THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II INTRODUCTION I T HAS BECOME commonplace to observe that the doctrine of God is in crisis, an acknowledgement that is softened somewhat in discerning that this is less a crisis of faith itself than of the cultural mediation of faith. For some this is theological disaster, marking the loss of the traditional concept of God to the forces of atheism and secularism. To others it is a liberating factor in that it signals the displacement of an alienating idea of God that clears the way for a long overdue theological reconstruction. One undeniable benefit has been a return of the doctrine of God to its rightful place of centrality in theological discourse--a privileged position it occupied in the 13th century thought of Aquinas and Bonaventure, in the 16th century thought of Luther and Calvin, one retained by Schleiermacher in the 19th century and regained by Karl Barth in the 20th century. Once again, God has become the focus of theological questioning. The difference lies in the way the question has shifted: now the burning issue is the absence or silence of God. THE NEW WAY OF RAISING THE QUESTION OF GOD Heretofore the starting point for religion and theology was Credo in unum Deum, the creedal distillate of the Christian Gospel. This was the Archimedian point of belief upon which depended anthropology, christology, ecclesiology, sacramentology, etc. Such is no longer the case due to the success of the atheist critique beginning with Feuerbach. The atheist challenge remains, either in the negative form of a massive indifference (here the very question of God's existence pales into insignificance, Sartre tells us, because it makes no difference 395 396 WILLIAM J, HILL, O.P. whatsoever to the quality of life: believers kill one another just as do unbelievers, and even do so in the name of God), or in the positive form of a religious humanism, even in some quarters of a theology without God. More radical still is what has been called " semantic atheism ", i.e. the contention that the very word "God" is without meaning, any meaning, that is, that can be validated in the public forum. Nietzsche's cry " God is dead " gives way now to the assertion that the very term "God" has no referent other than that arbitrarily given to it by believers; no objectively real referent, that is. What has occurred, in a spontaneous dialectic of history, whether for good or for bad, is the overthrow of classical theism, i.e. of that understanding in which God is the Supreme Being explaining the existence of everything else-a preunderstanding that precedes revelation and makes the latter credible. This Hellenic and Medieval notion of God was called into question when the cultural world that gave it birth ceased to exist. What was rejected was an objectifying of God, cognitively, by way of metaphysics. This could no longer be the point de depart for the doctrine of God; it was no longer possible to begin with an idea that was then subsequently given content from the sources of revelation. This rendered suspect any demonstrating or verification of God's existence-though it must be said that the atheist premise was equally incapable of validation. This precipitated a radical shift in the question about God. No longer was the concern "Does God exist? ", "Is he real? '', but rather now "Is God present and operative in human life?", and" Does that presence make a difference?". This was in fact a return to the biblical question concerning God's role in human history both individual and social, a question especially urgent in the post-exilic period. God now meant, not" He who is" (lpsum Esse Subsistens), nor even "He who is with us" (mit- Sein), but" He who will be who he will towards mankind", "He who will be the God of our future". The new note being sounded is that of futurity; somewhat muted is the note of divine transcendence, at least in the sense that transcendence was being deferred. THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 397 The shift then was to the God of revelation, more concretely to the God encountered in Jesus of Nazareth. At the very origins of faith then was the attempt to set aside all endeavor to speak about God, in favor of being content to speak about Jesus and his summons to love. The difficulty with this was the impossibility of grounding belief in that God who was the Father of Jesus, in anything other than Jesus's own authority in proclaiming the nearness of that God and his kingdom. But the preaching of Jesus rests on nothing more than his human authority, unless he be recognized as of divine status. This latter confession, however, as to who Jesus is, implies some sort of preunderstanding of God that the believer brings to the encounter with Jesus. Thus does it seem that we can begin neither with a natural theology nor with a purely biblical faith. Two resolutions to this aporia have emerged from within recent Catholic thought. One arises from rereading Aquinas thvough Kantian spectacles. The result is a Transcendental Thomism-its practitioners are Karl Rahner, Bernard Lonergan, Emerich Coreth, Joseph Lotz, and a host of disciples 1 whieh reconceives human subjectivity as universally oriented towards the Absolute, named at the start simply as Holy Mystery. In this anonymous affirmation of God, there is no prior seeking out of some objective concept of God (something humanly devised, then) with which to approach God. Rather, the human subject as such is always already standing before God. Human subjectivity is understood as intrinsically gifted with transcendence as God's unexacted gift Spirit in the World tr. William Dych (New York: 1 Cf. Karl Rahner: York: Herder & Herder, 1969) ; also a theological employment of the theory in Foundations of Christian Faith, tr. William Dych (New York: Seabury Press, 1978). Bernard Lonergan: Insight (New York: Philosophical Library, 1958) with theological application in Method in Theology (New York: Herder & Herder, 1972). Emerich Coreth: M etaphysik: Eine M ethodischSystematisch Grundlegung (Innsbruck: Tyrolia, 1961). J. B. Lotz: Das Urteil und das Sein (Pullach bei Munchen, 1957). Helpful also is Otto Muck: The Transcendental Method, tr. William Seidensticker (New York: Herder & Herder, 1968). 398 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. (or at least offer) of himself. This transcendence is necessarily mediated by categorical reality, above all by concrete historical events, but within such mediation there is conscious experience of this orientation to God which in fact defines man as man. Nonetheless, it remains nonobjective, no:nconceptual and unthematic. Categorical knowledge, by contrast, is precisely a thematizing, a focusing down as it were, of this transcendental orientation, of this prer;rasp (Vorgnff) of what is in fact the divine. The latter then constitutes a universal human experience which is subsequently given expression in the multiple and differing doctrines and beliefs which divide mankind. One common and universal experience is thus given varied expressions and articulations. The alternative view finds this to give human subjectivity more weight than it can bear. Accordingly, it gives greater stress to the object of faith which is in fact the very person and deeds of Christ who is within history" the manifestation of the goodness and the living kindness of God" (Titus 3: 4). This position is represented by Hans Urs von Balthasar for one, who 11egards theology as more a matter of aesthetics than of science, as an intuition of the splendor and glory of God revealed in Christ. 2 Johann-Baptist Metz advocates it, though differently in using memory as a theological category that stresses the primacy of genuine history over being, over what he would take to be only the illusion of history in Transcendental Thomism; and in preference to the emphasis upon presentiality characteristic of existential thought, one markedly operative in Bultmannian theology. 3 l\1etz's own thought then is a reaction against the bias for what is individual and private in the interest of what pertains to the social and communitarian. Edward Schillebeeckx also leans in this direction, first by promoting the hermeneutic role in theology (as a reinterpretation Love Alone, tr. Alexander Dru (New York: 2 Cf. Hans Urs von Balthasar: Herder & Herder, 1969. a J. B. Metz: Faith in History and Society, tr. David Smith (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969). THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 399 of living tradition) , but more recently by employing the social critical theory of the Frankfort School wherein greater place is given to the discontinuities and the negativities in history. This allows him to give greater emphasis to actual occurrences in their uniqueness, which do not participate in a meaning totality otherwise than by anticipating it. 4 All these theologians are reserved towards the transcendental project of allowing for a common inner experience shaping subsequent expression. They prefer to begin with the given symbols of the community (scriptural, liturgical, sacramental) which then shape subsesequent experiences. The Church then preexists its members whom it forms by incorporating them into itself. But this option, too, is not without difficulties of its own. Preeminent among them is the lack of some locus in the humanum which undergoes history, wherein humankind is open to and enabled to receive God's historical revelation. The only viable resolution of this dilemma seemingly is an even more radical fall back upon experience-not merely the experience of transcendence or of the Jesus-event-in all its contingency and secularity. This would seem to signal a retreat from metaphysics, and a natural theology built upon it, certainly from an essentialistic metaphysics. This then is an implicit acquiescence in Heidegger's charge that traditional theism is in fact an ontotheo-logic. Still, the doctrine of God has to be thought through, and it can be legitimately wondered if therefore all metaphysics can be abandoned. The language at work, for example, intends not only genuine meaning but also a real referent. The sole alternative to classical metaphysics need not be either linguistic analysis or biblical fundamentalism, nor may it mean collapse into uncritical belief or into action. The existence of a transsubjective referent to language here obviously cannot be verified empirically. So, at least in this minimal sense, the activity engaged in here is metaphysical, i.e. it is more than a purely empirical act. The rooting of such activity in experience means Jesus: An Experiment in Ohristology, 4 Edward Schillebeeckx: Hoskins (New York: Seabury Press, 1979), esp. pp. 618-619. tr. Hubert 400 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. that the metaphysical dimension is an a posteriori, not an a priori one. But if, by and large, old certainties have been eroded away, the beginnings of a recovery can only lie someplace in the preconditions to thought, in the prerational, even visceral reaction to existence. This lived experience may make it possible to mitigate any unvalidated presuppositions, especially since the experience at issue is an ordinary and universally accessible one, that is, not a specifically religious experience or encounter. Langdon Gilkey characterizes these as secular experiences in their very security, but occurring at a certain depth level that cannot fail to confront us with what is ultimate in life.5 They are not direct experiences of God but experiences of ourselves, of our very humanity, which are experiences of God only covertly and negatively. They are experiences of such realities as the giftlike character of existence, of the unconditioned value of life even in the face of death suggesting that the latter is not mere disappearance into the Void, of the transtemporal dimension to certain experiences of joy, of the awareness of being forgiven our betrayals, of the ambiguity of our freedom as rooting our capacity for love. These force upon us the question about God; the answers lie elsewhere, above all in the confessions of the positive religions. What must be noted, however, is that all such experiences are interpreted ones. are no such things as brute experiences which are value-free. From the very beginning then we are drawn up into the circle of faith. Philosophies of man no longer acquiesce in the Enlightenment's "prejudice against prejudice". Unavoidably we bring a nexus of preunderstandings, of theories and conceptual systems, to our experiences. Thus a hermeneutical circle arises inevitably between present experiences on one hand, and interpretive norms brought to them from the past on the other. Michael Polanyi has argued persuasively for the recognition that all human knowledge bears 5 Langdon Gilkey: Naming the Whirlwind: (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1969). The Renewal of God Language THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 401 within itself a fiduciary element: " We must now recognize be11ef once more as the source of all knowledge, explaining the impulses which shape our vision of the nature of things ... " 6 Conceiving the problem somewhat differently, Han-Georg Gadamer describes what happens as a" fusing of the horizons", i.e. as a bridging of the horizons of present experience with that forming the background of texts received from the tradition, to avoid either reading into the text something that is not there, or allowing the text to go uninterpreted. 7 The dialectical nature of this affirmation of God has been lucidly posed by Wolfhart Pannenberg: " Only if man, even outside the Christian message, is related in his being as man to the reality of God on which the message of Jesus is based, can fellowship with Jesus mean salvation to him ". 8 This preliminary idea-which makes possible the question but not the answer about God- is radically transonce it makes possible the encounter with Christ, not so much in the sense that the original " empty " concept is filled in and given content as that the very character of the question undergoes an enriching alteration. The faith encounter by way of the human life of Jesus, in other words, shapes the very question posed about God. One confirmation of this way of asking about God is provided by Karl Marx who predicted that Marxist theorizers needn't worry about the reality of God, for once the revolution succeeded the very term itself would vanish as otiose. Events have proven him mistaken. The word refuses to go away and is raised today perhaps with greater urgency than ever. Even Marxist theorists behind the Iron Curtain, while explicitly denying any real referent to the term, resort to it as a means of forestalling any absolutizing of the socialist state. For them, 6 Michael Polanyi: Personal Knowledge, Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962) p. 266. 7 Hans-Georg Gadamer: Truth and Met hod (New York: Seabury Press, 1975). s Wolfhart Pannenberg, " Speaking about God in the Face of Atheist Critique", The Idea of God and Human Freedom, tr. R. A. Wilson (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1973), p. 102. 402 WILLIAM .J. HILL, O.P. the term has the function of invoking a transcendence that alone is unconditional and so can function in a regulatory way in thought; it appeals to a transcendence but denies a transcendent. For Ernst Bloch, " God " is a cipher or a code word for the limitless possibilities inherent in the human project. 9 Another atheist-Marxist from Czechoslovakia has entitled one of his books God Is Not Quite Dead, in which the theme of "God" is used to signify a liberating potentiality in challenging all arbitrarily closed historical and social horizons. This very word is necessary to any notion of humankind in its totalmuch so that the death of God means eventually the death of man as a bearer of meaning. Indeed, Rahner has written that without this word man remains but a clever anirnal. 10 But the enigmatic figure of Karl Marx has cast yet another shadow on contemporary theology. This derives from his wellknown eleventh thesis on Feuerbach contending that the role of philosophy is not to construct one more theory about the world but to seek to change the world. This " second corning " of Marx" not in the dusty frock coat of the economist ... [but] ... as a philosopher and moral prophet with glad tidings about human freedom'' 11 has obvious attractions for the contemporary theologian. H God breaks into our history, becoming man in Jesus, proclaiming the nearness of the kingdom, and summoning to salvation, this certainly intends an abrupt change in the direction our history has taken. The consequence is a new and pronounced emphasis upon orthopraxis as the indispensable means of establishing orthodoxy, that is, of rendering credible the mysteries confessed by the Christian. Praxis here means a dialectic between theory on the one hand and practice or behavior on the other. Any dichotomy between speculative and practical reason is thus seen to be a disastrous one. Edward Schillebeeckx indicated how such orthopraxis is at once operaBloch: Das Prinzip Hoffnung, 2 vols. (Frankfort, 1959). Foundations of Christian Faith, p. 48. 11 Sidney Hook, cited by Francis Fiorenza in " Dialectical Theology Hope, I" The Heythrop Journal, IX, 2 (April, 1968) p. 144. 9 Ernst 10 Rahner: and THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VA'l'ICAN II 403 tive in two domains: the mystical and the ethical. 12 The former is the appmach to God in prayer, something that can assume a specifically Christian form but allows for non-Christian form as well. The ethical assumes from the very beginning a universal character, marking a concern Christians share with all mankind. Praxis as such is not a norm for truth; Oscar Wilde once observed that willingness to die for a cause is no proof for the truthfulness or goodness of that cause. At the same time, praxis can have a cognitive dimension and function. 11'1etanoia and the practice of God's kingdom are then the hermeneutical keys to interpreting Christian beliefs in the texts of the Bible, the Fathers and the teaching Church. It is in his own praxis of the kingdom-in his dealings with sinners, his miracles, his parables, his table fellowship with people, his attitude towards the Law-that Jesus comes to recognize God as Abba, caring for and offering a future to his children. 13 ]!'rom considerations such as these arises the centrality of hope in Christian existence. Recent refiection, even if allowing a temporal priority to faith, grants ontological primacy rather to hope. Christian life pivots on God's promises to us; if he is with us now, this "already" is the prolepsis of the "yet to come". If the kingdom is already inaugurated in Jesus's human life, its consummation lies ahead of us with the God who is to come as the future of humanity. Without succumbing to the myth of progress, we, like the Israelites of old, set out for the promised land-a land, however, that we ourselves must reclaim and cultivate, trusting in God's promises. Faith in a life to come, in the Eschaton, can only ring true if our hope motivates us to seek a better future here and now. One reservation should perhaps be registered concerning this granting of primacy to the future, one intended as a qualification not a rejection of such revitalization of the virtue of hope. 12Edward Schillebeeckx: Christ: The Experience of Jesus as Lord, tr. J. Bowden (New York: Seabury Press, 1980) esp. p. 658. 13 Schillebeeckx: The Schillebeeckx Reader, ed. Robert Schreiter (New York: Crossroad, 1984) pp. 147-148. 404 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. Hope wills the goodness of God to ourselves, but Christian charity, as our reflection of God's agape towards us, wills God's goodness to himself; we rejoice as it were that God is God. Love of God then which transcends considerations of past, present, and future should not be displaced from its absolute primacy by revivified hope. Simply put, our present love of God is the ground of our hoping for the God of our future. THE IDENTITY OF THE GOD CONFESSED When questions are altered in being newly proposed the result is a difference in the nature of the answers thereby available. It is hardly surprising then that the identity of the God who is newly emerging is that of historicity. The retreat from metaphysics in favor of a recourse to history refocuses what is meant by divine transcendence: God is now recognized less as the author of nature than as the Lord of history; he is not so much " above ,, us as " ahead " of us, less a God of the present than of the future. What this derives from is a pronounced anthropological dimension to theology, which is only to say that man himself has become the starting point for theological reflection. The question about God is after all man's question; the subjective component cannot be ignored. Man is conceived as historical in his very being; history is essential to man and not merely accidental, as if he possessed a nature intelligible in itself apart from its involvement in temporality. The starting point then for religious reflection is not human nature in the abstract but concrete humanity as damaged, as bearing the wounds of sin and suffering. Humanity, both individually and socially, consitutes itself to be what it is by the way it actualizes itself in playing out its freedom. Time is not something suffered as an imposed imperfection from which release is sought (as in Neo-Platonic thought) but a valued prerogative enabling humans to mature in a process of self-enactment. This new awareness of how we are immersed in history stresses human freedom and creative praxis in such wise that history is not the mere reiteration of changeless forms but is the genuine succession of THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 405 new and transient forms, meaning the possibility of growth, of genuine novelty in truth and value. 14 The upshot of this is that such stress on the historicity of mankind means that God cannot be a God pro nobis (and this is after all the God we seek) unless he is involved with us historically. The richest implication of this-and it is not one that should go unquestioned-is not that the deity enters our history from without, but that God himself is historical. Process Theology intends this literally: God himself "becomes", actualizing in his consequent nature values made available for his prehension by creatures, values previously lacking to him. This is panentheism pure and simple, by which is meant not that God is simply identified with the world (pantheism) but that he is dependent upon the world for his own beingness. Thus Whitehead can write " it is as true to say the world creates God as that God creates the world ". 15 Aquinas strove to preclude such understanding (for him a misunderstanding) by insisting that God's relation to the world-while acknowledged to be actual (God truly creates, knows, loves, redeems, etc.) and intelligible (thus relationes rationis)-were not "real" in the Aristotelian sense of bespeaking causal dependence.16 A modification of this position appears in the influential work of the Reformed theologian, Jurgen Moltmann. 1' Here too, the thought is panentheistic but in the qualified sense that God, who does not need the world by nature, chooses in his transcendent freedom to depend upon and be intrinsically affected by it. The identification of God's being as love demands this, in that love as such opens the lover to being affected by the beloved, to suf14 For a detailed development of this, cf. Langdon Gilkey: Reaping the Whirlwind: A Christian Interpretation of History (New York: Seabury Press, 1976) esp. p. 188f. 15 Alfred N. Whitehead: Process and Reality, Free Press Edition (New York: Macmillan, 1969) Part 5, Chap. 2, Section 5, p. 410. 16 Thomas Aquinas: Summa Theologiae, I, q. 13, a. 7, corp. 11 Jurgen Moltmann: The Crucified God, tr. R. A. Wilson and J. Bowden (New York: Harper & Row, 1974) p. 235f. 406 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. fering if the latter is affiicted. Theology in the Catholic tradition, granting that this is true in all instances of finite love, is less sure that such is the case with infinite love, which gives altruistically without being enhanced by anything it receives in return (more about this is in a moment). An alternative position, more accommodated to the Catholic understanding of tradition, prefers to say that while God does change he does so not in his own being but in the world. The genuine import of this is missed if it be interpreted to mean merely that finite realities assumed by God change (the obvious example being the humanity of Jesus). What is explicitly being maintained is that God himself changes, but not in himself but rather in his "other ". 18 Undergirding this manner of thinking is a philosophy of identity inspired by Hegel more than anyone else. Here the conception of God as pure being is considered empty and without content until God enacts himself by positing his" other "-non-being in short-so as to constitute himself in the very differentiating of himself from Nothing. What emerges from this is the notion of God as pure becoming rather than being; the very essence of deity is thus "event". The newness of this concept of God is underscored in what follows logically from it, namely that God is now a God of the future rather than of the past, i.e. not a God who appeared to us once and for all in the past but a God who continues to come to us out of the future-out of the future into the present by way of the past. God is with us not as a presence of eternity within time but as a presence of the future in the present, rus the impact of the future upon the present. Thus, divine revelation, while remaining definitive, is at the same time provisional: definitive because it is God's revelation that will not be repudiated and cannot be relativized; provisional in that it is not yet ended and is ever being enriched by new events. Some (Pannenberg, for example) even go so far as to say that the resurrection of Christ remains unfinished and open to future 1s Rahner: " On the Theology of the Incarnation", tions, Vol. 4, tr. Kevin Smyth, pp. 113-114. Theological Investiga- THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 407 consummation. 19 At any rate, this is certainly taken to be the case with the human enterprise. This historicizing of God means replacing the attribute of eternity with that of a primal temporality wherein God does not stand outside of time in a motionless nunc stans, but embraces all time-past, present, and future-within himself. Yet he does so successively. God accordingly has his own past and his own future-granted that due to the infinity of his temporality, his past had no beginning and his future will have no end. So viewed, God's being is in becoming and futurity is the mode of divine being. Such a God is not the ground of the phenomenal world but the source of events which he (as" the power over all that is," in Pannenberg's phrase) determines from within history, but within history understood from its end. Catholic thought has clearly moved in this direction but once again reservedly so. First, it has insisted that the consummation of history will not be a this-worldly one but something eschatological. Its achievement lies not within the capacities of humanity as such but in the transforming power of God alone when temporal history will have come to an end. Thus the myth of continual progress is resisted-if for no other reason than the paradox of the Cross. Secondly, however, a reservation is expressed on the openness of the future in that a greater claim is made of certainty regarding the direction of human history due to God's promises to which he will be faithful. The kingdom will come, and the Church will remain indefectible and infallible in its mediation of that kingdom. Still and all, that absolute future will not simply come, when history has ceased, as a reward earned in temporal life. It has in fact begun even now and entrance into eternal life will be the maturing of human freedom under grace into the fullness of the kingdom. This will be no mere termination but a true consummation. Genuine history thus constructs in freedom its 19 W. Pannenberg: "Response to the Discussion", Theology as History, Vol. 3 of New Frontiers in Theology, eds. J. M. Robinson & J. B. Cobb (New York: Harper & Row, 1967) p. 264, n. 74. 408 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. own definitive stage-granting God's entry into humanity's making of itself. By contrast, for Process Theology the human project can, in principle at any rate, still end in disaster; and in any case there will be no end to history. For Moltmann, God will be faithful tro his promises but in a recreative act which will mean a repudiation of what man will have made of history -thus the marked emphasis on the Cross as destructive and on the discontinuities rather than the continuities of time. The Catholic nuance mitigates this apocalyptic tone in favor of an eschatological one, i.e. the vector runs from the present into the future rather than from the future into the present. But that future with God lies neither at the end of history as its thisworldly termination, nor simply after history, but is already taking shape in the depths of present history. The heavenly Eschaton to come is already transpiring within history. At the very base of this revised concept of God lies a revitalized doctrine of the Trinity. God is intrinsically processive; divine life is the perichoresis of the Father uttering his Word, and appropriating himself as so uttered in a movement of love that is personified as Spirit. Divine being then is intrinsically self-expressive and self-unitive. But this divine circularity spirals outward, as it were, into the Void, culminating in the Incarnate Word as the self-expression of God into the Void, and in the Paraclete as God's loving reintegration of that humanity with himself. In this there is found the grounding of human history. It is not that human history is the foundation of the trinitarian processions but the other way around. At least a caution has to be introduced at this point: Incarnation and Pentecost cannot be necessary acts of God; rather they remain instances of his absolute freedom. But contemporary theology tends to view this phenomenon not as a matter of free choice (liberum arbitrium) but of freedom in a transcendent which lies deeper than the opposition between coercion or natural resultancy on one hand and mere option on the other. One way of expressing this is to say that the Logos eternally engendered within God comes forth THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 409 as the Logos to become incarnate; one might say as the Logos Incarnandus. However, this implies an inevitability, approaching a moral necessity (i.e. that God would not be fully a God of love if he failed to communicate into the world his very self) . As such, it can be contested as an excessive assertion. Some qualifiication seems called for then on the meaning of the verb " is " in the oft-cited proposition: " the economic Trinity is the immanent Trinity, and the immanent Trinity is the economic Trinity ". 20 Some such hesitancy seems called for in ol.'der to safeguard the gratuity and altruistic character of divine love for the world, of its unique character as New Testament agape rather than as Greek eras. Allied to this recouped trinitarianism is the contention that God's relations to the human life of Jesus as it unfolds historically are intrinsic ones. That human life, in its finiteness and oontingency, in its free decisions of love, is then constitutive of the very being of the Godhead. Otherwise, those events cannot be thought of as the definitive self-revelation and self-communication of God. Wolfhart Pannenberg, for example, contends that God cannot be understood on the basis of the ahistorical immanent Trinity alone. What is required is a " placing in question (Infragestellung) of God's deity within history. God is Father precisely in raising Jesus from the dead; he is Son in his self-differentiation from the Father within our history; and he is Spirit in his glorification of the Father and Son. Pannenberg himself goes so far as to write: "God's Godhead itself is at stake in history ". 21 The question of God's identity is here inseparable from the question of the meaning and the truth of Jesus's own history. What is questionable here is why this is not a collapsing of the immanent Trinity into the economic Trinity-a problem 20 Cf. K. Rahner: The Trinity tr., Joseph Donceel (New York: Herder & Herder, 1970) pp. 31-33 and 99-103. 21 'vV. Pannenberg: Grundfragen systematischer Theologie: Gesammelte Aufsatze, Band 2 (Gllttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1980), p. ll8; cited by Philip Clayton, "The God of History and the Presence of the Future", The Journal of Religion, 65/l (Jan., 1985) p. 104. 410 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. even more pronounced in Moltmann 22-and even an obliteration of the distinction between creator and creature. If intrinsic relation means God is formally constituted as God by his relations to Jesus so that these relationships could not be and apart from them God is not God-then a demurrer seems called for. It is rather true to say that these relations are extrinsic to God, in the sense that they are contingent to his being, and willed by him in all freedom. But, once it is granted that God has chosen to create a world, then by a conditional necessity he cannot fail to relate to it and essentially so, since its very beingness both as nature and as history exists only by way of a grounding in God's being. Nonetheless, God does characterize himself as the kind of God he is by the nature of these freely chosen relationships-bearing in mind that in the domain of history God could choose to relate to the world in the mode of silence and of refusal to communicate his very self. There is another implication of this historicizing of God's being (which is in fact an ontologizing of time, especially when it is understood as universal history as in Pannenberg's Universalgeschichte) in the tendency to shy away from the concept "redemption" in preference for the mme history-laden concept " liberation ". Jesus is less one who overthrows a disorder at the heart of human existence, conveyed in the precise Christian symbol of "sin", than one who inaugurates the freeing of humankind at large from our all-pervasive history of suffering. This is less a repudiation of a more traiditional theology of redemption than an insistence that an inner component of that redemption is earthly salvation within this world. Once again an appeal is made to a certain primacy of orthopraxis-without it orthodoxy is something incredible and ideological -and it highlights that Christianity cannot be left a:s a matter of the heart only, of personal conversion, without a reform of those social structures which oppress humanity. ':Dhe reason is that God has entered our history precisely as one who (in Schille22 Cf. J. Moltmann: The Trinity and the Kingdom, tr. Margaret Kohl (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1981). THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 411 beeckx's phrase) "has made the cause of mankind to be his (God's) cause". Salvation, which in the end will be God's eschatological transforming act (and here Christianity distances itself from Marxism pure and simple), is communicated to us within the ambiguities of history and not outside human suffering. The identity of God here emerging out of our inevitable encounter with suffering is that of a living God who enlists himself in opposition to all forms of evil and oppression; he is God among us. If there is a danger here it is that of supposing that the divinity of Jesus consists in his saving significance for us-but that is to misplace the emphasis and is contrary to the intention of most so-called liberation theology. The core theological point being made here is that the divinity of Christ is not something behind or alongside his humanity (this is a common misreading of Chalcedon's two nature theory) but is very God in our midst as man, i.e. in the mode and dimension of our humanity. Thus Schillebeeckx cites approvingly Piet Schoonenberg: " We cannot point to anything divine in Jesus that is not realized in and from what is human", and goes on to observe that failure to acknowledge this tempts us "to slip past this human aspect as quickly as we can in order to admire a ' divine Icon' from which every trait of Jesus as the critical prophet has been smoothed away ". 23 One implication of this is that the traditional formula " hypostatic union " can perhaps be more richly expressed as "hypostatic unity. Every theological position runs the risk of over-stating its basic insights. Two which are at least possible here are: i) overstressing the humanity of Jesus to the detriment of his divinity, and ii) giving an exaggerated prominence to present experiences (meaning interpreted experiences) as compared to what is available as normative in the New Testament and in Tradition. One illustration of both is the coalescence of love of God and love of neighbor. This should not be seen as an uncritical identity of the two. Genuine love of neighbor is in fact an implicit love of God (all 23 E. Schillebeeckx: Jesus, pp. 597 and 671. WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. three Synoptic accounts make this abundantly clear 24 ) but this does not compromise the primacy of one's relationship to God. God's immanence at the heart of our tragic human history has broached another profound and controversial question: Does God's love for us in its kenotic character, and its historical consummation on the Cross, mean that suffering is intrinsic to the Godhead? Does God in short absorb our suffering into his own beingness in order to transform and ultimately to overcome it? Once again, this is positively affirmed by Process Theology of its cosmic God. It is also central in Moltmann's crucified God-not that God suffers by a necessity of his nature, and thus unavoidably so, but rather that his love demands his taking upon himself, freely, the suffering of the beloved, that is, of humanity. Such a perspective enables Moltmann to understand the Cross as a transaction, not between God and man but between God and God, i.e. between the Father and the Son. 25 On the Catholic side, this understanding has been advanced by Hans Urs von Balthasar on the grounds that this is what the biblical symbols lead us to, in a non-metaphysical theology where conceptual clarity in its objectifying of God must give way to the" reduction to mystery ". 26 By this, something much more than a communicatio idiomatum is intended; it does not intend to say only that the humanity of Jesus suffers, which just happens to be the humanity of the Son of God. Certainly, finite love which achieves an identification, on the affective if not the ontic level, of the lover with the beloved (love as such is a unitive force-even in God) but is powerless to overcome 24 Mt. 22: 38-40; Mk. 12: 29-31; Lk. 10: 25-37. Moltmann: The Trinity and the Kingdom, p. 23. On this whole question of suffering in God, cf. W. J. Hill, "Does Divine Love Entail Suffering in God"?, God and Temporality, eds. B. L. Clarke & E. T. Long (New York: Paragon House, 1984) pp. 55-71. 2s Hans Urs von Balthasar, "Mysterium Paschale ", Mysterium Salutis, eds. J. Feiner & M. Llihrer, Vol. III/2 ( Einsiedeln: Benziger, 1969) pp. 133326; also available in French transl. of Mysterium Salutis, pp. 133-326; Vol. 12 (Paris: 1972), and in an independent publication entitled Theologie der drei Tage (Einsiedeln: Benziger, 1969). 25 J. THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 413 the sources responsible for the anguish of the beloved, is a love that renders the lover vulnerable. But divine love is omnipotent (its power is one in the mode of love) and so would seem to require not that God suffer with his creatures but that he enlist himself in the cause of alleviating and ultimately vanquishing that suffering. The way in which God chooses to do this, i.e. the mode of its efficacy, does, it must be granted, remain mysterious. Obviously, he does not will to banish suffering from without, choosing rather to enter into our suffering and overthrow it (we have at this point only his promises and the anticipation of their fulfillment in the Resurrection of Jesus) from within. But this is a matter not of God's own being as a history of suffering, his trinitarian history, but of his entering into and taking upon himself our history which we have marred with sin. The rhetorical and indeed religious power of a God who takes suffering into himself cannot be denied. Theologically, however, a stronger case can be made for precluding all possibility of suffering from the deity on the grounds of divine transcendence. 27 Does it make sense to say that God can will to be something lesser than God? Is it not problematic to conceive of God the Father punishing his Son by delivering him over to the " powers of darkness " rather than allowing such evil, which sin alone brings into the world, to work its destruction upon his assumed humanity out of a loving will to enter into solidarity with suffering humankind? On this view, Christ's cry of dereliction from the Cross is not really due to an abandonment of him by the Father. It expresses rather how profound is the alienation from God that results from sin, and its issue which is the experience of death. The more integral truth of the Cross is not that God turns aside from his Son on the Cross but that he remains with him precisely in the midst of what is, humanly speaking, abysmal failure-as he remains with us in our hour of darkness, inexorably setting his face against everything that kills the human 21 Cf. the persuasive argument for this position by Edward Schillebeeckx: Christ p. 724£. 414 WILLIAM J, HILL, O.P. heart. Operative in this concept of a suffering God is the danger of a mystique of death-i.e. the notion that suffering as such is redemptive and salvific, rather than its being such only in virtue of the love wherein it is undergone. Another clue to the identity of the God we seek presents itself in the revealed name of God, in that name whereby he is invoked by Jesus in the New Testament. There are no parallels in all of religious literature to Jesus's repeated use (170 times in the New Testament) of the name "Father", frequently in its Aramaic form of Abba. This is something far different from Plato's idea of Goodness, Aristotle's Unmoved Mover, Plotinus's One, and even from Yahweh of the Jewish scriptures though in this last instance God is being named on the basis of an historical acting in human history. As Claude Greffre has pointed out, this privileged name is not a designation for God but an invocation of him; it corresponds to a proper name. 28 It does not intend then the adscription to divinity of male or pate:1:nal characteristics as over against feminine or maternal ones, which latter can serve equally as symbols of divine attributes. This revealed name of God is derived from a symbol expressing God's relationship to a unique Son and conveying the notion of obedience-a filial obedience, however, grounded in an unqualified and confident love. What is simply absent from the term is any connotation of dominance m heteronomy. In the Jewish culture of the first century such obedience was highly extolled and was understood in terms of the relationship of the human son to his human father. God's fatherhood, as experienced for himself and revealed to us by Jesus, bespeaks a predilection for the "poor", meaning sinners, outcasts, the needy, the hungry, the sick, the deprived, the oppressed-a predilection however that is not exclusive of others. God's seeking out of these merely testifies to 28 Claude Geffre, "'Father' as the Proper name of God", Gonoilium, Vol. 143 God as Ji'ather, eds. J. B. Metz and E. Schillebeeckx (New York: Seabury Press, 1981) p. 43-50. THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 415 the universality of his salvific love: if God seeks out even these disadvantaged ones then clearly the kingdom of God is near. But it remains love that is the formal motivation for the liberation which God proffers in Christ. This is a liberation for all peoples from "all the slaveries to which sin subjugates them: ignorance, misery, hunger, and oppression ... In a word, liberation from the injustice and hate which originate in human egoism ". 29 There remains the question of God's responsiveness to the activity of his creatures. Does the God who has made himself the God of and for humanity change in response to the initiatives of men and women? Or does he remain the changeless, 3!pathetic divinity of traditional theism? Seemingly, God's transcendence precludes his determination by any creature in the sense of his acquiring perfections previously lacking to him (or any diminution of perfections already possessed). Still and all, there does remain a possible way of incorporating alteration within God in his dialogic relationship with his rational and free creatures. First of all, this might be understood as mutation, not in the order of God's very being but in the intentional order constituting his knowing and loving. The reason for such a suggestion is simply that God would be a different sort of God than he in fact is if he had chosen not to create a world or to create a world different from the one that does in fact exist. In either case he both knows and loves something that would not otherwise terminate his knowing and loving. This is compounded by the fact that in its human dimension that world changes freely, introducing genuine novelty into the world thereby so that there is obviously something new for God to know and to react to lovingly. This cannot be so without a mutation in the objects of divine knowing and loving. It would appear then that one must allow that God does change, not absolutely but relatively; the alteration does occur not in the divine nature but in God's free relating towards his 29 Jon Sobrino: Jesus in Latin America: cited by Juan Alfaro, "Jesus in Latin America", Theology Digest, 32/1 (Spring, 1985) p. 6. 416 WILLIAM J, HILL, O.P. self-determining creatures. The mutation is not one from potency to act (God is already fully actual and so without capacity for further perfecting) but, we may so speak, from act to act. With Schillebeeckx we can say, "God is new each moment ", 30 but not by way of an enhancement of his being. W. Norris Clarke has expressed this with welcome clarity: God's inner being is genuinely affected, not in an ascending or descending way, but in a truly real personal, conscious relational way by His relations with us ... [but without] ... moving to a qualitatively higher level of inner perfection than God had before. 31 Elsewhere, I have suggested that this insight can be richly exploited in trinitarian terms. 32 Remaining immutable on the level of his one divine nature, God is pure relationality on the distinct level of his threefold personhood. A central defining element in the concept of "person" is relation (the human person is thus a unique and freely posited, self-determining relationality within the commonality of humanity) . But why could not this regard not only that subsistent relationality which is the eternal Trinity, but incorporate the relationality of the three divine Subjects to human persons as well? If so, then we are enrubled to say that God absorbs into his own e:xiperiencewhatever novelty his free creatures introduce into the world, as these latter mark out their own destiny within the parameters set by God-that is to say, not apart from soE. Schillebeeckx: God is New Each Moment, tr. David Smith, Conversations with Huub Oosterhuis and Piet Hoogeveen (New York: Seabury Press, 1983. s1 W. Norris Clarke: The Philosophical Approach to God (Winston-Salem; North Carolina: Wake University Press, 1979), p. 104. s2 Cf. W. J. Hill: The Three Personed God (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1982) pp. 287-289; "Does the World Make a Difference to God?", The Thomist, 38/1 (Jan., 1974) pp. 146-174; "Does God Know the Future? ", Theological Studies, 36/l (March, 1975) pp. 3-18; "The Historicity of God", Theological Studies, 45/2 (June, 1984) pp. 320-333; "The Implicate World: God's Oneness with Mankind as a Mediated Immediacy'', Beyond Mechanism, ed. David L. Schindler (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1985). THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AFTER VATICAN II 417 certain definitive acts of God such as above all his raising of Jesus from the dead. CONCLUSION All of this leads to the conclusion that God's radical difference from everything that makes up the empirical world inhabited by men and women renders our awareness of him provisional and tentative in kind. In his incomprehensibility, he is known only as (in Rahner's phrase) "Holy Mystery." Our knowledge is positive, and counts as gain, in that we know that God is unknown and unknowable. So much so, that there simply are no proofs for his existence, though it remains possible to verify both the meaning and the truth of the assertion that" God is". This is verification in the sense that such an affirmation cannot be shown to be contrary to either experience or logic, that it is in other words entirely reasonable to confess God's reality. This is especially true if it be acknowledged that both experience and reason testify to a dimension in our knowledge of the world that belongs to mystery and so eludes conceptual grasp and objectification. The verification in question then is one rooted in concrete human experience, common experience that is always interpreted experience, and so includes from the beginning a fiduciary element. The quinque viae then of Aquinas remain valid, not in the sense of proving God's existence from a state of pure agnosticism, but by way of clarifying the question, pointing in the direction of its resolution, and giving logical formulations to the answers surmised. Ultimately, however, God is affirmed on the basis of his own self-revelatory act which is in fact a self-communication -one that occurs historically and culminates in the Christevent. Thus, the question of God is raised today in a nonmetaphysical way, in the sense that the one domain of truth with which metaphysics does not concern itself is that of historical contingency. It remains metaphysical in the looser sense that the concern and the language employed is trans-empirical. In the final analysis it is only by way of the life, the preaching, 418 WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. the death and resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth that God fully discloses himself to humankind, as a hidden God who wills to be nonetheless a Deus pro nobis, proffering salvation to all of humanity. On this account, he is the God of mankind's future, vouchsafing to us his promises, thereby rendering the Christian life one of hope, guaranteeing that he will prevail in the end over against the " deadliness of death" (Moltmann) . Such a God is not dead but present and operative in the midst of our history, both individual and social. l£ that presence appears more often than not in the mode of absence, much of the reason is that we look for him in the wrong places-for example in the structures of power rather than those of kenotic loveforgetting that divine omnipotence is power in the mode of love. WILLIAM J. HILL, O.P. Catholic University of America Washington, D.G. AN EXPLICATION OF THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS BOETHIUS IN THE LlGHT OF ST. THOMAS'S COMMENTARY OF HE WRITINGS o:f Ancius Manlius Severinus Boehius exercised a powerful influence on the nature and evelopment o:f mediaeval philosophy. The extent of his influence was such that I think it fair to say that anyone seeking more than a superficial grasp of mediaeval philosophy must acquire some first-hand knowledge of his work. The trouble is, however, that while The Corwlsation of Philosophy is well-known and much commented upon, Boethius's other works are relatively neglected. 1 Included in this latter group are the five theological tractates, one of which has this imposing title: Quomodo Substantiae In Eo Quad Sint Bonae Sint Cum Non Sint Substantialia Bona. This tractate also has the more managable title De Hebdomadibus and it is as such that I shall refer to it throughout this article. 2 I have chosen to give an explication of the De Hebdomadibus for three reasons. First the problem with which it deals (the nature of the relation between goodness and substance) is intrinsically interesting and Boethius's solution to the problem is a model of philosophical analysis. Second, in addition to the fact that the philosophical status of the nine axioms listed in the tractate is a matter of some scholarly controversy, the answer to the obvious question of how these axioms function in the tractate as a whole is not at all clear. And third, this tractate is philosophically significant to those philosophers who take St. 1 I am obliged to Professor Ralph Mcinerny for awakening my interest in Boethius and for his suggestion that the De Hebdomadibus would repay careful study. 2 All references are to the H. F. Stewart and E. K. Rand edition of The Theological Traotates and The Consolation of Philosophy, in the Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1973). 419 420 GERARD CASEY Thomas as their inspiration since it appears that St. Thomas's existence/essence distinction is adumbrated here. I shall begin my explication by giving a brief overview of the main lines of the tractate. Then I shall lay out the arguments contained in the statement and resolution of the dilemma which Boethius constructs, indicating (by means of Roman numerals in parentheses) where I think particular axioms are meant to apply. Finally, I shall display the axioms as perspicuously as possible and comment on them. Overview The ground plan of the De H ebdomadibus is as follows. It begins with a brief introduction which contains the nine axioms. Then the problem to be considered is outlined in the form of the following dilemma. Things which are are good. This is the basic assumption which will generate the dilemma. Things which are good are so either by virtue of their substance or by participation. If they are good by virtue of their substance then, since God is the only substantial good, we arrive at an impious conclusion: we identify creatures with their Creator. lf they are good by participation then we generate a contradiction: things do and do not tend toward the good. Therefore, the conclusion must be that things which are are not good, which manifestly contradicts the basic assumption. Boethius's solution to the dilemma makes use of a thought-experiment. Abstracting from the first good he distinguishes locutions such as ' to be ' from locutions such as ' to be good.' On the basis of this distinction he is led to conclude that goodness is either a property of things or a principle of things. Re-introducing the notion of the first good, he notes that it is good by virtue of its very being. Secondary goods are also good by virtue of their being but only because that being derives from the will of the first good. Boethius cautions us against likening the being of particular things to the being of the first good and concludes the tractate by considering and refuting two objections to his solution. THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS 421 The theme of the tractate is the problem of how substances can be good in virtue of their being without, at the same time, being substantial goods. Boethius is moved to deal with this particular problem by the appeal of a correspondent who urges him to elaborate on his hints towards a solution of this obscure question. Boethius warns his friends not to object to the obscurities resulting from brevity, remarking gnostically that such obscurity will be penetrated only by those worthy of penetrating it. To ensure the requisite obfuscation Boethius supplies us with a do-it-yourself argument kit in the form of nine axioms. "The intelligent interpreter," Boethius tells us "will supply the arguments to each point." 3 At the outset then it seems clear that it will be one of the reader's tasks to discern the use being made of the axioms in the subsequent discussion. The Problem I 1. Everything that is tends to the good 2. Everything tends to its like 3. Things which tend to the good are themselves good 4. Therefore, things which are are good Step 1 in this argument derives d'rom the common opinion of the learned. Step 2 has a similar ancestry. (Axiom IX) Step 3 is a particular application of Step 2, and Step 4, the conclusion, derives from Steps 1 and 3 together. Now that he has established the goodness of things which exist, Boethius goes on to consider how this is so. Things which are good are so either by participation or by virtue of their substance. These alternatives Boethius seems to consider to be both mutually exclusive and universally exhaustive. He proceeds to treat of each in turn. Things which are good are so by participation II 1. All things are good by participation s Boethius, De H ebdomadibus, 53-55. GERARD CASEY If all things are good by participation they are in no way good in themselves 3. All things are in no way good in themselves 4. All things do not tend to the good 5. All things do, and do not, tend to the good 6. Therefore, all things are not good by participation Q. Step 1 is the overall assumption of argument II. Step 2 is, presumably, a self-evident truth. 4 Step 3 derives from Steps 1 and 2 by modus ponens. Step 4 is derived by modus tollens from Steps 3 and I/3 (suitably recast in hypothetical form) . Step 5 is merely the conjunction of Step 4 and Step I/l, and the conclusion, Step 6, is derived from Steps 1 through 5 by reductio ad absurdum. With the elimination of the possibility of goodness by participation it seems as if all things must be good by virtue of their substance. Things which are good are so by virtue of their substance III 1. All things are good by virtue of their substance 2. If all things are good by virtue of their substance then the particular being of all things is good 3. The particular being of all things is good 4. If the particular being of all things is good then, if all things are good by virtue of their substance, they are like the first good 5. If all things are good by virtue of their substance they are like the first good 4 There is a difference between merely being something in a qualified way and being something in an essential way or in one's very substance. In other words, there is a distinction between the substance of a thing and the qualities which it participates. This implies, for Boethius, that if a thing is good by participation, then goodness does not penetrate its inmost structure. The substantial reality of a thing-its essence and existence-differs from its accidental qualities. Charles Fay, "Boethius' Theory of Goodness and Being," in James Collins, ed., Readin_qs in Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, (Westminster, Md: Newman Press, 1960), p. 171. THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS 49W 6. All things are like the first good 7. If anything is like the first good it is the first good 8. All things are the first good 9. Therefore, all things are not good by virtue of their substance Step I is the overall assumption of this argument. Step 2 is a self-evident assumption. Step 3 derives from Steps I and 2 by modus ponens. Step 4 is another self-evident assumption. Step 5 derives from Steps 3 and 4 by modus ponens. Step 6 derives from Steps I and 5 by modus ponens. Step 7 is yet another self-evident assumption. Step 8 derives from Steps 6 and 7 by modus ponens and is, as Boethius puts it, " an impious assertion." Step 9, the conclusion, derives from Steps I through 8 by reductio ad absurdum. Our basic assumption was that all things that are are good. But, as we have just seen, they cannot be so either by participation or by virtue of their substance. And since these seem to be the only possible alternatives we are faced with a dilemma. How are we to overcome it? The Solution Mentally separating that which is not actually separable, we remove from our minds the presence of the first good. Now, supposing that all things that exist are good, we ask ourselves how this could be so if they did not derive from the first good. According to Boethius we notice immediately that it is one thing for existent things to be good and quite another thing for them to be. (Axiom V) To show us that this is indeed the case, he considers a substance which is white, round, heavy and good. If the substance were not different from its roundness, heaviness, whiteness and goodness, then the identification of the substance with its attributes would lead us to identify the attributes with one another and this, as Boethius says, is " contrary to nature." 5 What about the suggestion that good 5 Boethius, De Hebdomadibus, 105-106. GERARD CASEY things might be nothing else but good, i.e. possessing only the quality of goodness? If this were the caise then, according to Boethius, we might more properly consider them (or rather it) to be the principle of things rather than things (or a thing) . (Axiom IV) There is only one thing that is simply good and we have prescinded from that. We can conclude from this that while things separated from the first good may be good, their very being will not be good. Now comes the crucial passage: But since they are not simple, they could not even exist at all unless that which is the one sole good had willed them to exist. They are called good simply because their existence has derived from the will of the good. For the first good, since it exists, is good in virtue of its existence; but the secondary good, since it has derived from that whose existence is itself good, is itself also good. 6 (Axioms IV, VII & VIII) So, the existence of good things depends on the will of the first good. In the case of the first good, its being and goodness are identical. Just as the being of particular things is derived from the will of the first good, so too is the goodness attached to that being. We might erroneously conclude from this fact that particular things are like the first good because they too are good in virtue of their substance. There is, however, a difference. The goodness of the being of particular things is not good under all circumstances but is so simply because of its derivation from the will of the first good. The being of the first good is good under all circumstances since it is simply good. So, the particular being of things is good but it is not like the being of the first good since the one derives from the other. (Axioms IV &VI) Therefore, the first good being removed from these things by a mental process, these things, though they might be good, yet could not be good in virtue of their existence, and since they could not actually have existed unless that which is truly good had produced them, therefore their existence is good and yet that which has derived from the substantial good is not like its source. 7 a Boethius, De Hebdomabidus, 117-125. 7 Boethius, De Hebdomadibus, 140-146. THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS 4Q5 If things did not derive their being from the will of the :first good it :is still possible that they could be good (perhaps, e.g. by participation) but their very being could not be good. Since particular beings cannot be separated from the first good except by a mental process we may conclude that: 1. all things depend for their being on the will of the good Q. the being of all things is good 3. although the being of all things is derived form the will of the first good all things are not thereby like it since there is nothing like it save itself. Boethius wants to salvage the transcendental character of goodness without allowing it to usurp the unique postion of the first good. The derivation of the being of all things from the will of the first good establishes the goodness of particular things and, at the same time, establishes an essential difference between the being of particular things and the being of the first good. Boethius concludes the tractate by considering and refuting some objections. 0 bjection # 1 If things which are good are so by virtue of their being, why are they not, say, white by virtue of their being? Response Boethius points to the difference between accidental and substantial predication. To be is one thing, to be white is quite another. (Axiom V) That from which things derive their being is good by its very nature but it is not white. It accords with the will of the first good that things be good by virtue of their being but not white by virtue of their being. If something is white then it is so because it was willed to be so by someone who is not himself essentially white. 426 GERARD CASEY Objection #2 Why then is not everything just? (And here, unlike the response to the previous objection, we surely do not want to claim that God is not just!) Response In order to reply to his objection, Boethius distinguishes between essence and action. Goodness is a characteristic of what someone is: justice is a characteristic of what someone does. While being and action are one and the same thing in God they cannot be equated in his creatures. We are not simply beings. Our being is not identical with our actions so we are good by virtue of our being but we are not just by virtue of our being. (Axioms IV, VII & VIII) The Axioms How are we to understand the axioms that Boethius presents to us? Are they merely a set of random principles which he kept by him on his desk for use in the writing of theological tractates? Or are they something more than that? Is there, for example, some order or systematic connection between them such as to render them especially suitable for the task in hand? If we rely naively on Boethius's statement that he is going to proceed in a mathematical manner we might be betrayed by our twentieth-century sophistication into treating the axioms as if they were constituents of a modern axiomatic system. As such we would expect them to be logically independent of one another and more or less equally fundamental to the system. On inspection, however, the axioms turn out to be concerned with a very few topics, namely, being, that which is, simplicity and complexity. Axioms II-VIII appear to contain three central theses plus some commentary on them, while the less centrally important axioms I and IX have ancillary functions. THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS 427 Axioms I A common conception of the mind is defined as " a statement which anyone accepts as soon as he hears it." 8 Two types of these are distinguished: one which is obvious to all men; and the other which is obvious only to the learned. Axioms II-VIII Basic Thesis 1 Esse and id quod est are different (II) Comment A (II) Esse is not yet, whereas id quad est is as soon as it receives the form which gives it being. Comment B (Ill) Esse does not participate in anything in any way, whereas id quad est can participate in something. Comment C (IV) Esse cannot possess anything outside itself, whereas id quad est can. Basic Thesis 2 Merely to be something and to be something in virtue of existence are different (V) Comment A (V) To be something signifies accident, whereas to be something in virtue of existence signifies substance. Comment B (VI) To be something requires accidentals participation, whereas to be something in virtue of existence requires substantial participation. s Boethius, De Hebdomadibus, 18-19. GERARD CASEY Comment C (VI) Accidental participation presupposes substantial participation. Bame Thesis 3 Simple things and composite things are different 9 Comment A (VII & VIII) In simple things esse and id quad est are unified, whereas m composite things esse is one thing and id quad est another. Axiom IX The principle contained in this axiom simply states the identity of natures of any two things one of which seeks the other. Comments on the Axioms Axiom I This first axiom is obviously procedural. It indicates that the remaining eight axioms are to be understood as common conceptions of the mind of the kind intelligible only to the learned. The presentation of such recondite theses is in keeping with the remarks Boethius makes in the introduction to the tractate to the effect that such obscure brevity has the immeasurable advantage of communicating one's meaning only to those worthy of receiving it. Axioms II-VIII Basic Thesis 1. Esse and id quad est are different As James Collins remarks" Among the outstanding philosophical difficulties presented by the Opuscula Sacra is the determination of the exact meaning for Boethius of the binary of esse and id quod est." 1 ° For P. Duhem, quad est signifies the 9 This thesis is not explicitly stated as such in the text. However, given the syntactical format of the two previous basic theses I do not think it too far-fetched to suppose that this is what Boethius had in mind. 10 James Collins, " Progress and Problem in the Reassessment of Boethius,'' The Modern Schoolman Vol. XXIII, no. 1, (1945), 1-23. In this section I THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS really existing concrete thing whereas esse signifies the specific nature or form common to all individuals in the same species. Roland-Gosselin, on the other hand, gives an essentially essentialistic account of the distinction. For him quad est signifies total essence whereas esse is a constitutive part of that essence. According to H. Brosch, quad est signifies the concrete essence while quo est (or esse) signifies the abstract or formal essence. Brosch also alerts us to the fact that Latin philosophical terminology of the period was neither firmly fixed nor unequivocal. He is not the only person to sound such a warning note. J. de Vries points out that if Boethius was not aware of the distinction between essence and existence then he could hardly have intended esse to signify either meaning of the term to the exclusion of the other. In agreement with de Vries, V. Schurr claims that for Boethius esse sometimes means essence, sometimes existence, with the essential connotation taking precedence on most occasions of use. He points to the later sections of the De Hebdomadibus as one place where the existential use is almost surely to be located. 11 (It will be remembered that this is the section of the tractate in which Boethius remarks on the of good things from the will of the first good.) To C. Fay, esse sometimes signifies form, sometimes essence, and sometimes actual existence. Fay agrees with Schurr in claiming that towards the end of the De Hebdomadibus esse takes on an existential connotation. 12 In am following very closely Collins' historical survey of the various interpretations which have been given to this crucial distinction. Precise references to the authors mentioned may be found in his article. See also Sr. H. V. Clare, "Whether Everything That is, Is Good: Marginal Notes on St. Thomas's Exposition of Boethius's De Hebdomadibus," Laval Theologique et Philosophique Vol. III, no. 1, (1947), 66-76; Vol. III, no. 2, (1947), 177194; Vol. V, no. 1, 1949), 119-140. 11 Cf. also Boethius, De Trinitate, 20ff. 12 According to Fay, this section of the Tractate contains Boethius's central insight, which is that since creatures are not simple, they could not in any way exist unless that which is solely good had willed them to be. Creatures are good in their existence inasmuch as their existence proceeds from the will of the first good, which is good in what it is. (Fay, p. 170) 430 GERARD CASEY view of all this it is difficult not to agree with F. Sassen's suggestion that we adopt the neutral term ' being ' as the translation for esse so as to avoid attributing to Boethius a terminological precision not warranted by the fluid state of seventh century Latin philosophical terminology. Comment A. For esse is not yet but quod est is as soon as it has received the form which gives it being. According to St. Thomas Aquinas all three comments on Basic Thesis I point to a difference in the mode of signification of the two terms, esse and quod est. Nor is all this to be referred to existent things themselves, of which he has not yet spoken. He is here referring to a way of thinking or to intention. Moreover by esse, one meaning is signified; by id quad est, another is signified, just as ' to run ' signifies something different from what 'that which runs' signifies; for 'running' and ' being ' signify abstract concepts such as whiteness whereas 'that which is ' (quad est) , i.e. being (ens) and running (currens), signify concrete realities, as white describes a concrete reality.13 Esse and quod est signify the same thing but they do so in different ways: quod est signifies concretely and esse signifies abstractly. Esse is that by which quod est exists: in itself, it cannot be said to exist. CommentB. Quod est can participate in something, but ipsum esse does not participate in any way in anything. lpsum esse cannot participate in anything for the simple reason that only what already is can participate and, as we know from Comment A, ipsum esse is not yet. It is apparent that the 1s St. Thomas Aquinas, "In Librum Boetei De Hebdomadibus Exposito," which can be found as Opuscula LXII in Sanctii Thomae Aquinatis, Opef\ci, Omnia, Tomus XVIII, (New York: Musurgia Publishers, 1948) . I have availed myself of a partial translation of St. Thomas' commentary which is to be found in Mary T. Clark, An Aquinas Reader (London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1972), 51-54. THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS 431 only sense of 'participation ' entertained here is the participation by a previously existing substance in an accidental form. In his commentary, St. Thomas, having distinguished three types of participation, has this to say: I shall pass however to the third way of participating, since It IS impossible according to the first two ways for absolute esse to participate in anything; for it cannot participate in the way that matter participates in form or accident participates in a subject because, as was said, esse itself signifies something apart. Nor can it participate as particular participates in a universal, for those things spoken of as a part can participate in something as whiteness in colour, but being itself (ipsum esse) is present in all things: whence others participate in it but it does not participate in anything else. But that-which-is, a being (ens), although this is a most common expression, is nevertheless referring to something concrete and so it participates in being itself (ipsum esse) not as the more common is participated in by the less common, but it participates in ipsum esse as the concrete participates in the abstract. 14 CommentC. Quad est can possess something besides what it is itself. But ipsum esse has no admixture of aught besides itself. Since ipsum esse is not yet, and since only what already is can participate, then it follows that ipsum esse cannot possess anything beside itself. In general, we cannot attribute to something abstractly signified anything other than that which is part of that thing so signified. For example: white, qua white, is colored but not soft or triangular; man, qua man, is rational, but not tall or beautiful.1-5 14 St. Thomas Aquinas, "In Librum Boetii De Hebdomadibus Expositio." De Trinitate, II, 43-41: ... forms cannot be substrates. For if humanity, like other forms, is a substrate for accidents, it does not receive accidents through the fact that it exists, but through the fact that matter is subjected to it. For when the matter which is subject to humanity receives any accident, humanity itself seems to receive it. But form which is without matter will not be able to be a substrate, nor indeed to be in matter, else it would not be a form but an image. 15 Cf. Boethius, 432 GERARD CASEY Basic Thesis 2. Merely to be something and to be something m virtue of existence are different. This thesis distinguishes between being something in a qualified manner and being something essentially, between quad esse simpliciter and id quod est aliquid.16 Comment A. To be something signifies an accident, to be something in virtue of existence signifies substance. The most obvious manifestation of the difference between being something and being something in virtue of existence is to be found in the modes of existence of substance and accident. A substance is a thing signified in an unqualified manner; an accident is what is signified by a qualification. CommentB. Everything that is participates in esse in order to exist but it participates in something else in order to be something. This comment introduces a broader notion of participation than was previously entertained. (Axiom III) 17 CommentC. Quod est participates in esse in order to be but it exists in order to participate in something else. This comment points out that substantial participation is presupposed by accidental participation. This correlates with what was said about participation in Axiom III. There it was noted that ipsum esse could not participate in any way, for only what already is (i.e. only what already participates (broad sense) in 16 See note 4 above. has this to say: "Here, participation is used in the broad sense as equivalent to any reception, and not in the strict sense as the reception of a determination extraneous to the original form or essence of a thing." (Fay, 11 Fay p. 171) THE DE HEBDOMADIBUS IN THE LIGHT OF ST. THOMAS substantial form) can participate form. 18 433 (narrow sense) in accidental Basic Thesis 3. Simple things and composite things are different. 19 Comment A. Every simple thing possesses as a unity its esse and its id quad est, while in every composite thing esse is one thing and id qwod est another According to St. Thomas, it is at this point that Boethius moves from the intentional to the real order: We should reflect that what was previously said about the difference between esse and id quod est was according to the mode of knowing; here, however, he indicates how it is applied to things. First, he shows this in regard to composite things; second, in regard to simple things such as: in every simple thing its esse and its id quod est are one. Therefore, we must consider that just as esse and id quod est differ in simple things as mental intentions, so in composite things they really differ. 20 In simple being the esse and the quad est are unified, i.e., that by which the simple being is and that which the simple being is are one and the same. There is obviously only one such Being despite the inference which might be drawn from the manner in which Boethius expresses himself in axiom VII. (Angels, though simpler than we, in that they are not com1s Professor RaJph Mcinerny warns us against making the blunder of thinking that we are here dealing with three distinct participations: It would of course be absurd to suppose that there are three participa· tions being distinguished here: participation in ipsum esse, participa· tion in esse substantiale, participation in esse aliquid. . . . Esse Commune is immediately divided into esse substantiale and esse acoidentale, per prius et posterius; these are not species of a generic esse. Rather, the one is esse simpliciter, the other esse secundum quid. (Mcinerny, 237-238) Ralph Mcinerny, "Boethius and St. Thomas Aquinas," Revista di Filosophia neo·scolastica, (Anno LXVI 1974), Fasc. II-IV, 219-245. 19 See note 9 above. 20 St. Thomas Aquinas, "In Libro Boetii De Hebdomadibus Expositio." 434 GERARD CASEY posed of matter and form, are nevertheless not entirely simple since their essence and existence are not identical.) Composite beings do not have that by which they are identical with that which they are: that by which they are is something other than they possess in themselves. The philosophical significance of the tractate is three-folq First in its treatment of the relationship between being and goodness, it adumbrates the high mediaeval notion of the transcendentals. Second, it provides a clear example of a particular philosophical methodology in action. Boethius has a firm grip on a small set of basic metaphysical principles. A specific problem is analyzed with an eye to the eventual application of these principles. The principles are indeed applied and the problem is solved. It is clear from the tractate that Boethius is conscious of his modus operandi. Neither the particular set of axioms employed, nor the use made of them, is in any way accidental. The procedure is not limited in use to the particular problem under discussion. Finally, even if the tractate were no more than a source of St. Thomas's real distinction, it would deserve our attention. But it is more than that. It provides us with a clear example of early Latin philosophical method (as we have seen) and, equally importantly, an example of an attempt to forge philosophically sensitive terminology from recalcitrant linguistic material. As such it reminds us of the fluid and nuanced character of all philosophical terminology and it should send us back to a study of St. Thomas's own works with a renewed interest in discovering what St. Thomas himself has to say when the layers of exposition and interpretation are stripped away. GERARD CASEY University College Dublin THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS: A Contribution to Recent Discussion* S T. THOMAS AQUINAS accepted and consistently defended Boethius' definition of person: "persona est substantia individua rationalis naturae." St. Thomas' analysis of this definition necessarily involves metaphysical questions because of the implications of the terms " substance" and " nature" and moreover it manifests the inescapahle imprint of the theological problematics which surrounded the issue (e.g. the Trinity and the hypostatic union). Both of these influences, metaphysical and theological, have engendered problems of interpretation and criticism. Contemporary discussions of person largely either continue the scholastic controversies or adopt a modern perspective from which to expose apparent contradictions in St. Thomas' doctrine. The purpose of this article will be limited to a consideration of the metaphysical problems concerning the relationship between individual substance, universal, nature, and existence. It is hoped that such a clarification will resolve not only the neoscholastic controversies, but also some of the contemporary problems. I. BOETHIUS' DEFINITION OF PERSON AND ST. THOMAS' EXPLANATION A. BOETHIUS' DEFINITION Boethius develops his definition of person in the Liber contra Eutychen et N estorium after a careful consideration of na* I have to thank cordially Father Brian Shanley, 0.P. for having revised completely this English version, devoting much time and energy to fit the text and the footnotes to the style of The Thomist. He adapted the version in good style and verified the Latin quotations. 435 436 HORST SEIDL ture and substance. 1 In the first chapter he sets out to define nature and discovers four possible meanings. The first and broadest definition, embracing both substances and accidents, describes nature as belonging to all things which by their being can be in some way or another be comprehended by reason: "natura est earum rermn quae, cum sint, quoquo modo intellectu capi possunt." A second definition, comprising substances alone both corporeal and incorporeal, describes nature as anything that can effect or suffer something: " natura est vel quod facere vel quod pati possit." A third sense, taken from the Aristotelian analysis of the motion of natural substances, describes nature as the immanent principle of movement: "natura est motus principium per se et non per accidens." Finally, nature can also refer to the formal cause which provides the specific difference: " natura est unam quamque rem informans specifica differentia" (cf. ST Ia. 29, I ad 4). It is this last sense which is most important. In sum, "nature" is a broad term encompassing both composite beings and their causes. Boethius continues in chapter two by first narrowing the relevant sense of nature to substances (thus excluding accidents) and then presenting a complete division of substances. The major distinction is between corporeal substances and incorporeal substances. Corporeal subdivides further into inanimate and animate, with animate dividing. into insensitive and sensitive and the latter dividing finally into irrational and rational. Incorporeal subdivides into rational and irrational (the life-principle of animals), with rational incorporeal substances being further distinguished into those that are immutable by nature (the Creator) and those that are not so by nature (the human soul and angels) but may become so by virtue of the immutable substance. Boethius then argues that person cannot be affirmed of inanimate beings or irrational animals. A 1 All citations from Boethius are taken from the Loeb text in Boethius: Theological Tractates and the Consolation of Philosophy, ed. H. F. Stewart and E. K. Rand (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1918). THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 437 final distinction of :substance into universal and particular leads to the conclusion that person must refer to an individual. Thus the background is set for the definition of person which opens the third chapter: " naturae rationalis individua substantia." Person must be an individual substance of a certain nature, namely rational, which nature accounts for the form or specific difference of the particular substance (the fourth meaning of chapter 1) . The connection of this definition with Aristotle's definition of man as a rational animal is unmistakable. It should also be noted that this definition of person is applicable not only to man, in whom the rational nature is not identical with his substance, but also to the angels and the three divine Persons whose substance is identical with their nature. Boethius realizes that he needs to correlate his definitions with established Greek terminology in order to clarify his meaning, especially concerning the difference between nature and person. The Latin persona corresponds historically to the Greek prosopon (the dramatic character assumed by an actor wearing a mask; famous individuals in their public presentations). Philosophica1ly, however, persona corresponds to the Greek hypostasis 2 (individual substance) and the Latin sub2 See the investigation of hypostasis by H. Dorrie in: Hypostasis, Wort- und Bedeutungsgeschichte (Mtinchen, 1976). According to this analysis, hypostasis does not yet occur in Aristotle in a philosophical sense ( p. 36, n. 130). Substantia as a translation of hypostasis in the sense of substance in the first category can be found first in Marius Victorinus' Rhetoric [Halen], pp. 211, 27 (p. 38, n. 141). According to Dorrie, the philosophical meanings of hypostasis developed historically from physical and medical ones, especially from sediments in fluids (e.g. the urine). Philosophical meanings came into existence only from the Stoics and the Peripatetics onward. Only in Plotinus does it mean the existence of immaterial substances. It seems to me, however, that Dorrie fails to consider adequately the non-physical prephilosophical meanings. According to Liddell-Scott (ninth edition, 1953), already in the fifth century hyphistanai means to place or set under, support, lay as a foundation; further, it also means to bring to a halt, with hyphistathai as to stand under as a support. Correspondingly hypostasis means also: standing under or supporting and substance or reality as opposed to mere semblance. This latter meaning was not originally limited to the coming-to-appearance of the precipitate of sediments and was still known to St. Thomas ( p. 22, n. 56) : "substantia enim so let dici prima inchoatio cuiuscumque rei" (ST Ila-Hae. 4, 1). 438 HORST SEIDL sta,ntia. Boethius defines hypostasis or substantia which is applied to the individual and includes the accidents as opposed to the essence, ousia, which excludes the accidents and to the ousiosios or subsistentia which applies to the substance in universali (the genus or species) . The greek term ousia, in La.tin: essentia, has in fact two meanmgs: I. as essence, nature, excluding the accidents, and 2. a·s substance, the universal (genus, species) as well as the individual, including the accidents, which is expressed more precisely by hypostaris (" under-lying " the accidents, i.e. supporting their being) . Applying these distinctions to man, Boethius reasons: man has essentia or ousia because he is; he is subsistentia or ousiosis because he is not an accident in a subject; he is substantia or hypostasis because he is such a subject of accidents and an individual, other then subsistentia or ousiosis; and he is a persona or prosopon because he is a rational individual. Boethius sums up his discussion in chapter 4 by stating that the nature is the specific property of any substance, while person is the individual substance of a rational nature 3 "natura est cuiuslibet substantiae specificata proprietas; persona vero ra.tionabilis naturae individua substantia." The Boethius distinctions serve as the basis for St. Thomas' discussion of person in the Summa Theologiae. B. ST. THOMAS' EXPLANATION OF BOETHIUS' DEFINITION IN ST Ia. 29 4 St. Thomas appropriates the Boethian definition in his treatment of the Divine Persons and begin with an explanation of the meaning of person in article 1: will be explained by Scholastics 3 Later, as we shall see, the distinction like Capreolus in the same way: Substance is the being which possesses a certain nature, while the nature is possessed by the substance. 4 This article cannot consider all the relevant passages in St. Thomas. See also I Sent. 25, I, 1 and 23, 1, I; II Sent. 3, 1, 2 and II, 1, 2ad 4; BOG III, 128, 130 and IV, 26, 52; and De Pot 9, 2 and 8, 4 ad 5. THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 439 Respondeo dicendum quod, licet universale et particulare inveniantur in omnibus generi, tamen speciali quodam modo individuum invenitur in genere substantiae. Substantia eni mindividuatur per seipsam, sed accidentia individuantur per subiectum quod est substantia: dicitur enim haec albedo inquantum est in subiecto. Uncle etiam convenienter individua substantiae habent aliquod speciale nomen prae aliis: dicuntur enim hypostaseis, vel primae substantiae. Sed adhuc quodam specialiori et perfectiori modo invenitur particulare et individuum in substantiis rationalibus, quae habent dominium sui actus, et non solum aguntur, sicut alia, sed per se agunt: actiones autem in singularibus sunt. Et ideo etiam inter ceteras substantias quoddam speciale nomen habent singularia rationalis naturae. Et hoc nomen est persona. Et ideo in praedicta definitione personae ponitur substantia individua, inquantum significat singulare in genere substantiae: additur autem rationalis naturae, inquantum significat singulare in rationalibus substantiis. 5 The reply considers successively the two components of the definition: the genus and the specific difference. In the first step the individual in the category of substance is separated from the individual in the other categories (accidents). The second step separates the rational individual substance from the non-rational (within the category of substance). Rational substances are superior because they act by their own initiative, a perfection which is a consequence of their rational nature. Action follows upon being and it is the rational soul which is the a.ct principle or formal cause (also efficient and final) of the free initiative in action. Thomas further clarifies the definition in the responses to the objections. He notes that although the individual as such is not definable, individual substance can stand as the genus insofar as it signifies not this or that individual (e.g. Socrates), hut rather as it signifies the common feature of individual primary substantial being (subsistence) as such. In the second response he explains that since the supposit as individual substance is the basis of person, the human nature of Christ is not the principle of a human person in Him because it has 5 All citations from the Summa Theologiae will be from the Marietti edition of the Leonine text. 440 HORST SEIDL been assumed by a divine being. In the fifth response he notes that the separated soul does not merit the name " person " (nor did it when it was united to the body) because although it subsists per se, nevertheless it does not have complete subsistence.6 In sum, the basis of the person (the genus of the definition) is the individual substance of man which exists substantially or subsists per se. The constitutive element of person (the specific difference is the rational nature by which the human individual is a person. II. METAPHYSICAL REMARKS ON THE PROBLEMS AR.ISING FROM THE CLASSICAL DEFINITION OF PERSON The schola.stic controversies concerning the meaning of person have been heavily influenced by the theological problem of why Christ has a human nature but is not a human person. What is it that is wanting in the human nature of Christ such that He is not a human person? Or, to focus the issue more sharply, what has to be added to the human nature in order to constitute it as a suppositum, individuum, or person? The divergent responses given to this question are largely derivative from a more fundamental conflict concerning the metaphysical distinction between nature or essence and esse.7 The Scotistic position denies the real distinction of essence and esse and maintains instead that existence is a direct consequence of the nature; it asserts that the human nature of Christ lacks a certain closure because it is open to assumption by the Word. Suarez, while maintaining that esse is really distinct 6 In ST Ia 75, 2, ad 1 St. Thomas indicates two criteria for the individuum and its incommunicabilitas: the first is subsistence as such and the second is perfection as a totum completum. The separated soul fulfills the first since it can subsist apart from the body. But it cannot fulfill the second condition since it retains the possibility of connection with the body (unibilitas). 7 See the survey of the controversies in I. Schweizer M.S.: Person und hypostatische Union bei Thomas v. Aquin (Fribourg, 1957). THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 441 from essence, nevertheless conceives of esse as the completing moment of the nature such that true personhood requires that the human nature be individualized and completed by its own act of existence. The Thomist position defends the real distinction of essie and essence such that esse is seen as the ultimate actuality of a nature which is potential to esse or existence while complete in its own formal order. Hence some Thomists have tried to locate the constitutive element of person in the rational individual's existence. 8 In recent times, U. Degl' Innocenti has vigorously revived the thesis that existence is the decisive or constitutive element of person and has cited texts from St. Thomas, Capreolus, and Cajetan to buttress his position. 9 I disagree with this position and propose to analyze his argumentation and especially his textual evidence in order to clarify the issue. Being his intention to justify the inclusion of existence in the definition of person or supposit, Degl' Innocenti begins his investigation with an apparently dissentrient text in Quodlibet. II, 2, 2 (4) which asserts that " esse is not part of the meaning of supposit." The s Among NeoThomists there is uncertainty whether Capreolus (as according to Cajetan) was the first to distinguish between the subsistence of the nature and the existence of the individual such that the complete subsistence of the nature with individual existence is the aonstitutivum formale of person. Normally the positions on this question are seen to fall into three families based on their resolution of the Christological question. The first, the Modus Theory, holds that the human nature of Christ has an incomplete modus subsistendi. The second, the Union Theory, holds that the lack of human personality in Christ is due to the connection of His human nature with the Word. The third, the Existence Theory, holds that the human nature of Christ is not also a person because it has no human existence but rather subsists by the divine existence. Schweizer asserts that these are the only possible kinds of solutions to the Christological problem. He properly categorizes the position of Jacques Maritain in the Les degres du savoir (p. 847) as a Modus Theory approach because Maritain argues that the human nature is open to several possible existences to which it is indifferent. Schweizer notes: "Erst wenn eine substantielle Natur ihren Modus der Abgeschlossenheit erhalten habe, sei sie auf ihre eigene Existenz hin determiniert." ( p. 39) 9 U. Degl' Innocenti, ll problema della person nel pensiero di S. Tommaso (Rome, 1967). 442 HORST SEIDL context of the remark is a discussion of the difference between nature and supposit in the angels. Since the difference cannot be due to a material principle, as is the case in material substances, it must be due to the esse which belongs more to the supposit than to the nature. Although the esse itself does not belong to the concept of the supposit, nevertheless it pertains to it: "Iicet ipsum esse non sit de ratione suppositi, quia tamen pertinet ad suppositum et non est de rationae naturae." 10 Degl' Innocenti solves the problem which this text poses for his thesis by distinguishing two different meanings for supposi,tum in the sentence. In the first clause, governed by licet, suppoS'itum includes the esse only indirectly; here the suppoS'itum is the individual nature to which esse is a:dded extrinsically and so is designated only connotatively (connotative or in obliquo) . But in the second clause, governed by tamen, the suppositum is the composite of nature and esse and so esse is included in the concept or definition. 11 This interpretation, however, seems untenable. First, it is highly unlikely that a single word should bear two different meanings in one and the same sentence. Secondly, according to St. Thomas (and Aristotle), existence is not part of the definition of anything but rather presupposed; therefore existence is only designated connotatively. While it is true that St. Thomas holds that immaterial substances are composed of essence and esse, in contrast to material substances composed of matter and form, nevertheless this composition is the very condition of any created nature's being and not a. part of its definition. Thirdly, Degl'Innocenti himself concedes that St. Thomas never explicitly distinguishes between two such senses of suppoS'itum. 12 10 Marietti edition, ed. Spiazzi (Rome, 1956). pp. 16-18. 12 Nevertheless, Degl' Innocenti believes that St. Thomas himself held that esse is the constitutive feature of person. He cites ST IIIa. 19, 1 ad 4 as evidence: "esse pertinet ad ipsam constitutionem personae." But this passage means the same thing as the "esse pertinet ad suppositum" of the Quodlibetal text. The issue in the Summa text is the distinction between 11 Degl' Innocenti, THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 443 In defense of his interpretation, however, Degl' Innocenti cites Capreolus and Cajetan as explicitly distinguishing these two senses of suppositum. In a passage in the Defensiones, Capreolus mentions two possible meanings of persona or suppositum: according to the first, suppositum is said denominatively of the individual which subsists per se; according to the second, suppositum is said formally of the composite of the individual and the being whereby it subsists. 13 According to Degl' Innocenti, this passage contains the crucial articulation (" distinzione capitale ") of Capreolus' interpretation of St. Thomas' concept of person because in the second or formal meaning of suppositum existence functions as the constitutive feature of person. 14 Yet Degl' lnnocenti's interpretation of Capreolus is erroneous because he fails to take adequate account of the context. Capreolus is defending his conclusion that Christ did not assume a human person or created supposit against five objections from Aureolus. The fourth objection claims that if personality adds something positively real to the nature, as Capreolus claims, then seven inconsistencies (inconvenientia) would arise. The passage in question is part of Capreolus' reply to the sixth problem: that the nature underlying the reality would appear more as the supposit than the composit of the nature and that reality (sc. being, subsistence) .15 Capreolus answers that the supposit of material things is neither an individualized nature nor the composite of nature and esse. action and being which will be considered below. The "esse completum et personale " is referred to the person as a whole complete supposit of which the nature is the constitutive part. 13 The passage reads: " Illa etiam persona, vel suppositum, potest dici dupliciter: primo modo, denominative, et sic suppositum dicitur illud individuum quod per se subsistit; secundo modo, formale, et sic suppositum dicitur compositum ex tali individuo et ex sua per se subsistentia." Defensiones Theologiae Divi Thomae Aquinatis, ed. Paban Pegues (Turin, 19001904) V: p. llOb. As will be seen, however, this passage is misleading if it is not read in con text. 14 Degl' Innocenti, pp. 35-36, n. 7. 15 Defensiones, p. 91. 444 HORST SEIDL Rather, the supposit is something intermediate: the individual nature standing under such esse. In this way the individual adds something to the nature (sc. individual principles, accidents) while the supposit adds something to the individual (sc. being or subsistence) .16 Further, the supposit is not a composition of nature and esse (" compositio ex his") , but rather a composition with these (" compositio cum his ") so that it is a unity rather than some third thing. The composite of the individual nature and its esse (the "aggregatum ") is not fittingly designated the supposit unless perhaps we distinguish" (nisi forte distinguamus) between the denominative designation of supposit (as individuum) and the formal designation whereby the supposit would be the composition of nature and esse. 17 Thus Capreolus makes this distinction only as an ad hoc hypothetical possibility (to a very special objection of Aureolus) after clearly stating his own position that the supposit is the individual nature standing under its esse (" individuum naturae stans sub tali esse ") and that it is no composition out of nature and esse. For Capreo]us, esse is a " formal aspect " of the whole supposit and is designated only " per modum connotati" or " in obliquo." 18 16 "Nos enim dicimus quod natura in rebus materialibus sit suppositum, nee quod compositum ex natura et ex esse sit suppositum; sed quod aliquid medium est suppositum, scilicet individuum naturae stans sub tali esse. In talibus enim individuum addit supra naturam, et suppositum supra individuum." (p. llOa). The additions mentioned in the sentence correspond to those made by Thomas in the Quodlibet text. 11 "Et inducit illa ad ostendenum quomodo angelus componitur ex essentia sua et ex esse suo; quae compositio magis proprie dicitur compositio cum his, quam compositio ex his. Dico ergo quod, quia ex natura individuata et ex esse non resultat aliquod tertium vere unum; ideo aggregatum illud non proprie dicitur persona; nisi forte distinguamus, sicut de albo, quod album est duplex, scilicet denominativum et formale." (p. llOb) What follows is the text cited above in n. 13 which must be read within this context. 1s ". . . quod St. Thomas intellexit personalitatem addere aliquid positivum supra naturam rationalem et individuum naturae rationalis ( sc. esse actu) . . . quia esse sic est de ratione suppositi quod non est pars illius nee intrat eius essentiam, sed se habet per modum connotati et importatur in obliquo, quasi dicatur suppositum esse idem quod individuum substantiale habens per se esse." ( p. 105a) THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 445 Degl' Innocenti also cites another text from Capreolus' Defensiones in order to support his thesis that esse is the constitutive part of the supposit. In the context of a discussion of the relationship between nature and supposit, Capreolus considers the view of an opponent who admits the real distinction of esse and nature but nevertheless wants to defend the thesis (contrary to St. Thomas) that supposit and nature are identical in angels. The opponent's argument asserts that "supposit and nature seem to signify nothing more than the concrete and the abstract; hence, the supposit doesn't signify any more than the nature because the abstract does not signify any more than the concrete." Capreolus rejects this thesis and replies that the supposit or the concrete differs from the nature or the abstract in that the abstract excludes everything that does not belong to the definition of the species while the concrete includes the abstract potentially and implicitly (as opposed to actually and explicitly). "One (the concrete) is designated as possessing, the other as possessed (the abstract) ; one (the abstract) is designated as a part, the other (the concrete) as a whole." 19 Degl' Innocenti misinterprets the text so as to construe esse as that which is excluded by the abstract and included by the concrete, as if the esse were included potentially in the concrete supposit and related to it as a part to a whole. Capreolus' text, however, has a different meaning. He is defending the difference of supposit and nature by saying that although they coincide essentially, they nonetheless have an asymmetric relationship to each other: the abstract nature excludes the con19 "Si autem quaeratur quomodo suppositum differt a natura in talibus ubi nihil accidit praeter rationem essentiae nisi ipsum esse (in talibus enim videtur significare suppositum et natura, abstractum et concretum, ex quo suppositum non aliud significat quam natura, nee abstractum dicit aliud quam concretum); respondetur quod pro tanto suppositum differt a natura in talibus, quia abstractum excludit a sui significatione omne quod non est de ratione specificata; concretum autem illud includit non actu, sed potentia, non explicite, sed implicite. Unum enim illorum significatur ut habens, et aliud ut habitum; unum per modum partis, aliud per modum totius." (I: p. 238b). 446 HORST SEIDL crete supposit; yet the concrete supposit includes, at least potentially, the abstract nature and is related to that nature as the whole to a part or the possessor to the possessed. Degl' Innocenti himseH concedes, in contradiction to his interpretation, that the concrete individual concerns esse actually and not potentially; to get around this difficulty he resorts to making the concrete supposit into a kind 0£ "concrete universal " (concretum univ ersale) .20 Turning now to Cajetan, Degl' Innocenti cites in support 0£ his thesis Cajetan's resolution 0£ an apparent contradiction in St. Thoma:s' teaching on the difference between supposit and nature in immaterial beings. The discrepancy arises from a comparison between the aforementioned Quod. II, 2, 2, where supposit and nature are said to differ insofar as esse does not belong to the essential nature but pertains instead to the supposit, and ST Ia. 3, 3, where it is asserted that supposit and nature are identical in immaterial substances because there is no ma.tter to account for accidents. 21 Degl' Innocenti purports to find in Cajetan's solution a confirmation 0£ the double meaning 0£ supposit: the one including esse only externally, the other including esse internally as a constitutive principle. Yet in fact both St. Thomas and Cajetan intend supposit consistently to mean the same thing. As Cajetan indicates in his commentary on the De ente, however, St. Thomas considers the relationship between supposit and nature from two different perspectives in the apparently contradictory texts. In ST Ia. 3, 3, the perspective is that 0£ the internal or intrinsic difference .between supposit and nature. Since the supposit 0£ a material substance intrinsically includes individual material principles which are not included in the definition of the nature, there is a difference between nature and supposit. In immaterial substances, however, which do not have any intrinsic prin20 Degl' Innocuti, p. 97 ss. his igitur quae non sunt composita ex materia et forma, in quibus individuatio non est per materiam individualem, idest per hanc materiam, sed ipsae formae per se individuantur, oportet quod ipsae formae sint supposita subsistentia. Unde in eis non differt suppositum et natura." 21 "In THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 447 ciples different from the nature, supposit and nature are the same from that perspective. Yet in Quod. II, 2, 2, there is another, extrinsic perspective according to which esse, as the existential act of the supposit, is accruing to the whole supposit (consisting of essentials and non-essentials) . Therefore nature and supposit are really distinct in every being except God. 22 Supposit means the same thing in either perspective and in nowise includes esse as its constitutive part; esse is designated only connotatively as the existential ad belonging to the whole supposit. Since the ultimate goal of Deg' Innocenti's analysis is to display esse as the constitutive feature of person, it is therefore necessary for him to analyze the meaning of esse. For St. Thomas, esse as aotus essendi can mean both the existence of a being as a whole and the act of its nature qua formal cause. 23 Degl' Innocenti makes a point of distinguishing between esse as existere, denoting the mere fact of a thing's being grasped by the senses (facticity), and esse as aotus essendi, denoting the ultimate actuality of the formal nature. 24 It is supposedly esse in the latter sense which is the constitutive element of the person. Yet this distinction does not mean what Degl' Innocenti asserts. The existence of the person as a whole is not reducible to the act of the nature qua formal cause. The formal cause of the man actualizes a material principle (the body) 22 "In substantiis autem separatis, aliis a prima, suppositum differt a natura duobus modis tantum, scilicet extrinsece secundum rem et secundum rationem. Nihil enim reale intrinsecum sibi includit suppositum in eis quod non includat natura, quia non individuatur per aliquod positivum contrahens naturam specificam, quod sit velut differentia individualis supposito intrinseca, sicut est in substantiis materialibus. Sed quia in eis, ut patebit, existentia differt realiter a natura, quae primo, ut dictum est, est actus suppositi, ideo suppositum in eis differt extrinsece a natura; addit enim extrinsece realitatem existentiae. Differt secundo secundum rationem, ut patet." Cajetan, In 'De ente et essentia,', ed. P. Laurent, (Marietti: Turin, 1934), p. 134. 23 The relevant texts are treated historically and systematically by A. Keller S.J. in Sein oder Existenz? Die Auslegung des Heins bei Thomas v. Aquin in der heutigen Scholastik, Pullacher philos. Forschg., (Mtinchen, 1968). 24 See Degl' !U!lOC!lnti,:p. 213-215. 448 HORST SEIDL and the resulting composite or whole is the supposit which enjoys personal existence. Esse belongs to the whole, not the form or nature alone. 25 The principal motive for seeking to make esse the constitutive feature of the person is its status as ultimate actuality. Since esse is related to the nature as act to potency, and since ad is prior and more perfect than potency, the highest constitutive feature of the person must be esse. This interpretation seems not only to accord with St. Thomas' unique metaphysical vision, moreover it seems also to respond positively to contemporary existential concerns. Yet, as I see it, the relationship between esse and essence must not be understood to reduce essence to a mere limiting or potential principle to esse. Essence of all beings is indeed a potential receptive principle to esse which it receives from a first causal source (esse subsistens) as actuality and ultimate perfection in the line of transcendency. In the line of immanency, however, essence is a real perfection in every being and so indeed can be said to cause a being's esse. Thus while it receives esse as actuality from a transcendent source, nevertheless essence in its turn is the formal cause or actuating principle in the individual supposit or person which also includes a material or potential principle (i.e., the body) .26 25 Although the esse of a being is one, it nevertheless can be considered from two perspectives: ( 1) as the act of the nature qua form and ( 2) as the existence of the whole which has the nature as its formal cause. It is esse in the latter sense which is more known to us and by which we gain the former. God as First Cause causes the existence of the formal cause which in its turn functions as a cause of the whole. In this sense it can be said that the nature is the cause of the personal existence of man: "unde patet quod actualitas per prius invenitur in forma substantiali quam in eius subiecto; et quia prim um est causa in quolibet genere, forma substantialis causat esse in actu in suo subiecto" ( STia. 77, 6). The existence of the whole man in an individual body is distinguishable from the actus essendi as an effect to its cause. Thus by reducing personal existence to the act of the nature, Degl' Innocenti undermines his own position that existence is the constitutimim of person. 20 In the definition of person "rational nature" functions as the specific difference (the decisive determination of the genus caused by the formal THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 449 Given this understanding of the relationship between esse and essence, it is not necessary to locate the constitutive element of person in esse. Nothing prevents maintaining both that there is a real distinction between esse and essence and that the rational nature of man is the constitutive element of the human person as is stated clearly in the texts of St. Thomas. Thus the Scotist view contains at least a partial truth insofar as it locates the essence of person in the rational nature of man which determines the special mode of the person's being (his individual being per se) .21 The error of those like Degl'lnnocenti who assert that esse is the constitutive feature of person is their preoccupation with the way the question is posed by the Christological issue of the hypostatic union. St. Thomas' philosophical treatment follows a decidedly different route (e.g. ST Ia. 29, 1). His procedure is to discover the special feature of person from an analysis of individual substances (the genus); he does not proceed from the rational nature of man in order to define personhood in the direction of the individual existent. 28 • The constituting feature of person is thus seen to lie in the rational nature which functions as the specific difference in the definition. The question of existence belongs properly to the supposit or subsisting individual which figures act) indicating precisely the formal act-principle by which the individual person exists. Therefore St. Thomas prefers to speak of "rational nature" rather than "rational essence" because "nature" better expresses the causal aspect (ST Ia. 29, 1 ad 4). The formal cause is a principle of actuality in the person, not of potentiality (the potential principle relies on his body and being an animal) . 21 To this extent the distinction made by H. Miihlen in Sein und Person nach Johan Duns Scotus (Paderborn, 1954) is instructive even for those who do not accept the full Scotist positfon. The author gains from Scotus the view that personal immediacy consists in the special mode of being or subsistence in the person and has "den Charakter des Fiir-sich-seins und Insich-seins " ( p. 99). But he goes beyond the Scotist position (in the sense of Heidegger and M. Muller) when he explains this character as "Verselbstung und Andacht als Grundmoglichkeiten menschlicher Personalitat" (pp. 106ff.). 28 "Hoc nomen 'persona' non est impositum ad significandum individuum ex parte naturae, sed ad significandum rem subsistentem in tali natura." ST Ia. 30, 4. 450 HORST SEIDL in the genus of the definition. Thus esse is not the formal constitutive feature of person and only enters into the consideration of person insofar as every person is generically an individual substance or supposit. 29 B. THE INDIVIDUALITY OF THE PERSON 1. Some Contemporary Positions Since the classical definition of person connects the individual substance with the universal rational nature, the question arises as to how these two apparently conflicting features are related. The classical scholastic solutions have been to assert that individuality results either from individual forms (the Scotist position) or from the body (the Thomist view). Contemporary proponents of the Thomistic position have offered some stimulating speculations concerning this issue. 0. Schweizer considers the person in terms of the specifically complete human nature ("in der spezifisch vollstandigen Menschennatur ") and states that since the nature by itself is universal and abstract, the body as principle of individuation beoomes a determinative element of the human person (" ein ausschlaggebendes Element der menschlichen Person") .30 J. Maritain believes that there is a tension in St. Thomas' thought between the individual and the person because a human being is an individual on the grounds of the material body while the person is constituted by the rational soul; man as an individual is only a part of the whole (sc. the state or the universe) while man as a person is a "relative whole" with regard to God. 31 29 Some reference must be made to the interesting discussions of these questions in two works of E. Forment: ( 1) Ser y persona, Second edition (Barcelona: 1983) and (2) Persona y modo substancial, Second edition (Barcelona, 1984). Forment agrees with Degl' Innocenti in locating the constitutive feature of person in existence, yet his argumentation is quite different because it is based mainly on a consideration of the theme of participation. 30 Schweizer, p. lll. s1 See Les droits de l'homme et la loi naturelle (New York: 1942), pp. 1314. See also the critical appraisal by J. Cocteau in Les fondements thomistes du persona,lisme de M a,rifoin (Ottawa, 1955). THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 451 The position of W. Kluxen merits special consideration. He maintains that the human person is the point of intersection of the nature ooncretized in the body and the equally concrete existence. By virtue of its particular essential determination, being passes from metaphysical universality (ens communissimum) to such extreme concretion that " existence appears as that of the singular individual existent in such wise that, in sharp contrast to the community of being as metaphysically conceived, the former is in the strictest sense incommunicable." 32 Further, it is equally important to Kluxen to note "that the form in the concrete individual does not remain in the generality which is proper to it by its very nature, but becomes itself the form of this individual. 33 The connection with the material body (as principle of individuation) is essential to the soul because it is of its very nature to be a part of man who is constituted by body and soul. Kluxen further asserts the identity in esse of man and soul to be such that by its connection with the body, the soul gains the personal being of man which it subsequently loses at the death of the body. Obviously, indeed, not all the commentators have been sympathetic and J. Endres has formulated some basic objections to the classical definition of person resulting from contemporary philosophical positions. 34 First, the classical definition of person contains an intrinsic contradiction because it tries to determine the person as individual when it can only point out the universal feature of a rational nature. This goes against the tradition's recognition that the individual is impos32 "das Sein als jenes des singularen, individuellen Seienden erscheint, wo es ganz im Gegensatz zur Kommunitat des metaphysisch begriffenen Seins im strengen Sinne inkommunikabel ist." W. Kluxen, " Anima separata und personsein bei Thomas v. Aquin," in Thomas von Aquin. Interpretation und Rezeption, ed. W. Eckert 0. P. (JWainz: 1974), p. 101. 33 "Dass die Form im konkreten Individuum nicht in der ihr von hause aus eigenen Allgemeinheit bleibt, sondern selbst individuell Form dieses Individuums wird." Ibid., p. 103. 34 "Thomasischer Personbegriff und neuzeitlicher Personalismus," in Eckert's collection ( p. ll 7ff.). 452 HORST SEIDL sible to define: individuum est inefjabile and de singularibus non est scientia. The classical definition of person can only consider man universally, even though it is precisely individuality and incommunicability which constitute personhood. Secondly, the classical definition fails to take into account the fea:tures of the human person which seem to be most important: selfconsciousness, freedom, and relationality. 35 Indeed, the classical emphasis on subsistence renders the person closed into himself. In sum, the classical view is too objective (" sachlich ") because of its derivation from a universal, abstract, and rational conceptualization. By contrast, the contemporary perspective (e.g. Personalism) is more sensitive to the ineffable, subjective, existential, singular, and historical character of the human person. Finally, it has been objected also that the human soul must be seen to be individual in itself instead of in dependence upon the material body. Q. Some Observations on the Contemporary Problematic The first issue to be considered is the relationship between the universal and the individual. The question is one of broad metaphysical significance, however, and should not be restricted to the special study of person. For both Boethius and St. Thomas, the relationship between universality and individuality is unproblematic because of Aristotle's resolution of the question. The essence or nature is not a Platonic universal concept opposed to or separate from the individual, but rather is immanent in the particular as its "to ti en einai" or formal cause (quad quid erat esse or Sosein) and so its principle of actuality .36 The universal (genus or species) is indeed related 35 See the characterization of this view in the articles on "Person" by A. Halder and M. Muller in: Staatslexikon, Sixth Edition, VI: 197-206 and Lexikon fur Theologie und Kirche, Second Edition, VIII: 287-290. It should be noted, however, that the latter article is problematic in terms of its translation of Boethius' definition. 36 Cf. my commentary in: Aristoteles' M etaphysik [M einer PhB], 30"'1/308, Vol. I, Second Edition, (Hamburg, 1982), pp. 3lff. and Vol. II, Second Edition, (Hamburg, 1984), pp. 387ff. THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 453 to the individual essence as to its fundamentum reale, but it does not subsist as such apart from the consideration of the intellect (cf. ST Ia, 76, ad 4) . Thus the rational soul as the formal cause or actuality of man is the constitutivum formale of person. Since the individual (e.g. Socrates) encompasses both essential features and non-essential features (accidents), it is strictly speaking indefinable by virtue of the latter. Yet the individual is definable as a member of a species on the grounds of its essence. Thus the ineffability or non-definable character of the individual holds insofar as the individual is considered in its concrete particularity, but it does not perdure when the individual is considered in its essential aspect. And the latter consideration does not ignore the relationship between the essence and the concrete individual being in which it is found; indeed the classical definition precisely indicates the necessary connection between the rational essence and the substantial being of the human individual. Thus while it must certainly be conceded that contemporary existential and historical considerations of the human person enhance our understanding, nevertheless such considerations could be assimilated by the classical perspective and find therein a certain needed corrective. Secondly, it should be understood that matter as the principle of individuation serves to individuate the whole composed of matter and form and not just the form alone. The formal cause becomes individual by matter only insofar as it is numerically one in the individual supposit; as such it is the act-principle for the individual being rendering its existence distinct from any other being. St. Thomas notes, however, that while the whole being, individualized by its matter, is incommunicable; nevertheless the form, although individualized by matter, or better still by the supposit, remains secundum rationem communicable to many. 37 Thus in the composite, the 37 See ST Ia. 13, 9: "considerandum est quod omnis forma in supposito singulari existens, per quod individuatur, communis est multis vel secundum 454 HORST SEIDL formal cause (e.g. the soul in man) remains the principle of specific universality and the matter remains the principle of individuality. Thirdly, it must be noted that the human soul possesses a certain individuality in itself apart from the body even though the body contributes an initial material condition. The reason for this is that the human soul (unlike animal souls) subsists per se even though it is united with a body (ST Ia. 75, fl) and so belongs to the realm of immaterial substances although it occupies the lowest rank therein (ST Ia. 89, I). St. Thomas consequently distinguishes two degrees of individuality: there is the incomplete individuality where something subsists per se and not as an accident and there is the complete individuality where something subsists independently as neither an accident nor a part. 38 The human soul enjoys the first or incomplete kind of individuality hut not the second or complete kind of individuality because it is a constitutive part of the nature of man, connected with a body, and fundamentally constituted so as to possess that capacity for conjunction (unibilitas) even after the death of the body. Yet the soul's qualified individuality is properly its own despite the necessary initial contribution of the material body .39 Fourthly, it cannot be inferred that the incarnated soul enrem vel secundum rationem saltem .... " See also the discussions of ST Ia. 30, 4 and De potentia 9, 2. The first text discusses the common feature of personality as not only in the genus and species, but also in the individual mode of existence. The second text, especially in the ad 2, likewise developes this point. ss "Ad primum ergo dicendum quod ' hoc aliquid' potest dici dupliciter: uno modo, pro quocumque subsistente: alio modo, pro subsistente completo in natura alicuius speciei. Primo modo, excludit inhaerentiam accidentis et formae materialis: secundo modo, excludit etiam imperfectionem partis. Unde manus possit dici 'hoc aliquid' primo modo, sed non secundo modo. Sic igitur, cum anima humana sit pars speciei humanae, potest dici ' hoc aliquid' primo modo, quasi subsistens, sed non secundo modo: sic enim compositum ex anima et corpore dicitur 'hoc aliquid.' " ST Ia. 75, 2 ad 1. See also I Sent. 25, 1, 1 ad 7 where St. Thomas distinguishes between three meanings of " incommunicabilitas." 39 See De ente et essentia, c.6. This point is much neglected nowadays. THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 455 joys personal existence on the grounds that its existence is identical with the existence of the man. The existence of the soul coincides only partially with that of the man; that is, only insofar as it is the formal cause of the existence of the whole man who is also constituted by the body as a. material or potential principle. In this life personal existence belongs to the supposit. Thus the soul does not lose personal existence at the death of the body because it never enjoyed it to begin with. The status of the soul after the death of the body, however, has been variously interpreted. Anton C. Pegis has asserted that there is a textual contradiction in the teaching of St. Thomas. 40 In Summa contra gentiles II, 81, St. Thomas considers the question of whether the rational soul continues to exist after the death of the body. The response hinges on whether the soul has any proper functions apart from the body. St. Thomas asserts that the soul does indeed have such proper functions, namely intelligere and velle, and so separate subsistence. After the death of the body the soul will enjoy another mode of existence (modus essendi) with a correspondingly more perfect mode of cognition (modus intelligendi) which is more conformable with the soul's nature. 41 Yet in Summa Theologiae Ia. 89, 1, in the context of a discussion on 40 "The Separated Soul and its Nature in St. Thomas," in St. Thomas Aquinas (1274-1974) Commemorative Studies (Toronto: PIMS, 1975), pp. 131-158. 41" Sciendum tamen est quod alio modo intelligit anima separata a corpore et corpori unita, sicut et alio modo est: unumquodque enim secundum hoc agit secundum quod est ... Esse vero separatae animae est ipsi soli absque corpore. Unde nee eius operatio, quae est intelligere, explebitur per respectum ad aliqua obiecta in corporeis organis existentia, quae sunt phantasmata: sed inteiliget per seipsum, ad modum substantiarum quae sunt totaliter secundum esse a corporibus separatae, de quibus infra agetur. A quibus etiam tanquam a superioribus, uberius influentiam recipere poterit ad perfectius intelligendum ..... Uncle et, quando totaliter erit a corpore separata, perfecte assimilabitur substantiis separatis quantum ad modum intelligendi et abunde influentiam eorum recipiet. Sic igitur, etsi intelligere nostrum secundum modum praesentis vitae, corrupto corpore corrumpatur, succedet tamen alius modus inteiligendi altior." The citation is from the Leonine text published by Marietti (Turin, 1961) nn. 1625-1626. See Maurer, pp. 132-134. 456 HORST SEIDL the possibility of intellectual operations by the separated soul, St. Thomas apparently contradicts the earlier teaching by asserting that the separated soul's cognitive operations are less perfect than those of the incarnated soul and even against its nature because it is proper to the human soul to perform intellectual operations in conjunction with the body. 42 W. Kluxen has noted a similar problem in St. Thomas' teaching. He interprets St. Thomas to imply tha:t separation from the body does not entail a deficiency in the soul's existence but rather in its nat:ure. 43 Since it belongs to the nature of the soul to be a part of man, connection with the body is essential to it; separation therefore results in a deficiency in nature. 44 Yet St. Thomas also implies that the nature of the soul is not exhausted by its function as the formal cause of the body; while it comes into being in a certain relationality with matter, it nevertheless subsists per se and survives the death of the body. Thus Kluxen perceives a certain tension or even contradiction in St. Thomas' teaching because the soul seems to have a kind of "twofold existence" (" eine zwiegespaltene Existenz ") . Separation from the body is both gain and loss (of personal being and its natural mode of cognition) for the soul. Kluxen even questions whether the soul's existence after death is true individual immortality or just a certain indestructibility .45 42 "Animae igitur secundum illum modum essendi quo corpori est unita, competit modus intelligendi per conversionem ad phantasmata corporum, quae in corporeis organis sunt: cum autem fuerit a corpore separata, competit ei modus intelligendi per conversionem ad ea quae sunt intelligibilia simipliciter, sicut et aliis substantiis separatis. Unde modus intelligendi per conversionem ad phantasmata est animae naturalis, sicut et corpori uniri: sed esse separatum a corpore est praeter rationem suae naturae, et similiter intelligere sine conversione ad phantasmata est ei praeter naturam. Et ideo ad hoc unitur corpori, ut sit et operetur secundum naturam suam." See Pegis, pp. 134-138. 43 Kluxen, p. 99. 44 Ibid., p. 105: "Die auf das Wesen gerichtete Betrachtung unterstreicht das Verwiesensein der Seele auf den Leib so stark, dass die 'Mangelhaftigkeit' der abgeschiedenen Seele ganz klar erscheint." 45 See W. Kluxen, " Seele und Unsterblichkeit bei Thomas v. Aquin," in Seele, ed. Kremer, (Leiden-Koln, 1984), pp. 66-83. THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 457 Despite the arguments of Pegis and Kluxen, however, the texts of St. Thomas need not be interpreted as entailing a contradiction. In Summa contra gentiles II, 81, the central issue is the possibility of operations by the separated soul as such and there is an emphasis on the fact that the separated soul belongs to the realm of immaterial substances and so is similar to the angels. In this regard it could perhaps be ventured that if the operations are specified by the formal nature, then the operations of the separated soul will be more specific and more natural because more spiritual. Yet such an inference is ruled out by Summa Theologiae Ia. 89, 1, where it is asserted that although the separate soul is capable of intellectual operations, such operations are imperfect and (in this sense) against its nature because the human soul is naturally connected to the body in being and in operation. Yet it must be noted that both texts teach that the separated soul enjoys another mode of existence. It is not so that the existence of the separate soul remains unchanged while its nature undergoes a diminishment (Kluxen). The nature of the soul remains unchanged. 46 Connection with the body, while conformable to the soul's nature, is nevertheless not essential to the soul itself; that is, connection with the body does not affect the nature of the soul itself, but rather its mode of being or subsistence (as suppositum). Therefore separation from the body does not entail a deficiency in the nature of the soul, but rather a change in its mode of being and this for the better. Fifthly, the understanding of substance involved in the classical definition of person is not antithetical to contemporary emphasis on freedom, self-communication, etc. These latter concerns involve the actions of the person which are distinct from and dependent upon the substantial being. Indeed it may be ventured that human actions can only obtain their true communicative openness when the person's existence is " closed" and self-subsistent in the classical sense. 46" et cum fuerit a corpore separata animae natura." ST Ia., 89, 1. [sc. anima], manente tamen eadem 458 HORST SEIDL It may be stated in conclusion that because the nature is designated by the universal but not identified with it, and since although the universal is opposed to the individual the nature is indeed immanent within the particular, therefore the classical definition which includes both the rational nature and the individual human being is not intrinsically contradictory. Nor is the classical definition inadequate for the contemporary quest to analyze and interpret personal human experience. For the classical understanding of substantial being and nature (qua essentia, sosein) gives them a transcendental or analogous universality (not generic) which does not exclude the particular but rather positively embraces it. Contemporary criticisms about "empty abstractions " fail to grasp the true intimate connection of such meanings with the individual existent. It is common nowadays to oppose personal values like responsibility and self-consciousness to the classical conception of substance in the way that subjectivity is opposed to objectivity (and human life to inanimate things). Yet this is a false dichotomy because the classical understanding or substantial being in its transcendental analogous charter embraces both subjects and objects and is indeed indispensable for a proper understanding of person and personal identity. 47 C. THE INDIVIDUAL ACTIONS OF THE PERSON Finally, I wish to consider briefly a third problem which concerns the question of personal action. The classical definition of person seems inadequate because it does not articulate the uniqueness of the personal activity by which the person achieves completeness and for which he is responsible. 48 1\fore47 The problems which arise for the understanding of person when the traditional concepts of substance and being are rejected in favor of a neopositivist or analytic approach can be observed in the interesting collection: Identitat der Person, ed. L. Siep, Aufsatze aus der nordamerikanischen Gegenwartsphilosophie (Basel-Stuttgart, 1983) . Translation from: The Identities of Persons, ed. S. Rorty (Univ. California Press, 1976). 48 Obviously this bears upon the legal aspect of person as it has been developed by modern thinkers such as Leibniz, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel. Yet THE CONCEPT OF PERSON IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS 459 over, it may be doubted that the unique individual and historical character of personal activity can be accounted for at all by the abstract classical definition. Obviously such criticisms merit careful and thoughtful consideration. Let it suffice here, however, to offer the following observations. First, St. Thomas clearly recognized the essential connection between person and action. ·when he discusses the meaning of the specific difference (natura rationalis) of the definition in ST Ia.. :29, 1, he immediately identifies rational substances with responsible activity (" dominium sui actus "). W. Kluxen has analyzed the ethical import of this teaching. 49 His Holiness John Paul II has considered this feature of the classical definition in the light of the contemporary phenomenological analyses of personal action in R. Ingarden, M. Scheler, J. de Finance, and M. Blondel. 50 Yet despite the intimate connection between person and action, the definition of person cannot encompass personal action because the definition is necessarily aimed at a being's essence. In man, the personal being is distinct from personal action and is related to it as a. cause to its effect. Instructive in this regard is the teaching of St. Thomas in Summa Theologiae Illa. 19, lad 8, where he denies that the hypostatic union in Christ entails the possibility of only one mode of operation by stating that although esse pertains to the very constitution of the person and so entails unity, nevertheless operation is an effect of the person according to his form or nature thus making it possible for there to be a plurality of operations in Christ without prejudice to his personal unity. 51 Personal actions do not conthe legal influence on the understanding of person was present even in the Scholastics. Alcuin, for example, developed the concept of person from that of legal power. Cf. V. Serralda, La phiiosophie de ia personne chez Akuin (Paris: 1978) . 49 Kluxen, Anima separata p. 113ff. 5o K. Woytila, The Acting Person, trans. Andrzej Potocki, D. Reidel: Boston, 1979). 51 "Ad tertium dicendum quod operari est hypostasis subsistentis, sed secundum formam et naturam, a qua operatio speciem recipit. Et ideo a 460 HORST SEIDL stitute the essence or being of man. To replace the primacy of personal being with the primacy of personal actions would result in activist or existentialist view of man. Secondly, St. Thomas likewise demonstrates in ST Ia. 2,9 1 that although he understood personal actions as individual, historical, and unique events (" actiones autem in singularibus sunt ") , nevertheless he did not consider this feature of personhood to be incompatible with the universal rational nature of man. As was seen above, the essential nature of each being is intimately connected with its individual existence as the formal specifying cause of its being and operation. In the case of man, his actions proceed from and are specified by his rational nature. The consequence of this intimate connection is that the nature of a being can be inferred inductively from the character of its operations. 52 Thus in the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas, the classical definition of person involves no failure in comprehension of personal activity. It is rather the case that human action is seen within the proper context of human being. Each individual human actualizes and achieves his personality through free, unique, historical actions grounded in his rational nature. The achievement of personality is the work of a lifetime; for not every act of man is necessarily a personal moral action, as on the other hand every personal action is certainly truly human. HORST SEIDL University of Nijmegen The Nether lands diversitate formarum seu naturarum est diversa species operationum: sed ab unitate hypostasis est unitas secundum numerum quantum ad operationem speciei ... Et similiter in Christo oportet quod sint duae operationes specie differentes, secundum eius duas naturas: qualibet tamen operationum est una numero in Christo, semel facta, sicut una ambulatio et una sanatio." 52 "Natura enim uniuscuiusque rei ex eius operatione ostenditur. Propria autem operatio hominis, inquantum est homo, est intelligere ... Oportet ergo quod homo secundum illud speciem sortiatur, quod est huius operationis principium. Sortitur autem unumquodque speciem per propriam forman. Relinquitur ergo quod intellectivum principium sit propria hominis forma." ST Ia. 76, 1. KARL RAHNER'S EXISTENTIAL ETIDCS: A CRITIQUE BASED ON ST. THOMAS'S UNDERSTANDING OF PRUDENCE I K ARL RAHNER'S THEORY of a "formal existential ethics," which he proposes as a necessary supplement to the "essential ethics" of the Thomistic naturallaw tradition, has been both praised as a brilliant adaptation of the tradition to contemporary philosophy as well as criticised as a misleading and unnecessary break with Thomism. William A. Wailace, one of the critics, characterizes Rahner's ethics as an unfortunate combination of mysticism and casuistry. 1 Personal moral decision-making, according to Wallace, should depend on the virtue of prudence plus " gifts of grace" instead of on a theory of private spiritual discernment. A genuine Thomism in his view already achieves what Rahner wants to accomplish with the problematic category of existential ethics and simultaneously provides more coherent and explicit safeguards against situationalism and abuse. 2 Rahner's chief expositor, James F. Bresnahan, claims in his extensive dissertation on Rahner's ethics that the extent of Wallace's misunderstanding of "the need for ' existential ' ethics is hard to convey in a short space," and that Wallace is wrong in thinking that Rahner displaces prudence. 3 In the 1 William A. Wallace, O.P., "The Existential Ethics of Karl Rahner: A Thomistic Appraisal,'' in The Thomist, 1963, vol. 27, pp. 493-515. 2 Ibid., pp. 510-513. a James F. Bresnahan, S.J., The Methodology of "Natural Law" Ethical Reasoning In The Theology of Karl Rahner, And: Its Supplementary Development Using The Legal Philosophy of Lon L. Fuller, 1972 Ph.D. dissertation, Yale University (available from University Microfilms, Ann Arbor, Mich., no. 72: 29520), footnote 106, pp. 77-78. 461 DANIEL M. NELSON course of this exchange, not much is said by either party about the characteristics of the virtue oi prudence itself. An investigation into the function and status assigned to prudence by St. Thomas may be of use for deciding whether existential ethics is in keeping with his moral teaching or, rather, a distortion. But first, in order to evaluate Wailace's criticism and claim that prudence is a preferable alternative to Rahner's proposal, a brief description of Rahner's categories of essential and exi,;tential ethics is in order. 4 Rahner uses the category of essential ethics in two ways. First, he identifies it Yvith what he portrays as a somewhat static and conservative natural-law tradition. Second, he uses it to refer to his own description of a rehabilitated dimension of ethical reasoning that complements and calls for a supplemental category of existential ethics. Essential ethics in both cases refers to the moral principles or laws derived from knowledge of the essential elements of human nature. The difference has to do primarily with disagreement about what it is that constitutes human essence. According to Rahner, essence is much less unchangeable and much more " open " than traditionally or ordinarily assumed. As a consequence, he argues, claims about natural law should be less absolute and universal than they often are. Whether one understands essence as fixed or fluid, however, essential ethics involves a syllogistic application of natural law to circumstances. A universal principle based on human essence 4 An understanding of Rahner's ethics is macle difficult by several factors: his thinking is deeply indebted to " transcendental" Continental philosophy; some of the relevant texts and criticisms are available only in German; passages dealing with ethics appear in widely scattered (and unindexed) essays; he does not conceive of himself primarily as an ethicist and thus is not systematic in his discussion of his moral theory; his prose may be charitably described as challenging; and the only extensive analysis of his ethics written in English is Bresnahan's 650-page dissertation, which contains a wealth of information and explication. Bresnahan has published two helpful summaries: "Rahner's Christian Ethics: in America, 1970, vol. 123, pp. 351-354 ancl "Rahner's Ethics: Critical Natural Law in Relation to Contemporary Ethical Methodology," in the Journal of Religion, Jan. 1976, vol. 56, pp. 36-660. KARL RAHNER's ETHICS 463 is contained in the major premise, an actual situation is described in the minor premise, and an imperative is presented in the conclusion. In Rahner's view, most versions of essential ethics have the defect of only anticipating problems in sufficiently analyzing the situation in question and in adequately articulating the relevant universal norm. They tend to suppose, Rahner notes, that" Whoever knows the universal laws exactly and comprehends the given situation to the last detail, knows also clearly what he must or may do here." 5 Rahner unabashedly affirms the authority of natural law and the legitimacy of its reference to essence for determining normative principles, 6 but he distinguishes between a permanent "core" essence knowable by " transcendental reflection " and an historically, culturally, and biologically changeable human nature available to empirical observation. 7 When discussing the permanent and necessary part of human essence, Rahner tends to focus on what he describes as its transcendent subjectivity and freedom. He understands freedom (not merely to choose between actions but primarily to create one's spiritual and moral future) as "a basic condition of the person" without which " man could not stand before God as a responsible agent ... , without it he could not be the subject of guilt before God nor of profferred and accepted redemption and pardon." 8 Although he recognizes the material dimension within which freedom operates, Rahner emphasizes the freedom to determine oneself rather than the contingent factors by which the self is determined. "On The Question of a Formal Existential Ethics," in 5 Karl Rahner, Theological Investigations, vol. ii, trans. Karl-H. Kruger, 1963, Helicon Press, Baltimore. 6 Rahner, " The Problem of Genetic Manipulation," in Theological Investigations, vol. ix, trans. Graham Harrison, l!l72, Darton, Longman & Todd, London, p. 231. 7 Rahner, "The Dignity and Freedom of Man," Theological Investigations vol. ii, pg. 236. In "The Experiment With Man" and " The Problem of Theological Investigations, vol. ix, pp. 205-250. Genetic Manipulation," Rahner discusses the human capacity, increasingly facilitated by science and technology, for self-manipulation. s Rahner, "The Dignity and Freedom of Man," pp. 246-247. 464 DANIEL M. NELSON By human transcendence and subjectivity Rahner means one's self-awareness precisely as such a free creature oriented to God 9 and able to reflect on what it is about human nature or essence that makes distinctively human activity possible. 10 That is, a distinctive feature of being human, according to Rahner, is the ability to reflect on the conditions of the possibility of being human. A related feature of Rahner's understanding of human nature is that he sees nature to be so penetrated and malleable by God's grace that it is impossible to draw as sharp a line between nature and grace as some naturallaw theorists suppose. 11 This results in a further qualification of what can be claimed to follow from an understanding of nature or essence in the way of natural law. Rahner nowhere denies the normativeness of the Thomistic catalog of the inclinations of human nature (self-preservation, sexual desire, the nurturing of offspring, to live in society, and to seek God) . But given his complex view of human essence, in which " essential " transcendence and freedom are related to empirically discernible contingent characteristics, and in which the lines between these two spheres are nowhere clear, he is reluctant to enumerate principles of natural law or to claim eternal validity for them. 12 This is the point at which Rahner introduces his "formal existential ethics "-formal because it contains no material content but rather has to do with the structure of a dimension of moral obligation, and existential because it has to do with individual imperatives rather than general obligations derived from essence 13-and the point at which, on Wallace's account, the virtue of prudence is unfortunately neglected. 9 Rahner, "The Problem of Genetic Manipulation," p. 231. Bresnahan, chapter 1, for a thorough discussion of Rahner's understanding of essence and for relevant citations. 11 Rahner, "Concerning the Relationship Between Nature and Grace," Theological Investigations, vol. i, trans. Cornelius Ernst, O.P., 1961, Helicon Press, Baltimore, pg. 315. 12 Rahner, "The Problem of Genetic Manipulation," p. 230. 13 Donal J. Dorr, "Karl Rahner's Formal Existential Ethics," in the Irish Theological Quarterly, 1969, vol. 36, pg. 213. 10 See 465 KARL RAHNER's EXISTENTIAL ETHICS A formal existential ethics refers to a moral reality to which, according to Rahner, essential ethics, by its very nature, cannot sufficiently attend. It refers more precisely and attentively than essential ethics to the element of human nature characterized freedom, subjectivity, and individuality. Whereas essential ethics applies to human nature in general, existential ethics applies to the unique individual who is, Rahner affirms, always more than one of many repeatable instantiations of humanity. Existential ethics is not intended by Rahner to verge on situation ethics, which in its extreme forms denies the authority of general moral norms and affirms the absolute uniqueness and autonomy of the individual, but it does correspond to what Rahner sees as the element of truth in situation ethics: that there is an important sphere of individual moral obligation not expressed by general rules. 14 Rahner refers to at least three main considerations compelling the development of existential ethics. The first is that even a redescription of essential ethics (one taking into account the openness of essence) does not adequately apply to the freedom characteristic of the human condition, a freedom that is encountered in the capacity to create one's moral and spiritual being by obeying an imperative beyond the moral law. It is not a freedom of indifferent autonomy but a freedom of absolute obligation to love God and one's neighbors. 15 The details of this obligation, Rahner says, cannot be specified precisely: the demand cannot be known in advance or sufficiently articulated by objective norms, although it always has to be fulfilled in concrete action. Only a "genuine individual ethics," which goes beyond essential ethics without contradicting objective norms and without slipping into situation ethics, " can preserve the mystery of freedom." 16 14 Rahner, "On the Question of a Formal Existential Ethics," pp. 220- 225. 15 Rahner, "The Dignity and Freedom of Man," pg. 247. "Theology of Freedom," Theological Investigations, vol. vi, trans. Karl-H. and Boniface Kruger, 1969, Helicon Press, Baltimore, pp. 187-190. 16 Rahner, 466 DANIEL M. NELSON The second consideration is the failure of essential ethics to do complete justice to the singular reality of a concrete situa.tion. This failure, according to Rahner, is manifested in the gap between the specific distinctiveness of a concrete situation and the generality of the language that attempts to describe the situation as a " case " in the form of a. proposition in the syllogistic scheme of practical reasoning. The failure is further expressed in the subsequent inability of the deduced imperative clearly and unambiguously to apply to the situation in question.11 Rahner claims that existential ethics, in contrast, contains a qualitatively different" pointing gesture" that specifies exactly, without mistake or distortion, what is to be done. The third factor compelling the formulation of an existential ethics follows from Rahner's observation that a system of natural law based solely on essence contains both positive and negative precepts that only establish the boundaries of what is or is not to be done. Although the negative precepts can never be contradicted, the positive precepts are frequently so broadly general that the individual is faced with a choice of a variety of possible options. 18 A choice is required, but the specifics of how to make the choice, or of how to put a particular choice into effect, are not given by essential ethics. Rahner denies that such choices are a matter of indifference and affirms the p11obahility that "from some other source altogether, only one of these ' permitted' possibilities is designated as the only morally right one " in the situation. 19 In summary, Rahner's formal existential ethics is an attempt to articulate what is involved in achieving a closer moral approximation of the will of God for a unique individual in a specific situation than can he determined by the application of a list of universal moral laws based on a universal human essence. Rahner does not deny that there is such an essence; he just denies the way in which it has been characterized and Rahner, "On The Question Of A Formal Existential Ethis," pp. 220-225. pg. 224. 19 Ibid., pp. 224-225. 11 ls Ibid., KARL RAHNERJS EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 467' that it is productive of a moral sytesm with the all-encompassing applicability or certainty claimed by some Thomists. Without denying the validity of the natural law as a legitimate expression of God's will, Rahner's claim is that God has something additional to say to the individual whether the individual recognizes the message is coming from God or not. While the essential dimension of morality refers to specifiable inclinations, and obligations, existential ethics refers to no "thing" in particular but rather to a capacity or a process of discerning obligation, of self-determination, and of relation to God expressed in concrete moral choice. Essential ethics has a content; existential ethics is a way or dimension of individual moral "being" that finds concrete expression in moral action. Assuming for the moment that there is such a dimension of moral obligation beyond the purview of what Rahner describes as essential ethics, and setting aside questions about the relation between essential and existential ethics and the possibilities of conflict, one has to ask (particularly in light of Wallace's charges of unwarranted mysticism at the expense of the virtue of prudence) how an existential ethics is known. Rahner says that one of two functions of the "organ " of conscience is involved-not the function operative in the syllogistic reasoning of essential ethics, but another part of conscience that operates as a " technique " for hearing individual imperatives. "If we seek a traditional name for this," Rahner says, " we would call it the charismatic art of 'discernment of spirits' ... the ability to discern the unique call of God for the individual as such ... " 21 This technique or art is described by Rahner in The Dynamic Element in The Church, especially in the essay on " The Logic of Concrete Individual Knowledge in Ignatius Loyola," where 20 Ibid., pg. 214. " Gerfren im heutigen Katholizismus," 1950, Benziger and Co., Einsiedeln, pg. 17. (Trans. by and quoted in Wallace, pp. 497, 495.) The essay appears in English as "Dangers in Catholicism Today," in Nature and Graoe, c. 1964, Sheed and Ward, N.Y. 21 Rabner, 468 DANIEL M. NELSON Rahner appropriates for existential ethics the second of three ways of religious decision-making, " the discernment of spirits," in Ignatius's description of the process of " election." 22 Rahner says the second mode of knowing God's will in this process is intellectual but non-discursive. In an ordinary discursive way of knowing, on this account, a judgment about the goodness of a motivation or impulse follows from a prior determination of the goodness of the consequent actions performed. In other words, discursive knowledge is a case of knowing a tree by its fruits. The non-discursive knowledge upon which Rahner says his existential ethics depends is the opposite: one knows the impulse to be supernaturally good from the start and decides what to do on the basis of its authority. In the discernment of spirits, Rahner says, one experiences a kind of " consolation " in a realm of pure transcendence where one encounters the express will of God himself without the mediation of any object of knowledge. 23 Anticipating at least one objection, Rahner says that to point out that an object-less experience is an unconscious experience is to miss the point: The absence of object in question is utter receptivity to God, the inexpressible, non-conceptual experience of the love of God who is raised transcendent above all that is individual, all that can be mentioned and distinguished, of God as God. There is no longer 'any object' but the drawing of the whole person, with the very ground of his being, into love, beyond any defined circumscribable object, into the infinity of God as God himself as the divina majestad. 24 This kind of explanation invites more objections, but Rahner says that the experience of such a " consolation " bears the " stamp of divine origin " and has the status of a first principle 22 Rahner, The Dynamic Element In The Church, trans. W. J. O'Hara, c. 1964, Herder and Herder, N.Y. 23 A helpful summary of this aspect of Rahner's ethics is provided by Dorr, pp. 211-229. 24 Rahner, The Dynamic Element In The Church, pp. 134-135. KARL RAHNER's EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 469 of logic or ontology. 25 It is self-warranting and, before its mediation by objects, indubitably reliable. 26 Perhaps in order to guard against charges of irrationalism or "Illuminism," Rahner maintains that this process operates within the boundaries of what is and is not permissible that already are established by natural law. He adds that although the requisite knowledge is " non-discursive," it is not finally divorced from reason: After all, these stirrings do not consist of merely indifferent, blind drives like hunger, thirst, and so on. They consist of thoughts, acts of knowing, perception of values, etc. They themselves contain an objective conceptual element, they can be expressed and verfied. The experience of consolations and desolations is not the experience of merely physiological states, but of impulsions having a rational structure. They are always also the product of one's own activity of an intellectual kind. 27 Rahner attempts to resolve the apparent tension between the non-discursive moment of this process and the "objective conceptual element" by speaking of a dialectic in which one places the memory of the object-less transcendent promptings, experienced in the moment of divine consolation, alongside the proposed concrete course of action as an " experimental test " of the rightness or wrongness of the choices to be made. The determination is made on the basis of "whether the two phenomena are in harmony, mutually cohere ... whether instead of smoothness, gentleness and sweetness, sharpness, tumult and disturbance arise. " 28 This entire process is not just available to a spiritual elite or only to Christians. Rahner claims it is employed without awareness by " nearly everyone " confronted by important choices, where the final decision is not made " by a rational analysis " but rather by a feeling of suitability and contentment accompanying and validating the proper decision.29 p. 142. p. 145. 27 Ibid., pp. 102-103. 2s Ibid., pg. 128. Cf. pp. 162-163. 29 Ibid., pg. 166. 25 Ibid., 26 Ibid., 470 DANIEL M. NELSON II There are undoubtedly a number of features of Rahner's acoount of essential and existential ethics where even a critic seeking a more flexible understanding of the traditional naturallaw doctrine would want to raise objections. My own reservations have to do with Rahner's analysis 0£ "essence "-with the presuppositions behind the distinction between a sphere of freedom and transcendence, on the one hand, and materiality on the other-and with the characterization of existential ethics' dependence on "non-discursive" knowledge. For example, aside from the question of whether it is a good idea to appea1 to spiritual promptings and consolations for moral knowledge and authority, there is the larger question of whether this kind of knowledge really is object-less and non-discursive. In other words, one could ask whether there is in fact any qualitative difference between a " pointing gesture," 30 such as supposedly specifies the application 0£ an existential imperative and an imperative command expressed verbally. If there is no difference in kind in the commands, one wonders what makes the category of existential ethics distinctive and necessary. If the difference between essential and existential ethics has to do rather with the way in which moral knowledge is obtained, one is driven back to the question of whether existential ethics is really just situational intuitionism with a painted-onhalo. These questions warrant further investigation, but vVallace's objection about Rahner's neglect of the virtue of prudence is more directly relevant to the question of whether Rahner's theory is a legitimate and compatible extension of St. Thomas's teaching. Wallace's objection suggests that the virtue of prudence as understood by Thomas may more straightforwardly accomplish with a. familiar and circumscribed vocabulary much of what Rahner wants to achieve with his problematic appeal to existential ethics. Not only may prudence make posso Ibid., pp. 20-21 KARL RAHNER's EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 471 sible within moral reasoning a :flexibility, a recognition of historical and cultural influences, and direct applicability to particular individuals in concrete cases, but it may do so without sharing Rahner's indebtedness to Kantian notions of subjectivity or to the philosophy informing transcendental Thomism. Wallace objects that Rahner's complaints a.bout the naturallaw tradition pertain to an " essentialist " doctrine found in neo-scholasticism but foreign to Thomas Aquinas, 31 so that although Rahner pays " lip service " to prudence in discussing the application of general principles to circumstances, he " first represents this inadequately, then states the problem in such a way that demands a solution in terms of a post-Tridentine doctrine which substitutes the voice of conscience for the prudential decision, then finally proceeds to show how the latter doctrine is itself inadequate." 32 Rahner's most substantial statement about prudence is as follows: The role assigned to this virtue by Aquinas is, of course, well known, though at various times it has been almost forgotten by some moral theologians. But the question is, what is the nature of this virtue and what is its object? If one tries to answer this question, one must candidly admit that prudence first envisages the full range of general principles, then the concrete circumstances, and inquires what principle or combination of principles is to be actually applied in precisely these circumstances. 33 He goes on to ask, rhetorically, whether these circumstances have to do with abstract essences or i£ there is also something absolutely individual and unique involved which prudence might discern. Asserting that prudence only makes a distinctive contribution to moral reasoning if the " 'inexpressibly individual' element" actually exists, Rahner claims that "the appeal to prudence ... does not solve the set of problems that we have in mind, but only notifies their presence." 34 pp. 500-502. pp. 506-507. 33 Rahner, The Dynamic Element in The Church, p. 23. 34 Ibid., pp. 23-24. s1 Wallace, 32 Ibid., 472 DANIEL M. NELSON The importance of all this, according to Bresnahan's explanation contra Wallace, is that prudence has to do more than juggle the objectifiable elements of the situation and the relevant universal principles. Prudence has to recognize "the immediate self-awareness of the 'person' in his uniqueness." The claim Bresnahan reiterates on behalf of Rahner is that prudence is a, bridge between essential and personal ethics (another way of referring to existential ethics) and that its true significance is diminished if the personal element is ignored. 35 Nonetheless, neither Rahner nor Bresnahan demonstrates that prudence actually plays in Thomas's understanding the role they envision for it. Moreover, Rahner has attributed to St. Thomas a foreign conception of a full-blown dimension of personal moral reality that prudence supposedly perceives. An adequate understanding of the function of prudence requires recognition of a private " personalist " or existential dimension of ethics, Rahner claims. He then refers to the existence of such a dimension as evidence that prudence has to do more than apply universal principles to essences and concrete circumstances, which, if Wallace is correct, is a misunderstanding of prudence to begin with. Bresnahan is right in defending Rahner against the charge of ignoring the virtue of prudence, but the more serious charge is that prudence as understood by Thomas obviates much of the need for Rahner's supplement. It does not obviate all of what Rahner says is the need for existential ethics, however, because Rahner, while identifying himself with Thomas, describes a dimension of personhood characterized by a subjectivity, transcendence, and freedom that explicitly depends on a very different philosophical vocabulary and consequently requires a corresponding theory of individual moral obligation. Bresnahan observes that Rahner's major study of Thomas claims "to be both interpreting Aquinas's very own thinking and yet also doing so in relation to basic staJrting points and a5 Bresnahan, pp. 75-78. KARL RAHNER's EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 473 methodologies (Kant's turn to the subject and' transcendental method,' Heidegger's phenomenology and search for 'fundamental ontology') which could not have been and were not in fact part of Aquinas's own explicit viewpoint and reasoning for his positions." 36 Rahner himself says his concern is not with the Thomas who was conditioned by his times and dependent on Aristotle, Augustine, and the philosophy of his day. There is also such a Thomas, and we could conduct a historical investigation about him. Whether or not we are correct in doubting that such an approach could get to the really philosophical in Thomas, the primary concern of this historical work is not to be 'history,' but philosophy itself. And if what matters is to grasp the really philosophical in a philosopher, this can only be done if one joins him in looking at the matter itself. It is only then that you can understand what he means. 37 Rahner's hermeneutical approach to Thomas Aquinas is noted here because an alternative description of prudence, one that does not depend on the philosophical concerns that Rahner believes he is justified in reading into Thomas in order to get to the "truth" behind Thomas's vocabulary, is most likely not going to attend to the kind of " subject" associated with Rahner's existential ethics and which is supposedly perceived by prudence. III Thomas unfortunately suffers the fate of being identified too closely with the tradition he inspired, with the result that many critics of the natural-law tradition think they are refuting St. Thomas in the course of dismissing a particular articulation of natural law. Or, as in Rahner's case, sympathetic attempts to correct the excesses or limitation of the tradition have little continuity with Thomais's own teaching. If Thomas is read as describing a basicaily Aristotelian ethics of virtue in which prudence is assigned much of the deliberative work and com36 Ibid., pp. vi-vii. 37 Rahner, Spirit In The World, trans. William Dych, c. 1968, Herder and Herder, N.Y., pp. xlix-1. Quoted in Bresnahan, p. vii. 474 DANIEL M. NELSON manding of action that later theorists attribute to the syllogistic reasoning of natural law, Rahner's refinements are superfluous at best. If prudence does something different than merely apply universals to "cases," and if it can determine obligation and specify the right thing for an individual to do in a concrete and contingent situation, there is no need to appeal to anything like existential ethics as a corrective or necessary addition to prudence-unless one wants to retain the bulk of Rahner's transcendental anthropology. In an authentically Thomistic ethics, rather than deducing conclusions from an array of naturally known principles, one is habituated to the correct judgment of what is to be done. Prudence is the perfected or developed habit concerned with " doing." It is the virtue "dealing with action and concerned with things good and bad for man," 38 both in matters of justice in social relations and in the development of an individual's own character. 39 Unlike the certain conclusions of the speculative sciences, the conclusions of prudence, which deals with practical matters, the " contingent individual incidents, which form the setting for human acts," are only probable. 40 Prudence deals with the singular as opposed to the universal. 41 Its judgments are conjectural and deliberative, 42 the opposite of non-discursive, involving a determination of "what happens in the majority of cases." 43 Prudence is related to universals in that it possesses knowledge of "general moral principles of reason," but its main focus is on the " individual situations in which human actions take place." 44 Thomas goes so far as to say that if it were necessary for an individual to have only one 38 St. Thomas Aquinas, Commentary On The Nicomaohean Ethics, trans. C. I. Litzinger, O.P., c. 1964, Henry Regnery Co., Chicago, # 1177. (Subsequent citations will be in the form, Ethics: 1177.) s9 Ethics: 1259. 4o Thomas, Summa Theologiae, Blackfriars Edition, McGraw Hill, N.Y., 2a2ae, 47, 9. (Subsequent citations will be in the form, Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 9.) 41 Ethics: 124 7. 42 Ethics: 117 4 and 1189. 4BSumma: 2a2ae, 47, 3. 44 Ibid. KARL RAHNER'S EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 475 kind of knowledge, one ought to choose knowledge of "particulars" because as this kind of knowledge is "closer to operation" it is more likely to lead to right action. 45 The development or perfection of prudence depends, in large part, on memory, maturity, and education. It uses principles which "are not inherited with human nature, but are discovered through experience and instruction." 46 One becomes prudent through practice 47 and through the " seasoning " of time 48 so that one is gradually and progressively enabled to deal with situations and to make a decision in the way a wise individual " would so decide it." 49 Rather than looking to universal rules for guidance about a future course of action, prudence "learns from the past and present." 50 Right reason about things to be done, or about " means," according to Thomas, also requires that one be correctly oriented to ends, which depends on the rightness of one's appetites or inclinations, the dominion of the moral virtues. 51 Thomas was engaged in reconciling an Aristotelian ethic of habituated virtues with a Christianized Stoic ethic of law in which the divinely promulaged natural law is part of the makeup of human minds. 52 Rahner's existential ethics is a response to a common version of this synthesis in which law predominates. To be sure, Thomas modifies the virtue ethic, but nonetheless the epistemic significance of the element of law is subordinated to the element of virtue. The role of law is theological: Whereas Aristotle sees human orientation to political 45 Ethics: 1194. 2a2ae, 47, 15. 47 Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 16. 48 Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 3. 49 Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 7. 50 Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 1. 51 Summa: la2ae, 57, 4. Cf. Ethics: 1269. 52 The preceding observations about the importance and role of prudence, and also the remark about the nature of the synthesis of law and virtue, are indebted to Professor Victor Preller's 1982 Princeton University seminar on Thomas Aquinas. See also Thomas Gilby's remarks in the appendices of vol. 36 of the Blackfriars edition of the Summa. 46 Summa: 476 DANIEL M. NELSON goods, Thomas insists on the Augustinian notion of human orientation to God as the final end. This Christian understanding of human ends changes the role played by prudence in that Thomas views the first principles of natural law, knowable by synderesis, as the first principles of practical reason. They function as a framework within which prudence operates, as a theological explanation for agreement about its judgments, and as a source of motivation. For Aristotle, in contrast, prudence or phronesis operates without first principles. Thomas's first principles, however, play a much more restricted role than Rahner assumes. The naturally known first principle of practical reason-that good is to be done and evil avoided-functions much like the so-called law of non-contradiction, the first principle in Thomas's account of the speculative sciences, stating that nothing can both be and not be at the same time. It is not the sort of principle from which specific conclusions can be drawn. In most cases, determinations of practical as well as speculative principles that actually are used for guiding thinking or behavior are made on the basis of what appears to happen most of the time. The first principles of natural law are associated, of course, with Thomas's list of natural inclinations. Although stated as rules on occasion, they primarily have to do with the achievement of goods. As rules or general principles, they are so abstract and general that they are devoid of any meaning except that which they receive in conjunction with the operation of the cardinal virtues under the of prudence. Prudence, rather than synderesis, determines what it actually means to act according to right reason in each case. This is where Thomas joins natural law and Aristotelian virtue. He associates the principle or inclination to preserve " being" with the virtue of fortitude, the inclination to achieve the goods necessary for the sustenance of life with temperance, and the inclinations to live in society and to know God with justice and prudence. Synderesis, which perceives first principles, only determines the ends of human action; prudence acting in accord with right KARL RAHNER'S EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 477 appetite and directing or perfecting the operation of the virtues 53 determines the means, what actions in particular are to be done. 54 Prudence, not a syllogistic application of the formal principles of the natural law which express those ends generally (to pursue good, to act according to right reason, to act justly), determines and commands what is to be done in order to achieve those ends on the basis of counsel and judgment 55 and in light of its experienced understanding of the common good. 56 Natural law plays no significant epistemic function in making moral determinations. It functions formally to account for the judgments of prudence. In order to carry out the actual work of determining what is to be done, prudence needs much more than the general precepts of natural law and an understanding of the circumstance in question. Prudence both shapes and is shaped by the virtues and general social agreement about the goods to which they are oriented. That is, rather than relying on the intuitions of synderesis and applying them syllogisticaily to circumstances, prudence depends on education into the customary judgments of society about what human goods in particular are appropriate and about how they are to be achieved. The judgments of prudence, in turn, become part of the content of moral education, which informs moral deliberation. Thomas notes that prudence has to do with things about which we deliberate, and that to deliberate well about what is to be done is the sign of a prudent individual. 57 He summarizes the mutual dependence of prudence and the virtues by observing, for example, that "the happiness of active living, which is gauged by the activiles of the moral virtues, is attributed to prudence perfecting all the moral virtues ... " 58 Making moral determinations, for Thomas, is not a matter 53 Ethics: 2111. 54 Summa: 2a2ae, 4 7, 6. la2ae, 57, 6. Cf. Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 8-9. 56 Summa: 2a2ae, 47, 10. 57 Ethics: 1189. 58 Ethics: 2111. 55 Summa: 478 DANIEL M, NELSON of applying universal laws to situations. Thomas's virtue of prudence does much of what Rahner says that essential ethics leaves undone, but it does so without verging on the excesses of existential ethics. It attends to singulars, both singular individuals and to unique circumstances. It does not regard an individual as only an instance of humanity in general, but then again it does not grant moral authority to each individual's autonomous subjective awareness, and it regards situations as contingent rather than as "cases." It does not limit freedom by confining obligation to a rigid and content-laden articulation of the natural law, but then again it does not make the achievement of a particular conception of freedom a moral imperative. Prudence is especially concerned with specifying what particular choice out of all the permitted possibilities is to be made here and now by an individual or a community. That specification and its consequent command is made by reference to the common good and within the context of agreement about virtues and ends rather than by reference to a private spiritual consolation or the law of nature. Prudence is to natural law for Thomas much as existential ethics is to essential ethics for Rahner. However, Thomas's conception of natural law and Rahner's understanding of essential ethics are far from equivalent, and the authority and certainty claimed by Thomas for prudence are quite different from Rahner's claims about existential ethics. Jl1,foch of the difference, as noted above, has to do with Rahner's notions of transcendence and subjectivity. There is, to be sure, an important element of transcendence in Thomas's ethics, but it is carefully qualified. For Thomas, the nature of the transcendent reality to which humans are ordered is unknown. Moreover, Thomas is reluctant to say we even have certain knowledge of the world we inhabit. As opposed to God's certain knowledge, we merely name the essences of things on the basis of their sensible accidents. For Rahner, humans are able " transcendentally " to deduce the conditions of the possibility of their being and behavior. KARL RAHNER's EXISTENTIAL ETHICS 479 As much as he wants to distance himself from the pretensions 0£ neo-scholastic views 0£ essence and 0£ human essence in particular, he still wants to say something certain about human essence and essential ethics. As admittedly flexible and conditional as his description of essence is, he claims it necessarily includes a sphere of transcendentally knowable freedom, individuality, and subjectivity requiring a supplemental existential ethics 0£ its own. Rahner and Thomas are both saying, in effect, that the essential ethics 0£ natural law does not encompass the whole 0£ moral obligation. For Thomas, in light of the limited content and epistemic power 0£ natural law, and because 0£ the contingent nature 0£ action and the uniqueness 0£ circumstances, which always could be other than they are and which admit 0£ exceptions, our moral deliberations require the discursive skill of prudence and its probable judgments. For Rahner, it is the same element 0£ contingency, plus an element 0£ private subjectivity foreign to Thomas, that requires the non-discursive, spiritually prompted discernments of existential ethics and its certain judgments. Along with his claims about the nature 0£ the reality to which existential ethics applies, Rahner introduces a claim about the certainty 0£ its conclusions that Thomas says is necessarily lacking, even with the assistance 0£ spiritual gifts, in human deliberations about what is to be done. I£ one doubts the existence of (or at least the possibility of gaining access to) the transcendental dimension of personhood that Rahner describes, i£ one shares Thomas's scepticism in the sense 0£ a reluctance to claim certain knowledge of God's will for specific human actions, and if one finds the discursive deliberations of prudence more reliable than the non-discursive discernment of spirits, then existential ethics appears to be a particularly imprudent alternative to the account of moral decision-making provided by Thomas Aquinas. DANIEL M. NELSON Princeton University Princeton, New Jersey SPACE-TIME AND THE COMMUNITY OF BEINGS: SOME COSMOLOGICAL SPECULATIONS INTRODUCTION X ERT EINSTEIN, in his essay "Relativity and the Problem of Space," makes several interesting comments on the implications of relativity theory for the Newtonian concepts of absolute space and time. Among these are the following: Since the special theory of relativity revealed the physical equivalence of all inertial systems, it proved the untenability of the hypothesis of an aether at rest. It was therefore necessary to renounce the idea that the electromagnetic field is to be regarded as a state of a material carrier. The field then becomes an irreducible element of physical description, irreducible in the same sense as the concept of matter in the theory of N ewton. 1 On the basis of the general theory of relativity ... , space, as opposed to" what fills space," which is dependent on the coorrdinates, has no separate existence. 2 There is no such thing as empty space, i.e., a space without field. Space-time does not claim existence on its own but only as a structural quality of the field. Thus Descartes was not so far from the truth when he believed he must exclude the existence of an empty space. The notion indeed appears absurd, as long as physical reality is seen exclusively in ponderable bodies. It requires the idea of the field as the representative of reality, in combination with the general principle of relativity, to show the true kernel of Descartes' idea; there exists no space " empty of field." 3 1 Albert Einstein, Relativity: York, 1961), pp. 149-150. 2 Ibid., p. 155. s Ibid., pp. 155-156. The Special and the General Theory 480 (New SPACE-TIME AND THE COMMUNITY OF BEING 481 Space-time is not necessarily something to which one can ascribe a separate existence, independently of the actual objects of physical reality. Physical objects are not in space, but these objects are spatially extended. In this way, the concept "empty space " loses its meaning. 4 These statements raise some interesting questions for the philosopher working within the Judaeo-Christian metaphysical and cosmological tradition. Einstein's concept of the spacetime continuum constituted by the field (or by the plurality of fields seen as interrelated) amounts in effect to a reduction of space-time to relation, to that which is constituted by a universal relational network. One may ask whether this concept is, as many seem to believe, a demolition of the classical and Christian view of the world, or whether, on the contrary, it amounts to a rediscovery of that view from the perspective of the vocabulary of contemporary physics. To ask the question in a slightly different way: Does relativity have anything to do with relativism and hence with the anti-ontological thrust of the latter? This question inevitably involves us in the more general question how the physical structure of the cosmos does or does not reflect the ontological structure of being-i.e., how is the cosmos as known by physics related to the world-order as the intelligible object of a philosophical cosmology? How are the various levels of cosmic order, from inorganic matter to the human level, related to one another? It will be the contention of the present essay that the relativistic concept of the cosmos not only is not destructive of the classical and Christian one, but converges with it, because the latter is grounded in the concept of being as being, and being in turn must be understood as the universal concept and reality which has reality by virtue of the community of beings, i.e., by virtue of relation. These concepts will be further clarified in the course of the discussion. Let it be clearly understood, however, that what follows does not pretend to constitute a rigorous logical derivation of a cosmological system but is 4 Ibid.," Note to the Fifteenth Edition," p. vi. 482 GEORGE A. KENDALL rather a series of speculations, of brief glimpses of areas of convergence which have drawn attention to themselves in the course of the struggle for ontological and cosmological truth. As such, they are presented as a step along the way in the search for understanding, not as an end, still less as a completed system. The discussion will, however, be loosely organized into the following areas: I) the concept of being as community; 2) the concept of extension in its function of relating physical to ontological concepts. The essay will conclude with reflections on some applications of interest to the philosopher and perhaps especially to the Christian philosopher. I The concept of being is, for Christian thought, inseparable from that of the analogy of being. This is the case because being is the ultimate analogous universal in which, as St. Thomas points out, all universals are grounded, 5 and because analogy is the logical tool by which Christian thought, whether explicitly or implicitly, seeks to clarify the meaning of universality. Now the analogy of being has two aspects: 1) A horizontal one, in which the analogy makes possible the predication of universal terms of a multiplicity of beings within a class; 2) A vertical one, in which the concept of analogy is applied to the problem of the possibility of predicating a term of both God and creatures. The concept of analogy is ultimately grounded in the vertical analogy which in turn makes possible the horizontal. Obviously, this needs further clarification. When we apply a predicate to a multiplicity of subjects, we may do so in three ways: I) Univocally, so that the predicate has the identical same meaning in application to each subject. 2) Equivocally, in a merely hornonymous way. 3) Analogously, so that the meaning of the predicate in its various applications is both the same and different. 5 St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Pt. 1, Q. 13, Art 5. SPACE-TIME AND THE COMMUNITY OF BEING 483 An effort must be made to clarify the peculiar character of the analogous term, which is so crucial to the present sion. The use of the universal term humanity provides a useful starting-point. This term is often mistakenly supposed to be a univocal term and is, in fact, routinely used in this manner by egalitarian ideologues, who are fond of insisting that all human beings share the same humanity, whatever may differentiate Lhem. Such a univocal concept of humanity is quite evident, for example, in the feminist effort to replace the terms man and woman with human being or person. Yet it seems evident enough, at least to the present commentator, that, while the term humanity can validly be applied to all human beings, it is applied analogously, not univocally. It can, for example, be stated correctly that both Jesus Christ and Hitler are human beings, but one would be on more questionable ground in trying to argue that their humanity is the same humanity. And yet, if they are not the same, yet not wholly equivocal, in what sense are we justified in predicating the same term in both cases? How can we talk intelligibly about the kind of fusion (not confusion) of what is common and what is not common, what is the same and what is other, in such cases? Wittgenstein's analogy with games has proven useful for clarifying this issue. 6 We can look at all the things which we call "games" and see that somehow they are all validly called "games;" they belong together. The temptation is to assume that we are justified in including them all under the same universal because there is some one respect in which they are all the same, some character of " gameness " which they possess in the same way, regardless of individual differences. The problem, however, is that when we look for some one feature common to all games, we never find it. We may identify some trait such as competitiveness which applies to most games, but it does not apply to all. Yet somehow, irreducibly and undeniably, games, as a group or family, do belong together. But how do we talk about the belonging-together of 6 Ludwig pp. 31 ff. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (New York, 1970), 484 GEORGE A. KENDALL things which are different, which are not reducible to a single univocal term? What is the basis for this apparent community of unlike things? It is here that the vertical aspect of the analogy becomes crucial. When we examine the relation of God to creatures, what we find is a situation in which God is the prime analogate and creatures are both united and differentiated in terms of the variety of relations which all have to God as the common term, a relation which can be called irnaging. This means, in effect, that it is first and foremost a common term in the realm of final rather than formal causality, which unites the creatures who make up the analogy. Formal causality follows because each member of the community strains toward the Creator, attempting to image the Creator, and thus the images, while different, can be said to form a family. Thus being as being could be thought of as the universal community of images of the Creator, Who is Being itself. For Christian thought, then, the cosmos is understood as the family of beings drawn into community by the analogous universality grounded in the diversity of relations to a common Creator Who is the final cause of all. The dynamics of the community involve both a vertical force, a reaching out, a tension, toward the reality of the transcendent end, and a horizontal force, a reaching out to one another in community. We are involved on both levels with the primordial reality of the reaching out of the Same tmvard the Other, to the extent that we could almost define a thing, a being, as a sameness reaching out toward otherness. Thus, in order to fully understand the analogous community, we must explore it somewhat more deeply in its aspect as a vestigiurn trinitatis. II If being is understood as the community of beings which are mutually other yet belong together, then we can say that, in one aspect, the basic structure of being consists of the triad of the Same, the Other, and the Relation which unites them SPACE-TIME AND THE COMMUNITY OF BEING 485 while maintaining and requiring their mutual otherness (since without otherness there could be no relation). This parallels the Trinitarian community consisting of the Father as primary identity, the Son as difference or otherness emerging out of that identity (and hence as the principle of form, of intelligibility, of limit, the Word or Logos), and the Spirit as the love uniting them. But this three-sided structure with its roots in the inner life of God is also in some sense the very structure of created being, that is, it enters essentially into the composite structure of being. We have, that is, the primary identity of each thing with itself, the otherness with which the non-self confronts it, and the mutual reaching out of the self and the other toward one another. Self and other in relation, community, is the primary structure of being. If we try to eliminate the threefoldness of the structure, we end up with something less than existent being, we end up, e.g., with pure sameness or pure otherness. This becomes clearer if we look closely at the classical dualities by which the composition of created being has been characterized, e.g., matter and form, substance and accidents, etc. Clearly, these are in reality not dualities but trinities. Each involves an element of sameness (e.g., matter, substance), an element of otherness (e.g., form, accident), and the relation which unites them. Without the relation which makes them an organic unity, they dissolve into their components and the fact that they are at all becomes incomprehensible. Let us take substance and accidents as an example: If accidents do not in some way inhere in substance so that the substance itself is truly modified by them, and if the substance itself is not truly present in the accidents and manifest in them, then we have neither substance nor accidents because there is nothing of which the substance is a. substance (it is not related to anything) , nor is there anything for the accidents or appearances to manifest. 7 What we are left with is a stratified 7 For an extended discussion of this issue, see Risieri Frondizi, The Nature of the Self: A Functional Interpretation (Southern Illinois University Press, 1971). 486 GEORGE A. KENDALL picture of things in which each thing has two layers, one of which is an immutable substance and the other a constantly changing flow of phenomena, neither of which has any demonstrable essential connection to the other-they are simply put together like a sandwich to make a " thing" which, however, is no real thing, but only a flow of chaotic appearances behind which one would like to believe is a noumenal something wholly inaccessible to knowledge or experience. The point of the above is that what we have by virtue of this threefold constitution of being is a situation in which there is a complete unity which yet pre-supposes clear distinction and otherness, the unity of community. And the relation which constitutes community has a kind of subsistent reality itself because community itself is always more than the sum of the parts which enter into it. Relation, one might say, is that which prevents the components from being flat and twodimensional, that by which the same stretches out, reaches out, toward the other. It is the principle of tension by which existents stand out and are both in their sameness and their otherness. The various dualistic systems of thought attempt to eliminate the three-sided structure and then replace it with a twosided or even (paradoxically) a "one-sided" structure (keeping in mind that "monism" is, in reality, simply a truncated dualism, a dualism which rejects one side of the duality but still pre-supposes it as that which is being negated) . The nature of this problem emerges more clearly when we consider that much of contemporary thought centers around the effort, usually unsuccessful, to overcome such dualisms as mind and body, male and female, etc. Modern dualism exemplified by thinkers such as Descartes, appears to have its spiritual source either in a rejection of existence or in an inability (of whatever etiology) to rea1ly see and appreciate the texture of created existence, perhaps reflecting a need to assert human dominance over a passive universe and thus to negate the presence of existence, i.e., of the act of existence which gives a SP ACE-TIME AND THE COMMUNITY OF BEING 487 thing an independent and unique, active reality, not reducible to anything else. In any event, with the loss of the appreciation for existence, there emerge which in a certain sense retain the elements of sameness and otherness but remove relation and thus really eliminate sameness and otherness as components of existence, reducing them to subjective concepts which need not be submitted to. Now much of contemporary thought is in fact an effort to overcome such dualisms. The problem is that when thinkers who lack an awareness of the trinitarian structure of reality try to do this, they generally attempt to reduce these dualities to a monistic unity rather than to restore the three-fold constitution of being. 8 When this happens, the end result is a kind of flattening of the structure of reality as experienced, a kind of removal from it of the vivid " standing out" of existents as unique othernesses bound to one another in community. Since it appears to be by and in this three-fold structure that we have the straining, the tension, to be and to be more abundantly, one of the things l;:,si: when we flatten the world out into this one-dimensional unity is the straining for immortality (though one could argue that this is not so much lost as suppressed) . But the straining for immortality must be understood as the tension of the created trinity to participate in the life, the community, of the uncreated Trinity. The end result of the suppression of this tension is an immanentism which affirms that "this world" is the only reality but which s The feminist movement is an interesting example: Feminists are correct, certainly, in observing that there is a fundamental disorder in the relations between men and women which, it might be argued, characterizes the modern outlook on sexuality. However, feminism's answer is a defective one because it seeks to eliminate the dualism characterizing the modern O