AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY I GRASP OF BEING I N NUMEROUS PASSAGES, which are to be found scattered throughout his works, Aquinas repeatedly insists that that which is first apprehended or conceived by the intellect is being (ens) .1 But from these statements an initial problem immediately arises. When Aquinas affirms that being is that which is first apprehended or conceived by the intellect is he talking about a priority which concerns the logical order or the psychological order? I shall first of all explain what I mean by these two expressions. By the " logical order " I intend to refer to the order of priority and posteriority which holds between different concepts on the basis of the relations of necessary inclusion and exclusion that hold between the contents of these concepts: between the rationcs that these concepts express. Certain concepts contain as a necessary part of their content the contents of other concepts which therefore need to be understood before they themselves can be understood: these other concepts which precede them in this manner are prior to them in the logical order. 2 1 See In I Sent., d. 8, q. 1, a. 3 c. and ad 3; In I Sent., d. 19, q. 5, a. 1, ad 2 and ad ult.; De Ver., q. 1, a. l; De Pot., q. 9, a. 7, ad 15; S.T., Ia, q. 5, a. 2; S.T., q. 16, a. 4, ad 2; S.T., Ia-Hae, q. 55, a. 4, ad 1; S.T., Ia-Hae, q. 92, a. 2; In I Met., 1. 2, n. 46; In IV Met., 1. 3, n. 566; In IV Met., 1. 6, n. 605; In X Met., 1. 4, n. 1998; In XI Met., I. 5, n. 2211; Sup. De Causis, Pr. VI, I. 6, n. 17 4. 2 "Dupliciter enim dicitur aliquid non possit intelligi sine altero. Aut ita quod non possit intelligi si non ponatur alterum esse . . . Sive ita quod quandocumque intelligitur unum, intelligitur alterum, sicut quicumque intelligit hominem intelligit animal. Et hoc modo "esse" potest intelligi sine vero, sed non e converso: quia verum non est in ratione entis, sed ens in ratione veri ... sed numquam potest intelligi intelligibile, secundum hanc rationem, nisi intelligatur ens. Unde etiam patet quod ens est prima conceptio intellectus." In I Sent., d. 19, q. 5, a. 1, ad 2., 555 556 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. By the " psychological order " I do not intend to refer to the order of the temporal genesis within individual consciousnesses of particular concepts-as it might be studied, for example, by the developmental psychologist. This is a purely empirical matter and one which might well vary greatly from individual to individual. As such, I do not consider this perspective, whilst of great interest in itself, 3 to be of direct relevance to the present consideration. Rather, by the "psychological order " I intend to refer to the order of priority and posteriority which necessarily holds between the various intentional conditions of possibility which must be realized if an act of understanding or intellectual cognition, considered in general, is to be carried out at all. If we now return to the initial problem its import will be immediately evident. After all, Aquinas would hardly identify the logical and the psychological orders, as I have characteried them, and what holds a certain position in one order might well turn out to hold a wholly different position in the other. Nevertheless, as will be seen in the course of this discussion, it seems that for Aquinas being is that which must be attained first in both the logical order and the psychological order. It must be noticed, though, that this primacy or priority which is attributed by Aquinas to our attainment of being in both the logical order and the psychological order only rarely seems to be discussed by him within the one and the same context. Each context where Aquinas affirms that being is that which is first attained by the intellect needs to be considered separately and to be closely scrutinized if one is to arrive at a correct determination of whether the cognitional priority of being which is affirmed in that particular context concerns the logical or the psychological order. Those passages 4 which affirm that being is that which is s See, for example, J. Farrelly, O.S.B., "Developmental Psychology and Man's Knowledge of Being," The Thomist, XXXIX [1975], p. 668-695. concipit quasi notissi4 For example, "Illud autem quod primo intellectus mum, et in quo omnes conceptiones resolvit est ens ... Unde oportet quod AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 557 first known or understood by the intellect in the logical order -ens est primum intelligible secundum rationem-present no great difficulty of interpretation. These contexts simply indicate that being, taken in the sense of the content of the concept of being in general (ens commune) which expresses the "nature" of being (ratio entis) and which is the direct object or proper subject matter of metaphysic, must be understood before it is at all possible to attain a properly metaphysical understanding of the contents of certain other concepts-for example, the transcendentals, the transcendental perfections, and even the categories-when these are understood metaphysically as opposed to the pre-metaphysical understanding of them which is operative in natural science and in everyday life. That is, these various concepts, if they are to be understood in accordance with their properly metaphysical significations, are all posterior in the logical order to the grasp of the " abstract " concept of being in general; and this, because they can only be so understood insofar as they are " grounded " by the intellect, by means of the operation of additio, 5 in the ratio entis.6 On the other hand, those passages which seem to affirm that being (ens) is that which is first grasped or apprehended by the intellect in the psychological order-ens est primum quod cadit in apprehnsione intellectus-give rise to a far more complicated problematic. As I have already intimated, it is clear omnes aliae conceptiones intellectus accipiantur ex additione ad ens." De Ver., q. 1, a. 1, "Ens secundum rationem est prius quam bonum. Ratio enim significata per nomen, est id quod concipit intellectus de re, et significat illud per vocem; illud ergo est prius secundum rationem, quod prius cadit in conceptione intellectus. Primo autem in conceptione intellectus cadit ens: quia secundum hoc unumquodque cognoscibile est, inquantum est actu .•. Unde ens est proprium obiectum intellectus, et sic est primum intelligibile ... " S.T., Ia, q. 5, a. 2. Notice how in this second text Aquinas moves from the priority of being in the logical order to its priority in the psychological order and grounds the former in the latter. 5 For a discussion of the operation of additio see De Ver., q. 21, a. 1. s For the additio of the transcendentals and the categories see De Ver., q. 1, a. 1. For the additio of the transcendental perfections [ vivere, intelligere] see Sup. De Oausis, Pr. XII, 1. 12, n. 281. 558 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. from many passages, 7 that Aquinas is convinced that we must have a certain preliminary grasp or original apprehension of being if we are to understand or know anything whatsoever. But it is precisely at this point that the difficulties commence. As Cornelio Fabro has remarked in this regard: A first clarification concerns the origin of the notion of ens: ·everyone realizes at once the importance of the problem. But it is just as necessary to recognize that the texts of St. Thomas are quite sparing of indications. If St. Thomas, as we have seen, is from beginning to end firm in the position that ens is the primum in every intentional sphere, he says on the other hand, almost nothing on how the human mind grasps such a notion ... how the ratio entis arises in the mind is not mentioned and one does not see how.8 Furthermore, one could well argue that it is precisely this situation that has been responsible for the state of affairs of which Joseph Owens has written: ... the current approaches to Aquinas in the knowledge of existence are at radical variance with one another. The divergencies cannot be explained away by patient comparison of the various ways in which each uses the same terms. They lie rather at the roots of the vital metaphysical thinking in each interpreter ... 9 Just what is the set of problems that emerges from the situation indicated by Fabro? I would suggest that it can be formulated quite succinctly in terms of two questions. 1 For example, "Primo enim quod cadit in imaginatione intellectus, est ens, sine quod nihil potest apprehendi ab intellectu; sicut primo quod cadit in credulitate intellectus, sunt dignitates . . ." In I Sent., d. 8, q. 1, a. 3; " ... dicendum quod id quod primo cadit in intellectu, est ens: unde unicuique apprehenso a nobis attribuimus quod sit ens ... " S.T., q. 55, a. 4, ad 1; "In his autem quae in apprehensione omnium cadunt, quidem ordo invenitur. Nam illud quod primo cadit in apprehensione est ens, cuius intellectus includitur in omnibus quaecumque quis apprehendit." S.T., IaIIae, q. 94, a. 2. s C. Fabro, C.S.S., "The Transcendentality of Ens-Esse and the Ground of Metaphysics," Internationai Phiiosophical Quartedy, VI ( 1966), pp. 423424. 9 J. Owens, C.Ss.R., "Aquinas on Knowing Existence," The Review of Metaphysics, XXIX ( 1976), p. 690. AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 559 The first question is whether the content of the preliminary grasp or original apprehension of being, which according to Aquinas must be first in the psychological order, is simply to be identified with the content of the concept of being in general (ens commune; ens inquantum ens) which is the direct subject matter of metaphysics. 10 But, surely, this could not possibly be the case. According to Aquinas the "abstract" concept of being in general has a content which expresses the ratio entis: " ratio autem entis ab actu essendi sumitur "; 11 " ens dicitnr quasi esse habens "; 12 " ens autem dicitur id quod finite participat esse ". 13 As such, this concept has a content which is not at all either readily orimmediately seized by the intellect.14 Rather, it has a content which, if it is to be seized at all by the mind, requires the performance of a highly sophisticated process of resolutive reasoning 15 a process of reasoning which involves, as its specific and constitutive element, the exercise of that properly metaphysical, third kind, of" abstraction " or distinctio which is the negative judgment of separation.16 The reply that I have just given to the first question gives immediate rise to the second question. If the content of this 10 "Unde oportet quod ad eamdem scientiam pertineat considerare substantias separatas, et ens commune, quod est genus, cuius sunt praedicta substantiae communes et universales causas. Ex quo apparet, quod quamvis ista scientia praedicta tria considerat, non tamen considerat quodlibet eorum ut subiectum, sed ipsum solum ens commune." In Met., Prooemium; " ... est quaedam scientia de ente inquantum est separabile; non enim solum pertinet ad hanc scientiam determinare de ente in communi, quod est determinare de ente inquantum est ens ... " In XI Met., 1. 7, n. 2259. 11 De Ver., q. 1, a. 1, ad 3. 12 In XII Met., 1. 1, n. 2419. 13 Sup. De Oausis, Pr. VI, 1. 6, n. 175. 14 "Unde scientia, quae de istis rebus considerat, maxime esse videtur intellectualis, et aliarum princeps sive domina." In Met., Prooemium. 15' Metaphysica, in quantum considerat ens et ea quae consequuntur ipsum. Haec enim transphysica inveniuntur in via resolutionis, sicut magis comunia post minus communia." ibid. rn "The best discussion of this theme still remains: L.-B. Geiger, 0.P., Abstraction et Separation d'apres S. Thomas," Revue des Sciences Philosophiq1tes et Theologiques, XXIII (1947), pp. 3-40. 560 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. preliminary grasp or original apprehension 0£ being, which we must have if we are to understand or know anything whatsoever, cannot possibly be identified with the content 0£ the concept 0£ being in general, with the ens commune which is the object 0£ metaphysics, just what is it then? Is the content 0£ this preliminary grasp 0£ being at all susceptible to conceptualization? Just what are the details 0£ the process whereby the intellect first grasps or apprehends this content? We are, in effect, back at the problem as it has been formulated by Fabro, but with the addition 0£ the all-important clarification that the content 0£ the preliminary grasp 0£ being is in no way to be confused, let alone identified, with the content 0£ the concept 0£ being in general which is the subject matter of metaphysics. 17 There is indeed a wide, though by no means discontinuous, chasm between our original apprehensiion 0£ being and the metaphysician's conceptual seizure of being in general a chasm which can only be bridged by the transition from everyday, pre-metaphysical, thinking to explicitly metaphysical thinking through a process 0£ resolutio secundum rationem 18 as well as secundum rem, which can only be effected by means of the negative judgment 0£ separation. 17 " This first concept of being is not the being of the science of meta· physics, but rather the most imperfect, confused, potential of all concepts." M. A. Glutz, C.P., "The Formal Subject of Metaphysics," The Thomist, XIX (1956), pp. 64·65. "That our first knowledge of being is not the being of the metaphysician is surely a point of common agreement. St. Thomas stated this as his position on many occasions. Furthermore, it is agreed that mediation is necessary if we are to arrive at a knowledge of being as being, of that common being which is the subject of metaphysics." J. Reichmann, S.J., "Transcendental Method and the Psychogenesis of Being," The Thomist, XXXII (1968), p. 456. 18" Ratio enim ... Quandoque vero procedit de uno in aliud secundum rationem ... resolvendo autem quando e converso, eo quod universalius est simplicius. Maxime autem universalia sunt, quae sunt communia omnibus entibus. Et ideo terminus resolutionis in hac via ultimus est consideratio entis et eorum quae sunt entis in quantum huiusmodi." In Boet. de Trinitate, q. VI, a. 1. AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 561 n If one is even to attempt to resolve the issues that arise within the second question, I would suggest that it is imperative to notice that Aquinas, to the very limited extent that he does so, almost always discusses the preliminary grasp of being, which is first in the psychological order, within contexts where he is primarily concerned with another, but intimately connected, matter. This is the problem of the genesis in the mind of the knowledge of the first principles of the understanding. For Aquinas, knowledge of the first principles is itself necessary as a condition of possibility in the psychological order. They also must be known if we are to understand or know anything at a]l. Furthermore, their emergence in the intellect is founded upon, or derived from, the content of the preliminary grasp of being .19 In several places Aquinas tells us that our knowledge of the first principles, and, by implication, of the content of the preliminary grasp of being from which they are derived, is attained naturaliter. 20 The epistemological status of the propositions which .formulate the first principles is that of being per se nota, or self-evident, to the intellect: in the terminology of modern and contemporary philosophy we would say that they are all " analytic " propositions. 21 The truth of the first principles is self-evident to all who comprehend the meanings of the terms which appear in the propositions which formulate 19 "Naturaliter igitur intellectus noster cognoscit ens, et ea quae sunt per se en tis inquantum huiusmodi; in qua cognitione fundatur primorum principiorum notitia, ut non esse simul affirmare et negare, et alia huiusmodi. Haec igitur sola principia intellectus noster naturaliter cognoscit ... " 0.G., II, c. 83, n. 1678. 20 For example, ". . . primas affirmationes quae naturaliter intellectus cognoscit, ut sunt dignitates ... " In I Sent., d. 19, q. V, a. I. 21 " Ex hoc enim aliqua propositio est per se nota, quod praedicatum includitur in ratione subiecti ... si igitur notum sit omnibus de praedicato et de subiecto quid sit, propositio illa erit omnibus per se nota: sicut patet in primis demonstrationum principiis, quorum termini sunt quaedam com· munia quae nullus ignorat, ut ens et non ens . . ." S.T., Ia, q. 2, a. 1. 562 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. them. First and foremost among these terms is the term "being" ("ens"). Clearly, the meaning of the term" being", which we must know if we are to have any knowledge of the first principles and their truth, corresponds to the content of that preliminary grasp of being with which this discussion is concerned. When Aquinas characterizes as naturaliter our manner of knowing the first principles, and the content of the preliminary grasp of being that they presuppose, does he mean that this knowledge is either innate to the intellect or, in some way or other, a priori to the operation of sensibility·--at least in the sense that it is not derived from it? Is it a knowledge that the intellect, on the occasion of the operation of sensibility, derives from itself and imposes upon, or at least actualizes within, the synthetic sensible image, or "phantasm", which is the product of the cooperation between the external and the internal senses? In other words, is, for Aquinas, the content of our preliminary grasp of being and the knowledge of the first principles derived from it, something akin to a Kantian a priori, purely formal, category: a necessary, "transcendental", condition of possibility which must be postulated if we are to give any satisfactory account at all of the fact that we can perform acts of understanding and knowing? As is well known, this question has been much discussed in contemporary Thomistic circles. Yet, in a way, it is somewhat bewildering that this situation ever came about. Certainly there are a few texts, which are to be found exclusively in the earlier works of Aquinas, which, at first reading, might lend themselves to being so construed as to enable one to argue for a "transcendental" interpretation of the thought of Aquinas on the issue of the original apprehension of being. But do they do so at all at a second, and closer, reading? Let us consider some representative texts: 1. ... just as from the truth of the divine intellect flow into the angelic intellect those innate species by which it knows all things; so from the truth of the divine intellect proceeds in an exemplary AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 563 way into our intellect the truth of the first principles by which we judge everything ... (De Veritate, q.l, a.4, ad 5) 22 Now, no matter what might appear to be the case at first sight, and no matter what some authors have made of this text, 23 it hardly supports any kind of "transcendental" interpretation. To see this, it suffices to recognize the precise import of the term e;vernplariter which is used to describe the manner in which the truth of the first principles proceeds from the divine to the human intellect. The point, of course, is that everything in creation may be said to proceed in an exemplary way from God 24-and this quite irrespective of the actual manner of generation in the natural order proper to any one thing in particular. If we bear this in mind, then it becomes obvious that in this context Aquinas is not really telling us anything at all about the actual process whereby the first principles, and the preliminary grasp of being from which they are derived, emerge in the intellect. An argument for a "transcendental " interpretation which bases itself on this text simply carries no logical force at all. Quite possibly all that Aquinas is doing in this text, by the use of exemplarist terminology, is to attempt a degree of reconciliation, on the purely verbal level, with the various illuministic explanations of the first principles which were widely current in his time and were ultimately Augustinian in inspiration. It is interesting to note that this text presents an accommodating exegesis of a text of St. Augustine. 25 It is even more interesting to notice that this seems to be invariably the case with 22 My translation. For an alternative, freer, translation see, St. Thomas Aquinas, Truth, transl. R. W. Mulligan, S.J., Chicago: 1952, p. 19. 2s See for example, J. Donceel, S.J., "Editor's Preface" to E. Coreth, S.J., Metaphysics, New York: 1968, p. 8. 24 "Deus est prima causa exemplaris omnium rerum ... Manifestum est autem quod ea quae naturaliter fiunt, determinatas formas consequuntur. Haec autem formarum determinatio oportet quod reducatur, sicut in primum principium, in divinam sapientiam, quae ordinem universi excogitavit, qui in rerum distinctione cons is tit. Et ideo oportet dicere quod in divina sa pientia sunt rationes omnium rerum ... " S.T., Ia, q. 44, a. 4. 25 See De Ver., q. 1, a. 4, ob. 5. 564 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. similar early texts where exemplarist terminology is applied to our knowledge of the first principles. 26 I would suggest that an analogous situation holds with respect to the frequent use made by Aquinas of innatist terminology in the tenth question of the Q. D. De V eritate,21 a terminology which simply does not appear in Aquinas's later, and less occasional, works.28 2. The same is to be said of the acquisition of scientific knowledge; that certain seeds of the sciences pre-exist in us, namely the first conceptions of the intellect which are known immediately by the light of the agent intellect through species abstracted from sensible objects, be they complex, as the axioms, or simple, as the notion of being, of one and the like, which the intellect apprehends immediately (De Veritate, q.11, a.I) .29 3. Indeed, some men thought that the agent intellect does not differ from our habitus of indemonstrable principles. But this cannot be the case, because we certainly know indemonstrable principles by abstracting them from singulars . . . the agent intellect must exist prior to the habitus of first indemonstrable principles in order to be the cause of it. Indeed, the principles themselves are related to the agent intellect as certain of its instruments, because the intellect makes things actually intelligible by means of such principles ... (Q. D. De Anima, a.5) .80 Both of these texts lend themselves even less to a " transcendental" interpretation. Certainly in the first Aquinas affirms that the content of the preliminary grasp of being and the first principles praexistunt in the intellect. But this preexistence is not meant in any absolute sense. Rather, it is a relative pre-existence: they pre-exist in the intellect only with 2a See for example, Q. Quodlibet., q. X, a. 7. example, De Ver., q. 10, a. 6, c. and ad 6. 2s I would suggest that it is important to notice that the text of De Ver., q. 10, represents the report of a live disputation held in Paris in 1257-58 (see J. A. Weisheipl, O.P., Friar Thomas d'Aquino, New York: 1974, pp. 362-363. To what extent is Aquinas's innatist terminology an expression of not only the Augustinian theme with which this question deals but also a desire to employ a terminology acceptable to his co-disputants? 29 My translation. ao Cited from St. Thomas Aquinas, On the Soul., transl. J. P. Rowan, St. Louis: 1949, p. 62. See also, Q. D. De Anima, a. 4, ad 6. 21 See for AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 565 respect to the acquisition of scientific knowledge. In this context Aquinas is simply affirming what we have already recognized: they are prior in the psychological order. Thus, in the second text, we are told that the agent intellect both precedes in existence and is the cause of the knowledge of the first principles and, by implication, of the preliminary grasp of being. Furthermore, in both texts, we are told a little as to the manner whereby we attain the first principles and the content of the preliminary grasp of being: " cognoscuntur per species a sensibilibns abstractas "; " abstrahendo a singularibus ." Once again, though, Aquinas tells us nothing about the details of this process. Just how do they come to be abstracted from singulars? But on one point there is no doubt. Whatever might be the manner of their emergence in the intellect they are certainly not furnished by the intellect itself, and from itself, in the manner of an a priori formal category. Somehow or other they are derived from, and not just imposed upon, the data furnished by sensibility. 4.... all the consideration of the speculative sciences is reduced to certain principles that man does not necessarily have to learn or find out, lest he be thereby bound to an infinite process. But of these principles he has a natural knowledge and of this order are the indemonstrable principles of demonstration . . . also the first concepts of the intellect as those of " being " and of " one " and the like ... objects of this natural order of cognition are made manifest to man by the light of the active intellect, which is natural to man, by which light things are manifested to us only inasmuch as through phantasms they are made intelligible in act ... phantasms, moreover, are received from the senses, wherefore the source of our knowledge of the aforesaid first principles is from sense and memory ... (In Boet. de Trinitate, q.VI, a.4) .31 5. . .. it is not acquired by demonstration or by any similar method, but it comes in a sense by nature to the one having it inasmuch as it is naturally known and not acquired. For first principles become known through the natural light of the agent intel31 Cited from, St. Thomas Aquinas, The Trinity and the Unfoity of the Intellect, transl. R. E. Brennan, St. Louis: 1946, p. 195. 566 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. lect, and they are not acquired by any process of reasoning, but by having their terms become known. This comes about by reason of the fact that memory is derived from sensible things, experience from memory, and knowledge of those terms from experience. And when they are known, common propositions of this kind, which are the principles of the arts and sciences, become known (In IV Met., 1.6, n.599) .32 In these last two texts that I shall consider we are told, first of all, precisely what Aquinas means when he characterizes both our original apprehension of being and our knowledge of the first principles as taking place naturaliter. By this term he intends to do no more than to insist that they are attained immediately in the sense that their seizure by the mind cannot be the result of a process of demonstrative, or in any way syllogistic-deductive, reasoning. There is no question of either innateness or any other kind of subjective a priori. To see this it is important to notice his extremely cautious terminology: "quasi per naturam "; "quasi ut naturaliter ". Secondly, in both texts we are told just a little more about how we come to know the meaning of the term " being " from which the first principles are derived. We acquire this knowledge by means of an experiential procedure which relies on the interaction of the senses and memory. Nowhere else in his works does Aquinas treat this crucial matter in any greater detail. But just why did Aquinas fail to pay more attention to this issue? The answer, I suspect, is that he was convinced that there was no real need to do so. This, not so much because his philosophical preoccupations were so different from those of our own (post-Cartesian and post-Kantian) times, as because, for him, there might well have been something supremely obvious about that original grasp of being whose content corresponds to the meaning of the term " being " from which we derive our knowledge of the first principles. But if this is indeed the case, what is it that has been neglected and has s2 Cited from St. Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the M etaphysios Aristotle, transl. J. P. Rowan, Chicago: 1961, vol. I, p. 242. of AQUINAS ON TRE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 567 thereby brought about the endless controversies over this issue which have so occupied, and so divided, contemporary Thomists? I would suggest, at least as a tentative hypothesis which can serve as a point of departure for discussion, that the problematic concerning the preliminary grasp of being has arisen because of the quite understandable desire, on the part of twentieth century Thomists, to defend, against competing philosophies, the validity of the Thomistic doctrine of the total abstraction of the universal from particulars. This amply justified concern with the vindication of total abstraction might well, nonetheless, have caused too much emphasis to have been placed on one particular epistemological perspective with respect to the sensible object. That is, the sensible object might well have been considered, quite correctly but possibly far too exclusively, only insofar as it appears to sensible consciousness through the phantasm as potential with respect to intellection. What might have been neglected, if not altogether overlooked, is that the potentiality which characterizes the sensible object is a wholly relative one. The sensible object is only to be characterized as potential with respect to the understanding, by the possible intellect, of the quiddity or nature which is realized within it. A nature becomes actually capable of being understood only insofar as it is abstracted from the phantasm by the agent intellect which impresses it (as the species intelligibilis impressa) on the possible intellect which, once actualized and informed by it, is rendered actually capable of understanding it through the formation of the universal concept (the species intelligibilis expressa or verbum) . But the actually perceived sensible object, as such and of itself, which appears to consciousness through the phantasm, is not at all merely potential but actual. 33 It is this actuality, this being-in-act, of the perceived sensible object as such which, in the psychological order, first confronts the intellect and which, 33 " ••• sensus fit in actu per sensibile in actu." B.T., q. 79, a. 3. 568 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. indeed, "moves" it. 34 What is first encountered by the agent intellect through the phantasm is not the sensible object as endowed with a potentially intelligible quiddity but, rather, the sensible object as actual in sensibility: primum enim quod cadit in imaginatione intellectus est ens. The first encounter between the intellect and extra-mental reality-or, more correctly, between the intellect and any part of that reality of which it is itself a part-is not an encounter with a mere potentiality. It is an encounter between two actualities: 35 the agent intellect and the perceived sensible object in act. Could it not be that it is precisely the grasp of this actuality, this entitas rei,36 which pertains to the perceived sensible object as such and of itself, and before it is in any way quidditative by intellected, which constitutes the content of our original apprehension of being? Could it not be this very actuality, 37 this being-in-act of the perceived sensible object, which is first excised by the agent intellect and by it impressed on the possible intellect as its primary actualization or informatio-as the very "dawn" of its cognitional vitality, a primary " information " whose content corresponds to that initial and most primitive meaning that the term " being" does and can have for the intellect, a meaning which, no matter how rudimentary, still enables the agent intellect to derive from it those first principles of the understanding by whose instrumentality it can then abstract the potentially intelligible aspect of the sensible object-its quiddity or specific nature. If this is indeed the case then there is no great difficulty in seeing just why Aquinas, in the texts that I have considered, repeatedly insists that our original apprehension of being is 34 " ••• phantasmata se habent ad intellectivam partem animae, sicut sensibilia ad sensum. Unde sicut sensus movetur a sensibilibus, ita intellectus a phantasmatibus." In III De Anima, 1. 12, n. 770. as Is not this the "Prima ergo comparatio entis ad intellectum est ut ens intellectui correspondeat ... " of De Ver., q. 1, a. 1? 36 De Ver., q. 1, a. 1. cognoscitur per id quod est in actu et ideo ipsa 37 " ••• unumquodque actualitas rei est quoddam lumen ipsius." Sup. De Oausis, Pr. VI, 1. 6, n.168. AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 569 derived from sensibility. Nor is there any great difficulty in seeing just why, as I suggested, the entire matter was no great problem for him. Ill I shall now present, in the form of a number of points, some general conclusions and a few further reflections which seem to me to follow from the interpretations that I have proposed of the texts that have been considered: 1. There most certainly is, for Aquinas, a preliminary grasp or original apprehension of being. Upon its content is founded our immediate, "natural", knowledge of the first principles of the understanding. Both this content, which corresponds to the most primitive meaning of the term " being ", and the knowledge of the first principles which is derived from it are necessary conditions of possibility for the performance of any act of understanding or knowing whatsoever. They are thus first and second, respectively, in the psychological order. 2. These two necessary conditions of possibility are presupposed by all instances of reasoning-no matter whether it be reasoning in the theoretical sciences, in the practical sciences, in the mechanical arts, or in any aspect of everyday life. Most significantly, as indispensable preliminaries to the mind's performance of its two most fundamental acts of simple apprehension and judgment, 38 they are presupposed by the various types of "abstraction " or distinctio which are constituted by the dynamic interplay of these two acts: the operations of total abstraction, formal abstraction, and negaas" .. , cum duplex sit operatio intellectus: una, qua cognoscit quod quid est, quae vocatur indivisibilium intelligentia: alia, qua componit et dividit: in utroque est aliquod primum: in prima quidem operatione est aliquod primum, quod cadit in conceptione intellectus, scilicet hoc quod dico ens, nee aliquid hac operatione potest mente concipi, nisi intelligatur ens. Et quia hoc principium, impossibile est esse et non esse simul, dependet ex intellectu entis ... ideo hoc etiam principium est naturaliter primum in secunda operatione intellectus, scilicet componentis et dividentis." In IV Met., 1. 6, n. 605. 570 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. tive separation which are operative within, and specific to insofar as they alone can yield to them their proper objects, the theoretical sciences of physics, mathematics, and metaphysics.89 3. Neither the content of the preliminary grasp of being nor the knowledge of the first principles derived from it is in any way some kind of " transcendental " formal element, analogous to a Kantian subjective a priori, category, that the intellect derives from itself and imposes upon, or at least actualizes within, the phantasm. Rather they emerge in the mind, in a non_,demonstrative manner, as the primary actualization of the possible intellect which results from the agent intellect's first encounter with the actuality of the perceived sensible object as such. An actuality, or being-in-act, which manifests itself primordially through the phantasm which presents the sensible object to consciousness. 4. The content of the preliminary grasp of being is not as yet explicitly metaphysical. One is neither a metaphysician, nor is one engaged in metaphysical thinking, solely in virtue of this original apprehension of being which is common to all men. 40 This is because the content of the preliminary grasp of being does not correspond to, and cannot simply be identified with, the ratio entis which is expressed by the concept of being in general (ens commune)--which is the object of metaphysics and can only be attained through negative sepof every man aration. In other words, the apprehensio must be kept quite distinct from the conceptio entis achieved by the metaphysician. 41 Now, undoubtedly, the content of the preliminary grasp of being will serve as the point of departure for that process of resolutive reasoning whereby the 39 See In Boet. de Trinitate, q. V, a. 3. quaedam communia quae nullus ignorat ... " S.T., la, q. 2, a. I. a contrary opinion, "Non senza ragione l' Angelico usa indifferentemente i termini apprehensio ( che sta per percezione intuitiva) e conceptio." L. Bogliolo, S.D.B., "Realismo Moderno e Realismo Tomista," San Tommaso e ii Pensiero Moderno (Studi Tomistici, 3), Rome: n. d., p. 46. 40 " ••• 41 For AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 571 metaphysician is enabled to seize that concept of being in general which is the object of his science-but this matter is beyond the scope of the present discussion. 5. The preliminary grasp of being does not involve any strict conceptualization of being. Its content represents no more than what might be designated as a vague and confused notion of being. That imprecise notion of being which is common to all men who, despite its lack of clarity, make constant use of it as is indicated by their ready utterance of the term " being ". This vague and confused notion of being corresponds quite simply to the everyday meaning of the term " being " when it is taken as having the grammatical form of a nouna meaning which, for obvious reasons, cannot be formulated precisely but can only be indicated descriptively by such phrases as: "that which is present"; " that which is given "; "the factual "-and, most commonly," that which I can touch and see and smell ... " 6. Being, as it presents itself to the mind through the vague and confused notion which is the content of our preliminary grasp of it, reveals itself as endowed with a certain intrinsic structure. It discloses itself as questionable or analyzable in terms of the two acts of simple apprehension and judgment. These two acts represent the intellect's initial response to this intrinmc 42 structure rather than operations whereby the intellect would impose upon particular instances of being initially empty categories which, somehow or other, it derived o.f itself. Of particular instances of being the intellect has no hesitation as to the possibility of addressing them in terms of some initial questions: what is it?-how is it?-is it, does it exist? The first question is answered through simple apprehension which grasps the quod qitid est, or "whatness ", of any particular 42 " ••• duplex est operatio intellectus. Una, quae dicitur intelligentia indivisibilium, qua cognoscit de unoquoque, quid est. Alia vero, qua componit et dividit, scilicet enuntiationem affirmativam vel negativam formando. Et hae quidem duae operationes, duobus, quae sunt in rebus, respondent." In Boet. de Trin., q. V, a. 3. 572 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. instance of being. The second question is answered by the judgment which, in its formal-copulative or "predicative" employment, either affirms or denies certain attributes of any particular instance of being. The third question is answered by the judgment which, in its existential employment, either affirms or denies existence or being of any particular instance of being. It must be noticed that this affirmation or denial of being of particular instances of being is in no way tautological. It represents the affirmation or denial of being, in the sense that the term " being " has when it is taken as having the grammatical form of a participle 43 (the vague and confused notion of being taken dynamically), of being in the sense that the term " being " has when it is taken as having the grammatical form of a noun 44 (the vague and confused notion of being taken statically). 7. The point that must be stressed at this stage is that, as long as the particular instances of being which confront the mind are understood merely in terms of the vague and confused notion of being which is the content of our preliminary grasp of it, the answers which will be given by the mind in simple apprehension and judgment will be of little, if any, explicitly metaphysical import. That is, no matter what these answers will later, from a metaphysical point of view, be discerned as having implicitly attained, simple apprehension and judgment, carried out solely in the light of the vague and confused notion of being, are just not capable of yielding to the performer of these acts anything more than merely everyday, pre-metaphysical, grasps of " whatness ", attributes, and existence. For example, the nature or " whatness " grasped, as pertaining to any particular instance of being, will not as yet be seized as the essence which is related as potential to, and is really distinct from, the participated esse ut aotus essendi 43 " ••• ens ... ab esse quod pertinet ad quaestionem an sit." Q. Quodlibet., q. II, a. 3. 44 " ••• ens secundum quod importat rei cui competit huiusmodi esse." AQUINAS ON THE PRELIMINARY GRASP OF BEING 573 which it receives, determines, and contracts. Similarly, attributes or properties will not as yet be fully understood as accidental forms which inhere in, or adhere to, the substance which is the composite of essence and the actus essendi. Finally, and most importantly, the existence or being (in the sense indicated by the term "being" taken as a participle-the vague and confused notion of being taken dynamically) which is affirmed by the judgment in its existential employment will not as yet represent the seizure, on the part of the performer of the judgment, of the actus essendi in the full richness and originality of its properly. Thomistic understanding. 45 At this, pre-metaphysical, stage the judgment in its existential employment will simply not be capable of yielding to its performer anything more than existence in its everyday sense of " givenness", "presence", "facticity "-as that which will later, foom a properly metaphysical viewpoint, be recognized as being no more than mere esse in actu, existentia. 46 In other words, as long as being is understood solely in terms of the vague and confused notion of being which is the content of our original apprehension of being, it is simply not possible to attain any properly Thomistic metaphysical insights. Their attainment requires much more than that preliminary grasp of being which is readily accessible to, and the common possession of, all men. The attainment by the mind of these insights will only be possible after the seizure of that concept of being in general (ens commime) which, by being " grounded " in the profounder appropriation of esse commune, can do full justice to the ratio entis. To conclude, I should like to insist upon the point that the very viability or possibility of the science of meta.physics, as it was conceived by Aquinas, does not depend merely on example, De Pot., q. 7, a. 2, ad 9. the authentic notion of Thomistic participation calls for distinguishing esse as act not only from essence which is its potency, but also from existence which is the fact of being and hence a "result" rather than a metaphysical principle." C. Fabro, "The Intensive Hermeneutic of Thomistic Philosophy," The Review of Metaphysics, XXVII (1974), p. 470. 45 See it, for 46 "Thus 574 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. whether we do or do not have a preliminary grasp of being. For Aquinas, that this is indeed the case and that this original apprehension of being is derived from sensibility, and is not furnished by the intellect from itself in some a priori manner, is really beyond reasonable dispute. It can be confirmed by a straightforward appeal to the experience of any man. Rather, the very possibility of the Thomistic science of metaphysics will be dependent upon whether, by means of a process of resolutive reasoning effected by negative separation, the mind can have access to that concept of being in general which is the object of this science. But I shall not consider this matter in the present context. MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. Yarra Theologiaal Union Melbourne, Australia IS GOD ESSENTIALLY DIFFERENT FROM HIS CREATURES? RAHNER'S EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION I INTRODUCTION N THIS PAPER we shall discuss two questions concerning the doctrine of God in the theology of Karl Rahner. What is it? On what is it based? In the process, we shall critically examine the relationship between the doctrine of God and Rahner's view of Christian revelation, focusing on the nature of theological method. Analysis will proceed in two ways: comparison of Rahner's method with what I see as the method of scripture (faith seeking understanding) and with that of traditional Thomism as represented by Etienne Gilson. In Foundatians of Christian Faith, Chapter "Man in the Presence of Absolute Mystery," Theological Investigations, volume 4, "The Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology," and Theological ln1Yestigations, volume 11, "The Experience of God Today " Rabner develops his doctrine of God from his concept of absolute mystery which is drawn from human experience of reality according to his transcendental method. This method itself establishes the foundation for answering the first question, as we shall see. In answering the second question it is important that we examine carefully the foundation and determining element for any concept of God and of the creature's relation with God. The following issues will have to be discussed also: the nature of and need for Christian revelation, the role of faith and the kind of relation which exists between the Creator God and creatures. We shall discuss how Rahner deals with the free grace of God's revelation and presence in history while synthesizing creaturely self-tran575 576 PAUL D. MOLNAR scendent experience with grace and revelation according to his transcendental method. Such synthesis perceives the reality of God according to the constructs of natural theology and eliminates any practical need for revelation and faith in the triune God as the only true God. Moreover, we hope to show that the starting point for Rahner's transcendental method [human experience] is the very £actor which causes irreconcilable conflicts for a theology which claims to be a theology based on revelation. Rahner's analysis of experience is profound and has been useful for many in describing the creature's relation with the Creator. But as long as it is thought that our self-transcending experiences provide a point of departure for knowing the true God, Christian theologians will always have difficulty actually distinguishing God from their ideas about Hirn. For scriptural faith the point of departure for knowing the reality of God was and remains God's own free self-manifestation in His historical interventions within the realm of experience. As we shall see, this very point is what Rahner seeks to uphold. But in fact his method causes him to be inconsistent. While he would insist that this historical intervention is what happened in Israel, in Christ and in the Church; his method cannot a11ow him to hold consistently that the only point of departure for knowing the truth about our experiences is the Word of God revealed and active in Christ and the Spirit. Thus, true knowledge of God for Rahner is simultaneously ascribed to the grace of God and to our innate knowledge of absolute being. This claim is actually indebted to the Cartesian method and, as we shall see, it causes logical and theological problems for a theology that claims to be a theology of revelation. Concerning Rahner's doctrine of God, then, we return to the opening questions: What is it? On what is it based? Following Rahner's own outline in Fottndations of Christian Faith these questions can only be answered together by tracing the development of his own logic based upon the transcendental experience of our" horizon." Rahner's doctrine of God begins RAHNER'S EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 577 from the assumption that an experience of one's "horizon " is an experience of God. And this assumption dictates what it is. Therefore, in Rahner's thought, these two questions cannot in fact be separated. Rahner provides no other foundation for this assumption than the idea that man must think and act in light of this horizon. Instead of pointing beyond the circle of human experience to show us that he has in fact spoken about a reality which totally transcends it, he directs us back to our experiences. While Rahner knows God is totally transcendent, his method ascribes even to the philosopher a knowledge of God which would follow a recognition of God's grace revealed in Christ. So, instead of consistently holding scriptural faith as the norm of his theological ontology, Rahner holds that being as experienced within and without the bible is "graced." My suggestion is that a scripturally grounded theology begins and ends in faith. It would allow God the freedom to be the originator as well as the one who completes the process of true knowledge. This would explain why theology has been described as fides quaerens intellectum. 1 Faith in the triune God would be a necessary prerequisite to philosophical reflection for this kind of theology. For Rahner it must be said that, in all three pieces under consideration, the word faith rarely appears. 2 And the idea that the truth of human knowl1 Perhaps the most renowned theologian to use this expression was .Anselm. Karl Barth's book entitled Anselm: Fides Quaerens Intellectum: Anselm's Proof of the Existence of God in the Context of his Theological Scheme, (Richmond: John Knox, 1960) displays a continued interest in this expression as it relates to theological method. 2 See, for e.g., K. Rahner, "The Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology," Theological Investigations. Vol. 4. (Baltimore: Helicon, 1966) 36-73, p. 60. This series, which now includes 20 volumes with several different publishers, hereafter will be abbreviated TI; the publishers, where different, will be indicated. Where Rahner does mention faith, the meaning of the word is defined by his transcendental method. Thus, its biblical meaning is distorted. Since Rahner deduces the meaning of faith from the "primordial mystery" which everyone always experiences (our term or whither or absolute being) he thinks that we must nnderstand biblical faith too as pointing to this experience and not to something outside it. This, of course, distorts the very 578 PAUL D. MOLNAR edge is determined solely by the object of the Christian faith would be unworkable in his system. In fact, Rahner's identification of the immanent and economic trinity 3 illustrates his meaning of biblical faith, since what determines truth for Rahner is our experience of our "whither" and faith in it as something that is always present. What determines truth for Paul (whom Rahner cites here) is the risen Lord alone. For Paul faith is true faith when it points to Him alone. Cf., e.g., 1Cor.12:3. a Rahner, "The Concept of Mystery," pp. 70-71. For more on the dogmatic problems involved in this identification see Paul D. Molnar, "Can We Know God Directly? Rahner's Solution from Experience," in Theological Studies, vol. 46, no. 2, pp. 228-61, pp. 230ff. and 248ff. A recent article by Leo J. O'Donovan, S.J. "A Journey into Time: The Legacy of Karl Rahner's Last Years," Theological Studies, vol. 46, no. 4, pp. 621-646 raises several objections to an analysis of Rahner's method, presented in my article in TS. His basic objections rest on the assumption that philosophy and theology indeed investigate the same object. What is demonstrated in that article, however, is that Rahner's dogmatic identification of the immanent and economic trinity, his definition of transcendental revela· tion and his theory of quasi-formal causality all compromise any true dis· tinction between philosophy and theology in the traditional sense. All of these terms follow from Rahner's method and in effect claim a direct relation between Creator and creatures which I have argued is excluded by the scriptural revelation. The author did not realize that Rahner's theology of the symbol, which, according to his own presuppositions, is put forward as an instance of an application of a general principle of being without restrictions (TI 4: 226-8) actually is the very factor which forces Rahner to reduce the trinitarian self-revelation to an instance of the general pattern of being necessarily expressing itself in se and ad extra. The problems with this thinking are analyzed extensively in that article. O'Donovan also cites "Numerous other inaccuracies of interpretation," of which he is only able to present three-all three of which are themselves inaccurate representations of what I actually stated in the article. The first asserts that I hold that the Trinity may be "defined." The point of the article clearly states that, although Rahner insists that God, in his transcendence always escapes definition he does in fact define Him according to the philosophical category of the nameless and in that way blurs the distinction between the immanent trinity and " absolute being." The second asserts that "the idea of 'pure nature' has no practical significance." The word practical in this context clearly means what Rahner means by "existential." And since Rahner holds that in existential reality man never exists without grace it is not at all inaccurate to interpret Rahner to mean that, practically speaking, "man ... is not ... pure nature ... but is mixed up with trace elements from actual nature, and hence its state of grace, (Tl 4: 187, "Nature and Grace"). The third asserts "that a symbolizandum RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 579 synthesis of the Christian God with the idea of God drawn from the self-transcending experience of Christians. Accordingly, what determines truth is the idea of God drawn from the experience of man's term, i.e., absolute being.' Rahner's method assumes that the Christian doctrine of the Trinity confirms this experience and the knowledge derived from it. In this paper we hope to show that wherever this assumption is at work, a scriptural theology of revelation cannot be held consistently and a clear distinction between philosophy and theology cannot be attained. A. God Rahner's presupposition for knowing God precludes dependence on the free revelation attested in scripture as I have described it above at the outset. Since he is a being who is " entrusted into his own hands and always in the hands of what is beyond his control," 5 Rahner assumes man is " a being oriented towards God." 6 Probably no one would deny that we and its symbol are ' identical.' " If the actual quote is read in context it is quite clear that the meaning of the word identical is the meaning Rahner himself attaches to the word when he describes the immanent and economic Trinity as strictly identical. It is clearly a symbolic ontological identity of essence which is distinct from but mutually determined by its appearance. Insofar as Rahner " identifies " the immanent and economic Trinity then it is perfectly appropriate to speak of symbolic identity since it is his theology of the symbol which provides the framework for understanding the nature of this " identity." 4 See, e.g., Rahner, " The Concept of Mystery," p. 49 where Rabner writes: "we begin ... with the finite spirit's transcendence, which is directed to absolute being." On p. 50 Rahner calls this "whither" of transcendence God. On this point see also Tl 11, "The Experience of God Today," (New York: Seabury, 1974), pp. 149-165, pp. 149-53ff. 5 K. Rahner, Foundations of Christian Faith: An Introduction To The Idea of Christianity. (New York: Seabury, 1978), p. 44. See also TI 4: 52 where Rhaner writes: " The Whither of transcendence is at no one's disposal. ... " TI 11, p. 151 expresses the same idea. By experiencing himself this way man is placed into "that mystery which reduces us to perplexity, which controls us and is not controlled by us." For more on this see Foundations of Christian Faith, hereafter abbreviated as Foundations, p. 42. 6 Rahner, Foundations, p. 44. See also Tl 4: 49 and TI 11: 153. 580 PAUL D. MOLNAR are all in some sense in the hands of what is beyond our control. But the fact that there are always things in life we cannot control neither proves that there is a God nor that we are oriented to this God rather than opposed to Him. By this assumption Rahner is compelled to describe knowledge of God as an orientation of human being according to his transcendental method. The meaning of the term God, for Rahner, is neither taken from scriptural revelation nor from dogmatics but from "this orientation to mystery." 7 This is why, for Rahner, "At this point theology and anthropology necessarily become one." 8 For Rahner, knowledge of God represents man's explication in reflection of "what is already present in his transcendentality." 9 p. 44. See also TI 4: 49 where Rahner writes: 7 Rahner, Foundations, "We inquire therefore into man, as the being who is orientated to the mystery as such, this orientation being a constitutive element of his being both in his natural state and in his supernatural elevation." s Foundations, p. 44. Rahner works out the logic of this insight in his Christology TI 4, " On The Theology of the Incarnation," pp. 105-20, p. 116. Rahner writes, "And if God himself is man and remains so for ever, if all theology is therefore eternally an anthropology ... man is forever the articulate mystery of God." See also TI 9, "Theology and Anthropology," (New York: Herder & Herder, 1972), pp. 28-45, p. 28 where Rahner writes, "anthropology and Christology mutually determine each other within Christian dogmatics if they are both correctly understood." 9 Foundations, p. 44. As usual the same idea is repeated in all of Rahner's pieces. See e.g., TI 4: 50 where Rahner writes: "All conceptual expressions about God, necessary though they are, always stem from the unobjectivated experience of transcendence as such: the concept from the pre-conception, the name from the experience of the nameless." On this point see also Tl 4: 57. See also TI 11: 149 where Rahner writes: "The so-called proofs of God's existence . . . are possible . . . only as the outcome of an a posteriori process of reasoning as the conceptual objectifications of what we call the experience of God, which provides the basis and origin of this process of reasoning." Thus, for Rahner the task is to "reflect upon an experience which is present in every man . . ." (TI 11: 150-51). Since this is so theology means "we can only point to this experience, seek to draw another's attention to it in such a way that he discovers within himself that which we only find if, and to the extent that we already possess it." (TI 11: 154). See also Foundations, p. 21 where Rahner writes: "The knowledge of God is always present unthematically and without name, and not just when we begin to speak of it. All talk about it, which necessarily goes on, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 581 Now, i£ God is free in the scriptural sense described above, Rahner's claim that knowledge 0£ God is always present in man's striving for " being as such " 10 illustrate the problem of harmonizing reason and revelation according to his method. According to such presuppositions man's very nature forces him to continually transcend his present experience toward something beyond. While there is no reason to doubt this experience, any claim that this is true knowledge 0£ God compromises the freedom of the Christian God; for this God is especially free in relation to such necessary strivings. We hope to show a real conflict between reason and revelation here which is solved only by revelation. 11 Rahner begins analyzing the term God by analyzing man's experience 0£ himself, and concludes: " The mere fact that this word exists is worth thinking about." 12 What does the word mean? " The present form 0£ the word reflects what the word refers to: the ' ineffable one,' the ' nameless one ' who does not enter into the world we can name as part 0£ it ... it expresses the whole in its unity and totality ... It means that which really is wordless." 13 Thus, Rahner writes " the word ' God ' which no longer refers by itself to a definite, individual experience, has assumed the right form to be able to speak to us 0£ God." 14 For Rahner, the term God signifies the "single whole of reality" and "the single whole" of man's existence. 15 And this is a significant insight. For it leads Rahner to conclude that " If the word ' God ' really did not exist, then neither would always only points to this transcendental experience as such, an experience in which he whom we call ' God ' encounters man . . . as the term of his transcendence ... " For Rahner's explanation of his method see Foundations, pp. 24-39. 10 Foundations, p. 35. 11 See text, infra, passim. 12 Foundations, p. 45. 13 Foundations, p. 46. For the same idea see esp. Tl 4, pp. 50·5lff. and Tl 11: 157, 160. 14 Foundations, p. 46. 15 Foundations, pp. 47-48. PAUL D. MOLNAR those two things exist any more for man, the single whole of reality as such and the single whole of human existence in the mutual interpretation of both aspects." 16 The word God " asks about reality as a whole and in its original ground." 17 Rahner does not rigorously distinguish between the reality of God and the word God. The fact that the word exists gives it a reality all its own. " This word exists, it belongs in a special and unique way to our world of language and thus to our world. It is itself a reality, and indeed one that we cannot avoid." 18 Indeed "We should not think that, because the phonetic sound of the word ' God ' is always dependent on us, therefore the word ' God ' is also our creation. Rather it creates us because it makes us men." 19 What creates us and makes us men? Apparently it is the synthetic word-reality which is "the totality of the world and of ourselves." 20 "This real word confronts us with ourselves and with reality as a whole, at least as a question. This word exists. It is in our history and makes our history. It is a word." 21 Rahner continues, "It is our opening to the incomprehensible mystery . . . it is itself the final word before wordless and worshipful silence in the face of the ineffable mystery." 22 B. Knowledge of God For Rahner, then, knowledge of God is really inseparable from one's transcendental experience of the world. It is a posteriori in the sense that it " is an a posteriori knowledge 16 Foundations, pp. 47-48. p. 49. Because Rahner believes this he identifies ontology with natural theology and natural knowledge of " absolute being" with knowledge of God, TI 4: 52. For more on this point see TI 1: 79-148, "Theos in the New Testament," esp. pp. 81-83 and 133. Compare Rahner, Hearers of the Word, (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969), hereafter abbreviated as HW, pp. 8ff. and pp. 53-68. 18 Foundations, p. 50 and TI 11: 160. 19 Foundations, p. 50. How or why a word can create us is not explained. 20 Foundations, p. 50. 21 Foundations, p. 51. 22 Foundations, p. 51 and TI 11: 160. 11 Foundations, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 583 from the world." 23 This is what Rahner describes elsewhere as categorical knowledge of revelation. 24 On this view "man's basic and original orientation towards absolute mystery," constitutes an experience of God. 25 And this experience is a " permanent existential of man as a spiritual subject." 26 Any conceptual proof for God is therefore simply a reflection on this "orientation towards mystery." 27 What proves the existence of God here is the fact " that speaking of God is the reflection which points to a more original, unthematic and unreflexive knowledge of God." 28 Foundations, p. 52. Karl Rahner and Joseph Ratzinger, Revelation and Tradition. Quaestiones Disputatae, 17. Tr. W. J. O'Hara (New York: Herder & Herder, 1966), pp. 13-21. For a similar idea see also HW, pp. 114-15. See also below, pp. B4-B7 and Foundations, pp. 153ff. 25 Foundations, p. 52 and TI 4: 42ff., 49ff., and TI 11: 155-56. Rahner ap· peals to the Vorgriff (prior apprehension) as the factor which guarantees this (p. 155). On this point see also HW, pp. 53-68, esp. p. 59. See also pp. 66-67. Cf. also K. Rahner, Spirit in the World, Tr. William Dych, S.J. (New York: Herder & Herder, 1968), hereafter abbreviated as SW, pp. 142· 44 and 156ff. 26 Foundations, p. 52 and TI 4: 49ff. 21 Foundations, p. 52 and TI 11 : 152ff. 2s Foundations, p. 52. Of course Rahner thinks this way because, in addi· tion to categorical revelation, he presumes the existence of what he calls transcendental revelation, Revelation and Tradition, pp. 13-21. Transcendental revelation refers to man's direct experience of the ontology of God himself via the incarnation and grace. For Rahner it is God's quasi-formal self. communication to man which accounts for man's "' entitative' divinization," i.e., "a transcendental divinization of the fundamental subjective attitude, the ultimate horizon of man's knowledge and freedom, in the perspective of which he accomplishes his life" (Revelation and Tradition, p. 16). This, for Rabner, is man's grace given supernatural existential. Thus, for Rahner, the visio beatifica is the direct apprehension of God, given by God himself. In reality it is the object of man's initial dynamism of spirit which recognizes being in general (TI 4: 60-61). Thus, Rabner describes grace as "an inner, objectless though conscious dynamism directed to the beatific vision" (TI 4: 61). And this insight leads directly to Rahner's explanation of the Creator/creature relationship in terms of a quasi-formal alteration in the knowing subject. See e.g. TI 4: 65-67ff. and p. 54, and 61 and also TI 1: 319-346 "Some Implications of the Scholastic Concept of Uncreated Grace," pp. 328-31. See also Foundations, pp. 118ff. and Chapter 5 where Rahner works out the logic of this theory of quasi-formal causality 23 24 See 584 PAUL D. MOLNAR Rahner insists that knowledge of God does not mean knowledge of something new coming from without but that "We are oriented towards God." 29 And because " This original experience is always present" everyone already knows God as he or she knows himself or herself. 30 "This unthematic and ever-present experience, this knowledge of God which we always haV'e ... is the permanent ground from out of which that thematic knowledge of God emerges ... in philosophical and the change in the structure of the creature, esp. at p. 149. See also Paul D. Molnar, Theological Studies, pp. 240ff. It is Rahner's quasi-formal explanation of the Creator/creature relationship that goes beyond the traditional distinction between nature and grace and ascribes true knowledge of God directly to man in his self-knowledge. That is why Rahner feels free to describe God's grace as a conscious dynamism of the creature whereas in fact, if one were to distinguish clearly nature and grace, one could never describe any creaturely activity as anything more than a creaturely activity. Leo O'Donovan, S.J., Theological Studies, p. 625 misses this point by assuming that Rahner's quasi-formal explanation of the operation of God's redemptive grace preserves this distinction, p. 626. It does not in fact even recognize it. Of course the real problem here which the author does not address is whether one can describe creation after the Fall as intrinsically open to God at all without becoming Pelagian in one's doctrine of God. 29 Foundations, p. 53, TI 4: 54, 61, 65-67ff., and TI 11: 156. so Foundations, p. 53. See also TI 11: 155, 161. This is why, for Rahner revelation has its existence in man's consciousness and is indeed subject to the structures of the knowing subject. " It [revelation] has its existence in man's own conscious thought and hence is subject to the a priori structure of human knowledge" ( 11: 91, "Reflections on Methodology in Theology") . .And this leads directly to the idea that knowing ourselves means knowledge of God. See TI 11: 154 and TI 13: 122-32, "Experience of Self and Experience of God," pp. 124-5ff. For Rahner "experience of God constitutes the enabling condition of, and an intrinsic element in the experience of self ... " Therefore " The experience of self is the condition which makes it possible to experience God" (p. 125), It is Rahner's concept of the luminosity of being which allows him to think this way. (See HW, pp. 39 and 43 and TI 4: 49. For Rahner there is an original unity between knowing and being.) See e.g. Foundations, pp. 149ff. for more on this idea of luminosity. Rahner writes of Revelation that it is " a modification of our transcendental consciousness produced permanently by God in grace. But such a modification is really an original and permanent element in our consciousness as the basic and original luminosity of our existence. .And as an element in our transcendentality ... it is already revelation in the proper sense" ( p. 149). See also Foundations, p. 132 for more on this. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 585 reflection . . . we are only making explicit for ourselves what we already know implicitly about ourselves in the depths of our personal self-realization." 31 At this crucial stage in the development of Rahner's doctrine of God it is clear that while Rahner believes God is free, his method of synthesizing natural and revealed theology causes him to believe that any proof of God's existence stems from an experience of ourselves. This methodological assumption compromises God's independence in relation to human experience and reflection. Thus, " The meaning of all explicit knowledge of God in religion and in metaphysics . . . can really be understood only when all the words we use there point to the unthematic experience of our orientation towards the ineffable mystery." 82 According to his method this is the foiindation for the doctrine of God. Everyone has an experience of an horizon that cannot be controlled which Rahner calls an experience of the reality of the transcendent God. Thus, when one is oriented towards what philosophy recognizes as mystery or absolute being it can legitimately be assumed that one is speaking about the scriptural God. Eventually Rahner claims that this "being" is identical with the immanent Trinity. 33 31 Foundations, p. 43, emphasis mine. Also, pp. 2lff. and TI 11: 154-55. p. 53. Emphasis mine. This same idea is expressed in TI 4 using the category of the " whither," pp. 50ff. and again in Tl 11: 149 and 150. For example Rahner writes: "But surely both together, the initial experience and the subsequent reflection, make it justifiable to speak of the 'experience of God today' ... " ( p. 150, emphasis mine). Cf. also TI 11: 159 where Rahner writes: "What is meant by God is to be understood on the basis of this experience . . ." (emphasis mine). " This experience is no mere mood, no matter of mere feeling and poetry carrying no conviction ... For it is present irremovably, however unacknowledged and unreflected upon it may be, in every exercise of the spiritual faculties even at the most rational level in virtue of the fact that every such exercise draws its life from the prior apprehension [Vorgriff] of the all-transcending whole which is the mystery, one and nameless. It is possible to suppress this experience, but it remains ... " ( 11: 159). Please Note: All that Rahner has offered here as proof for God as an independent entity confronting us, is our experience of ourselves in relation to our innate apprehension of an all-transcending whole. 33 Tl 4: 71-2. Why? Because "The three mysteries, the Trinity and its two processions and the two self-communications of God ad extra in a real 32 Foundations, 586 PAUL D. MOLNAR According to this description we do not have to wait upon God to reveal Himself at particular historical moments because it is assumed that this orientation to "mystery," which orientation and mystery can be adequately described by the metaphysician, and therefore what " we call God " 34 is truly the totally other, the God of Christianity. Now, how can Rahner say that God is truly transcendent and free and that both philosophers and theologians know Him in this way? In other words, the obvious question here is: if God is really transcendent (in the scriptural sense), then why does He not transcend this orientation, experience and definition as well? While Rahner would say it is this scriptural God we know, his very method renders such a God totally unknowable. 35 Indeed Rahner's presupposition is that formal causality corresponding to the two processions, are not 'intermediate mysteries.' They are not something provisional and deficient in the line of mystery which comes between the perspicuous truths of our natural knowledge and the absolute mystery of God, in so far as he remains incomprehensible even in the beatific vision. Nor are they as it were mysteries of the beyond ... behind the God who is for us the holy mystery." Obviously this is all true for Rahner because he really believes that what natural theology calls God and what Christians call God are one and the same thing. This, because of the luminosity of being. In fact, of course, the only way this could be true is if God were not free but subject to the a priori structures of the knowing subject. See also, Tl 4: 228. 34 Foundations, p. 54. 35 Cf. TI 11: 159. Our Vorgriff would not innately correspond with it. See text infra. See also SW where Rahner maintains that if God is an "absolutely 'unknown,' something 'coming from without' in every respect, [he] is not knowable at all to a human subject according to Thomistic principles" (p. 182). Such a God would not be subject to the a priori structures of the human mind since there would in fact be no original unity between knower and known. This insight would destroy Rahner's concept of luminosity as applied to God. Rahner could not hold his important insight that man is (via the species impressa) entitatively assimilated to God (Tl 1: 327-8). His entire theory of quasi-formai causality is based on this insight. Rahner cannot actually maintain a real distinction between philosophy and theology because of this. So in his philosophy of religion he maintains that man cannot prejudge whether revelation has occurred (HW, pp. 173-4). This view apparently maintains the freedom of God's revelation as unmerited and incalculable grace. But how do we know of this grace? Because we must reckon with God's silence. And here is Rahner's problem. There cannot possibly be RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 587 no reality at all, including God, transcends the limit of experience accessible to the metaphysician. Such a reality, says Rahner, could never be known. 36 Thus, being in general is the limit of Rahner's doctrine of God. God's being cannot transcend this. And of this "being" man always does have a "prior apprehension " (Vorgrifj) against which he interprets his experiences. So while Rahner the theologian insists that God is free, Rahner the philosopher assumes that the true 1iotirce of our knowledge of God is-" the transcendental experience of our orientation towards the absolute mystery." 37 In fact, because experience of orientation is the determinant here, Rahner's approach cannot conceive God actually existing apart from human experience: " we can speak of God and the experience of God ... only together." 38 Thus, " a radical distinction between a statement about ' God in himself' and ' God for us' is not even legitimate." 39 Identifying the immanent and ecoa real divine silence on this view since Rahner has already presupposed that his philosophy of religion, by which he knows this silence, is a " condition that is itself created by God's speaking" (HW, p. 174). And the fact that this is not a real possibility for God is confirmed by Rahner's belief that if God did not speak, man by nature could hear at least his silence (HW, pp. 16, 172, 175). This confusion of course invalidates any real distinction between what philosophy discovers as revelation and what the Christian believes is God's free revelation. 36 Foundations, p. 67. Being in general is the limit of all knowledge for Rahner. Rahner writes: "Our proposition about the comprehensibility of being in itself did indeed arise from the fact that in the first question about being every possible object of cognition is already anticipated under the aspect of being in general. There can, therefore, be no existent thing that does not automatically and objectively fit into the context of being in general. For this very reason every thing is comprehensible" (HW, p. 96). The same ideas are expressed in Foundations, pp. 24ff. 37 Foundations, p. 54 and TI 11: 159-60ff. 38 Foundations, p. 54. Also TI 11: 159 and TI 4: 50-1. This follows from his belief that being and knowing form an original unity, thus, "The question as to the ultimate cause of the possibility of subsisting-in-oneself is thus identical with the ultimate cause ... " (HW, p. 57). 39 Foundations, pp. 54-5. This is why Rahner has to insist on the identification of the immanent and economic Trinity-TI 4: 79-2. On any other view we would have a merely formal reconciliation of natural and revealed theology, i.e., of " one and three" (TI 4: 71) . 588 PAUL D. MOLNAR nomic Trinity is necessary for Rahner because he cannot conceive of the permanence of the humanity of Christ in any other way, and because our " experience of the incarnation and grace " 40 make it impossible that the being of God which man knows by reflecting upon himself be different from the being of God revealed. Because the starting point for knowledge of God is our experience of "mystery," 41 Rahner describes a "more original unity" 42 among 1) natural theology, revealed theology and 3) knowledge of God attained from "experience of existence," perhaps from mystical experience or visions. 43 This derives from historical experience itself. And knowledge of it "contains elements which subsequent theological reflection will appeal to as elernents of grace and revelation." 44 Moreover, "Everything which we say here about knowledge of God ... refers to a more original experience." 45 Rahner says this is not "natural philosophical knowledge of God" though in part it is.46 His point is that this experience of mystery (God) is what he will appeal to as the validation of his doctrine of God. 47 1. Revelation-Grace To the extent that Rahner includes grace and revelation as " elements " in our experience it is impossible to distinguish clearly between philosophy and theology, reason and revelation, and ultimately between nature and grace. Thus, for Rahner, "There is no knowledge of God which is purely natural." 48 And grace is not defined only as the free charis 40 TI 4: 68 and 72. TI 11: 155: 42 Foundations, p. 56. 43 Foundations, p. 55. 44 Foundations, p. 56. Emphasis mine. 45 Foundations, p. 56. 46 Foundations, p. 56. 47 Cf. also Tl 4: 53-4. 48 Foundations, p. 57. Obviously this is true for Rahner because "grace pervades the essence of man from his very roots with divine influence, and 41 Cf. also RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 589 of God revealed in Jesus, 49 but also as our orientation towards " the immediacy of God." 50 This means nothing other than thereby gives him the possibility of acting positively for his own salvation, and so implants in him a free and active tendency towards his own consummation" (TI 10: 273-289, "Immanent and Transcendent Consummation of the World," p. 280). It is precisely because the creature is endowed with this modality that " the difference between 'inner and outer' breaks down at this point. The orientation towards the self-bestowal of God as most radically different from the creature is the innermost element of all in it ... " (TI 10: 281). Thus, for Rahner's descriptions of experience, "it is no great loss if the analysis of man as potentia oboedientialis is not a ' chemically pure ' presentation of pure nature but is mixed up with trace elements from actual nature, and hence from its state of grace" (TI 4: 165-188, "Nature and Grace," p. 187; also TI 9: 28ff.). See also Foundations, Chap. 4. Because Rahner maintains that nothing but this "holy mystery" by which man always lives "even where he is not conscious of it" (TI 4: 54) is the true God ["He would not be God if he ceased to be this holy mystery" (TI 4: 54, emphasis mine)] Rahner concludes that "Grace and the beatific vision can only be understood as the possibility and the reality respectively of the immediate presence of the holy mystery as such" (TI 4: 55). "Grace ..• makes God accessible in the form of the holy mystery and presents him thus as the incomprehensible" (TI 4: 56). Thus, for Rabner, even God's grace cannot be different from the "absolute being" we all know and experience and define as God based upon our self-experience. Grace and glory for Rabner manifestly mean that we cannot control the horizon of our own existence. And this may be so. But this uncontrollability hardly means we have seen or recognized grace as an act of a God existing independently of this experience. From all this Rahner concludes that knowledge of God "has always been familiar to us" and indeed is "self-evident " (TI 4: 57; also 11: 161). Furthermore "Mystery is already there with the very essence of the natural and supernaturally elevated being of man" (TI 4: 59). It is clear that, having insisted that the being of God conform to what natural theology discovers as God on the basis of experience, Rabner must insist that graoe, i.e., knowledge of God revealed, is present all along "with the very essence of the natural ... being of man." Thus, there is no real distinction between nature and grace at this point. Indeed Rahner finally concludes that grace is "an inner, objectless though conscious dynamism directed to the beatific vision" (TI 4: 61). And the beatific vision is just a term that Rabner applies to the highest possible description of an immediate experience of God. 49 Cf. Ex. 33: 19, Mt. 10: 8, Rom. 11: 5f., Eph. 1: 5f. Grace is the incomprehensible free gift of God's turning to the creature which we cannot merit. It implies forgiveness of sin. See also Ex. 34: 9, Rom. 5:20 and Ps. 103: Bf. 50 Foundations, p. 57. 590 PAUL D. MOLNAR our " orientation towards absolute mystery." 51 " We call this orientation grace and it is an inescapable existential of man's whole being." 52 This clear synthesis of nature and grace is no mere accident of Rahner's thought. It is the unavoidable consequence of his method. At one and the same time he believes he can know the scriptural God, revelation and grace and also deduce their meaning from the experience of" not being at one's disposal." 53 This he assumes is an experience of" mystery" which he terms the experience of God. 54 So he thinks that when we experience our inability to control all this we are actually experiencing God. 55 "The transcendence in which ('y0d is already known ... may not be understood as an active mastering . . . of God himself ... By its very nature subjectivity is always a transcendence which listens, which does not control." 56 Rahner then makes his distinction between nature and grace identical with the distinction between our finiteness (being grounded in mystery) and the experience that this is not at one's disposal. This is described as the " unity between transcendence and its term." 57 The terrn or goal of this orientation or transcendence Rahner calls God. 58 It could have "a 51 Foundations, p. 52 and TI 4: 6lff. p. 57, emphasis mine, and also pp. 25 and 34. 53 Foundations, pp. 57-59, 43 and 75-76. See also TI 1: 156. See also TI 4: 51 where Rahner writes: "The whither of transcendence is at no one's disposal," and TI 4: 53 where he writes: "For the Whither ... the nameless being which is at the disposal of none and disposes of all ... we can call ' holy' in the strict and original sense." 54 TI 4: 54. " If man himself is therefore to be understood as the being of the holy mystery, it also follows that God is present to man as the holy mystery." 55 TI 11: 156, 160 et al. 56 Foundations, p. 58. This would have been a strange insight especially for the Johannine community or for Paul to accept. 57 Foundations, p. 58. Note that this is an exact rendering of the ontological principle of luminosity as Rahner has understood this. 58 Foundations, pp. 59-60. TI 4: 62. See also TI 11: 153 and 156. Rahner writes: " God is present as the asymptotic goal, hidden in itself of the experience of the limitless dynamic force inherent in the spirit endowed with knowledge and freedom" ( p. 153). See also TI 13: 123. 52 Foundations, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 591 thousand other names." 59 It could be "' absolute being' or ' being in an absolute sense ' " or the " ' ground of being ' which establishes everything in original unity." 60 Rahner calls it "the holy mystery." 61 His ultimate goal is to show that the term or source of our transcendence is " identical with the word ' God ' ... We must first describe the experience and the term together before what is experienced can be called God." 62 From this series of presuppositions it is perfectly logical for Rahner to conclude that God is experienced whenever we experience our term, horizon or the nameless and indefinable. Rahner contends that because the horizon (the term of transcendence) is infinite, it is not only not at our disposal, but it cannot be given a name. 63 In this way Rahner attempts to preserve God's freedom and transcendence. There is, however, a very serious and frequently overlooked problem with this position. If it were truly impossible to name this term-if it [the term] were truly transcendent and free-then it actually could not be conceptualized. Rahner, however, does name this term of experience the "nameless." It should be noted quite clearly that the idea of the "nameless " serves a very definite function in his thought from the very beginning. It is our experience of our horizon which is the basis, foundation and norm of knowing God. Thus, this term is not really unnameable. It is quite able to be categorized -but as that in human experience which is not at our disposal. This is an extremely significant point. Because Rahner conceives Creator and creatures under the dialectically necessary umbrella of an original unity between knower and known 59 Foundations, p. 60. It really makes little difference to Rahner what we name him since the term God refers to an experience on the basis of which that which we all experience (the term) is what "we call God" (TI 11: 159.). See also n. 127 below. 60 Foundations, p. 60. 61 Foundations, p. 60, TI 4. 53. 62 Foundations, p. 61. 63 TI 4: 37, 42, 53, 60. "The name God is the nameless infinity" (TI 4: 60). Also 11: 159. God, for Rahner, is "the all-transcending whole which is the mystery, one and nameless " (TI l l : 160). PAUL D. MOLNAR (horizon, term, nameless, mystery), his presuppositions do not permit a God who is free in the scriptural sense described above. So when he describes what is wrong with pantheism and dualism in a Christian doctrine of God he is unable to escape the pantheist dilemma. Against dualism Rahner writes, The difference between God and the world is of such a nature that God establishes and is the difference of the world from himself, and for this reason he establishes the closest unity precisely in the differentiation. For if the difference itself comes from God, and, if we can put it this way, is itself identical with God, then the difference between God and the world is to be understood quite differently than the difference between categorical realities ... God to be sure is different from the world. But he is different in the way in which this difference is experienced in our original, tmnscendental experience. In this experience this peculiar and unique difference is erperienced in such a way that the whole of reality is borne by this term and this source and is intelligible only within it. Consequently, it is precisely the difference which establishes the ultimate unity between God and the world ... 64 If God alone establishes and maintains the world in existence then the difjerence between God and creatures must be grounded in God alone. But then it could not be said that " God is the difference of the world from himself," since, as other, He alone establishes and maintains the world in its difference without ceasing to be God. Then, Rahner would have to admit, however, that we truly cannot experience our radical dependence on a transcendent other simply by experiencing our horizon since we are identical with our horizon and not with God. Thus, to experience our distinction and union with our term may be necessary. But it is not necessarily an experience of God. In fact, according to the scriptural view, nothing in creation is identical with God. And so, in a Christian doctrine of God where the method was dictated by this fact, one would have to acknowledge a continuing difference of essence between Creator and creatures. This would mean that faith in the Creator would be necessary to perceive 64 Foundations, pp. 62-3. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 593 and to maintain a clear and sharp distinction here without falling into pantheism or dualism. Rahner makes many distinctions since he knows that the Christian God is free, but he makes no such distinction and cannot because, according to his method he assumes that God and man are already one in intellectu. Thus, while Rahner insists that God is free to be silent, his method causes him to describe a God who is not really free to reveal himself or not. 65 Indeed, for Rahner," God is the most radical, the most original, and in a certain sense the most self-evident reality." 66 The important point here is that Rahner's definition of mystery is an ontological definition of man's relation with his horizon, which horizon is necessary as the condition of conceiving or experiencing anything. 67 This term is mystery because, logically enough, it is " nameless " and " not at our disposal ". 68 This terrn or mystery cannot be defined, even 65 See also TI 6: 71-81, "Philosophy and Theology," p. 75. Rahner writes that Revelation "presupposes as a condition of its own possibility the one to whom this revelation remains unowed." Also HW, p. 168. Rahner writes: "there would be no word of God were there no one who was at least intrinsically capable of hearing it." See also HW, p. 92 where Rahner writes: " In virtue of his nature as spirit, man constantly and essentially hears a revelation from God." Since, for Rahner, revelation occurs as a transcendental necessity of man's spirit which includes grace Rahner even writes: "revelation occurs of necessity," (HW, p. 93; see also HW, pp. 20, 94-6 and 147ff. See also Foundations, p. 172. 66 Foundations, p. 63 and TI 4: 57. See text, infra. 67 For more on this see HW pp. 66-7 where Rahner writes: "A revelation from God is thus possible only if the subject to whom it is supposed to be addressed in himself presents an a priori horizon against which such a possible revelation can begin to present itself in the first place." Thus, for Rahner, "God does not for his part initiate the relationship; he is already implicit in the openness of this relationship ... " (HW, p. 66, no. 9). This, of course, is why Rahner maintains that man by nature can come to terms with revelation and can perceive it (Tl 1: 83). This, because the whole of nature has always been " imbedded" in a supernatural context (TI 1: 81). Obviously that is why, for Rahner, natural knowledge of God and theological knowledge based on revelation cannot contradict each other. 68 Foundations, pp. 64-5. Obviously Rahner did not just invent this idea. He got this from the fact that " man experiences himself as being at the disposal of other things, a disposal over which he has no control," Founda- 594 PAUL D. MOLNAR by the Vorgnff Rahner insists. But the conflict which I have tried to illustrate here is that he has already defined it conceptually by the terms nameless, horizon, condition of the possibility, absolute being and holy mystery. This inconsistency is traceable to Rahner's starting point for his doctrine of God as noted above: one's unthematic experience of the absolute. He is unwilling to begin his transcendental method solely by acknowledging the normativity of the scriptural revelation. Instead, Rahner insists that this terrn is not only a mystery which can be described philosophically; but it is a "holy" mystery which we must worship. 69 And this synthesis of the object of philosophy and of theology represents the conflict of his method once again. It becomes even clearer when Rahner's thought is compared with Kant. Q. Rahner and Kant Rahner neither wishes to ignore Kant's critiques of pure and practical reason nor does he wish to leave us purely on the level of ideas. So, he insists that all of this is not just something going on in the mind of man because if this were true then we " would lose all connection with the original experience." 10 Does this assertion really overcome Kant and actually ref er us to God (a true transcendent other independent of us) ? Does this assertion point to anything beyond a regulative idea drawn from practical reason (man's experience of self-trantions, p. 42. Now this experience can hardly be disputed. But as a proof for the reality of God who transcends such an experience it presupposes what is not proven and is thus inadequate. This inadequacy follows from Rahner's method. He thinks he has discovered the being of God by examining man'g term. Thus, he writes: "there is and can be only one proof: in the whole questionable nature of man seen as a totality ... " TI 9: 127-44, "Observations on the Doctrine of God," p. 140. See also TI 11: 149. 69 Foundations, p. 66. See also TI 4: 61 and 67. On p. 67 Rahner writes: "We can therefore affirm at once with certainty that the two mysteries of incarnation and grace are simply the mysteriously radical form of the mystery which we have shown to be the primordial one, from the point of view of philosophy of religion and also of theology: God as the holy and abiding mystery ... " 10 Ji'Qitnd«tions,r· 67 and TI ll : 159-60, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 595 scendence) ? I do not see how these questions are answered by this assertion. In faithfulness to his method Rahner assumes that the universality of the experience proves that it cannot be just an idea. "For this term is what opens up and makes possible the process of transcendence. Transcendence is borne by this term, and this term is not its creation." 71 Yet, on the crucial question of what proves that this idea of a term determining the validity of our experiences, actually corresponds with a real and true " being," a Ding an sich, Rahner passes over the question and assumes that because we cannot describe our experience without this idea of a term or horizon-it must be real. So, while Kant asked metaphysicians to prove this connection between idea and reality, Hahner simply assumes it and by making that assumption he never really answers him. Thus, Rahner concludes: "The affirmation of the reality of the absolute mystery is grounded for us, who are finite spirits, in the necessity with which the actualization of transcendence as our own act is given for us." ' 2 Because the foundation for and validation of knowledge of God is a " self-validating" experience of one's horizon, Rahner, once again, does not conceptualize any independent freedom for God. "The basic and original knowledge of what 'being' is comes from this act of 71 Foundations, p. 67 and TI 11: 160. p. 67. Emphasis mine. The foundation for all of this in Rahner's thought is what was described above as the luminosity of being. Because Rahner assumes an original unity of the knowable and its cognition (HW, pp. 40-1) he argues that they "must derive from a single origin" (p. 41). Thus, the problem of objectivity for Rahner is solved by his assumption of this original unity between subject and object which necessarily must be deduced from the knowing subject. It is precisely on the basis of this insight that Rahner develops his notion of the pre-concept (Vorgriff) (HW, pp. 53-68) as part of man's subsisting-in-himself which is self-validating. Rahner assumes it is self-validating because of his assumption of the original unity between knower and known. So for Rahner our experiences are selfvalidating. And if you don't have one you simply cannot know what he is talking about, according to him. He writes: "We must experience here what mystery is, or we shall never understand its true and perfect sense" (TI 4: 53). 12 Foundations, 596 PAUL D. MOLNAR transcendence, and it is not derived from an individual existent which we know. Something real can encounter us only in knowledge, and to state that there is something real which is a priori and in principle inaccessible to knowledge is a selfcontradictory statement." 73 And according to his method that must be so. But the only way this can be true is if man possesses innately knowledge of every possible reality. Yet this possession is just what Kant called into question. If God is not an individual existent which we can know, then there is no real knowledge of God in his uniqueness and otherness as one who loves. And indeed if he is not an e3.:istent which truly is inaccessible to human insight, then he is not a real transcendent other at all; since he is accessible necessarily and always as we must affirm him as the term of all our transcendental acts. It should be stressed that by assuming that knowledge of God is a universal experience of man as he is. Ra:hner has precluded any real transcendence or freedom for God independent of what human experience ascribes to him. Thus, while it is clear that Rahner has profoundly indicated that we cannot leave the sphere of experience and reflection to know the transcendent God, he has not shown that knowledge of God is a free human response of faith to God's confrontation of His creatures in Christ and the Spirit as expressed in scripture. Rather, " In the act of transcendence the reality of the term is necessarily affirmed because in this very act and orily in it do we experience what reality is." 74 Here is the crux of the matter. It is here that the creature either needs God, grace, revelation and faith or has them as part of his ontology; in which case theology will never escape the appearance of redefining God, revelation, grace and faith as elements which can be seen and described without the need to choose between a strict philosophical and theological method. 73 Foundations, p. 67 and TI 11: 150. On p. 160 of TI 11 Rahner insists that this kind of God does not exist today. 14 Foundations, p. 68. Emphasis mine. Cf. also TI 11: 155-6, 159. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 597 3. Pantheism The hallmark compromise of the divine freedom implied by the creatio ex nihilo is the fact of mutual conditioning which determines Rahner's thought in significant ways. For Rahner there can be no God without man as there can be no man without God. This is because Rahner identifies knowledge of God with the necessity of affirming our horizon. Again, Rahner would certainly insist that God is free precisely because He is nameless. But the question I have raised here is whether the term of our experience which Rahner has described truly is nameless. For if it were, God would then be inaccessible to human insight. We would not be able to know him by experiencing ourselves. As I have suggested above, however, Rahner's method begins precisely by naming the nameless because he assumes there is an original unity between knower (man) and known (God). "We have discussed both the holy mystery, which exists absolutely and which we call by the familiar name 'God,' and our transcendence to this holy mystery together. In the original unity of this transcendental experience, the two are mutually dependent on each other for their intelligibility." 75 And indeed they are. But what has Rahner described here? According to his own presuppositions he has described man's original experience of his unity with the one and all of created being. We do not have to believe in the God of scriptural revelation to describe this mutually dependent relation. 75 Foundations, p. 68. For an example of Rahner's statement regarding proofs for the existence of God see Foundations, p. 69 where he writes: "That which does the grounding is itself grounded, as it were, and what is present in silence and without a name is itself given a name." Because Rahner thinks this way he actually maintains that "God confers on man the power to make a genuine answer to his Word, and so makes his own further Word dependent upon the way in which man does in fact freely answer" (Tl 1: 111). This follows again from his assumption that "In any act of cognition it is not only the object known but also the knowing subject that is involved" (Tl 11: 87). Indeed "It [knowledge] is dependent not only upon the object, but also upon the essential structure of the knowing subject . . . they mutually condition one another" ( p. 87, emphasis mine). See also Tl 4: 49 and HW, 39-41, 43. 598 PAUL D. MOLNAR Thus, this description of God does not result from faith seeking understanding. In order to describe the Christian God there would have to be a clear statement that His particular freedom precludes the idea that He can be described in revelation and grace as mutually dependent in this way. Faith in the Creator means knowledge of one who freely acts for us. This implies that He is dependent on no one and nothing to be and to be our God ad extra. Rahner's identifying knowledge of God with the necessity of affirming one's horizon then prevents him from speaking of God as an individual existent confronting man at specific points in history. And yet it seems to me that this is exactly the kind of act which scripture envisioned when it referred to God's grace and revelation. Whereas in scripture God is the Lord of Israel and the one who is revealed in the events of the cross and resurrection, for Rahner He is the " inconceivable and incomprehensible single fullness of reality. This fullness in its original unity is at once the condition of the possibility both for knowledge and for the individual thing known objectively." 76 Thus, the proofs for the existence of God express this experience of union and distinction between oneself and the ground of this experience, i.e., the term (horizon) .77 The metaphysical principle of causality itself comes from the same experience. 78 Thus, this principles too proves to Rahner that in his analysis of the experience of transcendence and its term he has truly described the Creator-creature relationship. Yet this is possible because Rahner has actually synthesized both Creator and creature under a metaphysical notion of being drawn from an experience of " absolute being." 79 Thus, all proofs of God spring from this " same transcendental experience." 80 76 Foundations, p. 69. Foundations, p. 70. 78 Foundations, p. 70. Rahner insists that causality should not be inter- 11 preted as in the natural sciences but in terms of experience of our term. 79 Foundations, p. 71. so Foundations, p. 71. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 599 4. Analogy of Being Rahner also re-defines the analogy of being using the transcendental method. We do not learn about God "from something which does not have much to do with God." 81 Because " transcendental experience is the condition which makes possible all categorical knowledge of individual objects, it follows from the nature of transcendental experience that the analogous statement signifies what is most basic and original in our knowledge." 82 Thus, for Rahner, analogy cannot mean a similarity between two utterly different beings [Creator and creature] which do not exist in an original ontological unity. It must mean " the tension between a categorical starting point and the incomprehensibility of the holy mystery, namely, God. We ourselves, as we can put it, exist analogously in and through our being grounded in this holy mystery which always surpasses us." 83 Here, as elsewhere, Rahner seems to maintain God's freedom and human freedom by distinguishing our categories (human freedom) from the holy mystery which always surpasses us (divine freedom) . But, inasmuch as this "holy mystery" has already been categorized as part of the very structure of created being and mutually determined by our experience of it, the problem of how to envision God's freedom remains. If this holy mystery is the Creator God existing utterly in Himself and in whom we can only believe, then it cannot logicaily be described as the necessary term against which all human knowledge takes place, i.e., the metaphysical idea of absolute being. This assumption by Rabner allows him to think he can describe God as the absolute instance of a general principle of being. Thus, when Rahner defines God as person he writes: "The statement that 'God is a person' ... is true of God only if, in asserting and understanding this statement, we open it to the ineffable darkness of the holy 81 Foundations, p. 72. s2 Foundations, p. 72, emphasis mine. sa Foundations, p. 73. 600 PAUL D. MOLNAR mystery." 84 When asked where our philosophy receives its content Rahner would say: " from our historical experience." 85 Consequently, while he intends to do a theological ontology, his method leads him to make the experience of self the foundation, norm and source of understanding God, revelation and grace. 86 The rest of Rahner's doctrine of God simply works out the logic of this "transcendental" reflection on experience. "Man implicitly affirms absolute being as the real ground of every act of knowledge ... and affirms it as mystery. This absolute . . . which is always the ontologically silent horizon of every intellectual and spiritual encounter with realities, is therefore always infinitely different from the knowing subject." 87 While this may be true I would say we cannot therefore leap to the conclusion that this absolute being is the Christian God. For in a Christian doctrine of God we speak of one who is of a completely different being and nature from the absolute being conceivable as the" single whole of reality." 5. Creatio Ex Nihilo At this point in his discussion in Foundations of Christian Faith Rahner explains the creation "out of nothing." 88 It is a clear expression of the fact that for the Christian theologian creation can in no sense be seen or described as necessary to God without denying God's freedom. But the conflict between philosophy and theology surfaces here once again. Though Rahner intends to maintain God's freedom in se and in revelation and though he states this eloquently, he does not realize that his method, which distinguishes us from God by distinguishing us and our term, cannot actually preserve the freedom he describes as a theologian. So while he writes: " God 84 Foundations, p. 74. p. 74. 86 Foundations, p. 75. None of this is contradicted in volume 4 or volume 11 (text 18ff., and 3-15 pp. supra). Both articles insist on the same point. 87 Foundations, p. 77 and also TI 4: 50. 88 Foundations, p. 78. 85 Foundations, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 601 does not become dependent on the world, but remains free vis-a-vis the world and grounded in himself," 89 his thinking does not bear that out consistently. Attempting to preserve human and divine freedom, Rahner says God does not become an object of categorical knowledge, which knowledge always involves mutual necessity between cause and effect and presumably leads to the definition of causality envisioned by natural science but which is inapplicable here. 90 Thus, Rahner is faced with the problem of explaining how we (in our categories) actually know God while maintaining His freedom. Instead of turning to the God of scriptural relevation he answers from his method by saying that God is the " absolutely distant term of the transcendence within which an individual finite thing is known." 01 And this answer demonstrates again the logical and theological problem involved in synthesizing natural and revealed theology as in the following dilemma. Either Rahner may argue that we have no categorical knowledge of God since he is free. This would preserve creaturely and divine freedom and point us to revelation as that which authenticates our concepts. Our concepts would be limited and would point beyond that limited range only when God intervened to enable it. But then, of course, Rahner would have to maintain that we have no real knowledge of God by reflecting on ourselves apart from scriptural faith in the triune God. Or he may argue that knowledge of our term. (which of course has to involve categories-the nameless being a category too) is real knowledge of God; in which case he has in fact denied his own description of God's freedom. But he cannot logically argue both that God is free (that we have no categories for him) and that we know him as the "term" of our spiritual dynamism. What is it that leads Rahner to believe he has maintained God's freedom here? Clearly, it is 89 Foundations, p. 78. Foundations, p. 70. 91 Foundations, p. 78. Emphasis mine. Do 602 PAUL D. MOLNAR the idea that God is the horizon we all experience necessarily as that which is " not at our disposal." 92 So, by conceptually making this" term" not just remote but" absolutely distant" Rahner believes he is maintaining the freedom of the Christian God. But the problem here is that no matter how distant this term may be, Rahner and any philosopher can still describe it (categorically) as the holy mystery, absolute being, the nameless or as Rahner himself stated " by a thousand other names," and indeed as the Creator God of Christianity, without ever believing in the triune God. Insofar as this is thought possible, the freedom of God implied by the Christian creatio ex nihilo recedes into the baokground since the transcendental method must claim a true knowledge of God as part of an experience of one's horizon. And whenever this assumption is the starting point of a doctrine of God, Christian revelation, which sees the scriptural word as its only norm for truth, becomes more a conclusion than a starting point for reflection. Onoe this happens it is hard to see why we would need Christian revelation in any practical way. 6. Categorical-Transcendental Revelation By removing knowledge of God from the realm of the categorical and placing it into the realm of experience Rabner posits an original unity between Creator and creatures. 93 Thus, this cannot be understood without an experience of freedom and responsibility. At this point Rahner applies his method to the scriptural understanding of God, revelation and grace. We know God " in a transcendental experience in which the subject ... is experienced as being borne by an incomprehensible ground . . . the absolute mystery which is not at our disposal ... Creatureliness, then, always means both the grace and the mandate to preserve and to accept that tension of analogy which the finite subject is ... " 94 92 See text pp. 6ff. and TI 11: 159-60. Foundations, p. 79. This is the more "primordial he presumes exists and defines in TI 4: 38ff. 94 Foundations, p. 80. Emphasis mine. 93 unity of the spirit " RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 603 The same procedure takes place in Theological Investigations, volume 4, " The Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology," and again in volume 11, "The Experience of God Today." And the results reveal once again how difficult it is to describe vevelation and grace as free acts of God calling for faith seeking understanding once it is assumed that experience can be a starting point equal to scripture in this matter. The transcendental method excludes the idea that a special inconceivable act of God within experience is the sole source of truth. Thus, the key to interpreting lectures two and three of Theological Investigations, volume 4, " The Concept of Mystery ... " is to realize that what dictates Rahner's view of incarnation, grace and glory and his identifying the immanent and economic Trinity is not a special inconceivable act of God. It is not the revelation of something previously hidden as it might be in scholastic school theology. Rather it is the fact that he believes each of these represents the radical proximity of God to creatures in their self-transcending experiences. That is why Rahner's distinction between nature and grace, reason and revelation and philosophy and theology can be perfectly clear in one description and become quite obscure in another. Each of these " supernatural " mysteries is taken by Rahner as a truth confirming one's unity and distinction with absolute being (mystery'-term-horizon) which one always experiences. Thus, incarnation, grace and glory are not truths that reveal something totally beyond the sphere of human experience. Rather they simply confirm that the holy mystery is indeed always present as the term of our experience is present. Consequently, the immanent and economic Trinity is identical and God's radically close relation with creatures can only be expressed in terms of quasi-formal causality. 95 While Rabner the theologian insists that truth is grounded in the triune God, in Christ and in grace, he is led increasingly away from a specifically Christian interpretation of those concepts as he applies his method. The operative principle of his method asserts that theological and philosophical truth can be known from 95 See Molnar, TS, pp. 240ff., 245-Sff. for more on this problem. 604 PAUL D. MOLNAR man's experience of and interpretation of himself. The problem here is that the triune God, Christ and grace tend to become instances of his general transcendental principles. In volume 11, "The Experience ... " Rahner writes: The experience of God to which we have appealed ... is not necessarily so a-Christian as appears at first sight. On the contrary ... it is precisely Christianity which makes real this experience of God in its most radical and purest form, and in Jes us Christ achieves a convincing manifestation of it in history . . . This experience of God ... really constitutes the very heart and centre of Christianity itself and also the ever living source of that conscious manifestation which we call ' revelation.' . . . Through this experience of God Christianity itself simply achieves a more radical and clearer understanding of its own authentic nature. For in fact in its true essence it is not one particular religion among others, but rather the sheer objectivation in history of that experience of God which exists everywhere in virtue of God's universal will to save all men by bestowing himself upon them as grace ... 96 Why should Christianity and not other religions possess this obj,ectivity? If the experience of God exists everywhere as this statement indicates then why should Christian experience be any more authentic than any other religious experience? Rahner intends to preserve Christianity's uniqueness but again his method explains that uniqueness as an instance of his general principle of being applied to human experience. Consequently, as a Christian theologian Rahner maintains Christianity is the " pure form " of an experience of God which all religions describe. Yet, this creates more problems than it solves. For if truth is contingent on anyone's experience of God then any statement that Christianity is the " purest " expression of religious experience can only make it appear that Christian experience is somehow inherently better than other religious experience. The problem which I have tried to present in this paper surfaces here once more. Any attempt to explain the objective uniqueness of Christianity by pointing to our subjective experience interpreted philosophically or religiously will always 96 TI 11: 164. Emphasis mine. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 605 describe grace and God's universal will to save as properties of creaturely being. Yet if scriptural faith and revelation are normative, then it is clear that the objective uniqueness of revelation never resides in anyone's religious experience, but in the uniqueness of the Christian God acting ad extra in free revelation and free grace. Rahner's argument would have been more convincing had he held that a Christian's experience is not one among others because it is tied to Christ alone. Instead he argues it is not one among others because it is a more radical form of what everyone experiences. Thus, Rahner believes that Jesus is a "convincing manifestation" of our self-experience in history. Yet, if this is so, it is hard to know why he was crucified and not installed as king of Israel or heralded as the solution to the philosophical problems of the Greeks. 97 If Rahner's norm here had been the word of God revealed he would have realized that Jesus (as true God and true man) brings us all that we, in our religious experiences cannot procure for ourselves, i.e., God's inconceivable act of revelation and salvation manifested in his life, death and resurrection. The prophets and apostles were witnesses to that truth. He would have realized that describing this self-sufficient revelation of a free God as a "conscious" or unconscious manifestation in ourselves compromises the very objectivity he sought to maintain. Instead of presenting Christianity as the purest or most radical form of religion he would have been more able to show that everyone, including Christians, depends always upon God's free grace for salvation and for objective verification of these truth claims. Christians cannot point to any religious experience or set of experiences as the pure or true form of religion any more than anyone from another religion can do it. This, because God's grace al,one makes "religion" true existentially and theoretically. Thus, Christians are those who actively live this truth. 98 97 Cf., e.g., 1 Cor. 2: 8. Acts 11: 26. The word Christians was first used at .Antioch to refer to the disciples who accepted the teaching of the apostles. Rahner's difficulty 98 Cf. 606 PAUL D. MOLNAR Rahner's conclusion really goes beyond the limits of theology to the extent that the principles of his method dictate the solution to this problem. He writes: "It is, therefore, a task precisely rfor Christianity itself to point ever anew to this basic experience of God, to induce man to discover it within himself, to accept and also avow his allegiance to it in its verbal and historical objectivation; for, in its pure form and as related to Jesus Christ as its seal of authenticity, it is precisely this that we call Christianity." 99 Is it now the task of Christians to point out to other Christians and non-Christians that they can achieve knowledge of God in this way and that their allegiance is to their experiences of " absolute being " which being can well be explained as a universal human manifestation without faith in Jesus and the Spirit and thus without employing a strictly theological method of faith seeking understanding? Again, it is another question entirely whether Christianity is the " pure form " of this experience at all since Christ actually points us away from any existential or conceptual self-reliance to complete dependence on Him. Thus I would say that biblical revelation is at variance with Rahner's conclusion as we are told that 1ve cannot really achieve knowledge of the true God in this way since we are dependent only on the One Mediator-to whom alone we owe allegiance.100 7. Mediated Immediacy Returning to Foundation of Christian Faith Rabner assumes once again that " grace " is embedded in the world of experience 101 and recognizing that leads to the truth of the Christian here is that he assumes that God's "universal will to save" is identical with grace as a constituent element in human experience. It really is not. And as long as grace is conceptualized in this way there can be no clear distinction between God's will and human experience which in fact is not structurally altered by the incarnation as Rahner thinks. Humans exist in relation to God's salvific act in Christ and the Spirit-not in identity with it. 99 TI 11: 164·5, emphasis mine. 100 See, e.g., Edward Schweizer, Jesus, (Atlanta, 1971), pp. 89-90. This is exactly what happened in Gnosticism. 101 Foundations, p. 81. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 607 doctrine of God. It is worth examining this final assertion by Rahner of how to find God in the world using the transcendental method. Rahner has established two things thus far in Foundations. 1.) · "As ineffable and incomprehensible presupposition, as ground and abyss, as ineffable mystery, God cannot be found in his world." 102 This is his way of insisting that God is free. Yet all religion, including the Christian religion, "declares phenomena existing within our experience as definite and exclusive objectifications and manifestations of God." 103 This is his way of insisting that we, as creatures, can know God. Examples of these phenomena are the pope (as vicar of Christ) and Jesus himself; "in this way God as it were appears within the world of our categorical experience ... " 104 In relation to this theological problem, namely, that God is the ineffable silent term of all knowledge and that religion claims a categorical knowledge of God, Rahner proposes his theory of "mediated immediacy." 105 This theory basically articulates the unity and distinction between ourselves and our horizon or term as discussed above. The conflict between reason and revelation is evident since at one and the same time Rahner affirms indirect knowledge of God through created symbols and experiences and direct knowledge of and experience of God through grace and revelation. It is, of course, this latter affirmation which I believe is excluded by God's freedom (creatio ex nihilo). While Rahner holds the creatio ex nihilo as any theologian would, his philosophical and theological explanations of it categorize grace and revelation as elements within human consciousness-as existentials of man as he exists in the world.106 p. 81. p. 81. 104 Foundations, p. 81. 105 Foundations, pp. 83ff. 102 Foundations 103 Foundations, 10s The reason he thinks this way is that within his system it is completely impossible to conceive of God acting in the incarnation, grace and glory (Tl 4: 66-72) while rema.ining absolutely other than the creature as the naturally 608 PAUL D. MOLNAR Yet, if Christian revelation means God freely reveals Himself in and through history without becoming dependent on known efficient cause. Thus when God acts (imparts himself) in the incarnation, grace and glory, this must take place via quasi-formal causality (TI 4: 67) because this signals the kind of entitative divinization of the transcendental subjective attitude necessary for Rahner's natural theology. Quasiformal causality means that "God imparts himself immediately of himself to the creature" (TI 4: 66) He must do this. Rahner writes: " God as his own very self must penetrate into the non-divine region of the finite" (TI 4: 67, emphasis mine). This, because the triune God can be none other than the holy mystery Rahner discovered as efficient cause from his philosophy of religion (natural theology). As efficient cause, God creates another. God does not act this way in relation to creation. He is "formal " cause acting in creation. The problem here is that the Creator God is not merely an efficient cause naturally known. In fact the Creator God, as efficient cause, is no less than the efficient cause acting in the form (creation). But Rahner cannot conceive of such a God and such a transcendent divine action on and in the creature. This is the case because he insists that revelation of the immanent Trinity cannot contradict the fact that the absolute holy mystery (the efficient cause) is the reality of God revealed. Thus, for Rahner there is no triune God transcending the concept of mystery drawn from experience. That is why, in his trinitarian doctrine Rahner can only conceive of God in his proper reality as the unoriginated origin, while in the incarnation, grace and glory we meet something less than this, i.e., the Real Symbol (Christ) ('PI 4: 228ff, and 237-241). As an example of Rahner's difficulty here consider this statement taken from TI 4: 67 "It is simply contradictory that something should belong completely to the order of creation, by being created, and still belong to the strictly divine order, by being strictly supernatural. Supernatural reality and reality brought about by the divine self-communication of quasi-formal, not efficient type, are identical concepts." This is a clear and necessary synthesis of supernatural and natural reality which must follow from Rahner's method. Rather than thinking of God's grace as his incomprehensibly free act on and in the creature-the act of the efficient cause (the Creator)-Rahner thinks of it as the quasi-formal alteration of the knowing subject, i.e., the reality "brought about" by God's immediate communication of himself to the creature in grace and glory. In fact this is a denial that the incarnation is a mystery of faith as " Scholastic " theology saw it. Isn't that the very mystery of our faith, i.e., that Jesus, being true God and true man, belongs to the creaturely sphere and yet is truly supernatural-no less God than the Creator-the efficient cause? And isn't the real problem of knowing God truly solved only by the fact that in Jesus we have the revelation of the Father (efficient ca use) only be ca use God has acted and does act freely (grace) on our behalf in Jesus and the Spirit? For Rahner's explanation of quasi-formal causality see also Tl l: 329ff. and Foundations, pp. 119-20ff. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 609 history then we really have no direct knowledge of God and any such claim would make our experience more than human or God less than transcendent in order to explain incarnation, grace and glory. The main point of New Testament Christianity is that we, as creatures, can know God truly when our thinking in faith points to his sovereign intervention in history. Sign and thing signified, though seen as related in faith, would not be synthesized. While Rabner continually insists on the distinction between sign and reality, he also synthesizes them to the extent that grace and revelation [what is signified] cannot transcend being in general which we experience and know from philosophy. 107 The New Testament view seems closer to the concept of mystery which Rabner rejects as Scholastic "school theology," since he believes that this view maintains that mystery is obscured and veiled and only accessible to faith. 108 Rabner cannot go along with this because, for him, ratio is a spiritual entity of absolute transcendence and therefore is the very faculty by which the presence of mystery is assured. 109 That is why Rabner asserts that God (as unknown) is included essentially in every act of cognition. 110 The comprehensive concept of mystery which Rabner has in mind 111 107 See text, p. 36, n. 17, p. 38, n. 33 and esp. p. 39, n. 36. For the same idea see also TI 4: 221-252, "The Theology of the Symbol," pp. 234-5 where Rahner writes: They [the principles of symbolic ontology] arise because the concept of being is 'analogous', that is, displays the various types of selfrealization of each being, and being in itself, and hence also the concept and reality of the symbol are flexible. But because these are necessarily given with the general concept of beings and being-as the 'unveiled ' figure of the most primordial 'truth' of being-the symbol shares this 'analogia entis' with being which it symbolizes." Rahner's explanation of God, Christ, Church and sacrament all bear the mark of this thought. For him " the symbol is the reality, constituted by the thing symbolized as an inner moment of moment of itself, [sic.] which reveals and proclaims the thing symbolized, and is itself f'uU of the thing symbolized" (7'I 4: 251, emphasis mine). This is why he thinks there is a mutual causal connection between the sacramental signs and God's grace (p. 240). See also K. Rahner, The Church and The Sacraments, Quaestiones Disputatae 9 (New York, 9163), p. 38. 10s TI 4: 38-40. 109 TI 4: 41. 110 TI 4: 4lff., 49-50. 111 TI 4: 48ff. 610 PAUL D. MOLNAR derives from his consideration of man in his natural and supernaturally elevated state as "oriented toward mystery." 112 This analysis follows from his method. It asserts that man can have a self-validating experience of God, and in that assertion the real need to depend on God's special intervention in history either in Israel, Christ or the Church or by awaiting the coming of the Holy Spirit can no longer be stated with the same clarity and consistency as in the New Testament and in the tradition. For our orientation already contains what scripture and the tradition claim we can only receive as free gift. Rahner clearly recognizes the problem here and states that God could be said to play an indirect role as the " primordial ground" of experience. Or, he says, a person might worship nature as divine or make scientific truth the answer thinking in this fashion. Nonetheless, despite the fact that "it is very difficult to distinguish clearly here between nature and supernatural grace in their mutual relationship " 113 this can be called "natural religion." 114 Here Rahner turns to Christian revelation again to explain God's transcendence and immanence. He says that categories such as sacrament, church, revelation and scripture only point to the " transcendental presence of God." 115 But how can he describe these in terms of "mediated immediacy"? His answer is clear. If God is to remain infinite while encountering us in religion " then this event must take place on the basis of transcendental experience as such." 116 This means that this presence must be a modality of this relationship. Since transcendental experience of absolute being allows for an immediacy of God, it must be true. Again Rahner is consistent in his method by holding that Christian categories do not point to ·specific interventions of God in history which can be seen 112 TI 4: 49. 11s Foundations, p. 85. p. 85. 115 Foundations, p. 85. 116 Foundations, p. 85. 114 Foundations, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 611 only in faith. Rather they point to the " modality of this transcendental relationship." 111 Of course, for Rahner, this modality is man's supernatural existential which he frequently describes in terms of quasi-formal causality. 118 And this explanation is ultimately traceable to his philosophy of the symbol which assumes fusion and mutual dependence of sign and thing signi:fied.119 But, in connection with his doctrine of God, this means " immediacy " to God " must be embedded in this world to begin with." 120 And this follows since he has already assumed that experience of our term (God-the single whole of reality-absolute being) is an inherent experience of man. Thus, religion simply is a moment in and modality of our transcendental and " mediated immediacy to God." 121 But what kind of God can be known directly by knowing the medium (religion) and God embedded in the religious medium? A God who " as the transcendental ground of the world has from the outset embedded himself in this world as its selfcommunicating ground." 122 Rahner clearly intends to say that the Christian God has been involved with the world since the very beginning. But as he explains how we interpret experience of the Christian God according to his method, he cannot really conceive of a God truly existing independently of the world (i.e. an immanent Trinity) . The significance of all this highlights the problem I have sought to clarify in this paper. Because our self experience is both starting point and norm for the question of God and his activity in the world, Rahner believes that the " categorical presence of God " is simply the religious subject objectivating his religious experiences. And as such they [categories-objectivations] perform a" valuable role." Actually" The role indeed 111 Foundations, p. 85. us See text, pp. 18 et al. and esp. p. 44, n. 105, p. 37, n. 28, and pp. 389 n. 35, et al. 119 See, e.g., TI 4: 236 and above, n. 106. Also TI 4: 228ff. 120 Foundations, p. 87. 121 Foundations, p. 87. 122 Foundations, p. 87. 612 PAUL D. MOLNAR really belongs to those phenomena in themselves." 123 This attempt to speak of a God who is and remains free in the scriptural sense ascribes too much to created phenomena. It assumes that all religious experience points to the reality of God insofar as it points to the horizon (term) of human experience. But this is the very assumption which causes Rahner to compromise the scriptural and the traditional distinctions between God (the true God) and his free grace and idols and existentials which might lead us away from the true God and not toward him. Rahner concludes his treatment in Foundations by defining God's intervention in history with an example of what validates our "good idea " which we think corresponds with God's intervention. "The moment I experience myself as a transcendental subject in my orientation to God and accept it, and the moment I accept this concrete world in which ... the absolute ground of my existence unfolds historically for me and I actualize it in freedom, then within this subjective, transcendental relationship to God this 'good idea' [his intervention] receives objectively a quite definite and positive significance." 124 Perceptively, Rahner aisks what is to prevent me from calling anything an intervention of God arguing in this fashion? His answer is: "Why, then, may this not be the case?" 125 How this question is actually answered can be a matter of no small concern to philosophers and theologians. Following the position for which I have argued, i.e., that the God of scripture is truly free even in his involvement in human experience, we would have to say that this may not be the case because God himself is not in any way dependent on anyone or anything to be God in himself or God for us ad extra. 123 Foundations, p. 88. Cf. also Tl 4: 221-252. Symbols must have this function for Rahner because being and appearance are intrinsically and essentially related so that one cannot really exist without the other. See pp. 230-lff. All of this is true for Rahner because he believes that symbols possess an " overplus of meaning" ( 225). See also above, n. 106. 124 Foundations, p. 88. Emphasis mine. 125 Foundations, p. 89. RAHNER'S EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 613 This insight would preclude arguing, as Rahner does, that our orientation to God contributes objectively to the positive significance of our ideas about his intervention in history. The only way Rahner's insight could be true is if the Christian God were in fact " embedded " in the world as a " ground of being " recognizable by the metaphysician and the philosopher of religion as well as by the theologian, thinking within the biblical faith. This is not to say that God cannot be conceptualized as a "ground of being." Obviously, insofar as we all actually depend upon God for our being He is the " ground of being." The question raised here is what specific object determines the truth of our metaphysical concept of God's being? If it is the immanent Trinity acting ad extra in Christ and the Spirit, then we cannot actually begin thinking about Him outside of faith in the Father, Son and Spirit. This would mean that we could not begin thinking about God truly as the " ground of being " prior to an acknowledgement of the unique being of God revealed in Christ and the Spirit. Any attempt to define God as the " ground of being " before believing in the immanent Trinity might lead directly to the conclusion of the Deists, i.e., that Christ is unnecessary really to know God.126 Interestingly, the position which I am questioning here is exactly what must be stated in a philosophy of symbolic reality. 121 But it is just this idea which obscures philosophical and theological investigation. 126 Etienne Gilson, God and Philosophy, (New Haven, 1979), pp. 104-5ff. above, nn. 106 and 121 and Molnar TS, 46, pp. 238ff. and 25lff. See also TI 4: 225ff. Rahner believes that " in the long run everything agrees in some way or another with everything else," (225). Thus, for Rahner, symbols are related essentially with what is symbolized and the two are intrinsically and mutually dependent. All of this is true because what is symbolized " passes over into the ' otherness ' of the symbol " ( 240) . In other words, in a symbolic philosophy, signs and things signified are embedded in one another in such a way that no clear and sharp distinction between them can be made. Clearly, this cannot apply to knowledge of God who is and remains different from the creature in his encounter with creation. This symbolic thinking is exactly what leads to Rahner's insistence on a quasi-formal explanation of the Creator-creature relationship once again (pp. 121 See 614 PAUL D. MOLNAR The philosopher can indeed bypass Christ and attempt to know God. He or she may always discover a " supreme being" but that is the most that can be discovered thereby. The theologian of revelation cannot bypass Christ [and by implication the Old and New Testaments] and attempt to know God. Thus he or she will know that the unity and Trinity of the Christian God would preclude any attempt to define God as a supreme being without allowing Christ and the Spirit the sole freedom to determine the truth of the concept. Then a clear and sharp distinction between the immanent and economic Trinity would be maintained since it would be very clear that the being of God revealed (the immanent Trinity) actually transcends and is different from the being of God recognized by the philosopher apart from biblical faith (supreme being recognized as the term of our experiences of self-transcendence). Because he is faithful to his method (attempting to harmonize natural knowledge of God with revealed knowledge) Rahner is actually unable to resolve this theological problem. Thus, he must maintain that what is categorized, i.e., "the holy mystery," is not conceptually beyond the religious phenomena which, in themselves, are supposed to convey God's grace. On this view the theological question of how we really know that this or that " concept " of God's intervention is true is left ambiguous. For Rahner, of course, the answer resides in his assumption that transcendental experience of one's horizon is a real experience of God simply because people experience themselves this way. And their experiences are selfvalidating. Thus, what "we call" God and his intervention ultimately depends not on God alone but on God as well as the strength of our transcendental experiences. I am arguing that this mutual coordination of God's action in history with 245ff.). The whole problem here centers on the fact that in a Christian doctrine of God-God is and remains ontologically different from his creatures even in the incarnation, grace and glory. There is in fact no original ontological unity between Creator and creatures as there must be for a symbolic ontological explanation of absolute being in relation to finite being. RAHNER'S EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 615 our historical self-experience compromises the unique objectivity and freedom of God envisioned by the scriptural revelation. Furthermore, this assumption by Rahner actually subverts the real need for Christian revelation as an independent source of truth coming to us from something other than our selfexperience. One does not need to believe in God's special presence in history in his Word and Spirit if one already possesses this truth in the experience of his orientation toward the absolute, which absolute may well have little or nothing to do with the eternally triune God of Christianity. 128 In Rahner's doctrine of God then we are told that we need this God. But his method ends exactly where it began, i.e., with man's experience of himself which he" calls" God. 129 And this leads to his theory of anonymous Christianity in which he spells out the implications of this position by maintaining that everyone can know and experience what Christians know and experience in faith simply by having these transcendental experiences. 130 Though 128 See, e.g., Gilson, pp. 105ff. and L. Feuerbach, The Essence of Christianity, (New York, 1957), pp. 50-58. The god of the Deists (cf. Gilson) and the god of Feuerbach are not the Christian God but an apotheosis, a mythological human invention. 129 See Foundations, pp. 53-4 and K. Rabner and K. Weger, Our Christian Faith: Answers for the Future (Crossroad, 1981), pp. 13 and 25. 130 See, e.g., Tl 12: 161-178, "Anonymous Christianity and the Missionary Task of the Church." On p. 161 many additional references to Rahner's treatment of this topic of anonymous Christianity are given. Rahner's position that Christianity is present in everyone in an incipient state (Tl 12: 164) simply confirms the fact that he is consistent in carrying through the logic of his method. If he did not say this he would have to deny that we could know God by knowing our term and that grace was embedded in creation. Ultimately he would have to deny his theory of luminosity and his philosophy of symbolic reality. Because human being is already changed ontologically ( obediential potency and supernatural existential) in virtue of the incarnation Rahner believes that people don't have to hear about Christ to be Christians. Rather, in deciding for or against themselves they already decide for or against God and Christ. The problem with anonymous Christianity is the same problem that is apparent in Rahner's doctrine of God. He never really shows us that we are believing in and knowing anything which truly transcends us and exists in reality apart from our experience and interpretation of that experience. Thus, God, grace, revelation and faith are simply 616 PAUL D. MOLNAR Rahner certainly wished to present a more open view of salvation in this theory, the net effect renders Christianity less rather than more necessary. This, because the pivotal factor which determines the truth of Christianity on this view is to have significant human experiences, beginning with the exqualities of man's experience interpreted philosophically and theologically for Rahner. As long as that is the case we really don't need to believe in Jesus and the Spirit before knowing the true God. And as long as this is the case we shall never answer the theological question of whether what we "call" God, grace, revelation and salvation are true as realities coming to us from a real God independent of us. For Rahner we don't need the grace of God revealed in Christ to explain " reality " to ourselves and others. God merely confirms our transcendental experiences and our interpretations of them. Thus, for Rahner, everyone is a believer whether he or she knows it or not. This, simply because everyone has unthematic experiences of absolute being in order to continue to exist meaningfully in the world. (On this see TI 7: 211-226, "The Eucharist and Our Daily Lives," p. 223). Rahner writes: "there may be many who face up to life bravely ... yet who do not regard themselves as believers at all. But . • . in their calm acceptance of their lives they actually achieve, implicitly and in principle what the conscious and professed believer does explicitly ... " On this same point see TI 5: 3-22, " Thoughts on the Possibility of Belief Today," pp. 12-13. And this leads to speculation like that of the 'questioner ' who poses for Rahner the assertion in Our Christian Faith " that everyone who lives their world-view with determination and co=itment will find that this world-view proves true" ( 19-20). In fact the answer to the question of which " world-view" is true cannot be answered by examining anyone's determination and commitment to it. And this is the predicament of Rahner's method-be begins and ends his thought about truth with the determination and commitment of one's transcendental experiences. See also pp. 12-13 of Our Christian Faith where Rabner insists that a person is a believer in the " unreflected core of their existence " as long, as he loves, is loyal and committed to the truth. The problem with this assertion is that on his presuppositions Rahner cannot tell us whose version of "truth " is really true, since we can in fact know the truth without knowledge of Christ. That is because what actually determines the truth of his doctrine of God is our reflection on this "unreflected core of existence." For this reason belief in God, for Rahner, means belief in mystery or human existence or reality as a whole. It ciinnot mean belief in the Christian God who transcends humanity and confronts people who experience him in judgment and grace according to the Old and New Testaments. It is obvious that one can live and be committed in fact without acknowledging the truth of Christianity. Paul's analysis of his own position in Galatians and Romans would provide a good example of this. Cf. also TI 6: 231-249, "Reflections on the Unity of Love of Neighbour and the Love of God," p. 232 and pp. 238ff. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 617 perience of our horizon. Any real dependence on Christ in the New Testament sense would demand faith and action with respect to Him alone. To sum up. We have seen what Rahner's doctrine o:f God states and we have seen that it is based on "transcendental experience." We have contended that this starting point compromises God's freedom and the consequent need to believe in the triune God before being able to make sense of the Creator/creature relationship. We have contended that this leads to Rahner's synthesis of nature and grace and to the idea that God's free grace and free revelation can be described as "elements" or modalities by the philosopher of religion as well as the theologian. C. Revelation as An Act of God-Innate Knowledge of Truth Now we must make this analysis and critique more precise by focusing on the nature of and need for Revelation in a Christian doctrine of God. Here we shall contrast the traditional Thomist view of Gilson with the transcendental Thomist view of Rahner. In addition, we shall draw out the implications of the scriptural revelation for theological method. In his book, God and Philosophy, Etienne Gilson develops the question of the proper relation between philosophy and theology by analyzing revelation and innate knowledge of the truth. It is clear that each problematic aspect o:f Rahner's thought mentioned above centered on how to understand the freedom of God in himself (the immanent Trinity), in his revelation (the economic Trinity), and on how we know him. We have seen that Rahner's starting point and theological method claims that everyone always has an experience of and knowledge of God. He equates this with experience of and knowledge of absolute being which he defines as mystery. This knowledge is innate and unavoidable, though it can be ignored.131 We have contended that it is this claim itself which compromises the scriptural portrayal of revelation in its free131 See text, passim. 618 PAUL D. MOLNAR dom, obscures the traditional distinction between philosophy and theology, nature and grace, and finally fails to distinguish adequately between God in himself (the immanent Trinity) and God for us (grace, incarnation and glory) ,132 1. Philosophy and Theology Gilson sets up the question as follows. He argues that while Greek philosophy sought to identify the ultimate origin of the world with a first philosophical principle, the Greeks could not actually show that the first principle was anything independent of the world which could actually relate with the world. Thus, he concludes that philosophy could not solve the question it had set for itself. 133 Then, he states that the answer was found in God's revelation to Moses. This is significant. For the solution to the philosophical problem of finding a first cause (an efficient cause), in Gilson's eyes, is answered only by "Him who is," i.e., Yahweh, God Himself. 134 We shall not examine Gilson's analysis of Augustine and Thomas in their attempts to think about this question in light of the bible and the inherited philosophies (Plotinus for Augustine and Aristotle for Thomas). While this is interesting and instructive we shall move directly to modern philosophy and theology in the interest of time and space. Descartes Gilson contends that Descartes confronted the same philosophical problem as the Greeks, i.e., the problem of natural theology and whether, by reason alone (this time including the idea of the Christian God) , man could reach the Creator God-Yahweh who was both transcendent and immanent. The Greeks could reason to a first principle but then this obliterated their religion which advocated not one, but many gods. As they held to their religion, this contradicted their 132 See text, infra. 1s3 Gilson, Chapter I. 134 Gilson, Chapter 2. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 619 philosophical idea of a first cause. 135 And this was indeed the conflict they faced. If the transcendent God could be known as a first cause (philosophically demonstrable) then he could not really be transcendent. And if God is truly transcendent as the one beyond the many (this world) then he cannot in fact be immanent. Thus, any religious reliance on such a God to save us would make little sense. When a Greek philosopher had to approach the problem of natural theology by a purely rational method, he found himself confronted only with the religious gods of Greek mythology. Whatever his name, his rank, or function, not one among the gods of Greek religion had ever claimed to be the one ... creator of the world, first principle, and ultimate end of all things. Descartes, on the contrary, could not approach the same philosophical problem without finding himself confronted with the Christian God. When a philosopher is also a Christian, he can very well say, at the beginning of his inquiry: let me pretend that I am not a Christian; let me try to seek, by reason alone and without the light of faith, the first causes and the first principles whereby all things can be explained. As an intellectual sport, this is as good as any other one; but it is bound to result in a failure, because when a man both knows and believes that there is but one cause of all that is, the God in whom he believes can hardly be other than the cause which he knows. 136 This difficulty parallels the predicament Rahner faces in his work on the philosophy of religion, Hearers of the Word, and recapitulates the conflicts discussed above between reason and revelation. Rahner writes: " The philosophy of religion . . . cannot pre-judge the possible content of ... an utterance of God. It cannot even pre-judge the question whether such an utterance has occurred." 137 But Gilson's words regarding Descartes seem to apply here as well, i.e., the God in whom he believes (the triune God) can hardly be other than the cause which he knows-i.e. the term or horizon-absolute being itself. And this is what philosophy of religion can demonstrate. pp. 78-9. pp. 78·9. 1s1 HW, p. 174. 135 Gilson, 136 Gilson, 620 PAUL D. MOLNAR Thus, while Rahner speaks of the triune God, and of his own work as a theological ontology, his method compels him to pre-judge the possibility of revelation and its content precisely because he insists that his philosophy of religion is a " condition that is itself created by God's speaking." 138 In other words if it were really true that a phi1osophy of religion could not pre-judge whether revelation had in fact occurred, then Rahner's attempt in Hearers of the Word to establish its possibility by looking at man is in vain, since we can never know exactly what we mean by revelation. The conflict which arises here compromises Rahn er' s own perception of the limits of the philosophy of religion. But more importantly, it causes him to re-define revelation according to an often unarticulated presupposition that all philosophy stems from God's revelation (speaking) . Gilson illustrates a similar problem in Descartes's thought. The whole problem of modern natural theology is there in a nutshell . . . Far from coming after the Greeks as though there had been nothing in between, Descartes has come after the Greeks with the naive conviction that he could solve, by the purely rational method of the Greeks, all of the problems which had been raised in between by Christian natural theology ... what he did, at least in metaphysics, was to restate the main conclusions of Christian natural theology as if Christian supernatural theology itself had never existed. 139 a. Innate Knowledge of God In line with natural theology Descartes posited that the idea of the Christian God was innate. 140 Yet as Gilson writes: "If we investigate into the cause why such an idea exists within us, we are at once led to posit, as the only conceivable explanation for it, a being who is possessed of all the attributes which attend our own idea of him, that is, a self-existing, infinite, all-powerful, one and unique being." 141 And, p. 174. pp. 79-80. 140 Gilson, pp. 81-2. 141 Gilson, p. 81. 138 HW, 130 Gilson, RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 621 When we think more attentively of God, we soon find that the non-existence of God is, strictly speaking, unthinkable. Our innate idea of God is that of a supremely perfect being; since existence is a perfection, to think of a supremely perfect being to whom existence is wanting is to think of a supremely perfect being to whom some perfection is wanting, which is contradictory; hence existence is inseparable from God and, consequently, he necessarily is, or exists. 142 But is this the true God? Gilson continues: It is a well-known fact that Descartes always despised history; but here history has paid him back in full. Had he ever so little investigated into the past of his own idea of God, he would have realized at once that though it be true that all men have a certain idea of the divinity, they have not all, or always, had the Christian idea of God. If all men had such an idea of God, Moses would not have asked Jehovah for his name; or else Jehovah's answer would have been: 'What a silly question! You know it.' Descartes was so anxious not to corrupt the rational purity of his metaphysics by any admixture of Christian faith that he simply decreed the universal innateness of the Christian definition of God. Like the innate Ideas of Plato, Descartes' innate idea of God was a reminiscence; not however, the reminiscence of some idea contemplated by the soul in a former life, but simply the reminiscence of what he had learned in church when he was a little boy. 143 b. God-Necessity of Creation Where did this decree leave Descartes's conception of the Christian God? According to Gilson, it forced him to maintain that creation was in fact necessary to God as he had reduced "He who is " (Yahweh) to the condition of a first principle.144 Gilson writes: Now it is quite true that a Creator is an eminently Christian God, but a God whose very essence is to be a creator is not a Christian God at all. The essense of the true Christian God is not to create but to be. ' He who is ' can also create, if he chooses; but he does not exist because he creates, nay, not even himself; he can create because he supremely is. 142 Gilson, pp. 81-2. pp. 82-3, emphasis mine. 144 Gilson, pp. 88-9. 143 Gilson, 622 PAUL D. MOLNAR We are now beginning to see why, and in what sense, the metaphysics of Descartes was a decisive moment in the evolution of natural theology. Evolution, however, is not always synonymous with progress; and this time it was destined to be a regress . . . What I am trying to make clear is the objective fact that, even as a philosophical supreme cause, the God of Descartes was a stillborn God. He could not possibly live because, as Descartes had conceived him, he was the God of Christianity reduced to the condition of a philosophical principle, in short, an infelicitous hybrid of religious faith and of rational thought. The most striking characteristic of such a God was that his creative function had integrally absorbed his essence. Hence, the name that was hereafter going to be his truest name: no longer 'He who is' but rather 'The Author of Nature.' .... after Descartes, he was destined progressively to become nothing else than that. Descartes himself was too good a Christian to consider Nature as a particular god; but, strangely enough, it never occurred to him that to reduce the Christian God himself to no more than the supreme cause of Nature was to do identically the same thing. 145 God did indeed become nothing more than Nature when Spinoza concluded that "A God who 'exists and acts merely from the necessity of his nature,' is nothing more than a nature. Rather he is nature itself." 146 God is the absolute essence whose intrinsic necessity makes necessary the being of all that is, so that he is absolutely all that is, just as, in as much as it is, all that it is 'necessarily involves the eternal and infinite essence of God.' 147 Thus, Gilson writes, " In the doctrine of Descartes, one may still wonder if God's essence involves his existence in himself or in our mind only; in the Ethics of Spinoza no hesitation remains possible." 148 Gilson concludes that " Spinoza's metaphysical experiment is the conclusive demonstration of at least this: that any religious God whose true name is not ' He who is ' is nothing but a myth." 149 And this necessary mythologfoal 145 Gilson, p. 89, emphasis mine. Ethics quoted in Gilson, p. 101. 147 Gilson, p. 101. 148 Gilson, p. 101. 149 Gilson pp. 103-4. 146 Spinoza's RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 623 idea of course opened the door to Deism and the French Enlightment which saw God as the great "watchmaker." In other words, as Gilson says, " God became again what he had already been in the Timaeus of Plato: a Demiurge, the only difference being that this time, before beginning to arrange his world, the Demiurge had consulted Newton." 150 In terms of modern philosophy, Kant really spelled the end of such naive speculations-at least to the extent that his critiques of pure and practical reason were not simply ignored. 3. Rahner-Descartes-Spinoza Though there are significant differences, there are also significant ways in which Rahner's doctrine of God follows the scheme from Descartes to Spinoza illustrated by Gilson. One really notable difference is that Rahner's foundation is more experience than thought. Yet there is no experience in nuce; there is only interpreted experience. Indeed Rahner himself expresses the opinion that although metaphysics is not the norm for his doctrine of God, it is experience. 151 For Rahner metaphysics directs man to the unthematic experience he already has of God. 152 In this sense Rahner clearly acknowledges that there is no experience in nuce; only interpreted experience. And it is in this sense that metaphysics is his criterion of truth. His criterion is and remains being in general as objectified by man on the basis of his experience of himself and of creation. 153 And the question here concerns what validates objectively our always subjective interpretation of God acting within the range of our experience. In what ways, then, can Rahner's thought be compared to that of Descartes and Spinoza? First, in practice Rahner maintains that we know the true God innately. It should be noted clearly that on one level of his theology he would deny this, while on another level, toward which he is led by his method, he actually maintains 150 Gilson, 151 Tl 9: p. 107. 133-36. 152 Tl 9: 138. 153 See text, infra. 624 PAUL D, MOLNAR this. 154 To the extent that he actually maintains the direct knowledge of God implied in his concepts of transcendental revelation and of quasi-formal causality Rahner is compelled to identify the God of natural theology with the triune God.155 Insofar as this takes place within his system he actually subverts the centrality for Christian revelation he certainly wished to establish theoretically. By maintaining in practice that revelation must be identical with the constructs of reason or nonexistent,156Rahner effects his belief that natural theology and Molnar, TS, 46, pp. 245-261. Molnar, TS, 46, pp. 240ff., esp. n. 57. Rahner's method forces him into this position since he must see the Trinity as the highest insta.nce of being accessible to the meta physician. Thus, he writes: " An aativities, from the sheerly material to the innermost life of the Blessed Trinity, are but modulations of this one metaphysical theme of the one meaning of being: self-possession, subjectivity," (HW, p. 49, emphasis, mine). I am stating that if God is really free-independently existing as the immanent Trinity even in his economic actions ad extra-then he factually transcends any idea of being accessible to the meta.physician and that the truth of metaphyiscs cannot simply be identified with the truth of revelation. In other words reason and philosophy are not useless in the theological enterprise, but neither are they on a par with revelation as in Rahner's thought. One's reasoning and philosophy are true as their object has independent and objective existence which can, within due limits, be demonstrated. Thus, I am basically arguing for what Gilson says: i.e., "Why should not we keep truth, and keep it whole? It can be done. But only those can do it who realize that He Who is the God of the philosophers is HE WHO IS, the God of Abraham, of Isaac, and Jacob," Gilson, God and Philosophy, p. 144. 156 See text supra and n. 6. Rahner's statements that there would be no word of God withotu someone intrinsically capable of hearing it (HW, p. 168) and that revelation is " an interior quality of the concrete historical essence of man " ( HW, p. 74) bear this out. For the same idea, see Foundations, p. 129 and Molnar, TS, 46, pp. 23lff. esp. n. 15. It would be unfair to Rahner not to perceive the nuance of his thought. It is not that he doesn't realize that the Christian God must be free. For he writes: " To prevent possible misunderstanding, it should be noted here that grace is the selfrevelation of God unto man. This self-revelation is the foundation and the final goal of all revelation. But from this results the fact that revelation, without detriment to its free origin, is an interior quality of the concrete historical essence of man." He really thinks this concept of revelation maintains God's freedom. The problem is that once revelation is conceptualized as part of the essence of man it factually loses the freedom for which I have argued. So while Rahner argues that "man ... can never integrate God as 154 Cf. 155 See RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION revelation theology investigate the same object. Indeed this is the very reason he gives for identifying the immanent and economic Trinity. 157 If Gilson's argument presented above is correct, however, we must say that inasmuch as Yahweh alone is God, this thinking is questionable. A theology in which reason is subordinate to this particular God would investigate in practice the meaning of experience in light of knowledge of the Creator God who is totally inaccessible to human insight apart from his free naming of himself. For this relevation to be recognizable philosophically or theologically it would have to be categorized as a free act on the same level a,s God's action as Creator. For this reason a clear and sharp distinction between philosophy and theology would have to be maintaineda distinction which would not necessarily follow from an experience of "absolute being." Such a distinction would stem not from experience or reflection but from the very nature of the God revealed to Moses and known within the context of biblical faith. Although we have noted that Rahner does indeed describe God as free, we have also shown that his method forces him to be unable to make this kind of clear and sharp a disposable element into his self-comprehension," (HW, pp. 74-5) this kind of integration actually takes place because he believes he can deduce the meaning of grace and revelation from examining man's spiritual experiences philosophically and theologically. Thus, Rahner can maintain quite clearly that God is free and at the same time write: "God is posited, too, with the same necessity as this pre-concept," ( HW, p. 63) when speaking of human knowledge of God and that revelation " has its existence in man's own conscious thought and hence is subject to the a priori structure of human knowledge." TI 11 [New York: Seabury, 1974], "Reflections on Methodology in Theology," 68-114, at 91. My point is that a revelation of God subject to the mind of man in this way constitutes a synthesis of the objects of philosophical and theological investigation and factually denies the freedom for God which Rahner, as a theologian, intended to maintain. 157 Cf. Molnar, TS, 46, p. 249 "He believes that this identification avoids a merely formal reconciliation of one and three ... Moreover, his so identifying emphasizes that the Trinity and its two processions, together with the two self-communications of God ad emtra in a 'real formal causality corresponding to the two processions,' do not come between our natural knowledge and the absolute mystery of God," p. 249. Cf. also TI 4: 72 for this idea. 626 PAUL D. MOLNAR distinction. This, because his doctrine of God is based on the idea that philosophy and theology are already one in their presumed common quest of being in an absolute sense. 158 Thus, for Rahner, what" we call God," on the basis of our religious experience really is God. In fact, however, there is a real conflict here which this claim overlooks, namely, that the God of Moses, Paul, and the Johannine community and the Synoptic writers and He alone, revealed Himself as "He who is". And the conflict ensues from the simple fact that this particular God was not a naturally known God corresponding with our innate ideas of absolute being. Second, Rahner then describes the Creator/ creature relation as mutually necessary and mutually conditioning since this is true of any naturally known god who is in fact identical [distinct in degree, but not in kind] with the sphere of creation as its " absolutely distant term." To that extent one does not really need to know Christ to know the Creator God, true revelation or God's free grace. This may be why Rahner argues that all of these realities are " embedded " in creation in one way or another. But as he does this Rahner cannot clearly distinguish the " elements " one from another with any consistency and indeed he thinks of grace at times as identical with our own human dynamisms. 159 To the extent that this difficulty exists within Rahner's thought it is clearly concommitent with the conclusion of Spinoza illustrated above. 160 158 See text, supra nn. 30, 33, 35 and 72. He must do this of course because he is being faithful to one of the six ontological necessities he thinks applies to the being of the Christian God in his self-revelation, i.e., "the necessity for all being to agree ontologically with its origin," Molnar, TS, 46, p. 242. 159 See text, pp. 8, 13-25. This is why Rabner can write that grace is an "inner ... dynamism toward the beatific vision," (TI, 4: 61). I would say that grace may allow us to make sense of our human spiritual dynamisms in a way that relates us to God toward whom we move eschatologically in the present. But that very recognition would preclude describing that grace as a dynamism which in itself remains always human and to that extent ambiguous. 160 See text, supra. This is also where Deism began to think about God. See Gilson pp. 104:ff. Compare Spinoza's view with Ralmer's statement that RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 6:Z7 Third, Rahner's thought about God reaches its logical conclusion in his theories of the anonymous Christian, in his explanation of creation as the paradigm of a possible utterance of God,161 and in his identifying the immanent and economic God is the " single whole of reality," above, p. 5. The rest of his theology works out the logic of this insight. What makes Rahner's theology so difficult is his simultaneous insistence that God is really free and his various theoretical attempts to show this. The problem to which I have called attention, however, is that once the Christian God is conceived under the metaphysical idea of absolute being an inadmissible synthesis of natural theology and revealed theology has taken place and God's actual freedom is not maintained. 161 See, e.g., TI 4: 115, 116; TI 11: 215-229, "Christology in the Setting of Modern Man's Understanding of Himself and of His World," p. 225; TI 5: 157-192, "Christology within an Evolutionary View of the World" pp. 177-8. Compare to TI 4: 23lff. This corresponds exactly with Rahner's philosophy of the symbol. Because sign and thing signified are mutually necessary for Rahner all of his descriptions of creation manifest the same difficulty. Cf. for e.g. TI 11: 220 where he writes: " ... the creation, considered as the constitution of the non-divine 'out of nothing,' is revealed as the prior setting and condition for the supreme possibility of his [God's] imparting of himself." This idea is exactly what leads Rahner to draw similar conclusions regarding grace. In TI 6: 71-79, "Philosophy and Theology,'' pp. 723 Rahner writes: " Grace exists ... by being the divinising condition of the latter [the person], and hence presupposes and incorporates into itself the whole reality of this person as the condition of its own possibility and makes it part of the factors of its own concrete being." Thus, for Rahner Philosophy is a "condition of the possibility of theology" (TI 6: 71). The problem here is that in his description of creation and of grace Rahner has denied God's freedom. For Rahner God actually needs an addressee and recipient of his grace: "Grace, understood as the absolute self-communication of God himself, must always presuppose as a condition of its own possibility (in order to be itself) someone to whom it can address itself and someone to whom it is not owed," TI 6: 75). The same is true of Revelation: "Accordingly, it must be said that since revelation is a moment in this free self-opening-out by gratuitous grace, it presupposes as a condition of its own possibility the one to whom it is not owed" (TI 6: 75). In this paper I have argued that if the God of scripture is really free then the fact that there are creatures at all and creatures who are in fact recipients of God's revelation and grace is and remains a miraculous creation of his free love in any given situation. It cannot therefore be described symbolically as an instance of creaturely being at all as Rahner believes. Similarly if Rahner had envisioned this kind of freedom for God he could not have described creation as the paradigm of a "possible " utterance of God. But inasmuch Rahner actually holds that 628 PAUL D. MOLNAR Trinity. While Rahner offers lengthy and profound explanations of God's freedom, his practical explanation of creatwn absorbs God's essence into his creative function. 162 To the extent that Rahner believes creation can be explained as a selfvalidating reality and that the Creator/creature relationship can be described as one of mutual conditioning, it is impossible for God really to be free to create or not, to reveal himself or not and still be God. Again, without wishing to deny the freedom of the Christian God, Rahner's method, which attempts a synthesis of the triune God and the god of natural theology, leads him into the same predicament as Descartes. By actually maintaining these two presuppositions throughout his system Rahner certainly appears to have done the very thing for which Gilson criticized Descartes: He reduced the God of the bible to the condition of a philosophical principle and then reunited his concept of the trinitarian self-revelation with this principle. Rahner's attempt to make this synthesis more viable for modern man than the Scholastic notion of mystery as something unknown which makes itself known to faith, reveals the conflicts that actually exist between Rahner's reconstruction of his concept of mystery based on an experience open to everyone and the traditional attempt to distinguish sharply the object of philosophical (absolute being) and theological (the immanent Trinity revealed) reflection. On these three points we can at least say that the content of Rahner's doctrine of God is regulated by his philosophy of creation is the "condition " for God's utterance ad emtra, creaturely selfexperience which is thought to be self-validating then becomes the determinant of what is possible for both God (defined as absolute being) and for creatures (defined as finite existents). And that is exactly the problem in Rahner's doctrine of God as it concerns revelation and grace which we have tried to highlight. See also TI 9: 134. For Rahner creation is the "condition for the possibility," of God's revelation and the "grammar" of his self-expression ad emtra. 162 See text. It is Rahner's claim that creation is a self-explaining fact that leads to all his other assertions. The most obvious fact which confirms all of this is his description of the creature and Creator relationship as mutually conditioning, above. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 629 being based on experience and explained in Christian categories. Though Rahner certainly did not intend it, the creatio ex nihilo, the Mosaic revelation, and the grace of God revealed in Christ become factually and existentially unnecessary to man's self-understanding within creation. This, because these Christian categories are merely categorical articulations of what is already innate in our experiences of self-transcendence. Thus, Rahner in fact re-defines the Chalcedonian unio, the doctrine of creation, and the doctrines of incarnation, grace and glory to conform to his philosophy of being. And by doing this he frequently synthesizes the being of God with the innate movements of the creature as illustrated above. His symbolic Christology is the supreme manifestation of this. 163 163 See e.g. Tl 4: 235ff. and Rahner's various pieces on Christology, including Chapter 6 of Foundations. For instance Rahner writes: " The theology of the Logos is strictly a theology of the symbol, and indeed the supreme form of it," Tl 4: 235. The problem obviously is that since symbols must express themselves to be themselves and because the symbol is full of the thing symbolized there can be no real freedom for God before or after creation or incarnation. He, as the supreme instance of symbolic ontology, must conform to these principles. But as this is the case, he cannot in fact be free. On this point see esp. TI 4: 227ff. In fact, because Rahner makes his doctrine of God and Christology conform to these principles of symbolic ontology, he cannot even begin to distinguish creature and Creator and even ends by confusing the humanity and divinity of Christ and Christ with creatures (TI 4: 236ff.). The following statement is analyzed at length in Molnar, TS, 46, pp. 248ff.: "It is because God 'must' 'express' himself inwardly that he can also utter himself outwardly; the finite created utterance ad emtra is a continuation of the immanent constitution of 'image and likeness' ... " (236-7). The problem with this is that he had previously described the functions of image and likeness as necessities corresponding with the functioning of symbols. And if God must express himself inwardly and that function is "continued" in creation and incarnation, then God must create and must communicate himself to the creature in grace. Thus, despite Rahner's insistence that God is free-inasmuch as he has substituted experience of absolute being for God, it is clear that this "God" is not free but subject to his principles of metaphysical ontology, i.e., all beings are symbolic because they must express themselves and the symbol is essentially constituted by what is symbolized so that they are mutually dependent. But, as noted in the text, Rahner has only described the term of human experience in this way. He has not described the being of God, i.e., the immanent Trinity. 630 PAUL D. MOLNAR An obvious question which unfortunately is beyond the scope of the present paper is: what can keep a philosophical theologian from the difficulties encounted by Descartes, Spinoza, the Deists, the Enlightenment generally and Rahner? 164 We can only suggest that the answer to this predicament may lie in perceiving that the differences between a Gilsonian Thomist and a transcendental Thomist may arise from the deeper question of the relationship between faith and understanding as seen in light of scripture. For Gilson the answer was to be found in an actual recognition of God's free selfrevelation. Rahner says the same thing, but his method does not maintain the kind of freedom for God's action that Gilson's method does. Gilson apparently meant to allow Yahweh the freedom to determine the truth of our ideas. He did this by never claiming that the ideas have this truth in themselves. Not even the idea of the supernatural can guarantee that we have spoken of a. truly transcendent other. In fact he really meant what he said when he wrote: "Why should not we keep truth, and keep it whole? It can be done. But only those can do it who realize that He Who is the God of the philosophers is HE WHO IS, the God of Abraham, of Isaac, and of Jacob." 165 And if this is true, then we really need to know what Yahweh did in Israel, in Christ and the Spirit, before we can distinguish 164 It is important to note that the problem here is a methodological one. Perhaps this is the key difference between a Gilsonian Thomist and a transcendental Thomist. Rahner begins his treatment of mystery (TI 4) by insisting that ratio is the way mystery is assured ( p. 41) and proceeds to ascribe revelation and grace to the knowing subject in its reflection on its term. This appears to be what " Scholastic" school theology wished to avoid in order not to claim that creation was a self-evident fact as Rahner does (TI 3: 24-34, "Thoughts on the Theology of Christmas," (p. 32). Rather, creation found its basis in the God of the Christian faith, i.e., "He who is." For that reason creation really was seen as not necessary to God and it was further seen that God could not truly be recognized by identifying the necessary movements of creaturely being with His inner being which is free. This thought is most clearly expressed in Gilson's analysis above. I believe this insight applies to knowledge of God as well as to knowledge of revelation, faith and grace. 165 Gilson, p. 144. RAHNER's EXPLANATION FROM REVELATION 631 a truly divine act from our self-experiences. This would imply that theology must be faith seeking understanding and not understanding seeking faith if it is to be successful in truly uniting and distinguishing the mystery of God and the mystery of creatures. It would appear from what was presented above that the outcome of Rahner's transcendental method is quite similar to the outcome of Cartesian logic. Both thinkers identify what is known in faith (God's free revelation and free grace) with the necessary movements of the human spirit toward absolute being which is a metaphysical construct drawn from experience. But this proves that we need to acknowledge and to know God's revelation first, before we can make sense of our " ultimate " origin and end as something actually transcending both the categorical and existential (transcendental experience) realms. And this means that we must at least question Rahner's method for doing theology insofar as it begins by assuming that an experience of the nameless is an experience of the true God. If Gilson can teach anything on this point it may be that the very nature of God revealed to faith compels us to begin and end our analysis with faith in Yahweh alone before actually finding the ultimate explanation of reality. For the New Testament that same truth was found in Christ alone since he alone was the eternal Word of God present in the flesh. The truth of the New Testament of course rested on the fact that this revealed word did not contradict but confirmed what Yahweh revealed previously in Israel. That is why, for Paul, recognition of the truth of our existence was tied to confession of Christ's Lordship which confession implied reliance on him alone and not any or all of our experiences, no matter how profound they may be. 166 PAUL D. MOLNAR St. John's University Jamaica, New York 166 Cf., e.g., l Cor. 12: 4ff. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED T I HEISM SEEMS to be caught in a dilemma. Speaking persuasively to the surrounding culture seems to demand hat theism sacrifice its own integrity as a significantly distinctive world-view; affirming its distinctiveness seems to result in moving itself to the periphery of the culture. Briefly, then, either theism acquires relevance at the price of forfeiting any claim to distinctiveness or it takes seriously precisely those things that make it seem significantly distinctive and thereby isolates itself from the rest of the culture. Such is the fate of theism as portrayed by (friendly?) critics of theism like Jeffrey Stout, Alasdair Macintyre, and Van A. Harvey. 1 The main question addressed in this paper is whether or not the theist (or his more specific variant, the Christian theist) has a sound response to this dilemma? How, if at all, can the Christian theist avoid the horns of the dilemma of redundancy and irrelevance? Stout, The Flight from Authority: Religion, Morality, and the 1 Jeffrey Quest for Autonomy (London and Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), especially Part 2. Alasdair Macintyre, "God and the theo· logians," in Against the Self-Images of the Age (London: Duckworth, 1971), pp. 12-26; see also Macintyre's essay, "The Fate of Theism," originally delivered as one of his Bampton Lectures at Columbia University in 1966. Macintyre's lectures were published in The Religious Si,qnificance of Atheism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969). For "The Fate of Theism," see pp. 3-29. Van A. Harvey, The Historian and the Belie1Jer: The Morality of Historical Knowledge and Christian Belief (New York: Macmillan, 1966); see also Harvey's essay, "The Pathos of Liberal Theology," Journal of Religion 56 1976: 382-391. For an illuminating discussion of the fate of theism, see Peter L. Berger, The Heretical Imperatives: Contemporary Possibilities of Religious Affirmation (New York: Doubleday 1980) . THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 633 The practical relevance of this dilemma for Christian doctrine was recently evidenced in Thomas Sheehan's review of Hans Kiing's latest book in the New York Review of Books. 2 After summarizing Kiing's views on the Christian doctrine of eternal life, Sheehan writes: Kiing . . . has pushed Catholic theology to the limits of its own language. In fact, he has brought it to the point where one can ask what its teachings have to offer that cannot be found outside the scope of its experience and discourse. For example, the hope in immortality he evokes is certainly not peculiar to Catholicism or Christianity. Nor is it an exclusively religious doctrine: we find it in pagan philosophy from the Greeks onward, even in thinkers who did not believe in a personal god .... On a broader scale, it is clear that religious experience is available outside Catholicism and Christianity; and for many people natural human experience, with no religious or transcendent dimension, is satisfying enough. What, then, does Catholicism claim to provide that cannot be found beyond its boundaries? I am not asking about the subjective aspects of experience, be it natural or religious (its felt quality, psychological genesis, personal meaning, and so on). I am asking an objective theological question: what does Catholicism claim that makes it unique, essentially different from non-Catholic religions and non-religious humanisms? 3 Sheehan's answer to this last question is clear. That which makes Christianity unique and essentially distinctive and which traditional believers sought to clarify and defend moves Christianity to the periphery of the culture. By identifying themselves primarily with the tradition in terms of classical Christianity, no one hears what Christians have to say but themselves. The only alternative to this self-imposed isolation, holds Sheehan, is to be intelligible to contemporary educated, secularminded men and women: in which case Christian theism may well have interesting things to say, but these will not be significantly distinctive in any Christian sense. To put this last 2 Thomas Sheehan, "Revolution Books, June 14, 1984, pp. 35-39. s Ibid., p. 38. in the Church," The New York Review of 634 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA point another way, the strategy of accommodation raises the question why one should be Christian at all. Some theologians have sought to avoid the horns of this dilemma by arguing that the dilemma, as posed here, gains its apparent force by posing false alternatives. The problem, as defined here, imposes an exclusive choice between two poles: first, classical Christianity and, second, contemporary structures of experience, thought, and society. But this way of posing the problem suffers from a basic mistake, they say. It creates the distinct impression that each of these poles is a fixed, static point and not historical. 4 Instead, they argue that an understanding of the Christian faith involves a theological methodology which is sensitive to the history of its evolution and development. Similarly, an interpretation of the contemporary structures of experience, thought, and society should include an understanding of those various factors which led to the formation of these structures. More exactly, a historically sensitive, theological method will require that one distinguish the kernel of Christianity, which can and should be detached, from the outmoded husk. Briefly, then, to distinguish the theistic kernel from the theistic husk is the wisdom this theological methodology offers for avoiding the horns of the dilemma. The idea here seems to be that Christian theism would undergo an interpretative process which would be like peeling off the outer layers of an onion in order to get at the essence of the onion. On this view, essential aspects of classical theism could be held onto that seem defensible or intelligible in the vocabulary of our secular-minded culture. Presumably, then, this theological methodology would make it possible for the theist to secure a hearing from a secular audience without doing violence to the central claims of Christian theism. 5 4 Many theologians have argued that the dilemma gains in apparent force by posing false alternatives. For a recent example, see Francis Schussler Fiorenza, Foundational Theology: Jesus and the Church (New York: Crossroad, 1984). 5 See Stout, op. cit., p. 146. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 635 One may be excused for having doubts about the success this approach has in avoiding the horns of the dilemma. We must note here that the question crucially arises: How exactly does one determine when a certain layer or layers are disposable externals or the essential inner cargo? 6 It seems to me that in order to determine this the interpreter of traditional theism will have to engage in what sociologist Peter Berger has called cognitive bargaining. In general, cognitive bargaining consists of compromises with respect to beliefs between traditional and modern modes of thought and practice. 7 In the case of the interpreter of traditional theism, what this amounts to is the following. It is the interpreter of theism, rather than the secularist, who experiences the greater pressures to be convincing. Accordingly, he attempts to reformulate theism by translating, in the manner of a Bultmann or a Tillich, traditional theistic claims into secular vocabulary. In other words, the interpreter of theism defending himself cognitively against his secular audience almost inevitably incorporates elements of the latter within his own defence. Ideally, I suppose, the give-and-take should be mutual. In fact, however, this process of cognitive bargaining operates mainly in one direction with the interpreter of theism offering the cultured despiser of classical theism " less and less in which to disbelieve." 8 Undoubtedly the problem which now emerges for the interpreter of theism is the problem of just where to draw the line. The line here represents that which he may not go beyond without dismantling the tradition of classical theism from within. Clearly, then, this approach does not avoid the horns of the dilemma. If anything, it brings us back to the fundamental issue that detrmines what Van A. Harvey has called the" pathos of Liberal theology." Harvey writes: s On this, see Stephen Sykes, The Identity of Christianity: Theologians and the Essence of Christianity from Schleiermacher to Barth (London: SPCK, 1984). 1 See Berger, op. cit., pp. 99-101. See also, Os Guinness, The Gravedigger File: Reports on the Subversion of the Modern Church (Downers Grove, Illinois: Inter-Varsity Press, 1983), especially chapters 10 and 11. s Macintyre, "Fate," p. 24. 686 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA [T]he problem the liberal faces concern[s] the degree to which Christian belief can be accommodated to modernity and remain recognizably Christian. If the cognitive surrender is unconditional, the theologian does achieve a remarkable harmonization, to be sure, but only at the cost of raising the question why one should be Christian at all. The pathos of the liberal theologian is that, if he identifies himself too unqualifiedly with modernity, he runs the risk of alienation from the very community his apologetic is to serve. If, on the other hand, he defines his role primarily in terms of classical Christianity, he runs the risk of being an obscurantist, alienated from the modern intellectual community of which he also wants to be a member. 9 It is interesting to note here that it is often the critics of theism who wish theists would be more orthodox. Why do the critics insist upon this? They believe, rightly, I think, that there can be no serious interaction with theism beyond a certain point if it is not recognizably theistic. As Jeffrey Stout puts it, "One wants one's conversation partners to remain distinctive enough to be identified, to be needed." 10 The question which can and should be asked, holds Stout, is whether Christian theism can be both critical enough to be respected and distinctive enough to be needed. Perhaps an even more basic question which now needs to be asked is how did Christian theism get into this predicament in the first place? IT Jeffrey Stout has recently provided us with an important perspective on the question regarding the predicament of Christian theism. In this paper I cannot hope, and do not propose to try, to examine the details of the historical scenario which he paints for us. I wish only to call attention to what I take to be the crucial importance in his account of what may 9 Harvey, "Pathos," p. 383. Stout, "The Voice of Theology in Contemporary Culture," in Religion and America: Spirituality in a Secular Age: editors Mary Douglas and Steven M. Tipton (Boston: Beacon Press, 1983), pp. 249-261; for this quote, see p. 260. 10 Jeffrey THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 637 be called the evidentialist challenge to religious belief.11 The evidentialist holds, first, that religious belief is not acceptable unless rational, and second, that religious belief is rational if and only if supported by argument and evidence. Evidentialism has almost always, perhaps always, offered classic foundationalism as its epistemological defence. Classic foundationalism may be understood as a doctrine about justified belief. The classic foundationalist holds that (1) Some beliefs are, epistemically, absolutely secure and properly basic-the idea is that some of our justified beliefs are not held on the basis of any other beliefs; these are the properly basic ones. All justified non-basic beliefs are justified wholly by the evidential support they receive from basic beliefs, (3) Any properly basic belief must be self-evident, evident to the senses, or based on incorrigible reports of experience. Now if classic foundationalism is true, then the justification of theistic beliefs must be foundationalist. However, some foundationalists, but not all, have argued that the theist is not epistemically justified in holding the beliefs which he does hold. They allege, first, that theistic beliefs are not supported by basic beliefs, that there is not sufficient evidence for them, and second, that a person is rational in accepting theistic beliefs only if he has sufficient evidence for them. 12 What is most interesting here is not the claim that theistic beliefs do not fit the foundationalist's criterion for justified belief. More interesting, but also more directly relevant to the question I am presently addressing, is that many Christians have held, 11 This is how Nicholas Wolterstorff refers to the challenge issued by Enlightenment thinkers when it comes to matters of religion. See Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God, editors Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff (London and Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983). For Stout's account of this challenge, see The Flight from Authority, chapter 6. For an extensive discussion of the 5tages of development theism underwent in the seventeenth and eighteenth century, see Hans W. Frei, The Eclipse of Biblical Narrative (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1974). 12 For a discussion of these claims, see Plantinga's essay, "Reason and Belief in God," in Faith and Rationality, pp. 17 ff. 688 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA whether deliberately or inadvertently, to classic foundationalism. More exactly, they have appealed to classic foundationalism in defence of what I am here calling evidentialism. That is, in response to the question, how, if at all, do we justify those beliefs which we hold, they opt for the evidentialist position. To pursue this issue further, I should like to examine briefly Stout's account of that period in British philosophical history when Christian theism sought to meet the evidentialist challenge. Here, I think, we have a prime example of what I earlier called, with Berger's help, cognitive bargaining. The theist defending himself cognitively against his secular critic incorporates elements of the latter's presuppositions within his own defence. Stout's discussion of the evidentialist challenge to religious belief has three phases. These phases correspond to the three stages of development theism underwent in the seventeenth and eighteenth century. Representative of the first stage is the philosophical theology of John Locke The second stage can be seen in the controversies over Deism, while the third can be seen in David Hume's (1711-1776) critique of religion. There are two inter-connected issues under discussion throughout the three stages: first, how exactly does one identify a proposition as revealed truth (i.e., a set o:f propositions or documents regarded as containing revelation from God) and, second, how does one decide what any such propotion means. 13 I now want to look briefly at each stage in turn. In raising the question, how is a revealed proposition to be identified, Locke does not doubt whether any revelation from God can be true. As Paul Helm puts it, "Anyone who believes, as Locke did, that God is a perfectly truthful being will assent to the proposition ' Any revelation from God is true.' This last proposition is analytic for Locke and for all theists. But saying this does not settle the epistemological question of 1a Paul Helm, "Locke on Faith and Knowledge," Phiiosophioal Quarterly 23 ( 1973) : 52-66. I have greatly profited from Helm's paper for my understanding of the issues that concerned Locke. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 689 how anyone knows whether or not a particular proposition is revealed by God." 14 So we must distinguish here. Whatever God reveals is infallibly true for l,ocke. What Locke wants to know are the grounds upon which men can claim to know that a proposition is revealed. In Locke's view, it is not a matter of faith that p is a revealed truth. He distinguishes the proposition "p, a revealed proposition, is believed" from" p is a revealed proposition because it is believed to be so." 15 This distinction is crucial: it must be possible to identify p as a revealed truth independently of anyone believing it to be so. How, then, is a revealed truth to be identified? In the Essay Concerning Human Understanding, J,ocke writes in answer to this question: Whatever God hath revealed is certainly true; no doubt can be made of it. This is the proper object of faith: but whether it be a divine revelation or no, reason must judge; which can never permit the mind to reject a greater evidence to embrace what is less evident, nor allow it to entertain probability in opposition to knowledge and certainty. 16 Reason must not only identify p as a revealed truth, but it must also decide what any such proposition means. Locke explains: Because the mind, not being certain of the truth of that it does not evidently know, but only yielding to the probability that appears in it, is bound to give up its assent to such a testimony, which, it is satisfied, comes from One who cannot err, and will not deceive. But yet it still belongs to reason to judge of the truth of its being a revelation, and of the signification of the words wherein it is delivered.17 But what is reason? And, correspondingly, on what grounds must it judge? Locke continues: Indeed, if any thing shall be thought revelation which is contrary to the plain principles of reason and the evident knowledge the 14 Ibid., 15 Ibid., p. 52. p. 55. 16 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding New York, 1961), Book IV, Chapter 18, Section 10, p. 588. 17 Ibid., p. 587. (London and 640 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA mind has of its own clear and distinct ideas, there reason must be hearkened to as a matter within its province: since a man can never have so certain a knowledge that a proposition, which contradicts the clear principles and evidence of his own knowledge, was divinely revealed, or that he understands the words rightly wherein it is delivered, as he has that the contrary is true; and so is bound to consider and judge of it as a matter of reason, and not swallow it, without examination, as a matter of faith .... Therefore nothing that is contrary to, and inconsistent with, the clear and self-evident dictates of reason has a right to be urged or assented to as a matter of faith, wherein reason hath nothing to do. 18 So what is purportedly revealed truth must be consistent with the principles of reason and the self-evident knowledge the mind has. But Locke does not mean to claim that revealed truth itself is self-evident; nor is it demonstratively supported (i.e., logically entailed) by such principles and knowledge. Locke uses such principles and knowledge as a negative criterion for identifying p as a revealed truth. Hence, while revealed truths do not consist of self-evident truths, they cannot consist of anything that is inconsistent with what is selfevident.19 Does Locke stipulate any other criteria, besides the one I just mentioned? Other than the criterion of not containing anything that is inconsistent with what is self-evidently true, Locke stipulates that a candidate-revelation must measure up to two other criteria: first, when originally given, it was accompanied by impressive external signs (e.g., miracles) and, second, there is an historically reliable account of the latter. 20 Yet even if a candidate-revelation measures up fully to all three criteria, even then it could never be known with certainty to be a revelation from God. Accordingly, the grounds upon which men can claim to know that pis a revealed truth are empirical, and hence can only be probable. For the moment I think that we have said enough about Locke. Let's go on to look briefly pp. 587-588. on Faith and Knowledge," p. 56. 20 Ibid., p. 56. 1s Ibid., 10 Helm, "Locke THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 641 at the second stage in the British discussion: the controversies over Deism. The Deists enthusiastically endorsed Locke's dictum about reason as the guarantor of revealed truth. In fact, they claimed to be more consistent in its use. This resulted in the following problem: if nothing that is inconsistent with the dictates of reason has a right to be assented to as a matter of faith, then assent must be withheld where it is impossible to discern what a revealed proposition means. However, what, then, of the mysteries of revelation such as the Trinity and the resurrection of the dead? Under these conditions faith in these mysteries would become an irrational belief. 21 In response to this problem, Locke went on to argue (in his controversy with Bishop Stillingfleet) that " faith and knowledge are independent, and that a proposition can be accepted as part of revelation even if it is not understood." 22 Locke explains: 21 Ibid., p. 59. Hans Frei puts it this way in The Eclipse of Biblical Narrative, pp. 52-53: "The deistic controversy, at once reacting to, shaping, and testing the notion of revelation, began a series of arguments about the credibility of special divine communication and (later on) of divine self-presentation through the medium of historical occurrences. Two issues were at stake from the beginning. The first was of a predominantly philosophical nature. It concerned the inherent rationality or credibility of the very idea of a historical revelation. Was it conceivable or intelligible? Is it likely, it was asked, that a perfectly good God should have left mankind without decisive guidance for so long, only to grant the privilege finally to a tiny, rude, and isolated fraction of the human race? Or is what is called revelation nothing more than a specific instantiation of what God had made known everywhere and all along, concerning truth and human happiness? Furthermore, is the appeal to the 'mystery' of revelation anything other than an admission that the idea itself is unintelligible, a token of that unwarranted intrusion of imagination or, worse yet, sheer ignorant superstitution into matters religious which the new intellectual rigor must repel? The second question was: Even granted the rationality or inherent possibility of revelation how likely is it that such a thing has actually taken place? ... The immediate question was whether there are good grounds for believing in the actual occurrence of the miraculous events constituting the indispensable evidence for historical revelation. How authoritative, in short, how well attested are biblical accounts, especially those of miracles, since the natural presumption in a 'scientific age' is obviously against them? " 22 Helm, "Locke on Faith and Knowledge," p. 59. 642 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA A definition of knowledge, whether a good or bad, true or false definition, could not be of ill or any consequence to an article of faith: because a definition of knowledge, which was one act of the mind did not at all concern faith, which was another act of the mind quite distinct from it. 23 And, in addition, he says: Let the grounds of knowledge be resolved into what anyone pleases, it touches not my faith: the foundation of that stands as sure as before, and cannot be at all shaken by it. 24 On the face of it, this view seems wholly inconsistent with the view Locke sets out in the Esb•ay. Be that as it may, of more importance now is to note that the Deists were not at all convinced by Locke's reply to their problem. Stout sheds some valuable light on their objection: The next stage of the British discussion arrives when Deists, marching behind Locke's dictum about reason as the guarantor of revelation, ask why, if all evidence is to be taken into account ... , the content of a putative revelation should not bear more directly upon our decision to accept or reject the proposition in question. If the proposition itself is inherently improbable, does this not make it less likely that the proposition is revelatory? 25 The Deists answer to this question is well known. We ought to accept only those claims of classical theism that can be established independently as probable hypotheses. Under these conditions the claim that " p is a revealed truth but I do not understand it " is regarded as totally unacceptable. Where it is impossible to discern what a revealed proposition means, that proposition is either improbable or redundant. "The supernatural mysteries of faith, in particular," as Stout puts it, " are declared paradoxical and, therefore, improbable. Hence the significance of John Toland's title Christianity not Mysterious (1696) ." 26 2s John Locke, Works ( 1823), Vol. IV, p. 282. 24/bid., p. 147. 25 Stout, 2e Ibid., The Flight from Authority, p. 116. p. 117. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 643 But there is still the third stage of development theism underwent at the hand of Hume's critique of religion. My understanding of this, pared down for my purpose here, is as follows. Hume subjected the minimal theism of Deism to the tests of its own standards of appraisal. He, in short, claims that their anaemic theism does not meet the standards that Deism itself lays down. What, then, about religion with revelation? What about classical Christianity itself? Well, says Hume, my critique of minimal theism has served the cause of faith and true religion. For by exposing the inability of reason to undergird the tenets of theism, I have thereby paved the way for grace to supply it instead. 27 He concludes that the Christian Religion not only was at first attended with miracles, but even at this day cannot be believed by any reasonable person without one. Mere reason is insufficient to convince us of its veracity: And whoever is moved by Faith to assent to it, is conscious of a continued miracle in his own person, which subverts all the principles of his understanding, and gives him a determination to believe what is most contrary to custom and experience.28 I have serious doubts as to whether Hume really intended to render a service to classical Christian theism. But even were it not so, Hume's profound influence upon certain strands of modern philosophical theology cannot be gainsaid. (Needless to say, by influence I do not mean that certain modern theologians hold to Hume's philosophy. I mean simply to refer to their mode of handling problems, their fundamental assumptions in the intellectual treatment of certain problems, and the kind of questions they ask-all this limits and disposes the answer they give.) In a fascinating but highly tendentious reading, Stout reconstructs the history of post-Humean theology as a story that takes Hume's accomplishment for granted 21 David Hume: An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, London 1748, Section X, par. 40. See also Terence Penelhum's essay, "Natural Belief and Religious Belief in Hume's Philosophy," Philosophioal Quarterly 33 (1983): 166-181. 2s Hume, Enquiry, sec. X, par. 41. 644 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA and does not attempt to refute him on his own terms, and asks simply what remains possible after Hurne. Now this is a strong claim. It would no doubt be possible to object to Stout's claim by pointing to the broadly inductive or probabilistic arguments developed by C.S. Lewis, E.L. Mascall, Basil Mitchell, Richard Swinburne, Wolfhart Pannenberg, and others. It seems obvious to me that these writers have indeed sought to refute Hurnean type arguments on their own turf, and to revive something like a natural theology by meeting the evidentialist challenge head-on. Unfortunately Stout fails to consider the merits of their work in his reconstruction of the history of post-Hurnean theology. Nevertheless, perhaps the real point at issue-the point which, it might be suggested, is really at the forefront of Stout's mind-is that any given attempt to defend theism in terms of an empirical probability calculus is in all likelihood a hopeless task. 29 But how could Stout know this in advance of someone's proposing such a defence? Suppose Stout is right, however. That is, let's suppose that the clash of probabilistic reasoning with religious beliefs is in all likelihood inevitable. Where then, one may ask, does the clash come? Sometimes Stout seems to suggest that the clash arises between the different ways in which beliefs are held: the religious believer typically gives unqualified assent to his beliefs, while those beliefs supported by probabilistic reasoning deserve only qualified or provisional adherence. Basil Mitchell is admirably explicit on the dilemma in which this places the would-be defender of the rationality of theistic belief: To the extent that he attempts to indicate how faith can be rationally defended, he is led to characterise faith in a way that fails to satisfy the religious mind; but if he portrays faith as it characteristically operates in the life and thought of believers, he describes something inevitably incommensurate with the only sort of justification that is available. 30 The Flight from Authority, p. 170. so Basil Mitchell, The Justification of Religious Seabury Press, 1973), p. l16. 20 Stout, Belief (New York: The THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 645 Sometimes he speaks, ala Hume, of religious beliefs as being highly unlikely on empirical grounds; and, correspondingly, that several alternative non-theistic explanations of the phenomena are nearly as good, if not equally good or better. 31 Sometimes Stout states the clash much more strongly, as when he says that religious beliefs are, in terms of the standards of intelligibility, paradoxes such that they are both supa and contra rationem. Now I would urge us to consider that all these clashes are not the same. For example, we could find it unacceptable to apply a probability calculus to the question of the existence of God without rejecting standards of intelligibility such as the law of non-contradiction. Furthermore, the notion of paradox has a wide scope of application: ranging from highly unlikely on empirical grounds to beyond the reach of our intellectual capacity to the logically inconsistent. Grace M. Jantzen is unmistakably correct when she writes that " one does not have to be in opposition to rationality to admit the former two, only the latter." 32 In addition, she says, "If rationality is defined in terms of an empirical probability calculus, then no doubt religion will have to oppose it-but why define it that way?" 33 Yes, why indeed? Perhaps Stout believes, following David Hume and W.K. Clifford, that a wise man proportions his belief to the evidence and that it is wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone to believe anything upon insufficient evidence. But this contention raises the following questions. What is evidence? What sorts of propositions are candidates for evidence? How do we determine which propositions count as evidence such that my beliefs are rational if and only if they are evident with respect to them? I cannot The Flight from Authority, p. 117. M. Jantzen, "'Religion' Reviewed," Heythrop Journal 26 ( 1985): 14-25. For this quote see p. 23. Jantzen's paper is a review of Leszek Kolakowski's book, Religion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982). I am indebted to her for helping me to gain clarity on precisely how varied the clash between reason and religion is. s3 Ibid., p. 23. 31 Stout, 32 Grace 646 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA recall that Stout ever gives any argument in support of this Humian and Cliffordian position. Still, what Stout does not fail to make clear is just how, and why, certain post-Humean theologies are caught in the dilemma of redundancy and irrelevance. Classical Christian theism, he holds, confronted by the challenge of evidentialism and its attendant demand, must either accept this demand or reject it. To accept the demand is to put one's most cherished beliefs at risk .... This would be to treat theism as a collection of hypotheses, or rather to transform theism .... into Deism-and therefore to accept a steady erosion of theism's traditional content. To reject the demand is to treat theism either as something to be believed in the face of evidence or as something to which evidence is not really relevant-in either event as something essentially removed from the critical rationality central to the culture. If evidence is treated as irrelevant, then the traditional theoretical content of theism is diminished just as radically as it would be in Deism. But if theism retains its traditional content while being believed in the face of evidence any genuinely critical intellect would consider a decisive refutation, it thereby sacrifices any serious claim for attention from the culture upon which it would like to have an influence. 34 However, it appears to be assumed by Stout that there is only one way to reject the demand of evidentialism: by pleading nolo contendere with respect to it. It must be confessed in fairness to Stout that there have been some theists who have tended, whether deliberately or inadvertently, to adopt a conformist stance regarding evidentialism-and therefore have surrendered the structure of rationality to the evidentialist. Be that as it may, this stance is surely unacceptable. I believe it is defensible to hazard the view that the evidentialist sees the structure of rationality mistakenly. Most evidentialists hold to a certain paradigm of rationality. They hold, as Nicholas Wolterstorff puts it, " a certain criterion for the application of the concept rational-the criterion being that of 34 Stout, The Flight from Authority, p. 102. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 647 classical foundationalism." 35 What Wolterstorff argues, along with Alvin Plantinga, as I understand them, is that if ever Christian theism is to avoid the horns of the dilemma of redundancy and irrelevance, Christian theists must be released from their adherence to classic foundationalism. Significantly, they argue that classic foundationalism does not live up to its own requirements, in essence showing that it is self-referentially incoherent, failing its own test for rationality. I will try, therefore, briefly to present their argument against classic foundationalism, and to suggest how it frees the theist from the dilemma. III Before pursuing the main part of their argument against foundationalism, ·it would probably be useful to clarify somewhat how Wolterstorff and Piantinga understand the dilemma faced by the theist. I said earlier that classic foundationalism may be understood as a doctrine about justified belief. The classic foundationalist holds that our beliefs are divided into those which need support from other beliefs and those which can support others and need no support themselves. Given this distinction, he further holds that beliefs which are self-supporting, basic beliefs (i.e., beliefs not inferred or reached as conclusions from other things he believes) are those which are self-evident, evident to the senses, or incorrigible reports of experience. Other beliefs, non-basic beliefs, are rational if and only if supported by basic beliefs. Evidentialism, we remember, is rooted in classic foundationalism. Regarding theistic beliefs, the evidentialist holds that a person is rational in accepting theistic beliefs only if he has sufficient evidence for them. Most exactly, he holds that theistic beliefs are thus justified only if they consist of basic beliefs (in the sense explained), or if they are inferred 35 Nicholas Wolterstorff, "Can Belief in God Be Rational if it has no Foundations," in Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God, editors Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff (L-Ondon and Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), p. 142. 648 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA from basic beliefs which supply adequate support for them. The story of modern philosophical theology from Hume to the present day is a story of attempts to show that theistic beliefs do or do not fit the foundationalist's criterion for justified beliefs.36 Theists have, by and large, not challenged the foundationalist's view regarding the structure of rationality, holds Wolterstorff. By not doing so, they have accepted, whether deliberately or inadvertently, the claim that they as philosophers, or scientists, or, more recently, as theologians, have no right to their theistic beliefs unless they are able to show that these beliefs follow from basic propositions accepted by all parties to the conversation-theist, agnostic, and atheist alike. Moreover, theists have led themselves to believe that, if foundationalism is true, they have no right, as scholars, to let their religious beliefs function as control beliefs within the devising and weighing of theories, i.e., with the project of exploring and developing the implications of Christian theism for the whole range of questions philosophers, scientists, and theologians ask and answer. 37 Finally, their conformist stance with respect to foundationalism has resulted in accepting the presumption that, as Basil Mitchell has said, " in case of conflict between religious and scientific or historical claims it is the former that must give way." 38 Briefly, then, Wolterstorff and Plantinga have argued that the adherence of Christian scholars to classic foundationalism has debilitated their work, holding them back, they claim, from the practice of authentically Christian scholarship. Wolterstorff states his claim this way: 36 N. Wolterstorff, "On Avoiding Historicism," Philosophia Reformata 45 ( 1980) : 178-185. s1 Alvin Plantinga, " Advice to Christian Philosophers," Faith and Philosophy 1 ( 1984) : 253·27 l. This is Plantinga's inaugural address as the John A. O'Brien Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. The points I am making in the text are, roughly, the same ones Plantinga makes on p. 260 of his paper. 38 The quotation is from an unpublished paper which Mitchell read to the staff of the Philosophy Department at Rhodes University, March 1984. The paper deals with Richard Swinburne and Nicholas Wolterstorff, and is called "Two Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion." See p. 11 for the quotation. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED ('" .. 649 I asked myself why it is that Christian scholars are so acquiescent in the face of scholarly claims which contradict their Christian convictions, and why they think it inappropriate, conversely, to let their Christian convictions guide their own scholarship. My answer was that they intuitively think of knowledge and science along foundationalist lines. That is, they hold intuitively to a foundationalist theory of knowledge. They intuitively think of knowledge as the goal of science. And they view the productions of theoreticians as, by and large, achieving this goal. For if one thinks of authentic scientiae as erecting a super-structure of certitudes on a foundation of certitudes, and if one thinks of our actual sciences as, by and large, authentic scientiae, then of course science will be seen as fundamentally OK as it is, and the relevance of the faith will be confined to the practice of such strategies as application interpretation, and harmonizing. 39 Here the point, I think, is the following. Presuming classic foundationalism to be true, Christian theists have confined the relevance of the Christian faith " to the offering of peculiarly Christian applications of received scholarship, to the offering of peculiarly Christian interpretation8 of received scholarship, and to accommodating . . . religious convictions to received scholarship." 40 Now Wolterstorff and Plantinga believe that a fourth strategy is available, one that does not, they maintain, accept conformism as an overriding rule. vVolterstorff writes: Common to the three strategies of harmonizing, setting theories within a context, and applying them is their conformism with respect to science. They all take for granted that science is OK as it is. In none of them is there any internal relation between Christian commitment and what goes on within the sciences. In none of them does Christian commitment enter into the devising and weighing of theories within the sciences.41 so N. Wolterstorff, "Christian Philosophy and the Heritage of Descartes," 20 pp., especially p. 10. This is an unpublished paper. Wolterstorff read it in the summer of 1979 at a conference on Locke. Descartes and the Rise of Modern Science, sponsored by the Institute for Christian Studies in Toronto, Canada. 40 Ibid., pp. 9-10. 41 N. Wolterstorff, Reason within the Bounds of Religion (Grand Rapids, Mich.: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1976, second edition, 1984), pp. 81-2. 650 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA I think we can understand Wolterstorff's proposal more fully if we remember that neither philosophy nor science nor theology evidences a single homogeneous structure. In many academic disciplines controversy is endemic; academicians as academicians disagree amongst themselves. But even were it not so, why should Christian scholarship degenerate into legitimizations of the academic status quo. Nowadays we expect, as Christians, that contemporary Christian social theories should be critical of both advanced industrial capitalism and state socialism. "VVe have learnt this and much more from recent political and liberation theologies. Correspondingly, why then should we expect anything less than a similar critical attitude regarding the classic foundationalist theory of knowledge and science? " Why should the Christian (or anyone else)," asks Wolterstorff, "surrender all his critical faculties in the face of it? " 42 Lest a mistaken impression be conveyed here, it must be said that in putting forth this proposal Wolterstorff and Plantinga do not at all mean to suggest that Christian scholars have nothing to learn from their non-Christian and non-theist colleagues. Nor do they mean to suggest that Christian scholars ought to retreat into their own intellectual ghettoes, assuming a posture of repudiation and isolation and conversing with only those scholars of similar breeding. Surely, says Plantinga, Christians have much to learn and much of enormous importance to learn by way of dialogue and discussion with their non-theistic colleagues ... We are all, theist and non-theist alike, engaged in the common human project of understanding ourselves and the world in which we find ourselves. If the Christian philosophical community is doing its job properly, it will be engaged in a complicated, many-sided dialectical discussion, making its own contribution to that common human project. It must pay careful attention to other contributions; it must gain a deep understanding of them; it must learn what it can from them and it must take unbelief with profound seriousness. 43 42 Ibid., p. 82. 43 Plantinga, "Advice", pp. 270-271. THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 651 So far I have referred quite generally to what Wolterstorff and Plantinga call the classic foundationalist view of knowledge, by which they mean quite generally the view that basic beliefs constitute the evidence in terms of which all other beliefs are justified. But it is important for us to describe more specifically the form of foundationalism that is being subsumed under this genera.I label. The foundationalist supposes, we remember, that there is a set of propositions, let's call it Es, such that my belief in God is rational if and only if it is evident with regard to Es. He also supposes that belief in God is not among the propositions to be found in Es. For the foundationalist, we noted earlier, a proposition is properly basic only if it is either self-evident or incorrigible or evident to the senses. Now Wolterstorff and Plantinga call that form of foundationalism which holds that Es is limited to such propositions basis-restrictive foundationalism. It is this species of foundationalism, which they take to be the classical view, that they launch an attack against. For purposes of brevity, I have decided to follow the main part of the argument set forward in some essays recently published by Plantinga. 44 In the main and for purposes of this paper, I shall sidestep many of the difficult conceptual problems surrounding the analysis of notions like self-evident and incorrigible. The fundamental principle of classical foundationalism is: (I) A proposition p is properly basic for a person S if and only if p is either self-evident to S or incorrigible for S or evident to the senses for S. What kind of propositions are self-evident, asks Plantinga? Well, arithmetical truths such as (2) 2 + 1 = 3: simple truths of logic such as 44 A. Plantinga, "Is Belief in God Rational?," in Rationality and Religious Belief, ed. C. F. Delaney (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1979), pp. 7-27; "Is Belief in God Properly Basic?," Nous 15 (1981): 41-51; "The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology," Christian Scholars Review 11 (1981): 187-198; and "Reason and Belief in God," in Faith and Rationality (see note 35) . EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA (3) No man is both married and unmarried; and the generalization of simple truths of logic, such as (4) For any proposition p the conjunction of p with its denial is false. 45 With respect to incorrigible propositions, some philosophers have taken these to consist in claims about one's own mental life, namely, propositions which describe my immediate perceptual experience, and propositions which describe my present sensations or feelings. Regarding the former, Plantinga gives the following as examples: (5) There is a tree before me, (6) I am wearing shoes, (7) That tree's leaves are yellow. Propositions (5) - (7) entail the existence of such material objects as trees, shoes, and yellow leaves. But I could mistakenly believe that there is a tree before me, etc. So more cautious claims must go into the foundation, such as (8) It seems to me that I see a tree, (9) I seem to see something yellow, or even, says Plantinga, as Chisholm puts it, (10) I am appeared yellowly to. Summarily stated: (11) p is incorrigible for S if and only if (a) it is not possible that S believe p and p be false, and (b) it is not possible that S believe -p and p be true. 46 Following this, Plantinga invites us to look more closely at (1). It contains two elements, he says. 45 Plantinga, "Reason and Belief in God," pp. 55-56. p. 58. I should stress that Plantinga wouldn't take "There is a tree before me " as an incorrigible proposition. It is, indeed a report of an immediate perceptual experience-or at least, Plantinga would take it that way. Such beliefs arise in us immediately. But it's not incorrigible. The incorrigible ones would be those given in ( 8) and ( 9) . Nicholas Wolterstorff reminded me of this point. 46 Ibid., THE FATE OF THEISM REVISITED 653 (12) A proposition is properly basic if it is self-evident, incorrigible, or evident to the senses; (13) a proposition is properly basic only if it meets this condition. (13) may indeed be true, says Plantinga. But what reason, if any, is there for accepting the proposition that a proposition is properly basic only if it is self-evident, incorrigible, or evident to the senses? Does this proposition itself display any of these relevant features? That is, suggests Plantinga, suppose the proposition (14) most propositions that display these relevant features are true itself displays one or more of these features. Plantinga then asks: Would that he a relevant answer to the question, what reason, if any, is there for believing that most propositions displaying this feature are true? It is hard to see how. The question is whether a proposition's displaying this feature is a reason for thinking it true; to reply that [ (14)] displays this feature is simply to invite the question again. Here the appeal to self-evidence seems entirely unsatisfactory. It is as if the theist were to reply to the question: "Why believe in God?" by pointing out that God requires us to believe in Him, and requires us to believe only what is true. This may indeed be so; but it does not apply a reason for belief for anyone who does not already believe. 47 But now suppose the foundationalist does accept (13) as basic. Suppose, that is to say, that he does not accept it on evidence provided by other propositions but instead accepts others on the basis of it. Well, argues Plantinga, according to (13) itself, (13) is properly basic for F only if [ (13)] is self-evident or incorrigible or evident to the senses for him. Clearly [ (13) ] meets none of these conditions. Hence it is not properly basic for F. But then F is self-referentially inconsistent in accepting [ (13)]; he accepts it 47 Plantinga, "Is Belief in God Rational?," p. 20. Unfortunately, when I wrote this paper I did not have access to the book where this article is found. My page reference here is to loose copy of the article that I have in my possession. Subsequent references are to this copy. 654 EDWARD J. ECHEVERRIA ns basic, despite the fact that [ (13)] does not meet the condition for proper bas\cality that [ (13)] itself lays down. 48 conclm1cs Plantinga, the foundationalist is "hoist by his own petard." For proposition (13) is itself neither selfcvicleni nor evident to the senses nor incorrigible. "\Vhy, then, 1ve accept such a criterion? Plantinga continues: But suppose we waive this point for the moment and leave the foundationalist to try to see how to achieve consistency here. Is there any reason to believe [ (13)]? If so, what is it? [ (13)] cer·tainly does nol appear to be self-evident; it is certaintly not incorrigible. It is not er.sy to see, furthermore, that it either follows from or is evident with respect to propositions that are self-evident m incon