FEEDING THE COMATOSE AND THE COMMON GOOD IN THE CATHOLIC TRADITION ROBERT BARRY, O.P. University of Illinois Ohampaign-Urbana, IlUnoi8 A A RECENT convention :sponsored by the Catholic Health Associaition in Boston, Laurence J. O'Connell, vice-president for ethics and theology, ma.de the following comments: I am concerned that some of those who are legitimately alarmed by the potential abuses associated with the public policy that authorizes the withholding and withdrawing of mechanical means of nutrition and hydration are sometimes publicly misrepresenting the Catholic moral tradition. In other words, in their well-intentioned and perfectly legitimate efforts to avoid the slippery-slope-that is, the wrongful withholding or withdrawing of nutrition or hydration from vulnerable dasses of patients-those advocates are placing the Roman Catholic moral tradition itself on the slippery slope. It is mistaken to say it is the church's teaching that we may never withhold or withdraw artificial nutrition and hydration. It is mistaken to uncritically refer to the removal of medically engineered nutrition in all cases as starvation-that is, the willful withholding of nutrition as morally obligatory. It is mistaken to say that the ethical standards of a single Catholic hospital are necessarily coextensive with the ethical standards of the Catholic Church. Just because an individual Catholic facility, for whatever reason, uniformly refuses to allow the withholding or withdrawing of technological feeding, does not mean that the Church itself disallows such withholdings or withdrawals. 1 It is not clear how the Catholic moral tradition can be put on the " slippery slope " by opposing certain forms of with1 "Church and State Overlap in Ethical Debate", American Medicai News. February 27, 1987. p. I. 1 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. drawal of feeding from specific classes of patients. Dr. O'Connell has misrepresented the thought of most of those who oppose the recent American Medical Association's new opinion which holds that artificially administered nutrition and fluids can be removed from terminally ill patients, even when they are not imminently dying. 2 There are no Catholic moralists who claim that it is always and everywhere morally wrong to withhold or withdraw feeding from patients. However, there are a number of moralists as well as bishops who now hold it to be wrong to withhold or withdraw feeding in those cases where the withholding or withdrawal becomes the fundamental and underlying cause of death. O'Connell is p11obably correct in saying that the policies of one hospital do not necessarily deteJ1IDine the moral doctrines of the universal Church, but neither does one national organization such as the Catholic Health Association with only a loose affiliation with the magisterial hierarchy of the Church necessarily do this either. The debate over the provision of ,aissistedfeeding is a debate over whether iit is morally legitimate ito withdraw feeding so 1tihat .t:he primary and fundamental reason why the person dies is that withdrawal. It is a debate over whether those with a certain " quality of life " can be permitted to be killed by omission. It is a debate over whether feeding provided by routine nursing measures that can significantly sustain the life is a medical treatment that should he governed by the criteria governing other treatments, or whether it is an 2 "Withholding or Withdrawing Life Prolonging :Medical Treatment" adopted by the Council on Ethical and Judicial .Affairs of the .Amercian Medical .Association on March 15, 1987, In its pertinent parts, it stated: The social commitment of the physician is to sustain life and relieve suffering. Where the performance of one duty conflicts with the other, the choice of the patient, or his family or legal representative if the ·patient to act in his own behalf, should prevail. Life prolonging medical treatment includes medication and artificially or technologically supplied respiration, nutrition or hydration. In treating a terminally ill or irreversibly comatose patient, the physician should determine whether the benefits of treatment outweigh its burdens. .At all times, the dignity of the patient should be maintained .•. FEEDING THE COMATOSE 8 aspect of normal care, like protection from exposure or hygienic care, that is to be accorded to all patients. In this piece, I wish to review the thoughts of some of the classical Catholic moralists and show their reluctance to authorize withdrawal of life-sustaining nutrition and fluids. I also wish to show that, where they did permit food and water to be removed, their arguments were either flawed or open to severe criticism. And I will also show tha.t assisted feeding can be required of patients because of the demands of the common good. The overall purpose of this effort is to show that requiring assisted feeding when its rejection or removal would be the fundamental cause of death is not foreign to the classical Catholic medical-ethical tradition. I. Thomas Aquinas Aquinas did not write any treatise devoted specifically to providing food and fluids, but he did note in his Super Epistolas S. Pauli that: A man has the obligation to sustain his body; otherwise he would be a killer of himself . . . by precept, therefore, he is bound to nurish his body and likewise we are bound to all the other items without which the body cannot live.8 In this passage Aquinas affirms an obligation to take food and fluids because of a general obligation to sustain life, and he ,asserts that £aii1ing to take them could be momlly equiVtalentto self-killing in some cases. He 1aipparently would not say thrus about medical treatments, for he would hold it licit to reject medical treatments in some cases without being a self-killer.4 The passage implies that there are more circumstances in s St. Thomas Aquinas, Super Flpistolos 8.PauU (Taurin-Romae: Marietti, 1953), II Thess., Lee. II, n. 77. Translation in Cronin, Daniel, The Moral Law in Regard, to the Ord,inary and, Flrotraordinary Means of Conserving Life (Dissertatio ad Lauream in Facultate Theologica Pontificiae Universitatis Gregorianae, Romae, 1958), p. 48. 4 Medical treatments that could be rejected without being a self-killer would be those which are rejected out of a due love for life and for the spiritual goods. 4 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. which one could licitly reject medical treatments than there are where one could reject food and water. Aquinas vaguely asserts a distinction between nutrition and fluids and medical treatments, and he imposes a stronger obligation to receive food and water than to receive medical treatments. The reason for this stronger obligation seems to be that food and water are ·seen as a means of sustaining life whether the person is sick or not, while medical treatments are therapeutic measures only to be used for those with clinical conditions. Elsewhere, he says in a statement in the Secunda Secundae that should be balanced against the previous one that: [l]t is inbred for a man to love his own life and those things which contribute to it, but in due measure (tamen debito proprio) which means those things which permit attainment of the final goal. Thus, those things which permit attainment of the final end of man are to be loved, but only in due measure. 5 In the previous statement, Aquinas warned against self-killing and a lack of respect for life, but in this one he warns against anxious concern for life and undue love for life-preserving measures. This statement imposes an obligation to have due respect for life and to have a moderate love for those things which sustain life. There is a duty to protect one's life by moderate means and he denounces an exaggerated fear of death which can cause an undue clinging to life. Aquinas has not defined what means of sustaining life are undue, and one must wait for later writers to deal with this issue. What precisely " due love of the things that sustain life " would be is not clear from this passage. It would seem that Aquinas is objecting to demands for radically expensive treatments that would not hold out much prospect of prolonging life. If this is true, then it would be hard to see how he could object to tube feeding for a medically stable patient given by routine nursing procedures. This would not seem to be an uncommon or exotic means of preserving life. B Summa Theologica, Blackfriars Translation, P. G. Wa.lsh. (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966), Anthony Rosa, O.P., and q. 126, a. 1. FEEDING THE COMATOSE 5 What he might mean by medical treatments that can permit the attainment of the final end of many is not clear. He may have been referring to those treatments which enaible a person to act rationally and interpersonally. However, that interpretation is unlikely because it would imply that there was no duty to give even palliative care to those who suffered emotional or mental disabilities. What Aquinas probably meant was that treatments which could sustain either biological life itself or human life in all its dimensions had to be given because both of these permit attainment of the final end of man. If he did not mean thait, it would be hard to see how he could have objected that refusal of feeding in some cases was selfIn relation to our contemporary controversy on assisted feeding, his principle would affirm a duty to receive and provide readily available forms of assisted feeding when their denial or refusal would be the fundamental cause of death of a medically stable patient. It should be recalled that what is "common" is relative to a society, and in our society assisted feeding administered by routine nursing measures is simply a common mode of providing nutrition, and it should be provided when its withdrawal would cause death. 2. Francisco Vitoria Francisco Vitoria requires patients to take ordinary measures to preserve life, and explicitly holds that a patient would have at least to use foods commonly employed by persons to conserve their life.6 Vitoria affirms an obligation to receive food and water when they can be readily provided by a given society. Only the use of ordinary foods, and mot exotic dishes, 1 Releotiones Theologioae, (Lugduni, 1587), Relectio IX, de 6 F. Vitoria, Temp n. 1, (Trans. in Cronin, op. oit., pp. 48-49). .Atkinson notes that the obligation to take drugs is less grave than the obligation to take food because food is per se ordered to the preservation of life. See his "Theological History on the Catholic Teaching on Prolonging Life" in Moral Responsibility m Prolonging Life Deoisions, edited by Donald McCarthy and .Albert Moraczew· ski, O.P. (St. Louis: Pope John Center, 1981). p. 98. 6 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. would be mo:mlly required, even if this would shorten the life of the patient. In his own way, he affirms an obligation to give and receive only what are customarily and commonly available forms of care and feeding in a society. He claims that it is one thing to destroy life ·and .another to cease to protect or prolong it. 7 One must never do the former, but he holds that it is not always necessary to do the latter. This formulation, however, is too vague and general to be useful, for failing to protect life in some instances is morally equivalent to destroying it. For example, permitting another to die by withholding protection from exposure is morally equivalent to destroying that person's life. Similarly, failing to sustain another's life by withholding life-sustaining food and water that can be provided by routine and customary means is morally equivalent to failing to protect. Nowhere does Vitoria affirm that " common " feeding could 'be rejected, because this would be killing by omission. Unfortunately, he does not explain what constitutes "common" feeding. What makes feeding " common " would seem to be relative to one's culture and technology, but Vitoria offers no opinion on ithi:s. But he does teach that talring food is not obligatory if great effort is required, and he probably means great effort on the palt of the patient. 8 Taking food when great effort would be demanded of the patient would require a radical exercise of the virtue of fortitude, ·and Vitoria would not impose such a demand as a matter of justice. The term " common " is purely formal, but it must be assumed to mean what is routinely provided to a patient in a given condition; this criterion is highly relative to the means available of provmding food and wiater. And there is no hint in Vitoria's thought that " ordinary " medical cusfoms could be violated. He discusses the issue of food and water under the aspect of the virtues, and affirms that failing to receive commonly avail7 See Atkinson, "Theological History of Catholic Teaching on Prolonging Life," p. 98. BlbU. FEEDING THE COlVIATOSE 7 ruble life-sustaning food and water would be against the virtue of fortitude, and :failing to provide it would seem to be against the virtue of justice. 9 Like Aquinas, he imposes a stronger duty to provide food than to provide medical treatments, for he holds that the obligation to take drugs is less seriqus than is the obliga;tion to take food. In order for medical treatments to be morally 'required in some circumstances, it would only be necessary for there to be some hope of returning to normal functioning or some form of recovery. But "common" food and water, or that by which regularly 'a man can live (satis est, quod det operam, per quam horno regulariter potest vivere), have to be given even if recovery is not possible, but if there is some hope of life.10 And he makes no explicit distinctions between biological, psychological, and spiritual life, and this implies that food and water must be given if there is some hope of continuing biological or physical life. If there is moral certitude that food and water could hold out " some hope of life " being continued, then it would seem that he would hold it obligatory to provide nutrition and hydration. There is no obligation to use the most expensive and costly treatments or foods to sustain life, but this should not be interpreted to mean that a person could be morally required to suffer destitution to pay for common feeding or ordinary medical care.11 For Vitoria it is not necessary to use every means available to sustain life, hut only to use those means which are 9 Ibid., p. 97. Vitoria discusses the taking of food under the aspect of temperance, but it would seem that denial of life-sustaining food and drink to an individual would not be against temperance as much as it would be against justice, while the refusal of life-sustaining food and water would be against the virtue of fortitude. 10 Ibid., pp. 98-9. The failure to preserve one's life could be rejection of those things "by which regularly a man can live". This would seem to consist in food and fluids taken orally or what modern authors call "ordinary" surgeries and medical treatments. The modern criterion seems to be that of requiring not just food and fluids but ordinary surgeries as well. 11 Ibid., p. 99. He affirms that expensive or exotic foods would not be required, and he does not hold that one would have to live in the most healthful climates either. See his Oommentaria a la Secunda Seoundae de Santo Thomas, (Salamanca, ed. de Hereda, O.P., 1952) in II-II, q. 147, a (transl. as in Cronin, p. 59 ) . 8 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. of themselves intended for that purpose and which are congruent with that end.12 And if there is a "kind of impossibility" in receiving food and water, Vitoria would not require their provision or acceptance. Thus, if there was profound revulsion to food, or a medical reason for rejecting it, he would not morally require it. It is not clear what he means by this, for food and water, hygiene and medicine all naturally aim at preserving life. On this point, Vitoria is ambivalent, for while he admits that food, water and medical treatments are naturally ordered toward life, he affirms a more stringent obligation to provide food and water than to provide medical treatments, implying that they 1are different in nature. 13 This ambivalence in Vitoria's thought is important, for Fr. Edward Bayer, a contemporary moral theologian, contends that there is an obligation to provide food and water orally or" connatul'lally '',but that this obligation ceases when a person needs assisted feeding.14 For Bayer, the natural aspect of oral feeding imposes the obligation, but it is by no means clear that such a distinction was made by Vitoria.15 It is not clear that Vitoria sees the mode of provision ,as being as crucial as the commonness of the mode of feeding. What is clear about Vitoria's thought, however, is that he believes that the provision of commonly avail3Jble, life-sustaining food and water is ethically obligatory. Relative to the contemporary debate on feeding medically stable comatose patients, Vitoria's teachings would imply that food and fluids, provided as an aspect of basic patient maintenance, could not be withheld from comatose patients because they are now an aspect of" common" feeding. He would not require their provision if it was medically impossible to provide it, or if the person was unable to receive it for clear medical reasons. And he does not demand that r1JJdical or extreme ex12 Relectiones, Relecti X, de Homicidio, n. 35. (transl. as in Cronin, p. 50). See Atkinson, "Theological History of Catholic Teaching on Prolonging Life", p. 99. 13 H[bid. u "Foregoing Life-Sustaining Food and Water: Thought". Unpublished :Manuscript, pp. 1-2. 1900 Years of Catholic FEEDING THE COl\.fATOSE 9 pense be experienced to provide it. But if receiving or providing food or water is " common " in a given culture, he would hold it to be morally required. He considered food and water to be different in nature from medical treatments, and he established difierent criteria for their provision and acceptance. He admits that there are elective forms of feeding, but those that are common modes of feeding ·are morally mandatory. By asserting that there is a stronger obligation to take food than there is to take medical treatments, he is affirming the principle that if assisted feeding and fluids provided as an aspect of basic patient maintenance could meet the nutritional and hydrational needs of the patient, they should be given. 8. Juan Cardinal de Lugo In the century after Vitoria, there was a widespread support among moral theologians for his teachings. Juan Cardinal de Lugo is important because he supported Vitoria's teachings, but he was also important because he drew clearer distinctions between morally permissible letting-die •and immoral killing based on the type of means being refused or withheld. He is noteworthy for being exceptionally liberal among his contemporaries for his view of what constituted an extraordinary means.16 Because of this, Atkinson notes that he was so liberal in his views that he accepted virtually any reason whatsoever for removing a medical treatment. For instance, he .held that drinking wine or abstaining from it could be an extraordinary form of care in some cases. With regard to the administration of extraordin·ary treatments, De Lugo claims that a person caught in a burning building would not have to use water to extinguish part of the fire, thus only delaying momentarily the time of death, because partially extinguishing the fire would be ·a futile attempt to preserve life.17 This is strictly applicable to a patient 16 Atkinson, "Theological History of Catholic Teachings on Prolonging Life", pp. 101-2. 17 De Lugo, Juan. Disputationes SckoZasticae et Morales, (ed. nova, 10 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. who is truly dying and for whom assisted feeding would not substantially sustain life. In such a case, the removal of food and fluids would not be the underlying and fundamental cause of death as would be the fire, and it would therefore be permissible to remove them. But whether these sorts of patients would have to be fed is not the issue today. The pertinent issue is whether the removal of .feeding should be morally permitted when its removal would be the fundamental cause of dearth. He holds that the only condition necessary for providing food and water is that there be " some hope of sustaining life" .18 The term " some" does not mean that it be ,a,hsolutely certain that life will be sustained, but only that there be some prospect of it being continued by the provision of food and water. This requirement that feeding be given when there is some hope of 1ife being preserved would seem to require its rprov:isionin thait case. He is one of the few classical moralists to give high priority to the judgment of a physician, and if a physician determines that a treatment is necessary he would require the patient to consent to the treatment. 19 De Lugo was primarily concerned with the morality of mutilations, and he held that they were obligatory if they could cure and if they did not involve great pain. If 'a mutilating therapy would be necessary for the health or well-being of the patient, but the patient rejected it, De Lugo would compel its acceptance. 20 De Lugo states that a patient: must permit [a] cure when the doctors judge it necessary, and when it can happen without intense pain; not, if it is accompanied by Parisiis, Vives, 1868-69), Vol. VI, De Justitio et Jure, Disp. X, Sec. l, n. 21 (transl. as in Cronin, p. 59). 1s Atkinson, "Theological History of Catholic Teachings on Prolonging Life'', p. 102. 19 De Lugo, foe. cit. 20 It is likely that De Lugo held this to prevent patients from committing suicide by rejecting medically indicated, beneficial and nonburdensome treatments from being provided. FEEDING THE CO:MATOSE 11 very bitter pain; because a man is not bound to employ extraordinary and difficult means to conserve lif e.21According to De Lugo, the failure to employ reasonably aV1aii1able mea:ns of preserving Life could he equivalelllt to taking one's life, but he does not identify the conditions under which this might occur .22 This principle applies when the means are not difficult to use and when death from the lethal cause could be easily .avoided. This would imply that assisted feeding would he required i£ it was rerudily ;a-v;aiLable and if !Lts provision could prevent death by starvation or dehydration. Thus, De Lugo was deeply concerned about the morality of removing food and water from patients, and he clearly believed that some withdmwals were immoral. 4. Fr. Gerald Kelly, SJ. A. The Usefulness of Assisted Feeding Fr. Gerald Kelly is important in the history of contemporary Catholic medical ethics because of his development of the doctrine of ordinary and extraordinary means. He developed his views on the requirements to receive medical treatments, and in his later writings he established a clearer normative position on the duties to receive care and treatment. Kelly claims that families and medical professionals should be brought into treatment decisions because they have moral duties demanding respect. 28 In holding this, he laid a foundation for the contemporary " covenantal " theory of medical decisionmaking espoused by Paul Ramsey .24 21J. De Lugo, Disputation.es Sohloasticae et Morales, Vol. VI, De Justitia et Jure, Disp. X, Sec. 1, n. 21. 22 Atkinson, "Theological History of Catholic Teachings on Prolonging Life", p. 102. Ulbid., p. 107. Kelly mentions this, it •seems, to affirm that families and health care providers have duties to provide care and that authoriza.tion of withdrawal of ca.re by either of these can constitute culpable killing. 2' See Paul Ramsey, The Patient as Person (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979) and Basia Ohristian liJthics (Chica.go: University of Chicago Press, 1950), pp. 367·388. ROBERT BARRY, O.P. In his advanced views Kelly provides us with the what has come to be 'accepted as the " classical " definition of ordinary and extraordinary means: Ordinary means are all medicines, treatments and operations which offer a reasonable hope of benefit and which can be obtained and used without excessive expense, pain or other inconvenience. Extraordinary means are all medicines, treatments and operations which cannot be obtained and used without excessive expense, pain or other inconvenience, or which if used, would not offer a reasonable hope of benefit.25 After making this distinction, he proceeds to ask if there could he a " useless ordinary " means of preserving life and if such a means could be morally required. Initially, Kelly argues that all ordinary means are obligatory, but this changes in his later works in which he replies that no one can be required to employ a means that is useless. He therefore declared some ordinary means to be elective because they were "useless ". 26 He writes: 1 [N]o remedy is obligatory unless it offers a reasonable hope of checking or curing the disease. I would not call this a common opinion because many authors do not refer to it, but I know of no one who opposes it, and it seems to have intrinsic merit as an application of the axiom, nemo ad inutile tenetur [i.e., No one can obliged to do what is useless]. Moreover, it squares with the rule commonly applied to the analogous case of helping one's neighbor: one is not obliged to offer help unless there is a reasonable assurance that it will be efficacious.21 Kelly argues correctly that a treatment is useless if it does not offer a reasonable hope of checking or curing a disease. In light of this definition, it would seem that provision of food and fluids by assisted means would be useful when it could prevent the person from succumbing to starv,ation or dehydra1 25 G. Kelly, "The Duty to Preserve Life", Theological Studies, XII ( 1951), p. 550. Means of Preserving Life" 2'6 G. Kelly, "The Duty of Using Artificial Tkeologioal Studies, XI ( 1950), pp. 218-9. 21 Ibid., pp. 207 -8. FEEDING THE COMATOSE 18 tion. For in that circumstance, it could " check ,, the " disease " of starvation. Oddly, Kelly argues that there would be no obligation to provide fluids and feeding to a patient by assisted means if the patient was unconscious and was expected to die within a few weeks.28 In this situation food and water should be provided because they could achieve their end of preventing death from dehydration or starvation and thus would not be useless because they could " check the disease ,,. Kelly does not hold that life-sustaining measures would have to" check disease for a certain period of time'', but only that they have this power. It is thus peculiar that Kelly considers assisted feeding useless simply because its power is temporally limited. Further application of his principle would imply that feeding which could only sustain life for short period of time is " useless,, would also seem to allow spoon-feeding to be withdrawn or withheld from a conscious termina1ly ill patient with even more time to live, because spoon-feeding is moil'e burdensome to others than is tube feeding. It could permit withholding insulin from a diabetic who was expected to live for a couple of weeks, even though its withdrawal would cause death, and it might even permit withdrawal of hygienic care or protection from exposure. Kelly's understanding of utility is correct, but it seems that he did not apply it properly in practice, for he did not see that feeding could fend off death for a limited period of time and was therefore useful. He is correct in saying that useless treatments need not be given, but he fails to see that some forms of assisted feeding were not useless when they could prevent death from dehydration or starvation even for a limited period of time by their mere provision. Kelly's belief that there should be no obligation to continue feeding a patient expected ·to die within two weeks if the patient is unconscious is quite remarkable. He asserts that a conscious patient should be permitted to decide whether or not to 1 :IS Ibid., P· 220. 14 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. receive feeding, but he holds there is no duty to give food and water to one in a similar state but unconscious.29 This view would radically limit the obligations of health care providers to the unconscious terminal patient, and it implies the moral ;permissibility of abandoning provision of all treatment for them. It is also quite discriminatory because it implies that capacity for psychological relating is the ground for the possession of moral rights. KeHy would undoubtedly object to reeently enacted Baby Doe Regulations of :the Child Abuse Aot which prohibited the removal of food and water from comatose infants, despite the fact that strong approval was given these regulations by the disaibled community. 30 Kelly's argument in favor of removing feeding from unconscious terminally ill patients is pertinent to the contemporary issue of providing feeding for the medically stllible comatose. F-0r, under some definitions of euthanasia, withdrawing food and wiruter from them would be mercy kiilling because the withdrawal would be done for the purpose of causing death to prevent a patient from experiencing severe pain. 81 Kelly correctly ·argued that the removal of some medical treatments in such cases was permissible, but feeding should not be withdrawn, since withdrawal of food and water would cause death as surely as would a lethal injection. The withdrawal of food and water, provided as an aspect of routine patient maintenance and of normal nursing care, is not 29 Ibid., p. 219. ao Non discrimination on the Basis of H andioap; ProceiVures and Guidelines Relating to Health Oare for Handicapped. Infants; Final Rule, 49 Fed. Reg. 1622, 1623 (January 1983). HHS reported that after a period of comment, 16,739 comments were received, 96.5% of which were favorable. See: "The Emergence of Institutional Ethics Committees" by Ronald E. Cranford and A. Edward Doudera, in their Institutional Ethics Oommittees and Health Oare Decision Making (Ann Arbor: Health Administration Press, 1984), p. 5. a1 Webster's Dictionary defines it as an "act or method of causing doo,th painlessly, so as to end suffering". Webster's New World Dictionary (Second College Edition, ed. David B. Guralnik. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1970), p. 889. FEEDING THE COMATOSE 15 merely the " occasion" of the patient's death, but is its cause.32 When one removes or refrains from throwing a life ring to a man who would drown without it, the remov;al or withholding is not the "occasion " of the man's death but is the cause. Similarly, the removal or withholding of these readily providable forms of feeding are the causes of the death of a patient who would be medically stable with their provision. He allows this withdrawal even though it would imply that death could be physically caused by removing a routinely available means of preserving life. Kelly ignores the issue of causation of death, and he seems to .feel that :there would be nothing wrong with causing death if death was expected in only a matter of days. Kelly's endorsement of withdrawing feeding from a comatose patient who was expected to die shortly did not go uncontested, however, for Fr. Joseph Donovan argued that IV feeding was an ordinary medical treatment and that there was no impossibility in feeding the comatose.33 He claimed that removing feeding in the instance where Kelly permitted it was morally equivalent to causing death, and he essentially charged Kelly with permitting mercy killing by omission when death was imminent. 34 Kelly agreed that .assisted feeding was an ordinary medical treatment and he justified this position by making assertions that many would question today. He claimed that this form of feeding was an ordinary medical treatment in the speeulative order but that it was an extraordinary treatment in the practical order because it was clinically useless.85 By admitting that a;ssisted feeding was speculatively obligafory but practi32 The claim that withdrawal of life-sustaining nutrition a.nd fluids that are readily providable does not kill the patient, but is merely the occasion on which the patient succumbs. See The Medica.Z-MoraZ New8Zetter, Vol. 24, No. 4, .April, 1987, p. 3. 3S Fr. Donovian's article appeared in Homiletic and PMtoraZ Review, XLIX, (August, 1949), p. 72. HKelly, "The Duty of Using .Artificial :Means of Preserving Life", p. 210. so .Atkinson, "Theological History of Catholic Teachings on Prolonging Life", p. 109. 16 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. cally elective, Kelly implicitly affirmed that there was something about assisted feeding that distinguished it from other forms of therapeutic, palliative or remedial medical treatment. But he was unable to ·see this difference precisely, and he did not impose obligations correlative to this difference. Kelly would have had no trouble teaching that a therapeutic procedure such as an ·appendectomy for a dying person was useless because the person would die from the other cause before he or she died from the appendicitis, and he seemed to think that assisted feeding could become extraordinary in exactly the same sense. What he did not see was that withdrawal of feeding creates a lethal condition, irrespective of the clinical picture of the patient. The inconsistency of thought compromises his claims about the optional chal'lacter of assisted feeding for various classes of patients. Kelly's view that care and treatment can be speculatively ordinary hut pl'iacticallyelective is not tenable today, and his authority in the issue can be rightfully challenged. His distinction between the speculative and practical has never been widely accepted by medical ethicists, and it is of uncertain utility. It is interesting that Kelly's argument for withdrawing food ·and fluids was never accepted into the mainstream of Catholic ethical teaching, even though his conclusion was. And conversely, Donovan's arguments were logically sound and implanted in the tradition, hut they have been rejected in recent decades. Kelly also did not f.ace the issue of causality squarely, for the withdrawal of feeding from such a person was not the mere occasion of death but was in fact the cause of death. It seems that Donovan was correct and that Kelly did in fact permit those near death to be killed by dehydration and starvation. Some contemporary right-to-die ,activists have charged that the Catholic trllldition has .allowed mercy killing by omission because of Kelly's views, and there seems to be support for this charge.86 ao See Gerald LaRue, l!Juth111fU1,8i!J, and .Religion. (Los Anglees: Hemlock Press, 1981). Kelly himself feared that his views might be interpreted as FEEDING THE COMATOSE 17 Kelly was apparently unaware of ·a diHerence between ordinary medical treatments and what ·some ethicists are now calling normal care or minimal care. 87 This category consists of hygienic care, protection from psychological support, feeding, and the maintenance of such devices as urinary catheters. Some now believe that to withhold these forms of care would be morally equivalent to killing by omission, but Kelly mentions none of this and it is not evident that he had a clear idea of what constituted killing by omission. B. Assisted Feeding and the Common Good More positively, Kelly is alniost the only moralist in the recent Catholic tradition to state explicitly that patients could be required to use extraordinary and per se elective measures if this was required by the common good or a higher value. 38 This is a superb insight, and it should be applied to protecting society from the emergence of socially and legally endorsed mercy killing. The common good can require a person to accept assisted feeding in order to prevent the social and legal endorsement of euthanasia by omission which would pose a clear threat to the handicapped, immature, unstable and medically vulnerable from mercy killing. Kelly holds that a civil leader can be required to receive medical treatments, •and that a father of a family could be morally required to receive them to protect his family. 39 If saving one's life is necessary for the weHare of family or the security of a nation, one must do so.40 A common good exists where there is a common goal, 1 being "Catholic euthanasia". See "The Duty of Using Artificial :Means of Preserving Life", p. 219. s1 See Smith, William, B. "Judeo-Christian Teaching on Euthanasia: Definitions, Distinctions and Decisions". The Linaore Quarter"liu, vol. 54, n. 1 (February, 1987), p. 29. Also see Barry, Robert "The Ethics of Providing LifeSustaining Nutrition and Fluids to Incompetent Patients", The Journal of Family and Culture. Vol. I, No. 2 (Summer 1985) p. 27. as Kelly, The Duty of Using Artificial Means of Preseroing Life, p. 206; p. 106. a9 Ibid., p. 216. 40 See Welty, Eberhard, Handbook of Christian Social Bthios (New York: Herde & Herder, 1963), p. 312. is ROBERT BARRY, O.P. and in the case of society, that goal is the well-being of all, and not just the maximization of individual liberties or rights. 41 The good of the community is prior :to private interest, and the individual is duty bound to strive for the common good. The common good can place demands on individuals, but there are filmirts to whait lit oan reqmre. Fir.st, nowhere is an individual released from the duty to do what is morally good, and appeals to the common good cannot release from this obligation. 42 Second, the order of values must be preserved which means that higher values must be protected at the expense of lower ones.43 Thus, morality can be promoted at the expense of •art or economic interest, for example. Third, in times of great crisis, higher values can be set aside for the attainment of lower ones.44 For example, educational activities can be suspended in time of war for the welfare of the entire community. Extraordinary measures can be commanded by the common good, so that a person can be required to make personal sacrifices to save another's life if that can be done without putting one's self or family in the same danger. Thus, one can be required to forego certain material advantages to protect the lives of others. Acting in behalf of the common good is required by justice, and is commanded by the virtue of universal justice which seeks to protect the well being of all by directing all actions toward the common good.45 The virtue of universal justice de41 St. Thomas says that "[T]he community has necessarily the sa.me goal as the individual." "The good of the individual is not a final end but is sub· ordinated to the common good." "Individual well-being cannot exist without the welfare of the community . . . therefore it is judging correctly in the light of the common good that man must recognize what is good for him." See ·Welty, op. cit, p. 94. This principle is in harmony with what some moralists call "universal justice" for such demands to be made. Universal justice is the most important of the. natural virtues, according to Thoma.a. Summa Theologica, II-II 58, 6-7. 42 Welty, Handbook of Christian Social Ethics, p. 112. 4s Ibid., pp. 112-3. 41 Ibid., p. 113. 45 Ibid., pp. 312-3. FEEDING THE COMATOSE 19 termines what demands can be imposed on a community by the common good. Virtues can be required by universal justice so ,that coura;ge could be required. in war, just as temperance could be commanded in times of famine. 46 That extraordinary forms of care or treatment should be obligatory for the common good is in accord with the principles of universal justice because it is an act of courage for the benefit of the entire community. They can be set aside in specific circumstances so that the individual can pursue the common good. Assisted feeding could be mandated for certain classes because allowing them to reject it or be denied it would place entire classes of handicapped, despairing, terminal and chronically sick patients at risk. Because there is so much imprecision in medical diagnosis and prognosis, feeding should be required. for all where it is medically possible so that those who should be justly given feeding are not denied it. By way of summary, one must be careful about invoking Kelly uncritically on the issue of ·assisted feeding, for there were evident inadequacies in his thought. To his credit, he admits that his principles were inherently imprecise, and he argues that, if one is to err in ambiguous situations, it should be on the side of life. He gave us many of the fundamental concepts by which we understand medical ethics today, but some of his analyses were not ·adequately consistent or insightful. He apparently did not believe that it was possible to kill terminally ill patients by denial of assisted feeding, and he gave no evidence of medically stable but comatose patients or persons with disabilities wishing to end their lives by starvation or dehydration, and thus he is in some respects not the sure.sit of guides for today's problems. Some of his contemporaries, such as Fr. Donovan, saw this and were critical of his insights, but Donovan's thought has not been given the prominent place that was given to Kelly's in Catholic medical-ethical tradition. This rebuts claims that the moral doctrines of the Church <16 Jbid., pp. 32-3. 20 ROBERT BARRY, O.P. should not be conditioned by public policy considerations, for Kelly explicitly asserts that the moral teachings of the Church do take into consideration issue of public policy. 5. Daniel Cronin Daniel Cronin :teaches that ordinary means hold out a hope of beneficial results, are commonly used, are p:voportionate to one's social position, and ·are not difficult to employ. Even though he does not say when it would actually become so, he agrees that feeding could become extraordinary if it was useless.47 It could ·also be rejected if it was impossible to provide, required great effor.t to receive, caused great pain, was radically expensive, or caused intense revulsion. 48 For Cronin, the patient possesses the dominant right to decide what treatments are ordinary or extraordinary, and if the patient is incompetent the physician should provide only ordinary treatments. 49 Cronin demands that the physician not only avoid practicing euthanasia, but also avoid even giving the impression of practicing it. Commenting on Vitoria's views on feeding patients, Cronin says the following: Food is primarily intended by nature for the basic sustenance of animal life. Food for man is basically and fundamentally necessary from the very beginning of his temporal existence. It is basically required by this human life and nature intends food for this purpose. That is why man has the right to grow food and kill animals. Furthermore, because it is a law of nature that man sustain himself by food, it is a duty for man to nourish himself by food. In the case of drugs and medicines, the same is not true. Drugs and medicines are intended per se by nature to help man conserve his life. However, this is not by way of exception. Drugs and medicines are not the basic way by which man is to nourish his life. They are intended by nature to aid man in the conserva47 Atkinson, "Theological Life'', pp. llO·lll. 4B[bi/l, 49 Ibid., pp. 112-113. History of Catholic Teaching on Prolonging FEEDING THE COMATOSE tion of his life when he is sick or in pain or unable to sustain himself by natural means. These artificial means are not natural means but they are intended by nature to help man protect, sustain and conserve his life. If man were never to be sick, he would never need medicines. If he is sick, however, it is quite natural for him to make use of artificial means of conserving life.5o It is hard to ·S'ee how rthese conditions, woo.Id make asssllited feeding optional for the comatose patient because these patients apparently do not experience pain, and tube feeding is apparently less burdensome for others than is spoon feeding. Thus, it would seem permissible to conclude that Cronin would not permit assisted feeding and fluids to be withdrawn from a patient if so doing would be the fundamental cause of death. 6. Joseph Sullivan Joseph Sulliv;an acknowledges cbhait there is a difference between feeding and medical treatments. 51 He argues that ordinary means of preserving life are required of all patients, hut he does affirm that there are two kinds of ordinary treatments. On the one hand, there are artificial ordinary treatments, such as surgeries, X-rays, transfusions and IV feedings.52 On the other hand, he suggests that there are natural ordinary means of preserving life such as feeding, protection from exposure, 50 Ibid., pp. 113-114. n J0bure of theology and the project of commentary on the four hooks of the Sentences. The theme of Aquinas' biblical meditation is not scientia hut sapientia. The second part of Aquinas' "Pmlogue " consists, as did Albert's, of a question on the status and method of theology. This Question 1 is of particular importance in that it clearly states that sacred doctrine is not principally to he considered soientia. After the biblical reflection-mediation, Aquinas presents an introductory question on the status and method of sacra doctrina in a more "scholastic" manner, specifying five articles that will be addressed: 1) its necessity; 9l) supposing that it exists, whether it is one or many; 3) if it is one, whether it is practical or speculative, and if it is speculative, whether it is wisdom, science, or understanding; 4) its subject; 5) its mode. 2 For a critique of this position see the review of Vanier by J. Hamer in Bulletin thomiste 9 ( 1954-1956), 596-601. See also E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas .Aquinas (New York, 1956); M. D. Chenu, Toward Understanding St. Thomas (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1964); J. Weisheipl, "The Meaning of 'Sacra Doctrina'," The Thomist 38 (1974), 64-67; B. Mondin, St. Thomas .Aquinas' Philosophy in the Oommentary to the Sentences (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975). Good arguments on the dating and circumstances of the work are to be found in J. Weishepil, Friar Thomas d'.A.quino: His Life, Thought, and Work (Garden City: Doubleday, 1974). 2Aquinas, Soriptum Super Libros Sententiarum, vol. 1, ed. Mandonnet (Paris: Lethielleux, 1929), q. 1 ( p. 6). [It should be noted that there is as yet no critical edition of this work. All references here will be to this edition, which at least provides a basic text, which is fundamentally a reprint of the Vives edition, and thus differs at times from the Parma edition. The Vives edition, prepared at the end of the 19th century by Abbe Frette, consulted some MSS in the Parisian libraries, but according to current scholarship these MSS reflected a revised text in the MSS tradition. Current scholarship holds that Bruxelles 873-885 (Bx3) and Madrid 516 (Md) reflect the primitive MSS tradition. For the decisive analysis, see E. Booth, "The Three Pecia Systems of St. Thomas Aquinas's Commentary 'In I Sententie.r- IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 33 In this Commentary Aquinas already proposes three types of questions concerning aacra doctrina: an sit (Article 1); quid sit (Articles 2, 8, 4); and de modo (Article 5). Yet there are some logica1 problems with this early schema.3 The question as to whether sama doctrina is one or many is proposed before a" what," a genus, such as" science," is established. Similarly, the question as to whether it is speculative or practical presupposes the untreated question as to what sort of thing it is. Aquinas will revise this early logical 'structure in his later Question 1. of the Summa Theologiae. Article 5: The Mode of Theology In his later Summa theologiae Aquinais will separate the concerns of this Article 5 into distinct articles on the senses and images of Sacred Scripture and the "argumentative status " (reasonableness) of sacred doctrine. But here these topic areas are combined in one Ar.tide. This Article does indeed appear to he either a very rough initial attempt that lacks Aquinas' customary logical organization and clarity, or the existing editions simply have included what were only partial and unfinished revisions. This final Article 5 of the " Prologue " is of particular interest because of the multiple dialectical relationships it has with the previous four a:r.ticles. The four objections in Article 5 question whether divine science: 1) is artificialis, 2) has one mode, 8) uses poetics and metaphor, and 4) is argumentativus (reasonable). The complex corpus of the Article addresses the necessity of sensible um," (late 1987) in La production du Zivre universitaire au moyen b,ge. }j]11JempZar et peoia. The critical edition by the Leonine Commission is still several years from completion. However, for all quotations of the Latin text in the present article, the Leonine Commission Editor for Book I of the Commentary, Prof. Louis Bataillon, has graciously checked the MSS collation sheet which has thusfar been completed, and it has been found that there .are only three variations in the Mandonnet text from current MSS evidence, as far as the presently cited texts are concerned. These variations will be noted. There is no published English translation of this Commentary.] s See discussion in J. Weisheipl, "The Meaning of 'Sacra Doctrina'," The Thomist 38 ( 1974), 64-67. 34 DOUGLAS C. HALL images, the narration of signs, the senses of Sacred Scripture, the ends of theology, and the "argumentative" (reasonable) status of sacred doctrine. One may expect that in a brief discussion of these complex themes, Aquinas will not be able to do them justice, and he may have felt" pressured" to attempt to do too much in his final methodological Article tin the " Prologue." There are two terms in this Article that present particular and important problems for interpretation: argumentativus and artificia.lis. In the response of this Article, Aquinas will state that the mode of sacred science is " argumentativus." The same term is later used in Question 1, Article 8 of the Summa Theologiae. In both works the shades of meaning and intended meaning of Aquinas have fong presented problems of interpretation for translators and commentators, ,and more strict Aristotelian " scientists " were often quick to miss the more subtle and complex significations. It is the case that " argumenta,tivus " does, at times for Aquinas, mean " proving the truth of something by a syllogism," demonstrating, " possible of being proven by a, syllogism," or iargumentative. 4 A " probatio argumentativa" is an apodictic demonstration. But an "argumentatio" has more subtle shades of meaning simply rus " a procedure of testimony," or "the presentation of evidence," 5 or " .a process of reasoning or being reasonable." 6 This is a point of great importance for an accurate understanding of the status and method of theology for Aquinas. When Aquinas describes sacred science •as " argumentative " the use of the term is analogical ,and is itself ex convenientia. In the response to the fourth objection in the present Article, Aquinas 1 4 See R. Deferrari and Iv.I. Barry, A Lericon of St. Thomas A.quiina8 (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1948), vol. I, p. 82. 5 Ibid. 6 Jt is the judgment of the present author that the best translation here is simply "reasonable," "being engaged in a proce.ss which involves reasoning." While acknowledging that, for Aquinas, sacred dootrine is "beyond" the range of reason, Aquinas also proposes that is has "reasonable" aspects. IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 85 himself will state, "argumenta tolluntur ad probationem articulorum fidei." Since these " first principles " of theology differ in status and mode of being known from the first principles of philosophical sciences, it is simply erroneous to think that Aquinas predicates " argumentative " of rational sciences and sacred science in the same manner, or that sacred science can literally be "argumentative" in the strict sense of the term. The term "a.rtificialis" used in the initial objection has also long presented complications for translators and commentators. However, the term is present in all known manuscripts, and thus Aquinas obviously intended something by this term. The problem is that the use of this term in this text is unique in the entire corpus of Aquinas. It is also complicated by some strange historical events. It seems that the expression "artificialis" for a mode of theology came from a mistake in John Scotus Eriugena's Latin translation of the Celestial Hierarchy II, fl of Ps. Dionysius. 7 Ps. Dionysius actually uses the term atechnos 8 when speaking of theologia. In the mystical negativity of Ps. DionySli.1Us,he would s:tress rthe blinding br:illiiance of divine revelation, as overpowering finite intellect, and there could be no question of an artistic construction in theology. By the term atechnos, Ps. Dionysius clearly meant "artlessly," "in an unsophisticated manner," " without craft or skill." However, John Scotus Eriugena translated this term as artificialiter. And thus one hais .a very clear instance where the meaning of P:s. Dionysius was reconstructed precisely into its opposite, with resulting contortions in theological ,aerobics in attempting to explain how it could be that theology has a mode which is artificialis. In aiddition fo being influenced by this :translation of P,s. Dionysius, Aquinas was also likely influenced hy ,a 18th century Franciscan theologian, Eudes Rigaud (Odo Rigaldi), whose Quaestio de scientia theologiae, pars II had as its Question 1: "Utrum modus procedendi in 1 See R. Roques, Libres sentiers vers l'·erige'7llism (Rome: Ed. dell'Ateneo, 1975), Chapter 2, esp. pp. 46-50. s Oelestial Hierarchy II, 2. PL 122, 1040A. 36 DOUGLAS C. HALL theologia mt artificialis vel non." 9 The approach of Odo Rigaldi was to distinguish two modes by which something could be artificialis. One according to human reason, and the other according to divine wisdom, especially as pertaining to salvation. The first mode is found in all sciences, but the second is found in theology, as it is concerned with salvation, piety, and human affect. Thus, for Odo Rigaldi, it was appropriate that theology be artificialis. Now, regardless of the mistranslation of Ps. Dionysius, all the MSS evidence indicates that Aquinas did use the term "artificialis" in his own Article 5. And the question then becomes not what Ps. Dionysius meant by atechnos, but what Aquinas meant. In the initial sitaitement of Aquinas' Artide, the quesrt[on posed with regard to the mode of the science of theology is that it seems to be "artificialissimus." This is not accurately understood as meaning " most artificial." 10 Here the context of the term is "modus artificialis" which refers to the way or manner of a scientific mode. This is made clear in the response to this first objection in Article 5: "modus artificialis dicitur qui competit materiae; unde modus qui est artificialis in geometria, non est artificialis in ethica; et secundum hoc modus hujus scientiae maxime artificialis est, quia maxime conveniens materiae." In the context of "modus artificialis/' it is best to understand " artificialis " as meaning a skillful ordering, as in scientific argument, in the sense of the term " artificiose " (in an orderly manner), or "artificiosus" (skillfull, accomplished in a.rt), or "artificium" (skill, knowledge, ingenuity). And at the same time the term does mean a skillful ordering of artistic 11 For the text see L. Sileo, Peoria della 8cienza teologica: Quaestio de 8cientia theologiae di Odo Rigaldi e altri testi inediti (1230-1250). 2 vols. Facultas Theologica-Sectio Dogmatica, Thesis ad doctorarum n. 277 (Rome: Pontificium Athenaeum Antonianum, 1984). The text for this Question is found in vol. 2, pp. 54-59. 10 "Artificialis, e" does mean "artistic" or "artificial" at times for Aquinas. See R. Deferrari and M .Barry, A. Leroicon of St. Thoma8 Aquina8, vol. 1, p. 88. IMMEDIACY .AND MEDIATION IN .AQUINAS 87 images or similitudes, and it is here related to the term "artifex" (master of an art, artist, craftsman) .11 In Article 5 the first objection is also complicated by variant texts between the Parma and the Mandonnet editions: Ad quintum sic proceditur. 1) [Parma ed. "Videtur quod modus procedendi non sit artificialis."] Nobilissimae scientiae debet esse nobilissimus modus. Sed quanto modus est magis artificalis, tanto nobilior est. 12 Ergo, cum haec scientia sit nobilissima, modus ejus debet esse artificialissimus.18 Now, in context, the initial statement of the Parma edition actually makes more sense. But the fact is that the MSS evidence at present favors the Mandonnet version. The Parma variant is found also in the 16th Piana edition, but nowhere else.14 Obviously, one cannot combine the Parma and Mandonnet editions here, for to do so would make no logical sense, especially in light of the response to this objection, as will be seen. It does not make sense to combine these editions so that the objection would read: "It seems that the mode of proceeding [for this science] is not artificialis. . . . Therefore, since this science is the most noble, its mode should be artificialissi11 Because of the interplays of these meanings impossible to concisely render into English, in the translations which follow the term will simply be presented in Latin. 12 Here the Mandonnet edition does read "tanto nobilior est," but L. Bataillon has informed the present author (Letter, June 25, 1987) that the majority of the MSS actually have "quanto modus es magis artificialis, nobilior est," without "tanto" :and this elimination does make for a smoother reading. 13 Q. 1, a. ·5, ob 1 ( p. 16). [Parma ed. "It seems that the mode of procedure for this science is not 'artificiaUs.' "] For the most noble science should be of the most noble mode. But insofar as a mode is more 'artifioialis' it is also more noble. Therefore, since this science is the most noble its mode ' should be 'artifioialis' to the greatest extent. 14 For L. Bataillon, the Parma variant "seems to be an unhappy tentative to unify the presentation of the articles by inserting th.is 'Videtur quod modus prooedendi non sit artificialis.' So the text is surely the Mandonnet one and there is no correction to be made to it" (Letter, June 25, 1987). But the question remains as to why, in these printed editions, the need was sensed to insert the phrase. 88 DOUGLAS C. HALL mus." The point here is that if one combines the Parma and Mandonnet editions, one has statements that the mode " is not artifioiaUs," and that it "should ·be artifioialissimus." Now, since the Parma addition is not reflected in the MSS evidence it can be eliminated. But then what one has is an objection stating the thesis which is argued in the corpus of the Article, .and which is also basically argued in the particular response to the first objection. This would not be the normal, logical procedure for Aquinas. Normally, the thrust of the objection is reversed in the corpus and in the response to the objootion. In order to get some sense of what the logical structure of the first objection iat least should be, it is helpful to look at the response to the first objection: Ad primum ergo dicendum, quod modus artificial,is dictur qui competit materiae; unde modus qui est artificialis in geometria, non est artificialis in ethica: et secundum hoc modus hujus scientiae maxime artificial,isest, quia maxime conveniens materiae.15 Thus, if the response to the objection is holding that sacred doctrine is maximally artifioialis1 then the logical objection must be that sacred doctrine is not "arlifioialis." In this regard, at least the Parma edition begins in a logically correct manner. But both the Parma and Madonnet editions then also state in the First Objection, "Ergo, oum haeo soientia sit nobilissima, modus ejus debet esse artifioialissimus." The hypothesis of the present •author is that the first objection should actually read, Ad quintum sic proceditur. 1) Nobilissimae scientiae debet esse nobilissimus modus. 16 Sed quanto modus est magis artificialis, 1s Q. I, a. 5, ad I (p. 18). To the first objection it is to be said that the mode 'artificialis' is said to pertain [to sciences] according to their subject matter, hence the mode which is 'artificialis' in geometry is not 'artificialis' in ethics, and according to this the mode of this science [sacred doctrine] is maximally 'artificialis,' because this mode is maximally in harmony with ["conveniens", fitting] its subject matter. 1s Again, from the MSS evidence, the later Parma ed. addition of "Videtur quod modus prooedendi. non sit artificialis" should not be in the text. IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 89 non 17 nobilior est. Ergo, cum haec scientia sit nobilissima, modus ejus non 18 debet esse artificialissimus.19 What is clearly the case is that in Aquinas' response he argues that sacred doctrine is " artificialis," and whether or not one accepts the above hypothesis for how the first objection should rea,d, the question remains as to how one can understand Aquinas' meaning in the response of the Article. The following interpretation may be suggested. Sacred doctrine is maximally "artificialis" because its ultimate "subject matter " is impossible to conceptualize or adequately represent in .any finite medium. What is implied here in Aquinas is the importance of the constructive imagination of the theologian, in attempting to find at least moderately satisfactory similitudes. The tension in such a view of the theological process is that it is not completely clear how what the theologian treats is the inexpressable reality " behind " the similitudes, rather than the similitudes themselves, as products of the constructive imagination. It is because of the inexpressability of the ultimate " subject matter " of sacred doctrine that it is ex convenientia for the "treated '' subject matter to be " artificialissimus." But it is, of course, the manner of this transition from that which cannot be conceived to that which is " artificialissmus " which is particularly difficult, or impossible, to explicate. Aquinas gives some indications of the problems in his response: Responsio. Dicendum, 20 quod m.odus cujusque scientiae debet in17 The hypothesis of the present author is thus that what came to be transscribed as "tanto" in many MSS should have been "non." 1s Here again, the hypothesis is that this "non" was somehow eliminated in the MSS traditions, but there is not one known MSS where either this "non" or another word is present. 10 [A. 5, ob l.] The most noble science should be of the most noble mode. But insofar as a mode is more artificialis, it is not more noble. Therefore, since this science is the most noble, its mode should not be artificialis to the greatest extent [emphasis added]. 20 The Mandonnet edition does have "Respondeo dicendum," but all the MSS read "Responsi-0. Dicendum . . ." And this is more in keeping with other critical editions, and the forthcoming Leonine Edition of this Commentary will certainly have the latter reading. 40 DOUGLAS C. HALL quzn secundum considerationem materiae . . . Principia autem hujus scientiae sunt per revelationem accepta; et ideo modus accipiendi ipsa principia debet esse revelativus ex parte infundentis, ut in visionibus [Parma ed. "revelationibus"] prophetarum, et orativus ex parte recipientis, ut patet in Psalmis.21 What Aquinas was trying to express in this text is not fully clear. It seems that he is trying to indicate that the orientation of one concerned with divine truth should be an orientation which searches for, intends, and is open to that which is beyond the merely "natural" realm of the created order. He seems to be dealing with the idea that the mode of reception of divine principles is itself a divine mode. It is not only the principles themselves which have ,a divine status. It is also notable that his example here of such a mode of reception is not that of a calm, Aristotelian science, hut the " visions of the prophets." There is clearly something in Aquinas' intention here that is far removed from merely professional, academic theology. It should be recalled that Aquinas' point of focus in this final Article 5 is the " mode " of theology, and that the mode of any inquiry has to be in accord with its subject matter, which was the topic of Article 4. The problematic in Aquinas' view of the subject matter o:f theology is that it has been said to be " ens divinum cognoscibile per inspiration.em." 22 The dialectic here is that ens divinum is not directly knowable by finite consciousness and yet, for many reasons, Aquinas wants to in21 Q. 1, a, 5, resp. (p. 17). The mode of any sort of science should be investigated according to a consideration of its subject matter ..• The principles of this science are, however, accepted by means of divine revelation, a.nd for the same reason the mode of accepting these principles themselves should be as revealed by God, from whom revelation flows, as in the visions of the prophets, and the mode of receiving these principles should be in an attitude of prayer, as is clear in the Psalms. [Here the MSS evidence favors the Mandonnet reading of "visionibus'' rather than the Parma reading of "revelationibus," but the Parma reading may be taken as an indication of the difficulty of understanding the present text, with a possible meaning of the revelation given to the prophets being received prayerfully.] 22 Q. 1, a. 4, resp. (p. 16). IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 41 sist on some knowability of God for finite consciousness. In the present response, Aquinas appeals to divine action, even using the dmmatic example of the visions of the prophets to express what it is like to receive the principles of this sacred science. The difficulty, of course, is how this divine light of inspiration, which ultimately is a revelation of the first truth, so high above human reason that it cannot be conceptualized or adequately represented, is yet communicated, partially, in the finite. There can be no complete, demonstrative apologetics for this, yet Aquinas attempts to trace a path. For Aquinas, the divine light of inspiration gives a habit of faith to the believer, and it is this habit of faith, as a participation in God's own Self-Understanding, that enables a metaphysical, participatory link between the believer and the First Truth, and also enables the believer to interpret the articles of faith and the preaching of the Church in order to reach through the sensible expressions to the First Truth. 23 What is sensed " through " language is something beyond language. Aquinas attempts to trace a link between the "original revelation " of the divine light itself and the expression of revelation in the finite symbols of Sacred Scripture: modus istius scientiae sit narrativus signorum, quae ad confirmationem fidei fa,ciunt: et quia etiam ista principia non sunt proportionata humanae rationi secundum statum viae, quae ex sensibilibus consuevit accipere, ideo oportet ut eorum cognitionem per sensibilium similitudines manuducatur: unde oportet modum istius scientiae esse metaphoricum, sive symbolicum, vel parabolicum. 24 There are two problems in phrasing for interpretation and translation here. Aquinas initially states simply "modus 23 Cf. a. 5, resp. ( p. 17). 24Q. 1, a. 5, resp. (pp. 17-18). The mode of this science is the narration of signs, which are given for the confirmation of faith, and because the principles of the faith are not proportionate to human reason in its state in this life, since human reason is accustomed to sensible things, it follows that our knowledge of these principles of faith will be led by sensible similitules, and hence it follows that the mode of this science is metaphorical, or symbolical, or parabolical. 42 DOUGLAS C. HALL istius soientiae," and the final phrase is also simply " modum istius soientiae." Both of these could be understood as either " the mode of this science," or " a mode of this science." The distinction is impor:ant, even ias what may he the intentional ambiguity on the part of Aquinas here is important. But if Aquinas meant the phrase to mean " a mode," or " one mode," it would be his custom to indicate this with "unus, a, um," which is not done here. This would indicate that he means "the mode." For the present interpreter-translator, either " a " or " the" is actually a correct interpretation of the tert, as long as one understands these in a proper context. In the present section of the Article, Aquinas is talking about the " spiritual ·senses" of Sacred Scripture, and the mode of theology is here by means of metaphor, symbol, and parable. But in Aquinas' view there is another mode of theology, which is •according to the " literal sense," and it is only in this mode that theology can be " .argumentative." It is the case that " a mode " of this science is through the sensible order by means of metaphor, 1symbol, and parable, and that the access to " content" for theology is at least principally in this manner. It is 1also the case that " a mode " for the reception of the principles of this ·science is the divine light of inspiration. But such "light" has no content. 25 Thus, "the mode" for receiving "content " is via the •sensible order. And this sensible order can be according to the " literal sense " or the " spiritual senses," but the latter cannot provide a basis for " argumentative" theology. Of comise, m twentieth century terms, ithere is far more of the " symbolic order " in the Sacred Scriptures than could possibly have been recognized by Aquinas in the thirteenth century. But aside foom this problem of the possibility of a " literal sense," a major tension must be noted here. Previously in this very Question 1, Aquinas has insisted on the" immediate" na25 For further discussion see our "Participated Trinitarian Relations," especially on the transformation of Dionysian mysticism by Albert the Great a.nd Aquinas. IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 43 ture of divine inspiration, which, as " immediate " would seem to circumvent the sensible order, with a direct infusion of divine light. However, here in the final Article 5, Aquinas is clearly talking about a mediated mode through the sensible order, where the constructive powers of human imagination have .a siigruificantrole. In 'such an 1approach, the process of interpretation is one at least proximally directed to the products of human, constructive imagination which, at least in the eyes of faith, have been guided in their construction by divine inspiration. While the ultimately hoped-for "object" may be the First Truth, beyond all adequate mediation, the interpretative process here is definitely medi,ated. One faces here a profound, fundamental, and dialectical tension in Aquinas' formulations. There is a sense in which divine inspiration is immediate, ,and •a sense in which the truth will .always be mediated in its parti,al expressions by means of constructive imagination in a particular historical community. And this mode of construction will then directly influence the reception of the truth. In Article 5, Aquinas is trying to address how the "principles" of theology are received. His main concern in the final Article 5 is not with the productive processes of theological reflection, but the starting points. However, a circle becomes .apparent, for the starting points for one generation's theology can be the products of the constructive imagination of previous generations of theological reflection. What is important in Aquinas' final Article 5 is his shift to a more " down-toeart:h " view of the theological process, rather than one which has at times ,seemed to be modeled on the intellectual processes of separate substances. His qualification .is clear: "ista prinoipia, non sunt proportiona.ta humanae rationi seoundum statum viae." But if there is a lack of such proportion (or proportionality), :the problem remains as to how such principles can possibly be received. The appeal to the mediation of the First Tl'Uth through the articles of faith, which can be articulated, does not" solve" the problem, for if ,these articles 44 DOUGLAS C. HALL point beyond themselves, one still has the problem of how the human subject can sense the further meaning, behind the mediation. An appeal to the " literal sense " of Sacred Scrip-ture also does not " ·solve " the problem, for the " literal sense " is still in finite language which cannot contain the First Truth. The dialectical tension should be clear: there is an insistence on immediacy, and the rather ·independent, a priori status of theology, at least in the reception of its principles, and with this status comes the assertion that theology should direct the other sciences as inferior sciences, as if theology were self-constituted without recourse to the natural order. But here in the final Article 5 there is a return to the natural order, not merely for the convenience of " utilizing" it, but for access to the meanings, or " principles " of theological reflection. In this return to the natural order, it is not the case that theological reflection has a prior constitution; rather, it enters into the processes of constructive imagination and interpretation in order to start to be constituted at all. In this approach, the "content " and " subject matter " of theological reflection is in the natural order, but-mysteriously-what is dialectically intended by theological consciousness is something which cannot be contained "in" language, or in any aspect of the natural, created order, no matter how artistically and imaginatively constructed. The nert point in Aquinas' rather involved response in this Article, also presents some difficulties. Aquinas has recognized that :there is ·a reception of biblical truth via metaphor, symbol, and parable, but this will not suffice for the production of "argumentative" theology. In an important transition, Aquinas then presents his own understanding of the three " theological tasks " presented by Sacred Scripture: Ex istis autem principiis ad tria proceditur in saCll'a Scriptura: scilicet ad destructionem errorum, quod sine argumentis fieri non potest; et ideo oportet modum hujus scientiae esse cuandoque argumentativum, tum pe'T' auctoritates, tum etiam per rationes et similitudines naturales. Proceditur etiam ad instructionem morum: unde quantum ad hoc modus ejus debet esse praeceptivus, sicut in IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 45 lege; comminatorius et promissivus, ut in prophetis; et narrativus exernplorum, ut in historialibus. Proceditur tertio ad contemplationem veritatis in quaestionibus sacrae Scripturae; et ad hoc oportet modum etiam esse argumentativum ... 26 The first point of interest here is that Aquinas does not now base the " argumentative " status of theology 1simply on the " literal " sense, but on the appeal to " authorities " and in the use of "similitudes" (or analogies). The second point of interest is that Aquinas lists the "contemplation of the truth" last, and one may therefore consider it as being stressed as the most important function. Of additional interest is the fact that Aquinas describes this goal as " contemplationem veritatis in quaestionibus sacrrae Scripture " (emphasis added) . Qua.estwnibus is used here as a technical term of mid-18th century theology. lt does not mean .a " reading " or a " commentary " on Sacred Scripture, but a process of mtional investigation and exploration. This "questionibus sacrae Scripturae" (emphasis ,added) , differs £rom ;the "immediate" corutemplaition of God presented in Article 1. Here in Article 5, this albeit brief phrase presents a much more" realistic" and "down-toearth " mode of contemplation, although it may be a less perfect mode in that it is more (not completely) an "acquired" mode of contemp1rutionthrough study. It is not completely an acquired mode of contemplation through study because this " quaestionibus sacrae Scripturae" begins with the act of faith which is an " infused virtue " inaugumted by divine action, but it is also an acquired mode of contemplation in that it involves 26 Q. 1, a. 5, resp. ( p. 18). From these principles there proceed three things in Sacred Scripture, namely, the destruction of errors, which cannot be accomplished without reasonableness, and for this reason it follows that this science is in some way argumentative, by appeal to the authorities or even by means of reasons and nautral similitudes. Secondly there is the instruction of morals, and insofar as this doctrine has this mode it should be prescriptive, as in law, threatening punishment and extending promises, as the prophets, and providing exemplars in narrative, as the historians. Thirdly .there is the contemplation of truth in the questioning [quaestionibus, "investigation," "rational examination"] of Sacred Scripture, and for these reasons it follows that the mode of this science is reasonable. 46 DOUGLAS C. HALL the very human process of " questioning,'' inqmnng into, analyzing in order to understand, and making dialectical clarifications in order to in part the meaning of Sacred Scripture as divine revelation. It may he recalled that in Article 1 of this " Prologue,'' Aquinas has stated that the end of human life is the contemplation of God, and that the contemplation of God is of two types: the rational contemp1ation possible in philosophy and a contemplation in which God " videtur immediate per suam essentiam," and that this perfect contemplation of God constitutes the vi,sion of God in heaven. 27 Compared to this " immediate " contemplation of God, Aquinas then tries to state in Article 1 how the theological contemplation of God in this life is imperfect compared with the vision of God in heaven, and yet the imperfect contemplation possible in this life is led rto the more perfect contemp1ation by means of the divine light of inspiration. It may be recalled that what Aquinas stated in Article 1 was: 1 1 Unde oportet ut ea quae sunt ad finem proportionentur, fini, quantenus homo manuducatur ad illam contemplationem in statu viae per cognitionem non a creaturis sumptam sed immediate e:x; divino lumi,ne inspiratam; et haec est doctrina theologiae [emphasis added]. 28 This is problematic, limit-discource, for many reasons. First, it is not conceivable how any being except God can attain the perfect contemplation of God to which Aquinas refers, a contemplation per, i.e., "in,'' or "through,'' God's own Essence. Secondly, it is not clear how there can be an " immediate" knowledge of God by means of the light of divine inspiration. How this " light " can ·actuate " knowledge " is not specified. ·21Q.1, a. 1, resp. (pp. 7-8). 2s Ibid., ( p. 8). Hence it follows that even as those things which are directed to an end are proportioned to that end, in order for the human subject to be led to that [perfect] contemplation [of God] in this life [it is necessary that] there not only be a knowledge [of God] through the created order but also an immediate [knowledge of God] by means of the divine light of inspiration, and this is the doctrine of theology [emphasis added]. IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS 47 All that Aquinas says is that philosophy offers an imperfect contemplation of God, while the divine light of inspiration, in this life, offers a more perfect contemplation of God, and it is this more perfect contemplation which is "dootrina theologiae," 29 the purpose of which is to lead one to perfect contemplation. If this " divine light " can have no " content " for human intellect, it can only function as an intentional principle for the interpretation of sensible content in human experience. Within Aquinas' more mature systematic thought further qualifications could be added. What Aquinas attempts in this early tert is a treatment of how the human subject can be proportioned to ,an end (the immediate contemplation of God) which is beyond the naturail possibilities for finite human nature to acoomplish. This is the theme with which Aquinas' introduces his treatment in Article 1: "ut ea quae sunt ad finem proportionentur fini." It is then the divine J,ight of inspiration which proportions the human subject to this end. It should be noted that if the function of .this " light " is to " proportion " the human subject, then its function is not properly one of providing "content," but of enabling the subject to reach "content," through the created order, because of the changed horizon, intentionality, or "proportionality to meaning,'' that the "light" of inspiration p11ovides. This· divine " light" of inspiration " proportions " the human subject. by providing a higher participation in God's own Immediate Self-Knowledge, which is beyond "content" and which i'S Pure Intentionality. The higher participation a:ffio11ded by the divine "light'' of inspiration does not in 1and of [rtsel:f y[eld formal " content." Here the doctrina theologiae which is the " divine light of in spimtion " can, in ,a fully consllistent manner, only mean that such inspihl.-.a;bionis the principle of thoolog.iml.mtentionially in the processes of tinteripretrution;not thrut thtis "iimmediaite divine light of inspimtion " the content for theological 29 This very strong statement is in all of the MSS which L. Bataillon has collated to date for the Leonine Commission edition. 48 DOUGLAS C. HALL reflection. But ·the problems in Aquinas' formulaition, and genena.tions of interpretation, iis that it.his "iimmeclirute divine light " cou1d itself be seen 1as providing " content " rather ,than merely making it possible for the theologian to interpret the sensible order in a way that then provides " limit-content." If this inspiration itself is thought to provide " content," then one must observe that there is a profound tension between Arl:icle 1 1and the concluding .Article 5. ANicle 1 can at least give the impression that theology is constituted on an independent, a pri,ori basis, simply because of the divine light of inspiration, and rbhen :it is because of this .:11, which first :signified ,a forest, ·and then lumber, later came to designate ,thart of which .anything is composed. And vo'1Jri1 describes 1somethinginsofa!l' as it is gr.asped by an interior knowing faculty of the soul. The adjective vo'1Jri1 and the noun vovs comes from the verb voloo which designates the act of perceiviing,of thinking and of conceiving. Both the adjective and the noun a wide range of knowing powers, either diTectly or indirectly, though ·all ,these powers are interior mental faculties. A good translation of vovs would be " mind " since " mind " can be .applied to The first, most general, precepts seem ito form a rather narrow category of principles that :are iimmediately known by all people a;s soon as ,they begin fo reason about practical affairs. Like 11ationalityitself, they are never entively absent, ·although their operation may be anesthetized by the force of passion.11 The secondary precepts comprise ·a much broader category, from principles that even the untutored can axrive at with just a Httle reflection (the prohibition of stealing, for example), .to rules thrut require the teaching of the wise men (such as the :admonition to respect the elderly). It seems to be a matter of just how clearly one gl'asps the goods on which s The prohibition of stealing offers an example of how a determinate principle concerning a relative good, such as private property, may not hold in every instance. As Thomas points out, it is not immoral in a situation of grave necessity to take in secret another's property and use it; because material things exist for everyone's sake, and the personal possession of property remains a good only so long as it works to relieve the needs of both yourself and your neighbor ( 2-2, q. 66, a. 7). 1'01-2, q. 94, aa. 5-6. Note that this is how Thomas speaks of primary and secondary precepts in the Summa theologiae. See R. A. Armstrong, Primary and Secondary Precepts in Thomistic Natural Law Teaching (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966) for a discussion of how Thomas' use of these terms changes from his early to his later work. 111.2, q. 94, a. 2, c.; a. 4, c.; a. 6, c. 96 KEVIN A. MCMAHON the moral precepts are based. The primary precepts simply point out these goods, .such a.s human life, to which we are inclined by nature. The secondary precepts, however, refer to these goods iin. greater detail, indicating more and more specifically the sort of :actions rthat will promote, 1and the sort that will injure, ·a prurlicular good. For the individual who fully understands the nature of these goods, hoth the primary and the •secondary precepts :are iSelf-evidenitlytrue. 12 But for those who cannot, do not, or simply refuse to reflect long enough Ito see the greater detruil of these goods, these secondary rules might very well appear false. Wirth rbhis in mind, the role of :the wise men becomes pretty clear. They have the job of educating those who are less in1sightful about the nature of human goods. And what is even more important, they can stem ·the development of evil haibits into community-wide evil customs, dispelling by ·their teaiehing the clouds tha;t egoism can crusrt over the citizens' practical reason. There is only one problem: Thomas writes that the aicquired virtue of wisdom is strictly a 1speculaitive v•irtue; !it is not concerned with moral action. 13 So what is one to make of the repeated references to the wise men? Irt is possible that Thomas is using the title " wise " in the broad sense of anyone who has the responsibility of ordering and governing others, after rthe mainner of Aristotle's good legislator. The idea of wisdom as ordering principle was an important one to Thomas. 14 Yet Arisrtortledoes not use wisdom (sophia) in this way, reserving for the legislator's virtue the name phronesis. 15 And even though one can find evidence for the view that Thomas himself was not ·so scrupulous, this answer still does not su:ffice.16 12 1-2, q. 100, a. 1, c; q. 94, a. 2, c. 13 2-2, q. 45, a. 3, obj. and ad I. 14 See Lawrence Boadt, C.S.P., "St. Thomas .Aquinas and the Biblical Wisdom Tradition," The Th-Omist 49 (1985) 575-611, especially pp. 592-96, 603. 15 Nicomachean Flthics 6, 114la20, 114lb23. L6 Boadt, in the article cited above, shows how Thomas parallels the biblical wisdom tradition in regarding wisdom in the highest sense as both BISHOPS' TEACHING ROLE IN ECONOMICS 97 Thomas is rtoo insistent that prudence or practical wi:sdom, even mthe unconditioned ;sense of in-aotical wO.sdom, the human good mgeneral, is not ·about moml principles. What is more, in spealcing of :a divinely revealed morial 1aw, and thereby opening up the possibilirty of ia much larger role fm one who would teach morial principles that are not self-evident to all, it is very difficult for Thomas ito get away with characterizing this teacher 1as having the virtue of the legislator, whose chief business is applying the means of .good Laws to the end of a virtuous community. And it is precisely in conjunction. with the divine law that Thomas speaks mosrt orfiten of the wise men. Despite all this, 1a less than precise use of the term " wise " might in bet be what is at work here. But there is another possibility. It could be that Thomas is referring ito that form of wisdom that is both speculative and active, namely the wisdom that is a ,gift of the Holy Spirit. 1 speculative and active. Thus, one commonly finds in Thomas the idea that wisdom (and the wise man) orders all things. Yet Boadt goes on to argue that Thomas derived this notion in part from .Aristotle; and this is a point that must be qualified. If Thomas in fact believes that .Aristotle considered the activity of ordering to be proper to the wise man, it might be because his Latin translation will sometimes render phronesis as sapientia (e.g., 2-2, q. 47, a. 5, obj. I). More likely, however, is that Thomas was so imbued with the biblical tradition (both Old and New Testament) that he read into Aristotle a connection between wisdom and action that the Philosopher did not have. A prime example of this is the statement "It belongs to the wise man to order." It occurs, among other places, in the opening of his commentary on the M etaphysios, and Boadt writes that it is taken from the first book of .Aristotle's PoUtios (I. 5). Yet .Aristotle does not speak there of wise men at all, but of natural rulers and natural slaves. It is Thomas who in commenting on the passage shifts from Rpeaking o.f rulers (prinoipantes) to wise men ( sapientes), and this because of a passage from the book of Proverbs: "the foolish man will serve the wise" (In Pol. I. 3. 68). Revealing, too, is a passage in 2-2, q. 45, a. 6, c. where Thomas cites Aristotle (Metaphysics I. 982al8-19) to the effect that the wise man establishes order. Actually, though, what .Aristotle says is that it is commonly held of the wise man that he gives rather than receives orders, and Thomas seems to be aware in his commentary that .Aristotle is regarding this as only an opinion (In Met. 1. 2. 41-42). Note that when it is a matter of establishing prudence as a distinct virtue, concerned with action, Thomas will quote Aristotle against the wisdom tradition, as in 2-2, q. 47, a. 2, obj. and ad 1. 98 KEVIN A. MCMAHON Of this wisdom Thomas writes, " it considers them (divine types) in so for as it contemplates divine things in themselves, and it consults them in so far as it judges of human acts by divine things, and direots human acts according to dvine rules." 17 The understanding wisdom has of divine things is due, not to the effort of reason, but to a " connaturality " with them that is an effect of cha;rity; beoause charity, Thomas notes, "unites us with God-a1s it is said in 1 Cor. 6: 17, 'He who is joined to the Lord is one spirit.' " 18 Why would Thomas, who follows Aristotle so closely in his discussions of wisdom, breaks with the Philosopher in speaking of the highest wisdom as both contemplative and active? The answer appears at the very beginning of the Summa contra gentiles. Since the end of the entire univierse i,s truth, it is with truth that the wise man must primarily be concerned. And so, he continues, divine Wisdom testifies that, in order to make truth manifest, he assumed flesh and came into the world, saying 'For this I was born, and for this I came into the world, in order that I might give testimony to the truth' (Jn. 18: 37) .19 Wisdom for Thomas is not merely some humanly acquired habit thait enables one to contempl,ate a divine and transcendent cause. The highest wisdom in this life comes of a personal union with >the divine Wisdom, who is also the divine Truth 17 Thomas is commenting on Augustine's statement that wisdom "indendit 'rationibus supernis,' scilioet divinis, 'et conspiciendis et oonsulendis ;' oonspiciendis quidem, seoundum quod divina in seipsis oontemplatur; oonsulendis autem, seoundum quod per divina iudioat de humanis aotibiis per divinas regulas dirigens aotus humanos" (2-2, q. 45, a. 3, c.). The Latin text of the Summa theologiae quoted here and following is the Ottawa edition, 19411945. 18 Huiusmodi autem oompassio sive oon1iaturaUtas ad res divinas fit per oa1·itatem, quae quidem unit nos Deo, secundum illud 1 ad Oor. 6 :17, 'Qui adhaeret Deo unus spiritus est' (2-2, q. 45, a.2, c.). 19 Et ideo ad veritatis manifestationem divina Sapientia oarne induta se venisse in mundum testatur, dioens, .Jn. 18 :37, 'Ego in hoc natus sum, et ad hoc veni in mundum, ut testimonium perhibeam veritati' ( 1. l. 4). Summa contra gentiles, 2 vols., ed. by Pera, Marc and Caramello (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1961), vol. 2, p. 2. BISHOPS' TEACHING ROLE IN ECONOMICS 99 (Jn. 14: 6). And this divine Wisdom., who deliberately made man, bound himself to m.an by taking hum.an flesh, in order that m.an might bind himself to him. The gift of wisdom must be active, because God is ootive, working to draw man into the divine life. Since man is essentially ·an ragent, and a cooperative agent, moving as a member of a community toward union with God, it makes sense for Thomas to speak of the wise man as an orderer. Since man moves toward his end by fostering the goods of his nature, and since his end consists in the union of his own nature with thart of God, one can see where there would be need for a teacher of secondary or derivative moral principles concerning these goods, just because the deepest significance of these goods :is that they image the unseen God (though Thoonas is none too explicit rubout 1this particular need) . And who better to :fi]l this role of teacher than the man gifted with wisdom, who by virtue of his connaturality with divine things ·oon best unde11standthe goods of our nature, and the sort of actions that promote or injure them. But now another difficulty 1arisers. The gift of wisdom belongs in some degree to ·aill who have .grace, and it may be received in ·a special degree by any individual, since it is one of the " gratuitous grares which ,the Holy Spriit dispenses as he wills." 2 As such, rthe wise men would consist of those individuals who are reoognzied in the community for their holy perspioocity. But rus Thomas 1Speak!s of :the wise men, they occupy 1a form.al, public position, rand have their authority by their office. Thus, in one of the plaices where he most clearly describes the function of the wise men, Thomas refers to the role Moses and Aaron had in Israel, .acting as teachel'!S by virtue of their divine commission to give God's law to the peopfo.21 Q 2·0 Quidam autem altiori gradu perficitunt sapientiae donum. • • • Jj]t iste gradus sapientiae non est communis omnibus habentitbus gratiam gratum facientem, sed magi& pertinet ad gratias gratis datas, quas Spiritus Sanctus 'distribuit prout vult,' secundum illud 1 ad Oor. JS:B, 'Alii datur per Spiritum sermo sapientiae,' etc. (2-2, q. 45, a. 5, c). 211-2, q. 100, a. 11, c. 100 KEVIN A. MCMAHON The need for divinely revealed law-the Law of Moses and the Law of grace-stems from man's vocation. It teaches of God's nature and guides human .action. It is, in fact, the neces·sary precondition for the possibility of the gift of wisdom. Wisdom in the perfected sense is an effect of the outpouring of the Spirit that constitutes the New Law. It presupposes faith in Christ, and acceptance of whatever precepts are associated with the reception and right use of. grace.22 Wisdom as it existed in Israel presupposed membership in the holy people formed by God. It seems, then, that whether one is speaking of wisdom in Israel or in the Church, a distinction must he made between the quality as it is possessed as a personal gift, and ais it is held in virtue of one's office of proclaiming the law that is the fundamental bond between the community and God. If it is co-rrect to say that the wise men spoken of in connection with the Old Law were the successors to Moses and AaJron, namely, the Levitioal priests, the elders, and to some extent the prophets, then their counterparts under the New Law would be those who succeed to Christ, the High Priest in whom all these roles have their fulfillment. These, of course, are the bishops. Thomas considers the bishops to be the premier teachers of faith and morals in the Church. Teaching is their special duty, he writes in his commentary on Ephesians.28 It is, in fact, their most important duty, he states in the Summa theologiae;24 mosrt impo·rtant because knowledge 22 1-2, q. 108, a. 2, c. 2a Writing on Ephesians 4:11 (which in Thomas' text reads, ".And indeed he gave some to be apostles, and some to be prophets, other evangelists, and others pastors and teachers, . • ."), Thomas interprets "pastors and teachers" as referring to the successors of the apostles, who in having the responsibility of watching over the Lord's flock also have the responsibility of teaching it. He states: "Quantum vero ad curam Eoolesia,e subdit: 'A.lios autem pa,stores,' oumm soilioet dominioi gregis habentes: et sub eodem addit, 'lilt dcotores,' ad ostendendum quod proprium oflioium pastoris Jiloolesiae, est dooere ea, qua,e pertinent a,d fidem et bonos mores" (In. Flph. 4, 4) St. Thomas Aquinas, Opera Omnia,, 24 vols. (Parma: Ficcadori, 1852-1873; reprint ed., New York: Musurgia Publishers, 24 Dicendum 1948-1950), vol. 13, p. 479. quod utrumque offi,cium, sciUcet docendi et baptiza,ndi, Dominus BISHOPS' TEACHING ROLEJ IN ECONOMICS 101 of the truth and the practical expression of it in right conduct are the beginning of one's par:ticipation in the life of God, which is perfected through the sacmments. This duty belongs to .the bishops by vil1tue of their aipostolic succession, :in which they share the apostles' representiation of Christ, for Christ initiated the full offer of gmce by his teaching and in his sacrifice.25 Thus, Thoma,s says of Christ: First, he taught the truth by inviting and by calling to faith; and in this he completed the will of the Father .... Second, he brought the truth itself to completion by opening up in us through his passion the door to life, and by giving the power to persevere to the perfected truth. 26 That the bishop succeeds to Chrsit's role as teacher and 1sanctifieris also shown when Thomas writes of Pentecost: The Holy Spirit descended upon the apostles, first in the form of a wind, in order to indicate the propagation of grace which is accomplished in the sacraments, of which the apostles were the ministers, and for this reason, Christ has said: Whose sins you shall forgive, they are forgiven them .... A second time, the Spirit was communicated to them in tongues of fire, in order to signify the propagation of grace which is accomplished through teaching, and for this reason, in chapter two of the Book of Acts, we read that, having been filled with the Holy Spirit, they began to speak. 21 Especially in his commentaries on the letters of St. Paul, Thomas emphasizes that Christ, the Son through whom we have received the Spirit, is the source of all grace. And as the Apostolis iniunmit, quorum vioem gerunt episcopi, aliter tamen et aliter. Nam offeoium dooendi oommisit eia Ghristus, ut ipsi per se illud emoeroerent, tanquam principalissimum; unde et ipsi Apostoli dixerunt, Acts 6 :2, 'Non est aequum nos relinquere verbum Dei et ministrare men.sis' (3, q. 67, a. 2, ad 1). 25 l-2, q. 99, a. 2, c.; Summa contra gentiles 4. 74. 2; 76. 1. 26 Primo doouit veritatem, invitando, et vocando ad fidem: et in hoc complevit voluntatem Patris. . . . Secundo consummavit ipsam veritatem, aperiendo per passionem suam in nobis januam vitae, dando potestatem perveniendi ad oonsummatam veritatem .•. (In Jo., 641). Latin text quoted by M. J. Le Guillou, Ghrist and Ohuroh, trans. Charles E. Schaldenbrand (New York: Desclee Company, 1966), p. 283, n. 59. 2r In Jo., 2739. Quoted by Le Guillou, ibid., p. 287. 102 KEVIN A. MCMAHON head, he gives of his fullness to his entire body. If, then, the bishops have a special authority to teach, it is because in representing the hea;d :they make present the guidance that the Spirit offers ito ·all the Church. 28 In preaching the word and celebrating the sacraments, which together constitute their teaching, the bishops express the faith that cannot fail. We conclude that Thomas' !reference to wise men in the moral life is ultimately :a reference to individua;1s who possess the gift of wisdom conferred by the Holy Spirit, indeed a special £orm of this gift, one that under the Old Law proceeded from one's role in conducting the divine worship, and under .the New Law proceeds .fl'lom o:ne',s full sacramental conformity .00 Christ, the one, true :sacrifice of which the Levitical offerings were but ·a type. This rorm. of wisdom is foundational, originative, but not entirely pel'lsonal. One can .and must distinguish betwieen those who are specially blessed with this gift iand those who :fill the role that malres this gift possible, recognizing that the two groups will seldom overlap. Such a distinction would be absurd if applied to wisdom in any other sense. The one considered best able to pass on wisdom would be the one who had ·acquired the most. But the giift of wisdom is nort :a;cquired. It comes to the Chureh as one body joined to Christ, and Christ remains with his Church through those consecrated as his successors. As individuals they may not be the most wise. But they are the most certainly wise, because so long as they intend to carry out the apostolic ministry, ·they represent infallibly the wisdom of Christ. And they are :the most importantly wise, because by 1 28 Si vero consideretur divina providentia, quae .Ecclesiam suam Spiritu sanoto dirigit ut non erret, sicut ipse promisit (Jn. 10 :26) quod Spiritus ad'Veniens doceret omnem veritatem, de neoessariis scilicet ad salutem; certum est quod iudicium .Ecolesiae universalis errare in his quae ad fidem pertinent, impossible est ( Quodl. 9, q. 8, a. 1). Quaestiones Quodlibetales, 9th ed., edited by Raymnod Spiazzi, O.P. (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1956), p. 194. See also Quodl. 3, q. 4, a. 2; S.T. I, q. I, a. 8, ad 2; 2-2, q. 5, a. 3, c; q. IO, a. 12, c. BISHOPS' TEACHING ROLE IN ECONOMICS 108 their entry into Chrsit's ministry they continue Christ's offer of participation in his life. And to enter his life, Thomas states, is to enter that of Wiisdom begotten. 29 The vibrancy of the Church's life depends upon those who have been specially gifted by the Spirit. Yet at the center of this life will be the bishops. Which is not to say that the bishop is without any personal wisdom. Since wisdom is pal't of all sacramental grace, there can never be a complete break between peirisonal wisdom and that of his office while a bishop remains fully a part of the Church. Still, Thomas was careful to encoura-ge among bishops the nurturing of infused wisdom through a life of prayer, as well as acquired wisdom through the discipline of study. 30 The light of wisdom comes through prayer, and irt comes through study, but both prayer and study must center on that which summarizes the truth of revel.ation: the Incarnation, recorded in Scripture and handed on in the Church's tradition. The understanding of the faith and of human morals in light of faith is a corporate activity that draws upon the contributions of saints and scholars. But it is the bishops, in union with the pope, who establish the context for this quest. 31 And as the search for understanding broadens in the realm of morality to include all men of goodwill, it is still the epis1 a. 6, c. so In his commentary on Titus, Thomas writes that the bishops must adhere to the "sermo fi-deli.s," "ut custodiant contra haereticos, et ideo dicit; 'et eos qui contradicunt arguere,' id est c01Wincere, et hoc per studium sacrae Scriptu.re." In epistoiam ad Titum 1. 3, Barma ed., vol. 13, p. 648. In the next line Thomas notes that such refutation pertailli! "ad opus sapientis," though he clearly means "wise" in the sense of learned. Le Guillou, referring to a passage from In 1 Oor., 222, writes that it is the duty of a prelate to assist his people "in developing their Christian life under the influence of the Spirit, through a living communion in the Eucharist, and through a life of service to their brothers. For this reason, the prelate must live a life of contemplation, and must grow in the knowledge of the Wisdom of God, in order that he might be an authentic mediator after the heart of God (Jer. 3: 15) ... " (op. cit., p. 289). n Summa ocmtra ·gentiles, 4. 76; In Symbolum Apostolorum scilicet "Credo in Deum" eropositio, a. 9; Ocmtra errores Graeoorum, pars altera, cc. 32-33. · 20 2-2, q. 45, 104 KEVIN A. MCMAHON copacy that, in its teaching of the divine law which contains the natural Law,32 provides the definiiitiveguidance. Although it is possible to cite specific examples in Thomas of moral principles, secondary precepts, :that can be clearly arrived at only in the light of revelation (one would be the indissolubility of marriruge), nothing like that is involved in the American bishops' prustora1. The principles underlying their letter-the responsibility of a community for its poor, for example-do not strike the typical American reader as surprising, though perhaps uncongenial. Aristotle says very much the same thing, with regard to citizens anyway, in the passage from the Politics we noted before. What the bishops are responsible for doing, and what in fact they do, is initiate and guide debate on central economic issues among those who have the prudence necess,ary to correctly apply the letter's principles to the American situation. However there is something more to the bishops' role. Thomas was simply commenting on Aristotle when he wrote, " ... man is naturally part of some group through which he receives help in living well." 83 But it was his Christianity which added in the De Regno: men form a group for the purpose of living well together . . . and a good life is one lived according to virtue. . .. Yet by living according to virtue man is ordained to a higher end, namely, the end of delight in God.... Consequently, since society must have the same end as the individual man, it is not the ultimate end of an assembled multitude to live according to virtue, but through a virtuous life to attain to the enjoyment of God.H s2 Thomas writes that all those things which belong to the natural law are fully handed down ("plenarie traduntur") in the Law and the Gospel 1-2, q. 94, a. 4, ad 1. sa In Ethic., I. I. Quoted by Robert J. Giguere, The Social Value of Public Worship According to Thomistic Principles, The Catholic University of American Philosophical Studies, vol. llO (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1950), p. 50, n. 12. 84 Ad hoc enim homines congregantur, ut simul 'bene vivant ... 'bona autem 'Vita est secundum virtutem . ••• Sed quia homo vivendo secundum virtutem ad ulteriorem finem ordinatur, qui consistit in fruitione divina, supra iam BISHOPS' TEACHING ROLE IN ECONOMICS 105 More recently Rans Urs von Haltha;sar made the same point when he wrote, " Human beings were created not rto he satisfied with themselves but that, deaid to self, they might, in Christ's possesism, possess all things m him." 35 What the hi.shops add ,to the principles gained by reason in their preaching of our creation in Christ ,and for Christ is an ,awareness of rthe depth of the community we are all called to form; it is, in £act, to add everything, and it is why their vocation extends to the civil realm. For even if the concern of the State is iOO provide for rthe material well-being of its people, this can never be done unless they realire how deeply they are tied to one ,another. What the bishops ,add by their sacramental role is the ,actual strength to bring about that communion that reason and faith perceive. In his Commentary on Colossians, Thomas indulged in a long but helpful metaphor. He remarked: Upon Christ depends the entire good of the body, that is, of the Church. For there are two goods in the body: the cohesion of its members, and its growth. And these things the Church receives from Christ .... In the body, there is a twofold cohesion of the members; in the first place, that which arises from contact, as the hand is joined to the shoulder, the shoulder to the chest, and so on. A second conjunction is that of the nerves, and for this reason, Paul says: 'the joints and ligaments.' And so it is that the Church draws its cohesion from faith and knowledge: 'one Spirit, one faith, one baptism' (Eph. 4:5). But this is not sufficient unless there is also the cohesion of charity and of the sacraments, and for this reason, he adds: organized by the nerves, because through charity each provides for the wants of others. 86 dia:imus, oportet eumdem finem esse multitudinis humanae, qui est hominis unius. Non est ergo ultimus finis multitudinis congregatae vivere secundum virtutem, sed per virtuosam vitam pervenire ad fruitionem divinam (De Regno 2. 3). The Latin text is taken from Aquinas, Selected Political Writings, ed. A. P. D'Entreves, ed., trans. J. G. Dawson (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1948), p. 74. It is actually the text of De regimine principum 1. 14. 85 Das Weizenkorn, p. 25. Quoted in The Von Balthasar Reader, ed. Medard Kehl and Werner Loeser, trans. Robert J. Daly and Fred Lawrence (New York: Crossroad, 1982), p. 57. 86 [n Ool., 129. Quoted by Le Guillou, op. cit., p. 279. 106 KEVIN A. MCMAHON What Thomas 1says: here of the Church is equa,lly true of the State; which [s why it.he papaJCy since Leo XIII has taught repeaitedly that in the drive for social justice, justice itself is nort enough; thait chaciity drawn rrom Christ will. alone ,succeed.81 ST Thus, Pius XI in Qua®esimo Anno (n. 137) stated: "For justice alone, even though most faithfully observed, can remove indeed the cause of social strife, but can never bring about a union of hearts and minds. • . . Then only will it be possible to unite all in harmonious striving for the common good, when all sections of society have the intimate conviction that they are members of a single family and children of the same Heavenly Father, and further, that they are 'one body in Christ, and everyone members one of another' (Rom. 12: 5), so that 'if one member suffer anything, all members suffer with it' (1 Cor. 12:26)." Cf. John XXIII, Pacem in Terris, nn. 37-8. CATHOLICISM, PUBLIC THEOLOGY, AND POSTMODERNITY: ON RICHARD JOHN NEUHAUS'S " CATHOLIC MOMENT" DAVID L. SCHINDLER University of Notre Dame HAT CATHOLICS should assume .their rightful place m the task of forming a culture, and indeed shaping a public philosophy in and for a pluralistic, dernocrwtic society, is ia suggestion which has not often been heard in the history of American culture, and certainly not from. nonCatholics. It is a suggestion thrut Richard John Neuhaus, a Lutheran pastor, nonetheless makes with eloquence and wit in The Catholic Moment. 1 The book makes for enjoyable and even exciting reading. It is difficult for a Catholic, even of a non-itriumphalistic sort, nort rto be moved by his suggestion: not to be stimulated into rserious upon the meaning of Catholic identity, particularly now in the pT"esent cultural situation in America and indeed the West, which seems-note the subtitle of Neuhaus's book-aptly described in terms of a modernity giving way to posrtmodernity, a modernility searching for genuinely postmodern patterns of thought. Neuhaus is insistent-and the insistence is refresb.ing-,that this reflection be carried through with integri,ty (cf., e.g., p. 150) : the Catholicism. for which our-a postmodern-culture [.g ripe is and must be ·a Caitholicisrn which is fiaithful to the Gospel and to tits own tradition. This double intention of Neuhaus to speak on behalf of a Catholicism which is in and for a postmodern world sets .the context for .the questions I wish to pose in the present inquiry. The meaning of Neuhaus' s Catholic moment is twofold: 1 The Catholic Moment: The Parado11J of the Church in the Postmodern World, by Richard John Neuhaus (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1987). All references in the text are to this book. 107 108 DAVID L. SCHINDLER [It] is the moment in which the Roman Catholic Church in the world can and should be the lead church in proclaiming and exemplifying the Gospel. This can and should also be the moment in which the Roman Catholic Church in the United States assumes its rightful role in the culture-forming task of constructing a religiously informed public philosophy for the American experiment in ordered liberty (p. 282) . In .the light of this and indeed of the overarching context md[ca;ted by the suhbitle of his book, I wish to direct attention in whait follows to three issues: what Neuhaus takes to be an authentic Catholic Christianity ·and Catholic Christian rtheology (tha;t is, a Christianity which iis f.aithful in" proc1aiming and exemplifyiing the Gospel ") ; what he takes to be the proper sense (the sense required by Ca.tholic Christianity) of the itask of forming ·a culture and " constructing a religiously informed public philosophy" in and for a plumlistic, democrrutic society such as that of America; and finally what he takes to be the ·appropriate sense of this fask in a world which he distinguishes as postmodern. Now Neuhaus develops his response to these issues in terms of wha;t he calls a paradoxical relation between the Church and the world. My purpose in what follows, therefore, will be to e:x;amine the meaning he accords " Catholic, " public," ·and "postmodern," m terms of this central notion of " paradox." I. In his discussion of the relation betwen rthe Church and the world, Neuhaus provides a sketch of the five types proposed by H. Richard Niebuhr (pp. 16ff.). These are: the Church against the world, the Church of the world, the Church above the world, the Church and the world in paradox, and the Church as the transformer of the wor1cl. The first, "the Church against the world," iis what is often identified as a sectarian model, evident for ex;ample in monasticism and in such communities ·as the Hutterites and Mennonites. The second type, " The Church of the world," can be exemplified in nmeitrenth century l.iberial theology 00:d its promotion of a THE CATHOLIC MOMENT 109 " cultural Protesitantism," wherein " rel[gion W18iS to be placed at the service of the besrt in the evolution of society" (p. 19). The model which views: the- Chur'Ch ia;s a transformer of the world "smacks of triumphalism" (p. 20), formerly of the Right, now in the post-V,aJtioanII era more commonly of the Left: the goal of the Church, perhaps even its exhaustive purpose, "is the estab1ishment of a Just Social Order" (p. 20). The fourth type, that of " the Church above the world," is exemplified in a theologian Hke Thomas Aquinas, who " aimed at ' synthesizing ' Christ and culture, Church and world, faith and reason, grace 1and nature" (p. 21) . Neuhaus's reasons for rejecting-even as he sees import.ant values in-the first three types can be put simply. While it is the case that Christians must always in some sli_gnificantsense be agai111St the world, they must also and at once be " for " the world: the relationship is always one of sic et non. Again, while the " Churich of the world" model legitimately emphasizes " the cosmic dimension of redemption " (p. 19) , the problem is that model all too easily removes any disson·ance between the Chmch and the world, and slides off into " talk about ' the secular city ' in which ' man come of age ' would USi.on of the rela1tiionof God 1and man rin Jesus Christ, and in ,turn of the relation of God and rbhe enrtire cosmos as mediated by Christ (ilhilough the Church in the Holy Sp[rit) , is rtrne, tihen :Lt follows rthat no enitirty or aspect of any enrbity of the OOSIIDOS is simply closed. No entity or iaspoot oif any entity ha:s iits proper idrotiity e:xiCept rel,rutively, iand hence as open from within: :a re1wbivity iand an openness, ith:rut is, which can only :be understood properly and finally in terms of the God of Jesus Ohriist ·and hence rthe tr.inibaa.iianGod of Christianity. 27 Tthe summairy questions which I wouJd piurt before Neuhaus, then, wiiith respect to the meaning of Catholicism and postmodernity, are the following: how is one to understand the graice-nruture relation in the light of the Nicene homoousion? Cain one undersrband thrut re1artion properly wirthourt understandmg it in terms of the onto1ogiieal intention suggested by 1 .24 See my "Catholicity and the State of Contemporary Theology," pp. 430434. It is crucial that the "already-not yet" character of the relation of God and the cosmos, established by God in Christ, be maintained, a.s well as the central role of human being in helping to realize this relation (on this, see especially the references given in nos. 6 and 7 of this article) . 25 See the beautiful and profound development of this theme in Ratzinger's Introduotion to Ohristianity, especially pp. 127-82. 26 In connection with my outline here of the meaning of the homoo'U8'ion, cf. the recent statements of Pope John Paul II: "The Christological definitions of the Councils and the Church's f.aith today," L'Osservatore Romooo, Eng. ed. (April 18, 1988), esp. p. 11; and the encyclical Dominum et Vivifi.oantem, esp. n. 50. 21 Cf. Walter Kasper, The God of JesiM Ghrist (New York: Crossroad, 1984). DAVID L. SCHINDLER the term homo<>usWn (" one iin being ") , and rindeed ias interpreted in the classical tradition? Does this term not indicaite a real simultaneity of unity and distinctness in Jesus: which is to say a 1'eal-'-direct, internal-relation of divine and human in Jesus? And if so, what then does ,it mean in turn to affirm that all of creation is created in and through (Jesus as) the Word, has its being in :the Woird? Does this ·affirmrution not mean that the real re1aJtion of God and man which !is Jesus's essentiially or by nature !is tin £11Jci mediillllted by JeS1Us (through hls Chureh in the Holy Spirit) to aU of creation, ,and rthait all of creation thereby shaxes in thrut real relation parrticipaitively or by ·adoprtion? That all of creation thereby mum be understood in ter:ms of this relation-and thus in terms of reLat!i.on? Whait then does this imply further in terms of rthe cosmic or :Wani.siformaitional:sense of Chr!i.sti1an!i.ty: in terms of the need borth to recognize and to help bring about this oivdering of ,all of be!i.ng to God (m Christ through his Church)? What does this need suggest for the Christi.an as he or she takes up the task of .fol'Illiing.and informing the culrturial .and polit!i.oallife of society? ,Jt bears empihrusiziingone final time thrut one can be under no il1usions .as to the diifficulty of .worlcinig through adequate ans;weirs to these queis:bioos: there is: of course an essential trut:h to Neuhaius's ins!i.stence thait a fully comprehensive vision will be ours only iin the End Time. And there should be no musiions as if:o the rirudieal nature of the questions. But in an important ,sense ithrut ii:s the rpotill.lt of cris!i.s: properly undeTstood, it sends us, or sihou1d send us,