times is the entire "mystery of Jesus," not only formulations about, or teachings of, Jesus. Developing the core distinction between "tradition" and "traditions" which he had inherited from Yves Congar, Schillebeeckx further emphasized that tradition is constituted by a history of vital experience: What was experience for others yesterday is tradition for us today, and what is experience for us today will in turn be tradition for others tomorrow. However, what once was experience can only be handed down in renewed experiences, at least as living tradition ... This means that Christianity is not a message which has to be believed, but an experience of faith which becomes a message, and as an explicit message seeks to offer a new possibility of life experiences to others who hear it from within their own experiences of life.s5 This understanding of a living tradition is central to Schillebeeckx's contemporary theological project. Fundamentally the 35 Schillebeeckx, Interim Report on the Books "Jesus" trans. John Bowden (New York: Crossroad, 1981), p. 50. and "Ohrist ", HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 119 living Christian tradition is constituted by the Holy Spirit (the "mystery in history") active in and through the Christian community (or as Schillebeeckx would emphasize now, Christian communities) .36 The expressions of the experience of Christian communities never fully name the deeper revelationin-reality. While that insight is not new to Schillebeeckx, two further critical perspectives extend its implications: 1) the present moment in the tradition is a source of revelation and not only an occasion for the interpretation of the earlier tradition; Distortion is possible-indeed inevitable-within a historical tradition both in its contemporary moment and in its earlier historical development. I. A New Moment in the Tradition The realization that past cultural forms of the tradition could not express adequately the living mystery of faith in new situations led Schillebeeckx, in his earlier herrneneutical writings, to seek new language to express the tradition in a new situation. In his more recent writings, however, Schillebeeckx has rejected this separation of tradition and situation as if the former were to be identified with revelation and the latter were "a mere field to be watered." 37 Taking seriously his claim that revelation occurs in human history, Schillebeeckx now views tradition (Jewish-Christian testimony to revelation and faith) and situation (the cultural, social and existential context of people to whom the gospel is announced here and now) as two poles of the one revelatory experience. In a more specific sense, Schillebeeckx uses the term situation to describe the present-day Christian situation as precisely a "new mo36 Schillebeeckx now writes of church more in terms of local ecclesial (critical) communities which in dialogue with one another form the "great church" (oikoumene) as a unity-in-diversity. See God is New Each Moment, pp. 82-83 for Schillebeeckx's discussion of the shift in his ecclesiological perspective. 37 Transcript of "The One Source of Theology." Lecture delivered at The American Academy of Religion, New York, 21 December, 1982. Cf. "Theologisch Geloofsverstaan Anno 1983." MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. ment " rn the ongomg Christian tradition or movement. states: He In the concrete praxis of the faith of the believers, their identity with or deviation from the tradition of faith can be observed ... The situation in this sense is itself already a piece of the Christian tradition in either an orthodox or a deviating sense.38 The dialectical interrelationship between present and past forms of living the gospel is really an encounter between different cultural forms of the one living gospel-the "permanent substance of faith." As both universal and historical, this " permanent substance " must be actualized and proclaimed in a unique way in every culture. No single framework of meaning can fully express the transformative and salvific power of the Christian Gospel which has its source in the unlimited critical and productive force of the Spirit of the Risen One. The conviction that that same Spirit is operative in Christian communities today undergirds Schillebeeck's claim that new experiences in the tradition carry a claim to authority since they emerge from contemporary communities' experience of what it means to follow Jesus today. Updating the Christian tradition involves more than repeating the kerygma or representing formulations of the Christian faith which were forged in different historical and cultural contexts. Rather, updating demands an interpretation which is faithful to contemporary new experiences (which may be completely foreign to the Bible) and which at the same time is faithful to the Christian tradition and in particular to "the phenomenon of Jesus." 39 The new expressions of the tradition which emerge as conas Ibid. 39 Schillebeeckx uses this expression in his Jesus book to refer to "Jesus" person, message, ministry, and death-a richly variegated extraordinary and distinctive life which taken as a whole can be interpreted historically in diverse ways." (Jesus, p. 51). Christian faith finds its source and norm in the reality of Jesus, not to be mistaken with "the historical Jesus," a historical reconstruction which though important, cannot adequately express the mystery of Jesus. (See Jesus, pp. 62-76). HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 121 temporary Christian communities "create a fifth gospel" with their lives which are either orthodox (though novel) or distorted interpretations of the tradition. It is the ta.sk of theological reflection, and ultimately of the pastoral leadership of the magisterium, 40 to distinguish between the two through a contemporary " discernment of the Spirit." 2. Ideology and the Distortion of Tradition The correlation between the tradition and present experience needs to be a mutually critical correlation not only because the " new moment " may be a distortion of the tradition, but also because the process of the transmission of a historical tradition necessarily admits the possibility that earlier moments of distortion in the tradition will have been legitimated through some form of ideology, and handed on authoritatively as "the tradition." 41 Moving beyond Gadamer's "hermeneutics of good will" and incorporating aspects of Habermas's "hermeneutic of suspicion," Schillebeeckx has forged a hermeneutical method of doing theology as a " critical and creative retrieval of the tradition." A brief review of the classic debate between Gadamer and Habermas in terms of their understand40 While emphasizing that the Word of God is entrusted to the entire church (cf. Dei Verbum #IO), Schillebeeckx continues to maintain that the official magisterium has " a distinct and irreplaceable function " in the Christian community. His recent writings, however, attend more critically to the concrete sociological process of the mediation of the Holy Spirit within the community, Hence he now emphasizes two critical dimensions: 1) the critical, prophetic role (as well as the tradition-preserving role) of the Holy Spirit, and 2) the possibility that the magisterium may operate in an ideological fashion, thus blocking the action of the Holy Spirit. See "The l\fagisterium and Ideology," Journal of Ecumenical Studies 19 (Spring 1982), pp. ii-17. Cf. Manuel Alcala, "Magisterium: An Interview with Edward Schillebeeckx," America 144 (March 28, 1981), pp. 254-58. 41 In his commentary on Dei V erbum, chapter II, Joseph Ratzinger notes that the "necessity of the criticism of tradition within the Church" was not dealt with adequately at Vatican II. See "Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation," in Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, Vol. III, ed. H. Vorgrimler (New York: Herder and Herder, 1969), pp. 184-190. MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. ing of tradition will contextualize Schillebeeckx's sublation of the two. 42 Critiquing the Enlightenment's fundamental prejudice against tradition, Gadamer argued that individuals necessarily stand within a tradition prior to any attempts to interpret or critique that tradition. He pointed to the existence of" the classical " which has survived the test of time and has been handed down through a variety of historical and cultural periods, constantly setting before us something that is true. One's horizon is formed by the influence of classic forms of tradition which have shaped a particular culture. The evolution and transmission of a tradition through a process of the reactualization of classic meaning is an ongoing process in which truth gradually unfolds itself. Gadamer did not eliminate the possibility of error within this evolutionary process; yet he argued that in the continual search for the meaning of tradition, " fresh sources of error would be excluded and unsuspected elements of meaning would emerge." 43 His concern was not the interpreter's critique of the tradition, but the real possibility of the interpreter being " pulled up short " in hearing the " claim to truth " of the tradition. Habermas challenged precisely this "false ontological selfunderstanding of hermeneutics", insisting that what appears to be truth proving itself may instead be "systematically distorted communication" which has acquired a certain permanence through force. Granting that one does stand within a " supporting consensus " prior to understanding, Habermas noted that consensus has its origins in a process of human so42 See Gadamer, Truth and Method, pp. 235-341; Jiirgen Habermas, "A Review of Gadamer's Truth and Method, in Understanding and Social Inquiry, ed. Fred R. Dallmayr and Thomas A. McCarthy (Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press, 1970), pp. 335-363. For analysis of the debate, see Paul Ricoeur, "Hermeneutics and the Critique of Ideology," in Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, ed. John B. Thompson (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 63-100; and Georges De Sscrijver, "Hermeneutics and Tradition," Journal of Ecumenical Studies 19 (Spring 1982), pp. 32-47. 43 Gadamer, Trnth and Method, pp. 265-66. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 123 cialization. A critical look at the social process of transmission of meaning reveals that institutional structures and dominant power groups in a society, in order to protect their own interests, block the free dialogue which alone can lead to true consensus. Every consensus stands under the suspicion of being "pseudo-communicatively induced " and therefore a delusion. What Gadamer calls classic truth may well be oppressive ideology. The hermeneutic presumption is that, while breakdowns in communication can and do occur when speaker and listener do not share a common pre-understanding or " world of discourse," those breakdowns can be overcome in a new actualizing interpretation of the tradition. Critical theory maintains that breakdowns in communication result from systematic distortions which cannot be repaired or transcended-resistance is the only appropriate response to the transmission of a repressive tradition or to the despotic exercise of authority. 3. Schillebeeckx's Hermeneutics: Critical and Creative Re- trieval of Tradition The insights of critical theorists enabled Schillebeeckx to grasp more concretely the problem of distortion within the transmission of the Christian tradition precisely as a historical tradition. Taking seriously the "flesh and blood affair" which constitutes human history involves the realization that history comprises a tradition of dis-grace and non-sense as well as a tradition of grace and meaning. Both his metaphysical and his hermeneutical perspectives explained concepts and concrete historical structures as necessary, but inadequate, expressions of the fullness of meaning (grace) which grounds history. Critical theory offered a further explanation of their inadequacy: repressive concepts and false structures emerge within the power struggle of human history. Un-truths or non-sense can be consciously or unconsciously legitimated by those in power in order to preserve their own interests. l'Z4 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. While incorporating the critical thesis that the human mediation of the tra.dition of faith provides the possibility of distortion (including systematic and structural distortion) , and thus that ideologica1lelements in the tradition need to be identified as such, Schillebeeckx has remained convinced that the living tradition of faith will ultimately transcend every ideological formulation and will break through all repressive processes and structures. This claim is grounded in his conviction that what is handed on in the Christian tradition is revelation-in-reality, the mystery of God active in and through human history. Hence the Holy Spirit is the ultimate subject and guarantor of the process of tradition. The critical dimension in the process of tradition emerges ultimately from the liberating and critical character of the gospel itself. The continuity in the tradition of faith is a continuity of experience, a continuity of faith-consciousness, a continuity of praxis, a continuity of discipleship. In every age and culture that experience of faith needs to be named differently (hence the need for a meaning-seeking hermeneutic); but in every age and culture that experience can also be distorted, blocked, or falsely identified (hence the need for ideology critique) . C. Theology: Faith-Praxis Seeking Historical Understanding The theological task remains, for Schillebeeckx, "faith seeking understanding." Both "faith" and "understanding", hmvever, need to be understood in terms of concrete human history. The faith which seeks understanding is the living faith of Christians and Christian communities as revealed in their praxis. Understanding (and judgment regarding the authenticity of this new moment in the tradition) are to be sought through a critical and creative retrieval of the history of" the great Christian tradition." The theologian attempts to locate the presence of the Holy Spirit living and active throughout the history of the tradition in spite of distortions and forgotten moments in its expression. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 125 1. The Starting Point: Tradition in its Contemporary Expression The starting point for Schillebeeckx's theology is no longer dogma, nor even human history or experience understood in some abstract sense. Rather, theological reflection begins with the tradition in its present moment as lived and expressed in concrete communities of faith. Particular attention is given to contrast experiences-new expressions of the tradition which conflict with earlier formulations of the faith while claiming to be faithful to the eschatological vision of the living Christian tradition in a new cultural moment. In a historical tradition oriented toward the future and grounded in the dynamism of the Holy Spirit, it is at least possible that new structures and expressions of faith are indeed creative actualizations of the tradition in a new time and culture. It is important to note here that the experience which Schillebeeckx describes as a source of revelation is ecclesial, rather than individual, experience: " The practice of the community is the sphere in which theology is born." 44 Further, "contrast experiences" which are grounded in the underlying dynamism of the Spirit are productive not only of new praxis, but also of cognitive and critical reflection. Because the ecclesial experience of critical communities is the sphere in which theology is born, the primary subject of theology is not the individual theologian, but the Christian community of faith. Schillebeeckx now identifies the " primary type of theology " as a non-academic or pastoral theology which emerges from the consensus fideHum as basic communities of believers name their experience of revelation in their concrete daily human lives. In this primary stage of theology, the role of the theologian is to help believers express their experience. 44 Schillebeeckx, 'l'he Ohurch with a Human Face, trans. (New York: Crossroad, 1985), p. 12. John Bowden 126 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. On the other hand, Schillebeeckx does not dismiss the necessary reflexive, hermeneutic, and critical dimension 0£ academic theology. Present actualizations 0£ the tradition may or may not be orthodox retrievals 0£ the " great Christian tradition." The role 0£ the theologian is to search critically £or the " logos " 0£ Christian reason behind a practice. The concrete experiences 0£ Christian communities constitute not the norm, but rather the agenda, for theological reflection. Now " contrasting " expressions 0£ the tradition remain that which is to be justified-or criticized-on the basis 0£ the larger history 0£ the Christian tradition. The spontaneity 0£ the consensus fidelium can unconsciously admit uncritical elements which distort the tradition. Intuitive certainty can be arbitrary. Hence the need for critical reflection and a disciplined theological hermeneutic. In his recent writings on ministry, £or example, Schillebeeckx begins with the already existing alternative practices 0£ critical base communities. The theological question, he suggests, is whether these alternative practices are the fruits 0£ the Spirit's productive and critical force in the face 0£ ideological distortion 0£ the church's ministerial structures or whether the alternative practices are themselves distortions 0£ the Christian tradition. 45 2. Interpreting the History of the Tradition: Retelling the Story Schillebeeckx's understanding 0£ the Christian tradition as the presence and power 0£ the Holy Spirit active in and through the Christian community (or communities) is key to understanding his critical hermeneutical method. Because faith is mediated concretely in and through history, theology (faith seeking understanding) necessarily involves critical historical investigation. On the other hand, the history 0£ the church 45 The Church with a Human Face, p. 5: "Is this a successful, a less successful, or an improper response?" HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 127 as a " flesh and blood affair " is the history of a sinful church, a pilgrim people. The theologian's historical investigation seeks to identify what can never be separated from history, and yet transcends it: " manifestations of grace," the presence of the Holy Spirit active in and through the concrete history of the church. 46 In addition to the faith perspective which he brings to his reading of history, Schillebeeckx consciously reads history from the perspective of the present and with a critical and emancipatory intent. While his work has been critiqued as biased for those very reasons, Schillebeeckx notes that historical consciousness precludes the possibility of a universal perspective. The hermeneutical structure of human consciousness is such that every interpreter, whether consciously or not, reads the past from the perspective of a contemporary pre-understanding. The more critical problem is whether one is aware of one's biases and whether one allows the text or tradition to challenge that pre-understanding; whether one not only interprets the tradition from the perspective of the present, but also allows oneself to be challenged by the tradition. A further theological reason for Schillebeeckx's interpretation of the past from the perspective of the present lies in his conviction that the Christian tradition is an eschatological tradition impelled by the power of the God of the future. Hence new moments in the tradition offer unique access to the Spirit's creative activity in history which is always new and surprising, yet remains unavailable in earlier readings of the tradition. The critical " bias " which has been so disputed in his theology emerges, Schillebeeckx claims, from the liberating and critical character of the gospel itself. The pre-understanding necessary to understand the liberating gospel of Jesus Christ is 46 Note Schillebeeckx's explanation of "theological exegesis" in Jesus, p. 39. Cf. the claim that " in and during historical investigation the theologian is ' doing theology ' " (The Church with a Human Face, p. 6) See also Bernard McGinn's analysis of the role of history in Schillebeeckx's theological method is discussed in " Critical History and Contemporary Catholic Theology: Some Reflections," Criterion 20 (Winter 1981), pp. 18-25. 128 MARY CA'fHERINE HILKERT, O.P. the practical-critical " bias " of orthopraxis, the lived experience of the gospel's call to discipleship. Christian communities and theologians must have concrete political commitments which are faithful to the gospel's liberating message if they are to understand that message. Orthopraxis forms the necessary pre-understanding of the historical, and more precisely the eschatological, " text " of the Christian tradition. Historical truth must be done-eschatological truth can be anticipated only in concrete human history. In his theological investigation of the Christian tradition, Schillebeeckx is attempting to interpret not only a text or past history, but rather what Paul Ricoeur calls "the world of the text," or "the world in front of the text "-the gospel, the reign of God in human history (revelation-in-reality) . From his earliest essays on hermeneutics Schillebeeckx has insisted that " interpretation goes beyond texts to the reality to which they bear witness." 47 Further, the basis for our contemporary appropriation of meaning from an earlier text or event is " the living relationship which we ourselves have with the same matter or reality that is discussed in the text." 48 The ultimate basis for reading the past tradition accurately is then the present experience of living in the same tradition of grace. From the perspective of the present, with the emancipatory intention of the gospel, and with a specifically theological focus, the theologian rereads the history of the Christian tradition. 'Dhrough a process of critical remembering and creative retrievals, he seeks to identify "manifestations of grace" in the history of the tradition, emphasizing forgotten or suppressed moments in that tradition and uncovering distortions which have come to be identified with the authentic tradition. A historical frame of reference allows one who stands in the same tradition to see the pa.st from the fuller perspective of its " effective history," and to trace the " counter-thread " in the 47 "Towards 4s Ibid. a Catholic Use of Hermeneutics," p. 33. HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX fabric of that tradition. 49 But what critiques the present perspective of the contemporrary theologian or theological community? How is the correlation of past tradition and present experience truly a mutually critical comelation? 3. Mutually Critical Correlation of Two Poles of the Living Tradition In a historical tradition of faith, the fundamental hermeneutical problem is that there is no unenculturated form of the universal gospel by which to measure the fidelity of other moments in the tradition. Even the original apostolic experience, the norma normans of the tradition, is available only in the historically-culturally conditioned form of the Scriptures. The scriptures (revelation-in-word) are indeed an essential mediation of the originating moment of the Christian tradition (the experience of salvation in Jesus/revelation-in-reality), yet because all language is culturally conditioned, the scriptures at the same time constitute the first of many "local theologies." 50 How then is one to distinguish authenticity from distortions in the plural historical mediations of faith-particularly in contemporary expressions of the tradition? Schillebeeckx admits the need for a " criteriology of orthodoxy " precisely so that in the process of enculturation " the identity of the liberating disclosure of meaning and truth of the Gospel does not come to any harm." 51 The most fundamental continuity of faith in a historical tradition oriented toward the future, he 49 Hence the attempt to retrieve the synoptic "memoria Jesu" as "counter-threads" in the largely Johannine fabric of the development of the church's traditional christology (see Jesus, pp. 570-71). Note this method throughout Schillebeeckx's ministry writings. See also "The Right of Every Christian to Speak in the Light of Evangelical Experience ' In the Midst of Brothers and Sisters,'" in Preaching and the Non-Ordained, ed. Nadine Foley (Collegeville: The Liturgical Press, 1983), pp. 11-39; and "Dominican Spirituality," in God Among Us, trans. John Bowden (New York: Crossroad, 1983)' pp. 232-248. 50 God is New Each Moment, p. 59. s1 Transcript, "The One Source of Theology." 130 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. suggests, is to be found in a continuity of praxis-the life of discipleship. The Christian tradition of faith must prove to be true in history. But Christian discipleship demands forms of expression in a global and nuclear age quite different from the first century following of Jesus. The problem remains: how and by whom are new forms of orthopraxis to be identified as authentically Christian discipleship? While not having worked out a detailed criteriology of orthodoxy, Schillebeeckx suggests that a contemporary "analogy of faith " or a " norm or proportionality " 52 needs to be used to demonstrate that a contemporary expression of faith is faithful to the living gospel in a new situation just as the medieval formulation of faith was faithful to the gospel in that time and the apostolic expressions of faith were faithful to the original experience of salvation in Jesus. Such a critical correlation of the fidelity of changing expressions of faith to the "substance of the Gospel" requires a critical perception of earlier expressions of faith in their original context, a critical perspective on contemporary culture, 53 and some common basis from which to identify "the substance of the gospel " in changing cultural forms. In his earlier writings Schillebeeckx located that common basis in "the objective perspective of faith"; in his contemporary writings he speaks of "the experience of grace." In either case, Schillebeeckx emphasizes that it is the Holy Spirit who initiates and sustains this "experience " of the " substance of the Gospel." Ultimately, then, the hermeneutical task of theology in52 For Schillebeeckx's use of "the analogy of faith" see "'l'heologisch Geloofsverstaan Anno 1983," pp. 14-15. For the "norm of proportionality," see The Understanding of Faith, pp. 58-63. 53 The dialogue and mutual critique of local churches in different cultural contexts also plays a significant role here. "No single community can monopolize the Spirit of God; as a result, mutual criticism on the basis of the gospel is possible within the local communities. Christian solidarity with other communities is an essential part of even the smallest grass-roots church communities." (Ministry: Leadership in the Community of Jesus Ghrist, trans .•John Bowden (New York, Crossroad, 1981) p. 73). HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 131 volves a process of " discernment of the Spirit " in which the church makes a critical judgment as to whether present experiences of faith are indeed possible faithful expressions of the " living mystery of Christ." As SchiUebeeckx describes the theologian's role in the process, by discerning the spirits, the theologian attempts to discover whether new experiences are really the present echo of the inspiration and orientation which, in the context of the recollection of the biblical mystery of Christ, present their identity anew in these experiences or prove alien to them. 54 Precisely because Christianity is a living tradition, the identity of faith is preserved by the Holy Spirit in new experiences and new expressions which are the present echo of the gospel-a living inspiration and orientation of grace. 4. The Role of Dogma in Schillebeeckx's Theology What then is the role of dogma in Schillebeeckx's contemporary theological method? Fundamentally Schillebeeck's understanding of dogma has not changed from that of his earlier writings. " A dogma is the correct, though never exhaustive, hearing of a reality of revelation or of a word of revelation." 55 It is " a new formulation, relating to a particular situation, of the mystery of salvation experienced in the church-the experience of faith itself in a particular phase of ecclesiastical expression." 56 Schillebeeckx would not deny that dogmatic formulations of the church's faith are important, even essential, since the lived tradition of faith is necessarily mediated through history and thus through differing historical necessarily mediated through history and thus through differing historical expressions. The problem remains, hmve»Tr, that no conceptual formulation of the living experience of foilh, regardless of its authority, importance, and value, can express fully 54 Christ, p. 43. Cf. Erfahrung und Glaube, p. DO. """Exegesis, DogmaticB, and the Development of Dogma," pp. 124-2.). 56" The Concept of Truth," p. 24. 132 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. the mystery to which it points. Dogmatic formulations, and even biblical formulations, are subject to the constraints and limitations of human language. In his early writings Schillebeeckx emphasized that dogmas point to the mystery of revelation-in-reality. With the shift to history and to the biblical God of the future, he further specified dogma as pointing to the future: " It is a close-up of a movement which is continuing and in which it functions." 57 Here the relationship between orthodoxy and orthopraxis becomes clear: " One can only do the future. Thus reinterpretation is also dependent on the activity of the whole Christian life which sheds new light on the dogma and allows new aspects of it to come forth ... it is in the doing of dogma that a dogma is once again reformulated." 58 From a critical perspective, Schillebeeckx adds the further caution that dogma, while pointing to and reexpressing the mystery of the gospel, is always developed in a specific historical context. Quoted out of the context of " the unity of its history " dogma can be used ideologically. 59 In terms of the function of dogma in his contemporary theological method, Schillebeeckx's Jesus project is both illustrative and controversial. His contribution to christology is neither a hermeneutical retrieval of Nicea or Chalcedon nor a critical turn against the dogma of the church. Neither does Schillebeeckx claim to have developed a total christology. Rather the stated purpose of the Jesus book was to establish the historical foundations of the Christian tradition which only in its later development was expressed in dogmatic formulations. Schillebeeckx was seeking to identify and represent the 57 The Crucial Questions on Problems Facing the Church Todny, ed. Frank J<'ehmers (New York: Newman, 1969), p. 64. 58 Ibid., pp. 64-65. Cf. Ghrist the Sacrament of Encounter with God, trans. Paul Barrett, Mark Schoof, and Laurence Bright (New York: Sheed and Ward, l!l63), p. 209: "Our life must itself be the incarnation of what we believe, for only when dogmas are lived do they have any attractive power." :rn "The Magisterium and Ideology," pp. 14-lii. HERl\iENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 133 original inspiration and orientation of the Jesus movementthe Christian tradition in history. Rather than a hermeneutics of dogma, Schillebeeckx's book explored an earlier stage in the development of the history of the Christian tradition-the development of the kerygma to which later dogma points. As a believing Christian theologian standing within the living tradition of the church, Schillebeeckx willingly affirms the classic statements of Nicea and Cha.Jcedon: I have no trouble with any of this, seen from within a Greek intellectual outlook and the questions posed by it at that time; it is straight gospel.60 The Christologica.J dogmas function as second-order affirmations preserving the accuracy and meaning embodied in the first-order confession of belief and prayer of the early Christian community which derived ultimately from their experience of Jesus as " the salvation of God." The very dynamic which demanded the transportation of the biblical kerygma into dogmatic language precisely so that the universal gospel could be proclaimed and preserved in a Hellenistic culture, is the hermeneutical inspiration of Schillebeeckx's own search for a new christology which can speak to the later century in a world of radical suffering. On the one hand Schillebeeckx admits that dogmas and creeds are irreversible and necessary because they have safeguarded the mystery of Jesus Christ in a specific historical and cultural context. On the other hand, Schillebeeckx remarks that " the dogma itself compels me to find a paraphrase that will be intelligible to Christians without their having first to be converted (in order to become or remain believers) to a philosophy or set of meanings which are alien and unintelligible to them." 61 While Schillebeeckx makes some attempts to find that paraphrase in Part IV of the Jesus volume (discussing the two natures in terms of the " parable of God " and " the para 60 61 Jesus, p. 567. The Schillebeeckm Gase, p. 51. 134 .MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. digm of humanity " and the unity in terms of a hypostatic identification inferred from Jesus's Abba experience), a theoretical reformulation of faith is not the focus of his writings. Rather, he proposes to move from theory to narrative and thus to shift to a language that can recapture the original expenence of the Christian movement. 5. Narrative-Practical Theology The shift from a theoretical reinterpretation of the truth of the gospel to a "doing of the truth" in history underlies Schillebeeckx's explanation of why his contemporary Christology constructed with a soteriological focus in the face of the global suffering of humanity has a narrative-practical, rather than a theoretical-dogmatic, intent. Christian faith is an experience which cannot be communicated through critical reason, argument, or theories. Theoretical discourse breaks down in the face of irrational suffering and remains unable to convey the " surplus of meaning " of an eschatological tradition which claims to speak of God as present in history. Rational thought can neither establish intelligible meaning in the non-sense of human history, nor express the "evocative surplus " of the dimension of grace in the fragmentary experiences of salvation in human history. Yet Christians claim that there is an ultimate meaning to human history to be found in the life, ministry, death, and resurrection of Jesus. That meaning is accessible, however, only in the following of Jesus in the concrete personal and social-political "imitation of Christ" and in the telling of the story which flows from that experience of discipleship. In the life-story of Jesus, human suffering is not theoretically resolved, but practically resisted, and ultimately defeated by the power of God. The life-praxis of the followers of Jesus who stand in solidarity with the crucified of the contemporary world is an active remembrance and retelling of the story of Jesus. By retelling the story of the original experience of salvation in Jesus, Schillebeeckx hopes that the original inspira- HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY IN SCHILLEBEECKX 135 tion/orientation of the Christian movement will take root again so that contemporary believers will be drawn into active discipleship-they too will " go and do likewise." 62 IV. Conclusion A. Summary Underlying the major shift in Schillebeeckx's theological method from a dogmatic to a hermeneutical-critical approach is a fundamental continuity rooted in his constant conviction that revelation occurs in history. Three significant threads of continuity can be identified in 1) Schillebeeckx's understanding of revelation, !fl) the distinction between revelation-inreality and revelation-in-word, and 3) his understanding of theology as " faith seeking understanding." 1. Revelation Throughout Schillebeeckx's writings, revelation remains the salvific encounter between God and humanity offered to human beings in history, but significant shifts have occurred as Schillebeeckx has plumbed the implications of that claim in the reality of concrete human history. Recognizing that human history is constituted by human beings who experience reality within the framework of a living tradition, Schillebeeckx has incorporated faith's interpretative framework into the very definition of revelation. Exploring the social and political dimensions of the salvific encounter and attending to the negativity and suffering which constitute the experience of twothirds of humanity, Schillebeeckx now describes the salvific encounter as "contrast experience" for most of the world today. Confronting the implications of human historicity and 62 Although this is Schillebeeckx's intent, the critique of William Portier is to the point: "Particularly in the Jesus book, the text functions primarily as data and critical remembering as narrative is rarely achieved." (Portier, "Edward Schillebeeckx as Critical Theorist," p. 366.) See n, 4 for Metz's critique on this point. 136 MARY CATHERINE HILKERT, O.P. historical consciousness, Schillebeeckx has grappled with the Christian claim that Jesus is universal Savior and has reinterpreted his original understanding of tradition as the process of the transmission of revelation in radically historical terms. If the promise of salvation is to be a universal offer in history, communities of believers must make the experience of salvation concretely available in the unique particularity of every time and culture. The claim remains constant: revelation occurs in human history; but its implications develop dramatically in the context of historical consciousness. 2. The Distinction Between Revelatian-ln-Reality and Revelation-In-Word From his earliest writings Schillebeeckx has emphasized that the mystery of revelation requires a necessary mediation and interpretation, but that no conceptual expression of the mystery can ever exhaust or adequately name the salvific encounter. In his earliest writings Schillebeeckx grounded this claim in a metaphysical-epistemological explanation of the relationship between concept and the reality intended. Arguing that a non-conceptual but objective dynamism allows the human mind to transcend conceptual knowledge and approach reality, Schillebeeckx maintained that while the concept has a definite reference to reality, reality is never grasped or possessed by the concept. Again, however, the claim that the offer of revelation occurs in concrete human history was to generate significant development in Schillebeeckx's understanding of the relationship between revelation-in-reality and revelation-in-word. An awareness of human historicity and a dawning historical consciousness deepened the twofold conviction that while the offer of salvation must be mediated in particular historical and cultural contexts if it is to be an offer for concrete human beings, still every expression of faith (whether in formulation or church structure) remains historically-culturally conditioned. There are no universal expressions of a faith that is mediated HERMENEU'flCS OF HISTORY IN 8C'HILLEBEI